You are on page 1of 1149

The Oxford Handbook of Culture

and Psychology
O X F O R D L I B R A RY O F P S Y C H O L O G Y

edito r -i n-chi e f

Peter E. Nathan

area e di tor s:

Clinical Psychology
David H. Barlow

Cognitive Neuroscience
Kevin N. Ochsner and Stephen M. Kosslyn

Cognitive Psychology
Daniel Reisberg

Counseling Psychology
Elizabeth M. Altmaier and Jo-Ida C. Hansen

Developmental Psychology
Philip David Zelazo

Health Psychology
Howard S. Friedman

History of Psychology
David B. Baker

Organizational Psychology
Steve W. J. Kozlowski

Methods and Measurement


Todd D. Little

Neuropsychology
Kenneth M. Adams

Personality and Social Psychology


Kay Deaux and Mark Snyder
OXFORD L I B R A RY OF PSYCHOLOGY

Editor in Chief peter e. nathan

The Oxford Handbook


of Culture and
Psychology
Edited by
Jaan Valsiner

1
1
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.

Oxford New York


Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto

With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam

Copyright (c) 2012 by Oxford University Press, Inc.

Published by Oxford University Press, Inc.


198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016
www.oup.com

Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,


stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise,
without the prior permission of Oxford University Press

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology / edited by Jaan Valsiner.
p. cm. — (Oxford library of psychology)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-19-539643-0
1. Ethnopsychology. 2. Culture–Psychological aspects. 3. Social psychology. I. Valsiner, Jaan.
GN270.O94 2012
155.8′2—dc22
2011010264

987654321
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
CONTENTS

Oxford Library of Psychology vii

About the Editor ix

Contributors xi

Contents xv

Chapters 1–1104

Index 1105

v
This page intentionally left blank
O X F O R D L I B R A R Y O F P S YC H O L O G Y

The Oxford Library of Psychology, a landmark series of handbooks, is published


by Oxford University Press, one of the world’s oldest and most highly respected
publishers, with a tradition of publishing significant books in psychology. The
ambitious goal of the Oxford Library of Psychology is nothing less than to span a
vibrant, wide-ranging field and, in so doing, to fill a clear market need.
Encompassing a comprehensive set of handbooks, organized hierarchically, the
Library incorporates volumes at different levels, each designed to meet a distinct
need. At one level are a set of handbooks designed broadly to survey the major
subfields of psychology; at another are numerous handbooks that cover impor-
tant current focal research and scholarly areas of psychology in depth and detail.
Planned as a reflection of the dynamism of psychology, the Library will grow
and expand as psychology itself develops, thereby highlighting significant new
research that will impact on the field. Adding to its accessibility and ease of use,
the Library will be published in print and, later on, electronically.
The Library surveys psychology’s principal subfields with a set of handbooks
that capture the current status and future prospects of those major subdisciplines.
This initial set includes handbooks of social and personality psychology, clini-
cal psychology, counseling psychology, school psychology, educational psychol-
ogy, industrial and organizational psychology, cognitive psychology, cognitive
neuroscience, methods and measurements, history, neuropsychology, personality
assessment, developmental psychology, and more. Each handbook undertakes to
review one of psychology’s major subdisciplines with breadth, comprehensiveness,
and exemplary scholarship. In addition to these broadly conceived volumes, the
Library also includes a large number of handbooks designed to explore in depth
more specialized areas of scholarship and research, such as stress, health and cop-
ing, anxiety and related disorders, cognitive development, or child and adolescent
assessment. In contrast to the broad coverage of the subfield handbooks, each of
these latter volumes focuses on an especially productive, more highly focused line
of scholarship and research. Whether at the broadest or most specific level, how-
ever, all of the Library handbooks offer synthetic coverage that reviews and evalu-
ates the relevant past and present research and anticipates research in the future.
Each handbook in the Library includes introductory and concluding chapters
written by its editor to provide a roadmap to the handbook’s table of contents and
to offer informed anticipations of significant future developments in that field.
An undertaking of this scope calls for handbook editors and chapter authors who
are established scholars in the areas about which they write. Many of the nation’s
and world’s most productive and best-respected psychologists have agreed to edit
Library handbooks or write authoritative chapters in their areas of expertise.

vii
For whom has the Oxford Library of Psychology been written? Because of its
breadth, depth, and accessibility, the Library serves a diverse audience, including
graduate students in psychology and their faculty mentors, scholars, researchers,
and practitioners in psychology and related fields. Each will find in the Library the
information they seek on the subfield or focal area of psychology in which they
work or are interested.
Befitting its commitment to accessibility, each handbook includes a compre-
hensive index, as well as extensive references to help guide research. And because
the Library was designed from its inception as an online as well as a print resource,
its structure and contents will be readily and rationally searchable online. Further,
once the Library is released online, the handbooks will be regularly and thor-
oughly updated.
In summary, the Oxford Library of Psychology will grow organically to provide a
thoroughly informed perspective on the field of psychology, one that reflects both
psychology’s dynamism and its increasing interdisciplinarity. Once published
electronically, the Library is also destined to become a uniquely valuable interac-
tive tool, with extended search and browsing capabilities. As you begin to consult
this handbook, we sincerely hope you will share our enthusiasm for the more
than 500-year tradition of Oxford University Press for excellence, innovation, and
quality, as exemplified by the Oxford Library of Psychology.

Peter E. Nathan
Editor-in-Chief
Oxford Library of Psychology

viii oxf ord l i b r a ry of psycholo g y


A B O U T T H E E D I TO R

Jaan Valsiner
Jaan Valsiner is a developmental cultural psychologist. He is the founding editor
(1995) of the major international journal Culture & Psychology (Sage) and Editor-
in-Chief of Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Sciences (Springer, from 2007).
He is also the recipient of Alexander von Humboldt Prize (1995) for his interdisci-
plinary work on human development.

ix
This page intentionally left blank
CO N T R I B U TO R S

Emily Abbey Mario Carretero


Department of Psychology Universidad Autónoma de Madrid and
Ramapo College of New Jersey FLACSO
Mahwah, NJ Argentina
Mayu Akasaka Pradeep Chakkarath
Graduate School of Letters Social Theory and Social Psychology
Ritsumeikan University Ruhr-University-Bochum, Germany
Kyoto, Japan Bochum, Germany
Cor Baerveldt Nandita Chaudhary
Department of Psychology University of Delhi
University of Alberta Department of Human Development and
Edmonton, Alberta, Canada Childhood Studies
Ana Cecília S. Bastos Delhi, India
Federal University of Bahia Michael Cole
Institute of Psychology/Institute of Public Health Department of Communication
Salvador, Brazil University of California, San Diego
Zachary Beckstead La Jolla, CA
Department of Psychology Carla C. Cunha
Clark University Universidade do Minho e Instituto Superior da
Worcester, MA Maia (ISMAI)
Tiago Bento Portugal
Department of Psychology and Communication Harry Daniels
ISMAI - Instituto Superior da Maia (ISMAI) Centre for Sociocultural and Activity Theory
Portugal Research
Angela Bermudez University of Bath
School of Education Bath, UK
Northeastern University Rainer Diriwächter
Boston, MA Department of Psychology
Christophe Boesch California Lutheran University
Max-Planck-Institut fur Evolutionäre Thousand Oaks, CA
Anthropologie Deborah Downing-Wilson
Leipzig, Germany Laboratory of Comparative Human
Ernst E. Boesch Cognition
University of Saarbrücken University of California, San Diego
Germany San Diego, CA
Angela Uchoa Branco Lutz H. Eckensberger
Laboratory of Microgenesis in Social Deutsches Institut für Internationale
Interactions Pädagogische Forschung
Instituto de Psicologia-Universidade de Brasília Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universität
Brasília, Brazil Frankfurt, Germany
Jens Brockmeier Wolfgang Friedlmeier
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Manitoba Grand Valley State University
Winnipeg, Manitoba, Canada Allendale, MI

xi
Mari Fukuda Irini Kadianaki
Graduate School of Humanities Department of Psychology
Ritsumeikan University University of Cyprus
Kyoto, Japan Nicosia, Cyprus
Alex Gillespie Heidi Keller
Department of Psychology Department of Culture and Development
University of Stirling University of Osnabrueck
Stirling, UK Osnabrueck, Germany
Simona Ginsburg Nikita A. Kharlamov
Department of Natural Science Department of Psychology
The Open University of Israel Clark University
Jerusalem, Israel Worcester, MA
Alfredo González-Ruibal Ayae Kido
Heritage Laboratory, Spanish National Department of Psychology
Research Council (CSIC) Ritsumeikan University
Santiago de Compostela, Spain Kyoto, Japan
Rom Harré Kalevi Kull
Department of Psychology Department of Semiotics
Georgetown University University of Tartu
Washington, D.C. Tartu, Estonia
Bob Heyman Robert Lecusay
Centre for Health and Social Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition
Care Research University of California, San Diego
University of Huddersfield San Diego, CA
Queensgate, Huddersfield, UK Xiaowen Li
Tomo Hidaka Department of Human Development
Graduate School of Humanities East China Normal University
Ritsumeikan University Shanghai, China
Kyoto, Japan Angélica López
Manfred Holodynski Department of Psychology
Institut for Psychology in Education University of California Santa Cruz
University of Münster Santa Cruz, CA
Münster, Germany Ana Flávia do Amaral Madureira
Antonio Iannaccone Department of Psychology
Institute of Psychology and Education Centro Universitário de Brasília
University of Neuchâtel Brasília, Brazil
Neuchâtel, Switzerland Riin Magnus
Robert E. Innis Department of Semiotics
Department of Philosophy University of Tartu
University of Massachusetts Lowell Tartu, Estonia
Lowell, MA Hala W. Mahmoud
Eva Jablonka Department of Social and Developmental
The Cohn institute for the Psychology
History and Philosophy of Science University of Cambridge
and Ideas United Kingdom & Africa and Middle East
Tel-Aviv University Refugee Assistance
Tel-Aviv, Israel Cairo, Egypt
Gustav Jahoda Ivana Marková
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
University of Strathclyde University of Stirling
Glasgow, Scotland, UK Stirling, Scotland, UK

xii contributo r s
Giuseppina Marsico Rebeca Puche-Navarro
Department of Education Science Centro de Investigaciones en Psicología
University of Salerno Cognición y Cultura
Fisciano, Italy Universidad del Valle
Mariann Märtsin Cali, Colombia
School of Social Sciences Elaine P. Rabinovich
Wales Institute of Social and Economic Catholic University of Salvador
Research, Data and Methods Bahia, Brazil
Cardiff University Susan J. Rasmussen
Cardiff, UK Department of Anthropology
Rebeca Mejía-Arauz University of Houston
Department of Psychology Houston, TX
ITESO University Carl Ratner
Guadalajara, Jalisco, Mexico Institute for Cultural Research and
Fathali M. Moghaddam Education
Department of Psychology Trinidad, CA
Georgetown University Barbara Rogoff
Washington, D.C. Department of Psychology
Kyoko Murakami University of California Santa Cruz
University of Bath Santa Cruz, CA
Department of Education Ivan Rosero
Bath, UK Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition
Behnosh Najafi Department of Communication
Department of Psychology University of California, San Diego
University of California Santa Cruz La Jolla, CA
Santa Cruz, CA João Salgado
Miki Nishida Instituto Superior da Maia (ISMAI)
Graduate School of Core Ethics and Frontier Portugal
Sciences Sergio Salvatore
Ritsumeikan University Università del Salento
Kyoto, Japan Department of Educational, Psychological and
Cristina Novoa Teaching Sciences
Department of Psychology Lecce, Italy
Georgetown University Tatsuya Sato
Washington, D.C. Department of Psychology
A. Bame Nsamenang Faculty of Letters
Human Development Resource Centre Ritsumeikan University
Bamenda, Cameroon Kyoto, Japan
Ria O’Sullivan-Lago Lívia Mathias Simão
Department of Sociology Institute of Psychology
University of Limerick University of São Paulo
Limerick, Ireland São Paulo, Brazil
Seonah Oh Noboru Takahashi
Department of International Studies Department of School Education
Kyoai Gakuen College Osaka Kyoiku University
Gunma, Japan Osaka, Japan
Chengnan Pian Kazuko Takeo
School of Sociology Faculty of Science Division 1
China University of Political Science and Law Tokyo University of Science
Beijing, China Tokyo, Japan

con tribu tors xiii


Eero Tarasti Brady Wagoner
University of Helsinki Department of Communication & Psychology
Institute of Art Research Aalborg University
Helsinki, Finland Aalborg, Denmark
Iddo Tavory Zachary Warren
Department of Sociology Department of Psychology
The New School for Social Research Georgetown University
New York, NY Washington, D.C.
Aaro Toomela Meike Watzlawik
Institute of Psychology Beratungsinstitut für Analyse und
Tallinn University Berufsfindung
Tallinn, Estonia Bremen, Germany
Jaan Valsiner Cynthia E. Winston
Department of Psychology Department of Psychology
Clark University Howard University
Worcester, MA Washington, D.C.
René van der Veer Michael R. Winston
Leiden University Department of History
Department of Education Howard University
Leiden, The Netherlands Washington, D.C.
Bert van Oers Toshiya Yamamoto
Department Theory and Research in Education School of Human Sciences
Faculty of Psychology and Education Waseda University
VU University Tokorozawa City, Saitama, Japan
Amsterdam, The Netherlands Tania Zittoun
Theo Verheggen University of Neuchâtel
Department of Psychology Institute of Psychology and Education
Open Universiteit Nederland Neuchâtel, Switzerland
Heerlen, the Netherlands

xiv contr i buto r s


CONTENTS

Part One • Historical Linkages of Culture and Psychology


Introduction: Culture in Psychology: A Renewed
Encounter of Inquisitive Minds 3
Jaan Valsiner
1. Culture and Psychology: Words and Ideas in History 25
Gustav Jahoda
2. Völkerpsychologie 43
Rainer Diriwächter
3. Cultural-Historical Psychology: Contributions of Lev Vygotsky 58
René van der Veer

Part Two • Inter- and Intradisciplinary Perspectives


4. The Role of Indigenous Psychologies in the Building
of Basic Cultural Psychology 71
Pradeep Chakkarath
5. Cultural Anthropology 96
Susan J. Rasmussen
6. Cross-Cultural Psychology: Taking People, Contexts,
and Situations Seriously 116
Heidi Keller
7. Archeology and the Study of Material Culture: Synergies
With Cultural Psychology 132
Alfredo González-Ruibal

Part Three • Positions in the Field


8. Enactivism 165
Cor Baerveldt and Theo Verheggen
9. Positioning Theory: Moral Dimensions of
Social-Cultural Psychology 191
Rom Harré
10. Macro-Cultural Psychology 207
Carl Ratner

Part Four • Semiosis in Culture and Psychology


11. Social Life of the Sign: Sense-Making in Society 241
Sergio Salvatore

xv
12. Meaningful Connections: Semiotics, Cultural Psychology,
and the Forms of Sense 255
Robert E. Innis
13. The City As a Sign: A Developmental-Experiential
Approach to Spatial Life 277
Nikita A. Kharlamov
14. Modeling Iconic Literacy: The Dynamic Models for
Complex Cultural Objects 303
Rebeca Puche-Navarro
15. Existential Semiotics and Cultural Psychology 316
Eero Tarasti

Part Five • Action, Self, and Narration


16. Culture: Result and Condition of Action 347
Ernest E. Boesch
17. Culture-Inclusive Action Theory: Action Theory in Dialectics
and Dialectics in Action Theory 357
Lutz H. Eckensberger
18. The Other in the Self: A Triadic Unit 403
Lívia Mathias Simão
19. Dialogical Theory of Selfhood 421
Tiago Bento, Carla C. Cunha, and João Salgado
20. Narrative Scenarios: Toward a Culturally Thick Notion of Narrative 439
Jens Brockmeier
21. Culture in Action: A Discursive Approach 468
Kyoko Murakami
22. Social Representations As Anthropology of Culture 487
Ivana Marková

Part Six • Tools for Living: Transcending Social Limitations


23. Life-Course: A Socio-Cultural Perspective 513
Tania Zittoun
24. Being Poor: Cultural Tools for Survival 536
Ana Cecília S. Bastos and Elaine P. Rabinovich
25. Cultural Psychology of Racial Ideology in Historical Perspective: An
Analytic Approach to Understanding Racialized Societies and Their
Psychological Effects on Lives 558
Cynthia E. Winston and Michael R. Winston
26. Belonging to Gender: Social Identities, Symbolic Boundaries and
Images 582
Ana Flávia do Amaral Madureira
27. Risk and Culture 602
Bob Heyman
28. Constructing Histories 625
Mario Carretero and Angela Bermudez

xvi contents
Part Seven • Emergence of Culture
29. Roots of Culture in the Umwelt 649
Riin Magnus and Kalevi Kull
30. Culture and Epigenesis: A Waddingtonian View 662
Iddo Tavory, Eva Jablonka, and Simona Ginsburg
31. From Material to Symbolic Cultures: Culture in Primates 677
Christophe Boesch

Part Eight • Human Movement Through Culture


32. Encountering Alterity: Geographic and Semantic Movements 695
Alex Gillespie, Irini Kadianaki, and Ria O’Sullivan-Lago
33. Crossing Thresholds: Movement As a Means of Transformation 710
Zachary Beckstead
34. Never “at-Home”?: Migrants between Societies 730
Mariann Märtsin and Hala W. Mahmoud

Part Nine • Culture of Higher Social Regulators: Values,


Magic, and Duties
35. Values and Socio-Cultural Practices: Pathways to Moral Development 749
Angela Uchoa Branco
36. The Intergenerational Continuity of values 767
A. Bame Nsamenang
37. The Making of Magic: Cultural Constructions of the
Mundane Supernatural 783
Meike Watzlawik and Jaan Valsiner
38. Duties and Rights 796
Fathali M. Moghaddam, Cristina Novoa, and Zachary Warren

Part Ten • Cultural Interfaces: Persons and Institutions


39. The Interface Between the Sociology of Practice and the
Analysis of Talk in the Study of Change in Educational Settings 817
Harry Daniels
40.The Work of Schooling 830
Giuseppina Marsico and Antonio Iannacone
41.Collaboration and Helping as Cultural Practices 869
Angélica López, Behnosh Najafi, Barbara Rogoff, and Rebeca Mejía-Arauz
42. A Cultural-Historical Approach to University/Community
Collaborative Interventions 885
Deborah Downing-Wilson, Robert Lecusay, Ivan Rosero, and Michael Cole

Part Eleven • Social Networks and Cultural Affectivity


43. Affective Networks: The Social Terrain of a Complex Culture 901
Nandita Chaudhary

con ten ts xvii


44. Peer Relations 917
Xiaowen Li
45. Culture in Play 936
Bert van Oers
46. Affect and Culture 957
Manfred Holodynski and Wolfgang Friedlmeier

Part Twelve • Toward Methodological Innovations


for Cultural Psychology
47.Ambivalence and Its Transformations 989
Emily Abbey
48. Guesses on the Future of Cultural Psychology: Past, Present, and Past 998
Aaro Toomela
49. Culture in Constructive Remembering 1034
Brady Wagoner
50. How Can We Study Interactions Mediated by Money
as a Cultural Tool: From the Perspectives of “Cultural Psychology of
Differences” as a Dialogical Method 1056
Toshiya Yamamoto, Noboru Takahashi, Tatsuya Sato, Kazuko Takeo,
Seonah Oh, and Chengnan Pian
51. The Authentic Culture of Living Well: Pathways to
Psychological Well-Being 1078
Tatsuya Sato, Mari Fukuda, Tomo Hidaka, Ayae Kido, Miki Nishida,
and Mayu Akasaka
52. Psychology Courting Culture: Future Directions and
Their Implications 1092
Jaan Valsiner

Index 1105

xviii contents
PA RT
1
Historical Linkages of
Culture and Psychology
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction: Culture in Psychology:
A Renewed Encounter of
Inquisitive Minds
Jaan Valsiner

Abstract
This introductory chapter outlines the historical picture of the recent interest in the linking of culture
and psychology, as well as the conceptual obstacles that have stood on the way of re-introducing
complexity of human psychological functions—higher cultural forms—to psychological research
practices. The avoidance of complex and dynamic phenomena (affective processes in feeling, religious
sentiments that take the form of values, and of the high varieties of cultural forms displayed all over the
World) has limited psychology’s knowledge creation. In the past two decades, with the emergence of
cultural psychology at the intersection of developmental, educational, and social psychologies and their
linking with cultural anthropology, sociology, and history, we have observed a renewed effort to build an
interdisciplinary synthesis of ideas. This takes place in the wider social context of the globalizing world.
Psychology needs culture to make sense of the human lives.
Keywords: cultural psychology, causality, quantity, quality, affect, globalization

This Handbook is a milestone in the effort to bring culture into psychology. Such enthusiasm is
re-unite two large domains of knowledge—one cov- needed—as revolutions, both in science and in soci-
ered by the generic term psychology, and the other by eties, need it. Innovation in any science is impos-
the equally general term culture. When two giants sible without the efforts of the scientists to explore
meet, one never knows what might happen—it can the not yet known lands of the ideas that may seem
become a battle or the two can amiably join their nonsensical from the point of view of accepted
forces and live happily ever after. The latter “happy knowledge yet tease the mind.
end” of a fairy tale is far from the realities of the his- The complexity of the task of bringing culture
tory of the social sciences. into psychology as a science has been considerable.
In the case of this Handbook, we have evidence It has been historically blocked by a number of social
of a multisided effort to develop the connections agents (representing rivaling ideologies) who saw in
between culture and psychology. The time may be this a damage to psychology as natural science (see
ripe—discourse about that unity has re-emerged Valsiner, 2012, Chapters 5–9). As a result, psychol-
since the 1980s, and cultural psychology has ogy has suffered from its self-generated image of
become consolidated since the mid-1990s around being an “objective science”—of deeply subjective
its core journal Culture & Psychology (published by and culturally organized phenomena. Such historical
Sage/London). The present Handbook reflects that myopia can be understood as a need for the discipline
tradition, while extending it toward new interdisci- to compete in the representational beauty contest
plinary horizons. The contributors— from all over of the sciences. Yet it cannot win that contest—
the World—enthusiastically take on the task to remaining such a frivolous competitor whose claims

3
to “objectivity” are easily falsified by yet another There can be very many different vantage points
innovation in the social or psychological domain. from where culture could enter into psychol-
ogy in the twenty-first century. First, of course,
Psychology’s “Blind Spot”: Personal Will there are the realistic connections with neighbor-
As a Cultural Phenomenon ing disciplines—cultural anthropology (Holland,
Historical myopia of a discipline has dire conse- 2010; Obeyesekere, 2005, 2010; Skinner, Pach, &
quences. Psychology of the last century turned out Holland, 1998; Rasmussen, 2011), and sociology
to be mute when basic human life phenomena— (Kharlamov, 2012)—from where such efforts could
famines, wars, epidemics, religious piety and preju- find their start. Yet in the last decade we also can
dice, political negotiations, and migration—have observe the move inside of the vast field of psychol-
been concerned. It has refrained from the study ogy. Psychology itself is a heterogeneous discipline—
of higher—volitional—psychological functions, within which we can observe a number of moves
while concentrating on the lower, simpler ones. toward embracing the notion of culture. Although
Thus, psychology of affect has many ways to deal it began from the educational and developmental
with basic emotion categories that are expressed concerns of the 1980s that mostly used the ideas
similarly all around the world—yet has not made of Vygotsky as the center of their new efforts, by
new breakthroughs in understanding the general- 2010s the effort also includes social psychology—
ized feelings that lead to desirous actions and gen- both in Europe and the United States—where the
eralized values. The intentional affective actions generic label “social” becomes frequently taken over
were actively investigated until the beginning of the by “cultural.”
twentieth century in psychology but rarely later. It Second, it is the rapid movement—of messages and
is the semiotic and narrative focus of our contem- people—that renders the former images of homoge-
porary cultural psychology that restores our focus neous classes that dominated cross-cultural psychology
onto these humanly important phenomena. The either moot or problematic. The tradition of compar-
most important cultural invention of the human ing societies (i.e., countries, re-labeled as “cultures”—
psyche is the simple claim, “I want <X>!”—and it e.g., of “the Mexicans” or “the Germans”)—which has
is precisely the least studied and understood theme been accepted practice in cross-cultural psychology—
in contemporary psychology. Although there is loses its epistemological value. Empirical comparisons
increasing interest, in cultural psychology, on the of the averages of samples “from different cultures”
“I” part (e.g., Dialogical Self Theories), the “want” (i.e., countries) can bring out interesting starting data
part of this simple meaning construction is rarely for further analysis by cultural psychology.
analyzed. The notable exception—Heider, (1958, All this is supported by real-life social changes.
1983)—is an example of a synthesis of different It is as if the globalizing movement of people
European philosophical and psychological tra- across country boundaries brings “cultural for-
ditions. Psychology has been fearful of the will- eigners” to be next-door neighbors. The issue of
ful human being and has instead presented the making sense of their ways of living becomes of
human psyche as an object influenced by a myriad interest for the already established colonists of the
of “factors” from all directions—biological, social, given place. It is hard to remain content with the
economic, even unconscious—rather than by the prototypical notions of “being American” when
volition that could break out from all these con- one sees a collective Islamic prayer unfolding in
fines and develop in new directions. the middle of a major U.S. airport. The world is
now different from the last century—we are in
Why Another Effort to Link Psychology close contact with “cultural others,” and all our
With Culture? social-psychological adaptations to this innovation
Given this complex history, bringing culture acquire a cultural accent. Contemporary social
back into psychology is also a very multifaceted psychology picks up the need to study such social
effort in today’s intellectual environment. Yet the events that carry complex cultural accents. It is
realities of social life guide us toward it—in a world supported by the demand of both the lay pub-
where people travel voraciously and their messages lics in different countries and their socio-political
travel instantly, the know-how of how “the others” organizations to understand and administer the
function is both necessary for life and profitable for “cultural others” yet retain their own dominant
businesses. centrality.

4 c ulture in psycholo g y
The Third Effort for Psychology in its Leipzig in 1879. It was followed in North America
History: How Can it Succeed? by the avalanche of the “behaviorist” ideology
This effort—uniting culture and psychology— (Watson, 1913), which has been slow to end. The
that has been taking place from the 1990s to the intermediate birth of “cognitive science” in the
present time is actually the third one1 in the history 1950s from the behaviorist roots was a half-resto-
of psychology. We can observe, in the recent two ration of the focus on higher psychological func-
decades, multiple efforts to bring culture into the tions. Hence, the cultural psychology movement
science in general. Likewise, psychology begins to that started in the 1980s constitutes another effort
enter into cultural arenas in many new ways that in that direction.
Little Albert,2 Ioni,3 or Sultan,4 or even the dogs of
Professor Pavlov could never have thought about. A The Obstacles to Innovation
number of our contributions to this Handbook— As psychology is non-neutral in its context of
those of Christophe Boesch (2012), Alfredo social existence, it is not surprising that its prog-
Gonzalez-Ruibal (2012) and Zachary Beckstead ress is constantly organized by different promoting
(2012)—give the readers a glimpse of new pathways fashions (e.g., the need to look “socially relevant”)
for future development of cultural psychology. in unison with a multitude of conceptual obstacles.
Of course, psychology’s historical inroads can The latter are often the targets of discourse in cul-
be seen to have delayed such return to culture. tural psychology that cannot avoid addressing them.
The issue has been ideological in the history of Their relevance, of course, transcends the work in
the science of psychology—how to treat complex, the realms of cultural psychology and would illumi-
meaningful, intentional, and dynamic psychologi- nate other fields of psychology.
cal phenomena? These phenomena were actively
addressed in the context of emerging psychology in Decision About Where Not to Look:
Germany by philosophers in the first seven decades Axiomatic Dismissal of Complexity
of the nineteenth century—yet all these contri- Many of the habits of psychology, in their
butions were lost as they were guided out of the insistence on the study of elementary phenomena
history of psychology as it was re-written after the (Toomela & Valsiner, 2010), have led to avoid-
1870s. According to most of the history textbook ing the complexities of the human psychological
views, psychology as science was born in 1879. functioning. This happens in a number of ways:
That origin myth dates back to Boring’s work on by imperative to quantify those phenomena
re-writing the history of psychology (Boring, 1929) that are of “scientific interest” and by develop-
that selected as science only some part of the wide ing theories inductively—moving toward gen-
intellectual enterprise of psychology of the nine- eralization from the thus selectively quantified
teenth century. evidence. This all happens with the belief in the
Psychology as a science was born in the work of elementaristic causality (factor X causes
German language environment—first in the 1730s Y; e.g., “intelligence” causes success in problem
(Christian Wolff’s Psicologia empirica in 1732 and solving; or “culture” causes “girls being shy”; see
Psicologia rationalis in 1734), followed by the Toomela, 2012, in this Handbook). In contrast,
anti-Wolff denial of psychology’s place among cultural psychology leaves such causal attributions
other sciences by Immanuel Kant. The birth of behind. Culture here emerges as a generic term
psychology as part of educational curriculae dates to capture the complexity of human lives—rather
to years 1806 and later—when Johann Friedrich than narrowly concentrating on their behavior.
Herbart started his first university course in psy- We are back to the study of psychological dynam-
chology (Jahoda, 2008; Teo, 2007). Yet in the early ics in all of its complexity (Valsiner, 2009a), yet
nineteenth-century psychology was the realm for we are still at a loss about how to do that. The
discourse by philosophers and theologians, with lead from the “second cybernetics” of the 1960s
natural scientists playing a secondary role. This (Maruyama, 1963) and the use of qualitative
power relation reversed in the 1860s in favor of mathematical models (Rudolph, 2006a, 2006b,
the natural sciences—particularly physiology. This 2006c, 2008a, 2008b, 2009; Rudolph & Valsiner,
led to the “elementaristic revolution” in psychol- 2008; Tsuda, 2001) instead of statistical inference
ogy that started from Wilhelm Wundt’s establish- can be a way to overcome the obstacles of unwar-
ing his laboratory of Experimental Psychology in ranted assumptions.

va lsin er 5
The Terminological Difficulty—Culture of imperatives rather than creating innovations.
Is Polysemic Psychology has suffered from too many consen-
Culture is in some sense a magic word—positive sual fixations of the “right” methods in the last
in connotations but hard to pinpoint in any science half-century (Toomela, 2007a), rendering its
that attempts to use it as its core term. Its impor- innovative potentials mute. Cultural psychology
tance is accentuated by our contemporary fashion- as a new direction entails an effort to un-mute
able common language terms (multiculturalism, the discipline. It is helped by the appeal—and
cultural roots, cultural practices, etc.)—hence the uncertainty—of the label culture.
perceived value of the term. Yet much of “nor-
mal science” of psychology continues to produce Culture As a “Container” as Opposed to a “Tool”
hyperempirical work using methods that do not The readers in this Handbook will encounter
consider substantive innovation, even after having two opposite directions in handling of the notion
learned to insert the word culture into politically of culture—that of a container of a homogeneous
correct locations in its various texts. In this sense, class (Fig. I.1A), and that of a unique organizer of
the fate of culture in contemporary psychology person–environment relations (Fig. I.1B). These
continues to be that of up-and-coming novice who two uses have little or nothing in common, once
tries to get its powerful parents to accommodate more indicating the vagueness of the use of culture
to its needs. in our present-day social sciences.
Cultural psychology is being sculpted in a vari- Of course the proliferation of the notion of
ety of versions—all unified by the use of the word culture in the social sciences is no issue of science
culture (Boesch, 1991; Cole, 1996, Shweder, 1990). only. Reasons for that increasing popularity of a
That may be where its unity ends, giving rise to a vague label are to be found beyond the boundar-
varied set of perspectives that only partially link ies of science—in the “culture stress” experienced
with one another. This may be confusing for those by local communities resulting from in-migration
who try to present cultural psychology as a mono- of “others” and temporary (or not so temporary)
lithic discipline—but it is certainly good for the outmigration of “our own” (Appadurai, 2006). Our
development of new perspectives. Heterogeneity globalizing world is also open to various projec-
of a discipline breeds innovation—whereas tions of oneself to the (far-away) others. Politicians
homogenization kills it. History of psychology start to pretend they can say something in a foreign
gives us many examples of originally innovative language in public, whereas production capacities
perspectives turning into established “theories or move from their “First World” locations to the so-
systems”—and becoming followed through sets called “developing countries.”

(A) (B)
C
P
P PERSONS
create
C SOCIETY in C
PERSONS are IN CULTURE
between
them
P P
C

BOUNDARY of “culture” IS ASSUMED BOUNDARY of “society” IS ASSUMED


TO BE RIGID AND DEFINED TO BE FLUID AND CHANGING

Figure I.1 Two meanings of culture in psychology. (A) Culture as a container (P = person). (B) Culture (C) as a tool within person.

6 c ulture in psycholo g y
The Hero Mythology—Replacing centuries (Jahoda, 1993, 2011). Such slow move-
Innovation by Finished Ideas ment results from projection of social values into the
Psychologists like to tell stories—beautiful sto- term—culture is not a neutral term. It is suspect—and
ries—about famous people of their kind who had appealing—at the same time. Its appealing label feeds
clever ideas that are still guiding our contemporary into the advancement of various streams of thought
thinking. Of course, it is in the communication in the social sciences (Rohner, 1984; Sinha, 1996),
process between a science and the society that the and the constructive openness in using it as an intel-
making of such “hero myths” operates in creat- lectual catalyst in psychology continues.
ing cultural connectors (Aubin, 1997, p. 300). The Although it is well-known (Valsiner, 2001,
popularity of “being X-ian” is a token in the pub- 2004a) that the term culture is vague, as it has been
lic legitimization of a particular perspective (e.g., proven indefinable, yet its functional role in public
“Vygotskian” is “promising,” “behavioral” is “past discourse has been growing steadily. Vagueness of a
its prime”)—independently of the particular ideas concept need not be an obstacle in scientific knowl-
used within these perspectives to make sense of some edge-building (many terms in many sciences are)
phenomenon. Freud, Skinner, Piaget, and Vygotsky and are kept vague, so as to enhance their generative
are often put on the pedestal for having revealed potential (Löwy, 1992). As Löwy has explained:
the great secrets of the psyche. Telling such stories
The long-term survival of imprecise terms points to
is dangerous for the ideas of precisely those persons
an important heuristic role. Adopting an over-precise
who are being honored. On the theoretical side,
definition may jeopardize a promising study, while
glory stories of various “giants” such as Vygotsky,
maintaining a poorly defined concept may propel
Bakhtin, Gadamer, Levinas, and others are likely
fruitful research. Imprecise terms may also facilitate
to promote the mentality of following previously
the study of phenomena that share some, yet poorly
expressed ideas, rather than developing new ones.
defined, characteristics, and that may help link
Rather than innovate historically solid intellectual
distinct disciplinary approaches. The fluidity of terms
perspectives—the makers of which tried, but still
at times of conceptual change makes retrospective
did not solve their problems—we seem to enjoy
discovery accounts especially problematic. Discoverers
turning these “classic thinkers” into some gurus and
tend to attribute a later, fixed meaning and imprecise,
follow them ardently. Taking a theoretical perspec-
fluid terms current at the time of the discovery.
tive becomes transformed into a membership of a
(Löwy, 1990, p. 89)
fan club of one or another of such guru figures—
leading to a variety of intra- and intergroup rela- The fate of culture in psychology and anthropol-
tionship issues of such groups of followers. The ogy fits Löwy’s point well. Since the 1990s, we have
main function of theories—being intellectual gen- seen the acceptance of the term by psychologists,
eral tools for understanding—easily gets lost. Social who pride themselves in its vagueness and make it
scientists seem to enjoy the game of social position- useful in various ways. In contrast, cultural anthro-
ing. We can still observe recurrent claims of “being pologists can be seen refusing to use it at all! Culture
X-ian” (“Vygotskian,” “Bakhtinian,” “Freudian,” as a term becomes useless in anthropology, whereas
“Habermasian,” “Levinasian,” etc.). I consider such it is becoming useful in psychology!
claims misleading, because the best way to follow
a thinker is to develop the ideas further—rather Psychology Is Becoming Global
than declare one’s membership in a virtual commu- Globalization in a science—like in economics
nity. But mere membership in a community is no and society—is an ambiguous process. It brings
solution to problems that the members of the com- with it emergence of new opportunities together
munity try to solve. The scientific community is a with the demise of old (and “safe”) practices. The
resource for providing new solutions—rather than immediate result of globalization is the increase of
a club, the membership of which is determined by “sudden contacts” between varied persons of dif-
loyalty to old ones. ferent backgrounds—with all that such contact
implies (Moghaddam, 2006). If “culture” is viewed
Vagueness in Science and its Functions in terms of a “container” (Fig. I.1A) that implies
We know that culture’s journey into psychology selective “border controls,” segregation of immi-
has already been in the making for more than two grants into “we <>they” categories, and emphasis

va lsin er 7
on acculturation (Rudmin, 2010). If, in contrast, hamburgers—in their places). In all of these adapta-
“culture” under globalization is seen as a tool (Fig. tions to such contacts, the diversity of both human
I.1B) it is the issue of relating to one’s next-door cultural and biological forms is being negotiated
neighbor—with both positive (mutual learning and (Kashima, 2007; Moghaddam, 2006).
support from one another) and negative (frictions
and open conflicts over trivial local issues) that The Gains—and Their Pains—in Cultural
come into our focus of observation. Psychology
Science also has to learn to tolerate its often less The last two decades of the twentieth century
affluent but better educated neighbor. Any casual were productive for cultural psychology. Following
reading of leading science journals, which may be the lead of the originators of the rebirth of the
published in North America or Europe, reveals cultural direction (Richard Shweder, Michael
the enormous mixture of the home countries of Cole, James Wertsch and Barbara Rogoff in North
the scientists. People from all continents collabo- America, and Ernest Boesch, Lutz Eckensberger,
rate in the solving of crucial scientific problems. Serge Moscovici, Ivana Markova and Ivan Ivic
Not surprisingly, together with the move toward in Europe), a number of younger-generation
international economic interdependence comes researchers started to look at human phenomena
internationalization of sciences. Like other sci- intertwined with their everyday contexts. By the
ences psychology is no longer dominated by few twenty-first century, many new research directions
(North American or European) models of “doing have become emphasized—ruptures as central for
science” in that area. Instead, creative solutions to new developments (Hale, 2008; Zittoun, 2004,
complex problems emerge from the “developing 2006, 2007, 2010), actuations as a new way to
world,” where the whole range of the variety of unite actions and meanings (Rosa, 2007), gener-
cultural phenomena guarantees the potential rich- alized significant symbols (Gillespie, 2006) as well
ness of psychology. as search for the self through looking at the other
(Bastos & Rabinovich, 2009; Simão & Valsiner,
Cultural Psychology: Its Indigenous Roots 2007) and finding that other in the contexts of
Of course different areas of psychology are dif- social interdependence (Chaudhary, 2004, 2007;
ferentially open to such internationalization— Menon, 2002; Tuli & Chaudhary, 2010). At the
cultural psychology in its recent new upsurge is same time, we see continuous interest in the cul-
thus a “developing science.” Looking back, much tural nature of subjectivity (Boesch, 2005, 2008;
has changed since mid-1990s (Valsiner, 1995, Cornejo, 2007; Sullivan, 2007) and the unpredict-
2001, 2004, 2009a, 2009b), mostly in the con- ability of environments (Abbey, 2007; Golden &
text within which the discourses of re-entering talk Mayseless, 2008). The topic of multivoicedness of
about culture into psychology have been framed. the self as it relates with the world has emerged as
Cultural psychology has been the witness—an a productive theme (Bertau, 2008; Joerchel, 2007;
active one—of the transformations that go on in all Salgado & Gonçalves, 2007; Sullivan, 2007),
of psychology as it is globalizing (Valsiner, 2009a, including the move to consider the opposites of
2009b). Nevertheless, within psychology, cultural polyphony (“intensified nothingness,” Mladenov,
psychology remains “indigenous”—emphasizing 1997). This is embedded in the multiplicity of dis-
the phenomena, rather than data, as these are cen- course strategies (Castro & Batel, 2008) in insti-
tral for science. tutional contexts (Phillips, 2007). Affective lives
Indigenous is not a pejorative word. We are all are situated in social contexts but by persons them-
indigenous as unique human beings, social units, selves as they relate to social institutions.
and societies—coming to sudden contact with oth-
ers of the same kind, and discovering that it is “the Old Disputes in New Form: Immediacy
other” who is indigenous, not ourselves. Different and Mediation
ways of actions follow: changing the other (by mis- It never ceases to amaze me how old disputes re-
sionary or military conquests) or using the other for emerge in terminologically new ways. When in the
production (by importing slaves, or allowing “guest 1950s psychologists were disputing the immediacy
workers” temporarily into “our country” to allevi- of perception (a la James Gibson) in contrast to the
ate labor shortages), or for consumption (creating constructive nature of the perceptual act (a la Jerome
consumer demands for our products—arms or Bruner and Leo Postman, 1950—not to forget

8 c ulture in psycholo g y
Ansbacher, 1937 for the origins), then 50 years it is the latter to which the enactivist viewpoint
later, we find a similar dispute in cultural psy- adheres.
chology around the issues of enactivism, focusing
on the immediate nature of cultural actions— Construction of Signs and Their Use—
and mediation—that centers on the distancing Alternative to Immediacy
from (yet with) the immediate action (Baerveldt In contrast to the enactivist orientation, the
& Verheggen, 1999, 2012; Kreppner, 1999; semiotic meditational direction (Boesch, 2005,
Christopher & Bickhard, 2007; Crisswell, 2009; 2008, 2012; Lonner & Hayes, 2007; Valsiner,
Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2007). Furthermore, 2007) accepts the notion of mediation as an axi-
the immediacy dispute is built around the John omatic given and concentrates on the construction
Dewey-inspired look at human development as of what kind of mediating systems can be discovered
seamless linking of person and context (Rogoff, in human everyday activities and in the domains
1982, 1993, 2003). The question of boundaries of feeling and thinking. The focus on cultural
between person and environment has been actively tools—or symbolic resources (Zittoun, 2006,
disputed in the last two decades. Of course, human 2007, 2012)—necessarily prioritizes the medita-
beings live within the boundary—circumscribed tional view in cultural psychology. This is further
by their skin. Futuristic film-makers, such as supported by the work to bring Charles S. Peirce’s
David Kroonenberg, have recently experimented semiotics to cultural psychology (Innis, 2005, 2012;
with images that make the skin transferrable and Rosa, 2007; Sonesson, 2010). Yet bringing in the
let objects enter and exit through the skin in sur- philosophy of Peirce is a kind of “Trojan horse” for
prising—and horrifying—ways. cultural psychology—if on the manifest level such
The roots of this new focus on immediacy are in importation allows for new look at the multitude
the resurgence of the centrality of the body in theo- of signs that organize human lives. Such appealing
rizing about human beings and its abstracted corol- closeness to reality is supported by Peirce’s abstrac-
lary in terms of the processes of embodiment of the tions as a mathematician.
mental processes (Varela, Thompson, & Ross, 1991).
Refocusing on the body—under the philosophy of The Unresolved Problem: Units of
fighting against “mind–body dualisms”—leads to Analysis
the elimination of the mind. And with the elimina- The difficulty of returning to the psychological
tion of the mind goes the focus on mediation. complexity in the context of cultural psychology is
in the rest of psychology accepting the notion of
Immediacy in Its Enactivist Form analysis units as the atomistic concept of divisibil-
The enactivist position has been put forth ity of the complexity to simplicity. Yet that tradi-
succinctly: tion cannot work if complexity as it exists—rather
than as it could be eliminated—is on the agenda for
Enactivism avoids the notion of “mediation” and
researchers (Matusov, 2007).
problematizes the representational or semiotic
The root metaphor of the question of units in
status of social and cultural objects in general.
psychology has been the contrast between water
Representation is a sophisticated social act and in
(H2O) and its components (oxygen and hydrogen),
that sense it is tautological to add the adjective
used in making the point of the primacy of the
“social.” Moreover, this specification becomes
Gestalt over its constituents widely in the late nine-
misleading when “social” is understood in terms of
teenth- through early twentieth-century thought.
sharedness, even when the notion of sharedness is
The properties of water are not reducible to those
systemic rather than aggregate one.
of either hydrogen or oxygen—water may put out a
(Verheggen and Baerveldt, 2007, p. 22)
fire, whereas the constituents of it burn or enhance
Of course, the enactivist move against ideas of burning. Hence the whole, a water molecule, is
mediation triggers a counteroffensive (Chryssides more than a mere “sum” of its parts. Furthermore,
et al., 2009) defending the role of social represen- it is universal—the chemical structure of water
tation processes precisely as acts of social construc- remains the same, independent of whatever biologi-
tion. The focus on social representation can be cal system (e.g., human body, cellular structure of a
dialectical (Marková, 2003, 2012), and the act of plant) or geological formation (e.g., an ocean, or in
representing can itself be embodied. It seems that a water bottle) in which it exists. Vygotsky expressed

va lsin er 9
the general idea of what a unit of analysis needs to of all social discourses about the phenomena, as
be like in psychology: well as about the social sciences that study these
phenomena. This challenge is most visible in the
Psychology, as it desires to study complex
field—in the deeply politically embedded activities
wholes . . . needs to change the methods of analysis
of NGOs in their relations with local government
into elements by the analytic method that reveals
agencies, community structures, and personal goals
the parts of the unit [literally: breaks the whole into
(Bourdier, 2008). Culture in the field is a politi-
linked units—metod . . . analiza, . . . razchleniayushego
cally contested, non-neutral complex used by all
na edinitsy]. It has to find the further undividable,
disputing sides for their objectives (Wikan, 2002).
surviving features that are characteristic of the given
Possibly precisely because of such multiplicity of
whole as a unity—units within which in mutually
vested interests, the process of “Westernization” can
opposing ways these features are represented [Russian:
be replaced by a notion of parallel development of
edinitsy, v kotorykh v protivopolozhnom
societies in contact. As Kagitçibasi (2005, p. 267)
vide predstavleny eti svoistva].5
has commented:
(Vygotsky, 1999, p. 13)

Vygotsky’s notion of units fits into the general . . . as societies modernize (with increased
structure, emphasizing the unity of parts and focus- urbanization, education, affluence etc.), they do
ing on their relationship. not necessarily demonstrate a shift toward western
However, it is easy to see how Vygotsky’s dialec- individualism. A more complex transformation is
tical units—into opposing parts of the whole—go seen in family patterns of modernizing societies with
beyond the water analogy. The whole (water)— cultures of relatedness. The emerging pattern shares
parts (oxygen, hydrogen) and relations—are fixed important characteristics with both individualism
as long as water remains water. In reality of human and collectivism while, as the synthesis of the two, it
development, the wholes are open to transforma- is significantly different from each.
tion. Together with charting out the pathways to Thus the crucial issue in cultural psychology is
synthesis, inherent in that unit is the constraining to handle phenomena of synthesis. So far the field
of options—the structure of the unit rules out some is as far from a productive solution for that prob-
possible courses for emergence. lem as Wundt, Krueger, and Vygotsky were about
Vygotsky found that holistic unit in word mean- a century ago. Psychology lacks the formal lan-
ing, as that meaning includes a variety of mutually guage that made chemistry back in the nineteenth
opposite and contradicting versions of “personal century capable of solving the synthesis problem
sense” (smysl). Through the dynamic oppositions theoretically.
(contradictions) between subunits (of “personal
sense”) of the meaning (znachenie), the latter devel- Varied Perspectives: Contested by
ops. Thus, we have a hierarchical unit where the “Indigenous” Psychologies
transformation of the znachenie at the higher level The meta-theoretical decision to build hierar-
of organization depends on the dialectical syntheses chical models of relationships means a new return
emerging in the contradictory relationships between to the question of parts–whole relationships. The
varied smysl’s at the lower level. And conversely, the parts belonging to a whole are necessarily operat-
emerged new form of znachenie establishes con- ing at a level subservient to that of a whole, and
straints on the interplay of smysl’s at the lower level. we have a minimal hierarchical system. That system
The loci of developmental transformations are in the is guaranteed by the central role of the agent—the
relations between different levels of the hierarchical acting, feeling, and thinking human being who is
order, not at any one level. always within a context while moving beyond the very
same context by one’s goal-oriented actions. As Tania
Tension Between Macro-Social and Zittoun has explained it:
Micro-Social Levels: Hierarchical
Relationships . . . there is no such thing as a context-free
Ratner’s (2008, 2012) call for a macrocultural competence or skill. However, the setting is not
psychology fills the void at the boundary of psy- everything; every activity is also undertaken by a
chology and sociology. Although doing that it person, actively making sense of the situation, of its
faces a new challenge—that of the political nature whereabouts, its goals and resemblances with other

10 culture in psycho log y


situations met by her—these processes are in large direct the knowledge construction along its political
part not conscious. orientations.
(Zittoun, 2008, p. 439)
Self-Reflexivity of Psychology: Advantages
Thus, by the very act of modifying the setting, of the “Cultural Look”
the person (actor) creates a hierarchical relationship Psychology’s theory construction site is itself
that sets oneself above the setting, yet in ways that culturally organized. It includes sensitizing con-
remain bounded with the setting (“bounded inde- cepts (social representations)—meanings that give
terminacy,” Valsiner, 1997). This hierarchy can be direction to empirical efforts of researchers (Joffe &
hidden from self-reflexivity and can occur at the Staerklé, 2007, p. 413). A sensitizing concept may
intuitive level of Umwelts. From a generic idea, block the advancement of a direction of research for
“either X or Y” (person OR context), we move to long time—as the history around developmental
“X into Y into X into Y . . .”—a mutually recursive logics (Valsiner, 2008b) shows. Although the core
feed-forward process. notion of “taking” may guide Western psychological
There is much to learn from the indigenous move- theories to accept the rationality of benefit maximi-
ment in contemporary psychology (Chakkarath, zation axiom that leads to the “independent self ”
2005, 2012; Choi, Han, & Kim, 2007; Li, 2007; notion as normative, the Indian focus on “giving”
Krishnan & Manoj, 2008). The productive use of the (Krishnan & Manoj, 2008) sets the stage for differ-
indigenous psychology movement for the concep- ent versions of “interdependent self ” theories. The
tual texture of cultural psychology becomes available generic social representation accepted in the occiden-
after the “colonizing” (treating “the other” society as tal worlds—such as Aristotelian two-valent logic—
a data source) and “independence” (the “other soci- makes the emergence of multitrajectory holistic
ety” claiming the value of their indigenous concepts) (yet structured) concepts much more complicated
is overcome. Instead of mere equality claims of the than in many cases of indigenous meaning systems.
“others’ ” concepts, the science of psychology can Existing meta-level social representations guide the
overcome its Euro-centric historical orientation by directions of theory construction in the sciences.
making some of these concepts the core terms (and For example, Western psychologies have had
treating their Euro-centric analogues as their deri- difficulty accepting the notion of development
vates). As Durghanand Sinha has noted: as it entails synthetic emergence of generalized,
Long before WHO defined health in positive abstracted phenomena. The focus has been on
terms as a state of complete physical, mental and “what was” (memory, history) or on “what we now
social well-being, the Indian conceptualization was think that was” (Galasinska, 2003; Goldberg, Borat
completely holistic as reflected in Susrut’s definition: and Schwartz, 2006; Mori, 2008; Wagoner, 2008,
prasannamendriyamanah swastha (or health is state of 2011) and rarely has considered “what is not yet—
delight or a feeling of spiritual, physical and mental but is about to become.” What is “being measured”
well-being). The aspect of sama or avoidance of is assumed to be “out there” in its essentialist form
extremes and having various bodily processes and (fixed quality) and in different amounts (quanti-
elements in the right quantity (neither too little nor ties). Once the quality is immutably fixed, it cannot
too much), that is, of maintaining proper balance, transform into new forms—hence, the difficulty of
has been constantly emphasized . . . well-being is nit developmental thinking in occidental psychologies.
equated with fulfillment of needs and production of It is only at present that questions of processes by
material wealth through the control and exploitation which the movement toward the future occurs begin
of nature. The capacity to develop and maintain to be analyzed (Järvinen, 2004; Sato et al., 2007).
harmonious relationship with the environment is Cultural psychology cannot deal with behavior as
considered vital. something “out there” that can be observed. Instead,
(Sinha, 1996, p. 95) we can observe meaningful conduct of goal-oriented
organisms (not only humans—Sokol-Chang, 2009)
Of course no governmental organization (WHO, who are in the process of creating one’s actual life
UN, or any other) has a privilege in defining scien- trajectories out of a diversity of possibilities (Sato
tific terms. A science cannot start from a local defi- et al., 2007, 2012). That process may be poorly
nition of a socio-political kind—it would reduce its captured by the use of real numbers (Valsiner &
generalizability and would let a social institution Rudolph, 2008), and hence careful qualitative

va lsin er 11
analyses of particular versions of human conduct are Gananath Obeyesekere’s Cultural World of
the empirical core of cultural psychologies. Person in Context
Culture for Obeyesekere consists of internal-
The Range of the Handbook—And ized ideas in the minds of persons, mediated by
Its “Missing Pages” consciousness. Because consciousness is primar-
Obviously a handbook of 51 chapters is a huge ily personally constructed, the “sharing” of culture
corpus of ideas and seems to be fully comprehen- between persons can only be episodic and partial
sive. Unfortunately we did not succeed in includ- (see Obeyesekere, 1977—demon possession is a per-
ing all the expected and desired relevant authors in sonal-psychological phenomenon that is not shared
the Handbook, for various reasons—mostly linked with others, yet can be exorcised by cultural rules).
with workloads and travel. Thus, the voices of tra- Furthermore, specific sophistic readings of cultural
ditional experimental social psychology (of Shinobu texts by constructive persons can bring into being
Kitayama and Hazel Markus), and its adamant forms of conduct that seemingly deviate from cul-
critiques (Richard Shweder), psychoanalytic cul- tural meanings yet are incorporated into those by
tural anthropology (Gananath Obeyesekere, Sudhir special conditions (e.g., the making of “Buddhist
Kakar), sociology of complex societies (Veena Das, eggs”; see Obeyesekere, 1968, p. 30). He has shown
Rama Chan Tripathi), socio-cultural semiotic per- how constructed discourses—such as the stories
spectives (Alberto Rosa), and the cultural psychol- of Maori cannibalism—proliferate (Obeyesekere,
ogy of work processes (Yrjö Engeström) did not 2005).
materialize by the time the Handbook project was
to be finished. The following entails a brief synopsis Culturally Reformed Psychoanalysis
of some of these. Obeyesekere has been working within a psycho-
analytic paradigm, enriching it with his hermeneutic
Social Psychology of Cultural Self—The stance, and diligently trying to reformulate its con-
Stanford Tradition ceptual structure on the basis of empirical evidence
The “Stanford tradition” emanating from the from the Sinhalese cultural contexts (Obeyesekere,
work of Hazel Markus since 1980s and prolif- 1963, 1968, 1975, 1976, 1977, 1981, 1984, 1990).
erating in North American social psychology is He has also taken a look at encounters between soci-
an outgrowth from the contextualist orientation eties (Obeyesekere, 1993) that reveal the “work of
in personality psychology of the 1970s. Markus’ culture,” as it
work starts from an empirical emphasis on the
. . . is the process whereby symbolic forms existing on
schematic self-descriptions. She gives new theoreti-
the cultural level get created and recreated through
cal life to William James’ notion of possible future
the minds of people. It deals with the formation
selves that is conceptualized in terms of subjective
and transformation of symbolic forms, but is not a
approach/withdrawal tendencies of a person who is
transformation without a subject as in conventional
facing possible futures (Markus & Nurius, 1986).
structural analysis . . .
Furthermore, the emphasis on “possible selves” con-
(Obeyesekere, 1990, p. xix)
stitutes a return to Gordon Allport’s idea of hier-
archical organization of personality and tentatively The work of culture is a developmentally pro-
explains the role of the personally constructed “pos- gressive process in its main scope (even if it may
sible selves” in the regulation of personality devel- include moments of temporary “regressions” in its
opment (e.g., Markus & Wurff, 1987). Although course—e.g., a person’s dissociation of the existing
proceeding from self-personological roots, Markus personality organization and being in turmoil for
creates a contrast between different collective cul- long periods of time (Obeyesekere, 1987, p. 104).
tures in terms of the opposition of independence The key idea is cultural constraints set up condi-
versus interdependence notions that organize the tions under which personal symbolic action takes
selves (Markus & Kitayama, 1991). In years since, place—be this the construction of women’s preg-
Kitayama has developed the notion of interdepen- nancy cravings in Sri Lanka (Obeyesekere, 1963,
dent self into a major research program in experi- 1985) or sorcery for retribution (Obeyesekere,
mental social psychology. The normal state of the 1975). On the other hand, each person acts in
self is interdependent—independence is merely a one’s unique ways, has unique personal history, and
special condition of interdependence. hence any “standard ritual” (e.g., that of exorcism

12 culture in psycho log y


of “demon dominance,” Obeyesekere, 1977, or in Obeyesekere adds this constructive-disjunctive
Christian traditions, Obeyesekere, 2010) needs to (of the symbol from the motive) dimension to the
accommodate a variety of specific conditions that culture-work idea, thus liberating the psychoanalytic
may be characteristic of a particular person. perspective from its expression-interpreting fate.

Overdetermination by Meaning Richard Shweder—The Voice of Culture


Perhaps the most central innovation of the psy- for Psychology
choanalytic thought that Obeyesekere introduces Starting from an anthropological background,
(and that moves him irreversibly away from psy- Richard Shweder’s voice in psychology over the
choanalytic explanations of the occidental ortho- recent two decades has undoubtedly pointed to
dox kind) is the move from overdetermination of the need to consider culture in psychology as a
motive (as emphasized by Freud and reflected in primary constituting factor of the self (Shweder,
dream analysis) to overdetermination of meaning 1984, 1991; Shweder & Much, 1987; Shweder
(Obeyesekere, 1990, p. 56). All events in human & Sullivan, 1990, 1993). The cultural richness of
life occur in polysemic contexts, being framed by India has certainly fascinated Europeans in very
a variety of cultural meanings, operating simulta- many ways, but it is rarely that occidental sci-
neously at different levels of symbolic remove from ence has attempted to provide in-depth analyses
deep motivations. Some of the cultural meanings of the cultural constructions in the Hindu world.
are closer to the motivations (events) that origi- Shweder’s approach recognizes the heterogeneity
nally triggered the personal symbolization process, and culture-inclusiveness of moral reasoning of
which utilized culturally available means. However, human beings (Shweder, 1995; Shweder & Much,
in human development, some levels of symboliza- 1987; Shweder, Mahapatra, & Miller, 1987).
tion may lose all of their connection with the ini- Shweder returns to the emphasis of culturally con-
tial “triggering event” and acquire symbolic life stituted person as an agent in both subjective and
of their own in the personality of an individual. collective domains:
Furthermore, Obeyesekere’s theoretical transposi-
tion of the notion of overdetermination to the sym- . . . to imaginatively conceive of subject-dependent
bolic level is an important idea: objects (intentional worlds) and object-dependent
subjects (intentional persons) interpenetrating each
. . . ”[S]ymbolic remove” is based on the other’s identities or setting the conditions for each
psychoanalytic idea that symbols in principle, if not other’s existence and development, while jointly
always in practice, show infinite substitutionability. undergoing change through social interaction . . .
Related to this idea is another principle of the work (Shweder, 1990, p. 25)
of culture that psychoanalysis has not, and could
not, consider seriously since it would threaten The personal minds (object-dependent persons)
the isomorphism between symbol and symptom. construct mental and affective order out of chaos of
And that is the principle of disconnection of the everyday events—hence, an illusory view of reality
symbol from the sources of motivation. Substitution is constructed by persons but on the basis of the
implies that symbiol X related to motive Y can be culture. Shweder has been a consistent critic of psy-
replaced by symbols A, B, or C . . . n. A, B, C are all chology’s “culture myopia” (taking the role of “the
“isomorphic replacements” of X, related to motive grand confusionist” by his own designation), point-
Y in identical or similar manner. “Disconnection” ing out that psychology—even its cross-cultural
questions the postulated isomorphism and version—has ignored culture as the central player in
suggests that A,B,C, . . . n might exhibit degrees the domain of human psyche.
of symbolic remove from Y and might eventually
lose its connection with Y . . . Admittedly, total A Single Example Matters: How Mr.
disconnection is rare, but one can make a reasonable Babaji is Important for Psychology
case that the more the symbol is removed from the Shweder’s specific work on the organization of
sources of motivation the more it gets the attribute the self in Hindu collective-cultural contexts takes
of arbitrariness, thus approximating the Saussurean the form of elaboration of specific personal-cul-
idea of the arbitrary relation between signifier and tural transformations of socially shared knowledge.
signified. Everyday conversations surrounding the developing
(Obeyesekere, 1990, p. 58) person are filled with cultural suggestions for how

va lsin er 13
to interpret the nature of experience in accordance the concerns by many scholars over the twentieth
with social representations (Markova, 2003, 2011). century (e.g., Baldwin, 1930; Michell, 1999, 2003,
Shweder encountered specific collective-cul- 2005; Rudolph, 2006a, 2006b), they point out:
tural organization of moral discourse in his efforts
Quantification is neither a necessary nor sufficient
to apply Kohlbergian moral dilemmas in Hindu
condition for science. No-one questions the scientific
contexts in Orissa. His elaborate dispute with
status of biology without quantification . . . . The
the informant Babaji (Shweder & Much, 1987,
price of quantification is a ‘loss’ of information, as
pp. 235–244) revealed how a Western collective-
when rich qualitative data are reduced to sets of
culturally shared “moral dilemma” (stealing/not
numbers, such as frequency counts, means, and
stealing a drug under life-threatening illness of
variances. Quantitative data have to be translated
one’s wife and drug-owner’s refusal to provide it
into qualitative statements if their meanings and
by special arrangements) can be translated into a
implications are to be spelled out, communicated to
completely different personal-cultural issue (i.e.,
and received by the researcher’s audience.
sinning vs. not sinning via stealing for one’s wife,
(Ho et al., 2007, p. 380)
even if the latter’s life is in jeopardy). By way of spe-
cific combination of collective-cultural meanings Qualitative perspectives are clearly on the ascent in
of “sin,” “wife” (as “belonging to” the husband), contemporary psychology at large (Diriwächter &
“multiple lives,” and “inevitability of death,” a set Valsiner, 2006, 2008; Gelo, Braakman, & Benetka,
of alternative personal-culturally allowable scenar- 2008; Mey & Mruck, 2005, 2007; Michell, 2004).
ios for the action of the person in a dilemma situa- This is more easily fitted to cultural psychology—
tion is being constructed (see also Menon, 2003, on where the molar level units of analysis resist quanti-
Hindu moral discourses). Cultural-psychological fication anyway (e.g., Toomela, 2008b, pp. 64–65,
investigations are necessarily of unique events—yet on psychology’s production of meaningless num-
of those that happen within a hierarchy of social bers). To ask the question “how much of [X= “love”,
contexts. Instead of situating cultural psychology “hatred”. . . .]?” presumes the unitary quality of that
on the socio-political landscape (Ratner, 2008, X and its nature together with homogeneity of the
2012), it is the macro-social organization of soci- presumed substance (X), which makes it possible to
ety that becomes analyzed in micro-social activity apply quantitative measurement units to it. Hence
contexts. Here the traditions of micro-sociology of the assumption of quantifiability rules out from the
culture give cultural psychology a lead—generaliza- outset the possibility of transformation of quality
tion from a carefully studied single specimen can by separating the latter from whatever numbers
be sufficient. are attached to the phenomena in the act of “being
measured.”
Qualitative Methodology As the Root for
All Methods in Psychology Unity of Quality and Quantity
A liberation movement is happening in psy- All quantitative approaches constitute a subclass
chology—an effort to topple the socially norma- of qualitative ones but not vice versa. Psychology
tive fixed role of the quantitative methods as having treats numbers as if they are objective in contrast
the monopoly of being “scientific.” Yet making to mathematics. For example, the difference of 0
the qualitative and quantitative methods look like (zero) and 1 (one) and 2 (two) in case of psychol-
they oppose each other as two rivals is an unpro- ogy’s assumption of interval or ratio scale treats each
ductive stance—which is even not overcome by the of these numbers as equally meaningful. Yet they are
“cocktail” metaphor of giving preference to “mixed not; the concept of 0 (zero) is in its quality different
methods.” from 1 or 2. Zero indicates a dialogue:
In reality, quantity is a derivate of quality. As
Zero means both all (excessive) or none (void). The
Ho et al. (2007) have demonstrated, contemporary
dialogical process includes the middle, which gets
social sciences that treat qualitative and quantitative
excluded in the dichotomies.
methods as if these were opposing methodologies
(Tripathi & Leviatan, 2003, p. 85)>
are introducing a false dichotomy. Research ques-
tions in psychology—as long as psychology is not Thus, psychology’s—not only cultural psycholo-
hyperformalized by mathematical ideas—are asked gies’—core conceptual problem is not merely “dual-
in philosophical terms, hence qualitatively. Echoing isms” of all kinds but of the understanding of the

14 culture in psycho log y


dualities (or multiplicities) inherent in what seems functioning—between the consensual reflection
to be a unitary point to which a number can be eas- about one’s group membership (e.g., “as an X [i.e.,
ily assigned (Wagoner & Valsiner, 2005). “an American”] I am Y [“individualistic”], not Z
The issue—treating science of psychology as an [“collectivistic”]) and the circumstances for action
act of assigning numbers to qualitative phenom- (“while an X in general—in situation S, I am Z”).
ena (to get data) has been discussed critically by Because each person is context-bound, no statement
Rudolph (2006a, 2006b, 2006c, 2009) as well as about one’s cultural label (“individualist” vs. “collec-
Toomela (2007b, 2008a). The social consensus of tivist”) can characterize the negotiation between the
number assignment guarantees no science—hence opposites and the situation demands. The tension
much of psychology’s data analytic practices are of is thus granted by the social community (see Mead,
the kind of cultural artifacts that may belong to a 2001/1931, on the role of community in U.S.
museum rather than contribute to advancement of society). By the regular cross-cultural psychology
knowledge. The cultural nature of the meaning of nomenclature, the United States is considered to be
“statistical significance” has been shown to be one “individualistic,” yet if one looks at the level of person–
of such widespread artifacts (Ziliak & McCloskey, community relations, it looks very “collectivistic.”
2008). That person is therefore necessarily analyzable as
More importantly, the crucial conceptual mis- a dynamic structure of multiple parts—such as
hap in psychology is the reduction of the notion of Autonomous-Related Self (Kagitçibasi, 1996, 2005;
abstract formal models of mathematics to the use of Tuli & Chaudhary, 2010) or in terms of dialogical
only one kind of numbers—real numbers. At the self (Hermans, 2001, 2002; Hermans & Dimaggio,
same time, many cultural-psychological phenom- 2007; Salgado & Gonçalves, 2007).
ena are better fitted with models using imaginary It is here—at the unity of various parts within
numbers (Valsiner & Rudolph, 2008) and topologi- the whole—that cultural-psychological processes
cal models (Rudolph, 2008a, 2008b, 2009). Such make stability out of instability; parents operate at
number systems may be better fitted for dealing the intersection of various cultural models (Keller,
with the phenomena of uncertainty of living (Abbey, Demuth, & Yovsi, 2008), and kindergarten teachers
2004, 2007, 2011; Golden & Mayseless, 2008) and evoke danger scenarios for children in the middle of
with dynamic boundaries-making (and unmaking) mundane everyday activities (Golden & Mayseless,
in human social lives (Madureira, 2007a, 2007b, 2008). The cultural-psychological worlds are relational
2011; Tsoulakas, 2007). Tsoukalas (2007) has worlds, yet that recognition leads us to inquire into
brought the issue of religiosities—differentiating what relational could mean.
doctrinal and imagistic types—back to our focus
of attention. Specific cultural practices of commu- Relationships As Boundaries
nication—turned into institutionalized framework Cultural tools both set up boundaries—by way
through activities like prayer (del Rio & Alvarez, of classification—and set the stage for transforming
29007), asking for forgiveness (Brinkmann, 2010; them (Boesch, 2008). As Boesch sets up these two
Phillips, 2007), apologizing, and many others may functions of culture—classification and transforma-
lead the way toward cultural psychology of religious tion—we can expand these from two different func-
sentiments. tions into one. Although classification (“this belongs
to A”) creates the distinction with the rest (non-A),
From Oppositional Terms to Unity of it also sets up the boundary {A || non-A}. The act of
Opposites classifying is simultaneously boundary-setting, and
Psychology has usually adhered to exclusive sepa- boundary is the trigger for its overcoming, by way of
ration of opposites along the lines of Aristotelian- transformation {A |is becoming| non-A}. As such,
Boolean two-valued logic. Consider the basic classification and transformation are two mutually
opposition of “individualist” versus “collectivist” linked processes. Boundaries of gender (Madureira,
cultures—a staple organizer of knowledge in cross- 2007a, 2007b, 2011) and body (Ingold, 2004) turn
cultural psychology. Societies on the Globe are out to be both solidly protected and quasi-perme-
divided into either “individualist” or “collectivist” able. Human social life entails constant boundary
and contrasted with each other. construction (Joffe & Staerklé, 2007) and trans-
Matsumoto (2003) has specified the location formation—social classes create their boundaries
where tension can be located in human cultural in urban globalizing worlds (Tevik, 2006) together

va lsin er 15
with opening up the possibility of transcending types become coordinated in the making of a holis-
these boundaries. By creating boundaries, we cre- tic cultural order (Diriwächter & Valsiner, 2008).
ate objects, which are simultaneously physical and Last—but not least—the increasing interest
cultural entities. in objects in cultural psychology leads to its new
relationship with another discipline—that of arche-
Cultural Objects ology. Empirical evidence from the structure of
Objects are not just material “things” that exist objects used by human beings in the past in various
in and of themselves but distinguished contrasts social contexts becomes functional for understand-
between a figure and the ground. Thus, a black ing the present and the future (González-Ruibal,
point on a white surface is an object, based on a 2005, 2006, 2011). It is in this historical focus—of
relationship of the figure and the ground. Human objects-in-their context (in case of archaeology)
cultural histories are filled with hyper-rich construc- and meanings-in-their context (in case of cultural
tion of such objects through abundant use of signs. psychology)—that a new interdisciplinary synthesis
We create our lives through ornaments, which seem of knowledge is likely to emerge in the future.
to us to carry decorative purposes, yet these decora-
tions abound and can be found in unexpected loca- Preview of the Handbook
tions (Valsiner, 2008). By our constructive actions The 12 sections of the Handbook are merely an
we turn things into objects. orientation device for the reader to orient oneself
We live among objects—and relate to them: in the large heterogeneous field of cultural psychol-
ogy. The chapters in the historical section (I) situate
The words “object,” objectus, objet, Gegenstand, ogetto,
both the previous efforts to unite culture and psy-
voorwerp all share the root meaning of a throwing
chology (Diriwächter, 2012; Jahoda, 2012) as well
before, a putting against or opposite, an opposing.
as provide an insight into the role of Vygotsky (van
In the English verb “to object” the oppositional,
der Veer, 2011). Different other chapters in other
even accusatory sense of the word is still vivid. In an
parts of the Handbook (Magnus & Kull, 2012 on
extended sense, objects throw themselves in front
the role of von Uexkyll; Tarasti, 2012, on various
of us, smite the senses, thrust themselves into our
philosophical tendencies that underlie the semiotic
consciousness. They are neither subtle nor evanescent
perspectives in cultural psychology) show how the
nor hidden. Neither effort nor ingenuity nor
scientific minds of various backgrounds have been
instruments are required to detect them. They do not
looking for solutions to similar problems. History
need to be discovered or investigated; they possess
of the social sciences is a rich ground for finding
self-evidence of a slap in the face.
out how different theoretical efforts emerged—yet
(Daston, 2000, p. 2)
failed to reach solutions to the problems.
It is not surprising that cultural psychology becomes The key message from our turn to history is the
increasingly interested in the study of meaningful need to rejuvenate the theoretical schemes of psy-
objects. Cultural objects are everywhere—in our pri- chology by touching on similar solutions attempted
vate domains of homes (including the homes them- in other sciences. Semiotics (Innis, 2010, 2012;
selves) and in public (in the streets, town squares, Magnus & Kull, 2012; Tarasti, 2012) stands out as
etc.). They are both stationary (temples, monu- a new and very promising peer for psychology. This
ments, etc.) and moving (buses, trains, airplanes, is complemented by bringing the science of archeol-
etc.). As Bastos (2008) pointed out, these objects ogy into contact with psychology (Gonzalez-Ruibal,
can be seen as “tattoos on the collective soul,” and 2012).
they bring into cultural psychology the method- Cultural psychology benefits from conceptual-
ological credo of visual anthropology. The kind of izing the notion of positioning—a geographic met-
meaning-making in the creation of such (moving aphor that allows for elaboration of the multiplicity
or stationary) wholes is of hybrid nature, includ- of psychological phenomena (Harré, 2012; Bento
ing indexical, iconic, and symbolic signs (to follow et al., 2012). When the notion of positioning is linked
C. S. Peirce’s basic typology). Cultural psychologists with that of social representations (Aveling et al.,
of the semiotic orientation have usually detected 2010) we gain a multifaceted dynamic view into the
varied versions of encoded versions in their descrip- human lives as these move through various social
tions of objects, whereas the jeepney example forces settings. Obviously such positions are themselves
us to look for principles by which different sign embedded in the macro-social settings, as Ratner

16 culture in psycho log y


(2008, 2012) reminds us. Through the synthesis using narratives (Brockmeier, 2011) or focusing on
of positioning theory, social representation theory the micro-level discourse phenomena (Murakami,
(Marková, 2003, 2012), and the macro-cultural 2011) is a notable direction for future development
look, cultural psychology can arrive at a hierarchy of of culture within psychological research. Into the
“niches” of socially embedded and personally con- human propensity of narrating—all over the life-
structed phenomena. All these are united through course—enter different semiotic resources (Eco,
the use of semiotic tools at all levels of that social 2009; Zittoun, 2007, 2012) and we consolidate our
hierarchy (Innis, 2012; Salvatore, 2012; Sonesson, selves around the images of fictional characters from
2010; Tarasti, 2012). novels, movies, or revered historical figures. The
Yet at the beginning of all efforts to unite culture connections of psychological data and different lit-
and psychology is the act—a purposeful, meaning- erary constructions are being explored in contempo-
ful, future-oriented movement by a willful person rary cultural psychology (Brinkmann, 2006, 2007,
(Boesch, 2011; Eckensberger, 2011). Action theory 2009; Johansen, 2010; Moghaddam, 2004). The
is unabashedly focused on the symbolic (see also creative writers may have had better insights into
Bruner, 1986; Salvatore, 2011). Although the semi- the complexities of the human psyche than North
otically organized ACTING PERSON–SOCIAL American college undergraduates diligently putting
POSITIONING–SOCIAL REPRESENTATION– pencil marks onto the myriads of Likert scales.
MACRO-CULTURAL ORDER hierarchy could be It is for the reason of providing resources that
considered the vertical axis of cultural psychology, it culture in psychology needs to consider the history
is important to pay attention to its horizontal coun- of human beings (Carretero & Bermudez, 2012;
terpart. The latter entails the transitions between Winston & Winston, 201=2). That history entails
different culturally structured contexts within which the construction of meaning about one’s social
human beings act, position themselves, and become and economic status as well as that of the others.
involved in macro-social activities. The home leads, “Being poor” may look different from various defi-
through an entrance, to the street, the city square, nitions of social positioning, as can objective state
to the road that leaves the city for the rural coun- of economic status (Bastos & Rabinovich, 2009,
tryside. Airplanes take us 10 kilometers above the 2012). So does the construction of the notion of
ground, where our positioning ourselves is sur- race (Winston & Winston, 2012). Behind all these
rounded by white clouds and thinking of the past socially constructed human phenomena are very
that we left behind while taking off and the future real biological bodies of Homo sapiens. Historically
that awaits us in the airport where we are about to oriented cultural psychology needs to look at the
land. Kharlamov (2012) brings to cultural psychol- phylogenesis of cultural means. The Handbook pro-
ogy the notion of moving between different spaces— vides a glimpse into our thinking about the new-
and the role of constant meaning construction “on est developments in the studies of primate cultures
line” as such movement takes place. This resonates (C. Boesch, 2012) and gives the readers a glimpse
well with the focus on migration as human main into the biosemiotic look at the animal world
modus operandi—from micro-migration (movement (Magnus & Kull, 2012). Theoretically, contempo-
between home and workplace, home and school), rary cultural psychology shares the ground with epi-
temporary work-related migration (sailors at sea, genetic thinking in biology (Tavory et al., 2012).
guest workers in foreign lands), immigration, and Human beings move around—as tourists, pil-
establishment of oneself in a far away place. By the grims, traders, warriors, or vagabonds. In such
twenty-first century, the latter includes extra-terres- movements, they enhance their horizons of “the
trial spaces—as long as the ideas of “colonizing the Other”—persons, customs, habits, and economic
Moon” (or Mars) are entertained as potential future opportunities. Understanding people-in-movement
projects. In all these migrations—real or imaginary, is a crucial task for cultural psychology (Gillespie
temporary or permanent—we can observe the unity et al., 2012; Kharlamov, 2012). The hybrid trajec-
of the self and the other (Bento et al., 2012; Simão, tory of self-willed movement—the pilgrimage—is
2012). The human being needs to relate to the other a cultural phenomenon that dynamically unites the
to be oneself and develop further while being one- otherwise static rural–urban, religious–secular, and
self. An important part in that is creating stories— nomadic–sedentary oppositions. The pilgrim’s path
both about oneself and about the other. In this is not geographic but psychological (Beckstead,
respect, the developing qualitative research practice 2012).

va lsin er 17
Complex psychological functions of social kind Encountering the rich material in this Handbook
are covered in Part X of the Handbook. Perhaps the is a multilinear experience for the reader—a worth-
most crucial issue is the way in which duties and while effort, so as to make sense of where psychol-
rights (Moghaddam et al., 2012) are linked with the ogy so far has failed and to get some ideas of better
construction of values (Branco, 2012). In a coun- future for the human sciences of the future. It is our
terweight to the Euro-American discourse on such hope that this Handbook becomes a rich resource
higher processes, Nsamenang (2012) has provided for future generations of thinkers who want to see
a contextualized perspective from the vantage point culture in the psyche and let psychology as a science
of African societies. enter the social realities of cultural organization.
The basic tenet of cultural psychology—in con-
trast to cross-cultural psychology—is the inclu- Notes
sion of the social institutions in which people 1. The first two having been the times of Völkerspsychologie,
1860–1920, and the efforts of the “culture and personality”
participate in the study of the cultural ways of
school in cultural anthropology in the 1950s.
living (see Valsiner, 2007, on two ways of knowl- 2. The boy who was trained by John B. Watson, one of the
edge creation). Our Handbook looks at a number originators of behaviorism
of social practices—those in the macro-structure 3. The infant chimpanzee who was raised by Ladygina-Kohts
of a school (Daniels, 2012; Marsico & Iannacone, (2002, original in 1935 ) in the classic study of chimpanzee
development in human environments
2012, Marsico, Komatsu & Iannaccone, 2012) The
4. Wolfgang Köhler’s best known research participant on the
educational contexts can—and do—change; our Tenerife.
Handbook covers the ways in which interventions 5. It is important to note that the intricate link with the
have been observed (Downing-Wilson et al., 2012; dialectical dynamicity of the units—which is present in the Rus-
Lopez et al., 2012). sian original-- is lost in English translation, which briefly stated
only the main point in a summarizing fashion: “Psychology, which
All human beings who participate in the activi-
aims at a study of complex holistic systems, must replace the method
ties of social institutions are acting on the basis of of analysis into elements with the method of analysis into units”
their affective relations with the immediate social (Vygotsky, 1986, p. 5). Yet it remains unclear in the English
worlds. Chaudhary (2012) demonstrates how the translation what kinds of units are to be constructed—those that
normative stance for such relations is the strategic entail oppositional relationships between parts—while in the
Russian original it is made evident.
coalition-making in family networks—filled with
affective construction of dramas. The centrality of
play (van Oers, 2012) in human lives guarantees References
Abbey, E. A. (2004). The blind leading the seeing : A path to self-
that within any social group there is constant dif- reflexivity. Culture & Psychology, 10(4), 409–415.
ferentiation of forms of new action. The peer group Abbey, E. A. (2007). Perpetual uncertainty of cultural life. In
sets the range of social constraints that enable fur- J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Socio-
ther innovative collective action (Li, 2012). cultural Psychology. (pp. 362–372). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
The crucial area for re-integration of culture and
Abbey, E. (2012). Ambivalence and its transformations. In
psychology is the creation of new methodology (Part J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychol-
XII). It needs to transcend the elementaristic logic of ogy. New York: Oxford University Press.
the General Linear Model by allowing for recogni- Abbey, E. & Falmagne, R. J. (2008). Modes of tension work
tion of cyclical nature of causal processes, focus on within the complex self. Culture & Psychology, 14(1),
95–113.
constant construction of variability (which leads to
Adams, M. (2004). Whatever will be, will be: Trust, fate and the
idiographic science; Molenaar, 2004), and accepting reflexive self. Culture & Psychology, 10(4), 387–408.
the multilinearity and multifinality of the psycho- Akkerman, S, Admiraalo, W., Simons, R. J., & Niessen, T.
logical processes (Sato et al., 2012). Ambivalence— (2006). Considering diversity: multivoicedness in interna-
rather than its absence—is the normal state of affairs tional academic collaboration. Culture & Psychology, 12(4),
461–485.
in psychological phenomena (Abbey, 2012). That
Ansbacher, H. (1937). Perception of number as affected by the
ambivalence is being temporarily overcome through monetary value of the objects: A critical study of the method
the use of cultural tools by persons (Boesch, 2011\2; used in the extended constancy phenomenon. Archives of
Eckensberger, 2011; Innis, 2011). New methods are Psychology, 215, 5–88.
emerging from this general line of thinking—collec- Appadurai, A. (2006). Fear of small numbers. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
tive techniques of looking at reconstructive memory
Arnett, J. J. (2008). The neglected 95%: Why American psychol-
(Wagoner, 2012) and the look at life trajectories in- ogy needs to become less American. American Psychologist,
the-making (Sato et al., 2012). 63(7), 602–614.

18 culture in psycho log y


Aubin, D. (1997). The withering immortality of Nicolas handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Bourbaki: A cultural connector at the confluence of math- University Press.
ematics, structuralism and the Oulipo in France. Science in Branco, A. U., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.) (2004). Communication and
Context, 10(2), 297–342. metacommunication in human development. Greenwich, CT:
Aveling, E-L., Cornish, F., & Oldmeadow, J. A. (2010). Diversity Information Age Publishers.
in sex workers’ strategies for the protection of social identity. . Brinkmann, S. (2006). Questioning constructionism: Toward
In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic transformation (pp. 302–322). an ethic of finitude. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 46(1),
London: Routledge. 92–111.
Baerveldt, C. & Verheggen, T. (1999). Enactivism and the Brinkmann, S. (2008). Changing psychologies in the transition
experiential reality of culture: rethinking the epistemo- from industrial society to consumer society. History of the
logical basis of cultural psychology. Culture & Psychology, Human Sciences, 21(2), 85–110.
5(2), 183–206. Brinkmann, S. (2009).Literature as qualitative inquiry: The nov-
Baerveldt, C. & Verheggen, T. (2012). Enactivism. In J. Valsiner elist as a researcher. Qualitative Inquiry, 15(8), 1376–1394.
(Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New Brinkmann, S. (2010). Guilt in a fluid culture? A view from posi-
York: Oxford University Press. tioning theory. Culture & Psychology, 16(2), 253–266.
Baldwin, J. M. (1930). James Mark Baldwin. In C. Murchison Bruner, J. S., & Postman, L. (1950). Perception, cognition, and
(Ed.), A history of psychology in autobiography. Vol. 1 behavior. In J. S. Bruner & D. Krech (Eds.), Perception and
(pp. 1–30). New York: Russell & Russell personality (pp. 14–31). Durham, NC: Duke University
Bastos, A. C. (2008). Jeepneys: tattoos on the collective soul. Press.
Culture & Psychology, 14(2), 237–243. Bunzl, M. (2003). Völkerpsychologie and German-Jewish emanci-
Bastos, A. C., & Rabinovich, E. (Eds) (2009). Living in poverty. pation. In H. G. Penny & M. Bunzl (Eds.), Worldly provin-
Charlotte, NC: InfoAge Publisher cialism (pp. 47–85). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan
Bastos, A. C. & Rabinovich, E. (2012). Being poor: cultural Press.
tools for survival. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of Carretero, M. & Bermudez, A. (2012). Constructing histories.
culture and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
Beckstead, Z. (2012). Crossing Thresholds: Movement as a chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Means of Transformation. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford Castro, P., & Batel, S. (2008). Social representation, change and
handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford resistance: On the difficulties of generalizing new norms.
University Press. Culture & Psychology, 14(4), 477–499.
Bertau, M.-C. (2008). Voice: a pathway to consciousness as « Chakkarath, P. (2005). What can Western psychology learn from
social contact to oneself. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & indigenous psychologies?—lessons from Hindu psychology. In
Behavioral Science, 42(1), 92–113. W. Friedelmeier, P. Chakkarath & B. Schwartz (Eds.), Culture
Bhawuk, D. P. S. (2008). Anchoring cognition, emotion and and human development: The importance of cross-cultural
behavior in desire: A model from the Bhagavad-Gita. In research for the social sciences (pp. 31–51). Hove, East-Sussex:
K. R. Rao, A. C. Paranjpe, & A. K. Dalal (Eds.), Handbook Psychology Press.
of Indian Psychology (pp. 390–413). New Delhi, India: Chakkarath, P. (2012). The role of indigenous psychologies in
Cambridge University Press. the building of basic cultural psychology. In J. Valsiner (Ed.),
Bibace, R., Clegg, J., & Valsiner, J. (2009). What is in a name? The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York:
IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 43(1), Oxford University Press.
67–77 Chaudhary, N. (2004). Listening to culture. New Delhi, India:
Boesch, C. (2012). From material to symbolic cultures: Culture Sage.
in primates. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of cul- Chaudhary, N. (2007). The family. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa
ture and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. (Eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Socio-cultural Psychology.
Boesch, E. E. (2005). Von Kunst bis Terror. Göttingen: (pp. 524–539). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Vanderhoeck & Ruprecht. Chaudhary, N. (2012). Affective networks: The social terrain of a
Boesch, E. E. (2008). On subjective culture. Culture & Psychology, complex culture. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of
14(4), 498–512. culture and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Boesch, E. E. (2012). Culture: Result and condition of action. Choi, C.-S., Han, G., & Kim, C.-W. (2007). Analysis of cul-
In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy- tural emotion. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), Cambridge
chology. New York: Oxford University Press. Handbook of Socio-cultural Psychology. (pp. 319–342). New
Bento, T., Cunha, C., & Salgado, J. (2012). Dialogical self. In J. York: Cambridge University Press.
Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. Christopher, J. C., & Bickhard, M. H. (2007). Culture, self and
New York: Oxford University Press. identity: interactivist contributions to a metatheory for cul-
Brockmeier, J. (2012). Narrative scenarios: Toward a culturally tural psychology. Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 259–295.
thick notion of narrative. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford Chryssides, A., Dashtipour, P., Keshet, S., Righi, C, Sammut,
handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford G., & Sartawi, M. (2009). We do not share! The social repre-
University Press. sentation approach, enactivism and the fundamental incom-
Boring, E. G. (1929). A history of experimental psychology. patabilities between the two. Culture & Psychology, 15(1),
New York: The Century Co. xxx–yyy.
Bourdier, F. (2008). Indigenous populations in a cultural per- Cole, M. (1990). Cultural psychology: A once and future disci-
spective. Anthropos, 103, 355–366. pline? In J. Berman (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation.
Branco, A. U. (2012). Values and sociocultural practices: path- Vol. 37 (pp. 279–336). Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska
ways to moral development. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford Press.

va lsin er 19
Cole, M. (1992). Context, modularity and the cultural constitu- Gillespie, A., Kadianaki, I., & O’Sullivan-Lago, R. (2012).
tion of development. In L. T. Winegar & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Encountering Alterity: Geographic and Semantic Movements.
Children’s development within social context. Vol 2. Research In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
and methodology (pp. 5–31). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cole, M. (1995). Culture and cognitive development: from Goldberg, T., Porat, D., & Schwartz, B. B. (2006). “Here
cross-cultural research to creating systems of cultural media- started the rift we see today”: student and textbook narra-
tion. Culture & Psychology, 1(1), 25–54. tives between official and counter memory. Narrative Inquiry,
Cole, M. (1996) Cultural Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard 16(2), 319–347.
University Press. Golden, D., & Mayseless, O. (2008). On the alert in an unpre-
Cornejo, C (2007). The locus of subjectivity in cultural studies. dictable environment. Culture & Psychology, 14(2), 155–179.
Culture & Psychology, 13(2), 243–256. González-Ruibal, A. (2005). The need for a decaying past. Home
Cresswell, J. (2009). Towards a post-critical praxis: Intentional states Cultures, 2, 129–152.
and recommendations for change in acculturation psychology. González-Ruibal, A. (2006). The past is tomorrow. Towards
International Journal of Intercultural Relations, 33, 162–172. an archaeology of the vanishing present. Norwegian
Daniels, H. (2012). The Interface between the Sociology of Archaeological Review, 39(2), 110–125.
Practice and the Analysis of Talk in the Study of Change in Greichen, G., & Gründer, H (2005). Deutsche Kolonien: Traum
Educational Settings. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook und Trauma. Berlin: Ullstein.
of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. Güss, C. D., & Tuason, M T. G. (2008). Jeepneys: values in the
Daston, L. (2000). The coming into being of scientific objects. streets. Culture & Psychology, 14(2), 211–236.
In L. Daston (Ed.), Biographies of scientific objects (pp. 1–14). Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science,
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. 316, 998–1002.
Diriwächter, R. (2012) Völkerpsychologie In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Hale, H. (2008). The development of British military masculini-
Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford ties through symbolic resources. Culture & Psychology, 14(3),
University Press. 305–332.
Diriwächter, R. & Valsiner, J, (2006). Qualitative Developmental Harré, R. (2012). Positioning Theory: Moral Dimensions of
Research Methods in their Historical and Epistemological Social-Cultural Psychology. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford
Contexts [53 paragraphs]. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
/ Forum: Qualitative Social Research [On-line Journal], 7(1), University Press.
Art 8. Available at: http://www.qualitative-research.net/fqs- Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations.
texte/1-06/06-1-8-e.htm. Accessed 9, January, 2010 Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Diriwächter, R., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2008). Striving for the Heider, F. (1983). The life of a psychologist. Lawrence, KS:
whole. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. University of Kansas Press.
Downing-Wilson, D., Lecusay, R., & Cole, M. (2012). Design Hermans, H. (2001). The dialogical self: Toward a theory of per-
Experimentation and Mutual Appropriation: Two Strategies sonal and cultural Positioning. Culture and Psychology, 7(3),
for Implementing Intervention Research. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), 243–281.
The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Hermans, H. J. (Ed) (2002). Special Issue on dialogical self.
Oxford University Press. Theory & Psychology, 12(2), 147–280.
Eco U (2009). On the ontology of fictional characters: A semi- Hermans, H. J. & Dimaggio, G. (2007). Self, identity, and
otic approach. Sign Systems Studies (Tartu University), 37(½), globalization in times of uncertainty: A dialogical analysis.
82–98. Review of General Psychology, 11(1), 31–61.
Eckensberger, L. H. (2012). Culture inclusive action theory: Ho, D. Y. F., Ho, R. T. H., & Ng, S.M (2007). Restoring quality
Action theory in dialectics and dialectics in action theory. In to qualitative research. Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 377–383.
J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychol- Holland, D. H. ( 2010). Symbolic worlds in time/spaces of prac-
ogy. New York: Oxford University Press. tice: Identities and transformations. In B. Wagoner (Ed.),
Freeman, M, (2004). The universal through local. Culture & Symbolic transformation (pp. 269–283). London: Routledge.
Psychology, 10(2), 239–248. Ingold, T. (2004). Culture on the ground: the world per-
Galasinska, A. (2003). Temporal shifts in photo-elicited nar- ceived through the feet. Journal of Material Culture, 9(3),
ratives in a Polish border town. Narrative Inquiry, 13(2), 315–340.
393–411. Innis, R. E. (2005). The signs of interpretation. Culture &
Gardner, K. and Osella, P. (2003). Migration, modernity and Psychology, 11(4), 499–509.
social transformation in South Asia. Contributions to Indian Innis, R. E. (2010). Minding feeling. IPBS: Integrative
Sociology, 37(1&2), v–xxviii. Psychological & Behavioral Science, 44(3), 197–207.
Gelo, O., Braakmann, D., & Benetka, G. (2008) Quantitative Innis, R. E. (2012) Meaningful connections: Semiotics, Cultural
and qualitative research: beyond the debate. IPBS: Integrative Psychology, and the forms of sense. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 42(3), 266–290. Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Gieser, T. (2006). How to transform into goddesses and ele- University Press.
phants: Exploring the potentiality of the dialogical self. Jahoda, G. (1993). Crossroads between culture and mind.
Culture & Psychology, 12(4), 443–459. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gillespie, A. (2006). Becoming other: From social interaction to Jahoda, G. (2012) Culture and psychology: words and ideas in
self-reflection. Greenwich, CT: InfoAge Publishing. history. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture
Gillespie, A. (2010). The intersubjective nature of symbol. . and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic transformation (pp. 23–37). Järvinen, M. (2004). Life histories and the perspective of the
London: Routledge. present. Narrative Inquiry, 14(1), 45–68.

20 culture in psycho log y


Joerchel, A. (2007). A dance between the general and the spe- Madureira, A. F. (2007a). The self-control ethos as a mechanism
cific: implications for the self concept. IPBS: Integrative of social exclusion in Western societies. Culture & Psychology,
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 254–261. 13(4), 419–430.
Joffe, H., & Staerklé, C. (2007). The centrality of self-control Madureira, A. F. (2007b). The psychological basis of homopho-
ethos in Western aspersions regarding outgroups: a social bia: cultural construction of a barrier. IPBS: Integrative
representational approach to stereotype content. Culture & Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 225–247.
Psychology, 13(4), 395–418. Magnus, R., & Kull, K. (2011). Roots of culture in the Umwelt.
Johansen, J. D. (2010). Feelings in literature. IPBS: Integrative In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 44(3), 185–196. chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kagitçibasi, C. (1996). The autonomous-relational self. European Marková, I. (1990). A three-step process as a unit of analysis in
Psychologist, 1, 180–186 dialogue. In I. Marková & K. Foppa (Eds.), The dynamics of
Kagitçibasi, C. (2005). Modernization does not mean dialogue (pp. 129–146). Hemel Hempstead: Harvester.
Westernization: Emergence of a different pattern. In W. Marková, I. (2000). The individual and society in psychological
Friedelmeier, P. Chakkarath & B. Schwartz (Eds.), Culture theory. Theory & Psychology, 10, 107–116.
and human development: The importance of cross-cultural Marková, I. (2003). Dialogicality and social representations.
research for the social sciences (pp. 255–272). Hove, East- Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Sussex: Psychology Press. Markova, I. (2012). Social Representations as anthropology of
Kashima, Y. (2007). Globalization, diversity and universal culture. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture
Darwinism. Culture & Psychology, 13(1), 139–139. and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Keller, H., Hentschel, E., Yovsi, R. D., Lamm, B. Abels, M., & Markus, H. , & Wurf, E. (1987). The dynamic self-concept: a
Haas, V.. (2004). The psycho-linguistic embodiment of paren- social psychological perspective. Annual Review of Psychology,
tal ethnotheories. Culture & Psychology, 10(3), 293–330. 38, 299–337.
Keller, H., Demuth, C., & Yovsi, R. D. (2008). The multi- Markus, H., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: impli-
voicedness of independence and interdependence: the case cations for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological
of the Cameroonian Nso. Culture & Psychology, 14(1), Review, 98(2), 224–253.
115–144. Marsico, G., Komatsu, K. & Iannacone, A. (Eds.) (2012).
Kharlamov, N. (2012). The City as a Sign: A developmental- Boundaries of school and home. Charlotte, NC: Information
experiential approach to spatial life. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Age Publishers.
Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford Marsico, G., and Iannacone, A. (2012). The work of schooling.
University Press. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
Kreppner, K. (1999). Enactivism and monadology: where are chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Baerveldt and Verheggen taking the individual and cultural Maruyama, M. (1963). The second cybernetics: Deviation
psychology? Culture & Psychology, 5(2), 207–216. amplifying mutual causal processes. American Scientist, 51,
Krishnan, L., & Manoj, V. R. (2008). “Giving” as a theme in the 164–179.
Indian psychology of values. In K. R. Rao, A. C. Paranjpe, Maruyama, M. (1999). Heterogram analysis: where the assump-
& A. K. Dalal (Eds.), Handbook of Indian Psychology tion of normal distribution is illogical. Human Systems
(pp. 361–382). New Delhi: Cambridge University Press. Management, 18, 53–60.
Kurien, P. A. (2002). Kaleidoscopic ethnicity: International migra- Matsumoto, D. (2003). The discrepancy between consensu-
tion and the reconstruction of community identities in India. al-level culture and individual-level culture. Culture &
New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Psychology, 9(1), 89–95.
Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition (1983). Culture Matusov, E. (2007). In search of ‘the appropriate’ unit of analy-
and cognitive development. In W. Kessen (Ed.), Handbook sis for sociocultural research. Culture & Psychology, 13(3),
of child psychology. Vol. 1. History, theory & methods 307–333.
(pp. 295–356). New York: Wiley. Matusov, E. (2008a). Applying a sociocultural approach to
Ladygina-Kohts, N. (2002). Infant chimpanzee and human child. Vygotskian academia: ‘our tsar isn’t like yours and yours isn’t
New York: Oxford University Press. like ours’. Culture & Psychology, 14(1), 5–35.
Li, X-W. (2007). Intra-individual research on the real transition Matusov, E. (2008b). Dialogue with sociohistorical Vygotskian
process. Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 353–364. academia about a sociocultural approach. Culture &
Li, X.-W. (2012) Peer relations. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford Psychology, 14(1), 81–93.
handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford Menon, U. (2002). Neither victim nor rebel: feminism and the
University Press. morality of gender and family life in a Hindu temple town. In
Lonner, W. J., & Hayes, S. A. (2007). Discovering cultural psy- R. A. Shweder, M. Minow, & H. R. Markus (Eds.), Engaging
chology: A profile and selected readings of Ernest E. Boesch. cultural differences (pp. 288–308). New York: Russell Sage
Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Foundation.
López, A., Najafi, B., Rogoff, B. & Arauz, R. M. (2012). Helping Menon, U. (2003). Morality in context: A study of Hindu under-
and Collaborating as Cultural Practices. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), standings. In J. Valsiner & K. Connolly (Eds), Handbook of
The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: developmental psychology (pp. 431–449). London: Sage..
Oxford University Press. Mey, G., & Mruck, K. (Eds) (2005). Qualitative social research:
Löwy, I. (1990). Variances in meaning in discovery accounts: The Methodological reflections and disciplinary applications.
case of contemporary biology. HSPS, 21(1), 87–121. Special Issue of Historical Social Research, 30(111), 1–331.
Löwy, I. (1992). The strength of loose concepts—boundary Mey, G., & Mruck, K. (Eds) (2007). Grounded Theory Reader.
concepts, federative experimental strategies and disciplinary Supplement to Historical Social Research, No. 19. Köln:
growth. History of Science, 30(90, part 4), 376–396. Zentrum für Historische Sozialforschung.

va lsin er 21
Michell, J. (1999). Measurement in psychology. Cambridge, UK: Obeyesekere, G. (1985). Symbolic foods: pregancy cravings and
Cambridge University Press. the envious female. International Journal of Psychology, 20,
Michell, J. (2003). Pragmatism, positivism and the quantitative 637–662.
imperative. Theory & Psychology, 13(1), 45–52. Obeyesekere, G. (1987). Re-flections on Pattini and Medusa.
Michell, J. (2004). The place of qualitative research in psychol- Contributions to Indian Sociology, 21(1), 99–109.
ogy. Qualitative Research in Psychology, 1, 307–319. [www. Obeyesekere, G. (1990). The work of culture. Chicago, IL:
QualReserchPsych.com] University of Chicago Press.
Michell, J. (2005). The meaning of the quantitative imperative. Obeyesekere, G. (1992). The apotheosis of Captain Cook:
Theory & Psychology, 15(2), 257–263. European mythmaking in the Pacific. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Mladenov, I. (1997). Unlimited semiosis and heteroglossia University Press.
(C. S. Peirce & M. M. Bakhtin). In I Rausch & G. F. Carr Obeyesekere, G. (2005). Cannibal talk. Berkeley, CA: University
(Eds.), Semiotics around the World: Synthesis in diversity of California Press
(pp. 1093–1096). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Obeyesekere, G. (2010). Deep motivation and the work of cul-
Moghaddam, F. (2004). From ‘Psychology in literature’ to ture in Christian penitential ecstasy. In B. Wagoner (Ed.),
‘Psychology as literature’. Theory & Psychology, 14(4), Symbolic transformation (pp. 120–141). London: Routledge.
505–525. Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1981). Phases in human perception/con-
Moghaddam, F. (2006). Catastrophic evolution, culture and ception/ symbolization process: cognitive anthropology and
diversity management policy. Culture & Psychology, 12(4), symbolic classification. American Ethnologist, 8, 451–467.
415–434. Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1987). The monkey as mirror: symbolic
Moghaddam, F., Novoa, C., & Warren, Z. (2012). Duties and transformations in Japanese history and ritual. Princeton, NJ:
rights. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture Princeton University Press.
and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1993). Rice as self: Japanese identities through
Molenaar, P.C.M. (2004), A manifesto on psychology as idio- time. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
graphic science: Bringing the person back into scientific Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1994). The power of absence: zero sig-
psychology, this time forever, Measurement: Interdisciplinary nifiers and their transgressions. L’Homme, 34, 2 (Whole
research and perspectives, 2, 201–218. No. 130), 59–76.
Mori, N. (2008). Styles of remembering and types of experience: Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1995). Structure, event and historical meta-
An experimental investigation of reconstructive memory. phor: Rice and identities in Japanese history. Journal of Royal
IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 42(3), Anthropological Institute, n.s., 1, 227–253.
291–314. Paranjpe, A. C. (2002). Indigenous psychology in the post-
Morioka, M. (2007). The possibility of a fuzzy zone of semiotic colonial context: An historical perspective. Psychology and
activity. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, Developing Societies, 14(1), 27–43.
41(3–4), 296–302. Phillips, R. (2007). Ambiguity in narratives of reconciliation.
Murakami, K. (2007). Positioning in accounting for redemption Culture & Psychology, 13(4), 453–460.
and reconciliation. Culture & Psychology, 13(4), 431–452. Pontecorvo, C. (2007). On the conditions for generative col-
Murakami, K, (2012) Culture in Action: A discursive approach. laboration: learning through collaborative research. IPBS:
In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy- Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(2), 178–
chology. New York: Oxford University Press. 186..
Nsamenang, M. B. (2012). The inter-generational continuity of Preucel, R. W. (2006). Archaeological semiotics. Malden, MA:
values. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture Blackwell.
and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. Rabinovich, E. P. (2008). How far is Brazil from Africa ? Culture
Obeyesekere, G. (1963). Pregnancy cravings (Dola-Duka) in & Psychology, 14(1), 145–152.
relation to social structure and personality in a Sinhalese vil- Ratner, C. (2008). Cultural psychology and qualitative meth-
lage. American Anthropologist, 65, 323–342. odology: scientific and political considerations. Culture &
Obeyesekere, G. (1968). Theodicity, sin and salvation in a Psychology, 14(3), 259–288.
sociology of Buddhism. In E. R. Leach (Ed.), Dialectic in Ratner, C. (2012). Macro-cultural psychology. In J. Valsiner
practical religion (pp. 7–40). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New
University Press. York: Oxford University Press.
Obeyesekere, G. (1975). Sorcery, premeditated murder, and Raval, V. V., & Kral, M. J. (2004). Core versus periphery:
the canalization of aggression in Sri Lanka. Ethnology, 14, Dynamics of personhood over the life course of a Gujarati
1–23. Hindu woman. Culture & Psychology, 10(2), 162–194.
Obeyesekere, G. (1976). The impact of Ayurvedic ideas on the Rogoff, B. (1982). Integrating context and cognitive develop-
culture and the individual in Sri Lanka. In C. Leslie (Ed.), ment. In M. Lamb & A. Brown (Eds.), Advances in devel-
Asian medical systems: A comparative study (pp. 201–226). opmental psychology. Vol. 2 (pp. 125–170). Hillsdale, NJ:
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Erlbaum.
Obeyesekere, G. (1977). Psychocultural exegesis of a case of spirit Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking. New York: Oxford
possession in Sri Lanka. In V. Crapanzano & V. Garrison University Press.
(Eds.), Case studies in spirit possession (pp. 235–294). New Rogoff, B. (1992). Three ways of relating person and culture.
York: Wiley. Human Development, 35(5), 316–320.
Obeyesekere, G. (1981). Medusa’s hair. Chicago, IL University Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development.
of Chicago Press. New York: Oxford University Press.
Obeyesekere, G. (1984). The cult of the goddess Pattini. Chicago, Rogoff, B., & Lave, J. (Eds.) (1984). Everyday cognition.
IL: University of Chicago Press. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

22 culture in psycho log y


Rogoff, B., Chavajay, P., & Matusov, E. (1993). Questioning Shweder, R. A., & Bourne, E. J. (1984). Does the concept of per-
assumptions about culture and individuals. Behavioral and son vary cross-culturally? In R. A. Shweder & R. A. LeVine
Brain Sciences, 16, 533–534. (Eds.), Culture theory: Essays on mind, self and emotions
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. (pp. 158–199). New York: Cambridge University Press.
New York: Oxford University Press. Shweder, R. A., & Sullivan, M. A. (1990). The semiotic subject
Rohner, R. P. (1984). Toward a conception of culture for cross- of cultural psychology. In L. Pervin, (Ed.), Handbook of per-
cultural psychology. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, sonality (pp. 399–416). New York: Guilford Press.
15(2), 111–138. Shweder, R. A., & Sullivan, M. A. (1993). Cultural psychology:
Rosa, A. (2007). Acts of psyche. In J. Valsiner, J., & A. Rosa, who needs it? Annual Review of Psychology, 44, 497–523.
A. (Eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Socio-Cultural Psychology Shweder, R. A., & Much, N. (1987). Determinations of mean-
(pp. 205–236). New York: Cambridge University Press. ing: discourse and moral socialization. In W. M. Kurtines &
Rudmin, F. (2010). Steps towards the renovation of accultura- J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Moral development through social interac-
tion research paradigms: What scientists’ personal experi- tion (pp. 197–244). New York: Wiley.
ences of migration might tell science. Culture & Psychology, Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J. G. (1987). Culture
16(3), 299–312. and moral development. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The
Rudolph, L. (2006a). The Fullness of Time. Culture and emergence of morality in young children (pp. 1–83). Chicago,
Psychology, 12(2), 157–186. IL: University of Chicago Press.
Rudolph, L. (2006b). Mathematics, models and metaphors. Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L.
Culture and Psychology, 12(2), 245–265. (1993). The “big three” of morality (autonomy, community,
Rudolph, L. (2006c). Spaces of ambivalence: Qualitative math- divinity), and the “Big Three” explanations of suffering. In A.
ematics in the modeling of complex fluid phenomena. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health. Stanford, CA:
Estudios de Psicología, 27(1), 67–83. Stanford University Press.
Rudolph, L. (2008a). The finite-dimensional Freeman thesis. Simão, L. M., & Valsiner, J. (2007). Otherness in question:
Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 42(2), 144–152. Labyrinths of the self. Greenwich, CT: InfoAge Publishing.
Rudolph, L. (2008b). A unified topological approach to Umwelts Simão, L. M. (2012). The Other in the Self: A triadic unit. In
and life spaces. Part II: Constructing life spaces from an J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychol-
Umwelt. In J. Clegg (Ed), The Observation of Human Systems. ogy. New York: Oxford University Press.
New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. Sinha, D. (1996). Culture as the target and culture as the source:
Rudolph, L. (2009). A unified topological approach to Umwelts A review of cross-cultural psychology in Asia. Psychology and
and life spaces. Part I: Umwelts and finite topological Developing Societies, 8(1), 83–105.
spaces. In R.I. Sokol-Chang (Ed.), Relating to Environments: Sinha, D., & Tripathi, R. C. (1994). Individualism in a collectiv-
A New Look at Umwelt. Charlotte, NC: Information Age ist culture: A case of coexistence of opposites. In U. Kim,
Publishers. H. C. Triandis, C. Kagitçibasi, C-C. Choi, & G. Yoon (Eds.),
Salgado, J., & Gonçalves, M. (2007). The Dialogical Self: Social, Individualism and collectivism: Theory, method and applica-
personal, and (un)conscious. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), tions (pp. 123–136). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Cambridge Handbook of Socio-cultural Psychology. (pp. 608– Sinha, D., & Tripathi, R. C. (2001). Individualism in a collectiv-
621). New York: Cambridge University Press. ist culture: A case of coexistence of opposites. In A. K. Dalal
Salvatore, S. (2011) Social life of the sign: sensemaking in soci- & G. Misra (Eds.), New Directions in Indian Psychology (pp.
ety. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and 241–256). New Delhi, India: Sage.
psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. Skinner, D. Pach, A., & Holland, D. (Eds.) (1998). Selves in time
Sato, T., Yasuda, Y., Kido, A., Arakawa, A., Mizoguchi, H., & and place. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Valsiner,J. (2007). Sampling reconsidered: Idiographic science Slunecko, T., & Hengl, S. (2006). Culture and the media: a
and the analyses of personal life trajectories. In J. Valsiner, J., dynamic constitution. Culture & Psychology, 12(1), 69–85.
& A. Rosa, A. (Eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Socio-Cultural Sokol-Chang, R. (Ed.) (2009). A new look at Umwelt. Charlotte,
Psychology (pp. 82–106). New York: Cambridge University NC: Information Age Publishers.
Press. Sonesson, G. (2010). Here comes the semiotic species:
Sato, T., Fukuda, M., Hidaka, T., Kido, A., Nishida, N. & Reflections on the semiotic turn in the cognitive sciences.
Akasaka, M. (2012). The Authentic Culture of Living Well: In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic transformation (pp. 38–58).
Pathways to psychological well-being. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), London: Routledge.
The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Sullivan, P. (2007). Examining the self-other dialogue through
Oxford University Press. ‘spirit’ and ‘soul’. Culture & Psychology, 13(1), 105–128.
Shweder, R. (1984). Anthropology’s romantic rebellion against Tarasti, E. (2012). Existential semiotics and cultural psychology.
the enlightenment, or there is more to thinking than reason In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
and evidence. In R. Shweder & R. A. LeVine (Eds.), Culture chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
theory (pp. 27–66). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Tavory, I., Jablonka, E., & Ginsburg, S. (2012). Culture and
Press. Epigenesis: A Waddingtonian View. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The
Shweder, R. A. (1990). Cultural psychology-- what is it? In J. W. Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Stigler, R. A. Shweder, & G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psychology University Press.
(pp. 1–43). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Teo, T. (2007). Local institutionalization, discontinuity, and
Shweder, R. A. (1991). Thinking through cultures. Cambridge, German textbooks of psychology, 1816–1854. Journal of the
MA: Harvard University Press. History of the Behavioral Sciences, 43(2), 135–157.
Shweder, R. A. (1995). The confessions of a methodological indi- Toomela, A. (2003). How should culture be studied? Culture &
vidualist. Culture & Psychology, 1(1), 115–122. Psychology, 9(1), 35–45.

va lsin er 23
Toomela, A. (2007a). Culture of science: Strange history of the Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
methodological thinking in psychology. IPBS: Integrative University Press.
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(1), 6–20. van Oers, B. (2012). Culture in play. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The
Toomela, A. (2007b). Sometimes one is more than two: When col- Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
laboration inhibits knowledge construction. IPBS: Integrative University Press.
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(2), 198–207. Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied
Toomela, A. (2008a). Variables in psychology: A critique of mind. Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press.
quantitative psychology. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Verheggen, T., & Baerveldt, C. (2007). We don’t share! The social
Behavioral Science, 42(3), 245–265. representational approach, enactivism and the ground for an
Toomela, A. (2008b). Vygotskian cultural-historical and socio- intrinsically social psychology. Culture & Psychology, 13(1),
cultural approaches represent two levels of analysis : comple- 5–27.
mentarity instead of opposition. Culture & Psychology, 14(1), Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language. 2nd ed. Cambridge,
57–69. Ma.: MIT Press
Toomela, A. (2012). Guesses on the future of cultural psychol- Vygotsky, L. S. (1999). Myshlenie i rech. 5th edition. Moscow:
ogy: Past, present—and—past. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Labirint.
Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford Wagoner, B. (2008). Narrative form and content of remem-
University Press. bering. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science,
Toomela, A., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.) (2010). Methodological 42(3), 315–323.
thinking in psychology: 60 years gone astray? Charlotte, NC: Wagoner, B. (2012). Culture in Constructive Remembering. In
Information Age Publishers. J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychol-
Tripathi, R. C., & Leviatan, U. (2003). Individualism and ogy. New York: Oxford University Press.
collectivism: In search of a product or process? Culture & Wikan, U. (2002). Generous betrayal. Chicago, IL: University of
Psychology, 9(1), 79–88. Chicago Press.
Tsoulakas, I. (2007). Exploring the microfoundations of group Winston, C., & Winston, M. (2012). Cultural Psychology of
consciousness. Culture & Psychology, 13(1), 39–81. Racial Ideology in Historical Perspective:: An Analytic
Tuli, M., & Chaudhary, N. (2010). Elective interdependence: Approach to Understanding Racialized Societies and Their
Understanding individual agency and interpersonal relation- Psychological Effects on Lives. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The
ships in Indian families. Culture & Psychology, 16(4), 477–496. Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Valsiner, J. (1995). Editorial: Culture and Psychology. Culture & University Press.
Psychology, 1(1), 5–10. Winther-Lindqvist, D. (2010). Symbolic group-play and social
Valsiner, J. (1997). Culture and the development of children’s identity. . In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic transformation
action. 2nd ed. New York: Wiley. (pp. 249–268). London: Routledge.
Valsiner, J. (2001). The first six years: Culture’s adventures in Yamamoto, T., Takahashi, N., Sato, T., Kazuku, T., Seonah, O, &
psychology. Culture & Psychology, 7(1), 5–48. Chengnan, P. (2012) How can we study interactions medi-
Valsiner, J. (2004). Three years later: Culture in psychology— ated by money as a cultural tool From the perspectives of
between social positioning and producing new knowledge. “Cultural Psychology of Differences” as a dialogical method.
Culture & Psychology, 10(1), 5–27. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psy-
Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies. New Delhi, chology. New York: Oxford University Press.
India: Sage. Ziliak, S. T., & McCloskey, D. N. (2008). The cult of statistical
Valsiner, J. (2008). Ornamented worlds and textures of feeling. significance: How the standard error costs us jobs, justice, and
Outlines: Critical Social Studies, 1, 67–78. lives. Ann Arbor, MI.: University of Michigan Press.
Valsiner, J. ( 2009a). Integrating psychology within the global- Zimmerman, A. (2001). Anthropology and antihumanism in
izing world. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral imperial Germany. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Science, 43(1), 1–16. Press.
Valsiner, J. (2009b). Cultural psychology today: Innovations and Zittoun, T (2004). Memorials and semiotic dynamics. Culture &
oversights. Culture & Psychology, 15(1), 5–39. Psychology, 10(4), 477–495.
Valsiner, J. (2012). A guided science: History of psychology in Zittoun, T (2006). Transitions. Greenwich, CT: InfoAge
the mirror of its making. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishing.
Publishers. Zittoun, T (2007). The symbolic resources in human lives. . In
Valsiner, J., & Rosa, A. (Eds.) (2007). The Cambridge Handbook J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Socio-
of Sociocultural Psychology. New York: Cambridge University cultural Psychology. (pp. 343–361). New York: Cambridge
Press. University Press.
Valsiner, J., & Rudolph, L. (2008). Who shall survive? Psychology Zittoun, T (2008). Speaking in tongues: commentary on
that replaces quantification with qualitative mathemat- Cubero, de la Mata and Cubero. Culture & Psychology, 14(4),
ics. Paper presented at the 29th International Congress of 431–441.
Psychology, Berlin, July, 21. Zittoun, T. (2012). Life course: A sociocultural perspective. In
van der Veer, R. (2012). Cultural-historical psychology : J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of culture and psychology.
Contributions of Lev Vygotsky. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The New York: Oxford University Press.

24 culture in psycho log y


CHAPTER

Culture and Psychology: Words and


1 Ideas in History

Gustav Jahoda

Abstract
This chapter provides an historical overview of the links of culture and psychology from antiquity to the
present time. The roots of interest in culture are traced to the social practices of travel—exploration,
trade, conquest, and administration—that lead to experiencing other human beings as living by very
different practices. Psychology emerged in the eighteenth and nineteenth century European thought
that carried various cultural prejudices into its mainstream. This took place in the context of basic
philosophical tension between nature and nurture as causal streams resulting in cultural differences. Over
most of the period nurture predominated, with a sharp reversal during the nineteenth century when race
came to the fore.Yet it was after the middle of that century that the terminology began to change and
culture—the name, not the concept—entered the vocabulary. Cultural psychology of today is in a position
to see mind and culture as mutually constituted.
Keywords: history, culture, Völkerpsychologie, mind, exploration, customs

Like some Freudian terms, culture has now it meant producing or developing something, such
become part of our everyday vocabulary. As such, it as “the culture of barley” or “the culture of the arts,”
is usually coupled with a range of adjectives to indi- and it is still applied in this sense, as in the phrase
cate some undefined properties of a category, such “the culture of bacteria.” In English, the first use of
as “adolescent culture,” “consumer culture,” “liter- “Culture” in the figurative sense of improvement
ary culture,” “tabloid culture,” “visual culture,” and or refinement by education and training dates back
so on. Such ordinary usage is regarded as unprob- to the early sixteenth century. More than three fur-
lematic, whereas the social sciences have agonized ther centuries had to elapse before it was employed
over the meaning of culture for more than half a in more or less its current quasi-technical sense by
century and continue to do so. In 1952, Kroeber Tylor ([1871]1958), whose approach will be more
and Kluckhohn published their well-known mono- fully discussed later. Initially culture was mainly used
graph that listed some 160 proposed definitions. in the singular to denote a property of humankind
For reasons that will be explained later, no defini- in general, and it was not until the 1930s that a clear
tion will be offered here, but the history of the word distinction came to be drawn between “culture-in-
will be outlined. general” and “a culture” as one of many different
The original source of the term was cultivation1, cultures.
as in “agriculture,” although already in Roman So far this may seem rather straightforward, but in
times Cicero used the expressions cultura animi for fact matters are more complicated. Tylor’s definition
the training of the mind and cultura mentis in a figu- began with the phrase “Culture or Civilization . . . ,”
rative sense to refer to philosophy. But for centuries indicating his view, then widely held, that these

25
terms were synonyms2. There are further compli- apart from the cumbersomeness of a constantly
cations because, as shown by Elias (1982), there changing vocabulary, there is a case for using the
are national differences in the meanings of these term culture as a kind of rough-and-ready shorthand
terms. In France, civilisation was seen as a univer- for past ideas. The argument rests on the fact that
sal feature of the (superior) West, encompassing a the absence of a term does not preclude the presence
cluster of features including economic, political, of concepts, otherwise articulated, which at least
technological, social, and moral ones. In Germany, broadly correspond to, or overlap with, what we
for historical reasons, civilization that transcends understand today by culture. These include expres-
national boundaries was conceived as something sions like “customs” or “the genius of a people.”
external and even threatening to their Kultur, Such notions again go back to antiquity and gradu-
which embodied their particular national values. In ally came to be more clearly formulated, so that
more recent times, these distinctions have become by the eighteenth century prominent thinkers put
somewhat blurred without being altogether elimi- forward ideas dealing with the relationship between
nated.3 It will be clear, therefore, that the term cul- salient features of peoples or societies and their psy-
ture is of relatively recent origin and that there are chological characteristics.
variations over time and place in the manner it is An example of past usage will help to illustrate
understood. this, and I have chosen for this purpose Michel de
Montaigne’s famous essay “On cannibals” written
Psychology: Its Historical Roots in the sixteenth century:
Let me now turn briefly to psychology, a term that
. . . il n’y a rien de barbare et de sauvage en cette
goes back to the end of the seventeenth century.
nation . . . sinon que chacun appelle barbarie ce qui
There was and remains a general consensus that it
n’est pas de son usage; comme de vray il semble que
refers to the study of the (mainly human) mind. In
nous n’avoms autre mire de la verité et de la raison
the present—historical—context, it will be inter-
que l’exemple et idée des opinions et usances du pais
preted more broadly as psychological features attrib-
ou nous sommes.
uted to (usually other) peoples.
(Montaigne [1580] 1954, p. 33)
At this point the reader might well begin to
doubt whether the implicit promise of the title of In the above, reproduced in the original archaic
this chapter is really capable of being fulfilled, as French, Montaigne is saying that everyone calls
it entails a retrospective application of the concepts “barbarism” whatever does not correspond to their
of “psychology” and “culture.” There seems to be own customs; and he states that we have no other
no fundamental difficulty with regard to psychol- criterion of truth and reason than the example of the
ogy, as long as one thinks of it as concerned with opinions and customs of the country in which we
the mind, which in turn is a key aspect of human find ourselves. Now these “opinions and customs”
nature. Ideas about human nature not only go back are important aspects of what we mean by culture.
to the beginning of recorded history but exist in The view that Montaigne can be regarded as having
some form in all known human societies, and they been concerned with culture is widely shared, and
are being studied now under the heading of “indige- a number of commentators have described him as
nous psychologies.”4 For earlier periods, long before one of the first “cultural relativists”—that is, taking
the advent of specializations, one can draw freely on the view that each culture should be judged only in
the writings of a wide range of thinkers, including terms of its own standards. Corresponding notions,
philosophers, physicians, naturalists, travelers and, such as Voltaire’s “moeurs et esprit” or Hume’s “moral
later, anthropologists and sociologists. Such usage causes” of differences between peoples, were wide-
is sanctioned by the practice of most conventional spread in the eighteenth century. This, of course,
histories of psychology. For despite of the fact that should not occasion any surprise. A term like culture
the term psychology dates back only to the sixteenth is a kind of construct that groups together a set of
century, authors usually have no compunction in phenomena and what makes up the set will largely
tracing origins back to antiquity. be a function of implicit or explicit theoretical
By contrast, there appear at first sight to be assumptions. Past thinkers made different assump-
strong objections to the retrospective use of the tions and applied different labels, yet they were
elusive term culture, which has undergone radical concerned with similar phenomena. Even today the
changes over time. Let me try to show that, quite boundaries between what is and what is not to be

26 c ulture an d psycho log y


treated as culture remain fuzzy, with considerable prevalent in their time. On the other hand, Thucidides
divergences of views. Thus I would submit that it is (c. 460–c. 400 BC) and Herodotus (c. 485–c. 425
defensible to employ the term culture diachronically BC) were historians whose work was at least partly
to designate a certain commonality of—admittedly based on observations. The former’s History of the
somewhat vague—meanings. Peloponnesian war was a masterly account of Greek
history but not only that. Thucidides wanted to
Antiquity and Middle Ages5 explain that history in terms of what he regarded
The Greeks as fundamental human nature and sought to ana-
The origins of most aspects of western thought lyze the motivations of the actors and as such was
can be traced back to figures from ancient Greece, described by Collingwood ([1946] 1961, p. 142) as
and the present theme is no exception. Among the founder of psychohistory. In undertaking this
them, one of the most prominent was of course analysis, he did not ignore the effect of external cir-
Aristotle (384–322 BC), whose teachings retained cumstances as these interacted with the common
their authority for more than one-and-a-half millen- human nature. The same principle was applied by
nia. Mainly in de Anima (but also in other works), his contemporary Hippocrates (c. 460–c. 377 B.C.)
he laid the foundations of a theoretical psychology. the “father of medicine.” According to him, one has
Here only a few relevant comments can be singled to consider a series of factors to arrive at a correct
out. Aristotle often disagreed with his teacher Plato judgment about illnesses: general human nature,
(c.428–c.348), but when it came to the external fac- the particular constitution of the individual, the cli-
tors (chiefly climatic and geographical) influencing mate in general and its specific manifestation, and
peoples’ psychologies, they followed much the same regional influences.
lines: Although Thucidides was able to personally
observe aspects of the war, he did not have much
Some regions are unsuitable or unfavourable, to say about other peoples. Herodotus, on the other
probably owing to the prevailing winds and the heat hand, traveled widely and collected extensive ethno-
of the sun; others because of the water or even the graphic data in Egypt, Babylonia, India, Persia, and
food that comes from the soil and which not only Scythia (the region north of the Black Sea). The list
provides better or poorer nourishment, but also can of topics he covered is a long one, including: race,
have no lesser consequences on the souls. looks, intelligence, virtues and vices, language, occu-
(Plato, Politeia II) pations and skills, food, sexuality, various rites (e.g.,
This is not to say that Plato placed major emphasis naming and funerals), sciences, arts, religion, his-
on such influences, because he took the view that tory, notable personalities, geography, and climate.
willingness to learn, strength of memory, and a keen In addition to direct observation, he also questioned
mind can be produced by education and appropri- local people. Well aware of the dangers of what we
ate laws. now call “ethnocentrism,” he was rarely judgmental.
Aristotle went into rather more details: His view is epitomized in the following passage:
. . . if someone were to assign to every person in the
Namely the peoples of the cold regions and those
world the task of selecting the best of all customs,
in Europe have a courageous character, but are
each one, after thorough consideration, would
behind in intelligence and skill; they also prefer to
choose those of this own people, so strongly do
be free but lack an organized state and are incapable
humans believe that their own customs are the best
of dominating their neighbours. Asian peoples, by
ones. Therefore only a madman would treat such
contrast, are intelligent and artistically gifted but
things as a laughing matter. There are many weighty
inactive, and therefore they live in subjection and as
proofs which confirm that all people have these
servants. The Greek people lives so to speak in the
strong attachments to their own customs, but let me
middle between them and therefore partakes of both
describe this particularly interesting one: during his
these characters. For it is courageous and intelligent.
reign, Darius summoned the Hellenes at his court
Hence it is free, has the best state, and is able to
and ask them how much money they would accept
dominate everything . . . . .
for eating the bodies of their dead fathers. They
(Aristotle, Politeia VII)
answered that they would not do this for any amount
The views of these philosophers were entirely of money. Later, Darius summoned some Indians
speculative, no doubt drawing on ideas that were called Kallatiai, who do eat their dead parents. In the

ja h oda 27
presence of the Hellenes . . . he asked the Indians how 500 to 1500. It has rightly been called the “Age
much money they would accept to burn the bodies of Faith”—gone were the bold speculations of the
of their dead fathers. They responded with an outcry, Greeks, and horizons narrowed. A great deal was
ordering him to shut his mouth lest he offend the written on what might be called “Christian psy-
gods. Well then, that is how people think, and so it chology” by St. Augustine or Thomas Aquinas, but
seems to me that Pindar was right when he said in his not without merit it was essentially the study of the
poetry that custom is king of all. soul.7 Contact with the world outside Europe was
(Herodotus [c. 440 BC], 2008, Book III, p. 38) limited, except for Muslim countries, which were
seen as the enemy. The world beyond was perceived
Herodotus also related the story of the Egyptian king
as being peopled by Pliny’s “monstrous races” (cf.
Psymmetichos (seventh century BC), who wanted
Friedman, J.B. (1981). The typical description cited
to find out experimentally who the first people were.
below is from the fabled Sir John Mandeville’s travel
For this purpose he obtained two newborn children
reports:
and handed them to shepherds, with strict instruc-
tions that not a single word must be spoken in their And in those isles there are many manner of folk
presence. One day, after 2 years, the children called of divers conditions. In one of them is a manner of
“bekos.” They repeated this when brought before folk of great stature, as they were giants, horrible
the king, who instituted enquiries from which he and foul to the sight; and they have but one eye,
learned that “bekos” was the Phrygian word for and that is in the midst of their forehead. They eat
“bread.” Hence, he concluded that they were the raw flesh and raw fish. In another isle are foul men
most ancient people.6 of figure without heads, and they have eyes in either
This brief sketch has concentrated on a just a few shoulder one, and their mouths are shaped round like
outstanding figures, and many more contributed. a horseshoe, y-midst their breasts. In another isle are
Even so, it will be clear that the outlook of some of men without heads; and their eyes and their mouths
the intellectual elite was wide-ranging and, in some are behind their shoulders.
respects, remarkably modern. (Letts ([1346?] 1953, Vol.1, pp. 141, 142)

The Romans The existence of the “monstrous races,” including


A great deal of their learning was transmitted creatures that were half-human and half-goat, was
to the Romans from the Greeks, and their brilliant believed by Albertus Magnus (1200–1280), one
innovations were mainly in technology. A huge of the great scholars of the Middle Ages. For him
compendium of all then existing knowledge, from a marginal case on the boundary between animal
Astronomy to Zoology, was assembled by Pliny the and human was the pygmy, of whom he probably
Elder (pp. 24–79). It includes sections on humans heard from Greek sources. His main criteria were
and quasi-humans, the latter becoming important psychological ones: pygmies have memory and are
later. In Julius Caesar’s account of the Gallic war, able to compare memory images, but they lack
he discussed not merely the characters of different abstract concepts. Albertus likened them to feeble-
tribes but described how cultural change can come minded humans possessing only the shadow of
about: reason. Hence, he concluded, they are incapable of
civitas—what we would call culture.
Among them the most courageous are the Belgers, An earlier saint and scholar, Isidore of Seville
because they live most remote from the civilization (c. 560–c. 636) had put forward a climatic theory of
(cultu atque humanitate) of the Roman province; and psychological characteristics:
also because traders bringing luxury goods, which
could weaken their character, seldom reach them. In accordance with diversity of climate, the
(De bello Gallico , I,I,3) appearance of men and their colour and bodily size
vary and diversities of mind appear. Thence we see
Other writers, like Tacitus, made similar comments. that the Romans are dignified, the Greeks unstable,
Generally, however, much of their thought on the the Africans crafty, the Gauls fierce by nature . . .
topic was derived from the Greeks. (cited in Slotkin, 1965, p. 5)

The Middle Ages Climatic theories of various kinds persisted until


These lasted from the fall of the Roman Empire the nineteenth century and were not confined
to the Renaissance, roughly the millennium from to Christian Europe. Regarding Europeans, the

28 c ulture an d psycho log y


Muslim writer Masudi (?1–956) noted, “The far- the way for a renewed interest in the cultures of
ther they are to the north the more stupid, gross, Greece and Rome, which in turn liberated minds.
and brutish they are” (cited in Lewis, 1994, p. 139). Renaissance travelers eagerly sought personal fame
In the year 1068, Said Ibn Ahmad, from Toledo in as well as proclaiming the goal of converting the
Spain, wrote a treatise on the types of cultures. He pagans. One can clearly discern the ethnocentric
divided them into two groups: those who contribute anchoring of the concern with exotic peoples. At
to science and learning, including Arabs, Egyptians, the same time there was a search for a perspective
Greeks, Romans and Jews and those he considered whereby one might locate “the Others” in time and
to be progressively more stupid and ignorant with space for the purpose of systematic comparison, and
increasing distance from the sun, including people with a view to gaining a better understanding of
living in the north; Chinese and Turks were treated one’s own individuality and society (Rowe, 1965).
as marginal. The period was also characterized by an
The most remarkable of the Muslim Arab schol- immense—albeit somewhat diffuse—curiosity,
ars was Ibn Khaldun (1332–1406) who wrote a trea- manifesting itself in a passion for collecting a wide
tise on the history and theory of social and political range of natural objects and artifacts, as well as by
change, which he regarded as cyclical. Many of his receptivity to new ideas. The travel literature result-
ideas have an astonishingly modern ring, such as ing from these voyages therefore found an avid
his view that stability depends on “group feeling”; public. Although the first-hand accounts by travel-
again, here are his comments on culture: ers were often sober and factual, it did not follow
that belief in the fabulous had disappeared. Popular
Culture is not an independent substance, but a
travel books embroidered the tales—describing, for
property . . . of another substance which is man.
example, the inhabitants of the New World as “blue
Hence the natural character of culture must have
in colour and with square heads.” One of the most
reference to what is natural to man, i.e. to his nature
successful of these collections, the Cosmographia
and is what differentiates him from the rest of the
by Sebastian Muenster (1544), presented an indis-
animal world.
criminate mixture of the old “monstrous races” and
(Mahdi, 1971, p. 173)
the newly discovered “savages.” Yet despite the per-
Significantly, the subtitle of his opus is A Study in sistence of fables, the Renaissance saw an unprec-
the Philosophic Foundation of the Science of Culture. edented expansion of the European intellectual
Although it is not clear what Arabic word was horizon in terms of both the physical and human
glossed as culture, there can be little doubt that it worlds.
must be close to our concept, probably more so With a vast expansion of travel, exploration, and
than any of the notions discussed so far. colonization, the material available for comparative
studies grew proportionately. From the beginning
From the Renaissance to the of that period, advice to travelers came to be pub-
Enlightenment lished. The advice included general admonitions of
Renaissance a vague kind (e.g., to mark down things observed)
In Christian Europe the fantastic image of the and moral warnings about dallying with women.
outside word was slow to change even after the Other works listed various kinds of customs and
dawn of the voyages of exploration. These began institutions that should be recorded and also men-
with Marco Polo who visited India and the Far East tioned the need to note the psychological disposi-
at the end of the thirteenth century. During the fif- tions of the people as well as their moral character,
teenth century, the Portuguese explored the West qualities, and abilities. Varen’s (1650) Geographica
Coast of Africa, later getting to the Cape of Good generalis achieved a wide circulation among travel-
Hope shortly before Columbus reached America. ers. The topics it covered, reproduced below (from
The following century saw the conquest of Mexico Malefijt, 1974, p. 45), are by no means outdated:
and Peru by the Spaniards, who also found New
Guinea. 1. Stature, shape, skin color, food habits
It was a new breed of men, created by the 2. Occupations and arts
Renaissance cult of the individual, who embarked 3. Virtues, vices, learning, wit [in the sense of
on these hazardous voyages of exploration. The all- intelligence]
embracing theological shell had cracked, opening 4. Marriage, birth, burial, name giving

ja h oda 29
5. Speech and language Of Children and Their Manners
6. State and government With us, a child of 4 years does not yet know
7. Religion how to eat properly; those in Japan eat by them-
8. Cities and renowned places selves with chopsticks from the age of 3 years.
9. History With us it is customary to whip and chastise
10. Famous men, inventions, and innovations boys; in Japan it is very rare to act in this manner,
and this applies even to reprimands.
It would, of course, be anachronistic to suppose that
the authors of such guides were thinking in terms of
anything like culture and psychology, as these cat-
The Japanese Manner of Eating
egories were then nonexistent. All they show is an
and Drinking
We drink with only one hand; the Japanese
interest in a range of topics we include under these
always do with two.
rubrics.
We like dishes cooked with milk, cheese, butter,
Among the travel literature, one of the most
or bone marrow; the Japanese abominate all that,
remarkable works, dealing with Japan, will be
which smells very bad to their nose.
briefly outlined. The first substantive contact with
Altogether Frois listed more than 400 binary
Europe began with Portuguese missionary activity
oppositions, throughout his tone remains neutral
in the sixteenth century, and from this stemmed
and objective. Differences capture attention and
the first coherent account of Japanese culture. The
interest, as already shown by Herodotus when writ-
Jesuit Father Louis Frois (1532–1597) wrote a slen-
ing about the “peculiar customs” of the Egyptians.
der volume entitled Treatise on the Contradictions
For example, he noted that Egyptian priests have
and Differences in Customs (Frois, [1585] 1998).
shaven heads, whereas in other nations they have
In the preface, he wrote: “Many of their customs
long hair.
are so strange and distant from ours that seems
almost unbelievable that there could be so many
oppositions [between us and] people who are so
The Sixteenth and Seventeenth
civilized [une grande police], have such a lively spirit
Centuries
The existence of a wide diversity of peoples
and natural wisdom” (p. 13). Evidently the good
having been established, the general question
Father was favorably disposed toward the Japanese,
arose as to the nature of the differences. The most
although he could hardly have approved of some
commonly postulated cause remained the cli-
of the customs he described. A few examples of
mate, viewed in broad sense,8 although there were
oppositions from several of his categories are cited
some dissenters. Jean Bodin (1530–1596) tried
below.
to classify peoples in terms of north and south
but was troubled by the fact that people in the
Persons and Their Clothes
same latitudes can differ. Nevertheless, as already
With us, there are many men and women with
noted, such ideas persisted. About the same
brownish spots on the skin; this is very rare with
time, a social interpretation of differences gained
Japanese, even though they are White. (Author’s
ground—namely, in the variety of customs. It was
emphasis added)
Montaigne, already cited, who most eloquently
With us, wearing painted clothes would be
described the power of custom:
regarded as mad or ridiculous; the Japanese do it
customarily. . . . the principal effect of the force of custom is to
seize and grip us so firmly, that we are scarcely able
Of Women, Their Persons and to escape from its grasp, and to gain possession of
Their Manners ourselves sufficiently to discuss and reason out its
In Europe, the honor and the supreme good of commands. In truth, since we imbibe them with
young women are the modesty and the inviolate our mother’s milk, and the world shows the same
cloister of their purity; the women of Japan set little face to our infant eyes, we seem to be born to
store by virginal purity, and losing it neither dishon- follow the same path; and the common ideas that
ors them nor prevents them from marrying. we find around us, and infused into our souls with
With us it is rare that women know how to write; the seed of our fathers, appear to be general and
an honorable woman in Japan would be held in low natural.
esteem if she did not know how to do it. (Cited in Slotkin, 1965, pp. 56–57)9

30 c ulture an d psycho log y


In his famous essay “On Cannibals” and else- began to change. It was the age of the scientific revo-
where, Montaigne applied this to what we would lution and John Locke (1632–1704), friend of Isaac
call “cultural differences” Newton, was an empiricist who stressed the need
for observation. His views on the environmental
The different customs I find in one nation after
determination of people’s characteristics were much
another please me by their very diversity . . . I am
the same as those of Descartes. Other developments
ashamed when I see my countrymen steeped in that
at that time contributed to the formation of a fresh
silly prejudice which makes them fight shy of any
perspective. Ludwig Seckendorf (1626–1692) and
customs that differ from their own . . .
William Petty (1623–1687) elaborated a system of
(p. 55)
social statistics dealing with births and deaths, show-
This insight was repeatedly voiced throughout the ing that human life is subject to order and regularity
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Here are some and could be studied quantitatively.
examples:
The Enlightenment
It is good to know something of the customs of In the eighteenth century, the authority of the
different people in order to judge more sanely of our churches became undermined by Newton’s dem-
own. onstration that the physical universe is lawful.
(Descartes, p. 104) This prompted the question whether one might
But there is another force, that ravishes away the not envisage causal laws of mind and society.
minds of men, and makes them addicted to certain Montesquieu was one of the first to attempt the for-
affections. Namely, that spirit which being appropri- mulation of such laws that would account for differ-
ate to every region, infuseth into men, as soon as they ences between societies (1689–1755):
are borne, the habits and affections of their owne I have first of all considered mankind, and concluded
country. that its infinite variety of laws and customs did not
(Barclay, p. 106) uniquely arise from arbitrary fancy. I have postulated
the principles, and have seen how particular cases fit
Custom is our nature. . . . What are our natural
them neatly.
principles but principles of custom ? In children they
(Montesquieu, [1748] 1964, p. 529)
are those which they have received from the habits of
their fathers . . ,. A different custom will cause differ- In the same work (p. 641), he also proposed that
ent natural principles. This is seen in experience; and various influences, including “the examples of
if there are some natural principles ineradicable by things past,” create “a general spirit [esprit général]”
custom, there are also some customs opposed to na- that corresponds fairly closely to what we mean by
ture, ineradicable by nature, or by a second custom. culture. The underlying assumption, then widely
(Pascal, p. 120) shared, was that human nature remains constant
and that differences result from varying historical
It is interesting that Pascal struggled with the prob-
circumstances. It was an optimistic age, based on
lem of the relationship between, in our terms,
the belief in inevitable progress driven by reason. Its
“nature versus culture,” an issue that has not gone
effects were regarded as cumulative. A typical state-
away. This is because culture is now often seen as
ment is that by Adam Ferguson (1723–1816). He
an evolutionary product (e.g., Aunger, 2000). The
begins by listing the commonalties between animals
general tendency to refer to custom in the sense
and humans, and then goes on:
of our culture long continued. Even at the end of
the nineteenth century, Bagehot (1872) employed Yet one property by which man is distinguished has
the phrase “the cake of custom” to refer to cultural been sometimes overlooked . . . In other classes of
traditions. Apart from custom, there is one other animals, the individual advances from infancy to
kind of expression, rare at that time but becoming age or maturity; and he attains, in the compass of a
more frequent subsequently: Harrington explained single life, to all the perfection his nature can reach;
national differences in terms of “The Genius of the but in the human kind, the species has a progress
Nations” (Slotkin 1965, p. 130). as well as the individual; they build in every age on
So far nearly all the ideas that have been reviewed the foundations formerly laid; and, in a succession
have been impressionistic and speculative, but dur- of years , tend to perfection in the application of
ing the second half of the seventeenth century, that their faculties, to which the aid of long experience is

ja h oda 31
required, and to which many generations must have 3. What is the extent of development of each of
combined their endeavours. their senses compared with what one encounters
(Ferguson, [1767] 1966, pp. 4–5) normally among ourselves?
4. What is the type of sensation in which they
Apart from the vocabulary used, this seems a fair
find most pleasure?
description of what is now referred to as “cultural
transmission.” There follow some comments on ways to esti-
In France Louis-Francois Jauffret (1770–1850) mate the degree of development of a particular sense
founded the Société des Observateurs de l’Homme modality, including the threshold as well as speed
in 1799. Its object was to study human nature, and accuracy of sensory judgment responses. An
including ethnic differences and their causes, the example given is the skill in estimating distances.
history of various peoples, and their customs and Observers should seek to establish whether innate
migrations, as well as child development from factors as well as practice contribute to the fre-
infancy onward. The membership consisted of a quently noted perfection of savage senses.11 They
galaxy of illustrious names in France, and a num- will also find out if blindness and deafness are more
ber of empirical studies were performed. One or less common than among Europeans, the effects
of the most ambitious ones took advantage of of such handicaps, and the modes of adaptation.
an opportunity to study “savages” at first hand. Other topics include abstract concepts; associa-
Napoleon approved the project of an expedition to tion of ideas; opinions and judgments; attention;
Australasia, and the Société commissioned Joseph- memory; imbecility; education; and child develop-
Marie Degérando (1772–1842) to prepare a kind ment. It will be noted that nearly all these topics
of handbook of methods for this purpose,10 enti- have subsequently become topics of cross-cultural
tled “Considerations on the Methods to Follow in research.
the Observation of Savage Peoples” (Degerando,
[1800] 1969). This is one of the most remarkable Against Enlightenment Thought
documents in the history of social science, which The idea of a social science based on the model of
reflects and advances the knowledge then available. physics was strongly opposed by Giambattista Vico
After two centuries, many of its recommendations (1668–1744). In The New Science ([1725] 1948),
are still valid. They will be briefly summarized, he wrote:
employing modern terminology.
At the outset, Degerando warns against a number . . . the world of civil society has certainly been made
of possible pitfalls in research, such as inadequate by men, and its principles are therefore to be found
sampling and communication errors. One should within the modifications of our own human mind.
not judge people in other cultures by ethnocentric Whoever reflects on this cannot but marvel that the
standards. It is best to become a participant observer philosophers have bent all their energies to the study
and learn the indigenous language. One should con- of the world of nature, which, since God made it, he
sider the effects of the presence of an observer. alone knows; and that they should have neglected the
The psychological topics he suggests reflect the world of nations, or civil world, which, since men
then prevailing “sensationist” theory of Condillac. had made it, men could come to know . . .
The first illustrative category will be described in (p. 331)
some detail, whereas for the others, just headings
The philosophers of the Enlightenment saw
will be listed.
human history as progressive pan-human stages
based on modes of subsistence: from hunting to pas-
Sensations toral to agricultural and finally to commercial. Vico’s
The first thing to be observed is the sensations
stages were essentially psychological in character and
of savage people, examining in detail their varieties
referred to “a world of nations,” and his concept of a
and focusing on the following four questions:
nation appears to have been very much the same as
1. What are the senses among them that are what we mean by culture. For him the language, mor-
most exercised, active, and finely discriminating? als, customs, myths, and rituals of a “nation” consti-
2. What are the conditions that might have led tuted a complex unity of interdependent parts.
to the more marked development of a particular Unlike Vico, Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–
sense modality? 1803) was in his youth an ardent disciple of the

32 c ulture an d psycho log y


Enlightenment but later came to question most of The Nineteenth Century
its ideas and values and moved much closer to the The First Half of the Nineteenth
position of Vico (although without knowing Vico’s Century
work). In opposition to the then prevalent view of This was a period of transition. With the rise of
the immutability of human nature, Herder stressed biology, human differences came to be increasingly
its variability, conditioned by historical and envi- attributed to “race,” and environmental factors
ronmental factors. tended to recede into the background. Yet most of
In one of his main works on The Origin of the figures to be discussed here bucked this trend.
Language (1772), he discusses its broader functions. One was Wilhelm von Humboldt (1767–1835),
Language, according to him, serves not merely as who was influenced by some of Herder’s ideas but
a means of communication but also as a mode of did not believe in cultural relativity, being convinced
transmitting the ideas and feelings of past genera- of “the governing principle of universal humanity.”
tions. Thus what Herder calls “tradition” is not just Humboldt’s dominant interest is epitomized in the
a static bundle of beliefs and customs but a process title of his most important work, On the Diversity
in which past and present are fused and that gives a of Human Language Construction and Its Influence
group of people their sense of identity. This clearly on the Mental Development of the Human Species
anticipates later ideas of the transmission of culture ([1836] 1999). He held that language is the main
through the generations. glue that holds human cultures together, and he
The key term Herder applies to such a group—or had a great deal to say on the relationship between
better, organic community—is Volk. A Volk is charac- language and thought.12 Moreover, he maintained
terized by a shared language and historical tradition that social processes are an essential prerequisite for
that shape the mentality [Volksgeist] of its members, adequate cognitive functioning.
not into any permanent mold but in constant move- The nature of mental processes was the main
ment of growth and development—or decay. A Volk focus of the work of Johann Friedrich Herbart
may or may not coincide with a nation-state—it (1776–1841), best known for his writings on edu-
certainly need not do so. This concept is in fact very cational and mathematical psychology. Of course,
close to what we mean nowadays by a culture, and it is not possible here to go into details of his com-
Herder’s somewhat flowery description of the way plex theories, but some basic features have to be
in which, from infancy onward, not merely collec- briefly indicated. He envisaged an intra-individual
tive ideas but also feelings and images are conveyed system whereby different Vorstellungen (ideas and/
is essentially an account of socialization into a par- or feelings, or presentations) interact, either com-
ticular culture. bining or opposing each other. They can rise above
The diversity of human languages and cultures and/or push each other below the threshold of con-
was, for Herder, a positive value, something “good” sciousness. Subsequently he put forward the pro-
and “natural.” In contrast to most philosophers posal that the forces in society analogously reflect
of the Enlightenment’ who established scales of the individual system, which is similar to Benedict’s
“ ‘progress” whereby to evaluate different societies as (1932) contention that culture is individual psy-
“high” or “low,” “barbaric,” or “polished,” Herder chology writ large.13 Herbart also recommended
was a relativist who considered that each culture that psychologists should study people from out-
must be approached, and valued, on its own terms: side Europe:
Thus nations change according to place, time and their . . . how many of us concerned with psychology
inner character; each carries within itself the measure have been to New Zealand? How many of us have
of its perfection, incommensurable with others. occasion to observe the savages in their home setting?
(Herder [1785] 1969, vol.4, p. 362) (1825/1890, vol.6, p. 16)

Herder was also unusual in that he did not share Herbart could therefore be regarded as one of the
the then quasi-universal assumption of a gen- ancestors of cross-cultural psychology, and he fur-
eral European superiority and disapproved of the nished the theoretical underpinning for Lazarus and
European practices to “subjugate, cheat, and plun- Steinthal’s Völkerpsychologie (Diriwächter, 2011).
der.” Thereby he went directly against the spirit of One of their main aims was to clarify the concept of
nationalism and colonization that was dawning the Volksgeist (spirit of the people), a concept whose
toward the end of his life. meaning is at least loosely related to that of culture.

ja h oda 33
Theodor Waitz (1821–1864), prominent follower (1826–1905). In his student days he attended lectures
of Herbart, devoted himself to the cause of “psychic by Lazarus, one of the founders of Völkerpsychologie,
unity” (a phrase he coined) as against the biological for whom he had a high regard. Among the afore-
race scientists. Like James Pritchard (1786–1848) mentioned eighteenth- and nineteenth-century
in Britain, he was faced with the problem that given writers, he was the first to have personally collected
the (then) stark contrasts between human groups, ethnographic material in various parts of the world,
the claim that they all had one common mind including Australia, New Zealand, North and South
appeared counterintuitive. Hence they accumulated America, China, and India. Unlike other travel-
a mass of ethnographic material in an effort to make ers who mainly reported about the geography of
their case, and Waitz wrote: the places they visited and the physical character-
istics of the peoples and their artifacts, Bastian was
However great the difference between their mental
mainly interested in their psychological features. He
culture and ours, we may, if time and opportunity
obtained information on religious beliefs and prac-
are favourable, learn to understand all their actions,
tices, myths, legal and political forms, customs, and
and we are thus justified in assuming in the human
so on.
species, only difference in culture.
In his travels, he found that peoples all over the
(Waitz ([1859] 1863, p. 274, emphases added)
world had a great deal in common as well as dif-
It might be tempting to conclude from the ending fering in many ways. He therefore postulated the
of this passage that Waitz used the term culture in existence of what he called “elementary ideas” that
its modern sense, but that would be a mistake, as are universally shared. He sometimes wrote in a
the earlier mention of “mental culture” indicates. manner suggesting that by “ideas” he also meant
The sense is that of “cultivation,” and some peoples “thought processes.” The differences between peo-
are said to be insufficiently “cultivated.” ples are said to result partly from the development
Yet around mid-century, a monumental work was of their particular languages which, according to
published by Gustav Klemm (1802–1867) under Bastian, afford valuable insights into national char-
the title “General Culture-History of Humanity” acters and partly from environmental and histori-
(Klemm 1843–1852),2 which at times does appear cal factors. The ultimate objective was to arrive at a
to employ the term Cultur in something like its comparative psychology:
modern sense.14 The work is historical and does
A comparative psychology can only be established
not deal with psychology, but it is mentioned here
on the basis of ethnology, which traces in the various
because it inspired what is widely regarded as the
ethnic groups [Volkskreisen] the genetic development
classical definition of culture by Tylor, usually cited
of mental products [Gedankenschöpfungen] and
as follows:
explains their local colouring in terms of geographical
Culture or Civilization, taken in its wide or historical contexts.
ethnographic sense, is that complex whole which (Bastian, 1868, p. XI)
includes knowledge, belief, art, morals, law, custom,
How far does Bastian’s notion of “elementary”
and any other capabilities acquired by man as a
or “folk ideas” correspond to a modern concept of
member of society.
culture? Here we have to remind ourselves that far
(Tylor [1871] 1958, p. 1)
from there being a generally agreed definition of cul-
From this, one might infer that his definition was ture, there are numerous varied ones. Among them
purely anthropological, but the next sentence shows is that of “a symbolic meaning system,” and this to
that he did not ignore psychological aspects: “The some extent resembled what Bastian had in mind.
condition of culture among the various societies of It should also be said that Bastian’s was essentially a
mankind . . . is a subject apt for the study of laws of collective psychology, located midway between psy-
human thought and action” (emphasis added). It will chology and anthropology and as such had a good
be noted that he treated culture and civilization as deal in common with Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie.
synonyms, an issue to be pursued below.
Culture and Psychology in the
Adolf Bastian Circle of Wundt
Another German figure of that period, very Völkerpsychologie was located outside the main-
much concerned with psychology, was Adolf Bastian stream of experimental psychology pioneered by

34 c ulture an d psycho log y


Fechner and Ebbinghaus. Not everybody was happy persons and their expressions of life comes
with experimental psychology, which to some about. . . . Before he learns to speak, the child is
seemed rather dry and mechanical, failing to do already completely immersed in the medium of
justice to the subtleties and complexities of human common contexts. . . . In this way, the individual
life. The most articulate critic was Wilhelm Dilthey becomes oriented in the world of objective spirit.
(1833–1911). Like Bastian, he had met Lazarus and (Dilthey, [1894] 1977, pp. 126–127)
had even worked with him for a time. But his initial
It may be noted that Dilthey’s ideas were one of
enthusiasm for Völkerpsychologie was later tempered
the sources from which almost a century later the
by reservations related to the speculative nature and
so-called “cultural studies” movement emerged.
diffuseness of the enterprise. He turned toward the
Karl Lamprecht (1856–1915) was an unorthodox
scientific side, became a pupil of Helmholtz, and
historian who thought that history was not bound
attended lectures on physiology.
to remain merely descriptive but could become sci-
After obtaining a chair in philosophy, he became
entific and thereby attain objective truth. Like many
increasingly preoccupied with problems of psychol-
of his contemporaries, he adopted an evolutionary
ogy, philosophy, and history, which he came to see as
framework, taking the view that humanity went
connected. Regarding psychology, he proposed that
through a set of distinct stages that were lawful. It
there are two distinct approaches to the subject: one
should therefore be possible to arrive at universal
is empiricist, concerned with hypothesis-testing and
historical laws. For Lamprecht, historical phases and
aiming at causal explanations, the other rests on lived
events are essentially of a psychic nature, so that any
experience and aims at understanding—a contrast
stage is characterized by a collective psychic state.
analogous to that drawn by Vico. While accepting
This he regarded as a kind of diapason, pervading
the legitimacy of the former, Dilthey described it as
all mental states, and thereby also all activities, in
formal and atomistic, ignoring the fact that the self
any given period.
has a functional unity that eludes any approach that
The auxiliary science that would enable historians
concentrates exclusively on its constituent parts.
to arrive at these sequences was the then emerging
Dilthey himself focused on Erlebnis or “lived expe-
social psychology. Furthermore, he devised and sought
rience,” and his two key concepts are Verstehen (a kind
to apply an empirical method for identifying the
of understanding15) and Bedeutung (or “meaning”).
sequence of distinct evolutionary stages.17 Lamprecht
Both of these operate within particular culture-
proposed a schema detailing the social-psychological
historical contexts. In this connection he took
factors operative in the course of history, which will
over from Hegel the notion of “objective spirit,”16
be summarized. He divided them first into natural
employing it in a manner that corresponds closely
and cultural ones. The natural comprised such influ-
to what we refer to as culture:
ences as climate, soil, flora, and fauna. The cultural
I understand objective spirit to be the various is further subdivided into material (e.g., economy,
forms in which the common ground that exists nutrition, population, and, oddly, custom) and ideal
is objectified in the world of the senses. In this (e.g., opinion, language, myth and religion, and art).
objective spirit, the past is a continuing presence for Altogether it is a rather strange mixture, yet nonethe-
us. Its domain extends from the style of life and the less somewhat distantly reminiscent of Berry’s (1976)
forms of economic interaction to the system of ends scheme. One could also mention the French Annales
which society has formed: to morality, law, the state, school of historians that began during the interwar
religion, art, science, and philosophy. period. At the outset, one of their principal tenets was
(Dilthey, [1894] 1977, p. 126) that each historical period features a particular kind
of mentality. So not only was Lamprecht directly
One could also gloss this as a reference to intersub-
focusing on culture but his ideas had certain reso-
jectively shared meaning systems. At any rate, the
nances in the twentieth century.
broad congruence between “objective spirit” and
what we know as culture is supported by the way in
Some Debates in Germany
which Dilthey characterizes what we would call the
To grasp the issues at stake, it is necessary to
acquisition of culture:
explain first that in German, a distinction had
From earliest childhood our self receives its long been drawn between scholarly or humane
nourishment from this world of objective spirit. It and scientific disciplines. The former were known
is also the medium in which the Verstehen of other as Geisteswissenschaften (literally “disciplines of

ja h oda 35
the spirit”) and the latter as Naturwissenschaften culture provides an approximate mirror image of all
(what we would call “natural sciences”).18 This the remaining parts.
dichotomy became the subject of a great debate. (Wundt, 1908, vol.3, p. 434)>
Its ostensible aim was the purely scholarly one
A more detailed treatment is to be found in
of conceptual clarification, but the fact that
Volume 7 of the Völkerpsychologie dealing with
it was conducted mainly by exponents of the
Society (Wundt, 1917).This contains a critical dis-
Geisteswissenschaften indicates that it was the sta-
cussion of the dichotomy of Natur- versus-Kultur-
tus of the Geisteswissenschaften that was chiefly at
völker (the term Naturvolk is roughly equivalent to
stake. Although the debate as such was not about
our “savages”). This distinction had usually been
psychology, psychology was nevertheless to be
drawn on the basis of the absence of history and
found at the heart of the controversy. The reason,
an organized state, but Wundt points out that these
no doubt, is the hybrid character of psychology
criteria are too vague for any clear division to be
that spans the divide separating the sciences from
possible. There is no Naturvolk without elements of
the humanities and social studies.
Kultur, consisting of the above-mentioned language,
In 1880, philologist Hermann Paul published
myth, and Sitte, and there are different levels of cul-
a book in which he argued that the opposite of
ture among these peoples. Hence the dichotomy is
Natur is not Geist (mind or spirit) but Kultur and
becoming redundant:
proposed the expression Kulturwissenschaften. The
characteristic mark of Kultur, he maintained, lies in [It is for this reason] that the concept of Kultur in
the involvement of psychic factors.19 The new label its actual extension to the peoples of the earth has
was adopted by the philosopher Heinrich Rickert become ever broader, while the concept of Naturvolk
(1848–1936), who defined Kultur as “the totality is gradually disappearing.
of objects to which generally recognized values are (Wundt, 1917, p. 121)
attached” (Rickert, 1910, p. 27). Thus the basic dif-
ference between Natur and Kultur is that the former, From this passage one might suppose that Wundt
unlike the latter, is value-free. This broad issue also had begun to think of culture in much the same
concerned Wundt, whose rather variable positions way as we do today. But one is rapidly disabused
will by outlined next. of this by an immediately subsequent—and
rather confused—discussion of the concept of
“culture-minimum.” In this he reverted to a
Wundt on Kultur
usage of Kultur as more or less synonymous with
It is difficult to examine Wundt’s ideas regarding
Zivilisation.
culture without the context of his Völkerpsychologie, to
The same theme is taken up in the tenth and
which they are closely related. Because Völkerpsychologie
final volume of his Völkerpsychologie, entitled
is dealt with in detail by Diriwächter (2011), all that
“Culture and History” (Wundt, 1920). There he
can be done here is to provide a sketch of his usages.
states that the absolute lower limit of Kultur is set
In his earliest relevant publication, Wundt
by the possession of language, which presupposes
(1863) employed the term in the then most prev-
at least a modicum of mental life. The question of
alent sense—namely, the higher forms of human
origins is a futile one, and it is more profitable to ask
intellect and creativity. In his later work, he gen-
what cultural products and events have been critical
erally takes it that the essence of Kultur consists of
for cultural development. Wundt reviews various
three elements—namely, language, myth, and Sitte,
turning points, like the invention of the plough or
a term denoting both “custom” and “morals.” In
the printing press, but raises various objections to
the Methodenlehre (1883), he refers to Kulturvölker
such simple schemes—particularly that they leave
as meaning “civilized peoples.” In a later edition of
out qualitative aspects of cultural values. These are
his Logik, Wundt (1908) makes a passing comment
implicit in the concept of Zivilisation, which is felt
anticipating the view that culture is not merely a
to be something that has been actively achieved,
random assembly of features but possesses some
whereas culture is merely the outcome of historical
unity and coherence:
processes—a rather curious distinction. This means
Cuvier20 maintained that one can reconstruct from a that civilization leads to a sense of superiority and of
single bone the typical form of the whole vertebrate a mission both to civilize and dominate more back-
to whom it belongs; similarly, each single part of a ward peoples.

36 c ulture an d psycho log y


Wundt regarded this as a valuable feature of civ- relate these, respectively, to general Völkerpsychologie
ilization, because it contained a purposive element and to what he regarded as its applied aspect, which
that is absent from culture. he called “ethnic characterology”—that is, dealing
Shortly afterward, there occurred a radical shift with the psychological characteristics of particular
in the meaning attributed to Kultur: peoples. There is no indication that any echoes of
the radical rethinking of the category culture by
Kultur is national. It is confined to a particular
Franz Boas (discussed below) ever reached Wundt.
national community [Volksgemeinschaft] which
Before going on to Boas, it is necessary to return
constitutes a coherent unity in terms of language,
briefly to Tylor, whose classical definition of cul-
custom, and intellectual cultivation [geistige Bildung];
ture was cited on p. 34. As already mentioned, in
but it lacks the tendency to go beyond these limits by
his time the favored explanation of human differ-
spreading the acquired cultural achievements more
ences was simply in terms of “race.” This opinion
widely . . .
was not shared by Tylor, who was an inheritor of
(Wundt, 1920, pp. 20–21)
the Enlightenment tradition of a basically unchang-
Here Wundt suddenly identifies culture with some- ing universal human nature.21 Under the influence
thing very much like Herder’s Volksgeist, seem- of environmental factors, its manifestations under-
ingly unaware of the change. He concludes that went progressive changes, occurring at varying rates
the notions of Kultur and Zivilisation are comple- among different peoples. Thus he was a social (rather
mentary: Kultur is bound to nationality, whereas than Darwinian) evolutionist, and the approach
Zivilisation embodies an ideal of humanity as a to the study of evolutionary stages was the “com-
unity under the leadership of the advanced nations parative method.” For example, ancient Swiss lake
(Kulturvölker). habitations were very similar to those of nineteenth-
The next section, entitled “Animal antecedents century Maoris, and this was taken to show that the
of cultural man,” reverts again to a wider concept of same evolutionary trajectory was being followed,
Kultur, applying to humans in general. However far although the Maoris were well behind.
one goes, he maintains, what one finds universally
among all those who have the physical characteris- Franz Boas
tics of humans are language, myth, and Sitte: Both racial and social-evolutionary theories
came to be rejected by Franz Boas (1858–1942).
As these three labels designate only the major
He was the main creator of a fresh concept of cul-
directions in which human life is distinguished
ture and came to dominate American anthropol-
from that of other organic beings, and although
ogy during the 1920s. He was born and educated
each of these directions comprises very different
in Germany, where he began by studying chemistry
forms, so all these factors and their influences on
and physics but later turned to biology and geog-
men may be subsumed under the collective name of
raphy. He also became interested in psychophysics
Kultur, so that in view of this Völkerpsychologie and
and attended lectures by Wundt. In 1882 he went
Kulturpsychologie are equivalent concepts.
to Berlin in preparation for a geographical expe-
(Wundt, 1920, p. 57)
dition to Baffin Island, and in Berlin he came to
In the end, therefore, Wundt overcame his misgiv- know Bastian. A year later he departed on the expe-
ings and accepted that what he had been doing dition, intending originally to compare the objec-
could be described as “cultural psychology,” because tively studied environment with the knowledge of
he seemed to have arrived at a conception of cul- it held by the Inuit inhabitants. As a result of his
ture-in-general that is close to our own. The path close acquaintance with the Inuit (e.g., he hunted
that led him to this position was not a straight one. with them) Boas came to understand that their
For a long time, Wundt swiveled between several knowledge was not just a reflection of the environ-
different and mutually exclusive notions of Kultur, ment but discovered that there was a tertium quid
varying according to context, as well as between an that intervened—namely, their culture. This was a
objective stance and one that uncritically accepted turning point in his career, and back in Germany he
the then prevailing ethos. applied for his Habilitation,22 and the members of
Wundt rarely drew a sufficiently explicit distinc- the commission included Dilthey and Helmholtz.
tion between “human-culture-in-general” and the Subsequently Boas emigrated to the United States,
varied cultures of different peoples; nor did he seek to where he embarked on fieldwork with the Indians

ja h oda 37
of the Northwest Pacific Coast and in 1899 became of relative emphasis. What is relevant here is the
the first professor of anthropology at Columbia fact that these anthropological discussions usu-
University in New York. ally involved psychological ideas and speculations.
In his theorizing about culture, Boas was greatly For example, Goldenweiser (1910) referred to “the
influenced by his German background, from Herder mechanism and psychology of borrowing behav-
onward. Although he initially shared Tylor’s social ior” (p. 285) and proposed that “the phenomena
evolutionism, he later abandoned it. He pointed out of diffusion [are] replete with psychological prob-
that similarity does not necessarily imply an identi- lems” (p. 287). In a similar manner, Boas (1910, pp.
cal cause, showing how the same outcome could 375–376) proclaimed, “the necessity of looking for
result from combinations of quite diverse historical, the common psychological features, not in outward
environmental, and psychological factors. He also similarities of ethnic phenomena, but in the sim-
objected to specific traits or complexes being torn ilarity of psychological processes in so far as these
out of their particular cultural context and lumped can be observed or inferred.” Although these were
together indiscriminately. He showed that biologi- American comments, in Britain, Rivers took part in
cal traits (i.e., “race”), language, and culture were the debate.
not intrinsically linked to each other and had to be William Halse Rivers (1864–1922) was an
studied using different methods. experimental psychologist at Cambridge when his
Generally, Boas was instrumental in changing anthropological colleague Alfred Haddon invited
the intellectual climate toward thinking about cul- him to take part in the Cambridge Anthropological
tures in the plural as entities that had a certain unity Expedition to Torres Strait in 1898. It was the first
based on history, environment, and psychology. His systematic cross-cultural research, although con-
enduring concern with psychology is clear from the fined to sensory processes;23 Rivers had little to say
title of one of his major works—namely, The Mind about culture at that time. He was then still a social
of Primitive Man (Boas, 1911); it is also implicit in evolutionist, but that changed when he became
an early definition of culture he proposed: actively involved in anthropological fieldwork. In
his very substantial book on Melanesia (Rivers,
Culture embraces all the manifestations of social 1914), he discussed at length the impact of culture
habits of a community, the reactions of the contact, especially through migrations, on cultural
individuals as affected by the habits of the groups in changes. In an essay on “The Contact of Peoples,”
which he lives, and the products of human activities Rivers wrote “. . . it becomes a matter of urgent
as determined by these habits. necessity to understand the process of blending [of
(Boas, 1930, p. 79) cultures]” (Rivers, [1913] 1926, p. 299). He always
Boas and his students, including Ruth Benedict stressed the importance of including a psychological
and Margaret Mead, shaped the character of approach, and in an address on “The Ethnological
American anthropology for many years and led to Analysis of Culture” ’ to the British Association for
its being called “Cultural anthropology” as distinct the Advancement of Science, he argued:
from British “Social anthropology,” but that came
Side by side with ethnological analysis, there must
later.
go the attempt to fathom the modes of thought
of different peoples, to understand their ways of
The Problem of “Convergence,” Rivers, regarding and classifying the facts of the universe.
and Bartlett It is only by the combination of ethnological and
The issue of how disparate cultures came to dis- psychological analysis that we shall make any real
play similarities, which were often striking, was advance.
extensively debated during the first two decades of (Rivers, [1911] 1926, p. 132)
the twentieth century. Tylor and other social evo-
lutionists had attributed them to universal human Rivers returned to Cambridge in 1908, and a year
nature; an alternative interpretation, putting the later Frederic Bartlett (1886–1969) became his
major emphasis on transmission through culture student, whom he inspired to pursue research con-
contact, was put forward in Germany. It is neither cerned with the effects of culture contact. In his
necessary nor possible to enter here into the details Fellowship Dissertation, Bartlett (1916) declared
of the debate, except to say that the sharp opposi- his intention of studying the process of convention-
tion between the two sides gave way to a question alization, whereby new elements are incorporated in

38 c ulture an d psycho log y


cultures as a consequence of contact; and he refers elimination of childhood mentality cannot appear.
in this connection to a passage by Rivers on “the There is no discussion, no exchange of points of
blending of cultures.” He stressed that the man- view. . . . There are thus only personalities who do not
ner in which he used the term conventionalization know themselves and a group which is everything.
implies the existence of social intercourse, the pass- In such a situation nothing is created by individuals,
ing of representations between individuals within a and nothing extends beyond the level of childhood
community. thought.
It is in this context that Bartlett carried out his (Piaget, [1928] 1995, p. 207)25
experiments on “repeated” and “serial” reproduc-
All such writings were about what we would
tions, also reported later in his classic volume on
now regard as culture, but in France this term was
Remembering (Bartlett, 1932). In 1923 he published
very seldom used until fairly recently. That was a
his Psychology and Primitive Culture in which he
matter of linguistic usage, but for quite different
sought to analyze the social-psychological processes
reasons some British anthropologists became some-
of culture change resulting from contact and bor-
what disparaging about the notion of culture dur-
rowing. When expounding the principles underly-
ing the interwar years. Radcliffe-Brown dismissed
ing cultural transmission, Bartlett made extensive
it as “a vague abstraction” (Radcliffe-Brown, [1940]
use of anthropological illustrations, largely drawn
1952, p. 190). Yet anthropologists could not really
from North America and Boas in particular. The
do without some kind of psychology, and so they
psychological theory underlying his analysis was
made up their own. Radcliffe-Brown used the con-
that of McDougall (1908). Although it is evident
cept of “sentiments,”, and Malinowski (who did
in hindsight that the work suffered from consider-
use the concept of culture) elaborated a “theory of
able flaws, it constituted the first systematic attempt
needs” whose aim was to provide a basis for analyz-
to interpret anthropological data in psychological
ing human behavior in any culture (cf. Piddington,
terms; he also recommended the method of serial
1957). Generally, they had scant use for the then
reproduction as a promising tool for the experi-
prevailing academic psychology.
mental study of cultural transmission.24 In his later
Matters were very different in America, where for
writings, the theme of culture recurs frequently,
Boas culture had been a key issue, and he had always
but he made little further empirical or theoretical
been keenly interested in psychology; and Boasians
contributions.
dominated the anthropological scene during that
period. Two of his most prominent students were
The Interwar Years: 1929s and 1930s Ruth Benedict (1887–1948) and Margaret Mead
During the 1920s and 1930s, British psycholo-
(1901–1978), both very much concerned with
gists generally displayed hardly any interest in cul-
the relationship between culture and psychology.
ture, and British social anthropologists turned
Benedict’s famous Patterns of Culture ([1934] 1946)
away from psychology. This was because their main
was partly inspired by Gestalt psychology, and the
inspiration had become Durkheim, who focused
emphasis she placed on psychological features is
on “collective representations” and did not believe
clearly seen in the following passage:
that what he understood by “psychology” was rel-
evant for the study of societies. Yet, in fact, he and Within each culture there come into being
his followers deduced a kind of social psychology characteristic purposes not necessarily shared by
from social (we would say cultural) facts. For exam- other types of societies . . . Taken up by a well-
ple, Marcel Mauss, in his classic essay on The Gift, integrated culture, the most ill-assorted acts become
used ethnographic material to deduce psychologi- characteristic of its peculiar goals, often by the most
cal principles involved in social exchanges that he unlikely metamorphoses. The form that these acts
regarded as universals. Similarly, Lucien Lévy-Bruhl take we can understand only by understanding first
(1857–1939) attributed a “pre-logic” to “primitive the emotional and intellectual mainsprings of that
peoples,” yet without describing them as childlike. society.
Following Lévy-Bruhl, the early Piaget went even ([1934] 1946, p. 42; emphasis added)
further when painting a picture of what he took
Mead took courses in psychology before becom-
“primitive society” to be:
ing a student of Boas at Columbia University. The
In a society where generations place all their task Boas set her was to research the way in which
influence on each other, conditions necessary for the the personality reacts to culture and she did that in

ja h oda 39
several cultures in the South Pacific. As the titles of The year of the outbreak of World War II saw
her famous trilogy (shown below) indicate, psycho- the beginning of what came to be known as the cul-
logical aspects of culture were salient for her: ture-and-personality school. Its main exponent was
Abram Kardiner (1939), an unorthodox psycho-
Mead, M (1928). Coming of Age in Samoa;
analyst, who collaborated with several anthropolo-
A Psychological Study of Primitive Youth for Western
gists. This school sought to link subsistence type,
Civilization
child training mode, and belief systems. It was later
Mead, M (1930). Growing Up in New Guinea;
described by Bruner as “a magnificent failure.” Yet
A Comparative Study of Primitive Education
it generated during the post-war years the field of
Mead, M (1935). Sex and Temperament in Three
“psychological anthropology,” which continues to
Primitive Societies
flourish.
All three books were aimed to persuade western Later still, more than half a century after the pio-
readers that culture is more important than biology neering work of Rivers, “cross-cultural” psychology
in shaping personality and behavior. An admittedly emerged, to be followed by “cultural psychology.”
impressionistic scan indicates that Benedict and But that is another story.
Mead were almost the only anthropologists occa-
sionally mentioned in early post-war psychology Concluding Overview and Future
texts. Yet in two interwar handbooks of social psy- Directions
chology (Murchison, 1935; Murphy et al., 1937) The broad overview that has been presented
culture had figured prominently. Several noted here is unavoidably rather sketchy. Nonetheless,
anthropologists contributed to the former, and the it should be sufficient to support the claim made
latter included the following warning: in the introduction that despite varying terminol-
ogy, there shines through an ever-present inter-
. . . . the concept of culture . . . has awakened us to
est in other people’s “customs”—to use the most
an immensely important fact regarding the limits of
common term of the past. Differences held a fas-
social psychology. It must be recognized that nearly
cination, and there was a good deal of speculation
all the experimental work in social psychology . . . has
about their causes, climate being the prime can-
value and is definitely meaningful only in relation to
didate; it was not until the Enlightenment that
the particular culture in which the investigation was
such causes as ecology and modes of subsistence
carried on.
were proposed, in a manner not unlike that still
(Murphy et al., 1937, p. 7)
prevailing.
These wise words were later forgotten, or at least not A related issue sometimes raised was that of
acted upon, and that remains true even today for nature-versus-nurture as the cause of differences.
most of experimental social psychology.26 Yet there Over most of the period, nurture predominated,
was a period when culture was taken seriously,27 with a sharp reversal during the nineteenth century
and it is an intriguing question why that concept when “race” came to the fore. Yet it was after the
subsequently suffered an eclipse in psychology. middle of that century that the terminology began
Farr (1996) suggests that it resulted from the rise to change and culture—the name, not the con-
of behaviorism and that may well be part of the cept—entered the vocabulary. For quite some time
answer: both the handbooks mentioned above were confusion prevailed, even in so acute a mind as that
in varying degrees inspired by Darwinian evolution- of Wundt: no clear distinction was made between
ism rather than behaviorism. Yet that cannot be the culture as a universal and the multitude of cultures
whole answer since Floyd Allport ([1933] 1969), over the globe.
archpriest of behaviorist social psychology, did dis- From earliest times, the notion of custom was
cuss the notion of culture in several passages. He indissolubly linked with psychological aspects. For
argued against cultural determinism and regarded differences in customs entailed differences in beliefs
the culture-versus-nature dichotomy as mislead- and behaviors, and these features were often noted
ing.28 For Allport, culture consisted of habits that, and even emphasized as early as Herodotus more
although learned from the social environment, are than two millennia ago. As some writers on culture
“organically grounded” (p. 508). He did not specify such as Cole (1983) and Shweder (1990) have it,
against whom his arguments were directed, but it culture and mind are really different facets of the
was probably the Boasian anthropologists. same phenomenon.

40 c ulture an d psycho log y


Notes 24. This claim has more recently been renewed by Kashima
1. In modern French/English dictionaries, the first transla- (2000).
tion given for culture is generally still “cultivation.” 25. For a more detailed discussion, see cf. Jahoda (2000).
2. For example, the German title of Freud’s book first pub- 26. For a complaint about the neglect of culture, see cf.
lished in 1930 was Das Unbehagen der Kultur (The uneasiness Jahoda (1988).
of culture); the English translation was “Civilization and its dis- 27. It must be said, however, that during the 1930s the topic
contents.” of “culture” was greatly outweighed by that of “race differences.”
3. For a discussion of current usages in the context of cul- This literature has been surveyed by Richards (1997).
ture and psychology, see cf. Krewer & Jahoda (1993). 28. “It seems almost as though the individual becomes a
4. In anthropology, they are called “ethnopsychologiews.” product of the ‘group’ or of ‘society,’ rather than of his own
5. For some of the material in this section, I am indebted to biological ancestry. Viewing human development in this light,
Chakkarath (2003). certain social scientists have proposed that all this range of mod-
6. Much the same proposal, although more sophisticated, ifications of the original tendencies should be set apart from
was put forward by the Société des Observateurs de l’Homme in these tendencies themselves as a separate category, to which the
late eighteenth century. name ‘culture’ or ‘civilization’ should be applied. Thus arises
7. For a detailed account, see cf. Peters (1962). the notion of culture as something entirely distinct from, and
8. The north–south divide continued to be regarded as a even antithetical to, human nature.” ([Allport [1933] 1969,
key factor, but the values attributed to them varied according to pp. 507–508).
the writers own geographic position. For Europeans, north was
good, for Muslims, it was bad. References
9. All the following quotations, where only page numbers Allport, F.H. ([1933] 1969). Institutional behavior. New York:
are indicated, are derived from Slotkin. Greenwood.
10. The expedition, which included a majority of natural Aristotle (circa 326 BC) Politeia, VII.
scientists, was dogged by ill fortune from the start. Although Aunger, R. Ed. (2000). Darwinizing culture. Oxford: Oxford
it produced some interesting findings, this was at a heavy cost: University Press.
one-third of the personnel (including the leader) died on the Bagehot, W. (1872). Physics and politics. London: King.
voyage. Bartlett, F.C. (1916). Transformations arising from repeated rep-
11. Until the cross-cultural work of Rivers (1901), it was resentation: contribution towards an experimental study of
widely believed that “savages” had more acute senses. the process of conventionalisation. Fellowship Dissertation,
12. Humboldt’s views greatly influenced the Völkerpsychologie St.John’s College, Cambridge.
of Lazarus and Steinthal. Bartlett, F.C. (1923). Psychology and primitive culture. Cambridge:
13. “Cultures from this point of view are individual psychol- Cambridge University Press.
ogy thrown large upon the screen, given gigantic proportions and Bartlett, F.C. (1932). Remembering. A study in experimental and
a long time span.” (Benedict, 1932, p. 24). social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
14. For a detailed analysis, see cf. Kroeber and Kluckhohn Bastian, A. (1868). Beiträge zur vergleichenden Psychologie. Berlin:
(1952). Dümmler.
15. It is a particular kind of comprehension specifically Benedict, R. (1932). Configurations of culture in North America.
related to human behavior. American Anthropologist, 34, 1–27.
16. In his rather indigestible Philosophy of Spirit, Hegel Benedict, R. ([1934] 1946). Patterns of culture. New York:
assumed the existence of spiritual facts that cannot be described Mentor.
as subjective states of individual persons but that have an inde- Berry, J.W. (1976). Human ecology and cognitive style. New York:
pendent, objective existence. Sage.
17. For an account of this method, see cf. Jahoda (1991). Boas, F. (1910). Psychological problems in anthropology.
18. There is no exact equivalent to Wissenschaft in English; American Journal of Psychology, XXI, 371–384.
the word is usually, and misleadingly, translated as “science.” Boas, F. (1911). The mind of primitive man. New York: Macmillan.
19. Because “psychic factors” are also present in animals, Boas, F. (1930). Anthropology. Encyclopaedia of the social sciences,
Paul argued that one has to recognize the category of ani- vol.2. (pp. 73–110). New York: Macmillan.
mal culture and therefore include the study of animal behav- Chakkarath, P. (2003). Kultur und Psychologie. Hamburg: Kovac.
ior among the Kulturwissenschaften. At the time that was Cole, M. (1983). Culture and cognitive development. In
regarded as absurd, but the existence of “animal culture” is P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology, 4th ed.,
now accepted. vol.1. New York: Wiley.
20. Georges Cuvier (1769–1832) was a distinguished French Collingwood, R .G. ([1946] 1961]. The idea of history. London:
naturalist. Oxford University Press.
21. This is not strictly true: In his later years, Tylor became Degerando, J.-M. (1800] 1969). The Observation of Savage
persuaded that race differences in the complexity of the convolu- Peoples, transl. F.T.C. Moore. London: Routledge & Kegan
tions of the brain set limits to the progress of some races. Paul.
22. Habilitation is an examination by thesis that entitles the Dilthey, W. ([1894] 1977). Descriptive Psychology and Historical
candidate to consideration for a chair. Understanding. The Hague: Nijhoff.
23. Some years later, the German anthropologist Richard Diriwächter, R. (2011). Chapter 2, this volume.
Thurnwald (1913) carried out some psychological studies in the Elias, N. (1982). The civilizing process. Oxford: Blackwell.
Solomon Islands. He explicitly referred to cultural factors in cog- Farr, R.M. (1996). The roots of modern social psychology. Oxford:
nition (p. 4). Blackwell.

ja h oda 41
Ferguson, A. ([1767] 1966). An essay on the History of Civil Montesquieu, C. de Secondat ([1748] 1964). Oeuvres Complètes.
Society. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Paris: Editions du Seuil.
Friedman, J.B. (1981). The monstrous races in medieval art and Murchison, C. Ed. (1935). Handbook of social psychology.
thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Worcester, MA: Clark University Press.
Frois, L. ([1585] 1998). Européens & Japonais: Traité sur les con- Murphy, G., Murphy, L.B. & Newcomb, T.M. (1937).
tradictions & différences de moeurs. Paris: Chandeigne. Experimental social psychology. Revised ed. New York: Harper.
Goldenweiser, A.A. (1910). Totemism, an analytical study. Peters, R.S. (1962), Brett’s history of psychology. London: Allen
Journal of American Folklore, 23, 179–293. & Unwin.
Herbart, J.-F. ([1825] 1890). Psychologie als Wissenschaft neu Piaget, J. ([1938]1995). Genetic logic and sociology. In I.Smith,
gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik. Zweiter, (ed.) Sociological studies. (pp. 184–214) London: Routledge.
analytischer Teil [Psychology as a science newly founded on Plato (circa 380 BC) Politeia, II.
experience, metaphysics and mathematics [Second, analyti- Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. ([1940] 1952). Structure and function in
cal part]. (1825/1890), vol.6, pp.1–338. In Collected Works primitive society. London: Cohen & West.
[Joh. Fr. Herbart’s sämtliche Werke] edited by Karl Kehrbach. Richards, G. (1997). Race, racism and psychology. London:
Langensalza: Beyer. Routledge.
Herder, J.G. ([1785] 1969). Herder’s Werke, [Herder’s Works] Rickert, H. (1910). Kulturwissenschaft und Naturwissenschaft.
5 vols. Berlin: Aufbau. [Humanities and sciences]. Tübingen: Mohr.
Herodotus ([c. 440 BC] 2008) The histories. R.B. Strassler (Ed.) Rivers, W.H.R. (1901). Part I. Introduction and vision. In
London: Quercus. A.C. Haddon (Ed.), Reports of the Cambridge Anthropological
Humboldt, W. von ([1836] 1999). On the Diversity of Human Expedition to Torres Straits, vol.2. Cambridge: Cambridge
Language Construction and Its Influence on the Mental University Press.
Development of the Human Species. 2nd rev. ed., Cambridge, Rivers, W.H.R. ([1911] 1926). The ethnological analysis of
MA: Cambridge University Press. culture. In W.H.R. Rivers, (Ed.). Psychology and ethnology,
Jahoda, G. (1988). J’accuse . . . . In M.H. Bond (Ed.), The cross- (pp. 120–140). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner.
cultural challenge to social psychology. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Rivers, W.H.R. ([1913] 1926). The contact of peoples. In
Jahoda,G. (1991) Dessins primitifs, dessins d’enfants et la ques- W.H.R. Rivers (Ed.). Psychology and ethnology, (pp. 299–317).
tion de l’évolution. Gradhiva, 10, 60–70. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.
Jahoda, G. (2000). Piaget and Levy-Bruhl. History and Psychology, Rivers, W.H.R. (1914). The history of Melanesian society. 2 vols.
3, 218–238. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kardiner, A. (1939). The individual and his society. New York: Rowe, J.H. (1965). The Renaissance foundation of anthropol-
Columbia University Press. ogy. American Anthropologist, 67, 1–20.
Kashima, Y. (2000). Maintaining Cultural Stereotypes in the Shweder,R.A. (1990). Cultural psychology – what is it ? In
Serial Reproduction of Narratives, Personality and Social J.W. Stigle, R.A. Shweder & G. Herdt (eds.). Cultural psy-
Psychology Bulletin, 26, 594–604. chology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Klemm, G. (1843–52). Allgmeine Cultur-Geschichte der Slotkin, J.S. (1965). Readings in early anthropology. Chicago:
Menschheit, 10 vols. Leipzig. Aldine.
Krewer, B. & Jahoda, G. (1993). Psychologie et culture: vers une Thurnwald, R. (1913). Ethno-psychologische Studien an
solution du ‘Babel’? International Journal of Psychology, 28, Südseevölkern. [Ethno-psychological studies of South Sea
367–375. peoples] Leipzig: Barth.
Kroeber, A. L. & Kluckhohn, C. (1952). Culture: A critical review of Tylor, E.B. ([1871]1958). Primitive culture. (Part I) New York:
concepts and definitions. Cambridge, MA: Peabody Museum. Harper.
Letts, M. ([1346 ?] 1953). Mandeville’s travels. 2 vols. London: Vico, G. ([1725] 1948).The New Science, tr. T.G. Bergin & M.H.
The Hakluyt Society. Fish. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Lewis, B. (1994). The Muslim discovery of Europe. London: Waitz, T. ([1859] 1863). Introduction to anthropology. London:
Phoenix. Anthropological Society.
Mahdi, M. (1971). Ibn Khaldun’s philosophy of history: A Study in Wheeler, J.T. (1890). An analysis and summary of Herodotus.
the Philosophic Foundation of the Science of Culture. Chicago: London: George Bell.
University of Chicago Press. Wundt, W. (1863). Vorlesungen über die Menschen- und Thierseele.
Malefijt, A. de Waal (1974). Images of man. New York: Knopf. [Lectures on the human and animal mind]. 2 vols. Leipzig:
McDougall, W. (1914). Social psychology. 8th ed. London: Voss.
Methuen. Wundt, W. (1883). Logik, 2 vols. Vol.2: Methodenlehre [Rules of
Mead, M. (1928). Coming of age in Samoa. New York: Morrow. method]. Stuttgart: Enke.
Mead, M. (1930). Growing up in New Guinea. New York: Wundt, W. (1908). Logik, (3rd. ed.) 3 vols; vol.3: Logik der
Morrow. Geisteswissenschaften [Logic of the human sciences], Stuttgart:
Mead, M. (1935). Sex and temperament in three primitive societies. Enke.
New York: Morrow. Wundt, W. (1917). Völkerpsychologie, vol.7: Die Gesellschaft
Montaigne, M. ([1580]1954). Montaigne: Selected essays. A. Tiller [Society]; Leipzig: Kröner.
& A.M. Boase (Eds.) Manchester: Manchester University Wundt, W. (1920). Völkerpsychologie, vol.10: Kultur und
Press. Geschichte [culture and history]; Leipzig: Kröner.

42 c ulture an d psycho log y


CHAPTER

Völkerpsychologie
2
Rainer Diriwächter

Abstract

Völkerpsychologie is, so to speak, the grandfather of cultural psychology who has been left sitting in the
corner, full of nostalgia, while yearning for and dreaming of the old days when ambitions and spirits
surrounding his existence ran high and dedicated disciples tried to use his knowledge to explain complex
mental phenomena. However, it is not the case, as many would like us to believe, that Völkerpsychologie
needs to remain an outdated model that has no connection with the present. Many of its problems stem
from language barriers, lack of cultural-historical understanding, and the absence of any considerable
synthesis that would present it as a unified theoretical model ready to be applied in today’s research.
Völkerpsychologie, like cultural psychology, is still a work in progress, albeit one that has been left to fend
for itself without anyone seriously considering its continuation or integration.
Keywords: Völkerpsychologie, culture, history of psychology, Wundt, folk psychology

“Die Personen vergehen, aber die Völker bestehen”


—Wilhelm Wundt, 1914, p. 4

It is almost hard to believe that less than 100 years focuses on the psychological aspects of ethnicity.
ago, the name Völkerpsychologie was once widely However, in the strictest sense, Völkerpsychologie
used, becoming a part of the vocabulary of the edu- is to be translated into “peoples’ psychology” or
cated German public, psychoanalysts, and ethnogra- folk psychology, and it was to present an alternative
phers alike (see Jahoda, 1993). But since then, much to “person psychology” or “individual psychol-
has changed. Nowadays, Völkerpsychologie has sunk ogy.” It is clear that readers who are familiar with
into the abyss of time, and through this chapter I Völkerpsychologie would be quick to raise objections
hope to spark some readers’ interest in the rich theo- with the aforementioned translation. For example,
retical literature, certainly beneficial to the study of Danziger (1980, p. 303) called folk psychology
culture and psychology, that is gathering dust in the an “absurd mistranslation” of the discipline. To
archives of libraries throughout the world. be sure, folk psychology is not ideal, as it brings
Giving an adequate translation of the term with it a lot of connotations. However, as Webster’s
Völkerpsychologie is virtually impossible. Its broad Dictionary (1987) defines folk as either “a group of
use and distinct “German-ness” makes it especially kindred tribes forming a nation” or “the great pro-
difficult for non-Germans to grasp. At its core, portion of the members of a people that determines
Völkerpsychologie relies heavily on ethnology and the group character and that tends to preserve its

43
characteristic form of civilization and its customs, language community. Through this language com-
arts and crafts, legends, traditions, and superstitions munity, a self-awareness begins to emerge, one in
from generation to generation,” it may well be the which we come to realize that we are not isolated
closest translation to the original word.1 Further, individuals, rather we are I’s who are located in a lan-
the term folk psychology was used as the transla- guage community relative to a YOU.
tion of Völkerpsychologie by E.L Schaub, who trans- Language is one of the primal strengths of
lated (with the cooperation of the author) Wundt’s humans. According to Humboldt, every language
Elemente der Völkerpsychologie. Thus, in an effort to contains its unique form, based on a particular
remain true to the original intentions, the German Weltanschauung. That is, our outlook on the world
term will be applied throughout this chapter. is built in language because those who share a lan-
guage develop a similar subjectivity. By being born
Language, Weltanschauung, and the into a language community, humans are immedi-
Origins of Völkerpsychologie ately exposed to a particular relationship with their
There may be little doubt that Völkerpsychologie world. Because of language, this relationship is to a
finds its roots in German idealism and can be espe- large extent mental (Volkelt, 1922). In other words,
cially said to have been influenced to some degree language can be seen as the creating force as well as
by the philosophies of Hegel,2 Herder, and, nota- the tools of higher mental processes.
bly, Herbart (Jahoda, 1993; see also Danziger, 1983; For Humboldt, language was a lively process,
Eckardt, 1997; Krueger, 1915; Schneider & Müller, one that never rests and thus cannot be truly cap-
1993; Volkelt, 1922; Wundt, 1877). Nonetheless, it is tured by any signs. Hence, for him the true defini-
Wilhelm von Humboldt (1767–1835) who is gener- tion of language could only be a developmental
ally credited to have laid the immediate groundwork (genetische) one (Krueger, 1915, p. 7). Through
for Völkerpsychologie3 (Krueger, 1915; Volkelt, 1922). vocalisms, the internal language form could be
Humboldt, a philologist, philosopher, statesman, and discovered; it develops through the interaction of
one of the founding fathers of the University of Berlin objectivity and fantasy with momentary moods. It
(1810), has also been described as one of the founding is precisely the feeling-factor (Gefühlsfaktor) that
fathers of neo-humanism (Knoll & Siebert, 1967). enhances the subjective occurrences in the listener.
This is largely because of his idea that education Although language receives its final definitions
(Bildung) operates on two levels: first, that the goal within the individual, the continuity of language
of humans is education on the individual level and forms is only guaranteed through life within
second, that education serves the purpose of broader society, and thus the entire objectivity of human
humanity—namely, to reach an ideal. thought rests therein. This would be precisely the
It is important to recognize that Bildung does not point on which the pioneers of Völkerpsychologie
necessarily mean education in the scholarly sense but would touch base.
includes the education we gain from all aspects of life.
According to Humboldt, the education of the indi- The Zeitgeist: A New Psychology Discipline
vidual occurs through historical experience. Here the in the Making
need for synthesis occurs when the broader masses Somewhat comparable to the Greek city-states
pass down ideas to the individual. The connection of antiquity, Germany had developed a national
between individuals occurs through understand- culture in the late eighteenth century but was split
ing, which in turn occurs through language. Hence, into numerous independent states. Since the days
language assumes a central position when we try to of Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803) at the
understand and analyze humans. It may not be sur- latest, German philosophers had come into con-
prising, then, to learn that language was to become tact with the idea that social relations are not only
one of the main themes in Völkerpsychologie. grounded in power, but also involve cultural com-
However, language is not a complete product; munities (i.e., das Volk). The notion of national-
rather it is a process that contains a historical char- ism, albeit certainly a preoccupation of the upper
acter (Steinthal, 1860). This character is “shaped” classes, found increasing (although nowhere near
through the individual, the I, who speaks it. But the overwhelming) support. This was well-reflected in
individual is also limited to that understanding for the political arena prior to 1866, when there was a
which language allows. The geistige (spiritual/mental) general political struggle for and against national-
attachment to language occurs through the respective ism between liberals and conservatives (see Eckardt,

44 völker psyc ho log i e


1997). It is precisely through this political climate in what became known as the “Second Reich” of
that we see Völkerpsychologie emerge. Germany. Although the unification was marked by
In 1860, Moritz Lazarus (1824–1903), a profes- authoritarian aristocracy, the German identifica-
sor of psychology in Bern, and his brother-in-law, tion as separate peoples, das Deutsche Volk, caught
Hajim Steinthal (1823–1899), a philologist from on. German preoccupation was to lay with honor
the University of Berlin (for a biographical review, and dedication to their community4 or folk (Volk),
see Eckardt, 1997), began the task of developing and with that general notion of distinctness among
the new academic discipline of Völkerpsychologie. different “tribes,” the focus of psychology needed
As with any fresh start, getting an ambitious pro- to expand to include the study of that uniqueness
gram underway was no easy undertaking. The term of different Völker, social classes, or ethnic groups.
Völkerpsychologie was, of course, not chosen for the That is, the study of psychology was also to include
purposes of attracting fame or to announce that the products of collective mental processes of peo-
something new had been discovered; rather, it was ples identified as a unified body (e.g., the Germans),
to draw attention to an area that had only recently distinctly separate from others (e.g., the French).
been approached and still needed further develop- Individual psychology was limited to the focus of
ment (Steinthal, 1891, p. 11). the capabilities of one person. However, the person
The central aims of Völkerpsychologie were to was always part of relationships with the masses
investigate the psychological aspects of groups of (e.g., family, community, society, etc.). Hence, the
people living in communities bound by common need arose to expand the investigation to include
language, myths, and customs. In the midst of collective capabilities of peoples living together and
international unrests and conflicts between neigh- how a person “evolved” within that “togetherness.”
boring countries, it seemed that the time was right
for a psychological discipline that would account Völkerpsychologie: The Individual As
for the national character of people to better under- Part of the Volk
stand their ways of thinking. After all, the German- Much debate of early Völkerpsychologie surrounded
oriented states and the young republic of France had the notion of individual versus collective spirit (Geist)
not been the best of neighbors, and their frequent and soul (Seele). The underlying question was whether
disputes had led to much bloodshed. it was possible to study collective mental phenomena.
The trend for a nationalistic-oriented psychology Such a study was indeed seen as possible as society
is nicely captured in a letter that Lazarus wrote to dominates over its individual members. Lazarus and
his friend Paul Heyse on November 29, 1870 (dur- Steinthal (1860) defined the Volksgeist (or collective
ing the Franco-Prussian War): spirit) as “the inner activity, according to content
as well as form, which each individual has in com-
France is a beacon in the midst of chaos. I personally
mon with the Volk; or: that which each individual
do not yet have the courage to dissect this issue with my
has in common in terms of inner activity” (p. 29).
folk-psychological (völkerpsychologisches) scalpel . . . , but
The Volksgeist was to be governed by the same prin-
my thoughts of course are all around that topic, and I
ciples as the individual spirit; however, the collective
can already say today: the big, though futile, displays of
was much more complex and extended (see Jahoda,
strength of the French, which will cost us and them much
1993). In any case, the Volksgeist could be objectively
bloody work, will only serve to make us stronger, and
studied by examining intrapsychic events: thoughts,
them for the future more cautious, hopefully also better,
sentiments, and dispositions that were objectified
and will uphold, foremost, the dignity which seemed to
through books, art, and other products of cognitive
have come to an end with Sedan and the pitiful republic.
processes (Eckardt, 1997; Jahoda, 1993).
(as quoted in Schneider & Müller, 1993, p. 94)
For Lazarus and Steinthal (1860), psychology
It certainly seems that the national feeling was a driv- represented a third science, placed between natural
ing force in Lazarus’s approach to Völkerpsychologie. science and history (p. 16). Psychology differs from
After the Franco-Prussian War of 1870/71, under natural science because it makes the human spirit
the leadership of Wilhelm I and Otto von Bismarck, the object of investigation, something materialists
the German people saw unification come true, as would undoubtedly see as a mere appendix to physi-
Germany was finally united and declared an Empire ology. However, psychology does look for underly-
in the Hall of Mirrors in Versailles on January 18, ing laws that govern psychical processes. Because
1871 (see Noble et al., 1994), thereby reigning humans are ever-changing, their mental capacity

diriwäch ter 45
needs to be seen as being in a constant, never-ending, being parts of the whole, through being a partici-
dynamic state of “becoming.” With the experiences pant and representative of societal values. Only the
we gain, we grow, and as a result our Volk becomes collective idea or spirit of the Volk brings meaning
different over time. Therefore, psychology needs to to the individual. After all, ideas do not emerge
account for the dynamics of society, the historical from nowhere; rather, they transform from previous
forces, and the complex web of social structures in ideas that have been passed down through commu-
which individuals find themselves. nal efforts. Thus, our “individuality” is integrated in
Both Lazarus and Steinthal repeatedly warned our community.
their readers of the incomplete picture given when In fact, identification with the Gemeinschaft is
examining humans only from an individualistic what gives Volk its meaning. We, as a Volk, share
perspective, without regard to their place within similar dangers, faith, happiness, and identities.
human society (e.g., Lazarus, 1862, 1865; Lazarus According to Lazarus and Steinthal (1860, p. 35),
& Steinthal, 1860; Steinthal, 1887). They proposed membership in a race is based on objective crite-
that one should study the spirit of people as part of ria (e.g., skin color, but also bone structure, etc.);
a community or society. Similarly to Humboldt and however, membership in a Volk is based on inher-
Herbart, Lazarus and Steinthal reasoned that no man ently subjective standards. We identify and choose
has become what he is because of himself; rather, to be a member of a Volk, and the Volk recognizes
man has become what he is through being part of us as a part of them. This notion of belonging is a
a larger community. It was Lazarus and Steinthal’s bidirectional, dynamic process (Wechselseitigkeit). In
(1860) belief that humans cannot be raised in soli- this sense, Völkerpsychologie positioned itself along-
tude, and that those few who have been raised in the side individualistic psychology so that it became its
forest, absent from civilization and other compan- necessary extension. The myriad of questions posed
ions, resembled humans merely through their physi- by psychology can only be answered by the com-
cal similarities (p. 3). Humans are social beings, and bined efforts of both Völkerpsychologie and individ-
to understand them, we must examine them from a ual psychology.
Volk perspective; we must understand the influences
society has on them and how humans develop within Lazarus and Steinthal’s Program for
the social structures and through the social tools (e.g., Völkerpsychologie
language) that have been passed down from one gen- For Steinthal (1887, p. 248), the myriad of
eration to the next. Hence, of primary importance questions psychology poses could be addressed by
for Völkerpsychologie was determining the relationship a research program sorted into the following three
between the whole and the individual (p. 31). categories:
Moreover, Lazarus and Steinthal (1860, p. 5)
warned their readers not to separate society and the I. General Psychology: The study
individual so that one looks at the individual, then of mechanisms of thoughts/imagination
society, and then puts one into the context of the (Vorstellungen), feelings (Gefühle), and drives
other. Instead of retroactively attributing certain social (Triebe).
influences to the individual, the object of investigation II. Völkerpsychologie: The study of the
was to be the dynamic processes of the two that inter- collective “mental” (geistige) life. [This implies the
mingle in complex ways. Gesellschaft (society) cannot coexistence of members of society living together.
be broken down into smaller circles, such as families, Völkerpsychologie can be divided into] (a) synthetic
without realizing that they are constantly connected Völkerpsychologie [see Lazarus, 1865], which deals
to a Gemeinschaft (community). Psychology would with the general requirements of collective mental
always be one-sided if it were merely to examine the life, and (b) the use of these requirements within
person without context. Or as Lazarus (1862) put it: ethnology, pre-history, and history. It needs to be
added that whereas (a) results in a self-standing
We cannot emphasize the following enough, society
theoretical construct, (b) only exists implicitly.
does not consist of individuals as such, rather it is
III. Individual Psychology [the reader may
within and from society that individuals exist.
want to note that Steinthal lists this at the end):
(p. 419)
The study of the individual, which can only be
For Lazarus, the individual receives his/her prop- examined within the historical context of a given
erties through being linked within society, through culture. Individual psychology, in a synthetic form,

46 völker psyc ho log i e


is incorporated within the previous two categories, then and now, inherently controversial and difficult
but its application appears in biographies. to define.
The task for Völkerpsychologie was to objectify
collective mental life to be able to study it. That is, The Spirit of Early Völkerpsychologie
wherever people are living together, the result of and the Journals that Made it Famous
their “togetherness” is that subjective processes man- Lazarus and Steinthal’s central aim was to achieve
ifest in objective content, which in turn becomes a synthesis of the humanities and social sciences in
the norm and organ of the former. Lazarus (1865, regards to the study of the Volksgeist—to study the
p. 41) takes language to exemplify this idea. When collective mind through the combined forces and
several individuals operate under similar motives the strengths that each academic discipline could
and conditions, thereby sharing a common under- bring to the table. This spirit is nicely captured
standing, the subjective activity of talking results in through Lazarus and Steinthal’s (1860, p. 1) open-
an objective language. This language then represents ing statement in the first volume of Zeitschrift für
objective content for the subsequent speech acts of Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft (Journal of
the individuals. It provides laws for thoughts and Völkerpsychologie and Speech Science), where they
further represents the organ that is open for further invited all researchers to participate:
development through ensuing speech acts by all We are not only asking those men who are working in
members of society. What has been born through the field of psychology, rather we are asking anyone who
the actions of individuals in relation to others (or is investigating the historical appearances of language,
the self ) becomes a mental content that rises beyond religion, art, literature, science (Wissenschaft), customs,
the individual. It becomes generality vis-à-vis the law, the societal-, home-, and state- constitutions; in
actions of the individual. In short, we are molded short, we are asking everyone who is researching the
by the “organ,” which in turn is molded by us. historical life of ‘civilizations/cultures’ (Völker) in any
For Lazarus and Steinthal (1860), the objecti- of its manifold aspects, so that the discovered facts out
fication of collective mental life—that is, the core of the most inner workings of the ‘mind’ (Geist) can be
program of Völkerpsychologie—was broad and could explained, hence, revealing their psychological causes.
be found in language, myths, religion, customs, art,
science, law, culture, and, most notably, history. It What ensued over the next 30 years of the
was especially the historical aspect that was impor- journal’s existence was an accumulation of 200
tant for the emerging discipline of Völkerpsychologie original works that, perhaps not surprisingly, had
because it attempted to understand the history of little to do with its contemporary psychology that
humanity and its peoples (Völker) through which was building up along the lines of natural sci-
psychical laws were revealed (Lazarus, 1865, p. 2). ences. However, Eckardt’s (1997, p. 72) claim that
We needed to understand the historical forces that under the numerous reviews published in the first
underlie collective life; hence, analysis of history 20 volumes of Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
combined with the synthesis of Völkerpsychologie Sprachwissenschaft, not a single one addressed the
would result in the discovery of the very nature pioneering breakthroughs of Fechner, Helmholtz,
of collective mental life (Volksgeist). Only through Wundt, Ebbinghaus, and other experimen-
such a program would we be able to understand tal psychologists may be somewhat misleading.5
such constructs as individual personality because Nonetheless, the great majority of the journal’s
only in and through the community does the per- articles (67 of 200) focused on issues surrounding
son become a “mental/spirited” being (geistiges linguistics (Sprachwissenschaft), followed by religion
Wesen). As Steinthal (1891) would later say, “The and mythology (26 articles).
spirit (Geist), before it becomes individual and per- Many of the controversies surrounding early
sonal, is in reality a collective spirit, a spirit of the Völkerpsychologie (see Eckardt, 1997; Jahoda, 1993)
entirety (Gesamtheit), an objective spirit, and it is are comparable to what Valsiner describes as “ideo-
that which forms the object of Völkerpsychologie” (p. logical taboos” (2001) or “theories as identity mark-
12). It should be made clear that none of the advo- ers” (2004). Indeed, the topic of culture has again
cates of Völkerpsychologie saw the spirit (Geist) as a become very fashionable, and today’s institutional
mystical substance; rather, it should be understood taboos may well be much more rigid in regard to
similarly to how we interpret the concept of mind. methodology than in the heydays of Völkerpsychologie
It goes without saying that such concepts remain, when the spirit of the great pioneers ran high while

diriwäch ter 47
they embarked on their quest to discover the col- of members of a Volk were to be made the object of
lective manifestations of the inner workings of investigation; in terms of how morals and customs
the human mind. This is not to say that German left their mark. In this regard, birth, the selection of
academia was not riddled by politics (which has names (baptism), childhood, education, love, mar-
been discussed in detail by Ash, 1995); rather, it riage, aging, and dying would all represent points of
is to point out that at the very least not much has interest. Weinhold believed that these morals and
changed in regard to trying to enforce proper eti- customs had developed over a long period of time
quette for psychology research methodology along and could be traceable through people’s folklore.
with the political maneuvers that would help estab- A related section would be the material that provides
lish ideological supremacy for one’s own approach the basis for physical life. To this area belong the
at the expense of others. different methods and conditions through which
Volume 206 of Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie we take our nutrition, including living conditions,
und Sprachwissenschaft brought the first epoch to clothing, and technical material (see also Weinhold,
a close. The grand synthesis had not yet occurred, 1891).
and Völkerpsychologie was far from being guided by a The second area of Volkskunde, the mental/spiri-
unified systemic approach, free of controversy (thus, tual one, would first need to address religious con-
no different than the general state of psychology ceptions and customs. To this area belonged all belief
today). The predominantly philological approach systems, and especially the beliefs in those Gestalts
of the journal had not helped much to shed light that are anchored in the fantasy and feelings of a
on the Volksgeist, and a fresh start was needed. This Volk, developed over time, that have been brought
new start was announced on the first five pages of forward to consciousness from the days when
Volume 20, when Weinhold (1890) announced a demonic forces ruled over man and earth. Certainly
new scientific (Wissenschaft) discipline—namely, fairy tales and sagas would prove to be a rich source
that of Volkskunde. The literal translation of of those “dark” ages but also poetry (especially those
Volkskunde is folklore; however, in his opening as poesies that could no longer be traced to a particular
well as closing statements, Weinhold was careful to person and that have not been taken over by other
distinguish between those folklorists who merely Völker), songs (especially children’s songs), melodies,
collected folk-traditions as if it were a fashionable dances, legends, riddles, and, from all this, most
sport7 and those who took the matter seriously— importantly language would provide an immense
that is, from a scientific (wissenschaftlichen) perspec- treasure chest for gaining access to the historical
tive. To the latter belonged those people who were mental roots of a Volk. In this respect it needs to be
familiar with “history and linguistics, with anthro- mentioned that language was important from the
pology and psychology, with the history of juris- psychical perspective—that is, not in terms of gram-
prudence, with history of national economics, of mar (which was to be left to linguists) but rather in
natural history, literature, and art” (pp. 1–2). When terms of how sentences, sounds, and words found
done correctly, Volkskunde was to become a national their origins (Weinhold, 1891, p. 7). Of particular
and historical science with the aim of examining a interest would be the study of words8 and how their
Volk in all its life expressions (Lebensäusserungen). meanings emerged over time—how certain semi-
First, the new discipline would have to research a otic mediations were conveyed through statues, and
particular Volk, and only then could one make com- later through live talk (i.e., speeches).
parisons and conclusions, which should eventually Similarly to Lazarus and Steinthal’s opening
merge with anthropology. After all, anthropology remarks in the Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
and Volkskunde had the same scientific end-goals. Sprachwissenschaft back in 1860, we again find a
Weinhold (pp. 2–4) went on to say that body remarkable enthusiastic spirit in Weinhold’s (1891)
and mind, or material and spirit, would present call for participation in this transformed program
the two main halves of the new field. The first half when he writes, “[W]e wish that the cultural research-
would explore the physical appearances of a Volk. It ers in the Netherlands, in the Scandinavian lands,
would need to penetrate the historical conditions of in England and America will join us in our broth-
a Volk, the gradual development, its relationships, erly ranks” (p. 10). With the new aims in mind, the
and its geographical distributions. In short, the ter- Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft
rain upon which the Volk lived needed to be histori- got transformed into the Zeitschrift des Vereins für
cally explored. The next step required that the lives Volkskunde (Journal of the Volkskunde Association),

48 völker psyc ho log i e


with Weinhold replacing the aging Steinthal as edi- putting its elements and developmental stages in
tor in 1891. It is an often overlooked fact that the an explicatory relationship, so too is there a need
former journal did not end after 20 volumes per se; to make as the object of psychological investigation
rather, it merely took on a new title to capture its the analogous genetical and causal investigations of
new approach but retained the earlier title as a sub- those actualities which pertain to the products of
heading for several more years.9 higher developmental relationships of human society,
The 26 volumes of Zeitschrift des Vereins für namely the folk-communities (Völkergemeinschaft).
Volkskunde are filled with in-depth analysis of top- (Wundt, 1888, p. 2)
ics from around the world, such as fairy tales (e.g.,
by the Grimm brothers), Volk riddles (e.g., “The The simple, elementary mental processes
Riddle of the Fish in the Water” by Robert Petsch), could be studied via internal perception (innere
Volk customs (e.g., “The Use of the Death-Crown in Wahrnehmung). This should not be mistaken for
Germany” by Otto Lauffer), rhymes, songs, sagas, introspection, however. In fact, Wundt was opposed
poetry, mysticism, biographies, religious practices to the form of introspection (Selbstbeobachtung)
(e.g., “The Journey of the Soul into the Afterlife” that J.S. Mill or Edward Titchener would much
by Julius von Negelein), gender studies (e.g., “The later advocate (Danziger, 1980). For Wundt, as for
Woman in Islam” by Martin Hartmann) . . . in many other psychologists of those days, introspec-
short, the diversity in contents by far surpass those tion was closer to retrospection, or the observation
volumes edited by Lazarus and Steinthal from 1860 of an unreliable memory image. Instead, Wundt
to 1890. The choice to refocus the attention of the proposed that the processes we want to observe
discipline away from linguistics and instead toward can be produced via experimental presentation of
the study from the Volk about the Volk in a man- respective stimuli (Diriwächter, 2009). These exper-
ner that includes folklore, but is not itself folklore, imental situations, however, were limited in their
provided a means to broaden the perspective from scope and did not allow for the examination of the
which to investigate collective mental processes. higher processes of thought. Experimental internal
To alleviate the confusion about the differences perception was usually limited to examine simple
between Völkerpsychologie and scientific Volkskunde, relationships as they occurred but not higher mental
Steinthal (1891, p. 17) captured the fundamental processes.
difference by emphasizing that it is not that each To understand higher psychological processes,
of them takes a different slice from mental occur- only historical comparisons, the observation of our
rences; rather it’s in the way the two disciplines look mind’s creations (Beobachtung der Geisteserzeugnisse),
at them. If it is done in a more synthetic way, then could be looked at. It was these products that
it is called Völkerpsychologie; if it is done more ana- Wundt saw as central to Völkerpsychologie. The
lytically, then we count it as Volkskunde, or history. simple psychological experiences were to be studied
In any case, Volkskunde would always be a psycho- experimentally, whereas the products of the higher
logical discipline, as the spirit (Geist) of any person, processes (which could be seen as having properties
no matter how distinguished he/she is, always rests of “objects of nature”) preceded the folk-psycholog-
within the Volk. However, despite its ambitions, ical analysis. With Wundt, Völkerpsychologie was to
no systematic synthesis of materials can be found fill the voids of the limited applicable experimental
within the editions of Zeitschrift des Vereins für analyses by examining under a historical-genetic
Volkskunde. It seems that this was left to be done by approach complex mental functions, thereby deter-
a later generation of researchers. mining both the social dimensions of the mind and
the psychic processes.
Wilhelm Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie However, for Wundt (1888), the broad con-
Wilhelm Wundt10 (e.g., 1888, 1911, 1917) had ception of what academic fields should belong to
been an avid reader of Lazarus and Steinthal’s publi- Völkerpsychologie made it vulnerable to attacks.
cations on Völkerpsychologie, and he agreed that the Wundt was especially opposed to integrating his-
discipline was a necessary extension of the individu- tory per se (a core component of Völkerpsychologie for
alistic approach. Lazarus and Steinthal) on the grounds that (1) his-
tory is already integrated in the subdisciplines (e.g.,
Just like it’s the objective of psychology to describe language, myth, art, etc.) of Völkerpsychologie, and
the actuality of individual consciousness, thereby (2) there is a great risk of making causal inference

diriwäch ter 49
on historical grounds without accounting for natu- humanity. Examining the different levels of mental
ral and cultural factors (Wundt, 1888, pp. 3–7). In development in which humans continuously find
other words, there is the risk of psychologizing his- themselves is the way of true psychogenesis (Wundt,
tory, something that was certainly not the objective 1912, p. 4).
of Völkerpsychologie. Instead, Wundt proposed that In this sense, the continuous progression from
Völkerpsychologie should be divided into the fol- one level to the next, including the in-between
lowing main areas: language, myth, customs, and stages that connect the stages to more complex,
morals. higher cultures, makes Völkerpsychologie in its true
What these areas have in common is that they nature a developmental discipline. Each stage has its
originate in communal life. They are further related own unique characteristics that mark the achieve-
because they have an historical context. The roots ments of the group under examination. For exam-
of this assumption can be found already in the ple, whereas primitive man is said to be closest to
works of Johann Georg Hamann (1730–1788) and nature, comparable to wild animals, the man of the
Johann Gottfried von Herder (1744–1803), who totemic era is already distinguished by a realization
tried to supplement Immanuel Kant’s philosophy of of the possession of a soul. In fact, the totem itself
pure reason with a philosophy of language, culture, is the manifestation of a soul, either the soul of an
and history (Nerlich & Clarke, 1998, p. 181). Aside ancestor or the soul of a protective being, often
from language, it was especially historical develop- in the shape of an animal. In this regard, Wundt
ment (not to be confused with history as a disci- (1912, pp. 114–115) carefully noted that the dif-
pline) that was central to Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie ference between primitive and totem is not neces-
in that it gave direct insight into the products of sarily indicative of a lesser and greater development,
creative synthesis of many individuals. as humans in both stages are best adapted for their
level of development.
Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie as a Each stage is marked by distinctive characteristics,
Social-Developmental Perspective directly relating to the products of higher level men-
For Wundt (1888, 1911, 1912, 1917), tal processing. More specifically, the products relate
Völkerpsychologie was, in essence, a social-develop- to the elements of our psyche, not in an atomistic
mental discipline: social because it predominantly sense, but rather in an elementaristic sense as per-
moves within societal dimensions; and develop- taining to the units of processes. These elementaristic
mental because it also needs to examine the differ- processes, however, make sense only when looked at
ent steps of mental development in humans (true in relation to the whole. Thus, taking context into
psychogenesis), from underdeveloped to higher account also becomes an absolute necessity.
cultures (it goes without saying that the suprem- Nonetheless, Wundt’s general claim that he
acy of one culture over another is in the eye of the was investigating the historicity of the psyche
beholder). was somewhat problematic. In his Elemente der
Examining the products of higher mental pro- Völkerpsychologie, it was not always clear whether
cesses brings with it a myriad of methodological he was indeed adhering to that claim. That is, what
problems, most notably that products of mental pro- is investigated is not the historicity of the psyche
cesses are subject to interpretations. It is important in and of itself but the development of the men-
to note that this applies not only to Völkerpsychologie tal objectifications of psychical activity during the
but also to any division of psychology. However, it is course of history. As Eckardt (1997) points out:
especially the broad perspective of Völkerpsychologie
Although the reconstruction of cultural development
that has raised the eyebrows of the critical inves-
implies an aspect of historicity in the psyche, it still
tigator. For example, unlike his predecessors (i.e.,
has to be distinguished if the historical changes of the
Lazarus and Steinthal), Wundt (1912) attempted a
psyche or the psychological parameters of historical
form of völkerpsychologische synthesis in his Elemente
development are the objects of investigation. In
der Völkerpsychologie, where he traced the roots of
other words, the historicity of the psyche is not to be
modern man by emphasizing a seemingly univer-
mistaken for psychologizing the historical.
sal primitive man (Urmensch). The connection can
(p. 104)
be traced through various developmental stages:
(1) primitive man, (2) the totemic era, (3) the ages The problem of psychologizing history may well
of heroes and gods, and (4) the development of be rooted in Wundt’s determination to separate

50 völker psyc ho log i e


psychology into a lower and higher discipline—an to show the complex state of affairs (Tatbestände)
obstacle that Wundt’s successors would later over- from these elements alone (Sander, 1922, p. 57).
come (see Diriwächter & Valsiner, 2008). To find It may be helpful to use one of Wundt’s (1894,
general laws about the fundamental psychical p. 113) own examples on how this worked. When
functions based on the objectification of complex looking at our sensations, every conscious percep-
psychic processes seemed to be a methodological tion (Wahrnehmung) can be divided (zerlegt) into
impossibility. The main problem was the jump from elementary sensations (the reader may want to note
one level to the other (i.e., from higher to lower). the deductive approach). However, our experience
That is, Wundt was forced to leap constantly from is never just the sum of these sensations (in the
the products of interaction to intra-individual pro- additive sense). Instead, through the connections
cesses, whereby the crucial mediating process never of these sensations something new is created, with
really went beyond general theoretical postulates unique characteristics that were not contained in
(Danziger, 1983). the sensations alone. Therefore, although we can
abstract elements from a phenomenon, attempting
Creative Synthesis: From Elementary to put these elements together again will not result
Processes to Wholeness in the original phenomenon. For example, through
Under the principle of creative synthesis I understand numerous light-shades/impressions (Lichteindrücke)
the fact that psychical elements, through their causally we create spatial forms (räumliche Gestalt). No mat-
related bi-directional processes (Wechselwirkungen) as ter how nativistic our philosophical orientation is,
well as the resulting consequences thereof, create connec- this conscious perception is something creative as
tions which may be psychologically explained through opposed to the sum of all the light-shades/impres-
their components, but at the same time those connections sions, which is the substratum (Substrat) of the per-
contain new characteristics which are not contained in ceptive act. Wundt saw this principle as valid for
the elements. all psychical relationships; it guides mental develop-
—Wundt, 1894, p. 112 ment from the first to the last step.

Wundt felt that creative synthesis was the nec- Transformation in Creative Synthesis:
essary link between the lower mental processes Elevation to the Cultural Level?
(i.e., sensory perceptions) and the higher processes Volkelt (1922, p. 88) points out that for Wundt,
that give our life meaning. The higher ones were synthesis had a double meaning. First, synthesis is
the foundation of Völkerpsychologie. However, it the inverse of psychological analysis—that is, it is
needed to be understood that Völkerpsychologie was a task in which psychologists take the abstracted
not really a self-standing discipline; rather, it was products of their analysis and place them together
intimately connected to the lower processes—that again. It must be noted that the object of synthesis
is, those connected to physiology (Wundt, 1917), (the totality) is the starting point of analysis, and
albeit this connection was never truly shown. abstracted components need to be reintegrated
Sensations, according to Wundt, are the prod- into the original totality. In other words, synthesis
uct of isolated abstractions. They become the end is the inversibility of psychological analysis, a task
result of psychological analysis when components of in which psychologists are capable of reproducing
a totality can no longer be reduced—that is, they the abstract elements in a synthesized whole. This is
are the elements that precede consciousness/aware- where Wundt’s primary concern about grasping the
ness. Nevertheless, although such elementary pro- person in his/her entirety becomes clear.
cesses can be temporarily examined in isolation, it The second meaning of synthesis, according to
needs to be reiterated that they too are constantly Wundt, is that it is a real genetic process of meld-
connected with other components that lead up to ing originally unrelated elements. As mentioned
the wholeness of experiences. Although it may well above, when we are looking at an object, we may
be possible to further abstractly differentiate aspects say that it consists of certain elements (i.e., the
of the elements (sensations), it comes at a cost: the light-shades/impressions reflected on our retina).
destruction of the experiential totality. A psychol- However, we do not perceive this object in terms
ogy that takes these elements as the starting point of its elements; rather, it is the object in its total-
of analysis, from which they build up to create the ity on which we reflect. The genetic process of
immediate experience, will always find it impossible melding unrelated elements goes unnoticed, and

diriwäch ter 51
our psychological processes thus begin at the level The Case of Synthesis Transformation,
of synthesis. Nevertheless, although unnoticed, Thoughts, and Language: An Example
the finalized synthesis has undergone a genetic That Wundt unknowingly anticipated and
process. stood at the threshold of Ganzheitspsychologie (see
The finalized synthesis is precisely the point that Diriwächter, 2009) becomes especially evident in
some of Wundt’s closest students (e.g., Krueger, his dealings with the higher totalities within a self-
1915, 1922; Sander, 1922; Volkelt, 1922) picked contained discipline: Völkerpsychologie. Of these
up on when they transformed the Leipzig School higher totalities, language was given particular
into one that took Ganzheitspsychologie (or holis- attention to be able to trace mental development (or
tic psychology) as its guiding principle (see synthesis transformation), and Wundt devoted two
Diriwächter, 2008 for a discussion on the doctrine volumes of his Völkerpsychologie (volumes I & II) for
and main tenets of Ganzheitspsychologie). For this task. For example, Wundt (1912, pp. 436–458)
them, Wundt’s notion of creative synthesis was not divided language into two domains:
a true synthesis but rather only another form of
1. Outer phenomena: this domain consisted of
aggregation based on the researcher’s manipulations
a person’s actual produced or perceived utterances.
of elements. Hence, it did not tell us much about
The outer phenomena can be described as the
the true experience of the psyche’s totality. Instead,
organized system of sounds of language. However,
there is a necessity to incorporate qualitative ele-
this aspect is just the expression of much deeper
ments that circumscribe the psyche in its entirety
cognitive processes:
by leaving the realm of the synthesized aggregates
2. Inner phenomena: this domain entailed
to the sphere of holistic measurement. Any attempt
the cognitive processes that underlie the outer
to incorporate the products of elementary processes
phenomena. These processes organize the
into a totality (Ganzheit) requires the person to
person’s thoughts. They allow for analysis of the
leave the method of summation of properties and
phenomena encountered and to put mental images
acquire the process of qualitative description of
into words that are then presented in the form of
the experienced phenomenon from the perspective
organized utterances. Or, in the case of a listener,
of the totality. When all is said and done, we are
to comprehend a speaker’s utterances by extracting
interested in explaining the entirety of experience
meaning from the perceived sound units (see
and not merely its isolated products. In that sense,
below). In short: The cognitive processes constitute
analysis of the psyche should be a top-down process
the inner mental domain of speech.
and not vice versa.
If we give up the genetic elemental synthesis Sentence production, according to Wundt (1912,
(the melding of unrelated elements) and replace pp. 436–458), begins with a Gesamtvorstellung (a
it with the genetic totality (Ganzheits) transfor- unified idea that entails the whole mental config-
mation, then the creative character of develop- uration) that one wishes to express. The analytic
ment is no longer hindered: each higher totality function of apperception prepares us to express our
is in relationship to the totalities out of which it Gesamtvorstellung by analyzing it into components
emerged—a creative novelty. The person’s devel- and structure that retains the relationship between
opment does not progress from scattered elements the components and the whole. Let’s say that I mar-
to a synthesized whole; rather, it progresses from vel at how green the grass is today and wish to share
one totality/whole to another (Volkelt, 1962, this perception. What I first need to do is to dis-
p. 27). For Wundt’s successors at Leipzig, creative sect this unified idea (the grass is green) into com-
synthesis did not mean that scattered elements ponent parts, which at the most basic level consist
connected to form a new whole but, rather, that of a subject (grass) and predicate (green). Thus, the
an old synthesis was restructured. Synthesis does basic structural division consists of two fundamen-
not replace the aggregate structure; rather, a dif- tal ideas that can be represented through a simple
ferent synthesis replaces previous ones. Elements tree diagram (see Figure 2.1 below).
were not of much use because in isolation they These basic ideas receive their corresponding
had no meaning, and thus for Wundt’s students symbols (i.e., words) with the addition of function
the notion of cumulating elementary processes words such as “the” and “is,” which are required
needed to be dropped and replaced with the prin- in a particular language for full sentence creation.
ciple of psychical totality. The result is that through an analytic process, I was

52 völker psyc ho log i e


able to describe the transformation of an inexpress- Wundt would not have phrased it so, one could say
ible, organized whole (the Gesamtvorstellung) into that these labels rest on the foundation of creative
an expressible sequential structure of symbols (the synthesis transformations.
words) that manifested themselves by means of a That such ideas are not far removed from a
sentence (the media of language), whereby in the discipline called cultural psychology should not
present case above I have shared verbally two fun- be surprising. In his tenth (and final) volume of
damental ideas (grass and green). Naturally, the Völkerpsychologie, titled Kultur und Geschichte (cul-
more complex our Gesamtvorstellung is, the more ture and history), Wundt (1920), to the best of my
expanded our analysis must become, which in turn knowledge, brings Völkerpsychologie for the first time
results in more complex tree diagrams. In each case, close to cultural psychology:
we are examining the results of a creative synthesis—
As these three labels [language, myth, customs] only
the meanings that have become united as a
describe three main directions, according to which
Gesamtvorstellung and are now deconstructed via
human “mental” life (Seelenleben) differs from all
the tools (e.g., words) that our system of language
organic beings, and while each of these directions
has provided.
encompasses various appearances, we can say that
In the case of comprehending a person’s
these factors and their development in relation
Gesamtvorstellung, the above process now needs
to humans are joined under the general term of
to be reversed. That is, a listener (the receiver of
culture, so that in this regard Völkerpsychologie and
a communicative event of meaning exchange) is
the psychology of culture (Psychologie der Kultur) are
confronted with a transmission of sequential com-
equivalent terms/concepts (Begriffe).
ponents (such as “green” or “grass”) that now need
(p. 57)
to be synthesized into a whole (a creative act). In
principle, this proceeds via a reversed tree diagram However, as Jahoda (1993) emphasizes, culture
(see Fig. 2.1 below) by which particular components (in the German sense of Kultur) did not always have
(e.g., words and grammar) are linked and melded the same meaning for Wundt. According to Jahoda,
(one after the other) as they arrive in the listener’s culture was sometimes “the expression of the higher
mind. The words and grammatical structure of the forms of human intellect and creativity; it meant art
transmitted sentence are merely the tools through science, knowledge and high-level skills, sophistica-
which the listener can try to reconstruct the speak- tion and savoir-faire” (p. 185). At other times, the
er’s Gesamtvorstellung. Beyond that, the words label culture was more or less used synonymously
(the parts) are of no particular relevance. Thus, as with the term civilization or nationality (the later
Wundt pointed out, we usually retain the meaning especially after World War I). Hence, a clear defini-
(inner phenomena) long after we have forgotten tion of culture was not always apparent in Wundt’s
the specific words (outer phenomena) that the per- writings (a problem that also occurs in present-day
son spoke to convey that meaning. studies on culture and psychology).
Nonetheless, what present-day readers of
Völkerpsychologie and Culture Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie can benefit from is the
The investigation of language (as well as myth and wide breath of scope with which he approached
customs) comprised the core of Völkerpsychologie, as the subject. Although many things he wrote are
these were seen as universal phenomena across all arguably outdated and in some cases flawed,11 he
human civilizations and thus made humans dis- nevertheless demonstrates a remarkable talent for
tinguishable from other organic beings. Although inquisition, curiosity, and, above all, skills with
which to relate and integrate information that was
Gesamtvorstellung previously left nearly exclusively to the domain of
anthropology or ethnology, thereby broadening
the scope of psychology beyond the laboratory
setting.
However, taking the notion of creative synthesis
Subject Predicate transformation as the basis to approach the disci-
[grass] [green]
pline of Völkerpsychologie, one could arguably make
Figure 2.1 Tree diagram depicting the dissection of a unified the discipline more focused and proceed to study
idea into its most basic components. culture as Wundt’s successor, Felix Krueger (1953,

diriwäch ter 53
pp. 321–323), suggested by applying the following times of stress—and rejects outsiders. Thus, despite
principles: the holistic emphasis on heterogeneity, it is best to
start such studies on the völkerpsychologische level in
1. The highest level of totality (e.g., culture)
peoples who exhibit a great degree of unique char-
weighs most on its sub-totalities (e.g., the
acteristics that are not found in other communities
individual).
(similarly to the aims of Volkskunde).
2. Just like life in general, communal
Through the fusion of Völkerpsychologie with new
(Gemeinschaft) and cultural life is hierarchically
ideas, the horizon may open to allow for investi-
organized.
gations that were previously not methodologically
3. The emphasis is on experience, most
possible on the level of Völkerpsychologie alone.
notably the centrality of feeling and the structural
The criticism of Eckardt (1997) that Wundt’s
orientation, as well as the complexity of whole,
proclaimed unified historical-genetic approach to
which is dynamic and all-encompassing.
investigating psychological phenomena was more
These principles have finally been addressed in a “psychologizing” of history than a historizing of
more recent cultural-psychological publications the psyche would have to be re-examined in light
(e.g., Valsiner, 2000; Valsiner & van der Veer, of the experiential factors that could be deduced
2000). Communal life has internal roots and bor- from a new Völkerpsychologie that is grounded not in
ders that embed it within its environment. In this the past but in the present. This would be possible
regard, the focus shifts from the products of peoples because we are now aware of other approaches that
(as in Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie) to their experiences are grounded in the feelings and structures that are
as a complex phenomenological whole. For Krueger experienced in the totality of a phenomenon as it
(1953), social life was grounded in tension among the occurs.
group, its environment, and the individual will. In John Greenwood (1999) once added to the criti-
fact, this tension (in the form of opposites) increases cism of Wundt by stating that although Wundt did
as a Volk progresses and develops. Reaching higher recognize the possibility and potential of forms of
levels of totality (e.g., from primitive to civilized social and/or cultural psychology (the investigation
cultures) is tied to pain and must be gained by some of psychological processes that are grounded in cul-
sort of force (e.g., hard labor or battle). And natu- tures or social groups) distinct from individual psy-
rally, true to the doctrine of any Völkerpsychologie, it chology (the investigation of psychological processes
is futile to study individuals independently from a that operate independently of cultures and social
group; rather, the group membership is the basis for groups), his own work lacked concrete details. That
the individual. Collective experiences are embedded is, although he felt that there was a need for bring-
not in the individual but in the totality of the group, ing individual psychology and Völkerpsychologie into
of which the individual is but a mere subtotality. organic relation theoretically as methodological
procedures, he did not recognize that a similar need
Future Directions: The Place for existed with regard to the concrete facts and pro-
Völkerpsychologie in Today’s Cultural cesses with which these psychologies were supposed
Psychology? to deal. This criticism, of course, would also need
Although rare, attempts have been made to con- to re-examine the new form of Völkerpsychologie
duct völkerpsychologische analysis from Krueger’s because newer approaches do not necessarily make
(1953) perspective. For example, Dürckheim- that dual distinction, as Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie
Montmartin (1934) examined the structural forces and physiological psychology did.
of community life with Krueger’s theory guid- Moreover, Greenwood (2003) even went so far
ing his analysis. Consistent with the notion of no as to make the controversial suggestion that perhaps
parts without the whole, Dürckheim-Montmartin there may be a space for experimental procedures in
reiterates that true membership of a group implies Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie, something that has not
spontaneous action in accordance with the collec- previously been deemed possible. However, in this
tive will, whereby the individual does not feel forced regard we should be very careful not to fall into the
but, rather, pledges himself/herself to act. The phe- linear causality model (as is so often applied in main-
nomena experienced by the collective people (Volk) stream social sciences today). I can only imagine that
are most clearly distinguishable when the Volk Wundt would be shaking his head in disbelief if
remains rather homogeneous—that is, united in social sciences came forth presenting research under

54 völker psyc ho log i e


the heading of Völkerpsychologie in which claims are than cultural psychology, as culture (in the German sense of
made that “A caused B.” Instead, alternative mod- Kultur) was merely incorporated into the approach (see also
Jahoda, 1993), although Wundt does compare Völkerpsycholo-
els of causality would need to be applied, such as gie and the “psychology of culture” at one point (see below).
catalyzed systemic causality models (Valsiner, 2000, Nevertheless, Völkerpsychologie was to focus on all aspects of peo-
pp. 74–76; see also 2004) that would not only be able ple living together, not just culture per se.
to capture the essence of Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie 2. Although not without criticism (see Schneider & Müller,
but would be closer to real-life events. It is clear that 1993).
3. However, according to Thurnwald (1924, p. 32), it
in such an approach, the catalyzed system necessarily was Wilhelm Humboldt’s 2-year-younger brother, Alexander
needs to include the historical nature of the Volksgeist, von Humboldt, who coined the term Volkerpsychologie. Thus,
something that completely removes the model from it remains unclear who was the first to have coined that term.
present-day mainstream linear approaches to ones Jahoda (1993, p. 145) followed up claims that Humboldt was
that turn the causality issue into one of emergent the first and found that these claims rest on mere assertions.
4. This idea was nicely captured by Wundt (1915) as
or synthesis causality. After all, we must remember Germany’s Second Reich was soon to near it’s end when, shortly
that theories are not supposed to take on the role after the outbreak of World War I, he advocated German ideal-
of a set mental (and socio-ideological) position; rather, ism and a social state in which the duty of citizens was to live for
they are the tools that help us look at phenomena the community and not for themselves.
(see Valsiner, 2004). 5. For example, Achelis (1889) published an article in honor
of Gustav Theodor Fechner (1801–1887) and in it addresses sev-
Holzner (1961) proposed several specialized eral of Fechner’s important points in his system of psychology.
subdivisions of Völkerpsychologie that are abstracted Thus, the scholars of Völkerpsychologie were aware of the theories
from a general Völkerpsychologie. In that regard, in experimental sciences but may have not necessarily been on
Völkerpsychologie would consist of a völkerpsycholo- the “cutting edge,” and certainly did little to incorporate it into
gische description of cultural content, a sociologi- Völkerpsychologie theory. The three articles that Eckardt (1997,
p. 71) highlights as specifically psychology-related are to be clas-
cal analysis of the totality of society, and disciplines sified as a form of philosophic-psychological essays. The authors
that specifically focused on studying social stratifi- were Lazarus (1868) and Meyer (1878, 1880). The reader may
cations, the totality of communal life, socialization, wish to note that the latter reference has been cited wrongly in
and personality. In the past, these studies would Eckardt’s text (he provides the same year and issue number for
predominantly require a comparative analysis, but both of Meyer’s publications) and is given in the corrected form
in the references below.
with the framework of modern cultural psychol- 6. This volume also contains a complete name and topic
ogy, they could become experiential to include index, stretching over all 20 volumes of Zeitschrift für Völkerpsy-
phenomenology of the higher levels of totality on chologie und Sprachwissenschaft.
topics like feelings and emotions, thereby utilizing 7. He made it a point to emphasize those people who
the rich methodological knowledge that has been belonged to the folklore guild, which held an international con-
gress from July 29 to August 3, 1891 in Paris, France.
introduced by various cultural psychology research- 8. Weinhold (1891) believed that the lower a person’s edu-
ers (for a general overview, see Valsiner, 2000). cation, the fewer words are needed for talk.
Finally, Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie has done little 9. The title Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwis-
to integrate the actual developmental processes, senschaft continued to be displayed under the title Zeitschrift des
and such an approach would be a desirable addi- Vereins für Volkskunde until the new editor, Karl Weinhold, passed
away in 1901. In 1902, when Johannes Bolte became Weinhold’s
tion to Völkerpsychologie as a part of today’s cul- successor, the old title of Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
tural psychology. After all, development implies Sprachwissenschaft finally became history. The new journal would
processes that engulf the entire person or persons, continue until the midst of World War I, by then under a new
and this form of totality needs to be accounted for. editor, Fritz Boehm, when the lack of personnel in the printing
One can now only hope that the present-day gen- factory and money problems would force it out of existence.
10. A biographical account can be found in Rieber and Rob-
eration of cultural psychologists will dare to step inson (2001).
into the footsteps left behind by the early giants of 11. For example, in his approach, Wundt faced considerable
Völkerpsychologie and complete the ambitious proj- difficulties in explaining the intermediate steps of cultural devel-
ect that, until now, has been left dormant but ready opment. In his Elemente der Völkerpsychologie (1912), despite his
for a re-awakening. emphasis on context, Wundt is often accused of reconstruct-
ing the cultural development of humans (e.g., Eckardt, 1997;
Werner, 1953). First of all, the way Wundt breaks down the
Notes development of humans into elements leads to the assumption
1. Other translations of the term Völkerpsychologie, such as of an Urmensch, which by its nature is the same for all humans.
cultural psychology, could be equally misleading as none really The development is then similar for all of mankind, given the
grasps the spectrum of this discipline. Völkerpsychologie was more environmental conditions. Werner (1953), for example, opposes

diriwäch ter 55
this by noting that if two human cultures are superficially similar Krueger, F. (1915). Über Entwicklungs-Psychologie: Ihre
today, it does not guarantee that they are not of different origins Sachliche und Geschichtliche Notwendigkeit. Arbeiten zur
and of different functional relevance. Further, the interpretations Entwicklungspsychologie: 1. Band - Heft 1. Leipzig, Germany:
of the völkpersychologische elements are tainted by our own devel- Verlag von Wilhelm Engelmann.
opmental stage (which is arguably operating out of a different Krueger, F. (1922). Wilhelm Wundt als deutscher Denker.
world than the world it is analyzing). In A. Hoffmann (Ed.), Wilhelm Wundt -;Eine Würdigung
This has proven to be a fundamental problem for völkerpsy- (pp. 1–44). Erfurt, Germany: Verlag der Keyserschen
chologische analysis: capturing and determining cultural units or Buchhandlung.
cultural layers that are so formed that all the outer manifestations Krueger, F. (1953). Entwicklungspsychologie der Ganzheit. In
of these cultural layers are carried by the distinct mental unique- E. Heuss (Ed.), Zur Philosophie und Psychologie der Ganzheit:
ness of a higher unit. (Werner, 1953, p. 11) Schriften aus den Jahren 1918–1940 (pp. 268–325). Berlin,
This issue, however, will always remain a problem for psy- Germany: Springer Verlag.
chology. No matter how well we design an experiment, no matter Lazarus, M. (1862). Ueber das Verhältnis des Einzelnen
how objective we try to be, the results are always subject to the zur Gesammtheit. Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
interpretations of those who are investigating the matter. Sprachwissenschaft, 2(4), 393–453.
*This chapter is a revised and expanded version of the fol- Lazarus, M. (1865). Einige Synthetische Gedanken zur
lowing publication: Völkerpsychologie Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
Diriwächter, R. (2004). Völkerpsychologie: The Synthesis that Sprachwissenschaft, 3(1), 1–94.
never was. Culture & Psychology, 10(1), 85–109. Lazarus, M. (1868). Zur Lehre von den Sinnestäuschungen
Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 5(2),
113–152.
References Lazarus, M., & Steinthal, H. (1860). Einleitende Gedanken
Achelis, T. (1889). Zur Würdigung G. Th. Fechners. Zeitschrift über Völkerpsychologie, als Einladung zu einer Zeitschrift
für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 19(3), 164–192. für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft. Zeitschrift für
Ash, M.G. (1995). Gestalt psychology in German culture, Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 1(1), 1–73.
1890–1967: Holism and the quest for objectivity. New York: Meyer, J.B. (1878). Das Wesen der Einbildungskraft. Zeitschrift
Cambridge University Press. für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 10(1), 26–41.
Danziger, K. (1980). The history of Introspection reconsid- Meyer, J.B. (1880). Genie und Talent. Eine psychologis-
ered. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, che Untersuchung. Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
241–262. Sprachwissenschaft, 11(3), 269–302.
Danziger, K. (1983). Origins and basic principles of Wundt’s Nerlich, B., & Clarke, D.D. (1998). The linguistic repudiation
Völkerpsychologie. British Journal of Social Psychology, 22(4), of Wundt. History of Psychology, 1(3), 179–204.
303–313. Noble, T.F.X., Strauss, B.S., Osheim, D.J., Neuschel, K.B.,
Diriwächter, R. (2008). Genetic Ganzheitspsychologie. In R. Cohen, W.B., & Roberts, D.D. (1994). Western civiliza-
Diriwächter & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Striving for the Whole: tion - The continuing experiment (Vol. II). Princeton, NJ:
Creating Theoretical Syntheses (pp. 21–45). Somerset, NJ: Houghton Mifflin.
Transaction Publishers. Rieber, R.W., & Robinson, D.K. (2001). Wilhelm Wundt in his-
Diriwächter, R. (2009). Idiographic Microgenesis: Re-visiting tory: The making of a scientific psychology. New York: Kluwer
the experimental tradition of Aktualgenese. In J. Valsiner, Academic/Plenum.
P.C.M. Molenaar, M.C.D.P. Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Sander, F. (1922). Wundt’s Prinzip der schöpferischen Synthese.
Dynamic Process Methodology in the Social and Developmental In A. Hoffmann (Ed.), Wilhelm Wundt - Eine Würdigung
Sciences (pp. 319–352). New York: Springer. (pp. 55–58). Erfurt, Germany: Verlag der Keyserschen
Diriwächter, R. & Valsiner, J. (2008). Striving for the Whole: Buchhandlung.
Creating Theoretical Syntheses. Somerset, NJ: Transaction Schneider, C.M., & Müller, M. (1993). Die Völkerpsychologie
Publishers. - Entstehung und Weiterentwicklung unter kulturpsycholo-
Dürckheim-Montmartin, K. (1934). Ganzheit und Struktur: gischen Aspekten. Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Psychologie,
Gemeinschaft. Neue Psychologische Studien, 12, 195–214. 52(2), 93–102.
Eckardt, G. (1997). Völkerpsychologie – Versuch einer Steinthal, H. (1860). Wilhelm v. Humboldt’s Briefe an
Neuentdeckung. Weinheim, Germany: BELTZ Psychologie F.G. Welcker. Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und
Verlags Union. Sprachwissenschaft, 1, 221–244.
Greenwood, J.D. (1999). From Völkerpsychologie to cultural Steinthal, H. (1887). Begriff der Völkerpsychologie. Zeitschrift
psychology: The once and future discipline? Philosophical für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 17, 233–265.
Psychology, 12(4), 503–514. Steinthal, H. (1891). An den Leser. Zeitschrift des Vereins für
Greenwood, J.D. (2003). Wundt, Völkerpsychologie, and experi- Volkskunde, 1, 10–17.
mental social psychology. History of Psychology, 7(1), 70–88. Thurnwald, R. (1924). Zum gegenwärtigen Stande der
Holzner, B. (1961). Völkerpsychologie: Leitfaden mit Bibliographie. Völkerpsychologie. Kölner Vierteljahreshefte für Soziologie,
Würzburg, Germany: Holzner Verlag. 4, 32–43.
Jahoda, G. (1993). Crossroads between culture and mind: Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and human development: An introduc-
Continuities and change in theories of human nature. tion. London: Sage.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Valsiner, J. (2001). The first six years: Culture’s adventures in
Knoll, J.H., & Siebert, H. (1967). Wilhelm von Humboldt – psychology. Culture & Psychology, 7(1), 5–48.
Politician and educationist. Bad Godesberg, Germany: Valsiner, J. (2004). Three years later: Between social positioning and
Verlagsgesellschaft Rudolf Müller. producing new knowledge. Culture & Psychology, 10(1), 5–27.

56 völker psyc ho log i e


Valsiner, J., & van der Veer, R. (2000). The social mind. New Wundt, W. (1894). Ueber psychische Causalität und das Princip
York: Cambridge University Press. des psychophysischen Parallelismus. Philosophische Studien,
Volkelt, H. (1922). Die Völkerpsychologie in Wundts 10(1), 1–125.
Entwicklungsgang. In A. Hoffmann (Ed.), Wilhelm Wundt – Wundt, W. (1911). Völkerpsychologie - Sprache, Mythus und Sitte
Eine Würdigung (pp. 74–105). Erfurt, Germany: Verlag der (Erster Band: Die Sprache). Leipzig, Germany: Verlag von
Keyserschen Buchhandlung. Wilhelm Engelmann.
Volkelt, H. (1962). Wilhelm Wundt auf der Schwelle zur Wundt, W. (1912). Elemente der Völkerpsychologie. Leipzig,
Ganzheitspsychologie. In F. Sander & H. Volkelt (eds.), Germany: Alfred Kröner Verlag.
Ganzheitspsychologie (pp. 15–30). Munich, Germany: C.H. Wundt, W. (1914). Über den wahrhaften Krieg. Leipzig, Germany:
Beck’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung Alfred Kröner Verlag.
Weinhold, K. (1890). Was soll die Volkskunde leisten? Zeitschrift Wundt, W. (1915). Die Nationen und ihre Philosophie. Leipzig,
für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 20, 1–5. Germany: Alfred Kröner Verlag.
Weinhold, K. (1891). Zur Einleitung. Zeitschrift des Vereins für Wundt, W. (1917). Völkerpsychologie und Entwicklungs-
Volkskunde, 1, 1–10. psychologie. Psychologische Studien, 10, 189–238.
Werner, H. (1953). Einführung in die Entwicklungspsychologie Wundt, W. (1920). Völkerpsychologie - Eine Untersuchung der
(3rd ed.). Munich, Germany: Johann Ambrosius Barth. Entwicklungsgesetze von Sprache, Mythus und Sitte (Zehnter
Wundt, W. (1877). Philosophy in Germany. In. G.C. Robertson Band: Kultur und Geschichte). Leipzig, Germany: Alfred
(Ed.), Mind - A Quarterly Review of Psychology + Philosophy Kröner Verlag.
(Vol. 2, pp. 493–518). London, GB: Williams & Norgate.
Wundt, W. (1888). Ueber Ziele und Wege der Völkerpsychologie.
Philosophische Studien, 4, 1–27.

diriwäch ter 57
CHAPTER

Cultural-Historical Psychology:
3 Contributions of Lev Vygotsky

René van der Veer

Abstract
A brief outline of Vygotsky’s major ideas is presented with only cursory reference to their historical
background. Drawing on psychological and linguistic research, Vygotsky developed a theory of the
development of mind. Central is the idea that the child’s naturally given mental processes become
transformed by the acquisition of speech and meanings. Through speech the child acquires a worldview
that reflects reality in a more adequate way. The driving force in creating new meanings for the child
is education in school. Given that meanings and schools differ in different cultures, children and
adults living in different cultures will think along different lines. Attention is paid to the argument that
Vygotsky overemphasized the role of speech to the detriment of the child’s concrete operations
with reality.
Keywords: Cultural-historical psychology, history of psychology, speech, concept
formation, lower and higher mental functions, social interaction, cross-cultural research

Cultural-historical psychology is connected Social History


with the name of Lev Vygotsky and originated in Born in a Jewish family in Belarus in 1896, which
the 1920s in what was then the Soviet Union. The then formed part of the Russian empire, Vygotsky1
definitive account of Vygotsky’s conception cannot could not avoid participating in and witnessing
yet be provided—given the inaccessibility of a sub- the social turmoil his country went through in the
stantial part of his writings (Van der Veer, 1997)— early twentieth century (Van der Veer & Valsiner,
but enough is known to give a fairly accurate picture 1991). This included several pogroms against the
of what he was up to. However, the understanding Jews, the October Revolution in 1917, the Civil
of Vygotsky’s ideas is made more difficult by the fact War from 1917 to 1923 (with foreign interven-
that they originated a long time ago and in a differ- tion), the collectivizing of farming in the late 1920s
ent culture. Theories often reflect the social context and early 1930s with resulting famines and millions
and historical period in which they were written, of death, and widespread political terror during the
and Vygotsky’s theories formed no exception. No reign of both Lenin and Stalin (Conquest, 1986).
social scientist in his time and country could permit Practically from the beginning of the new state in
himself to ignore the socio-political events taking 1917, the authorities began curtailing the freedom
place, nor could he fully escape the pressure of social of speech and scientific research. Some unwelcome
demands. This makes it essential for an understand- investigators were exiled or arrested, and others
ing of Vygotsky’s theories and their social embed- were fired or criticized in public (Chamberlain,
dedness to provide a brief account of that rather 2006). Researchers reacted by complying or try-
remote period in a country that no longer exists. ing to avoid sensitive subjects; only a few openly

58
resisted the new official ideology to the extent that Functions
this remained possible (Van der Veer, 2000). As the One of Vygotsky’s principal claims is that human
new official doctrine was loosely based on Marx’s consciousness is a uniquephenomenon in the ani-
ideas about class struggle and Engels’ ideas about mal world and develops in ontogeny. It is unique in
the origin and nature of man, the social sciences that it is based on the use of cultural means, which
and humanities were most vulnerable for criticism become internalized by the individual (Vygotsky,
from above. As a result, the researchers within these 1997c; Vygotsky & Luria, 1994). Vygotsky was pri-
domains attempted to develop a Marxist psychol- marily thinking of the unusual power of words as
ogy, a Marxist sociology, a Marxist anthropology, cultural means to transform our mental activities.
and so on. Vygotsky was one of the younger genera- Drawing on the work of the linguists Jakubinsky
tion of psychologists who tried to develop this new (1923), Potebnya (1926), and, ultimately von
Marxist psychology and one who, in the process, Humboldt, he emphasized the capacity of words to
developed close ties with high officials, such as the influence both the other and the self (Bertau, 2009).
minister of education Lunacharsky and Lenin’s wife Words can be used to urge another person to do
Krupskaya. One might think, then, that his writings something, but they can also be used to steer one’s
would be full of obligatory terms and references as own behavior. Words can be used to make a plan
shibboleths of the right worldview and, more gener- for the day, to form an intention, and to memorize
ally, that he did not sincerely believe in the ideas he a list of objects. Because such use of words does not
advanced, like so many of his generation. This, how- develop overnight, children and adults may differ
ever, does not seem to have been the case. Vygotsky’s substantially in their way of mental functioning, in
work is relatively free of the standard criticism of their consciousness.
class enemies and bourgeois mentality, and one gets Take the phenomenon of memorization. It is
the impression, while reading his private notebooks obvious that animals have memory, just like it
and letters, that he truly believed in the possibil- is clear that preverbal infants learn to recognize
ity of a Marxist reform of psychology and society at their mother, but Vygotsky argued that this is a
large. Also, in his attempts to develop his own new type of memory that is qualitatively different from
version of a Marxist psychology, he steered his own typically human, verbal memory. Using words,
course—for example, relying heavily on contempo- we humans may make a list of errands, we can
rary linguistic studies—which in the end made him think of categories of objects to be bought (veg-
suspicious for ideological hardliners. In the final etables, meat, dairy, etc.), we can describe pictures
years of his brief life, Vygotsky suffered criticism or music in words (which may help to recognize
and harassment from the Soviet authorities, and no and remember pieces of music or art), and so on
one knows what would have been his fate had he and so forth. Vygotsky preferred to call the first
not died from tuberculosis at the age of 38 years type of memory—that of infants and animals—
(Van der Veer, 2000). “natural memory” and the second type “cultural
memory,” and, more in general, he distinguished
Basic Ideas natural from cultural mental functions. Cultural
Vygotsky developed his ideas over a period functions always involve the use of cultural means
of about 10 years, and given this relatively short such as words, and natural functions do not.
period, one would expect to find a reasonably con- Vygotsky posited that cultural functions are much
sistent oeuvre without major revisions. In Vygotsky’s more powerful than natural ones and, conse-
case, this expectation is not vindicated, however. quently, also spoke of higher and lower functions.
Characteristic of Vygotsky is that he was constantly In this conviction, he may have been strength-
lecturing and writing—he published several hun- ened by his own feats as a memory artist. Using
dreds of books and articles in one decade—and various classic tricks, he showed his own students
revising his ideas in the process. That implies that how one can memorize long lists of words or
while reading one of Vygotsky’s publications, one numbers and thus increase one’s memory capacity
always has to take into account when it was writ- immensely. Subsequent researchers (e.g., Cole &
ten or published. However, in what follows, I will Gajdamaschko, 2007) have tried to soften the
avoid that problem by presenting mostly concepts natural-cultural dichotomy on several grounds,
and ideas that Vygotsky still adhered to by the end but there is no doubt that the distinction itself is
of his life. a valid one.

va n der veer 59
Origins a combination of socially acquired features, ideas,
Inasmuch as words are first learned and used in skills, et cetera.
social interaction, we can conclude with Vygotsky Incidentally, Vygotsky’s emphasis on the social
that higher mental functions have a social origin. nature of mind may seem Marxist, and in Vygotsky’s
Vygotsky accepted Janet’s view that in human his- case, it was certainly also inspired by Marx’s writ-
tory, words were originally commands (i.e., ego ings, but it should be said that the social emphasis
instructs or urges alter to do something). However, was shared by several non-Marxist thinkers of the
it belongs to the peculiar nature of spoken words time as well. In 1939, for example, the sociologist
that we also hear them and that we may instruct Norbert Elias wrote in a remarkable essay on “the
ourselves. Speaking to ourselves, we wander through society of individuals”:
the day and, in a way, human “consciousness is,
[E]ven the nature and form of his solitude, even what
as it were, social contact with oneself ” (Vygotsky,
he feels to be his ‘inner life’, is stamped by the history
1925/1997, p. 78). Vygotsky argued:
of his relationships . . . one must start from the
We are conscious of ourselves because we are structure of relations between individuals in order to
conscious of others and by the same method as we understand the ‘psyche’ of the individual person.
are conscious of others, because we are the same (Elias, 1935, pp. 33, 37)
vis-à-vis ourselves as others vis-à-vis us. I am
Indeed, this is not far from a statement made by
conscious of myself only to the extent that
Vygotsky’s collaborator Luria (1979, p. 43), who
I am another to myself . . . the social moment in
wrote that “we needed, as it were, to step outside
consciousness is primary in time as well as in fact.
the organism to discover the sources of the specifi-
The individual aspect is constructed as a derived
cally human forms of psychological activity.” Our
and secondary aspect based on the social aspect and
most intimate core, our private ideas and feelings
exactly according to its model.
have their origin in human interaction and make
(1925/1997, p. 77)
use of (are molded by) the available cultural means
It is not difficult to see this statement as a further in a specific society.
elaboration of the dualis concept developed by von
Humboldt, who emphasized the social nature of Means
speech and its importance for the understanding of There are different usages of the word “social” in
the self: the above passages that should be distinguished. Of
course, one can say that human babies are social in
Language, however, develops only socially
the sense that they depend on others and seek the
[gesellschaftlich] and man only understands himself
presence of others. In this regard, human babies do
because he tentatively tested the intelligibility of his
not differ from the young of other primates. Or, one
words on others.
can say with Elias that to understand an individual
(quoted in Bertau, 2009, p. 61)
one needs to look at the history of his or her rela-
So, in this view we know ourselves only through tionships. But Vygotsky was aiming at something
the medium of social speech, via the shared mean- more specific. What Vygotsky had in mind was the
ings of existing language and becoming conscious slow change of learning, memory, vision, hearing,
of oneself is formulating one’s experiences in words and so forth into human learning, human memory,
acquired through others. That implies that our and so on. This takes place by the acquisition of cul-
most intimate, private, and personal feelings—to tural means transmitted and/or acquired in a social
the extent that they can be verbalized—are never- context. In this sense, the mental faculties of a child
theless very social and that becoming an individual of, say, 7 years may not have become fully socialized
or personality does not imply becoming less social. or culturalized.
As Vygotsky put it in his book on the psychology of According to Vygotsky, the understanding and
art, “We should not say that feeling becomes social acquisition of cultural means goes through several
but rather that it becomes personal . . . without ceas- stages in ontogeny, and the first cultural means
ing to be social” (Vygotsky, 1925/1986, p. 314). In often have a concrete, material nature. At first,
this way, Vygotsky also undermined facile individ- the young child will disregard cultural means even
ual–society dichotomies: society is within the indi- when they are made available; then the child will use
vidual and our uttermost individuality consists of the material means in a purely formal way, without

60 c ultural -h i sto r i ca l psycho log y


understanding them and without improvement of open, social variants under the influence of peers
the performance. Subsequently, the child will make and adults.
use of the material means and profit from them. Vygotsky (1932) criticized Piaget’s contention
And, finally, the child will internalize the cultural and performed several little experiments to refute his
means and no longer need material support. One views. Vygotsky noted, for example, that egocentric
of Vygotsky’s favorite examples was that of count- speech was absent or greatly reduced when the child
ing, which for children still depends on the con- was alone or surrounded by deaf children. This sug-
crete availability of body parts such as fingers and gests that egocentric speech is meant by the child as
toes but which most adults can do without this social communication. Vygotsky also observed that
dependence. Another of his examples was that of the incidence of egocentric speech rose when the
memorizing an intention such as the purchasing of child was confronted with unexpected problems.
some present. Children may need to rely on such This suggests, in his view, that egocentric speech has
material means as a knot tied in a handkerchief to some function in the solution of problems. Finally,
remind them of their intention. Adults, however, Vygotsky noticed that egocentric speech becomes
may tie a mental knot by vividly connecting the less intelligible as children grow older, which is not
image of some situation or person with the inten- consistent with Piaget’s idea that egocentrism grad-
tion to buy the present. This switch from external ually disappears. From these results, Vygotsky drew
to internal means is not always fully complete for the conclusion that so-called “egocentric speech”:
a specific function—adults may still use the strata- (1) originates in normal, communicative speech and
gem of tying knots in handkerchiefs—and neither branches off at a later stage; (2) has as its function to
can one say that it is always generally present in steer the child’s behavior when the need arises; and
adults, perhaps, but Vygotsky argued that it is char- (3) becomes less and less intelligible for the outsider
acteristic of human mental development. And one until it has become proper private or inner speech.
might add that the fact that we have gone through According to Vygotsky, then, egocentric speech is
this development is what makes it so difficult for an intermediary stage between normal, communi-
humans to fully grasp the bovine or porcine word- cative speech and inner speech. Like communica-
less worldview. In any case, the above examples tive speech, it is audible, and like inner speech, it
give an idea of Vygotsky’s concept of the gradual serves to guide the child’s thinking (Van der Veer,
acquisition of cultural means in social interaction 2007).
to steer one’s own behavior. Of course, it is very difficult to describe and ana-
lyze the nature and function of inner speech given
Words its intimate nature, and Vygotsky’s reasoning here
Speech itself was the subject matter of Vygotsky’s was necessarily largely hypothetical. He began (fol-
final chapter in his posthumous book Thinking and lowing Jakubinsky, 1923/1988, pp. 27–43) with
Speech (1934). His discussion of private or inner positing that inner speech must be shorter because
speech and its relation to social speech, on the one one need not spell out details that are known to
hand, and thinking, on the other, was partially the speaker but not to the listener. In inner speech,
inspired by the reading of his contemporary, Jean speaker and listener coincide, which means one
Piaget. Piaget (1923; 1924) first described the phe- can be much less explicit. With Paulhan (1928),
nomenon of children who, during play, speak for Vygotsky added that inner speech is dominated by
themselves in a way that is often not intelligible personal connotations—that is, in inner speech
to other children. Piaget hypothesized that such subjects may, on the basis of their private experi-
speech is unintelligible, because young children are ences, attach private meanings to words that do
unable to take the other’s point of view—that is, not coincide with their lexical meanings. The word
children up to age 7 or 8 years do not realize that “sun,” for example, may acquire strongly nega-
the other child does not have the same knowledge, tive connotations for a person with delicate skin,
tastes, or feelings as they themselves. In a word, they whereas for others it may be an entirely pleasant
are egocentric. Only gradually will children learn to word. In sum, the chances are that inner speech
replace their egocentric speech with social speech. made audible would not be entirely intelligible to
Piaget’s background philosophy was that children other people given its abbreviated nature and its
are originally autistic, and their autistic thought and personal connotations and jargon. In itself that is a
speech is gradually suppressed and replaced by more comforting thought, but more important is to see

va n der veer 61
how Vygotsky attempted to trace our inner voice supposedly precedes the verbal understanding and
from social dialogues. As stated above, in his view, designation of the experience). In other words, as
verbal thinking begins with social speech (i.e., ego adults we live in a conceptual world and it is very
utters things meant to be heard by alter) but after hard or impossible to regress to the preverbal world
a series of transformations becomes utterly private of the newborn and once again experience a mean-
and presumably unintelligible to the social other. ingless universe. With the acquisition of words, the
Again, then, thoroughly private mental processes child’s phenomenal world begins to change; the
originate in social interaction. In a recent investiga- child learns to classify things, animals, and persons
tion, Werani (2010) investigated whether Vygotsky in several more or less coherent groups. Vygotsky
was right in suggesting that inner speech may have a posited that the most fundamental changes in the
function in problem solving. Using thinking aloud child’s understanding of the world take place in
protocols, she was able to show that overt speech adolescence when children develop full-fledged sci-
was connected with the complexity of the task and entific concepts. Younger children do interpret the
the quality of the solution. It may be inferred that world in intelligent ways, but their conceptual grasp
this holds for inner speech as well (cf. Lloyd & is inadequate compared to that of trained adults. (It
Fernyhough, 1999; Zivin, 1979). is here that Vygotsky’s research into concept forma-
tion discussed below becomes relevant.) Conversely,
Systems in diseases such as schizophrenia, Vygotsky (1997b,
If Vygotsky was right in his claim that mental p. 103) claimed, the subject loses his ability to use
faculties such as memory and perception gradually adequate concepts.
become dominated or transformed by the acquisi- It is not just perception that becomes, so to
tion of verbal meanings and concepts, then it follows speak, intellectualized. The same holds true for
that mental processes are mutually connected in a memory and feelings. Vygotsky believed that our
system that in adults is dominated by verbal think- feelings become trained to gradually fit into a his-
ing. With several contemporaries (e.g., Charlotte torically determined cultural system. When and to
Bühler), Vygotsky believed that in children men- what extent we feel jealous is determined by our
tal functioning may be dominated temporarily by culture, Vygotsky argued. And the appreciation of
other functions such as perception or memory— music and wine is framed in elaborate systems of
that is, children behave led by what they perceive or technical terms that co-constitute the experience.
remember, without thinking too much—but that in Thus, what in children may be primary experi-
adults thinking has the dominating role. In one of ences become refined aesthetic feelings in the adult
his later writings, Vygotsky developed this notion of through the introduction of complex conceptual
the systemic structure of mind. His basic claim was, systems. In a sense, then, mental functions that
in his own words: originally operated in isolation become connected
through language.
It is not so much the functions that change . . . what
is changed and modified are rather the relationships,
Brains
the links between the functions. New constellations
It is, of course, tempting to speculate about the
emerge that were unknown in the preceding stage.
cerebral substrate of a system of mental functions.
That is why intra-functional change is often not
Vygotsky believed that brain systems are not pre-
essential in the transition from one stage to another.
given but that connections between different zones
It is inter-functional changes, the changes of inter-
of the brain develop in ontogeny. When the images
functional connections and the inter-functional
of two different objects are evoked in tandem and
structure that matter. The development of such new
become connected for the subject, then this pre-
flexible relationships between functions we will call a
sumably means that new connections are formed
psychological system.
between the loci where these images and their names
(Vygotsky, 1997b, p. 92)
are stored. In other words, the neural network of
One of Vygotsky’s examples was that of percep- meanings and images is constantly being revised as
tion. In adults, perception is dominated by knowl- the person grows older. Also, the social other may
edge. We see what we expect to see, and it is almost stimulate the connection between different cortical
impossible to find what Wundt called the “immedi- centers of the subject through instruction and so
ate experience” (i.e., the sensational experience that on. To Vygotsky this once more showed that social

62 c ultural -h i sto r i ca l psycho log y


interaction is crucial for cognitive development: cor- were told the name of an object and asked to find
tical centers that were originally unconnected now another object of the same name in a group of
form a cortical network thanks to outside interfer- objects differing on various dimensions (color, size,
ence. The functional plasticity of the brain permits etc.). They found that younger children’s approach
the dynamic systemic structure of mind. to that task was qualitatively different from that
The idea of a flexible systemic brain structure of adults. The attempts at classification by chil-
also allows us to understand cases of compensa- dren were inconsistent, based on concrete features,
tion in patients with brain lesions. Subjects may, and often unsuccessful. The last preconceptual
for example, lose the ability to name an object they stage is reached in pre-adolescence when children
perceive—that is, the visual image of the object no classify the objects on the basis of what Vygotsky
longer triggers its name. However, when allowed to called “pseudo-concepts.” Children might gather
touch the object, they may regain its name. That all objects of the same form but be unable to state
finding seems to imply that in a complex system their joint property in an adequate way. Thus, they
of cortical centers responsible for the storage of the might select all triangles because “they look the
sound, image, touch, and name of the object, some same” but be unable to state the abstract concept
connections may be lost but may be compensated “triangle” and its defining properties. Superficially,
for by others. A better understanding of the exact they seemed to experience the world as adults do,
nature of such interfunctional systems may allow us and nothing prevented successful communication
to devise means of compensation for brain patients. between children and adults, but deeper probing
It was Luria, Vygotsky’s former collaborator, who learned that children of that age conceptualize the
developed this approach into the new discipline of world differently from adults.
neuropsychology. A recent replication in South Africa, using
Ultimately, for Vygotsky the most important Vygotsky’s original material and experimental setup,
implication of the system notion was that of the has verified Vygotsky’s assertion that true concep-
possibility of deliberate control. The well-trained tual thinking only becomes possible in adolescence
adult is capable of using his thinking to improve (Towsey, 2009; Towsey & Macdonald, 2009). In
his memory feats, for example. As thinking is noth- their meaning-making efforts, children are guided
ing other than the use of cultural means such as by the culturally determined meanings available in
words to solve problems, this is equivalent to stat- the words around them, but they reach the (adult)
ing once more that we may use cultural means to stage of full-fledged scientific concepts only after a
enhance memory performance. That is to say, by lengthy process of development.
making deliberate use of cultural signs, we can
lift our perception, memory, and attention to new Teachers
levels. Ultimately, we may even be capable of fully It is education that plays a fundamental role in
dominating our passions by framing them in cul- children’s growing ability to make use of scientific
turally accepted meanings. As we reasoned before, concepts. Inspired by Piaget, Vygotsky made a dis-
the attention of children is dominated by factors tinction between everyday concepts and scientific
outside their control. Similarly, children are the concepts. Everyday concepts are based on concrete
slaves of their passions. Adults, however, are ideally and sometimes irrelevant features of phenomena
capable of steering their own behavior; they are less and do not form part of a coherent conceptual sys-
spontaneous, they can ignore external or internal tem. Scientific concepts reflect essential, abstract
stimuli, they can choose to conceal their feelings, properties of phenomena and are logically con-
and they can become capable of deception. Thus, nected to other, related concepts. Such scientific
with Spinoza, Vygotsky (1997b, p. 103) believed economic concepts as supply, demand, scarcity,
that man, through his intellect, has gained power turnover, and profit, for example, form part of the
over his affects and other mental processes. interconnected system of concepts called economic
theory. Characteristic of scientific concepts is that
Concepts they are explicitly and systematically introduced in
Vygotsky’s evidence for conceptual change in an educational setting and that students are trained
childhood and adolescence rested on several of his to define them, to state their interrelationships, and
own investigations, which he described in Thinking so on. In other words, students make conscious
and Speech (1934). Subjects of different age groups and deliberate use of these concepts, realizing their

va n der veer 63
interconnectedness. Vygotsky posited that the mas- for that suggestion. Also, he suggested that children
tering of such scientific concepts in school carries differ in their ability to profit from assistance and
over to everyday life and that children’s everyday that the difference between their independent and
concepts become transformed by them. Thus, the assisted performance has differential prognostic
child’s original concept of a worker as someone value. More than standard cognitive tests, assisted
who goes to work (with concrete images of cloth- performance would give us an indication of the
ing, factories, etc.) will become enriched by the children’s potential, their independent performance
idea that a worker is someone who sells his labor in the near future. This suggestion has long been
to an employer in accordance with the system of ignored, but the recent dynamic assessment move-
economic concepts mentioned above. Everyday ment—also inspired by Feuerstein, who indepen-
concepts, on the other hand, give bone and flesh dently reached similar conclusions—is exploring its
to scientific concepts. They provide the rich con- potential (cf. Van der Veer, 2007).
crete details that scientific concepts lack and are tied
to the child’s concrete reality. Vygotsky, thus, pos- Cultures
ited that everyday and scientific concepts mutually If higher cognitive processes are determined by
enrich each other but nevertheless emphasized the the acquisition of cultural means, if instruction
leading role of scientific concepts in creating new plays a fundamental role in creating new zones of
and deeper understanding of reality. As often, he cognitive development, then it follows that higher
discussed some empirical investigations that cor- thought differs between cultures. The lower, natural
roborated his view, but these left much to be desired mental functions will be shared because they belong
in terms of research methodology (Van der Veer & to the human make-up, but the higher, cultural
Valsiner, 1991). functions should differ because they depend on
different cultural means from sometimes radically
Zones different cultures. This was a conclusion that was
The leading role of school or, more generally, unusual for that time: contemporaries were inclined
instruction in stimulating children’s mental develop- to attribute the different mentality of ‘savages’ to
ment was emphasized by Vygotsky time and again. their different bodily constitution or animal-like
In the final years of his life, he lectured about edu- nature (Jahoda, 1999). Vygotsky followed another
cation as supposedly creating a new zone of mental line of reasoning:
development. His basic idea was very simple. Some
We have no reason to assume that the human brain
tasks children can solve themselves, independently.
underwent an essential biological evolution in the
Others are only within their reach when they receive
course of human history. We have no reason to
assistance or scaffolding from more capable peers or
assume that the brain of primitive man differed
adults. Using the hints and prompts of parents or
from our brain, was an inferior brain, or had a
teachers, they then reach above their present abili-
biological structure different from ours. All biological
ties. The interesting thing to note is that children
investigations lead us to assume that biologically
cannot utilize all the hints they receive; some assis-
speaking the most primitive man we know deserves
tance is so beyond their present abilities that they
the full title of man.
fail to profit from it. But there is a twilight zone
(Vygotsky, 1997b, p. 97)
between their present darkness of ignorance and
their future brightness of understanding, and just Thus, Vygotsky denied that there could be any rel-
as the daybreak announces a new day, that twilight evant biological differences between contemporary
zone announces the child’s understanding in the persons of different races or cultures. However, if
near future. What the child can do today with sup- we cannot attribute the existing differences in men-
port, she can do tomorrow independently. In other tality to nature, then they must be attributed to
words, we may use the children’s assisted perfor- nurture, to the way human children are raised in
mance to predict their future independent perfor- various societies, and to the cultural means these
mance. Vygotsky clearly suggested that parents and children master. But do we find any deep differ-
teachers, by giving hints and prompts, were of para- ences in cognitive functioning between cultures?
mount importance in calling into life (rather than This is largely an empirical matter, and Vygotsky
laying bare) new levels of the child’s understanding, and his associates were among the first investiga-
but in this context he provided no empirical backing tors who tried to answer this question through

64 c ultural -h i sto r i ca l psycho log y


scientific investigation. Alexander Luria, Vygotsky’s In Vygotsky and Luria’s view, it takes the Western
closest collaborator, found important cognitive dif- school instruction to develop truly scientific
ferences in the Islamic population of Kazakhstan in abstract reasoning in children, and Luria provided
the early 1930s. Previous investigators had found data to prove that the subjects’ capacity for abstract
various minorities in Central Asia to score low on thought was directly linked to the number of years
intelligence tests, and in an effort to explain the dif- of schooling received. Given the right education,
ferences medical anthropologists had measured the they might make “a leap of centuries” (Luria, 1976,
size of their skulls (cf. Van der Veer, 2007). Luria p. 164). Now, as then, these conclusions are viewed
took another approach: after due preparation and as debatable. It is contentious to compare cultures
with the help of interpreters, he offered Kazakh on a developmental scale. It is risky to draw general
subjects intellectual riddles and carefully discussed conclusions about subjects’ general ability to reason
the proposed solutions with the subjects—challeng- abstractly on the basis of their failure or refusal to
ing them for better arguments, expressing dissent, solve the presented tasks. It is doubtful whether
and so forth—in a manner not unlike that used by Western school is essential in creating abstract abili-
Piaget in his clinical interviews with children. He ties. Be that as it may, Vygotsky’s and Luria’s find-
found that his subjects failed to solve several cogni- ings have been verified time and again, and now,
tive tasks in the manner that he found to be superior as then, it is unlikely that the differences found are
and that was common in most adult Western sub- caused by genetic differences. The exact nature of
jects. Thus, asked to group together three of four the differences in higher reasoning is still subject of
objects, subjects failed to sort them according to considerable debate, whether it be cognitive differ-
their function or to abstract properties. For exam- ences or moral reasoning à la Kohlberg.
ple, when asked which object did not belong in the
series “glass, saucepan, spectacles, and bottle,” the Conclusions
subjects could not reach a solution. They did not say In the early 1930s, Vygotsky advanced a set of
that three of the objects were vessels (function) nor ideas that was quite unlike that of contemporaries
that three others were made of glass (abstract prop- such as Karl and Charlotte Bühler, Kurt Koffka,
erty). Instead, they imagined concrete situations in Kurt Lewin, Jean Piaget, Wilhelm Stern, and Heinz
which these objects would fit together despite Luria’s Werner. He posited a peculiar theory about the
suggestions that other solutions were possible. Luria merging of natural and cultural lines in child devel-
concluded that “different psychological processes opment. The cultural line was based on the acquisi-
determined their manner of grouping which hinged tion of cultural means that transformed the child’s
on concrete, situational thinking rather than on functioning. Applying the socially acquired cultural
abstract operations which entail the generalizing means to the self, the child becomes conscious of
function of language” (Luria, 1976, p. 77). Similar his or her mental functioning. The mastering of
results were reached with other cognitive tasks such cultural means takes years and is only finished in
as hypothetical reasoning: the subjects reacted to adolescence. At first, higher mental functioning
the tasks in ways that differed from those of Western needs the support of concrete material actions
subjects and relied on their concrete, everyday expe- and objects but gradually the child becomes able
rience. Thus, when subjects were told that all bears to operate on the purely mental level. The most
on Nova Zembla were white and that Jaan was a important cultural means is speech, with its variants
bear on Nova Zembla, they refused to draw any social, egocentric, and inner speech. The inclusion
conclusions about Jaan’s skin color because they had of speech into mental functioning implies that the
never been on Nova Zembla. inter-relationships between different mental func-
On the basis of such results, Luria and Vygotsky tions become changed and form a dynamic system.
were inclined to speak of different levels of cognitive On the level of the cortex, this probably means that
functioning—that is, they reasoned that the non- different cortical centers become connected and dis-
Western subjects had not yet reached the Western connected depending on life experiences. A primary
level of abstract reasoning. In their view, the Islamic role in intellectual development is played by educa-
culture to which the subjects belonged did not offer tion, which teaches children a logically connected
the necessary cultural means to solve the tasks pre- worldview. Children can profit from education
sented, and therefore, the subjects could not mani- when it falls in their zone of proximal development.
fest the required hypothetical scientific thinking. To the extent that cultures offer different cultural

va n der veer 65
means inside or outside education, subjects from Thus, Leontiev shifted the emphasis from speech
different cultures will display different modes of to concrete operations, with reality mediated by
thinking. Children from different cultures may have speech. Undoubtedly, this move was motivated
the same intellectual potential, but they do end up by his wish to stay closer to orthodox Marxist
thinking in fundamentally different ways. thought with its emphasis on the role of concrete
labor in the development of human consciousness.
Future Directions Whether Leontiev’s view substantially differed from
In the 1920s and 1930s, Vygotsky’s ideas were Vygotsky’s stance and, if so, whether it constituted
virtually unknown in the West and thus met with an improvement has since been the subject of con-
no criticism there. In fact, it is very difficult to siderable debate.
find any mention of his person or work (Van der
Veer, 2007). In the Soviet Union this was differ- The Dialogue that Could Not Be
ent: in the late 1920s and early 1930s, his work It is very interesting to note that what Leontiev
first met with criticism, which was continued and Gal’perin wished Vygotsky to do—to shift the
after his death in 1934. The first criticisms were emphasis from speech to concrete actions—was to
largely ideological and can be left aside in this some extent realized in practice by Vygotsky’s con-
context (Van der Veer, 2000). However, shortly temporary Jean Piaget, albeit in his own original
after his death several of his closest collaborators— way. Just like Vygotsky, the young Piaget attached
notably Aleksey Leontiev (1935, 1937) and Pyotr fundamental importance to language and social
Gal’perin (1935)—began to voice criticism that interaction, but gradually he began put more
needs to be taken seriously. Gal’perin, among emphasis on the importance of the child’s concrete
other things, argued that the distinction between operations. It would have been highly interesting
natural and cultural mental processes as made by to see what happened had these two great scientists
Vygotsky leads to the unfortunate consequence been able to communicate and criticize each other’s
that children age, say, 7 years may be said to func- ideas in this respect. What is more, I think it would
tion naturally, outside culture. He pleaded to trace still be beneficial to confront the two theories more
the origin of mediated actions to the “child’s first substantially than has been the case to date. I offer
cry”—that is, he believed that the role of cultural, just a few examples from an introductory book on
semiotic means should be studied already in the Piaget to show what kind of topics might be worth
child’s proto-language. Second, Gal’perin argued discussing.
that Vygotsky laid too much emphasis on verbal
consciousness and ignored the child’s concrete the child’s ability to profit from training depends on
operations in the real world. Vygotsky’s claim that his initial developmental level”. . . [only]
education is the driving force of development, those at a transitional level showed considerable
Gal’perin deemed “idealistic,” because it suggested progress . . . the child can profit from external
that the child’s ideas are changed by those of his information . . . only when his cognitive structure is
teacher (the social other) without intervention of sufficiently prepared . . . / . . . Interest and learning
the real world. Leontiev elaborated this criticism are best facilitated if the experience presented
and gradually developed it to create his so-called to the child bears some relevance to what he already
“activity theory.” In his view, the subject matter of knows, but is at the same time sufficiently novel to
psychology was “activity as a relationship to real- present incongruities and conflicts . . . the child’s
ity, to the objects of this reality” (Leontiev, 1935, interest is aroused when an experience is
p. 68). Acknowledging the central role of speech, moderately novel.
Leontiev nevertheless claimed that speaking with (Ginsburg & Opper, 1979, pp. 217–219, 226)
others, or social interaction in general, could not
This statement seems to deal exactly with the situ-
be the driving force behind changes in ego’s con-
ation that Vygotsky described in discussing his
sciousness. In his view:
concept of the zone of proximal development. The
The social nature of the child’s mind thus does not question to ask might be to what extent the “hints
reside in the fact that he interacts with others but in and prompts” discussed by Vygotsky differ from the
the fact that his activity (his relationship to nature) is Piagetian type of education that hoped to create
objectively and socially mediated. incongruities and conflicts in the child’s mind in a
(Leontiev, 1935, p. 74) transitional stage.

66 c ultural -h i sto r i ca l psycho log y


Ginsburg and Opper also offer the following Conquest, R. (1986). The harvest of sorrow: Soviet collectivization
observation: and the terror-famine. Alberta, Canada: University of Alberta
Press.
Adults often believe that once a child has learned Elias, N. (1939). The society of individuals. In N. Elias (Ed.).
The society of individuals (pp. 1–66). Oxford: Blackwell.
the linguistic label for an object, he has available the
Gal’perin, P. Y. (1935/2009). Sistema istoricheskoy psikhologii
underlying concept. But Piaget has shown that this is L.S. Vygotskogo i nekotorye polozheniya k ee analizu
often not the case . . . only after a period of cognitive (tezisy). Kul’turno-Istoricheskaya Psikhologiya, 1, 118–123.
development does the child use these words and Ginsburg, H. & Opper, S. (1979). Piaget’s theory of intellectual
understand them in the same way as the more mature development. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Jahoda, G. (1999). Images of savages: Ancient roots of modern
person.
prejudice in western culture. London: Routledge.
(Ginsburg & Opper, 1979, pp. 223) Jakubinsky, L. P. (1923/1988). O dialogicheskoy rechi. In
L. P. Jakubinsky (Ed.), Izbrannye raboty. Moscow: Nauka.
Is this not the same conclusion that Vygotsky Leontiev, A. N. (1935/1983). Psikhologicheskoe issledovanie
reached in his own research on concept formation? rechi. In A. N. Leontiev, Izbrannye psikhologicheskie proizve-
If not, what are the differences? Finally, Ginsburg denija. Tom 1 (pp. 65–75). Moscow: Nauka.
and Opper formulated what can be called a law of Leontiev, A. N. (1937/1988). Uchenie o srede v pedologicheskikh
internalization: rabotakh L.S. Vygotskogo: Kriticheskoe issledovanie. Voprosy
Psikhlogii, 44, 108–124.
First the child physically sorts or otherwise Lloyd, P., & Fernyhough, Ch. (1999). Lev Vygotsky: Critical
manipulates objects . . . later, he can sort the objects assessments. London: Routledge. (4 volumes).
Luria, A. R. (1976). Cognitive development: Its cultural and social
solely on a mental level.
foundations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(Ginsburg & Opper, 1979, p. 225) Luria, A. R. (1979). The making of mind. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Again, one might ask whether this is fundamen- Paulhan, F. (1928). Qu’est-ce que le sens des mots? Journal de
tally different from what Vygotsky discussed when Psychologie, 25, 289–329.
describing the internalization of cultural means. Piaget, J. (1923). Le langage et la pensée chez l’enfant. Neuchatel,
I offer these examples for contemplation, not to Switzerland: Delachaux et Niestlé/
argue that Vygotsky and Piaget basically thought Piaget, J. (1924). Le jugement et le raisonnement chez l’enfant.
Neuchatel, Switzerland: Delachaux et Niestlé.
along similar lines. But I do believe that many Potebnya, A. A. (1926/1989). Mysl i yazyk. In A. A. Potebnya
researchers who quote Vygotsky to make some (Ed.), Slovo i mif (pp. 17–200). Moscow: Pravda.
point might just as well have quoted Piaget, who Towsey, P. M. (2009). More than a footnote to history in cul-
now for them seems outdated, perhaps. A thorough tural-historical theory: The Zalkind summary, experimen-
confrontation of both theories by impassionate tal study of higher behavioural processes, and ‘Vygotsky’s
blocks’. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 16, 317–337.
researchers would be quite beneficial, I believe, for Towsey, P. M. & Macdonald, C. A. (2009). Wolves in sheep’s
the progress of psychological science. It is high time clothing and other Vygotskian constructs. Mind, Culture,
that we make some fundamental steps in our under- and Activity, 16, 234–262.
standing of the development of the human mind. Van der Veer, R. (1997). Major themes in Vygotsky’s theoretical
The replication and criticism of Vygotsky’s many work: An introduction. In R. W. Rieber & J. Wollock (Eds.),
The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky. Volume 3. Problems of the
research projects against the background of other theory and history of psychology (pp. 1–7). New York: Plenum
fundamental theories may contribute to this cause. Press.
Van der Veer, R. (2000). Vygotsky criticized. Journal of Russian
Notes and Eastern European Psychology, 6, 3–9.
1. He was born as Lev Simkhovich Vygodsky but changed Van der Veer, R. (2007a). Vygotsky in context: 1900–1935. In
his patronymic and surname for reasons that have not been fully H. Daniels, M. Cole, & J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge
clarified. companion to Vygotsky (pp. 21–49). Cambridge, NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Van der Veer, R. (2007b). Lev Vygotsky. London: Continuum.
References Van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky.
Bertau, M. C. (2009). Anreden, Erwidern, Verstehen: Elemente Oxford: Blackwell.
einer Psycholinguistik der Alterität. Munich, Germany: Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Psikhologiya iskusstva. Moscow: Iskusstvo.
Ludwig Maximilians University (Habilitation). Vygotsky, L. S. (1997a). Consciousness as a problem for the psy-
Chamberlain, L. (2006). The philosophy steamer: Lenin and the chology of behavior. In R. W. Rieber & J. Wollock (Eds.),
exile of the intelligentsia. London: Atlantic Books. The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky. Volume 3. Problems of
Cole, M., & Gajdamaschko, N. (2007). Vygotsky and culture. the theory and history of psychology (pp. 63–79). New York:
In H. Daniels, M. Cole, & J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Plenum Press.
Cambridge companion to Vygotsky (pp. 193–211). Cambridge, Vygotsky, L. S. (1997b). On psychological systems. In
NY: Cambridge University Press. R. W. Rieber & J. Wollock (Eds.), The collected works of

va n der veer 67
L.S. Vygotsky. Volume 3. Problems of the theory and history of Vygotsky, L. S. (1934). Myshlenie i rech: Psikhologicheskie issledo-
psychology (pp. 91–107). New York: Plenum Press. vaniya. Moscow: Gosudarstvennoe Sotsial’no-Ekonomicheskoe
Vygotsky, L. S. (1997c). The history of the development of higher Izdatel’stvo.
mental functions. In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), The collected works of Vygotsky, L. S., Luria, A. R. (1994). Tool and symbol in child
L.S. Vygotsky. Volume 4. The history of the development of higher development. In R. van der Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The
mental functions (pp. 1–251). New York: Plenum Press. Vygotsky reader (pp. 99–174). Oxford: Blackwell.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Psikhologiya iskusstva. (3rd edition). Werani, A. (2010). Inneres Sprechen: Weiterentwicklung eines
Moscow: Iskusstvo. theoretischen Konzeptes auf empirischer Grundlage. Munich:
Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). Psikhologiya iskusstva. Moscow: Pedagogika. Ludwig Maximilians University. (Habilitation)
Vygotsky, L. S. (1932). Predislovie. In J. Piaget (Ed.). Rech i mysh- Zivin, G. (1979). The development of self-regulation through pri-
lenie rebyenka. (pp. 3–54). Moscow-Leningrad: Uchpedgiz. vate speech. New York: Wiley.

68 c ultural -h i sto r i ca l psycho log y


PA RT
2
Inter- and
Intradisciplinary
Perspectives
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

The Role of Indigenous Psychologies


4 in the Building of Basic Cultural
Psychology
Pradeep Chakkarath

Abstract
In this chapter, the author traces some of the common historical roots and features of indigenous
psychology and cultural psychology. He then considers the extent to which the mainstream
historiography of psychology’s encounter with culture conveys a misleading impression and why
correcting this impression is of general importance for a science that deals with human development
and functioning in varying socio-historical and cultural environments. Examples from Indian psychology
are used to illustrate the potential of indigenous psychology to add to our scientific knowledge. Finally,
conclusions are drawn about how and whether indigenous psychological knowledge and methodologies
can help the cause of cultural psychology, what can be learned about the research skills that different
research environments demand, and what kinds of inequalities hinder a more fruitful exchange of
knowledge within the psychological community.
Keywords: indigenous psychology, cultural psychology, historiography, ethnocentrism, Indian theories
about self-concepts, hybridity, third space

The current psychological literature on the rela- had an impact on psychology’s cultural turn in the
tionship between culture and the human psyche dif- twentieth century (Jahoda, 1982; 1992)
ferentiates between subdisciplines and/or approaches b. cross-cultural psychology, which emerged
on the basis of their historical lines of development, from psychological anthropology and has always
their basic theoretical assumptions, and the research been inclined toward mainstream psychology’s
methods they consider appropriate for the investiga- nomothetic/quantitative approach and an
tion of the psychological role of culture. Although experimental paradigm in which culture is treated
their historical lines of development can be traced like just another quasi-independent variable
back quite far into the history of thought, when it (Berry et al., 2011)
comes to the historical impact of the approaches c. Soviet Russian cultural historical
and their scientific merits and the number of schol- psychology, which helped uncover the role of the
ars representing these fields, the following subdisci- contextual dependence of human psychological
plines and/or approaches may be named the most development and the complex process of the
influential: cultural mediation of meaning through social
interaction (Vygotsky, 1930/1978; Wertsch, 1985)
a. psychological anthropology, a research d. cultural psychology, which (in its current
tradition that introduced psychological theories and form) owes much of its interdisciplinary character,
methods into cross-cultural scientific field work and its focus on the “meaning making process” in

71
human action and experience, to the Soviet school indigenous and cultural psychology bear a strong
and is also characterized by its corresponding family resemblance. In the next step, I will present
preference for qualitative and interpretative some of the main features and goals of indigenous
methods (e.g., Boesch, 1991, 1996; Bruner, 1987, psychology as they are portrayed by prominent rep-
1991; Chakkarath & Straub, in press; Cole, 1996; resentatives of the field. There, I will also take the
Lonner & Hayes, 2007; Ratner, 2002; Shweder, opportunity to critically comment on that portrayal
1990; Valsiner, 2009) and to add to it. Drawing on examples from Indian
e. indigenous psychology, which shares many psychology (and contrasting them with stereotypical
perspectives with cultural psychology, but (in its views that are deeply embedded in Western accounts
current form) resulted from the dissatisfaction with of the “Asian” and the “Indian psyche”), I will then
the historically and politically rooted dominance of try to illustrate the impact indigenous psychological
certain other psychological disciplines (including theories can have on various aspects of human devel-
cultural psychology) and the frequently insufficient opment and why this should have the attention of
expertise of their representatives when pursuing psychology in general. Finally, in the same line, I will
their goals in other cultural contexts than their summarize the potential of an indigenous approach
own (e.g., Chakkarath, in press; Ho, 1998; Kim & to improve and refine the foundations and state of
Berry, 1993; Kim, Yang, & Hwang, 2006). the art of cultural psychology.

Taken together, these fields are frequently and Cross-Cultural, Cultural, and Indigenous
collectively referred to as “culture-sensitive,” “cul- Psychology: A Historical Sketch
ture-inclusive,” or “culture-informed” psychology. A Critical View of the Mainstream
Although they consider themselves culture-sensi- Historiography of Psychology
tive, they nonetheless vary as regards the extent to The mainstream historiography of psychology,
which they agree or disagree that (1) psychology particularly as written by Western historiographers,
should follow the nomothetic paradigm of the nat- portrays psychology as a comparatively young sci-
ural sciences and (2) the established methodologi- entific discipline rooted in the scientific enthusiasm
cal standards and procedures of natural scientific of eighteenth century’s European Enlightenment
psychology will enable us to deal with the psycho- and institutionalized at Western universities in the
logical role of cultural phenomena. It is also the late nineteenth century. This narrow, Eurocentric,
extent of agreement or disagreement with these and misleading but dominant historical view stems
positions that determines whether the positions from a characterization of psychology not based
mentioned above consider themselves to be more a on its broad range of research topics and questions
subdiscipline or an alternative, new conception of but primarily on its quantitatively oriented research
mainstream psychology—that is, a new paradigm methods. These methods were devised by early
for doing psychological research and analysis. scholars of the field in accordance with Descartes’,
In the following, I will focus on the latest of the Newton’s, and Boyle’s models of rigorous science as
culture-inclusive approaches to psychology: indig- exemplified by then modern astronomy, physics,
enous psychology. I will try to characterize its self- and chemistry. Thus, observation, experiments, and
understanding and to evaluate its potential to refine the quantitative processing of data were regarded
the approach of cultural psychology, the discipline it as the via regia to discover the universal natu-
is most closely related to. In doing so, I will first sketch ral, rationally understandable laws governing the
the historical development of indigenous psychology human psyche. The year in which Wilhelm Wundt
and its historical relationship to cultural and cross- established the first “Institute for Experimental
cultural psychology. I am not beginning this chapter Psychology” at the University of Leipzig, 1879, is
with a historical sketch merely to follow academic commonly marked as the founding year of psy-
convention but, rather, to show that even the histo- chology as a science. However, Wundt himself had
riography of psychology, including culture-informed a far less reductionist idea of psychology in mind.
psychology, reveals shortcomings that are interesting Rather, he proposed a culture-inclusive and mul-
for our understanding of the importance of perspec- timethodological psychology that he called “dual
tives from indigenous psychology. That will also help psychology” and that was meant to do justice to
to show why the relationship between indigenous the investigation of man as a natural as well as a
and cross-cultural psychology is so distant while cultural being. Thus, his conception represents the

72 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


variety of topics and approaches that were to be One of the leading proponents of that criticism
found even in the nineteenth-century beginnings was Giambattista Vico. At the beginning of the eigh-
of psychology far more appropriately than com- teenth century, Vico (1725/1968) laid the ground
mon historiography does (Wundt, 1900–1920). for a social scientific theory that did not conceive
For the history of the more recent culture-sensitive of human beings as simply mechanically function-
subdisciplines and approaches to psychology, it is ing entities, as proposed within the mathematical
particularly significant that nineteenth-century psy- framework of the natural sciences. Vico stressed
chology (along with philology, philosophy, anthro- that the human realm is not ruled exclusively by
pology, sociology, religious studies, and others) was foreseeable regularities but much more by circum-
among the very first institutionalized disciplines to stance, coincidence, opportunity, chance, and a
apply a culturalistic perspective to the social sci- wide range of complex psychological phenomena
ences (Jahoda, 2011). The same perspective showed like love, hatred, courage, fear, indecision, capri-
up in Wundt’s conception of a culture-integrative ciousness, heedlessness, and fantasy. This complex-
psychology to which he dedicated the 10 volumes of ity cannot be described and understood in terms of
his Folk Psychology (Völkerpsychologie). Within that modern physics or any other kind of methodologi-
framework, Wundt, one of the founders of physi- cal monism, especially if one considers that nature,
ological and experimental psychology, declared that society, individual, and psyche are interdependent
in addition to investigating the elementary mental and in constant flux. Because humans are capable of
processes using natural scientific methods, psychol- giving meaning to things, events, themselves, and
ogy also needed to investigate the higher or more the historical dimensions of the world and their
complex processes and products of the mind like existence, they need to be understood in their own
language, religion, myths, art, and social practices. terms and by using methods that allow us to analyze
Because these higher mental processes are histori- the processes and structures of the individual as well
cally shaped, creative, and dynamic phenomena that as the collective production of meaning.
cannot be brought under control in a laboratory, As this short recapitulation of an influential line
psychology, according to Wundt, needed to avail of thought in the history of social science and psy-
itself of knowledge and methods from the social chology shows, it is not as clear as many historiogra-
sciences and the humanities as well (Diriwächter, phers of psychology suggest why the natural science
2011). Terminologically and intellectually, Wundt’s paradigm became so powerful in twentieth-century
conception of folk psychology reflected an influen- psychology. They propose that culture as a psy-
tial tradition of social scientific thought that found chological topic was not taken seriously before the
its well-documented expression even earlier in the twentieth century, before psychological instruments
Journal of Folk Psychology and Linguistics (Zeitschrift were used in anthropology, before the Russian
für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft) founded school of Vygotsky investigated the influence of
by Moritz Lazarus and Heymann Steinthal in 1860. socio-cultural aspects on human development, and
The journal served as an interdisciplinary panel for before cross-cultural psychology—the nomothetic
psychologists, linguists, anthropologists, ethnolo- approach to culture-inclusive psychology—was for-
gists, and historians, all with a common interest mally acknowledged as a subdiscipline of psychol-
in the investigation of different languages, myths, ogy. However, highly sophisticated theorizing about
institutions, diffusion processes, thinking and the cultural nature of man has existed for centuries.
communication styles, differences in education If we only identified as beginnings those that fol-
and learning, personal and interpersonal percep- low natural science models, we would be ignor-
tion as well as in the dynamic and reciprocal effects ing previous theorizing and the quality thereof.
within all these domains. Thus, this early concep- This momentous decision, however, could remain
tion of a culture-inclusive psychology embraced incomprehensible if the factors leading to the self-
topics and perspectives that could be traced back understanding of our discipline and the cultural
to scholars as different as Johann Gottfried von narrations about its development are not investi-
Herder and Wilhelm von Humboldt. These schol- gated using a cultural and indigenous psychological
ars themselves can be seen in a line of thought that approach. To my knowledge, such an analysis of the
arose as a critical assessment of the adequacy of mainstream historiography of psychology has never
the Newtonian paradigm for the field of the social been conducted. However, it would help us under-
sciences. stand why important contributions to the changed

ch a kka rath 73
and much more diverse field that now makes up neighboring peoples and European foreigners), and
what we call “psychology” were overlooked and did information about the geophysical environment,
not find the recognition they deserve. In the follow- including flora and fauna. The product was his
ing, I will provide a short example of early contri- Historia general de las cosas de Nueva España, later
butions to our field of research that foreshadowed known as Florentine Codex, a bilingual opus written
many of the topics, theories, and methodologies at in Nahuatl and Spanish, supplemented by hundreds
the core of approaches like cultural and indigenous of ethnographic illustrations and various comments
psychology. by Sahagún himself (Leon-Portilla, 2002).
Sahagún was not the only missionary who
Missionaries as Forerunners of Cultural refined social scientific fieldwork in the sixteenth
and Indigenous Psychology century. Many examples can also be taken from the
When the Age of Discovery began in the late Jesuits’ approach to intercultural perspective-taking.
fifteenth century and European overseas expansion In China, for example, they further developed their
led to the rise of colonial empires in remote parts accommodation method: They acquired profound
of the world, there was an increase in reports and general and intellectual knowledge of the host soci-
reflections on non-European cultures, expedited ety, dressed, behaved, and talked like the members
by the introduction of Gutenberg’s printing press. of the various Chinese societal groups— especially
Interestingly, at a time when Christian mission was the literate elite because they were the ones most
closely linked to European imperialism, the main interested in the Western scientific knowledge that
progress in the attempt to methodically investigate the Jesuits were able to offer and that served as a
foreign cultures and their members was achieved by common ground of understanding on which the
sixteenth-century missionaries. Perhaps the most missionary work could be built. The Jesuits applied
impressive account in this regard was given by the psychological assumptions in the field of intercul-
Franciscan Bernardino de Sahagún in Mexico. tural communication. Instead of simply trying to
Sahagún studied at the University of Salamanca, convey Christian concepts and beliefs to the Chinese,
the birthplace of modern Western linguistics and they tried to find out what field of knowledge their
philology. He was therefore very much aware of Chinese interaction partners were especially inter-
the complex problems involved in spreading the ested in, what they had already contributed to that
word of the Gospel among the natives who only field, and what kind of Western knowledge could
spoke Nahuatl and were unable to understand serve as a valuable contribution to the Chinese
Spanish, Latin, or any other European language. body of knowledge. Thus, they first tried to identify
So Sahagún, who was to stay two-thirds of his culture-specific intellectual interests that promised a
long life in Mexico, trained some of the natives in successful intercultural exchange and then took that
Spanish and field observation, had them interview exchange as a starting point for further exchange
indigenous experts, and took the data collected as on various levels and topics, including religion and
well as data from his own observations as a starting philosophy. One famous example of this method
point for the construction of questionnaires writ- was Jesuit missionary Matteo Ricci’s “Treatise on
ten in Nahuatl. He selected three groups of Nahua Mnemonic Arts,” which he wrote to teach Western
experts from three different regions, who studied memorization techniques to the Chinese. Ricci,
the data collected and confirmed that the testimo- who had studied the Chinese and their languages for
nies Sahagún had gathered were authentic and not more than a decade before writing his book, chose
biased by Christian or Spanish attitudes or points of this topic cognizant of the importance of memoriz-
view. He sorted the information into three catego- ing vast amounts of text from the Chinese classics
ries or main themes: information related to gods, when preparing to apply for a position in Chinese
religious beliefs, and religious practice; informa- civil service administration. At least in Ricci’s case,
tion related to the “human sphere”; and informa- the Chinese nobility and literati welcomed his
tion related to “facts of nature.” It took Sahagún efforts and—as he had expected—became inter-
decades to complete his project of documenting ested in learning more about Western and Christian
the indigenous perspectives on religion, history, thinking in general.
aspects of social life (e.g., characterizations of good Like Sahagún, many of these missionaries
and bad qualities in parents as well as children, the developed outstanding approaches to methodi-
respondents’ perceptions of others—for example, cally investigating a foreign culture to understand

74 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


how people from that culture view and understand • Compared to Western psychological thinking
the world. They learned the languages of the cul- and research, as it was laid down in the nineteenth
tures they were staying in fluently, became familiar century within the framework of the laboratory-
with the natives’ oral and written traditions, and based experimental and nomothetic paradigm, all
employed the method of long-term interactive previous thinking and research of a psychological
and non-interactive observation in manifold ways. nature is prescientific.
Although these missionaries’ main goal was always • The academic institutionalization of culture-
to promote their faith and to persuade the natives sensitive psychology became possible as soon
to convert to Christianity, the methods they used to as psychology conceived of culture as one more
achieve this goal were culture-sensitive and rooted independent variable within an experimental
in the methodological, hermeneutical, and psycho- or quasi-experimental research design. Because
logical question about how beliefs, worldviews, and that—at least as a broader movement—did not
concepts can be translated into the meaning sys- take place before the twentieth century, all earlier
tems of a foreign culture without naively tapping approaches to the psychological investigation of
into the pitfalls of ethnocentrism. Thus, these mis- the relationship between culture and humans were,
sionaries became forerunners of cultural anthro- scientifically speaking, inadequate and unsuitable.
pology, ethnolinguistics, and cultural psychology. • The history of psychology is a success
In so far as they were interested in the indigenous story of scientific progress. Within this linear
cultures and mindsets of their members, they were understanding of progress, it seems that culture-
also pursuing one of the main goals of indigenous sensitive psychology developed from prescientific
psychology: acknowledging that scientific theories speculation during the Early Modern Age, to naïve
have a certain cultural and historical range and that conceptions of “folk psychology” in the nineteenth
in many cases they may not provide the concepts, century, to the testing and measuring procedures
the methodological equipment, or the intercultural within psychological anthropology at the turn of
competence to adequately deal with the foreign the twentieth century, and finally to cross-cultural
and the others. psychology, the nomothetic approach of culture-
Not surprisingly, the Catholic Church crit- informed psychology.
icized many of the missionary field workers for • Against this background, cultural psychology
their attempts to combine Catholic tenets with ele- then appears to be a new and critical endeavor
ments of the indigenous (e.g., Nahua or Confucian) that, just a couple of decades ago, resulted from
belief systems. Sahagún’s work, for example, was dissatisfaction with cross-cultural psychology’s ways
not published until the early nineteenth century. of dealing with the topic of culture.
The Spanish inquisition prevented the publication, • Finally, indigenous psychology appears to
because—willingly or unwillingly—it attested to a be the latest of the branches of culture- sensitive
remarkably high level of civilization of the Nahua psychology and seems to have its beginnings within
people and their culture, even before their conver- the academic post-Colonial protest movement
sion to Christianity. Moreover, because Sahagún’s against imperialistically imposed (culture-
emic approach had allowed the indigenous peo- insensitive) guidelines and standards of the best
ple to convey their own views, the 12 volumes of way to do culture-informed psychology.
the Florentine Codex contained depictions of the
Spanish that were not altogether favorable. After As the few examples given above have shown, and as
publication, it contributed to that century’s cul- I tried to show in more detail elsewhere (Chakkarath,
turalist perspectives in the social sciences but was 2003), this historiographical account is unconvinc-
mainly ignored by the historiography of the social ing. Essential features of both cultural and indig-
sciences, including the historiography of psychol- enous psychology can be traced back at least to the
ogy, even of culture-inclusive psychology. culture-informed scientific fieldwork performed in
the sixteenth century, shortly after Europe’s discov-
Historiography and Scientific Importance ery of distant cultures in the West and the East. Thus,
of an Indigenous Psychological Perspective achievements by researchers like Sahagún and Ricci
Western historiographies convey a number of took place far before the scientific revolution and
assumptions about culture-sensitive psychology, far before the culturalization of the social sciences in
including the following: the nineteenth century. Scholars like Vico, Herder,

ch a kka rath 75
and Humboldt emphasized early that humans, historical contexts might foster different paths of
because they are social, cultural, and self-conscious individual and social development, including the
beings who give meaning to their lives, actions, and development of scientific thinking. These differ-
beliefs, cannot be scientifically investigated within ences could include the concept of development,
the experimental and mathematical-statistical para- which is not necessarily as tightly linked to the con-
digm of modern physics. Against this history of cept of science as it is in the dominating Western
ideas, nomothetic approaches to the investigation of traditions of thought. Concepts like these might
the cultural dimension of the human psyche do not function as thinking caps, which might be useful
appear to be a plausible consequence of consecu- in a certain regard but might also be a hindrance
tive linear steps toward cross-cultural psychology. to a sounder understanding of the psychological
Rather, nineteenth-century psychology can be seen meaning of culture in the world of meaning-making
as an interruption of a scientific tradition that fore- humans (Bruner, 1987; 1991). It might also prevent
shadowed core positions and methodological con- us from identifying and acknowledging valuable
victions held by cultural and indigenous psychology contributions to our discipline because having a cer-
until today. tain mindset prevents us, for example, from expect-
With regard to the psychological aspects of his- ing contributions to culture-sensitive science from
toriography and what is usually called “scientific missionaries and within the early times of Western
progress,” there are some interesting lessons to be colonialism. Moreover, the evaluation of the qual-
learned that can be related to important theories of ity of these contributions—especially within a
the philosophy of science and moreover to Wundt’s culture-specific understanding of development and
idea of a dual psychology. Like Herbert Butterfield progress—might be guided by presentist judgments
(1949), Michael Polanyi, and Stephen Toulmin (i.e., by measuring achievements of the past against
(1961) before him, it was especially Thomas Kuhn our current understanding of proper science). This
(1970) who tried to explain scientific progress— is not only true in diachronic perspective—that is,
that is, the success of certain paradigms over the genesis of science over time in its own culture
others—by drawing upon concepts taken from as well as in other cultures—but also in synchronic
cognitive and social psychology. His model of para- perspective (e.g., with regard to judgments about
digmatic change makes use of Butterfield’s theory different current approaches within a given cul-
about “mental transpositions” that take place when ture as well as across cultures). Here, we also have
scientists—primarily in times of considerable and to face one of the most problematic impediments
rapid social change—put on new “thinking-caps” when dealing with the psychological investigation
that help them to assess various phenomena in a of culture: culturally and historically embedded ste-
new way so that they can still be interpreted and reotypes about “us” and the “others,” and the dense
understood although the contextual conditions and bundle of stereotypes known as ethnocentrism
familiar frameworks of thinking might be chang- (Chakkarath, 2010c).
ing. Kuhn uses the term gestalt switch to describe It should be clear that the psychological inves-
the change within the cognitive process that sup- tigation of these aspects in a culture-sensitive way
ports the paradigmatic change. We could also call it can profit considerably from conceiving of certain
a change within the scientist’s mindset. traditions of doing psychology as indigenous tradi-
If we take this psychological view on the history tions. Of course, that includes Western psychology
and the historiography of psychology seriously, it and all its subdisciplines as well and is not chal-
becomes obvious that this perspective is an essential lenged by Western psychology’s claim that it is
aspect of what Wundt called the “higher” mental fac- oriented toward universalism because (1) the fre-
ulties and processes of our mind, which he—in line quent reiteration of its claim of universal validity
with Vico, Herder, Humboldt, Lazarus, Steinthal, might be one of its many indigenous features, and
and others—wanted to be investigated so that we (2) even most non-Western conceptions of psychol-
would understand the inter-relationship between ogy that we know of share the very same claim. A
onto- and phylogenesis and between the individual closer look at some of the key features of current
psyche and the social and cultural conditions of its indigenous psychology as well as some examples
functioning and development. Moreover, this per- from Indian psychology, which I will present in
spective demands a culture-sensitive approach to the next section of this chapter, will help illustrate
investigation because different socio-cultural and these points.

76 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


As a first result, we should keep in mind that indigenous psychologists share many of critical psy-
only a proper historiography of psychology can chology’s point of views, the topic of power and how
help us understand the development of cultural and it has been exercised in spreading Western psychol-
indigenous psychology (Pickren, 2009), and that, ogy all over the world plays a much more important
at the same time, it is an indigenous psychological role in the indigenous psychology literature. Thus, it
perspective that can help us develop that kind of is not surprising that indigenous psychology, at least
historiography. It is also an indigenous psychologi- in this regard, echoes the main themes of postcolo-
cal perspective that helps to arrive at a sounder and nial studies, which frequently reflect on the lasting
culturally informed understanding of psychology as psychological effects of colonialism, including the
a cultural construction (Marsella, 2009) and its role role of science as one of colonialism’s most effective
in shaping the cultural and mental frameworks of instruments. Within the latest discussions of indige-
our thoughts, feelings, and behavior. nous psychology, the question of power with respect
to various levels of human relationships is a crucial
Indigenous Psychology one. Critical psychology and cultural psychology
The Recent Development of Indigenous have been focusing more closely on intracultural
Psychology aspects of unequal power distribution—for exam-
Indigenous psychology is a term that characterizes ple, debates about appropriate scientific approaches
the latest approach within culturally informed or (and the dominance of quantitative methods) or
culture-sensitive psychology that aims to deal more gender-related issues. Indigenous psychology adds a
appropriately with the relationship between culture focus to the intercultural, international, and global
and the human psyche. Although frequently the effects of power (e.g., the role and effects of colo-
beginning of indigenous psychology is associated nialism, Eurocentrism, and scientific hegemony).
with the books and articles that first started using the Apart from this specific point of view, indigenous
term in the 1970s, as we saw in the historical sketch psychologists and cultural psychologists often cite
given above, key elements of the approach can be the same intellectual sources. Thus, the contributions
traced back much further, at least to the theoretical of Jerome Bruner and Ernst Boesch, the founders
and methodological attempts of certain sixteenth- of twentieth-century cultural psychology, also play
century missionaries to make learning about the a prominent role in indigenous psychology. This is
perspectives of members of indigenous cultures an especially true for their criticism of mainstream psy-
essential part of empirical social scientific work by chology’s attempt to decontextualize human behav-
letting those members speak for themselves. Within ior, thought, and feelings, an effort that lost sight
the more recent discussions about the status quo of human beings as intentionally acting individuals
of psychology, however, one notices that, at least who are deeply embedded in a complex web of cul-
in Europe, many of the debates within so-called turally mediated meanings from birth on. According
“critical psychology”—especially as initiated by the to this picture, humans are bound to this web and
German psychologist Klaus Holzkamp in the mid- at the same time take part in weaving and modify-
1960s—concerned topics and questions broached ing the web. Although these webs are the scaffolds
by cultural but also by indigenous psychologists. A of what we call culture and are therefore universal,
strong critic of behaviorism, Holzkamp drew upon the structures themselves are different and even vary
the theoretical foundations of the Russian socio-his- within a given society and its subgroups. They also
torical school of psychology and analyzed phenom- vary between people from different regions and
ena like perception, cognition, and motivation as environments and between people with different
historically and culturally shaped concepts of mean- socio-cultural histories, worldviews, and value and
ing. Moreover, his critical psychology also focused belief systems. As we saw above, these contributions
on aspects of power and power differences in rela- to the European history of science were quite early
tionships and society as well as their effect not only and elaborate but were superseded by the paradigm
on the psycho-social well-being of individuals and of natural science as it was promoted by biological
groups but also on the success of certain psycho- and psychological behaviorism.
logical theories. As for the latter, critical psychology Along the lines drawn by critical psychologists
took up many elements of Thomas Kuhn’s analyses and cultural psychologists and dating back at least
of the mechanisms behind what is considered scien- to Vico, scholars from non-European and non-
tific progress. Although cultural psychologists and American countries, many of whom had become

ch a kka rath 77
acquainted with Western psychology during a emphasizing that the Western notion of autonomy,
period of colonialization, began evaluating the which is understood to contrast with dependence,
adequacy of Western psychological theories and is not applicable to the specific make-up of the
procedures for their indigenous populations. One Japanese psyche. Within the amae relationship, the
of the first attempts to contrast a specific national mother exercises a maximum of indulgence and care
psychology with mainstream (especially U.S. that, according to Doi, serves as the basis for the
American) psychology was Berry’s (1974) portrait child’s efforts to become an autonomous person in
of a “Canadian psychology.” A few years later, the Japanese sense. According to Western attach-
Rieber (1977) used the term indigenous psychology ment theory, an overprotective mother hinders
to describe early nineteenth-century attempts to her child’s autonomy development and is therefore
develop an American psychology that would fit the evaluated as problematic. However, the Japanese
genuine socio-historical and intellectual context mother experiences herself as warranting her child’s
of the United States. Interestingly, however, most positive development, which makes her feel fulfilled
assessments in this direction came from countries and happy. Doi thus questions Western attach-
that were not usually represented in the samples of ment theory’s characterizations and categorizations
mainstream psychology: the so-called “WEIRD” of secure as opposed to insecure types of children
samples of Western, Educated, Industrialized, and mother–child relationships. He then uses his
Rich, and Democratic societies (Henrich, Heine, analyses to develop a more general theory on the
& Norenzayan, 2010). Sinha (1969, 1984, 1986) indigenous specifics of the Japanese understanding
documented the necessity of indigenizing Western of individuality, autonomy, responsibility, freedom,
psychology to fit the people and their specific cul- and self, thereby showing the broader relevance of
tural environments in India; Doi (1973) and Azuma amae for a deeper psychological understanding of
(1986) followed suit in Japan, Diaz-Guerrero (1977) the Japanese culture and its members.
in Mexico, Enriquez (1977, 1978, 1990, 1993) in Some of the main aspects of Doi’s theory, espe-
the Philippines, Ho (1982, 1998) in China and cially his insistence on the strictly indigenous and
other East-Asian countries, Yang (1986, 2000) in unique nature of self-development in Japan, have
Taiwan, and Kim (Kim & Berry, 1993, Kim, 2001; been criticized (e.g., Yamaguchi & Ariizurni,
Kim, Yang, & Hwang, 2006) in the Republic of 2006). Nonetheless, his assessment that the range
Korea. Moreover, Indigenous Psychologies was also of Western attachment theory is culturally restricted
the title of a frequently cited collection of essays was also welcomed within Western psychology
documenting the early attention that the approach (Rothbaum & Morelli, 2005) and psycho-analysis
received at the interface of anthropology and psy- (e.g., Johnson, 1993) and thus serves as one of
chology (Heelas & Lock, 1981). only a few examples of the success of a non-West-
Of the earlier publications mentioned above, ern theory in Western psychology. Like Doi, other
some not only request modifications of Western researchers, including cross-cultural, cultural, and
approaches to make them fit non-Western contexts indigenous psychologists, identified concepts they
and subjects, but they also doubt the general scientific believed to be culture-specific—that is, indigenous
value of some core Western concepts when it comes (for a list of researchers, countries, and examples, see
to merely understanding psychological phenom- Kim, Yang, & Hwang, 2006). Similarly, the fields of
ena in certain cultures. The probably best-known cultural psychiatry and counseling have identified
example of this challenge to Western psychology indigenous features of mental illness and therapy as
is Takeo Doi’s (1973) criticism of Western attach- well as different attitudes toward the “abnormal” in
ment theory and his assumption that the Japanese different cultures (Gielen, Fish, & Draguns, 2004;
concept of amae represents a culture-specific form Pedersen, Draguns, Lonner, & Trimble, 2002)
of interpersonal behavior and related personal feel- that are of interest for indigenous psychological
ings that can only be understood within the seman- perspectives. Taken together, the sum of examples
tics of the Japanese language. He offered various and the perspectives taken by some authors might
approximate translations (e.g., “indulgent depen- create the impression that indigenous psychology
dency” or “craving for affection”) that are meant to advocates a strong cultural relativism that shows up
describe the unique relationship between Japanese when, for example, the term indigenous psychology
mothers and their children and that he sums up as is replaced by indigenous psychologies. However, as
“personal freedom within safety and dependence,” we will see, this may only be true for a minority

78 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


of psychologists, even for a minority of those who Whereas that book focused on the “anthropology
would call themselves indigenous psychologists. All of the self,” a later book edited by Enriquez (1990)
in all, one can state that indigenous psychology is presented the first collection of international essays
currently undergoing a phase of self-discovery as addressing a larger number of more genuinely psy-
can be seen in the special issue of Applied Psychology: chological topics (with a clear emphasis, however,
An International Review (1999) as well as in the vari- on “Filipino psychology”), thus documenting the
ety of topics and methodological approaches docu- broad spectrum of a field that the title of the book
mented in the Asian Journal of Social Psychology, the identified as Indigenous Psychology. Three years
journal of the Asian Association of Social Psychology later, Kim and Berry (1993) published a volume
(AASP), which was founded in 1995. A special with a title focusing again on numerous Indigenous
issue published in 2000 documents the historical, Psychologies. Their book gained more recognition,
philosophical, and methodological debates that probably in part because the selection of topics as
have continued since then (e.g., see Greenfield, well as the higher number of authors from different
2000; Jing & Fu, 2001; Kim, 2001; Kim, Park, countries showed that the movement had already
& Park 2000; Moghaddam, 1987; Shams, 2002; gained momentum. In the introduction to that
Shweder, 2000; Sinha, 1998; Triandis, 2000; Yang, book, the editors suggested that we conceive of
2000; see also the additional special issues on indig- indigenous psychologies “as the scientific study of
enous psychologies of Australian Psychologist, 2000, human behavior (or the mind) that is native, that
Asian Journal of Psychology, 2005, The Psychologist, is not transported from other regions, and that is
2005, and the International Journal of Psychology, designed for its people” (Kim & Berry, 1993, p. 2).
2005 and 2006). The manifold spectrum of the Although this definition gives us a glimpse of the
field is also well-documented in two books edited direction of impact the investigation of indigenous
by Kim and Berry (1993) and Kim, Yang, and psychologies might have on mainstream psychol-
Hwang (2006). Although both publications show ogy’s claim of universal validity, it also raises ques-
that the movement is represented by psychologists tions about the character and aims of indigenous
from many corners of the world, they also show the psychologies. First, it is almost impossible to verify
striking number of Asian psychologists among its whether a tradition of psychological study was solely
prominent spokespeople. For example, the increas- developed within a given region and only for the
ing role of indigenous psychology in India is tell- people of that region. From what we know about
ingly documented in the so-called “Pondicherry the history of science, we may assume that scientific
Manifesto of Indian Psychology” (2002). Signed knowledge—as almost any cultural achievement—
by 160 Indian psychologists in 2002 (among them has been spread across regions and cultures since
some of the most prominent Indian researchers), the beginning of scientific thinking. We may also
the manifesto characterizes psychology in India as assume that one of the reasons why the diffusion of
a “western transplant, unable to connect with the psychological knowledge across cultural boundar-
Indian ethos and concurrent community condi- ies was frequently successful is that various cultures
tions (. . .) by and large imitative and replicative of found at least some of the foreign psychological
western studies, lacking in originality and unable to theories applicable to themselves. So it seems more
cover or break any new ground” (p. 168). Also, the plausible that in many cases we are dealing with
first International Conference of Indigenous and indigenous psychologies that resulted from import
Cultural Psychology was held in Asia (Indonesia) and indigenization. We need to remember that, for
in 2010. On that occasion, the Asian Association of most of history, human societies did not develop
Indigenous and Cultural Psychology was launched and psychologies solely for themselves and that many
the publication of the Asian Journal of Indigenous societies were willing and quite flexible in inte-
and Cultural Psychology announced. grating foreign knowledge into an already existing
indigenous body of knowledge. The readiness of
On the Current State of Indigenous European regions to import U.S. American psy-
Psychology chology since the early twentieth century is a very
As mentioned above, the first book entitled prominent example of the continuity of this devel-
Indigenous Psychologies (Heelas & Lock, 1981) was opment. However, a process in which indigenous
published in the early 1980s and combined perspec- psychologies were designed hermetically within a
tives from cultural anthropology and psychology. specific region and only for that region’s people,

ch a kka rath 79
and then exported into the regional and cultural of groups in developed Western societies nor the
contexts of other people, would have to be con- plethora of cultures and subcultures distributed
sidered an imposition. A prominent example of across the world.
this kind of process—at least if we take the criti- 3. Indigenous psychology advocates the use
cal assessment by many Asian, African, and Latin of multiple methods and various research designs
American psychologists seriously—is the export and does not consider an exclusively quantitative
of psychology during European imperialism and research design appropriate for dealing with a
colonization (Holdstock, 2000; Howitt & Owusu- variety of cultural environments and subjects.
Bempah, 1994; Moghaddam, 1987; Paranjpe, 4. Indigenous psychology considers a close
2002). Moreover, with regard to the validity and cooperation between “insiders” and “outsiders”—
reach of psychological theories, the definition of that is, the conflation of internal and external
indigenous psychologies as given above suggests a views, a sine qua non for the development of
certain relativist position that, according to some integrative theories about the relationship between
researchers in this field, actually became quite culture and individuals.
influential. 5. Psychologists within mainstream Western
A third collection of essays (Indigenous and psychology have been testing the hypotheses
Cultural Psychology) edited by Kim, Yang, and that are based on Western samples using new
Hwang (2006) documents the development of samples in foreign cultures. Thus, they have
indigenous psychology since then and its state of mainly been testing the ethnocentrically biased,
the art in the early twenty-first century. In part, the ready-made psychological theories formulated by
title signals how the issues mentioned above entered the specific sample of psychologists they belong
the discussion about the character and goals of the to. Indigenous psychology acknowledges that
discipline. Instead of highlighting several indig- individuals in all cultures have a complex and
enous psychologies, the title advocates one indig- developed, practical and episodic, understanding of
enous psychology—that is, it focuses more on one themselves. However, most of them are not trained
overarching conceptual and scientific approach than academically to identify and describe the structures
on multiple traditions of psychological thinking. In and processes that are the grounds for the
addition, the title (as does the whole book) empha- development of such understandings. It is therefore
sizes indigenous psychology’s familial relationship the task of indigenous psychology to translate and
to cultural psychology. arrange the indigenous subjects’ knowledge in a
In light of the debates mentioned above and by way that allows for accurate psychological testing.
extending and modifying Kim and Berry’s (1993, 6. Indigenous psychology pushes for the
pp. 3–4) list of six aspects of indigenous psychol- integration of various perspectives without
ogy, Kim, Yang, and Hwang (2006) provided a advocating various psychologies. In other words,
list of 10 aspects that, against the background of it is not to be equated with cultural relativism
discussions I have portrayed so far, reflect how the but rather with a culture-informed and genuinely
discipline is striving for a clearer scientific profile. integrative psychological approach. At the
I paraphrase: same time, facing the claim that there may be
many examples of indigenous concepts that
1. Indigenous psychology emphasizes the need do not have an equivalent translation in other
to investigate psychological phenomena in their languages, indigenous psychology aims to verify
specific ecological, historical, and socio-cultural the psychological relevance of these concepts.
contexts. In this regard, it has two complementary goals:
2. It does not, as the term might suggest and to identify truly indigenous psychological
as many of the leading cultural and psychological phenomena and, at the same time, to more
anthropologists of the twentieth century did, thoroughly test psychological theories that claim
concentrate on the investigation of so-called universal validity.
“exotic” people in distant regions of the world. 7. Although there are attempts to stress the
Rather, it aims to investigate all cultural and ethnic relevance of philosophies, religions, and other
groups. Of course, this includes the WEIRD worldviews within indigenous psychology,
samples, but it recognizes them as only one very indigenous psychology should not be equated with
specific sample that neither reflects the variety a thought tradition of a specific culture. To prove

80 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


that any given thought tradition has psychological of cultural relativism has been held by or attrib-
relevance, its hypotheses need to be translated into uted to many different prominent social scientists
psychological concepts and empirically tested. (e.g., Franz Boas, Margaret Mead, Ruth Benedict,
8. Humans are culturally shaped agents of their Clifford Geertz, Kenneth Gergen, Richard Shweder)
culture who themselves stabilize as well as change and has played and still plays an important role as
it. They are the subjects as well as the objects of a heuristic and critical tool in cultural anthropology
psychological research who not only possess insight as well as other cultural sciences. It is not an unsci-
into their inner and outer worlds but also send and entific position, but one that characterizes specific
receive communications about their and others’ traditions and schools, cultures of scientific think-
insights. To deal with this complexity adequately, ing, so to speak. As such, from a scientific point of
researchers must integrate the perspectives taken view, it is nothing to worry about (contrary to the
by all individuals participating in the interactions reservations of prominent cross-cultural psycholo-
under investigation, including their own scientific gists like Poortinga, 1999, and Triandis, 2000) but,
perspective. rather, something we need to deal with scientifically
9. Indigenous psychology supports an (Geertz, 1984). Moreover, if we take the approach
interdisciplinary approach to the investigation called indigenous psychology seriously, we should
of culture. It should be clear that, by definition, be open to the possibility that we may find psycho-
any culture-informed psychology should take logical phenomena that can only be found in certain
advantage of knowledge provided by other cultures and contexts or that function differently
scientific disciplines (e.g., sociology, anthropology, across cultures—that is, play a different role for dif-
philosophy, philology, the science of religion, ferent people who are embedded in different webs
history). of meaning. We would then call these phenomena
10. Finally, according to indigenous psychology, indigenous. If, however, indigenous psychology is
indigenization from without can be as useful not open to that perspective and considers itself an
and necessary as indigenization from within. approach that is exclusively interested in universals,
“Indigenization from without” refers to the then it becomes a mere complimentary science to
importation of already existing psychological mainstream psychology and I am not sure if that
theories and methods into another culture and would fit its self-understanding.
the process of their adaptation to the cultural The list given above also shows an ambivalent
and environmental specificities of the other attitude toward the role of religions and other
culture. “Indigenization from within” refers to the worldviews. On the one hand, it emphasizes that
development of theories and methods within a we should not hasten to view historically developed
certain culture, based on indigenous knowledge; worldviews or any other traditions of thought that
of course, this “internal” knowledge can also somehow address psychological issues as relevant for
be exported to refine general psychological indigenous psychology. On the other hand, many
knowledge. examples of so-called “indigenous concepts” pre-
sented in various studies are embedded in the con-
This characterization of indigenous psychology con- text of religions or other worldviews, which are also
tains key features emphasized by most researchers frequently used to explain certain aspects of human
within the field. However, although certain features thought and behavior. Although it is certainly true
are highlighted, others are not mentioned at all or that we need to prove empirically the psychologi-
downplayed, thus reflecting a certain ambivalence cal relevance of these kinds of theories, it is also
toward particular issues that reflects the differing true that before doing so we need to render more
views held by different researchers. precisely the theories in question and also evaluate
For example, as I mentioned before, the list whether there are indigenous theories of psycho-
attempts to avoid the impression that indigenous psy- logical relevance. Therefore, indigenous psychology
chology advocates cultural relativism, which might should consider as one of its tasks and competen-
be the reason why the term indigenous psychology cies the identification and accurate presentation of
is favored over the term indigenous psychologies. indigenous theories that have hitherto been ignored
However, without going in depth into the fields of by mainstream psychology. In this regard, it is also
the philosophy of science and epistemology, let us important to note that the relevance of these kinds
simply note that in one way or another, the position of indigenous theories should not depend solely on

ch a kka rath 81
their successful translation into the nomenclature of 2002; Straub, 2006). Because the question of what
previously existing theories but on the evaluation of cultural psychology can learn from the indigenous
the role they play within the theory of origin. In approach is at the center of this chapter, it needs to
addition, if indigenous psychology shares the cul- be addressed. However, before I attempt to propose
tural psychologist’s conviction that we need to inves- an answer, I think it would be appropriate to at least
tigate psychological phenomena in their specific give an exemplary sketch of an indigenous psycho-
ecological, historical, and socio-cultural contexts, logical perspective on a key topic of psychology in
then it should acknowledge that these contexts are general, to show how it helps to decrease stereo-
often co-constructed, structured, and considerably typical and ethnocentric perceptions of the “other”
influenced by religions and other worldviews. that are deeply embedded in our cultures, including
Against the background of the socio-historical the sciences, and to show how it might help refine
aspects of psychology and their importance as out- our understanding of the inseparable relationship
lined in the first section of this chapter, let us add between culture and humans, an endeavor that cul-
a final comment: Indigenous psychology should tural and indigenous psychology share.
consider the analysis of psychology’s development
to be one of its main tasks, especially with regard Psychology of the Indian Self: Eurocentric
to indigenous and national but also global aspects. and Indigenous Views
Some researchers highlight the effects of colonialism Stereotypes in the Western View
and the colonialists’ psychology on the people liv- of Asia and India
ing in former colonies and also note that the recent There is a long and influential Western tradi-
emergence of indigenous psychology is related to tion of viewing the regions and peoples living to
post-Colonial reassessments of the socio-cultural the east of Europe, the formerly so-called “Orient”
impact of Western science in general (Bhatia, 2002; and the “Orientals” (Said, 1978/2003)—especially
Marsella, 2009; Moghaddam, 1987; Smith, 1999). “Asia” and the “Asians”—as distinctively different
Others tend to deal with these issues at the periphery from “Europe” and the “Europeans” (Chakkarath,
of their work or even largely ignore them. However, 2010a). The interest of culture-inclusive psychol-
ignorance toward these aspects will fail to do jus- ogy in the comparison of “East” and “West” is still
tice to the goal of properly understanding all aspects salient in many research designs and publications of
involved in human psychological development. cross-cultural and cultural psychology (Ward, 2007)
Therefore, these issues should not be left to histo- and was also the focus of earlier influential contri-
rians, sociologists, and politicians but should be of butions by Western sociology or cultural and psy-
utmost importance to psychologists, especially to chological anthropology. For example, Max Weber’s
psychologists interested in indigenous perspectives. seminal studies on world religions and their mean-
I will return to this characterization of indige- ing for cultural and economic development was to
nous psychology in the last part of the chapter, but a considerable extent a comparison of Western and
now, following this portrayal, I believe it is necessary Eastern rationality and had a profound influence
to raise the question concerning the extent to which on Western scientific assessments of Asian culture
the aims of indigenous psychology listed above differ and psyche. Ruth Benedict’s The Chrysanthemum
from those of cultural psychology. As we saw above and the Sword may have been criticized by many for
in the historical sketch of early culture-sensitive field its “national character” approach and overly simple
research, both the indigenous psychology approach (and somewhat demeaning) dichotomous compari-
and the cultural psychology approach can be traced son of the Japanese “shame culture” with the Western
back to the same historical beginnings. It would go “guilt culture,” but it nonetheless established pat-
beyond the scope of this chapter to list the main terns of comparison that still have a palpable impact
characteristics of cultural psychology, but I will say on cross-cultural comparisons of “Easterners” and
this: I cannot help getting the impression that most “Westerners” (cf. Chakkarath, 2010c).
of the foundational work outlining cultural psy- In culture-inclusive psychological research, the
chology’s program and self-understanding proposes focus of interest is frequently on “self ” and “cog-
a very similar view of humans as culturally shaped nition” (i.e., two central domains of psychological
shapers as well as very similar perspectives on how research in general). These topics, especially with
to proceed methodologically when investigating the regard to self-concepts, have been investigated for
human psyche in a culturally informed way (Ratner, several decades now, ever since Hofstede based his

82 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


individualism–collectivism differentiation on an Herodotus’ Histories from the fifth century BC or
impressively large data pool from more than 40 Pliny’s Natural History from the first century AD).
countries (Hofstede, 1980). This differentiation According to most of these authors, India is a land
has also been discussed among European scholars of miracles and wonders, an image that has survived
since antiquity and regained prominence with the for millennia and that became the basis of India
individual-centered view of man propagated by portraits, especially in the age of Romanticism.
thinkers of the European Renaissance. It also shows Although this portrait is not necessarily pejorative,
up in Triandis’ (2001) differentiation between in many cases it was accompanied by assumptions
ideocentric and allocentric tendencies and Markus about the almost complete “otherness” of Indians
and Kitayama’s (1991) well-established distinction as compared to other peoples of the world. For
between the independent and interdependent self. example, until the Middle Ages, even “monsters”
These and similar theories frequently draw upon (i.e., creatures [like dog-headed men] that bridge
the broader differentiation between Westerners and the gap between animals and humans without
Easterners and also make use of additional dichoto- belonging to either of the two groups were said to
mous constructs like individual orientation versus abound in India, reiterating a topos deeply embed-
group orientation, autonomy versus relatedness, sep- ded in European views about the East; see Jahoda,
aration versus connectedness, high versus low self- 1999). Accordingly, many European travelers like
monitoring, high versus low context dependence, Ludovico di Varthema, who visited the country
stability versus instability, and so forth. Theories in the sixteenth century, interpreted sculptures of
about the underlying cognitive basis of intercul- Indian deities as images of monsters. Even in the
turally varying self-other perceptions and thinking Age of Enlightenment and under the perspectives of
styles also place their bipolar concepts in the frame- philosophical rationalism and empiricism, histori-
work of the geographical East–West dichotomy. cally developed stereotypical ideas about India were
Well-known examples are Nisbett’s The Geography not completely abandoned (Chakkarath, 2010c).
of Thought, in which Western and Chinese cognitive Hegel was only one of many leading European
styles are contrasted (2003) or Peng’s studies on dif- scholars of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries
ferences between U.S. Americans and East Asians who declared these alleged intellectual deficits to be
in perception, interpretation, and reasoning (Peng psychological deficits and related them to societal
& Nisbett, 1999). Against this background, I have deficits,− an enduring thinking pattern that Gergen
chosen the analysis of the self to illustrate how an (1994) identified as a “deficit discourse.” Although
indigenous perspective might increase our culture Hegel’s verdict on the intellectual achievements of
sensitivity in developing psychological theories and Asian cultures was broadly general, he found some
research. The example I am going to present as an gradual differences between different Asian civi-
indigenous psychological discourse is taken from lizations, especially between China and India. In
India and focuses on the academic debate between comparing the Chinese and the Indian cultures,
Hindu and Buddhist scholars about the nature of he claimed that the failure of Indian thinkers to
the self. I will start with a few remarks about some come up with the idea of a stable and autono-
influential stereotypes in the European tradition of mous self was to blame for their failure to build
portraying India and the Indian self before I con- modern, clearly defined, stable, autonomous,
trast these views with indigenous Indian accounts and reliable nation-states like those in Europe or
of the self. that in China. Instead, the almost complete lack
In many of the theories mentioned above, the of proper scientific thinking and the boundless
attributes of a stable, independent, autonomous, and erratic style of Indian self-theories resulted
rational, and responsible self are usually related to in declaring the subject–object difference an illu-
Westerners, whereas attributes deficient in these sion so that neither a concept of individuality or
qualities are usually related to Easterners. This line personality nor a historical consciousness or a con-
of thought can also be found with regard to many ceptualization of individuals as historical persons
European scholars’ view of India, which itself can could arise. Hegel’s account of the psychological
easily be traced back to European antiquity where nature of the Indian self is a diagnosis of deficits,
the earliest written accounts of India and its peo- and as for many scholars after him, including some
ple by “Westerners” can be found in the works of twentieth-century social scientists (e.g., Weber and
Greek and Roman authors (e.g., Ctesias’ Indica and Benedict), it is especially these deficits that allow

ch a kka rath 83
one to differentiate between Westerners and most and needs constitute the root of failure, disappoint-
Easterners, including Indians. ment, frustration, aggression, shame, and many
In the following, let us try to take an indig- other negative states, it follows that the psychologi-
enous psychological perspective on the Indian self cal processes that lead to this fateful condition of
and see the extent to which it confirms or disputes selfishness need to be analyzed, understood, and
core aspects of the Western assessments exemplified controlled. Otherwise—and this is another central
above. To also show the character and quality of aca- conviction in the Hindu belief system—the selfish
demic discourse within indigenous Indian analyses actions and behavior will result in a cycle of end-
of the self, I will first present some key features of less death and rebirth (samsara). The driving force
Hindu traditions of thought and then contrast them behind the process of samsara is believed to be the
with assessments by Buddhist psychology. accumulated sum total of the individual’s good and
bad deeds that Hindus relate to the universal law of
karma. The function of the karma concept can be
Indigenous Views of Self and Identity:
illustrated as follows:
Hindu and Buddhist Perspectives
Hindu beliefs play different roles in the every- Karma can be conceived of as similar to the law
day lives of different Indians—depending espe- of gravity that, metaphorically speaking, “weighs”
cially on the region they live in, their social class, and “judges” the qualities of matter and decides its
caste, gender, and education—but there are central velocity, direction, and place in the universe as well
tenets that most Hindus share (for a more detailed as its function within the larger cosmic order. A
description, see Chakkarath, 2005; in press). One fundamental assumption of this theory is that, like
is the belief in brahman (“eternal universal soul”), matter, psychological phenomena, too, are subject
the all-encompassing life force that embodies all to natural laws. The natural law of karma is believed
aspects of existence and that is reflected in atman to evaluate one’s moral behavior as “good” if one
(“individual self ”), the life force that makes any lives according to the cosmic law of being (dharma).
living being part of brahman. It is a core convic- Because dharma is understood as the representation
tion of Hindu believers that not understanding the of a just world that attributes a precisely defined
relationship between brahman and atman is deeply place and function to everyone and everything, each
problematic because ignorance of the true nature of Hindu must follow certain rules and fulfill specific
this relationship results in suffering. Suffering is the duties, recognizing that selfishness will only harm
underlying principle of all existence, and human that order. This code of conduct that constitutes the
beings are equipped with a cognitive system that is Hindu way of life involves doing what is right for
the main source of human suffering. However, they the individual, the family, the caste (jati), the society,
can be trained to cope with life’s miseries and even and the cosmic order. The rules of conduct were
to overcome them. laid down in various dharma shastras, compilations
The problem of suffering arises especially from of laws that help one to give practical meaning to
the nature of the individual self and the psychologi- the theoretical aspects mentioned above and thus
cal processes that cause its development. In other show that, from a Hindu point of view, there is no
words, it is mainly caused by processes within the real difference between the religious and the social
human psyche: The individual develops the con- spheres. This becomes even clearer in the conviction
viction that he is a unique and separate entity, in that not only one’s membership in a particular caste,
principle unrelated to the rest of the world, which but even the biological, physical, psychological, and
he sees as the “other” sphere of life. Thus, the indi- social conditions of one’s life (whether one ends
vidual constructs an opposition between himself up being a plant, an animal, a demon, or a human
and the world instead of recognizing that all beings being, a member of a higher or a lower caste, male
and things and phenomena of the world, including or female, attractive or unattractive, ambitious or
himself, are reflections of one and the same—that unambitious, more or less intelligent) are decisively
is, brahman. This ignorance is the source of ego- influenced by one’s conduct in one’s previous life.
ism (i.e., unawareness of the interrelatedness and Thus, the whole belief system is metaphysically
interdependence of all existing things) and results legitimized, which makes it possible for anyone to
in selfish behavior, driven by uninhibited emotions, perceive social reality as just and fair, an assessment
greed, the need for a diversified and adventurous that has helped stabilize the Hindu society and the
life, and so forth. Because these kinds of desires caste system for thousands of years.

84 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


Here, we should note that contrary to many the senses and the emotions (e.g., absence of anger).
Western thinkers’ stereotypical assessments of the The model also helps one to train these capabilities:
Indian self, the metaphysically induced, psycho- According to the Yoga system, the best known sys-
logical pressure put on the Hindu to take care of tem of Indian-applied psychology, these capabilities
his psyche actually results in stability, not diffu- correspond to those that constitute the moral pre-
sion. One can easily recognize the importance of a requisite of moksha.
stable self within the Hindu self-theory in the idea Buddhist analyses of the self are partially based
of rebirth: According to the atman concept, there on the Hindu diagnosis that psychological prob-
are core aspects of the individual self that remain lems are caused by cognitive processes. However,
stable and unchanged through all rebirths. Thus, although the Buddhist scholars have maintained
a person’s (immortal) core identity is composed of various elements of the Hindu framework (e.g., the
a kind of matrix into which the sum total of his idea of suffering as the fundamental principle of
karma is entered from birth to birth. This core all being, the concept of karma as well as the belief
identity ensures that much of the responsibility for in samsara and karma-dependent rebirth), there
the current life as well as for the preceding exis- are crucial differences. From early on, Buddhism
tences can be attributed to the individual himself. argued against the idea of an immortal core self
In addition, we should note that following a rigid (atman) that provides personal identity through
normative system of rules and fulfilling one’s spiri- all transmigrations. Similarly to the Hindu self-
tual as well as social duties does not result in world theory, the Buddhist theory of the non-self (anat-
renunciation (as, for example, has been claimed by man) is closely related to psychological theories of
the classical Western sociology of religion, follow- cognition.
ing Max Weber and Louis Dumont) but in com- The Buddhist theory of cognition and self is
mitment to worldly things that need to be taken based on a detailed analysis of the psychophysi-
care of for the sake of societal and universal order cal condition of humans, which is believed to be
as well as for individual satisfaction. This aspect empirically examinable by anyone through system-
is also emphasized in the socially institutionalized atic and regularly executed meditation exercises,
Hindu model of ideal human development (ashra- which play an important role in the Buddhist way
madharma), a four-stage life-span model that aims of life. With respect to contents as well as abstrac-
to help (mainly male) members of society attain tion and systematization level, these analyses rank
the central material, psychological, and spiritual among the most important psychological contribu-
goals that not only reflect the Hindu value system tions of Asian science. Again, I can only describe
but also Hindu psychology’s assessment of human the analyses here very briefly, so what follows is
needs and desires (see Chakkarath, 2005; in press). merely a sketch (for a more detailed description, see
The consecutive goals encompass the acquirement Lamotte, 1988).
of knowledge (including knowledge about one’s rit- At the core of the analyses is the view that a per-
ual and social duties); the accumulation of material son or one’s “I consciousness” is collectively consti-
wealth; the satisfaction of genuine human desires, tuted by the five “aggregates” (skandha):
such as the desire for sexuality, conjugal love, art, fil-
ial affection, fine clothes, savory food and other lux- 1. physical form (rupa), which includes the four
uries; and finally spiritual development and release elements: earth (solidity), water (liquidity), fire
from samsara. The model also suggests at what stage (temperature), and wind (expansion)
in life one should pursue the different goals and 2. sensations and feelings (vedana): unpleasant,
makes clear that human development, including pleasant, or neutral sensations that stem from
cognitive development, does not end with old age contact between the six internal sensory organs
because spiritual goals can be achieved more easily (eyes, nose, ears, tongue, body, and mind) and the
when the need for material and sensual satisfaction corresponding external objects (appearance, smell,
have calmed. Moreover, the model makes clear that sound, taste, touch, and mental object)
possessing specific psychological capabilities are 3. perceptions (sanna): the perception of
especially necessary to pass through the life stages appearance, smell, sound, taste, physical form, and
successfully—namely, knowledge and the readiness spirit
to learn, concentration and truthfulness, honesty, 4. volitional formations (sankhara), from
reason, patience, forgiveness, self-control, control of which the six expressions of will emerge, which

ch a kka rath 85
can be directed toward all of the sensations and to defend the idea that both flames are identical.
perceptions specified above Buddhism declares the Hindu belief in a stable,
5. consciousness (vinnana), consisting of unchanging, and even immortal self an expression
consciousness of the six sensory organs and the of psychologically deeply rooted human selfishness:
external objects assigned to them. It is out of ignorance, fear, weakness, and desire that
man develops the idea of atman to find consolation.
Humans are thus described as an aggregate of dif- Considering itself partially a critical reform move-
ferent mutually causal factors that are in constant ment, from early on, Buddhism aimed to destroy
flux and temporary. The 6 internal sense bases the psychological roots of these kinds of metaphys-
(organs) and their 6 external sense bases (objects) ical beliefs and thus also developed a perspective on
are called the 12 sense bases and, combined with the psychology of psychology and psychologists.
the 6 forms of consciousness, they are called the Although the various schools of Hindu and
18 elements (dhatu). When the physical factors are Buddhist thinking forbid us to make overly gen-
taken into consideration, every mental procedure eral statements about the two traditions, nonethe-
can be described as an entirely specific combina- less, the basic differences in the conceptualizations
tion of these elements among themselves and with of the self may have some explanatory power with
the perception and will phenomena they cause. The regard to differences in certain attitudes favored
key result of this Buddhist analysis is that by means within Hindu and Buddhist conceptualizations of
of this thus restructured and constantly changing the relationship between the self and the “other”
causal structure, the illusion of a “self ” that wit- (Chakkarath, 2010). Although it is not my inten-
nesses all these events is created that does not cor- tion to say that in practice Hindus do not show
respond to anything in reality because this self is compassion for the misery of others, it is still inter-
also only the result of a process that is constantly esting to see that, at least on a theoretical level, the
beginning and ending. Thus, the notion of a per- development of compassion plays a conspicuously
sonal soul or a lasting identity, for example, of the more important role in Buddhism. As we have seen,
baby growing to become an adult or even the dead it is a Hindu conviction that each individual forges
person is refuted. On the one hand, reconstructing his own destiny and that it is the destiny of an igno-
(i.e., interpreting) such convictions as the result of rant and selfish individual to be punished with new
psycho-physical causal relationships provides a way suffering in another life. This view, together with
of explaining the development of an individualistic the Hindu understanding of unchanging personal
self-concept. In addition, we also see why a key fac- identity through all rebirths, is the basis for the
tor of human suffering is seen in this view of self. In idea that, on the whole, samsara provides cosmic
the causal nexus mentioned above, it causes selfish and societal justice. The orthodox Buddhist theory,
attitudes and resultant actions, which lead to nega- however, holds that there is no identity between the
tive karma, which results in rebirth yet again. producer of bad karma and the being that results
The question concerning what can be under- from it (for Vasubandhu’s classic arguments, see
stood by “rebirth” if there is no “soul” with lasting Duerlinger, 2006). This means that in the end,
identity is the most-discussed philosophical ques- the one who is accumulating bad karma is caus-
tion of Buddhist philosophy and metaphysics. The ing suffering for another being. In other words,
perhaps most descriptive and most concise answer, the producer of bad karma is responsible for the
which will have to suffice here, is a parable from creation and suffering of an existence that itself is
the non-canonical text Milindapanha, in which an innocent. Therefore, at least in theory, the karma-
Indian Buddhist monk explains the theory to one of related guilt that a Buddhist feels is different from
the Greek governors installed in Northern India by the guilt experienced by a Hindu. It follows that
Alexander the Great in fourth century BC: Rebirth a Buddhist believer should show compassion for
without a soul is like the flame of an oil wick, which everything that suffers because everything that suf-
was ignited with the flame of another oil wick; the fers is suffering innocently. Of course, the concept
second flame is not identical to the first but was cre- of the non-self (anatman) serves as an argument for
ated as a function of the first and continues on when Buddhism’s rejection of the Hindu caste system.
the first is extinguished. Although we can admit that Against the background of the Buddhist self-theory,
there is some causal nexus between the first and the membership to a certain caste cannot be justified
second flame, we do not have plausible arguments by personal guilt. On the contrary, according to the

86 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


Buddhist point of view, the caste system does not introspective methods as a basic research procedure
reflect justice but adds to injustice and the miser- were short-lived in Western psychology. In fact,
able situation of the lowest castes and the outcasts. Watson, the father of behaviorism, even called them
For Hindus, however, their caste is an important an alien and “un-American” import from Germany,
aspect of their belief system and their socialization thus contributing a little anecdote to the question
context. It is the cornerstone of Hindu identity that concerning whether behaviorism would consider
is constituted within the manifold and intertwined itself an indigenous psychology (Costall, 2006).
aspects of the Hindu worldview, psychological anal- In contrast, in India and other Asian countries,
ysis of cognitions and the self, conceptualizations of more elaborate techniques of introspection and
the other, and a model of ideal development that training of respective skills have been employed and
along with the caste system provides the framework refined for more than 2,500 years and are commonly
to socially institutionalize this “identity web.” referred to as “meditation.” Especially Buddhist
Descriptions of Hindu and Buddhist analyses of scholars have provided extensive, highly detailed,
psychological phenomena can hardly be adequate and very precise theories and descriptions of medita-
when they are removed from the general philo- tion practices that not only serve the observation and
sophical and spiritual framework in which they analysis of psychological processes and mental states
were developed. For most of the time since psychol- but are also employed to achieve those changes in
ogy was established as a modern Western science behavioral and psychological traits said to decrease
at Western universities and then implanted in uni- suffering and increase well-being (Conze, 2002;
versities around the world, these philosophical and Lutz, Dunne, & Davidson, 2007). Of course, this
spiritual elements made it easy for modern psychol- twofold function of meditation practice can also be
ogists, including modern Indian psychologists, to found in non-Buddhist traditions of psychology—
disregard India’s and other cultures’ indigenous the- for example, in the Hindu systems of Patanjali’s
ories as mere pre-scientific speculation (Chakkarath, Yoga and Siddhi Yoga or in the Hindu medical sys-
2010b). Another indicator of the “unscientific” tem of Ayurveda. The systematic procedures that
character of these theories was the assumed lack of can be found in all these traditions have often been
an empirical method, which would assure that these compared to the systematic steps taken in medicine:
theories meet the standards of modern Western Identification of disease via detection of symptoms,
psychology. However, at least in the case of the diagnosis of causes, prognosis, treatment, and pre-
indigenous theories and debates presented above, scription. From a psychological point of view, we can
one should be aware that the analyses of the inter- hardly challenge the scientific nature of these highly
relationship between cognition and self as well as systematic procedures. On the contrary, we should
the development of coping and regulation strategies recognize that they aimed at a synthesis of careful
were carried out by employing the probably most observation, scholarly exchange about the adequacy
elaborate techniques of introspection known in the of the observation and the observation techniques
history of psychology. Interestingly, introspective (over the millennia), theory development based on
methods of a different kind were considered useful the analysis of the phenomena observed, and appli-
in the beginning of modern Western psychology. cation of the resulting knowledge—for example, in
Although Wundt did not consider them a reliable therapy (Rosch, 1997). Although there is little rea-
method, on certain occasions in his laboratory in son to doubt the scientific nature of many aspects of
Leipzig, subjects were asked to give verbal protocols Hindu and Buddhist psychology (Paranjpe, 1998),
of their inner experiences. More advanced intro- we have good reason to acknowledge that the indig-
spective methods were used regularly by research- enous psychological traditions, which could only be
ers from the Würzburg school (e.g., Bühler, Külpe, presented fragmentarily above, applied psychologi-
and Marbe), who trained their subjects’ introspec- cal knowledge within an integrative view of the psy-
tive skills before asking them to report about their chophysical and social aspects of life, an aim that is
inner experiences during certain problem-solving not unfamiliar to Western psychology.
tasks. Binet used similar methods in France, as did
Titchener in the United States. James M. Baldwin, What Can Cultural Psychology Learn
in his The Story of the Mind (1898), even called from Indigenous Psychology?
introspection the most important source of psy- We began this chapter with a critical look at
chological data. Nonetheless, attempts to advance the mainstream historiography of psychology and

ch a kka rath 87
its culture-sensitive branches. We saw that when a psychology’s self-understanding and goals that were
view of the genesis of so-called “Western” (especially described in the second section of this chapter.
European and U.S. American) culture-sensitive psy- First, indigenous psychology can be seen as an
chology tries to avoid stereotypical narrations about approach that adds to our psychological knowledge
linear development and steady scientific progress, a by investigating various indigenous psychologies—
very different picture of psychology’s history results that is, traditions of psychologically relevant thought
than that conveyed in mainstream Western histo- and research. Second, this investigation itself prof-
riography. For example, we saw that high-quality its from the expertise of the indigenous researchers
culture-sensitive field research, which foreshadowed involved. Third, the beginnings of recent indig-
central positions of cultural and indigenous psy- enous psychology are rooted in historical, political,
chology, was carried out long before the Newtonian and sociological discussions about Western psychol-
paradigm of laboratory- and experiment-based ogy’s international hegemony that was established
modern natural science was introduced. A certain in the era of Colonialism. Therefore, it is natural
group of psychologists adopted that monistic and for indigenous psychology to deal with questions
nomothetic paradigm, whereas others suggested about the indigenous character of Western psychol-
alternative approaches. Although these alternative ogy, the question of indigenization from within and
approaches were rooted in some of the best tradi- without, and the effects of an imposed psychology
tions of European intellectuality and scientific on people who experience it as unfamiliar to the
research and had considerable impact on other ecological, historical, and socio-cultural environ-
cultural sciences, in psychology, they were typically ments in which they and their ancestors have lived.
ignored for most of the twentieth century. In this Of course, this is felt especially strongly if essential
historiographic description, which does not show aspects of these environments still have the influ-
a continuous linear development but a variety of ence they have had for hundreds and thousands
paths and interruptions, things are much more dif- of years (e.g., the philosophical and psychological
ficult to explain, and questions arise that are more foundations of the Indian caste system). Such socio-
difficult to answer. Of course, the explanations and historical dimensions and the relationship between
answers cannot be given in a single chapter, but simultaneously existing (e.g., imported and indig-
hopefully it has become clear that the answers need enous) conceptions of psychology can both be
to include the psychological factors that Wundt investigated much more thoroughly if we apply an
and other forerunners of cultural and indigenous indigenous psychological perspective.
psychology identified as “higher” or more com- Apart from what can be learned about the higher
plex processes and products of the mind. When mental processes from investigating the manifold
these scholars propagated an interdisciplinary and paths that scientific thinking can take, a less eth-
multimethodical approach for the psychological nocentric account of psychological theories and
investigation of domains like history, religion, art, applications that can be found across cultures might
science, myths, social institutions, and interactions, provide even more accurate and fairer historiogra-
they held core positions of current cultural and phies. It might also provide psychological knowledge
indigenous psychology. The issue concerning how from which other indigenous traditions, including
certain psychological traits on the cultural and indi- Western traditions, can profit. For example, as the
vidual level are reflected, socio-culturally fostered, illustrations taken from Indian psychology have
and intergenerationally transmitted is crucial for shown, a life-span perspective on development, and
understanding the interplay of the various factors the insight that cognitive development does not
in various cultural domains that influences human end after schooling or with early adulthood, might
psychological development and socialization. Of appear to be a revolutionary perspective only within
course, in this context, from a traditional cultural the paths taken by the European psychology of cog-
psychological point of view, the history of psychol- nition and aging. In other traditions, this perspec-
ogy might appear as only one discipline among tive might have been there for millennia and might
innumerous scientific disciplines in which inves- have affected human psychological development in
tigators could be interested. From an indigenous ways all psychologists are interested in. The same
psychological perspective, however, the genesis of holds true for Buddhist scholars’ analysis of iden-
specific traditions of doing psychology comes into tity and their theory that self and personality are in
focus for several reasons that result from indigenous a constant flux that depends on changing contexts

88 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


and interactions that simultaneously influence cog- the question concerning the scientific value of reli-
nitive, emotional, and volitional processes within gions and worldviews for indigenous psychology. As
the individual. In the elaborate analyses of Indian we have seen, people hesitate to acknowledge the
psychology, there are many findings and ideas that value of psychological theories that can be found in
foreshadowed modern Western perspectives on the religious, philosophical, or any kind of ideological
topic of self and identity. This includes more recent frameworks. This skepticism is typical within post-
theories in Western personality research—for exam- Enlightenment Western science, although there
ple, the concept of identity configurations (i.e., the were once intellectual Western traditions that aimed
modes in which individuals integrate the mani- at reconciling our interest in spiritual goals with our
fold [e.g., worldly and religious] aspects of their interest in scientific goals. This integrative concept
self–other perceptions into a meaningful whole) of knowledge can still be found in living intellec-
(Schachter, 2004, 2005). Because indigenous psy- tual traditions—for example, in Hindu, Buddhist,
chological perspectives can help detect these contri- and Confucian schools of thought. Lately, it has
butions and inform the scientific community about even been rediscovered in Western psychology,
the findings, there might be a lot to learn, not only where investigating the concept of “wisdom” has
from our own culture’s past but also from going gained some interest (e.g., Baltes & Staudinger,
beyond the ethnocentric boundaries of our own 1993; Richerson & Boyd, 2005). If indigenous
cultures. There we might find the roots of theories psychologists are hesitant to acknowledge the sci-
that we usually find exclusively in historiographies entific value of these thinking traditions for their
of Western psychology and other social sciences and own work, then they may of course have good rea-
celebrate as the milestones of these disciplines. sons for it. However, they might also be influenced
As the examples of psychological research on by ethnocentric conceptions of science that are
self-concepts have shown, socio-historically grown not necessarily part of the indigenous psychologies
stereotypes and the resulting ethnocentric per- that, according to a prominent definition discussed
spectives still have an impact on how we conceive in the second section, were once designed for the
of “the others” and is one of the main reasons we indigenous populations. In other words, indigenous
conceive of them as others at all. Interestingly, even psychologists should always ask themselves whether
cross-cultural psychology, which largely favors the their discipline and their own mindset really provide
nomothetic paradigm of the natural sciences and the openness for new perspectives that is required if
emphasizes the scientific need to identify psycholog- they want to take the investigation of any indigenous
ical universals, has come up with countless theories phenomena seriously and not simply stumble into
that focus on cross-cultural differences. Hofstede’s the pitfalls of stereotypes and ethnocentrism them-
culture dimensions, probably the most influen- selves. Parenthetically, labeling certain non-Western
tial theory in cross-cultural psychological research traditions as “Hindu,” “Buddhist,” or “Confucian”
and upon which a lot of cross-cultural research is also contributes to a stereotypical differentiation
based, is a prime example. The same holds true for between “real” science (e.g., “Western” psychol-
many theories developed by cultural psychologists. ogy) and “worldviews.” Moreover, it has successfully
Taken together, many aspects of the frequently cited distracted us from the question whether “Western”
theories in so-called “culture-sensitive psychology” science is also a worldview or at least unreflect-
remind one of stereotypical assessments that are edly transports stereotypes that, for example, can
deeply embedded in Western traditions of think- be traced back to Christian traditions of thinking
ing about the “others” and can be traced back to (Altman & Rogoff, 1991). It is interesting, anyway,
antiquity. From a psychological point of view, it is that one of the most influential concepts in culture-
not astonishing that these stereotypes also show up informed psychology, the concept of individualism,
in the theories proposed by some indigenous psy- is frequently traced back to Christian—especially
chologists. In the long run, stereotypes (especially Protestant—roots. Nonetheless, no one would seri-
when they successfully enter the frameworks of our ously propose renaming “Western psychology” as
scientific thinking or are already part of frameworks “Protestant psychology.” However, from an indig-
that are imported from other traditions) can make enous psychological perspective, it makes perfect
us believe in the accuracy and the heuristic value of sense to instead call any tradition of psychologi-
the stereotypes ourselves. One example illustrating cal theorizing and research indigenous. Although
the complex problems that need to be solved here is considerations like these are not completely new to

ch a kka rath 89
cultural psychologists, the indigenous psychologi- relevant theories that already exist in indigenous
cal approach and the methodological reflections it traditions of thought, it often has to deal with the
requires could help to improve cultural psychology’s religions and other worldviews in which these theo-
methodological awareness, too. This includes what ries are embedded. Although even some indigenous
can be learned about the very specific role of indig- psychologists are hesitant to occupy themselves with
enous psychologists studying natives in indigenous worldviews, we should be reminded that, for exam-
contexts outside the Western world, which is none- ple, religion was a central topic in the beginnings
theless, to a certain extent, represented in these con- of modern psychology, and many of the founders
texts—for example, by the indigenous psychologists of the discipline were also founders of the psychol-
themselves. By borrowing well-known concepts ogy of religion. Although the investigation of these
from post-Colonial studies (Bhabha, 1994), we may topics continued to play an important role in neigh-
say that the hybridity of these research contexts, as boring disciplines like anthropology and sociology,
well as the hybridity of the psychologists dealing they almost disappeared in mainstream psychol-
with it, puts them in a “third space” and shows that ogy. Interestingly, there is also little interest in the
for them there is much more involved than for most culture-inclusive branches of psychology, including
of their colleagues in Western parts of the world. cultural psychology (see, for example, Tarakeshwar,
In addition to the points already mentioned, I Stanton, & Pargament, 2003; for rare cultural psy-
want to emphasize that the psychological relevance chological approaches to the study of religion, see
of indigenous traditions of thought, including psy- Belzen, 2010; Chakkarath, 2007; Sen & Wagner,
chological theories, does not solely depend on the 2009; Straub & Arnold, 2008). Therefore, the
question whether they meet specific standards of indigenous perspective on what is relevant for doing
scientific truth. Many of the thoughts presented in proper culture-sensitive psychology might draw cul-
the examples from so-called “Hindu and Buddhist tural psychologists’ attention to its neglect of these
psychology” can be understood as answers to ques- (and other) topics. We will only be able to provide
tions that are very familiar to Western psychology, the kind of “thick” description (Geertz, 1973) nec-
too: What factors influence human development essary for attaining a sounder understanding of the
and to what extent are individuals and societies able relationship between culture and psychology if we
to influence them? What role do culture and world- succeed in understanding which topics, domains,
views play with regard to developmental paths, and phenomena are really relevant for achieving the
developmental tasks, educational goals, socializa- goals of culture-informed psychology.
tion and internalization processes, cognitive styles, Although the psychological relevance of indig-
attribution styles, evaluation of the “normal” and enous theories does not depend on the proof of
the “abnormal,” and intervention strategies? The their scientific validity, some theories might none-
answers usually have an impact on the social and the theless meet the standards of valid scientific prin-
individual level. On the social level, for example, ciples. As stated above, some indigenous theories
they find expression in social institutions and for- might even add to our scientific insight and help
malized social interactions; on the individual level, modify or increase our inventory of theories. As
they are reflected in many individuals’ subjective I have indicated in the context of indigenous Indian
theories about selfhood, the others, relationships, psychology, indigenous theories can even make us
proper attitudes, life goals, suitable coping strate- reconsider the adequacy of our inventory of meth-
gies, and so forth. Therefore, indigenous theories ods. The experience of doing research in contexts in
play a crucial role in culture-specific features of the which the subjects are less familiar with typical (and
socialization context and thus assist us in guiding frequently standardized) testing or interview proce-
our thorough investigation of the complex develop- dures has resulted in the indigenization of various
mental niche. In part, they can be compared to the methods commonly used in Western psychology.
impact that Freud’s seminal theories had on so many One example is the so-called “ladder rating” in
levels and so many domains in Western societies which the standard two-dimensional, multiple-point
and sciences, although the value of Freud’s work as rating scale is substituted by a tiny wooden ladder
a scientific theory has never been unchallenged. with multiple steps. Using this three-dimensional
Because indigenous psychology not only strives instrument, researchers ask illiterate Indian respon-
to develop theories and approaches through indi- dents to indicate the extent of their agreement with
genization but also aims to identify psychologically certain statements by placing their fingers on one

90 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


of the lower or higher steps of the ladder (Sinha, that both culture-sensitive perspectives have a lot in
1969). Apart from making such a simple modifica- common and share some of their intellectual and
tion to meet at least some of the necessities of the historical roots. As we have seen, the main differ-
specific context, indigenous psychologists have also ences arise from the different socio-cultural and
come up with more complex adaptations of research socio-political circumstances of both perspectives’
procedures to the indigenous people. For example, more recent development and the related different
based on his experiences with qualitative field work problems most indigenous psychologists have to
in the regional and ethnic variety of the Philippines, deal with as compared to most cultural psycholo-
Enriquez (1993) proposed to relate duration, place, gists. Let me summarize these differences, this time
and frequency of investigations as well as the size of with an emphasis on the unequal distribution of
the investigated groups and the selection of research certain intercultural competencies.
staff to the habits of the investigated people. For The broader historical sketch given in the first
some cases, “Filipino psychology” even recommends section of this chapter and the description of indig-
having the subjects interview the researchers before enous psychology’s more recent development as
they are interviewed themselves because that would portrayed in the second section give the impression
familiarize them with the unfamiliar procedure and that the theoretical and methodological founda-
result in less of a feeling of hierarchical asymme- tions are to be found in German folk psychology
try between the investigators and the respondents (Völkerpsychologie), the Russian cultural historical
(Pe-Pua, 2006). Although these are examples of the school, critical psychology, and cultural psychol-
indigenization of methods used in Western psychol- ogy. Even if we think about earlier roots like the
ogy, meditation techniques as described earlier can field studies conducted by some missionaries in the
be considered indigenous methods. Usually, how- sixteenth century, the impression remains that even
ever, in Western psychological literature, meditation indigenous psychology owes its main assumptions
is emphasized as a coping strategy, a therapeutic pro- to discourses within Western psychology (or psy-
cedure to reduce suffering and to increase well-being chologies). It is thus not surprising that indigenous
(e.g., Lutz, Dunne, & Davidson, 2007). Western psychology seems so similar to cultural psychol-
psychologists largely ignore—and that is true for ogy. However, this impression may have resulted
cultural psychologists as well—the fact that medita- from a mainstream historiography dominated by
tion is also a highly advanced introspective method a Eurocentric assumption that outside of Europe,
that has always been the basic empirical procedure there were no important contributions to what we
by which many results of indigenous Asian psychol- call “psychology” (in a Western sense). Thus, it is
ogy were obtained. So, with regard to indigenous still a task for indigenous psychologists to come up
psychological methodology and methods, there are with alternative indigenous historiographies of non-
also things that can be learned or at least consid- Western contributions.
ered by cultural psychologists, too. Is it possible that The dominance of Western historiography as
Enriquez is right that outside the Philippines, we well as the need to relate indigenous psychological
should also adapt our procedures much more fre- work to Western conceptions of psychology to be
quently to the different groups that vary with regard taken seriously in the international scientific com-
to social origin, education, ethnicity, gender, and so munity are symptoms of an ongoing asymmetry
forth? And is it possible that even most cultural psy- of power distribution in international psychology
chologists do not really expect that there are non- (Moghaddam, 1987). It becomes especially evident
Western traditions of methodical empirical research in the fact that even indigenous psychologists most
that could be valuable for the whole discipline? In frequently link their work to psychological theories
other words, would it be useful to transplant non- of Western origin and research executed within the
Western indigenous concepts into Western psychol- standard framework of Western psychology. Western
ogy? It is worth mentioning that compared to their discourses are mainly about Western authors as are
treatment in psychology, these kinds of questions the so-called “international discourses.” The domi-
are dealt with much more visibly in anthropology nant language of psychology is English, and there-
(Denzin, Lincoln, & Smith, 2008; Smith, 1999). fore any findings from indigenous psychology, even
Finally, let me return to the question concerning potentially culture-specific concepts, need to be
the differences between indigenous and cultural psy- translated into English to be published in the lead-
chology if there are any. Actually, it seems obvious ing journals. This situation is quite comfortable

ch a kka rath 91
for most Western psychologists, who often live in cultural psychologists and indigenous psychologists
English-speaking countries, whereas indigenous share many scientific positions, all in all, they are
psychologists from non-English-speaking countries differently positioned. Because cultural psychol-
have to adapt to psychology’s dominating culture. ogy’s more recent development has been situated in
They have to learn its language, read its psycho- a predominantly Western setting and accompanied
logical literature, take part in its debates (which are by scientific debates that mainly reflect correspond-
mainly about its authors), and so forth. At the same ing intellectual traditions, most psychologists who
time, indigenous psychologists need to be equipped advocate the indigenous perspective work in non-
with the skills and knowledge required to con- Western environments with non-Western people
duct the kind of research that meets the standards who usually do not correspond to the WEIRD sam-
of their own scientific perspectives (as described ples that provide the largest proportion of data col-
above): language skills, sufficient knowledge about lected to test Western psychological theories. Many
the indigenous environments and the people, about of these indigenous psychologists are trained in
indigenous authors and their literature, method- Western psychology and equipped with the knowl-
ological versatility, and so forth. edge this training provides. Frequently, however,
The effects of this asymmetry of power and of they experience dissatisfaction with this Western
intercultural competence can be summarized as fol- knowledge in non-Western research contexts. The
lows: The intercultural competence and expertise criticism that has arisen from this situation is very
that an indigenous psychologist needs to meet the similar to the critical assessments of Western sci-
standards of his discipline and to be heard are rarely ence and its exercise of power that is brought for-
met by Western psychologists. Not even the Western ward within post-Colonial studies. The situation in
cultural psychologists read non-Western texts hav- which many indigenous psychologists are working
ing psychological relevance in the sense described can thus be described as a third space constituted by
above. Their discourses are mainly influenced by shared histories, overlapping contexts, and hybrid
Western—mainly Western European and U.S. actors. It is especially this difference from which
American—intellectual traditions. This situation the specific expertise and the specific competencies
not only underscores why indigenous psychology arise from which cultural psychology can profit in
is needed and could improve cultural psychology, many ways. This includes a greater knowledge of all
it also appeals to all branches of culture-informed topics and methods that might be relevant for psy-
psychological research to inform themselves much chological research (e.g., religions and other world-
more than they currently do. views, indigenous concepts pertaining to self and
other, indigenous methods like meditative intro-
Conclusion spection) and, in addition, a more thorough reflec-
Having developed from similar traditions within tion on the role of the psychologist as a culturalized
the history of psychology, cultural and indigenous figure within various and sometimes very different
psychology share many common features and contexts. For the future development of both, psy-
goals. Both favor the emic over the etic approach chologists from both fields should not just be satis-
and both suggest multimethod research designs for fied with peaceful co-existence but intensify their
the investigation of culture and the human mind. peaceful collaboration. Both fields would fulfill the
Moreover, both share the conviction that the higher main purpose of all branches of culture-informed
cognitive processes and their inter-relatedness with psychology: to collect as much psychologically
environmental aspects as well as with the elemen- relevant information as is needed to understand
tary cognitive processes need to be investigated in humans and culture.
an integrative and interdisciplinary manner that
reflects the human potential to give meaning to the Future Directions
world and ourselves in manifold ways and innumer- 1. How can indigenous psychologists find a
ous areas. Therefore, both disciplines investigate common definition of their discipline and their
history, mythologies and other cultural narrations, relationship to other culture-sensitive psychologies,
art, social institutions, religions, world views, sci- including cultural psychology?
ence, and so forth, to identify the psychological 2. How can psychological methodology profit
relevance of these topics for human development, from indigenous/indigenized methodologies and
thought, feeling, and behavior. However, although indigenous/indigenized methods?

92 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


3. What cultural psychological insight can be Chakkarath, P. (2005). What can Western psychology learn from
gained by investigating the specific situation that indigenous psychologies? Lessons from Hindu psychology.
In W. Friedlmeier, P. Chakkarath, & B. Schwarz (Eds.),
many indigenous psychologists are in and that Culture and human development: The importance of cross-
we characterized as “third space,” in which hybrid cultural research to the social sciences (pp. 31–51). New York:
researchers study indigenous (and occasionally Psychology Press.
hybrid) subjects? Chakkarath, P. (2007). Zur kulturpsychologischen Relevanz
4. What can be done to minimize the negative von Religionen und Weltan schauungen [The cultural-
psychological relevance of religions and world-views]. In
effects of politics and unequal power distribution G. Trommsdorff & H.-J. Kornadt (Eds.), Kulturvergleichende
in the field of international psychology? Psychologie (Vol. 1, pp. 615–674). Göttingen, Germany:
5. To what extent can indigenous psychology Hogrefe.
refine our understanding of “psychological Chakkarath, P. (2010a). The Indian self and the others: Individual
relevance?” and collective identities in India. Taiwan Journal of East Asian
Studies, 7, 1–23.
6. Do we need a historiography of psychology Chakkarath, P. (2010b). Internationalizing education and
written from a cultural and indigenous the social sciences: Reflections on the Indian context. In
psychological perspective, and how would it differ M. Kuhn & D. Weidemann (Eds.), Internationalization of
from conventional historiographies? the social sciences: Asia – Latin America – Middle East – Africa
– Eurasia (pp. 87–114). Bielefeld, Germany: Transcript.
Chakkarath, P. (2010c). Stereotypes in social psychology: The
Acknowledgment “West-East” differentiation as a reflection of Western tradi-
This chapter was written during a fellowship at the Institute
tions of thought. Psychological Studies, 55, 18–25.
of Advanced Study at the University of Konstanz, part of the
Chakkarath, P. (in press). Indian thoughts on psychological
university’s “Cultural Foundations of Integration” Center of
human development. In G. Misra (Ed.), Psychology and psy-
Excellence, established in the framework of the German Federal
choanalysis in India. New Delhi, India: Sage.
and State Initiative for Excellence. The author would like to thank
Chakkarath, P., & Straub, J. (in press). Cultural psychology. In
Tamara Herz for proofreading the final draft of this paper.
N. Azari, P. Brugger, A. Runehov, P. Duran, R. Paloutzian,
R. J. Seitz, et al. (eds.), Encyclopedia of sciences and religions.
References Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Altman, I., & Rogoff, B. (1991). World views in psychology: Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline.
Trait, interactional, organismic, and transactional per- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
spectives. In D. Stokols & I. Altman (Eds.), Handbook of Conze, E. (2003). Buddhist meditation. New York: Dover.
environmental psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 7–40). Malabar, FL: Costall, A. (2006). “Introspectionism” and the mythical origins
Krieger. of scientific psychology. Consciousness and Cognition, 15,
Baltes, P. B., & Staudinger, U. M. (1993). The search for a 634–654.
psychology of wisdom. Current Directions in Psychological Denzin, N. K., Lincoln, Y. S., & Smith, L. T. (2008). Handbook
Science, 3, 75–80. of critical and indigenous methodologies. London: Sage.
Berry, J. W. (1974). Canadian psychology: Some social and Diaz-Guerrero, R. (1977). A Mexican psychology. American
applied emphases. Canadian Psychology, 15, 132–139. Psychologist, 32, 934–944.
Berry, J. W., & Poortinga, Y. H., Breugelmans, S. M., Chasiotis, Diriwächter, R. (2011). Völkerpsychologie. In J. Valsiner (Ed.),
A., & Sam, D. L. (2011). Cross-cultural psychology: Research Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
and applications. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University University Press.
Press. Duerlinger, J. (2006). Indian Buddhist theories of persons:
Bhabha, H. (1994). The location of culture. New York: Routledge. Vasubandhu’s refutation of the theory of a self. London:
Bhatia, S. (2002). Orientalism in Euro-American and Indian Routledge.
psychology: Historical representations of “natives” in colonial Enriquez, V. G. (1990). Indigenous psychology: A book of read-
and postcolonial contexts. History of Psychology, 5, 376–398. ings. Diliman, Philippines: Akademya Ng Sikolohiyang
Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychol- Pilipino.
ogy. New York: Springer. Enriquez, V. G. (1993). Developing a Filipino psychology. In U.
Boesch, E. E. (1996). The seven flaws of cross-cultural psychol- Kim & J. Berry (Eds.), Indigenous psychologies: Research and
ogy. Mind, culture and activity, 3, 2–10. experience in cultural context (pp. 152–169). Newbury Park,
Bruner, J. (1987). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: CA: Sage.
Harvard University Press. Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic
Bruner, J. (1991). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Books.
University Press. Geertz, C. (1984). Anti-anti-relativism. American Anthropologist,
Butterfield, H. (1949). The origins of modern science: 1300–1800. 86, 263–278.
London: Bell. Gergen, K. J. (1994). Realities and relationships: Soundings in
Chakkarath, P. (2003). Kultur und Psychologie: Zur wissenschaftli- social construction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
chen Entstehung und zur Ortsbestimmung der Kulturpsychologie Press.
[Culture and psychology: On the scientific genesis and localiza- Gielen, U. P., Fish, J. M., & Draguns, J. G. (2004). Handbook of
tion of cultural psychology]. Hamburg, Germany: Kovac. culture, therapy, and healing. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

ch a kka rath 93
Greenfield, P. M. (2000). Three approaches to the psychology of Nisbett, R. E. (2003). The geography of thought: How Asians and
culture: Where do they come from? Where can they go? Asian Westerners think differently and why. New York: The Free
Journal of Social Psychology, 3, 223–240. Press.
Heelas, P., & Lock, A. (1981). Indigenous psychologies: The anthro- Paranjpe, A. C. (1998). Self and identity in modern psychology and
pology of the self. London: Academic Press. Indian thought. New York: Plenum.
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest Paranjpe, A. C. (2002). Indigenous psychology in the post-
people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–83. colonial context: An historical perspective. Psychology and
Ho, D. Y. F. (1998). Indigenous psychologies: Asian perspectives. Developing Societies, 14, 27–43.
Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 29, 88–103. Pe-Pua, R. (2006). From decolonizing psychology to the devel-
Hofstede, G. (1980). Culture’s consequences: International differ- opment of a cross-indigenous perspective in methodology.
ences in work-related values. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. In U. Kim, K.-S. Yang, & K.-K. Hwang (Eds.), Indigenous
Holdstock, T. L. (2000). Re-examining psychology: Critical per- and cultural psychology: Understanding people in context
spectives and African insights. London: Routledge. (pp. 109–137). New York: Springer.
Howitt, D., & Owusu-Bempah, J. (1994). The racism of psychol- Pedersen, P. B., Draguns, J. G., Lonner, W. J., & Trimble, J. E.
ogy: Time for change. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. (2002). Counseling across cultures (5th ed.). Thousand Oaks,
Jahoda, G. (1982). Psychology and anthropology: A psychological CA: Sage.
perspective. London: Academic Press. Peng, K., & Nisbett, R. (1999). Culture, dialectics, and reasoning
Jahoda, G. (1992). Crossroads between culture und mind: about contradiction. American Psychologist, 54, 741–754.
Continuities and change in theories of human nature. New York: Pickren, W. E. (2009). Indigenization and the history of psychol-
Harvester Wheatsheaf. ogy. Psychological Studies, 54, 87–95.
Jahoda, G. (1999). Images of savages: Ancient roots of modern Pondicherry Manifesto of Indian Psychology. (2002). Psychological
prejudice in Western culture. London: Routledge. Studies, 47, 168–169.
Jahoda, G. (2011). Culture and psychology: Words and ideas in Poortinga, Y. H. (1999). Do differences in behavior imply
history. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and a need for different psychologies? Applied Psychology: An
psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. International Review, 48, 419–432.
Jing, Q., & Fu, X. (2001). Modern Chinese psychology: Its Ratner, C. (2002). Cultural psychology: Theory and method. New
indigenous roots and international influences. International York: Plenum.
Journal of Psychology, 36, 408–418. Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How
Kim, U. (2001). Culture, science, and indigenous psychologies: culture transformed human evolution. Chicago: University of
An integrated analysis. In D. Matsumoto (Ed.), The hand- Chicago Press.
book of culture and psychology (pp. 51–75). New York: Oxford Rieber, R. W. (1977). Thomas C. Upham and the making of
University Press. an indigenous American psychology. Annals of the New York
Kim, U., & Berry J. W. (1993). Indigenous psychologies: Experience Academy of Sciences, 1, 186–202.
und research in cultural context. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Rosch, E. (1997). Transformation of the wolf man. In J. Pickering
Kim, U., Yang, K. S., & Hwang, K. K. (2006). Indigenous (Ed.), The authority of experience: Essays on Buddhism and psy-
und cultural psychology: Understanding people in context. chology (pp. 6–27). Surry, England: Curzon.
New York: Springer. Rothbaum, F., & Morelli, G. (2005). Attachment and culture:
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd rev. Bridging relativism and universalism. In W. Friedlmeier,
ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. P. Chakkarath, & B. Schwarz (Eds.), Culture and human
Lamotte, E. (1988). History of Indian Buddhism. Leuven, development: The importance of cross-cultural research to the
Belgium: Peeters Publishers. social sciences (pp. 99–124). New York: Psychology Press.
Leon-Portilla, M. (2002). Bernardino de Sahagún: First anthro- Sahagún, B. de. (1970–1982). Florentine codex: General history
pologist (transl. by M. J. Mixco). Norman, OK: University of the things of New Spain (From the Sequera manuscript of
of Oklahoma Press. 1578–1579) (rev. ed., Vols. 1–13). Santa Fé, NM: School of
Lonner, W. J., & Hayes, S. A. (2007). Discovering cultural psy- American Research and The University of Utah.
chology: A profile and selected readings of Ernest E. Boesch. Said, E. (2003). Orientalism (with an afterword from 1995 and a
Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. new preface). London, UK: Penguin Books. (Original work
Lutz, A., Dunne, J. D., & Davidson, R. J. (2007). Meditation published 1978).
and the neuroscience of consciousness: An introduction. Schachter, E. P. (2004). Identity configurations: A new perspec-
In P. D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E. Thompson (Eds.), tive on identity formation in contemporary society. Journal
The Cambridge handbook of consciousness (pp. 499–551). of Personality, 72, 167–200.
New York: Cambridge University Press. Schachter, E. P. (2005). Context and identity formation: A theo-
Markus, H., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: retical analysis and a case study. Journal of Adolescent Research,
Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. 20, 375–395.
Psychological Review, 98, 224–253. Sen, R., & Wagner, W. (2009). Cultural mechanics of fun-
Marsella, A. J. (2009). Some reflections on potential abuses of damentalism: Religion as ideology, divided identities and
psychology’s knowledge and practices. Psychological Studies, violence in Post-Gandhi India. Culture & Psychology, 15,
54, 23–27. 299–326.
Moghaddam, F. (1987). Psychology in the three worlds: As Shams, M. (2002). Issues in the study of indigenous psycholo-
reflected by the crisis in social psychology and the move gies: Historical perspectives, cultural interdependence and
towards indigenous Third World psychology. American institutional regulations. Asian Journal of Social Psychology 5,
Psychologist, 42, 912–920. 79–91.

94 indigenous psycho log i e s i n bui ldi n g ba sic cu ltu ra l psych ology


Shweder, R. A. (1990). Cultural psychology: What is it? In Tarakeshwar, N., Stanton, J., & Pargament, K. I. (2003).
J. W. Stigler, R. A. Shweder, & G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psy- Religion: An overlooked dimension in cross-cultural
chology (pp. 1–43). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University psychology. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 34,
Press. 377–394.
Shweder, R. (2000). The psychology of practice and the practice Toulmin, S. (1961). Foresight and understanding: An enquiry into
of the three psychologies. Asian Journal of Social Psychology the aims of science. London: Hutchinson.
3, 207–222. Triandis, H. C. (2000). Dialectics between cultural and cross-
Sinha, D. (1969). Indian villages in transition. New Delhi, India: cultural psychology. Asian Journal of Social Psychology, 3,
Asia Publishing. 185–195.
Sinha, D. (1986). Psychology in a third world country: The Indian Triandis, H. (2001). Individualism and collectivism: Past, pres-
experience. New Delhi, India: Sage. ent, and future. In D. Matsumoto (Ed.), Handbook of culture
Sinha, D. (1997). Indigenizing psychology. In J. W. Berry, and psychology (pp. 35–50). New York: Oxford University
Y. H. Poortinga, & J. Pandey (Eds.), Handbook of cross- Press.
cultural psychology, Vol. 1: Theory and method (pp. 129–169). Valsiner, J. (2009). Cultural psychology today: Innovations and
Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. oversights. Culture & Psychology, 15, 5–39.
Smith, L. T. (1999). Decolonizing methodologies: Research and Vico, G. (1968). The new science of Giambattista Vico
indigenous peoples. London: Zed Books. (T. G. Bergin & M. H. Fisch, trans.). Ithaca, NY: Cornell
Spence, J. D. (1985). The memory palace of Matteo Ricci. New University Press. (Original work published 1725.)
York: Viking. Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher
Straub, J. (2006). Understanding cultural differences: Relational mental processes In M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, &
hermeneutics and comparative analyses in cultural psychol- E. Souberman, (Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
ogy. In J. Straub, D. Weidemann, C. Kölbl, & B. Zielke Press. (Original work published 1930.)
(Eds.), Pursuit of meaning: Theoretical und methodological Ward, C. (2007). Asian social psychology: Looking in and look-
advances in cultural and cross-cultural psychology (pp. 163– ing out. Asian Journal of Social Psychology, 10, 22–31.
213). Bielefeld, Germany: transcript. Wertsch, J. V. (1985). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind.
Straub, J., & Arnold, M. (2008). Acting as missionaries: The reli- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
gious self in intercultural practice: An approach from action Yang, K. (2000). Monocultural and cross-cultural indigenous
theory and cultural psychology. In J. A. v. Belzen & A. Geels approaches: The royal road to the development of a bal-
(Eds.), Autobiography and the psychological study of religious anced global psychology. Asian Journal of Social Psychology
lives (pp. 319–368). Amsterdam, Netherlands: Rodopi. 3, 241–263.

ch a kka rath 95
CHAPTER

Cultural Anthropology
5
Susan J. Rasmussen

Abstract
This overview of cultural anthropology begins with a brief discussion of historical, recent, and current
trends in theory and method. Next, there is a critical analysis of two broad issues concerning the
anthropological subject: namely, tensions between approaches and perspectives emphasizing the
individual, practice, and agency, on the one hand, and those emphasizing collectivities, institutions, and
structure, on the other; and tensions between shared universal themes, on the one hand, and local
cultural variations, on the other. There follow illustrative examples from selected relevant topics,
including enculturation, altered states, healing, the body and senses, and personhood. The chapter
concludes with a brief sum-up and key questions for future directions in cultural anthropology.
Keywords: cultural anthropology, cultural theory, ethnography, psychological anthropology,
enculturation, altered states, personhood

Anthropology, the study of humankind at the issues concerning relationships between individu-
most comprehensive and holistic level, is a broad als, cultures, and collectivities as well as variations
discipline that straddles the social sciences and the on universal themes.
humanities and is comprised of several subfields or Although in some respects, cultural anthropol-
branches: social/cultural or simply, cultural anthro- ogy’s subject matter overlaps with its “sister” social
pology; linguistic anthropology; archaeology; and sciences, sociology and psychology, its distinctive-
physical or bio-anthropology. Some anthropologists ness consists in its tendency toward more qualita-
also recognize an additional branch called applied tive, micro-, small-scale, and intimate perspectives
anthropology, which involves the application of on cultural phenomena. Whereas most sociologists
anthropological concepts, theories, and methods tend toward the study of groups and institutions
to public policy recommendations; whereas oth- as their subject or unit of analysis, and most psy-
ers locate this latter specialty within each of the chologists focus on mental processes, most cultural
traditional four branches. Central to social/cul- anthropologists emphasize their holistic intercon-
tural anthropology are several key concepts: cul- nections and work within a theoretical framework
ture, cultural relativism, holism, field research or built on the culture concept.
fieldwork, ethnography, ethnology, comparison,
translation, and concern with both shared (uni- The Concept of Culture
versal) themes and local diversity or variations in Although the culture concept, in its classic and
the expression of culture and the organization of reformulated senses, constitutes the unifying para-
society. This chapter will examine cultural anthro- digm for all subfields or branches of anthropology,
pology; it will particularly focus on concepts and cultural anthropology is that branch that focuses

96
most intently on contemporary (living) human cul- the rise of science in western Europe between the
tural and social beliefs, knowledge, and practices sixteenth and eighteenth centuries, contributed to
through in-depth study of a single cultural set- increasing interest in a human- and nature-centered
ting, as well as comparative cross-cultural studies. universe. Discoveries by Charles Lyell, the geologist,
Cultural anthropologists conduct ethnographic field suggested that the age of the Earth was much older
research or “fieldwork,” which includes a method than that proposed by the Church, and the evolu-
called participant-observation, involving intensive tionary theory proposed by Charles Darwin, the
submersion in the everyday life of the community, naturalist, emphasized transformation, rather than
and depending on the topic and setting of research, immutability, of life forms and suggested long-term
also additional techniques, such as guided conversa- evolutionary interconnections. Much of this work
tions and more structured interviews, life histories, was stimulated by European exploration and colo-
case studies, genealogies, censuses, and (in more nial domination, which promoted a growing inter-
complex settings) network analysis and snowball est in human physical and cultural variation and
sampling. Ideally, anthropologists approach field change. Eighteenth century philologists studied the
research with an attitude called cultural relativism. history of languages, and, with the German Idealist
Cultural relativism does not imply justifying prac- philosophers, became interested in the connections
tices that the researcher finds morally or ethically between language, mind, and nation—for example,
repugnant but, rather, involves refraining, in so Kant’s distinction between noumena (things or
far as possible, from judging cross-cultural prac- objects directly perceived in the world) and phe-
tices solely from the standpoint of the researcher’s nomena (things or ideas indirectly experienced)
own cultural values and being aware of one’s own as well as Hegel’s concept of zeitgeist or “spirit of
biases and their sources and effects on construct- the times or nation,” which associated culture, in
ing ethnographic knowledge. In contemporary its early conceptualization, with learning, language,
cultural relativism, there is particular effort made individual psychological identity, and group affili-
to refrain from ranking beliefs and practices across ation. Naturalists pursued the connections among
different cultural settings and in historical eras: ide- plant, animal, and human life. Many traveled on
ally, the researcher analyzes social/cultural beliefs, scientific exploratory expeditions beyond Europe.
knowledge, practices, and behavior in a variety of
contexts: historical, political, social, psychological,
The Main Issues
and economic. On the other hand, some anthro-
The problem for many theorists, in these con-
pologists today advocate “activist anthropology,”
texts, was the following: how humans were similar,
an approach involving greater engagement with
how they were different, why, and what shared uni-
political issues—for example, advocacy for indig-
versal themes and local variations implied. These
enous peoples’ rights. There is much debate in the
conditions prompted the collection of data on this
discipline concerning these issues (Bodley, 1975;
diversity—for example, flora, fauna, and folklore
Tsing 2005).
from the “folk” at home and from so-called “primi-
tive” peoples abroad, for purposes of classification.
History of Cultural Anthropology and Carolus von Linnaeus formulated botanical and zoo-
the Culture Concept logical taxonomies, and the Romantic Nationalism
Until very recently, anthropology was primarily a movement encouraged the preservation of “quaint”
western European science. Many concepts central to customs from the rural peasants. Some early evolu-
the discipline originated in philosophical concepts tionary anthropologists, such as Edward Tylor and
and political policies extending from classical Greece James Frazer, interpreted exotic customs as “surviv-
through the Renaissance, Enlightenment, and als” or remnants of past practices; ethnographic
Scientific and Industrial Revolutions. Although there analogies were made between marginal practices
are increasing influences from scholars from post-co- assumed to derive from Europe’s past and the prac-
lonial backgrounds today, anthropology nonetheless tices of non-Western peoples, in grand schemes of
owes much in its origin and development to these the origins of culture. This early version of the com-
historical legacies in Europe: for example, tensions parative method, which featured ethnocentric and
between the “sacred” and “secular” worldviews of racist ranking of cultures and societies in an effort
the Medieval Catholic Church and the secular views to find the origins of civilization, differed from the
of the Renaissance and ensuing Age of Reason, with relativistic cross-cultural comparison as practiced

ra sm u ssen 97
by anthropologists today, whose purpose is not to latter concept now recognized as a political device
rank or find origins but rather to yield insights into and an oversimplification, despite human physical
the range of human cultural and social behavior in variation. Second, for some time culture remained
terms of similarities and differences. At that time, defined in the singular, in the Enlightenment sense
anthropology was only beginning to emerge as an of a civilization—that is, with implied greater or
academic discipline at universities in Europe and lesser degrees of cultivation—and having superior
the United States, and its branches or subfields of or inferior connotations, all based on very ethno-
study had not yet become distinct; for example, bio- centric value judgments, with Europe believed to
logical or physical anthropology was not yet sepa- stand at the pinnacle or apex of development.
rate from cultural anthropology, and there was a Beginning in the early twentieth century, anthro-
conflation of physical characteristics with sociocul- pologists such as Franz Boas in the United States and
tural phenomena—for example, a misguided equa- Bronislaw Malinowski and A.R. Radcliffe-Brown in
tion made between physical attributes of so-called Britain spearheaded the newly diverging branch of
“race” and culture. In the first theoretical school (socio)cultural anthropology; they began to ques-
called unilineal evolutionism in academic anthro- tion the assumptions, theories, concepts, and meth-
pology, which arose in the mid-to-late nineteenth ods of the nineteenth-century unilineal evolutionists
century, peoples outside of Europe and their beliefs and began to promote direct fieldwork and cultural
and practices, as representatives of earlier phases or relativism. Yet many, despite individual opposi-
stages of European institutions, beliefs, and prac- tion to colonialism, continued to work for colonial
tices, were thought to be capable of progress on the administrations—for example, Evans-Pritchard
ladder of civilization but moving at different rates. (1940) among the Nuer in the then-Anglo-Egyptian
Additional processes—wider, wider demographic Sudan. The concept of culture changed radically. The
and economic changes in Europe from industri- method of field research became mandatory for full
alization and bureaucratization in the nineteenth professional status in cultural anthropology. Modern
century—also encouraged the growth of the social anthropology today owes a debt to these theorists,
sciences—for example, the rise of penal reform, who reacted against previous Victorian anthropolog-
and the disciplines of demography, sociology, and ical paradigms of unilineal evolutionism—for exam-
psychiatry (Foucault, 1978). Emile Durkheim (an ple, “social Darwinism,” the distorted application
early founder of anthropology and sociology) and of Charles Darwin’s evolutionary theory to human
his student Marcel Mauss were concerned with the social practices. Franz Boas, a German-Jewish immi-
perceived breakdown of reciprocity in European grant who had suffered from anti-Semitism, became
society in the wake of these changes. August Comte interested in salvaging the cultures of the Native
promoted positivist objective data collection. Karl American Indians. Bronislaw Malinowski, a Polish
Marx formulated his theory of alienation from the aristocrat who became stranded in the Trobriand
products of one’s labor is his critique of capitalism. Islands off Australia upon the outbreak of World
All these questions were initially addressed in a War I, similarly experienced marginal status himself,
context of domination: increasing colonialism by began undertaking intensive fieldwork and local lan-
European state powers beyond Europe and national- guage study, and became interested in the function,
ist domination by these state governments over mar- rather than the origin, of practices such as ritual and
ginalized rural peoples, so-called “peasants” or “folk,” economics. Both these theorists rejected the hereto-
in Europe itself. There was the view that adminis- fore prevalent “armchair scholarship,” racism, and
trators and missionaries shared a civilizing mission, speculative grand generalizations on the origins and
popularly called the “White Man’s Burden.” Many sequences of human culture.
Victorian unilineal evolutionists at first worked at In the United States, Boas’s historical-particularism
a distance from these remote locations, conducting school of thought distinguished among culture, race,
armchair research; only a few of the early anthro- and language and advocated studying particular cul-
pologists conducted direct fieldwork. tures and their histories directly, without ranking or
proposing grand universal schemes of human origin
Impacts on Culture Theories or development. Boas and his colleagues and students
These conditions had several consequences for also founded the subfield of culture and personality
early theories of culture. First, in Darwinian circles, within cultural anthropology, which examined chil-
at least, culture tended to be equated with race—the drearing customs across diverse cultures, emphasizing

98 c ultural ant hro po log y


learned cultural—rather than universal biological— twins as anomalous, and thus analogous, to birds in
influences on personality. that both share qualities such as multiple births, and
both are believed to mediate, in the sky, between
Anthropologies Across the Atlantic humans and Kwoth, or Spirit. In France, Durkheim
Initially, ethnographies tended to describe and his students also emphasized the importance of
entire cultures or communities comprehensively “social facts,” from direct observation, and devel-
(Malinowski, 1926). Soon, however, cultural oped the concept of the collective unconscious as
anthropologists began to focus intently on a specific an overarching belief of a group, much more than
problem or issue in anthropological theory, either a sum total of individual viewpoints. Durkheimian
drawing on their primary data from a single cul- sociology also analyzed symbolic classifications as
tural/social setting in an ethnography or, in other reflecting society, not nature—for example, spirit
cases, drawing on secondary data collected by several pantheons often reflect human social divisions.
different researchers in several different cultural set-
tings, in a cross-cultural comparison or ethnology. Recent Trends in Modern Cultural
The ethnographies of Margaret Mead, a student of Anthropology
Franz Boas and Ruth Benedict and an early theorist From these insights, there emerged several
in the “culture and personality” school, examined important new understandings of culture. This con-
concepts of adolescence and gender in Polynesian cept became defined more in the plural than in the
societies (Mead, 1928, 1935), exploring how these singular and acquired more neutral connotations, as
differed from American psychologists’ concepts at denoting the sum total of a group’s belief system. In
that time. For example, Mead found that Samoan the formulation of Clifford Geertz, founder of inter-
adolescents were permitted much more freedom pretive anthropology, culture is transmitted through
and experienced less anxiety than their American learning and is widely shared (Geertz, 1973). In
counterparts, thereby suggesting, she argued, that this formulation, the anthropologist “reads” a cul-
the alleged stresses of adolescence were neither uni- ture like a text—that is, as one would interpret and
versal nor biologically based. Mead also studied translate a poem or novel. Thus, the cultural anthro-
gender constructs in three societies of New Guinea pologist first interprets the local culture in the field
and argued that male and female roles were a result in Geertz’s words, reads it “over the shoulders of the
of nurture, rather than nature. Although some of native,” and then “translates” this into terms under-
Mead’s findings were later disputed by other anthro- stood by his/her audience at home. Thus culture is
pologists (Freeman, 1983; Gewertz, 1983), her like a literary text. In Geertz’s textual approach, as in
work was nonetheless important in its early ques- the pioneering Boasian schools of historical-particu-
tioning of widely held assumptions of universals in larism and culture and personality, the anthropolo-
life course and gendered experiences. gist seeks cultural relativism, but nonetheless still
In Britain, the structural-functionalist school of retains much authority as translator, and the culture
thought similarly opposed unilineal evolutionism, concept, although more relativistic, tends to imply
eschewing history and origins and instead, some- a monolithic homogeneity.
what like Durkheim in France, advocated synchronic This more modern view of culture has been
analysis of the structure and function of institutions accompanied by important changes in anthropolo-
in terms of how they promote harmonious conti- gists’ methods; “ethnography” has come to refer
nuity of society. Later, students of Malinowski and to several practices: fieldwork with participant-
Radcliffe-Brown developed increasingly complex observation, the description of a cultural setting or
theories of the connections between social struc- community (usually focused on a specific issue or
ture and cultural knowledge or belief: E.E. Evans- problem in anthropological theory), and the writ-
Pritchard, in his works on the ecology, political ing practice itself. Ethnology, more comparative
system, and religion of the Nuer people of the then- work, draws more systematically on data from dif-
Anglo-Egyptian Sudan, described how local religion ferent settings to compare several distinct societies,
was refracted in social life and how local philoso- to pursue cross-cultural comparisons of specified
phy was not child-like but, rather, was metaphorical beliefs and practices. Notwithstanding their differ-
(Evans-Pritchard, 1940, 1956). For example, when ences, both ethnography and ethnology are analyti-
some Nuer say that “twins are birds,” they do not cal, in the sense that they both engage wider issues
view them as equivalent but, rather, view human and debates in anthropology. For example, the work

ra sm u ssen 99
of Mary Douglas (1966) examined the meanings communities, as well—for example, the Internet
of purity, pollution, and ritual restrictions called (Boellstorff, 2010).
“taboos” in both historical and cross-cultural terms. There have also been changes in the writing of
In her theory of anomaly, Douglas argued that ethnographies, a practice following data collection
food taboos’ meanings, for example, do not arise in the field, in which the cultural anthropologist
from strictly hygienic or ecological conditions in proceeds to analyze the data and write a descrip-
local consciousness (even if one of their functions tion of a single cultural or community setting. This
may be hygienic or ecological) but, rather, have to description, a literary genre using literary devices
do with symbolic classification of human cultural (Clifford & Marcus, 1986), has recently been the
systems; many forbidden foods, such as pork in topic of much critical reflection in cultural anthro-
Islam and Orthodox Judaism, are not easily classi- pology. Classical or “realist” ethnographies—for
fied and therefore are anomalous. Here, meaning example, those of Evans-Pritchard on the Nuer
rather than origin, cause, or function is important (1940, 1956) and of Malinowski on the Trobriand
in cultural classification, recalling in some respects Islanders (1926, 1927)—tended to use rhetorical
Durkheimian sociology and also Levi-Straussian techniques similar to those used in a novel, which
structuralism. were previously considered objective, with only a
Since approximately the mid-twentieth cen- single meaning determined by the author/researcher.
tury, in addition to Geertz’s comparative literature More subjective reflections by the author/researcher,
hermeneutic approach to culture as text, additional as well as his/her consultants and assistants in the
influences have derived from linguistics. French field, initially were either omitted or appended in
structuralism, brought by Claude Levi-Strauss separate prefaces and afterwords (Evans-Pritchard,
(1963) to cultural anthropology, draws on princi- 1940; Marcus & Fischer, 1986). Recently, there
ples and methods from linguistics: culture is seen as have been efforts at greater experimentation in eth-
a system of communication, and meaning derives nographic writing projects—for example, includ-
from contrast. In particular, Levi-Strauss analyzed ing references to the personal experiences of the
the structure of myths and symbols to elicit meaning researcher, accounts of the circumstances of data
from binary oppositions, which revealed mythemes, collection, and recognition of local collaborators
or the smallest units of meaning in myth, which (Rabinow, 1977; Stoller, 1987, 1989; Gottlieb &
were analogous to the phonemic principle in linguis- Graham, 1994; Marcus, 2005).
tics. According to Levi-Strauss, this construction of Most recently, the concept of culture has been
meaning is a universal characteristic of all human undergoing additional revisions, for several reasons.
mental logic, which finds expression in a variety of The mid-to-late twentieth century saw liberation
domains. Symbolic anthropologists and semioti- movements among colonized peoples, ethnic minor-
cians drew extensively on these ideas, applying them ities, and women, who have contributed much more
to ritual symbolism (V. Turner, 1967), kinship (D. to cultural anthropological theory. Anthropologists
Schneider, 1980), popular culture (Drummond, now come from diverse backgrounds. Postcolonial,
1996), and advertising (Barthes, 1982). post-structural, post-modern, and gender studies
Other trends have addressed ethnography. Until have conducted critiques of the old canons, in some
recently, much anthropological field research focused cases rejecting all the major schools of anthropo-
on small-scale and rural communities remote from logical thought. Feminist anthropologists (Rosaldo
the researcher’s own (home) community. In current & Lamphere, 1974; Butler, 1999) have critiqued
reformulations of culture, which have responded androcentric male bias in some earlier anthropo-
to new cultural formations such as globalization, logical works. Other scholars—for example, Byron
borderlands, and dynamic practices (such as sci- Good (1994) in medical anthropology—have pro-
ence and technology), the concept of culture has posed replacing cultural belief with cultural knowledge
expanded to include more complex settings, such as to render anthropological concepts of non-Western
urban milieu and even virtual, online communities; systems more commensurate with Western systems.
accordingly, fieldwork may now take place in any Talal Asad (in Clifford & Marcus, 1986) conducted
community—rural or urban, locally or abroad— a critique of the Geertzian interpretive anthropolog-
and sites of fieldwork for cultural anthropologists ical concept of cultural translation, arguing that the
today are expanding to include such places as sci- translation of culture is not the same as the transla-
entific laboratories (Rabinow, 2003) and virtual tion of language. Asad has also written a critique

100 c ultural ant hro po log y


of the old structuralist binary opposition between sensitivity to the need for specification in cultural
“sacred” and “secular” in anthropological studies analysis, and some anthropologists now tend to use
of religion and has questioned the assumption that “cultural” in the adjective form more often than as a
secularism always produces greater liberty, drawing noun to avoid the older totalizing, neatly bounded
on examples from history, and arguing that there sense of this concept (Faubion, 2001; Rasmussen,
can be oppression in both religious and secular set- 2008). However, locality remains important, albeit
tings (Asad, 2003). not as an isolated entity but more as a space of
encounter. In these newer formulations, moreover,
Interdisciplinary Links political-economy approaches emphasizing power
In tandem with these trends, there have also and semiotic-expressive approaches emphasizing
occurred much cross-fertilization and interdisci- symbolism, once seen as oppositional, are often
plinary dialogue between the social sciences and becoming intertwined (Rasmussen, 2001; Tsing,
humanities—particularly among anthropology, 2005). In these developments, a central concern has
literary criticism, semiotics, and comparative litera- been with the units of analysis—that is, the anthro-
ture. For example, the comparative literature scholar pological subject.
Edward Said (1978) in his work, Orientalism, cri-
tiqued some ethnographic portrayals of Middle The Anthropological Subject
Eastern peoples in an exaggerated exoticism (e.g., Recurrent and Emerging Issues in the Study
literary and historic portrayals of the Orient as of Culture, Society, and the Individual
sensual and the West as logical) and encouraged Cultural anthropology, from its inception and
anthropologists to reflect more carefully on the his- throughout its transformations, has been con-
tory of their relationships with peoples glossed as cerned with what constitutes the human sub-
“Other.” In his work “The Invention of Africa,” V.Y. ject. As a science of anthropos (Rabinow, 2003),
Mudimbe (1988) explored the historical and social anthropology’s most basic, pervasive concern has
construction of the “idea” of Africa. been with relationships among individuals, institu-
Additional influences have come from the Soviet tions, and belief/knowledge systems. In this focus
Semioticians Mikhael Bakhtin and V.N. Volosinov, on individual/culture/collectivity connections,
whose works written during Stalin’s reign and later two broad issues have reverberated throughout the
translated into English critiqued authoritarian discipline. First, there have been tensions between
forms of literary analysis: these scholars proposed theories and concepts emphasizing personal/
locating meaning not in the text but rather in the individual agency and practice on the one hand and
utterance, suggested that meanings are not mono- those emphasizing collective/institutional forces of
lithic but are multiple, and that meanings are dia- structure and the group on the other. Second, there
logically constructed by not solely the author but are debates over the extent of universals in human
also by the reader and other forces such as the his- belief and practice, on the one hand, and the extent
tories readers of a text bring to the interpretation to which, and what explains, specific cultural differ-
of a literary work. These critiques, as well as wider ences in human belief and practice on the other. In
political and economic processes of globalization, this latter concern, studies have tended to empha-
mass media and communications, and transcul- size either cultural universals (e.g., Levi-Strauss’s
tural or transnational processes, such as accelerat- analysis of myths as manifesting a universal human
ing labor migration and refugee flight of vulnerable mental logic) or cultural specifics (e.g., Mead’s eth-
peoples and human rights concerns, have encour- nographic critique of T. Stanley Hall’s theory of a
aged moving toward a concept of culture empha- universal, biologically based experience of adoles-
sizing more process and practice—of culture as an cence). The individual/collectivity issue, its roots
encounter, as negotiable, and as relational (Eriksen, pervasive in social theory, is addressed here first,
2003; Gupta & Ferguson, 1997) rather than tex- in terms of the tendency of the theoretical pen-
tual or structural in the older, static sense of this dulum to swing back and forth between these two
concept. Arjun Appadurai (1996), for example, has poles of emphasis. Addressed next is the problem
proposed new terms for culture such as ethnoscape of universals versus local cultural variations, with
and technoscape. These terms have not, however, a particular focus here on approaches in the sub-
replaced the term culture in the mainstream disci- field of psychological anthropology within cultural
plinary discourses. But they have brought greater anthropology.

ra sm u ssen 101
Following discussions of these two theoretical no more than an aggregation of individuals brought
issues pertaining to the individual in culture and together in realization of individual goals. The focus
society, there is a review of work relevant to these is not on wider power structures, whether cultural/
concerns: culture and personality and encultura- symbolic, social, or material.
tion; altered states, including trance possession/ The third major position on this issue includes
mediumship and dreams and healing and medico- doctrines that emphasize that these two processes
ritual specialists; and concepts of body, senses, and and forces are complementary—that is, both struc-
person/self. These topics, although not representa- tural influences on human action and individual
tive of all issues or topics in cultural anthropology, agency are capable of changing social structure.
have received much attention, have raised key ques- In this view, there are moves toward emphasizing
tions, and have suggested future directions in the practice, process, and relations (e.g., post-struc-
discipline. tural and post-modern theorists such as Anthony
Giddens and Pierre Bourdieu). In these works, a
Collectivities and Individuals; number of interesting formulations of alternatives
Structure and Agency to either extreme of emphasis have emerged; for
Structure and agency constitute two main shapers example, Peter Berger and Steven Luckman in The
of outcomes. Most theories tend to emphasize indi- Construction of Social Reality (1966) argued that
vidual practice or collective social action. In this trend, society forms individuals, who create society in a
there have been approximately three main positions continuous dialectic. Anthony Giddens (1984), in
taken. First is the position involving doctrines that his concept of structuration, opposed the dualism of
social/cultural life is largely determined by social structure and agency out of hand, favoring a duality
structure and that individual agency or practice can of structure in the sense that structure constitutes
be explained as mostly the outcome of structure or both the medium and the outcome of conduct it
institutions; examples include French Structuralism recursively organizes and structure constitutes rules
of Claude Levi-Strauss, with its emphasis on univer- and resources that do not exist outside actions but
sal mental logical structures; Durkheimian norma- continuously impact its production and reproduc-
tive sociology and its influence in anthropology; the tion of action. Giddens also opposed analogies
British social anthropological school of structural- between social and physical structures (e.g., the
functionalism (e.g., Radcliffe-Brown); and some British structural functional “machine” or “body”
Marxist theories. model of society). For Giddens, there is structure,
The second position includes doctrines that but this is more fluid and negotiable. Even in these
reverse the above emphasis, stressing instead the more nuanced approaches, the issue remains of not
capacity of individuals (individual agents) to con- solely who we are but who we are in relation to ideas
struct and reconstruct their worlds, and the neces- (cultural knowledge, or values), practice (agency),
sity of explanations in actors’ terms. Examples and structure (institutions).
include utilitarianism as formulated by John Locke, One prominent concern, shown in the pervasive
and the associated Economic Man liberal and neo- presence of the adjectives “structural” and “post-
liberal economic theories of cost–benefit analysis; structural” in anthropology, has been with struc-
ethnomethodology and related game theory studies ture: what is it and from where does it derive? Also,
of Frederik Barth (e.g., the individual flexibly wear- how does one conceptualize the changing relation-
ing different “hats” of identity); and the dramatur- ship between structure and agency? These concerns,
gical concept of social action analogous to theatrical still very much alive in cultural anthropology, can
performance of Erving Goffman, centering on the be traced back to the emergence of the social sci-
human actor’s presentation of self and impression- ences as academic disciplines in the late nineteenth
management on a kind of stage. These share an and early twentieth centuries. As founder of both
emphasis on the immediate situation and individual anthropology and sociology, Emile Durkheim (1895,
calculations during social interaction, a philosophi- 1912) addressed the problem of social cohesion in
cal school of thought holding that utility entails the so-called “poly-segmentary societies” that he consid-
greatest happiness of the greatest number of persons ered based on mechanical solidarity, in contrast to
and in which the assumption is that individuals the organic solidarity of modern societies with their
rationally pursue their own interests and this seeps division of labor (Parsons, 1965, p. 39). Parsons
down to benefit all in the long term. Here, society is traces Durkheim’s early opposition to utilitarian

102 c ultural ant hro po log y


and psychological explanations to other currents her statement that “there is no society, only individ-
in French intellectual history—namely, Descartes, uals and families.” For Durkheimians, by contrast,
Rousseau, Saint-Simon, August Comte, and Fustel society is a system formed by association and a dif-
de Coulanges (Parsons, 1965, pp. 39–65). His deep ferent reality with its own characteristics.
concern was to mediate between British empiricism Yet Durkheim does not dismiss psychology
and utilitarianism and German idealism. completely; he believes it plays an important role
in preparing for the study of social phenomena
The Issue of Structure (Parsons, 1965). Indeed, Durkheim thought that
In his Rules of the Explanation of Social Facts the essential elements of culture and social structure
(1895 [1958]), Durkheim critiques functional utili- are internalized as part of the individual personality.
tarianism (Parsons, 1965) and, in my view, implic- Nevertheless, an element of exteriority is involved in
itly, also British structural-functionalism, by arguing moral authority because, although internalized, the
there is more to interpreting social facts than social normative system must also objectively be part of a
morphology; the utility of a social fact may lead to system extending beyond the individual (Baerveldt &
social insight, but it does not explain its origins. Verheggen, 2011; Tavory, Jablonka, & Ginsburg,
Function does not create the social fact; facts come 2011, this volume). It is not subjective in the sense
from somewhere deeper. Prior forces must exist to of a purely private individual, for it is also a cultural
produce the fact. Also, facts can exist without serv- object in sense relevant to idealistic tradition. For
ing a purpose; they may have never been used or example, the meaning of success cannot be estab-
may have lost their utility—for example, because of lished without understanding the interplay between
this, causes of a social phenomenon and its function the motivation of the actor and the normative claims
must be studied separately, and cause must be stud- impinging on him from his social environment,
ied before its effects. Also confronted here is the issue expressed in the distinction made by a student of
of where social phenomena originate. Previously, Durkheim’s, Marcel Mauss, between two types of
Comte and Spencer asserted that society is a system personhood/self: le moi (me) and la conception de
derived from an individual psyche of humans set up la personne sociale (concept of social person). For, at
to achieve certain goals. In their view, social theory the same time, as Nsamenang (2011) points out in
is an extension of psychology. Durkheim disputes the present volume, the social environment of any
this argument: it is not individual wants and needs given actor of reference is composed of other actors
that dictate how humans act but social forces that whose action must be also analyzed as interactional.
transcend them; he asserted that it is not individual Anomie, or normlessness, thus makes achieving
wants and needs that dictate how a human acts but, goals meaningless from lack of clear criteria.
rather, social forces that transcend them. Only soci- Durkheim later theorized on religion, sym-
ety remains to explain social life, as this pressures bolic systems, and collective representations (1912
an individual to act and think in certain ways. This [1954]) and emphasized a theory of culture in
is accomplished through association. We are not relation to that of society. Here religion is the pri-
merely the sum of our parts; in association, we act mordial matrix, from which principal elements of
differently than we do as individuals. We become culture emerged by the process of differentiation—
a separate entity that transcends our individuality. specifically, in totemism, the origin of religion. The
For example, this view would explain some unex- classification in cultural belief/knowledge that dis-
pected election results as not resulting from the sum tinguishes between sacred and profane is similar
total of atomistic, individual opinions but instead to the distinction between moral obligations and
from the work of structural facts (e.g., economic expediency or utility. For Durkheim and those
forces) and collective representations (e.g., cultural influenced by this theorist, such as Marcel Mauss
values) that transcend individuals’ consciousness (1936) and later, Mary Douglas (1966), the quality
and actions—in other words, a collective conscious of sacredness does not reside in any intrinsic prop-
in a kind of crowd psychology a la Gustav Lamont. erties of the object treated as sacred but, rather, in
Society is a given reality, having exteriority from its properties as a symbol and its position to other
the point of view of its own members, but it also objects, seen by Durkheim as collective representa-
regulates or constrains their action. This view is very tions, which became defined in recent and contem-
opposed to a utilitarian view, as expressed by the porary cultural anthropology as symbolic systems
former British Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher in (Turner, 1967). In this formulation, there is a close

ra sm u ssen 103
integration between the religious system of represen- Shared Universal Themes, Local Cultural,
tations and the structure of society itself, linked by and Personal Variations
the attitude of moral respect that Durkheim called Another stream of thought in cultural anthro-
“awe.” According to Durkheim, this integration is pology, psychological anthropology (which arose
particularly close in primitive religion but also exists from its ancestral school, culture, and personality)
in others. Any cultural system must have a collective approaches the problem of the anthropological
aspect, for symbolization that is wholly private is subject by focusing on individual mental aspects of
no longer cultural or even truly symbolic; this later humankind in learning the culture and weighs the
influenced Clifford Geertz’s (1973) concept of cul- relative power of shared universal common themes
ture as shared, public, and translatable. and local variations. The complex processes by
In the wake of this legacy, several more nuanced which an individual acquires traits his or her soci-
approaches to this issue have tended to retreat ety considers desirable—or undesirable—involve
somewhat from the normative traditions of the learning to experience the world in a particular way.
Durkheimians and the British structural-functional- Enculturation and socialization practices are one
ists and place greater emphasis on agency and prac- focus. These differ widely from culture to culture
tice, although differing nonetheless from the older and are processes by which the individual learns
ethnomethodological and utilitarian emphases, by knowledge, values, and skills required in a particular
giving some nods to the power of structure. society. Because of this great variation, anthropolo-
For example, in his work Outline of a Theory of gists have asked whether people who grow up in dif-
Practice (1977), Pierre Bourdieu addressed conti- ferent societies learn to see the world differently. So
nental philosophy as much as anthropology. But completely does socialization shape our experience
Bourdieu drew on the Marxist concept of habitus of the world that we come to see our own world-
and also emphasized practice to explore the question view as natural. Psychologically oriented cultural
of human agency. In Bourdieu’s formulation, habitus anthropologists have used cross-cultural studies as
consists of a system of durable, transposable dispo- a basis for considering whether people universally
sitions, structured structures predisposed to func- perceive the world in the same way in some con-
tion as principles of generation, and structuring of texts, whether they think about it in same way, and
practices and representations that can be objectively whether concepts of person/self are universal.
regulated and regular without in any way being the The history of psychological anthropology has
product of obedience to rules. The term disposition been marked by attempts to distinguish human
signifies the special place the body occupies in habi- universals from characteristics that are particular
tus; dispositions are cultivated through interaction to specific, local populations of different cultural
with a whole symbolically structural environment, and community settings. One major focus in this
and these cultivated dispositions become inscribed debate has been Sigmund Freud’s concept of the
in body schema and in schemes of thought. For Oedipal complex. Freud thought that all male
example, Bourdieu discusses the Kabyle sense of children are subject to the Oedipal complex, in
honor, emphasizing the dual location of honor in which they sexually desire the mother and resent
both the mind and the flesh. In Bourdieu’s con- the father. Bronislaw Malinowski (1927) suggested
ception of habitus, mastery of body is essentially that the Oedipal complex is associated with patri-
successful in corporation (literally, the taking into lineal inheritance, but some other anthropologists
the body) of particular social meanings, inculcated see what they consider to be Oedipal patterns cross-
through various bodily disciplines oriented to such culturally in myths and dreams.
mundane practices as standing, sitting, speaking, The Oedipal complex takes its name from the
walking, and organization in space. In mastering story of the Greek hero Oedipus, who unknowingly
the body, the child develops skills to act in and on killed his father and married his mother. Freud sug-
the world. This is a dialectical process Bourdieu gested that the Oedipal story expresses conflicts that
calls “the appropriating by the world of a body thus are universal in the developmental cycle of males
enabled to appropriate the world” (Bourdieu, 1977, throughout the world. According to Freud, boys
p. 89). Thus the ideology or culture is not only in become sexually aroused by their mothers during
our head but also in our bodies (e.g., is embodied), intimate contact occasioned by maternal nurtur-
and although there is some room for agency, struc- ing and, as a result, become envious of their fathers.
ture tends to reproduce itself. Melford Spiro described the resulting conflict in the

104 c ultural ant hro po log y


boy’s mind: “As result of his wish to possess exclu- their sisters, despite strong sexual taboos between
sive love of the mother, boy moreover develops wish siblings. Brother–sister incest is also a prominent
to kill father and to replace him in his relationship theme in Trobriand myths. Melford Spiro argues
with mother (in mind of little boy, to kill means to that the brother–sister incest theme in these dreams
eliminate, to banish, to get rid of )” (Spiro, 1982, p. and myths suggests that sexual attraction and hostil-
4). At the same time, the boy admires his father and ity are deflected from their true objects, mother and
seeks to emulate him. father, and displaced onto less threatening subjects,
Malinowski ([1927] 1955) rejected Freud’s sister and maternal uncle. Thus Oedipal complex is
contention that the Oedipal complex is universal. not absent among Trobrianders; rather, it emerges
Rather, he argued, the tension between father and in disguised form as love for one’s sister and hostility
son described by Freud results from European sys- toward one’s mother’s brother (Spiro, 1982).
tem of patrilineal inheritance, rather than from sex- Whether the Oedipal complex is universal con-
ual competition for the mother. Because, under the tinues to be debated in anthropology. Freud sug-
patrilineal system, a boy inherits property and social gested that unconscious conflicts are expressed in
status from his father, the boy feels resentment dreams of individuals and myths of societies. Allen
toward his potential benefactor, who has authority Johnson and Douglass Price-Williams (1996) con-
over him. At the same time, the father feels ambiva- ducted a cross-cultural survey of myths and tales
lence toward his son, who will eventually assume and concluded that the Oedipal complex is indeed
control of his status and property as the father grows universally represented in these societies, suggesting
older and dies. that mother–son attraction and father–son hostility
Among Trobriander Islanders, Malinowski noted, is a theme in all societies (Womack, 2001, p. 186).
descent is matrilineal, which means a boy inherits This debate is not settled, however.
status and property from his mother’s brother rather The foregoing debate raises wider issues, such
than from his father. In the Trobriands, boys have as the relative influence of socialization and pat-
warm, affectionate relationships with their fathers terns of social organization on individual practices
because they do not see them in authoritarian role (Nsamenang, 2011, this volume). Recall that Franz
(Malinowski, [1927] 1955, p. 31). By contrast, Boas, as founding father of American anthropol-
the relationship between the boy and his mother’s ogy, in the early twentieth century emphasized the
brother is one of tension and conflict, as the boy will importance of culture. This insight influenced a
inherit his status and property through his mother’s number of anthropologists who studied the rela-
line, from the senior male, his maternal uncle. The tionships among culture, childrearing practices, and
maternal uncle is also in charge of disciplining the adult personality. The works of those anthropolo-
boy and feels ambivalent toward his heir, who will gists became known as the culture-and-personality
eventually displace him and take property away school. Although contemporary anthropologists
from his own son. According to Malinowski, it is reject these researchers’ overemphasis on uniformity
competition over authority and status, rather than within cultures and oversimplification of complex
over sexual access to the mother, that is the source of variables, the culture-and-personality school pro-
anxiety between a boy and the man from whom will vided an important basis for development of psy-
inherit his social position. Thus the Oedipal com- chological anthropology.
plex does not exist among matrilineal Trobriand One topic within this school concerned defin-
Islanders. ing “normal” and “deviant” behavior as shaped
Other anthropologists have more recently by socialization or enculturation. Ruth Benedict
re-analyzed Malinowski’s data to challenge his (1934) discussed how societies tolerate a range of
view that the Oedipal complex does not occur in behaviors considered normal and have means for
matrilineal societies. For example, Annette Weiner dealing with behavior that violates the norm—
(1976) found that fathers in the Trobriand Islands sometimes providing a niche for those who do not
still maintain social, emotional, and economic ties conform to normative expectations; for example,
with sons, despite the matrilineal emphasis, in gift- some Native American Indians have very flexible
giving and other exchanges. Melford Spiro (1982) concepts of gender roles in which biological men
found that in their dreams, Trobriand subjects never may become cultural females, formerly called “ber-
dreamed of having sexual intercourse with their dache” and now called “two spirits” (Whitehead in
mothers but did have some sexual dreams about Ortner, 1981).

ra sm u ssen 105
In some non-Western medicine, shamans or Cross-cultural studies of medico-ritual healing
mediumistic healers treat a variety of disorders, through altered states of consciousness—namely,
both physical and psychological. Anthropologists trance—illustrate these dynamics vividly. According
(Harner, 1990; Kendall, 1989; Winkelman, 2000) to the established biomedical allopathic medical
have noted that shamanic healing can be effective, model, recall that illness tends to be classified as
in part because it treats underlying tensions in the either physical or mental (organic or non-organic).
group instead of isolating the individual. Shamans Deviance from the ideal is often regarded as an
also treat illnesses through medico-ritual therapies, individual problem rather than as an affliction of
such as spirit possession (Rasmussen, 1995, 2001), the group as a collectivity. Most societies do not,
that are similar to techniques used by Western however, distinguish so neatly between physical
psychotherapists. (organic) and mental (non-organic) illness, nor do
they always draw a rigid boundary between inten-
Altered States (Spirit Possession/ tional and unintentional deviance. Treatment is
Mediumship/Shamanism; Dreams) usually aimed at identifying problematic relation-
and Healing ships within the group. In these societies, the source
According to the widespread biomedical model, of the problem is often attributed to outside forces,
a human being is a physical entity, a thing existing either naturalistic, human/social (personalistic), or
apart from other such physical entities. These indi- spiritual—for example, malevolent ghosts or shades
vidualistic and Cartesian mind/body dualist views (Foster, 1977). Traditional mediumistic healers,
are reflected in the allopathic or biomedical model widely called shamans in anthropology, frame their
of healing, in which illness is treated as a failure of diagnoses and treatments in symbolic terms. The
one’s organs or of bodily mechanisms. For exam- use of symbols in medico-ritual treatments express
ple, an illness may be diagnosed as a renal failure, a complex ideas in dramatic forms and allow indirect
failure of kidneys to perform as they ordinarily do. expression of emotional and social issues, (Turner,
Following from that diagnosis, treatment may be 1967), such as the unequal treatment of co-wives
confined to repairing kidneys rather than treating (Rasmussen, 1995, 2001, 2006).
the system that gave rise to failure of kidney to per- By attributing illness or nonconforming behav-
form as expected. In fact, kidneys share a relation- ior to demons or spirits, the shaman can diffuse
ship with every other aspect of body, including the and defuse the powerful emotions generated by
circulatory system, which delivers oxygen and other competing interests and conduct psychotherapeutic
nutrients to kidneys, and lungs, which take in air healing. The shaman uses symbols to treat a disor-
and provide oxygen that every part of body requires der within the social context. For example, he/she
(Womack, 2001, p. 183). might diagnose an illness as the result of not pleas-
By contrast, shamans or mediumistic healers ing an ancestor. In so doing, the healer brings to
trace the origins of illness to disrupted social rela- the surface tensions underlying the illness or deviant
tionships. This is an alien concept in Western bio- action of patient undergoing the medico-ritual and
or allopathic medicine, which until recently has addresses wider social conflicts.
tended to emphasize isolated, biological causes of Anthropologists have noted that many indige-
disease. Recent research is suggesting that although nous healers use techniques similar to those used in
the biomedical tradition is necessary for healing Western psychotherapy. In the former, symbols are
some diseases, it is an oversimplification in some used to communicate, whereas in the latter, medical
contexts of healing. Medical conditions such as terminology is used. For example, a shaman may per-
cancer, hypertension, and asthma may be related form a ritual drama by symbolically journeying into
to the expression or repression of emotions, which the realm of spirits. This journey is usually accom-
is also related to socialization and cultural expecta- panied by percussion music, which encourages the
tions about the appropriate way to behave in social patient and/or the healer to enter an altered state of
groups. Underlying the biomedical model is the trance, and malevolent spirits are dramatized with
idea that individuals are discrete units that stand in gestures and/or obliquely referred to in song verses
opposition to a culturally coherent group. This view (Rasmussen, 1995). Levi-Strauss (1963) explained
is at variance with some other models, which view the effectiveness of a shamanic treatment of a dif-
humans as members of groups, fulfilling their desti- ficult labor among the Cuna Indians of Panama,
nies only through social interaction. who guided a woman through a potentially fatal

106 c ultural ant hro po log y


childbirth through ritual use of symbols. The sha- first-person spirit encounter narratives from Asabano
man made ritual figures, chanted invocations per- culture. Asabano understand dreams to allow travel
sonifying the birthing woman’s pains as important in a spiritual dimension, such that a personal soul
figures in local myth, and purified the birthing room can leave the body and contact other spirits. The
by burning herbs. He changed the story of his jour- Asabano spiritual world is rich in indigenous tradi-
ney to the realm of Muu, the female power respon- tion but also reflects rapid cultural change they have
sible for forming the fetus. The shaman diagnosed seen in recent decades. Dreamed spiritual encoun-
the problem as Muu having exceeded her role and ters predispose people to perceive spirit beings in
capturing the soul of the mother-to-be. Through the waking life and are a significant cause of religious
persuasiveness of these metaphoric chants, in which convictions.
Muu is persuaded to release the woman’s soul, and Despite the diverse ways cultures influence and
the shaman exhorted his spirit figures to help him extract meanings from dreams, everywhere at least
rescue her soul, a successful childbirth occurs. These some dreams are understood as a means of actu-
rituals, featuring spirit possession and mediumship, ally traveling across spatial, temporal, and spiritual
are often open to the public, and the audience may dimensions (Lohmann, 2003) Common dream
participate in the healing process through support experiences are of person/self in motion, being and
for their person undergoing the healing. Whereas doing what one cannot in alert consciousness. Thus
in Western psychotherapy the patient speaks, in this dreams are experiences of some kind of transporta-
case the healer speaks (chants). Levi-Strauss ana- tion and transformation of body and soul. There are
lyzes the shaman’s account of his journey into the many shamanic dream journeys reported in anthro-
abode of Muu as a description of the woman’s body, pology of religion and medical anthropology from
and the patient understands this subconsciously different parts of the world. Thus there are rich vari-
and then relaxes, understands pain as not arbitrary ations on common themes in cultural understand-
but rather meaningful, and allows the birth to take ings and practices surrounding transformations of
place. Thus, in his symbolization, the shaman pro- body, senses, and person or “self.”
vides the sick woman with a language by means
of which unexpressed, and otherwise inexplicable, Concepts of Body, Senses, and
psychic states can be immediately expressed (Levi- Personhood/Self
Strauss, 1963, p. 198). In anthropology, the body, senses, and person-
Another important altered state or out-of-body hood have been accorded central importance since
experience is dreams, but these are given diverse approximately the nineteenth century. This inter-
interpretations in different social and cultural set- est developed along several lines. First, historically,
tings. Thus, although dreams are individually expe- anthropology has been more inclined to pose ques-
rienced, they are culturally informed (Lohmann, tions about the universal “essence” of humanity, as
2003, p. ix). Dreams are expressed in accordance the context of European colonialism prompted early
with social values pertaining to communication, scholars to address problem of human universals of
concepts of person, spirituality, and notions of ontology (knowing; understanding) in relation to
public/private. Roles of dreams vary, from a casual variations of social relationships. As a consequence,
topic of conversation, a psycho-analysis topic, to the ontological centrality of human embodiment
divine revelations, shamanic mediumistic journeys became one focus in the quest of universals.
to heal, and political meetings. Dreams also allow One early question raised concerned the range
many people to experience continued participation of social and cultural arrangements necessary for
of ancestors in their daily lives, and this too may survival and reproduction of self and body. Several
influence decision-making. Stewart and Strathern streams of study were important here: in nineteenth
(in Lohmann, 2003, pp. 43–61) examine dreams century unilineal evolutionism, there was a conver-
phenomenologically in two Melanesian societies, gence of questions of universals in these theorists’
the Hagen and the Duna; here, the dead come to quest for universals in human origins. Central here
visit the living in dreams and may warn of future was the relationship between culture and nature.
problems or attacks. In this, the body played a part, as it offered one
The spiritual and emotional connection of solution to the problem of cultural relativism and
dreams is widespread. Roger Ivar Lohmann (in psychic unity of humankind. But opposed to this
Lohmann, 2003, pp. 189–211) presents a series of was another line of development that contributed

ra sm u ssen 107
to anthropological study of the human body in was symbolic classification through the medium of
nineteenth century social Darwinism during the the body itself; for example, the body becomes a
Victorian period. There were three key ideas here: central metaphor of political and social order (e.g.,
that human beings were essentially a part of nature, food taboos reflect the wider order).
rather than outside it; in a distortion of Charles The body has long been an important locus of
Darwin’s theory of natural selection, there arose discourse, not solely in biology and medicine but
the theory of universality of the fittest and unequal also in the human sciences, although in the latter it
ranking of cultures in terms of phases of progress to has often been denigrated. In the seventeenth cen-
explain social change; and more recently, there have tury, rationalists believed that the sensuous body
been studies in twentieth century physical anthro- was an object to be distrusted because it led to
pology of the expression of emotions in humans— subjective, rather than objective, perceptions. Also
for example, Konrad Lorenz on aggression. denigrated were the “lower senses”—that is, non-
Another question that directs anthropological visual sense modalities. But later there were trends
attention to person/self and body has been, “What is toward greater attention to the body and extra-
it to be human?” In more recent structural and sym- visual modalities, as well, as a vital subject of cul-
bolic studies of the late twentieth century, theories tural study. These trends arose from critiques of the
such as Claude Levi-Strauss’s proposed that humans rationalists—for example, Montaigne, Nietzsche,
are cultural because of meaning contrasts—specif- Husserl, and Heidegger.
ically certain prohibitions (e.g., the incest taboo Karl Marx suggested a dialectical relationship
and purity and danger categories) (Levi-Strauss, between the body and the social and natural worlds.
1963; Douglas, 1966). This focus on contradictions For example, Marx recognized that it was only by
between body and soul, and instinct versus social attending to human engagement in sensuous practi-
solidarity, opposed civilization to nature and argued cal (i.e., material) activity that he could understand
that categories of reality—for example, pure and “real, corporeal man.” In other words, Marx insisted
impure, sacred and profane—reflected categories of that the body is not just there but acts upon the
culture, not nature. world and is, in turn, acted upon by the world that
Also relevant to these ideas was German roman- they body has helped to create. Marx saw this dia-
ticism of the nineteenth century, whose tripartite lectic as mediated most fundamentally by human
division of body (Leib), spirit (Geist), and soul labor. However, subsequent writers have explored
(Seele) conveyed that idea that because humans are this dialectic in terms of a much broader compass;
unfinished as biological creatures, not at home in for example, Michel Foucault (1978) traced the
nature, they require the protective canopy of insti- historical development of scientific discourse (i.e.,
tutions and culture. The point here is that the body conversations that represent and study and form
is constructed by culture and society; the latter, policies) and institutions impinging on the body in
with language, filter and buffer nature (Baerveldt & practices seemingly as disparate as sexuality, psycho-
Verheggen, 2011, this volume). analysis, medicine, and the penal system, as well
Now, from these streams of thought, three fun- as physical spaces such as architecture. Scientific
damental propositions have remained influential in study involves surveillance and control, not merely
anthropology and sociology: human embodiment knowledge, of the body. This is Foucault’s concept
creates a set of constraints, but also the body has of the panoptic gaze, power at different levels in the
the potential to be elaborated on by socio-cultural system.
development—that is, in Western philosophi- In more recent social theory, most views of the
cal and social theory, the body generally appears body analyze this as not merely a natural object but
as a constraint and potential; there are contradic- as one socially, historically, and politically consti-
tions between human sexuality and socio-cultural tuted. This idea animates the most recent and cur-
requirements; and these natural facts are experi- rent (i.e., mid-to-late twentieth and twenty-first
enced differently according to the classification century) work on the body. Erving Goffman has
system (e.g., gender constructs). This insight lead described how the body forms the implicit foun-
to the issue of body as a classificatory system. dation for stigma. Feminist theorists such as Susan
Mary Douglas (1966), for example, theorized that Bordo (1993) examine more general representa-
humans respond to disorder, such as risk, uncer- tions of bodies—particularly of women’s bodies—
tainty, and contradictions; their principal response within myriad discourses and institutions, such as

108 c ultural ant hro po log y


art, advertising, and popular romances, and ask how body as a “prolegomenon,” suggesting that the lack
these shape both how women experience their bod- of more critical analysis of the body could lead to
ies and how others treat them as embodied beings. anthropology’s falling prey to biological fallacy and
Now, these writers insist that discourses and institu- related assumptions that are paradigmatic to bio-
tions impinge as powerfully as does (Marxian) labor medicine (Scheper-Hughes & Lock, 1988, p. 6).
process on how body is lived. This biological fallacy, the Cartesian mind–body
Also, another aspect of common ground shared split, has multiplied into a number of other binary
by Marx and many of these writings is a dual con- relationships in Western societies, such as culture/
cern with the ideological (symbolic and expressive) nature; society/individual, spirit/matter, and so
and material (political and economic) aspects, or, forth (Scheper-Hughes & Lock, 1988, p. 10). These
in Foucaultian terms, discourses and techniques of authors write this essay specifically because they see
the lived body. But Marx’s and Foucault’s and many body concepts as being quite significant to anthro-
feminists’ body studies almost always and often pologists for understanding culture and societies, on
implicitly concern the Western (Euro-American) the one hand, and for increasing knowledge of the
body. cultural sources and meanings o health and illness,
Finally, also relevant in developing a theory of on the other (ibid., p. 8), and because they want
body was the traditional emphasis in social/cul- to prescribe alternatives to accepted approaches and
tural anthropology on comparison and the study concepts.
of small-scale, non-industrial, and more recently, of These authors propose seeing the body as “physi-
more industrial large-scale societies. Scholars from cal and symbolic artifact, naturally and culturally
Marcel Mauss’s (1935) “Techniques of the Body” produced” (ibid., p. 7). They conceptualize three
have found that cross-culturally, the body is an distinct but related body perspectives anthropol-
important surface in which marks of social status, ogy should take in its study: the individual body;
family, position, ritual prohibitions, social affili- the social body; and the body politic. They assume
ation, and religious condition are displayed (e.g., that most humans have a concept of individual
tattoos in Polynesian societies). Mauss catalogued body—that is, they phenomenally lived experience
cross-cultural variations in bodily techniques for all of the body-self, separated into other body-selves.
manner of activities, from swimming to sex, empha- They highlight alternative ways of looking at the
sizing how powerfully each society inscribes itself on individual body-self and accounting for relations
the body of each of its members and how resistant between mind, body, culture, nature, and soci-
the body can be to altering techniques it “knows.” ety (ibid., p. 11). Recognizing different concepts
Although these processes are present everywhere, (monistic, holistic, multiplistic) of body-self is key
they are most obvious and directly expressed in to any anthropological understanding of way soci-
smaller-scale societies. Mauss’s point here was that eties diagnose and treat illness and the way they
these techniques are not consciously taught; rather, define health, the way they define selves as healthy
they are shaped by and express a habitus, a notion and treat perceived individual and societal illnesses.
Mauss invented, but one that the French ethnogra- These authors make a final suggestion that an explo-
pher and social theorist Pierre Bourdieu, as shown, ration of body-image (body boundaries, distortions
later developed further. in body perceptions) is essential to the concept of
The body has also become a popular focus in individual body—for example, point out that a
medical anthropology within both cultural and relationship between people’s choice of symptoms
bio-anthropology, over the past several decades and concepts of body image should be considered
in particular, from concerns over AIDS and other to come to a better understanding of social and cul-
pandemics. A seminal essay on the body in this tural meanings of humanity and perceived threats
area, “The Mindful Body” (1988), was authored by to human health, well-being, and social integration
Nancy Scheper-Hughes and Margaret Lock. This is (ibid., pp. 17–18).
an attempt to deconstruct, uncover, and problema- Turning to their concept of the social body,
tize and ultimately to encourage resistance to con- Lock and Scheper-Hughes discuss how the body is
ventional Cartesian concepts of the body heretofore culturally and socially representative, stating that
accepted by earlier anthropologists. Scheper-Hughes “Cultural constructions of and about the body are
and Lock label the failure of medical anthropology useful in sustaining particular views of society and
to critically examine accepted conceptions of the social relations” (ibid., p. 19). The body is used

ra sm u ssen 109
representationally to devise and justify social values or altered states experienced in illness and healing is,
(e.g., as in symbolic equations involving left and as shown, another way anthropologists attempt to
right handedness). Links have been made between move beyond a restrictive, Cartesian viewpoint and
health or sickness of individual bodies and social re-explore notions of human agency in society.
bodies for centuries. These authors suggest that most Another trend, since around the 1970s, has been
common symbolic use of body has been to classify to question the classical supposition that rigorous
and humanize living spaces (ibid., p. 21). Point to research methods always result in objectively “true”
differences between ethnomedical and biomedical observation. The concept of the sensuous body (i.e.,
concepts of social relations in the healthy or sick focus on the senses in studies) emerged as a new
body; for example, ethnomedical systems see social site of cultural and political analysis. Initially, many
relations as inevitably linked to individual health works considered the body as a text that could be
and illness. They suggest that ethnomedical concepts “read” hermeneutically and consequently tended to
seem to entail a unique kind of human autonomy ignore context and multisensorial modalities. There
(ibid., p. 21) that industrialized modern world has have been calls for greater attention to not solely cat-
lost. These societies do not appear to experience the aloguing local cultural concepts of body and senses
same sort of body alienations (anorexia, bulimia, into the ethnographic record but also incorporat-
etc.) experienced in Western societies, which seems ing them into anthropological theory. As Herzfeld
also to be linked to capitalism and its regimenta- (2001, Chapter 11) notes, sight and writing have
tion. They point very specifically also to the body been widely associated with power; anthropology is
as machine metaphor as one of the sources of body primarily verbal and textual, but much cultural and
alienation in industrialized societies. Their overall social life is more complex and involves additional,
sentiment is that in industrialized Western society, extravisual, and nontextual sense modalities.
“the human shape of things and even the human In response to these problems, there are
shape of humans is in retreat “(ibid., p. 23). attempts to consider how knowledge and percep-
Expanding on the concept of social body, tions of legitimacy and truth in many societies
Scheper-Hughes and Lock use the concept of body devolve from not simply vision and text, but also
politic to suggest that the relationship between social from modalities of smell, touch, taste, and hear-
and individual bodies is more than metaphors and ing. Classen (1997) describes how historically and
collective representations of natural and cultural culturally in Euro-American philosophies and cul-
(ibid., p. 23). This relationship is ultimately about tures, theories tend to be based in perceptions of
power, about social control of bodies. Societies do the body and senses that are inflected with gen-
not control bodies only in times of crisis but often dered values. For example, the sense modality of
aggressively reproduce and socialize kinds of bodies sight has in the west often been considered asso-
they need or require to sustain themselves (ibid., p. ciated with masculine values and the sense modal-
25). Ways in which societies reproduce and social- ity of touch with feminine values. In pre-modern
ize bodies are through body decoration and through Europe, women were seen as the imperfect result
constructing concepts of politically correct bodies. of an insufficient amount of heat during the pro-
Although the politically correct body is often sup- cess of conception and gestation. Sex differences
posed to be healthy, it can actually mean grotesque in temperature were drawn from Aristotle, Galen
distortions of human anatomy. The body politic and other ancient authorities and supported by
has brutal ways of conforming individual bodies contemporary scholarship and folklore. The innate
to requirement of socio-political establishment: coldness of women was considered by physicians
medicine, criminal justice, psychiatry and vari- and philosophers to be the cause of particular char-
ous social sciences, and even torture. They further acteristics of the female body: storing food as fat,
point out that, post-Malthus, the body-politic con- menstrual blood, milk, enabling them to carry and
cept involves finding ways to control populations, nourish children (Classen, 1997, p. 3). Because of
involving control of sexuality, gender, and repro- this lack of heat rising up into their heads, women’s
duction. These authors propose that an anthro- bodies were allegedly broad at the bottom and nar-
pology of the body involve a theory of emotions row at the top. By contrast, “hot” men had narrow
because emotions may provide a vital link, a bridge, hips and broad shoulders; baldness was a sign of
between mind and body, individual, society, and burning up of the hair on their heads. Heat also
body politic (ibid., p. 29). Tracking emotional states caused men’s sexual organs to be external, whereas

110 c ultural ant hro po log y


insufficient heat obliged women’s sexual organs to her anger at her husband. He also described vividly
remain within the body (Classen, 1997, p. 3). how Songhai cosmology/philosophy and medico-
Among some other peoples, the thermal attri- rituals later inspired him to cope with his cancer
butes of the body and the different senses are not treatments in the United States (Stoller, 2004).
conceived as hierarchically nor represented as Rasmussen (1999) analyzed the role of aroma as
rigidly in ranked or oppositional terms, as in the channeling communication in Tuareg society and
major European philosophical and scientific tradi- also analyzed its role in constructing ethnographic
tions, despite widespread cultural differentiation knowledge; among the Tuareg, for example, scents
according to gender constructs—for example, the are used to diagnose non-organic (mental) illnesses,
prevalent association in some cultures of written and many pleasant scents are associated with spir-
texts with scriptural scholarship. Rasmussen (2006) its. Perfume and incense are used as a medium to
describes how, in Tuareg culture, visual and writ- communicate among humans and between humans
ten texts are associated with Islamic scholarship and and spirits—for example, in medico-ritual healing.
Qur’anic healing, which tends to be dominated by Their use is taken seriously and are not merely aes-
men, and touch in healing is more associated with thetics, an alternative, or less credible, in contrast to
female herbalists and other non-Qur’anic healers. aromatherapy in the United States. Islamic schol-
All of these healers are respected and sought out by ars use scents to diagnose mental states. Diviners
both women and men at different times; thus, here place scented bark inside their mouth to aid their
the sense modalities, although having associations, memory in healing and place perfumes in cowrie
are not rigidly dichotomized by gender, nor are they shells to their tutelary spirits in a special pact that
hierarchically ranked. Although the Quranic heal- enables the diviner in a dream to foretell the future
ing by marabouts is often described as a science, and conduct psycho-social counseling. Certain
nonetheless, non-Qu’ranic healing is not denigrated scents, however, are also considered dangerous, and
or considered less reliable but as specialized in heal- aroma in general can also be used to express anti-
ing certain ailments—for example, stomachaches social feelings, conflicts, and struggles. For example,
and women’s reproductive and marital problems many Tuareg believe that a person can catch illness
(Rasmussen, 2006). Although Tuareg also differ- through the scent of someone who already has the
entiate according to gender and make gendered illness, somewhat like Victorian contagion theories.
thermal/humoral associations in their counteractive The aromas of certain medicinal trees are believed
medical system, there is marked absence of a defi- to cause infertility in young women; that is a reason
ciency model here. There is also flexibility according given by some Tuareg for the predominance of older
to context. In local counteractive theories of balance women in the herbal healing profession. The nose
and harmony, for example, hot and cold states of the and mouth are the principal orifices through which
body and diseases are caused for men and women disease and more general pollution (from both
alike by an imbalance of these forces (Rasmussen, physiological and social sources) enter the body; for
2006). Women should ideally be cool, and men ide- example, smith/artisans can convey anger at nobles’
ally warm, but even these ideals should not become not sharing food with them, even if food is out of
too pronounced or intensified; for example, a man sight, through smelling it. Thus one must hide food
can become too hot and fall ill. The goal is to find from smell and not solely from view. Also, local cul-
equilibrium between hot and cold; one should avoid tural values show great concern with protecting the
an excess of either thermal states. body from what enters through the nose, as well as
Recently, there have been analyses of how the mouth. In rural areas, most men wear a face-veil
anthropological and ethnographic knowledge sys- over the nose to protect from evil spirits and other
tems are constructed through extravisual sense malevolent powers, as well as to express respect and
modalities. Paul Stoller (1987, 1989) has described reserve, important values in the male gender role,
ethnographic insights from sound and taste. In particularly among nobles. Also, incense and per-
his apprenticeship with a Songhai sorcerer/healer fume are believed to not just mask unpleasant odors
in Niger, he learned about ritual healing powers but to actually dispel them, to repel evil spirits and
by tasting local herbs and listening to the heal- disease; they work like a religious amulet. For exam-
er’s incantations and learned about social conflicts ple, incense is burned during weddings and passed
through the gustatory medium of food, when a co- around a circle of guests, who saturate their clothing
wife of his field host prepared a bad sauce to express with it. New mothers and babies also are protected

ra sm u ssen 111
from jealousy by incense burning nearby along with who had been missing for a long time from his Nuer
a metal knife stuck in the sand of the tent floor and community, for whom mortuary rituals were held,
Islamic amulets placed around it. Thus in Tuareg thereby defining his status as deceased. Even upon
culture, society, ritual, and healing and sociability, his return many years later, he remained defined as
aroma is not solely a part of cosmetics and aesthetics deceased and thus was no longer a full social person
but also acts powerfully in medico-ritual and phar- in the community of the living. In many cultures,
maceutical contexts (Rasmussen, 1999, 2006). there is no concept of what the English expression
More broadly, the studies of these cultural uses “self-made man” (or person) implies; rather, one’s
of taste, the gustatory modality, and scent and the achievements cannot be isolated from the achieve-
olfactory modality reveal magic, religion, and sci- ments of one’s lineage or clan. Also, many cultural
ence as not so neatly opposed. Anthropologists knowledge systems conceptualize components of
should attempt to understand, represent, and take personhood in distinctive ways: for example, in
seriously other peoples’ ways of constructing experi- some communities in the Congo, a person’s shadow
ence and knowledge, and the study of sense modali- is key to identity and cannot be stepped on or
ties and body and person/self contribute profound photographed without threatening one’s identity
insights into these issues. (Jacobsen-Widding, in Jackson & Karp, 1990).
This demonstrates the need, recognized widely in Historically, there have been at least three basic
anthropology, to take analysis of the body to another attempts to define personal identity in Western (i.e.,
level. The focus here is on the cultural construction Euro-American) philosophy since the Enlightenment
of what it means to be a person, or human—that that have influenced, to varying degrees, anthropol-
is, identity and expectations concerning how the ogy: (1) mental/idealist based; (2) material based;
person or “self ” acts in cultural and social settings and (3) illusion, construct, or memory-based. First,
and how different cultures elaborate on this iden- those who define personal identity in mentalistic
tity. Despite their very different approaches to this terms view our identity through time as a func-
topic (philosophical approaches tend to be more tion of the continuity of our thoughts, beliefs, and
influenced by European Enlightenment concepts feelings—for example, medieval religious theory
and Anthropological approaches attempt to elicit of the soul as the seat of personal identity, where
more culturally relative concepts), there has been reason and will reside (e.g., St. Augustine) (later,
some influence of philosophy on anthropological Rene Descartes substituted mind for soul in this
theories, and both anthropology and philosophy scheme). Next, those who explain personal identity
share questions regarding how the concept of per- in terms of the continuity of our bodies; accord-
son is defined and used in social interaction. Both ing to this group, despite changes we undergo in
anthropology and philosophy, as heirs to Classical growth and development, there is a basic physi-
and Enlightenment theories predominantly from cal unity of our identity that is responsible for our
Western European historical and political and intel- remaining the same person (e.g., Gilbert Ryle); this
lectual milieu, are concerned with distinguishing position opposes Cartesian and other older forms
between continuity over time that enables social of dualism. Finally, some philosophers have argued
agents to characterize an individual as a person and that personal identity is just an illusion without
with an epistemological problem posed by differ- an independent existence or substance. For exam-
ences between social attributes and self-knowledge. ple, Thomas Hume believed that all existence was
For example, in an early study, Marcel Mauss distin- a matter of perception. For John Locke, personal
guished between le moi and la conception sociale de la identity was seen as based on self-consciousness,
personne; the former is the externally imposed cul- in particular on the memories of past experiences.
tural and social identity; the latter consists of one’s All these theories suggest a non-uniform (Western
self-definition or self-concept. and other view of ) notion of personal identity and
How is person/self relevant to the anthropologi- self; even in our own culture, we can hardly sum
cal subject? Anthropology’s primary concern is to up in one set of language terminology a unitary
examine comparatively and historically ideas about notion of self, because there has been historical
power, personhood, and agency, cultural ideas about change and internal cultural diversity even within
how humans interact with each other in terms of self that category commonly called “the West.” Thus
and social concepts of identity. For example, Evans- the problem is how we know this: Which data do
Pritchard (1940, 1956) described the case of a man we examine? Useful are data from psycho-analysis;

112 c ultural ant hro po log y


popular lay folk notions; childrearing advice; and as mentally ill and felt they were helping Alice by
healing systems. Thus one may tentatively general- preventing her from engaging in what they saw as
ize, with some caution, contemporary “Western” inappropriate social behavior.
(i.e., Euro-American) notions of personhood as
generally (albeit with exceptions) more individual- Future Directions in Cultural
istic (Battaglia, 1995, Introduction) relative to some Anthropology
other cultural concepts of personhood. Yet neither These highlights in cultural anthropological
Western nor non-Western concepts of personhood studies share a concern with representing culture
are unitary or static; everywhere, these concepts and society as more fluid, dynamic, and relational
may change in relation to economics, history, poli- and a vision of individuals and collectivities as
tics, and social processes. mutually influential. As noted, there have recently
Thus, most recent and current studies of con- been critiques of all the canons of anthropological
cepts of person/self attempt to elicit a fuller range thought (culture and personality, Durkheimian,
of expression of person/self beliefs in different structural-functionalism, interpretive, and French
contexts, regardless of where these prevail. For structuralism schools) for oversimplifying the vari-
example, according to Didier Kaphagawane (in ables involved in studying culture and society and
Karp & Masolo, 1990), the work of early scholar also for overestimating the degree of conformity and
Placide Tempels on Bantu philosophy tended to continuity in culture and society. In all societies,
reproduce Enlightenment philosophical bias view- values are often contradictory. Culture and society
ing a person as divided between mind or ideas and and the persons comprising them can no longer be
material body. Kaphagawane shows how, among reduced to clear-cut, essentialized entities, and their
the Bantu-speaking Chewa in Malawi, munthu localities are no longer always literal, geographical,
denotes humans in certain situations but not oth- or neatly bounded.
ers. Munthu refers to a person with social and mor- Thus many cultural anthropologists now recog-
ally valued qualities, not without them. Thus to nize the need to explore the following questions:
state that someone is not a munthu does not imply
1. What are some emerging new spaces or
he/she is not a human but, rather, that he/she lacks
localities of culture?
approved moral and social conduct. Thus person-
2. Why, alongside resistance, dissent, and
hood is not a stable category but is disputed and
personal practice and agency, does society
negotiated, and changes, even within a single com-
nonetheless tend to reproduce itself?
munity and during the same era.
3. What leads some persons to internalize the
In addition, most recent studies of personhood
rules or habitus of learned dispositions more fully
or concepts of person/self in anthropology have
and others less fully?
focused on factors that shape cross-cultural varia-
4. In globalization, what are some forces of
tions in definition of self/person. The question posed
relocalization, and how can scholars in their
is, “Where do these concepts come from?” Based on
analyses escape this binary opposition?
her study of French-Portuguese bilingual speakers,
5. How can scholars in their analyses, similarly,
Michele E.J. Koven (2000, p. 437) suggests that
escape circular arguments concerning individual/
bilingualism allows people to express different kinds
culture/collectivities and local/universal processes?
of selves in each language. Desjarlais (2000, p. 467)
6. How can the culture concept be reformulated
suggests that actions and diffuse understandings
to encompass virtual aspects of human life?
they effect are commonly rooted in relations of dif-
ferential powers and authorities. Alice, a resident of
a shelter, had represented herself as “happy on the REFERENCES
Appadurai, A. (1996). Modernity At Large. Minneapolis:
street” until authorities (police, psychiatrists, social University of Minnesota Press.
workers) started to treat her badly by forcing her Asad, T. (1986). The Translation of Culture. In J. Clifford &
to take medications, confining her in psychiatric G. Marcus. (Eds.). Writing Culture, Berkeley, CA: University
hospitals, and requiring her to follow the edicts of of California Press.
Asad, T. (2003). Reformations of the Secular. Cambridge:
psychiatric and legal institutions (Desjarlais, 2000,
Cambridge University Press.
p. 468, quoted in Womack, 2001, p. 184). Whereas Baerveldt, C. & Verheggen, T. (2011). Enactivism. In J. Valsiner
Alice had seen her life on the streets as an expres- (Ed), The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology. New York:
sion of her competence, authorities viewed Alice Oxford University Press.

ra sm u ssen 113
Barthes, R. (1982). Empire of Signs. New York: Hill and Wang. Jackson, M. & Karp, I. (1990). Personhood and Agency in Africa.
Battaglia, D. (1995). Rhetorics of Self-Making. Berkeley, CA: Washington DC: Smithsonian Institution Press.
University of California Press. Johnson, A. & Price-Williams, D. (1996). Oedipus Ubiquitous:
Benedict, R. (1934). Patterns of Culture. New York: Mentor. The Family Complex in World Folk Literature. Stanford, CA:
Berger, P. and Luckmann, T (1966). The Social Construction of Stanford University Press.
Reality. London: Allen Lane. Karp, I. & Masolo, D. A. (2000). African Philosophy as Cultural
Bodley, J. (1975 [1990]). Victims of Progress. Mountain View, Inquiry. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
CA: Mayfield Publishing Company. Kendall, L. (1989). Old Ghosts and Ungrateful Children:
Boellstorff, T. (2010). Coming of Age in Second Life: An A Korean Shaman’s Story. In C McClain (Ed.). Women
Anthropologist Explores the Virtually Human. Princeton, NJ: as Healers (pp. 138–157). New Brunswick and London:
Princeton University Press. Rutgers University Press.
Bordo, S. (1993). Unbearable Weight. Berkeley, CA: University Koven, M. (1998). Two Languages in the Self/The Self in Two
of California Press. Languages: French-Portuguese Bilinguals’ Verbal Enactments
Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge, and Experiences of Self in Narrative Discourse. Ethos 26,
UK: Cambridge University Press. 410–455.
Butler, J. (1999). Gender Trouble. New York: Routledge. Levi-Strauss, C. (1963) Structural Anthropology. New York: Basic
Classen, C. (1997). Engendering Perception: Gender Ideologies Books.
and Sensory Hierarchies in Western History. In Body and Lock, M. & Scheper-Hughes, N. (1988) The Mindful Body.
Society. London: Sage Publications. Medical Anthropology Quarterly 1, 6–47.
Clifford, J. & Marcus, G (1986). Writing Culture. Berkeley, CA: Lohmann, R. I. (2003). Dream Travelers. New York: Palgrave/
University of California Press. MacMillan.
Desjarlais, R. (2000). The Makings of Personhood. Ethos 27, Malinowski, B. (1925). Magic, Science, and Religion. New York:
466–489. Macmillan.
Douglas, M. (1966) Purity and Danger. London: Routledge and Malinowski, B. (1927). Sex and Repression in Savage Society.
Kegan Paul. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Drummond, L. (1996) American Dreamtime. Boston: Rowman Marcus, G. (2005). Ocasiao. Walnut Creek: Alta Mira Press, a
and Littlefield. division of Rowman and Littlefield.
Durkheim, E. 1964[1895]. The Rules of Sociological Method. NY: Marcus, G. & Fischer, M (1986). Anthropology as Cultural
The Free Press of Glencoe. Critique. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Durkheim, E. (1912) The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. Mauss, M. (1935). Techniques of the Body. Economy and
Tr. By Joseph Ward Swain. London: Allen and Unwin. Society 2, 70–88.
Eriksen, T. H. (2003). Globalization. London: Pluto Press. Mead, M. (1928). Coming of Age in Samoa. New York: Morrow.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. (1940). The Nuer. Oxford, UK: Oxford Mead, M. (1935). Sex and Temperament in Three Primitive
University Press. Societies. New York: William Morrow.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. (1956). Nuer Religion. Oxford, UK: Mudimbe, V. Y. (1988). The Invention of Africa. Bloomington,
Oxford University Press. IN: Indiana University Press.
Faubion, J. (2001). The Shadows and Lights of Waco: Millenianism Nsamenang, B. (2011) Intergenerational Continuity of Values.
Today. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. In J. Valsiner (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Culture and
Foster, G. (1977). Medical Anthropology and International Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Health Planning. Social Science and Medicine 11, 527–534. Parsons, T. (1965). Unity and Diversity in the Modern
Foucault, M. (1978). The History of Sexuality. New York: Random Intellectual Disciplines: The Role of the Social Sciences.
House/Vintage. Daedalus 94, 39–65.
Freeman, D. (1983). Margaret Mead and Samoa: The Making Rabinow, P. (1977). Reflections on Fieldwork in Morocco. Chicago:
and Unmaking of an Anthropological Myth. Cambridge, MA: University of Chicago Press.
Harvard University Press. Rabinow, P. (2003). Anthropos Today: Reflections on Modern
Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Equipment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Books. Rasmussen, S. (1995). Spirit Possession and Personhood among
Gewertz, D. (1983) Sepik River Societies: A Historical Ethnography the Kel Ewey Tuareg. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
of the Chambri and their Neighbors. New Haven, CT: Yale Press.
University Press. Rasmussen, S. (1999). Making Better “Scents” in Anthropology.
Giddens, A. (1984). The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Anthropological Quarterly 72(2), 55–74.
Theory of Structuration. Berkeley, CA: University of California Rasmussen, S. (2001). Healing in Community: Tuareg Medicine,
Press. Contested Terrains, and Cultural Encounters. Westport, CT:
Good, B. (1994). Medicine, Rationality, and Experience. Bergin & Garvey Press.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Rasmussen, S. (2006). Those Who Touch: Tuareg Medicine Women
Gottlieb, A. & Graham, P. (1994). Parallel Worlds. Chicago: in Anthropological Perspective. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois
University of Chicago Press. University Press.
Gupta, A. & Ferguson, J. (1997). Anthropological Locations. Rasmussen, S. (2008). The People of Solitude: Recalling
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. and Reinventing Essuf (the Wild) in Traditional and
Harner, M. (1990). The Way of the Shaman. San Francisco, CA: Emergent Tuareg Cultural Spaces. The Journal of the Royal
Harper and Row. Anthropological Institute 14, 609–627.
Herzfeld, M. (2001). Anthropology: Theoretical Practice in Culture Rosaldo, M. & Lamphere, L (1974). Women, Culture, and
and Society. Malden, MA: Blackwell/UNESCO. Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

114 c ultural ant hro po log y


Said, E. (1978). Orientalism. New York: Pantheon Press. Tsing, A. (2005). Friction: An Ethnography of Global Connection.
Schneider, D. (1980). American Kinship: A Cultural Account. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Turner, V. (1967). The Drums of Affliction. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
Spiro, M. (1982). Oedipus in the Trobriands. Chicago: University University Press.
of Chicago Press. Weiner, A. (1976). Women of Value, Men of Renown: New
Stoller, P. (1989) The Taste of Ethnographic Things. Philadelphia, Perspectives in Trobriand Exchange. Austin, TX: University of
PA: University of Pennsylvania Press. Texas Press.
Stoller, P. (2004). Stranger in the Village of the Sick. Boston: Whitehead, H. (1981). The Bow and the Burden-Strap.
Beacon. In S. Ortner & H. Whitehead (Eds.). Sexual Meanings
Stoller, P. & Olkes, C. (1987). In Sorcery’s Shadow. Chicago: (pp. 80–116). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
University of Chicago Press. Press.
Tavory, I., Jablonka, E., & Ginsburg, S. (2011). Culture and Winkelman, M. (2000). Shamanism: The Neural Ecology of
Epigenesis: A Waddingtonian View. In J. Valsiner (Ed.). Consciousness and Healing. Westport, CT: Bergin & Garvey.
The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology. New York: Womack, M. (2001). Being Human: An Introduction to Cultural
Oxford University Press. Anthropology. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

ra sm u ssen 115
CHAPTER

Cross-Cultural Psychology: Taking


6 People, Contexts, and Situations
Seriously
Heidi Keller

Abstract
This chapter explores the role of culture for human psychology. First, the history of this relationship
is briefly outlined. The early conceptualizations were characterized by a holistic understanding
and methodological plurality. This wisdom, however, was ignored for much of twentieth century
psychology, when different perspectives with different ideological underpinnings prevailed—notably,
cross-cultural approaches, cultural approaches, and indigenous approaches. Recently the field has
opened again, setting the stage for the development of integrative views. Different challenges for the
future are formulated. The careful conceptualization and definition of culture for empirical studies,
diverting from the practice of comparing the needs of citizens of different countries is a necessity.
An integrated conception of culture and biology is an inevitable next step. The contents of cultural
models need to be considered. Finally, a developmental perspective on psychological phenomena is
crucial. Methodological openness and plurality of approaches is needed for the empirical realization.
It is concluded that psychology in general needs to be culture-inclusive to overcome the sole
representation of a minority of the human population.
Keywords: Völkerpsychologie, cultural, indigenous, socio-demographic characteristics, autonomy,
relatedness, developmental tasks, evolutionary approaches, mixed methods

Cross-cultural psychology in its most gen- in the study of human behavior . . . . . encourage
eral sense deals with the study of the relationships the incorporation of the knowledge and expertise
among culture and human behavior, emotion, and gained by cross-cultural . . . . psychology into the
thought. The International Association for Cross- main body of psychology and develop and promote
Cultural Psychology (founded in 1972) defines its the application of psychological knowledge to social
scope in the constitution as follows: phenomena and problems in all countries. Last but
not least IACCP wants to facilitate communication
“. . . . further the advancement of knowledge about and cooperation among scholars who study the
psychological functioning of humans in all human relationships between culture and human behavior
societies; develop and test theories about the and serve as a fertile ground for communication,
relationships between culture and human behavior; discussion and social encounters in general.”
test the generalizability of theories from all branches (http://www.iaccp2010.com/)
of psychology and related disciplines in all human
societies . . . . . encourage the development of valid Cross-cultural psychology is understood here
measurement techniques and research methodology as one, nevertheless very important, branch of

116
psychology. The argument developed in this chap- founder of modern psychology with the establish-
ter, however, will be that psychology and culture ment of the first psychological experimental labo-
mutually constitute each other and that all branches ratory in Leipzig, Germany in 1879 (for a more
of psychology need to be culture-inclusive; Joan detailed discussion, see the Chapters 1 and 2).
Miller made this claim in 1999 when she stated Based on Lazarus’ and Steinthal’s ideas, Wundt
that psychology is and always has been cultural conceptualized Völkerpsychology as complemen-
(Miller, 1999). Most of the psychological science tary to the psychology of the individual with an
is developed by Western scholars and is based on emphasis on the historical and social dimensions
empirical findings from Western research par- of human behavior and experience. The target was
ticipants. It is even worse because it is not only the cultural-historical analysis of the Volksgeist,
Western, but Western, Educated, Industrialized, especially language, art, myth, and customs. He
Rich, (Democratic origin) (WEIRD), as Henrich, understood human psychology and psychological
Heine, and Norenzayan (2010) have argued in a development as not determined merely by sensa-
review paper. Thus, the majority population of this tion but also by the meaningful influences of the
planet is not represented in psychological science. individual’s spiritual and mental [geistig] environ-
Before we look into the future, first we shall look ment—his culture. Wundt thus clearly stressed
back briefly to track the origins of thinking about the cultural dimension of human psychological
the role of culture for psychology. functioning and the importance to understand
human behavior within the complexity of its his-
Culture in Psychology—Before torical and cultural embeddedness. He also made
Cross-Cultural Psychology clear that the prevailing research methods adopted
The concern about the influence of culture on from natural sciences are not sufficient to study
psychology goes back to Moritz (Moses) Lazarus human psychological functioning adequately. As
(1824–1903). He applied the laws of the psychol- Edwin Boring (1950) concluded: “Wundt never
ogy of the individual to the nation and to mankind held that the experimental method is adequate to
and established a new branch of research with his the whole of psychology: the higher processes, he
article, “Über den Begriff und die Möglichkeit thought, must be got at by the study of the history
einer Völkerpsychologie als Wissenschaft” (“About of human nature, his Völkerpsychologie” (Boring,
the term and possibility of folk psychology as a sci- 1950, p. 328).
ence”) (in Prutz’s “Deutsches Museum” [German This holistic understanding of psychology and
Museum], 1851) in which he coined the term the necessity of different methods for the study
Völkerpsychologie (folk psychology; for more exten- of human psychological functioning, however,
sive discussions of the historical origins, see the got lost afterward for most of the twentieth cen-
chapters of Diriwächter and Johoda in this vol- tury and has only recently come at the verge of
ume). Some years later, Lazarus, in collaboration rebirth. This temporary amnesia can be certainly
with Heymann Steinthal (1823–1899), his friend attributed to psychology’s struggle to belong to
and brother-in-law, established the Zeitschrift für the pantheon of science that was understood for
Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft (Journal a long time as natural science and experimental
of Folk Psychology and Language Science, vols. i–xx, methodology.
Berlin, 1860–90; continued as the Zeitschrift des
Vereins für Volkskunde [Journal of the Association for Different Perspectives on the Role of
Folk Science]). Culture for Psychology
Lazarus and Steinthal developed the conception The loss—or rather the ignorance—of a holistic
of Volksgeist (folk consciousness) as the structure approach to human psychology in North American
of congruent, historically emerged values. They and European mainstream psychology has been
considered every person to be unique, and such embodied in different perspectives that were dis-
uniqueness was expressed through its Volksgeist, the cussed in quite controversial terms in the follow-
unchanging spirit of a people refined through his- ing decades. These different views (characterized
tory. Völkerpsychologie as a science, however, only as cross-cultural, cultural, and indigenous) as well as
became popular in psychology much later and their methodological implications will be briefly
mainly with reference to the 10-volume edition of portrayed in the following as the prevalent perspec-
Wilhelm Wundt, (1832–1920), who was also the tives in the past. Such brief characterizations by

keller 117
necessity risk being stereotypical, and it should be 1992). The Five-Factor Model is conceptualized as
stressed that there is considerable variation in each a comprehensive taxonomy of personality traits,
of the conceptions, as well as overlap among them. which are thought to describe consistent pat-
Nevertheless, the stereotypical portrays capture some terns of thoughts, feelings, and actions. Originally
of the reality of the field—for example, that some identified in the United States, it is repeatedly
cross-cultural psychologists accuse cultural psychol- demonstrated that openness to experience, con-
ogists of being hermeneutically unscientific whereas scientiousness, extroversion, agreeableness, and
some cultural psychologists accuse cross-cultural neuroticism can be identified in a wide variety of
psychology of being positivistic and reductionistic. cultures, suggesting that the personality trait struc-
These debates somehow represent continuity of the ture is universal. Much effort is being awarded to
nineteenth-century ideological struggles. In fact the methodological issues and sophisticated statistical
stereotypical views are particularly pronounced in procedures to prove this aim. This conclusion, how-
this area because they tap into the basic understand- ever, remains nevertheless an illusion because the
ing of the model of man and personhood. statistical absence of differences does not confirm
that there are no differences. Evidence for other
Cross-Cultural Psychology factors and other structures of personality from
Most of cross-cultural psychology—especially in non-Western cultures, which have been presented
its early days—can be characterized as conceiving as well, are often criticized from methodological
of culture as outside of the individual, a bounded points of view.
entity that can be treated as an antecedent or inde- Another strand of research that follows this sec-
pendent variable. The comparison of different index ond approach is informed by biologically based
variables (cultures) should explain or predict dif- assumptions about the universality of human func-
ferences in psychological phenomena. Much of the tioning—for example, attachment research. It is
studies reporting differences on cognitive styles can argued that all infants are biologically predisposed
be subsumed here (e.g., Witkin & Berry, 1975), to develop attachments to caregivers to survive and
demonstrating, for example, differential suscepti- develop. This assumption is extended to the notion
bility to optical illusions depending on contextual/ that attachment is the same across cultures, emerges
cultural (socialization) experiences. There has also along the same developmental trajectories, and
been some recent research on information process- has the same developmental consequences across
ing labeled as cultural psychology that seems to be cultures (van IJzendoorn & Sagi, 1999). To prove
conceptually similar to the cross-cultural research these claims, evidence from diverse cultural con-
ideology. Comparing East Asians and Euro- texts is accumulated, yet very often on very shaky
Americans, Nisbett and colleagues (e.g., Masuda & conceptual grounds when, for example, the age of
Nisbett, 2001) have demonstrated that East Asians the mother is taken as a measure of her sensitiv-
perceive and reason more holistically, whereas Euro- ity toward her infant with the argument that older
Americans perceive and reason more analytically. mothers have more domestic helpers and therefore
However, proponents of this research tradition do more time for infant care.
not understand themselves as cross-cultural in the Although in general, biological approaches
aforementioned sense, but as using experimen- informed by ethology utilize a variability of assess-
tal methodology to prove the inter-relationship ment procedures (e.g., observations, contextual
between culture and social systems. analyses, interviews), the universalist cross-cultural
Another branch of cross-cultural psychology approach mainly draws on experimental method-
manipulates culture as an independent variable ology and self-report measures. Experiments by
to demonstrate its nonexistence. These studies are definition manipulate variables, so that particular
mainly aimed at confirming the universal nature of functions can be observed. However, the experi-
humans and psychological laws. This conception mental setting is always reducing the complexity
of absolutism (Berry, Poortinga, Segall, & Dasen, of psychological processes and moreover is context-
2002) is based on the assumption that all psycho- independent. Experimental paradigms as well as
logical processes and the way they are expressed self-report measures have mainly been developed
are universal. An example of this line of thinking in Western laboratories but are nevertheless applied
is research on the conceptions of personality, espe- in diverse environments. The epistemological chal-
cially the big Five-Factor Model (Costa & McCrae, lenges of equivalence of meaning, structure and

118 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


function go well beyond the – nevertheless serious – personality/psychology make each other up (e.g.,
problems of translation. Shweder, 1990; Valsiner, 2007). In both cases, cul-
Although all of these so-called “cross-cultural ture, behavior, and mind are not regarded as sepa-
approaches” explicitly include culture to explain rate entities. Another distinction within the various
human psychological functioning, little emphasis is approaches, which can be subsumed under the
actually assigned to the definition of culture. Culture umbrella cultural psychology, is the focus on either
is basically set equivalent with country. According to symbolic meaning or shared practices. Because
this understanding, individual persons belong to there are vast differences among different strands
a culture assuming the relative similarity of all the of cultural psychology (for an overview, see Valsiner,
persons who belong to the given culture as well as 2007; Boesch & Straub, 2006), however, we use the
stability of culture over time (Valsiner, 2007). If cul- plural in the following.
ture is further specified, mainly overarching cultural Cultural psychologies aim at studying meanings
dimensions, especially individualism/collectivism and activities in context to assess how cultural beliefs
(Hofstede, 1980/2001; more sophisticated systems of and social practices regulate, express, and transform
value are also widely discussed, see Schwartz, 2006). the human psyche. There is a wide spectrum of
Individualism/collectivism had an overarching suc- vigor concerning this conception ranging from cul-
cess story in dominating cross-cultural research ture-specific expressions of universal predispositions
for several decades while being heavily criticized at to the rejection of the psychic unity of humankind
the same time from empirical as well as conceptual altogether. The focus is on everyday practices and
grounds (e.g., Poortinga, 2011; Sinha & Tripathi, routines that are considered to express as well as cre-
1994). We will come back to these dimensions later. ate culture. The prime subject of study is individuals’
Culture as a system of meanings that can be defined creation of meaning systems—particularly shared or
and described has been left to cultural anthropology normative systems of social groups. The conception
to a large extent. of a dialogical nature of person and culture requires
Because individuals belonging to one national a naturalistic approach and the study of everyday
group have been assumed to share culture, the selec- practices. The focus on meaning systems implies a
tion of participants for empirical studies was rather primacy role of language and its constitutive func-
convenience-guided. Therefore, the prioritized par- tion, as well as an interpretative methodology.
ticipants of cross-cultural studies have been college Moreover, individuals are not considered as pas-
students for a long period of time. College students sively “acquiring” culture; rather, culture is dynami-
are certainly not representative—if there is such a cally created and recreated in social interactions,
thing like representativeness—for their respective which in turn are embedded in broader cultural
countries. They are higher educated, coming mainly meaning systems and practices. Individuals can “dis-
from middle-class backgrounds, and often repre- tance” themselves from the concrete activity setting
sent outliers in a more global perspective (for more by reflecting on the context of which he or she is a
discussion on this, see Henrich et al., 2010). Given part. Thus cultural meaning is analyzed and reorga-
the socio-demographic similarity of college students nized in personally novel forms as it is being con-
across countries, it can be assumed that they form a structively internalized (Chaudhary, 2004; Valsiner,
special cultural group in itself, so that similarities in 2000, 2007).
psychological phenomena can be expected. We will In contrast to cross-cultural psychology, the con-
revisit these contextual considerations later. ception of culture and the contextual situatedness of
individual’s behavior are central to the research. The
Cultural Psychologies consequence is that studies are often non-comparative
Cultural psychology, in its most general sense, but concentrate on an in-depth understanding of
deals equally with the study of the relationships one culture and is changing dynamics over historical
between culture and human behavior. However, time.
the relationship between culture and person is dif- In her book, Weaving Generations Together (2004),
ferently conceived of as compared to traditional Patricia Greenfield documents 20 years of research
cross-cultural psychology: some approaches within with the Zinacantec Mexican Indians, where she
this field conceive of culture as inside the individual not only could document and analyze cultural prac-
(e.g., Boesch, 1980) and others as being in dialogi- tices and their socio-cultural change (e.g., changing
cal relationship to the person, so that culture and strategies of girls learning to weave) but also the

keller 119
implications of such changes on both the cultural systems, particularly shared or normative systems of
products (patterns and designs of fabrics) and cog- a cultural group. Besides the development of proce-
nitive processes within this group. However, cul- dures and assessment tools from a within-cultural
tural comparisons are not excluded but may serve perspective, indigenous psychologies also aim at
the purpose of elaborating meaning systems by the the development of psychological concepts and
method of contrast (e.g., see Demuth, 2008). theories. Thus, folk theories, for example, are not
As mentioned before, there is a relatively new an object of study as for cultural psychologies but
branch of cultural psychology that focuses on cul- are also the source for the development of formal
tural differences in attention, perception, cogni- psychological models and theories (Greenfield &
tion, and memory—especially between East Asian Keller, 2004). Indigenous conceptions are part of a
and Euro-American participants. This approach is scientific tradition advocating multiple perspectives
rather experimental or quasi-experimental in nature. but not multiple psychologies. Therefore, modern
Although participants in studies are selected accord- proponents of indigenous psychologies have aban-
ing to citizenship of countries, underlying cultural doned the plural form and instead talk about indig-
conceptions of the self are implied, especially the enous psychology.
conception of the independent (Euro-Americans) The preferred participants and contexts for cul-
and the interdependent (East Asian) selves (Markus & tural psychologies are relatively stable subsistence
Kitayama, 1991). These self-construals are based on village cultures, whereas indigenous psychologies
broader cultural meaning systems such as Western mainly address elite populations like university
individualism and East Asian Confucianism. students and deal with cultural change primarily.
Common to all branches of cultural psycholo- However, the founders of indigenous psychologies
gies is the understanding of culture as an inherent mentioned before did not primarily work empiri-
part of human psychological functioning. Some cally, with the exception of Diaz Guerrero, who
cultural psychologists share with cross-cultural developed the Mexican psychology also by con-
psychologists that cultural evidence is needed for trasting it to Euro-American views. In any case,
basic psychological theories to refine and/or expand the cultural inside view serves the goal to develop
these theories so that they become more relevant indigenous conceptions of psychological function-
to the predictions, descriptions, and explanations ing, which is also demanding the development of
of ALL human behaviors—not just Western ones indigenous methodologies.
(Markus & Kitayama, 2003). Indigenous psychology also has a political stance
in voicing non-Western perspectives as equally
Indigenous Psychologies/Psychology important as Western ones to develop a truly inter-
The emergence of indigenous psychologies is national psychology—a seemingly trivial notion
often characterized as motivated by the intention of that nevertheless is grossly under-represented in
decolonizing the mind. To achieve this mind decol- scientific discourse still today (see the weird psychol-
onization, research and theories should be devel- ogy, Henrich et al., 2010).
oped from a within-culture/indigenous perspective Also until today, there have been voices arguing
without participation from abroad. It is therefore a that these different approaches are incommensu-
vital characteristic that indigenous psychologies can rable, because they rest on different science theo-
only be formulated by indigenous people—that is, retical paradigms and models of the person that are
cultural insiders by socialization. Particularly prom- exclusive of each other. However, what is congru-
inent are the Indian perspective (as formulated by ent or contradictory, commensurable or incom-
Durghanand Sinha), the Philippino perspective mensurable, compatible or incompatible is itself a
(developed by Virgilio Enriquez), and the Mexican matter of the worldview one holds. A Confucian or
ethnopsychological perspective (as developed by Hinduistic worldview will have different concep-
Rolando Diaz Guerrero). This origin is differ- tions of compatibilities than a Western eclectic phi-
ent from cultural psychologies that mainly are the losophy or neo-Kantian analytical worldview. In the
field of alien researchers who nevertheless spend a remainder of this chapter, we pursue the argument
substantial amount of time in “their” culture and that these different perspectives are complementary
learn the local language. Indigenous psychologies in several respects. Basic to this point of view is the
share with cultural psychologies the prime subject definition of some core terms/conceptions that will
of study—that is, subject’s creation of meaning be presented in the following. The conception of

120 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


culture with which we will begin is certainly the and to transmit culture. Therefore, development
most central one. can be understood as cultural learning. Culture has
evolved to facilitate individuals’ social encounters
Conceptions of Culture with each other as a faster track than genetic adap-
The three approaches differ in their conception tation. Therefore, culture is situated in social pro-
of culture. Whereas much of cross-cultural psychol- cesses. For too long, an unsubstantiated rejection of
ogy equates culture with country or concentrates on the role of biology for human psychology has domi-
the bipolar dimension of individualism/collectiv- nated all three perspectives represented earlier. It is
ism, cultural psychologies often focus on processes therefore necessary to develop a differentiated view
and neglect content and indigenous psychology on the interplay of culture and biology.
spans from a process orientation to a comparative
perspective (Mexican ethnopsychology) without The Role of Biology for Cross-Cultural
further specification. Psychology
In the following we would like to propose an A consideration of the impact of biology and the
approach that defines culture as a contextual- evolutionary history of humans beyond the physical
adaptive process through differential emphasis of body structure has been regarded as an attack against
particular content domains. In line with cultural the free will, self-determination, and reflexivity.
psychological conceptions, our starting point is cul- Although this debate can by and large be regarded
ture as a socially interactive process with two main as historical, there are occasionally voices coming up
components: the creation of shared activity (cul- that try to question the role of biology for human
tural practices) and the creation of shared mean- psychology. The sometimes hostile attitude toward
ing. Shared activities concern the material side of biology has been expressed from cross-cultural psy-
culture. They are adapted to survival, which brings chologists who, interestingly enough, share with
in the inseparable relationship between culture and ethologists the search for universals and by cul-
biology that will be dealt with later, and it involves tural psychologists who emphasize the uniqueness
goal-directed action. Shared meaning (cultural inter- of humans, however, without consideration of the
pretation) concerns values, beliefs, folk models, and content, hence also focusing on a universal nature.
ethnopsychologies. This conception situates culture It is amazing that the self-evident question, “How
in everyday contexts and behaviors (Greenfield & can the universal human nature appear irrespective
Keller, 2004; Keller, 2007). of extremely different environments?” has so far not
been raised. This question on these premises would
Adaptive Nature of Culture lead logically only to one answer: Culture does not
We consider cultural practices and meaning sys- matter—a truly biologistic attitude. On the other
tems to be adaptive. The aspect of adaptation defines hand, nobody questions that, for example, plants
culture as a functional system in an eco-social envi- develop very different phenotypes depending on the
ronment. Thus, cultural practices, routines, and ecology in which they grow.
artifacts help to master environmental challenges In fact, evolutionary theories assign culture a sys-
and define competence. Children co-construct cul- tematic place for understanding human psychology,
tural knowledge during ontogenetic development and there is a conceptual closeness between genuine
with their social partners. They profit from the cultural and evolutionary approaches. This closeness
accumulated cultural knowledge of the ancestral will be demonstrated with a comparison of one of
generations and the cultural niches that prior gener- the most important conceptions of psychocultural
ations have constructed (Tomasello, 1999; Laland, research, the Whiting model (1975), which has
Odling-Smee, & Feldman, 2000). During devel- set the stage for the famous six cultures study, the
opmental processes, knowledge is acquired that is first cultural comparative study of child-rearing and
helpful for current problems and at the same time a development with basic assumptions of evolution-
preparation for future challenges. However, knowl- ary theory (Keller, 2010).
edge that is functional at one ontogenetic level must Whiting summarized the philosophy of the psy-
not need to be helpful at later levels and vice versa chocultural model in the introduction of the six cul-
(Bjorklund & Pellegrini, 2002). tures book on child-rearing (Whiting, 1963, p. 4):
Culture, as such, is part of our biological nature.
Implicit in the research design is a general concept
Humans are equipped with the means to acquire
of the relation of personality to culture, which may

keller 121
be presented as follows: The ecology of the area socialization pressure by parents, other caregivers,
determines the maintenance systems, which include and teachers, we are analyzing these differences as a
basic economy and the most elementary variables cause in the process of socialization.
of social structure. In other words, the type of crops (Whiting & Pope Edwards, 1988, pp. 5–6)
grown, the presence or absence of herding, fishing,
Age, gender, and context are the major determi-
and so on, depend on the nature of the terrain,
nants of behavioral and psychological differentia-
the amount of rainfall, the location of the area
tions from evolutionary theories as well.
vis-à-vis centers of invention and diffusion. These
Moreover both approaches share the common
basic economic conditions determine in part the
interest in universal as well as differential patterns. “. . .
arrangement of people in space, the type of houses,
[I]n spite of individual differences, there are behavior
and household composition. These in turn set the
regularities for children of a given age and sex in each
parameters for child-rearing practices.
cultural community. That is, there are meaningful
(p. 4)
norms . . .” (Whiting & Pope Edwards, 1988, p. 10)
And continues: To test the universal patterns, a cross-cultural
It is assumed that different patterns of child rearing approach is crucial, because looking for universal
will lead to differences in the personality of children principles can best be achieved “. . . by replicating
and thus to differences in adult personality. studies in a variety of cultural contexts” (Whiting &
(p. 5) Pope Edwards, 1988, p. 10). This approach is clearly
different from cultural (as well as anthropological)
Child-rearing practices eventually lead to the
perspectives that assume that behavior is infinitely
shaping of the adult personality. Thus, the original
malleable and that cultures produce uniqueness.
model assumes a causal chain from ecological con-
The focus of the research following the Whiting
text to the adult psychology.
psychocultural model is on normative aspects, on
the “natural man” approach, indicating great psy-
The Input from Evolutionary
chobiological similarity among the peoples of the
Theorizing
world (Whiting, 1977).
Evolutionary theorizing also considers the envi-
ronment as the starting point of the causal chain We are impressed that there is a finite number of
leading to human psychology and behavior but general programs governing the lives of children
adds to the proximate level of functional relation- growing up throughout the world, as well as a finite
ships between context and psychology the ultimate and transculturally universal grammar of behaviour
goal of reproductive success, or optimal genetic fit- that children can use in interpersonal interactions.
ness. Thus, the core assumption is that humans, (Whiting & Pope Edwards, 1988, p. 17)
like any other species, strive for optimal represen-
This matches exactly the biological notion of an
tation of their genes in the next generation. This is,
inborn reaction norm. A reaction norm describes
of course, an assumption of unintentional, maybe
the pattern of phenotypic expressions of a single
unconscious, “as-if ” decisions. Environmental con-
genotype across a range of environments. The pat-
ditions comprise material and ecological resources
tern, however, does not contain numerous options
as well as social complexity including material and
but a limited number of possibilities (Keller &
social niches that prior generations have created.
Chasiotis, 2006).
The crucial components in the environment are the
Both approaches stress the contextual adapta-
resources that an individual is able to exploit and
tion, on the one hand, and consequent necessary
possibly to accumulate. Whereas the model for psy-
variability, on the other. This does not mean uni-
chocultural research deals with the environment on
versality with regard to human psychological func-
a descriptive basis, evolutionary theory differenti-
tioning but phrasing the assumption that universal
ates types of environments with respect to strategic
principles underlay the human nature that allows
reproductive decisions.
for diversity.
Both conceptions are turning the prevailing the-
As a species, humans are biologically primed
ories of socialization upside down:
to acquire, create, and transmit culture. Cultural
Rather than analyzing the age, sex, and cultural differences are variations on themes of universal
differences in children’s activities and companions importance and differential emphases put on par-
as simply the result of developmental changes of ticular practices (Rogoff, 2003). Culture represents

122 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


the legacy of preceding generations as expressed in history (including migrations), maintenance sys-
the dispositions, the consciousness, and the psy- tems (including economic parameters), and settle-
chology of each living individual whose plasticity ment/family structure (like household composition
allows change to adapt to changing surroundings. and family type). This model, developed from a cul-
At the same time, humans inherit niches that are tural psychological and anthropological perspective,
composed of material and social resources. As such, has much in common with an evolutionary view
culture is the primary mode of human adaptation on the human psychology that also relates human
(Keller, 2007). behavior and psychology to contextual demands of
Culture and biology are not opposites, and they the environment. This closeness/coherence in per-
are not independent forces. They are both part of spective, however, is considered as incompatible by
the human nature and have to be conceived of as some cultural psychologists, because culture and
systematically inter-related. Culture selects, rein- biology are thought of contradictions—a view that
forces, and optimizes biological predispositions. rests on multiple theoretical and empirical miscon-
The challenge for cross-cultural psychology in the ceptions (see Boesch, this volume).
future will be to assign a systematic place to biol- Based on the literature and our own research
ogy, especially evolutionary theorizing for its fur- program, we propose to capture the environmental
ther development. Moreover, process and content parameters as socio-demographic characteristics, as
need to be addressed. The question that therefore they can be understood as contingent on the physi-
has to be addressed is: How can groups of people be cal characteristics of the environment as outlined in
defined who share culture? the Whiting model. We especially understand the
level of formal education, age at first birth, number
Who Shares Culture? of children, and household size as forming particu-
Because culture is the nature of humans, it is evi- lar cultural milieus. People sharing these character-
dent that humans generally share culture. However, istics are likely to share similar worldviews, norms,
this statement is not as trivial as it sounds at a first and values that are represented in particular cultural
glance. This statement has wider epistemological models. Cultural models are understood as overarch-
implications. Human culture is defined by some ing meaning systems that organize and coordinate
cultural psychologists as self-reflexive, intentional, different domains of life. We will discuss cultural
and self-conscious agency that is shared by all models in more detail later (Keller, 2003, 2007).
humans and that distinguishes humans from other From a traditional cross-cultural psychology
species, including their closest primate relatives. understanding of culture (as characterized earlier)
There is, however, more and more evidence that and from experimental thinking in general, this
chimpanzees, bonobos, orangutans, and other pri- view is often criticized as confounding variables such
mates teach their offspring, have developed rituals as SES or education and culture. The argument,
and traditions, not only use tools but go with tools however, only holds true if we conceive of them
to particular places (e.g., for nut-cracking or fishing as independent variables that can and should be
and keep the tools afterward), cooperate, and mur- manipulated with the assumption that their expla-
der their own offspring as well as other conspecifics. nation of variance can be independently calculated.
Although quantitative and qualitative differences are We argue, however, that they cannot be conceived
substantial, culture in this sense cannot be claimed of independent, because they inter-relate structur-
as being uniquely human (for a detailed discussion ally and psychologically. The structural inter-rela-
of this field, see Boesch, this volume). tionship is expressed in statistics documenting that
Therefore, the question is: Is it possible to system- higher levels of formal education are correlated with
atically identify characteristics of groups that share later parenthood and less offspring, irrespective of
particular cultural practices and meaning systems the country or society. Psychologically, they together
that differ from other groups? Here, we have to come form a social milieu, a developmental niche, a par-
back to the role of adaptation. With the model of ticular learning environment. The conception is
psychocultural research, Beatrice and John Whiting presented in Figure 6.1.
(1975) proposed a conception linking human psy- Gender is certainly another candidate that
chology, human culture, symbols, and artifacts should be included in this conception. Gender
directly to the eco-social environment, composed of studies have recently employed a similar strategy
physical parameters (like climate and geography), with the intersection analysis. Intersection analysis

keller 123
behaviors and shared meanings that differentiate
Level of
cultural groups. Historically there have been two
formal education
extreme positions within cultural psychology: a
complete neglect of content, referred to in the last
paragraph, and the concentration on single case
studies with all individual idiosyncrasies that some
cultural psychologists share with cultural anthro-
Age at Cultural Household
first birth model size
pologists. However, cross-cultural psychologists are
interested in comparisons with regard to content of
shared meanings and practices. Yet, comparisons are
often made prematurely. As argued in the previous
section, samples are seldom theoretically selected,
Number of
but more or less a matter of convenience. Mainly
children social psychological studies have utilized question-
naires, assessed data sets from foreign locations
wherever possible (a practice that especially criticized
Figure 6.1 Cultural models as representation of socio-demo-
by indigenous approaches) without denying the role
graphic variables.
that local scholars have played. Many studies have
compared only two samples, so that the Journal of
is understood as the necessity to conjointly address Cross-Cultural Psychology has pursued for some time
gender, ethnicity, social class, health, age, language the policy—namely, that studies comparing two
with respect to worldviews, daily practices as well as samples from two different backgrounds/cultures
sexual orientations. It is considered as important to are not acceptable for publication, as the results
assess the simultaneity of effects and not separate or could just reflect sample differences/similarities that
statistically control them (Krüger-Potratz, 2005). do not pertain to cultural differences/similarities.
This definition of the cultural environment It is obvious that adequate translation and other
makes countries or societies obsolete as units of questions of equivalence were crucial to these strat-
analysis. Every country hosts multiple socio-de- egies. However, this resulted in a focus on cross-
mographic environments and, according to these cultural methodology at the expense of theoretical/
criteria, multiple cultures. The consequences for conceptual development. This may be one reason
research strategies in this understanding would why the dimensions specifying cultural contents
imply selective sampling of individuals who share (power distance, individualism/collectivism, mascu-
socio-demographic characteristics. linity vs. femininity, uncertainty avoidance), when
A related question here is whether the same dif- first introduced by Geert Hofstede in his 1980 book
ferential variables have the same effect in different Culture’s Consequences—International Differences
countries. That is, are individuals with higher levels in Work Related Values (second, extended edition
of formal education more similar in psychological 2001), received such an extraordinary attention. The
variables across different countries than individuals dimension of individualism/collectivism especially
with higher and lower levels of formal education dominated cross-cultural research for some decades.
within the same country? These kinds of analyses This dimension measures how individuals define
would help to further specify the culture concept. themselves in relation to group memberships. In
The challenge for the future of cross-cultural individualist cultures, individuals develop and dis-
psychology is to adopt a differentiated view of cul- play their unique personalities and select their social
ture along these lines and to define cultural groups relationships and affiliations. In collectivist cultures,
more carefully—with the required conceptual individuals are primarily defined and act as group
background. The relationship between cultural and members, like the family, a religious group, a work-
individual levels in cross-cultural research should be place, and others. This dimension has been found to
addressed from this conceptual perspective. be related to countries’ economies.
A similar, equally named dimension was pro-
The Contents of Culture posed by Harry Triandis (e.g., Triandis, Leung,
Another aspect that we consider to be crucial is Villareal, & Clark, 1985) as one of several cultural
to look at what are the particular contents of shared syndromes. Cultural syndromes consist of attitudes,

124 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


beliefs, norms, and values that are shared, for exam- social change in Turkey. Markus and Kitayama
ple, by people in a particular historical epoch or (1991, 1998), on the other hand, restrict their
geographical area. The shared ideas are organized model to the comparisons of U.S. Americans and
around themes—syndromes—and form subjective East Asians—mainly Japanese—which is one reason
culture as a society’s “characteristic way of perceiv- why this approach is qualified as cultural instead of
ing its social environment” (Triandis, 1972, p. viii). cross-cultural. Kağitcibaşi (2005) as well as Triandis
Individualism and collectivism form one such related their models to socio-cultural context (soci-
syndrome. Triandis (1994) has suggested that indi- etal and socio-demographic characteristics)—that
vidualism evolves in societies that are complex, like is, they differentiated between social milieus and
information societies and loose societies, (i.e., norm accordingly based their studies on participants
and values for correct behavior are not completely from different socio-cultural background (SES,
mandatory); collectivism accordingly emerges in level of formal education, urban-rural distinction,
societies that are both simple, like hunter and gath- etc.), whereas the individualism/collectivism and
erers, and tight (i.e., normatively regulated). Triandis the conceptions of Markus and Kitayama refer to
conception is psychologically much more complex nationalities. Moreover, they base their studies on a
than Hofstede’s concept; nevertheless it also repre- specific socio-demographic group (IBM employees
sents a one-dimensional bipolar dimension. in Hofstede’s case, mainly university students in the
Although individualism/collectivism has become case of Markus and Kitayama) and generalize these
an all-time citation star and has influenced decades findings on a national level. It is interesting that the
of research, methodological and conceptual criti- psychological core conception of individualism/
cism has been raised right from the beginning as collectivism and independence and interdepen-
well. One of the major points of criticism was and dence have been proposed from these very differing
still is the bipolar one-dimensional nature that is approaches, as well as from cultural anthropology
regarded as too simplistic, dividing the world into (Shweder & Bourne, 1984).
two cultural groups with nothing else (grand divide In this sense, it is commonly stated that indi-
theory). Of course, it is not implied in the concep- vidualism/independence is based on autonomous
tion that there is nothing else beyond individual- and separate agency that is self-contained, self-as-
ism/collectivism (not to forget that Hofstede had sured, and self-determined; others are perceived and
proposed 4 and later 5 [adding time perspective defined in terms of individual wishes, desires, and
later] dimensions, and Triandis named at least 10 intentions. Interdependence/collectivism is defined
cultural syndromes). as prioritizing the needs and intentions of the
Yet, the major assumption of one-dimensional (reference) group as prior to individual concerns.
bipolarity has been seriously challenged, because Relationships are modeled by roles and social expec-
autonomy and relatedness, as the core concepts of tations. Harmonious social relationships are defined
these dimensions, can in fact co-exist in individu- as a mature way of being. The theoretical and meth-
als as well as in cultures. Çiğdem Kağitcibaşi (1997, odological frameworks, in which these conceptions
2005) has made a strong case for this co-existence of are embedded, nevertheless are very different.
autonomy and relatedness that she applied to fami-
lies and selves. Also the conception of the indepen- Autonomy and Relatedness Reconsidered
dent and interdependent selves, which Markus and Based on the essence of these conceptions, we
Kitayama proposed in a very influential paper in have proposed concentrating on the dimensions of
1991, conceives of two constructs that are defined autonomy and relatedness as the basic and orga-
as independent from each other. One difference nizing principles of broader cultural worldviews.
that is notable among individualism/collectivism, Beyond stating that they are independent of each
Kağitcibaşi’s model, and the Markus and Kitayama’s other, we define the relationships between them and
approach is the scope of reach. The cross-cultural differentiate different modes of autonomy and relat-
conceptions of individualism/collectivism have edness that are qualitatively distinct from each other
been applied on a worldwide scale, where countries as adaptations to different environmental demands.
are ranked with respect to the distance to the indi- We differentiate the following two modes of
vidualism pole. Also, Kağitcibaşi’s four-field schema autonomy as universal capacities, albeit with dif-
is basically a general worldwide model, although ferent adaptational value in different environments.
it was mainly developed with studies concerning Psychological autonomy refers to mental processes,

keller 125
based on reflective and self-reflective ways of being. from the point of view of psychological autonomy
It centers on the realization of personal desires, but as the healthy way of development from a
wishes, and intentions. Individual psychological hierarchical relational perspective. This exclusivity,
autonomy can be defined as the self-centered feeling however, does not mean that the conceptions are
of having control and being in control of all avail- one-dimensional, bipolar, and monolithic. It also
able choices. This conception represents what is usu- does not imply, neither logically nor empirically,
ally defined as autonomy or agency in the literature. that autonomy and relatedness are the only relevant
It describes and is adapted to the Western middle- dimensions of human functioning.
class lifestyle with high levels of formal education. Cultural stereotyping can be avoided when
From the first day of life, children are mirrored their culture is defined in terms of socio-demographic
feelings, wishes, and intentions and are supported profiles as we suggested earlier. The milieu of
to realize them. We have suggested a complemen- socio-demographic characteristics has to be com-
tary facet of autonomy that focuses on actions and plemented with the nature of economic activities.
their responsible performance and control. Action There is psychological and anthropological evi-
autonomy represents the individual’s capacity to per- dence supporting different worldviews of farmers
form actions and comprises the intention, the plan, and herders, fishers, or nomads living in the same
and the performance of an action under the con- ecological environment. The history of settlement
trol of the acting individual. Action autonomy is a patterns also has been demonstrated as influenc-
universal human capacity. However, the nature and ing cultural conceptions of the self (Kitayama &
timing of actions that are individually controlled Imada, 2010). Differentiated conceptions of con-
varies across cultural contexts. Action autonomy is textual models will need to be defined. With Pervin
the preferred mode of autonomy for a cooperative and Cervone’s (2010) definition of personality, we
lifestyle as, for example, in subsistence-based farm- suggest that cross-cultural psychology deals with
ing economy with low levels of formal education. what all humans have in common, with what some
Children are trained from early on to take respon- humans have in common, and with what is particu-
sible actions to support the family. lar to the individual.
Relatedness can also have different faces. Another challenge for cross-cultural psychology
Psychological relatedness may mean self-selected rela- for the future will certainly be to deal with the con-
tions between separate, self-contained individuals tent of culture in terms of autonomy and related-
that can be defined and negotiated from the point ness and to identify possible other dimensions, from
of view of the individual agency. This conception a contextual perspective.
of relatedness can be understood as in the service
of psychological autonomy. Thus, psychological Plurality of Methods
autonomy would be the leading principle for the Cultural, cross-cultural, and indigenous psy-
lived conception of relatedness. Hierarchical related- chologies together host an armentarium of research
ness is defined as a network of relationships, based strategies and methodologies. Traditionally cross-
on hierarchically structured roles that are manda- cultural psychology has been associated with quan-
tory life long. There is no room and also no wish for titative methodology from experiment to survey,
individually negotiating expectations and obliga- whereas many cultural as well as indigenous psy-
tions related to (family) relationships (Keller, 2007; chologies employ more qualitative approaches.
Keller & Otto, 2011). Hierarchical relatedness can Recently there has been a trend advocating mixed-
be associated with action autonomy. In this case, methods approaches (e.g., special issue of the
hierarchical relatedness is the leading principle also Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 2009), thus
for (action) autonomy. linking back to the heritage of the psychocultural
These two models are conceived of as prototypes. approaches of the Whitings and others. Whiting
Prototypes imply that the patterns can be found and Child started with statistical analyses of rela-
empirically in relatively pure modes. This does not tionships in the dataset of the Human Research Area
exclude, however, variability across and between the Files (Whiting & Child, 1953). Whiting and Pope
prototypes. The prototypes as described here imply Edwards (1988) analyzed “the mundane or typical
partly mutually exclusive views on processes and patterns of interaction between frequent social part-
behavioral regulations. For example, mother–child ners “ (p. 10) from quantitative data recorded with
symbiosis is regarded as a pathological condition the use of systematic standardized observations, and

126 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


“these quantitative data enable the researcher to val- contexts (e.g., co-sleeping), practices (e.g., training
idate subjective impressions” (p. 10). However, this motor development), and interactional exchanges
understanding of the relationship between quanti- (e.g., body contact and body carrying). Accordingly,
tative and qualitative methodology is not shared by children’s developmental achievements as well as
many cultural psychologists. developmental trajectories may differ in content,
The six-culture study itself represents a mixed- timing, and structure.
method research design (Whiting, 1963), where The particular solutions of earlier developmental
ethnographic information is compiled and portraits tasks prepare pathways for the solution of later ones.
of individual life stages are drawn based on behav- However, these pathways are not deterministic in
ioral observations and interviews with qualitative the sense that the early pattern allows only for one
data used to illustrate general patterns. As such, the particular set of later consequences. It is obvious
different approaches thus use an impressive array that along developmental pathways, a multiplicity
of methodologies and research strategies, although of influences shape developmental outcomes. And
individual scholars may have strong preferences as the human plasticity allows for modification, com-
well as strong dislikes for particular methods. pensation, and restructuring at any time of develop-
The future challenge for cross-cultural psychol- ment. Nevertheless the development of continuity is
ogy will be to develop more tolerance for diverse easier than that of discontinuity, and most individu-
methodologies as well as more sophisticated designs als experience coherence and consistency through-
and analysis methods from a mixed-methods out their biographies.
perspective. This conception of development combines a
causal sequence of influences with a co-constructive
Introducing Development in mode of development. Because experiences are indi-
Cross-Cultural Comparisons vidually constructed and appropriated, the active
We have argued that the human psyche can be role of the developing individual and the contex-
understood as result of adaptational processes to tual constraints and affordances form one system.
contextual demands. Therefore, cross-cultural dif- The emergence of cultural phenotypes is crucial for
ferences in psychological functioning cannot be understanding cultural/cross-cultural differences.
present from birth on—they need to develop in the Therefore, more emphasis on psychological devel-
particular context in which the baby is born. We opment is necessary for the future of cross-cultural
have proposed to define development along these psychology.
lines as the cultural solution of universal develop-
mental tasks (Keller, 2007). There is an extensive Conclusion: Taking Culture Seriously and
literature in psychology on how to define develop- What It Implies
mental tasks. We propose a broad understanding in Cross-cultural psychology, as any psychological
terms of topics or themes that have evolved during discipline, is inevitably a cultural science, because
the history of humankind to solve adaptive prob- any attempt to understand psychological phenom-
lems. Therefore, their solution must be contingent ena needs to take into account the social cultural
upon the particular environmental conditions. This environment, ontogenetic history, and ancestral
enables the development of contextual competence heritage. Cross-cultural psychology, on the other
(Weisner, 2002). Developmental pathways are orga- hand, is also inevitably a biological science, because
nized in coherent and meaningful sequences. The any attempt to understand psychological phenom-
conceptions of autonomy and relatedness, as dis- ena needs to take into account the evolved pre-
cussed earlier, provide such meaning structures in dispositions and the behavioral constraints and
terms of developmental organizers. The socialization affordances that evolved over the history of human-
goal of psychological autonomy supports the early kind. In the previous paragraphs, we have proposed
development of an independent self as expressed reconceptualizing cross-cultural psychology on the
in contexts (e.g., babies sleep in their own beds), basis of such a unified conception of culture and
practices (e.g., child-centered dyadic social encoun- biology with a focus on the emergence of cross-
ters), and interactional exchanges (e.g., contingent cultural differences during developmental pathways
mirroring of infant signals). The socialization goals with consideration of cultural content domains.
of hierarchical relatedness supports the early devel- Cross-cultural, cultural, and indigenous approaches
opment of an interdependent self as expressed in can and should be meaningfully combined. This

keller 127
will only be possible when scientists and researchers breastfeeding positions are all exclusive, face-to-
develop openness for other worldviews and particu- face situations. Cultural environments like the Nso
larly accept the equivalence of different worldviews farmers practice multiple caregiving systems with
for human functioning in different contexts. less emphasis on special bonds between mother
This paradigm shift has tremendous implications and child beyond the nurturing one. Therefore,
also for the applied fields and social policy. Two exam- programs often fail and do not succeed in raising
ples should demonstrate the implications. Example 1 breastfeeding rates, because they do not account
concerns policy programs that international organi- for the cultural realities of the people whom they
zations like the World Health Organization (WHO) address. The important message is that there is no
or the United National Children’s Fund (UNICEF) one best way to raise a child but contextually adap-
promote in poverty-stricken environments. The sup- tive pathways.
port of breastfeeding is a common focus of such Example 2 concerns the reality of migrants who
programs. Breastfeeding is generally considered as a shift from a rural farming background into the
very important way to improve infants’ health and Western urban metropolis. Many migrants have
development as the best source of nourishment for internalized the cultural model of relatedness with
infants and young children. Adequate breastfeeding its strong family connectedness based in hierarchy
support for mothers and families could save many and obligations. The public life and the educa-
young lives. tional system, however, is organized according to
The WHO, in line with other associations, the cultural model of autonomy, which is adaptive
recommends 6 months of exclusive breastfeeding. to Western middle-class families. Daycare and kin-
However, breastfeeding rates are not reaching the dergarten treat the small child as an autonomous
necessary timelines to be beneficial. Globally, less agent by providing multiple choices during the
than 40% of infants under age 6 months are exclu- day and encouraging active verbal participation
sively breastfed. Nevertheless women in very diverse of children in the daily activities. Migrant parents
environments (e.g., middle-class German mothers often experience the curricula as a massive threat
as well as Nso farmer mothers) agree that breast- against their family cohesion and the core values
feeding is the healthiest way of infant nutrition. and norms. Accordingly, they do not send their
However, the reasons that women from these two children to the educational institutions anymore,
contexts consider are very different. For the Western which otherwise would be very beneficial (e.g.,
middle-class mother who is on maternity leave, the in terms of second language acquisition as well as
breastfeeding situation is a time of exclusive mutual support of developmental domains that are con-
attention with abundant eye contact. For example, sidered as important in the host culture). Many
a mother from Los Angeles says in an interview that misunderstandings are also pre-programmed in
breastfeeding is “. . . a great time to do the bond- the Western middle-class expectation of active
ing thing with your child, cause they stare in your participation (educational partnership) of par-
eyes and you stare in their eyes.” For the Nso famer ents in the kindergarten, whereas many migrant
mother who has to continue the household chores parents expect a strict separation of responsibili-
and the farm work after delivery, it is important that ties between family and institution—educational
she can do breastfeeding as a co-occurring activity. efforts and attainments are clearly not seen as the
The following is an excerpt from an interview about family’s responsibility.
breastfeeding with a Nso farmer woman: “At times Daycare providers and other professionals profit
she wanted to prepare something and the child was enormously from learning to know other cultural
disturbing her, when she was already anxious to pre- models beyond their own. However, there is a step
pare something quickly, then she is selling potatoes further to go. The often heard message, “Now, they
and breastfeeding the child at the same time.” are here, they have to do it our way,” grasps it too
Programs to promote breastfeeding, however, short. Family values and norms are very deeply
do not account for these diverse contexts with the rooted in the personality and resistant to change,
different needs. Breastfeeding is promoted with because they coincide with what is considered a
the Western middle-class philosophy as creating a good person. The confrontational method there-
special bond between mother and baby and foster- fore is clearly prone to misachievement. Programs
ing the exclusive dyadic interaction between the need to be developed from cultural knowledge to
mother and child. UNICEF recommendations for acceptance.

128 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


The wide-ranging implications also afford para- humans that need to be negotiated from any indi-
digm shifts of the culture free or better monocultural vidual in any culture. We have proposed to differ-
mainstream psychology. If culture is acknowledged entiate autonomy and relatedness along contextual
at all in textbooks and handbooks of psychology, it demands. Nevertheless, the search for other possible
is considered to provide variability. The argument panhuman themes should also be pursued.
that is put forward here is that the systematic influ- Finally, the study of the emergence of cultural
ence of culture for human psychology needs to be phenotypes is crucial for understanding cultural/
fully introduced with a necessary paradigm shift cross-cultural differences. Therefore, more emphasis
(for a discussion of the reception of culture in psy- on psychological development is necessary for the
chology, see a special issue of the Journal of Cross- future of cross-cultural psychology. All these con-
Cultural Psychology, Lonner, Smith, van de Vijver, & ceptual challenges afford a pluralism of method-
Murdock, 2010). Cross-cultural psychology, includ- ologies and methods that have been existing in the
ing cultural and indigenous approaches, therefore beginnings of cross-cultural psychology. Thus, the
has to become an essential ingredient of the psycho- future also has to be linked to the roots.
logical sciences. As we have said earlier, psychology These challenges, however, are not particular to
cannot be based on the investigation of WEIRD cross-cultural/cultural psychology only. They address
people (Henrich et al., 2010) only but also needs important dimensions that need to be addressed for
to include Non-Western, Indigenous, Colored, all of psychological science. Behavior and mental
Emic people (NICE). But NICE people are not one representations emerge during ontogeny within
homogenous category, a contextually based careful particular cultural contexts. As we have argued in
description of samples that deliver study results is an the introduction, we only have knowledge about
unquestioned necessity. the psychology of a very small part of the global
population that is even unique in different respects
Future Directions in affluence, level of formal education, and related
In the previous paragraphs, we have identified socio-demographic characteristics (Henrich et al.,
challenges for the future of cross-cultural psychol- 2010). Is has to be understood that this context is
ogy. First, we argue, that the careful conceptualiza- associated with one kind of psychology only. There
tion and definition of culture for empirical studies is a tremendous task to master in the future to con-
represents an area of neglect. We have proposed to struct psychological knowledge in diverse contexts.
abandon the strategy to define citizens of particular The cross-cultural perspective can take the lead in
countries as cultural groups and to adopt a contextu- establishing a psychological science that better rep-
ally based view of culture as representation of socio- resents humankind.
demographic variables. This conception should be
further developed, including the nature of economic References
Berry, J. W., Poortinga, Y. H., Segall, M. H., & Dasen, P. R.
activities that also inform patterns and structures (2002). Cross-cultural psychology: Research and applications.
of lifestyles. The relationship between cultural and Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
individual level in cross-cultural research should be Bjorklund, D. F., & Pellegrini, A. D. (2002). The origins of human
addressed from this conceptual perspective. nature: Evolutionary developmental psychology. Washington,
DC: American Psychological Association.
An integrated conception of culture and biology
Boesch, E. E. (1980). Kultur und Handlung [Culture and activ-
is an inevitable necessity for the future of cross-cul- ity]. Bern: Hans Huber Publ.
tural psychology. We have proposed an integrated Boesch, E. E. & Straub, J. (2006). Kulturpsychologie. Prinzipien,
understanding of evolutionary approaches and cul- Orientierungen, Konzeptionen [Cultural psychology.
tural psychologies as the basis to explore similarities Principles, orientations, conceptions]. In H.-J. Kornadt &
G. Trommsdorff, G. (Eds.), Kulturvergleichende Psychologie.
and differences in human functioning at a non-
Enzyklopädie der Psychologie. Serie VII. Themenbereich C “Theorie
random basis. und Forschung” (pp. 25–95). Göttingen: Hogrefe.
We have also stated an amazing neglect of the Boring, E. G. (1950). A history of experimental psychology
consideration of the content of culture for a long (2nd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
time and an overly inclusive application of the con- Chaudhary, N. (2004). Listening to culture: Constructing reality
ception of individualism/collectivism. However, the from everyday day talk. New Delhi: Sage.
Costa, P. T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1992). Revised NEO Personality
manifold and often justified criticism of individu- Inventory (NEO-PI-R) and NEO Five-Factor Inventory
alism/collectivism should not supersede the fact (NEO-FFI) manual. Odessa, FL: Psychological Assessment
the autonomy and relatedness are core themes of Resources.

keller 129
Demuth, C. (2008). Talking to infants: How culture is instantiated Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self.
in early mother-infant interactions. The case of Cameroonian Implications for cognition, emotion and motivation.
farming Nso and North German middle-class families. Doctoral Psychological Review, 98, 224–253.
thesis, University of Osnabrück, Faculty of Human Sciences, Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1998). The cultural psychol-
Department of Culture & Psychology. ogy of personality. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 29(1),
Greenfield, P. M., & Keller, H. (2004). Cultural psychology. 63–87.
In C. Spielberger (Ed.), Encyclopedia of applied psychology Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (2003). Culture, self, and the
(pp. 545–553). Oxford, UK: Elsevier. reality of the social. Psychological Inquiry, 14, 277–283.
Greenfield, P. M. (2004). Weaving generations together. Evolving Masuda, T., & Nisbett, R. E. (2001). Attending holistically
creativity in the Maya of Chiapas. Santa Fe, NM: Sar Press. versus analytically: Comparing the context sensitivity of
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weird- Japanese and Americans. Journal of Personality and Social
est people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, Psychology, 81(5), 922–934.
61–135. Miller, J. G. (1999). Cultural psychology: Implications for basic
Hofstede, G. (1980/2001). Culture’s consequences. International psychological theory. Psychological Sciences, 10, 85–91.
differences in work related values. Beverly Hills: Sage. (Second Pervin, L. A., & Cervone, D. (2010). Personality. Theory and
edition 2001, Culture’s Consequences – Comparing val- research (11th ed.). New York: Wiley.
ues, behaviors, institutions and organizations across nations. Poortinga, Y. H. (2011). Research on behaviour-and-culture:
Thousand Oaks: Sage). Current ideas and future projections. In A. Chasiotis, S.
Kağitcibaşi, C. (1997). Individualism and collectivism. In Breugelmans & F. van de Vijver (Eds.), Fundamental ques-
J. W. Berry, M. H. Segall & C. Kağitcibaşi (Eds.), Handbook tions in cross-cultural psychology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
of cross-cultural psychology. Volume 3: Social behavior and appli- University Press.
cations (2nd ed., pp. 1–49). Boston: Allyn, & Bacon. Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development.
Kağitcibaşi, C. (2005). Autonomy and relatedness in cultural New York: Oxford University Press.
context: Implications for self and family. Journal of Cross- Schwartz, S. H. (2006). Value orientations: Measurement, ante-
Cultural Psychology, 36(4), 403–422. cedents and consequences across nations. In R. Jowell, C.
Keller, H. (2003). Socialization for competence: cultural models Roberts, R. Fitzgerald & G. Eva (Eds.), Measuring attitudes
of infancy. Human Development, 46(5), 288–311. cross-nationally—lessons from the European Social Survey (pp.
Keller, H. (2007). Cultures of infancy. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. 161–193). London: Sage.
Keller, H. (2010). Linkages between the Whiting model and con- Shweder, R. A. (1990). Cultural psychology - what is it? In
temporary evolutionary theory. Special Issue of the Journal of J. W. Stigler, R. A. Shweder & G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psy-
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 41(4), 563–577. chology. Essays on comparative human development (pp. 1–43).
Keller, H., & Chasiotis, A. (2006). Evolutionary perspectives on Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
social engagement. In P. J. Marshall & N. A. Fox (Eds.), The Shweder, R. A., & Bourne, E. J. (1984). Does the concept of a
development of social engagement: Neurobiological perspectives person vary cross-culturally? In R. A. Shweder & R. A. LeVine
(pp. 275–303). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Eds.), Culture theory: Essays on mind, self and emotion
Keller, H., & Otto, H. (2011). Different faces of autonomy. In (pp. 158–199). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
X. Chen & K. H. Rubin (Eds.), Socioemotional development Sinha, D., & Tripathi, R. C. (1994). Individualism in a collec-
in cultural context (pp. 164–185). New York: Guilford. tive culture: A case of coexistence of opposites. In U. Kim,
Kağitcibaşi, C. (2005). Autonomy and relatedness in cultural H. C. Triandis, C. Kağitcibaşi, S. Choi & G. Yoon (Eds.),
context: Implications for self and family. Journal of Cross- Individualism and collectivism: Theory, method and applica-
Cultural Psychology, 36(4), 403–422. tions (pp. 123–136). Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Kitayama, S., & Imada, T. (2010). Implicit independence and Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition.
interdependence. A cultural task analysis. In B. Mesquita, L. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Feldman Barrett & E. R. Smith (Eds.), The mind in context Triandis, H. C. (1972). The analysis of subjective culture. New York:
(pp. 174–200). New York: Guilford Press. Wiley.
Krüger-Potratz, M. (2005). Interkulturelle Bildung. Eine Triandis, H. C. (1994). Culture and social behavior. New York:
Einführung [Intercultural education. An introduction]. McGraw-Hill.
Münster: Waxmann. Triandis, H. C., Leung, K., Villareal, M., & Clark, F. L. (1985).
Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Feldman, M. W. (2000). Allocentric versus ideocentric tendencies. Convergent and
Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural discriminant validation. Journal of Research in Personality, 19,
change. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 131–146. 395–415.
Lazarus, M., & Steinthal, H. (1860). Einleitende Gedanken Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and human development: An introduc-
über Völkerpsychologie, als Einladung zu einer Zeitschrift tion. London, UK: Sage.
für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft [Introductory Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies. New Delhi,
thoughts about Völkerpsychology as an invitation to a India: Sage.
Journal of Völkerpsychology and linguistics]. Zeitschrift für van IJzendoorn, M. H., & Sagi, A. (1999). Cross-cultural pat-
Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 1(1), 1–73. terns of attachment: Universal and contextual dimensions.
Lonner, W. J., Smith, P. B., van de Vijver, F. J. R., & Murdock, E. In J. Cassidy & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Handbook of attachment:
(2010). Entering our fifthe decade: An analysis of the influ- Theory, research, and clinical applications (pp. 713–734). New
ence on the Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology during York: Guilford Press.
its first forty years of publication. Journal of Cross-Cultural Weisner, T. S. (2002). Ecocultural understanding of children’s devel-
Psychology, 41(3), 301–317. opmental pathways. Human Development, 45(4), 275–281.

130 c ross-c ult ur al psycholo g y


Whiting, B. B. (Ed.) (1963). Six cultures. Studies of child rearing. Whiting, J. W. M. (1977). A model for psychocultural research.
New York: Wiley. In P. Leiderman, S. Tulkin, & A. Rosenfeld (Eds.), Culture
Whiting, B. B., & Pope Edwards, C. (1988). Children of differ- and infancy (pp. 29–47). New York: Academic Press.
ent worlds. The formation of social behavior. Cambridge, MA: Whiting, J. W. M., & Child, L. (1953). Child training and per-
Harvard University Press. sonality. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Whiting, B. B., & Whiting, J. W. M. (1975). Children of six Witkin, H., & Berry, J. W. (1975). Psychological differentia-
cultures: a psycho-cultural analysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard tion in cross-cultural perspective. Journal of Cross-Cultural
University Press. Psychology, 6, 4–87.

keller 131
CHAPTER

Archeology and the Study of Material


7 Culture: Synergies With Cultural
Psychology
Alfredo González-Ruibal

Abstract
Human cognition does not rest upon individual minds alone but is distributed across persons, things,
and time. Archeology, the discipline of things par excellence, has much to offer to researchers
interested in cognitive processes. The material world is crucial in processes of enculturation and
cultural transmission, in shaping daily experience and perceptions, and in orienting action. In this
chapter, the concept of material culture is examined as it is commonly understood today in archeology
and material culture studies. Furthermore, the diverse roles of material culture in relation to cognition
are explored through specific examples from prehistoric, historic, and contemporary societies.
Keywords: material culture, material agency, distributed cognition, built environment, enculturation,
archeological theory

Psychology and Archeology its greatest impact among those working in the earli-
Archeology’s links to psychology are stronger and est phases of the evolution of humankind (Renfrew
more diverse than usually acknowledged, although & Zubrow, 1994; Renfrew & Morley, 2009). In
the interest to establish such links has been mostly fact, the concerns of cognitive archeologists have
unidirectional so far: Since the mid-1980s, arche- been basically centered on evolutionary matters—
ologists have been exploring the complex issue of that is, the development of cognitive skills in human
mind and cognition from the material remains of beings: When did abstract thought, aesthetics, or
the past—a daunting but certainly not impossible the use of material culture as external symbolic stor-
task. On the contrary, psychologists have not been age appear for the first time? The field more akin to
interested in the lessons that might be obtained cognitive archeology is not cultural but evolution-
from archeology. They may think that because ary psychology and cognitive science and, therefore,
archeologists work with the material world, they this approach will not be discussed here. However,
are in a disadvantaged position to access the human also in this case, it has been archeologists who have
mind. Also, they may perceive archeology as a field approached cognitive and evolutionary psychology,
far removed from the theoretical debates that affect rather than the other way round.
other sciences, such as anthropology or sociology, Another meeting point between archeologists
which intersect with psychology in several ways. As and psychology (rather than psychologists) is learn-
we will see, neither idea is really true. ing and the configuration of motor skills: Which
The theoretical current known as cognitive or psychomotor changes have to occur so that an
cognitive-processual archeology is responsible for apprentice becomes proficient at making wheel-
the psychological turn in archeology, which has had turned pots or a certain kind of flaked stone tool

132
(e.g., Roux & Corbetta, 1989; Stout, 2002)? Again, Besides, the particular aim of cultural psychol-
this is not a matter that has to do specifically with ogy is closer in one sense, at least, to archeology
cultural psychology per se but with cognitive science than to anthropology. According to Shweder and
(but see Boesch, 1993). Sullivan (1993, p. 508) “Cultural psychology is
Beyond the evolution of cognitive skills, the truth the study of constituted or compiled experiences
is that at least since the early 1980s, archeologists (what Geertz has called ‘experience-near’ concepts)
and psychologists have been sharing more concerns in contrast to explicated experiences (‘experience
than they may think: identity, personhood, and self distant’ concepts).” Material culture is all about
(Hernando, 2002; Fowler, 2004), human and social constituted experiences: there is nothing closer to
agency (Robb & Dobres, 2000), emotion (Tarlow, experience than materiality. In recent years, interest
2000a), perception of the environment (Tilley, among cultural psychologists in material culture has
1994; Ingold, 2000), memory (Jones, 2007), dis- increased (Valsiner, 2009, pp. 22–24), a fact that
tributed cognition (Malafouris, 2004), and encul- has to be related with an awareness of the impor-
turation (Hodder & Cessford, 2004; Stark et al., tance of objects in culture. For Cole (1998, p. 144),
2008), to mention but a few. artifacts, because of their simultaneous material and
ideal nature, are the fundamental constituents of
Can Archeology Be Useful for Cultural culture, which in turn is fundamental in shaping
Psychologists? cognitive processes. It would be unfair to forget,
Perhaps surprisingly, there has been no attempt however, that one of the first psychologists to point
at dialogue between cultural psychology and arche- out the relevance of material culture—or tools—was
ology. This is despite the fact that archeology (the Vygotsky himself. “The most significant moment in
only science that has the methodological tools to the course of intellectual development which gives
study human beings from 2.5 million years ago birth to the purely human forms of practical and
to the present) can contribute to cultural psychol- abstract intelligence, occurs when speech and practi-
ogy by increasing the number of cultures and cul- cal activity, two previously completely independent
tural contexts at the disposal of the psychologist. lines of development, converge” (Vigotsky 1978,
Archeology’s potential contribution to cultural psy- p. 25). Practical activity, for Vygotsky, was charac-
chology does not end there—rather, it starts there. terized by the use of material tools. Furthermore, he
[The gist of archeology lies in its being the science considered practical intelligence in children as prior
of material culture par excellence; the discipline to independent speech, given the existence of this
of things (Olsen, 2003, p. 89), and material cul- practical intelligence in primates as well.
ture, as Latour (1991) said of technology, is society However, the difference between humans and
made durable. The main aim of cultural psychology apes is the capacity to make complex tools by the
is to understand how the mind is affected by cul- former, which implies a developed anticipatory cog-
ture. Traditionally, visions of culture as proposed by nition. I am not referring here to the use of non-
anthropologists have emphasized its immaterial side modified tools (such as twigs or stones) among
(ideology, institutions, myths, kinship) and, simi- primates or to the debate on primate cultures (for
larly, visions of psychological process as developing this, see C. Boesch, Chapter 31) but to the mak-
on a disembodied mind have predominated in psy- ing and use of secondary tools (such as retouched
chology (Cole, 1998, p. 118). This disembodied flakes). The first lithic industries of 2 to 2.5 million
image of culture and mind has come under attack years ago, although apparently rough, imply a com-
during the last decade, and today many research- plex and elaborate thinking that goes well beyond
ers agree in that human beings do not create and the abilities of chimpanzees (cf. de la Torre, 2004).
live culture in an ethereal, ideal void. Their lives Interestingly, however, as Vygotsky already noted,
and thoughts are inextricably entangled in a mate- this sophisticate practical intelligence exists before
rial world. As a matter of fact, almost everything in the appearance of speech. In this sense, it is worth
the cultural lives of human beings could be consid- noting that for archeologists, evolutionary biologists
ered material culture, because there are very few—if and philosophers alike, one of the defining charac-
any—activities that are not materially mediated in teristics of human beings is the capacity to make
one way or the other—even singing or storytelling and use composite tools. Other elements, such as a
implies materiality: at the minimum, a technique of developed speech and symbolic capacity, come later.
the body (Mauss, 1973). However, Vygotsky was right at pointing at the

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 133
relevance of studying practical intelligence and the mind or materiality as having the leading role. It
use of signs together, instead of as two separate phe- is more an issue of subtle and ongoing adaptations
nomena. He did not just encourage the study of both between the two (Boesch, 1993).
signs and things as intertwined but considered them Cognitive-processual archeologists, those who
equally important: “[S]peech and action are part of most explicitly draw on psychology and cognitive
one and the same complex psychological function, science in their work, have tended to view material
directed toward the solution of a problem at hand” culture as a form of “symbolic storage” (Renfrew &
(Vygotsky, 1978, p. 25). The elaborate operations Scarre, 1998), following Donald’s concept of “exo-
involved in the production of early stone tools are graphic storage” (see below, Memory and Material
not possible without some process of signification Culture). Written texts and signs are well-known
that is absent in apes. These operations comprise forms of exographic storage, but things can be used
two elements that according to Christopher Boesch for coding information as well. They help us remem-
(this volume) distinguish humans from primates: ber past events, historical episodes, or myths, some-
the persistence of cultural traits for extended peri- times in a very explicit way, such as the decorated
ods of time (e.g., bifaces, used for more than a mil- sticks of the Maori that allowed them to remember
lion years) and the presence of nonadaptive cultural long geneologies or the churingas used by Australian
traits: there is more than one way of making a lithic aborigines, wooden plaques encoding the history of
point—technical diversity here indicates a cultural a totem (Rodríguez Mayorgas, 2010, pp. 42–45). In
logic that goes beyond pure adaptation. other cases, the relation between artifacts and infor-
Archeologists, who work with the material results mation is less similar to textual transmission. Artifacts
of past human activity, are in a privileged position can store and convey nonverbal information about
to explore practical intelligence. This is by no means economic and political status, age, gender, ethnicity,
restricted to the period before the appearance of and personal identity (Wobst, 1977; Ames, 1984;
speech, inasmuch as in Homo sapiens nonverbal Schiffer & Miller, 1999). Cognitive-processual arche-
behavior continues to play a paramount role. A final ologists have not been the only ones in exploring the
quote from Vygotsky leaves clear the importance he capacity of things to transmit meaning. Actually, it
conceded to tools as an inextricable part of what is was post-processual or interpretive archeologists who
to be human: “The entire existence of an Australian first drew attention to the fact that material culture
aborigine depends on his boomerang, just as the is meaningfully constituted (Hodder, 1982, 1986)
entire existence of modern England depends on her and, as such, can be decoded. Although cognitive-
machines” (Vygotsky & Luria, 1993, p. 74). Things processual archeology relies on cognitive science, and
make people. interpretive archeology is based on hermeneutics and
In this line, my main concern in this chapter semiotics (Hodder, 1994; Preucel, 2006), the truth is
will be to show how materiality shapes the lives that differences are not as great as one might think. In
of human beings, mediates their relation with the both cases, material culture is perceived as something
world, directs their actions, triggers or inhibits feel- external that is loaded with meaning and manipulated
ings, educates them in the social environment, and by human actors (or minds).
participates in cognitive processes, such as memory
and learning. Toward a Symmetrical Approach to
Mind and Materiality
Material Culture, Materiality, Since the early 1980s, many archeologists and
Distributed Cognition anthropologists have called attention to the impor-
Psychologist and neuroscientist Merlin Donald tance of things in determining culture and have criti-
wrote: “[W]e cannot have a science of mind that dis- cized the oblivion to which the material has been
regards material culture as we cannot have an adequate subjected (see an overview in Olsen, 2006). In recent
science of material culture that leaves out cognition” years, some of them have insisted that objects are not
(Donald, 1998, p. 186). This is widely acknowledged just important—they have agency as well. They are
in archeology and material culture studies today. The not passive containers of culture. Thus, Gosden has
question at the moment is not as much whether mind noted that it is not necessarily the mind that imposes
and materiality are related but how to envisage that its form on material objects but very often just the
relationship. This relationship is better perceived as opposite: things shape thoughts (Gosden, 2005,
symmetrical: we should avoid understanding either p. 196). Anthropologist Alfred Gell (1998) also

134 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


remarked that material objects—particularly art— in the neurons of the potter’s brain, the muscles of
have agency. Nevertheless, saying that artifacts have the potter’s body, the ‘affordances’ . . . of the pot-
the capacity to affect people does not really imply a ter’s wheel, the material properties of the clay, the
transformation of the ontological perspective on the morphological and typological prototypes of exist-
relationship between mind and matter. As Knappett ing vessels as well as the general social context in
has pointed out, “in acknowledging that objects which the activity occurs.”
can be agents and agents can be objects, a dualism The material turn of the last decade has made
between objects and agents remains” (2002, p. 98). us more aware of the inseparability of people and
A more radical stance, and a real break with previ- things and the relevance of the material world in
ous perspectives, came during the last decade with shaping our cultural and psychological experience.
the debates on the limitations of Cartesian or- If cultural psychology is the study of “the way cul-
more generally—modernist dualisms. Archeologists, ture and psyche make each other up” (Shweder &
like practitioners from other disciplines (e.g., Sullivan, 1993, p. 498), then taking the material
Butler, 1993; Latour, 1993; Descola, 2005), side of culture seriously should be a must for cul-
have critically examined the divides established tural psychologists. In the following section, we will
between present/past, individual/collective, subject/ see which are the main characteristics of material
object, culture/nature, material/immaterial, and culture as it is currently understood.
mind/body. Following the principle of ontological
symmetry defended by Latour (1993), Law (1991), Ten Points on Material Culture
and Callon (1991) as well as other proponents of Material culture is used to think in both an
Actor-Network Theory in science and technology explicit and in an implicit way (Henare et al., 2007;
studies, some archeologists argue for a “symmetri- Knappet, 2005). Cognitive processes are distributed
cal archeology” that considers things and people among people and things. As cultures vary, so do the
as fundamentally inseparable (Olsen, 2003, 2007; particular relations among individuals, groups, and
Shanks, 2007; Webmoor, 2007; Witmore, 2007). objects in any particular culture. Although cognitive
This is a radical change with regard to previous the- scientists often take into consideration technology
ories that espoused the primacy of human actors alone and more specifically explicit cognitive tech-
over things and the separation between humans nologies (such as computers or navigational devices;
and objects. e.g., Hutchins, 1995; Dror & Harnad, 2008), cog-
However, similar views have been defended by nitive processes are distributed also among other,
other scholars within cognitive science and cogni- less technically complex, things. If we bear in mind
tive archeology (Knappet, 2002, 2005; Knappet that for human beings, social orientation is as
& Malafouris, 2008). Clark (2008, p. 13), for important as spatial orientation, we can consider,
example, has insisted that we have to abandon for example, that mausolea—which simultaneously
the image of ourselves as disembodied, reasoning help us remember, mourn, and know about social
engines and goes as far as to suggest that “certain classes—are important navigational devices implied
aspects of the external world . . . maybe so inte- in social cognition. On the other hand, even from
gral to our cognitive routines as to count as part the point of view of spatial orientation, we do not
of the cognitive machinery itself ” (Clark, 2008, p. have to think of extremely sophisticate machines: a
15, author’s emphasis). In turn, Malafouris (2004, broken branch that allows a hunter to find his way
p. 57) has argued that human cognition is embod- in the tropical forest is also a cognitive device. In this
ied, situated, extended, enacted, distributed, and sense, Coman et al. (2009, p. 126) rightly consider
mediated, as opposed to the ethereal and indepen- that to understand the navigation of a blind person,
dent mind of earlier cognitive archeologists, which a researcher must account for the mechanisms of
projected itself onto the material world. Like sym- the brain and the nervous system on the fingertips,
metrical archeologists, he considers that the rela- but also “the nature of the cane—its length, rigid-
tionship between the world and human cognition ity, graspability, and so on.” Objects, then, are also
is one of “ontological inseparability.” To illustrate involved in our cognition in an unconscious way in
his point, Malafouris (2004, p. 59) resorts to the daily practice. We think through things even when
potter’s wheel: “the cognitive map of knowledge we do not think about them. In fact, as Heiddegger
and memory may well be extended and distributed (2002, pp. 13–14) noted, it is precisely when we

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 135
do not think about things that the thingness of the active materiality of the world is fundamental for
thing is working best: understanding the human being. As Ernst Boesch
(1991, p. 334) has eloquently remarked:
The equipmentality of equipment consists in
its utility. But what about this utility itself? In “it is the permanence of things that provide
understanding it do we already understand the individuals with a cadre permitting the building of
equipmentality of equipment? In order for this to over-situative action structures. Thereby, they provide
be so, must we not look out for the useful piece of the conditions for those constancies in I-world-
equipment in its use? The peasant woman wears her relationships without which the construction of
shoes in the field. Only then do they become what identity would be difficult to conceive.”
they are. They are all the more genuinely so the less
We cooperate actively in the making of the material
the peasant woman thinks of her shoes while she is
world that surrounds us, but making things makes
working, or even looks at them, or is aware of them
ourselves simultaneously. A potter is constituted
in any way at all. This is how the shoes actually
through her making pots, a basket-maker through
serve. It must be in this process of usage that the
his making baskets. Making things affects senso-
equipmentality of equipment actually confronts us.
rimotor skills (Boesch, 1993; Roux et al., 1995;
The cognitive role of common artifacts is even more Crown, 2001; Stout, 2002) and, more importantly,
important in those societies that have no other perceptions of oneself, society, and the world, as the
means of transmitting information and preserving teaching of technical processes incorporates social
memory apart from oral communication (Kus & information and attitudes that are not strictly ori-
Raharijaona, 1990, p. 23). ented to technical ends (Dobres, 2000; Wallaert-
As the example of the cane of a blind person Pêtre, 2001).
shows, things are not something that merely inter- Yet making artifacts is only part of the constitu-
act with our minds and bodies. Material culture is tion of the self in relation to materiality. Subjects
an inherent part of ourselves, of our own physi- are made through the use of things as well (Miller,
cal existence. Consider bodily ornaments, cloth- 1987), especially in those cultures where handi-
ing, body modifications, hairstyles, but also glasses, crafts have vanished and technological knowledge
microscopes, or audiphones, who have become part is socially very restricted—for example, in indus-
of ourselves as sensory prostheses (Witmore, 2006, trial and post-industrial societies. In the modern
p. 281). It is not only our mind that is extended world, we construct our subjectivities through the
through things (Clark & Chalmers, 1998) but our consumption of fashion (Boesch, 1991, pp. 321–
entire body. We are material culture (Webmoor & 324; Roche, 1996), homes (Miller, 2001a), vehicles
Witmore, 2008) or, as Haraway (1991, pp. 149– (Miller, 2001b), food, art, and many other things.
181) has argued, cyborgs, “hybrids of machine and Furthermore, the way we abandon and destroy
organism,” a mixture of technology and biology that material culture is also part-and-parcel of our iden-
blurs the distinction between nature and culture. tity (e.g., Marcoux 2001). Although destruction
This is not just the case of postmodern humans but might be particularly characteristic of the modern
of every hominid since at least 2.5 million years ago, world, it has always played a role in culture. The first
when the first stone tools were made (Knappett, agricultural communities of the Balkans destroyed
2002, p. 98). their houses purposefully after a certain period, in
We are material beings immersed in a mate- what was in all probability a ritual cycle (Stevanovic,
rial world. We may say that we are in a “state of 1997, see below). The Malanggan of New Ireland
thrownness” (Heidegger’s Geworfenheit) in the (Küchler, 2002, see below) leave their elaborate
material world, or even better, as Tim Ingold (2009, funerary carvings to be slowly destroyed by the ele-
p. 5) eloquently puts it, we live “in the throwing,” as ments (as opposed to our emphasis on monumen-
this is better described as a fluid process. The world, tal preservation). This is related to conceptions of
then, is not just a blank, neutral scenario for human death, for sure, but also to a peculiar experience of
dramas to unfold, a source of problem-specifying what to be human is. It has recently been argued that
inputs (Clark, 2008, p. 16), or something to be different types of structural forgetting are specific
fashioned by thoughts that emerge in a separate to different social formations and that late moder-
sphere of mental activity (Thomas, 1998, p. 155). nity is characterized by massive oblivion based on
It is something deeply enmeshed in our lives. The superhuman speed, megacities, consumerism, and

136 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


perishable urban architecture (Connerton, 2009). to close a door in a way that no human actor ever
In the same vein, it can be said that late modern could (Latour, 2000). A pot with a handle forces us
subjects cannot be understood without their inti- to hold it in a particular way, and throwing a spear
mate relationship with the continual and mas- involves a different bodily gesture than using a bow
sive destruction of things and the environment and arrow. A mosque imposes a bodily behavior and
(González-Ruibal, 2008). One the defining char- a mental attitude. Wearing a toga and wearing trou-
acteristics of the twentieth century has been the sers preclude and allow different sets of actions and
proliferation of artifacts purposefully designed to prescribe a different bodily hexis. In sum, objects
bring destruction on a large scale and aimed at civil- impose on us the necessity that is inscribed in them
ians. The concept of the mass destruction of cities (Boltanski, 1990, p. 141). They order and orches-
shaped a peculiar psychology in the industrialized trate our behavior and, in doing so, they play the
world even before cities were actually destroyed by role that Durkheim recognized to supra-individual
bombers. The abolition of time and space brought social norms inscribed in collective consciousness
about by modernity created at the same time a hith- (ibid.).
erto unheard-of sensation of extreme vulnerability Cognitive processes are not just distributed
(everybody, everywhere can be annihilated), which through people and things; they are also distributed
was further spread by the nuclear menace of the through time (Cole & Engeström, 1997, p. 19). Past
Cold War (Escalona, 1982). actions and events can condition the future actions
In sum, it is the whole life cycle of things and and events. Yet time is embedded in things and
people (from birth to death) that is ineluctably things have their own temporality, which does not
intertwined, and this implies looking simultane- have to coincide with human time (Olivier, 2008).
ously at how people use (and discard) things, and Actually, the temporality of things is entangled with
how things use (and destroy) people. However, the human temporalities in manifold and complex ways.
relationship between consumption and destruction Things are made in the past and conceived for the
is more ambivalent than one may think. We have to future: in this way, they abolish the radical divide
bear in mind that the destruction of objects may turn between past, present, and future (Witmore, 2006;
out to be liberating: iconoclasm has often played a González-Ruibal, 2006a). Therefore, the material
revolutionary role in the history of humankind. We environment has an outstanding capacity to exert
only have to remember episodes such as Luddism an influence in people, long time after their creators
(the destruction of machines by enraged workers in have passed away (Cole & Engeström, 1997, p. 9).
the early days of the Industrial Revolution) or the They continue to guide our actions and participate
destruction of the Berlin Wall. Similarly, consump- in our cognitive processes even when the original
tion can become alienating and create dependencies meanings of those artifacts have been deeply trans-
where there was none, a fact well known in situa- formed—for example, the plan of a Roman city
tions of culture contact. (Olivier, 2008). Something of the deep and more
Material culture has agency. This is perhaps abstract meaning of things, however, may still work
one of the most widely agreed tenets in current in the present in an unconscious manner. The com-
archeology and material culture studies (Gell, plex ways in which temporality is weaved into the
1998; Olsen, 2003; Gosden, 2005; Knappet & fabric of past objects has attracted the attention of
Malafouris, 2008) but also among psychologists: scholars outside the discipline. The case of Sigmund
This is what “active externalism” is all about—the Freud is well-known in the realm of psychology,
capacity of the environment to act upon us (Clark but many others have found inspiration in ruins:
& Chalmers, 1998, pp. 8–12). We could even argue Walter Benjamin, Alois Riegl, and Georg Simmel
that culture at large has agency thanks to material are three of the best-known examples of thinkers
culture. “Culture, reminds Valsiner (2007, p. 255), of ruination. It is the combination of a particular
regulates action . . . It opens some possibilities for temporality with the blurring of nature and cul-
acting, thinking and feeling, while simultaneously ture that has elicited more investigation (Simmel,
closing others.” For its very physical nature, materi- 1959, p. 260; see also Hetzler, 1988). This simul-
ality is in a privileged position to regulate social and taneous collapsing of nature and culture, present
individual action. It promotes, inhibits, or sets the and past bewilders modernity but not necessarily
pace of certain actions and operational sequences. other rationalities and time perspectives, where
A particular kind of key, for example, can force us Cartesian boundaries are less clear or simply absent

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 137
(cf. Descola, 2005). Meaningfully, the perception of
ruins is tightly linked to notions of landscape that
developed in northern Europe after the sixteenth
century (cf. Simmel, 2007). Our fascination with
ruins speaks volumes, then, about the peculiarities of
the Western mind in more than one respect. The “fas-
cination of patina” (Simmel, 1959, p. 262), on the
contrary, does not seem to be a Western prerogative,
as Alain Schnapp (1996) has proved: The ancient
Chinese, for example, already showed a keen inter-
est in the ruins of their ancestors and valued ancient
artifacts for their historical and aesthetic qualities.
Ancient bronze vessels from the Shang Dynasty
(mid-2nd millennium BC) achieved extraordinary
prizes among collectors and antiquarians, centuries
before Western-style archaeology arrived to China.
Sometimes material culture carries codified
symbolic information (Wobst, 1977; Schiffer,
1999), and it is often designed to be communica-
tive and representational (Hodder, 1994, p. 395):
for example, the choice of clothes, transmits infor-
mation on ethnic (Wobst, 1977) or social status
(Hodder, 1994, p. 395). Thus, we not only live Fig. 7.1 Trajan’s column in Rome. It depicts the conquest of
immersed in a material world but also in a material Dacia (modern Romania) by Emperor Trajan between 101 and
world that is full of, even saturated with, meaning. 106. Material culture here works like a text that can be read.
The advantage of material meanings is that they
are always at work. They do not normally need to However, most objects are not symbolic in
be activated to transmit information (like a myth the same way as a text: The relationship between
that has to be told or a story that has to be read material culture and meaning is seldom completely
from a book). Following the Peirceian terminology conventional and arbitrary. Unlike verbal sym-
(see Preucel, 2006, for an archaeological take on bols, material ones bear a direct material relation
the subject), we can say that material culture can to their referents (Beach, 1993). This is because
be iconic, indexical, or symbolic. A wedding ring is most artifacts are actually better understood as
an example of a material symbol (Knappet, 2002, indexes than as symbols (Knappet, 2002, p. 104;
pp. 103–104), whose explicit meaning is conven- Jones, 2007, p. 19). An example of an index is the
tional. Icons are another category of material signs young breasts modeled in mud that the Gumuz
that are clearly conceived to transmit coded infor- women of Ethiopia use to decorate their granaries
mation. Trajan’s column in the Roman Forum (Fig. 7.2). There is a relation of contiguity, typi-
(Fig. 7.1.), for example, is to be read as a commem- cal of indexes, between the breasts (representing
oration of a specific military victory (the conquest of human fertility) and the granary (representing the
Dacia, modern Romania, by the Roman army) and fertility of the fields). Furthermore, this indexical-
therefore has a well-structured and accessible icono- ity brings the whole body into play, blurring the
graphic program that combines images with written distinction between human and non-human mate-
text. Very often, artifacts carry at the same time iconic riality: By modeling breasts on mud, Gumuz girls
and symbolic information: Trajan’s column does not are extending the surface of their bodies beyond
just transmit an iconic message of military victory, it their anatomic limits. The meaning of material
is also a metaphor (a symbol) of imperial power. And culture is not just produced by social convention
in some cases the indexical, symbolic, and iconic are but also through pragmatic understandings of
combined. Consider World War I memorials that the material world—the relationship between the
incorporate actual elements from the war (such as breasts and the fertility of the fields is based on a
a rusty bomb shell), symbolic representations of the real, indexical connection between two reproduc-
nation, and iconic representations of soldiers. tive processes.

138 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


Figure 7.2 Decoration of a Gumuz granary
in western Ethiopia. An indexical sign that
works in practice.

This is related to another point: the relationship prehistoric and historic times. For a long time, the
between material culture and practice (Hodder, issue of how persons are constituted as such was
1994, p. 396). Most of the time, material culture undertheorized in the discipline, as opposed to his-
works through the evocation of sets of practices tory and anthropology. The panorama started to
that are not discursively perceived and that, some- change in the 1980s, with the import of postmod-
times, cannot be put into words. A roof tile is not ern interests in individual agency and identity, and
meant to consciously represent anything, to convey by the 1990s many archeologists were looking for
any explicit meaning (as Trajan’s column or even the individuals in the past (e.g., Meskell, 1999). The
Gumuz granary). But this does not mean that they post-processual take on personhood came under
are not meaningful. They are enmeshed in cultural severe criticism in the early 2000s because of their
practices and systems of meanings that involve other anachronistic nature. Critics point out that by try-
artifacts, ideas, memories, bodily gestures, speech ing to find individual agents in other cultures, the
acts and built spaces: a kitchen knife may not have highly individualized late capitalist person is being
any powerful symbolic meaning attached, yet the projected onto past societies, which are thus per-
(culturally mediated) associations it can bring to ceived as amalgamations of self-conscious individu-
mind are many and varied. They are certainly not als endowed with fluid and changeable identities
the same if the knife is in a kitchen, at an airport in constant negotiation (Casella & Fowler, 2005).
control, or flashing in a dark alley. As archaeologists The interest in particular individual lives came
insist, context is vital to understand things. Context along with the introduction of the post-modern
and things together allow us to behave in prac- politics of identity (age, class, race, gender, sex,
tice. Material culture is therefore tightly related to nationality, ethnicity) in the discipline, which fur-
practical knowledge that allows us to act in specific ther fragmented prehistoric and historic identities
domains of action (Hodder, 1994, p. 398). along post-modern lines (Díaz-Andreu et al., 2005).
Starting from the concept of material culture out- Although post-processual archeology has been rele-
lined above, I will address now four main concerns vant in expanding the research agenda and in point-
of archeology and psychology where it is possible ing out the relevance of identity and personhood,
to see how the discipline of things can contribute the approach has resulted in a transformation of all
to the project of cultural psychology: personhood, past societies into a sort of distorted mirror image of
emotion, space, and memory. our own late modern existences.
Archeologists like Felipe Criado (2001) and
Self and Personhood Almudena Hernando (2002) were among the first
The last decade has witnessed an important debate to call for a more critical exploration of selfhood
in archeology concerning the idea of personhood in in the past, drawing upon anthropological and

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 139
historical theory. They emphasized the collective societies normally produce a proliferation of dis-
and relational nature of prehistoric concepts of tinct artifacts and categories of artifacts to satisfy a
personhood, an idea that was later independently myriad of tastes that are enmeshed in complex social
developed in the Anglo-Saxon archeological tradi- strategies (Bourdieu, 1984). Nevertheless, even in
tion (Fowler, 2004). British archeologists relied on collective cultures, there are people that tend to
Melanesist anthropology—particularly in the work develop more individuality than others. Ritual spe-
of Marilyn Strathern (1988)—to support their per- cialists in segmentary societies, for example, tend to
spectives on prehistoric personhood. Strathern con- use a very peculiar material culture and wear extrav-
tends that the Melanesian person is not individual, agant clothes and adornments (Devlet, 2001). We
but “dividual,” multiply constituted through rela- have to understand this not just as a mere symbol of
tions with other persons. Besides being dividual, status or a materialization of mythologies but also
members of Melanesian societies are also partible. as an index of the more individualized self of the
They are composed of different substances inherited ritual specialists, which leads them to channel their
from the parents or acquired through kinship and need for differentiation through the use of artifacts.
affinal relations. In certain contexts, such as mar- Actually, following a symmetrical approach, we
riage, ceremonial exchanges, and death, persons can could say that extraordinary objects and apparel are
be decomposed—they give away parts of their selves indistinguishable from the ritual specialist’s self: the
in the guise of pigs and other valuables. But the bod- shaman or diviner is a very particular cyborg within
ies themselves are conceived as decomposable, too: a society of more homogenous cyborgs. Similarly,
people can detach from parts of their own bodies as even in highly individualized societies, there are
well as attach to themselves parts (or substances) of material elements that reinforce the ties between
other peoples’ bodies. Relational identities have also different members of the community and therefore
been described as fractal and permeable (Fowler, have a very important psychological role. In the case
2004), as opposed to the bounded and indivisible of late modern Western society, we can see this in
self of modernity. Currently, there is a widespread the urban tribes that resort to the same clothing and
belief in archeology that self-identity is either rela- items to create a sense of belonging among their
tional (most prehistoric societies), and suspiciously members.
similar to the Melanesian self depicted by Strathern,
or individual and well-bound (historical and, espe- Relational Identities
cially, modern Western societies). This dual schema Relational identities were prevalent in the world
reminds the independent/interdependent distinc- at least until the sixteenth century AD. It was prob-
tion proposed by Markus and Kitayama (1991) and ably not before the twentieth century that the indi-
is sometimes perceived in too radical terms. LiPuma vidual self came to dominate globally. Relational
(1998) considers that we have to take into account identities are characterized by a series of material
elements of individuality in the construction of the markers, some of which explicitly encode informa-
self among non-modern societies and, similarly, ele- tion about the identity of a particular community,
ments of relationality (or dividuality) in societies whereas others are of a rather unconscious nature.
with highly individualized persons. For Hernando Among those objects that explicitly encode social
(2008, p. 68), both relational and individual iden- information, we may consider bows and arrows
tities have at least one thing in common: they are (Wiessner, 1982; Pétrequin & Pétrequin, 1990). In
both fantasies, creations of the human mind whose many cultures, arrows have an assertive character—
aim is to neutralize the anxiety that would cause the that is, they express personal identity, craftsman-
true understanding of the powerlessness that defines ship, and taste. However, they also convey, in a very
our relation to the world. And what could be better explicit way, information about the identity of the
to give an appearance of solidity to a fantasy than group to which the person who made the arrows
material culture? belongs. Thus, the Ye-Ineri, an ethnic group from
Materiality is deeply involved in the construction Irian Jaya (New Guinea), make different arrows
of both relational and individual selves. Societies depending on age, function of the arrow (war or
where relational forms of identity prevail tend to hunting), and personal ability. However, it is still
produce homogeneous objects and styles that under- possible to distinguish easily a bundle of arrows
score the shared identity and relations between from the Ye-Ineri group and a bundle of arrows
members of the society, whereas individualistic from the Tangma community. Whereas in a society

140 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


where independent selves prevail there are scarce during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
limits to personal innovation, among the Ye-Ineri and the evolution of independent selves from col-
and Tangma, despite an apparent liberty, the lim- lective ones—a phenomenon that has its correlates
its are very well-demarcated. The boundaries for in the organization of domestic space and refuse
personal creativity are enforced in daily practice disposal. The relevance of the technologies of food
through moral sanctions and social disapproval consumption for shaping a collective self is clearly
that do not necessarily imply explicit verbal con- visible among many Sub-Saharan communities.
demnation. A way of curtailing personal creativity The case of the Komo is telling. They are a highly
in a society of interdependent self is not buying, egalitarian small-scale society of slash-and-burn
exchanging, or accepting in ritualized occasions (or agriculturalists, who live in villages of less than
accepting grudgingly) those artifacts that clearly 200 inhabitants in the Sudanese-Ethiopian border-
deviate from the norm. land (Theis, 1995). As in other neighboring groups
Some artifacts and technical knowledge in (James, 1988), community values are continuously
societies of interdependent self are so crucial in enforced in daily life. One of the mechanisms for
promoting identity that they can be considered buttressing a communal identity is the working
technologies of the self, following Foucault (1988), party: a family calls relatives and neighbors to lend
but rather than an individual self, they help create a a hand with the harvest or the building of a hut
collective self. Unlike items that bear explicit ethnic and, in compensation, provide food and beer. The
information (such as bows and arrows), technolo- artifacts and the body gestures employed in these
gies of the collective self are often unconscious or, rituals are essential for the perpetuation of rela-
at least, beyond verbal discourse. A good example is tional selves (Fig. 7.3): Everybody forms a circle
the technology of food consumption. This technol- and drinks from the same big pot using straws, giv-
ogy includes artifacts, body techniques, and oper- ing their backs to the outer world and their faces
ational sequences. Changes to the technology of to neighbors and relatives (González-Ruibal et al.,
food consumption often imply dramatic transfor- 2009, p. 60). A sense of solidarity is extraordinarily
mations in society and identity: Deetz (1996, pp. reinforced in this way.
86–87) has equated the evolution from commu- Relational identities are also expressed in the way
nal vessels to individual dishes in North America the dead are treated. It seems logical that if persons

Figure 7.3 A group of Opuuo (a people closely related to the Komo), drink beer from a common pot in a working party
(western Ethiopia).

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 141
are considered partible and decomposable, their Individual Identities
bodies are too (Jones, 2005). Burials from Europe The strong development of individuality in the
and the Near East during the Mesolithic (i.e., the West since the fifteenth century comes hand-in-
period of the last hunter-gatherers before the emer- hand with an extraordinary increase in the number
gence of agriculture in the Old World) often kept and variety of artifacts through which new, diverse,
only disarticulated bones (Verjux, 2007), because and often conflictual selves were channeled and
the human remains were buried after a period of constituted: gardens (Leone, 1984), houses and
exposure to the elements or because the bones were headstones (Deetz, 1996), portraits (Burke, 1995),
dug up and reburied. These practices continued and even toothpicks (MacLean, 2009). Some of
with the first agrarian communities in the period these items are used in a communicative manner to
known as Neolithic (Thomas, 2000). Some egalitar- consciously display personal and social taste and sta-
ian societies still practice, or practiced until recently, tus—that is, as symbols: clothes, silver, or chinaware
secondary burials. That is the case of the Uduk of (Goodwin, 1999; Schneider, 2006, pp. 206–207).
Sudan (James, 1988), who used to dig out one or In other cases, things become intrinsically related
more of the bones of a recent tomb, anoint them with the self in an unconscious manner—this is
with red ochre, and return them to the grave, a the case of toothbrushes and other items of per-
ceremony that was meaningfully called “Settling sonal hygiene and bodily care (Gaitán, 2005), as
the Grave” (James, 1988, p. 131). The idea was to well as writing and reading materials (Hall, 2000,
ensure that the spirit could make a complete and pp. 80–83). Both categories of artifacts are related
clean break from the body (ibid., p. 127). The skull, in that they have to do with ideas of care (physi-
in particular, tends to receive a differential treat- cal or psychical), and they are therefore crucial in
ment in many cultures. Modified and decorated fostering and cultivating the individual self. In this
skulls abounded during the late Mesolithic period sense, they are technologies of the self (Foucault,
in the Levant (Kuijt, 1996), and this practice is 1988; Fowler, 2004, p. 13) but also “core objects,”
well-known from ethnographic contexts in areas as Boesch (1991, p. 333) has called them: “one
like Melanesia (Zegwaard, 1959). Kuijt (1996) which, by its usages and ritual connectedness,
interprets skull removal and other mortuary prac- appears to be vital for the definition of a culture.”
tices (such as lack of grave goods) in the Near East as A particular technology of the self that has devel-
part of the strategies developed by complex hunter- oped since the mid-sixteenth century in the context
gatherers and incipient agriculturalists to limit the of the Counter-Reformation has been the material
accumulation of power and authority. culture of bodily discipline. Whips, sticks, cingula,
As people are perceived as inseparable from and cilices (Brandão & Nassaney, 2008) were aimed
the collective in relational cultures, tombs are at purifying the self by mortifying the sinful body.
often collective. The skeletons of different people Although cilices have been used since Antiquity,
appear mingled together and sometimes it is dif- their success in early modernity has to be related
ficult to refit individual bodies (Fowler, 2001). to the progressive imposition of dualistic ideas that
Sometimes, even animal bones appear mixed with created a divide between mind and body—the first
human remains: this probably means the relational being equated with the self (and soul)—and the
self included relations with non-humans as well increasing importance of the individual person and
(Descola, 2005). The treatment of the deceased was individual salvation.
a very straightforward way of transmitting ideas of It would be wrong, however, to think that tech-
the self and community in the broad sense. There nologies of the individual self exist only in moder-
seems to have been a tendency among those societ- nity or in evolved state societies, such as the Greek
ies where corpses and bones were manipulated not and Roman world examined by Foucault (1988).
to hide away the event of death, as opposed to soci- Technologies of bodily care that evince a strong
eties with only one death ritual. In fact, many of awareness of the individual self have developed since
the rituals of excarnation, dismemberment, burial, the mid-2nd millennium BC in Bronze Age Europe,
and reburial of bones were attended by the entire when razors and mirrors, dress pins, and individu-
group, and sometimes parts of the dead were ritu- alized weaponry became widespread among elites
ally consumed (Conklin, 1995; Boulestin, 2009), (Treherne, 1995). Those items were indispensable
which is the most powerful way of showing a sense to constitute individual selves in the midst of rather
of community. homogeneous communities.

142 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


The difference with modernity is that technolo- group differences through artifacts, but she will also
gies of the self and individualized material culture become aware of her own uniqueness as an individ-
become extremely generalized, eventually cutting ual through the use of particular objects and through
across social classes, race, and gender. In our global- the consumption choices that she will be compelled
ized, late capitalist world, almost everybody wants to make (Baudrillard, 1968, pp. 196–197): toys,
to be unique. In fact, artifacts in modernity can be a clothes, books, cars, DVDs, web-blogs. From her
powerful way of holding the self together in disrup- earliest childhood, she will recognize herself in pho-
tive scenarios, such as civil conflicts, wars, and dic- tographs. She will learn that her self is modifiable
tatorships. Artifacts may help to link one with his or but not decomposable, both in its physicality, in its
her self prior to the traumatic experience (e.g., the social attachments, and in its psychic qualities. She
handicrafts made by prisoners) (López Mazz, 2009, will read self-help books or philosophy, sculpt her
pp. 39–41) or to create a new self, which incorpo- body in the gym, or operate her breasts. Yet there
rates (and domesticates) the traumatic experience. is a limit to what an individual can become even in
This is the case of trench art, the artifacts produced modern societies: prisons, reform schools, and asy-
by soldiers in World War I (Saunders, 2009). lums are institutions that model the deviated self
To summarize, material culture is fundamental in through all kinds of material and immaterial tools
constituting the self as relational or independent and (Foucault, 1975; Casella, 2007), which, again, are
the whole spectrum between one possibility and the aimed at the individual person—individual cells,
other. A child belonging to a small-scale, egalitarian solitary confinement cells, psychological assistance.
community will arrive to a homogenous world in
which all artifacts look the same and private posses- Emotion and Material Culture
sions are minimal—he will associate himself with Emotional experience is universal, but emotions
sameness rather than difference. Through those arti- are culturally variable, as anthropologists have abun-
facts (houses, pots, or cultivated fields), the child dantly demonstrated (Lutz & White, 1986; Tarlow,
will learn to live in a society where relations among 2000a): cultural meanings, experiences, and values
humans and non-humans are more important than attached to emotions vary from society to society.
individual persons. Furthermore, as the child grows, According to Shweder:
he will progressively use technologies of the collec-
To understand the emotional life of a person is to
tive self—that is, techniques, technical knowledge,
understand the types of feelings (anger, envy, fear,
and artifacts that make him relate to others and that
depersonalization, shame, joy, love, homesickness,
will constitute his psychical existence as part of a
and so on) felt by that person, the distribution and
communal body—for example, weapons and strat-
frequency of those feelings across time and context,
egies used in communal hunting or spindles and
the kind of situations that elicit them, the wishes
songs in communal weaving ceremonies. In some
and fantasies that occur with them and the action
cases, such as in many societies of hunter-gather-
tendencies set off by them.
ers, private possessions are reduced to almost nil.
(1991, p. 242)
Everything has to be given away if someone asks for
it (and vice versa: one is allowed to use almost every- What can be the contribution of archeology to
thing from everybody). The boy who is born in a explain the emotional life of individuals and societ-
community of relational self will never see or make ies? We have to take into account that emotions are
an iconic representation of himself, only idealized not always easily verbalized, especially overwhelm-
representations of Men, Women, Ancestors, Gods, ing emotions—what Valsiner (2007, p. 312) calls
and everything in between. By attending funerals “hyper-abstracted and over-generalized higher level
where bodies are manipulated, carved up, buried, total feelings.” Actually, feelings themselves cannot
dug up, and reburied, he will learn to perceive his be observed, only indexes of them (gestures, facial
body as plastic and decomposable, a continuum in movements, heartbeats) (Shweder, 1991, p. 242),
the mass of human and animal bodies that populate and indexes are the raw material with which arche-
the world. ologists work. Besides, emotions are often triggered,
If we consider now a girl born in a late modern, oriented, or conditioned by the material world
highly individualistic society, we will see her exposed (Valsiner, 2008).
from her birth to a highly differentiated mate- Emotion has figured prominently in recent
rial world. She will learn to understand social and archeological debates (Tarlow, 2000a). The basic

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 143
problem is how can we actually know what other with the material world is central to experience, and
peoples experienced in the past? Unlike ethnogra- the materiality of the body offers some possibilities
phers, archeologists rarely have the opportunity of experience and precludes others (Tilley, 1994).
of an intersubjective experience—or “subjective Thus, cold, heat, hunger, or pain—although con-
pilgrimage,” as Valsiner (2007, p. 311) aptly puts ceived in different ways and endured to different
it—with living people. In the case of historical arche- degrees by different cultures—affect all human bod-
ology, this can be somehow mitigated through the ies, and these have limits as to what they can see and
use of texts (including personal diaries and letters). interact with from a certain topographical position.
For illiterate societies, the problem we face might Also, the materiality of the landscape itself has not
be deemed insurmountable. We are forced to make changed much in many cases: the physical environ-
inferences based on analogies with similar societies ment interacts with physical human bodies in spe-
documented ethnographically as well as on our own cific ways, irrespective of culture (Tilley, 2004).
subjective experience. The latter has been the object The important point to bear in mind is that the
of much discussion. Since Christopher Tilley’s semi- emotions archeologists are better able to retrieve are
nal book, A Phenomenology of Landscape (1994), the those related to hyper-abstracted and overgeneral-
philosophical insights of phenomenology have been ized feelings—the kind of feelings one has when
widely applied to prehistoric archeology, especially entering a gothic cathedral, a megalithic tomb, or
in the British Isles (Brück, 2005). Interest in past a prison cell. Instead of trying to discern in detail
feelings has led, in some cases, to subjective excesses particular emotions, archeologists are at their best
and to a trivialization of phenomenological theory when they explore the material mechanisms that
(cf. critique in Olsen, 2006). However, most arche- trigger those emotions in different cultural con-
ologists have avoided both the most objectivist and texts. In which places was the greater investment
the most subjectivist positions, adopting nuanced made in material devices oriented toward affection?
perspectives. Therefore, there are those who, from a Which spaces were more emotionally charged?
relativistic and constructivist stance, stress the enor- Those related to collective identity, political power,
mous difficulty of approaching subjective experi- religion, punishment, individual achievement, life,
ences of people belonging to other cultures (Tarlow, death, liminal states? Which spaces displayed more
2000a; Brück, 2005), even if basic human similari- varied devices for triggering sentiment?
ties across cultures are acknowledged. On the other If a place is emotionally invested to a high
hand, there are those who emphasize our ability degree, it can help us know the importance of such
to connect with past senses of place through our place in society, as well as the activities related to
own bodily experience (Tilley, 1994), although they that place—for example, tombs of children in the
accept that specific meanings and precise feelings West are often overcharged with indexes of affec-
mostly escape the archeologist. tion. It is difficult not to feel moved by some of
Admittedly, access to particular emotions of other these tombs displaying a variety of toys, teddy
cultures from material remains alone is extremely bears, letters, photographs and flowers. This is
difficult and always requires some sort of cultural because children are not supposed to die in an
translation. There is no true immediate experience industrialized society but also because childhood
of the past: in the case of prehistoric societies, we has been marked as a well-defined and valuable
are dealing with people who had a wholly differ- period of human life mostly in modernity (Ariès,
ent cosmology and rationality, which deeply shaped 1987). On the contrary, in many pre-industrial
their perceptions of the world (Thomas, 2004, societies, child tombs are very inconspicuous, and
pp. 216–217; Brück, 2005, pp. 54–55). Nevertheless, in some prehistoric cultures they were not even
we can still have some access to past emotions with- buried at all (Scott, 1999). However, prehistoric or
out resorting to texts. On the one hand, the work ancient societies should not all necessarily show the
of cultural psychologists has proved that most basic same kind of emotional behavior, although some
emotions (such as anger, disgust, fear, happiness, tendencies applied. In her study of the Egyptian
sadness, and surprise) appear in most cultures, village of Deir el-Medina (late 2nd millennium BC),
although they are expressed in very different ways Meskell (1999) proposed that the death of children
(Heine, 2010). After all, there is a shared biological was experienced as a painful event, based on the
basis that explains human emotion. On the other elaborated burials of non-aristocratic children and
hand, the physical engagement of the human body on contemporary texts.

144 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


Emotional Framing of Political Lives Neolithic Europe
Another case has to do with elements of affection Megalithic tombs were built all over Western
in political life. Political celebrations tend to mobi- Europe by early farmers during the period known as
lize different kinds of emotions: power is sensuous Neolithic (i.e., between the early fifth and early third
and corporeal, and not just in premodern societ- millennia BC). They were the first monumental, col-
ies (Kus, 1989; Mbembe, 2000; Linke, 2006). As lective tombs—the first monuments at all—in most
Tarlow (2000a, p. 719) reminds: places where they were built (Fig. 7.4). During the
second millennium BC, monumental burials still
“Hegemony and authority in social contexts are
existed in different places of Europe, such as south-
constituted through such emotional experiences
ern Britain and southern Portugal, but they were
as awe, respect, fear, shame, and guilt, as well as
erected for individual persons or particular power-
familiarity and security.”
ful families. Megalithic tombs soon developed into
These emotional experiences are framed by material a very complex architecture with immense possibili-
apparatuses. However, emotion in political contexts ties to shape and direct emotion. Subtle changes in
varies wildly from culture to culture. To use two temperature, texture, darkness and light, sound,
opposite examples: Versailles was devised so as to and visibility configured very particular experiences
arouse overwhelming feelings of superhuman gran- of community, death, afterlife, and the sacred. Also,
deur, a fact that fits well with a divine conception the tomb itself was not the only important element
of power. A place that is known by its address (10 for framing social experiences. Tombs were inserted
Downing Street) on the contrary, is completely bereft in meaningful landscapes in which other monu-
of material devices to trigger emotion, although ments and natural features interacted to create a
these may arise for different motivations. This sense of place (Tilley, 1994). During the last decade,
speaks eloquently about the conception of power in there have been many attempts to avoid intuitive
contemporary liberal democratic societies. approaches to Neolithic emotions. Archeologists
try to provide contrasted accounts of the ways in
Death and Emotion: Neolithic Europe which “hyper-abstracted and over-generalized feel-
and the Modern West ings” were fostered and enhanced inside tombs
Understanding emotion in context, then, helps us and in megalithic landscapes. Regarding landscape,
understand culture. In what follows, we will look at Geographical Information Systems (GIS) have been
a place loaded with emotion—cemeteries—in two used to recover the way it was experienced in the
different cultural environments: Neolithic Western past in a more objective manner (e.g., Criado &
Europe and Euro-American modernity. Villoch, 2000; Llobera, 2003; Wallace, 2007). GIS

Figure 7.4 A megalithic tomb from Galicia


(Spain) after excavation. Ritual activities
took place around the mound, in front of the
entrance and inside between 3800 BC and
2700 BC.

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 145
analyses allow making visible connections, which speech, and movement could have been used to pro-
are unknown or known intuitively, between differ- voke an altered state of mind. The issue of sound has
ent monuments and natural features. received significant attention. Watson and Keating
Megalithic tombs were open monuments in (1999), for example, analyzed the particular sounds
which rituals took place and where corpses were of a stone circle (a sort of sanctuary or shrine) and
being buried, exhumed, and reburied in a regu- a passageway-type megalithic tomb. The authors
lar basis. They are excellent examples of “scripted of the research discovered that a single drum was
dramatic everyday life situations” (Valsiner, 2007, capable of generating approximately 4 Hz to 5 Hz
p. 250) that are crucial in the psychological devel- at between 120 decibels and 130 decibels inside
opment of human beings. Overwhelming feelings a megalithic tomb, a level of exposure that could
were achieved through different means: one is the result in balance disturbance, pressure on the ears,
art that covers part of the huge stones (Fig. 7.5). speaking difficulties, vibration, drowsiness, and
Unlike in the modern world, art was not a normal headaches. Also involved in enhancing experience
occurrence in the Neolithic. People did not live in and creating meaning was texture, which involved
an “ornamented world” (Valsiner, 2008) as we do. touching and therefore a bodily experience of the
Thus, entering a profusely engraved tomb must monument (Cummings, 2002). In this context, it
have certainly been regarded as a liminal event, an is worth remembering, with Warnier the basic role
entrance into another world—and it is precisely of the skin in the ontogenesis of the human subject:
entrances and passages that are most often deco- “The psyche is constructed as an envelope by ‘anacli-
rated (Bradley, 1989). Sensations were probably sis’ on the anatomical-physiological functions of the
enhanced, at least in some cases, with the use of skin” (2006, p. 187). Here, anaclisis is understood
consciousness-altering substances, which interacted as related to a process by which psychic experiences
with the images to foster hallucinations and visions build on—or are propped against—bodily motions
(Dronfield, 1995a, 1995b). The images—spirals, and emotions. Differences between smooth and
lozenges, arcs, meanders, and curves—are thought rough surfaces in megaliths could have triggered dif-
to be inspired in the visions themselves. Dronfield ferent emotional responses and be imbued with dif-
(1995b, p. 547) proved that Irish passage-tomb art ferent meanings. Finally, the textures of light must
is fundamentally “similar to (as opposed to merely have been very important in the megalithic expe-
resembling) arts derived from endogenous subjec- rience. Light is manipulated in many architectural
tive vision.” traditions to orient emotional responses (Bille &
However, it is not strictly necessary to consider Sorensen, 2007). Although similar effects to those
the use of drugs to explain the way the mind was of megaliths could have been previously achieved
altered inside the tomb. Songs, sounds, dancing, in natural spaces, such as caves, by hunter-gatherers

Figure 7.5 A decorated slab from the megalithic tomb of Knowth in Ireland.

146 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


(Reznikoff & Dauvois, 1988; Waller, 1993), the emotion. And with good reason—as we saw in the
difference is that megaliths were the first explicit case of megaliths, a redundant, saturated material
attempt at creating and manipulating sensory con- environment was fundamental in triggering and
ditions to affect the subject in an artificial way. amplifying emotions.
The relevance of megalithic tombs in the social One of the main differences between modern
lives of early agriculturalists should not be underes- and pre-modern cemeteries is the prevalence of
timated. As I have pointed out, these were regular visual experience and visual codes in the former,
arenas for social interaction (much more than mod- in line with the enormous importance conferred
ern cemeteries). The term tomb is misleading for us, to the sense of vision in modernity (Levin, 1993).
as we divide the world of the dead and that of the Although hearing still plays a role (choirs, ser-
living in a very clear-cut way and try to avoid any mons, reading of religious texts), bodily senses are
contact with the former. In addition, the megaliths less prominent than in non-modern communities.
were probably used if not by the whole community, Tombs (much less corpses) are not designed to be
at least by a large part of it, including children and touched or to have a particular sound—and human
adolescents. Although the most secluded parts of remains do not smell. The experience of death is
the tomb could have been accessed only by a few, sober, clean, individual, and introspective. The
the ceremonies in the necropolises were attended suburban cemeteries that spread through northern
in all likelihood by the entire group. Watson and Europe from the late eighteenth century onward—
Keating (1999) proved that sounds made inside a particularly the Anglo-American garden cemetery
megalithic tomb could be heard outside, emerging (Tarlow, 2000b)—played a prominent role in shap-
from the passage entrance. Megaliths, then, were ing the emotions of death as individually experi-
an essential element in the emotional economy enced. Garden cemeteries were located in pastoral
of the early European farmers. The rituals carried locations. This was justified on hygienic grounds,
out inside and around the tombs were emotionally but in fact, it was not only physical dirt and pollu-
intense and involved the whole community: actually, tion that preoccupied urban reformers but also the
they helped reinforce the sense of community—and moral and emotional cleanliness that the new cem-
communitas (Turner, 2002). The sensorial quali- eteries brought with them (Tarlow, 2000b, p. 227).
ties of the megaliths enhanced the experience and The isolated tombs and the manicured landscape
channeled and amplified the emotions. The relation had a double effect (Fig. 7.6): On the one hand,
with the deceased and with the ancestors was very they calmed down and sifted emotions, fostered
close: One literally entered the house of the dead introspection, and enabled self-reflective attitudes
and manipulated the bones of one’s relatives. (just the opposite of emotionally loaded, collective
megaliths). On the other hand, they permitted the
The Modern Western World experience of emotions (even the more violent ones
Quite the opposite is the case of modern cem- that one could not restrain) without being seen by
eteries. Despite cycles of ostentation and restrain in many people, a situation of relative intimacy that
funerary ceremonies, the general trend in European could hardly be achieved in overcrowded city
and North American funerals during the nine- churchyards.
teenth and twentieth centuries has been toward Although similar trends toward suburban,
the restriction of emotions. For the last hundred hygienic cemeteries have existed in southern Europe
years, ostentation in tombs and funerals has been from the mid-eighteenth century (Calatrava, 1991),
regarded in most Western societies as a sign of bad there are important national differences. Anglo-
taste and low or marginal status (Cannon, 1994, Saxon cemeteries are much more individual-oriented
p. 440; Parker-Pearson, 1982, pp. 104–107). This than Mediterranean ones. In the United Kingdom,
process has been explained on economic and social the United States, and other places with a strong
grounds—investments in status markers changing Protestant tradition, tombs are individual and sit-
from funerary display to other realms to main- uated wide apart in vast cemeteries. On the con-
tain class distinctions. However, there seems to trary, in Spain and other Mediterranean countries,
be deeper reasons for this general trend toward tombs are often cramped together around churches,
more sober cemeteries and rituals: It seems that an often in multi-niche structures (Tarlow, 2000b,
excess of materiality in funerary ceremonies and p. 222)—a translation to the material world of
tombs was unconsciously equated with an excess of a more relational identity within a culture of the

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 147
Figure 7.6 Victorian cemetery in Glasgow:
isolated monuments to the individual self.

Figure 7.7 Between the individual and the


relational self: a cemetery in Galicia (Spain).

individual self (Fig. 7.7). Anglo-Saxon cemeter- However, the more interdependent Catholics
ies are spaces for melancholic, individual feelings. would interpret this as aloofness and individualistic
Mediterranean necropolises are more appropriate behavior.
for open, collective emotions and expressions of Finally, another element that can be enlight-
family and neighborhood solidarity. According to ening as to the relation among self, emotion, and
Tarlow, death in societies of independent self is the issue
of memorials. In modern cemeteries, it is the per-
An appreciation of Protestant virtues of simplicity formative act of reading the name of the deceased
and nature was a central part of British identity in on a tombstone—an individual act—that provokes
the nineteenth century. In their own understandings, the most powerful feelings. Significantly, one of
the Protestant nations were distinguished from their the most successful war memorials ever built is the
overblown Catholic neighbours by an authenticity of Vietnam Veterans Memorial in Washington D.C.
unmediated, pure moral feeling. (Wagner-Pacifici & Schwartz, 1991), in which
(2000b, p. 224) reading is absolutely essential for unleashing intense

148 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


feelings. Its success lies in two facts: it commemo- a whole that is forcing us to adopt a certain atti-
rates individual lives (the entire monument is a list tude: the quality of light, the books, the curtains
of names), and it abolishes the difference between and shelves, the texture of the walls and floors.
past and present (by uttering the name of the dead, Houses, in particular, are a critical element in every
people are able to evoke a strong sense of presence). culture and are endowed with an especially power-
This fits better the modern self than collective, ful agency. They intimately shape our behavior and
abstract memorials, as those built after World War experience of the world beginning in our child-
I. Whereas in the Vietnam Veterans Memorial the hood; they give us ontological security by creating
focus is on the individual, in World War I memo- predictability and routinization (Giddens, 1984);
rials the focus is on collective sacrifice (Winter, they replicate the cosmos (Preston Blier, 1987); help
1995, pp. 78–116). Unlike other monuments, and us know our place in society (Donley-Reid, 1987);
because of the controversial and divisive character of and guide affection (Bachelard, 1964). They even
the war, the Vietnam Veterans Memorial was actu- shape our bodily memory: “The house where we
ally explicitly designed so as to avoid collective mes- are born,” writes Bachelard (1964, p. 32), “is physi-
sages and to evoke instead “ ‘feelings, thoughts, and cally inscribed in us. It is a group of organic habits.”
emotions’ of a variant and private nature” (Wagner- Another important consequence, in psychological
Pacifici & Schwartz, 1991, p. 393). In short, the terms, of the built environment, is its capacity to
Washington memorial can be considered the quint- affect our modes of spatial reasoning. It seems obvi-
essential monument to the dead in highly individu- ous that the perception of space cannot be the same
alized late modern societies. However, what the among a group of slash-and-burn agriculturalists
memorial achieves in the short term, it loses in the who live in single-celled huts separated wide apart
longuée duré, a fact that is also eloquent of modern and among people living in square, multiroomed
identity: after a few generations, it will fail to trig- houses in a cramped city. Kent (1990) has dem-
ger intense emotions, when the names of the indi- onstrated that structures become more segmented
vidual dead fall into oblivion (Wagner-Pacifici & as social organization becomes more complex and
Schwartz, 1991, pp. 417–418). This is in opposi- hierarchical. Segmentation of the space increases in
tion to the megalithic chambers, where the bones parallel to conceptions of intimacy, individualism,
of the remotest ancestors and the newcomers to the political power, religion, and, more generally, with
tomb were mingled together. Every ceremony held the development of modes of rationality that tend
in the megalith was an intense, emotional experi- to fragment, divide, and sort out the world in spe-
ence. Individuals did not matter—it was the always- cific categories. All these transformations in space
regenerated, cyclical self of the community that and the self are particularly visible in modernity
mattered. The Vietnam War Memorial will fail to (Deetz, 1996).
evoke presence in less than a century. The megaliths I will review here two cases that exemplify well
evoked it for millennia. how domestic space is deeply inscribed in persons’
minds and bodies: the Swahili house of the Eastern
Space and Order African coast and the Bertha house of Ethiopia.
The agency of material culture as a framework They are not, properly speaking, archeological cases:
over our actions is nowhere more obvious than in the first is an ethno-historical study and the second
the built environment (Parker Pearson & Richards, an ethnographic one, but research was carried out in
1994): it orients everyday life by offering certain both cases by archeologists with archeological meth-
spaces for programmed action, while closing other odologies and questions in mind.
possibilities (Dovey, 1999, p. 11). Walls, rooms,
doors, and decorations act as “semiotic blockers” The Swahili House: Hierarchical
(Valsiner, 2007, p. 68) that regulate the semi- Order
otic hierarchies of the dialogical self. The agency The Swahili house is a perfect example of how
of buildings is clearly seen, for example, when we social values are materialized in space and hence
enter a library and immediately start to speak in internalized through daily interaction with the built
a low voice (Donley-Reid, 1990, p. 116). It is not environment by those who use it. The Swahili live in
only the verbal messages (signs of “Silence” or the the coast of Eastern Africa, from southern Somalia
librarian’s command) that make us lower the vol- to northern Mozambique, and they are a mixture
ume of our voice. It is the material environment as of native Africans and Arab merchants, who traded

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 149
in this area since the eighth century AD (Horton protect them (Donley-Reid, 1982, p. 66). The dirti-
& Middleton, 2000). Their hybrid culture takes est and less valued part of the house, the kitchen,
elements from the indigenous cultures and the for- was also located in the lower floor. The masters
eign traders. Swahili houses of the patrician group lived in the richly decorated upper story and slept
(waungwana) had a rectangular layout and two in beds. Within this story, polluting activities (such
floors, as opposed to the circular huts that prevailed as sexual intercourse, childbearing, and cleaning of
in Eastern Africa. Also, unlike traditional houses in corpses) took place in the most secluded room of
the region, they were substantially built in coral, the house, the ndani, which was the most lavishly
lasted several generations, and were richly adorned decorated part of the house as well (Donley-Reid,
with elaborate geometrical carvings. The possession 1987, pp. 187–188). Valsiner (2008, p. 69) notes
of long residence in a single place (ustaarabu) was that the meaning of decoration is often linked with
considered to be a moral quality inherent to being the notion of nonfunctional or excessive kind of
Swahili—and different from the local “barbarians” decoration. This certainly applies to the baroquely
(Horton & Middleton, 2000, p. 179). For a start, ornamented ndani—an index of a strong fear of
then, living in a coral house made their waung- pollution.
wana owners feel different (and superior) from The different qualities of the materials employed
the surrounding African communities and Swahili in the construction of the house; the difference in
commoners. But it also made them anxious: They textures, decorations, and furniture; and the differ-
were in a minority position in relation to both the ential location of the masters’ and servants’ rooms
African and Islamic worlds and to disenfranchised all helped to make people internalize through daily
communities (slaves). The solidarity between the practice the social order of the Swahili world. In
waungwana and their fear of the outside was mate- addition, some ceremonies made social order even
rially expressed in the bridges and internal pas- clearer and more redundant for those who inhab-
sageways that connected the patricians’ houses and ited the house. The ritual kutolewande took place
allowed the Swahili to avoid the street and pres- 40 days after the birth of a free-born child (Donley-
ent a united front toward strangers (Donley-Reid, Reid, 1982, p. 70). The baby was then carried
1982, p. 65). It is logical that this anxiety was also around the house, from the ndani, where he or she
expressed through rituals related to the boundar- was born, to the rest of the rooms in what could be
ies of the house (Donley-Reid, 1987, p. 189) and considered a prototypical “social guidance drama”
an obsession with purity. The house, besieged by (Valsiner, 2007, p. 233). The mother, the female
the polluted city, was the locus of purity par excel- relatives, and the slaves accompanied the baby in
lence, but this had to be continuously maintained his or her first tour of the social world that he or she
through cleansing, whitewashing, prayer, and ritual will inhabit. The child was shown the rooms, their
observance (Horton & Middleton, 2000, p. 183). function, the artifacts, and furniture associated to
Purity was a quintessential moral quality of women, each room as well as the people who use them. The
too, who were strongly linked to the house (as in tour ended in the entrance door where, if the baby
other Islamic societies). Women shared other moral was a girl, she was told that the outside belonged
qualities with the house, such as shame and beauty to men only. That will be the limit of her world.
(ibid.). In a sense, the materiality of the house deter- Naturally, the ritual was only symbolic for the child,
mined the woman’s personhood and identity. Inside but it helped emphasize in a powerful way the social
the Swahili house, the female mind, body, and spa- order that was reproduced in practice by the house-
tial order were bound together. hold members every day. It also marked the begin-
The house was not the residence of the waung- ning of the slow and long process of enculturation
wana only. Female slaves (madada) and concubines for the child.
shared the home with their masters. The built space
was loaded with explicit and implicit meanings, and The Bertha House: Order Without
it was used in daily practice to show everybody his Hierarchy
or her place within the house and within society The Swahili are a deeply hierarchical society
at large. Thus, the lower story—where the slaves and with a complex state religion. The case of the
lived and slept on the floor on mats—had unplas- Bertha (González-Ruibal, 2006b), who live in west-
tered and undecorated walls. Slaves were considered ern Ethiopia and eastern Sudan, is quite different.
unclean and therefore did not need any devices to The Bertha are Muslim, too, but their concern with

150 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


pollution and purity is very different—and less that sustain the Bertha’s identity are neither
pressing. They are a rather egalitarian community, explicit nor representational.
with little social differentiation. Like the Swahili, Despite their regional variations, all Bertha houses
the Bertha are a hybrid people as well, heavily follow a similar spatial logic, that is deeply imprinted
influenced by the Islamic Sudan. The equivalent of into the Bertha’s mind and that regulates their cul-
Swahili patricians in Bertha land was the Watawit, tural behavior and their practical understanding of
the traditional ruling class, a mixture of Arab mer- the world (González-Ruibal, 2006b, pp. 392–397).
chants and local women. However, the indigenous As in other vernacular African traditions (Preston
element has always had an overwhelming weight Blier, 1987), the Bertha house is anthropomorphic:
among the Bertha and an egalitarian ethos tended to the roof (alu) is the head of the house; the space
curtail the most visible manifestations of power. The indoors, the stomach (iyu); the entrance, the mouth
order of domestic space among the Bertha has little (ndu); the poles flanking the entrance, the eyes (are,
to do with the anxieties of the Swahili. However, which also means “face”); the rest of the poles are the
the Bertha house is also a structuring structure and feet (khu); and the rear part of the house, the back
a faithful representation of the cosmos. (gundi). This perception of the house as a human
The house itself is much simpler, from an body has far-reaching consequences, because it
architectural point of view, than the Swahili man- means that the regionalization of the body (Giddens,
sions. Although there are three different types of 1984, p. 124) is transferred to the domestic space,
houses (González-Ruibal, 2006b, pp. 383–384), with all its implicit meanings and connotations. Like
they all share some features, such as a circular lay- the human body, the house is divided into two main
out, bamboo walls, and thatched roofs. Externally, parts: the front and the back (Fig. 7.8).
they are very recognizable, even from afar, because The front is where all human communication
of their particular rooftop (shimbir), crowned and relations take place: it is the area of the sight
with four long and thin poles. The rooftop and (are, eyes) and the speech (ndu means both mouth
the long stick planted near the house to protect and language in Bertha). It is also the place of knowl-
it against the evil spirits of thunder are symbols edge (are p’adiya, lit. “eye strong,” means “wise”). In
of the Bertha identity. They have an “emblemic” front of the house, men gather to drink coffee early
use—that is “they transmit a clear message to a in the morning, women chat and care for the small
define target population about conscious affil- children, men weave baskets and bamboo mats,
iation or identity” (Wiessner, 1983, p. 257). and women make pottery. Rituals and ceremonies
However, the most important material elements also occur in the frontal space: Islamic praying,

Shul-gundi Handung-are
(back) (face)

Grinding
stones
Cooking
Pots

Shetab
(storing platform)
Katiya
ang-le-kharang
(hearth for sauce Anqareb Are Ndu
Entrance Mu-iyu (eyes) (mouth)
and coffee) (bed) (stomach)
ang-le-tuk’s
(hearth for Mu-iyu
porridge) (stomach)

Anqareb
(bed)

Hu
(feet)

Figure 7.8 The Bertha house: a structuring structure. (Adapted with permission from González-Ruibal, 2006b.)

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 151
rainmaking activities, traditional sacrifices, wedding visionaries—instinctively know that. It is not by
rites, beer drinking in working parties, and so forth. chance that social engineering has always aimed at
The space is kept clean by women, who sweep the changing architecture for changing people’s minds.
floor at least twice a day. The rear of the house, on This was the case with Soviet buildings: Buchli
the contrary, is a space devoid of activities, people, (1999) studied the evolution of the Narkomfin
and artifacts. It is the place of death and dirt, where building in Moscow, an attempt at achieving the
rubbish is thrown away, where small children were communalization of daily life by eliminating petit
traditionally buried, menstruating women urinate, bourgeois domesticity. Nonetheless, other attempts
and rituals related to the exorcism of evil spirits take at transforming ways of thinking and behaving
place. The back of the house is never swept. The through space can be counter-hegemonic. That was
same front–back organization is replicated indoors, the case with the architecture of the Pueblo Indians
with clean, social activities taking place in the fron- after the 1680 revolt and the utopian communities
tal area (such as sleeping, entertaining guests, and of the first half of the nineteenth century in New
making coffee) and dirty ones in the rear area (such England, studied by Preucel (2006). After the Pueblo
as brewing beer and cooking fermented food). revolt, the Cochiti leaders of the rebellion founded
For the Bertha, then, as for the Swahili, order- villages endowed with a double plaza that encoded
ing the domestic space is not an abstract activity the cosmological and social principles of the Cochiti
that can be verbalized and rationalized in an explicit worldview, so as to fix and make effective in prac-
way. It basically works in practice. Practical logic tice the revitalization discourse, which was critical
enables the organization of “all thoughts, percep- with the exploitative system of the Spanish empire.
tions and actions by means of a few generative prin- Similarly, the followers of Transcendentalism who
ciples, which are closely interrelated and constitute founded utopian communities relied heavily on
a practically integrated whole” (Bourdieu, 1990, architecture to create a new social order—and a new
p. 86). It has often been said that the organization individual—that stood against incipient industrial
of space among egalitarian, small-scale societies is capitalism and its dehumanizing practices. Culture,
much more flexible and less scripted than among according to Shweder and Miller (1993, p. 512)
hierarchical ones. Yet even egalitarian societies live is “that subset of possible or available meanings,
in a material world that precludes certain actions in which by virtue of enculturation . . . has so given
certain spaces and favors others. Under the appar- shape to the psychological processes of individuals
ent chaos and disorder of the Bertha house lays a in a society that those meanings have become, for
powerful order that is no less strict—even if it has those individuals, indistinguishable from experience
fewer rules—than the one enforced by the Swahili itself.” The built space, in any society, goes a long
house. A Bertha woman would never, ever, make way in achieving that seamless conflation of mean-
pots behind her house. The relation between back ing and lived experience.
space, dirt and death is heavily imprinted in her
mind from her earlier childhood, even if she cannot Memory and Material Culture
render those relations explicit in speech. With the rise of cognitive archeology in the 1980s
Both the Swahili and the Bertha house, then, emerged the interest for material culture as a form
allow knowing the order of the world for those who of memory container. Renfrew (1998), one of the
inhabit them. Furthermore, both houses are con- main proponents of the paradigm, argued that the
cerned with purity and pollution. The difference is appearance of the first agrarian societies (ca. 9500
that the logic of the Swahili house—as a hierarchical BC in the Near East) coincided with a new cogni-
society—is basically concerned with contamination tive phase in the development of the human mind,
caused by the violation of the socio-political order characterized by external symbolic storage employ-
(masters and slaves, locals and foreigners), whereas ing material culture. This phase (the Neolithic in
the central theme in the Bertha house—as an egali- archeological terms) would lie between two periods
tarian community—is pollution brought about by previously described by Donald (1991): the linguis-
disturbances in the cosmological order (life and tic and mythic culture of the early Homo sapiens and
dead, good and evil, society and the Other). the theoretic culture of literate societies. The mate-
In sum, built space is crucial in the psychologi- rials put to mnemonic uses varied with the devel-
cal development of human beings within any par- opment of agrarian societies. Probably, the earliest
ticular culture. People—and especially political containers of memory were houses, especially in

152 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


the Near East (Hodder & Cessford, 2004) and the codified in order to store specific memories. This is
Balkans (Borič, 2003). In Western Europe, tombs related to the growing interest in the social sciences
became the focus of collective memory (Edmonds, on collective memory. It is now widely accepted
1999), later to be replaced by artifacts that were ritu- that memory is not something exclusively indi-
ally deposited in public ceremonies (Bradley, 1990). vidual but socially shared (Connerton, 1989), as
In places like Mesoamerica and North America, Halbwachs (1994 [1925]) proposed more than 80
cultic spaces materialized collective remembrance years ago. In fact, the archeological record preserves
among early farmers and complex hunter-gather- more instances of social remembrance, from monu-
ers (e.g., Shady Solís et al., 2000; Pauketat & Alt, ments to fossilized daily routines, than personal (or
2003). More generally, the diversification of mate- group) mnemonic devices. This turning away from
rial culture with the Neolithic and the appearance the notion of symbolic storage is also related to a
of new supports to convey messages (such as pot- wider awareness of the peculiar mnemonic nature
tery, textiles, and architecture) and the generaliza- of things, as opposed to texts. Things are ontologi-
tion of old ones (sculpture and painting) certainly cally closer to what Connerton (1989, pp. 72–73)
favored the storage of memory. The semiotic world calls incorporating practices than to inscribing
of the first agriculturalists, then, was very different ones. Inscribing practices are devices for storing and
from that of the hunter-gatherers, with its limited retrieving information (books, computers, sound
amount of human-made symbolic containers. Some tapes). Incorporating practices imply the inten-
of the mnemonic devices developed by early agrar- tional or unintentional transmission of information
ian and sedentary societies developed through time primordially through bodily posture, which is, in
to such an extent so as to evolve into writing; this turn, tightly interwoven with technology and arti-
is the case of the Mesopotamian tablets of the late facts (Mauss, 1973).
fourth millennium BC (Rodríguez Mayorgas, 2010, Andrew Clark (2008, p. 14) comments that
pp. 97–103). Other mnemonic devices were very certain Alzheimer’s sufferers maintain an unex-
complex but did not become proper writing sys- pected high level of normal, independent func-
tems, such as the Inca knotted strings (Cole, 1998, tioning. Their success is explained by the use
p. 168; Rodríguez Mayorgas, 2010, pp. 104–107). they make of diverse external aids such as labels,
memory books, diaries, and leaving important
Beyond External Storage objects in open view. This is, for Clark, just an
The idea of material culture as a form of mne- extreme example of the normal use of external
monic external storage has been under attack from aids (computers, compasses, maps). The author,
different quarters, including some cognitive arche- however, like other psychologists and cognitive
ologists. Malafouris, for example, considers the scientists (Beach, 1993; Klumb, 2001), focuses on
computational model of cognition (based on a pro- explicit and conscious cognitive uses of material
cess of encoding–storage–retrieval) does not ade- culture, those that are closer to the idea of things
quately explain the mnemonic role of objects (also as external symbolic storage. Yet we are not capa-
Thomas [1998], from an interpretive perspective). ble of orienting ourselves just when we use a map,
Artifacts, writes Malafouris (2004, p. 57), “remind read a history book, or write a laundry list. We
you, sometimes even force you to remember, with- live in a material environment that is saturated of
out including the content of what precisely is to be social meanings and memory traces. Even if we do
remembered,” unlike texts or information contained not want to remember, artifacts force us. This is
in a hard disk. The most serious objection to the the- because, as Boesch has noted:
ory of external symbolic storage is that it does not
truly consider a dialogical self. It envisions culture our objectual surroundings establish and
(and cognition) as something that takes places in the environment of meanings, often delicate and
head and that is projected into a passive world (see intimate, expressing itself even in unreflected
above Material Culture, Materiality, Cognition). banalities . . . the lavender sachet in the lingerie
Recently, archeologists have been more interested drawer, symbolising, without us realising it, the
in how places and things are suffused with memory blending of opposing principles, such as the enclosed
and the effect that this has on people (Van Dyke space and the open air, the civilised and the natural,
& Alcock, 2003; Jones, 2007) rather than in the the daily and the unusual.
way particular objects or monuments are explicitly (1991, p. 331, my emphasis)

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 153
This is why we throw away our ex-lover’s possessions, Cessford (2004, p. 31) have argued that daily prac-
despite not being mnemonic aids proper and never tice and memory were inseparable in Çatalhöyük,
intended to be (in the way a grocery list or a knot because social regulations were not simply imposed
in the handkerchief are). The lover’s possessions are but constructed through habituation practices,
indexes that remind us of his or her presence, as the which, in a nonliterate society, play the same role
lavender sachet brings out memories of nature and as writing in the construction of social memory.
openness. The things Clark mentions in his example Connerton (1989) has explored this duality through
are (with the exception of the objects put in a visi- the concepts of inscribing and incorporating prac-
ble place) symbols; but material culture, as we have tices. The second are particularly characteristic of
already seen, works more often as an index (Jones, nonliterate peoples. Although Connerton referred
2007, pp. 22–26). There lies the power of things: basically to bodily gestures and performances, we
They keep reminding us of other things, people, have to include here the use and manipulation of
places, and events to which they are associated, artifacts as well as the artifacts (including archi-
whether we want to or not. If we scale up and go tecture) that shape bodily practices. The fact that
from personal cases to society at large, we can get houses follow exactly the same plan for hundreds
an idea of the important role that materiality plays of years proves their fundamental role in preserv-
in shaping collective remembrance, which is in turn ing collective memory. It also reveals the prospective
crucial for shaping our present (and future) behav- qualities of material culture, as technical decisions
ior. This mnemonic and prospective power of things taken at a certain point in time were still having
is well-exemplified in the following examples. As in an effect on the regulation of society and commu-
previous sections, I will resort to both ancient and nity life 2,000 years later. Sometimes even specific
modern cultures. iconic decorations (such as depictions of bulls) were
repeated through several phases spanning hundreds
Keeping History Cold: Materiality and of years (Hodder & Cessford, 2004, p. 35), a phe-
Memory in Prehistoric Societies nomenon that guarantees the long-term transmis-
Çatalhöyük, in modern Turkey, is one of the sion of mythological knowledge. Furthermore, in
most important early agrarian villages studied by Çatalhöyük there are some houses whose mnemonic
archeologists (Hodder, 2006). In its main phase of role seems to be more prominent than in others:
occupation, around the seventh millennium BC, it They have long sequences of occupation, elaborate
could have hosted up to 8,000 individuals. The vil- decorations, and many burials. They were formerly
lage had many mud huts, tightly packed together, interpreted as shrines and today as houses of power-
with no streets or plazas; people entered their houses ful lineages (Hodder, 2006). At any rate, they epito-
from the roof. According to Hodder and Cessford, mize the need for preserving memory that is present
in Çatalhöyük, in every other house and reveal the link that existed
between memory and power.
instead of social rules being imposed by centralized
The logic of Çatalhöyük is present in other
authorities manipulating public rituals . . . the
Neolithic communities in Europe and the Near
reproduction of dominant groups (elders or lineage
East. A compelling example is that of the so-called
heads) was intimately tied to the construction of
“Linear Pottery Culture” (LPC), which represents
bodily routines that were repeated in daily house
the expansion of early farmers from Hungary to
practices over days, months, years, decades, centuries,
eastern France between 5500 BC and 5000 BC.
and even millennia.
Despite its vast territory, the LPC is extremely
(2004, p. 22)
homogeneous in house form, burial practices,
One of these practices was the replastering of walls, and pottery decoration. Jones (2007, pp. 93–105)
which was carried out annually and for up to a hun- considers that this homogeneity is related to spe-
dred years before the house was completely rebuilt cific memory practices, which are again clear in
(carefully following the old plan). Other repetitive the domestic sphere. The long rectangular houses
activities, such as sweeping and plastering certain had their doorways oriented toward the previ-
floors or burying people under them, were impor- ous area of settlement (the LPC people expanded
tant in the processes of enculturation through from Hungary toward France), as if remembering
practice but also in perpetuating in time meaning- their origins, and they preserved the original layout
ful, ancestral ways of doing things. Hodder and for centuries—“a kind of mythological archetype”

154 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


(Jones, 2007, p. 103). These material practices, in space and order, people are often instinctively aware
Jones’ opinion, provided a way of coping with new of the agency of material culture in shaping social
environments. Cultural memory enabled people to life. They also know that things transmit memory
move forward while remaining attached to the past and that with memory comes certain moral values
(Jones, 2007, p. 100). I would argue that the mem- and cultural predispositions—hence, the widespread
ory practices of Çatalhöyük and the LPC are best phenomenon of damnatio memoriae since Antiquity.
understood as mechanisms to “keep history cold.” The idea is to cut short forever not just a particular
Assmann (2001, p. 35) suggests that in all societies, remembrance but also the possibilities of repetition,
there are devices whose purpose is to maintain the because it is repetition (Assmann’s “time of regen-
“cyclical time of regeneration.” In egalitarian, non- eration”) that makes the past always present. Thus,
literate communities, mechanisms of regeneration the destruction of malanggan, potlatch commodi-
prevail, in opposition to what Assman calls the “loci ties or bronze axes was not actually aimed at putting
of history,” which account for events and change. an end to something (those particular things) but to
The latter are to be found in some state societies, regenerate something else (society or the cosmos).
where transformation is perceived as positive— It is the cycle of production and destruction that
especially in modernity after the fifteenth century. maintains memory in those contexts. The problem
is when destruction itself becomes an end—that
Destruction As Memory Practice is, when the central point is to obliterate a cultural
Material memory is not necessarily based on world and start a new one ex nihilo. The annihi-
constructive processes. Destruction can be a posi- lating thrust implies a radical change in the notion
tive way of maintaining memories (Rowlands, of temporality, from a cyclical time to a linear one,
1993), provided that it takes place in a dramatic, with millennial or teleological connotations. It is
ritualized setting and is regularly repeated. A good not by chance that revolutionary programs based
example is the destruction by fire of Neolithic mud on destruction often imply the emergence of linear
houses in the Balkans (Stevanovic 1997). Every few notions of time (or even the very notion of time):
years, houses were destroyed and then built anew that is the case with Christianity (Cullmann, 1964,
following the previous layout, in what can be con- pp. 51–60) and modernity. Significantly, the French
sidered an act of cyclical regeneration. Another case Revolution and Fascist Italy simultaneously inaugu-
of social remembrance through destruction is the rated new calendars and tried to raze previous cul-
malanggan. The people of New Ireland make very tural landscapes (Zerubavel, 1977; Bosworth, 2005,
elaborate funerary sculptures (called malanggan) that p. 201). The purpose of destruction is to obliter-
take months to be finished and require great skills. ate the old material civilization and the old ways of
The ritual itself lasts a few hours, and after that, the thinking embedded in it.
wooden sculptures are left at the mercy of the wind This is exactly what is happening in the more tra-
and rain in ritual areas (Küchler, 2002). Memory ditional parts of Spain under the impact of moder-
is thus deposited in the technical cycle as a whole, nity. In Galicia, in particular, the destruction of the
which includes the creation of the statue and use traditional material environment has acquired enor-
but also its abandonment and eventual disappear- mous proportions (González-Ruibal, 2005). This
ance. Rowlands (1993, p. 149) has described other results from the traumatic character of the process
contexts in which the destruction of material culture of modernization in the region: hundreds of thou-
serves to remember, such as the deposits of bronze sands of peasants were forced to emigrate to other
objects that were ritually buried in Europe during European countries and the Americas in search
the Late Bronze Age (1200–800 BC) or the famous of jobs. During their stay abroad, Galicians were
potlatch of the Kwakiutl Indians of the British exposed to a radically different material culture in
Columbia, in which large amounts of commodities places like New York and Buenos Aires. In a strange
were not only given away by wealthy patrons but and often hostile social environment, their remem-
also burnt and destroyed. The ceremonies in which brance of their birthplace was heavily tinged with
artifacts are destroyed, buried, or abandoned are, in nostalgia and affection; a highly idealized ancestral
all cases mentioned, dramatic enough to be deeply homeland emerged from their daydreaming.
impressed into collective memory. This ideal image suffered a hard reality check
However, destruction can also be an effective when they returned to Galicia from the late 1970s
way of erasing memory. As we saw in the section of onward. The idealization process was reversed on

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 155
arrival and the birthplace began to be character- The new material culture exemplifies the change
ized in negative terms, as a backward, oppressive from a culture where a relational self prevailed and
locale—the source of all moral and material miser- where memory was communally built and transmit-
ies that forced people to emigrate. Yet it was not ted within the community to a society of indepen-
enough with destroying in the mind the memory dent selves, where individual memories—successful
of the cozy traditional home. The entire cultural biographies—try to impose themselves in the cul-
landscape had to be shattered and replaced by a new tural landscape. Mechanisms to shape and regulate
one, free of the social and mental constrictions that the relational self and preserve memory (traditional
characterized the premodern environment. Using clothes, agricultural implements for collective work,
Sigmund Freud’s terminology, we can say that what vernacular houses) were replaced by monuments
the Galicians suffered was not a process of mourn- to the individual self, material memories of per-
ing caused by the disappearance of something that sonal triumphs (expensive cars, luxurious modern-
had been loved, but melancholia, marked by ambiv- ist houses). Nevertheless, the relationship with the
alence toward the object (loved and hated at the past, as in every melancholic process, is ambivalent.
same time): Traditional artifacts are often not destroyed but just
left to decay. Something of the old love prevails and
Just as mourning impels the ego to renounce the
haunts the former peasants.
object by declaring its death . . . each individual
The Galician case is only an extreme example
battle of ambivalence loosens the fixation of the
of the forms of oblivion that are embedded in late
libido upon the object by devaluing, disparaging
modern materiality. For Connerton (2009), late
and, so to speak, even killing it.
modernity is characterized by a particular regime of
(Freud, 2006, p. 324)
forgetting that is enforced in everyday life through
Devaluing and even killing the object that sum- the built environment. The scale of human settle-
moned traumatic memories was what the Galicians ment, the production of speed, and the destruction
did. They engaged in a rage of destruction of the of the urban fabric generate a particular “cultural
old material world: from plows to houses (Fig. 7.9). amnesia” (Connerton 2009, p. 99). Whereas medi-
eval and early modern cities used to have conspic-
uous landmarks that created an effect of spatial
cohesion and places of gathering that fostered
social cohesion, new cities are formless, segregated
spaces and, therefore, unmemorable and unsocial.
Besides, the continuous refashioning of the built
environment prevents any possible social recollec-
tion of shared places. We might say that supermod-
ern cities fail to transmit memory, but we may as
well argue that they succeed in creating forgetful-
ness: Connerton (2009, p. 125) makes the point
that the production of oblivion is intrinsic of the
political economy of late capitalism. Cultural
amnesia is not produced by accident but by a
necessity of the system—so that we forget where
things come from (González-Ruibal & Hernando,
2010). The question that emerges from the study
of material memory practices in late modernity is:
How does living in a post-mnemonic culture affect
human cognition?

Conclusions and Future Directions


Archeology works with more cultural variation
than any other social science, because archeologi-
Figure 7.9 A traumatic breakage with a relational identity: cal methods can be used to understand all prehis-
forgetting the past in a Galician village. toric, historic, and contemporary societies from

156 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


the beginning of humankind to the present. The other types of cultural objects are involved in both
possibilities for cultural comparison are almost infi- social and spatial orientation and are, therefore,
nite, and differences often emerge when contrasting worth of study by psychologists. In fact, other
opposite contexts. However, archeologists agree that categories of cultural objects, such as houses or
working with the past is just one of the defining cars, have recently been taken into account by
characteristics of their discipline. The other, and per- cultural psychologists (Valsiner, 2008, p. 23). Their
haps more important, is its focus on materiality. In point in common is that they are artifacts explicitly
this chapter, I have tried to show the great relevance inscribed with meaning. The focus is in people
that material culture has in shaping our percep- openly making statements with objects. Although
tions and experiences of the world. Material things those studies are certainly an important and
are a crucial component of the “extended mind” exciting line of research, it would be interesting
(Clark & Chalmers, 1998), and this fact is enjoying to look at other kinds of artifacts that are less
increasing recognition by psychologists and cogni- obviously loaded with meaning. This implies a
tive scientists. As we have seen, Cole (1998, p. 144) turn from explicit to implicit meanings, from the
argues that things are the quintessential constituents symbolic and iconic to the indexical. To make
of culture because of their twofold character, simul- better sense of the indexical, of unconscious traces
taneously material and ideal. Here, I have argued and practical behavior, psychologists have to span
that a third dimension of things has to be taken into their range of research and include things that do
account to understand their relevance in shaping the not seem too relevant or meaningful at first sight,
social mind: temporality. Things from the past have things that are overlooked or taken for granted by
a continuing effect in the future. Our experiences human actors. Archeologists know well that every
are framed by an inherited material environment, single object counts, no matter how humble.
sometimes hundreds or even thousands of years old. 2. Systems of artifacts involved in
From this point of view, archeology is doubly perti- psychological processes. Things cannot be
nent, because—unlike other disciplines engaged in understood in isolation or out of context:
the study of things—it deals both with materiality archeologists and anthropologists of technology
and with time. For cultural psychologists and arche- know that we have to explore entire material
ologists, it should not be difficult to find a common inventories and their structural relations
ground. After all, they are interested in similar phe- (Baudrillard, 1968; Lemonnier, 1992;
nomena as mediated by culture. The development González-Ruibal, 2006a). As signs are only
and constitution of the self in relation to society, the meaningful in relation to other signs, artifacts
social shaping of emotions, the way the built envi- are only meaningful in relation to other artifacts
ronment affects human experience, and the material (including the human body). Thus, cars have to
frame of memory practices are the four themes that be explored in relation to urban space and houses
I have chosen to explore in this chapter because of but also in relation to late modern technologies
their meaningful and manifold ramifications. of the self, such as web-blogs and cloth, and
Cultural psychology could benefit from study- cloth, in turn, has to be understood as related to
ing things with an archeological sensibility—that furniture and cell phones. Real things have also
is, with an understanding of the agency of mate- to be confronted with virtual things and with the
rial culture, its inseparability from human beings, products of the cultural and moral imagination.
and its temporality. Some new lines of research for How do artifacts that are explicitly encoded with
an archeologically inspired cultural psychology that meaning and artifacts that work in practice relate
takes things seriously could be the following: to each other? How do they interact to frame
daily experience?
1. The interactions between human 3. The temporality of things. People are born
psychological processes and material culture to a material milieu that they have not created but
beyond cognitive technologies and explicit that deeply affects their being. The psychological
symbolical objects. Psychologists interested in development of individuals takes place in a
material culture have often focused on explicit cultural landscape saturated of meaningful
cognitive or mnemonic technologies and memory cues, some of them extremely old, some
artifacts—maps, computers, GPS, compasses, and very recent. Does the human mind develop
so forth. Here, I have tried to show that many differently in heavily material and conservative

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 157
historical environments and in landscapes where Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: a social critique of the judg-
memory is swept away every generation or not ment of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Translated by R. Nice.
materialized in the first place? How do different Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Stanford, CA: Stanford
memory practices and temporalities of things University Press. Translated by R. Nice.
affect the way people perceive themselves, society Bradley, R. (1989). Death and entrances: a contextual analysis of
and the world? Thus, whereas Europeans live megalithic art. Current Anthropology 30(1), 68–75.
in cultural landscapes that have grown through Bradly, R. (1990). The passage of arms: an archaeological analy-
sis of prehistoric hoards and votive deposits. Cambridge, UK:
accretion of diverse material pasts, the materiality Cambridge University Press.
of which is considered important for the Brandão, J. A. & Nassaney, M. S. (2008). Suffering for Jesus:
present (at least since early modern times), the Penitential practices at Fort St. Joseph (Niles, Michigan)
Buddhist tradition tends to regenerate the past by during the French Regime. Catholic Historical Review 94(3),
destroying or altering its materiality, which is not 476–499.
Brück, J. (2005). Experiencing the past? The development
valued, and by rebuilding it anew (Byrne, 1995). of a phenomenological archaeology in British prehistory.
Also, how do the different layers of time have an Archaeological Dialogues 12(1), 45–72.
effect on people? The issue of time is inextricable Buchli, V. (1999). An archaeology of socialism. Oxford, UK: Berg.
from memory: What is the role of material culture Burke, P. (1995). The Renaissance, individualism, and the por-
in creating and reconfiguring habit, cognitive, trait. History of European Ideas 21(3), 393–400.
Butler, J. (1993). Bodies that matter. On the discursive limits of
and personal memory (Connerton, 2009, pp. “sex”. New York: Routledge.
139–141)? What is the relation between open Byrne, D. (1995). Buddhist stupa and Thai social practice. World
commemorative practices and unconscious Archaeology 27(2), 266–281.
mnemonic traces? Calatrava, J. A. (1991). El debate sobre la ubicación de los
cementerios en la España de las Luces: la contribución de
Benito Bails. Espacio, Tiempo y Forma, Serie VII, Historia
References del Arte, 4, 349–366.
Ames, K. L. (1984). Material culture as nonverbal communi- Callon, M. (1991). Society in the making: the study of technol-
cation: A historical case study. In E. Mayo (ed.): American ogy as a tool for social analysis. In J. Law (ed.): A Sociology
Material Culture. The Shape of Things around Us. (pp. 25–47). of monsters: essays on power, technology, and domination.
Bowling Green, OH: Bowling Green State University (pp. 83–103). London; New York: Routledge.
Popular Press. Cannon, A. (1994). The historical dimension in mortuary
Ariès, P. (1987). El niño y la vida familiar en el Antiguo Régimen. expressions of status and sentiment. Current Anthropology
Madrid: Taurus. 30(4), 437–458.
Assmann, J. 2001. The hot and the cold in history. In Measuring Casella, E. C. (2007). The archaeology of institutional confinement.
historical heat. Event, performance and impact in China and Gainesville, FL: University Press of Florida.
the West. Symposium in honour of L. Rudolf G. Wagner Casella, E. C. & Fowler, C. (2005). The archaeology of plural and
on his 60th birthday (pp. 29–40). Heidelberg November changing identities. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum.
3rd–4th 2001. Clark, A. & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis
Baudrillard, J. (1968). Le système des objets. Paris: Gallimard. 58(1), 7–19.
Beach, K. (1993). Becoming a bartender: The role of external Clark, A. (2008). Where brain, body and world collide. In
memory cues in a work-directed educational activity. Applied C. Knappet and L. Malafouris (eds.): Material agency.
Cognitive Psychology 7(3), 191–204. (pp. 1–18). New York: Springer.
Bille, M. & Sørensen, T. F. (2007). The anthropology of lumi- Cole, M. (1998). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline.
nosity. Journal of Material Culture 12(3), 263–284. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bachelard, G. (1964). La poétique de l’espace. Paris: Presses Cole, M. & Engeström, Y. (1997). A culture-historical approach
Universitaires de la France. to distributed cognition. In G. Salomon (ed.): Distributed cog-
Boesch, E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychology. nitions. Psychological and educational considerations. (pp. 1–46).
Berlin: Springer. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press,.
Boesch, E. (1993). The sound of the violin. Schweizerische Coman, A., Brown, A. D., Koppel, J. & Hirst, W. (2009).
Zeitschrift für Pschycologie 52(2), 70–81. Collective memory from a psychological perspective. Inter-
Boltanski, L. (1990). L’amour et la justice comme compétences. national Journal of Culture, Politics and Society 22(2),
Trois essais de sociologie de l’action. Paris: Métailié. 125–141.
Borič, D. (2003). “Deep time” metaphor. Mnemonic and apo- Conklin. B. (1995). “Thus Are Our Bodies, Thus Was Our
tropaic practices at Lepenski Vir. Journal of Social Archaeology Custom”: Mortuary Cannibalism in an Amazonian Society.
3(1), 46–74. American Ethnologist 22(1), 75–101.
Bosworth, R. J. B., (2005). Mussolini’s Italy: life under dictator- Connerton, P. (1989). How societies remember. Cambridge, UK:
ship. London: Allen Lane. Cambridge University Press.
Boulestin, B., Zeeb-Lanz, A., Jeunesse, C., Haack, F., Arbogast, Connerton, P. (2009). How modernity forgets. Cambridge, UK:
R-M., & Denaire, A. (2009). Mass cannibalism in the Cambridge University Press.
Linear Pottery Culture at Herxheim (Palatinate, Germany). Cook, I. A., Pajot, S. K., & Leuchter, A. F. (2008). Ancient
Antiquity 83(322), 968–982. Architectural Acoustic Resonance Patterns and Regional

158 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


Brain Activity. Time and Mind: The Journal of Archaeology, a seminar with Michel Foucault. (pp. 16–49). Amherst:
Consciousness and Culture 1(1), 95–104. University of Massachusetts Press.
Criado, F. (2001). Problems, functions and conditions of Foucault, M. (1975). Surveiller et punir. Naissance de la prison.
archaeological knowledge. Journal of Social Archaeology 1(1), Paris: Gallimard.
126–146. Fowler, C. (2001). Personhood and Social Relations in the
Criado, F. & Villoch Vázquez, V. (2000). Monumentalising British Neolithic with a Study from the Isle of Man. Journal
landscape. From present perception to the past meaning of Material Culture 6(2), 137–163.
of Galician megalithism (north-west Iberian peninsula), Fowler, C. (2004). The archaeology of personhood. An anthropo-
European Journal of Archaeology 3, 188–216. logical approach. London; New York: Routledge.
Crown, P. (2001). Learning to Make Pottery in the Prehispanic Freud, S. (2006). Mourning and melancholia. In A. Phillips
American Southwest. Journal of Anthropological Research 57(4), (ed.): The Penguin Freud Reader. (pp. 310–326). London:
451–469. Penguin.
Cullmann, O. (1964). Christ and time. The primitive Christian Gaitán, F. (2005). With a hint of Paris in the mouth: Fetishized
conception of time and history. Louisville, KY: Westminster Toothbrushes or the Sensuous Experience of Modernity in
John Knox. Late 19th Century Bogotá. In L. Meskell (ed.): Archaeologies
Cummings, V. (2002). Experiencing texture and transformation of materiality. (pp. 71–95). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
in the British Neolithic. Oxford Journal of Archaeology 21(3), Gell, A. (1998). Art and agency: an anthropological theory. Oxford,
249–261. UK: Oxford University Press.
Deetz, J. (1996). In small things forgotten: an archaeology of early González-Ruibal, A. (2005). The need of a decaying past. An
American life. New York: Anchor. archaeology of oblivion in contemporary Galicia (NW
De la Torre, I. (2004). Omo revisited: evaluating the techno- Spain). Home Cultures 2(2), 129–152.
logical skills of Pliocene hominids. Current Anthropology 45, González-Ruibal, A. (2006a). The past is tomorrow. Towards
439–467. an archaeology of the vanishing present. Norwegian
Descola, P. (2005). Par-delà nature et culture. Paris: Gallimard. Archaeological Review 39(2), 110–125.
Devlet, E. (2001). Rock art and the material cul- González-Ruibal, A. (2006b). Order in a disordered world. The
ture of Siberian and central Asian shamanism. Bertha house (Western Ethiopia). Anthropos 101(2), 379–402.
In N. S. Price (ed.): The archaeology of shamanism. (pp. González-Ruibal, A. (2008). Time to destroy. An archaeology of
43–55). London; New York: Routledge. supermodernity. Current Anthropology 49(2), 247–279.
Díaz-Andreu, M., Lucy, S., Babič, S., & Edwards, D. N. (2005). González-Ruibal, A., Ayán, X., Falquina, A. & Sahle, Y. (2009).
The archaeology of identity. Approaches to gender, age, status, Arqueología de los pueblos nilóticos: una prospección arque-
ethnicity and religion. London, New York: Routledge. ológica y etnoarqueológica de la región de Gambela (Etiopía
Dobres, M. A. (2000). Technology and social agency. Oxford: occidental). Informes y Trabajos 3, 53–62.
Blackwell. González-Ruibal, A. & Hernando, A. (2010). Genealogies of
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the human mind: Three stages in the destruction. An Archaeology of the contemporary past in the
evolution of culture and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Amazon forest. Archaeologies 6(2).
University Press. Goodwin, L. B. R. (ed.) (1999). An Archaeology of Manners. The
Donald, M. (1998). Material culture and cognition: conclud- Polite World of the Merchant Elite of Colonial Massachusetts.
ing thoughts. In C. Renfrew and C. Scarre (eds.): Cognition New York: Springer.
and Material Culture: the Archaeology of Symbolic Storage. Gosden, C. (2005). What do objects want? Journal of
(pp. 181–187). McDonald Institute Monographs. Cambridge: Archaeological Method and Theory 12(3), 193–211.
McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research. Halbwachs, M. (1994 [1925]). Les cadres sociaux de la mémoire.
Donley-Reid, L. (1982). House power: Swahili space and sym- Paris: Albin Michel.
bolic markers. In I. Hodder (ed.): Symbolic and structural Hall, M. (2000). Archaeology and the modern world. Colonial
archaeology. (pp. 63–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University transcripts in South Africa and the Chesapeake. London; New
Press. York: Routledge.
Dovey, K. (1999). Framing places: Mediating power in built form. Haraway, D. (1991). Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention
London, New York: Routledge. of Nature. New York: Routledge.
Dronfield, J. (1995a). Migraine, light and hallucinogens: the Heidegger, M. (2002 [1960]). The origin of the work of art.
neurocognitive basis of Irish megalithic art. Oxford Journal of In Off the beaten track. (pp. 1–56). Cambridge: Cambridge
Archaeology 14(3), 261–275. University Press. Edited and translated by Julian Young
Dronfield, J. (1995b). Subjective vision and the source of Irish and Kenneth Haynes.
megalithic art. Antiquity 69(264), 539–549. Heine, S. J. (2010). Cultural psychology. In S. T. Fiske,
Dror, I. E. & Harnad, S. (eds.) (2008). Cognition distributed. D. T. Gilbert & G. Lindzey (eds.): Handbook of social psychol-
How cognitive technology extends our minds. Amsterdam; ogy. New York: Willey.
Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins. Henare, A., Holbraad, M. & Wastell, S. (eds.): (2007). Thinking
Edmonds, M. (1999). Ancestral geographies of the Neolithic: through things: theorising artefacts ethnographically. London;
Landscapes, monuments and memory. London; New York: New York: Routledge,.
Routledge. Hernando, A. (2002). Arqueología de la identidad. Madrid:
Escalona, S. K. (1982). Growing up with the threat of nuclear Akal.
war: some indirect effects on personality development. Hernando, A. (2008). Género y sexo. Mujeres, identidad y mod-
American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 52(4), 600–607. ernidad. Claves de Razón Práctica 188, 65–70.
Foucault, M. (1988). Technologies of the self. In L. H. Martin, Hetzler, F. M. (1988). Causality: ruin time and ruins. Leonardo
H. Gutman & P. Hutton, (eds.). Technologies of the self: 21(1), 51–55.

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 159
Hodder, I. (ed.) (1982). Symbolic and structural archaeology. Latour, B. (2000). The Berlin key or How to Do Words with Things.
Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. In P. Graves-Brown (ed.): Matter, Materiality and Modern
Hodder, I. (1986). Reading the past: current approaches to inter- Culture. (pp. 10–21). London; New York: Routledge,.
pretation in archaeology. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge Law, J. (ed.) (1991). A Sociology of monsters: essays on power, tech-
University Press. nology, and domination. London; New York: Routledge.
Hodder, I. (1994). The interpretation of documents and material Lemonnier, P. (1992). Elements for an anthropology of technol-
culture. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (eds.): Collecting ogy. Ann Arbor, MI: Museum of Anthropology, University
and interpreting qualitative materials. (pp. 393–402). of Michigan.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Leone, M. P. (1984). Interpreting ideology in historical archaeol-
Hodder, I. (2006). The leopard’s tale: revealing the mysteries of ogy: using the rules of perspective in the William Paca Garden
Çatalhöyük. New York: Thames & Hudson. in Annapolis, Maryland. In D. Miller & C. Tilley (eds.):
Hodder, I. & Cessford, C. (2004). Daily Practice and Social Ideology, Power and Prehistory. (pp. 25–35). Cambridge:
Memory at Çatalhöyük. American Antiquity 69(1), 17–40. Cambridge University Press.
Horton, M. & Middleton, J. (2000). The Swahili. The social land- Levin, D. M. (1993). Modernity and the hegemony of vision.
scape of a mercantile society. Oxford; Malden, MA: Blackwell. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: The Linke, U. (2006). Contact zones: Rethinking the sensual life of
MIT Press. the state. Anthropological Theory 6, 205–225.
Ingold, T. (2000). The perception of the environment. Essays on live- LiPuma. E. (1998). Modernity and forms of personhood in
lihood, dwelling, and skill. London; New York: Routledge. Melanesia. In M. Lambek and A. Strathern (eds.): Bodies and
Ingold, T. (2009). The textility of making. Cambridge Journal of persons. Comparative perspectives from Africa and Melanesia.
Economics 2009: 1–12. (pp. 53–79). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
James, W. (1988). The listening ebony. Moral knowledge, religion, Llobera, M. (2003). Extending GIS-based visual analysis: the
and power among the Uduk of Sudan. Oxford: Clarendon. concept of visualscapes. International Journal of Geographical
Jones, A. (2005). Lives in fragments? Personhood and the European Information Science 17(1), 25–48.
Neolithic. Journal of Social Archaeology 5(2), 193–224. López Mazz, J. M. (2009). An Archaeological View of Political
Jones, A. (2007). Memory and material culture. Cambridge: Repression in Uruguay (1971–1985). In Funari, P. P.,
Cambridge University Press. Zarankin, A., & Salerno, M. (eds.): Memories from Darkness.
Kent, S. (1990). A cross-cultural study of segmentation, archi- Archaeology of Repression and Resistance in Latin America.
tecture, and the use of space. In S. Kent (ed.): Domestic (pp. 33–43). New York: Springer.
architecture and the use of space. An interdisciplinary cross- Lutz, C. & White, G. M. (1986). The anthropology of emotions.
cultural study. (pp. 127–152). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Annual Review of Anthropology 15, 405–436.
University Press. MacLean, J. S. (2009). Mission Santa Catalina’s mondadiente
Klumb, P. (2001). Knoten im Taschentuch: Der Einsatz von de plata (silver toothpick): materiality and the construc-
Gedächtnishilfen im Alltag. Zeitschrift für Entwicklungs- tion of the self in Spanish La Florida. In C. L. White (ed.):
psychologie und Pädagogische Psychologie 33(1), 44–49. The Materiality of Individuality: Archaeological Studies of
Knappett, C. (2002). Photographs, skeuomorphs and mari- Individual Lives. (pp. 125–139). New York: Springer.
onettes. Some thoughts on mind, agency and object. Journal Malafouris, L. (2004). The cognitive basis of material
of Material Culture 7(1), 97–117. engagement: where brain, body and culture conflate. In
Knappett, C. (2005). Thinking Through Material Culture. An E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden y C. Renfrew (eds.): Rethinking
Interdisciplinary Perspective. University of Pennsylvania materiality: The engagement of mind with the material world.
Press. (pp. 53–62). Cambridge, UK: McDonald Institute for
Knappet, C. & Malafouris, L. (2008). Material agency. New York: Archaeological Research.
Springer. Marcoux, J.-S. (2001). The ‘casser-maison’ ritual: constructing
Küchler, S. (2002). Malanggan: art, memory and sacrifice. Oxford, the self by emptying the home. Journal of Material Culture
UK: Berg. 6(2), 213–235.
Kuijt, I. (1996). Negotiating Equality through Ritual: A Markus, H. R. & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self:
Consideration of Late Natufian and Prepottery Neolithic Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation.
A Period Mortuary Practices. Journal of Anthropological Psychological Review 98(2), 224–253.
Archaeology 15, 313–336. Mauss, M. (1973 [1935]). Techniques of the body. Economy and
Kus, S. (1989). Sensuous human activity and the State: Towards Society 2(1), 70–88.
an archaeology of bread and circuses. In D. Miller, M. Mbembe, A. (2000). De la postcolonie. Essai sur l’imagination
Rowlands & C. Tilley (eds.): Domination and resistance. (pp. politique dans l’Afrique. Paris: Karthala.
40–54). London; New York: Routledge. Meskell, L. (1999). Archaeologies of social life: age, sex, class et cet-
Kus, S. & Raharijaona, V. (1990). Domestic space and the tenac- era in ancient Egypt. Oxford; Malden, MA: Blackwell.
ity of tradition among some Betsileo of Madagascar. In S. Miller, D. (1987). Material culture and mass consumption.
Kent (ed.): Domestic architecture and the use of space. An inter- Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
disciplinary cross-cultural study. (pp. 21–33). Cambridge, UK: Miller, D. (ed.). (2001a). Home possessions: material culture
Cambridge University Press. behind closed doors. Oxford, New York: Berg.
Latour, B. (1991). Technology is society made durable. In J. Law Miller, D. (ed.) (2001b). Car cultures. Oxford, UK; New York:
(ed.): A Sociology of monsters: essays on power, technology, and Berg.
domination. (pp. 103–131). London; New York: Routledge,. Olivier, L. (2008). Le sombre abîme du temps. Paris: Gallimard.
Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Cambridge, MA: Olsen, B. (2003). Material culture after text: remembering
Harvard University Press. things. Norwegian Archaeological Review 36(2), 87–104.

160 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


Olsen, B. (2006). Archaeology, hermeneutics of suspicion and Schiffer, M. B. (1999). The material life of human beings:
phenomenological trivialization. Archaeological Dialogues Artifacts, behavior, and communication. London; New York:
13(2), 144–150. Routledge.
Olsen, B. (2007). Keeping things at arm’s length: a genealogy of Schnapp, A. (1996). The discovery of the past: the origins of archae-
asymmetry. World Archaeology 39(4), 579–588. ology. London: British Museum. Translated by I. Kinnes and
Parker Pearson, M. (1982). Mortuary practices, society and G. Varndell.
ideology: an ethnoarchaeological study. In I. Hodder (ed.): Schneider, J. (2006). Cloth and clothing. In C. Tilley, W. Keane,
Symbolic and structural archaeology. (pp. 99–113). Cambridge, S. Küchler, M. Rowlands & P. Spyer (eds.): Handbook of
UK: Cambridge University Press. material culture. (pp. 203–220). London; New York: Sage.
Parker Pearson, M. & Richards, P. (1994). Architecture and order. Scott, E. (1999). The archaeology of infancy and infant death.
Approaches to social space. London; New York: Routledge. British Archaeological Reports IS 819. Oxford, UK:
Pauketat, T. & S. Alt. (2003). Mounds, memories and con- Archaeopress.
tested Mississippian history. In R. Van Dyke & S. Alcock Shady Solís, R., Machacuay, M. & Aramburú, R. (2000). La
(eds.): Archaeologies of memory (pp. 151–175). Malden, MA; plaza circular del templo mayor de Caral: su presencia en
Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Supe y en el área norcentral del Perú. Revista Boletín del
Pétrequin, P. & Pétrequin, A. M. (1990). Flèches de chasse, Museo de Arqueología y Antropología 8, 2–25.
flèches de guerre, le cas des Danis d’Irian Jaya (Indonésie). Shanks, M. (2007). Symmetrical archaeology. World Archaeology
Bulletin de la Société Préhistorique Française 87(10–12), 39(4), 589–596.
484–511. Shweder, R. A. (1991). Thinking through cultures. Cambridge,
Preston Blier, S. (1987). The anatomy of architecture: ontology and MA; London: Harvard University Press.
metaphor in Batammaliba architectural expression. Chicago: Shweder, R. A. & Sullivan, M. A. (1993). Cultural psychology:
Chicago University Press. who needs it? Annual Review of Psychology 44, 497–523.
Preucel, R. (2006). Archaeological semiotics. Oxford, UK: Simmel, G. (1959). Georg Simmel, 1858–1918. A collection of
Blackwell. essays, with translations and a bibliography. Edited by K. H.
Renfrew, C. (1998). Mind and matter: Cognitive archaeology and Wolff. Columbus, OH: The Ohio State University Press.
external symbolic storage. In C. Renfrew & C. Scarre (eds.): Simmel, G. (2007). The philosophy of landscape. Theory, Culture
Cognition and Material Culture: the Archaeology of Symbolic & Society 24(7–8), 20–29.
Storage. (pp. 1–6). McDonald Institute Monographs. Stark, M., Bowser, J. & Horne, L. (2008). Cultural transmission
Cambridge, UK: McDonald Institute for Archaeological and material culture: breaking down boundaries. Tucson, AZ:
Research. University of Arizona Press.
Renfrew, C. & Morley, I. (2009). Becoming human: innovation Stevanovic, M. (1997). The age of clay: The social dynamics
in prehistoric material and spiritual culture. Cambridge, NY: of house destruction. Journal of Anthropological Archaeology
Cambridge University Press. 16(4), 334–395.
Renfrew, C. & Scarre, C. (eds.), (1998). Cognition and Material Stout, D. (2002). Skill and Cognition in Stone Tool Production.
Culture: the Archaeology of Symbolic Storage. McDonald An Ethnographic Case Study from Irian Jaya. Current
Institute Monographs. Cambridge, UK: McDonald Institute Anthropology 45 (3), 693–722.
for Archaeological Research. Strathern, M. (1988). The gender of the gift: problems with women
Renfrew, C. & Zubrow, E. B. W. (eds.) (1994). The ancient mind: and problems with society in Melanesia. Berkeley: California
elements of cognitive archaeology. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.
University Press. Tarlow, S. (2000a). Emotion in archaeology. Current Anthropology.
Reznikoff, I. & Dauvois, M. (1988). La dimension sonore des Tarlow, S. (2000b). Landscapes of memory: the nineteenth-cen-
grottes ornées. Bulletin de la Société Préhistorique Française tury garden cemetery. European Journal of Archaeology 3(2),
85(8), 238–246. 217–239.
Robb, J. & Dobres, M. A. (eds.) (2000). Agency in archaeology. Theis, J. (1995). Nach der Razzia: Ethnographie und Geschichte
London; New York: Routledge. der Koma. München: Trickster.
Roche, D. (1996 [1989]). The culture of clothing. Dress and Thomas, J. (1998). Some problems with the notion of external
fashion in the Ancien Regime. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge symbolic storage, and the case of Neolithic material culture
University Press. Translated by J. Birrell. in Britain. In C. Renfrew & C. Scarre (eds.), Cognition
Rodríguez Mayorgas, A. (2010). Arqueología de la palabra. Oralidad and Material Culture: the Archaeology of Symbolic Storage.
y escritura en el mundo antiguo. Barcelona: Bellaterra. (pp. 149–156). McDonald Institute Monographs. Cambridge,
Roux, V. & Corbetta, D. (1989). The Potter’s Wheel: Craft special- UK: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research.
ization and technical competence. New Delhi, India: Oxford Thomas, J. (2000). Death, Identity and the Body in Neolithic
& IBH. Britain. The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 6(4),
Roux, V., Bril, B. & Dietrich, G. (1995). Skills and learning dif- 653–668.
ficulties involved in stone knapping: the case of stone-bead Tilley, C. (1994). A phenomenology of landscape. Oxford: Berg.
knapping in Khambhat, India. World Archaeology 27(1), Tilley, C. (2004). The materiality of stone. Explorations in land-
63–87. scape phenomenology, Oxford, UK: Berg.
Rowlands, M. (1993). The role of memory in the transmission of Treherne, P. (1995). The warriors beauty: The masculine body
culture. World Archaeology 25(2), 141–151. and self-identity in Bronze Age Europe. Journal of European
Saunders, N. (2009). People in objects: Individuality and the Archaeology 3(1), 105–144.
quotidian in the material culture of war. In C. L. White Turner, V. (2002 [1969]): Liminality and communitas. In
(ed.): The Materiality of Individuality: Archaeological Studies M. Lambek (ed.): A reader in the anthropology of religion.
of Individual Lives. (pp. 37–55). New York: Springer. (pp. 358–374). Malden, MA; Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

g o n z á l e z - ru i b a l 161
Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies. Foundations Webmoor, T. (2007). What about ‘one more turn after the social’
of cultural psychology. New Delhi, India; Thousand Oaks, in archaeological reasoning? Taking things seriously. World
CA: Sage. Archaeology 39(4), 563–578.
Valsiner, J. (2008). Ornamented worlds and textures of feelings: Webmoor, T. & Witmore, C. (2008). Things Are Us! A
the power of abundance. Critical Social Studies 1, 67–78. Commentary on Human/Things Relations under the Banner
Valsiner, J. (2009). Cultural psychology today: Innovations and of a ‘Social’ Archaeology. Norwegian Archaeological Review
oversights. Culture & Psychology 15(1), 5–39. 41(1), 53–70.
Van Dyke, R. & Alcock, S. (2003). Archaeologies of memory. Warnier, J.-P. (2006). Inside and outside. Surfaces and containers.
Malden, MA; Oxford, UK: Blackwell. In C. Tilley, W. Keane, S. Küchler, M. Rowlands & P. Spyer
Verjux, C. (2007). Les pratiques funéraires mésolithiques en (eds.): Handbook of material culture. (pp. 186–195). London;
Europe. Divertité dans l’espace et dans le temps. In L. New York: Sage.
Baray, P. Brun, & A. Testart (eds.): Pratiques funéraires et Wengrow, D. (2006). The Archaeology of Early Egypt. Social
sociétés. Novelles approches en archéologie et en anthropologie Transformations in North-East Africa, c. 10,000 to 2,650 BC.
sociale. (pp. 15–35). Dijon, France: Editions Universitaires Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
de Dijon,. Wiessner, P. (1983). Style and social information in Kalahari San
Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind and society. The development of higher projectile points. American Antiquity 48(2), 253–276.
psychological processes. Edited by M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, Winter, J. (1995). Sites of memory, sites of mourning. The Great
S. Scribner & E. Souberman. Cambridge, MA; London: War in European cultural history. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge
Harvard University Press. University Press.
Vygotsky, L. & Luria, A. R. (1993). Studies on the history of behav- Witmore, C. (2006). Vision, Media, Noise and the Percolation
ior: ape, primitive, and child. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. of Time. Symmetrical Approaches to the Mediation of
Translation and notes by V.I. Golod and J.E. Knox. the Material World Journal of Material Culture 11(3),
Wagner-Pacifici, R. & Schwartz, B. (1991). The Vietnam 267–292.
Veterans Memorial: Commemorating a Difficult Past. The Witmore, C. (2007). Symmetrical archaeology: excerpts of a
American Journal of Sociology 97(2), 376–420. manifesto. World Archaeology 39(4), 546–562.
Wallaert-Pêtre, H. (2001). Learning how to make the right Wobst, M. (1977). Stylistic behavior and information exchange.
pots: apprenticeship strategies and material culture, a case In C. E. Cleland (ed.): For the Director: Research essays in
study in hand-made pottery from Cameroon. Journal of honor of James B. Griffin. (pp. 317–342). Ann Arbor, MI:
Anthropological Research 57, 471–493. Museum of Anthropology, University of Michigan.
Wallace, S. (2007). Why We Need New Spectacles: Mapping the Zegwaard, G. A. (1959). Headhunting practices of the Asmat
Experiential Dimension in Prehistoric Cretan Landscapes. of Netherlands New Guinea. American Anthropologist 61(6),
Cambridge Archaeological Journal 17(3), 249–270. 1020–1041.
Waller, S. J. (1993). Sound and rock art. Nature 363, 501. Zerubavel, E. (1977). The French Republican Calendar: A Case
Watson, A. & Keating, D. (1999). Architecture and sound: an Study in the Sociology of Time. American Sociological Review
acoustic analysis of megalithic monuments in prehistoric 42(6), 868–877.
Britain. Antiquity 73(280), 325–336.

162 arc heolog y and t he st udy o f mat e ria l cu ltu re


PA RT
3
Positions in the Field
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Enactivism
8
Cor Baerveldt and Theo Verheggen

Abstract
Enactivism is an emerging perspective both in cognitive science and in cultural psychology. Whereas
the enactive approach in general has focused on sense-making as an embodied and situated
activity, enactive cultural psychology emphasizes the expressive and dynamically enacted nature of
cultural meaning. This chapter first situates enactivism within a tradition of expressivist thinking
that has historical roots both in radical Enlightenment thought and Romantic reactions against the
rationalization of human nature. It then offers a view of our human biology that can be reconciled
with an account of meaning as irreducibly normative. By emphasizing the consensual rather than
the supposedly shared nature of meaningful conduct, enactivism avoids some of the classical pitfalls
in thinking about culture. In the conclusion a genetic enactive psychology will be presented, which
understands sense-making not as a mediated activity but as a competence acquired through cultural
training and personal stylization.
Keywords: enactivism, expression, consensual coordination, emotion, normativity, cultural training

Enactivism is an emerging perspective in cog- Hegel (1770–1831), Johann Friedrich Herbart


nitive science proposed most explicitly by Varela, (1776–1841), and Wilhelm von Humboldt (1767–
Thompson, and Rosch (1991) as an alternative to 1835) (see Jahoda, 1993; Diriwächter, 2004). But
representational theories of cognition. As a perspec- cultural psychology can also be seen as more broadly
tive in cultural psychology, it was first proposed by connected to secularizing tendencies in Western
Baerveldt and Verheggen (1999) as a way to give an cultural history going back to Baruch Spinoza
account of consensually orchestrated personal con- (1632–1677) and running through the work of
duct, without evoking culture as an already estab- Giambatisto Vico (1668–1744), Johann Wolfgang
lished meaningful order. Both enactive cognitive von Goethe (1749–1832), and Johann Gottfried
science and enactive cultural psychology are char- Herder (1744–1803). The Enlightenment in its dif-
acterized by a focus on sense-making as a situated, ferent forms spurred a strong call for cultural plural-
embodied activity. ism and an emphasis on a broad ideal of education.
Like cultural psychology itself, enactivism has Particularly in Germany, both ideas were strongly
roots that predate psychology in its modern academic linked to that of the unity of a people in terms of a
form. Cultural psychology and its historical precur- cultural tradition. Informed by both Enlightenment
sors have been associated with expressivist streams ideas and Romantic reactions against the rational-
with roots grounded particularly in German ideal- ization of human nature, the psychologist Moritz
ism, through the work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Lazarus (1824–1903) and his brother-in-law, the

165
philologist Hajim Steinthal (1823–1899), fol- is fundamentally different from the social-political
lowed in the footsteps of Herder, Herbart, and thought that follows, for example, from the writings
von Humboldt and proposed the new discipline of Locke, Hume, Hobbes, and Montesquieu (for an
of Völkerpsychologie (Eckhardt, 1997; Diriwächter, extensive discussion of Spinoza’s historical role in
2004). The new discipline concerned itself with the “radical Enlightenment,” see Israel, 2001).
spiritual and mental (geistige) processes not so much Particularly interesting for our discussion here
at the level of the individual but at the level of cul- is the way Spinoza already understands percep-
tural communities. Central was the idea of a people tion: not as the result of the impact of external
(Volk) as unified not by biological heritage but by stimuli but as a consequence of the way the per-
common language, taste, poetry, and customs. Of ceiver is disposed to the world. “The human mind is
particular interest to our own argument is the way adapted to the perception of many things, and its
Lazarus and Steinthal already saw psychology as a aptitude increases in proportion to the number of
third science, situated between the natural sciences ways in which its body can be disposed” (Spinoza,
and historical disciplines (Diriwächter, 2004, p. 90). 1677[2001], p. 62). The Latin disponere means “to
As such, their Völkerpsychologie rejected reductively arrange,” or to put in order. In the Nicomachean
biologistic or organismic understandings of the Ethics, Aristotle uses both the Greek diathesis (from
individual, stating instead that individuals inher- dia + thithenai to set), which refers to dispositions
ently emerge within a network of communally in a more general sense, and hexis (translated in
enacted meanings and linguistic practice. In contrast Latin as habitus), which refers specifically to deeper
with the newly emerging hermeneutic disciplines, and more active dispositions like the ones involved
however, Völkerpsychologie remained committed to in moral character. Already for Aristotle such dis-
giving lawful accounts of psychological processes positions are deeply embodied and cannot just be
(Eckhardt, 1997; Diriwächter, 2004). Although passed on by simple instruction. Instead, a hexis is
in hindsight fundamental questions can be asked acquired by the cultivation of our “natural” tenden-
about the success of Lazarus and Steinthal’s new cies by repeated action.
program, with the notable exception of Vygotsky’s
Anything that we have to learn to do we learn by
cultural-historical psychology, the possibility of a
the actual doing of it: people become builders by
genetic psychology situated between the biologi-
building and instrumentalists by playing instruments.
cal and the human sciences still remains scarcely
Similarly, we become just by performing just acts,
explored.
temperate by performing temperate ones, brave
by performing brave ones. (. . .) In a word, then,
Enactivism and radical Enlightenment
like activities produce like dispositions. Hence we
Enactivism aims at giving an account of situated
must give our activities a certain quality, because it
meaningful action that remains connected both to
is their characteristics that determine the resulting
biology and to the hermeneutic and phenomeno-
dispositions.
logical studies of experience. Enactivism in the form
(Aristotle, 2004, p. 92)
that will be presented here is most closely related
to the work of the biologists Humberto Maturana The notion of “disposition” that derives from
and Francisco Varela, who have attempted to offer a Aristotle and was passed on through the Scholastic
radically new understanding of life and knowledge. tradition to such diverse thinkers as Spinoza, Herder,
However, to see the historical connections between Wittgenstein, and Bourdieu implies a particular
their program and that of the expressivist tradition understanding of determinism that is highly relevant
that informed early cultural theory and cultural for an enactive cultural psychology and strongly at
psychology, we need to see it as part of a particular odds with the causal assumptions of mainstream
“radical” tradition in Western Enlightenment think- cognitive and representationalist accounts of percep-
ing that can be traced at least to Spinoza. Although tion. This understanding of determinism is crucially
it advances the central tenets of a secular, determin- related to what could now be called “organizational
istic, and hence fully scientific worldview, this strain autonomy,” a concept that—with all its biologi-
of thought has also provided a radical—but some- cal connotations—is central to enactive thought.
what forgotten—alternative to reductionist forms Interestingly, Spinoza already claims that “a compos-
of rationalism. It can potentially serve as a basis ite individual can be affected in many ways and yet
for a form of cultural and historical thinking that retain its nature,” as long as “the bodies composing

166 enactivi sm
the individual continue and reciprocally communi- largely learned, or acquired as a consequence of
cate their motions in the same manner as before” our socialization. Although the nervous system is
(ibid., p. 61). The link, in perception and action, equipped with “sympathetic abilities” and a general
between determinism and autonomy characterizes capacity for emotionality, the structure of human
enactive thought from Spinoza, through Vico and reason is essentially the structure of language
Herder, to Bateson, Maturana, and Varela. We find it (Fischer, 1997).
as well in the work of Vygotsky (see below), for whom Herder also already presented a holistic concep-
Spinoza was an important source of inspiration. tion of culture wherein culture is neither a mere
aggregate, nor a homogenous unity, but the dynamic
Johann Gottfried Herder and Expression product of reciprocal relations between its constitu-
in Psychology ent parts or individual actors—each an autonomous
With regard to enactive cultural psychology’s whole in its own right—which are not mechanically
historical precedents, next to Spinoza the work of activated by external forces but by their own source
Herder is particularly relevant. Herder was a central of energy. In culture, moreover, the parts that con-
figure in the neo-Spinozist movement that swept stitute the whole through their interconnections are
through Germany in the late eighteenth century. characterized by self-generated activity, indeed not
Where it proved hard for Enlightenment thinkers unlike the Leibnizian monads, with the important
to radically break with a providential understand- understanding that for Herder those monads are
ing of history, Herder stands out as a thinker who not wholly self-contained (for a more extensive dis-
attempted to reconcile, on the one hand, a secular cussion, see Barnard, 2003).2
and empirical understanding of history and the dif- Like Maturana, Herder recognizes that the
ferences between cultures with, on the other hand, notion of operational closure or self-generated activ-
a general cognitive understanding of the “powers ity does not preclude, but rather qualifies the idea
of the soul” as an embodied meaning giving capac- of social interaction. Thus, despite what could be
ity (Herder, 1778/2002b). Taylor (1995) credits considered an organismic view of culture, human
Herder for standing at the beginning of an expres- reason and meaning are for Herder always histori-
sivist understanding of language and mind that is cally and culturally bound. Herder was one of the
in contrast with the designative or representational first to see the need to link advances in historical
understanding still dominating psychology and methods to advances in psychology, particularly by
cognitive science. connecting what he called the Zeitgeist (the partic-
It is remarkable that Herder’s understanding of ular “spirit” or style of thinking and feeling of an
language does not only resemble the account given age) to insight into human motivation (Barnard,
by Maturana, which we will discuss later, but that in 2003, p. 108). Herder may also be the first to have
a way strikingly similar to Maturana, he already con- made room for a psychology situated between the
nects it to what can be considered an early version explanatory methods of the natural sciences and the
of the idea of the self-referentiality and operational “Verstehende” methods of the human sciences.
closure of the nervous system (Herder, 1778b/2002; Through nineteenth century German Völker-
see also Fischer, 1997). Herder speaks of the soul as an psychologie, this idea would come to have a profound
“organic but self-referential being that acts accord- influence on Wundt (1900–1920), who particularly
ing to its own laws of mental connections” (Herder, in his later work expressed his believe in “a distinct
1989, p. 182, op cit. Fischer, 1997, p. 307).1 Rather methodological approach to analyze and explain the
than understanding perception as merely the result ‘psychic processes that are bound, in virtue of their
of an imprint of the external world on our senses genetic and developmental conditions, to spiri-
that reaches the brain mechanically, Herder speaks tual communities [geistige Gemeinschaften]’ ” (Kim,
of sensual activity as the way the soul “imagines” an 2006). As Danziger (2001) notes, for Wundt, “men-
outer object and of the image beheld by the soul as tal or cultural communities were not formed through
“a phenomenon that is constructed by the soul itself deliberate decision making but through sponta-
upon the instigation of the senses” (ibid.). Herder neous forms of interaction at a pre-rational level”
(1778/2002b) frequently uses the word “irritation” (p. 87). Wundt was interested in cultural domains
(Reiz) in a way similar to Maturana’s use of the term of behavior insofar as these domains are governed by
“perturbation” (see below). He also insists that the psychological laws of development, rather than by
active power of the soul is not merely innate but contingent historical conditions. Where the second

ba erveldt, verh eggen 167


half of the nineteenth century would see a battle odds with the representationalism of the Cartesian
between biologically or racially oriented under- tradition. We maintain that recovering an inher-
standings of the unity of a people on the one hand ently social and cultural psychology remains impos-
and cultural-historical orientations (represented by sible as long as the links with representationalism
Herder and Völkerpsychologie) on the other, leading and Cartesian mentalism are not radically severed.
to the gradual demise of the latter, Wundt still saw Enactive cultural psychology, as we will argue, is an
the possibility of formulating genetic psychological attempt to draw out the psychological implications
laws—not at the level of micro-functional or physi- of an ontological understanding of life and meaning
ological processes, but at the level of cultural expres- that remains radically nonrepresentational.
sion (e.g., Wundt, 1897/1902, p. 23). According
to Wundt, the expressive features of consciousness The Enactive Program
lie beyond the scope of experimental research but Although the word enactivism was introduced
require genetic-historical research of the mind and by Varela, Thompson, and Rosch (1991) to denote
its creations. a particular paradigm in cognitive science, it has its
roots in the program of a biology of cognition ini-
Cultural Psychology and the Wrong tially proposed by Maturana (1970, 1975, 1988a,
Enlightenment 1988b) and further developed by Maturana and
In the historical link between cultural psychol- Varela (Maturana & Varela, 1980, 1987; see also
ogy and the idea of expression lies the main inspi- Varela, 1979, 1981). The enactive approach as pre-
ration of enactive cultural psychology but also the sented by Varela, Thompson, and Rosch can be seen
point of contention between enactive and represen- both as an attempt to reconcile the study of cog-
tational understandings of culture. We claim that nition with the systematic examination of human
early historical attempts to link culture and psyche experience and as an effort to offer a radical alterna-
were largely based on the idea of expression and tive to representational accounts of cognition that
not on that of representation. The word represen- divorce cognition from embodied action. Although
tation (French: représentation, German: Vorstellung) we sympathize with the general tenets of the enac-
functions prominently in the work of early cul- tive program thus conceived, our own interest has
tural theorists like Durkheim, Wundt, and the been in the possibility of an enactive cultural psy-
Völkerpsychologen. However, whereas in the French chology (Baerveldt & Verheggen, 1999; Baerveldt,
and German language, the concept clearly has an Verheggen, & Voestermans, 2001; Baerveldt &
expressive or presentational connotation, this sense Voestermans, 2005, Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2001,
gets largely lost if it is mistakenly translated as rep- 2007). As we hope to demonstrate in this chapter,
resentation in the English language and appropri- a radically cultural enactivism requires more than
ated by a psychology dominated by cognitivism and an account of human experience that builds up
mentalism. For Durkheim, for example, the word from biological autonomy to society and culture. It
representation referred not only to the conceptual requires us to acknowledge the irreducible norma-
depiction of reality but more even to a dramatic tivity of everyday life and of even our most personal
enactment of the meaning and unity of societal life actions and expressions. For humans, to perceive
(Verheggen, 1996). and to act is to perceive and act in a way that always
Even social psychologists who claim to offer a remains sensitive to normative (hence social) cor-
more psychological understanding of Durkheim’s rection: we can be “right” or “wrong” about what
représentations collective (e.g., Moscovici, 1988) have we see or do in ways that cannot be accounted for
typically only taken up the more conceptual, repre- merely in terms of the constraints imposed on us by
sentational understanding and ignored the expressive our physiology.
one. Consequently, they miss a crucial opportunity To develop an account of this irreducible nor-
to propose a psychology of cultural life and remain, mativity, which still remains biologically possible
instead, caught up in the study of “lay representa- and does not loose itself in subjective idealism,
tions” of life or of the dissemination of scientific we draw from Maturana’s work on language and
representations into everyday discourse. Spinoza, sociality (particularly Maturana, 1978a, 1978b;
Vico, Herder, German Völkerpsychologie, and Wundt Maturana & Verden-Zöller, 1996). Maturana has
all offer a primarily expressivist understanding of occasionally talked about the idea of cognition as
mind, culture and life, which is fundamentally at the bringing forth rather than the representation of a

168 enactivi sm
world, a notion that has made some of his interpret- those normative practices is to be reconciled with
ers call him a “bring forthist” and not, for example, our biological nature, we first need to ask the ques-
a constructivist (Proulx, 2008). Both the notion of tion what, biologically speaking, makes us human.
“enactment” and that of “bringing forth” are meant And this, in turn, brings us back to the question
to orient the audience to “knowing” as an ontologi- what constitutes a biological account. Indeed, any
cal category, and it is this ontological understanding account of ourselves and of what makes us human
of knowing that we take up in our program for an stands within a fundamental circularity. This circu-
enactive cultural psychology. Hence, when we use larity cannot simply be dismissed in the name of
the term enactivism to refer to our own work, we a science that privileges linear logic but needs to
use it in a sense that takes it out of the confines of a be acknowledged as indispensable to the aim of
more narrowly conceived cognitive science program understanding itself. For Maturana, the question of
and into the realm of cultural expressions of reality. our humanity is crucially related to us being able
to ask such questions and to account for ourselves
Enactivism and a Humanized Biology and our actions by constituting a metadomain of
Maturana and Varela’s thinking is complex distinctions that allows us to operate as “observers.”
and wide-ranging but has been discussed in great Human beings are biological entities, but they are
detail elsewhere (for a concise summary of their simultaneously the kinds of creatures that are partly
own thinking, see particularly Maturana & Varela, constituted by their own self-understanding (Taylor,
1980). In this section, we will expound some of 1985; Hacking, 1995; Martin & Sugarman, 2001).
the formal underpinnings of their work and draw The question, therefore, becomes: How is self-un-
out implications for psychological understanding. derstanding biologically possible? Only after the
While briefly touching on Maturana and Varela’s biology of understanding and self-understanding
biological understanding of “life” in general, we will has been formally laid out will we be able to address
discuss in more detail their biological understanding the outlines of an enactive cultural psychology.
of cognition and social interaction and its possible
implications for the psychological understanding of The Formal Roots of Enactivism
behavior, action, and expression. We are interested Although their collaborative work is most often
in cultural psychology at the cross-section with associated with the theory of autopoiesis and is even
biology, but contrary to the mainstream in Western called “autopoietic theory,” Maturana and Varela’s
rational thought, we believe that the irreducibly nor- thinking can in large part be seen as a series of
mative nature of culturally shaped conduct cannot implications following from two related concepts.
be understood in reductionist biological terms. Yet, The first is the idea of structural determination and
rather than pursuing a human psychology cut off concerns the issue of what it means to give a ratio-
entirely from its biological roots, we maintain that nal or scientific account of the behavior of any kind
the psychology of human behavior can in principle of natural system. The second is the concept of
be reconciled with a properly “humanized” biology self-reference and closure, as expressed in the organi-
(Voestermans & Baerveldt, 2001). zational closure of living systems and more particu-
Far from proposing some kind of anthropomor- larly in the operational closure of the nervous system.
phic projection onto our pregiven biological nature, Together, the concepts of structural determination
what we have in mind here is the recognition that and self-reference/closure lead to radical implica-
any attempt to describe and explain human behav- tions for our understanding of living systems, intel-
ior necessarily sets out from the pre-reflective, prac- ligent behavior (cognition), and social action.
tical understanding of that behavior within the Maturana and Varela are biologists and their
cultural normative realm. For example, to call a cer- work is often linked to advances in biological sys-
tain action “walking,” or “writing,” or “conversing” tems theory and cybernetics, as represented by
is to already identify it in light of a practical cultural the work of Warren McCulloch, Norbert Wiener,
understanding, without which the very notion of John von Neumann, Gregory Bateson, and Heinz
behavior or action is meaningless. Therefore, what von Foerster. However, enactive cultural psychol-
is to be explained, biologically or psychologically, ogy is not just an elaboration of biological systems
is in some sense always already understood and theory but a radical attempt to rethink psychologi-
distinguished within the coherences of our nor- cal and social thought in light of a non-reductionist
mative practices. If a hermeneutic explication of ontology that potentially allows us to think of the

ba erveldt, verh eggen 169


irreducibly normative and historical character of compensable, thus specifying the system’s range of
human conduct, yet without cutting off human- possible interactions without disintegration. In
ity from the rest of the natural world. Laying out other words, the structure of a system at any given
the basis of such an attempt requires us to rethink moment in time determines what entities and events
some of our basic understandings concerning cause, in its medium it can interact with, as well as the way
determinism, and human agency. it will behave in each of those interactions.
It is important to realize that on Maturana’s
Structural Determinism account, structure is not a static entity. On the
Any system that is observed as a composite uni- contrary, the structure of a system necessarily alters
ty—that is, an entity composed of parts—is distin- with every interaction it undergoes. It’s organiza-
guished as such in terms of its structure. Structural tion, however, remains constant as long as the sys-
determinism refers to the principle that for any tem maintains the integrity of its own constitutive
natural system, it is the structure of the system internal relations. As a general term for the range of
itself that determines its behavior and the changes possible interactions in which a system can engage,
it can undergo. Although natural systems obviously Maturana uses the word domain. Hence, a system’s
undergo structural changes as a consequence of domain of possible interactions is determined by its
interaction with an environment, those interactions own structure, whereas the domain of interactions
with an environment can only trigger the system’s in which it can enter without disintegration is con-
behaviors and changes, but they cannot bring them strained by its defining organization (see Maturana,
about. To use a simple example from the biological 1988a, 1988b).
world, a honeybee may be able to navigate using the The principle of structural determinism leads to
ultraviolet light of the sun, whereas a human being one of the central explanatory constructs in enactive
lacks this particular spectral sensitivity. This is so theory with regard to the interaction between dif-
because the structure and organization of the bee’s ferent systems: that of structural coupling. Because
compound eyes is different from the retinal struc- natural systems are determined by their own struc-
ture of human eyes. Although the “trigger” (e.g., ture and not by anything outside of them, interac-
the multispectral light of the sun) can be seen by an tion between different systems cannot be mutually
observer as in both cases the same, this trigger does instructive. Instead, two (or more) systems can
not determine the structural changes in the respec- engage in a history of recurrent interactions by mutu-
tive systems. ally triggering (not determining) structural changes
Maturana and Varela distinguish the structure in each other. Such a history of interlocked conduct
of a system from its organization. Where organiza- means that the systems mutually select congruent
tion is understood as the relations between com- paths of structural change in each other, leading
ponents of the system that constitute the system’s to structural congruence: as long as the systems in
class identity (eggs, rocks), its structure is defined interaction maintain their own defining organiza-
as the actual material embodiment of that organiza- tion, they change together, in practical agreement.
tion (Maturana & Varela, 1980; Maturana, 1988a, On an enactive account, structural determinism and
1988b). Consequently, a system’s structure can structural coupling are precisely what constitutes a
change while its class identity remains the same, as system as a historical system. The system’s ontogeny
long as the system maintains the network of rela- is its history of structural transformations—that is,
tions between components that specify its defining the course of its structural coupling with its envi-
organization. In Maturana’s words, “a particular ronment and with other structurally determined
composite unity conserves its class identity only as systems. The result of the structural coupling of
long as its structure realizes in it the organization a system with its environment is called ontogenic
that defines its class identity” (Maturana, 1988b, adaptation (Maturana & Guiloff, 1980, p. 140) and
pp. 6, iv). For example, putting an object on a table the result of the structural coupling between two or
will create a series of specific structural changes in more organisms is called a consensual domain (ibid.,
the table, but the table will remain a table as long p. 141). An example of ontogenic adaptation in the
as it maintains the network of relations that specify everyday cultural realm is wearing a pair of shoes: in
it—in the eye of an observer—as a table. As long a history of recurring and recursive interactions, our
as the table maintains its integrity or class iden- feet and our shoes change together, such that the
tity, the perturbations it undergoes can be seen as degree of congruence between them increases and

170 enactivi sm
we experience our shoes as becoming more com- an environment and establish consensual domains.
fortable (Maturana & Poerksen, 2004, pp. 83–84). Maturana presents a general outlook on science,
Other examples are playing a musical instrument or which, although explicitly mechanistic, is also
using a fountain pen. holistic and non-reductionist. Maturana’s use of
Similarly, we also become mutually adapted the word mechanistic differs principally from that
to others in a history of consensually coordinated of reductionist Newtonian science and makes use
action. A consensual domain is a historical domain of the etymological roots of the words “mecha-
that requires continuous structural changes in all nism” and “machine” as referring to a structured
systems involved. Again it is crucial to realize that whole (Greek: mēkhanē) rather than partes extra
although we may speak of mutual “influences” partes only connected by external forces. Science,
those influences are not instructive. For example, according to Maturana, can only deal with struc-
I can say that I am influenced by my mother or by ture-determined systems, and any explanation of
a certain historical author, but as becomes particu- the changes a system undergoes should be one
larly clear in the case of the latter, this influence is in terms of the system’s own structure and not
not one that runs in a causal line from the author in terms of the external forces that impinge on it
to me but precisely the other way around, from my (Maturana, 1988a, pp. 36–37). Whether a table
affective and intellectual dispositions to the author. collapses under the weight put on it is determined
I read the author because I am interested, and by the structural properties of the table and not
my reading is not a receiving of information but by the objective weight as measured by an external
a dwelling in the style of the author, as Merleau- observer. Hence, to understand Maturana’s strong
Ponty (e.g., Merleau-Ponty, 1964) has frequently insistence that science can only give mechanistic
stated. This is what makes my relation to the author explanations, it is extremely important to see that
a historical one. his understanding of this term is fundamentally at
Because the behavior of the systems establishing odds with the conventional use.
a consensual domain is structurally coupled, once Consequently, Maturana has been explicit in his
a consensual domain is established, each member rejection of the standard notion of causality and
of the coupling can (in principle) be replaced by a causal relations in scientific explanations:
system that is equivalent with respect to the struc-
(. . .) the notion of causality is a notion that pertains
tural features involved in the coupling (Maturana,
only to the domain of descriptions, and as such it
1978a). This is crucial for an understanding of
is relevant only in the metadomain in which the
culture and language, which rely on the structural
observer makes his commentaries and cannot be
or dispositional equivalence of their participants
deemed to be operative in the phenomenal domain,
for their maintenance and historical continuation.
the object of the description.
Speakers of a particular language can (in principle)
(Maturana & Varela, 1980, p. xviii)
understand each other, and members of a culture
are (in principle) able to make sense of each other’s The notion of structural determinism allows Maturana
expressions. Consensual domains are both deter- and Varela to maintain that their account is fully
mined by the respective structures of the coupled deterministic or mechanistic, yet to escape at
organisms and by the history of their recurrent the same time the reductionist implications of a
interactions. Yet, they are neither shared represen- Newtonian worldview in which the behavior of
tations nor are they mediated by anything external bodies is seen as entirely determined by external
to the history of interlocked conduct between the causes and impacts, or the dualism of Descartes in
organisms involved. We will return to this after we which the movement of bodies can be caused by
have dealt more explicitly with the problem of cog- a mind that remains ontologically entirely exter-
nition and language. nal to it.3 In this sense, their work also shows a
Before we move on to the particular charac- close resemblance to that of Gregory Bateson,
teristics of living systems (organisms) and sense- who, while remaining within a thoroughly natu-
making systems, let us make a few intermediate ralistic framework as well, spoke of the biosphere
comments. The above remarks about structural as a complex dynamical system, characterized by
determinism apply to all systems that can be ratio- circular chains of determination and possessing
nally understood and not just to living systems, all the defining properties of “mind”4 (Bateson,
although only living systems can actively adapt to 1979).

ba erveldt, verh eggen 171


The Organizational Closure of Living closed in the sense that “( . . .) their organization is a
Systems circular network of interactions rather than a tree
Maturana’s general orientation with regard to sci- of hierarchical processes” (Varela & Goguen, 1978,
ence made him realize that an adequate character- p. 292). In addition, an autopoietic system produces
ization of living systems could not be one in terms its own components (e.g., molecules, cells) and
of referential (e.g., functional or semantic) relations its own boundary with its medium. In the opera-
specified by an observer within a metadomain of tions of an autopoietic system, everything has to be
description. Maturana’s early work with others on subordinated to its autopoiesis, or it disintegrates
the visual system of the frog (e.g., Maturana, Lettvin, (Maturana, 1978, p. 33).
Mcculloch, & Pitts, 1960) already convinced him Maturana and Varela are careful in the use of
of the need for a novel understanding of percep- formal terms like autonomy and organizational clo-
tion that was not based on the idea of information sure to avoid the confusion that often results from
abstraction from sensory data and that did not rely a less rigorous use. For example, their point is
on some notion of representation.5 He became empathically not that autopoietic systems exist inde-
aware that to that end he would have to character- pendently from interaction with a medium, as self-
ize perception and cognition as biological phenom- enclosed entities that can only confront other such
ena, which in turn required him to reflect on the self-enclosed beings without hope of any meaning-
fundamental nature of any biological phenomenon. ful contact. Rather, it is that living systems can only
Maturana wrote later that the key insight came to be defined as living systems in terms of their closed
him when he realized that the questions “What is organization—the relations between components
cognition?” and “What is a living system?” were that remain invariant through structural changes—
essentially the same (in Maturana & Varela, 1980). and not in terms of their interactions with anything
Given the principle of structural determinism, he outside of them. Organizational closure and self-
realized that an adequate answer to this question production determine the relations and interac-
could only be one in terms of the particular structure tions in which a living system as a unit can engage
and organization that distinguished living systems without disintegrating, and hence those relations
from non-living systems. With Francisco Varela, he and interactions with a medium7 cannot specify
proposed a formal definition of “autopoietic sys- the system as a living system. Indeed, for Maturana
tems,” introducing a term that has since come to be and Varela, the notion of autopoiesis serves as a
a cornerstone of his work and that of Varela on bio- formal minimal definition of a living system, with
logical autonomy (e.g., Varela, 1979), the biology the understanding that living systems are autopoi-
of language and social systems (Maturana, 1978a, etic systems realized within a physical space. But
1980), the biology of cognition (e.g., Maturana & autopoiesis also serves as a formal minimal defini-
Varela, 1980), enactive cognitive science (Varela, tion of a cognitive system, because an autopoietic
Thomson, & Rosch, 1991,6 Thompson, 2007), and system is essentially a system that “acts” effectively
the biology of love (Maturana & Verden-Zöller, with regard to its own self-maintenance, regardless
1996, 2008). of whether it is endowed with any particular cogni-
Maturana and Varela (1980; see also Maturana, tive architecture, like a nervous system, and regard-
1978b; Varela, 1979) have defined an autopoietic less of whether its behavior appears as meaningful to
system as a system that is organized as a network an external observer. Defining cognition as effective
of relations between components that (1) through action dispels the need to introduce representation
their interactions, recursively regenerate and realize or some other class of mediational entities between
the network—components and relations between the cognizer’s world and the cognizer’s actions.
components—that produces them, and (2) con- Thus, the concept of autopoiesis entails at the same
stitute the system as a unity distinguished from its time an ontological and an epistemological claim:
background. Autopoietic systems can therefore be to live is to know and to know is to live.
considered as homeostatic systems that keep their
own organization invariant while going through The Operational Closure of the
continuous structural change (Maturana, 1975, p. Nervous System
318). Autopoietic systems are autonomous in the A structurally determined system can be seen
sense that they are distinguished from a background to operate in two non-intersecting phenomenal
by their own operations and they are organizationally domains: the domain of its internally realized states

172 enactivi sm
and the domain of its interactions as a unity with world. But, in addition to that, the nervous system
its environment. The human body, for example, is also a dynamic self-referential system that con-
can both be seen as a micro-operational system in stantly interacts with its own self-generated inter-
terms of it physiology and as an expressive behav- nal states (Maturana, in Maturana & Varela, 1980,
ioral system in terms of its interactions with a p. 13). Although Maturana and Varela explicitly
natural or cultural medium. However, although reject the language of input and output with regard
these domains are operationally non-intersecting, to the operations of the nervous system, we could
they are nonetheless orthogonally interdependent stretch the language a bit and say that in a sense the
or coupled, through the system’s particular his- brain is the main source of its own input.
tory as both a composite unity with a differentiated As a consequence of the brain’s internal coherence
internal structure and a simple unity (the organ- and self-referential activity, activities in an organism’s
ism as a whole) interacting with its environment sensory surfaces cannot be seen as straightforward
(Maturana, 1988b, Section 6.3). In humans, this signals from which the nervous system somehow
history or ontogeny involves a process of cultural extracts information about the outside world. Rather,
training, and below we will return in detail to the such activity serves merely as a modulation of the
implications of Maturana and Varela’s understand- complex internal dynamics of the nervous system
ing for an understanding of cultural training. itself. Maturana and Varela claim that the brain does
The domain of structural states and the domain not function like an input/output machine but as an
of interactions cannot be reduced to one another. operationally closed system, yet structurally participat-
For example, we cannot explain actual behavior in ing in the organization of the organism as a whole.
the relational domain in terms of the internal opera- The brain is organized as a network of reciprocally
tions of the nervous system nor can we explain what related subnetworks, which continuously maintains
happens in the nervous system in terms of the objec- certain invariant patterns of sensory-motor correla-
tive stimuli or sense data to which an organism is tions. Consequently, it gives rise to behavior of the
presumably exposed. That we can nonetheless make organism as a whole within a delimited space or
general statements about the relation between brain relational topology. An organism without a nervous
and behavior is a consequence of the way the sen- system may interact with its medium in a physical
sory and motor surfaces of the human organism—as or chemical way, but it cannot make the relations
a consequence of its evolution—are mapped onto holding between physical events part of its domain
the topology of the brain. Because the organism’s of interactions (Maturana, in Maturana & Varela,
sensors and effectors operate in a dual way, both in 1980, p. 13). Possessing a nervous system means that
the domain of interactions of the organism and as an organism can be disposed to the world in a greatly
part of the closed relational dynamics of the ner- expanded variety of ways and can therefore perceive
vous system, the two domains intersect structurally, the world in an equally large number of ways.
although they remain operationally separate (see par- Note that in the vast majority of cases, activ-
ticularly Maturana, 1988b; Section 7.6). This is the ity in the sensory surfaces of the nervous system is
reason that the relation between those two domains brought about by the organism’s own motions in
cannot be understood in causal terms but only in the broad sense of that word. For a living system,
historical terms. moving around in the world and perceiving the
Cognition as such does not inherently rely on world are inseparably entwined. In light of that, it
a nervous system, then, but a nervous system dra- is impossible to speak of perception as simply the
matically expands an organism’s domain of possible result of neutral sensory stimuli emitted by a per-
interactions, both by expanding the space of its pos- ceiver-independent world.
sible internal states and by allowing it to interact with
its own internal states. To illustrate the former, we “(. . .) the overall concern of an enactive approach to
could use the analogy of our pulmonary system. Just perception is not to determine how some perceiver-
like the progressively subdividing system of bron- independent world is to be recovered; it is rather, to
chi, bronchioles, and alveoli dramatically extends determine the common principles of lawful linkages
the effective surface of CO2/O2 exchange, so does between sensory and motor systems that explain
the infinitely more differentiated internal structure how action can be perceptually guided in a
of our nervous system extend the effective sensory perceiver-dependent world.”
and motor surfaces that allow us to interact with a (Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1999, p. 173)

ba erveldt, verh eggen 173


Similarly, O’Regan and Noë (2001) present their a Wittgensteinian notion—but not propositional
sensory motor contingency theory of perception as an agreement or equal mental content. We will come
enactive theory and claim that perception needs to back to this point later in this chapter.
be understood not in terms of sensory input but in In everyday life, we respond to each other’s
terms of the dynamic interdependence of sensory actions and expressions in terms of what we take
stimulation and embodied activity. them to mean. Meaning in this sense is not pre-
On all those accounts the particular nature of a fixed in the expressions themselves—as messages
perceptual experience cannot just be derived from to be decoded—but grasped in a practical, situated
an objective account of the reality perceived. What way. One of the main points of contention in the
appears from the perspective of an external observer discussion between enactivist and representational
as the world outside of the organism is, seen from understandings of culture concerns the issue of
an operational perspective, only an a modulation what allows such embedded interpretations to be
of experiences that arise as a consequence of the mutually meaningful. Precisely in answering this
self-organizing properties of the nervous system. question, proponents of a representational or medi-
According to Varela (1984) the mechanisms that ational cultural psychology see the need to evoke
are involved in self-organizing behavior of this kind culture as a system of already meaningful represen-
are inherently hermeneutic. Operationally closed tations or semiotic devices. Obviously culture can
systems do not adapt to the properties of a prefixed be studied as a symbolic system or as the history of
world but bring forth or enact a world as a domain of objectified expressions. However, problems emerge
significance with respect to the maintenance of the when culture as an objectified semiotic system is
organism’s systemic integrity. Operationally closed first epistemically cut off from the dynamic consen-
systems live in a phenomenal domain that remains sual coordinations of action by which meaning is
closed to the external epistemic eye. continuously produced in the first place and then
only subsequently used to explain sense-making
Consensual Coordination and practices in everyday life.
“Common” Sense Although there is clearly a place for the herme-
As we indicated above, the notion of operational neutic study of historical objectifications (e.g., in
closure does not prohibit social interaction but art, in technology, in established cultural rituals),
rather qualifies our understanding of it. On an enac- it makes epistemologically and psychologically no
tive account, interaction cannot be instructive and sense to explain everyday sense-making as medi-
social interaction can only be interaction between ated by culturally available semiotic tools or to
operationally closed systems—that is, structurally understand socialization as a process of internal-
determined systems capable of actively engaging the izing objectified cultural meaning. Notions like
world. This does not imply that the social can be “internalization” and “externalization,” which since
reduced to properties of individual cognitive sys- Berger and Luckmann’s seminal text have come to
tems. As argued, the domain of internal relations be commonplace in the social sciences (Berger &
of the nervous system and the relational domain of Luckmann, 1967), often present a superficial dia-
social interaction are non-intersecting and non-re- lectics and mistakenly put mind and culture in
ducible. Rather, it does imply that systems in social external causal relation to each other.8 The notion
interaction are always mutual interpreters of each of operational closure is meant to prevent us from
other’s actions. Precisely because they can neither this epistemic smuggling that occurs when sense-
have access to each other’s experience nor determine making is explained on the basis of sense already
the content of each other’s experience, they have to made. It allows us to focus more clearly on the activ-
express themselves and make sense of each other’s ity of sense-making itself, as a consensual coordina-
expressions consensually, yet each within their own tion of actions between human agents, who remain
cognitive or experiential domain. Indeed, expres- as such experientially autonomous. From an enac-
sion in social interaction is con-sensual, but with- tive perspective, the practical intelligence involved
out experience, strictly speaking, being shared. The in grasping embedded meaning, or “sense,” requires
necessity to maintain cognitive integrity requires no mediation but only our ability to act within a
mutual attunement rather than mutual instruction consensual domain.
or mutually imposed regulation. Hence, social inter- It is particularly the notion of operational closure
action involves “agreement in action”—to borrow that has been criticized by advocates of a cultural

174 enactivi sm
psychology that emphasizes openness, social inter- the correctness and appropriateness of actions and
action, and the possibility of sharing a semiotic expressions. As Wittgenstein (1956/1978, 1980),
cultural system. Unfortunately such critiques have probably more than anyone else, has extensively
often been based on misreadings and conjectures demonstrated, such standards for correctness require
triggered by the word “closure.” For example, normative stage setting, which can be provided only
Kreppner (1999) accuses enactivism to be a new by regular community practices and not by isolated
kind of monadology, in which fully self-enclosed organisms or individuals. The normativity of prac-
individuals are considered to operate blindly within tices and of personal action/expression embedded
a system of pre-established harmony, but he is thus within such practices is at the heart of any genuinely
confusing the notion of closure as a formal opera- cultural psychology.
tional term with that of closedness and the impos- Historically, the study of human behavior
sibility of interaction.9 Similarly, Chryssides et al. has been caught up in unproductive oppositions
(2009) consistently mistake operationally closed between those who understand human behavior
systems in social interaction for self-contained as part of the natural world and those who see it
individuals, although the literature on enactivism as an expression of something that is uniquely and
and autopoiesis makes abundantly clear that self- distinctively human. Varela (1991) has expressed
conscious individuals can only arise in the relational the hope that the notion of autopoiesis may help
domain of language (Maturana, 1978a, 1988a, to overcome the fruitless opposition, originating
1988b; Baerveldt & Verheggen, 1999). As we have in nineteenth century biology, between mechanist/
adamantly pointed out elsewhere (Baerveldt & reductionist viewpoints on the one hand and holist/
Verheggen, 1999; Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2001, vitalist on the other. If that be the case, it may also
2007), the central concept in enactive cultural have implications for psychology, which itself has
psychology is that of the consensual coordination of been divided between a largely mechanist biology
actions, but such a consensual coordination can- on the one hand and the more holistic humanities
not be adequately understood without the notions on the other. Fundamentally rethinking the rela-
of structural determinism and operational closure. tion between the component elements of a living
Before we move on to the enactive understanding of system and its organization as a whole has histori-
language and normativity, let us be clear once more cally been at the heart of several attempts to think
that Maturana and Varela deliberately and consis- of human physiology as involving a precarious
tently speak of closure in the operational or math- part/whole dialectics (e.g. Plessner, 1928/1975;
ematical sense of recursivity and not of interactional Goldstein, 1935/1995; Von Weizsäcker, 1940/1995;
closedness (Maturana & Varela, 1980). Obviously, Buytendijk, 1965/1974; Polanyi, 1958; Merleau-
the formal need for any autopoietic system to main- Ponty, 1942/1963, 1945/1962; Bateson, 1972,
tain its own defining organization and to distin- 1979).10 Important in all these accounts is the idea
guish itself as a unity from its background requires that somehow even in the basic physiological opera-
it to maintain a dynamic relation with its medium. tions of a living system, the organization that speci-
But as our discussion above shows, such a dynamic fies the organism as a whole is already implied. The
relation cannot be understood in terms of mutually radical implication, still to be rigorously elaborated,
instructive interaction or shared mental content. It is that in a crucial sense our own physiology is already
can only be understood as a consensual coordina- a characteristically human physiology.
tion of actions. Buytendijk (1974) expressed the need for an
“anthropological physiology,” centrally concerned
Autopoiesis, Purpose, and Intentionality with the body as expression of sense and Merleau-
The theory of autopoiesis as discussed until now Ponty (1942/1963) spoke of “le corps sujet,” the
presents a minimal account of meaning or signifi- body subject, as an ambiguous unity of subjectiv-
cance in the biological realm. If it is to contribute ity and anonymity and always exceeding “le corps
to a psychological account of culture, however, objective,” the objective body as conceived by an
then we will need to find a connection between the observer. Attempts to humanize our physiology have
minimal signification implied in the organization of (in principle) different implications for the relation
the living and sense-making as a culturally embed- between body and culture than accounts deriving
ded normative practice. Normativity in the realm from a reductionist physiology that is grounded
of everyday conduct involves implicit standards for in a causalistic ontology. They require us to admit

ba erveldt, verh eggen 175


“meaning” and “significance” in their fully human bent to fit the study of the life-world is unsuited to
sense as part of the natural world, yet without imply- address the life-world as normatively structured.
ing biological reductionism. The relation between Attempts in contemporary cognitive science to
the body as organism and the body as expression of naturalize a Husserlian phenomenology still rooted
sense is at the heart of enactive thinking, but, as we within the philosophy of consciousness (e.g., Petitot,
will see, this relation can be interpreted in different Varela, Pachoud, & Roy, 1999) may in fact come
ways, depending on how “organism” and “sense” are dangerously close to a sophisticated form of repre-
understood sentationalism, as Dreyfus already argued almost
Enactivism, as conceived by Varela, Thompson, three decades ago (Dreyfus, 1982). Thompson
and Rosch (1991), is an attempt to connect the (2007) admits that their initial dismissal of Husserl
body as an organizational whole to the body as lived in the 1991 book was inspired by Dreyfus’ depiction
experience. Varela, in the final years of his life, came of Husserl as a proto-cognitivist, and he expresses
to see autopoiesis as a way to give a formal natu- his current belief that enactivism can be reconciled
ralistic grounding to Kant’s idea (in the Critique of with a sophisticated reading of Husserl’s later work.
Judgment) of the organism as a “natural purpose” As cultural psychologists, we are interested in mean-
(Weber & Varela, 2002; Thompson, 2004). Kant ing in a normative sense; hence, we remain skeptical
already linked this idea to that of self-organization of attempts to derive an understanding of norma-
but, according to Thompson, only lacked the for- tive conduct from a philosophy of consciousness
mal language of self-reference we possess now. From or biologically grounded intentionality. Following
the perspective of a radically cultural enactivism, Dreyfus in this regard, we maintain that enactive
however, what is still lacking in Kant is not so much psychology and cognitive science may be better
the mathematics of self-reference and nonlinear served by breaking more radically with the philoso-
dynamics but an adequate account of the historical phy of consciousness and by following Heidegger,
dimension of sense and purpose. This is a critique Dewey, and Wittgenstein in asking about the intel-
already voiced by Wilhelm Dilthey, who argued that ligibility, unity, and order of public normative
although life encompasses both the organic and the conduct rather than private experience (Dreyfus,
mental, the values and purposes that inhere in it 1982, pp. 26–27). Like Dreyfus, we are interested
could only be fully understood in their temporal or in connecting the idea of normative practice to that
historical fulfillment (Dilthey, 2002, p. 249). of skillful coping at a psychological level. If human
Whereas Varela and Thompson in their subse- conduct is irreducibly normative, then we cannot
quent work—and despite their earlier critique— work our way up to it from a theory of intentional-
increasingly came to link the idea of biological ity grounded in the individual organism.
sense-making to Husserl’s phenomenological idea Although autopoiesis may (in principle) provide
of intentionality (e.g., Varela, 1999; Thompson, a basic naturalized understanding of purpose and
2007), we remain critical of attempts to move too intentionality in the biological realm, it can as such
quickly from the operational domain to conscious- not deal with the normativity of intention and pur-
ness and intentionality, without fully acknowledging pose in the human cultural realm. Thus, the prob-
the inherent embeddedness of human conduct in lem of intentionality and natural teleology brings
normative cultural practice. Even in his later work, us back to the problem of culture and the mean-
Husserl arrived at culture only secondarily, through ing or sense of historically situated action. Indeed
the philosophy of transcendental consciousness, the notions of sense and purpose are, as Thompson
whereas on the cultural account that we are propos- acknowledges, emergent relational properties and
ing here, the intentional relation of human actors to do not belong to the organization of autopoietic
their world is inherently a normative one: meaning, systems proper. On our account, they are indeed
sense, purpose, and intentionality are ever so many irreducibly normative notions that cannot simply
words for actions that remain sensitive to the possi- be derived from the natural teleology of individual
bility of getting it wrong. For example, the meaning organisms. Instead, they require a historical under-
of a word like “honor” is not derived from honor standing that nonetheless fully recognizes the partic-
as an ideal object in a self-sufficient consciousness ular organization of our closed human physiology.
but stands in relation to the countless cultural per- This brings us to the crucial issue of how embodied
formances that can properly be called honorable or human beings enter the domain of language and
dishonorable. Even a Husserl who is stretched and culture and how our natural teleology becomes

176 enactivi sm
attuned to a historical normative world. Given the on information transfer or mutually instructive
principles of structural determinism and organiza- behaviors. Yet, such systems can become structurally
tional closure, we cannot suddenly bring in a mean- coupled, and through a history of interlocked con-
ingful cultural order from the outside, as it were, or duct, a consensual domain can be established. Given
introduce language as a semiotic system that makes the structural plasticity of the nervous system and
shared cultural meaning possible. The question is the fact that all of its states are internally generated,
not “How does culture enters the human mind?” or the nervous system can recursively interact with the
“How is culture transmitted into and transformed states generated in it through consensual interac-
within the individual?”, as Kreppner (1999, p. 209) tion, thus allowing for a consensual coordination
suggests, but How does a particular coordination of of a consensual coordination of actions. According
our actions historically give rise to both “mind” and to Maturana, the consequence of such a recursive
“culture”? An account of human conduct as irreduc- consensual coordination of actions is language or
ibly normative need not be at odds with the recog- “languaging.”
nition of the biological roots of cognition. Thus we Again, it is important to maintain clean epis-
return to the issue of the relation between human temological accounting and to avoid phenomenal
physiology and human normative conduct and ask reductionism. Although operationally speaking
how, to paraphrase Herder, “die Natur dem Geist language becomes possible because both internally
halbwegs entgegenkommt” ([how] nature meets and externally generated perturbations of the ner-
spirit halfway). vous system12 map in the same phenomenal domain
of relations of relative nervous activity (Maturana,
Living in Language 1978a, pp. 48–49), language as such exists only in
The role of language is crucial in the way enac- the relational domain:
tive cultural psychology understands the entwine-
. . . [L]anguage is a biological phenomenon because
ment of personal conduct with the normative order
it results from the operations of human beings as
of culture. However, on the formal grounds we just
living systems, but it takes place in the domain of the
spelled out, language itself cannot be understood
co-ordinations of actions of the participants, and not
as a superpersonal structure detached from lived
in their physiology or neurophysiology. Languaging
embodied practice. As Merleau-Ponty has shown,
and physiology take place in different and non-
language never fully breaks the bond with the lived
intersecting phenomenal domains.
significance of bodily perception and expression,
(Maturana, 1988a, p. 45)
and in living speech there is no separation between
what is expressed and the manner in which it is Language has become a central focus in Maturana’s
expressed. For Merleau-Ponty (1964), language’s work, particularly from the late 1980s—arguably
meaning is therefore always indirect, ambiguous, even more than autopoiesis. Whitaker (2003) has
and allusive, just as for Maturana, it is connotative pointed out that there is also a shift in Maturana’s
or implicative before it can be denotative. Although work on language itself, from an early focus on the
it may be possible to conceive of other generative “mechanics” of language as rooted in operations
domains of expression (e.g. dance, ritual, music, of structurally determined systems in consensual
visual art), we could say that language constitutes coordination (Maturana, 1978a) to a focus, in later
at least a paradigm case for irreducibly normative work, on the orienting role of language in everyday
expression. As such it must be connected both to consensual practice (Maturana, 1988a).
our biology and to our history of consensual coor- Although Maturana’s account of language does
dinations with each other. not principally change and remains grounded in the
In Maturana’s earlier writings (e.g., Maturana, biology of cognition, his later focus on the social
1978a, 1978b, 1980), language as a biological phe- role of language seems to make it more adaptable
nomenon is considered a direct consequence of the for attempts to develop the enactive framework in a
ability of our nervous system to recursively interact socio-cultural direction. Indeed, whereas Varela and
with its own states.11 Language as a relational phe- Thompson are interested in the implications of the
nomenon, however, arises in the domain of human’s biology of cognition for enactive cognitive science,
consensually coordinated action. As discussed we have drawn particularly from Maturana’s under-
above, interaction between structurally determined standing of language in an attempt to develop the
and operationally closed systems cannot be based general outlines of an enactive cultural psychology

ba erveldt, verh eggen 177


(Baerveldt & Verheggen, 1999; Baerveldt, Verheggen, other’s mind nor simply put the right ideas in each
& Voestermans, 2001; Baerveldt & Voestermans, other’s mind.
2005; Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2007). Conceiving of language as orienting behav-
Although a focus on language as a social or ior fits well with social pragmatic approaches
relational phenomenon may seem to fit well with to language as a way to establish joint attention
discursive and semiotic approaches to culture, we and grammar as a way to perspectively orient one
have been careful to avoid the problem of phe- another with regard to the objects of joint atten-
nomenal reductionism, as displayed particularly tion (e.g. Tomasello, 1999). The idea of grammar
in approaches that give regulatory or semiotic as an orienting device has been well-demonstrated
status to cultural models, representations, and by Bamberg (2001), who showed that in produc-
mediational tools (Wertsch, 1985, 2007; Valsiner, ing either an “anger narrative” or a “sadness nar-
1998; Holland & Quinn, 1987; D’Andrade & rative,” 9-year-old children have typically learned
Strauss, 1992; Moscovici, 1988, 1998; Farr, 1996, to use grammatical features like transitivity and
1998; Marková, 1996, 2008) as well as discursive active/passive constructions to orient an audience
approaches that reject naturalism yet take the con- with regard to discourse purposes like blame or
stitutive and illocutionary power of language for empathy. Orienting behavior does not produce
granted (Gergen, 1999; Edwards, 1997; Edwards specific effects in the other—we can’t make others
& Potter, 1992). The implication of Maturana’s empathize with us—but relies for its success on the
account is that language cannot primarily be a capacity and willingness of the other to respond
semiotic system and that words and signs cannot in a way that remains sensitive to the cooperative
be properly conceived of as tools for the control of domain of interaction. Viewed from an enactive
actions, or mere rhetorical resources, but need to perspective, such orienting behavior is part of a
be accounted for in terms of culturally coordinated consensual dance in which neither partner controls
practices and acquired bodily dispositions. Culture the behavior of the other, but both continuously
as a symbolic or semiotic system does not explain adjust to one another to establish and maintain
consensual practice but requires explanation in common ground for the duration of the interac-
terms of the historically coordinated practices that tion. Linguistic behavior is orienting behavior and
give rise to it (Maturana & Verden-Zöller, 1996; although the notion of orientation may seem to
Baerveldt & Verheggen, 1999). have some similarity to that of regulation and co-
regulation in semiotic and mediational approaches
Language as Orienting Behavior to culture and language (e.g., Fogel, 1993;
Because interaction cannot be instructive or Valsiner, 1998), it avoids the implication of those
informative, enactivism conceives of communica- concepts that instructive interaction is possible. Of
tion as orienting behavior. Systems in communica- course the notion of language as orientation is not
tion do not transmit information to one another incompatible with genetic approaches to semiosis
through a discrete communication channel but or sense-making as such, as we will discuss later
mutually orient each other within their respective on. But reconciling a genetic cultural psychology
cognitive domains (Maturana & Varela, 1980, p. 57). on more Vygotskyan grounds with the enactive
We live in language, but when language is used to framework will require a reorientation from the
communicate, the partners in the communication language of mediation and control to that of coor-
recursively coordinate their actions in a manner dination, orientation, and style.
that orients them each within their own cogni-
tive domain (Maturana, 1978). Those cognitive Language and Emotion
domains remain operationally separate but become Whereas in his earlier work on language
structurally coupled in a history of mutually trigger- Maturana is particularly interested in the way lan-
ing behavior. Again, it is important to see that the guage gives rise to observers as well as to objects as
notion of mutual “triggering” does not imply that the products of recursive consensual coordinations
no genuine communication occurs. On the con- of actions that conceal their own origin, he became
trary, it is a formal way of indicating that genuine in his later work predominantly interested in the
communication within a linguistic domain requires role of emotions. As dynamical dispositions for
some kind of embodied “attunement” and that the action, emotions specify the relational domain in
partners in communication can neither read each which human beings operate. Maturana maintains

178 enactivi sm
that phylogenetically, our humanity did not Normativity, Training, and Style
arise directly as a consequence of our possession Our insertion into a cultural-historical order
of language or rational thought but as a conse- takes place not through the internalization of cul-
quence of a particular configuration of emotion— tural models or social representations nor by taking
particularly emotions related to intimacy—that up already meaningful semiotic devices. Rather, our
made consensual behavior possible (Maturana & socialization into the ways of a culture involves a
Verden-Zöller, 1996). Rational thought as such historical process of continuous attunement to consen-
is a consequence of us living in language, but the sually orchestrated community practices. Or, to use a
particular domain of rational behavior in which we different metaphor here, we are not like containers,
operate at any given moment in time (e.g., mak- each possessing, among other things, the shared ide-
ing love, or engaging in an academic argument) ational resources of our culture; we are like threads,
is specified by our emotions (Maturana, 1997). In intricately interwoven with the fabric of communal
the flow of our emotions, we continuously move life, yet each maintaining our own unique indi-
from one kind or class of relational behaviors to viduality.13 Enactive cultural psychology aims at a
another (ibid.). As we go through an ongoing flow genetic psychological understanding of the “warp
of emotions in our everyday lives, emotion and and weft” of personal lives in community.
language braid together in what Maturana calls
conversations, and the transgenerational conser- The Pivotal Role of Cultural Training
vation of living in conversations is what he calls As argued above, we are agents capable of being
culture: affected by the world, and the way we can be affected
is determined not by anything outside of us but by
In these circumstances, a culture is a closed network
the way we are disposed to the world. Those disposi-
of conversations which is learned as well as conserved
tions involve themselves an intricate entwinement
by the children that live in it. Accordingly, the worlds
or braiding of language and emotion in the body,
that we live as human beings arise through our living
and this entwinement makes both our life-world
in conversations as particular domains of consensual
and our psychological competences irreducibly nor-
coordinations of coordinations of consensual
mative. A central question for an enactive cultural
behaviors and emotions
psychology, therefore, concerns the particular his-
(Maturana, 1997)
tory of training by which normative dispositions
Hence, where we saw earlier that the enactive cog- are acquired. We use the word training here very
nitive science proposed by Varela, Thompson, and much in the Wittgensteinian sense of the word
Rosch moves in the direction of a transcendental (see Wittgenstein, 1956/1978, 1958/1974). In
grounding of consciousness and intentionality in contrast with representations, normative disposi-
the natural purpose of the organism, Maturana’s tions can be understood neither as states of mind,
ideas about the entwinement of body, emotion, and nor as states of the body. As Wittgenstein’s analyses
language seem to point in the direction of a more have convincingly demonstrated, skills and disposi-
immanent grounding of our ways of being disposed tions are dynamic and can only be demonstrated in
to the world. Elsewhere (Baerveldt & Voestermans, practice—that is, in the public realm where they are
2005), we discussed the entwinement of embod- susceptible to normative correction. As such, they
ied normativity and affectivity in terms of the nor- are not merely externalizations of knowledge that
mative structure of our human reality. We argued we must first possess internally.
that normativity is indeed inherently embodied Charles Taylor (1995) has argued that the
and affective in nature, just like our emotions expressions of linguistic agents take place within a
and bodily dispositions are inherently normative. realm of irreducible rightness, where the appropri-
Understanding that language occurs in two struc- ateness of expressions is not merely a matter of their
turally coupled but non-reducible phenomenal pragmatic effect in a social situation. For example,
domains and that linguistic behavior is always the words “I am sorry” may be the right words to
embodied and entwined with emotion opens the use regardless of whether they are successful in
way to a genetic understanding of cultural norma- restoring the contact between us (pp. 104–106).
tivity through the acquisition of durable bodily The cultural realm of jokes, requests, apologies,
dispositions and normative skills. We will return to offenses, and so forth is irreducibly normative,
this below. but also inescapably ambiguous, as, for example,

ba erveldt, verh eggen 179


the question “Is this a joke or an offense?” can be is typically called an embodied skill and what
resolved neither by appealing to a prefixed reality Wittgenstein calls a technique, rather than a set of
nor on the basis of representational knowledge. rules: “[O]nly through a technique can we grasp a
As Aristotle already saw, normative action requires regularity” (Wittgenstein, 1956/1978, VI.2). In the
practical understanding, and this practical under- case of concept formation, the crucial implication
standing is dispositional rather than propositional. is that concepts can principally not be detached
It is acquired as personal knowledge or understand- from techniques of application and hence neither
ing and cannot simply be passed on or internalized. from their mode of acquisition. Our understanding
It requires repetitive practice and personal training. of a concept is inherently a genetic one. One does
To master a skill, one has to practice that which is not simply possess a concept, but one demonstrates
to be mastered. (L. de- + monstrare to show) conceptual under-
Training on Wittgenstein’s account is a history standing by showing that one can go on in practice.
of trials or attempts in a context of normative cor- For Wittgenstein, as for enactivism, to know is to
rection. Indeed, like in Vygotsky’s genetic account, show and it is in this sense that the performances
for Wittgenstein, cultural training initially relies on both of the novice and of the cultural master can
the guidance of those already more competent than never be truly internal; they remain bounded to
the novice learner. For Wittgenstein, the crucial public criteria and normative correction.
moment in entering the normative realm lies not
primarily in the use of signs but in the nature of the Training and Normative Competence
training process itself, which fixes and constrains Situated normativity involves an intricate rela-
our ways of acting in such a way that we become tionship between unreflective skillful action, percep-
bound to the normativity of cultural practices (for tion, and emotion, and according to Wittgenstein,
a comparison of Wittgenstein and Vygotsky in this this relationship is forged by cultural training and
regard, see Williams, 1999, pp 188 ff.). We could participation in communal customs (Rietveld,
say that through training we develop a practical feel 2008). On an enactive account, the transition to
for the situated and dynamically enfolding norma- normative understanding is marked not by the use
tivity of particular cultural practices. To return to of tools or signs as such. Rather, it is marked by
our metaphor above, training is precisely the way the unreflective ability of actors to recognize their
in which we are woven into the normative fabric own behavioral or expressive response to the expres-
of society. sive conduct of others at different times as in some
Wittgenstein recognized that the irreducible sense the same. Normative judgments are recur-
normativity of cultural practice is nonetheless a sive judgments of sameness in our own expressive
genetic accomplishment on the level of individual responses. They are neither possible by virtue of
actors. In Wittgenstein’s terms, the behavior of the some kind of introspection, nor as a consequence
novice may conform to a rule (in the sense that in of conscious reflection, but rather because of the
the eye of an observer it fits certain patterns), but it way those responses are embedded in community
is not yet genuine rule following (in the sense that practices. Crucial in such recognition is the social
the actor recognizes the normativity of these pat- nature of normative understanding. There is noth-
terns). Indeed, not unlike the way Vygotsky sees a ing in individual instances of behavior that can
crucial qualitative change in a child’s development serve as objective standard for recognizing similar
from pseudo-concepts to genuine concepts (see instances. For example, there are no objective stan-
van der Veer & Valsiner 1991, pp. 264–265), so dards for what constitutes a joke or an offense. To
does concept formation on Wittgenstein’s account say it slightly differently: If recognition of sameness
require a qualitative change from mere conformity in behaviors or expressions would merely be based
to the rules implied in the concept to acting with on the cognitive powers of isolated individuals, any
a sense of the necessity of those rules. In enactive behavior could be made out to be the same or differ-
terms, this qualitative change can be seen as a move ent as any other behavior, at an individual’s whim,
from mere repetition or regularity, as facilitated by so to say (Williams, 1999, pp. 174–175). Therefore,
the training situation, to participation in a domain required for recognitions of sameness are commu-
of recursive consensual coordinations of actions that nal standards or constraints that facilitate normative
allows one to grasp that regularity. What is acquired correction; one has to be able to say/recognize: this
in this process is what in the enactive paradigm is not how you (properly) use a table/pen/hammer,

180 enactivi sm
this is not a (proper) joke/request/apology, or this is are able to recognize sameness or regularities in our
not the proper word for that, and so forth. consensual uses of tables, such that particular uses
Normative distinctions require that the agent come to have normative status. This is when we can
making them is capable of recursively recogniz- say: “This is (not) how you use a table,” or “This is
ing coherences and regularities in her/his own (re) (not) really a table.” No particular table is inherently
actions. a standard or exemplar for tables in general. A table
On Wittgenstein’s account, the standards for the can only acquire this particular normative status by
recognition of sameness cannot be provided by mere its place within a particular cultural practice.
regularities in individual behavior over time; rather, In practice, there is always a possibility that a
those standards can only be provided by regularities table is used in a nonconventional way (e.g., to slide
in community practices. As we argued above, even down a hillside, to block a door) or that something
perceptual features of objects are not just stimu- else than a “standard” table (e.g., an orange crate,
lus features (e.g., we don’t perceive the wavelength a glass plate hanging on four cables from the ceil-
of light falling on the retina); they are consensual ing) is used as one. However, nonstandard uses and
distinctions in the sense described above. On an deviations can be recognized as such not because we
enactive account, we cannot just impose concep- have a fixed concept of things like tables but because
tual categories onto our perceptual understanding we have regular, common, or normal uses for them
of the world; rather, in conceptual understanding, within our everyday practices. This means that con-
we recursively distinguish our own generic and cepts and normative uses must be rooted in histori-
differential response to the entities we first distin- cal regularities—that is, in the practical harmonious
guish within a domain of regularities or coherences agreements over time of a community of people. We
in forms of life—a consensual domain. Normative can only have a concept of table if there is a regu-
(e.g., linguistic or conceptual) distinctions are nec- lar and largely harmonious use of tables—that is, a
essarily second (or higher)-order distinctions—that custom concerning tables. Moreover, what is true for
is, consensual distinctions of consensual distinc- a concept like “table” is even more evident in the
tions. Therefore, normative sameness relies on case of concepts for intangible entities like “honor”
regularities in consensually coordinated actions and and “motherhood.” The concept and normativity of
what is recursively recognized as the same is not the honor and motherhood cannot be an abstraction
objective stimulus features of pregiven entities or from anything that is given to us in terms of mere
events but one’s own repeated behavioral response stimulus features. Instead, the concepts of honor
to certain events or situations as part of regular and motherhood can only arise against the back-
or repeated community responses. Things (tables, ground of historical practices that are recursively
hammers, jokes, offenses) are the same because recognized and idealized in a way that allows both
we are recursively (but not necessarily reflectively) for normative correction and creative stylization.
aware that we typically respond to them in similar Hence, our response to entities like tables, or
ways and that this is the way we ought to respond jokes, or offenses is never fixed. On the contrary,
to them under normal circumstances. in our cultural training we gain a certain expressive
Take a simple concept like “table.” The concept freedom, not—as some have argued—by the medi-
of table is not merely an abstraction of the stimu- ational use of signs but by acting within a domain
lus features of all (or many) particular tables. We of recursive consensual coordinations of actions that
don’t arrive at it through inductive extrapolation, allows signs to have meaning in the first place. Such
like Bruner, Goodnow, and Austin (1965) have recursive consensual coordinations involve both
proposed, but through a certain repetition in our skillful conformity with normative community
practices. Tables are tables by virtue of the prac- practice and coherent deformations or stylizations
tices we have organized around them. The concept of those practices (Baerveldt, 2007, 2009). Herein
“table” can therefore only be a recursive consensual lies the difference between a linguistic or norma-
coordination of those practices. In everyday life, we tive agent and a nonlinguistic animal like a dog.
use tables to sit around, to put things on and to eat Behaviorally speaking, a dog could be conditioned
from. Those consensual practices are not prescribed to respond in a predictable way to a signpost, but
by any particular rule, but they are the dynamical this would not yet imply that it has a conceptual
consequences of a history of consensually coordi- or normative understanding of the signpost. The
nated actions. The concept of table arises when we dog has no awareness of getting it right or wrong.

ba erveldt, verh eggen 181


Taylor (1985, p. 228) has noted that historically Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and Merleau-Ponty have
the role of the awareness of the normativity of our most cogently critiqued the insidious Cartesianism
expressions is what distinguishes Herder’s expres- at the heart of our understanding. Critical to the
sivist account of language from Condillac’s more program of an enactive cultural psychology is
designative understanding. Herder (1772/2002a) whether their critique holds up against the enactive
uses the word Besonnenheit, which typically gets view we have presented.
translated in English in terms of “reflection.”14 But
as argued above, this Besonnenheit is not a cognitive Representation and the Problem of
power of isolated individuals; it is the hallmark of Normative Sameness
operating within the irreducibly normative realm of Any ideational account of culture, or any account
language. of culture as involving an orchestration of people’s
In his introduction to the 1962 English trans- beliefs, has to deal with the problem of normative
lation of Vygotsky’s Thought and Language Jerome sameness of beliefs—that is, the issue of how the
Bruner credits Vygotsky for being the true architect people constituting a historical community seem to
of the “Second Signal System,” proposed initially by have certain beliefs in common. The need to under-
Pavlov, “that provides the means whereby man cre- stand the sameness of beliefs in normative terms fol-
ates a mediator between himself and the world of lows from some of the fundamental problems with
physical stimulation so that he can react in terms the mentalism of a standard cognitive account. On
of his own symbolic conception of reality” (Bruner, a mentalist account, beliefs are essentially mental
1962, p. x). As Bruner explained 20 years later, the representations, which implies that the problem of
notion of the Second Signal System captures the dis- sameness can be tackled only in terms of the ref-
tinction between stimuli that act directly on the ner- erential relation involved in such representations,
vous system (the First Signal System) and those that either to states of affairs in the real world or—as
are mediated by language and concepts (the Second) in Husserl’s phenomenology—to ideal objects in
(Bruner, 2004, p. 10). As we discussed above, on the mind. It is well-known that Wittgenstein spent
the enactive view, there are no stimuli that can act the best part of his later life to contest this refer-
either directly or in a mediated way on the nervous ential view of mind, and we will only briefly deal
system. Instead, in humans, a recursive consensual with it here. Earlier we evoked Wittgenstein in sup-
coordination of actions facilitates the normative port of the enactive paradigm and the dispositional
stage setting that is required for the use of signs, understanding of cultural learning we are propos-
tools, and concepts. The proper genetic question is ing here. Now we will address the implications of
therefore not primarily how we take up culturally Wittgenstein’s analysis for an understanding of nor-
available signs but how we acquire the embodied mative sameness and confront the enactive/disposi-
dispositions that allow us to act competently within tional view of culture with attempts to understand
human consensual domains and language. culture in terms of socially shared representations.
The main issue to be addressed in this section is
Culture and Belief whether introducing the idea of shared or social rep-
Now that we have discussed the idea of the resentations can salvage the representational view or
normativity of culture as involving an intricate whether social representation theory remains essen-
entwinement of linguistic behavior and emotion, tially caught up in Cartesian mentalism. We hope
established through cultural training, are we in this discussion may cast further light on the differ-
a position to confront some of the problems that ence between a representational and a dispositional
plague a cultural psychology still caught up in a or enactive account of normative sameness.
mentalist framework? Cultural psychology, in many
of its incarnations, is often seen as an attempt to Social Representations
overcome Cartesian dualism and self-contained Following Wittgenstein in this regard, on an
individualism by introducing the idea of the inher- enactive account, what is required to anchor refer-
ently social nature of knowledge and understand- ential or representational relations are not mental
ing. Yet, at the heart of such attempts remains often capacities but regular uses, or practical—as opposed
a more insidious form of Cartesianism that remains to merely propositional—community agreement
mentalist in its orientation and that maintains a fatal in the uses of words, symbols, or signs. Meaning
gap between knowledge and being. Philosophers like or sense has an irreducibly normative dimension,

182 enactivi sm
and standards of correctness can only exist as part everyday life becomes orderly in the first place.
of community practices. This effectively dispels the When social representation theorists speak, after
need to evoke mental representations, but of interest Moscovici, of the anchoring and objectification of
to the possibility of a genuinely social and cultural knowledge, they again describe the way in which
psychology is the issue of whether a more systemic objective reality is generated by a process in which
notion of representations and common beliefs can conscious knowledge recedes into the background of
escape the implications of Cartesian mentalism. taken-for-granted, common sense knowledge. Their
Advocates of a social representation approach to psy- dialectics is similar to that of Berger and Luckmann
chology (e.g., Moscovici, 1988, 1998; Farr, 1996, (1967) sociology of knowledge but entirely misses
1998; Markova, 1996, 2008) have attempted to the Wittgensteinian critique that points to the
offer such a systemic understanding, using what necessity of the practical normative stage setting or
they consider to be a social, rather than merely men- consensual practice that is required for anything to
tal, understanding of representation. count as knowledge.
From an enactive perspective, we have elsewhere A more radically cultural psychology can take
critiqued some of the basic epistemological assump- its cues from Wittgenstein but also, for example,
tions underlying social representation theory and Heidegger by prioritizing cultural practice over
similar theories relying on a notion of shared cul- shared knowledge and conscious deliberation. For
tural knowledge (Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2001, Wittgenstein, like for Heidegger, understanding
2007). Even purportedly systemic theories of the is only exhibited in our doings, and as such it is
intrinsically social in psychology often remain sur- misleading, even, to talk about background intelli-
reptitiously committed to a form of mentalism, by gibility as mere common sense knowledge. Rather, in
conceiving of the social in psychology as shared both Wittgenstein and Heidegger, we find the idea
representations, schemata, cultural models, and so of a total coordination of our background practices
forth. For example, Farr (1998) presents what he that generates, as it were, a total style of being, or
calls a “minimal definition” of a social representa- form of life, in light of which particular things can
tion: “A representation is social if it is, or has been, show up for us as meaningful. Understanding the
in two or more minds” (p. 291)—thus implying primary way in which we are bound to such a total
that before they are social, representations can be normative world cannot rely merely on a theory of
in just one mind. Nonetheless, social representa- common sense knowledge. It requires an account
tion theorists have often been careful to distinguish of how practical activities become consensually
themselves from an overly mentalist social psychol- coordinated and ritualized and how participants to
ogy, stating, for example, that social representations cultural practices acquire the dispositions to act as a
involve actions as much as thought (Chryssides et al., matter of course, with right, but without requiring
2009), that they involve both conscious and uncon- justification, to paraphrase Wittgenstein.
scious accounts of meaning (Daanen, 2009) and
that they are dynamic rather than static (Markova, Normativity and the Holomorphic Principle
2008). Still, Markova maintains “that representa- The problems with a social representation
tions are modalities of knowledge and their functions approach become particularly clear when we con-
are to shape activities, communication and to create front the enactive approach with what we consider
reality” (p. 474, our emphasis). to be one of the most sophisticated attempts of social
In all these cases, the sharedness of the repre- representation theorists to deal with the problem of
sentation is supposed to rescue it from mentalism, the normativity of practices. Wagner and Hayes
but it is precisely in the way an epistemic notion (2005) claim, “If meaningful practice is to be estab-
of knowledge is prioritized as “shaping” activity lished for the social whole, (the group), one has to
and “creating” reality that the Cartesian schema is assume that its parts (the individual members) share
essentially maintained. On the Cartesian account, a representation which contains the essential aspects
meaningful order does not inhere in life but can of the entire situation, that is, the entire group”
only be imposed through knowledge. Indeed, social (p. 278). Such holomorphic social representations
representation theory first limits its social account are seen by them as conditions for meaningful social
to lay knowledge of life and then mistakenly identi- practice in the sense that they allow social actors to
fies this knowledge as that what orders life, rather “meaningfully correlate their actions” rather than to
than identifying the consensual practices by which be at the mercy of blind “trial and error and erratic

ba erveldt, verh eggen 183


experience.” However, how those representations turns out that not enactivist but precisely mental
acquire their semiotic and regulatory power in the and social representationalist accounts of culture are
first place remains unclear in their account. For essentially prefixed harmony models. They presup-
example, what makes it possible for the members of pose the commonalities in human understandings
a community to understand those representations for which they allege to account.
in the same way, if indeed social representations are Shared representation cannot underlie agree-
precisely supposed to make common understanding ment in action, because such agreement requires
possible? Moreover, how does one know that one’s both the kind of dynamical stage-setting itself
own representation of the total social situation is facilitated by histories of consensually coordinated
indeed the same as that of others within the com- conduct and the mastery by social actors of specific
munity? If social representations are supposed to do semiotic competencies; competencies that, as we
explanatory work here, the argument is essentially saw, can only be acquired by a history of training.
tautological. Therefore, to remain consistent, we have to reverse
Advocates of sharedness and openness have the epistemic and ontological priorities by assum-
rightfully argued that a psychology of ideational ing that social representation is not a condition for,
processes cannot be a psychology of isolated indi- but a consequence of, the social-normative nature
viduals. Enactive cultural psychology, too, consid- of practices. Seen in this light, the holomorphic
ers fully-fledged cultural competence to exist in the principle is reflected in the idea of the irreduc-
relational or normative domain. As we discussed ible normativity of human action and expression.
earlier, the enactive argument for operational clo- Individual actions and expressions make sense only
sure has often been misunderstood as an argument against the background of the totality of a world
for self-contained individualism or, worse, an argu- that in its communal and historical character is irre-
ment for a form of reductionism that attempts to ducibly normative. Such a totality cannot be one
derive the properties of culture entirely from the that is conceptually grasped or shared; it must be
properties of individual cognitive agents. However, implied in the way we already live and expressed as a
as we have just argued, the problem of reductive whole in an entire style of being.
individualism is a consequence not of recognizing Rather than representational knowledge, cultural
the operational integrity of cognitive agents but of competence is a stylization of a total way of life, a way
endowing those agents with internal mental proper- of simultaneously grasping the world and one’s own
ties like beliefs and assuming that culture as a collec- way of being in the world. For example, learning to
tive system must somehow imply a mechanism for become a man in a world governed by honor requires
the sharing of beliefs. not just the accumulation of cultural knowledge of
If, in Cartesian fashion, the problem of a com- honor but the acquisition of a general way of going
mon world is conceived of as that of the relation of about in the world—for example, by particular
inner cognitive schemata to an independently exist- displays of masculinity and sexual prowess, verbal
ing world or to the cognitive schemata of others, mastery in the realm of competition with other
the notion of sharedness appears to be the only way man, demonstrating proper respect with regard to
to restore common reality. Indeed, on the surface it superiors, showing control over the women in one’s
seems that social representation theory offers a way household, and demonstrating trustworthiness and
to break out of self-contained individualism and honesty with regard to equals and hospitality with
Cartesian dualism, by opening up the mind to the regard to guests (e.g., Bourdieu, 1979; Gilmore,
possibility of shared mental content. But it is pre- 1987). All of those virtues belong to an integral
cisely the language of mental content—and not that world, which relies for its consensual enactment on
of operational closure—that inevitably leads back a largely implicit sense or practical understanding
to mentalism and self-contained individualism, as of the game by its participants. This practical sense,
it is unable to adequately conceive of the normativ- acquired through an ongoing process of cultural
ity of ideational activity. Sharedness cannot really training, allows them to express the right things at
be a solution here. As we have argued elsewhere the right time in the right proportion (Bourdieu,
(Verheggen & Baerveldt, 2007), it is the makeshift 1990). With Heidegger, radically cultural enactiv-
solution that remains after we have already mistak- ism holds that such grasping or understanding of an
enly started our account of culture, or our common entire world necessarily precedes and embraces cog-
world, from the idea of mental content. Now it nition in a more narrow—merely epistemic—sense

184 enactivi sm
of that world. This makes stylized cultural compe- becoming a competent moral agent—that is, a per-
tence an ontological category rather than a merely son within a normative world.
epistemic one. As we argued before, this is the gen-
eral ontological understanding of “knowing” within Future Directions
the enactive program, which makes knowing effec- Enactive cultural psychology is centrally con-
tively indistinguishable from believing and being cerned with the dynamic consensual coordination
(Baerveldt & Voestermans, 2005).xv of actions by which meaning and sense are continu-
ously enacted or produced. One of the most impor-
Enactivism and the Need for a tant implications to follow from a radically enactive
Genetic Psychology cultural psychology involves the need to resist the
Enactive cultural psychology is concerned with common tendency to attribute causal power to
the normative dispositions—expressive skills and culture and to use it in an explanatory account of
styles—that make us competent cultural practitio- our coordinated actions. The appeal to a non-dif-
ners. The crucial implication of an enactive view is ferentiated and abstract notion of culture is char-
that such normative dispositions cannot be under- acteristic of so-called “cross-cultural approaches” in
stood as internalized rules, norms, or representa- psychology, even where they have recently come to
tions. There is nothing in the individuated human be called “cultural psychology” (e.g., Kitayama &
organism that could be recognized as normative, Cohen, 2007). Whereas cross-cultural psychology is
because normativity essentially belongs to the social mainly interested in finding psychological universals
domain and is inherently bound to public, or con- through cross-cultural comparison, the label “cul-
sensually enacted, standards. However, becoming a tural psychology” is typically used to indicate a field
participant to a cultural community requires that of psychological study that is more concerned with
our natural affective responsivity must be brought the ways cultural values, belief systems, and practices
into accordance with structured community prac- shape psychological processes. Unfortunately, cul-
tices. Because the demand for clean epistemological tural psychology thus conceived remains too often
bookkeeping prohibits phenomenal reductionism, committed to an abstract notion of culture and fails
we cannot smuggle cultural normativity into an to adequately describe the genetic and dynamic pro-
operational account of what happens in the human cesses by which people become competent partici-
organism. This also precludes any straightforward pants to their cultures. Therefore, enactive cultural
account of socialization as the internalization of psychology allies itself with other genetic psycho-
cultural rules. Strictly speaking, normative skills or logical approaches to culture but is in turn careful to
dispositions exist neither purely in the relational or avoid accounts that assign causal or semiotic power
expressive domain, nor in the operational domain, to culture apart from the way cultural meaning is
but express how those domains become structurally continuously enacted by its participants. Cultural
coupled through a history of cultural training, so normativity is embodied and consensually enacted.
that they move in the same direction, so to speak. In conclusion we want to briefly point out three pos-
Hence, although we can indeed give either a rela- sible directions for the genetic psychological study
tional account of social practices or an operational of embodied normativity, involving what we call
account of the self-referential operations of the ner- conversation, ritualization, and stylization. Our pro-
vous system, psychology has the possibility to insert posal here is not meant to be exhaustive; we merely
itself, as it were, between these two accounts, not want to point out some directions that may help us
by way of phenomenal reductionism but by way to go beyond a cultural psychology for which a mere
of a genetic account of the manner in which cul- appeal to culture holds explanatory power.
tural competence and normative style are acquired Language is at the center of most socio-cultural
and enacted. Rather than being limited to either approaches in psychology and in this sense our enac-
the study of cultural variation in neural processes tive approach is no exception. Although we already
(e.g., Chiao & Ambadi, 2007) or to the hermeneu- discussed the implication of an enactive approach
tic explication of the normativity implicit in our for an understanding of linguistic development and
historical practices (as in the tradition of Dilthey’s concept formation, a direction to be further devel-
historical hermeneutics, see Dilthey, 1977), cultural oped concerns the microgenetic role of conversa-
psychology can play a unique and critical role in tion in everyday life. As argued above, language is
understanding the genetic principles involved in embodied and the normativity of conversational

ba erveldt, verh eggen 185


interaction involves a braiding of emotion and lan- orchestrated conduct with mere conventionality or
guage as we move through the consensual domains commonalities in behavior.
we ourselves help to constitute. This means that A final direction for psychological research we
language cannot primarily be rhetorical or propo- want to point at here follows from the implication
sitional. Where discursive approaches like those of of an enactive approach that the generic normativity
Edwards and Potter (1992) mainly attend to issues of culture can only be taken up by its participants
of accountability and the anticipation of counter by being personally expressed. Genuine expressive
descriptions, an enactive approach would see such form, according to Merleau-Ponty (1964), never
issues as premised against a background of con- merely represents a given norm but always expresses
sensual and largely harmonious practice. The vast a coherent deformation of the norm and potentially
majority of conversation is necessarily participatory the birth of a new norm. Enactive cultural psychol-
and consensual, and although words like “I love ogy invites us to move away from an account of cul-
you,” “I’m sorry,” and “Look how beautiful” may ture as an already established normative system and
take on strategical utility, it requires a rather cynical toward an account of culture as an ongoing styliza-
outlook on language to claim that this strategical tion of a normativity that remains, so to speak, with-
use is all there is to language. Still, enactive cultural out positive terms. On the enactive account we have
psychology remains sympathetic toward the fine- presented here, the fabric of culturally orchestrated
grained analysis afforded by conversation analytical everyday life is considered to be inherently consen-
techniques, precisely because such techniques allow sual and normative. Yet, each expression, or each
us to render visible the ways in which consensual enactment of cultural normativity, is at the same
reality is actively maintained. time a unique stylization of that normativity. For
Ritualization is another way in which consen- example, whereas all cultures may be characterized
sual reality comes to have normative force without by implicit and explicit norms for the expression of
it having to rely in advance on a common semiotic masculinity and femininity, such norms are not just
system. Genetically speaking, ritualization is a pro- given and passed on; rather, each individual agent
cess that can take place in different genetic domains. takes up and enacts those norms in a personally sty-
For example, the idea of language as a consensual listic way. Seen in this light, culture itself is never a
coordination of a consensual coordination of actions fixed norm. It is a style—an ongoing deformation
fits quite well with both evolutionary and historical of deformations—that allows for an almost infinite
accounts of language as emerging out of gestural variety of recognizably meaningful expressions. A
forms of communication through a process of ritu- society that becomes increasingly multicultural and
alization (e.g., Armstrong & Wilcox, 2007). Of par- multiform is a particularly fertile ground for styliza-
ticular interest to an enactive cultural psychology, tion. Therefore, enactive cultural psychology is not
however, is the study of the ritualizations of every- interested in culture as a fixed conventional system;
day life. With its focus on more explicitly linguistic rather, it asks how human agents acquire expressive
forms of conduct, cultural psychology so far has or stylistic freedom by becoming masters of their
generally overlooked the ontogenetic role of ritual own culture.
in the enactment of consensual reality. For example,
how does a gift come to seal a friendship, how may
Notes
going out for a coffee come to communicate sexual 1. The original reference is to Herder, J. G. (1989). “Ideen
interest, and how does paying the bill after dinner zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit.” In: M. Bol-
establish social dominance; such questions require lacher (Ed.), Johann Gottfried Herder: Werke, Vol. 6. Frankfurt am
an account in terms of ritual rather than discursive Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag; translation by Fischer, 1997.
“aboutisms.” Ritualization is a natural consequence 2. Deleuze (1993) has shown that Leibniz’s monadology
can be interpreted in a way that shows it as organized around
of the repetitive and recursive character of human the idea of expression. According to Deleuze, Leibniz—just like
social practices. Thus, the ritualization of everyday Spinoza—relies on the idea of expression to overcome the fun-
life may give rise to countless gestures and signs damental problems inherent in Cartesianism. Viewed this way,
whose meanings remain largely tied to the particu- even Leibniz appears hardly as the spokesman for self-contained
lar domains in which they arise. individualism that some such as Kreppner (1999), make him out
to be (see below).
The study of everyday rituals and their forma- 3. From their particular understanding of structural deter-
tion may help to re-orient a cultural psychology that minism it also follows that determinism does not imply pre-
now often remains biased by confusing culturally dictability. Predictability is a notion that pertains only to the

186 enactivi sm
cognitive domain of an observer and has no value in the domain outer contrast. Valsiner’s own view is that collective culture and
of structural and organizational relations that determine the sys- personal culture are connected by a cyclical process of internal-
tem under observation. Moreover, because an observer, as a sys- ization and externalization or, in Vygotsky’s terms, between per-
tem operating within the natural world, is herself a structurally sonal sense and interpersonal meaning. This perspective allows
determined system, it follows, first, that an observer can only him to understand the genetic process by which self-regulation
attempt to predict the behavior of other structurally determined emerges (for an extensive discussion, see Valsiner, 1998, pp 100
systems with whom s/he interacts and, second, that therefore the ff.). From our own perspective, however, both inner and outer
structural features that the observer can distinguish in the system are modalities of expression, and as such we consider the notion
whose behavior is to be predicted are limited by the structure of of cultural appropriation to be more properly interpreted in light
the observer him- or herself. of Spinoza’s monism. Indeed, Vygotsky (1987) understands the
4. Bateson is generally recognized as one of the fathers of inner and the outer on a developmental continuum and not as
enactive thinking, and his thinking, too, has been compared to ontologically different substances or pseudo-locations (see also
Spinoza’s (e.g., see Charlton, 2008). In an attempt to radically Berducci, 2004). We propose an enactive or expressivist alter-
break with Cartesian dualism, Bateson specified six criteria for native to the internalization/externalization thesis in the idea of
mind: (1) A mind is an aggregate of interacting parts or compo- “style” (see below) and leave open, here, the issue of whether this
nents; (2) The interaction between parts of mind is triggered by perspective can be reconciled with Vygotsky’s cultural-historical
difference; (3) Mental process requires collateral energy; (4) Men- psychology.
tal process requires circular (or more complex) chains of deter- 9. Kreppner also simplifies Leibniz’s idea of pre-established
mination; (5) In mental process, the effects of difference are to harmony, which for good reason would later prove to be
be regarded as transforms (i.e., coded versions) of the difference extremely fruitful for von Uexküll’s idea of the Umwelt.
which preceded them; and (6) The description and classification 10. Most of these authors were profoundly influenced by
of these processes of transformation discloses a hierarchy of logi- Gestalt psychology in its various incarnations, and their thinking
cal types immanent in the phenomena. Although, Bateson uses prefigures in many ways that of present-day enactive thinkers.
the language of energy and information rather than that of struc- For example, the German physician and physiologist Viktor von
ture determinism, he comes to conclusions about the systemic Weizsäcker (1886–1957), whose work is now all but forgotten,
character of life and mind quite similar to those of Maturana. spoke extensively about the Gestaltkreis as both a dynamic unity
5. In his introduction to Autopoiesis and Cognition, Mat- of perception and movement and a coherency of perceiving sub-
urana (in Maturana & Varela, 1980, pp. xiv–xv) writes that the ject and world (see von Weizsäcker, 1940/1996). Particularly
language used in their original work on the frog’s visual system in the tradition of Goethe’s expressivist Lebensphilosophie, the
was still steeped in the traditional epistemology of information German-speaking world gave rise to various forms of holistic
pick-up and computation. In his studies on color perception in thinking with regard to life, which predate more recent ideas
subsequent years, Maturana came to the realization that many of self-regulation and biological autonomy. For example, in the
different visual configurations can give rise to similar color expe- early 1900s, we see Hans Driesch’s idea of organischen Regula-
riences. Therefore, to connect invariances of nervous activity to tionen and Jakob von Uexküll’s idea of the Umwelt und Innen-
the perception of color, rather than attempting to correlate the welt of animals. Then, in response to the perceived atomism of
activity in the retina with external physical stimuli, he realized his predecessor Wilhelm Wundt, Friedrich Krueger gave rise to
he would have to correlate the activity in the nervous system as the Leipzig school of Ganzheitpsychologie, later continued by
internally determined with the color experience of the subject. Friedrich Sander in the idea of Aktualgenese. Around the same
Although Maturana does not use the term, his crucial realization time we find in the Berlin tradition of Gestaltpsychologie Köhler’s
was that the color space of an observer is enacted by the dynamic idea of spontane Selbstgliederung and Selbstregulation. Unfortu-
activity of the nervous system itself and not determined by the nately, few of these ideas seem to have been preserved for poster-
external world, which plays only a triggering role in the phenom- ity (for a more detailed discussion, see Ash, 1991; Valsiner, 1998;
enon of perception. Valsiner & van der Veer, 2000).
6. In fact, the word “autopoiesis” itself is not used in The 11. Maturana claims that operationally speaking, language
Embodied Mind, although Varela, Thompson, and Rosch speak became possible when, as a consequence of having subjected act-
in more general terms about the autonomy of living and cogni- ing and interacting in the domain of pure relations to the process
tive systems (see also below). Thompson (2007) discusses it in of evolution, humans developed the ability to interact not only
detail, however, in his more recent book. with physical events but also with their own internal states (Mat-
7. Maturana and Varela use the term medium to refer to the urana, in Maturana & Varela, 1980).
space in which the organism realizes itself. The term is not simi- 12. From the perspective of the nervous system itself, there is no
lar with “environment,” which refers to the surrounding context internal or external, and the terms refer here merely to whether—on
as discerned by an observer. For the existence of the organism the account of an observer—the sensory surfaces of the organism
as a structure-determined system, it is necessary to maintain its are involved in those perturbations.
structural coupling with its medium—that is, to preserve struc- 13. Our use of the metaphor should not be confused with
tural complementarity between its own structure and that of its that of Cole (1992), who speaks of a mutual interweaving of per-
medium (Maturana, 1988b, section xiii). son and culture. In Cole’s view, culture and cognition are mutu-
8. Vygotsky and activity theorists like Leontiev have used the ally constitutive, but we believe this way of putting it is based
word appropriation (Russian: prisvoenie, German: Aneignung), on a category mistake. Rather, we speak of culture as a historical
which, as Valsiner (1998) notes, in the Russian language carries process of ongoing consensual coordinations of action.
a two-sided connotation. Valsiner points out that appropriation 14. Forster, in his translations of Herder’s Philosophical Writ-
is always an active, co-constructive process, yet insists—with ings (Herder, 2002), translates the two key terms Besinnung and
Leontiev—that this process only exists because of an inner/ Besonnenheit as taking-awareness and awareness, respectively,

ba erveldt, verh eggen 187


and points out that Besonnenheit is for Herder a precondition reversed: Essays by Pierre Bourdieu. London: Cambridge
of Besinnung (p. 82, note 33; on this point, see also Barnhard, University Press.
2003, p. 115, note 25). Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Stanford, CA: Stanford
15. Of course, given the inherent normativity of believing, University Press.
beliefs can still be held to standards of adequacy but not by evok- Bruner, J. S. (1962). Introduction to L. S. Vygotsky. In E.
ing a pre-given world. As Spinoza has argued, all experience is a Hanfmann and G. Vakar (Eds., Trans.), Thought and lan-
matter of being affected in a certain way, and for him the crucial guage (pp. v–x). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
distinction is between affects that are adequately understood and Bruner, J. S. (2004). Introduction to thinking and speech. In
affects that are not adequately understood. According to Spinoza, R. W. Rieber, D. K. Robinson (Eds.), The essential Vygotsky
whether an affect is adequately understood does not depend on (pp. 9–25). New York: Kluwer/Plenum.
independent truth conditions, but on our ability to articulate Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J. J., & Austin, G. A. (1965). A study of
the genetic links that show the cause of our affects to lie within thinking. New York: John Wiley.
our own nature. Buytendijk, F. J. J. (1974). Prolegomena to an anthropologi-
cal physiology. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
(Original work published 1965.)
References Charlton, N. (2008). Understanding Gregory Bateson: Mind,
Aristotle (2004). The Nicomachean Ethics. (J.A.K. Thomson, nature, and the sacred earth. New York: SUNY Press.
Trans.). London: Penguin. (Revised by H. Tredennick, origi- Chiao, J. Y. & Ambadi, N. (2007). Cultural neuroscience: pars-
nal translation published 1953) ing universality and diversity. In: S. Kitayama & D. Cohen
Armstrong, D. F. & Wilcox, S. (2007). The gestural origin of lan- (Eds.), Handbook of cultural psychology. New York: The
guage. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Guilford Press.
Ash, M. G. (1991). Gestalt psychology in Weimar culture. Chryssides, I., Dashtipour, P., Keshet, S., Righi, C., Sammut,
History of the Human Sciences, 4, 395–415. G., & Sartawi, M. (2009). Commentary: We don’t share!
Baerveldt. C. (2007). Cultural psychology as the study of nor- The social representation approach, enactivism and the
mative experience. In: V. van Deventer, M. Terre Blanche, fundamental incompatibilities between the two. Culture &
E. Fourie & P. Segalo (Eds.), Citizen city: Between construct- Psychology, 15, 83–95.
ing agent and constructed agency (pp. 104–114). Concord, Cole, M. (1992). Context, modularity and the cultural con-
Ontario: Captus. stitution of development. In L. T. Winegar and J. Valsiner
Baerveldt. C. (2009). Psychology is dead. Long live psychol- (Eds.), Children’s development within social context. Vol. 2,
ogy! The possibility of a post-critical psychology. In Th. Teo, Research and methodology (pp. 5–31). Hillsdale, NJ:
P. Stenner, A. Rutherford, E. Park & C. Baerveldt (Eds.), Erlbaum.
Varieties of theoretical psychology: International, philosophical Daanen, P. (2009). Conscious and non-conscious representation
and practical Concerns. Toronto: Captus. in social representations theory: Social representations from
Baerveldt, C., & Verheggen, Th. (1999). Enactivism and the expe- the phenomenological point of view. Culture & Psychology,
riential reality of culture. Culture & Psychology, 5, 183–206. 15, 372–385.
Baerveldt, C., Verheggen, Th., & Voestermans, P. (2001). Human D’Andrade, R. G., & Strauss, C. (Eds.) (1992). Human motives
experience and the enigma of culture. Toward an enactive and cultural models.
account of cultural practice. In J. R. Morss, N. Stepenson Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
& H. van Rappard (Eds.), Theoretical issues in psychology Danziger, K. (2001). Wundt and the temptations of psychology.
(pp. 49–57). Boston: Kluwer. In R. W. Rieber & D. K. Robinson (Eds.), Wilhelm Wundt
Baerveldt, C., & Voestermans, P. (2005). Cultural psychology in history: The making of a scientific psychology. New York:
and the normative structure of reality. Theory & Psychology, Kluwer/Plenum.
15, 449–473. Deleuze, G. (1993). The fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (Tom
Bamberg, M. (2001). Why young American English-speaking Conley, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota
children confuse anger and sadness: A study of grammar in Press.
practice. In: K. E. Nelson, A. Aksu-Koç & C. E. Johnson Dilthey, W. (1977). Descriptive psychology and historical under-
(Eds.), Children’s language: Volume 10: Developing narra- standing (R.M. Zaner & K.L. Heiges, Trans.). The Hague:
tive and discourse competence (pp. 55–72). Mahwah, NJ: Martinus Nijhoff. (Original works
Erlbaum. published 1894 and 1927.)
Barnhard, F. M. (2003). Herder on nationality, humanity and his- Dilthey, W. (2002). The formation of the historical world in the
tory. Montreal, Canada: McGill-Queen’s University Press. human sciences. In R.A. Makkreel & F. Rodi (Eds.), Selected
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. New York: works Vol. 3. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Ballantine. Diriwächter, R. (2004) Völkerpsychologie: The synthesis that
Bateson, G. (1979). Mind and nature: A necessary unity. New York: never was. Culture & Psychology, 10, 85–109.
E. P. Dutton. Dreyfus, H. (1982). Introduction. In H. Dreyfus (Ed.), Husserl,
Berducci, D. (2004). Vygotsky through Wittgenstein: A new intentionality, and cognitive science (pp. 1–27). Cambridge,
perspective on Vygotsky’s developmental continuum. MA: The MIT Press.
Theory & Psychology, 13, 329–353. Eckardt, G. (1997). Völkerpsychologie—Versuch einer Neuentdeckung:
Berger, P., & Luckmann, T. (1967). The social construction of real- Texte von Lazarus, Steinthal und Wundt. Weinheim, Germany:
ity: A treatise on the sociology of knowledge. Harmondsworth: Beltz Psychologie Verlags Union.
Penguin. Edwards, D. (1997). Discourse and cognition. London: Sage.
Bourdieu, P. (1979). Algeria 1960; The disenchantment of the Edwards, D., & Potter, J. (1992). Discursive psychology. London:
world; The sense of honour; The Kabyle House or the world Sage.

188 enactivi sm
Farr, R. M. (1996). The modern roots of social psychology. and biology of language and thought: Essays in honor of Eric
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. Lenneberg (pp. 27–63). New York: Academic Press.
Farr, R. M. (1998). From collective to social representations: Maturana, H. R. (1978b). Cognition. In P.M. Hejl, W.K. Köck
Aller et retour. Culture & Psychology, 4, 275–296. & G. Roth (Eds.), Wahrnehmung und Kommunikation
Fischer, B. (1997). Toward a constructivist epistemology: Johann (pp. 29–49). Frankfurt: Peter Lang.
Gottfried Herder and Humberto Maturana. The European Maturana, H. R. (1980). Man and society. In: F. Benseler, P.M.
Legacy, 2, 304–308. Hejl, & W.K. Köck (Eds.), Autopoiesis, communication, and
Fogel, A. (1993). Developing through relationships. Chicago, IL: society: The theory of autopoietic system in the social sciences
University of Chicago Press. (pp. 11–32). Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.
Gergen, K. (1999). An invitation to social construction. London: Maturana, H. R. (1988a). Reality: The search for objectiv-
Sage. ity or the quest for a compelling argument. Irish Journal of
Gilmore, D. D. (1987). Honor and shame and the unity of the Psychology, 9, 25–82.
Mediterranean. Washington, DC: American Anthropological Maturana, H. R. (1988b). Ontology of observing: The biological
Association. foundations of self, consciousness and the physical domain
Goldstein, K. (1995). The organism: A holistic approach to biol- of existence. In R. Donaldson (Ed.), Texts in cybernetic theory:
ogy derived from pathological data in man. New York: Zone An in-depth exploration of the thought of Humberto Maturana,
Books. (Original work published 1935.) William T. Powers, and Ernst von Glasersfeld. Felton, CA:
Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effect of human kinds. In: American Society for Cybernetics [conference workbook].
D. Sperber, D. Premack & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cog- Retrieved online January. 2010, from Alfredo Ruiz (Ed.), at:
nition: A multidisciplinary approach (pp. 351–383). Oxford, http://www.inteco.cl/biology/ontology/index.htm.
UK: Clarendon. Maturana, H. R. & Guiloff, G. (1980). The quest for the
Herder, J. G. (2002a). Treatise on the origin of language. In M. intelligence of intelligence. Journal of Social and Biological
N. Forster (Ed.), Herder: Philosophical writings (pp. 65–166). Structures, 3, 135–148.
New York: Cambridge University Press. (Original work pub- Maturana, H. R. (1997). Metadesign. Santiago de Chili: Instituto
lished 1772.) de Terapia Cognitiva INTECO. Retrieved January, 2010,
Herder, J. G. (2002b). On the cognition and sensation of the from the World Wide Web: http://www.inteco.cl. . A version
human soul. In M. N. Forster (Ed.), Herder: Philosophical of this text has been published as Maturana, H. R. (1997).
writings (pp. 187–244). New York: Cambridge University “Metadesign”, In J. Brouwer and C. Hoekendijk (Eds.),
Press. (Original work published 1778.) Technomorphica. Rotterdam, Netherlands: V2_Organisatie.
Holland, D., & Quinn, N. (Eds.) (1987). Cultural models in lan- Maturana, H. R., Lettvin, J., Mcculloch, S., & Pitts, W. (1960).
guage and thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Anatomy and physiology of vision in the frog. Journal of
Press. General Physiology, 43, 129–175.
Israel, J. I. (2001) Radical enlightenment: Philosophy and the Maturana, H. R. & Poerksen, B. (2004). From being to
making of modernity, 1650–1750. Oxford, UK: Oxford doing: The origins of the biology of cognition. Heidelberg,
University Press. Germany: Carl-Auer.
Jahoda, G. (1993). Crossroads between culture and mind. Maturana, H. R. & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cogni-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. tion: The realization of the living. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
Kim, A. (2006). Wilhelm Maximilian Wundt. The Stanford Reidel.
encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition), Edward Maturana, H. R. & Varela, F. J. (1987). The tree of knowl-
N. Zalta (Ed.), retrieved from: http://plato.stanford.edu/ edge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston:
archives/win2009/entries/wilhelm-wundt/ Shambhala.
Kitayama, S., & Cohen, D. (eds.). Handbook of cultural psychol- Maturana, H. R. & Verden-Zöller, G. (1996). Biology of love.
ogy. New York: The Guilford Press. In G. Opp & F. Peterander (Eds.), Focus Heilpadagogik.
Kreppner, K. (1999). Enactivism and monadology: Where are Munchen/Basel, Germany: Ernst Reinhardt.
Baerveldt and Verheggen taking the individual and cultural Maturana, H. R. & Verden-Zöller, G. (2008). The origin
psychology? Culture & Psychology, 5, 207–216. of humanness in the biology of love. Exeter, UK: Imprint
Marková, I. (1996). Towards an epistemology of social rep- Academic.
resentations. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 26, Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). The structure of behavior. (A. Fisher,
177–196. Trans.). Pittsburg, PA: Duquesne University Press. (Original
Marková, I. (2008). The epistemological significance of the the- work published 1942.)
ory of social representations. Journal for the Theory of Social Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. (C. Smith,
Behaviour, 38, 461–487. Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published
Martin, J., & Sugarman, J. (2001). Interpreting human kinds: 1945.)
Beginnings of a hermeneutic psychology. Theory & Psychology, Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). Signs. (R. C. McCleary, Trans.).
11, 193–207. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. (Original work
Maturana, H. R. (1970). Biology of cognition. Biological published 1960.)
Computer Laboratory Research Report BCL 9.0. Urbana, Moscovici, S. (1988). Notes towards a description of social repre-
IL: University of Illinois. sentations. European Journal of Social Psychology, 18, 211–250.
Maturana, H. R. (1975). The neuropsychology of cognition. Moscovici, S. (1998). Social consciousness and its history.
In P. Garvin (Ed.), Cognition: A multiple view. New York: Culture & Psychology, 4, 411–429.
Spartan. O’Regan, J. K., & Noë (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision
Maturana, H. R. (1978a). Biology of language: The epistemology and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24,
of reality.” In: G.A. Miller & E. Lenneberg (Eds.), Psychology 939–1011.

ba erveldt, verh eggen 189


Petitot, J., Varela, F., Pachoud, B., & Roy, J-M. (1999). Naturalizing Varela, F. J., Thompson, F., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied
phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cogni- mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge,
tive science. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. MA: MIT Press.
Plessner, H. (1975). Die Stufen des Organischen und der Verheggen, Th. (1996). Durkheim’s représentations considered
Mensch: Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie. as Vorstellungen. Current Perspectives in Social Theory, 16,
Berlin/Leipzig: Gruyter. (Original work published 1928.) 189–219.
Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical Verheggen, Th., & Baerveldt, C. (2001). From shared repre-
psychology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. sentations to consensually coordinated actions: Toward an
Proulx, J. (2008). Some differences between Maturana and intrinsically social psychology. In J. R. Morss, N. Stepenson,
Varela’s theory of cognition and constructivism. Complicity: & H. van Rappard (Eds.), Theoretical Issues in Psychology
An International Journal of Complexity and Education, 5, (pp. 59–67). Boston: Kluwer.
11–26. Verheggen, Th., & Baerveldt, C. (2007). ‘We don’t share!’
Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: The normative aspect Exploring the theoretical ground for social and cultural psy-
of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117, chology: The social representation approach versus an enac-
973–1001. tivist framework. Culture & Psychology, 13, 5–27.
Spinoza, B. (2001). Ethics. (W. H. White, Trans.). Hertfordshire: Voestermans, P, & Baerveldt, C. (2001). Cultural psychology
Wordsworth. (Original work published 1677.) meets evolutionary psychology: Toward a new role for biol-
Taylor, C. (1985). Self-interpreting animals. In: C. Taylor, ogy in the study of culture and experience. In J. R. Morss,
Philosophical papers: Vol 1. Human agency and language N. Stepenson & H. van Rappard (Eds.), Theoretical issues in
(pp. 45–76). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. psychology (pp. 69–81). Boston: Kluwer.
Taylor, C. (1995). The importance of Herder. In C. Taylor, Vygotsky, L.S. (1987). The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky:
Philosophical arguments (pp. 77–99). Cambridge, MA: Vol.1, Problems of general psychology. (R. W. Rieber and
Harvard University Press. A. S. Carton (Eds.). (N. Minick, Trans.). New York:
Thompson, E. (2004). Life and mind: from autopoiesis to neuro- Plenum.
phenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology Wagner, W., & Hayes, N. (2005). Everyday discourse and common
and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 381–398. sense. The theory of social representations. New York: Palgrave
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Biology, phenomenology, and Macmillan.
the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Belknap. Weber, A. & Varela, F.J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural pur-
Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. poses and the autopoietic foundations of biological individu-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.
Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind: A sociogenetic approach to Weizsäcker, V. Von (1996). Der Gestaltkreis: Theorie der Einheit
personality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. von Wahrnehmen und Bewegen. Stuttgart, Germany: Thieme.
Valsiner, J. & van der Veer, R. (2000). The social mind: construc- (Original work published 1940.)
tion of the idea. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wertsch, J. V. (1985). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind.
Van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
A question for synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Balckwell. Wertsch, J. V. (2007). Mediation. In H. Daniels, M. Cole, &
Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Vygotsky
Elsevier North Holland. (pp. 178–192). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Varela, F. J. (1981). Describing the logic of the living, in Whitaker, R. (2003). Encyclopaedia autopoietica: An annotated
M. Zeleny (Ed.), Autopoiesis: A theory of living organization lexical compendium on autopoiesis and enaction, version 1.0.1.
(pp. 36–48). New York: Elsevier. Retrieved January 12, 2010 from the World Wide Web:
Varela, F. J. (1984). Living ways of sense-making: A middle http://www.enolagaia.com/EA.html.
path for neuroscience. In: P. Livingston (Ed.), Disorder and Williams, M. (1999). Wittgenstein, mind and meaning: Toward a
order: Proceedings of the Stanford International Symposium social conception of mind. London: Routledge.
(Sept. 14–16, 1981) (pp. 208–224), Saratoga, CA: ANMA Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical investigations (G.E.M.
Libri. Anscombe, Trans.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In (Original work published 1958.)
A. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the origin of self (pp. 79–107). Wittgenstein L. (1978). Remarks on the foundations of mathemat-
Dordrecht: Kluwer. ics. (G.E.M. Anscombe, Trans.). (3rd edition). Oxford, UK:
Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: a neurophenomenology Blackwell. (Original work published 1956.)
of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Culture and value. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
& J-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: issues in con- Wundt, W. (1900–1920). Völkerpsychologie (Vols. 1–10). Leipzig,
temporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 266–314). Germany: Engelmann.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Wundt, W. (1902). Outlines of psychology (C. H. Judd, Trans.).
Varela, F. J., & Goguen, J. A. (1978). The arithmetic of closure. St. Claires Shores, MI: Scholarly Press. (Original work pub-
Journal of Cybernetics, 8, 291–324. lished 1897.)

190 enactivi sm
CHAPTER

Positioning Theory: Moral


9 Dimensions of Social-Cultural
Psychology
Rom Harré

Abstract

A fundamental way in which cultures differ is in the taken-for-granted systems of rights and duties
implicit in the way lived storylines unfold in everyday social episodes. Positioning Theory developed as
a method of analysis aimed at revealing the storylines and implicit (sometimes explicit) ascriptions and
resistances to ascriptions of rights and duties to perform actions expressing social acts appropriate to
the situations recognized by participants in a strip of life. Analysis reveals a mutual determining of the
meanings of social actions as acts, lived storylines unfolding and local distributions of rights and duties so
to act. The concept of “positioning” has taken on two main senses in these studies—as the attributes of a
person or group relevant to positioning and, in the other sense, as an attribution of rights and duties. The
extensive literature of positioning theory includes studies ranging over great differences of scale from
the intrapositioning in which a person engages in private moral reflections through positioning issues
between the members of a small group of people in intimate interaction, up to the positioning discourses
of the protagonists of nation-states or religious communities.
Keywords: position, positioning, moral order, rights, duties, storylines, social representations.

To appreciate the place of Positioning Theory in contrast between the failed project of experimental
cultural/discursive psychology, a glance at the recent psychology and the growing successes of the discur-
history of psychology will be helpful. There are two sive/analytical approach.
paradigms for psychology that still confront one
another, especially in the United States. The main- The Old and New Paradigms
stream among psychologists in the United States According to the Old Paradigm, the task of psy-
still depends on a tacit presumption that psychology chology is to find the causes of behavior, although
is a causal science and that the proper methods are behaviorism as a primitive version of this paradigm
modeled on the experimental procedures of a rather has been abandoned in name and to a lesser extent
narrow part of physics. The rise of alternative concep- in practice. Much research in social psychology,
tions of psychology, as a study of patterns of meaning psychology of the emotions, cognitive psychol-
making and incorporating attention to moral orders, ogy, and so on is still based on the manipulation of
in Western Europe (particularly France, the United dependent and independent variables, abstracted
Kingdom, and Scandinavia) with reflections of these from real-life episodes, the results analyzed using
ideas in Asia and Australasia, presents an expanding statistical measures on the relative numbers of
global consensus on the human sciences. Smedslund instances of each behavioral type emitted by the
(2009) has developed a brilliant summary of the subjects.

191
According to the New Paradigm exemplified attention, to logical memory, and to the formation of
in such developments as cultural and discursive concepts. All the higher functions originate as actual
psychology, the task of psychology is to find con- relationships between individuals.
venient representations of bodies of knowledge (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 57)
that are required for the accomplishments of the
intentions, plans, and projects of human agents. In the context of social psychology according to
According to this paradigm, psychological phenom- the Old Paradigm, social phenomena were to be
ena are sequences of meanings of thoughts, actions, analyzed as if they were the result of individuals
feelings, perceptions, and so on, ordered according responding to extra personal stimuli inducing dis-
to norms, standards of correctness that may be only positions to behave in certain ways and bringing
local. New Paradigm research projects must con- about corresponding dispositions and responses in
form to two methodological principles: the relevant others. Then, these dispositions were
activated by local stimulus conditions. Tajfel’s stud-
Do not abstract phenomena of psychological
ies of prejudice (Tajfel, 1981) treated it as a state
interest from real-life episodes to such a degree that
induced in an individual, a belief or an attitude or
the original meaning is lost.
some such, rather than a feature of a matrix of social
Do not eliminate persons from the analysis
practices. Rather than trying to identify causes and
since the topic of investigation is the work of active
effects as the core explanatory devices in accounting
embodied knowledgeable agents attempting to
for human actions, according to the principles of
bring their projects to fruition.
the second cognitive revolution, we should look for
Positioning Theory is one of the ways that New narrative conventions—storylines immanent in the
Paradigm psychology has developed both in the- discourse practices in which psychological phenom-
ory and in method. The emphasis on local mean- ena actually exist.
ings and on local and labile moral orders of rights It is worth noting that the priority given to
and duties to act and to believe links Positioning public collective process over private personal cog-
Theory very closely to cultural psychology. Indeed, nition in the work of Vygotsky and Wittgenstein
it would be appropriate to see it as a part of the has been the topic of a long running debate among
program of the study of psychology as a cultural philosophers. Neo-subjectivists—particularly those
phenomenon. who follow the lead of J. R. Fodor (1976)—have
argued that the entire domain of psychology is
The Second Cognitive Revolution comprehended by mental states and the causal rela-
The New Paradigm approach came in part from tions between them. Language is made possible
the realization that many instances of cognitive by an inherent “language of thought” reproduced
processes, such as remembering and deciding, are in each human individual rather than as the most
not located in individuals but often exist only in advanced form of the practices of social commu-
a network of symbolically mediated interactions nication. In a recent article reviewing the debate
between the members of a group. Perhaps cognition Hans-Johann Glock has demonstrated the flaws in
is primarily interpersonal and only secondarily and neo-subjectivism by showing that the requirement
derivatively intrapersonal. The center of primary that a concept can be shared among several people
cognition shifts from the individual to the local cannot be met by any theory that depends on the
group, such as family, peers, research team, and so type/token distinction, as does Fodor’s. Concepts
on. This had been anticipated by L. S. Vygotsky (see as mental particulars would be tokens of con-
van der Veer, 2011). It is worth reproducing the cepts as abstract types. If it is concept as type that
famous aphorism in which he, echoing Pierre Janet, is shared, this would require the shared concept
applies this insight to an outline of the core process to be abstract. However, shared concepts appear
of human development. concretely in the actual discourses among human
beings, focused on common topics (Glock, 2009).
Every function in the child’s cultural development Cultural and discursive psychologists need not be
appears twice: first, on the social level, and later, troubled by the fear that at some deeply theoretical
on the individual level; first between people level, their enterprise has been undermined by an
(interpsychological) and then inside the child argument that purports to locate everything mental
(intrapsychological). This applies equally to voluntary “in the mind!”

192 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


Abilities and Skills and the Conditions and duties to act opens up another dimension, that
Under Which We Employ Them of the responsibility of the actor and of the group in
The rules for the use of skill and ability con- which the action occurs. With responsibility goes
cepts presume that the concept of a skill includes the role of praise and blame.
an intentionality component, tacit or explicit. Skills
and abilities are realized in activities that are directed Beyond the Notions of Causality
toward some end or outcome, even if the action to When a person behaves in a certain way in a
accomplish the end has become habitual. Moreover, particular social and material environment, he or
activities that realize skills and abilities are subject she and also they can be held responsible for what
to assessments of success, propriety, correctness, and has been done—that is, the actors must be treated
quality. This means that associated with any cluster as agents. It follows that social psychology must
of skill and ability concepts, such as those involved include moral concepts in its explanatory armory. It
in musical performance or sawing wood, are one or cannot be based on hypothetical causality.
more normative systems, involving extrapersonal, In the remainder of the chapter, I take the con-
social-historical and other collective considerations. cepts of “ability” and “agency” for granted without
When we come to use skill and ability concepts further analysis. The focus will be on the implica-
to explain some strip of human behavior, a three- tions of adopting the concept of “position” as a
level cognitive structure is required. generic concept covering assignments of rights and
duties to act and to know or believe at the core of
The Abilities Progression social psychological explanations. Position displaces
A psychologist observes a person, X, doing some- concepts such as “balance” (Heider, 1958), “dis-
thing, and interprets this strip of activity as the car- sonance” (Festinger, 1957) and “social compari-
rying out of a task—say, helping an aged person, Y, son” (Tajfel, 1981). These outmoded concepts are
out of a chair. What should we ascribe to the actor embedded in a theory of social psychology that
on the basis of this observation? Presuming the task focuses on hypotheses of essentially passive and
has been successfully accomplished, we can say that automatic personal cognitive processes that ignore
X has demonstrated that he or she has the ability the social origin and active efficacy of people as joint
to do it. Here is a two-level format—the behavioral constructors of social and psychological reality.
sequence is the phenomenon and the ascribed skill
is basis of an explanation—although more would Positioning in Relation to Social
be required, including whatever it was that set the Psychology
whole process in motion. However, we then notice Outlines of Positioning Theory
that Y is not a bit grateful for the assistance—he/she In all human interactions, there are asymmetries
indeed is rather cross. To understand this, we need in the resources for social action that are available
to insert a level between behavior and ability: the to each individual in concrete circumstances. Earlier
moral level. Has X been accorded the right to do theories that were sensitive to the importance of
this? Perhaps X is a paid caregiver and believes he moral norms presumed that differences in moral
or she has the duty to assist the old person to rise. standing as actors were to be explained by identify-
Here, we have a clash of tacit beliefs—X’s beliefs ing the kinds of social acts that were available to
about duty with Y’s beliefs about rights. individuals as members of groups or professions
In summary, we have the following layout: and so on—the domain of role theory. This was far
too primitive and coarse-grained to deal with real-
X can do Z X has an ability
life social episodes. Positioning Theory is based on
X may/may not do Z X has or lacks some position
the principle that not everyone involved in a social
X does Z X is an agent
episode has equal access to rights and duties to per-
A project may fail at any one of these stages. A per- form particular kinds of meaningful actions at that
son may have planned some activity but lacks the moment and with those people. In many interesting
skills to carry it off. Even equipped with the nec- cases, the rights and duties determine who can use
essary skills and relevant knowledge, a person may a certain discourse mode—for example, issuing
not be authorized to carry out the project in ques- orders, giving grades, remembering a past event. A
tion. Introducing the moral dimension through the cluster of short-term disputable rights, obligations,
attention that must be paid to beliefs about rights and duties is called a “position.”

h a rré 193
Positions are related both to the storylines real- because positioning someone as incompetent rela-
ized in the unfolding of episodes and to the acts that tive to other members is a familiar device to take
are the meanings of the intentional actions of the away the right to carry out some task. The impor-
people who take part. If a man and a woman are tance of this duality shows up in discussions of a
living out a nurse–patient storyline, then the man’s person’s character and history as an essential part
expressions of concern are readable as commisera- of the Congressional Hearings for appointments to
tion rather than condescension. the Executive or the Supreme Court in the United
We can explain differences in the availability of States. A study by Gilbert and Mulkay (1982,
rights and duties to act in certain ways for a per- pp. 383–408) showed how rights to be believed
son in a certain situation by reference to the social can be manipulated by rival teams of researchers
and personal attributes of that person in that situa- in debates about the acceptability of conflicting
tion. For example, who is positioned with the right research results. The role of character assassination
and perhaps even the duty to switch off a life sup- in such debates can be seen in terms of Positioning
port system of someone declared to be brain dead? Theory as a way of deleting the right of the claims of
The assignment of such a right can be a matter for a certain research team to be believed. In Classical
debate and conflict, in short of a discursive social Positioning Theory, these discursive procedures are
process, that takes account of the social and even identified as pre-positioning, on the basis of which
physical attributes of the people who claim that moral assignments are made—that is, actual acts of
right. There is no role of life closer (Grattan, 2008, positioning proper.
pp. 113–145).
Positions importantly determine the way people Alternatives to Position
have access to cultural resources. For an example of Erving Goffman (1981, p. 128) introduced the
claims for rights of access and denial of rights of term footing to refer to one sort of positioning pro-
access, contemporary life offers that of women in cess. He noticed that it was sometimes necessary for
Saudi Arabia who not only do not have a right to a person to deliberately establish a place in a con-
drive cars but do not have right of access even to versation from which to be heard as a legitimate
knowledge of car management. This predicament speaker. Such a move, if tacitly accepted by the
can be expressed in terms of positions—in this case, group into whose conversation the outsider wishes
rather long-term ones. In such examples, position to intrude, allows the new member of the group the
comes close to an earlier concept: role. But in any right to be heard. Establishing that right is position-
individual Saudi family, real life will involve the ing oneself with respect to the others. However,
negotiation of positions. Some women may learn Goffman does not present the rights aspect of foot-
to drive in secret. ing in such an overt way. It is “the alignment we
We will be concerned with the details of the eth- take to ourselves and the others present as expressed
no-methods of distributing rights and duties among in the way we manage the production or reception
individual people, confirming existing position dis- of an utterance.”
tributions, and/or changing an existing distribution The concept of “voice” is well-established in socio-
of rights and duties, and so on. An important feature linguistics. Voice refers to a pseudo-person whose
of positioning procedures is the use of estimates of utterances are marked with the social location from
personal character in making such assignments. In which one is speaking. Torode’s study of the relation
the early days of Positioning Theory, the two current between speech patterns and social order in school
senses of a position were in use but not clearly dis- classrooms (Torode, 1977, pp. 87–97) uses the idea
tinguished (e.g., Davies & Harre, 1990). The word of transcendent and mundane voices, speaking as a
was used to refer to personal, historical, social, and member of an external authority and speaking as a
cultural attributes of a person, as these were overtly member of the local group. As he worked out this
ascribed by some pattern of discursive acts. It was analysis, the voices were positioned in the sense of
also used to refer to a cluster of beliefs, some implicit this chapter—that is, the relevant rights and duties
and some explicit, as to the rights and duties proper of speaker and listeners relative to the social loca-
to a person who was taken to have the ascribed attri- tion of voice were tacitly understood and conceded
butes, or at least claimed to have them. by speakers and listeners alike. Only Brian Torode
The connection between positioning in the first himself could make the implicit explicit. He showed
sense and positioning in the second sense is close that rights to reply to and challenge commands

194 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


were tightly restricted in conversations in which the sense of positioning is referred to as pre-positioning,
teacher adopted the transcendental voice, the “we” of a distinction needed to keep the difference between
authority, not the “we” of the persons present on the the discursive processes by which rights and duties
occasion. Those who adopted the mundane voice of are assigned or resisted and the grounds that are
a member of the group of persons in the classroom, available to justify these assignments or resistances
choosing the pronouns “I” and “you,” had greater should they be challenged.
difficulty in establishing and maintaining authority.
The pupils took for granted their right to challenge The Problem of Rule
the orders of the teacher because in an egalitarian In a recent paper critical of Classical Positioning
group rights are equally distributed. Theory, Bamberg (2008) makes use of an under-
standing of the role of the concept of “rule” in
Positioning as Pre-Positioning and social psychology that is explicitly rejected by posi-
Positioning as the Assignment of tioning theorists. Positioning Theory depends on
Rights and Duties taking Wittgenstein’s (1953) account of orderly
Classical Positioning Theory appeared in feminist human activity in terms of rule following (in PI,
writings in the 1980s. The first explicit formulation pp. 138–242) as emphasizing its normative char-
of the concept of position to refer to both implicit acter which could be signaled by the metaphor of
and explicit beliefs that people display in their `rule following’. Potter and Wetherell (1987) took
intimate social practices was a Davies and Harré the same line in a challenge to a literalist use of `rule,
(1990) study of a two-member exchange, rich in by some social psychologists. Positioning Theory is
social nuances. Positioning beliefs were immanent not a procedure “to extract from discourse the sets
in the speech acts people were required, forbidden, of rules that people use” (Bamberg, 2008). To say so
or entitled to perform, according to local tacit con- confuses rules as instructions, which indeed people
ventions. Positioning Theory referred to the study do use to get things done—usually technical tasks,
of the discursive processes by which people were with rules as a term of art for psychologists and oth-
ascribed, took up, refused, contested, and so on- ers in their writings to express in legible and share-
the rights and duties they found themselves with in able form their intuitions as to the implicit norms
the local social world. The point was always a moral immanent in the orderly practices of a form of life.
one. The aim was to highlight practices that inhib- This distinction was firmly insisted on by Garfinkel
ited certain groups of people from performing cer- and was the basis of his technique for eliciting overt
tain sorts of acts. Given that selves were produced formulations of tacit rules. He contrived to have
in local discursive practices, these tacit restrictions people deliberately act in a manner that would have
were of considerable moment. Of course, there broken the hypothetical rule and recorded the ways
were no restrictions literally. However, in the light that people marked the infraction. Only if they did
of the spread of a different array of practices, one was one entitled to claim that there had been a nor-
can express the sense of possibilities unfulfilled in mative practice. Grammarians publish sets of rules
such expressions as “restrictions.” At that time and to present the norms implicit in the orderly prac-
in those publications, there was a persistent ambi- tices of one’s mother tongue. They are not “extract-
guity in the use of the concept of positioning, dis- ing from discourse the rules that people use.” Native
cussed above On the one hand, it meant ascribing speakers do not use these rules!
a characterological attribute or revealing biographi- The general tenor of a very interesting recent
cal incident to someone that was germane to the paper by Korobov and Bamberg (in press) is to resist
assignment of positions in the other sense, rights another fundamental idea that position theorists
and duties. share with the social representation school of social
Something like the former sense of position psychology (see Markova, 2011). It is the idea that
and positioning appears in Bamberg’s use of the to account for the stability of patterns of action,
concept of position (Bamberg, 2008). Positioning one must postulate repertoires of positions and sto-
from this point of view is a discursive procedure rylines immanent in a culture that are represented
for the ascription of an attribute to someone. in the bodies of shared social knowledge distrib-
To avoid any ambiguity between the two related uted as social representations among the mem-
senses, in most Positioning Theory studies, such bers of a group. This idea does not undermine the
as Moghaddam, Harré, and Lee (2009), Bamberg’s uniqueness of every human act. In the absence of

h a rré 195
a body of shared linguistic knowledge, there could what discursive processes is this accomplished on a
be no speaking or writing—but this does not show particular occasion?
that speaking and writing cannot be both original Positioning Theory is as much a matter of the
and intelligible. The same holds for social action social processes for the assignments of duties as it is
as the living out of storylines indigenous to a cul- of assignment of rights. Nevertheless, in the femi-
ture and the processes of distributing positions and nist input into Positioning Theory from Hollway
understanding utterances as speech acts. Although (1981), Davies and Harré (1990), and others, rights
we mobilize such items as beliefs and rules to get had pre-eminence. Women had a plethora of duties
things done, we do not construct them ab initio on and a minimum of rights in those bad old days. To
this or that occasion. Yet the way they are realized keep track of all this, we need to have a conceptual
may be quite distinctive and unique to a particu- analysis of the concepts of “right” and “duty,” with
lar occasion. The issue is not whether certain sto- some sense of the historical transformations of these
rylines exist as discursive resources, but how they concepts in actual applications in the management
do. They are very rarely the result of following sets of social order.
of instructions!
The Positioning Triangle
Positions and Positioning The position a person occupies at any moment in
Taken abstractly, a position is a cluster of beliefs an evolving strip of life is determined in part by the
with respect to the rights and duties of the members storyline that is realized in the unfolding episode. If
of a group of people to act in certain ways. These the storyline is “nurse and patient,” then within this
belief clusters may be tacit, existing only as imma- action schema there are positions such as a “right to
nent features of unchallenged patterns of action. be given care” and a “duty to provide care.” People
They may be explicitly formulated as rules and con- taking part in an episode that they are interpreting
ventions. Because positions are ephemeral compared in terms of this storyline can be expected to act in
with roles the focus of research interest must include accordance with their then-and-there beliefs as to
the social/cognitive processes by which positions are their positions as implicit in the local moral order.
established. This dynamics is positioning—that is, Moreover, the actions of the people who are living
processes by which rights and duties are assigned, out such an episode are made sense as the result of
ascribed, or appropriated and resisted, rejected, or the intersection of two clusters of beliefs: what sto-
repudiated. The upshot of acts of positioning is a ryline is unfolding and what positions are thereby
pattern of explicit and implicit beliefs, held by indi- available to the actors. A third component of a
viduals and among the relevant group in which the positioning analysis can be picked out as the social
action is going on. meanings to which the actors are orienting in what
As a process, positioning may proceed through a they do then and there. In short, we have a triangle,
sequence of phases. For example, the ascription of with the three vertices occupied by positions, sto-
rights and duties may be consequential on a prelim- rylines, and act interpretations. The constituents of
inary phase in which the moral character, intellec- the three vertices mutually determine one another.
tual or practical competence, biography, and so on, If any one changes—for example, by a successful
of a person, a group or even a category of persons challenge to the distribution of rights and duties—
are ascribed, sometimes on the basis of explicit evi- then all three change. Change the distribution of
dence. As suggested above it will be convenient to rights and duties and the storyline that has been
call this discursive process “pre-positioning.” In the realized thus far may be transformed. At the same
second phase, explicitly or implicitly, these ascrip- time, the meanings of what has been said and done
tions are used as grounds for the distribution or by the actors are also transformed. The future rela-
deletion and withdrawal of rights and duties. These tions between the actors and the subsequent form
moves are accomplished by second order social acts, taken by the unfolding strip of life will be different
sometimes overt but sometimes immanent in the after changes in any three components of the posi-
form of unfolding social episodes. At the meta- tioning triangle.
level, those who claim the right or duty to distribute I turn now to a more detailed exposition of the
and redistribute positions must be positioned so to constituents of the three vertices: acts, positions,
do. This opens up another research dimension. By and storylines.

196 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


The First Corner of the Positioning of Human Duties. Why? Because they can be taken
Triangle: Rights and Duties for granted? Surely not.
The basic structure of the interconnected con- Even in the twentieth century, the symmetry
ceptual pattern of the concepts of rights and duties principles are not universally acknowledged, even
goes something like this: in those countries where talk of rights is ubiqui-
tous. On the other hand, my upbringing was old
Rights: My rights are what you (or they) must do fashioned Protestant, in which only duties figured.
for me. I still find it almost impossible to claim or activate
Duties: My duties are what I must do for you my rights, if any.
(or them). In fact, rights are generally taken to be prior
These definitions are couched in terms of social neces- to duties. People tend to think about their rights
sities. But from whence comes the “must?” The basic and then look for a source of dutiful response from
structure of personal attributes that underlies the way someone else. By the 1960s, John F. Kennedy could
rights and duties emerge and are related depends on find it necessary to remind Americans that they
a simple distinction between a person’s (or a group’s should take heed of what they could do for their
powers) and the vulnerabilities of another person country—a duty concept.
or group of persons. In all human relations, there Everyone can find some way in which he, she,
is a possibility of an imbalance between the powers or they are vulnerable, hence engendering a right in
of some people and vulnerabilities of others. The search of a duty. “They should do something about
genesis of rights and duties on particular occasions it.” The “should” is normative and hence marks
and among specific people or groups of people goes the formulation of a duty, however vaguely. It has
according to the following patterns: often been remarked (apropos for example of health
needs) that rights can expand seemingly without
If I (we) have a vulnerability that you (they) have the end—this is one way we can understand the origins
power to remedy, then you have a duty to remedy my of the client society. In the absence of a duty code,
vulnerability and I have a right to be the recipient of the courts have taken on a new role, in which claims
the exercise of that power. to rights are adjudicated and duties prescribed by
identifying who are to be the relevant dutiful.
A right–duty pair emerges from this reasoning and
The fact that there are societies that recognize
frames possible actions. These future actions are only
only duties and have very weak notions of rights
possibilities, because whether or not the actions that
shows that the symmetry presumption is not a con-
would fulfill the rights–duties pattern actually occur
ceptual truth. There are historical examples of social
depends on other features of a concrete situation
systems that seem to involve complex hierarchical
such as the risks to the actors, the conscientiousness
patterns of reciprocal duties with no explicit formu-
of the powerful, and the skill of the recipients in
lations of rights. For example, the feudal systems
presenting their needs and so on.
in fourteenth-century England and France seem to
have been based on formal recognition of a vassal’s
The Symmetry Presumption duties to the lord and the lord’s duties to the vassal.
In our time and place, our moral universe is built We misread Magna Carta if we take it to be a medi-
around a general presumption that for every duty eval Bill of Rights. King John failed in his duties to
there is a right and for every right a duty. The seem- his vassals, who forced him to acknowledge that he
ingly a priori claims to rights, enshrined in various had certain duties to them. These duties were for-
charters and constitutions, are a modern and (for mally set out in oaths of fealty (Critchley, 1978).
the most part) English and French innovation from The reciprocal duty pattern of these oaths of alle-
the seventeenth century. The Founding Fathers of giance as fealty is very clear. Similarly, the Shogunate
the United States quickly added a Bill of Rights in Japan and the cult of bushido among the Samurai
to the Constitution, but they overlooked a Bill who maintained an orderly society seems to have
of Duties. Jefferson’s “life, liberty, and the pursuit been a predominately duty-based system. Everyone
of property” (revised by Hamilton to the pursuit in a hierarchy of dutiful relationships was a vassal
of happiness) was a detailing of rights. The U.N. ultimately of the Shogun himself (Nitobe, 1969,
Human Rights charter is not matched by a charter Ch. IX).

h a rré 197
In contemporary life, there is much talk of duties an action. Both levels can be revised and contested
to the environment, in which people are positioned subsequently. An actor may claim that what he or
in sometimes quite specific ways. Duties to the envi- she did was not an action, that it was not intended.
ronment are necessarily asymmetrical. Trees have Even if the intention to do something is not con-
vulnerabilities, so we who have power over nature tested, an actor may claim that the meaning or
have duties with respect to them, but trees have no social force of the action was not as it had been
rights. They are not agents, so we cannot call on supposed. A cough might be an automatic reaction
them to do anything to remedy our vulnerabilities, to blockage of the airway, but it can be deliberately
such as climate change. Trees are instruments, not used as a warning.
agents. Positioning Theory has been applied, for the
Philosophers have introduced the concept of most part, to verbal interactions, to episodes
supererogatory duty (Raz, 1975). This is a felt unfolding as conversations. Positioning theorists
demand on the basis of a personal conviction that can help themselves to J. L. Austin’s well-known
something should be done. In taking on a super- distinction between the forces of speech actions. A
erogatory duty, the moral force is felt only by the speech act, such as congratulating someone, appears
individual who feels committed to that duty. Such as the illocutionary force of the speech action, say-
a duty has no legal or even customary force. Again ing “Well done!”; however, the material and social
philosophers have noticed that informal or super- consequences of the speech action being understood
erogatory duties, when felt by a number of indi- in that way, given that meaning, is the perlocution-
viduals (particularly if one or more these people are ary force of the speech action. Compare “In saying
socially influential), evolve into formal obligations. ‘Stand back, I warn you!’ with “By saying ‘Stand
Not so long ago individuals positioned themselves back, I’ll save you!”
as having a duty not to smoke in the vicinity of In this presentation, we will rely on common
other people. In the intervening era, some people sense (folk) categories for acts. Gestures will be
felt that they had a duty to protest against smoking treated within the same analytical framework. For
by others. Now this duty is enshrined in law. We purpose of positioning analysis, a strip of life will
have a reciprocal right to clean air. be taken to be sequences of overlaying and imbri-
Nevertheless there is a strong contemporary cated acts borne by actions that were intended by
emphasis on the distribution of and claims to rights. the actors.
Given the various and variable relations between
duties and rights depending on culture, history, topic, The Third Corner of the Positioning
and so on, positions may turn out to be very com- Triangle: Storylines
plex. If someone demands a right based on a super- The basic principle of Positioning Theory as
erogatory duty, how is such a claim to be enforced? an application of discursive psychology is simply
How does positioning work in a social order that is that strips of life unfold according to local narra-
exclusively or almost exclusively duty-based? There tive conventions, some explicit, some implicit.
has not yet been any substantial research into this Explicit storylines are exemplified in the unfolding
question. Duty-based moral orders are rare in our of ceremonies, in the formats of rule-bound games,
time. Their connection with honor moralities has in the procedures in courts of law. The positions
been sketched but not taken up as a major research are predetermined, and there are procedures by
project. which they come to be occupied by specific actors.
Something more is needed for implicit storylines.
The Second Corner of the Positioning Narratological analysis can reveal them. The study
Triangle: Actions and Acts of storylines is a branch of narratology. It depends
Cultural and discursive psychology both depend on the principle that strips of life are usually lived
on a distinction between taking a behavioral per- stories for which told stories already exist. The same
formance as an intended action by a human agent story can be expressed in different media, words,
and the meaning that the agent and others involved film, plays, and life; in the contexts of everyday
give to that behavior. We can usefully adapt two life, there is rarely any explicit recourse to plot or
vernacular terms to mark this distinction. An action scenario. This is the domain of narratology proper,
is a meaningful, intended performance (speech or the study of the storylines realized in improvised
gesture), whereas an act is the social meaning of episodes.

198 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


Some distinctions are in order. Explicit storylines heard as authentic independent voices. The psychia-
must be distinguished from chronicles (proaeretic trist attempts to meld the two story lines into one as
principles), which simply describe a time sequence a single autobiography. In so doing, a single person-
of events. In Russian narratology, this appears, ality is restored or recreated. In the classical study
roughly, as the distinction between “fabula” and of MPS, Morton Prince’s record of the discourses
“sjuzhet.” For narrative, we need a plot and cast of in which Christine and Sally Beauchamp appeared
characters. Both are limited in scope and variety. as presentations of the same human being, the
There are two analytical schemes that prove use- therapy was grammatical. Prince insisted that Miss
ful. The analytical categories of Griemas (1990) are Beauchamp refrain from talking of her life events in
presented as six actants. These are Seeker, Object terms of three pronouns—“I,” “you,” and “she”—
sought, Sender (of the Seeker), Receiver (of the Everything she reported must be tied to “I”. In this
object sought), Helper, Opponent. The scheme way he hoped to recreate a single autobiographical
proposed by Kenneth Burke (1945) and picked up storyline.
by Erving Goffman (1959) involves a Pentad. The Autobiography can be viewed as a device for
five elements are Act, Scene, Agent, Agency, and positioning oneself in the act of presenting a self-
Purpose. According to Burke we should attend to narrative. An autobiography is not a chronicle
the Ratios, the way these elements need to be used because it is not only a history but also a manifesta-
in analytically in pairs. tion of personhood. Every normal human being has
Just as was the case with position and positioning a repertoire of autobiographies, each freely accessible
so, too, the important concept of storyline appeared from every other. This is not the case with the story-
in early positioning theory studies with two mean- telling of someone presenting Multiple Personality
ings. On the one hand, it was used to describe the Syndrome.
unfolding of the structure of an episode in terms A narratological analysis of MPS can be set out
of a familiar story—for example, “Beauty and the in formal schema as an analytical tool for the study
Beast” or one of Vladimir Propp’s folktale action of the problems of a patient, P.
sequences in accordance with his 36 action catego-
1. P tells two distinct autobiographies, A1 and
ries. (Propp, 1968). This was the sense of narrative
A2, which are not freely accessible one from the
in the writings of Jerome Bruner (1990). A story is
other.
told by a social psychologist as a representation of
2. Each autobiography displays a distinctive set
the act sequences. On the other hand it was used
of personal qualities, including knowledge of past
to refer to stories told by social actors, perhaps as
events.
accounting moves to make a lived storyline intelligi-
3. When living out A1, events relevant to A2
ble and warrantable. Although positioning theorists
are not accessible, and when living out A2, events
have drawn concepts from Agirdas Greimas for the
relevant to A1 are not accessible.
analysis of lived storylines, the examples he presents
4. Each A1, A2, and so forth, establishes a
in his (1990) book are analyses of told stories.
position.
Positioning Theory: Worked Examples Beran and Unoka (2004), like Prince, use pro-
Here are two worked examples to show how put- nouns as persona and position indicators. Their
ting together the three vertices of the positioning analysis displays two persona positions presented
triangle reveals the dynamics of the play of rights sequentially.
and duties in the unfurling of a complex episode. Elsa positions herself as an authoritative witness
of the past having the right to be heard and believed.
Example 1: Intrapersonal Positioning Her narrative’s original past tense changes to present
In the case discussed in this section, the person tense as she retells the story of the trial of the man
displaying Multiple Personality Syndrome (MPS) who raped her.
offers two storylines to the therapist (Beran & Marian is evoked by Elsa when Elsa is asked to
Unoka, 2004, pp. 151–161). There is the story of tell the story again, as one who is trying to stop
herself as Elsa and the story of herself as Marian. Elsa telling the tale. This is a positioning move,
These storylines are tied in with primary acts of as Marian is resisting Elsa’s self-positioning as
character pre-positioning that supports claims of one who has a right to tell the story and to be
positioning each persona as having rights to be believed.

h a rré 199
The therapist induces Elsa to talk as Marian, Here, Obama is making a reactive pre-positioning,
explaining why the story should not be told. In responding to an implicit positioning move that
this telling Elsa is referred to in the third person, would entail his not having the right to rule in a
and Marian adopts the first person, positioning predominantly Christian country.
herself as authoritative—that is, having the right More telling, because it is more intimate, is
to be believed. Then the therapist induces Elsa to Obama’s claim to a special attribute, the ability to
tell the story as Elsa in the first person. In this way, bring people together. To claim this, he offers the
the therapist makes both stories available, the telling following:
and the resistance to the telling. In the new situa-
“but what I look at as the trajectory of my life
tion, Elsa is able to explicate the significance of the
because, you know, I was raised by a single mom.
second voice. Marian is the name of her husband’s
My father left when I was two and I was raised by
mistress with whom she had a quarrel.
my mother and my grandparents. . . . what was
most important in my life was learning to take
Example 2: Interpersonal Positioning
responsibility not only for my own actions, but
The recent public political debates in the run-up
how I can bring people together to actually have
to the recent American Presidential election provide
an impact on the world.”
a rich field of material for study. To illustrate how
(Obama, 2009; ABC News, February 26, 2009)
ascribing and persisting positioning moves works
in a two-person discursive interaction, we will look This snippet serves to rebut the “all words but no
at an excerpt from the Primary debates between deeds” accusation that Clinton had made about him.
Barack Obama and Hillary Clinton, selected from Responding to a neutral query, Clinton makes
a comprehensive analysis of all four encounters a pre-emptive pre-positioning move by introducing
(Harré & Rossetti, 2010). The issue in positioning an autobiographical snippet:
theory terms boils down to this: “Do I (Barack or
“You know, I have, ever since I was a little girl, felt
Hillary) have the right to stand as a candidate for
the presence of God in my life. And it has been a gift
a macro-positioning exercise, the general election,
of grace that has for me, been incredibly sustaining.
which will give me the right to rule?” (Harre &
But, really, ever since I was a child, I have felt the
Rossetti, 2010).
enveloping support and love of God and I have had
This example is taken from CNN Democratic
the experience on many, many occasions where I felt
Candidates Compassion Forum (April 13, 2008).
like the holy spirit was there with me as I made a
Both Obama and Clinton introduce autobiographi-
journey.”
cal material as pre-positioning moves. The chain of
(CNN Democratic Candidates Compassion Forum, April 13,
inferences runs from an autobiographical snippet
2008)
through a claim for competence or experience to
a self-ascription of the right to be the Democratic As the debate unfolds, the negative consequences of
candidate to achieve the ultimate ascription of a this pre-positioning move become apparent. This
position in the formal ceremony on the White introduces an unfortunate image of the privileged
House Law—the right to rule. We need not follow child “born with silver spoon in her mouth,” whose
every step of this progression—the first two moves conscience calls for her to act as Lady Bountiful.
are enough to show how the pre-positioning works Obama’s call to duty does not come from a kind
and how Obama’s moves undercut Clinton’s self- of contingent condescension but from being posi-
positioning. tioned, in the descriptive sense, as “one of us.”
In response to the charge that he criticizes peo-
ple for “clinging to their religion,” Obama responds Example 3: Group Positioning via
with the following: Protagonists
A conflict of this nature may take two main
“I am a devout Christian . . . I started my work
forms.
working with churches in the shadow of steel plants
that had closed on the south side of Chicago, [I • The antagonists may share a story but by
claim] that nobody in a presidential campaign on the adopting contrary positions use that storyline to
Democratic side in recent memory has done more to express and so to nourish a conflict.
reach out to the church and talk about what are our • The antagonists may have adopted
obligations religiously . . . ” irreconcilable storylines that are such that two

200 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


positioning triads exist, and there is no discursive Six main storylines can be distinguished in the
bridge from one to the other. documents in which the discourse that revolved
around the Georgetown town/gown conflict was
I shall illustrate both possibilities in some detail, with
carried on. Some of the storylines were challenged
an analysis of the positions, storylines, and speech
by dissenting opinions that were a direct negation of
acts through which a seemingly irresolvable conflict
the storyline. Other readers would, no doubt, dis-
between Georgetown University (GU) and the sur-
cern other storylines. A strip of human life is indefi-
rounding residential Georgetown Community (GC)
nitely complex—it would be a huge mistake to claim
was nourished and sustained (Slocum & Harre,
that one’s analysis was exclusive and complete!
2003, pp. 110–118). Although there is a long his-
tory to this dispute, the most recent eruption of this
“town-gown” conflict was instigated when GU put in Storylines With Which Georgetown Community
a request to the District of Columbia to be permit- case Is Expressed
ted to increase its student enrollment in a proposed 1. The Students as Savages Storyline: Students
“campus plan.” An acrimonious conflict between are ravaging and violating the affluent and
the University and certain people in the neighbor- prestigious Georgetown neighborhood, spoken
ing GC began. This dispute appears, at first sight, to for by GC.
be chaotic, with the ground shifting in almost every 2. The Aggressive University Storyline: GU is
encounter. Positioning Theory provides an analysis encroaching upon the Georgetown neighborhood’s
that shows that the strips of life interwoven in the territory. GU is arrogant and hypocritical in that it
stream of encounters are orderly. cares only for its students and neglects the interests
There is a question of scale in any analysis where of the community.
the discourses are public. Are we disputing about the 3. The Parent/Children Storyline: GU is a
role of universities in the management of student negligent parent, and the students are unruly
behavior? Are we disputing about exactly how many children.
new student places Georgetown should create? The first and third storylines are sometimes
We need to know who/what groups are pre- woven together in some of the actual discourses of
sented in the narratives as the main actors in the the activists on the community side. Although the
conflict. These are the beings who will be adopt- second and third storylines are apparently contra-
ing and defending positions or are themselves being dictory, they are sometimes to be found intermin-
positioned by others. Are they individual people, gled in the discourse of one individual.
voices, protagonists, and so on?
The next step consists of a detailed analysis of
Storylines With Which the Georgetown
people’s perceptions of the conflict. The point is
University Case Is Expressed
not to reveal what really happened but to analyze
4. The Malicious Residents Storyline:
an episode to reveal one or more possible narrative
Neighborhood activists are hostile extremists who
forms to which speakers oriented in the course of
discriminate against students. They are jealous
these encounters. There is a further step in these dis-
of the students and wish them harm. They are
cursive encounters in which, in commenting on the
hindering GU development.
positionings of others in the debate, some of those
5. The Benevolent University Storyline: GU has
involved take a step back and adopt a position with
been responsible and cooperative. Its students are
respect to the positionings already accomplished—
responsible members of the community, and, in
the right to comment on first-order positioning tri-
general, they are idealists and leaders.
ads. Some people even believe that they have a duty
6. The Historical Rights Storyline: GU and its
to do so. Thus, an analysis of the meta-positioning
students were here first—namely, since 1789!
discourse is also required.
The disputes, disagreements that fuel the
Finally, we should be able to discern who does
conflict are, we contend, maintained and made
and does not possess positioning power and the basis
orderly and attractive by virtue of the storylines with
on which this power allocated. We can gain insight
which the dispute is expressed.
as to what role differences in positioning power play
in the conflict. This may reveal why some of the sto- In the dominant discourse of the GC activists,
rylines are more dominant (although not necessarily storylines 1 and 3, the Students as Savages and
more pervasive) than others. GU as Neglectful Parent are embedded within a

h a rré 201
broader set of discursive conventions we label “The The Psychological Status of the Relevant
American Dream.” Coming to live in Georgetown Bodies of Knowledge
is the ultimate realization of the American Dream. A great deal of local knowledge is required to act
The story is not supposed to end with the hero sur- unhesitatingly and successfully in the various con-
rounded by drunken, dirty, and noisy savages. In texts that require positioning of oneself and others.
this storyline, rights (including the right to posi- However, it seems more natural to use the word
tion others) are acquired to the extent that one pays “belief ” for the cognitive resources drawn on in the
taxes, owns property, and steps into the dramaturgy ways I have described.
of the American Dream. Indeed, one so positioned There are two ways that beliefs can be related to
also acquires the duty to `do something about “the locally meaningful actions: A belief may be tran-
destruction of the proper ending to this storyline.” scendent to an action that is held independently of
The activists’ speech acts are to be classified, from the actual occasion of the action, perhaps even able
their positions, as protests, displays of righteous to be expressed in propositional form, as a principle
indignation, doing one’s duty by society, reprimands or rule. However, a belief may be immanent in the
to the unruly, and so on. action—a feature of the social context of the flow
In the discourses of GU, the GC activists are of activities by the people involved in a life episode
positioned as devoid of rights to interfere with that exists as a customary practice. The background
the progression of the university’s development— beliefs that shape positioning activities can be of
particularly with the campus plan. An anonymous either kind.
administrator positions herself as spokesperson for Positioning analysis of an episode can pres-
the institution as having the duty and the right to ent both kinds of belief as explicit formulations.
take on lower order positions rights and duties as The fact that research results must be expressed
partner and neighbor to the surrounding commu- in propositional form to be read and understood
nity, engendering, ideally, reciprocal position in by other people should not tempt us to overlook
the GC discourse. Accordingly, the failure of the the important distinction between beliefs that are
community to accept this benevolent positioning is immanent in patterns of action and those that are
culpable. Positioned as rejected suitor, GU has the held by individuals as bodies of knowledge. Studies
right to issue utterances that have the illocution- in the framework of Réprésentations Sociales (Farr
ary force of rebuke, chastisement, and accusation. & Moscovici, 1987) also display this duality in the
In rejecting the positionings of GU, GC activists way that the sources of social order are supposed to
appear in this storyline as morally defective—for exist. A social representation can exist as a body of
example, stubborn and uncooperative. knowledge, but it can also exist as a social practice
Just as the generic storyline of the American or custom that has no other existence than in the
Dream underlies the specific storylines of Students repeated actions of the members of the social group.
as Savages and the University as Neglectful Parent, The problem of how similarity of repetitions with-
underlying the storylines of both the activists’ and out a cognitive schema is accomplished is not easy
the University administration’s seemingly anti- to solve. Even successive imitation would require
thetical narratives is another generic storyline, the short-term memory. As Greimas (1990, p. 13) puts
almost universal “Students are Children and the the point: “All doing presupposes a knowing-how-
University is their Parent.” The dispute is main- to-do . . . Thus, to discourse, which is a manifesta-
tained by GC pre-positioning the University tion of a doing, there corresponds the subject of
as Neglectful Parent and the University pre- discourse [not what it is about but who produces it],
positioning itself as Responsible Parent, thus fixing a subject endowed with discursive competence.”
the distribution of positions vis-á-vis the actions An important qualification of the ideas of social
appropriate to each side. The position in which representations in Positioning Theory, and where
the University has been put involves both rights it differs from Moscovici’s original Durkheimian
(in loco parentis) and duties to manage the stu- concept, concerns the way that in many cases of
dents’ behavior. At the same time, that generic or public activities by a group of people, the totality
pre-positioning puts the students into the specific of the knowledge required for the locally correct
position of ones without civil rights (e.g., to drink performance of an episode with positions properly
in bars), and as having the duty of obedience to distributed, the representation is distributed among
the University. the actors—some having this part, others having

202 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


other components of the total performance. The processes by means of which rights and duties are
whole only comes into existence in the course of distributed among people with respect to acquiring
a symbolically mediated mass event. However, not knowledge of certain matters, having beliefs about
everyone on the scene is positioned with the right political and religious matters, being ignorant of the
or the duty to perform a certain element of the total rules of proper behavior in this or that situation,
action. Just think of the distributed social repre- and so on.
sentation and the complex patterns of positioning
among the singers, musicians, stage hands, and so Duties in Relation to Knowledge,
on, in the performance of an opera. Belief, and Ignorance
However, in either case the repetition of discur- Positioning processes with respect to ignorance
sive practices and the stability of storylines need to and knowledge come to the fore most often in cases
be accounted for. Social representations as bodies of where people are held culpable for not remedying
knowledge shared among the members of a com- the one and for acquiring the other. People have
munity have this stabilizing function. In Bamberg’s a duty to acquaint themselves with the well-publi-
previously quoted paper (2008), the paradox that cized dangers of swimming off certain beaches. The
takes the heart out of the Potter et al. attempt at proper duties of paparazzi do not include the use
a treatment of psychology without cognition is the of telescopic lenses to photograph famous people
use of the English language by these authors. They sunbathing. Turning to positioning with respect
take for granted that there is a body of linguistic to belief there are two psychological phenom-
knowledge shared by their readers that enables their ena in play here. There is belief as a disposition,
texts to be understood. Grammars and lexicons as and there is believing as an act. Are there certain
shared and relatively permanent cognitive resources beliefs that someone has a duty to hold? Is believ-
are necessary conditions for the possibility of their ing in something a duty that someone has to fulfill?
own discursive projects. Sometimes the positioning of a person or persons is
content-targeted. For example, with respect to reli-
Positioning in Relation to Knowledge gious matters, people who are members of a certain
and Belief faith or denomination are reminded forcefully of
In the first section of this chapter, positioning their duty to believe the tenets of that faith. In a
analysis was used to amplify the depth of the analy- more low-key way, a similar kind of duty seems to
sis of the sources of particular social actions, in rela- be implicit in science, where an experimental dem-
tion to the way rights and duties are assigned to the onstration is not just supportive of a factual claim
people engaged in a certain social episode. However, but engages the moral order of the scientific com-
of equal importance is the way rights and duties are munity. Whereas the experimenter has a duty to be
implicated in what we can know or believe. Rights competent and truthful, the onlooker has a duty
and duties are also involved in how we deal with to believe.
ignorance. In philosophical terms, we could call Sometimes the positioning is source-targeted.
this phenomenon “epistemic positioning.” There Van Woudenberg (2009, p. 50) cites examples of
are important questions about how rights to know the positioning of doctors as having a duty to believe
something are distributed and contested, how duties what their patients tell them. On the other hand,
to remedy ignorance are imposed, and so on. lay people are positioned as having a duty to believe
We start with the commonplace observation that what experts tell them. There are innumerable
people are praised and blamed for what they believe, examples of such acts of positioning in discussions
know and don’t know, forget, and are ignorant of. of what we should believe about global warming.
To take a prominent contemporary issue, jour- The same holds in religious contexts. The congre-
nalists are often blamed for acquiring knowledge gation has a faith-relative duty to believe what the
of the lives of prominent people in ways that we priest or mullah or shaman tells them.
believe they should not have used. The evaluations Even a cursory survey of positionings with
expressed in such opinions tell us we are in moral respect to belief reveals the presence of long-running
territory. Once again, as in the management of and often acrimonious conflicts over how rights and
social action, the key moral concepts are rights and duties are distributed. So far as I know, this matter
duties. The research domain that opens up is the has received very little attention from cultural and
identification and study of the social and cognitive discursive psychologists.

h a rré 203
Considering the demands of “duty to know” and The promulgation of officially imposed epistemic
its complementary demand, “duty to remedy igno- positions opens a new dimension of positioning dis-
rance,” there is rarely much conflict. Some of these courses. Everyone is positioned by the central posi-
duties are fixed in law, but some are supererogatory. tioning act, in contrast to most positing studies to
The reprimand “You should have known (found out date that are concerned with very local and ephem-
about) so and so” is commonplace in family circles eral positionings. The authorities position everyone
and no doubt elsewhere. Again this looks like a in an authoritarian religious society with the duty to
likely area for systematic research. believe the tenets of the established religion or polit-
The duty to acquire knowledge is a reflection ical philosophy. The logic of the duty/right relation
of the duty to remedy ignorance. Thus what it is entails that there is no right to disbelieve.
said that a person is ignorant of defines the dutiful In the absence of a right to disbelieve, the way is
task of remedy. Among the domains of knowledge open for the punishment of those who do. In forced
where ignorance pre-positions someone with the conversion, members of a community position
duty to remedy the lack are social and legal rules. themselves as having both the right and the duty to
How far acquiring current etiquette is a matter for demand that others change their beliefs. There have
discussion, but learning the Highway Code in the been numerous studies of the psychological pro-
United Kingdom and being able to display knowl- cesses by which this apparently paradoxical transfor-
edge of it is a requirement for obtaining a driver’s mation is accomplished. Spontaneous conversion is
license. The legal principle that ignorance is no outside the domain of positioning processes. The
excuse is routinely overruled in many cases—and Positioning Theory research question concerns the
here, again, is a field for positioning research. How discursive processes by which someone becomes
is the positioning of someone as having a certain convinced of the moral basis of proselytizing.
duty revised? In everyday life, there is much discus- Rights to know are severely restricted in most
sion of duties to acquire everyday arts in the context societies, sometimes more by law than by custom.
of some people calling on others as having the duty In many cases, positioning claims by journalists
to perform minor technical jobs. For example, some eventually reach the courts, where the doctrine of
people declare that everyone has a duty to learn how the public good is used to override the rights of indi-
to restore a circuit breaker. Men are said to have viduals to privacy. In Positioning Theory terms, this
a duty to be competent in baby care, and so on. amounts to the denial of the existence of a position
The discursive practices by which these positioning of the right to know everything about a person.
acts are accomplished is another field for research. More complex psychologically are duties to
Positioning students as having a duty to learn as a remember in relation to rights to forget. One may be
fulfillment of a duty to know is the foundation of positioned as having a duty to forget a minor injury
the grading system in a major discursive practice in that one has suffered at the hands of someone else.
educational institutions. However, rights to forget are more tendentious. For
None of these positionings seem to attract seri- example, political activists dispute the implicit self-
ous controversy. There is a huge difference between positionings that sustain the amnesias that occur in
the contestability and the accusations of irrational- the historical recollections of whole nations on the
ity between positionings in relation to these every- grounds that we do not have the right to forget such
day practices and criticisms of fundamentalism and evils as the Holocaust and the Killing Fields.
the making of hasty scientific claims—for example, Finally, there are rights to ignorance. A physi-
in the case of cold fusion. cian may position a patient as having a right not to
know his or her medical condition on the grounds
Rights in Relation to Belief, Knowledge that such knowledge might have a deleterious effect
and Ignorance on the patient’s general health. Disputes do occur
In the case of the right to believe, positioning over this matter. A patient may demand to be told,
practices serve to roughly distinguish liberal from regardless of how distressing the knowledge may
authoritarian societies. This topic also introduces prove to be. The doctor’s duty of care overrides the
the idea of a mode of positioning that links rights to duty to inform the patient of his or her situation.
permissions. Positioned as having a right to some- Many epistemic rights and duties were implicit
thing is more or less equivalent to being given per- until recent legislation in the form of informa-
mission to engage with it. tion laws opened up rights that were not hitherto

204 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


recognized and codified those that were. This should representations of moral orders implicit in the cases
prove a rich field for Positioning Theory research. analyzed. These are roughly the features of a kind
What effect has the British Freedom of Information of generalized Judeo-Christian moral order from
Act had on people’s beliefs about their positions, and which local orders can be derived when we consider
what storylines have been used to resist disclosures? the overt formulation of a working body of shared
These are questions of immediate public interest and knowledge as system of `rules’. Many interesting
are hardly touched on in formal research projects. contemporary examples of positioning discourses
Research should enable social psychologists to and their consequences in the lived storylines of
catalogue some of the procedures by which epistemic participants arise within an implicit background
positioning is accomplished. In particular, there is of honor moralities. This matter deserves extended
the question of the pre-positioning personal charac- treatment, but it is worth noting briefly how dif-
teristics, histories of abilities that support position- ferent honor moralities are from the deontic and
ing a person or persons as having duties and rights utilitarian moral systems usually studied by moral
in respect of knowledge, belief, and ignorance. For philosophers. Contemporary virtue morality comes
example, one cannot be positioned as having a duty closer in that issues of honor are often linked to
to disclose knowledge one does not have. One can- local notions of virtue. This shows up very clearly in
not have a right to knowledge that would be used courtroom proceedings in murder trials where the
to harm someone else. For example, information victim is often a relative, regretfully often a sister or
on how to make explosives and construct bombs daughter of the accused. “She dishonored our fami-
ought not to be published on the Internet, on the ly—therefore, we had a duty to kill her.” The rights
Positioning Theory grounds that people do not have of the men of the family vis-à-vis honor are implicit
the right to know. in the law that the members of the community sub-
scribe to (Harré, 1983, pp. 240–242).
Reflexivity of Positioning
Psychology is, in large part, a cluster of discursive References
practices. There are the activities of experimenters Bamberg, M. (2008). In D. Schriffrin & A. De Fina (Eds.).
and their subjects as co-participators in the social Georgetown Round Table Proceedings.
events called “experiments.” Results must be writ- Beran, E & Unoka, Z. (2004). Construction of self-narrative in
ten up according to certain conventions, subject to a psychotherapeutic setting. In U. M. Quasthoff & T. Becker
(Eds) Narrative Interaction. Amsterdam and Philadelphia,
meta-discursive activities of the peer review and so PA: Benjamin.
on. Positioning as a discursive practice is as much Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
a part of the activities of those who practice psy- University Press.
chology as a science as administering questionnaires Burke, K. (1945). A Grammar of Motives. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
and publishing articles and books. The practices of Prentice Hall.
Critchley, J. S. (1978). Feudalism. Boston: Allen and Unwin.
the sciences are embedded in long-standing conven- Davies, B. & Harré, R. (1990). Positioning: The discursive pro-
tions of the distribution of rights and duties among duction of selves Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour,
the participants. Even so apparently obvious a step 20, 43–63.
as the inserting of a statistically analyzed table of Edwards, J & Potter, J. (1994). Discursive Psychology. (Chs. 1,
results at the end of an article in a mainstream jour- 5–7) London: Sage.
Festinger, L. (1958). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Evanston,
nal plays its part in pre-positioning the author as IL: Row and Peterson.
one with a right to be believed. Duties of care are Fodor, J. R. (1976). The Language of Thought. Hassocks, Sussex:
presupposed everywhere. Harvester.
Gilbert, G.N. & Mulkay, N. (1982). Warranting scientific
Future Perspectives beliefs. Social Studies of Science, 12, 383–408.
Glock, H.- J. (2009). Concepts: where subjectivism goes wrong.
The place of Positioning Theory as a research Philosophy, 84, 5–29.
program within the general field of cultural psychol- Goffman, E. (1959). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life.
ogy is evident when we consider the importance of Garden City, NY: Anchor.
social representations of local moral orders in the Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of Talk. Philadelphia, PA: University
management of specific cases as a discursive prac- of Pennsylvania Press.
Grattan, K. (2003). The dispute over the fate of Terri Sciavo.
tice. The examples introduced above as illustrations In R. Harré & F. M. Moghaddam. The Self and Others:
of the power of positioning analyses are grounded in Positioning Individuals and Groups in Personal, Political and
a background of common features to all the social Cultural Contexts (pp. 113–145). Westport, CT: Praeger.

h a rré 205
Greimas, A. J. (1990). Narrative Semiotics and Cognitive Discourses. Nitobe, I. (1969). Bushido: The Soul of Japan. Tokyo: Charles
(Trans. P. Perron & F. H. Collins), London: Pinter. Tuttle.
Harré, R. (1983). Personal Being. Oxford: Blackwell; Cambridge Prince, M. (1904). The Dissociation of a Personality. New York:
MA: Harvard University Press. Johnson Reprints.
Harré, R., Moghaddam, F. M., Pilkerton-Carnie, T, Sabat, S, & Propp, V. (1968). The Morphology of the Folk Tale. Austin, TX:
Rothbart, D. (2009). Recent advances in Positioning Theory. University of Texas Press.
Theory and Psychology, 19/1, 5–32. Raz, J. (1975). Permissions and supererogation. American
Harré, R. & Moghaddam, F. M. (2003). The Self and Others. Philosophical Quarterly, 12, 161–168.
Westport, CT: Praeger. Slocum, N. & Harre, R. (2003). Disputes as complex social
Harré, R. & Rossetti, M. (2010). The right to be a candidate for events: on thee uses of positioning theory. Common
the right to rule. In F. M. Moghaddam & R. Harré (Eds.), Knowledge, 91, 100–118.
Positioning in the Political Process. New York: Springer. Smedslund, J. (2009). The mismatch between current research
Harré, R. & van Langenhove, L. (1999). Positioning Theory. methods and the nature of psychological phenomena:
Oxford, UK: Blackwell. what researchers must learn from practitioners. Theory and
Heider, F. (1957). The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations. Psychology, 19, 778–794.
Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press. Tajfel, H. (1981). Human Groups and Social Categories. Cambridge,
Hollway, W. (1984). Gender difference and the production U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
of subjectivity. In J. Henriques, W. Hollway, C. Irwin, Torode, B. (1977). The revelation of a theory of the social world
L. Venn, & V. Walkerdine (Eds.) Changing the Subject: Social as grammar. In R. Harré (Ed.). Life Sentences. Chichester,
Regulation and Subjectivity. London: Methuen. West Sussex: Wiley.
Korobov, N. & Bamberg, M. (in press). Strip poker: they don’t Van der Veer, R (2011). Cultural-Historical Psychology. In
show nothing: Positioning identities and adolescent male J. Valsiner (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of culture and psychol-
talk about a television game show. ogy. NY: Oxford University Press.
Markova. I (2011). Social representations and culture. In Van Woudenberg, R. (2009). Responsible belief and our social
J. Valsiner, Handbook . . . institutions. Philosophy, 84, 47–74.
Moghaddam, F.M. & Harré, R. (2010). Positioning and the Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Thought and Language. Cambridge, MA:
Political Process. New York: Springer. MIT Press.
Moghaddam, F. M., Harré, R. & Lee, N. (2008). Global Conflict
Resolution through Positioning Analysis. New York: Springer.

206 posi ti oni ng t he o ry


CHAPTER

Macro-Cultural Psychology
10
Carl Ratner

Abstract
This chapter explains macro-cultural psychology as a psychological theory and discipline. It
conceptualizes psychological phenomena as part of macro-cultural factors—social institutions,
artifacts, and cultural concepts. Specifically, macro-cultural psychology explains how psychological
phenomena originate in macro-cultural factors, embody their features, represent macro-cultural
factors, solidify and sustain macro-cultural factors, and are objectified in them. The chapter
presents examples of these points with regard to emotions, adolescence, mental illness, agency,
sensory processes, and self-concept. Macro-cultural psychology is shown to be a coherent general
psychological theory that encompasses biological processes and individual variations within
macro-cultural cornerstones, in logically consistent ways. The theory draws on the pioneering
work of Vygotsky, Luria, and Leontiev.
Keywords: macro-culture, interpersonal interactions, social structure, mental illness, agency, emotions,
adolescence,Vygotsky, sensory processes

The central tenet of macro-cultural psychology (levels, layers) from the micro, interpersonal level,
is that psychological phenomena are elements, or to broader levels, some of which are indirectly
parts, of macro-cultural factors. Macro-cultural experienced—such as children being affected by
factors are social institutions, artifacts, and cul- parents’ working conditions, as these affect par-
tural concepts. They are the broad, enduring cor- ents’ interactions with children. The broadest
nerstones of social life. As such, macro-cultural level, which forms the framework of parameters
factors are crucial to our survival and fulfillment. for all the other narrower levels, is the macro-social
Human psychology is intrinsic to this scenario. structure:
Psychology evolved to plan and implement macro-
cultural phenomena, thereby enhancing our sur- [T]he complex of nested, interconnected systems is
vival and fulfillment. Psychology is the motivation, viewed as a manifestation of overarching patterns of
perception, emotions, self-concept, reasoning, and ideology and organization of the social institutions
memory of cultural behavior that forms artifacts, common to a particular culture or subculture. Such
concepts, and institutions. The discipline of macro- generalized patterns are referred to as macrosystems,
cultural psychology explores the cultural origins, within a given society or social group, the structure
locus, characteristics, and function of psychologi- and substance of micro-, meso-, and exosystems tend
cal phenomena. The term macro-cultural psychol- to be similar, as if they were constructed from the
ogy may be traced to Bronfenbrenner’s ecological same master model.
model. He enumerates a set of social contexts (Bronfenbrenner, 1979, p. 8; Ratner, 1991, pp. 172–178)

207
The macro-level is the core of, and key to, all the the premises of historical materialism, which are
layers and factors in a society. “Public policy is a part valid for any historical phenomenon in human
of the macro system determining the specific prop- society. It is only to be expected that on this level the
erties of exo-, meso-, and microsystems that occur development of behavior will be governed essentially
at the level of everyday life and steer the course of by the general laws of the historical development of
behavior and development” (ibid., p. 9). human society.
Cultural psychology was originally conceived as (Vygotsky 1986, pp. 94–95)
macro-cultural psychology. This emphasis was main-
Likewise,
tained by Moritz Lazarus and Heymann Steinthal
in their journal Zeitschrift fur Völkerpsychologie und Already in primitive societies . . . the entire
Sprachwissenschaft [Journal of Cultural Psychology psychological makeup of individuals can be seen to
and Linguistics], which was inaugurated in 1860. It depend directly on the development, the degree of
seems that the term Völkerpsychologie was coined by development of the production forces, and on the
Wilhelm Humboldt at the turn of the nineteenth structure of that social group to which the individual
century (see also Diriwächter, 2011). It was contin- belongs . . . Both of these factors, whose intrinsic
ued by Wundt, who believed that macro-cultural interdependence has been established by the theory
factors are more conducive sites for psychologi- of historical materialism, are the decisive factors of
cal research and analysis than variable individual the whole psychology of primitive man.
consciousness: (Vygotsky, 1994b, p. 176)

Speech, myths and customs constitute a series of A.N. Leontiev (1977) further explains this per-
closely related subjects which are of great importance spective in his article “Activity and Consciousness”
to general psychology for the reason that the (available online: http://www.marxists.org/archive/
relatively permanent character of speech, myths, leontev/works/1977/leon1977.htm) in his book
and customs renders it relatively easy to recognize Problems of Dialectical Materialism: “Despite all
clearly through them certain psychical processes, its diversity, all its special features, the activity
and to carry out through them certain psychological [Tatigkeit] of the human individual is a system that
analyses. Such recognition of general processes and obeys the system of relations of society. Outside
such analyses are much easier here than in the case of these relations human activity does not exist. How
transient compounds of individual consciousness. it exists is determined by the forms and means of
(cited in Ferrari et al., 2010, p. 97) material and spiritual communication that are gen-
erated by the development of production and that
Studying psychical processes in macro-cultural
cannot be realised except in the activity of specific
factors is also advantageous for understanding cul-
individuals. It stands to reason that the activity of
tural components and features of psychology.
every individual depends on his place in society, on
Macro-cultural psychology utilizes these under-
his conditions of life.” For instance, Leontiev speaks
standings of psychology in culture and culture in
of “the objective contradictions of commodity pro-
psychology to conduct empirical research on the
duction, which generates a contradiction between
cultural psychology of individuals. The macro
concrete and abstract labour and leads to the alien-
aspect of culture and cultural psychology was also
ation of human activity” (ibid.).
emphasized by psychological anthropologists such
Leontiev goes on to say that activity is fostered by
as Shweder in the 1980s. However, it was displaced
social labor: “Historically, the appearance in activ-
by more personal and interpersonal notions of cul-
ity of goal-oriented action processes was the result
ture. I have worked to expand the original macro
of the emergence of a society based on labour.”
emphasis of cultural psychologists. Vygotsky, Luria,
Activity is not a natural impulse of human beings
and Leontiev developed the most interesting, origi-
that originates within the individual. Leontiev
nal, thorough, and central principles of macro-
adds a historical note that “The method of scien-
cultural psychology. Vygotsky said, “Higher mental
tific analysis of the generation and functioning of
functions [are] the product of the historical devel-
human consciousness – social and individual – was
opment of humanity” (Vygotsky, 1998, p. 34, my
discovered by Marx.”
emphasis).
Of course, internal conscious activity is recipro-
Once we acknowledge the historical character of cally the subjectivity that animates external activity.
verbal thought, we must consider it subject to all “the phenomena of consciousness constitute a real

208 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


element in the motion of activity” (ibid.) Therefore, that people will interpret their personal experiences
both arise and function interdependently. The point in ways that support the political position: “this
is that internal subjectivity activity does not arise transformation of personal meanings into adequate
on its own (“first”) but only under the stimulus (or more adequate) objective meanings shows that
of external social activity. “Once we acknowledge this occurs in the context of the struggle for people’s
the common structure of external, practical activ- consciousness that is waged in society.” This struggle
ity and internal, mental activity we can understand is evident in American media stations.
the exchange of elements that constantly takes place Social structuring of personal meanings is not
between them, we can understand that certain always successful and complete. Discrepancies erupt.
mental actions may become part of the structure “There is no disappearance (nor could there be) of
of direct practical, material activity and, conversely, the constantly proliferating discrepancy between
external-motor operations may serve the perfor- personal meanings which carry the intentionality,
mance of mental action in the structure of purely the partiality of the subject’s consciousness, and
cognitive activity” (ibid.). the objective meanings, which though ‘indifferent’
Leontiev provides an important discussion of to them are the sole means by which personal mean-
personal meanings in relation to social activity and ings can be expressed. This is why the internal move-
collective representations. He acknowledges per- ment of the developed system of the individual’s
sonal meanings as an idiosyncratic sense of the com- consciousness is full of dramatic moments. These
plex of experiences that comprise one’s personal life. moments are created by personal meanings that
“Whereas external sensuousness associates objective cannot “express themselves” in adequate objective
meanings with the reality of the objective world in meanings, meanings that have been deprived of
the subject’s consciousness, the personal meaning their basis in life and therefore, sometimes agonis-
associates them with the reality of his own life in this ingly, discredit themselves in the consciousness of
world, with its motivations. It is the personal mean- the subject” (ibid., my emphasis).
ing that gives human consciousness its partiality.” For instance, despite the active efforts of banks
However, personal meanings about one’s own life and right wing media to blame American individu-
are not free inventions. They interpret personal life als for the Great Recession that began in 2008 (by
in social terms, through social values and concepts. accusing them of borrowing credit that they could
Individuals draw upon society in order to interpret not afford), many people realize that they were often
the specificity of their personal lives: “In contrast the victim of financial fraud on the part of financial
to society the individual has no special language of institutions. However, these breakthroughs are few
his own with meanings that he has evolved himself. and far between.
His comprehension of reality can take place only Leontiev concludes this important article with a
by means of the “ready-made” meanings he assimi- key statement that distinguishes macro cultural psy-
lates from without – the knowledge, concepts, and chology from mainstream psychology: “although a
views he receives through intercourse, in the vari- scientific psychology must never lose sight of man’s
ous forms of individual and mass communication. inner world, the study of this inner world cannot be
This is what makes it possible to introduce into his divorced from a study of his activity and does not
consciousness or even impose upon that conscious- constitute any special trend of scientific psychologi-
ness distorted or fantastic notions and ideas, includ- cal investigation.”
ing those that have no basis in his real, practical This sentiment gives an entirely new meaning
life experience.” Social meanings are so powerful to psychological phenomena. They are rooted in
that they distort people’s lived experiences. This is historical forces such as government policy, wars,
obvious today as oppressed people routinely define immigration, mode of production, technology, art,
their problems in terms of conservative social ideol- industrialization, nuclear family, religious beliefs.
ogy that mystifies the sources and solutions of their Psychological phenomena are subjective aspects of
lived problems. I have termed this the psychology of these cultural-historical phenomena; psychology is
oppression (Ratner, 2011d). not a realm of its own, independent of these.
Indeed, societies struggle to structure personal In an unpublished paper written in 1929, entitled
meanings so as to steer people toward a political posi- “Concrete Psychology”—a term he took from the
tion. Various political interests struggle mightily to French Marxist philosopher-psychologist Georges
capture people’s personal meanings to their side so Politzer—Vygotsky said, “We derive individual

ratn er 209
functions from forms of collective life. Development macro-cultural factors generate the abstract features
proceeds not toward socialization, but toward indi- of psychology we just mentioned.
vidualization of social functions (transformation Examples of concrete features of macro-cultural
of social functions into psychological functions)” factors are: leadership in society X is dominated by
(Vygotsky, 1989, p. 61). I shall demonstrate that the feudal aristocracy, or learning is measured by
the original social forms that generate psychological paper-and-pencil tests of rote memory. We would
functions are macro cultural factors. expect these concrete features of macro-cultural fac-
Of course, history is made by people; however, tors to generate correspondingly concrete features
when we speak of historical activity we refer to of psychology.
individuals acting, often social leaders and spokes- Macro-cultural psychologists would trace
people (government officials, business leaders, “symbolic thinking” (in general) to abstract social
leaders of community organizations), operating at interaction and communication. We would trace
the macro-cultural level to shape social policy and specific forms of symbolic thinking (e.g., deductive
community opinion through cultural media such as logic) to particular features of macro-cultural fac-
legislation, news reports, magazine articles, and art tors. For example, Goldman (1992, pp. 15, 17, 18,
forms. History does not refer to personal history or 83) examines the potential impact of the commod-
individuals expressing some personal inclination of ity form on consciousness by looking at advertis-
their own. ing that transforms our meaning systems as well as
A central tenet of macro-cultural psychology is our desires into commodities. Goldman examines
that macro-cultural factors generate abstract and the effects on consciousness of “the commodity-
concrete features of psychology. Macro-cultural sign,” which is a commoditized kind of symbol,
factors have abstract features that generate abstract a sign that misrepresents products by associating
features of psychology; and macro-cultural factors them with false and irrelevant situations (e.g.,
have concrete features that generate concrete fea- cigarettes with nature, deodorant with popularity,
tures of psychology. Examples of abstract psycho- cereal with a star athlete). The commodity-sign is a
logical features are: “people think, remember, have new kind of symbol that is specifically organized by
self-concepts, use language” and “people remem- Capital to serve its interest of stimulating sales and
ber and think in symbols.” These are what main- profit. Capitalism is built into the commodity-sign
stream psychologists generally study. They study and into our meaning systems. This takes the form
memory, perception, emotions, language acquisi- of building misrepresentation into the commodity-
tion, and mental illness. They are rarely interested sign. Because humans think in symbols (an
in concrete forms of these, such as an individualis- abstract characteristic of thinking), if symbols are
tic self, romantic love, contextual memory, ancient commodified, then our concrete thinking is that
Greek sexuality, and Victorian maternal love. Even we think in commodity-signs. Commodity-signs
when mainstream psychologists do address cultur- structure consciousness in concrete ways, such
ally concrete forms of psychology, they typically as accepting false associations and appearances
misconstrue them as abstract, universal, natural as true, generating strong emotional desires for
forms. mundane products, stimulating impulsive action
Examples of abstract features of macro-cultural (consumerism), and defining human events (social
factors are: macro-cultural factors are socially orga- popularity, good motherhood, happy children,
nized and involve symbolic communication; mac- love) in terms of consumer products. Improving
ro-cultural factors involve positions of leadership; (demystifying) consciousness therefore requires
and schools are organized into different grades, and critiquing and altering the commodity-sign that
they measure students’ learning. These features are mystifies consciousness.
abstract because they are indefinite and lack any If consciousness/agency is mystified by com-
specific substance. The mere fact that cultural fac- modity-signs, then it can only be demystified by
tors are socially organized leaves open what kind of critiquing and altering commodity-signs. This
organization it is. Similarly, grades could be deter- requires a specific social analysis of the cultural
mined and measured by various criteria. Similarly, mediational means that people use to understand
the fact that society has positions of leadership is things. Consciousness cannot demystify itself by an
abstract because leadership could take many forms. abstract cognitive act (e.g., “try to be more open to
We would expect that these abstract features of information”), which ignores the concrete capitalist

210 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


form that symbols have. Concrete cultural problems proliferated, so did the signs and sounds that
cannot be solved by abstract acts. described them and their manufacture.”
In this example, we see that abstract and con- (p. 22)
crete aspects of psychology stem from abstract and
Burke and Ornstein are speaking about “thought”
concrete aspects of macro-cultural factors. The
and “grammar” in general, not the grammar of a
abstract and concrete are interdependent and call
particular language. The authors observe how food
for each other. When we examine abstract aspects
production changed human social organization and
of cultural factors and psychology, we are led to
psychology. Food cultivation allowed a relatively great
examine their concrete features that fill them out.
deal of food to be produced in a small area, com-
Conversely, when we examine concrete aspects, we
pared with hunting and gathering, which required
are led to identify abstractions. For example, when
large areas. This allowed for larger populations to
we examine why concrete commodity-signs affect
live in concentrated areas, allowing for communities.
consciousness, the answer lies in the abstraction that
“Where it had once taken 15 square miles to support
“thinking occurs in symbols.”
a hunter-gatherer, a settler now needed only three”
Macro-cultural psychology is a comprehensive
(p. 38).
theory that explains both abstract and concrete
aspects of human psychology as resulting from and
Producing Nature Stimulates
residing in macro-cultural factors. We dispute the
Consciousness, Will, Agency, Self
contention that natural processes generate abstract
In addition, cultivating food entailed artifi-
features of psychology whereas only concrete fea-
cially duplicating nature. Seeds or roots were col-
tures are generated by cultural factors; this would
lected and artificially planted, instead of growing
dichotomize psychology into two distinct and anti-
naturally from plants. Nature was divided into ele-
thetical orders of reality with different mechanisms
ments (seeds, roots) and then duplicated by human
and processes.
action. This led to a stupendous breakthrough in
Let us examine how abstract and concrete
consciousness. Consciousness came to represent
features of macro-cultural factors generate cor-
nature and redesign it according to human purpose.
respondingly abstract and concrete features of
According to this analysis, thinking was generated
psychology.
by rudimentary agricultural production. The artifi-
cial duplication of nature in production generated
Macro-cultural Factors Generate Abstract a corresponding artificial duplication of nature in
Features of Psychology thought. Economic production generated thought
Burke and Ornstein (1995) explain that tools,
(pp. 39–40). This is why symbolic consciousness,
cooperation, and communication in general—
expressed in artistic representations of things, devel-
not any particular form of these—spurred general
oped during the rise of agriculture in the Neolithic
human advances in thinking rather than any par-
Revolution 10,000 years ago (Ratner, 2006).
ticular kind of thinking. Hunting in groups requires
Of course, this development was dialectical,
“the ability to plan, communicate, and cooperate.
not linear. Rudimentary, accidental/spontaneous
These communicative abilities . . . laid down the
collecting and planting of a few seeds generated
mental matrix necessary for thought and reason,
rudimentary representational thinking of seeds as
language and culture” (p. 11).
representing plants. This advance of thinking led to
To cut a tool demands a set of operations carried more deliberate understanding of seeds and to more
out in a specific order. The instructions for tool careful gathering and planting them. This stimu-
making might have been serial sounds specifying lated more advanced thinking, and so on.
the sequence of physical manipulation necessary to Humans’ reproducing nature led to another
make the tool. So it might be that the first noises breakthrough in consciousness—namely, will or
accompanying the ‘grammar’ of sequential tool agency. In reproducing nature, humans made nature
making might have also laid down the basics of the happen (made plants grow), and this expanded their
grammar of language, because grammar is based agency and sense of self.
on sounds that only make sense (as do successful Social interaction that mediates responses to
tool-making actions) if they are done in the correct objects also provides the differentiation of indi-
sequence. The tool and the sentence would be vidual from nature that is vital to forming a distin-
one and the same thing. As the tools refined and guishable self. Social mediation also generates the

ratn er 211
cognitive mediation of behavior through planning, transported back and forth among interlocutors.
deliberating, and imagining. All of these activity- The social interchange of information requires that
generated psychological functions and self then fur- it be encoded in a vessel of transportation. This is
thered the activity of reproducing nature. language. Animals that lack this social interchange
Nature was no longer received as it stood. It of information never develop a linguistic system
was reorganized by humans. This marked the break for encoding and transmitting it. Animal
of humans from natural existence. Tools greatly communication is primarily animated by one
expanded humans’ ability to rearrange nature. individual’s reaction to an object—for example, a
“Tools released the tool-users forever from the predator. In contrast, human language is primarily
slow development of natural processes. Now tools animated by social interchange—that is, the desire
could supplant biological evolution as the main to share information with other humans to decide
source of change” (Burke & Ornstein, 1995, how to collectively deal with objects.
p. 10).1 Paradoxically, the more humans could arti- Human language is part of humans’ social
ficially reproduce the world according to their own mediation of their reaction to objects. We do not
needs, the more deeply they understood the world react immediately and individually to things. We
as it exists. The development of human subjectivity react to things by engaging in a social process.
entailed a development of objectivity. Conversely, We utilize the collective strength of a social group
animals’ natural existence, submerged in nature and as the basis of reacting. This involves sharing
following its cycles and dictates, results in limited, information about objects with which we are
superficial consciousness of the world. dealing before we act. Language serves this purpose
of facilitating social mediation of our responses to
Social Cooperation/Coordination objects. This is why language is primarily directed
Stimulates Thought, Will, Agency, toward social interchange, it is not primarily a
Purpose direct expression of an individual encounter with
Thinking was another psychological capacity an object, as animal sounds are.
that was fostered by social cooperation and com- The social purpose of language is what
munication. Social cooperation spurred communi- stimulates it to be a symbolic vessel (representative)
cation that spurred symbolic meaning that spurred of information. The need for such a vessel is to
symbolic thinking. Let us examine each of these convey information to others to mediate their
three steps. reactions to nature, it is not to encode information
for one’s individual, immediate use. Mere encoding
1. Social cooperation requires precise
of objects is not the basis of symbols and language.
communication about the social activity.
It is the social transmission of information that
This makes social interchange the object of
is the basis of language that takes the form of
communication; communication is a social act that
encoding objects in symbols. Symbolization
involves sharing of information to further social
is a cognitive means to achieve a social end.
coordination. This social act and social objective
Symbolization is a socially inspired, socially
is what makes human language distinctive from
required, and socially informed cognitive process.
animal utterances. Animal utterances are essentially
3. As many scholars have observed, social
automatic individual expressions of feeling.
symbols that constitute language become the
A fearful animal involuntarily shrieks. This
means of thought. Thought rests upon language,
individual expression may coincidentally alert
which rests upon social cooperation and
other conspecific individuals to the danger,
coordination. Thought is thus a product of social
however, the shriek is not essentially a social act
activity. The social communicative basis of thought
directed at other individuals for the purpose of
is reflected in the etymology of “conscious.” It is
engaging in a social activity that unities them.
derived from Latin conscious, meaning having joint
The absence of these social features distinguishes
or common knowledge with another person.
animal calls from human language.
2. Language needs to be precise, complex, Because culture offers such enormous advantages
organized, and symbolic about particular objects over individual behavior governed by natural mecha-
and social interchanges to pass specific information nisms, all psychological functions such as intention-
to other members. Linguistic symbols must ality, will, self, agency, purpose, understanding, and
contain information in symbolic form that can be interpretation developed primarily to effect social

212 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


activity. Psychological functions did not develop complex, vast, dynamic cultural stimuli. Culture is
as individual functions to facilitate individual reac- the most complex, changeable, abstract, symbolized
tions to objects. environment, and it requires complex, modulated,
Will, purpose, and agency only exist where the flexible, willful subjectivity to envision, maintain,
actor can construct or produce behavior. This situ- and process these features of culture.
ation is characteristic of society. Society is humanly For example, when students are anxious about
constructed; it is not natural. People have wide lati- an impending test, the students’ anxiety is based on
tude in the kind of society they can construct. It an understanding of the educational system’s rule
can be cooperative or competitive, frugal or prof- that test scores are indicators of intelligence and that
ligate (speculative), monogamous or polygamous, future opportunities in education and work depend
gender equal or unequal, autocratic or democratic, on high test scores. Test anxiety is thus based on
structured into classes or relatively egalitarian, mili- understanding of social systems and future possi-
taristic or pacifistic, sexually permissive or sexually bilities: “There’s a good chance that the admissions
punitive, permissive child-rearing or strict child- committee of Harvard would like my GPA four
rearing, education through apprenticeship or for- years from now.”
mal teaching in schools, religious or atheistic, state Emotions cannot be based on a simple, imme-
religion or secular state. This latitude of choice diate, animalistic sensitivity to physical colors and
(which is not equivalent to free, capricious, or ran- odors. Such simple, natural, animalistic processes
dom choice) is fertile ground for developing will are designed to deal with relatively simple, circum-
and purpose. scribed, stable, overt, physical stimuli. As such, they
Animals that graze on naturally occurring grass cannot rise to the level of macro-cultural emotions
do not, and cannot, construct/produce their condi- we have been describing. A fundamentally new
tions; they find them ready-made and are beholden and different kind of emotionology and operating
to them. When grass is plentiful, the animal is well- mechanism must exist for emotions to be appropri-
fed; when grass is scarce the animal is hungry. The ate to complex, variable, symbolic cultural environ-
animal cannot do anything about its life conditions. ments and factors.
It lacks will and purpose because it is a natural crea- To love a country is not simply a matter of
ture that passively endures its natural environment associating an animalistic emotion of pleasure to
and is governed by automatic, involuntary, natu- “country.” Loving a country requires a different
ral processes suitable to natural existence. Natural kind of love than an animal is capable of experienc-
determinants of behavior are inversely related to ing. Loving a country is loving a general abstrac-
agency, will, self, and purpose. tion that has no physical sensory attributes. With
Burke and Ornstein are correct to identify human emotion, it is not simply the object that is
rudimentary acts on nature (such as gathering different from animal stimuli; the quality of love
and planting seeds) as contributing to the sense of that relates to this different kind of object is also
producing and the capacity to produce. However, different from what animals experience. The form
the opportunities for this kind of production were or quality of love adjusts to the form and quality of
undoubtedly few and far between, given the inde- the object being loved. If the object of love is a mas-
pendence of natural processes from man. Far more sive abstraction like Russia, the love for that object
conducive to regular, sustained construction was is abstract. Macro-cultural factors generate distinc-
social organization. That is why I theorize that tive psychological attributes that are geared to the
social construction was the primary impetus to the macro-cultural level.
human capacity to produce and to develop will and These macro attributes of psychology extend
purpose. to micro level stimuli and to natural stimuli such
as physical sounds, smells, and colors. For exam-
The Cultural Basis and Character ple, we become afraid of an animal in the woods
of Emotions because we utilize the macro-properties of emo-
Vygotsky emphasized that cultural factors and tions that originated on the macro-level to deal
cultural operating mechanisms elevate and expand with macro-cultural factors. We become afraid of
consciousness beyond animal consciousness. Human the bear because we recognize it to be “a bear,” not
consciousness is more active and agentive because it simply a form of a certain size, color, and odor. The
has a cultural operating mechanism that deals with physical features trigger conceptual knowledge and

ratn er 213
this is the basis of our emotion. Physical features The Darwinian Basis of Macro-cultural
do not directly generate our emotions. They are Psychology
mediated by cultural knowledge of the physical My argument for macro-cultural psychology is
features. Darwinian—new environments require new behav-
We utilize our conceptual knowledge of bears to ioral mechanisms and anatomical features. When
construe it as dangerous. We do not simply become psychologists attempt to reduce human psychol-
afraid because of its size or gestures. If we didn’t ogy to animal mechanisms, they are violating this
believe it to be dangerous, or if we had a gun with Darwinian principle. They postulate similar behav-
which we could kill it if necessary, then we would ioral mechanisms in radically distinct environments.
not fear the bear. Our emotion depends on abstract, They are ignoring the fact that the human cultural
conceptual cultural knowledge about things (“bears environment is qualitatively different from animal
are dangerous,” “this gun will kill the bear”), which physical environments and therefore requires dis-
is required by cultural life. Animal fear is not gen- tinctive behavioral mechanisms and anatomical
erated by this process or operating mechanism. features.
It is a different kind of fear from what humans Gordon explained the distinctive, emergent
experience. macro-cultural character of psychology with respect
The emotions we employ in face-to-face inter- to emotions:
actions similarly originate at the macro-level.
Social life produces emergent dimensions of emotion
Anger and guilt are based on ethical and legal
that resist reduction to properties inherent in the
values of macro-culture. If Jill injures John by
human organism . . . Socially emergent dimensions
mistake, then John would typically understand
of emotion transcend psychological and physiological
this and not become angry. But if Jill deliber-
levels of analysis in terms of (1) origin, (2) temporal
ately injures him, then he legitimately becomes
framework, (3) structure, and (4) change.
incensed. The reason is that anger is triggered
(Gordon, 1981, p. 562)
by the ethical and legal principle that deliber-
ate, willful injury is wrong. Western legal prin-
ciple distinguishes between willful and accidental Psychological Phenomena Maintain/
injury, condones different responses to them, and Solidify Culture
dispenses different punishments for them. Anger Returning to our macro-cultural psychological
is a legally sanctioned reaction to deliberate harm analysis of test anxiety in school, we observe that
but not to accidental or incidental injury. (If John it not only reflects an understanding of the edu-
did become angry at an unintentional injury, this cational system—it reciprocally reinforces the sys-
would be a sign that he lacked the social com- tem. It motivates students to adhere to the system’s
petence to assess whether a particular injury to requirements to study material that social authori-
him was intentionally or unintentionally caused ties mandate. This is an important way in which
by Jill—which is the cultural-legal criterion for psychology is cultural. It can only direct individu-
experiencing anger). Research shows that cultures als to culturally appropriate behavior if it is infused
devoid of the concept of personal responsibil- with cultural content. Anxiety must be generated by
ity experience little anger. Injury is attributed to a culturally formed concern for test scores if it is to
fate or accident, and it generates frustration and direct students to learn material that is on tests.
annoyance but not anger at a person (Ratner, Intelligence is similarly socially defined by test
1991, pp. 77–78; 2006, pp. 106–107). scores so that it motivates students to study test
Interpersonal guilt similarly rests upon a cultural- material to demonstrate their intelligence.
legal criterion that one is directly responsible for an
injury. If someone feels guilty after unintentionally Psychological Phenomena Are Socially
inflicting harm, then other people will console her Shared and Distributed
by saying, “Don’t feel guilty, it wasn’t your fault, you Because culturally formed emotions (and other
couldn’t have helped it.” They help alter her emo- psychological processes) sustain social systems, they
tion of guilt by explaining that the social basis for must be socially shared among masses of people to
it—namely, personal responsibility—did not exist. generate mass participation in the culture. If cultur-
This revised social understanding of her action less- ally formed psychological processes were limited to
ens her emotional feeling of guilt. a few individuals, or if they were shot through with

214 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


idiosyncratic meanings, then they would lose their demanded, educational success is not useful. Society
ability to promote culturally appropriate action nec- does not encourage them to acquire the educational
essary to sustain the social system. psychology of worrying about tests and studying
hard to pass them. Of course, official propaganda
Although each person’s experience of emotion has
proclaims that all students should try as hard as they
idiosyncratic features, culture shapes the occasion,
can to score well. But this is pure rhetoric that pre-
meaning, and expression of affective experience.
tends that the social system is open to all applicants.
Love, pity, indignation, and other sentiments are
In fact, it is not, and it has no room to accommo-
socially shared patterns of feeling, gesture, and
date the masses of people who would ideally like to
meaning.
go on for higher education and high-skilled jobs.
(Gordon, 1981, p. 563)
Consequently, the social system implicitly discour-
Oyserman and Markus (1998, pp. 123, 109, 107) ages masses of students from acquiring the cultural
explain why this must be true. psychology that would animate their demands for
higher education and high-skilled jobs.2
Although individuals are highly active in the process
Of course, educators do not acknowledge their
of self-making, the materials available for writing
role in discouraging (cooling-out) students from
one’s own story are a function of our public and
studying hard and experiencing test anxiety. They
shared notions of personhood. American accounts
pretend that this failure is the students’ own disin-
of the self, for example, involve a set of culture-
terest, rather than the system’s. This is a classic case
confirming ideas and images of success, competence,
of blaming the victim. Macro-cultural psychology
ability, and the need to “feel good.” The public
corrects this distortion by exposing the cultural
representations of selfhood that characterize a
basis of the psychology of people who are frozen out
given sociocultural niche function as common
of the upper levels of the social hierarchy.
denominators—they provide the primary structure
of the selves of those who live within these contexts.
Macro-cultural Factors Generate Concrete
These shared ideas produce necessary, although often
Features of Psychology
unseen, commonalities in the selves of people within
Macro-cultural factors generate concrete features
a given context. Although making a self appears to
of psychology just as they generate abstract psy-
be an individual and individualizing pursuit, it is also
chological features. This is a Darwinian argument.
a collective and collectivizing one. From a societal
Darwin’s environmentalism was specific regarding
perspective, self-construction is too important to be
physical features such as particular kinds of food and
left as a personal project. Social integration and the
predators with specific characteristics that selected
social order require that individuals of a given group
for specific anatomical traits of species. Social envi-
have reasonably similar answers to the “who am I”
ronments of humans are equally specific, and their
and “where do I belong” questions.
characteristics must be enumerated to understand
These remarks apply equally to all psychological particular psychological characteristics. To remain
phenomena. From a societal perspective, motiva- tied to cultural abstractions would be as inadequate
tion, emotions, perception, reasoning, and memory as if Darwin had referred to environments as “com-
are too important to be left as personal projects. posed of living matter” without enumerating spe-
They must all be congruent with macro-factors to cific forms and features.
ensure the endurance of these factors. Situating psychological phenomena in macro-
The social sharing of psychology is qualified by cultural factors enables us to transition easily from
the heterogeneity of cultural factors. Cultural fac- abstract features to concrete ones, for both are pres-
tors are neither homogeneous singly or collectively. ent in the same locus of macro-cultural factors. This
Any one factor is heterogeneous, and there are dif- avoids the common problem of remaining stuck in
ferences among them as well. This heterogeneity abstractions and ignoring concrete culture and con-
of macro-cultural factors introduces heterogeneity crete psychology.
into psychology as well. In our case of emotions, our analysis of abstract
Education, for example, is only functional for a features of macro-cultural factors leads to asking
select strata of the population for whom intellec- additional questions about their concrete features
tual competencies are required. For the masses of that foster concrete aspects of emotions. We can
people for whom intellectual competencies are not move from abstractions about success in school

ratn er 215
affecting future social positions and therefore social control functions [to subordinate workers
generating text anxiety to inquiring into the com- to capitalists] . . . Middle class personnel specialists
petitive structure of grades and future educational like Frederick Taylor and Elton Mayo were truly
and occupational opportunities and the differen- appalled by the amount of open anger they found
tial rewards that accrue to them, which place great among workers. They therefore amended their own
pressure on test scores and augment test anxiety for original agendas to build in explicit attempts to
those students striving for the opportunities. We banish anger from the workplace (pp. 248–249).
can inquire into a school’s specific policies, require- These macro-cultural requirements, features, and
ments, pedagogy, differential treatment of students functions of emotional regulation were then incor-
of different classes and gender, budget, quality of porated into family emotionology by the 1940s.
physical infrastructure, bureaucracy, and decision- Parents were urged by specialists and authors to
making process. employ ventilationist techniques with their chil-
dren. “Let children talk it out, label it, but in the
Emotional Regulation process defuse the whole emotion. Gone was the
Historian Peter Stearns (1989) describes concrete idea that anger could be disciplined but channeled”
historical aspects of emotions. He talks about three (p. 243).
styles of emotional control—during the American Stearns’ description reveals that emotional regu-
colonial era, Victorian era, and late twentieth cen- lation was a social issue; it was publicly discussed
tury. These are broadly shared cultural patterns of and organized by social leaders of macro-cultural
emotional regulation that were instigated by social factors to facilitate those factors. It was not a spon-
leaders to facilitate new macro-cultural factors. For taneous, personal expression; it did not originate in
example, as the modern capitalistic system uprooted the interpersonal domain of the family. It occurred
community structures and their corresponding reli- at a particular historical time for historical reasons.
gious values, the family unity and individual pri- It was a necessary subjectivity for particular cultur-
vacy were emphasized, and they combined to push al-historical activities.
for the creation of internalized emotional standards
By the 1930s and 1940s, alterations in business
that would not depend on outsiders’ judgment or
climate that stressed bureaucratic or sales skills over
enforcement (pp. 236, 248). The twentieth century
entrepreneurship placed a growing premium on the
push for new emotionology was spearheaded by
kind of emotional control that could assure smooth
leaders of the Protestant middle class in the United
personal relationships outside (as well, at least ideally,
States who were social pioneers of new macro-cul-
within) the home (p. 251).
tural factors. The new, internally regulated emotion-
ology was also spearheaded by American industrial This research on the style of emotional regulation
psychologists and other personnel authorities in the demonstrates that, as Vygotsky and Luria said, the
1920s, who launched a new effort to limit anger form and mechanisms of psychological phenomena
expressed in the workplace and to develop appro- are historically shaped as much as the content is.
priate mechanisms to accomplish this end . . .
.Secretarial training also shifted toward insistence on Concrete Cultural Features of
firm emotional control. Foremen were taught that Emotions: Mother Love
anger control was a key part of their jobs, and by the The cultural-historical organization of the con-
1940s, an array of retraining programs attempted to tent of maternal love is a fascinating example of
inculcate the lesson that smooth human relations macro-cultural psychology. Lewis (1989, p. 210)
constituted an end in itself, not a random, personal explains that the idealization of mother’s love (in
uprising. To achieve the new goals of anger control, the United States) was brewed in the same caul-
a series of strategies were devised . . . They involved a dron as Revolutionary political thought . . . The
ventilationist tactic when anger boiled up: Have an Revolutionary brew was seasoned by a variety of
aggrieved worker repeat his angry complaint several ingredients—republicanism, liberalism, evangeli-
times, so that the emotion would wear off and be cal Protestantism, and sensationalist psychology,
replaced, hopefully, by an embarrassed willingness and just as each of these strands of thought would
to drop the whole affair (p. 243). contribute to political thought, so too would they
Workplace anger drew attention after a period affect the conceptualization of family roles. The
of rising labor unrest; suppression had obvious late-eighteenth century revolt against patriarchy

216 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


dethroned both fathers and kings; and it said that based on these principles; by the 1960s, most did
citizens in a society, like members of a family, should not. Instead, motherhood came to be conceived as
be bound together by affection rather than duty. The a deeply fulfilling but fundamentally private experi-
Revolution . . . made of affection a political virtue. ence and a single (thought central) component of a
This is a pregnant statement because it shows how more multifaceted self (pp. 2–3).
psychology is brewed in cultural-historical-political Plant’s statement reveals how the psychology of
factors and also supports them, thus being a political motherhood is vital to a social order of family rela-
phenomenon. Affection was additionally political tions, work, and politics. Traditional motherhood,
in that it tended to appreciate women’s gender role, and maternal love, anchored an entire social order
which emphasized affection. Valuing a psychological in Victorian times. Traditional psychology of moth-
element that is organized by a social role validates erhood and maternal love ensconced women in the
the social role. home, away from work and politics, and it tied their
The cultural-historical organization of mother’s children to them and to restrictive moral codes. This
love was a cultural prop for the entire social struc- is a crucial point about the cultural function of psy-
ture that included separate gender spheres. “The 19th chology. The sentiment that maternal love is the pur-
century’s description of woman’s nature and role est and deepest sacrifice known to mankind is not a
derived from seemingly incontrovertible assump- simple, natural, circumscribed emotion; it is fraught
tions about the nature of a mother’s love” (Lewis, with political origins and repercussions. It implies
1989, p. 209). Psychology is thus a cultural linch- that women have no other social function beyond
pin. Psychology is a subjective cultural factor or the raising children. Women are to sacrifice themselves
subjective side of cultural factors. for the good of the country to rear model citizens.
Plant (2010) deepens this description of the cul- The notion that maternal love was sentimental
tural-historical nature of maternal love. She explains also objectified psychologically women’s exclusion
how it dramatically changed—not simply that it from the masculine realm of calculated rationality.
changed—over the first half of the twentieth cen- The notion that mothers were pure and were the
tury in the United States. She demonstrates that this watchdogs of moral purity similarly reflected and
psychological change was necessary to the develop- reinforced their exclusion from the materialistic,
ment of capitalism and how capitalism worked to political, commercial “impure,” “immoral” world.
adapt maternal love to its changing practices. Her Every psychological element of Victorian maternal
book traces the repudiation of (nineteenth century, love compounded middle class women’s domestic
Victorian) moral motherhood and the rise of a new role and their exclusion from public positions of
maternal ideal that both reflected and facilitated political and economic power.
White, middle-class women’s gradual incorpora- Culture is objectified in psychological attributes
tion into the political and economic order as indi- just as psychology is objectified in cultural artifacts,
viduals rather than as wives and mothers. It argues concepts, and institutions. Culture is objectified in
that the interwar period witnessed the emergence psychological attributes because these attributes are
of an antimaternalist critique that ultimately helped designed to accomplish cultural purposes.
to discredit four long-standing precepts that had Because psychology is a cultural linchpin, a new
defined late Victorian motherhood: the belief that modern form of motherhood and maternal love was
the mother/homemaker role was a full-time, life- necessary for anchoring and facilitating a new social
long role, incompatible with the demands of wage order in which women worked and purchased prod-
earning; the notion that motherhood was not sim- ucts outside the home, and in which children had
ply a private, familial role, but also the foundation to be free to cope with demands of free market jobs,
of female citizenship; the conviction that mothers consumerism, and politics. Traditional psychol-
should bind their children (especially their boys) to ogy of motherhood had to be undone if mothers
the home with “silver cords” of love to ensure their and children were to participate in the burgeon-
proper moral development; and the assumption ing consumer capitalism. Attacking or defending
that motherhood involved immense physical suffer- it is a political act that has political repercussions
ing and self-sacrifice. Of course, such ideas have not (see Susman, 1979, for similar cultural changes in
entirely lost currency in American culture today. In personality).
the early twentieth century, however, most middle- Traditional motherhood-maternal love was
class Americans shared a conception of motherhood undone by the social demands of consumer

ratn er 217
capitalism and also by its spokespeople, who explic- tantamount to abandoning the Victorian middle
itly attacked it and urged more consumer capitalist- class gender role! “The decline of the iconic mother
friendly forms. “The demystification of mother love [and sentimental maternal love] reflected a funda-
should be seen as part of a much broader transfor- mental transformation of the gendered structure of
mation of gender ideology and sexual relations” American political culture” (p. 56). The mother was
(p. 8). “The sheer pervasiveness of consumer cul- redefined as just another individual rather than pos-
ture, its increasingly blatant commercialization . . . sessing distinctive capabilities outside the hustle and
led many to view . . . sentimentalism in increasingly bustle of commercial society. “No longer a sacred
alarmist terms” (p. 43). Sentimentalism was an calling and duty, motherhood and homemaking
obstacle to the expansion of the materialistic, com- came to be construed as an emotionally fulfilling
mercialized free market. ‘job’—one that would ultimately end” (p. 116).
The most severe critics of American motherhood A fascinating corollary to the change in women’s
were not conservatives but liberals (p. 5). “Initially, maternal role and psychology of love was the change
the attacks on American motherhood emanated in the conception and experience of childbirth. The
primarily from psychological professionals and the traditional Victorian conception and experience was
cultural avant-garde. By the 1940s, however, anti- one of intense, irremediable pain and suffering. This
maternalism had gone mainstream” (p. 8). In addi- incarnated and expressed (and reinforced) the femi-
tion, the Office of War Information began urging nine social psychology of frailty, sacrifice, pitiable,
cultural producers (of media) to support its Woman and in need of condolence and protection. Women
power campaign which sought to draw women into were supposed to be sickly in daily life and in child-
the workforce (p. 41). As a result of all this, “The birth. A pale complexion was regarded as beautiful
New Woman who demanded a career, the vote, and because it objectified this social psychology.
even sexual satisfaction directly challenged accepted “By the late 1930s, a growing number of obste-
notions of female nature” (p. 9). tricians, writers, and mothers themselves had begun
Between World War I and World War II, to challenge this view of childbirth by depicting
momism was attacked as emasculating the nation, it as a wholly normal and natural event” (p. 119).
rather than upholding its moral fiber. Sentimental The new dictum was that pregnancy should be as
maternal love was denounced as unnatural and normal for a woman as wage-earning is. “The nor-
unhealthy for mother and child. Motherhood was malization of childbirth in the 1940s and 1950s
shifted to a private relationship between individu- helped to fuel, but was also fueled by, the broad
als rather than a cultural duty. This accorded with cultural shifts this book has traced” (p. 119). This is
the expansion of the individualistic free market and a keen statement of the dialectical role that psychol-
consumerism. The doting mother was chastised as ogy plays in culture. “For motherhood to be truly
interfering with the individual development of chil- modernized, with the emphasis shifted from self-
dren. Maternal attachment was rejected as narcissis- sacrifice toward self-realization, childbirth itself had
tic; it should be controlled and displaced by a love to be transformed from a dangerous and dreaded
that encouraged children’s independence and emo- ordeal into an exhilarating experience” (p. 120).
tional separation (p. 88). New emotional norms Even the term for childbirth—labor—lost its earlier
(feeling rules) were promulgated. “Wherever young meaning of travail (pain, strenuous, self-sacrificing
couples looked—in popular magazines, Hollywood effort) and became a nondescript term. The associa-
films, or professional literature—they found their tion of frailty with middle class status changed to
desires for autonomy validated and their ambiva- sensuous experience representing middle class status
lence and antagonism toward their parents, espe- for women (pp. 121–122). Culture was objectified
cially their mothers, legitimized” (p. 109). Maternal in new psychological attributes that functioned to
morality was condemned as restrictive of individ- maintain that culture.
ual’s freedom—as it was on the economic market- As childbirth was reconceptualized away from
place. “Experts in the 1940s and 1950s repeatedly suffering and sacrifice, and in need of chivalrous
condemned ‘self-sacrificing’ mothers who con- male protection, it came to be regarded as enjoy-
centrated all of their energies on their children” able and normal for the individual mother. And
(p. 115). Mothers were urged to diversify their ener- most interesting is that this reconceptualization of
gies and activities as they participated in the economy childbirth (in line with new social roles) led to a real
and politics. Abandoning maternal self-sacrifice was change in the experience of childbirth. Childbirth

218 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


was experienced as less painful than before. Of the liberatory potential of psychology/behavior so
course, it was physically uncomfortable; however, that we do not idealize psychology/behavior as more
as cognitive theories of emotion explain, the dis- transcendent of society than it actually is. We apply
comfort was modulated by the sense of individual a macro-cultural psychological critique to the psy-
prowess and agency and physical satisfaction of the chology of people as well as to psychological doc-
mother—just as athletes minimize discomfort of trines that articulate this psychology.
injury as they concentrate on the importance of the The macro-cultural psychology of maternal love
game. Childbirth was no longer regarded as a com- can be summarized in the following principles of
plicated, sacrificial, mystical experience. This altered macro-cultural psychology (a full list of the princi-
the sensation of childbirth. Middle-class mothers ples will be compiled after additional examples):
endorsed the normal easy childbirth associated with
peasant women who were known to resume work 1. Abstract aspects of maternal love are rooted
immediately after birth. The French obstetrician in macro-cultural factors such as social institutions
Fernand Lamaze popularized the sense of natural and cultural concepts. Maternal love for children is
childbirth. a cultural phenomenon just as love for a country is,
or just as fear of failing a school test is. Mother love
Now the woman who suffered least—who thrived
involves concern for the child as a social being,
during pregnancy and experienced little if any pain
with moral character, appropriate social skills for
during childbirth and its aftermath—came to be
succeeding in society, even an attractive physique
deemed most worthy of that increasingly coveted
and health. Mother love includes a view of the
adjective, “feminine.”
child’s future and preparing her for it. All of these
(p. 145)
aspects of maternal love involve conscious thought,
Plant’s analysis reveals that maternal love was planning, reason. Maternal love is not natural;
a product of historical forces, as Vygotsky stated. it is not analogous to a mother dog nuzzling her
Modern maternal love was fostered by modern puppies, whose protective sense involves none of
capitalist social institutions in combination with these concerns, mental processes, and activities.
cultural concepts that were articulated by social 2. The abstract aspects of maternal love are con-
leaders (experts, professionals, government policies, cretized by concrete aspects of macro-cultural fac-
business and community leaders). Changing oppor- tors. The cultural psychology of maternal love is
tunities and requirements of social institutions necessary to a social system. It generates socially
generated a sense of new maternal love among the appropriate behavior. Psychology is an active ele-
middle class that was articulated by social leaders. ment of society; it is not a passive byproduct.
This pincer movement was exemplified in the Maternal love generated social relations.
writing of Betty Friedan in The Feminine Mystique 3. A social system strives to organize a culturally
(1963). “By giving voice to the inchoate frustrations appropriate form of maternal love to sustain itself.
of countless middle-class women, Friedan helped Failure to organize this kind of sentiment would
to spark the feminist movement of the 1960s and undermine the social system. New social opportu-
1970s” (p. 147). In other words, the institutional nities and requirements for new skills generate the
pressures such as economic needs for women to work incentive for new psychological competencies in
and consume products generated popular inchoate parents and children. In addition, spokesmen of the
frustrations and desires for a new social psychology society explicitly attack traditional cultural forms of
including maternal love. Friedan articulated these maternal love to discredit them and move people to
and congealed them into an outlook and a cultural adopt new cultural forms. These exhortations fall on
psychology. Women embraced this perspective and receptive ears because people felt the need for new
utilized it as their “mediational means” for dealing competencies from changing opportunities and
with contemporary events and relationships and requirements of macro-cultural factors.
their own self-concept.3 4. Within the social structure that organizes the
This kind of macro-cultural psychological analy- concrete psychology of maternal love, the dominant
sis illuminates the cultural origins of psychology, cultural factor is the political economy. The capi-
and it importantly illuminates the cultural limits to talist political economy is commodity production.
psychology—for example, in consumer capitalism Commoditization and commercialization were
or Victorian domesticity. It enables us to evaluate dominant influences on Western maternal love.

ratn er 219
5. Maternal love is a complex of cultural- parameters or the cultural quality of maternal
psychological elements that share common love will be subverted, and this would undermine
features while being distinct. The complex is a the social structure that requires an appropriate
unity of differences, as Hegel said. Each feature maternal love to generate appropriate social
contributes its distinctive character to the behavior.
complex. Each feature also expresses/represents/ 9. Psychological phenomena such as sensations
refracts the entire complex of motherhood of childbirth depend on cultural concepts. They are
through its own distinctive position. For higher social mental functions, as Vygotsky said.
example, Victorian, middle-class childbirth The pain of childbirth incarnated, crystallized,
possessed the distinctive psychology of suffering and objectified the social psychology (role) of
that crystallized other aspects—sentimental, motherhood in sensory experience. The feeling
dutiful, frail, accepting, needy—and added to state is only apprehended through a cultural-
them. hermeneutical analysis that elucidates the social
6. Psychology (e.g., maternal love) is formed psychology (role) that it expresses.
on the macro-cultural level for macro-cultural
purposes, it is objectified in macro-cultural factors, We are concerned to demonstrate that mac-
it objectifies culture, it supports culture, it is ro-cultural psychology is a general psychological
socialized by macro-cultural factors, it represents theory that explains all psychological phenomena.
a social position within society, it represents The example of maternal love represents how all
membership within society, and it gains access to psychological phenomena originate in macro-cul-
social positions. tural factors, embody these factors, are objectified
The manner in which maternal love incarnates, in them, objectify/represent them, and also sustain
and expresses macro-cultural factors may be macro-cultural factors. To demonstrate the general
depicted as in Figure 10.1. applicability of macro-cultural psychology, it will be
7. Maternal love was not formed as a personal helpful to present a few additional examples of psy-
invention to express personal desires. On the chological phenomena.
contrary, the personal desire and quality of
maternal love was fostered by macro-cultural Adolescence
factors. Condon (1987, pp. 7–8) explains how changes in
8. Personal variations in the quality of maternal technology and social institutions among the Inuit
love are internal to the culturally circumscribed Eskimos fostered adolescence and adolescent psy-
parameters. They must not violate these chology. In traditional times, before Euro-Canadian

individual
consumerism autonomy

Maternal maternal
love role/identity

social
work demands
on children
Figure 10.1 Cultural Constitution (Determinations)
of Maternal Love

220 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


contact, the transition from childhood to adulthood position, as Bourdieu emphasizes. It is the macro-
was rapid and unaccompanied by a prolonged period cultural complex that drives adolescence, creates the
of adolescence. The harsh arctic climate and scarcity space for it, fosters it, demands it, is its telos, and
of resources forced children to quickly acquire adult forms its attributes.
skills for survival. They did so in the isolated nuclear
family, which was dispersed over a wide area with lit- Self
tle interfamilial contact. Interactions with parents far The modern Western self is a historical product
outweighed in importance interactions with peers. that was spawned by economic changes in England
This complex of factors precluded an adolescent social during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
and psychological stage in between childhood and These changes entailed activities that increased
adulthood. the reliance on personal judgment, initiative, and
In the modern period, interlocking technological responsibility. Businessmen made business deci-
and institutional changes have dramatically changed sions on their own to maximize their own profit.
the progression of Inuit life stages. Increased eco- They did not follow traditional community business
nomic prosperity and security allow parents to earn practices, consult with community members, or act
a living without the contribution of their children. for the benefit of the community. An individualistic
This allows children to attend school rather than self was therefore built into the economic changes.
work. In addition, the population is concentrated The culture of modern individualism emerged
into settlements, which enables children to form a most prominently and pervasively in England in
peer culture. This peer culture adopted many of the the century leading to the English Revolution. It
styles portrayed on television, which became afford- began with the rise of a Puritan opposition in the
able with the new standard of living. These inter- 1560s . . . Its constituents were the product of pro-
locking factors place children in a separate social found changes in the English economy. During that
position from their parents, which was impossible century, the privatization of agricultural holdings
earlier. They contribute to the elaboration of a stage and the emergence of a national market had stimu-
of life now referred to as the “teenage” years. lated widespread commercialization with incentives
This description reveals how adolescence was for specialized production, technological improve-
formed by interrelated changes in institutions, ments, and a consolidation of holdings. The increas-
artifacts, and physical demography of the popu- ing role of individual initiative, business acumen,
lation. Adolescence is a social role, a social stage and responsibility for success in this new market
of life, a social space, and a social psychology. It economy generated a rising group of enterprising
does not originate inside individuals from intra- rural gentry, yeomen, and artisans . . . The depen-
organismic processes—whether natural or personal. dence of fortune on an individual’s own actions
Adolescence is a complex cultural phenomenon that increased the reliance on personal judgment and
includes social positions, social organization, tech- initiative (Block, cited in Ratner, 2006a, pp. 82–83;
nology, and psychology. The psychological element cf. Ratner, 2002, pp. 41–42).
is part of the macro-cultural complex. It is qualita- This description highlights the continuity
tively distinguishable from concentrated population between macro-culture and psychology. The eco-
settlements, economic prosperity, and attending nomic revolution consisted of economic privati-
school, and it can be studied as a distinctive element zation that entailed and necessitated individual
and promoted as such. We can reasonably talk about initiative and responsibility. The individual self was
the psychology of adolescence and understand the an integral part of the capitalist economic revolu-
subjective experience as such; it is not eliminable tion. Capitalist business required an individualistic
or reducible to the other cultural elements. In fact, self that took individual initiative and responsibil-
we must talk about it to have a complete picture of ity for actions. Capitalism and individualism went
adolescence. However, it is always an element of the hand-in-hand: macro-culture and psychology. They
macro-cultural complex on which it depends (origi- were two sides of the same coin; they were continu-
nates), which it expresses, represents, embodies, and ous with each other, on the same plane, indispens-
supports. The subjectivity of adolescence cannot able for each other.
exist without the objective conditions. Psychological Within this spiral, capitalist development was
dispositions would be impossible without the social the leading element. This is what businessmen

ratn er 221
sought to achieve. Individualistic self was the sub- manager, and told them to leave the premises at
jectivity necessary to implement capitalism. The self once, they would laugh at her. Her power to dismiss
was functional for capitalism; it did not arise on its them is a legal, institutional power. Anyone who
own, in a vacuum. Businessmen did not one day just occupied the manager’s position, or role, would
decide to develop a new form of self. They did so to have the same power by virtue of the position, not
realize a socio-economic objective. Incipient capitalist their individuality.4
development was the stimulus and telos of the indi- The workers’ response is also determined by the
vidualistic self. It also provided the constituents of legal structure of the institution. Their agency is
the self, its concrete qualities. (The individualistic self reduced by the institutional structure (in propor-
is not an abstraction, as cross-cultural psychologists tion to the degree to which the manager’s agency is
construe it Ratner, 2012c.) Reciprocally, the indi- augmented by it). This is a function of the organiza-
vidualistic self provided the subjectivity to develop tion of the institution. It is not a function of leader-
capitalist businesses. For subjectivity (e.g., the self) ship in general.
to implement capitalist business practices, it had to A different institutional structure would elicit
adjust itself to them and take their form. The dialec- different kinds of agency from both manager and
tical opposite of consciousness’s forming capitalism is workers. The manager and workers would jointly
that it conformed to the needs of capitalism. discuss management-proposed layoff plans and
These points are true for all psychological phe- investment plans in a worker-owned cooperative.
nomena. Psychology evolved as the behavioral The corporate manager’s agency extends far
mechanism for constructing and maintaining mac- beyond her employees in her firm. It affects the
ro-cultural factors. Culture was the stimulus and education of children she has never met. This effect
telos of psychology, and both the general and spe- results from the institutional structure of society:
cific properties of culture provided the constituents Education is funded by tax revenue, which is taken
of psychological phenomena. from wages, which depend on corporate hiring poli-
cies, which depend on investment strategies.
Agency The corporate manager does not directly affect
Because cultural issues underlie psychology and your education by interacting with you (or with tax
behavior, agency is actually social agency. One’s collectors, or policy makers) personally, as one indi-
ability to affect one’s own behavior and that of oth- vidual to another individual. Rather, she affects your
ers is socially determined by the institutional struc- education through the network of social institutions
ture of society. This structure mediates agency and that are linked to her corporation. It is the institu-
augments or restricts it. Agency is formed by and tional connection between wages, taxes, educational
in macro-cultural factors; it is not an attribute of budgets, training and hiring of teachers, and build-
an individual who freely exercises it. This must be ing of schools that gives her business action the abil-
true for agency to engage in culturally appropriate ity to affect your education, and the education of
behavior, which is necessary for cultural mainte- millions of students (see Ratner, 2006, p. 60).
nance. This point is demonstrated by considering She could never have such vast effect over so
the agency of a corporate manager and an employee many students individually. She could never meet
in a capitalist firm. and influence so many students on an interpersonal
The manager has enormous power to realize her basis. As an individual, she would have no power to
goals and to affect her employees and the commu- make you attend a school with many resources and
nity at large. This power stems from the institutional small classes, or a poor school with few resources
structure of the corporation and its relation to other and large classes. But she can make your school, and
institutions. The manager has the power to sum- many schools, rich or poor, good or bad, through
marily terminate the employment of her employees. her wage and investment policy as corporate man-
They, in turn, must obediently leave the premises ager. Her agency is far greater through impersonal
when she orders them to. If they do not, the police institutional connections than it is through per-
will forcibly remove them. Both behaviors are medi- sonal, individual connections.
ated by the legal structure of the institution. The Similarly, middle class people have more power-
manager’s power to terminate employees is not a ful agency than poor people because of the intellec-
personal power based on personal qualities. If she tual and social capital they have acquired through
walked up to employees as an individual, not as a their class position. It is naive to believe that every

222 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


individual has agency in an equivalent form without and residential areas and their respective scents”
specifying its cultural organization. (ibid.).
Nor does agency have any intrinsic capacity to
Indeed, because most smells were subject to
understand, resist, and transform unfulfilling con-
interpretation, they were incredibly malleable and
ditions and behaviors. Agency can take any num-
could be used to advance several agendas, whether
ber of forms. Nazis and slave owners had agency.
concerning the social makeup of a community or the
Prisoners do also. Agency does not necessarily lead
development of its natural environment. Using their
any of these individuals to transcend their condi-
noses, Americans thus developed an alternative way
tions and behavior (Ratner, 2009). Agency has
of understanding the world and of wielding power,
cultural origins, characteristics, mechanisms, and
one that responded quickly to variable circumstances
function just as all psychology does. Agency only
and emotions.
becomes truly fulfilled when it pointedly adopts a
(ibid.)
critical cultural perspective and works to transform
the macro-cultural factors that oppress people. Olfaction, perception in general, and psychology
Agency only becomes fulfilled and critical through in general, is a proxy for culture, represents culture,
the social standpoint it adopts. It is not critical and and promulgates/reinforces culture.
fulfilling in and of itself. Agency does have the abil- Interestingly, third world cities such as Bangkok
ity to reflect on behavior and conditions; however, have developed different categories of odors to
this is an abstract ability that must be concretized by signify different social values/distinctions. Thais
specific social analysis and action.4 developed an “olfactory dualism” in which the pub-
lic stench of refuse was not bothersome, but body
Sensory Processes: Olfaction odors were. This reflected the personalistic nature
Chiang explains how our sense of smell is orga- of Thai society that required the utmost cleanliness
nized by cultural and political factors. Her account of individuals.
dovetails our earlier discussion of pain associated A complete cultural psychology of olfaction
with childbirth. “Odors are invested with cultural must emphasize that individuals invest odors with
values and employed by societies as a means of and cultural meanings that define odors as pleasant or
model for defining and interacting with the world” unpleasant, refined or gross. This cultural content
(Chiang, 2008, p. 407). The perception and evalu- (significance) of olfaction is one source of evaluat-
ation of odors is part of culture, expresses culture, ing a group of people who are associated with a par-
and is a window into culture. The smells to which ticular odor. However, people are unaware of this
we are sensitive, and the sensory quality of smells, acculturating of odor. People erroneously assume
depend on the social practices they are associated that their perception of smell is natural and that
with. “In deciding what smelled good and what the reason they dislike an odor and the people and
smelled bad, people were making decisions about activities associated with it is natural, not cultural.
what activities and people they valued” (ibid.). The People thus reify their psychology—their percep-
natural smell did not determine the value assigned tion—as natural and use it to explain their social
to it. For example, smells associated with racial behavior—for example, individuals justify their
and ethnic minorities and the working class—the abhorrence of manual labor and laborers as having a
smells of their bodies, homes, and labor—were natural basis in olfaction (“Of course I loathe them,
evaluated negatively because these activities and they smell so foul”).5
their actors were socially disparaged. Wealthy Macro-cultural psychology negates the reifica-
people surrounded themselves with different odors tion of psychology and social categories by explain-
(e.g., perfumes) to distinguish themselves socially. ing that cultural practices, status, and values define
Perfumed scents were perceived as pleasant because the physical odor and the social activities and actors
of their social association—just as bodily appear- who partake of an odor. It is not the case that odors
ances were infused with cultural significances that have naturally unpleasant qualities that define peo-
determined their attractiveness. “The social and ple who emit them. Naturalistic conceptions of psy-
material dimensions of odors became inseparable” chology generate naturalistic, reified conceptions of
(ibid.). Odor became a proxy of social standing. social distinctions, whereas cultural conceptions of
“Zoning laws in contemporary Western cities have psychology generate cultural, changeable concep-
created ‘domains of smell’ that separate industrial tions of society.

ratn er 223
Mental Illness It is as if something is thrown in me, bursts me
Forms (symptoms) of mental illness are cultural asunder. Why do I divide myself in different pieces?
phenomena (Ratner & El-Badwi, 2011). Consider I feel that I am without poise, that my personality is
the remarkable parallel between Kraepelin’s descrip- melting and that my ego disappears and that I do not
tion of schizophrenia (dementia praecox) and T.S. exist anymore. Everything pulls me apart. The skin
Eliot’s description of modern society. Kraepelin is the only possible means of keeping the different
defined schizophrenia as “a loss of inner unity of pieces together. There is no connection between the
intellect, emotion, and volition”; T.S. Eliot diagnosed different parts of my body.
the modern condition as a widening rift between (Sass, 1992, p. 15)
thought and emotion, intellect and sensation, and a
general failure to achieve unity of sensibility” (Sass, The symptoms of schizophrenia—withdrawal,
1992, p. 357). It could not be coincidental that highly idiosyncratic and abstract patterns of thinking,
the inner, psychological loss of unity and the outer, and a preoccupation with hidden meanings— bear
social rift arouse simultaneously. The “modern con- unmistakable congruence with the broad social rela-
dition” clearly fosters psychological disintegration. tions and concepts of capitalism (such as individual-
The psychological and the social are continuous ism, privacy, privatized meaning). Sass (pp. 369–371)
with one another on the same plane. Psychologists explains it well:
and psychiatrists try to break the unitary plane and Consider the emphasis on disengagement and
place psychology and society in separate realms. The self-consciousness that was fostered by the ideas of
unity (homology) of psychological disturbance and philosophers like Descartes, Locke, and Kant (as
social relations is seen in historical accounts of men- well as by patterns of socialization in daily life) . . .
tal illness. (Sass, 1992, p. 362). This turned modern human beings away from the
The feeling of personal worthlessness (i.e., the search for an objective external order, enjoining
“inferiority complex”) is a historical construct of us instead to turn inward and become aware of
recent origin. Previously, individuals felt a sense of our own activity . . . to take charge of constructing
sinfulness but not personal inadequacy. The notion our own representation of the world . . . Central
of personal worthlessness only arose during the past to these tendencies is a pervasive detachment, a
century, evidently reflecting a rising individualistic disengagement that demands that we stop simply
concern over personal inadequacy that is bred by living in the body or within our traditions and
intense competition (Ratner, 1991, p. 270). This is habits, and by making them objects for us, subject
a momentous fact for macro-cultural psychology. them to radical scrutiny and remaking.
For it says that even a sense of personal worthless- Related currents, more closely associated with
ness is a historical construct, not a personal one. If romanticism and its aftermath, have tended to glorify
anything seems to qualify as a personal construct it the inner self, by implying that human fulfillment
is the haunting sense that one is worthless. Yet the lies in discovering one’s own uniqueness and recog-
possibility of this feeling is itself historical. Although nizing the central role of one’s own subjectivity. (It is
people have always suffered misfortune and defeat, only with romanticism that autobiographies come to
the psychological response to this, and interpreta- be filled with forms of self-reflection focused on the
tion of it, as blaming oneself and feeling worthless drama and idiosyncrasies of one’s own inner life . . . )
is historically cultivated. If schizoids and schizophrenics, like other human
Another pathological symptom, the schizophrenic beings, are subject to the influences of their social
divided self, only emerged in the late nineteenth cen- milieu, it is not hard to see how a number of their
tury in conjunction with multiple, disjunctive social core traits (the asocial turning inward, the lack of
roles. Although earlier views recognized distinct spontaneity, the detachment from emotions, the
functions or components of self such as soul and hyperabstractness, the anxious deliberation and cog-
body, these all revolved around one self. The nine- nitive slippage, and the exquisitely vulnerable sense
teenth century marked a new conception of differ- of self-esteem, for example) might be exaggerations
ent selves or personalities within one individual. This of tendencies fostered by this civilization . . .
was reflected in Robert Louis Stevenson’s Dr. Jekyll [This is why] what evidence there is suggests
and Mr. Hyde (1886). This cultural-historical frag- that schizophrenic illness did not even appear, at
mentation is recapitulated in the symptomatology of least in any significant quantity, before the end of
mental disorder. As one patient said, the eighteenth or beginning of the nineteenth . . .

224 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


Catatonia was not described until after 1850. Even and bureaucratization of modern life; and Emile
more telling is the absence or extreme rarity of Durkheim—on the juggernaut of industrialization
descriptions of clear instances of individual cases of and the growing reflectiveness that cause traditional
schizophrenia, at least of the chronic, autistic form, values to lose their quasi-natural status.
in either medical books or general literature prior to (ibid., p. 371)
the nineteenth century. The first clinical descriptions
are those of Haslam and Pinel in 1809; the first Mental Illness and Capitalism
literary descriptions that definitely qualify are those Foucault describes the structural congruence
of the main characters in George Buccaneer’s story between symptoms of mental illness and the alien-
“Lenz” and Honore de Balzac’s “Louis Lambert,” ated, exploitive character of capitalism. He debunks
both written in the 1830s—and this despite the the idea that mental illness is a separate realm from
fact that easily recognizable descriptions of all other society. In fact, the phenomenological sense of sep-
major mental diseases, including affective psychoses, arateness and delusion that many patients experi-
can be found in ancient as well as Renaissance ence is caused by and recapitulates the alienation,
and eighteenth century texts. Many writers in the self-obfuscation, and contradictions of capitalism.
eighteenth century made systematic attempts to It is not caused by a deficit in consciousness itself.
describe the known forms of mental illness, which “It is not because one is ill that one is alienated, but
resulted in works like Pinel’s diagnostic system insofar as one is alienated that one ill” (Foucault,
(1901). But despite the striking clinical picture that 1987, p. xxvi).
schizophrenia presents (at least in its acute and florid
It would be absurd to say that the sick man
forms), one can find no account of it in these or
machinizes his world because he projects a
any earlier works. (ibid., pp. 364–365). Even Eugen
schizophrenic world in which he is lost . . . In fact,
Bleuler, who coined the term schizophrenia in 1908,
when man remains alienated from what takes place
described a “specific type of alteration of thinking,
in his language, when he cannot recognize any
feeling, and relation to the external world which
human, living signification in the productions of his
appears nowhere else in this particular fashion.”
activity, when economic and social determinations
(ibid., p. 14)
place constraints upon him and he is unable to feel at
Sass (1992, p. 10) explores “one of the great iro- home in this world, he lives in a culture that makes
nies of modern thought: the madness of schizophre- a pathological form like schizophrenia possible . . .
nia—so often imagined as being antithetical to the Only the real conflict of the conditions of existence may
modern malaise, even as offering a potential escape serve as a structural model for the paradoxes of the
from its dilemmas of hyperconsciousness and self- schizophrenic world.
control—may, in fact be an extreme manifestation To sum up, it might be said that the psychological
of what is in essence a very similar condition.” dimensions of mental illness cannot, without
Sass explains the methodology necessary to elu- recourse to sophistry, be regarded as autonomous . . .
cidate the congruence between macro-culture and In fact, it is only in history that one can discover the sole
psychological symptoms: concrete apriori from which mental illness draws . . . its
necessary figures.
A comprehensive model of the social origin both
(Foucault, 1987, pp. 83–85, my emphasis)
of schizophrenia and of the modernist sensibility
would need to go beyond this discussion of abstract In sum, although individuals construct morbid
ideas and mentality and to acknowledge as well symptoms, their construction is shaped by macro-
how each of these conditions is intricated with the cultural factors and it is made from cultural fac-
modern social order—with patterns of political tors. Detachment, skepticism, subjectivism, and
and bureaucratic organization, family structures, other psychological mechanisms of mental illness
economic practices, and technological developments were objective constructs objectified on the macro-
of modernity. The most influential descriptions of cultural level by novelists and philosophers. They
these aspects of modernity come from the founding were not spontaneously constructed by mental
fathers of sociology: Karl Marx—on the alienating patients. This is an important tenet of macro-cul-
consequences of certain economic structures tural psychology, that psychological constructs are
and relationships; Max Weber—on the growing macro-level constructs that are widely known in a
rationalization, technologization, secularization, population. These are the mediational means that

ratn er 225
individuals draw on as their psychological mecha- (e.g., the biochemistry of testosterone or a neuro-
nisms for dealing with stress and other social fac- transmitter), does not naturally have the ability to
tors. Of course, not all individuals draw on the same detect, understand, and respond to cultural events
cultural tools; however, they draw on some cultural in a predefined manner (see Joseph & Ratner,
tool for their psychological operations. This makes 2012). The operating mechanism of mental illness
these operations cultural. is no more a simple, automatic, biological response
Macro-factors generate mental illness by exert- to stress than maternal love is a simple, automatic,
ing specific stressors and stresses on people—for biological response to color, odor, and size of phys-
example, alienation, detachment, insecurity of ical stimuli.
unemployment, and competition (which were not
prevalent in other societies)—and unique models Demographic Variations in Mental Illness
for coping with these stresses—for example, frag- The fact that not everyone in a culture becomes
mentation, skepticism, detachment, subjectivism. mentally ill does not negate the fact that men-
This two-pronged cultural influence can be dia- tal illness is cultural. Society—especially modern
grammed as in Figure 10.2. society—is complex and diverse, and not everyone
in it is exposed to the same stressors in the same
Biological Explanations of Mental Illness degree. The fact that some people escape it simply
The fact that mental illness is generated by cul- means that they occupy more sheltered social posi-
tural pressures such as alienation, oppression, and tions. People who are exposed to stressors intensely
social contradictions and utilizes cultural concepts and extensively will suffer more illness than those
such as detachment, skepticism, and subjectivism as exposed in lesser degrees. Detailed research has
its operating mechanism makes mental illness a cul- proven that mental illness is monotonically related
tural phenomenon that is not reducible to biochem- to the number of social stressors encountered
ical processes. The latter cannot determine/generate (Ratner, 1991, Chapter 6). This is why mental ill-
the symptoms of mental illness because they are not ness is over-represented in the lower classes where
sensitive to the cultural stressors Sass and Foucault stressors are greater.
enumerated, nor are they capable of generating What is remarkable about the cultural content
culturally specific symptoms such as detachment, and historical specificity of forms of mental ill-
depression, schizophrenia. ness is that they exist among people in the depths
An operating mechanism is required in humans of despair and disorientation. One might expect
that is sensitive to social stress and generates cul- estranged, confused, anxious, isolated individuals to
tural-psychological symptoms to it. Biological strike out with random, idiosyncratic responses that
processes must be invested with cultural sensitiv- lack social significance and commonality. However,
ity before they can detect and respond to complex, the fact is that the victims draw on cultural mod-
symbolic cultural events. Biology must be raised to els (values, concepts, practices) as their mediational
the cultural level, it must be acculturated, to pro- means for coping with adversity. Even in their mis-
cess cultural events and behavior. Biology, per se ery and confusion, they display social sensitivity to,
and social dependence on, macro-cultural factors
to guide their psychological reactions. This is why
there is social coherence to mental illness in particu-
Stressors-
stresses
lar historical epochs. Our epoch has schizophrenia,
Symptoms eating disorders, and hyperactivity that other eras
lacked. Conversely, the Victorian era had thousands
of cases of hysteria that disappeared today because
the cultural-historical stressors, stresses, and coping
Macro mechanisms have changed.
cultural Coping North American and European symptoms of dis-
factors mechanisms turbance rest on Protestant values of individualism,
self-control, rationalism, activism, and introspec-
tion. Catholic societies that value communalism,
Figure 10.2 Two-Pronged Cultural Shaping of Mental Illness fateful acceptance of destiny, and higher authority

226 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


manifest quite different symptomology. Whereas consequences, and demographics are cultural.
American patients tend toward active symptom- Individuals utilize cultural means to cope with
atology with ideational distortion and elaboration, cultural stressors even in non-normative manners.
Catholic Latin patients tend toward passive symp- Individual activity does not make mental illness
tomatology with a suspension of cognitive effort. an individual creation. Its causes and constituents
Americans tend toward obsessional thoughts, intel- are cultural. Unhappy individuals did not sponta-
lectualization, guilt, and self-blame, whereas Latinos neously invent the thin body image as an ideal for
suffer more somatic complaints, sleeplessness, and feeling successful; they appropriated it from the mac-
obesity. Americans are more lonely and suspicious ro-cultural level where it (recognizably, commonly)
than Latinos, whereas Latinos are more dependent represented middle-class identity and success.
(Ratner, 1991, pp. 268–278; see Marsella & Yamada, Jackson (1993, p. 212) explained this well:
2007 for cultural variations in mental illness).
Anorexia and bulimia manifest demographic Our subjectivities, including that aspect of them we
variations. These implicate cultural stressors, stresses, understand as our emotions, are shaped by social and
and coping skills in the disorders. A demographic cultural processes and structures, but are not simply
analysis reveals that 90% of anorectics are women. passively accepted by us. We actively participate in
In addition, these eating disorders become prevalent working ourselves into structures, and this, in part,
among non-Western women to the extent that non- explains the strength of our subjection to them. We
Western countries adopt capitalistic social relations. create for ourselves a sense of what emotions are, of
Eating disorders have increased sixfold in the past what being in love is. We do this by participating
25 years in Japan with increasing industrialization, in sets of meanings constructed, interpreted,
urbanization, and the fraying of traditional family propagated, and deployed throughout our culture,
forms following World War II. Additional macro- through learning scripts, positioning ourselves within
cultural factors that spurred eating disorders include discourses, constructing narratives of self. We make
middle-class gender roles for Japanese women and sense of feelings and relationships in terms of love
slim body ideals of beauty.6 because a set of discourses around love pre-exists us
Anorexia is rare on the Caribbean island of as individuals and through these we have learnt what
Curacao. The few cases that exist are confined to love means.
well-educated, high-income women of light skin,
who have lived abroad. No cases of anorexia are Mainstream Psychology versus Macro-Cultural
found among the majority Black population. Psychology Regarding Mental Illness
Macro-cultural psychology accounts for this demo- Psychologists and psychiatrists are insensitive to
graphic fact. Curacao women who become anorexic these social origins, mechanisms, characteristics,
are middle class, light-skinned individuals. As such and functions of mental illness.
they adopt light-skinned, Western, middle class ide- In North America, especially in the United States,
als of thinness. This class significance of slimness is the discussion of social factors in the development
what accounts for the “tyranny of slenderness” in of psychotic disorders has changed profoundly over
modern society. Achieving the thin body that rep- the last 40 years. Whereas macro-social factors (such
resents middle-class status (as a collective represen- as migration and poverty) were once the subject of
tation) is a means to gaining middle class identity. study and discussion, they have fallen from promi-
Black, lower class women have no hope of entering nence and have given way to a preoccupation with
the middle class so they do not strive to adopt its micro-social issues; the social environment has been
proxies such as slim body form. Body image and reduced to the clinic, and research efforts have
eating disorders to achieve it are objective, objec- focused on how clinicians diagnose psychosis in
tified, objectifying cultural means (coping strate- minority populations (Jarvis, 2007, p. 291).
gies) to achieve cultural objectives under particular
cultural stressors and stresses (cf. Ratner, 2002, Macro-Culture and Micro-Family in Mental Illness
pp. 39–40, 49–-50; Ratner, 2006, pp. 100–101). A great deal of mental illness occurs in destruc-
tive family interactions (Ratner & Badwi, 2011).
The Normativity of Non-Normal Psychology However, these are precipitated by broader macro-
Non-normative psychology is actually normative stresses that Sass and Foucault enumerated. Indeed,
because its causes, constituents, meanings, social this point is the crux of Bronfenbrenner’s ecological

ratn er 227
model, which situates micro-level interactions within relations (score of 115), whereas the United States
the sphere of macro-processes. Bronfenbrenner and United Kingdom had the lowest score of 80.
terms microlevel interactions as proximal processes, Only 40% of German 15-year-olds spend time chat-
which are reflections of distal macro-cultural pro- ting with their parents several times a week, whereas
cesses, as moonlight reflects sunlight. Shared, uni- 90% of Hungarian children do so. Only 60% of
fying macro-cultural factors explain why so many Finnish 15-year-olds eat the main meal with their
families in a country are so dysfunctional as to pro- parents several times a week, in contrast to 93% of
duce mental illness in their children. A purely fam- Italians. Other personal eating habits are equally
ily analysis cannot explain varying prevalence and structured by society. Whereas 80% of Portuguese
forms of dysfunction in different societies. 11- to 15-year-olds eat breakfast every school day,
Micro, proximal processes cannot be the primary only 46% of American children do. Where 25%
source of mental illness that is historically specific of American 13- to 15-year-olds report being over-
and variable. Individual, separate interactions can- weight, only 6% of Polish peers do. (UNICEF,
not explain the cultural coherence and similarity Child poverty in perspective: An overview of child
that it manifests. The millions of families in one well-being in rich countries, Innocenti Report Card
country that generate particular forms of mental ill- 7, UNICEF Innocenti Research Centre, Florence,
ness in their children do not coordinate with each 2007). Demographic distribution of personal
other to produce similar stresses and coping mecha- behaviors demonstrates that they are shaped by cul-
nisms. The similarity in symptoms across millions tural factors; they are not purely personal choices.
of separate patients must be explained by broader Purely personal choices and idiosyncratic behavior
cultural similarities at the macro-level. These radiate would not manifest systematic group differences.
down to micro-level family interactions and unify Obviously, the majority of German children did
them with shared characteristics. not spontaneously (i.e., personally) decide to forego
Mental illness testifies to an important principle chatting with their parents. Nor did this new norm
of macro-cultural psychology: seemingly personal, arise through sequences of interpersonal dialogues
marginal psychological reactions are actually macro- among children across Germany. Broad macro-
level phenomena. factors, which German children do not control or
even understand, structured their lives, aspirations,
Interpersonal Behavior and values, expectations, and practices impersonally, in
Macro-Cultural Psychology ways that interfered with family chatting. (This kind
The case of mental illness demonstrates that of impersonal structuring-socializing of individual
individual, interpersonal psychological phenomena psychology by macro-cultural factors is an impor-
are uncannily shaped by macro-cultural factors and tant topic in macro-cultural psychology.)
reflect their politics, despite the fact that the phe- An important macro-cultural factor in this regard
nomena are not directly controlled by social leaders. is consumerism. Consumer capitalism presses chil-
Other personal acts are equally socially distributed dren—through numerous macro-cultural pressures,
psychographics. A striking example is the fact that stimuli, inducements, affordances, and models—to
Australia’s homicide rate is around 1 per 100,000 separate from restrictive parental authority to be
population, whereas the U.S. homicide rate is “free” to accept consumer pressures for impulsive
around 6 per 100,000, or six times higher. Clearly, shopping. (We saw that this pressure was impor-
central macro-cultural factors are at work in shaping tant in loosening the bonds of maternal love for
individual decisions to kill each other (and them- one’s children.) Tight-knit families, including those
selves in suicides). that eat and chat together, keep the child within
Similarly, the quality of children’s interpersonal the sphere of parental authority and resist the pull
relationships (with peers and family members) of consumerism. Such behaviors on a wide social
varies enormously among countries with different scale are only possible where consumer capitalism
macro-cultural factors. A compilation of measures is weak.
by the United Nations, which includes single-par- Cook documents the commodification of child-
ent households, number of times the family eats hood by consumer capitalism and how it pressures
together per week, talks together, and how kind and requires freedom from family restraints. It is not
and helpful peers are to children among OECD useful to think of children—or persons generally—
countries, found Italy to have the best interpersonal along the lines posed by neoclassical economic

228 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


thought, as initially independent, encapsulated 6. Psychological phenomena embody features
beings who confront an equally identifiable “market of macro-cultural factors as their constituent
sphere” and who thereby make discrete choices within operating mechanisms and content. This is true
it or become merely socialized into it. Consumption for abstract and concrete features of psychological
has become a necessary and indispensable context— phenomena. Abstract features of psychology
although not sufficient in itself—in which the per- embody abstract features of macro-cultural factors;
son’s self develops because commerce produces most concrete features of psychology embody concrete
of the material world with which a child comes into features of culture. Macro-cultural psychology
contact . . . It is around consumption and display—in parsimoniously explains abstract and concrete
the interaction with the material world—that per- aspects of psychology.
sonhood and agency tend to crystallize (Cook, 2004, 7. Macro-cultural factors are political, formed
p. 145). Cook explains that psychology is built into through political struggle, and impart their politics
macro-cultural factors—for example, individualism to psychological phenomena.
is built into the free market—and that psychology 8. Psychological phenomena recapitulate the
crystallizes around the characteristics of macro-cul- politics of macro-cultural factors in the subjectivity
tural factors—for example, personhood embodies of individuals. Psychological phenomena animate
the material of consumer capitalism. politically appropriate behavior. Psychological
phenomena are objectives of political struggle.
Macro-Cultural Psychology Is a Unitary, Groups struggle over concepts of self, masculinity,
Consistent, Parsiimonious, Comprehensive childhood, motherhood, sexual freedom, rote
Psychological Theory memory in school, and conceptions of mental
The foregoing discussion of macro-cultural psy- illness.
chology can be summarized in the following theo- 9. Psychological phenomena are cultural
retical principles (which are more complete than the means (cultural capital) for achieving cultural
selected principles I listed in summarizing Plant’s objectives/success by individuals.
historical analysis of maternal love). 10. Psychology is a cultural state of being, a
cultural state of mind, a cultural identity, and
membership. Psychology objectifies culture—for
Principles of Macro-cultural
example, sentimental maternal love objectifies
Psychology
Victorian culture and women’s domestic position,
1. Macro-culture and psychology are mutually
whereas modern maternal love objectifies women’s
constitutive and interdependent—two forms of the
roles as workers and consumers in the free market;
same distinctive human order. Psychology energizes
just as the recent sexual revolution among Chinese
cultural factors and it dialectically acquires their
urban young women objectifies their changing
cultural features.
work and family roles.
2. Within this spiral of culture and psychology,
11. The fact that psychology is cultural and
macro-cultural factors are dominant. They are
political—that is, reflects the cultural-political
the impetus of psychological formation, and they
features of macro-cultural factors—does not mean
organize the form and content of psychological
that people’s psychology understands the cultural
phenomena.
politics of macro-cultural factors. Typically, the
3. Psychological phenomena are formed in
cultural politics of macro-cultural factors mystifies
macro-cultural practices on the macro-cultural
these factors—to prevent people from critically
level to serve macro-cultural purposes.
evaluating and transforming them—and this
4. Psychological phenomena are public,
mystification is recapitulated in psychological
objective, objectified cultural phenomena;
phenomena. The individualistic self is a primary
collective representations.
example of a fictitious ideology that is recapitulated
5. Public, objective, objectified psychological
in fictitious self-understanding of people as
phenomena serve as templates/scripts for
independent of society, masters of their own
a. acquiring psychology
action, and governed by individual mechanisms
b. expressing psychology.
such as genes. Reincarnation is another fictitious
Psychological phenomena are thus objectified, cultural concept that mystifies people about the
objective, objectifying cultural phenomena. real origins of their personality and social position.

ratn er 229
People’s cultural psychology may be a stunted, across the front. Or Abercrombie’s “cute butt
mystified psychology that I call the psychology of sweatpants” and “skinny” jeans that are “fitted
oppression. It can only be comprehended as such with a little stretch for a sexy look to give you the
by adopting an external, critical perspective on perfect butt”
the social origins, characteristics, and function of “We propose that sexualizing girls’ clothing
psychological phenomena (Ratner, 2011b). is an important socializing agent in which the
12. Psychological phenomena are macro- social role of the objectified female is perhaps
cultural factors. They represent and solidify innocuously presented, ‘put onto’ girls, associated
cultural factors through animating culturally with popularity and ‘coolness,’ and then eventually
appropriate behavior. Historian Warren Susman endorsed by the girls themselves. Clothing can
(1979, pp. 212–213) shows how personality function as both a contributor to and a sign of
is a macro-cultural factor in the sense that it the process by which some girls begin to think
characterizes and represents a society: “One of and evaluate themselves according to a narrow,
the things that makes the modern world ‘modern’ sexualized model of feminine attractiveness” (ibid,
is the development of consciousness of self . . . p. 10). Evidence for this is the fact that Girls
Consciousness itself became a key word in the 17th as young as age six are critical of their bodies,
century . . . It is striking to see the interest as early expressing body dissatisfaction and interest in
as the 17th century in what was called ‘character.’ ” dieting.
These psychological phenomena were clearly Girls define themselves in terms of the macro
cultural features. cultural factor, they do not define the macro
Psychological phenomena solidify cultural cultural factor in terms of their “own” idiosyncratic
coherence through culturally structured, shared desires. This conforms to Vygotsky’s and Leontie
subjectivity. Psychology binds individuals to v’s conception that individual psychology depends
culture through imparting cultural features of upon social psychology.
consciousness/subjectivity. An additional example of macro cultural factors
13. Psychology is embodied in macro-cultural containing, expressing, and socializing cultural
factors, is transmitted, and is socialized by them. psychological meanings is reported by (Shepherd,
As Oyserman and Lee (2008, p. 331) put it, 2011, p. 129).
‘‘one of the ways in which meaning is organized participants who had been shown a video of black
in context is through the meaning provided by Americans in a park had less negative associations
salient and accessible culture and that once a with blacks than did participants who had been
particular cultural focus is cued, it is likely to shown a video of black Americans in a gang-related
carry with it relevant goals, motives, actions, context. They had similar results when blacks were
ways of interpreting information, and processing shown in a sequence with a church as opposed to in
strategies.” a sequence with a city street. The traditional inter-
Clothing, for example, socializes sexuality. pretation of these results is that contextual cues ac-
The American Psychological Association’s Task tivate automatic stereotypes, which are assumed to
Force on the Sexualization of Girls, 2007, studied be stable and unrelated to context. In this version,
the ways that artifacts such as clothing sexualize local context perturbs stable associations; the repre-
girls—i.e., make them sexual and structure their sentation of the target is the same but the context
sexuality in particular forms (sexualization is a within which the target is located varies, thus shap-
form of making subjectivity, or subjectification in ing activation. We could also read these results as
Foucault’s term). Goodin, et al. (2011) looked at evidence of how the types of associations (both the
sexualizing clothing available to preteen girls as a content and the emotional valence, positive or nega-
possible socializing influence that may contribute tive) individuals have with a member of a particular
to the development of self-objectification in social group depend on the particular context or
preteen girls. Sexualizing clothing was defined as set of cues and there is no baseline representation
clothing that revealed or emphasized a sexualized of a social group apart from the context. [Thus, no
body part, had characteristics associated with fixed meaning that people have to minorities, e.g.]
sexiness, and/or had sexually suggestive writing. The meaning of a social group member is given
E.g. Abercrombie thong underwear in children’s through interaction with the context. Concepts of
sizes with “wink wink” and “eye candy” printed place (park, church, and street) carry sets of relevant

230 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


associations that alter the cognitive associations of Academic psychology can only become scien-
the perceiver. tific if it ceases to reflect and reinforce capitalism
14. These aspects of cultural psychology and instead adopts an external critical perspective
comprise a general psychological theory— on capitalism—an anti-capitalist perspective. Then
macro-cultural psychology—that explains all it can free itself of the mystifications inherent in
psychological phenomena. bourgeois society and it can recognize the cultural
15. Macro-cultural psychology is an ideal type character of psychological phenomena.
of the main parameters of human psychology. Vygotsky goes so far as to identify the errors of
Individual and group variations/transformations bourgeois (academic) psychology as the basis of fas-
issue from this framework. cistic (academic) psychology that took root in Nazi
16. The discipline of psychology is a macro- Germany:
cultural factor that represents and solidifies cultural
It would be naïve to think that these absurd
factors. Vygotsky (1933/1994) spoke of bourgeois
structures [of fascistic Psychology] are in no way
psychology, the psychology of fascism, and Soviet
connected with the general crisis occurring in
psychology to express this.
bourgeois psychology and that bourgeois psychology
17. Although approaches to psychology
is in no way responsible for these constructions . . .
reflect and reinforce macro-cultural factors, they
Essentially, Jaensch’s system [of Nazi psychology]
do not necessarily understand these factors or
is built on the same methodological foundations as
psychological phenomena (just as psychological
all the rest of bourgeois psychology. It represents an
phenomena do not necessarily understand
integration of idealism and mechanism . . . In the
their own cultural characteristics, origins, and
majority of psychological schools these elements,
function—as stated in 11 above). Approaches to
unknown to the authors themselves, are intertwined
psychology are often unscientific and ideological
with one another . . .
and overlook and obscure important aspects
Sociology is completely left out of Jaensch’s
of human psychology. Not all approaches are
system. It is only race and blood which immediately
equally scientific and penetrating. Epistemological
determine the structure of personality and through it
relativism and pluralism are false concepts.
politics as well. Here too, all that Jaensch has done is
For example, Vygotsky regarded bourgeois aca- to push to the extreme and treat with cynical blunt-
demic psychology as bogged down in a profound ness that which is already part of the very foundation
crisis: “the profound crisis which has afflicted bour- of bourgeois scientific research.
geois psychology during the past few decades . . . (ibid., p. 334)
a process of degeneration and decay which had
Vygotsky counterpoised Soviet psychology to bour-
previously been woven into [its] general fabric”
geois psychology and fascist psychology in terms
(Vygotsky, 1994a, p. 327). In other words, bour-
of their scientific merit and the political interests
geois academic psychology reflects and reinforces
they represent. The latter two approaches are sci-
bourgeois society (as the name implies), yet it fails
entifically dubious and politically conservative. In
to scientifically understand bourgeois society and
contrast, Vygotsky argues that Soviet Marxist psy-
the psychology of its people. Psychology is in cri-
chology is scientifically superior to the other two
sis precisely because it reflects and reinforces the
approaches, and it also represents the political strug-
mystifications of capitalism! One of the primary
gle for humanity against the forces of reaction that
mystifications of capitalism is to deny its coer-
are bolstered by bourgeois and fascist psychology
cive affect on human behavior and to pretend that
(ibid., p. 335). Social scientific adequacy depends
individuals are free to construct their own behav-
on adopting a progressive political standpoint.
ior. This prevents recognizing the social elements
Similarly, social scientific inadequacy and political
of capitalism that organize behavior/psychology.
conservatism go hand-in-hand. In this way, social
Recapitulating this mystification prevents bour-
science is thoroughly political.7
geois psychology from comprehending the psy-
chology of people, which is, in fact, organized by
capitalist social relations. (Bourgeois psychology
The Theoretical Character of
reinforces capitalism by insulating it from criti-
Macro-Cultural Psychology
Macro-cultural psychology is not simply
cism as a social system and attributing problems to
an acknowledgement of cultural influences on
individual deficiencies.)

ratn er 231
psychology. It explains the nature of psychological psychology is not an interactionist model. It is a
phenomena, their origins, constituents, mechanisms, unified, integrated model in which all elements are
characteristics, loci, and function. Macro-cultural modified so as to be congruent with macro-cultural
psychology explains psychology as a cultural phe- factors. Macro-cultural factors are the dominant
nomenon. Macro-cultural psychology explains why element because they are the cornerstones of soci-
and how psychology is cultural. Macro-cultural psy- ety, which is the basis of our civilization, humanity,
chology develops methodology for evaluating and and consciousness.
refining this perspective—that is, for identifying the Because mainstream psychology and psychiatry
extent to which macro-cultural factors are the ori- oppose this view and regard psychology as heavily
gins, constituents, mechanisms, characteristics, loci, determined by biological processes, we must explain
and function of psychology. how the latter are, in fact, subsumed within macro-
Macro-cultural psychology takes macro-level cultural psychology.
forms and processes of psychological phenomena
as the basis (i.e., prototype) of human psychology. Natural, Biological Processes and
Rather than these cultural forms and processes being Cultural Psychological Phenomena
extensions of simpler, natural, universal, or personal Being a public, socially constructed phenomenon
ones, the cultural forms are the basic, primary, origi- at the macro-cultural level for cultural purposes,
nal prototypes that are the basis of intrapersonal and and possessing cultural features and mechanisms,
interpersonal psychological expressions. psychology cannot logically be simultaneously gov-
For example, the prototype of human emotions is erned by natural, biological processes.
macro-level emotions such as love for one’s country, Of course, psychology involves and includes
anger at injustice, love of art, national shame, dejec- natural, biological processes, such as neuronal and
tion about political trends, resentment of a rival hormonal activity, just as it involves breathing air.
country’s technical superiority, fear of economic However, just as breathing air is merely a precon-
depression, and admiration for a form of govern- dition of psychology that plays no specific deter-
ment. These emotions, informed by consciousness mining role in the form, content, origins, locus,
of abstract phenomena, are the basis of our personal mechanisms, and function of psychology, so other
love for our spouses, children, and pets. They are natural biological processes play no specific deter-
also the basis of our fear of bears in the woods. mining role either. Their role is analogous to that of
Macro-cultural psychology is a Copernican shift breathing. Without breathing, hormones, and the
in our understanding of psychology. Whereas main- brain, psychological activity would cease; however,
stream psychology explains culture in terms of the with them it is only potentiated, not determined.
individual adults in terms of childhood experiences, Vygotsky and Luria have cleverly argued that
the human in terms of animal processes, the large biology changes its role in behavior from animals
in terms of the small, the complex in terms of the to humans. It does determine animal behavior in
simple, and the extrinsic (culture) in terms of the natural environments; however, biology changes to
internal (mind, biology), macro-cultural psychol- a potentiating, energizing function with regard to
ogy explains the small, the simple, the individual, human social behavior. This is only logical, and it is
the child, and the internal in terms of stimulation Darwinian, for we have seen that the fundamental
and organization by the large, the complex, the principle of Darwinism is that organismic behavior
adult, and the extrinsic (culture). is a function of environment. Culture is a radically
Macro-cultural psychology utilizes its tenets as different environment from nature; therefore, cul-
the foundation of a comprehensive, coherent, gen- tural behavior and its mechanisms must be radi-
eral psychological theory that explains, describes, cally different from natural behavioral mechanisms
and predicts all psychological phenomena. In addi- of animals. Vygotsky and Luria (1993, p. 170)
tion, macro-cultural psychology incorporates bio- have explained this important point as follows:
logical and personal processes into its rubric in a “[B]ehavior becomes social and cultural not only in
principled, logically consistent fashion. It does not its contents [i.e., what we think about] but also in
simply add macro-cultural principles to indepen- its mechanisms, in its means . . . A huge inventory of
dent biological and personal processes. This kind of psychological mechanisms—skills, forms of behav-
algorithmic addition of factors or variables is char- ior, cultural signs and devices—has evolved in the
acteristic of interactionist models. Macro-cultural process of cultural development.”

232 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


“Higher mental functions are not simply a neural impulses. Einstein was not a great physicist
continuation of elementary functions and are not because his neurons worked quickly. That did not
their mechanical combination, but a qualitatively contribute to his knowledge and insight. And den-
new formation that develops according to completely dritic complexity is well-known to be the result of
special laws and is subject to completely different experience, not its cause. No biological reduction-
patterns.” “Thus, it is difficult to expect that ism of intelligence to physical processes as determi-
evolution of higher mental functions would proceed nants adequately explains intelligence.
parallel to the development of the brain.” Altering and subsuming biological processes to
(Vygotsky, 1998, pp. 34, 36) fit within the unitary framework of macro-cultural
psychological theory preserves the essentially cultural
Vygotsky and Luria make the important point character of psychology by subordinating all other
that elementary natural processes operate in differ- elements to it. Natural, biological processes are ren-
ent ways from cultural conscious processes. This is dered congruent with culture and supportive of cul-
why the former cannot govern the latter. They can- ture. They are eliminated as countervailing forces with
not even serve as the basis of the latter. their own determining mechanisms that could chal-
Elementary natural processes are actually inimi- lenge and weaken (through interacting with) culture
cal to cultural conscious processes. Elementary and mitigate its influence. Interactionism is pluralis-
natural processes are automatic, mechanical, invol- tic in that it postulates diverse factors/variables that
untary, physical processes; they possess natural each contribute a certain independent percentage of
properties that directly impel behavior. Natural “variance” to the resultant psychology. Interactionism
processes, for example, operate in hummingbirds to thus weakens the influence of each factor by coun-
automatically impel them to fly toward red-colored tering different factors. For example, intelligence or
flowers; or they impel male dogs to involuntarily personality are said to be X% culturally based and Y%
and mechanically mount and mate with a female biologically based. Whatever percentage is attributed
dog who emits a particular scent during her fertile to biology is subtracted from cultural influence. This
period. Hummingbirds and dogs do not think about denies the essential cultural nature of psychology. It
what they are doing, they cannot control it, they reduces culture to just another aspect of psychology.
cannot plan it or imagine it, or remember (relive) it Biological determinism or reductionism is not com-
in specific detail; they do not appreciate the object patible with cultural organization of psychology.
of their behavior, as a human male appreciates his Interactionism is factually wrong (cf. Ratner,
sexual partner or appreciates a beautiful sunset or 1998, 2004, 2006, 2011a), and it is also illogical
painting. This is why elementary natural processes because it juxtaposes incompatible mechanisms.
cannot determine psychology in the way that they Contemporary maternal love, for example, cannot
determine behavior of birds and dogs. be socially constructed amid fierce political strug-
It is oxymoronic to claim that intelligence is gle to serve cultural purposes and social positions
biologically determined because biologically deter- and simultaneously be mechanically, involuntarily
mined behavior has the form of mechanical, auto- impelled by biochemical properties of hormones.
matic, simple acts such as a hummingbird flying This is obvious from the fact that Victorian women
toward a red flower. This sort of behavior is not possessed the same biochemical hormones as modern
intelligent. It is the antithesis of thoughtful, insight- women, yet their quality and experience of mater-
ful intelligence. To claim that intelligence is bio- nal love were qualitatively different. Hormones are
logically determined, even in part, is to ignore the certainly involved in both kinds of maternal love
nature of intelligence and the nature of biologically but only as energizing mechanisms of behavior,
determined behavior. thoughts, feelings, and experiences whose content
Psychobiologists claim that biology determines is culturally determined and variable. It is illogical
“part of ” intelligence through increasing the speed to claim that 40% of the quality of contemporary
of neuronal conductivity, or the complexity of den- maternal love is biological—that is, biologically
dritic branching. However, this is unintelligible. determined. None of it is biologically determined.
Intelligence is a matter of profoundly understanding Biology has lost its determining function in human
relationships and underlying causes and implications behavior, which is only “natural” given the unique
of things. It is a matter of insight and knowledge. cultural environment in which people live that
It has nothing to do with the speed of conducting calls for socially constructed, designed, voluntary,

ratn er 233
changeable behavior. Culture determines the form, lesser degree in all flaws of bourgeois psychology is
content, and conditions of behavior. In contrast, the rejection of the social nature of man.”
the form, content, and conditions of animal behav- Zinchenko (1984, p. 73) also acknowledges the
ior are determined by natural, biochemical ele- overlooking of cultural psychology as a profound
ments. There is no way that these two discrepant error: “The exclusion of the real process of the sub-
mechanisms could jointly determine the features ject’s life, of the activity that relates him to objective
of psychological phenomena. Elementary, natural reality, is the underlying cause of all misinterpreta-
mechanisms would impede the development of psy- tions of the nature of consciousness. This is the basis
chological features because natural mechanisms are of both mechanistic and idealistic misunderstand-
antithetical to cultural-psychological mechanisms ings of consciousness.”
and features. The only way that biological processes Moscovici (2001, pp. 109–110) explained this
can participate with cultural processes is for them to error as follows:
bequeath their determining properties over behav-
Society has its own structure, which is not definable
ior to culture and for biological processes to recede
in terms of the characteristics of individuals;
into the background as a general potentiating sub-
this structure is determined by the processes of
stratum of behavior.
production and consumption, by rituals, symbols,
Vygotsky put it thus:
institutions, and dynamics that cannot be derived
The struggle for existence and natural selection, the from the laws of other systems. When the “social” is
two driving forces of biological evolution within studied in terms of the presence of other individuals
the animal world, lose their decisive importance as it is not really the fundamental characteristics of
soon as we pass on to the historical development of the system that are explored but rather one of its
man. New laws, which regulate the course of human subsystems—the subsystem of interindividual
history and which cover the entire process of the relationships. The kind of social psychology that
material and mental development of human society, emerges from this approach is a “private” social
now take their place. psychology which does not include within its scope
(1994b, p. 175) the distinctiveness of most of the genuine collective
phenomena. It can therefore be argued that . . .
Personal expression and communication are sim-
social psychology has not been truly concerned
ilarly derivative functions of macro-cultural emo-
either with social behavior as a product of society
tions. The latter are capable of explaining the former
or with behavior in society . . . For these reasons it
because broader, more complex phenomena can
is ambiguous to maintain that social behavior is
explain smaller, simpler ones. The converse is not
currently the real object of our science.
possible. Simple, natural, physical, or personal pro-
cesses do not have the scope (e.g., the great abstrac- This avoidance of concrete social behavior—
tion and depth of knowledge) to generate emotions whether intentional or not—impedes the scientific
that are necessary to initiate, sustain, and reform development of psychology as a science. It also renders
broad macro-cultural factors such as country. psychological science politically impotent as a force
for social critique and change and for psychological
Conclusion: Restoring the Macro-Cultural enrichment. For the academic discipline of psychol-
Basis and Character of Psychology ogy to become scientific and to improve the social
Because psychology is part of macro-cultural environment in ways that will enrich psychological
factors—and is a macro-cultural factor in that it functions and social relations, it must elucidate the
objectifies, represents, and consolidates culture—it macro-cultural origins, characteristics, mechanisms,
must be comprehended by “zooming out” from the and function of psychological phenomena. This is
individual and family to the social system. what macro-cultural psychology aims to do (Ratner,
Unfortunately, most of psychological science has 2006, 2008, 2011a,b, 2012a,b).
been devoted to “zooming in” on the individual and
marginalizing the cultural complex of which he is Future Directions
a part (see Michaels, 2008, for political examples Elucidating the general features of macro-
of this problem). Vygotsky (1994/1933, p. 334) culture. Elucidating the dominant factors,
decried this in the strongest terms: “Another mis- marginal factors, the structural organization of
take . . . which is, essentially, inherent in a greater or macro-cultural factors in general.

234 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


Elucidating specific features of culture, such The United States was, after all, a class-stratified
as the particular principles that govern macro- society, and there was something potentially threatening
to the established order about organizing the educational
cultural factors in a particular society (e.g., how system so as to arouse high hopes, only to shatter them
capitalist economic relations permeate educational later. At the same time, however, the political costs of
institutions, the media, social science, religion, turning back the popular demand for expanded
entertainment, and news reporting). Elucidating schooling were prohibitive in a nation placing so much
the politics of who controls macro-cultural stress on equality of opportunity. What vocationalism
promised to do was to resolve this dilemma by, on the one
factors and for what interests (e.g., is the society hand, accepting the democratic pressure from below to
dominated by an aristocracy, capitalist leaders, provide access to new levels of education while, on the
a political party—the Communist Party?) Is the other hand, differentiating the curriculum to
social structure egalitarian and cooperative or accommodate the realities of the economic division of
pyramidal; autocratic or autocratic? labor. The aspirations of the masses for upward mobility
through education would not, advocates of
Researching ways that psychological vocationalization claimed, thereby be dashed; instead,
phenomena embody abstract and concrete features they would be rechanneled in more “realistic” directions.
of macro-cultural factors.
3. Because Friedan articulated frustrations and desires that
Researching whether psychological phenomena had been stimulated by consumer capitalism, her feminist
transcend macro-cultural factors. What other kinds agenda was not radical. It opposed traditional social roles for
of factors do they reflect? women, however, only to support consumer capitalist roles. For
Identifying positive and negative psychological example, Friedan emphasized that women’s work should be paid
effects of the specific features of macro-cultural in accordance with market commodification of labor, and she
condemned volunteer work for the community. And Friedan did
factors. so implicitly without acknowledging that her feminist agenda
Identifying how positive effects be enhanced of women’s social psychology, social relations, and social activ-
and negative effects diminished. What changes in ity derived from and reinforced consumer capitalism. Conse-
macro-cultural factors are necessary to accomplish quently, “Friedan’s fans conceptualized motherhood in highly
these changes? individualistic terms [of personal happiness, self-fulfillment, and
involvement in work], drawing few if any connections between
What is the actual (concrete) power/agency that their maternal responsibilities and the broader social and politi-
individuals have to control their social institutions cal world” (Plant, 2009, p. 161). Friedan’s critique focused on
in particular social systems? attacking traditional psychology/behavior of women—for exam-
Researching the extent to which people ple, sexual passivity, limited career ambitions, and identity cri-
comprehend the macro-cultural factors that form ses (which she called the feminine mystique)—and urging new
forms of behavior/psychology without an analysis of the political
their social relations and psychology? economic basis of either. “Friedan portrayed [traditional] Ameri-
Researching ways that macro-cultural factors can mothers as parasitical and pathological . . . She blamed them
organize psychological phenomena—which is for the mental problems of WW II servicemen, the difficulties
different from interpersonal influence/socialization. of children suffering from severe mental illnesses like autism and
Developing methodology to answer these schizophrenia, and ‘the homosexuality that is spreading like a
murky fog over the American scene” (p. 147). This is hardly a
questions. How can we study the concrete features radical social critique.
of macro-cultural factors and their psychological Friedan insisted that “the feminine mystique was a mental
correlates? The same for abstract features. construct and as such something women could change with
Identifying ways that people with a given equally powerful ideas. Friedan argued that women could dis-
cultural psychology can critically evaluate it and cover the answers in themselves and not through religious, eco-
nomic, political, or social change. If they had the wrong ideas,
the macro-cultural factors that shape it. all they needed was the right ones, which her book provided”
(Horowitz, 1998, p. 221).
Notes Friedan did not articulate a critique of consumer capitalism
1. Human artifacts eliminate any short-term natural balance that was necessary for women to achieve a truly more demo-
humans have with nature. (Our population is not immediately cratic, cooperative, humane social structure, social relations, and
dependent on what nature naturally provides us.). We must learn social psychology. Friedan’s work “promotes solutions (advanced
the limits of how much we can distress nature and still survive. education and self-realization) that tended to be feasible only
We must plan and regulate our use of nature because we are for middle-class and upper-middle-class women” (Plant, 2010,
not immediately consumed by our excesses as animals are. (For p. 150). Years later, Friedan did help to found the National Orga-
example, animal overpopulation quickly results in starvation to nization for Women, which worked to pass the Equal Rights
restore natural population levels.) Amendment; however, this was primarily a middle class move-
2. Community colleges in the United States were structured ment to enable middle class women to join mainstream society
to perform this cultural function, as Brint and Karabel (1987, (a la Condoleezza Rice and Margaret Thatcher), not to transform
p. 11) document in a brilliant historical study. its structure (cf Michaels, 2008).

ratn er 235
Horowitz keenly observes how far Friedan’s middle class objectively of normal weight (75% of the women) or even under-
feminism departed from her earlier political work and class weight (30% of the women) according to health charts.
analysis. From her studies in psychology at Smith College and The reason for the failure to achieve slimness is that the ideal
Berkeley under left-wingers such as Tolman, James Gibson, is contradicted by another aspect of consumer capitalism, the
Koffka, Erikson, and also Lewin in Iowa, she was inspired to join constant stimulating of consumption to increase sales and profit.
labor struggles, anti-fascist, and anti-capitalist struggles during One form this takes is the stimulating of constant food con-
the 1930s and 1940s. Yet her feminism incorporated none of sumption, especially profitable, processed, addictive food such
this political class analysis. “In opposition to all that she knew as junk food. This culminates in obesity among one-third of the
as a labor journalist, she apparently believed that America had American population. The clash of competing cultural pressures
become a middle-class society . . . The way Friedan minimized and collective representations generates intra-psychic struggle
race [and class] as a factor in women’s history and in contempo- over which one to pursue.
rary society is striking” (Horowitz, 1998, p. 211). Achieving the cultural ideal of slimness requires controlling
“In addition, she ignored the efforts of working-class and oneself to abstain from the opposite culture pressure to con-
Popular Front (left-wing) feminists in labor unions and in the stantly consume. This is why anorexics report intense struggles
Congress of American Women [to advance the political move- to control and renounce their urge to eat. Contradictory cultural
ment for the feminist agenda]” (Horowitz, 1998, p. 213). She pressures generate the need to control and renounce one in favor
made it seem that feminism was made by and for middle class of the other. External pressures make control and renunciation
women, and could be independent of broader political struggles central issues in anorexia. This is often portrayed as a struggle
for change in the class structure. between good and evil, mind and body, purity and contamina-
Friedan even denied the political origins of her own social tion. However, these meta-physical notions mask the cultural
consciousness. She claimed that she came to political con- clash of slenderness versus consumption that is rooted in con-
sciousness out of a disillusionment with her life as a suburban sumer capitalism.
housewife (Horowitz, 1998, pp. 2, 237 ff.). Horowitz’s external 7. Vygotsky says that capitalism not only impedes the devel-
analysis of her life and work confirms an important point that opment of scientific psychology, it also impedes the development
self-presentation in narratives cannot be accepted at face value in of fulfilling psychological phenomena of people: “the source of
social scientific research (Ratner, 2002, Chapter 4). the degradation of the personality [lies] in the capitalist form of
4. With agency being socially constituted, it cannot neces- manufacturing” (Vygotsky, 1994b, p. 180). Vygotsky links psy-
sarily be held responsible for its actions. Under conditions of chological fulfillment to social change in his 1930 essay, “The
oppression, alienation, and mystification, where people’s agency Socialist Alteration [Transformation] of Man.” He says the con-
is organized by social forces beyond their control and awareness, tradictions of capitalist political economy are “being resolved by
people cannot be held responsible for their behavior. (This is rec- the socialist revolution . . . Alongside this process, a change in
ognized in American law.) Responsibility presupposes awareness the human personality and an alteration of man himself must
of, and control over, the factors that organize behavior. To hold inevitably take place” (Vygotsky, 1994b, p. 181).
people responsible for their behavior under conditions of oppres- Here, we see that Vygotsky explains personal degradation
sion, alienation, and mystification is to insidiously divorce behav- and degeneration of academic psychology in the same terms.
ior from social conditions. It implies that people can control their Capitalism is the root of both, and socialism is necessary for sci-
behavior regardless of conditions. Holding people responsible for entific psychology and for fulfilling psychological phenomena.
behavior, they do not comprehend or control is also to blame the Psychological fulfillment and psychological science both depend
victim of external forces. To blame people for being poor when upon critique and transformation of society. The converse is also
they are deprived of work by corporate investment decisions is true as scientific psychology and psychological change contribute
clearly to blame the victim. To blame consumers for borrowing to social critique and transformation. Psychological fulfillment,
credit and consuming many products is also to blame the victim. psychological science, and progressive political change are inter-
And to blame students for maintaining segregated social groups dependent and inseparable.
when they are recapitulating broad cultural segregation in hous-
ing, schooling, and employment is to blame the victim.
Responsibility for behavior is cultural just as agency and all References
psychology are. Responsibility must be achieved just as genuine Brint, S., & Karabel, J. (1989). The diverted dream: Community
agency and fulfilling psychology must be achieved through creat- colleges and the promise of educational opportunity in America,
ing cultural conditions that enable them. They are not abstract, 1900–1985. New York: Oxford University Press.
natural universals independent of concrete culture. People will Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The ecology of human development.
only be responsible for their behavior when they live in genuinely Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
democratic institutions which they can control. This is the same Burke, J., & Ornstein, R. (1995). The axemaker’s gift: A double-
condition that enables genuine agency and fulfilling psychology. edged history of human culture. New York: Putman.
5. This kind of reification is the essence of religion as well. Chiang, C. (2008). The nose knows: The sense of smell in American
People invent a concept of god(s) but they pretend that it was History. The Journal of American History, 95, 405–417.
god who invented them and guides their behavior. Condon, R. (1987). Inuit youth: Growth and change in the
6. Most women do not achieve the slender ideal. This gener- Canadian Arctic. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University
ates enormous anxiety and self-deprecation. By 8 years of age, 40% Press.
of American girls wish to be thinner than they are, and this per- Cook, D. (2004). The commodification of childhood: The chil-
centage doubles in only 3 years, as 79% of 11-year-old girls wish to dren’s clothing industry and the rise of the child consumer.
be thinner than they are. This testifies to the power that social ide- Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
als have over individual psychology, and the difficulty of renounc- Ferrari, M., Robinson, D., & Yasnitsky, A. (2010). Wundt,
ing them. Most women who are dissatisfied with their weight are Vygotsky, and Bandura: A cultural-historical science of

236 mac ro-c ult ur al psycholo g y


consciousness in three acts. History of the Human Sciences, Ratner, C. (2007). A macro-cultural-psychological theory of
23, 95–118. emotions. In P. Schultz, & R. Pekrun (Eds.). Emotions in
Foucault, M. (1987). Mental illness and psychology. Berkeley, CA: education (chap. 6). Academic Press.
University of California Press. (Originally written 1962.) Ratner, C. (2006). Cultural psychology: A perspective on
Goldman, R. (1992). Reading ads socially. New York: Routledge. psychological functioning and social reform. Mahwah,
Goodin, S., Van Denburg, A., Murnen, S., & Smolak, L. (2011). NJ: LEA.
“Putting on” sexiness: A content analysis of the presence of Ratner, C. (2008). Cultural psychology and qualitative meth-
sexualizing characteristics in girls’ clothing. Sex Roles, 65, odology: Scientific and political considerations. Culture and
1–12. Psychology, 14, 259–288.
Gordon, S. (1981). The sociology of sentiments and emotion. In Ratner, C. (2009). Harre’s social philosophy and political phi-
M. Rosenberg & R. Turner (Eds.), Social psychology: Sociological losophy: A social scientific critique. Journal for The Theory of
perspectives (pp. 562–592). New York: Basic Books. Social Behaviour, 39(4), 448–465.
Horowitz, D. (1998). Betty Friedan and the making of “The Ratner, C. (2011a). Macro-cultural psychology: A political philoso-
Feminine Mystique”: The American left, the Cold War, and phy of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
liberal feminism. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Ratner, C. (2011b). Macro-cultural psychology, the psychology
Press. of oppression, and cultural-psychological enrichment. In
Jackson. S. (1993). Even sociologists fall in love: An exploration P. Portes & S. Salas (Eds.), Advances in cultural historical
in the sociology of emotions. Sociology, 27, 210–220. theory and praxis with non-dominant communities. New York:
Jarvis, G. (2007). The social causes of psychosis in North Peter Lang.
American psychiatry: A review of a disappearing literature. Ratner, C. (2012a). Macro Cultural Psychology. In T. Teo (Ed.),
Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 52, 287–294. The encyclopedia of critical psychology. New York: Springer.
Joseph, J., & Ratner, C. (2012). The fruitless search for genes in Ratner, C. (2012b). Macro cultural psychology: its development,
psychiatry and psychology: Time to re-examine a paradigm. concerns, politics, and direction. In M. Gelfand, C. Chiu, &
In S. Krimsky & J. Gruber (Eds.), Genetic explanations: sense Y. Hong (Eds.), Advances in culture and psychology (vol. 3).
and nonsense. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kurki, M., & Sinclair, A. (2010). Hidden in plain sight: Ratner, C., & El-Badwi, S. (2011). A cultural psychological
Constructivist treatment of social context and its limitations. theory of mental illness, supported by research in Saudi
International Politics, 47, 1–25. Arabia. Journal of Social Distress and The Homeless, 20,
Leontiev, A. N., (1977). Philosophy in the USSR, Problems of #3–4. (http://www.sonic.net/~cr2/cult psy mental illness.
dialectical materialism. Moscow: Progress Publishers. pdf.
Lewis, J. (1989). Mother’s love: The construction of an emo- Sass, L. (1992). Madness and modernism: Insanity in the light
tion in nineteenth-century America. In A. Barnes & of modern art, literature, and thought. New York: Basic
P. Stearns (Eds.), Social history and issues in human consciousness Books.
(pp. 209–229). New York: NYU Press. Shepherd, H. (2011). The cultural context of cognition: What
Luria, A. (1971). Towards the problem of the historical nature the Implicit Association Test tells us about how culture
of psychological processes. International Journal of Psychology, works. Sociological Forum, 26, 121–143.
6, 259–272. Stearns, P. (1989). Suppressing unpleasant emotions: The devel-
Luria, A. (1976). Cognitive development: Its cultural and social opment of a twentieth-century American style. In A. Barnes
foundations. Boston: Harvard University Press. & P. Stearns (Eds.), Social history and issues in human con-
Marsella, A., & Yamada. A. (2007). Culture and psychopathol- sciousness (pp. 230–261). New York: NYU Press.
ogy: Foundations, issues, nad directions. In S. Kitayama, Susman, W. (1979). “Personality” and the making of twentieth-
& D. Cohen (Eds.), Handbook of cultural psychology century culture. In J. Higham & P. Conkin (Eds.), New
(pp. 797–818). New York: Guilford. directions in American intellectual history (pp. 212–226).
Michaels, W. (July/August 2008). Against diversity. New Left Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Review, 52, 33–36. Vygotsky L S (1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA:
Moscovici, S. (2001). Social representations: Explorations in social The MIT Press.
psychology. New York: New York University Press. Vygotsky, L.S., (1989). Concrete human psychology. Soviet
Oyserman, D., & Markus, H. (1998). Self as social representation. Psychology, 27, 2, 53–77.
In U. Flick (Ed.), The psychology of the social. (pp. 107–125). Vygotsky, L., & Luria, A. (1993). Studies on the history of behav-
New York: Cambridge University Press. ior: Ape, primitive, and child. Mahwah, NJ: LEA. (Originally
Oyserman, D., & Lee, S. (2008). Does culture Influence what written 1930.)
and how we think? Effects of priming individualism and col- Vygotsky, L. (1994a). Fascism in psychoneurology. In R. Van der
lectivism, Psychological Bulletin 134: 311–342. Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Vygotsky reader. (pp. 327–337).
Plant, R. (2010). Mom: The transformation of motherhood in Oxford, UK: Blackwell. (Originally written 1933.)
modern America. Chicago: University Chicago Press. Vygotsky, L. (1994b). The socialist alteration of man. In R. Van der
Ratner, C. (1991). Vygotsky’s sociohistorical psychology and its Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Vygotsky reader. (pp. 175–184).
contemporary applications. New York: Plenum Publishers. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Ratner, C. (1998). Prologue to Vygotsky’s Collected Works, Vygotsky, L. (1998). The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (vol. 5).
vol. 5. New York: Plenum Publishers. New York: Plenum Publishers.
Ratner, C. (1999). Three approaches to cultural psychology: Zinchenko, P. (1984). The problem of involuntary memory.
A critique. Cultural Dynamics, 11, 7–31. Soviet Psychology, 22, 55–111. (Originally published,
Ratner, C. (2004). Genes and psychology in the news media. 1939.)
New Ideas in Psychology, 22, 29–47.

ratn er 237
This page intentionally left blank
PA RT
4
Semiosis in Culture and
Psychology
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Social Life of the Sign: Sense-Making


11 in Society

Sergio Salvatore

Abstract
This work intends to provide a conceptualization of the power of signs to produce the sense of reality
of the world to which they refer. To this end, a dynamic field model of sense-making is proposed that is
based on the central idea of the bivalence of meaning—the meaning of X entails what is being interpreted
by the meaning-maker (the in presentia meaning) but also the whole gestalt working as conditional
context that sets the stage for the interpretability of the sign (the in absentia meaning). In metaphoric
terms, the latter can be considered the “semiotic silicone”— as it allows the closure of the Gestalt
grounding any interpretation. This model is meant to deepen the understanding of how sense-making
works as well as establish the link between semiosis and social life.
Keywords: sense-making, sign, semiotic field theory, presentification

“I am a European!” This statement—often is a rather recent invention (Ariès, 1960/1962);


made—seems clear, but it is not. Identifying with nevertheless, it is a taken-for-granted assumption
a country—or even a conglomerate of countries— orienting scientific and political discourse as well
patriotic identity is a member of an infinite set of as daily life.
signs that are assumed to refer to objects, char- In this work I will refer to these kinds of signs
acteristics, or facts of the world (the race, the to address a general issue, which goes beyond them
community, love, the group, childhood, human and is a very basic aspect of sense-making: the psy-
nature, the Holy Ghost, Homer, the unconscious, chological valence of signs—that is, the fact that we
the market, the culture, etc.). As one can see, they experience them as referring to entities that have a
refer to objects that are very different from each life of their own in the world.
other. Some of these objects concern interpersonal I have chosen to focus the analysis on signs like
relationships. A couple decides to separate because “Europe”, market, couple, and the like, because of
their love is over. Other signs (e.g., the market, their semiotic status. As will be made clear below,
the community) play a role in socio-political and every person, whether it be a student of sense-mak-
economic transactions. Others are active within ing or a soldier, a broker, or a wife, is aware that signs
scientific discourse (the unconscious is a classi- of this kind do not refer to things—namely, entities
cal example of this; see Moscovici, 1961/2008). endowed with their own substance corresponding
Some of these signs are confined to specific dis- to a specific aggregate of energy-matter extended
courses and social domains (only Christians con- over a specific space-temporal domain (like “stone”,
sider the Holy Ghost an existing entity). In other “mountain”, “water”, as well as “electromagnetism”,
cases, they have a more generalized diffusion. For etc.). At the same time, every person conceives of
example, the idea of childhood as a fact of nature and uses them as if they were existing entities/facts

241
and as such able to have an effect on experience objects (mathematical entities, objects like golden
and therefore to affect one’s own and others’ way mountain, square circle, or the current king of
of thinking and acting. Needless to say, people vary France), even if they do not exist in the world,
in where they put the distinction between signs even if they are lacking any extentional property,
referring to things and signs concerning not-things- subsist. As Eco (2009) highlights, this idea comes
but-however-existing-entities/facts (see below for from Avicenna, who claimed that existence is an
a definition). Yet everyone in one way or another accidental property of the object (i.e., it does not
makes this distinction. precede and ground the object; rather, it may or
I am interested in this distinction for two rea- may not be a value of it). It is logically required
sons. First, because the latter kind of signs are the by the recognition of the fact that to state that
ones mostly involved in the regulation of social something has no being, this something must be
life and that mostly reveal the role that social life present. Now, if one accepts that the subsistence
plays in sense-making. Second, because it makes it of the object is independent from and fundamen-
clear how the sense of referring to the world (what tal to its very existence, one has to conclude that
we indicate below with expressions like “value of the psychological presentation of the object is not
existence”) may not be conceived of as a taken-for- based on, and does not mirror, its value of empiri-
granted quality of the sign, as such grounding the cal existence; rather, it grounds it.
sense-making. On the contrary, the fact that some Contemporary psychology has pushed aside the
signs are conceived of as referring to existing enti- notion of presentation, moving the focus onto rep-
ties/facts, yet not endowed with substantial content, resentation. In this terminological shift, there is a
highlights how the valence of existing entities/facts major conceptual change. Cognitive psychology is
is not the mere mirror of the fact that these enti- not interested in how the psychological value of the
ties are pieces of the world. And once it is clear that representation comes about—namely, the fact that
the “value of existence” is not an inherent quality it is a re-presentation. Its functionalist standpoint
of (at least some) signs, one is led to assume it is led to scotomization of the issue of the generative
a psychological phenomenon—actually, the very process of psychological life, fully substituted by the
basic psychological phenomenon—that needs to be task of describing its way of working. My work, in
modeled. this sense, is a way of coming back to the future:
This means bringing the problem of the presen- to the theoretical problem of how the process of
tation, as highlighted by Continental Psychology presentation is performed and how it produces the
between the nineteenth and twentieth centu- value of existence of signs.
ries (Albertazzi, Jacquette, & Poli, 2001a), back One last preliminary observation is required.
into the scientific agenda. Already at the level of Needless to say, the issue I intend to address is
perception, psychological processes are not con- laden with ontological implications—I cannot but
fined to repetitively mirroring the world (as the use terms such as existence, life, world, and the like.
term “represent” implies), assembling the senso- Nevertheless, I consider the model I propose agnos-
rial tracks the latter leaves on the subject. Rather, tic and neutral from the point of view of ontological
every psychic act is oriented toward an object—it assumptions.
is a perception, a judgment, a feeling of some- It is agnostic in the sense that it does not provide
thing (Brentano, 1874/1995)—that is actively any statement concerning the ontological status of
construed in its psychological reality. Persons do signs. I will deliberately reduce to the minimum any
not perceive pieces of experience that are then statement concerning the ontological status of the
collected and hence signified; they perceive totali- semiotic process on which I focus. The reference to
ties. And, given that, as Kanizsa’s (1955) experi- the existence and reality of the signs will have to be sys-
ments showed, these totalities are not held in the tematically understood as concerning how the sign are
field of experience, they have to be conceived of considered and used by the semiotic interpreters—not
as the product of the constructive activity inher- in an absolute sense. This is so because my aim is to
ent to the mind—indeed, of its capability of pre- provide a model of the process that produces the value
sentification. According to Meinong (Albertazzi, of existence of the signs as the basic semiotic “fuel”
Jacquette, & Poli, 2001b; Valsiner, 2009), the for sense-making. Therefore, I am not interested in
psychological object has a content of being that whether such value of existence mirrors the world.
is independent of its ontological status; some Once one recognizes how the value of existence

242 social li fe o f t he si g n
varies among people, circumstances, and kind of Signs that Create Existence
sign, one is justified in seeing the issue of the value Acts and Consequences: Based on the Signs
of existence of the signs not as an inherent datum of Maybe most of the people of the world have
the world—akin the equidistance of the points of a somehow had a direct or indirect impact on their
circumference from the center—but as a phenom- life as a result of acts performed by other people
enon to be addressed. in accordance to what the United States means for
It is neutral, because it is not contingent to a them. And those other people, in turn, have expe-
specific ontological frame. It is evident that if one rienced the United States in terms of the acts that
assumes an idealist-constructivist ontology, the other people performed in accordance with it-
problem of the value of existence of signs is easy to and so forth, in an infinite intertwining of infinite
highlight in its relevance. This is so because assum- dimensionality.
ing intensional semantics and more generally the Yet, people are able to recognize that “the United
separation between language and world (as this States” is not a thing (as I have defined above—
ontological approach does) obviously raises the namely, an entity endowed with substantial con-
issue of how signs are able not only to semantically sistence). Nobody has ever been able to touch the
map the world but more deeply how they are able United States or invite them to dinner. If I forget
to present it—namely, to make it a psychological to ask for a visa, I will not be able to enter “the
experience for the semiotic interpreter. Yet, even United States”. Yet I am aware that it is not the
from the point of view of an extensional seman- United States that will prevent me from entering,
tics and more in general from within the frame of but someone—a frontier police officer—who will
a radical realistic ontology, which states that only do it as if she were executing the United States’
what is real is signified, one would anyway have the will—that is, in accordance with what “the United
theoretical problem of clarifying the process of how States” means for her/him. Moreover, the frontier
what is real in the world becomes real for the sub- police officer will be able to have a commitment to
ject representing it. her action insofar as she regards “the United States”
In sum, I am proposing a shifting of perspective— as if it was an existing entity.
consider the value of existence of the signs as an Thus, signs like “the United States”, “Europe”,
explicandum rather than an explicans. I am ori- as well as “family”, “love”, “will”, “motivation”,
ented to consider this shift the main meaning of “value”, “University”, “community” and so forth,
my contribution. In a recent work, Eco (2009) are (may be) recognized as different from those
addresses the problem of how fictional characters signs that refer to things, but this does not mean
(e.g., Anna Karenina), even if they are recognized they are considered a virtual, fantastic representa-
as such, are able to move people’s emotions and tion. On the contrary, they are assumed and used
actions; the paradigmatic example to which Eco as referring to a real entity—namely, an entity that
refers is the Werther effect, leading many young has existence. And as such they are able to regulate
people, on the publication of the book by Goethe, the collective action. People kill and die in the name
to kill themselves, so as to share the destiny of of such signs.
their hero (and if one considers this just an excess In sum, signs like “the United States” play a pow-
of romantic souls, think that a similar phenom- erful regulating role in social life, and in this sense we
enon happened in 1950, this time as reaction of can say that they have value of life, not because they
the defeat of Brazil with Uruguay in the final of are believed and used as referring to substantial enti-
World Cup soccer championship). On the one ties but because they are believed and used as referring
hand, Eco raises an issue similar to the one with however to existing entities by someone and for this
which I deal. On the other, however, the very fact reason are able to affect (regulate, constrain, orient
of addressing the issue of the capacity of fictional or the like) that person’s acts (broadly speaking).1
sign to mobilize emotions shows that the theoreti- This means that a sign like United States refers to
cal problem is much broader—it does not concern objects that have a contingent rather than universal
only fictional signs but every kind of sign and is existence (their existence depends on the fact that
not only related to the emotional reaction but someone believes in it) within a certain domain. For
more basically to the value of existence that feeds this reason, we define this kind of sign as a Value-of-
the emotional reaction. Existence-Producing Sign (VEPS), to underline that

sa lvatore 243
they have a meaning that is felt, thought, and used as The point at stake is that the VEPSs are a product
real—namely, as endowed with the sense of quality- of sense-making. As such, they are not ubiquitous
of-reality (SQR). In sum, VEPSs have SQR. and invariant phenomena. As the dynamics of par-
An Italian poet and singer, Fabrizio D´Andrè, ticipating in the collective good shows, their ways
wrote: “They dreamt so hard that the blood started of functioning, as well as the output they provide,
to drip from their noses.” are variable. For example, take the ways values like
Nation or Obedience, which have had an existen-
VEPS Is Unstable tial concreteness for whole generations, can lose all
The VEPSs play a fundamental role in social their existential meaning in a relatively short time
and individual life. Subjectivity as well as inter- and distance.
subjectivity are shaped and sustained by this kind This raises the issue of identifying the conditions
of signs (Rommetveit, 1992). From emotions felt in which the dynamics of sense-making are able to
and communicated to working organizations, from produce the cultural constructions generating SQR.
the care of the body to sexuality, from the system
of justice and security to the distribution of duties Sense-Making and Meaning
and resources, from the sense of membership of a I maintain that a processual model of sense-mak-
community to deviant behavior—all these fields of ing is required for this issue to be addressed. Such a
experience sustaining our personal and social lives model is grounded on confuting two premises.
are made up of institutions, namely generalized First is the idea that the meaning is the sign’s
VEPSs, taken for granted in their SQR, and as such correspondence with the piece of world to which
reifying the existential concreteness of the individ- it refers. An authoritative example of this exten-
ual, interpersonal, and social scenarios. sional theory of the sign is that provided by Frege
Interestingly enough, the VEPSs’ SQR does not (1892/1980), who distinguished between sense and
need to be absolute to work. In fact, in most cases meaning. The meaning is the thing the sign denotes,
it can be present in some social and subjective whereas the sense is the way of denoting it (i.e., of
domains (family, school, work, groups of peers) referring to it). Therefore, there can be many senses
while being silent in others, where further insti- for the same meaning. For example, “Moon,” “the
tutional beliefs are salient. Take, for example, a white ball in the night sky,” and “the earth’s only
person’s desire to act consistently with and serving satellite” are different senses of the same meaning
the “collective interest” (e.g., to behave honestly, (in this case, the planet we call Moon).
to pay taxes, to participate in local committees, to Second is the idea that the meaning is the content
help reduce pollution, etc.). This desire depends that the sign expresses/conveys. This is the structur-
on the fact that the person feels she is a member alist vision of the sign (de Saussure, 1916/1977),
of the collective community and thus feels the col- which holds that a sign is made up of the link
lective good she wants to pursue as if it belonged between a signifier (the expression) and a signified
to her (on the rule of the identification in the con- (the content). Any perceivable element of the world
struction of the collective goods, see Olson, 1965; (an object, an event, an image, a sound) can work
Putnam, 1993). And this means that the produc- as signifier; the signified is the concept, the idea that
tion of collective goods requires people to feel is associated to the signifier. This association is the
the community as an existing entity—namely, in arbitrary product of a conventional code provided
terms of VEPS. Yet this feeling is unstable both by the encyclopedia shared within a given commu-
from a spatial (intersubjective) and a temporal nity; yet once defined, it is quite stable and power-
(intrasubjective) point of view. For example, the ful, so that the sign appears as the fusion of these
Italian phenomenon of organized crime (mafia, two components. Consequently, the occurrence of
ndrangheta, camorra) would not be understandable the perceivable signifier instantiates the conveyed
if one did not take into account that in most of the signified.
territorial areas where this phenomenon is rooted Despite various differences, these two perspec-
(regions like Sicily, Calabria, Campania), the feel- tives share a basic assumption: the extralinguistic
ing of being part of a public collective is notably nature of meaning—that is, the idea that meaning
absent or may be largely marginal in contrast with is independent and precedent to the (use of the)
the salience of the network of primary social and signs. For the extensional theory the meaning is the
family linkages. reference, for the structuralist theory it is the idea.

244 social li fe o f t he si g n
In both cases, however, it is something that is sepa- the world in itself but of signs and combinations of
rate and prior to the displaying of the signs, as such signs producing such a sense of worldness—what
grounding and motivating this display. In the final we call SQR here. However, not doubting is a sign.
analysis, both these general conceptions of meaning A dictionary is the emblem of this separateness
consider it as the uphill condition of sense-making: and self-referentiality of language. No dictionary
signification is possible because there is something defines the lemmas by connecting them to the thing
(the meaning) that can/must be signified. One can to which they refer. Words are defined in terms
say “Moon” (the sign) because and insofar as there is of other words—namely, in terms of a pattern of
the concept (the |moon|) and/or the concrete object co-occurrences of signs. The dictionary shows that
of the world (the moon) it stands for. meaning is not connected to ostensibility; it emerges
A closer look to this extralinguistic assumption through the way signs combine with each other.
leads us to realize why it is unsatisfactory. In brief, Sense-making (in the sense of the process of dis-
paradoxically it assumes as its premise what is actu- playing signs) is not the mobilization of meanings
ally the consequence of the phenomenon it intends pre-existing somewhere and independently. Rather,
to model—namely, meaning. Take the meaning of meaning is the product of sense-making (for opera-
the sign “moon.” Whether it be the moon or the tive models implementing this tenet, see Andersen,
|moon|, however we refer to it through and in the 2001; Salvatore, Tebaldi, & Potì, 2009).
terms of other signs (in this case, moon and |moon|,
entailing the use of capitals and of the sign “|”), we Sense-Making As Flow of Interpretations
grasp neither the thing nor the idea directly. Rather, Peirce’s vision of semiosis as an infinite flow
what we do is to make an association between a sign of interpretation provides a useful way for under-
and another sign performing the function of stand- standing meaning as the product of sense-making.
ing for a thing and an idea. And so on ad infinitum. A sign:
To be more precise, what I am calling “thing” and
“. . . or representamen, is something which stands to
“idea” are just signs involved in a given combination
somebody for something in some respect or capacity.
with previous and following signs.
It addresses somebody, that is, creates in the mind
One could say that any version of the extralin-
of that person an equivalent sign, or perhaps a more
guistic assumption is necessary to understand the
developed sign. The sign stands for something, its
semiopoietic capability of language. Indeed, we
object. It stands for that object, not in all respects,
imply and act out this assumption every time we use
but in reference to a sort of idea which I have
signs. Even now, as I am typing on my keyboard,
sometimes called the ground of the representamen.”
I have to assume that the words I am choosing are
(Peirce, 1897/1932, vol. 2, p. 228)
selected because they are the ones whose mean-
ing is the closest to the one in my mind and that Sign (representamen) stands for the object through
I want to express. Therefore, one could turn the the mediation of another sign (the equivalent sign)
accusation of paradoxicality back at me and state motivated “in the mind of that person.” The equiva-
that I am grounding myself on the extralinguistic lent sign qualifies in which “respect or capacity,” the
assumption to produce a text aimed at criticizing representamen sign, represents the object (i.e., the
it! Nevertheless, the very central point is that the ground of the representation). Hence, the sign per-
necessity of the extralinguistic assumption is not forms its semiotic function (the standing for some-
evidence coming from outside the language. Rather, thing else) through the relation with another sign
it is a representation, a sign, whose value as fun- (the equivalent sign, also defined interpretant by
damental element of the language is in turn a sign Peirce) that, in turn, will be interpreted by another
rather than an inherent characteristic of the world. sign. Semiosis is the infinite process of interpreta-
In other words, the extralinguisticness concerns the tion of signs by means of other signs elicited in the
content of the assumption, not its nature, which mind of the interpreter.
instead is still linguistic.2 However, the assumption An important point at stake here is that Peirce’s
is a sign and as such plays a grounding, regulative view of sense-making as infinite semiosis actually
role on sense-making. Our mental and social life leads us to realize that semiosis never goes outside
is fully immersed in such a flow of signs (Mininni, itself. The object is assumed to trigger the flow of
Ligorio, & Traversa, 2012). We do not doubt the signs; nevertheless, the kind of relationship the sign
world outside it; yet we do not get experience of has with it (what Peirce defines ground) is given by

sa lvatore 245
the relationship the sign establishes with the follow- More particularly, I propose to consider SQR as the
ing sign (i.e., the interpretant). global effect of the stability of the flow of interpretation,
where this stability consists of the only real fact that
Namely, a sign is something, A, which brings
the flow reproduces itself through time. As long as
something, B, its interpretant sign determined or
signs are used—namely, as long as people commu-
created by it, into the same sort of correspondence
nicate with each other—there will be SQR. In this,
with something, C, its object, as that in which itself
the SQR works in a way akin to light. Light is per-
stands to C.
ceived and conceived of as a thing (e. g., “Give me
(Peirce, 1902/1976, vol. 4, pp. 20–21)
a light, please”) or a quality (e.g., “The room is light
Using Peirce’s terminology, the meaning of A (i.e., and airy”). Yet, it is actually a process—an inces-
in which respect A stands for the thing C—namely, sant flow of photons. This flow is not retained in
the ground of the representamen) is not given by the semiotic construction of any of the versions of
the relationship A through C but by the relation- light. It is the cause of the perception, not its object/
ship between A and its interpretant B, the latter content. What we perceive is the emergent, macro-
relationship being assumed equivalent to the former scopic effects produced by the invariance (stability)
(A<>C=A<>B=B<>D=D<>E= . . .). This leads to the of the constantly changing flow of photons. In the
conclusion that meaning is the way signs combine same way, meaning is the emergent global effect of
with each other—the trajectory of the chain of signs.3 the incessant flow of signs interpreting each other.
Meaning is given by the capability of semiosis to Let us see how this happens in more detail.
keep signs in (some kind of ) correspondence with
the reality they refer to by means of their connection The SQR As an Emergent Effect of
with other (interpretant) signs, in turn in correspon- the Flow of Signs
dence with reality by means of other interpretant To understand the semiotic mechanism ground-
signs, and so on, in an infinite flow. Every new ing this process of emergence, one has to take into
interpretant somehow rewrites the relationship with account that any sign is interpretable only in accor-
the object the previous signs have shaped through dance with some constraints that reduce the virtu-
their combination; at the same time, in the very fact ally infinite possibilities of interpretation (Salvatore
of doing it, it keeps this relationship active, opening & Venuleo, 2008). These constraints are further
to further potentiality of signification. meanings that have to be taken for granted.5 This
Sense-making consists of that recursive, asymp- means that any interpretation is possible only under
totic stream of interpreting signs. It is permanently a semiotic scenario working as an unthought prem-
stretched out toward its ungraspable object (De ise (Christopher & Bickhard, 2007). This scenario
Leo, 2008).4 And this permanent tension makes constitutes the condition of interpretability of the
it an inexhaustible generative dynamics. We can sign. The condition of interpretability can be seen as
and must always interpret because no interpreta- the definition of the version of world—among those
tion is conclusive: each triggers a further one, just possible (Bruner, 1986)—within and according to
as any step toward the horizon moves the horizon which sign is interpreted.
itself ahead. Sense-making is thus the incessant ten- Take the case of a man in the sea who is wav-
sion of filling the emptiness between language and ing his arms and shouting “I’m drowning. Do
the world. Incidentally, this idea is quite close to something for me!” Moreover, suppose that there is
the psycho-analyst Wilfred Bion’s statement that someone on the beach seeing and hearing him. It
thought emerges through absence (Bion, 1967). is easy to think that this woman will interpret the
man’s words as a request of help aimed at avoiding
The Process of Production of SQR death by drowning. And so she will dive into the
I have used the term SQR above to denote the water to save him or will ask someone else to do
semiotic value of VEPS—namely, their being viewed it. Now, although the woman’s interpretation may
and used as referring to existing, although not sub- be fast, it is not immediate. The woman has to acti-
stantial, entities. This raises the question of how the vate some premises qualifying the semiotic scenario,
SQR is produced. making the man’s words interpretable. In this case,
A processual model of sense-making is required some of these very basic assumptions concern the
that looks at the SQR as the product emerging fact that people don’t want to die, that it is a good
from within semiosis (Salvatore & Zittoun, 2011). thing to help people to survive, that the content of

246 social li fe o f t he si g n
the sentence is representative of the state of the per- signs will go on reproducing the SQR of the ver-
son uttering it, and so forth. As one can see, these sion of the world grounding them. In sum, signs
assumptions are very basic generalized meanings are interpreted through the activation of semiotic
constituting the condition of interpretability of the gestalts—namely, generalized premises working as
man’s words. Without them, the man’s words would the condition of interpretability.
remain uninterpretable and he would probably end
up on the seabed. The Role of Semiotic Gestalt-
Most importantly, what enables the interpreter Construction: Reification
to perform her hermeneutic job is not the objec- These semiotic gestalts are constantly kept active
tive “truthfulness” of her unthought premises. That through the very fact that the flow of interpreta-
would entail an extralinguistic anchor point. The tions for which they are the condition of possibility
fact is that these assumptions ground and shape the unfolds through time. And therefore, as long as and
interpretation of the signs and therefore feed into a insofar as the flow of interpretations goes on, the
further unfolding of the incessant semiotic flow. In assumption of quality-of-reality is reified—namely,
other words, the premises are not an object for dis- SQR is experienced not as a meaning but as a fact
cussion and validation. As conditions of interpret- endowed with value of life (Salvatore & Venuleo,
ability, they ground and regulate the interpretation, 2010). SQR is a very generalized and regulative
without being involved as content of it—they are the meaning: it is the basic assumption that the inter-
unthought device of thinking. Therefore, their truth- preters have to make to carry out their hermeneutic
fulness is not a matter of judgment and/or agree- work—namely, add new interpretants to the chain
ment. Rather, it is the very product of their working of interpretation. In other words, SQR is what we
as the regulative ground of the interpretations. In need to put in the foreground to be able to think.
the terms of the previous example, the woman on SQR is the basic condition of interpretability of signs.
the beach can interpret the man’s words only on the An imaginary example inspired by Wittgenstein
condition of assuming a version of world and on the (1953/1958) provides an illustration of the semiotic
condition of living this version as if it were the only process of reification, which is the output and at the
possible world—that is, the world. Actually, this same time the grounding of sense-making. Imagine
world is just one of the semiotic possibilities. a man with a box that cannot be opened. And imag-
One could imagine other versions of worlds— ine that this man claims that inside the box there are
for example, a world where people like to drown some little balls. This claim triggers a dialogue about
(version 2) or where they consider the organization the balls—their properties, the implication of their
of funeral rituals more important than avoiding the ownership, and so forth. Imagine that this dialogue
death of other people (version 3). Take version 2: goes on for a long time, from one person to another,
the woman will dive, but as she reaches the man, she until nobody can remember its starting point. Now,
will probably help him to drown, having interpreted insofar as the language game goes ahead (i.e., as the
the utterance “Do something for me” in accordance flow of interpretations reproduces itself through
with the assumption of the desirability of death. time), the presupposition of the existence of the
In the case of version 3, the woman will run away ball—the assumption that is the condition of inter-
from the sea to start organizing the post mortem pretability of the flow—remains valid. This means
ceremony in anticipation of the man’s impending that it is believed and felt as a fact by the partici-
drowning. pants in the language game. Namely, it is reified. In
Let us come back to version 1 (the one we con- sum, it is not the existence of the balls that grounds
sider the only version, therefore not merely a ver- the talk on the balls, but it is the talk about the balls
sion but the real world as it is supposed to be), that reify the SQR of the balls.
and suppose the woman will try to save the man. Consider another instance: the financial system
The interpretation of the man’s word associated is a paradigmatic example of a flow of signs that
with this reaction will keep alive the SQR of the constantly keeps the SQR of its premises active
version of the world that works as the condition through the very fact of reproducing itself through
of interpretability of the woman’s interpretation. time. Money is a very abstract concept, as is shown
And because further signs will be triggered by the by the fact that it can be associated with an infi-
woman’s action—for example, the man will thank nite number of things. Its SQR is produced by the
her, calling her “his guardian angel”—these further fact that the existence of its value is the condition

sa lvatore 247
of interpretability of the exchanges it prompts. of interpretability of the signs they are dealing with.
Thus, we could say that sense-making is like playing And given that one of the properties associated with
Monopoly. While they are part of the game, play- the regal status of the Emperor is that this condition
ers give value of life to banknotes and contracts— is inconsistent with appearing naked, then what
namely, the signs mediating their exchange—because they see is interpreted in the light of the assumption
such conventions are assumed as if they create the that he is dressed in a very rare and valuable weave
SQR required to play and enjoy the game. What that has the quality of being invisible to stupid peo-
differentiates Monopoly from sense-making is that ple. Thus, we see a hierarchical system of premises
one cannot stop playing with semiosis and therefore at work. The perception of the man known as the
turn off the SQR of premises. All one can do is to Emperor is a sign interpreted in accordance with
change the content of the premise, not stop making the premise that his clothes are made of a kind of
premises. woven fabric that may either appear or not depend-
ing on the quality of the observer. This premise is in
The VEPS As Stable Condition turn grounded on a further premise that serves as
of Interpretability a condition of interpretability of the former—the
According to the consideration provided above, regal status of the Emperor. It is only on the condi-
the semiotic mechanism of reification can be con- tion of assuming the royalty of the Emperor that
sidered in terms of the following general law: any the idea of such fantastic clothes becomes meaning-
meaning working as the ground (i.e., as condition ful. Moreover, we need to introduce another very
of interpretability) of any practice of sense-making basic premise to close the gestalt: the very basic,
acquires and keeps SQR in the framework of that grounding idea that everyone has of silliness as an
practice. undesirable status. As the tale tells us, as long as this
The statement attributed to Jesus: “For where network of premises works in a regulative role, the
two or three are gathered together in my name, sense-making regulated by them endows them with
there am I in the midst of them” (Matthew, 18:20) SQR. When they lose their regulative salience, they
is the most powerful image of this tenet I am able to lose their SQR. Yet, if one sees the issue through a
find; a representation (to be there) is endowed with more detailed lens, then one can realize that actually
SQR (Jesus’ presence not as mere representation or not all the premises have lost their salience. At least
belief, but presented and viewed as a fact) insofar as some of them keep their stability, even after the rup-
two or more persons share the assumption that what ture of the previous framework, when the Emperor
they believe is real (i.e., being there in the name of ). starts to be thought of and described as naked. The
This is the wonderful power of language to generate assumption of the Emperor’s royalty continues to
the conditions of its power! retain its salience in the new framework; otherwise,
What I want to focus on now concerns the spa- the embarrassment as well as the other reactions at
tial-temporal stability of the salience of the condi- the sight of the naked man would be meaningless.
tion of interpretability. The general law given above Even more in-depth, the assumption of the undesir-
considers this point when it states that the SQR of a ability of the status of stupidity is not destabilized by
given premise is contingent to the framework of the the transition to the new framework; it also works
practice of sense-making that such a premise regu- as a condition of interpretability in the new context
lates. As long as it works as a salient condition of (i.e., people see the Emperor as naked not because
interpretability, the premise is the invariant ground they agree to be considered stupid, but because they
of the ongoing variability of the flow of interpreta- realize other aspects that in any case they interpret
tions. But how stable is (or must be) the salience of in the light of the assumption that stupidity is an
the premises? unfair status).
To answer this question, one has to take into In sum, as our interpretation of the Anderson
account that the premises are not single meanings. tale shows, the premises have different degrees of
Rather, they are a hierarchical6 network of general- stability to their salience. Needless to say, these dif-
ized significances. ferences do not depend on the inherent property of
Anderson’s tale “The Emperor’s New Clothes” the premises. Rather, they are consequence of the
illustrates this point. People see and act as if the way people and groups enact the practices of sense-
Emperor were dressed, because they use the assump- making. As a result of these practices, some prem-
tion of the royalty of the Emperor as the condition ises can be moved more easily from the background

248 social li fe o f t he si g n
to the foreground of sense-making, and in this system is able to reach through time. The concept of
way they can be made objects of signification and meta-stability enables us to realize how in semiosis
therefore subject to critique and/or falsification. the invariance/stability of meaning is the product of
Others are endowed with a higher power to hold an ongoing process, rather than the reflection of a
in the background, and in this way they retain their static element.8
salience as a regulative unthought source of think-
ing and acting.7 Bivalence of Meaning: “Semiotic Silicone”
The VEPS can thus be conceived of as quite sta- The discussion of the quality-of-reality pre-
ble premises, able to keep their salience as the con- sented so far leads us to focus on the mechanisms
dition of interpretability through time and space. of sense-making involved in the micro-dynamics
Thanks to this power, they can serve to regulate of the reification of signs. According to my the-
meaning, without being affected by the ongoing sis, these mechanisms are rooted in the bivalence
changes occurring within the semiotic flow; as such, of meaning (Abbey & Valsiner, 2007; Carli, 2007;
they work as basic, invariant sources and grounds of Ribeiro, Gonçalves, & Santos, 2012; Valsiner,
SQR. From the standpoint of the dynamic theory 2007). Generally speaking, bivalence is depictable
of systems (Lauro-Grotto, Salvatore, Gennaro, & in the following way: Taking A as what the sign
Gelo, 2009; Salvatore, Laura-Grotto, Gennaro, & makes present, then the meaning is not A but the
Gelo, 2009), such invariance is a meta-stable trend bond of A and not-A (henceforth the complement
that appears only at some level of scale—that is, A), according to which A emerges as a presence. In
a regularity in the ever-changing dynamics of the other words, the meaning of a sign does not only
system. Figure 11.1 provides an example of meta- consist of the sign that follows the previous one in
stable trend (from Salvatore et al., 2009). At a the flow of interpretation (i.e., the A); but it also
molecular level of scale, (that defined by 1 as the encompasses the whole gestalt that makes such a
unit of analysis), the trajectory appears highly vari- sign the one that occurs instead of the infinite oth-
able. At a higher level (that defined by 10 as the ers that do not occur (henceforth we indicate this
elementary unit of analysis), the trajectory designs a whole as the complementSign).
stable trend, defined by an almost quadratic curve, Complement A consists of both connections—in
depicting the increasing–decreasing movement of presentia and in absentia. On the one hand, any A
the extension of the variability (i.e., the peaks) the entails an infinite number of connections with

60,000

50,000

40,000

30,000

20,000

10,000

0,000
1
5
9
13
17
21
25
29
33
37
41
45
49
53
57
61
65
69
73
77
81
85
89
93
97
1
5
9
3
7
1
10
10
10
11
11
12

Figure 11.1 An example of meta-stable pattern.


(From Salvatore, Lauro-Grotto, Gelo, Gennaro, 2009)

sa lvatore 249
other signs. We have already dealt with this point the interpretandum acquires sense. In sum, the
when we stated that the meaning of a sign is the set meaning is not used up in the content of the utter-
of combinations it has with other signs. Yet, these ance, because any practice of sense-making instan-
bonds in presentia are, at the same time, relation- tiates the whole semiotic field—namely, the infinite
ships in absentia—saying that the set of combina- in presentia and in absentia bonds—grounding the
tions associable to the sign S contains X, Y, and Z “sensefulness”10 of this content (Salvatore, Forges-
means that S is not associable to M, N, O . . . .; any Davanzati, Potì, & Ruggieri, 2009).11
presence of signs is at the same time the absence of Pantomime provides a fine image of the bivalence
other signs. One could say that meaning concerns of meaning and sense-making. The mime produces
this split—namely, the border placed between what some movements that work as signs (henceforth, S).
is thus made present and what is thus made absent. The spectator sees these movements as an action
The relationship between figure and background (henceforth, A). For the spectator, S stands for A: S
illustrates this point. Any time a form (A) is extrap- instantiates A, and A is the interpretation of S. Yet
olated, it is being made pertinent compared to it would be misleading to consider A the content of
something else (the complementA) that plays the S. A is not contained in S; rather, it is the spectators
role of background. Because there are infinite ways that build A as the interpretation of S. Moreover,
of separating figure and background, there are infi- the spectator performs this interpretative activity,
nite possible figures. And this means that any figure adding a set of other data of imagination (i.e., other
is not the autonomous, self-contained content of a signs) that work as a complement of S and in so
representation, but the product of a specific rela- doing define the contextual totality that makes S
tionship with the background: the background is therefore interpretable and thinkable. So the mime
part of the meaning of the figure and not something moves his arms and hands in a certain way; yet the
simply put aside. It is necessary if the figures are to interpretation of these movements as pulling a rope
be understood.9 requires the spectator to complete the gestalt with
Consider the occurrence of a certain sign— a set of data of imagination concerning a long thin
say, “s”. That sign is experienced by us as holding object being grasped by the mime, connected at the
a given content—say, |s|. For example, if someone opposite end with something that resists the mime’s
utters the word “pipe,” everyone sharing the speak- efforts. This set of data of imagination is the comple-
er’s code will consider this sign as having the value mentSign (cS) completing the interpreted gestalt—
of denoting that device used for burning tobacco that is, the context. Thus, we arrive at the following
with the aim of breathing in the smoke produced. definition: CON = (S + cS): the context is produced
When we think and communicate, we act as if by the sign performed by the mime integrated by the
this experience of the signs were truth—namely, interpreter’s complementary activity of interpretation,
that sign s has a specific self-contained content thanks to which the interpreter makes a figure endowed
|s|. Actually, this association is not given prior to with sensefulness. It is only on this condition that
the production of the sign, as an inherent prop- the movements of the mime become interpretable
erty of the sign (Visetti & Codiot, 2002); rather, as pulling a rope.
it is the product, the first product, of sense-mak- The interpretation starts, is constrained by, and
ing, emerging through the network of connections has the interpretandum as its target; yet, strictly
within which the sign is part (Salvatore, Tebaldi, speaking it does not concern it. Rather, the inter-
& Potì, 2006/2009). The context is this network pretandum is the trigger element for the constructive
of sign combinations whose contingency qualifies function of producing a new sign complementing
the significance the interpreter attributes to each of the former. The interpretation does not specify some-
them. Thus, sense-making always and in any case thing that is within the interpretandum, but it adds
performs a double operation. On the one hand, something further to it. When the spectator signifies
it defines a denoting entity (what we are used to the mime’s movement, her hermeneutic work is not
experiencing as the content of the sign)—namely, limited to the representation of what she perceives.
the making of a pertinent presence (henceforth, the Rather, she provides something else, complement-
interpretandum). And yet on the other hand, sense- ing the context. It is the introduction of this data
making leads to the emergence of the complement of imagination that, working as a semiotic silicone,
of that presence—namely, the semiotic scenario allows the closure of the gestalt that makes up the
according to, through, and in the terms of which interpretation.

250 social li fe o f t he si g n
The Backward Mechanism reproduction of the semiotic flow and the reifica-
Taking into account the bivalence of sense-mak- tion of the signs.
ing, we need to conclude that sense-making can-
not but reify.12 The notion of bivalence of meaning Future Directions
leads us to expect that any incoming sign does not The starting point of this contribution was the
specify something that is already within/conveyed need for a processual conception of sense-making,
by the previous; rather, it adds something further to modeled as an uninterrupted flow of signs, working
it: the kind of closing support (“semiotic silicone”) as a dynamic field. This conception puts aside the
that is needed to bring the emerging gestalt into idea of meaning as prior sense-making. Meaning is
an appropriate form. The form of the gestalt can the emergent field product of sense-making. This
change through time, but one gestalt is always in model provides a different way of understanding
the process of formation, because of the very fact how people, who inevitably speak and think from
that constantly new signs are introduced in the flow. within and through the flow of signs, are able to feel
Therefore, the stability of the semiotic flow is some- and act as if there were a social world-out-there.
how kept and reproduced and with it the SQR. I have focused on a central aspect of this general
Bivalence of sense-making leads to an inversion issue: how some signs (the VEPS, as I have called
of the naïve view, according to which what comes them) are able to be felt and used as if they refer
before (the interpretandum) causes/regulates what to things, although they have no other connection
follows (the interpretant). One must avoid confus- than that with other signs. My proposal is that semi-
ing the occurrence of the sign with the semiotic osis provides the sense of its being in touch with the
function this occurrence performs within the flow world from within itself, as the consequence of the
of interpretations. Actually, it is not the sign that very fact that the flow of signs goes on through time
occurs, but a fact—it would be better to say, a sen- (and it does somehow go on).
sorial modification in the interpreter that is assumed This proposal entails a vision of sense-making
as a fact. This occurrence is a function of the state based on the idea of the bivalence of signs: signs are
of the material field at the moment of the occur- made not only of what they represent but also of
rence.13 In itself, the occurrence has no meaning. the whole field of meaning (the semiotic silicone)
What I have above called “condition of interpret- working as condition of interpretability of the sign
ability” does not concern it. The construction of the itself. I have devoted the second part of this work
condition of interpretability is not the effect of the to showing how this bivalent model allows us to
interpretandum’s capability to trigger an interpre- conceptualize the microdynamics of sense-making,
tant. On the contrary, the condition of interpretabil- in terms of a backward mechanism—signs do not
ity works retrospectively, as the backward creation motivate the following ones; rather, they are con-
of the context (the gestalt), thanks to which the strued as signs and interpreted as such by the fol-
occurrence can work as a sign—namely, it is treat- lowing ones. Moreover, we have underlined how the
able up to now as the interpretant of the previous bivalent model leads us to distinguish two levels of
chain of signs. The linkage between interpretandum interpretation. On the one hand, any sign is recog-
and interpretant works like the least common mul- nized by how it is interpreted. On the other hand,
tiple rather than the greatest common divisor: the however, this recognition is based on a hermeneutic
meaning is not (constrained within) which elements work in absentia—namely, on the projection of the
(the divisors) the two signs have in common but sign on a gestalt providing the condition of inter-
what they produce (the gestalt) through their being pretability thanks to which the sign is addressed as
placed in common. senseful, and therefore interpretable (i.e., standing
Hence, semiosis is inherently unlimited, because for something else). Consequently, the analysis of a
the chain of signs lacks the power to constrain the set of signs (a text) means retrieving the generalized
further possibilities of sign production. The subse- meaning grounding the semiotic encounter with
quent sign defines the condition of interpretability the text. In this sense, hermeneutic analysis is always
of the previous one, rather than vice versa. And a recursive function, aimed at grasping the semiotic
given that we cannot but interpret, any interpreter construction that has to be produced to perform an
will be able to find a way to do it; even if the spe- act of interpretation.
cific gestalt may change through time, the construc- Needless to say, further developments are
tion of a gestalt will be performed, and with it the required to study in-depth the various aspects of the

sa lvatore 251
model that have not been addressed in this paper. with the pragmatic approach to meaning that sees it as the effect
In particular, there are three aspects that I see as the the sign provides on the addressee. In our view, however, this
effect has to be conceptualized as a further sign: an equivalent
most relevant to examine. First, the modeling of the sign. Be it a reaction, a refusal, or an affective appraisal of the
microdynamics of the backward mechanism and addresser’s sign, the addressee’s response works as the interpre-
more generally the way the bivalence of meaning tant of the former, and in so doing develops the chain of signs
works in sense-making. In this perspective, a line comprising the meaning and keeps itself active and transforming
of investigation I consider promising is to use the through time.
4. Claiming this linguistic, processual and nonexpressive
topology to depict the field dynamics of the chain nature of meaning does not mean assuming a nihilist position
of signs. Second, at the current level of formulation, that rejects any kind of connection between language and world.
the model addresses the issue of the SQR only in Actually, the separateness of language, as I use it here, does not
its general aspect—namely, as the problem of how entail its isolation. Rather, it is the condition of sense-making—
sense-making produces it. Yet, from a descriptive not its limit. It is precisely because semiosis is an autonomous,
self-referential, and recursive process that it can make meanings
point of view, it is quite evident that signs are used emerge. Autonomy is required for the development of the self-
with different gradients of SQR. The sign “stone” regulative intrasystemic dynamics that leads to the development
and the sign “the flying horse” differ from each of these processes of emergence.
other as concerns their SQR. Yet between these two 5. This point is highlighted by Peirce’s triadic theory:
extremes, there are many signs that, according to the interpretant is a way of depicting the linkage between the
representamen and the dynamic object. Therefore, any sign,
the circumstances and to users, have an intermedi- any interpretation, is possible on condition that (1) there is a
ate level of SQR. Take, for example, fictional char- dynamic object in relation with the sign standing for it; (2) this
acters (Eco, 2009; Valsiner, 2009) that may or may relationship concerns a specific aspect of the dynamic object (the
not be endowed with SQR in a variable fashion and ground); (3) the ground is signified by an equally specific aspect
that do not have the same SQR as either “stone” of the sign (e.g., the image of the pipe stands for the pipe only
in some perceptual properties and not in functional ones—that
or “flying horse.” Consequently, it is not enough is why we cannot use it for smoking; at the same time, not all
to model how SQR is produced—one also has to the elements of the image of the pipe are relevant to its function
understand what makes such production variable of standing for the pipe (e.g., the chemical composition of the
across the practices of sense-making. Finally, I con- paper on which it is drawn is not relevant).
sider it important to validate the model to test its 6. In semiosis, the hierarchical linkage among the premises is
intransitive in its nature (Valsiner, 2007)—that is, a given mean-
capability to ground analysis of specific patterns ing A can be superordered compared to B, B can be superordered
of sense-making. In this chapter, I have made sev- compared to C, and at the same time C can be superordered
eral references to phenomena of sense-making. Yet, compared to A. This is so because the hierarchical organization
these references have had a merely exemplificative of meaning is not an invariant structure but is contingent to the
function; I have not used the model to understand dynamics of sense-making.
7. The idea of the European Community as an entity is an
them, but vice versa. In the final analysis, it is in example of how a meaning can have a variable gradient of SQR
this possibility—that the model enables us to get a through time and space. In some areas of the European popula-
deeper understanding of the phenomena of social tion—as well as at some points in the recent history of the Euro-
exchange—that the conceptual value of the theoret- pean people—the European Community has been experienced
ical proposal lies. (is being experienced) as a concrete entity, something to belong
to and by which it is acceptable to be affected in our own lives.
In other historical moments and other domains of the European
Notes population (e.g., in a not insignificant part of the Italian as well
1. My discussion does not require that the recognition of the as the English population), the European Community is little
fact that a given sign does not refer to a substantial entity should more than a name.
be fixed and systematic among people. On the contrary, it is usual 8. The example of Monopoly can help to illustrate this point.
for many people at certain times and in certain circumstances to During the game the Monopoly banknotes work as if endowed
regard signs like “the United States” as substantial entities and at with SQR for the players. Yet, as soon as the game ends, they
other times, and in other circumstances, as nonsubstantial enti- lose their salience. Therefore, because they do not have enough
ties. What is relevant and required for the sake of our discussion, cross-spatial/temporal stability, they cannot be considered as
therefore, is the potentiality of this sign to be used as referring to VEPS. On the other hand, the value of money is quite a ubiqui-
nonsubstantial entities. tous assumption in contemporary society. It is salient before and
2. Confusing these two levels—the nature of the object rep- after the game and at the same time is not suspended during the
resented by the sign and the nature of the sign representing it is game. On the contrary, the SQR of the money grounds the very
like concluding that if a person says, “I am not speaking,” then possibility of considering Monopoly meaningful. It works as a
she/he is not speaking. condition of interpretability of the local condition of interpret-
3. The idea of meaning as the trajectory of the chain of signs ability of the game and the acts of playing it. In sum, money
is close to the seminal idea of Wittgenstein (1953/1958) of is a meaning that retains its stability through many space/time
meaning as the use of the words. More generally, it is consistent frameworks. In this sense, it is a meta-stable condition of sense-

252 social li fe o f t he si g n
making, which is made salient through the variability of the local Bucci, W. (1997). Psychoanalysis and Cognitive Science. New York:
dynamics of semiosis. That is the same as saying that it is a very Guildford Press.
powerful VEPS. Carli, R. (2007). Pulcinello or ‘on ambiguity’. Rivista di psico-
9. Interestingly enough, psychoanalytic theory has concep- logia clinica/Journal of Clinical Psychology (Online Journal)
tualized the affects as the first form of meanings emerging from 3. Retrieved on 28th of February, 2009 from http://www.
the proto-differentiation of the field of experience as an indistin- rivistadipsicologiaclinica.it/english/number3_07/Carli.
guishable totality (Bucci, 1997; Matte Blanco, 1975). htm
10. I use this term to stress that what is at stake here is not Christopher, J. C., & Bickhard, M. (2007). Culture, self and
the semantic and/or pragmatic validity of the content—namely, identity. Interactivist contributions to a metatheory for cul-
if the interpreter considers it agreeable or not. In a more gener- tural psychology. Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 259–295.
alized way, “sensefulness” concerns the very plausibility of the De Leo, D. (2008). The communicative experience: between
act of interpreting the sign (of considering it a sign worth being inexpressible and elusive. Integrative Psychological &
interpreted). Thus, the content can be meaningful or not, but it Behavioural Science, 42(2), 179–186.
is viewed so as a result of the fact that the interpreter addresses Eco, U. (2009). On the Ontology of fictional characters: A semi-
it—that is, as a result of the fact that it is considered “senseful.” otic approach. Sign Systes studies, 37(1/2), 82–98.
Therefore, a sign can have sensefulness but not meaningfulness Frege, G (1980, 3rd ed.) On sense and reference (M. Black, Trans.).
but not vice versa. In P. Geach, & M. Black (Eds. and Trans.) Translations
11. Recently, Bang (2009) has underlined the role of the from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78).
emptiness in sense-making. This concept is another way of high- Oxford, UK: Blackwell. (Original work published 1892).
lighting the interdependence between the visible (in presentia) Kanizsa, G (1955) Margini quasi-percettivi in campi con sti-
and latent (in absentia) sides of meanings. molazione omogenea [Almost perceptual contours in field
12. Needless to say, the SQR can appear in the discourse with homogeneous stimulation]. Rivista di Psicologia 49(1),
as the content of a statement. For example, this is true when 7–30.
one says: “I do not think that this actually happened.” Neverthe- Lauro-Grotto, R. P., Salvatore, S., Gennaro, A., & Gelo, O.
less, the SQR as a specific content of a statement (say “SQR”) is (2009). The unbearable dynamicity of psychological pro-
not to be confused with the SQR as the global sense of connec- cesses: Highlights of the psychodynamic theories. In
tion with the world that emerges from semiosis as a whole (say J. Valsiner, P. Molenaar, M. Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.).
|SQR|). The latter is a highly generalized feeling, an embodied Dynamics process methodology in the social and developmental
meaning, inherently associated with sense-making (Salvatore & sciences (pp. 1–30). New York: Springer.
Zittoun, 2011), whereas the former is a discrete sign that may Matte Blanco, I. (1975). The Unconscious as Infinite Sets. An Essays
or may not be used in communication. The latter is a recursive in Bi-Logic. London: Gerald Duckworth and Company Ltd.
interpretation of the former, which is possible precisely because Mininni, G., Ligorio, B., & Traversa, R. (2012). The singular
of the former. patterns of discourse. For a psychoidographic analysis of
13. It is outside the scope of this work to address the issue of language. In S. Salvatore, A. Gennaro, & J. Valsiner (Eds.).
how the state of the field produces new occurrences. Making Sense of Infinite Uniqueness: The Emerging system of
Idiographic Science. Yearbook of Idiographic Science – Volume
4. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.
References Moscovici, S. (2008). Psychoanalysis: Its image and its public
Abbey, E., & Valsiner, J. (2005). Emergence of meanings (G. Duveen, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press (Original work
through ambivalence. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung/ published 1961).
Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 6(1), 58. Olson, M. (1965). The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and
Albertazzi, L., Jacquette, D., & Poli, R (2001b). Meinong in His the Theory of Groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
and Our Times. In L. Albertazzi, D. Jacquette, & R. Poli Press.
(Eds.). The school of Alexius Meinong (pp. 3–48). Aldershot, Peirce, C. S. (1932). In C. Hartshorne, & P. Weiss (Eds.),
UK: Ashgate. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vol. 2. Cambridge,
Albertazzi, L., Jacquette, D., & Poli, R (Eds.) (2001a). The school MA: Harvard University Press (Original version: 1897).
of Alexius Meinong. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Peirce, C. S. (1976). In C. Eisele (Ed.), The new elements of
Andersen, S. (2001). The Emergence of Meaning: Generating mathematics by Charles S. Peirce. The Hague, Netherlands:
Symbols from Random Sounds - A Factor Analytic Model. Mouton Publishers (Original version 1902).
Journal of Quantitative Linguistics, 8(2), 101–136. Putnam, R. (1993). Making Democracy Work. Princeton, NJ:
Ariès, P. (1962). Centuries of Childhood: A Social History of Family Princeton University Press.
Life (R. Baldick, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books (Original Ribeiro, A, Gonçalves, M, & Santos, A. (2012) Innovative
work published 1960). moments in psychotherapy: From the narrative outputs to
Bang, J. (2009). Nothingness and the Human Umwelt A the semiotic-dialogical processes. In S. Salvatore, A. Gennaro,
Cultural–Ecological Approach to Meaning. Integrative & J. Valsiner (Eds.). Making Sense of Infinite Uniqueness: The
Psychological & Behavioural Science, 43(4), 374–392. Emerging system of Idiographic Science. Yearbook of Idiographic
Bion, W. R. (1967). Second thoughts. London: Maresfield Science – Volume 4. Charlotte, NC: Information Age
Library. Publishers.
Brentano, F. (1995), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint Rommetveit, R. (1992). Outlines of a dialogically based social-
(L. L. McAlister, Ed.) London: Routledge. (Original work cognitive approach to human cognition and communica-
published 1874). tion. In A. H. Wold (Ed.). The Dialogical Alternative towards
Bruner, J. S. (1986). Actual Minds, Possible Words. Cambridge, a Theory of Language and Mind (pp. 19–44). Oslo, Norway:
MASS.: Harvard University Press. Scandinavian University Press.

sa lvatore 253
Salvatore, S., Forges Davanzati, G., Potì, S. & Ruggeri, R. Salvatore, S., & Zittoun, T. (2011). Outlines of a psychoana-
(2009). Mainstream Economics and sensemaking, Integrative lytically informed cultural psychology. In S. Salvatore, &
Psychological and Behavioral Science, 43(2), 158–177. T. Zittoun (Eds.), Cultural psychology and psychoanalysis in
Salvatore, S., Lauro-Grotto, R., Gennaro, A., & Gelo, O. (2009). dialogue. issues for constructive theoretical and methodologi-
Attempts to grasp the dynamicity of intersubjectivity. In cal synergies (pp. 3–46). Charlotte, NC: Information Age
J. Valsiner, P. C. M. Molenaar, M. C. D. P. Lyra, & Publishers.
N. Chaudhary (Eds.). Dynamic process methodology in the social Saussure, F. d. (1977). Course in General Linguistics (W. Baskin,
and developmental sciences (pp. 171–190). New York: Springer. Trans.). Glasgow, UK: Fontana/Collins. (Original work pub-
Salvatore, S., Tebaldi, C., & Poti, S. (2009). The discur- lished 1916)
sive dynamics of sensemaking. In S. Salvatore, J. Valsiner, Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in Minds and Societies. Foundations of
S. Strout, & J. Clegg (Eds.), YIS: Yearbook of Idiographic Science Cultural Psychology. New Delhi, India: Sage Publications.
2008-Volume 1 (pp. 39–72). Rome: Firera Publishing. Valsiner, J (2009). Between fiction and reality: Transforming the
Salvatore, S., & Venuleo C. (2008). Understanding the Role semiotic object. Sign Systes studies, 37(1/2), 99–113.
of Emotion in Sensemaking. A semiotic psychoanalytic Visetti, Y. M., & Cadiot, P. (2002). Instability and theory of
oriented. Integrative Journal of Psychological and Behavioral semantic forms. Starting from the case of prepositions. In
Science, 42(1), 32–46. S. Feigenbaum & D. Kurzon (Eds.), Prepositions in their
Salvatore, S., & Venuleo C. (2010). The unconscious as source Syntactic, Semantic and Pragmatic Context (pp. 9–39).
of sense: A psychodynamic approach to meaning. In Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
B. Wagoner (Ed), Symbolic Transformation. The Mind in Wittgenstein, L. (1958, 2nd ed.). Philosophical Investigations.
Movement Through Culture and Society (pp. 59–74). London: Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell (Original work published
Routledge. 1953).

254 social li fe o f t he si g n
CHAPTER

Meaningful Connections: Semiotics,


12 Cultural Psychology, and the
Forms of Sense
Robert E. Innis

Abstract
This chapter explores what a philosophically oriented semiotics has to offer to cultural psychology. In as
much as semiotics, as the general theory of signs, deals with multiple forms of meanings, its concerns are
distinctively cultural. But in as much as semiotics is concerned with the experienced reality of meanings,
its concerns are distinctively psychological. Nevertheless, semiotics is not itself a cultural psychology
nor a psychology of culture, nor a substitute for them. This chapter presents key elements from the
semiotically relevant work of C.S. Peirce, Karl Bühler, Michael Polanyi, Ernst Cassirer, and Susanne Langer
to focus on the power of semiotics to model the self, situate the semiotic frames of cultural meaning,
broaden the notion of signification, and to delineate the fundamental groundlines of the plenum of
consciousness and establish the thresholds of sense, including the role of the tacit dimension and the
semiotic relevance of embodiment.
Keywords: signs, modeling the self, cultural frames

Semiotics is the study of signification in the upon. In fact, semiotics takes its core categories
most general sense of that term. It is an essentially from quite different intellectual traditions and is
transdisciplinary study of processes of meaning- by no means a monolithic system or framework,
making and the meaning systems and sign systems despite the claims of many of its practitioners and
in which they are embodied and expressed. Because proponents.
of the transdisciplinary nature of semiotics, it can The differentiated conceptual toolbox of semi-
and does function as a kind of “big tent” within otics actually allows it to engage very diverse ana-
which different types of reflections and investiga- lytical, critical, and reconstructive tasks in different
tions take place. Philosophers, biologists, cultural ways. In as much as semiotics deals with multiple
theorists, psychologists, linguists, art historians, lit- forms of meanings, such as language, art, ritual,
erary theorists, and many more find its conceptual myth, religion, even science and technics, its con-
tools helpful, indeed indispensable, for carrying cerns are distinctively cultural. But in as much as
out their studies. The central concept of semiotics semiotics is concerned with the experienced reality
is the sign. What Vygotsky said about words can of meanings, its concerns are distinctively psycho-
be said, more generally, about the sign: it too not logical. Nevertheless, semiotics is not itself a cultural
only is “a direct expression of the historical nature psychology nor a psychology of culture, nor a sub-
of human consciousness” but also is “a microcosm stitute for them, although its problems and themes
of human consciousness” (Vygotsky, 1934, p. 256; intersect with them at many points. In the words
see also van der Veer & Valsiner, 1991). But how we of Umberto Eco, the subject matter of semiotics
are to frame this concept is not universally agreed is “co-extensive with the whole range of cultural

255
phenomena, however pretentious that approach I had got another. Yea, the very thoughts would not
may at first seem” (Eco, 1976, p. 6). come to me. So my faculty of discussion is equally
localized in my inkstand.
From Semiotics to Cultural Psychology (CP 7.366)
So, what does semiotics have to offer that could
Mental existence is embodied semiosis. The pro-
be of most benefit to cultural psychology, which
duction and interpretation of signs in which our
seems to have the same scope, from the experiential
thoughts come to us, and we come to thoughts,
side, as semiotics does from the side of the analysis
depends on objectively available semiotic tools in
of the logic of cultural forms? What challenges does
just the way Peirce was dependent on his metaphor-
semiotics pose to cultural psychology? And where
ical and real inkstand. This insight was developed
do semiotics and cultural psychology overlap to
and generalized by the rich psychological tradition
their mutual benefit?
initiated by Vygotsky. The semiotic tradition deriv-
ing from the structuralist project deriving from
Thresholds of Semiosis Ferdinand de Saussure’s Course in General Linguistics
In his A Theory of Semiotics, Umberto Eco
confirms Peirce’s and Eco’s claims. Its concurrence
claimed that “signification encompasses the whole
is epitomized in Elmar Holenstein’s laconic asser-
of cultural life, even at the lower threshold of semi-
tion that structuralism “draws our attention to the
otics” (Eco, 1976, p. 46). That lower threshold is
root-like attachment of the world’s subjective con-
the actional-affective-perceptual field itself in which
stitution to sign systems” (Holenstein, 1976, p. 5).
the whole of cultural life, the upper threshold, is
But it is not just the world’s constitution that is at
ultimately grounded and located. Eco’s claim was
issue. It is also the constitution of subjectivity itself.
another formulation and consequence of the funda-
Peirce’s contention that the mind is a developing
mental and startling semiotically grounded thesis of
sign is paralleled in Roland Barthes’ claim that “man
C. S. Peirce, the American philosopher and founder
is articulated to the very depths of his being in dis-
of a major strand in semiotics:
tinct languages” because “the psyche itself is articu-
“[T]he content of consciousness, the entire lated like a language” (Barthes, 1977, p. 47). The
phenomenal manifestation of mind, is a sign semiotic problem, however, is how language itself
resulting from inference . . . .the mind is a sign is structured and how it should be modeled. Even
developing according to the laws of inference.” if language is the semiotic system par excellence, as is
(Peirce, 1868, p. 53) almost universally admitted, that really means that
although it exemplifies the features of semiosis, it
Peirce divided these laws of inference into the
does not entail that it establish them or function as
three distinctive forms of induction, deduction, and
the prime model of semiosis. Semiotics, or the gen-
abduction, or hypothesis formation, to which the
eral theory of signs, takes as its task the construction
construction and interpretation of signs is attrib-
of a semiotic model that is comprehensive enough
uted. Abduction, according to Peirce, is the source of
to delineate the ultimate conditions of semiosis no
all novelty. The human mind for Peirce, however, is
matter what sign forms they may take. Semiotics
not enclosed within the skin of an individual organ-
wants to schematize the most fundamental distinc-
ism. Rather, the organism is enclosed within, or
tions between the various systems of signs, among
embodied in, or self-spinning into, a semiotic web,
which language may or may not have a certain pri-
a network of signs and sign relations that are the
macy or primordiality.
support of its mental existence. Its mind is no more
Near the end of his book, Eco goes on to say
inner than outer. It is both, as Peirce illustrated in
that “semiotics can define the subject of every act of
his famous example of the inkstand. In a provoca-
semiosis only by semiotic categories; thus the subject
tive and eminently generalizable and remarkably
of signification is nothing more than the continu-
contemporary passage, Peirce wrote:
ously unaccomplished system of systems of signifi-
A psychologist cuts out a lobe of my brain (nihil cation that reflects back on itself ” (1976, p. 315).
animale a me alienum puto) and then, when I find I This self-reflecting system is, on this account, essen-
cannot express myself, he says, “You see, your faculty tially open, or continuously unaccomplished, hav-
of language was localized in that lobe.” No doubt it ing no greatest upper bound. The unending spiral of
was; and so, if he had filched my inkstand, I should semiosis (or semioses) is a perpetual dynamic oscil-
not have been able to continue the discussion until lation between two intrinsically related thresholds,

256 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


an upper threshold of systems of signs and mean- and what are their relations to one another? And
ings of all sorts circulating in society as cultural what precisely are such approaches expected to offer
forms and a lower threshold defined by the limits of in the context of the problems and issues of a cul-
the lived body as a matrix of lived-through, but not tural psychology?
explicitly articulated, activities. The problem that all The following discussion will illustrate, with no
theories dealing with the mind and its socio-cultural claim to completeness and with a quite definite
matrices have to face is how to model this whole leaning toward the philosophical side of semiotics,
process—or the sets of processes occurring between a very personal choice of possible answers to these
these two limits. And the question has to be faced of questions by sketching central concepts and catego-
what contribution semiotics—however we define its ries from five quite different approaches to the sche-
nature, range, and scope—can make to this model- matization of consciousness, represented by C.S.
ing process. What types of semiotic categories and Peirce, Karl Bühler, Ernst Cassirer, Susanne Langer,
models have been put forth? Which ones do we and, as a kind of philosophical wildcard, Michael
really need? Is there one privileged way to model Polanyi, whose work on tacit knowing and meaning
this semiotic subject? Perhaps, in light of the com- stands outside of semiotic currents in the strict sense
plexity of the semiotic subject, there is, in fact, no but bears upon them in challenging ways. Others,
privileged way but, rather, the various approaches coming from other home disciplines, would no
to defining the thresholds of sense and meaning and doubt look to other resources, but, as I have tried
the logic of consciousness have differently weighted to show elsewhere (Innis, 1982, 1992, 2002, 2009),
heuristic powers of foregrounding different aspects the aforementioned thinkers are of extraordinary
of pertinence and relevance. This fact would have value.
important implications for the tasks and methods
of a broadly based cultural psychology and for our Framing the Semiotic Matrix
being able to situate its intersections with semiotic C. S. Peirce, as the initiator of one of the most
concerns. powerful traditions in semiotics, proposes a semiotic
What then, more specifically, can cultural psy- approach to consciousness and cognitional structure
chology find in semiotics’ toolbox that it both can that has as its focal point its essential dimensional-
and should use for its tasks? In what senses can a ity. Although this is certainly not on the surface a
semiotic analytical framework, broadly and flex- startling thesis, and in fact is a core thesis of cultural
ibly understood, be helpful for cultural psychology? psychology, Peirce’s actual derivation of and devel-
How far can we push meaning or semiosis down opment of it is. Peirce argued that the dimensions
into the perceptual, actional, and affective stratum, of consciousness are correlated with his fundamen-
and how much are semiosic processes at the higher tal and well-known triadic differentiation of signs
levels characterized and conditioned by structures of into icons, indexes, and symbols. Consciousness
semiotic (and other forms of ) embodiment already exemplifies, and exists in, three different semiotic
limned on the lower levels? If the mind is, to repeat modes, corresponding to iconicity, indexicality, and
Peirce’s formulation, a sign developing accord- symbolicity. Iconicity is the semiotic mode that is
ing to the laws of inference and is, according to based on resemblance and is, on Peirce’s account,
Peirce’s rich and illuminating metaphor, a plenum exemplified by sign systems composed of images,
or “bottomless lake,” how are we to model this field metaphors, and diagrams, to each of which Peirce
of consciousness? Where are we to draw the lines devoted clear and stimulating analyses. Indexicality
through this plenum so that the significant joints is the semiotic mode that is based on existential
of consciousness would be differentiated and char- connection. It is exemplified by all species of signs
acterized? And what is the exact role of a semiotic that point, be it fingers, directions of the eyes, sign
approach to accomplishing this task? Does semi- posts, tracks in the snow, symptoms of disease, per-
otics itself point to a kind of limit to what could sonal and relative pronouns, definite articles, and
be called the “principle of effability”—that is, that so forth. Symbolicity is the semiotic mode that is
experience is best characterized as a semiotic pro- based on convention or law. It is exemplified par
cess? Or is recognition of such a limit actually an excellence by language and mathematical and other
unexpected enrichment of the semiotic framework? notation systems that have a full degree of semiotic
Indeed, more generally, which semiotic approaches freedom and openness. Peirce engaged in multiple
are we to use, either exclusively or predominantly, taxonomic and schematic characterizations of these

in n is 257
sign types with their attendant subdivisions. These already works with: that resemblances are not just,
sign types are semiotic frames within which and by in certain instances, “given” but rather “taken.” To
means of which we give meaning to the world. They see a resemblance on the basis of shared qualities—
are, looked at another way, “access structures” in especially of domains seemingly distant from one
which we are embodied and by means of which we another—is to perform an interpretive and semiotic
articulate the world and express it in signs. act. It is an activity that is both spontaneous and
On the side of their psychological instantia- methodically pursued. A Peircean semiotics would
tion, Peirce points out that the general schematiza- point a part of cultural psychology’s research agenda
tion of sign types into icons, indexes, and symbols to the study of the variability of image formation,
corresponds to feeling, reaction, and synthesis or, of different metaphorical networks, and of the vary-
more generally, habit-taking. These are the three ing conditions in which diagrammatic expressions
fundamental—indeed ultimate—ingredients of and forms of argumentation have developed. To the
consciousness, although they are not elements semiotic phenomenology of the internal content
in any Humean sense, as Peirce’s commitment to of these forms and their historical development,
synechism involved holding to a principle of conti- for which Peirce supplied the foundation, cultural
nuity. They are the psychological side of the semi- psychology would add a genetic and explicitly
otic frames within which consciousness functions. socio-cultural dimension. Semiotics and cultural
A feeling, on Peirce’s account, is an immediate psychology work hand-in-hand here.
consciousness of a quality, such as redness, bitter- As to the dimension of altersense, this is the
ness, the taste of quinine, or the odor of attar. It realm of indexes or indices. Indexicality takes two
is by means of feelings that we access the world in radically different forms: natural and conventional.
its suchness and do so without comparison. Peirce Natural indices belong to the most basic stratum of
illuminatingly called it “primisense,” exploiting the reading nature, of following traces, of determining
ambiguity of “sense” as both a power and a type of which traces and indications are pertinent. There is
meaning. A reaction is a felt sense of resistance, of great variability in this regard, as the anthropolo-
interruption, of a breaking into consciousness of gists have shown us. Eskimos read the traces of their
something other, such as running into a closed door (to us) minimally differentiated environments with
or being startled by a sudden whistle. Peirce cor- as much confidence as rain forest dwellers read the
respondingly calls this dimension of consciousness traces of their profuse environments. A Bedouin
“altersense.” Law or convention appears psycho- at home in a desert landscape sees differences that
logically as achieved synthesis or rational habit. The are imperceptible to the city dweller. Natural intel-
ability to take on differentiated sets of habits, and ligence on this level, or in this dimension, which
to control these habits, is the mark of rationality. includes animal and human spheres, is common to
Human life consists more and more of the rational all organisms. It is connected with sensory acuity
construction and reconstruction of habits, includ- and also with being hardwired to respond to sensory
ing on the lower threshold perceptual habits where cues by reason of the body that one has inherited
qualities and resistant particulars are synthesized or genetically. Ecological and environmental psychol-
mediated into unities. Peirce calls this dimension ogy, certainly components of a comprehensive cul-
of consciousness “medisense.’ It is important to tural psychology, must explore these domains in the
realize that for Peirce, these are simultaneous pres- company of a semiotically informed phenomenol-
ent dimensions of consciousness as such. But each ogy. But trained and habitualized natural intelli-
dimension can be foregrounded in different modes gence extends further out to indices that, although
of attending, which are themselves both embodied natural in one sense, are also culturally discerned
in, and enabled by, distinct sign systems. and maybe even determined. I am thinking here
In as much as “primisense” or quale consciousness specifically of such phenomena as the symptoms
explores the world through objectified and expressed of disease, slips of the tongue, inadvertent ges-
systems of resemblances, Peirce would instruct a tures, and so forth, that point beyond themselves
semiotically aware cultural psychology to explore to objects and states of affairs. Conventional indices
the cultural manifestations and variability of our encompass all the pointing signs of every sort that
sense of finding resemblances and capturing them we have constructed to steer us through the world,
in systems of iconic signs. Such a cultural psychol- including, clearly, language in its indexical dimen-
ogy would develop with new tools the notion that it sion. But, it could be said without exaggeration

258 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


that natural science in its technological side is also representamen used by every scientific intelligence
a way of capturing the signs of nature or even of in order that they may embody any meaning” (CP
provoking nature to emit signs. In this sense, natu- 2.229). Such a task is, on first glance, one of the
ral science would be a set of practices that attend to proper tasks of a general theory of signs. Looked
what is taken to be pertinent and would be subject at this way, on the grammatical or syntactic level,
to all the subjective factors that condition patterns semiotics is concerned with the internal constitu-
of attending. Once again, cultural psychology could tion of signs, their defining properties and relations
take another look at the history of science as a vari- to one another, and their essential differences. It
able set of patterns of attending to particulars and wants to determine the formal features of sign types
ascribing relevance to experienced linkages. How is and distinguish them, in terms of their intrinsic
this done? Why are some linkages made rather than properties, from one another. Cultural psychol-
others? To answer such questions, cultural psychol- ogy, taking these properties as given, would study
ogy would not only join forces with semiotics but the social and cultural conditions of how one learns
with the history of science and with psycho-analysis these systems of differences—that is, how they are
in the broadest sense. in themselves perceived and apprehended. It would
Medisense captures what is involved in the sym- also ask whether, by reason of our semiotic embodi-
bolic dimension of consciousness. It is the mark of ment in different sign types with different syntactic
human mentality as such, building as it does on the structures, we develop very different cognitive strat-
iconic and indexical dimensions. Indeed, the human egies and modes of thinking that influence how we
approach to the world is constituted by forms of access the world. Such an issue clearly bears upon
mediation all the way up, as consciousness builds the logical dimension of signs.
a more and more coherent and interlinked world The task of a semiotic logic is to determine the
and recognizes that it is doing so, a point argued with conditions that make it possible that representamina
great force by Deacon (1997). Peirce’s emphasis on “may hold good of any object, that is, may be true.
medisense is intended to foreground the abductive, Or say, logic proper is the formal science of the con-
interpretive dimension of consciousness and cogni- ditions of the truth of representations” (CP 2.229).
tion. It implies a kind of semiotic constructivism— Looked at this way, on the logical level, semiotics
that is, the thesis that the world is known through is concerned with the bases of the relations of signs
the interpretation and production of signs. And to their objects, not their syntactic or grammatical
these different systems, as formulated in objective differences from one another: resemblance in the
structures, lay variable networks of concepts over case of icons, existential connection in the case of
experience. Symbolic consciousness is, in this sense, indexes, convention in the case of symbols. These
motivated without being caused by an objective bases have psychological reality, but it is not the job
world putatively accessible outside of some sym- of semiotics to explore them. Rather, they are inter-
bolic scheme. For Peirce, the latter alternative is pretive frames to be used by cultural psychology in
simply not possible. There is no way, Peirce argues, its investigations of the variability of contents in
of accessing reality in a mind-independent or sign- the mental appropriation of the world in different
independent way, even if one asserts that there is a socio-cultural contexts. Cultural psychology would
mind-independent reality. So, in this way semiot- study, however, which iconic forms circulate in soci-
ics’ central idea coincides with the research project ety, which indexical signs intervene in and structure
of cultural psychology, which studies the subjective both the social and individual sensoria, and which
conditions and genesis of objective symbolic struc- symbols structure the life-world on its many levels.
tures. On this conception, the focal point of cultural In this, it would appear that once again, semiotics
psychology would be the genesis and development and cultural psychology, looked at through Peircean
of meanings in experience, whereas semiotics itself eyes, would work hand-in-hand (see Valsiner & van
would supply the formal frame for the analysis of der Veer, 2000)
the meanings of experience. The task of a semiotic rhetoric, according to Peirce,
Peirce distinguishes a grammatical, a logical, and is “to ascertain the laws by which in every scientific
a rhetorical dimension of the analysis of the signs, intelligence one sign gives birth to another, and
the representamina, that carry meaning. especially one thought brings forth another” (CP
The task of a semiotic grammar or syntax is, as 2.229). Looked at this way, semiotics is concerned
Peirce puts it, to “ascertain what must be true of the with the relation of signs to their users, whether

in n is 259
producers or receivers. On the objective side, semi- is a continuum, differently weighted at different
otics would study the forms of argumentation, the levels and stages, but with the same ingredients at
laws of birthing of ideas in the consciousness of oth- every level and stage. Feeling, reaction, and hab-
ers, whereas cultural psychology would attempt to its of synthesizing are, as Peirce puts it, “constant
situate these forms in distinctive matrices and situ- ingredients of our knowledge” and result from “con-
ations. A clear example of this, which also encom- genital tendencies of the mind” (CP 1.374). In one
passes the syntactic and logical sides, is Nisbett’s The sense, as Peirce formulates it in a kind of Scholastic
Geography of Thought (2003). It is evident that there mode, they can be understood as “three parts or
is an important linkage between the two disciplines faculties of the soul or modes of consciousness”
in this domain. (CP 1.374)—no matter what the level is or the cul-
Peirce’s semiotic project, consequently, presents tural matrix in which consciousness is embodied.
in an integrated way a set of conceptual tools, ana- Peirce summarizes the three categories of conscious-
lytical models, and heuristic pointers. But it not ness in the following compressed text:
just the well-known triadic schemata of (1) feeling,
. . . first, feeling, the consciousness that can
reaction, and synthesis; (2) icon, index, and sym-
be included with an instant of time, passive
bol; or (3) syntactic, semantic, and rhetorical that
consciousness of quality, without recognition of
characterize Peirce’s project and set the tasks for a
analysis; second, consciousness of an interruption
developed semiotic theory that would supply the
into the field of consciousness, sense of resistance,
linkage to cultural psychology. Peirce points out
of an external fact, of another something; third,
that to understand what is involved in any achieved
synthetic consciousness, binding time together, sense
act or process of semiosis, or meaning-making, there
of learning, thought.
are five factors that have to be considered. (1) Signs
(CP 1.377)
make their (2) objects known through their proper
significant effects—that is, their (3) interpretants, to The three categories, according to Peirce, are com-
or in an (4) interpreter, and they do so, as Peirce puts prehensive and exclusive, characterizing indubitably
it, (5) “not in all respects, but in reference to a sort “three radically different elements of consciousness,
of idea, which I have sometimes called the ground of these and no more” (CP 1.382): immediate feeling,
the representamen” (CP 2.228). Peirce understands the polar sense, and synthetical consciousness (“the
this notion “in a sort of Platonic sense, very famil- consciousness of a third or medium” [CP 1.382]).
iar in everyday talk” (CP 2.228) It appears to be If we agree, as I have proposed, to call the lower
introduced to maintain continuity of reference of threshold the “affective-actional-perceptual thresh-
a thought at different times. But it is also clearly old” and the upper threshold the “symbolic thresh-
meant to point out the aspectival dimension of a old,” I think we can see that on Peircean terms, they
sign’s relation to its object or to a cluster of back- are both intrinsically semiotic and can be modeled
ground conditions for a successful semiosis. in the same way. Affective-actional-perceptual con-
sciousness instantiates the categories of semiosis just
The Semiosphere as much as explicitly cultural consciousness does.
An important thing to note is that Peirce’s com- An object on this level for Peirce is composed of
plex model, with its differentiation of sign types, a first—a qualitative suchness—and a second—an
its specification of ingredients of consciousness, its undergone set of resisting particulars—joined into
delineation of the factors of semiosis, applies not a whole by means of a third—a synthetic, indeed
just to the upper threshold of semiosis, where we are synthesizing, lawfulness or habit. Such an object is
dealing with objectively circulating systems of signs a configuration of iconic/qualitative, indexical/reac-
that make up the cultural order or what Lotman tive, and symbolic/mediating moments. Perceptual
(1990) called the semiosphere. It also applies to objects are emergent from a field of qualitative char-
the lower threshold, where the feeling, acting, and acters and indexical particulars synthesized by the
perceiving organism first starts to draw the lines in interpreter or knowing subject. For Peirce, quite
the continuum of experience. This is of the utmost generally, “every kind of consciousness enters into
importance for understanding the emergence of cognition” (CP 1.381). Although, as Peirce puts it,
meaning and the variable and culturally defined feelings “form the warp and woof of cognition,” and
situations in which it occurs, which is the main con- although the will, in the form of attention (to the
cern of cultural psychology. For Peirce, cognition other), constantly enters, perceptual consciousness,

260 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


when it is carried to completion, is neither feeling nor expenditure of energy and effort, an attending to
the polar sense. It is “consciousness of process, and the other in some way or the other; or (3) a concept
this in the form of the sense of learning, of acquir- or idea, something belonging to the logical order of
ing, of mental growth.” It cannot be immediate for mediations. But rather than looking at them as dis-
it cannot be “contracted into an instant.” It is “the tinct, Peircean semiotics would instruct us to look
consciousness that binds our life together. It is the at them as dimensions of meaning of signs with dif-
consciousness of synthesis” (CP 1.381)—or, rather, ferential weightings in different contexts and situa-
synthetic consciousness. A semiotically informed tions. The peculiarity and richness of Peirce’s model
cultural psychology then would explore the whole of semiotics and of semiosis is that these types of
culturally variable configurations and panoplies of interpretants allow us to access the realm of mean-
feelings, of forms of attention to the other and of ings in both a structured and a phenomenologically
symbolic construals. It is not reducible to cognitive open way. Once again, they tell us what to look for,
psychology in any restricted sense. It is extended to but they do not tell us what we will find.
ways of world-making, where the various worlds are In this way, a Peircean approach to understand-
not defined in purely conceptual terms but in terms ing the semiotic subject, the socio-psychological
of different types of sign configurations and mean- side that is the theme of cultural psychology, by
ing structures. using the typology of signs and their significant
So, the affective-actional-perceptual field and the effects as an access structure to the perceptual field
cultural field, characterized by objectively circulat- in particular—a unity of feeling, reaction, and syn-
ing sign systems, are informed by the three semiotic thesis or qualities, resistances, and unities—allows
modalities and are not to be thought of in terms of us to model the field of consciousness, also on the
a polar opposition between reified lower and higher higher level, generally both in its individual and
levels. The same elements or ingredients are pres- social dimensions. The objective field of signs, in
ent on all levels, although they may be differently which we are embodied and which circulate extra-
weighted or foregrounded in any specific instance and intrapsychically, becomes an access structure
of accessing the world. Icons, as objective signs, to both the inner and the outer world. Between
are the firstnesses of thirdness, indexes the second- these two worlds there is no divide in principle, as
nesses of thirdness, and symbols the thirdnesses of Peirce argued in his early 1868 papers with their
thirdness. This is the foundation of Deacon’s (1997) powerful attack on introspection and unmediated
core insight into the distinctiveness of the symbolic intuition of one’s mental states. Access to oneself is
species. always mediated just as access to the world of the
This introduces a real complexity into the tasks of non-self is always mediated. The semiotic self (see
a cultural psychology that is fine-grained and phe- Wiley, 1994) quite generally is a sign developing
nomenologically acute: it must oscillate between the on the three levels of feelings, reactions/resistances,
low and the high. It also implies, on the human level, and mediating syntheses. And the access to the
that the symbolic field, or more generally thirdness world for this semiotic self is through the forms of
or mediation, enters into and permeates the spheres sense charted in the great typology of signs. Peircean
of feeling and action. The semiotic subject—that semiotics, in this way, intersects with and offers
is, the semiotic self that is the object of a cultural analytical tools to cultural psychology and indeed
psychology—is, according to the Peircean model, a would offer us a way to interpret, and maybe to
three-dimensional or three-layered self-assembling and, re-interpret, the results of cultural psychology—at
on the reflexive level, self-interpreting field. least in some respects. Knowing the world involves
Indeed, corresponding to the stratification of concrete processes of sign production and sign
the interpreter, or semiotic self, is, looking back at interpretation, being caught up in a play of infer-
the factors of semiosis, the stratification of types ence, being embodied in one’s speculative instru-
of interpretants that qualify this subject. Peirce’s ments, which, in the Peircean case, correspond to
revolutionary insight is that a sign or a sign con- the great division of signs into icons, indices, and
figuration gives rise to proper significant effects in symbols. They are, as the ultimate frames of all sys-
sign users. Interpretants are the meanings of signs tems of expressions, objective trajectories, vectors,
or sign configurations. But, as Peircean semiotics or carriers of consciousness, with their own differ-
claims, the meaning of a sign can be (1) an emo- entiated and historically emergent internal logics
tion, feeling, or affect; (2) a pattern of actions, an and grammars.

in n is 261
The heuristic fertility of the Peircean semi- Objects and states of
otic categorical scheme, which is indeed power- (Gegenstände und Sachverhalte)
ful, does not by any means, however, exhaust the Representation
possible substantial contribution of semiotics to
Expression (Darstellung)
the tasks of a cultural psychology. Other semiotic (Ausdruck)
or semiotically relevant thematizations of the field Appeal
of consciousness lay rather different grids over the (Appell)
phenomena of consciousness in general and in so
doing deepen, broaden, and refocus the problem of Sender Receiver
(Sender) (Empfänger)
the nature of the ultimate distinctions to be drawn
in the plenum of consciousness as such and whether
these are universal or culturally determined. They
Figure 12.1 Bühler’s Organon Model of Language
help us delineate in more detail the groundlines of
the psychological side of the play of signs in human
life. They also illustrate in their own way the big
philosophical precision. And, indeed, Bühler him-
tent character of semiotics and force us to recognize
self attempted to generalize his schema.
that all semiotic models, or models with intrinsic
Bühler, with no advertence to Peirce’s delinea-
semiotic importance, are pragmatic. Semiotics is
tion of the five factors of semiosis, has diagrammed
part of a comprehensive toolbox for analyzing the
the fundamental features of the focal semiosic event
construction of meanings, but it is not some super-
in the following way, exemplified (see figure 12.1)
science that tells us beforehand all that we can, or
in the case of language:
should, know.
The circle/triangle in the middle of the diagram
stands for the sign event in its material and formal
The Situation of Language
reality. It is important to recognize this duality: the
This is illustrated by another close link between
sign event has a concrete side as well as an abstract
semiotics and the tasks of a cultural psychology, to
side. Bühler’s schema charts the realm encompassed
be found in the alternative schematization of a semi-
by Peirce’s five factors, but with some interesting
osic event, the focal point of semiotics, proposed by
and crucial differences, including a factor that does
the great German psychologist of language, Karl
not appear in the schema but that is nevertheless of
Bühler, whose masterwork Theory of Language is
crucial importance for cultural psychology. Bühler,
a classic exemplification of the fusion of semiotic,
for his part, explains his diagram in the following
philosophical, and psychological themes (Bühler,
manner, into which I have interpolated in brack-
1934/1965). Here, we find heuristic clues directed
ets a translational gloss to generalize the schema
toward cultural psychology that originate not from
beyond the purely linguistic level. Looked at this
the philosophical side of semiotics, as Peirce’s does,
way, it becomes evident that other issues than those
but from the psychological side itself.
dealt with by Peirce are introduced or, at least, made
Bühler formulated his schema, which he called
more explicit and given a different weight. Bühler
the “organon model” of language, with explicit
writes:
semiotic (or, as he called it, sematological) intent
but without the recourse to metaphysical cat- The circle in the middle symbolizes the concrete
egories, or philosophical taxonomy, that marked acoustic phenomenon [sign-configuration or sign-
Peirce’s approach. Nevertheless, although it high- event]. Three variable factors in it go to give it the
lights a slightly different pattern of relations than rank of a sign in three different manners. The sides of
the Peircean schema, it still shows that explicitly the inscribed triangle symbolize these three factors. In
semiotic categories are both helpful and neces- one way the triangle encloses less than the circle (thus
sary for modeling the groundlines of the field of illustrating the principle of abstractive relevance).
consciousness in the broadest sense and for estab- In another way it goes beyond the circle to indicate
lishing the basic outlines of the cognitional struc- that what is given to the senses always receives
ture that is to be filled in by a comprehensive and an apperceptive complement. The parallel lines
methodologically self-aware cultural psychology. It symbolize the semantic functions of the (complex)
is especially important because Bühler’s work was language sign [sign-configuration]. It is a symbol by
marked by both methodological sophistication and virtue of its coordination to objects and states of

262 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


affairs, a symptom (Anzeichen, indicium: index) by reveal forms of subjectivity, willingly or unwill-
virtue of its dependence on the sender, whose inner ingly—a point Langer made a centerpiece of her
states it expresses, and a signal by virtue of its appeal theory of art (see Langer, 1953). But these features
to the hearer, whose inner or outer behaviour its can be coded and socially shared. And hence they
directs as do other communicative signs. are subject to comprehensive analysis by a fusion of
(Bühler, 1934, p. 35) semiotic and cultural psychological investigations.
Forms of expressed subjectivity are social forms,
It is clear that the coordination of a sign configu-
as the American pragmatist philosopher and social
ration to objects and states of affairs, which Bühler
psychologist G. H. Mead showed, not private pos-
assigns to the symbol, is accomplished in three ways:
sessions of an isolated epistemological or psycho-
iconically, indexically, and symbolically. All three
logical subject. Cultures embody and are shaped
forms of such coordination are exemplified in lan-
by these forms. They can be studied and compared
guage. For Bühler, they are all semiotic modes of
from culture to culture.
representation, a term shared by Bühler and Peirce,
As to the sign configuration’s relation to the
and the proper logical work of a sign or sign con-
receiver of the sign, this is the locus of what Bühler
figuration. These modes are differentiated (as has
called the appellative function or Peirce’s rhetorical
been noted) by Peirce according to their different
dimension. The goal here is to steer the receiver, first
bases for the coordination: resemblance for iconic-
in terms of behavior, in specific directions, giving rise
ity, existential connection for indexicality, and con-
to Peirce’s energetic interpretant. But in an impor-
vention for symbolicity. But for Bühler, they are all
tant way, Bühler is also pointing to Peirce’s affective
modes of representation in being directed toward
interpretant, to the informing of the subjectivity of
an objective world. Representation, which Durst-
the receiver in terms of affective qualities. And, fur-
Andersen (2009) generalizes to modeling, occurs
ther, he is pointing to the sharing of an objective
in three modes when we orient ourselves to objects
orientation to objects and states of affairs. The goal
and states of affairs.
of the appellative function is, therefore, also able to
The relation of the sign or sign configuration to
guide the perceptual and conceptual orientations of
the sender or utterer of the linguistic sign configu-
the receiver, provided that he or she shares the same
ration, however, is not analyzed by Bühler accord-
situation with the speaker.
ing to a private intention. This is very important
Bühler rightly emphasizes that these three
for cultural psychology. Rather, Bühler thinks of the
notions—representation, expression, and appeal—
sign configuration as having moments, objectively
are semantic concepts. Although he admits the rela-
discernible moments, that reveal the subjective atti-
tive dominance of the representational function of
tudes and orientations of the speaker—who does not
language for humans (confirmed and argued for, as
have to be an identifiable individual. These moments
I have already indicated, with neurological detail
belong to social forms. The moments are read off of
and in Peircean terms by Deacon), Bühler is very
the objective semiosic event, not the private subjec-
clear that the relation to objects and states of affairs
tivity of the speaker, which is nevertheless embodied
“does not capture everything for which the sound is
in them. In fact, the speaker utilizes them—and
a mediating phenomenon, a mediator between the
in creative circumstances modifies them or creates
speaker and the hearer” (1934, p. 37). Bühler then
novel moments. Peirce, in another context, speaks
adds a comment that I think bears upon Peirce’s
of the “material quality” of any sign configuration,
murky notion of a ground, upon which cultural
what I would call its “distinctive feel.” This qual-
psychology could certainly throw some empirically
ity is intrinsically joined to the sign configuration’s
derived light. Bühler, as a psychologist of language,
objectively experienced properties, which are social
speaks of a “speech situation,” a notion that can be
facts. To take an example, Bühler remarks that
generalized. He points out that
although the “chalk marks drawn by mathemati-
cians and logicians on the blackboard still contain . . . each of the two participants has his own position
an expressive residue,” tracing the degree of effort, in the make-up of the speech situation, namely the
the carefulness of execution, the clarity of material sender as the agent of the act of speaking, as the
formulation, the lyric poet’s poem or constructed subject of the speech action on the one hand, and the
utterance offers “a richer yield” of expressive fea- receiver as the one spoken to, as the addressee of the
tures. The kinds of expressive features of an utter- speech action on the other hand. They are not simply
ance, or of an objectively accessible sign event, a part of what the message is about, rather they are

in n is 263
the partners in an exchange, and ultimately this is the Die Krise der Psychologie (1927), to use these three
reason why it is possible that the sound as a medial semantic functions to model the whole realm
product has a specific significative relationship to of perceptions and indeed to distinguish three
each, to the one and to the other severally. autonomous, but related, types of psychology:
(1934, pp. 37–38) an experiential psychology, a behavioral psychol-
ogy, and a cultural psychology. So, there is also a
Generalizing, it not just speech or language as a
Bühlerian triad, with a slightly different twist than
medial event but any sign configuration whatsoever
Peirce’s: experience, behavior, and objective form.
that is at issue.
The focal thesis proposed by Bühler is that the
In any speech situation, or situation of the pro-
three sense-functions exemplified in the sign types
duction and exchange of signs, any one of the three
of symptom/indices, signals, and symbols can be
relationships can have dominance and be in the
used to give a theoretical account of perceptions
foreground, although Roman Jakobson (1960) later
[Wahrnehmungen] quite generally—admittedly a
expanded the relationships to six (adding the poetic,
rather wide notion (1927, p. 75). The psychology
phatic, and metalingual functions to Bühler’s origi-
of experience deals with indices, the psychology of
nal three). Let us avoid these complications in the
behavior deals with signals, and cultural psychology
current context and consider Bühler’s thesis:
deals with symbols. Accordingly, Sinnesdaten—what
. . . each of the three relationships, each of the three is given in the experiential field—perform three
semantic functions of language signs discloses and different semantic functions in structuring human
identifies a specific realm of linguistic phenomena intercourse with both the natural and the social
and facts . . . .’Expression in language’ and ‘appeal world. As indices [Anzeichen], certain phenomena
in language’ are partial objects for all of language indicate both the properties of objects and the inte-
research, and thus display their own specific riority of associated subjects, founding the perceptual
structures in comparison with representation judgment [Wahrnehmungschluss] whose content is
in language. To put it briefly, lyric poetry and a Sachverhalt or state of affairs in both the exter-
rhetoric have something specific to themselves that nal common world and in the world of interiority.
distinguishes them from epic poetry and drama; and Bühler will locate psycho-analysis in the indexical
their structural laws are even more obviously different dimension. As signals, the “given” sign configura-
from the structural law of scientific representation. tions elicit and steer the behavior or action of sub-
(1934, p. 39) jects in shared actional and pragmatically oriented
situations or fields, where there is a sender and a
A complete semiotics would thematize these struc-
receiver, who do not have to be thematically inten-
tural laws both generally and, in the hermeneutic
tional agents. As symbols, the sign configurations can
mode, in particular instances. It would extend an
be iconic (abbildend) or signifying through existen-
analysis in terms of semantic functions to the whole
tial connection or conventionally—that is, through
realm of cultural phenomena, not all of which
symbolizing or objectively indicating. In this way
clearly have to realize all of them. It would investi-
they represent, or point to, objects, structures, and
gate the many objective features such structural laws
relational complexes, eliciting (releasing) and steer-
display or manifest. Cultural psychology’s approach
ing recreative (nachschaffen) acts of reading, inter-
not just to language but to cultural phenomena
preting, and understanding.
quite generally would have to attend to all the ways
According to Bühler, looked at from the part of
these three (or six, if we follow Jakobson) seman-
the subject, the play of signs in experience—both
tic relations are encoded. They are clearly socially
natural and social—releases and steers (1) percep-
defined and constituted. Indeed, the focus on the
tion in the broadest possible sense, (2) behavior,
situation of the speech event, or any semiosic event,
and (3) understanding. Bühler, writing as a philo-
injects a distinctive cultural element into it, an ele-
sophically informed psychologist, leads us to engage
ment that is dialogical to the core. In this respect,
in a semiotic framing of perception, behavior, and
Bühler’s investigations intersect with Bahktin’s work
symbolic understanding, all the while showing that
on the polyphonic nature of the verbal situation and
there is no radical gulf separating the lower and the
of verbal interaction, as Durst-Andersen has shown
higher thresholds on both the descriptive and oper-
(2009).
ative levels. Still, Bühler’s triad is not the Peircean
Bühler, in a way paralleling Peirce but without
triad of feeling, action, and mediating synthesis but
any reference to him, proposes in his prescient,

264 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


perception, behavior, and objective form. These adds a precision: “ ‘face’ and ‘descriptive features’
are clearly social forms, filled with cultural content are figurative names for two, not for one and the
and following culturally conditioned laws. Here same method of guaranteeing their diacritical
is another semiotic organizing device or heuristic function, for the ‘face’ in our sense belongs to the
schema for cultural psychology to work with. domain of Gestalten and the ‘descriptive features’
A further distinguishing feature of Bühler’s essentially belongs either completely or exten-
position that intersects with cultural psychology sively to the domain of ‘summative connections’
is its emphasis on diacrisis and on the principle of [Undverbindungen]” (p. 2).
abstractive relevance, two intertwined concepts that Phonology, for Bühler, is concerned with spe-
are of great importance in determining the “forms cific types of differential invariants, abstract types,
of sense,” the conditions of which, from the psy- that are present in the inexhaustible sound-fund
chological side, cultural psychology is concerned [Lautschatz] of a language. It is not the task of cul-
to establish. Bühler insightfully and astutely uses tural psychology, but of linguistics, to determine
the perception of a word-sign as a heuristic key these. But cultural psychology must acknowledge
to understanding not only perception and behav- the powers needed to grasp them and to look for
ior but the whole field of experience. The analysis, differential invariants in the cultural contexts of
analogous to but not identical with Peirce’s pro- experience. In the case of language, these invari-
posal, reveals something essential about the lower ants are ideal unities, single classes of sounds func-
threshold. This threshold is itself modeled accord- tioning as notae [Kennzeichen] in the sound-whole
ing to the constitution and perception of the lin- [Lautgestalt]. They are functional, not substantial,
guistic sign. Nevertheless, Bühler does not propose unities. This is a permanent insight of the structur-
that perceived objects or structures of behavior are alist tradition in semiotics deriving from Saussure,
language-like nor that the realm of objective forms an insight that Bühler willingly acknowledged.
be considered in themselves as language-like. Diacrisis, Bühler shows, aims at discriminating these
More specifically, Bühler instructs us to take functional unities and through them of grasping the
recourse here to the distinction between phones word as a sense-filled unity. Now it is precisely sense-
and phonemes, a distinction that is well-known filled unities of all sorts and at all levels of complex-
in linguistic circles and was much discussed at the ity that a culturally informed psychology shares with
time he was writing. It is, in my opinion, of funda- semiotics as its subject matter. Cultural psychology
mental and permanent importance for understand- thematizes the individual and social conditions
ing or schematizing cognitive forms with the help of emergence and interiorization of these uni-
of semiotic categories. Phones are material enti- ties, whereas semiotics discovers and analyzes their
ties; phonemes are formal entities, systems of sig- “logic” and their “content.” But these two tasks are
nificant differences immanent in the phonic reality. not in opposition and, in fact, could be thought of
This commonplace distinction, Bühler insightfully as two sides of a coin, despite clear methodological
claims, points to specific perceptual powers that we contrasts and demands.
have. Bühler remarks: Out of this notion of “recognizing differences
that make a difference” (an anticipation of the work
Phonemes are sound-marks in the word’s tonal
of Gregory Bateson who made this idea a center-
reality and in every word they can be counted. But
piece of his own reflections), Bühler derives his
the word-image is also Gestalt-like, it has a tonal
principle of abstractive relevance, which has perma-
face or aspect, that also changes like a human face in
nent epistemological importance despite what looks
the changing course of the expressive or appellative
like a rather scholastic and analytic context. The
function.
notion has already appeared in Bühler’s explication
(Bühler, 1934, p. 258)
of his diagram of the organon-model of language.
Indeed, one can only agree with Bühler’s further Bühler writes:
comment that there is a remarkable “constancy
of the phonematic signaling of word-images in In the case of signs that bear a meaning, the situation
the course of their changing sound face” (p. 259). is such that the sensible thing, this perceptible
Their sound-form is a type that determines any something with which we are immediately dealing,
particular token of itself, a distinction that also is does not have to enter with the total plethora of
found in Peirce. In fact, to go a step further, Bühler its concrete properties into the semantic function.

in n is 265
Rather it can be the case that for it to fulfill its Therein lies the great chance for those who want to
function as a sign only certain specific abstract tackle anew the problem of abstraction as linguists,
moments are relevant. That, in the simplest words, is relying on the findings of phonology.
the principle of abstractive relevance. (1934, p. 288)
(Bühler, 1931, p. 38)
Bühler is certainly right that the phenomenon
The heuristic rule Bühler issues to cultural of abstraction as a cognitive achievement lies at
psychology is to study systems of relevance in all the core of semiosis, understood as a process giv-
meaning-bearing situations. Different cultural ing rise to abstractions—that is, products existing
frames perform different acts of abstraction, tak- in objective form. It is these objective forms, and
ing different abstract moments as relevant. The not just in the format of language, that semiotics,
sensible thing that Bühler so laconically mentions oriented toward the description of sign types and
can be a whole intricated socio-cultural situation their contents, studies for the most part, whereas
or cultural context: meaning systems of every sort the psychological side in its empirical detail and
and scale. Cultural psychology, then, looked at levels is the focal point of psychology. The ques-
from the point of view of a semiotics inspired by tion semiotics would put to cultural psychology is:
Bühlerian elements, is concerned with systems of What are the social and cultural matrices that con-
pertinence and not with descriptions of the way dition a tergo—that is, from behind, the processes
the world is independently of its being taken. In of abstraction and what influences do the actual
this the interests of cultural psychology and semi- abstractions that one is assimilated into have on
otics coincide, and once again, cultural psychol- the psychological conditions of abstraction itself?
ogy will supply empirical content to an analytic Bühler himself, in this context, is pointing down-
frame that will be a part of cultural psychology but ward toward the lower threshold that in his opinion
clearly not the whole of it. Cultural psychology is is already semiotically rich and to which language is
more fine-grained on the conditions of realization not related as a veneer. The situation is quite differ-
side than semiotics, which supplies a kind of upper ent. Bühler writes:
analytical blade to the conceptual armature of cul-
tural psychology. The linguistic fixating and grasping of perceived
It should be noted, then, that Bühler’s sugges- states of affairs is prepared and rooted in the
tion allows us to use the perception of language and processes we are accustomed to calling “perceptions”
linguistic unities as a heuristic tool for understand- and to separating off in an unjustifiably rigorous way
ing semiotic phenomena rather than using language from a “following” linguistic apprehension . . . The
itself as the primary model for understanding semi- orientational instrument of human language which
osis. Here is a ringing text in which Bühler issues a is produced in linguistic intercourse potentiates
challenge, from the psychological side, to a semiot- what the natural signals and symptoms accomplish,
ics of culture: which we in the process of perception derive from
things and our speech partners and to which we are
If linguists and language theorists today feel inspired indebted.
once again to essay forth from their own domain into (1934, p. 252)
the age-old dispute of the masters concerning the
problem of abstraction, they can give good reason for Nevertheless, Bühler’s pushdown to the lower
doing so. For the one who knows how to turn the old threshold also challenges or at least seems to modify
interest around, to turn the gaze of the abstraction Eco’s and Peirce’s thesis, but also his own, about
theorist away from the things that are being named the comprehensiveness of semiotic terminology
to the naming activity of the words themselves, to in the description of consciousness, whether indi-
the tonal structure, he gains a new chance for dealing vidual or social. Bühler saw the complexity of try-
with this issue. And he does so for the simple reason ing to balance semiotic with non-semiotic factors
that these structures are not only ready at hand in the description of consciousness. More specifi-
but also produced by the persons who know them. cally, Bühler thought that the Gestalt principle was
Indeed, they are produced precisely for this end by “phylogenetically originary” (Bühler 1960, p. 74).
every speaker of a language, so that his conversational Despite his deep commitment to an explicitly semi-
partner can recognize correctly each sound structure otic model for analyzing the groundlines of con-
for what it is and can distinguish it from others. sciousness, Bühler never gave up his adherence to

266 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


the validity of the concept of a whole. In his Die Bühler’s language theory is based on a fundamen-
Krise der Psychologie, he wrote: tal distinction between what he calls the Zeigfeld and
the Symbolfeld—that is, the deictic field, defined by
It is not correct to conflate the concepts of structure
pointing, and the symbol field, defined by articu-
[Struktur], sense [Sinn], and value [Wert]. The
lating or conceptual grasping. The general notion
concept of a whole [der Begriff der Ganzheit] with
is that language frees itself from indexicality as it
its constitutive moments is the widest concept and
heads toward and is transformed by symbolicity.
to it is ordered knowledge by insight. Intentionally
But Bühler writes:
produced wholes that are meaning structures . . .
can only be a restricted domain of structures quite Perhaps we overestimate the freeing from the deictic
generally. field; perhaps we underestimate the fact of the
(Bühler, 1927, p. 137) essential openness and the need, proper to every
Clearly there is no strict opposition posited between linguistic representation of a state of affairs, to be
wholes and meaning structures. Bühler is noting completed by our knowledge of this state of affairs.
here a peculiar tension between diacrisis on the Or, what is the same thing: perhaps there is an
basis of indexical properties and the grasp of struc- expansion of all linguistically constituted knowledge
ture or form on the basis of a perceptual apprehen- from a source that does not run in the channels
sion that does not rely on an explicit reading of of the linguistic symbol system and nevertheless
determining indices. In fact, perception is marked produces genuine knowledge.
by the emergence of structures as configurations (1934, p. 255)
from an irreducible parts/whole correlation. The This source is our material, or what Peirce called
whole is more than the sum of its parts, an emer- “collateral,” knowledge that is needed to make sense
gence, and in the case of produced meaning struc- of signs. Bühler calls it Sachwissen, knowledge of a
tures, there is an intrinsic duality between the domain, or material knowledge, knowledge of the
selectivity of pertinence, which involves elimina- thing meant. Is not one of the tasks of cultural psy-
tion of irrelevancies, and the emergence of nov- chology to explore this dimension of our knowing,
elty, which involves a kind of addition of meaning. which is certainly culturally relative and differen-
Bühler puts it this way, in a context where these tially distributed? It is the support of our under-
notions apply to language primarily in its meta- standing of signs, which do not make a closed circle
phorical dimension but can also be extended to from which there is no escape.
cultural systems of meaning. There is, however, another form of support of our
Overlapping, falling away, selection, the difference understanding that is more distinctively semiotic.
effect are expressions for one and the same simple Bühler asserts that the deictic field (Zeigfeld) and
phenomenon, which it is necessary to place beside the symbol field (Symbolfeld) are “the two sources
the criterion of Übersummativität, which alone has out of which in every case the precise interpreta-
been emphasized in Gestalt theory since the time tion of linguistic expressions is nourished” (1934,
of von Ehrenfels, in order to describe completely p. 149). Pointing and representing, not in them-
the role of attributive structures in language . . . selves but as semiotic systems (rather than isolated
Übersummativität and Untersummativität of acts), also supply collateral knowledge, but it comes
attributive structures increase the productivity from being embodied in a semiotic field. The gen-
of language to an astonishing degree and make eral point Bühler wants to make is that all semiosis,
possible a laconic form of naming. Admittedly, the and all the knowing effected by semiosis, is field-
system also has at its disposal a correction for the dependent. Signs must be situated or located in a
indefiniteness or ambiguities of these structures. surrounding field to do their work. This field is not
(Bühler, 1934, pp. 349–350) just a linguistic field. Bühler is making a general
semiotic point, which can, I think, be extended out
Where is this “correction” to be found? In to the whole realm of cultural analysis.
answering this question, Bühler introduces a most
important notion, that of Sachwissen, or material Thought that is expressed in speech, along with it
knowledge, which certainly belongs to the subject every other operation with representational symbols
matter of a cultural psychology, although it is intro- in the service of knowing, is in need of a symbol
duced in a specifically linguistic context. How so? field in exactly the same way as the painter needs

in n is 267
his painting surface, the cartographer his coordinate The background to Polanyi’s position, which
system of latitudinal and longitudinal lines, and the stands midway between semiotics and psychology,
composer his still-otherwise-constructed surface, or and its relevance to cultural psychology, is fore-
put in general terms, just as every two-class system of grounded in the following texts from Wolfgang
representational signs. Köhler, which still maintain their challenging posi-
(Bühler, 1934, p. 254) tion in our attempts to think through the problem
of the ultimacy of the semiotic project in general
The reference to a two-class system is central, exem-
and its relation to supplying analytical and episte-
plified in Bühler’s “dogma of lexicon and syntax,”
mological underpinnings to cultural psychology.
or sign unit and surrounding field of relations. Is
They concern, first of all, the schematization of
not cultural psychology dedicated to investigat-
the lower threshold but bear upon the possibility
ing the surrounding relational fields of meaning
and nature of a valid modeling of this threshold in
units, their genetic conditions on both the indi-
upper-threshold terms.
vidual and social levels, and the degrees and stages
Consider the following formulation of one of
in which they are learned? Does not a generaliza-
Köhler’s most challenging theses:
tion of Bühler’s insights help formulate in a laconic
manner just what cultural psychology can do and In Gestalt psychology we distinguish three major
is doing? traits which are conspicuous in all cases of specific
organization or gestalt. Phenomenally the world
Between Signification and Structure: is neither an indifferent mosaic nor an indifferent
Semiotic Relevance of Tacit Knowing continuum. It exhibits definite segregated units or
But can we take another look at the tension contexts in all degrees of complexity, articulation
between structure and signification to which Bühler and clearness. Secondly, such units show properties
draws attention? Is there a way to specify their rela- belonging to them as contexts or systems. Again, the
tions in more detail, this time from an epistemo- parts of such units or contexts exhibit dependent
logical position that has great semiotic relevance but properties in the sense that, given the place of a
was not developed within any of the major semiotic part in the context, its dependent properties are
traditions? Michael Polanyi’s theory of tacit know- determined by this position.
ing, which is based on a generalization of Gestalt (Köhler, 1938, p. 85)
theory, needs to be incorporated into any semiotic
model that strives to contribute to framing central Other relevant aspects and contexts are specified by
issues in cultural psychology and the model(s) of Köhler in his classic Gestalt Psychology:
mind that it both presupposes and tries to develop.
Gestalt psychology holds [that] sensory units have
It also adds some new insights and concepts that
acquired names, have become richly symbolic, and
bear upon other issues that lie immanent in Bühler’s
are now known to have certain practical uses, while
conceptual system.
nevertheless they have existed as units before any of
Philosophizing, as Bühler partially did, with the
these further facts were added. Gestalt psychology
tools of and against the background of Gestalt psy-
claims that it is precisely the original segregation of
chology, Polanyi offers us a way around the dichot-
circumscribed wholes which makes it possible for
omy between structure and meaning by means of
the sensory world to appear so utterly imbued with
his fruitful distinction between existential and rep-
meaning to the adult; for, in the gradual entrance
resentative meanings and wholes. He further specifies
into the sensory field, meaning follows the lines
how the recognizing of these wholes arises through
drawn by natural organization; it usually enters into
tacit, not explicit, processes and how his indispens-
segregated wholes.
able distinction between focal and subsidiary aware-
(Köhler, 1947, p. 82)
ness adds a new twist to our understanding of the
parallel ways we are embodied in or indwell sign The fundamental questions in this context are:
systems and meaning systems at both thresholds, Is the original segregation a semiotic process, and
including our indwelling in language, which he, what is the relation between the notion of a cir-
along with Ernst Cassirer, discuss in probal terms. cumscribed whole in all its varieties and a meaning?
The analogy of the probe is a rich image-schema of Are circumscribed wholes at the lower threshold
our relationship to and use of language as well as sign configurations or able to be analyzed as sign
other expression systems. configurations?

268 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


Polanyi introduces an indispensable set of con- about the issue of the relations between perception
cepts here that joins together in a creative unity and semiosis and about the thresholds of sense. On
the notion of structure with that of meaning. It Polanyi’s account, structure and meaning are not
is extraordinarily important for establishing a suf- opposed in principle, once we accept his fundamen-
ficiently rich and flexible model of cognitional tal distinction between the two kinds of awareness.
structure that would inform, frame, and support Most generally, his claim is that the genesis of mean-
the investigations of a cultural psychology. Polanyi ing is the genesis of ordered contexts. It seems to me
argues that in any grasp of, or construction of, a that this is a key insight to be followed up by cul-
“circumscribed whole,” we attend from certain tural psychology as well as by a genetically oriented
things, which include our bodies, while we attend to semiotics and philosophy of knowledge. The kind
the whole. In Polanyi’s terminology, we are subsid- of meaning denoted by “existential” is “meaning as
iarily aware of the particulars of any whole while object,” or more generally, “meaning as ordered con-
we are focally aware of the whole. Now, more gen- text,” which can be a self-enclosed world. A physical
erally, Polanyi points out that “when something is object, in as much as it is a coherence, is a meaning,
seen as subsidiary to a whole, this implies that it on this account. It does not just have a meaning
participates in sustaining the whole, and we may projected onto it. It is a resisting experienced sense-
now regard this function as its meaning, within filled unity. It is suffused by a distinctive quality or
the whole” (Polanyi, 1958a, p. 58). The subsid- suchness, marked by its indexically functioning
iary particular is a kind of semiotic vector that is particulars, and integrated by a mediating act. Such
not independent of, although clearly not identical a characterization corresponds to Peirce’s distinc-
with, what it means. Polanyi, in a deep and pene- tions, which we discussed earlier, and which Peirce
trating passage, distinguishes in Personal Knowledge also labeled as primisense, altersense, medisense,
two kinds of wholes and two kinds of meanings: the three indispensable and ever-present factors or
an explicit sign/object whole and the kinds of wholes ingredients in cognition. Systems of contrived order
exemplified by physiognomies, tunes, and patterns. such as sign systems are themselves ordered wholes,
Here is an important link with Bühler and Köhler. which in addition to being internally structured,
Polanyi writes: with their own internal objects, inform us about,
or refer to, objects and states of affairs that are in a
The distinction between two kinds of awareness real sense “independently objective.” On Polanyi’s
allows us readily to acknowledge these two kinds of account, thing meaning and sign meaning are both
wholes and two kinds of meaning. Remembering at one and the same time autonomous and related
the various uses of a stick, for pointing, for exploring forms of meaning. The thing meant, even whole
or for hitting, we can easily see that anything cultural orders such as mythic and aesthetic worlds,
that functions effectively within an accredited does not have to exist outside of the frame, but there
context has a meaning in that context and that is no thing meant independent of some frame. The
any such context will itself be appreciated as point is to determine, both directly and reflectively,
meaningful. We may describe the kind of meaning the frames. This process of determining is first and
which a context possesses in itself as existential, to foremost active and constructive, whereas the pro-
distinguish it especially from denotative or, more cess of analyzing the internal logic of these culturally
generally, representative meaning. In this sense pure specific frames is both empirical and interpretive.
mathematics has an existential meaning, while a Polanyi draws an ontological consequence
mathematical theory in physics has a denotative from these considerations, just as Peirce did,
meaning. The meaning of music is mainly existential, something that perhaps a pure semiotics, focus-
that of a portrait more or less representative, and so ing on the internal structures of meaning systems,
on. All kinds of order, whether contrived or natural, and a philosophically pure cultural psychology
has existential meaning; but contrived order usually would hesitate to do. Consider the following text
also conveys a message. of Polanyi:
(Polanyi, 1958a, p. 58)
Since tacit knowing establishes a meaningful
Although this admittedly controversial passage relation between two terms, we may identify it
needs some unpacking and refining, and maybe with the understanding of the comprehensive entity
even reformulation in places, it contains funda- which these two terms jointly constitute. Thus,
mental insights about the nature of meaning and the proximal term represents the particulars of

in n is 269
this entity, and we can say, accordingly, that we Consider the following passage and its range of
comprehend the entity by relying on our awareness examples:
of its particulars for attending to their joint
meaning. We may instantly recognize a familiar writing or
(Polanyi, 1966, p. 13) voice, or a person’s gait, or a well-cooked omelette,
while being unable to tell—except quite vaguely—by
The joint meaning is an emergence, an instance what particulars we recognize these things. The
of Peircean thirdness or Bühlerian-Ehrenfeldian same is true of the recognition of pathological
Übersummativität, which could take numerous symptoms, of the diagnosis of diseases and the
different forms: affective in the case of feelings, identification of specimens. In all these instances we
actional in the case of goal-directed behavior, learn to comprehend an entity without ever getting
and conceptual in the case of language and other to know, or to know clearly, the particulars that are
constructed systems. However, one of the deep- unspecifiable because they are unknown.
est and most fateful consequences of the notion (Polanyi, 1958b, p. 45)
of attending from is its extension to how we are
conscious of our bodies and the consequent notion This is the way we are assimilated into cultural
of indwelling, Polanyi’s term that refers to the same forms, through apprenticeship and practice, on
phenomenon that embodiment does in the phe- both technical and popular levels. An important
nomenological tradition. Polanyi writes in The qualification follows:
Tacit Dimension: But a particular pointing beyond itself may be fully
All thought contains components of which we visible or audible and yet be unspecifiable in the
are subsidiarily aware in the focal content of our sense that if attention is directed on it focally—so
thinking, and all thought dwells in its subsidiaries, that it is now known in itself—it ceases to function
as if they were parts of our body. Hence thinking as a clue or a sign and loses its meaning as such.
is not only necessarily intentional, as Brentano has (Polanyi, 1958b, p. 45)
taught: it is also necessarily fraught with the roots it
Analysis alone does not give us access to the mate-
embodies. It has a from-to structure.
rial knowledge of the participants in a culture. They
(1966, p. x)
are participants first and foremost. Analysis come
Just as we dwell in our bodies, Polanyi, observes, so afterward. Primum vivere, deinde philosophari. Thus,
we dwell in all the subsidiary clues that we integrate Polanyi allows us to see how signs in experience and
or synthesize into comprehensive wholes. The anal- the experience of signs are not contrasted in any
ogy of the probe is, then, extended to language— principled way to one another, once we can distin-
and I would add to all cultural forms. “We can, guish between dwelling in and analyzing. Even tacit
accordingly, interpret the use of tools, of probes, knowledge relies on an interpretation of signs, but
and of pointers as further instances of the art of an interpretation that avoids the cognitive stance
knowing, and may add to our list also the deno- ascribed to the epistemological subject. Knowing,
tative use of language, as a kind of verbal point- as John Dewey put it, is not a “Kodak fixation” nor
ing” (1966, p. 7). The extension here is: Cultural is the mind a kind of “mental carbon paper.”
forms are embodiments of the art of knowing. This Polanyi’s notion of indwelling, which certainly
essentially cultural process of integration or synthe- modifies our picture of the knowing subject, allows
sis of fields of particulars into meaningful wholes, us to understand what it means, quite generally, to
Polanyi argues—and in my opinion has shown—is be embodied in sign systems and also, from a totally
essentially tacit. It is also not something over which different angle, shows us what unlimited semiosis
we have control and so it does not involve thematic entails: We are inside the play of signs and never
reading of signs, although we are clearly often pre- outside. There is no explicit greatest upper bound
sented with sign configurations that demand stren- from which we can survey the total range of experi-
uous interpretive effort. Polanyi’s model of tacit ence. Read the following passage from the preface
knowing shows, I think, that thinking of experi- to Polanyi’s Personal Knowledge, which talks about a
ence itself in semiotic terms does not entail pos- post-critical philosophy and not an a-critical philos-
tulating an explicitly cognitive relationship to the ophy, in light of what I have just said and with the
continuum or plenum of experience, into which we appropriate interpolation of semiotic terms along-
are drawing lines. side Polanyi’s own terminology.

270 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


I regard knowing [semiosis] as an active Forms of Sense and the Mind of Feeling:
comprehension [signifying] of the things known Cassirer and Langer
[meant], an action that requires skill. Skilful In his Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Cassirer
knowing and doing [skilful sign-production and wrote that the “concept of consciousness seems to
interpretation] is performed by subordinating a set be the very Proteus of philosophy” (1929, p/ 48).
of particulars [signs and sign-configurations], as Certainly, it is also the same for a cultural psychol-
clues or tools, to the shaping of a skilful [semiosic] ogy that accepts the task of charting the contours
achievement, whether practical or theoretical. We of consciousness shaped in the course of cultural
may then be said to become “subsidiarily aware” interactions. The task Cassirer set for himself was to
of these particulars [signs and sign-configurations] uncover what he called “the original attitudes and
within our “focal awareness” of the coherent entity formative modes of consciousness”—that is, a kind
[object-domains] that we achieve [signify]. Clues of a priori structure within which meanings are con-
and tools [signs and sign-configurations] are things stituted and expressed. Cassirer described his goal,
used as such and not observed in themselves. echoing but transforming the static schema of Kant,
They are made to function as extensions of our as an attempt to resolve “the question of the structure
bodily equipment [mental equipment] and this of the perceptive, intuitive and cognitive conscious-
involves a certain change in our own being. Acts of ness” (1929, p. 57), from which arise the “three form
comprehension [acts of semiosis] are to this extent worlds” (1929, p. 448) that constitute progressively
irreversible, and also non-critical. For we cannot more objectifying relations to the world. These form
possess any fixed framework within which the worlds make up the ultimate frame of sense-giving
reshaping of our hitherto fixed framework could be and sense-reading. The distinctiveness of Cassirer’s
critically tested. project is that it is also based on a tripartite semiotic
(Polanyi, 1958a, p. vii) schema that, like Peirce’s, does not just refer to suc-
cessive phases of a process of knowing and mean-
This rotation of our problem adds new descrip- ing-making but to “its necessarily intertwined . . .
tive and explanatory categories to semiotics and constitutive factors” (1929, p. 9), what Peirce called
exemplifies, once again, the big tent, non-dog- the “permanent ingredients” of consciousness. It
matic, and non-overreaching nature of semiotics also gestures toward a kind of teleology and hier-
as an analytical framework and transdisciplinary archization, as if perception, intuition, and cogni-
project. As to the tasks of a cultural psychology, it tion were phases in a process. The distinctiveness of
points to a host of analytical and descriptive tasks: Cassirer’s procedure, however, mainly results from
to recognize and validate the tacit dimension— its correlation of these factors with three different
that is, that we can know more than we can say, semiotic categories or sense functions. Indeed, they
to show that knowing and skillful doing have the are, in reality, not so much phases as dimensions.
same logical structure, and that the body, includ- The form worlds, defined by the three sense func-
ing our exosomatic or semiotic body, is an essential tions, are the ultimate frames or matrices of sense-
component of all knowing, which is not a matter giving and sense-reading, which for Cassirer are by
of the head alone. It also suggests that the from–to no means restricted to the explicit and thematic use
structure of awareness is actually isomorphic with, of signs.
while still enriching, the sign–interpretant–object Cassirer correlated the psychological and philo-
triad foregrounded by Peirce and that the lines sophical term perception [Wahrnehmung] with the
that divide up the continuum of experience can be semiotic category of expression [Ausdruck]—that is,
modeled in flexible, yet complementary ways. This with the level of sense and meaning that we have
last claim lies at the heart of the project of a cultural been calling physiognomic or existential or quali-
psychology. tative. Expression is the sense function where sign,
But this is by no means the end of the matter. meaning, and object are so indissolubly joined that
I would like, in concluding, to point out how ele- the sign is taken to participate existentially in, or
ments from two other interlinked semiotic theories, have an ontological affinity with, its intended reality.
those of Ernst Cassirer and Susanne Langer, can For Cassirer, word magic and mythic consciousness
contribute to the mutual enrichment between cul- are prime exemplifications of this stratum or form
tural psychology and semiotics. of consciousness. They are continued, although

in n is 271
residually, in higher forms of religion and their dis- that they both point to and constitute recedes. This
tinctively affective configurations. Expression, then, meaning space accesses, indeed constitutes, a world
is the realm primarily of physiognomic and quali- of law-governed events that are defined by their
tatively defined meanings. Mythic consciousness is relations to one another and not to our intuitional
analyzed in volume one of Cassirer’s Philosophy of or objectively oriented capacities. It is exemplified
Symbolic Forms. in modern mathematical physics and the notation
Cassirer correlated the psychological and philo- systems that make it possible (as well as the various
sophical term intuition [Anschauung] with the semi- systems of pure mathematics and symbolic logic).
otic category of representation [Repräsentation or A general reflection on this stratum, and a correla-
Darstellung], with the grasp or constitution in the tion of it with the two other strata, is the subject of
experiential continuum of objects with properties volume three of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms,
and their embodiment in language, the subject of devoted to the phenomenology of knowledge in the
the volume two of his Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. semiotic mode.
It is the recognition of objects by properties, func- According to Cassirer, the basis for the differenti-
tioning as marks or diacritical features, that intro- ation of these three sense functions is the increasing
duces a kind of indexical feature into perception. distance between the sign and the realities accessed
The perceived properties support the perceptual through it—indeed, an increasing transparency
process and do so in such a manner that the sup- of the sign, a disappearing of its material charac-
ports themselves are connected with what they point ter and physical reality and underpinnings, which,
to. This second sense function, representation, is however, can never be left behind. Even abstract
the sense function where the relations among signs, systems of signs have a kind of diaphanous or even
meanings, and objects have moved to a higher level disembodied feel, which makes up, paradoxically,
of abstraction but are still bound to the sensory their semiotic body. This is what Peirce called the
order. Whereas mythical consciousness, a true semi- material quality of the sign, which each sense func-
otic phenomenon, works within the dimension of tion, semiotically considered, has. By means of this
affectively charged identity, or at least identification “spiritual triad” (1929, p. 101), Cassirer wanted to
of sign with object, representation introduces differ- place precisely the forms of sense-giving in relation
ence, although in a rather different sense than one is to one another and to analyze their inner logics
familiar with in the structural and post-structuralist and developmental stages, which he did under the
traditions. As Cassirer puts it in a way resonant rubric not just of his philosophy of symbolic forms
with later discussions, “The aim of repetition lies in but of a philosophy of human culture, epitomized
identity—the aim of linguistic designation lies in in his An Essay on Man (1944). Cultural psychology
difference” (p. 189). On this level, the word is not engages paradigmatic exemplifications of these sense
the thing; the image is not the imaged. Words and functions. Indeed, I think that cultural psychology
images, doing the work of representation, articu- could examine and evaluate the psychological valid-
late the world without being a part of it. Language ity of Cassirer’s rather high-road schematization of
and art for Cassirer exemplify in clearest fashion these sense functions. Here, the descriptive tasks of
this sense function, albeit in rather different ways. semiotics both coincide with and inform those of a
They grasp [begreifen] the world, upon an intuitive cultural psychology.
[anschaulich] base, to be sure, but they do not take This is nowhere clearer than in the work of
hold [greifen] of it in any material or magical fash- Langer, who consciously in many and impor-
ion, despite their engrossing and magical effects on tant ways has continued and extended Cassirer’s
the psychological level. attempt to broaden the scope of semiotics to the
Cassirer correlated the scientific [wissenschaftlich]— history of culture as such and to base it on a dis-
that is, theoretical—understanding [Erkenntnis] tinctive and original model of mind. In her early
with pure signification [Bedeutung], with the grasp work, The Practice of Philosophy (1930), Langer
of abstract relations, a grasp based on free and unmo- argues that philosophy’s proper object is interpreta-
tivated systems of signs. This third sense function, tion—indeed, the interpretation of interpretations
pure signification, is the stratum of sense functions that are expressed in various sign systems. In a way
farthest removed from normal sensory, intuitive paralleling Peirce, but with no explicit use of his
supports. The concrete physical reality of the sen- terms, Langer argues that human beings spread two
sible, vectorially functioning signs and the objects very different sign systems, the discursive and the

272 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


presentative, over the continuum of experience. In of sensibility, awareness, excitement, gratification
her classic Philosophy in a New Key, this distinction or suffering” which belong to physiological events
becomes one between discursive and presentational when they reach a certain level of complexity and
forms. It is the job of semiotics to study the gen- are felt (Langer, 1967, p. 4). Mentality and feeling,
eral logic of signs and symbols and then to explore Langer proposes, are synonymous. Mentality is a
the specific logic of each general class of sign sys- field of “felt impingements and activities” (Langer,
tems and their specific exemplifications in language, 1967, p. 9) and covers not just the normal notion
myth, ritual, art, science, and so on. The realm of of feeling but also thought, sensation, dream, and
human rationality is divided into these two semi- actions. Feeling is “the modulus of psychological
otic modes, corresponding roughly to a distinction conception” (Langer, 1967, p. 21) and being felt is
between saying and showing, a distinction she takes a phase of vital processes, “a mode of appearance,
from Wittgenstein and uses in her own way—head- and not an added factor” (Langer, 1967, p. 21).
ing toward results that Wittgenstein himself would The chief thesis explored and defended by Langer
not have sanctioned. But Langer goes further in her is that “the entire psychological field—including
analysis. Like Cassirer, she sees the human being human conception, responsible action, rationality,
as animal symbolicum, but she pushes the symbolic knowledge—is a vast and branching development
capacity all the way down to the lower threshold of feeling” (1967, p. 23) and that there is no “primi-
of meaning-making, which she subsumes under the tive forms of feeling which is its ‘real’ form” (1967,
rubric of symbolic transformation. p. 19).
Langer notes that the human mind is to be How is feeling to be known? How does it make
understood as a transformer and not a transmitter. It itself known? Langer’s idea is that the heuristic key
not only grasps forms but transforms, rendering the to feeling is to be found in images, specifically art
data of experience meaningful. “Meaning accrues images.
essentially to forms,” she writes in Philosophy in a
An image does not exemplify the same principles
New Key (p. 90), with a generous gesture toward
of construction as the object it symbolizes but
Gestalt psychology’s central thesis. By connecting
abstracts its phenomenal character, its immediate
the grasp of form with the recognition of symbolic
effect on our sensibility or the way it presents itself
structure, Langer herself pushes meaning down and
as something of importance, magnitude, strength or
arrives at a position similar to Peirce’s. But, just as
fragility, permanence or transience, etc. It organizes
with Peirce, Langer does not remain on the level of
and enhances the impression directly received. And
individual subjective transformations of experience
as most of our awareness of the world is a continual
but extends her attention out to all those objective
play of impressions, our primitive intellectual
forms that emerge out of these transformations.
equipment is largely a fund of images, not necessarily
Langer’s contention is that recognizing two radically
visual, but often gestic, kinesthetic, verbal or what
different types of symbolic transformations broad-
I can only call “situational.”. . . [W]e apprehend
ens our very notion of rationality. And, moreover, in
everything which comes to us as impact from the
her final trilogy, Mind: An Essay on Human Feeling,
world by imposing some image on it that stresses
Langer attempts to develop a comprehensive con-
its salient features and shapes it for recognition and
cept of feeling to cover the total mental field and to
memory.
connect it with symbolization as the central activity
(1967, p. 59)
of human mentation. The structures of feeling are
accessed and exemplified in paradigmatic form in This is the root of Langer’s notion of a form of
the rise of the art symbol, a pregnant image that feeling—which Langer applies to her analysis of art
displays the life of feeling in objective form. (Langer, 1953). But the point is actually more gen-
For Langer feeling is, quite generally, “whatever eral. Langer thinks that the original act of the mind
is felt in any way, as sensory stimulus or inward is, by a kind of abstraction, to impose, or recognize,
tension, pain, emotion or intent.” It is the “mark a form in the flux of experience and to construct
of mentality” (Langer, 1967, p. 4). Feeling, on some symbolic representation of it, rooted in the
Langer’s conception, characterizes physiologi- symbolizing activity of the imagination. The process
cal systems, not as an additional reality but as a is most evident in the production of artistic sym-
dimension or phase of the system. Psychology, on bols, which exist in imaginal form. But projection
Langer’s conception, is “oriented toward the aspects does not take place only in the symbolic form of art.

in n is 273
Symbolic projection in all modalities aims to inter- object von Uexküll calls the “effector arc.” Although
cept every form of meaning in experience. Once we can distinguish between the “perceptual arc” and
again, cultural psychology and semiotics coincide. the “effector arc,” we must all the while acknowledge
Langer asks cultural psychology to extend its range the intimate relations between the two. In fact, the
to examining all the manifestations of mind but perceptual and the effector are dimensions rather
especially the symbolic images of art. Langer adds than separate spheres, because the organism is never
an aesthetic twist to cultural psychology. It asks it merely passive nor purely active, never merely inter-
to contribute to a semiotic exploration of “the form preting or materially constructing. Indeed, Cassirer
of felt life” (Langer, 1967, p. 64). It introduces the saw that in the case of humans, it is precisely the
notion of symbolic exemplification as a challenge to ingression of articulate meaning systems, what he
cultural psychology to make sure that it encompasses, called the “symbolic network,” into these two other
from its own point of view, the whole phenomenal systems that transforms the whole. von Uexküll’s
manifestation of mind. The material quality of a revolutionary insight is that we should think of all
sign configuration can be generalized: every sign these arcs in semiotic terms—that is, in terms of
configuration has a distinctive feel, whether in the meaning and of differential cue carriers. The recep-
discursive or presentational mode. Each type of sign tor arc is marked by the grasp of differences in the
configuration embodies gradients. These gradients perceptual field, which Gregory Bateson also fore-
reflect the ways we access the world. Cultural psy- grounded. Although other organisms are for the
chology, on the experiential side, follows the lead most part confined to predetermined fields of cues,
of semiotics and at the same time enriches it with humans are open to a vast array of articulate cues,
empirical detail. It shows cultural psychology to be having not an Umwelt but a Welt—that is, not an
both modeling and phenomenologically empirical environment but a world—or in Langer’s terms,
at one and the same time. But it challenges cultural an “open ambient.” This human world is an open
psychology to focus on image fields and to avoid all world, permeated by articulate, exosomatic systems
form of logocentrism, to insert the symbolic imagi- that inform and embody perception, in the broad
nation into its object domain. Indeed, because the sense of that term. This world is constituted by the
basic idea of semiotics is that meaning must appear, material and semiotic results of human constructive
Langer tells us that semiotics as well as cultural psy- action, which introduce vast systems of differences
chology must collaborate not just in the analysis of into the natural and the social world. These effected
the logic of the forms of feeling but in the experi- differences are themselves perceived by the organ-
ence of these forms as they appear to and in cultur- ism in a continuous and ever-expanding spiral.
ally defined and situated persons and groups. Cassirer’s delineates our situation in a ringing
remark:
The Universal Relevance of von Uexküll’s
Physical reality seems to recede in proportion
Functional Circle
as man’s symbolic activity advances. Instead of
Finally, I would like to note that Jakob von
dealing with the things themselves man is in a
Uexküll’s functional circle, presented in his Theory
sense constantly conversing with himself. He has
of Meaning (1940), displays, within what has
so enveloped himself in linguistic forms, in artistic
become an explicit biosemiotic context, the cir-
images, in mythical symbols or religious rites that
cuit of meaning of any organism qua tale. It is
he cannot see or know anything except by the
extremely important, as heuristic schema, for the
interposition of this artificial medium.
proper understanding not just of the task of a gen-
(Cassirer, 1944, p. 25)
eral semiotics but of another way of formulating the
frame for a cultural psychology that understands Is this not the goal of both semiotics and cul-
the bodily roots of semiosis. Any organism, on von tural psychology—to study this sign-dependent and
Uexküll’s account, is defined by a deep receptivity to -constituted artificial medium and process in which
perceptual stimuli and by varying degrees and types human beings “weave the symbolic net, the tangled
of reactions that change the originating stimuli in a web of human experience?” Can we not adapt and
constant dynamic spiral. The path from the mean- extend Vygotsky’s closing reflection to the widest
ing-bearing object to the organism von Uexküll semiotic frame, thinking of “sign” when he speaks
calls the “receptor arc.” The path from the organ- of “word.” “Consciousness,” he writes, “is reflected
ism to the meaning-bearing and meaning-receiving in a word [sign] as the sun in a drop of water.

274 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


A word [sign] relates to consciousness as a living cell addressee. Furthermore, Bühler’s organon model
relates to a whole organism, as an atom relates to the foregrounds the pivotal phenomenon of abstraction
universe. A word [sign] is a microcosm of human and the mental processes of diacrisis. Bühler sees
consciousness” (1934, p. 256). As Peirce puts it, the human mind as focused on systems of relevance
“the word or sign that man uses is the man himself ” both in the apprehension of the linguistic sign and
(Peirce, 1868, p. 54). in the cultural world quite generally. Moreover, the
differentiation of expression, appeal, and represen-
Conclusions and Future Perspectives tation, as semantic functions is correlated by Bühler
Cultural psychology and a broad-based semiot- with the semiotic distinction between indexes, sig-
ics, it is clear, intersect at many levels and in many nals, and symbols. On this basis, Bühler saw three
ways. Cultural psychology, in as much as it deals principal domains for psychology to study: (1) the
with human meaning-making on the experien- structures of experiencing subjects, (2) the forms of
tial and socio-cultural levels, is in need of explicit behavior and behavioral steering, and (3) the sys-
schemas of the various forms that meaning-making tems of formed content found in objective mean-
takes. Semiotics, however, does not offer one uni- ing systems. Cultural psychology should avail itself
fied schema but, rather, a bundle of schemas that of Bühler’s suggestions here in terms of the tasks
can guide cultural psychological investigations. The of psychology as well as drawing on his advanced
various semiotic schemas have different points of notion of a field, which is not restricted to a purely
origin and consequently rather different kinds of linguistic field.
relevance for cultural psychology. They foreground Michael Polanyi adds to the focal concerns of a
and schematize different features of meaning-mak- cultural psychology the important notion of a tacit
ing processes and give them different weight. Prior dimension, that we can know more than we can
to concrete investigations, they do not tell cultural say, and the notion of skillful knowing and doing.
psychology what it will find, but they do point out Could cultural psychology, taking up Polanyi’s
some distinctive types of things with which cultural hints, not be advanced by adverting to the revolu-
psychology will concern itself and supply it with tionary nature of Polanyi’s distinction between focal
analytical tools that will inform and thicken its and subsidiary awareness and the consequent key
empirical investigations. concept of indwelling? Moreover, Polanyi’s insis-
The Peircean schema has a twofold value: (1) it tence on the tacit assimilation of cues and clues
offers a triadic model of sign types— icons, indexes, shows that knowing does not involve an explicit or
and symbols—that has great heuristic power, and (2) thematic cognitive stance. It also shows that know-
it delineates with remarkable clarity the five factors ing is fraught with the roots that it embodies, roots
of semiosis, of the production and interpretation of over which we have no control at the primary level
signs, that make such a process the entangled phe- of assimilation.
nomenon that it is. Of special importance is Peirce’s Ernst Cassirer and Susanne Langer point the
notion of an interpretant, or the “proper significate way to a semiotically grounded philosophy of cul-
effect” of a sign. Peirce’s model of the self shows it to ture, Cassirer by offering his own tripartite schema
be three-leveled, with the self engaging the world on of sense functions, expression, representation, and
the level of feeling, effective action, and cognition. pure signification and pointing to how they inform
Semiotics would point cultural psychology toward and structure the whole realm of symbolic forms
empirical investigations of the social and cultural that make up the world, Langer by developing the
exemplifications of these interpretant realms and general notion of symbolic transformation and
the varieties of contents mediated by icons, indexes, a comprehensive concept of feeling. Both rely on
and symbols at the various stages of an individual’s a vast realm of data from the human sciences and
and a culture’s development. show how semiotics does not legislate from on high
Karl Bühler offers a semiotic schema developed but exists in symbiotic relationship with the whole
not from a logical or philosophical point of view cultural and biological world. Such a position joins
but from a generalization of a speech event. Bühler them to von Uexküll’s attempt to fuse the biological
showed that language is not just a representational and the cultural, the lower and upper thresholds of
tool, carrying out a representational function. A human meaning making.
speech event also reveals or expresses the subjectiv- The various positions with which we have dealt
ity of the speaker and it steers the behavior of the in this article have one major lesson for cultural

in n is 275
psychology. They all teach us that semiotics without Innis, R. E. (2009). Susanne Langer in Focus: The Symbolic Mind.
the study of cultural forms is empty, and the study Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Jakobson, R. (1960). The Speech Event and the Functions of
of cultural forms without semiotics is blind. Language. In Linda R. Waugh & M. Monville-Burston
(Eds.), On Language: Roman Jakobson. Cambridge, MA.:
References Harvard University Press, 1990. (First part of his 1960 paper,
Barthes, R. (1977). Rhetoric of the Image. In S. Heath (Ed.), “Linguistics and Poetics.”)
Image, Music, Text. (pp. 32–51). New York: Hill and Wang. Köhler, W. (1938). The Place of Values in a World of Facts. New
Bühler, K. (1927). Die Krise der Psychologie. Introduction by York: New American Library.
Herbert Rohracher. Frankfurt am Main: Ullstein, 1978 Köhler, W. (1947). Gestalt Psychology. New York: New American
(reprint). Library.
Bühler, K. (1931). Phonetik und Phonologie. Travaux du cercle Langer, S. K. (1930). The Practice of Philosophy. New York: Holt.
linguistique de Prague 4, 22–53. Langer, S. K. (1942). Philosophy in a New Key: A Study in the
Bühler, K. (1934). Theory of Language. (Trans. Donald Goodwin). Symbolism of Reason, Rite, and Art. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard
Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1990. Original publication: University Press.
Sprachtheorie. 1934. Jena: Gustav Fischer. Langer, S. K. (1953). Feeling and Form. New York: Scribner’s.
Bühler, K. (1930). Das Gestaltprinzip im Leben des Menschen und Langer, S. K. (1967/1972/1982). Mind: An Essay on Human
der Tiere. Bern, Switzerland: Verlag Hans Huber. Feeling. 3 vols. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins.
Cassirer, E. (1923). Language. Vol I of The Philosophy of Symbolic Lotman, Y. M. (1990). Universe of the Mind. A Semiotic Theory
Forms 3 vols, translated by Ralph Manheim. New Haven, of Culture. Translated by Ann Shukman. Introduction by
CT.: Yale University Press, 1953. (German original, 1923). Umberto Eco. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Cassirer, E. (1925). Mythical Thought. Vol. II of The Philosophy of Nisbett, R. E. (2003). The Geography of Thought. New York: Free
Symbolic Forms, translated by Ralph Manheim. New Haven, Press.
CT.: Yale University Press, 1953. (German original, 1925). Peirce, C. S. (1868). Some Consequences of Four Incapacities.
Cassirer, E. (1929). The Phenomenology of Knowledge. Vol. III In Houser & Kloesel (Eds.), vol. I, 1992. Bloomington, IN:
of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, translated by Ralph Indiana University Press.
Manheim. New Haven, CT.: Yale University Press, 1953. Peirce, C. S. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6,
(German original, 1929). 1931–1935, Charles Hartshorne & Paul Weiss (Eds.), vols.
Cassirer, E. (1944). Essay on Man. New Haven, CT: Yale 7–8, 1958, Arthur W. Burks (Ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press. University Press..
Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Polanyi, M. (1958a). Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical
Language and the Brain. New York: Norton. Philosophy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Durst-Andersen, P. (2009). The Grammar of Linguistic Semiotics. Polanyi, M. (1958b). The Study of Man. Chicago, IL: University
Reading Peirce in a Modern Linguistic Light. Cybernetics and of Chicago Press.
Human Knowing. 16 (3–4), 37–79. Polanyi, M. (1966). The Tacit Dimension. Chicago, IL: University
Eco, U. (1976). A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana of Chicago Press.
University Press. Saussure, F. de. (1916). Course in General Linguistics. C. Bally, A.
Holenstein, E. (1976). Roman Jakobson’s Approach to Language: Sechehaye, & A. Riedlinger (Eds.). Translated by Roy Harris.
Phenomenological Structuralism. Bloomington, IN: Indiana LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
University Press. Uexküll, J. von. (1940/1982). Theory of Meaning. Trans. Barry
Houser, N. & C. Kloesel, C. (1992). The Essential Peirce: Selected Stone and Herbert Weiner. Special issue of Semiotica 42(1),
Philosophical Writings. Vol. I (1867–1893). Bloomington, 25–82.
IN: Indiana University Press. Valsiner, J. & van der Veer, R. (2000). The Social Mind:
Innis, R. E. (1982). Karl Bühler: Semiotic Foundations of Language Construction of the Idea. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
Theory. New York: Plenum Press. University Press.
Innis, R. E. (1985). Semiotics: An Introductory Anthology. van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky:
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. A Quest for Synthesis. Oxford, UK and Cambridge, MA:
Innis, R. E. (1992). Consciousness and the Play of Signs. Blackwell.
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Vygotsky, L. S. (1934/1986). Thought and Language. Newly revised
Innis, R. E. (2002). Pragmatism and the Forms of Sense: Language, and edited by Alex Kozulin. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Perception, Technics. University Park, PA: Penn State Wiley, N. (1994). The Semiotic Self. Chicago, IL: University of
University Press. Chicago Press.

276 meani ng fu l co nne ct i ons


CHAPTER

The City As a Sign:


13 A Developmental-Experiential
Approach to Spatial Life
Nikita A. Kharlamov

Abstract
The galloping urbanization of the world simultaneously transforms human society into a thoroughly
urban society and dismantles the traditional “rural–urban” dichotomy. It is increasingly recognized in
urban studies that human spatiality entails a complex pattern of settlements and dwellings. I propose
a developmental-experiential theoretical framework for addressing what Stanley Milgram called the
experience of living in cities. This framework particularly focuses on the atmosphere of living in cities.
Founded on organismic-developmental axiomatic base introduced by Jacob von Uexküll, Heinz Werner,
and Bernard Kaplan, and developed as cultural-developmental approach by Jaan Valsiner, the proposed
framework centers on the experience of individual organismic relating to spatial environment. I draw on
the work of Manuel Castells, Edward Soja, and Yi-Fu Tuan to conceptualize the emergence of meaningful
places as the outcome of experiencing space. The concept of encounter introduced by Ash Amin and
Nigel Thrift is used to locate the experience of the banal, everyday city life. Following Erving Goffman, the
central question for the framework becomes the question of organization of experience. This question is
tackled through Jaan Valsiner’s notions of semiotic mediation and regulation. I specifically focus on spatial
signs that humans use to regulate the meaning-making process that creates as meaningful what Georges
Perec called species of spaces, such as towns and cities. “The city,” from this standpoint, becomes one
of the most important signs that mediate and regulate our experience of environments we inhabit.
I discuss a number of theoretical and methodological directions in which this framework could be further
developed to revive the urban, or settlement, psychology, which failed to develop as a viable subdiscipline
despite the proposals of Georg Simmel and Nikolai Antsiferov in the early twentieth century, and the
latter proposals of Milgram. This discipline should join efforts with settlement sociology and settlement
geography to tackle the multiple challenges of urbanization by exploring its experiential dimension in its
fascinating cultural diversity and intra- and interindividual variation.
Keywords: city, development, encounter, experience, meaning, person-environment-behavior, place,
space, sign–spatial, Umwelt, urban psychology

“The metropolis reveals itself as one of those great


historical formations in which opposing streams which
enclose life unfold, as well as join one another with
equal right.”
—(Simmel, 1903/1997, p. 185)

“Every city has its own face.”


—(Antsiferov, 1925, p. 25)

277
“The Great Khan owns an atlas in which are gathered
the maps of all the cities: those whose walls rest on solid
foundations, those which fell in ruins and were swallowed
up by the sand, those that will exist one day and in whose
place now only hares’ holes gape . . . The catalogue of
forms is endless: until every shape has found its city, new
cities will continue to be born. When the forms exhaust
their variety and come apart, the end of cities begins. In
the last pages of the atlas there is an outpouring of net-
works without beginning or end, cities in the shape of Los
Angeles, in the shape of Kyōto-Ōsaka, without shape.”
—(Calvino, 1972/1974, pp. 137–139)

“Don’t be too hasty in trying to find a definition of the


town; it’s far too big and there’s every chance of getting
it wrong.”
—(Perec, 1974/2008a, p. 60).

Georg Simmel, whose lecture, The metropolis and city! But what does it mean then to live in a post-
the mental life (1903/1997), attained a monumental city? What is the experience of living in the city?
position in urban literature and in the imagination Defining the meaning of the terms “urban” and
of urban scholars, understood the city as the medi- “city” is a monumental task that radiates the feeling
ating vehicle between societal-cultural transition of futility. These words—along with mind, society,
to modernity and the everyday life of the people power, economy, and many others—belong to the
(Kharlamov, 2009). For him, metropolis existed as a class of foundational concepts that travel through
spatial and psychic,1 or even spiritual,2 environment human sciences, ever settling the research inter-
and was visible, ostensive, and palpable. In fact, ests, guiding generation of questions and research
Simmel’s metropolis is well-known to have been programs, and at the same time evading attempts
the fin-de-siècle Berlin (Jazbinsek, 2003). However, to create solid and agreed-upon definitions and
only 70 years after Simmel’s piece, Italo Calvino operationalizations.
conveyed an image of the great omniscient Kublai What makes the notions of city and urban spe-
Khan flipping through the pages of a wondrous atlas cial among foundational concepts is that they are to
that predicted the end of the city form as we know some extent ostensive. That is, there is some a priori
it. Calvino’s friend Georges Perec simply stated that obviousness to these notions, a possibility to detect
there is no quick way of arriving at a structured the presence of the urban by merely looking at a
understanding of what a “town” is, instead proceed- place, pointing a finger at a location, and suggesting
ing by way of scrupulous documentation of town- that it is an urban location, before invoking pow-
ness of that, as he called it, “species of spaces.” ers of reflection and scientific reasoning (Fig. 13.1).
But how do we approach this ostensiveness?
Method: you must either give up talking of the town,
about town, or else force yourself to talk about it as
The “Soul of the City”: Calls for an
simply as possible, obviously, familiarly. Get rid of
Urban Psychology
all preconceived ideas. Stop thinking in ready-made
At least some (and probably all) cities have such a
terms, forget what the town planners and sociologists
powerful grasp on our sensory and cognitive appara-
have said.
tus that they attain a lasting and individual identity.
(Perec, 1974/2008a, pp. 61–62, italics in original)
Nikolai Antsiferov, an early Soviet urbanist, devel-
And yet, as Nikolai Antsiferov succinctly stated, oped a holistic, organicist conception of the city
places where people live have unique identities (1925). He identified three dimensions and, cor-
(“faces”), so that we still can recognize Los Angeles respondingly, divided the urban science into three
even if we agree that it has no form but the vast, branches. The physical form, “the physical nature
endless sprawl. We even ordinarily recognize it as a of the city constituting its concrete, material base”

278 th e c i t y as a si g n
Figure 13.1 An urban place—Malaya
Ordynka Street, Moscow, Russia
(Photograph by author, 2005)

(ibid., p. 21), was to be the subject matter of urban 2. “Whether the observer is a tourist, a
anatomy. The functions of urban organism, “the newcomer, or a longer-term resident”; and
city pulsing with all its organs through the activity 3. “The popular myths and expectations each
of the society” (ibid., p. 22, italics removed), were visitor brings to the city.”
the domain of urban physiology. Finally, Antsiferov
Milgram suggested that a program of research on
asserted that the city has a synthetic image, recog-
these subjective dimensions of perceiving the city
nizable in the flow of time, and stated that “the soul
should be augmented by measures of objective fac-
of the city [is] a historically formed unity of all ele-
tors, such as population and its density, characteris-
ments, constituting the urban organism as a con-
tics of urban society such as the geographic origin
crete individuality” (1925, p. 26, italics in original).
of migrants, national culture, and history of a given
In this secular definition he attempted, predating
city (ibid., p. 25). He even suggested to study, in
many concerns in urban studies of the late twenti-
addition to behavioral measures, and following the
eth and early twenty-first centuries, to capture the
work of Kevin Lynch (1960), the “cognitive maps”
constellation of landscape, history, memory, and
people have of their cities.
architectural and planning styles (ibid., Chapter 4)
The urban psychology according to Antsiferov
that makes the city. This was what, according to
and Milgram, however, apparently never blos-
Antsiferov, urban psychology should study.
somed, especially with respect to proposing inte-
Writing 45 years after Antsiferov, Milgram (1970/
grative theories and conceptual frameworks. In
2010) proposed an agenda for urban psychology. In
the United States (and elsewhere) “urban psychol-
addition to the issues familiar to social psychology—
ogy in the year 2009 barely exists as a discipline,
such as bystander intervention and role behavior—
with no journal, organization, or degree program”
Milgram’s seminal article contained a section entitled,
(Takooshian, 2009, p. 916). Takooshian suggests
nebulously, “Further aspects of urban experience”
that the impact of Milgram’s proposal has dissi-
(ibid., pp. 20 ff.). Echoing Antsiferov (1925), and
pated, even as the original article became a citation
presumably independently from him, Milgram pro-
classic. Indeed, today what amounts to urban psy-
posed to study the “‘atmosphere’ of great cities”
chology is concerned quite narrowly with a range of
(ibid.). This phenomenon encompassed such things
familiar psychological topics—such as prosocial and
as the “vibrant” and “frenetic” character of New York’s
antisocial behaviors, attitudes, health, locating them
city life. Milgram treated this phenomenon in terms
in the cities as external settings—essentially as inde-
of how people perceive cities and suggested that at least
pendent variables. A recent report of the American
three factors are responsible (1970/2010, pp. 21–22):
Psychological Association Task Force on Urban
1. “Implicit standard of comparison,” such as Psychology (American Psychological Association
the person’s hometown; [APA], 2005) stated that urban psychology deals

kh a rl a m ov 279
with urban environments, ranging in scale from and the Sign, I suggest that the city is a meaning, or,
inner cities to metropolitan areas, and: more specifically and importantly, it is the sign that
organizes meaning-making around human settle-
the central question for urban psychology concerns
ments and ultimately defines what we mean by the
how the distinctive characteristics of the people and
city and what it means to live in a good place.
places that make up urban environments give rise to
The chapter begins with an examination of the
particular types of experiences and behaviors, and
notion of “the city” in context of recent discussions
have particular consequences for mental health, well-
on the end of modern city forms and the emergence
being, and human development.
of radically new settlements such as decentered
(APA, 2005, p. 2)
urbanized regions. This establishes the core problem:
Although this definition sounds promising, in If today there is indeed a new essence to the urban
reality it furthers the dissipation of its subject matter form and urban life, what is the experience of living
by approaching the notion of urban in a non-prob- in these new settlements? And how do people make
lematic way: the urban, for APA Task Force, is what sense of these new surroundings? The remainder of
the U.S. Census Bureau defines it to be, through the chapter is devoted to outlining a developmen-
a threshold of population density. It also includes tal-experiential approach to encountering space and
what is non-rural, or non-agricultural, and what is making sense of it. I consecutively discuss the devel-
“part of the global system of economic production opmental axiomatic base, the notions of space and
and distribution” (ibid., pp. 1–2). Consequently, the place, and introduce the concepts of experience and
rest of the report documents a wide range of issues encounter. I then examine the semiotically mediated
psychology has been studying for varying lengths in nature of experience and the regulative function of
the past century, such as acculturation, aging, gay, culture. The final part of the chapter is devoted to
lesbian, bisexual, and transgender identities, home- discussing how humans recognize different species
lessness, substance abuse, physical and mental health, of spaces on the basis of spatial signs, and the impli-
urban decay, urban schools, and even vulnerability to cations of this approach to understanding the nature
terrorism.3 In studying all these, psychology largely of cities and urban life. The chapter concludes with
takes urban for granted and dissolves in absence of an a number of future directions of inquiry.
integrating, central psychological concept that would
define the subject matter of this subdiscipline. Are We Really All Heading Urban? Or,
What Are the Spaces We Inhabit Today?
Developmental-Experiential Approach to “Sometime early next [twenty-first] century,
Life in Spaces: Structure of the Argument if present trends continue, more than half of the
The present chapter is an attempt to approach world’s population will be classified as urban
spaces Homo sapiens live in, or dwell in, or inhabit, rather than rural,” predicted David Harvey (1996,
beginning with the guiding intuition of ostensive- p. 403). He went on the Marxist track to elaborate
ness. It is an attempt to provide novel theoretical on the notion of urbanization as a process fueled
and methodological tools for addressing the very by technological innovation and founded on the
basic question about urban life: What constitutes the social-economic-political process of “relentless
city? It is also an attempt to find the subject matter capital accumulation”: “We are all embroiled in a
for an urban psychology—or psychology of human global process of capitalist urbanization or uneven
settlement spaces—in developmental axiomatic base spatio-temporal development” (p. 414). Indeed, in
applied to the phenomenon of spatial experience. An 2007 a United Nations (U.N. Population Fund
answer to this question is the ontological foundation [UNFPA], 2007) report stated, “[T]he world is
for any further inquiry into human settlement form. about to leave its rural past behind: By 2008, for
I explicitly adopt a perspective focused on persons— the first time, more than half of the globe’s popula-
the sentient inhabitants of environments—and their tion, 3.3 billion people, will be living in towns and
intentionality, which is the source of meanings and cities” (ibid., p. 6). This statement was immediately
activities that define cities as spatial forms, and focus picked up by urban practitioners, pundits, and
thus on psychic experience of urban living. Hence academics from across the spectrum of disciplines
the title of the chapter: furthering the move taken by dealing with cities and urban life.
Gottdiener and Lagopoulos (1986), whose seminal Remarkable as this statistical statement is,
collection on urban semiotics was entitled The City however, it raises more questions than it provides

280 th e c i t y as a si g n
answers. It is a statistical assertion of the highest, as rurban: neither city nor country but everywhere
most general scale.4 Unpacking its meaning requires a mixture of both. Just as Southern California is
asking: What constitutes a city? Given the gallop- the least rural of all the regions in America, so,
ing pace of urbanization all over the world, is there paradoxically, Los Angeles is the least citified of all
still salience to the dichotomy “urban–rural”? Or the cities of America.
maybe the distinction becomes an example of unity (McWilliams, 1973, pp. 12–13)
of opposites—as with sustainable local agriculture
For today’s urban studies, Los Angeles has become
initiatives in the heart of American inner cities and
a paradigmatic city: “the city that displays more clearly
with high-speed Internet connections in Northern
than other cities the fundamental features and trends
Russian villages? What kind of life then is urban life?
of the wider urban system” (Nijman, 2000, p. 135).5
How is the city shaped by its inhabitants, and how
Jan Nijman—who claims that Miami, rather than Los
is it, in turn, shaping them? What is cultural about
Angeles, could serve as a paradigmatic American city
this process? What is the future of human settle-
for the twenty-first century—inserts a caveat that the
ment forms and human mobility patterns in face of
paradigmatic city is not a city that all other cities will
fossil resource exhaustion and global warming? And
become but, rather, a future-projected extreme most
not least—as thinkers such as Iris Marion Young
clearly manifesting the general trends. The imagi-
(1990) and David Harvey (1996) remind—what is
nation of Los Angeles found its way into concepts
the justice dimension of human settlement process?
underscoring the regionalized nature of settlement
These questions form the crux of urban studies and
patterns, such as the “multicentered metropolitan
demand cooperation and integration across disci-
region,” which Gottdiener and Hutchison have called
plines. The underlying complexity of “50% urban
“the first really new way people have organized their
population” statement underscores the topicality
living and working arrangements in 10,000 years”
and urgency of these questions about urban life not
(2006, p. 5). In contrast to the bounded traditional
only for abstract scientific thinking but for broad
city with a recognizable central core, such as the city
domains of public concern and applied policy.
reflected in the classical concentric ring growth model
of the Chicago School (Burgess, 1925), the “new form
The New Urban Form: Urban, Suburban, of settlement space . . . can be typified by two features:
Post-Suburban, Apocalyptic . . . It extends over a large region, and it contains many
One possible track of unpacking the issue of separate centers, each with its own abilities to draw
what constitutes a city is to start with the assertion workers, shoppers, and residents” (Gottdiener &
that today cities go beyond the traditional, modern Hutchison, 2006, p. 5). Fishman succinctly expressed
urban form into something radically new—such as the gist of this new city: “the creation of a decentral-
the sprawling urbanized region with multiple centers. ized environment that nevertheless possesses all the
In 1987, Robert Fishman, in his seminal history of economic and technological dynamism we associate
the American suburban model, suggested that the with the city” (1987, p. 184).
traditional model of city with an identifiable core Fishman’s vision could create an impression of
(which in modern times has been “augmented” optimism toward this new form of city living. Not
with a rim of bedroom suburbs) is being replaced all observers are that optimistic. Davis (1990/2006)
by “technoburb”: “With its highways and advanced painted a bleak picture of Los Angeles as a city of
communication technology, the new perimeter city inequality, oppression, disenchantment, and unfree-
can generate urban diversity without urban concen- dom, an apocalyptic landscape before apocalypse
tration” (p. 17). Fishman’s vision of “technoburbs” itself. Among other things, Davis’s pessimistic vision
and “techno-cities” (1987, Chapter 7) was inspired epitomizes a wider trend of post-1990 urban studies,
first and foremost by Los Angeles—the iconic urban with a prominence of calls for social and, importantly,
sprawl developed literally from a scratch of a few spatial and urban justice (following, among others,
thousand homesteaders over (at best) some 150 the theoretical proposals of David Harvey, 1996, and
years into a megalopolis of well over 16 million Iris Marion Young, 1990) juxtaposed with an over-
people. The entire region manifests the dissolution arching pessimism toward the present and future of
of rural–urban dichotomy. the city as a livable space. The looming question is
whether cities today indeed are the seats of the “good”
In effect, Southern California constitutes a single dynamism and diversity or the spatial train of moder-
metropolitan district which should be characterized nity is headed uncontrollably toward the catastrophe

kh a rl a m ov 281
of dystopia, as visualized in movies such as Blade and shared (or collective) activity (or “time-sharing
Runner (1982).6 The utopian dimension of this ques- social practices”) across the domains of human life
tion is of primary importance: utopian thinking, as from the constraints of material, physical space.8
John Friedmann defined it, is “the capacity to imag- Castells, however, did not embark on the track of
ine a future that departs significantly from what we unbounded techno-optimism. His cautious note
know to be a general condition in the present” (2000, is founded on the distinction between “space” and
p. 462), and this capacity requires combining a cri- “place.” Defining space as “the material support of
tique of the present condition with a constructive time-sharing social practices” (ibid., p. 441), and
vision for the future (ibid.). The answer to the ques- thus grounding it in material, objective realm of
tion “What does it mean to live in the city?” is foun- practice, he introduced the subjective, meaningful
dational, for without a clear understanding of this, it is dimension of space by defining place as “a locale
impossible to constructively proceed along construct- whose form, function, and meaning are self-con-
ing normative visions of cities without falling into the tained within the boundaries of physical contiguity”
traps of ideal cities (Kharlamov, 2010). (ibid., p. 453, italics removed). The overwhelming
majority of people, according to him, “still live in
Life in Places and Thirdspaces: Locating places” (ibid., p. 458)—and thus there is a mis-
the Urban Experience match, a “structural schizophrenia” (ibid., p. 459)
Even if Los Angeles may be just one of the urban between the logic of places and the logic of flows.
places of today, and other cities may assume differ- In this statement, Castells captured the essence
ent spatial forms—especially outside the United of the urban problem today. If the social, economic,
States with its car-centered highway mobility political, cultural life is becoming increasingly
regime—there appears to be a broad consensus in detached from the identifiable and personally recog-
urban studies that cities today are on the forefront nizable locale in space, then how should we account
of the broader social, cultural, political, and eco- for the personal experience of spaces and places?
nomic7 change. One of the possible approaches to And what is the relation of this personal experi-
this new configuration of human life is offered by ence to the objective configurations of space such
Manuel Castells. Castells’ trilogy, The Information as those captured by concepts like “multicentered
Age: Economy, Society, and Culture (1996/2010), offers metropolitan region?”
a grand survey of human condition in the late twen- Another way to locate this problem can be
tieth and early twenty-first centuries informed by drawn from the work of Soja (2000), whose dis-
the overarching concept of network society, Castells cussion of “postmetropolis” rests on the conceptual
suggested that cities—especially megacities such as foundation he called “trialectics of cityspace.” It is
Tokyo, New York, Mexico City, and, of course, Los worth examining this conception at some length.
Angeles—manifest the spatial logic of this new soci- Addressing the “spatiality of human life” and high-
ety. In a statement echoing Fishman’s, Castells cap- lighting the intrinsic spatiality of the city as a “mate-
tures the nature of mega-cities: “It is [the] distinctive rial and symbolic habitat for human life” (ibid.,
feature of being globally connected and locally dis- pp. 6–8), Soja drew on the work of Henri Lefebvre
connected, physically and socially, that makes mega- to conceptualize Firstspace as a perspective that views
cities a new urban form” (1996/2010, p. 436, italics cityspace as “physically and empirically perceived
removed). He called the new spatial logic “the space as form and process, as measurable and mappable
of flows.” configurations and practices of urban life” (Soja,
2000, p. 10). Conceptualizing the city in terms of,
The space of flows is the material organization of
for example, spatial distribution of population and
time-sharing social practices that work through
arriving at a concept of “multicentered metropolitan
flows. By flows I understand purposeful, repetitive,
region” is an application of Firstspace perspective.
programmable sequences of exchange and interaction
In terms of Secondspace, “cityspace becomes more
between physically disjointed positions held by
of a mental or ideational field, conceptualized in
social actors in the economic, political, and symbolic
imagery, reflexive thought, and symbolic represen-
structures of society.
tation, a conceived space of the imagination” (ibid.,
(Castells, 1996/2010, p. 442, italics removed)
p. 11, italics in original). Thus, Secondspace could
In a nutshell, space of flows is about the disconnec- be interpreted as a meta-perspective on phenomena
tion of simultaneous interaction, communication, such as urban theories and personal representations

282 th e c i t y as a si g n
of cities in memories or “mental maps.” In addition John Urry, following the work of Heidegger, sug-
to these two perspectives, Soja suggested employ- gests that atmospheres “stem from how people are
ing a Thirdspace (a term derived from the work of ‘attuned’ to particular places” (2007, p. 73). How do
Bhabha, 1990) perspective and recognizing and we approach these atmospheres in Thirdspace? One
understanding cityspace as “fully lived space, a interesting path is to concentrate on the multiple
simultaneously real-and-imagined, actual-and-vir- “texts” that the city produces as a result of expres-
tual, locus of structured individual and collective sive activity of the urbanites. This was the path Soja
experience and agency” (ibid., italics in original). In (2000) took in his excavation of Thirdspace of 1992
three main parts of his book, Soja outlines, respec- L.A. “Justice Riots,” as he called them.9 I suggest
tively, the three perspectives, focusing first on the that another fruitful path is to develop theoretical
“geohistory of cityspace,” outlining the evolution and methodological tools to grasp the psychic experience
of human cities that culminates, not surprisingly, of the city. I will now turn to assembling a theoreti-
in Los Angeles. The second part of his book is a cal framework geared to this task.
sweeping overview of urban theory, particularly that
which takes Los Angeles as its paradigm and source From Space to Place: Development of
of imagination. The third part—concerned with Meaningful Environment
Thirdspace—withdraws from the scholarly writing I am learning to drive a car. My friend, who is
of the first two parts. In it, Soja presents a collage teaching me, sits in the passenger seat and guides
of fragments—poetry interspersed with newspa- me while I am concentrated on safely keeping the
per excerpts and quotations from philosophers vehicle on the road, maintaining speed, and making
and urbanists—all focused in different ways on the turns at my teacher’s command. One day I make
1992 riots in Los Angeles that followed the acquit- a left turn into a long stretch of road outside the
tal of four White police officers who beat up a Black dense residential neighborhood, and for the next
driver (Rodney King). This collage is an attempt 10 minutes or so I drive at the speed of about 40
to approach the lived space of Los Angeles and the miles per hour on a well-paved freeway with few
complexity of experiences and perspectives involved cars. We like this road so much (it has little traffic,
in one particular iconic event. the turns are wide and easy, there are no confus-
Castells’ suggestion of a “structural schizophre- ing intersections or blind driveways, and the other
nia” between the logic of space of the network soci- drivers appear to be polite) that for the next cou-
ety and the experiential world of living humans ple weeks we use this road for our lessons while I
and Soja’s attempt to grasp the lived space of post- am getting more comfortable with operating the
metropolis point toward a lacuna in urban theory car on an open road. One evening as I drive into
and methodology of urban studies. Every objective one of the most beautiful sunsets I have ever seen,
measure in the urbanists’ toolboxes points toward I suddenly realize that this road, which I by now
changes in urban form, urban process, and urban know down to each turn, lane, and road sign, actu-
life. Population growth; migration patterns; changes ally goes past Worcester Regional Airport. Not only
in economic structure, production, and consump- has my newly developed level of comfort with the
tion; emergence of creative/knowledge economies; car allowed me to pay attention to the sunset and
religious and ethnic tensions; the demise of tradi- notice that it is very beautiful—it has also allowed
tional structures of urban governance; explosion of me to pay enough attention to the surroundings
the city territory and the dissolution of urban/rural to realize that what used to be just a road in the
dichotomy; and the development of mostly urban middle of nowhere (I could not remember after the
“evil paradises” (Davis & Monk, 2007)—pockets first couple drives how we got there and where we
of neoliberal exploitation and totalizing negation of drove) in fact is somewhere—and this somewhere is
human rights across the world, from Los Angeles near the regional airport. What could be anyplace
to Dubai and Kabul—suggest that urbanization became a specific, defined, relatively meaningful
became the global conditio humana. And yet it place marked by a landmark. What has happened
appears that the urban experience—especially those to this stretch of urban space? Apparently, the phys-
transient qualities of urban life that Antsiferov ical, built environment on the fringes of the city of
(1925) called “the soul of the city” and Milgram Worcester has not changed because of my newly
(1970/2010) referred to as the atmosphere of great developed recognition. But for me as a person, it is
cities—escapes from the urbanists’ nets. no longer an undefined space—instead, it is a place

kh a rl a m ov 283
imbued with meaning and (admittedly romantic) relative globality and undifferentiatedness towards
memory of the first prolonged experience of driving states of increasing differentiation and hierarchic
a motor vehicle. How did this happen? integration” (Werner & Kaplan, 1963/1984, p. 7;
see also Valsiner, 2000, Chapter 2). It follows from
Assuming a Developmental Perspective on this principle—which is a fundamental axiomatic
Human Spatiality principle of developmental science according to
How do spaces become places? The answer to this Werner and Kaplan—that differentiation, articu-
question requires exploring the notions of space and lation, and integration of space (Valsiner, 2000,
place from a developmental standpoint. This explo- p. 20) by the organism is inherent in its very basic
ration will open the pathway for tackling the issue functioning in relating to environment.
of what the city is and how it acquires the urban
quality for humans. Relating to Environment: Human
Spatiality and Human Umwelt
Axioms of Developmental Approach The notion of relating to environment derives
The “developmental perspective in any science entails from von Uexküll’s theoretical biology. Central for
investigation of general laws of emergence of novelty von Uexküll (1940/1982) has been the concept of
in irreversible time” (Valsiner, 2000, p. 17, italics in Umwelt—the subjective phenomenal world that
original). Valsiner further suggests that novelty—the each organism inhabits and that is the only reality
new phenomena that are different from those that accessible to this organism.10 “Everything that falls
have happened in the past—emerges on at least two under the spell of an Umwelt (subjective universe)
distinguishable levels: on an individual level and on is altered and reshaped until it has become a useful
the comparative-collective level. What was novel for meaning-carrier; otherwise it is totally neglected”
me as a person in recognizing the airport was not (ibid., p. 31). von Uexküll develops the model of
novel on a collective level of the population of driv- functional circle to account for the organism’s rela-
ers driving past it—and yet it was novel at the time tion to environment. This model accounts for per-
when the road was first opened. Similarly, the notion ception of objects as meaning-carriers and activity
of airport for me was no longer novel, although at of the subject (organism) as meaning-receivers in
one point in my past I discovered what an actual that subjects perceive objects as perceptual cue-car-
airport is when I first went to an airport to fly for riers and act on the objects as effector cue-carriers.
the first time, armed with the culturally shared— At the center of the functional circle is the notion
but, until that point, abstract and not validated by of sign, which is the general mediator of meanings
personal experience—knowledge of what is an air- of any events, internal and external. Thus the model
port. And yet in the past there was an emergence of of functional circle accounts for perception of the
the airport as a cultural-technological phenomenon world, making sense of it (making it meaningful
as humans extended the existing technologies such for the organism) and acting on it as a meaning-
as the harbor and the train station to accommodate ful reality (see Magnus & Kull, 2012, for a more
the newly invented flying machines. detailed explanation of Uexküll’s theory; see Chang,
The developmental axiom of “becoming and 2009, for a range of its applications in cultural
dynamic self-maintenance” (Valsiner, 2000, p. 20) psychology).
implies that the study of emergence of meaningful Werner and Kaplan’s (1963/1984) developmen-
places necessarily deals with the question of how tal theory explicitly relies on von Uexküll’s concep-
these places become meaningful and how the mean- tion and allows one to treat it dynamically and to
ing is maintained in irreversible time as a stable ask how meanings emerge, or develop, in the pro-
phenomenon. This dynamic, processual axiom is a cess of the organism’s living in environment, and
pathway to access the lived reality of Soja’s (2000) what function these meanings play in maintaining
Thirdspace and to understand how people create the relation to this environment. This is what they
meaningful locales that Castells (1996/2010) called call “organismic-developmental framework” (ibid.,
places—and to unpack their atmospheric qualities. Chapter 1). Given the concern of this chapter with
Developmental treatment of this question requires the “city” as meaning, this question becomes: What
applying the “orthogenetic principle”: “organisms is the nature and role of the meaning of the city in
are naturally directed towards a series of transforma- human relating to built environment? To proceed
tions—reflecting a tendency to move from a state of with this discussion, it is necessary to apply the

284 th e c i t y as a si g n
organismic-developmental framework to emergence constructs a reality” (1977, p. 8; see also the notion
of places from undifferentiated space and to intro- of experience in Boesch, 2012). Experience encom-
duce the notion of “experience of space.” A concep- passes the entire spectrum of possibilities of relating
tual framework pertinent to this task was developed to a reality11: sensation, perception, and conception
in human geography by Yi-Fu Tuan. on a continuum from more emotional to thought-
ful modes. It is externally related and ranges from
Experiential Geography and the Emergence passive contemplation to active exploration of the
of Meaningful Places world and acting in it.12
There isn’t one space, a beautiful space, a beautiful It should be noted that Tuan’s treatment of
space round about, a beautiful space all around us, experience is in broad accord with phenomenol-
there’s a whole lot of small bits of space, and one of ogy, and a relevant parallel can be made to Erving
these bits is a Métro corridor, and another of them Goffman’s Frame Analysis (1974/1986). Goffman,
is a public park . . . In short, spaces have multiplied, who was drawing on William James’s question,
been broken up and have diversified. There are spaces “Under what circumstances do we think things
today of every kind and every size, for every use and are real?” (James, Principles of Psychology, quoted
every function. To live is to pass from one space to in Goffman 1974/1986, p. 2, italics removed) as
another, while doing your very best not to bump well as on Alfred Schuetz’s (1945) phenomenology
yourself. of multiple realities defined as “provinces of mean-
(Perec, 1974/2008a, pp. 5–6) ing” (rather than provinces of being or physical exis-
tence), interpreted experience as anything that occurs
Georges Perec, the French writer and the keen- to a person in a situation. Goffman assumed “that
est observer of the “infra-ordinary” in the fabric of when individuals attend to any current situation,
our everyday life, understood the problem of this they face the question: ‘What is it that is going on
chapter only too well. His book, Species of Spaces here?’ ” (Goffman, 1974/1986, p. 8). Definitions of
(1974/2008a), which he himself aptly called a situations (a familiar term from phenomenology and
“sociological” undertaking on “how to look at symbolic interactionism) stem from answering this
the everyday” (Perec, 1978/2008c, p. 141), covers question.
exactly the different species of spaces—arranged on The crucial research problem becomes: how
the scale of rising abstraction from the book page can people make sense of situations, come up with
to apartment and street to the world and space in their definitions, and proceed with their activities?
general. In terms of the organismic-developmental That is, how is experience organized? Goffman’s aim
framework, emergence of species of space is the became “to try to isolate some of the basic frame-
result of differentiation of space—the “nothingness, works of understanding available in our society for
the impalpable, the virtually immaterial; extension, making sense out of events” (ibid., p. 10)13—and
the external, what is external to us, what we move his conceptual device was “frame”14: “definitions
about in the midst of, our ambient milieu, the space of a situation are built up in accordance with prin-
around us” (Perec, 1974/2008a, p. 5)—and its artic- ciples of organization which govern events—at least
ulation into meaningful places (which could be fol- social ones—and our subjective involvement in
lowed by hierarchical integration according to, for them . . . [frame analysis is] the examination in these
example, the relation to home). terms of the organization of experience” (ibid.,
pp. 10–11). The relevance of Goffman’s conceptual-
The Nature of Spatial Experience ization for the present theoretical framework is that
and Its Organization it explicitly postulates the fundamental necessity
What fuels this developmental process of differ- of meaning-making in situations—that is, of mak-
entiation and articulation, for Yi-Fu Tuan (1977), ing sense of experience—and raises the question
is experience of space. It is the key to conceptual- of organization of experience. Although his argu-
izing space and place and a means of distinguish- ments are made for social situations, and the pres-
ing the two without giving any of the concepts ent chapter is concerned with spatial experience, the
primacy. Experience is another foundational con- general question is the same, and the core issue is
cept in sciences that resists stable definition. Tuan to approach it developmentally: How do meanings
defined experience as “a cover-all term for the var- emerge in situations, and what is the effect of signs
ious modes through which a person knows and on experience?

kh a rl a m ov 285
What is spatial experience? Amedeo, Golledge, Thus, Tuan reinforces what is implicit in von
and Stimson underscore the relation of space to Uexküll’s Umwelt conception: Space is not in
situations: “[S]pace’s most dominant expression in and by itself a causal factor. Space alone is static
the human context [is] its role as a dimension in and inert. It is spatial experience, the developmental
situational surroundings in which human activities process of meaning-making, that produces an articu-
are commonly enacted and experiences are felt” lated and organized world of sensible places.15 This
(2009, p. 5). For Tuan (1977), similarly to Perec is consistent with the notion of space as a form of
(1974/2008a), space is general, unspecified, vague, social life introduced by Simmel in his attempt to
and expansive; there is little human attachment to develop the sociology of space in the seminal chap-
space. In von Uexküll’s terminology, it is nothing ter (Space and the Spatial Ordering of Society) of
more than a sign-based orientational framework his opus magnum, Sociology (Simmel, 1908/2009,
for the organism’s Umwelt. Space is the physical Chapter 9): “[S]pace remains always the form, in
environment before human experience. The devel- itself ineffectual, in whose modifications the real
opmental process of experience of environment energies are indeed revealed . . . Not space, but the
transforms it into place, which begins with a “pause psychologically consequential organization and
in movement”, allowing for the minimal moment concentration of its parts have social significance”
of attention to environment. “An object or place (pp. 543–544). Filippov (2008) clarifies that this
achieves concrete reality when our experience of it is is, in its foundation, a Kantian position, and that
total, that is through all the senses as well as with the what Simmel had in mind when he developed his
active and reflective mind” (Tuan, 1977, p. 18). sociology of space was a “concrete phenomenol-
ogy of sociality” (ibid., p. 106)—that is, an inquiry
From Space to Meaningful Places into how, in the course of social life, specific, con-
Tuan postulates that the process of experienc- crete, particular forms such as the “territory” or
ing the world and thus creating places is a universal the “boundary” become socially meaningful and
human process that also closely follows development hence attain an important role in social life (ibid.,
of human organisms through life-course, from birth p. 116). Importantly for the present discussion, the
to death. “All people undertake to change amor- city could be interpreted as one of such meaningful
phous space into articulated geography” (ibid., forms.16 Thus, Simmel’s sociology also leads to the
p. 83). This is the essence of environmental mean- issue of the organizing principle that transforms
ing-making and environmental knowing—and this abstract form of space into socially meaningful
conceptualization corresponds to developmental forms such as the city.
axioms expressed in Werner and Kaplan’s orthoge- As Agnew (2005) has suggested, Tuan’s concep-
netic principle (1963/1984). It occurs on an indi- tualization was one of the first attempts in con-
vidual level—as when I slowly learned the details of temporary human geography to seriously define
a stretch of the road to realize at one point that it space and place in a way that would not make one
passes by an airport. I acquired novel spatial knowl- prioritized at the expense of the other. Agnew has
edge (see Golledge & Stimson, 1997, Chapter 5). indicated that there are at least three meanings of
For each organism, development of complex spa- place that have to be accounted for: “as location or
tial knowledge presupposes mobility—movement, a site in space where an activity or object is located
with occasional pauses, through spaces and mak- and which relates to other sites or locations because
ing sense of them (Jensen, 2009; Urry, 2007). It of the interaction and movement between them”;
also occurs on collective level—“Polynesian and “as locale or setting where everyday-life activities
Micronesian navigators have conquered space by take place”; and “as sense of place or identifica-
transforming it into a familiar world of routes and tion with a place as a unique community, land-
places” (Tuan, 1977, p. 83)—and today, when scape and moral order” (ibid., p. 89). Implicitly,
satellites have ended geographical discoveries on Agnew has already situated these meanings on a
Earth, we continuously re-enact this articulation continuum from more detached and abstract to
through the practices of tourist gaze (Urry, 2002), more personal and embodied. In a humanistic per-
which has not subsided with the proliferation of spective, which both Tuan and Agnew follow, “the
electronic media and instantly accessible images of focus lies in relating location and locale to sense of
faraway places but, on the contrary, is further rein- place through the experiences of human beings as
forced by them. agents” (ibid.).

286 th e c i t y as a si g n
Spatial Cognition and Spatial Behavior: synonym to cognitive map—and clearly translated
Lessons from Environmental Psychology theoretical concern with representations of the city
and Behavioral Geography into practical terms of urban planning and archi-
Thus far, the outline of a developmental perspec- tectural design (his latter book, Good City Form
tive on meaning-making in the spatial Umwelten [1981], further developed normative standards for
of human beings bypassed the notions of spatial the highly legible city). The prominently applied
cognition and spatial behavior. These notions, how- character of Lynch’s research and the clear path to
ever, demarcate well-developed research programs practical recommendations led to lasting popularity
in the closely related fields of environmental psy- of mental mapping as well as the widespread focus
chology and behavioral geography, and therefore it on cognition of built environment.
is imperative to clearly identify their relevance in This applied focus on orienting in space has its
context of the present discussion, keeping in mind twin in research on navigating in space. Behavioral
the overarching interest in the meanings of spaces approach to the city favored by behavioral geog-
we inhabit. raphy is focused on the role of perception, cogni-
Research on spatial cognition and learning focuses tion, memory, and ability play in performance of
on how people acquire, store, and operate with the space-related tasks. A particularly important task is
information about space they inhabit (Golledge & orientation, or wayfinding (Golledge, 1999)—how
Stimson, 1997, Chapter 7). It is concerned with ori- humans get around the urban environment and
entation in space, and it assumes that humans rou- what factors facilitate success in these tasks.
tinely form representations of their environments, Both spatial cognition and spatial behavior
that environmental experience leaves a discernible perspectives have particular practical relevance to
trace in human memory, and that this trace is acces- design of environments—architectural design on
sible at some later point in time. This research pro- scale of small buildings, and urban and transpor-
gram fits into the broader paradigm of cognitive tation planning on the scale of cities and urban
science, whose “founding axioms are that people districts as wholes.18 They also often share the
come to know what is ‘out there’ in the world by cognitive-representational axiomatic base. Some inte-
representing it in the mind, in the form of ‘mental grative attempts have focused on linking cognitive
models’, and that such representations are the result representations and computations with behav-
of a computational process working upon informa- ioral performance, as in the proposal by Carlson,
tion received by the senses” (Ingold, 2000, p. 163). Hölscher, Shipley, and Dalton (2010) to consider
One particularly salient concept integrating the intersection of built environment, person’s cog-
research interest in spatial cognition is that of cog- nitive map, and individual strategies and abilities, as
nitive map—“an individual’s knowledge of spatial constituting the complex outcome of navigation in
and environmental relations, and the cognitive pro- space. Presumably, good fit between the three would
cesses associated with the encoding and retrieval of lead to successful performance, whereas (as in their
information from which it is composed” (Kitchin example of the recently constructed Seattle Public
& Blades, 2002, p. 1). This definition explicitly Library) lack of fit leads to confusion and frustra-
employs the metaphor of “map,” essentially posit- tion on part of the users.
ing that each of us has in our head a representation, It follows from the cognitivist, representational,
a version of space we know, and that we use it in a and behavioral axiomatic bases of these approaches
way similar to the way we use a paper map—to find that the inquiry is geared toward examining those
our way around. Kitchin and Blades (2002) have ways of relating to space that are relevant to task per-
provided one of the most integrative syntheses of formance, at the expense of other kinds of engagement
research using this concept. with environment, including aesthetic engagement.
Historically, cognitive mapping approach The latter is often subsumed under pragmatically
received a powerful thrust with the publication of defined qualities of aesthetic response to environ-
the seminal work of Kevin Lynch (1960). His book, ment, and linked back to cognition. Generally, this
The Image of the City, explicitly adopted a textual makes the inquiry functional—that is, it conceives
metaphor of urban environment as he was concerned of humans as users of environment who respond to
with legibility of the city—that is, the capability of it with more or less success and satisfaction. Indeed,
the environment to be read and understood by the since the early years of environment-behavior
urbanites.17 He used the notion of mental map—a research, satisfaction is often posited as the ultimate

kh a rl a m ov 287
goal of experience: “environmental experience is von Uexküll’s phenomenological meanings with
an active process in which the individual utilizes cognitive schemata, which potentially follow uni-
his resources in order to create a situation in which versalist principles. There is also a question regard-
he can carry out his activities with a maximum of ing whether it is possible to apply a developmental
satisfaction” (Ittelson, Franck, & O’Hanlon, 1976, axiomatic base to these approaches. Cultural vari-
p. 199). In less teleological versions it is still pos- ability is another domain where these approaches
ited as the most important evaluative domain of fall short as they implicitly follow cognitivist axi-
experience. Thus, Jack Nasar (1989) proposed to oms of universal perceptive-cognitive apparatus.
examine experience of urban public spaces (percep- The less clearly definable atmospheric (Antsiferov,
tion, cognition, and evaluation) through related 1925; Milgram, 1970/2010; Urry, 2007) qualities
concepts of urban cognition (“knowledge of where of environments, such as memory, desire, and spirit
we are—orientation—and how to get to desired recognized by Leonie Sandercock (1998/2003), also
destinations—wayfinding” [p. 33]) and urban easily evade such frameworks.
esthetics (“urban affect or perceived quality of the Finally, and most importantly for the purposes
urban surroundings” [ibid.]). Nasar’s suggestion to of this chapter, neither approach is concerned
assume that relations between “urban physical fea- with the specificity and distinctiveness of “species of
tures, perceptual/cognitive measures of those fea- space”—assuming uncritically that space, such
tures, affective appraisals of the scene, psychological as “city” or “town” or “Lake District” beloved by
well-being, and spatial behavior” (p. 37) explicitly Romantic poets Samuel Taylor Coleridge and
frames urban esthetics as following the same cog- William Wordsworth, is a given environment
nitivist input–output axiom. It thus reinforces the that people relate to using their particular mental
prominent “person–environment” dualism as well schemata or practical schemes. In that sense, space
as the older Cartesian ontology that “divorces the remains an external “independent variable” that is
activity of the mind from that of the body in the not explicitly addressed from a psychological stand-
world [so that the] body continues to be regarded as point. Indeed, it could be said that the urban focus
nothing more than an input device whose role is to of wayfinding studies stems much more from the
receive information to be ‘processed’ by the mind, demands of urban policy and concerns of traffic
rather than playing any part in cognition itself ” planning than from internal theoretical concerns.
(Ingold, 2000, p. 165). In this it much more follows what Ingold (2000)
Transactional approach in environmental psy- called the building perspective than the experiential,
chology (Werner & Altman, 2000) offers a less existential, phenomenological dwelling perspective
explicitly teleological and cognitivist perspective he has advocated.
that attempts to bridge the gap between environ-
ment and the human as it defines people and situ- Encountering the Environment
ation holistically “by their unifying processes, and If persons and environments are in a mutually
the changing relations among them” and “empha- constitutive relationship, then the issue becomes
sizes the dynamic unity between people and set- how to conceptualize the connection between them.
ting” (ibid., p. 23). Werner and Altman have In Goffman’s (1974/1986) framework, experience
further stipulated that time and change are intrinsic of social situations presumably requires being in a
to the person–environment phenomena and that social situation or being exposed to one. What does
there are multiple perspectives on the same situ- it mean to be an environmental situation? What does
ation, which should be interpreted in terms of its it mean to be exposed to the world? More apposite
patterns and forms rather than determinist cause- to the task at hand: If space as such is undefined and
and-effect chains. This approach, however, does not abstract, and place is a result of its becoming mean-
specify what role meanings play in relation of people ingful through human experience, then what are
to environments nor does it contain conceptual tools conditions under which experience happens? And
to approach cultural diversity of possible person– what is the nature of the emerging meaning?
environment relations. What is missing in the scheme so far is a con-
To sum up, cognitive-representational and ceptual tool that would bring together persons and
behavioral approaches broadly focus on represen- environments and clarify where and under what cir-
tations of space that people have and the behavior cumstances, spaces become places and pauses occur
people manifest in space. This essentially replaces in movements. The nature of the intersection of

288 th e c i t y as a si g n
time and space, that moment of being open to the infrastructure in the largest metropoli of the world.
world (cf. Agamben, 2002/2004) at which experi- Second, attachment to place and meaning of place
ence creates places and emerges as urban experience, as a dwelling or home is itself never fixed, a reached
should be identified. goal, but always a meaning-in-the-making.
One of the ways of conceptualizing this intersec- In developmental terms, then, encounter is what
tion is to use the term encounter. Amin and Thrift brings the city into being as a novel experience in the
(2002) have developed this notion to establish a irreversible time. It is only in encounters that places
basic ontology for an everyday urbanism that would become “urban”: “places . . . are best thought of
attempt to “grasp the significant banality of everyday not so much as enduring sites but as moments of
life in the city” (pp. 8–9). Encounter, the minimal encounter, not so much as ‘presents’, fixed in space
building block of urban life, is the coming together and time, but as variable events; twists and fluxes
of different entities. In our case, these entities are of interrelation” (Amin & Thrift, 2002, p. 30). In
human and the urban environment (although Amin a similar way, Jensen defines place as “mobility-de-
and Thrift forcefully reject limiting the enquiry to fined spatio-temporal event that relates to the way
just humans but include all the different kinds of life we configure narratives of self and other” (2009, p.
in the city, such as animal life). “The city is made up 147), thus connecting place to subjectivity and iden-
of potential and actual entities/associations/togeth- tity. In summary, places are not stable and given in
ernesses which there is no going beyond to find advance, not external independents—as they are for
anything ‘more real’ ” (p. 27). Process and potentiali- cognitive-representational environmental psychol-
ties are the watchwords of encounter ontology that ogy and behavioral geography—they only become
focuses on processual, dynamic character of reality. places when humans encounter space, and only in
Encounter is the formative “being there,” which this encounter places develop as such.20
all experience of spaces begins with, the moment
of exposure to the environment, the moment when Organizing Experience: Signs and the
human (without differentiating mind and body) is Regulatory Function of Culture
phenomenally exposed to the world.19 Experience emerges in the encounter of human
The most important contribution of this notion to and environment. It is what transforms spaces into
the present framework is that it explicitly renders the meaningful places. It is also what constitutes urban
city in a processual, developmental way, emphasiz- life on the most basic level. Experience, however, is
ing the moment of becoming: “encounter, and reac- not predetermined by the setting so that each per-
tion to it, is a formative element in the urban world” son entering the setting would experience the same
(Amin & Thrift, 2002, p. 30). Neither the city nor thing (this is what the adepts of spatial determin-
the human experience of it is thus pre-given, as built ism would have us believe, and this is what cogni-
environment or as cognitive representations. On the tivist-representational frameworks tend to draw in
contrary, they only come together, and inseparably, through the back door). Neither is it entirely free-
in the actual encounter. Encounter of human and flowing. The crucial issue is to consider what regu-
space is exactly what gives rise to experience that lates the emerging experience.
transforms mere point in space into what Agnew
(2005) interpreted as a defined location, a locale of Culturally Specific Ways of Relating to
activities, and a sense of place. The dynamic char- the World: Erving Goffman’s Insights
acter of encounter emphasized by Amin and Thrift This question logically follows from the devel-
allows us to clarify two of Tuan’s (1977, p. 198) rel- opmental approach as it is the question about how
evant arguments on place and time. Tuan has stated novelty—in each moment of experience—emerges
that it takes a pause in time and movement for a and develops. Ingold identified the anthropolog-
place to emerge and that it takes time for attachment ical dimension of this question (the anthropolog-
to place to develop. Conceptualizing experience as ical problem of perception and cognition) as the
an emergent outcome of encountering space allows problem of cultural variation: “Take people from
making these arguments dynamic. First, no place is different backgrounds and place them in the same
just one pause in movement. Indeed, even for the situation: they are likely to differ in what they
“stable” aboriginal communities referenced by Tuan, make of it” (2000, p. 157). This is what Goffman
keeping place stable is an achievement, a result of (1974/1986) was concerned with when he con-
routine day-to-day work akin to maintaining urban structed his frame analysis. For Goffman, it is the

kh a rl a m ov 289
“primary frameworks,” “schemata of interpretation,” p. 52 ff.) between the organism’s inner world and its
that are responsible for “rendering what would oth- environment (as well as between Umwelten of dif-
erwise be a meaningless aspect of the scene into ferent organisms and species). Thus, the relation is
something that is meaningful” (1974/1986, p. 21). mediated by meaning.
These frameworks are shared among members of a Valsiner (2007, p. 32 ff.) interpreted this medi-
group and are the foundation of its culture21: ating function of meaning as semiotic mediation
within the larger understanding of culture as reflex-
Taken all together, the primary frameworks of a
ive distancing of human and the world, which at the
particular social group constitute a central element
same time plays a regulative role vis-à-vis psychic
of its culture, especially insofar as understandings
processes.
emerge concerning principal classes of schemata,
the relations of these classes to one another, and the The person creates a distance—by way of semiotic
sum total of forces and agents that these interpretive mediation—in relation to the here-and-now
designs acknowledge to be loose in the world. context . . . This reflection—which is cognitive and
(Goffman, 1974/1986, p. 27) affective at the same time—allows the psychological
system to consider contexts of the past, imagine
Human culture is thus first and foremost the spe-
the contexts of the future, and take perspectives of
cific way of relating to the world. Unfortunately, the
other persons (in the form of empathy).
notion of frame, apparently contrary to intentions
(Valsiner, 2007, p. 33)
of Goffman as well as Bateson (1972), from whose
work on play and fantasy the notion originated, Culture “takes the form of constructing and using
has come to bear a lot of resemblance to cognitivist signs to transform the here-and-now setting of the
computational schemata. Also, in Goffman’s treat- human being . . . human cultural relating to the world
ment this notion and the entire analytical apparatus entails simultaneous closeness to, and distancing from,
of frame analysis is limited to social situations and the actual situation the person is in” (Valsiner, 2007,
their definitions—leaving out nonsocial experience p. 72, italics in original). In place of Goffman’s frames
as well as affective, emotional dimension of expe- and cognitivist computational schemata, this concep-
rience.22 How then could we approach the issue of tualization identifies signs as specific mediators and
organization and regulation of experience—in our regulators. Through specific identifiable signs, cul-
case, spatial experience—while keeping in mind ture regulates the affective engagement with envi-
Goffman’s insight about its cultural specificity? ronment. Emergent meanings (or, in semiotic terms,
signs) serve a function of connecting the inner world
Semiotic Mediation and Regulation of the organism with the world around the organism.
in Umwelten Some of these signs attain the property of being “pro-
One conceptual advantage of von Uexküll’s con- moter signs”—signs that guide “the possible range
ception of Umwelt is that it is explicitly concerned of variability of meaning-construction in the future”
with theorizing the relation between the organism (Valsiner, 2007, p. 58).
and the environment. Instead of following a behav- This raises the question of levels of development,
iorist mechanistic tradition23 of theorizing this rela- and given the present concern with the most basic
tion away, he established a functional circle between encounter with space in Thirdspace (Soja, 2000),
the inner and the outer world of the organism. the proper level to start the inquiry would be micro-
genesis—“a form of emergence (and disappearance)
Umwelt as the world of meaningful objects, is
of biological, psychological form within an immedi-
always paired by its intra-organismic counterpart—
ate, short time frame” (Valsiner, 2007, p. 356, n. 1).
Innenwelt (inner world). If umwelt denotes the
As “the human immediate living experience is pri-
outside world as it appears to the animal via its
marily microgenetic, occurring as the person faces the
perceptual and motor apparatus, then Innenwelt
ever-new next time moment in the infinite sequence
refers to the experience side of the phenomena as
of irreversible time” (ibid., p. 301), humans organize
experienced by the organism.
this experience developmentally through signs. This
(Magnus & Kull, 2012, p. 651, italics in original)
microgenetic process is part of a larger hierarchical
The vehicle of this relation is meaning—which developmental structure involving also mesogenesis
plays a connecting role (von Uexküll drew a musical (process in structured, repetitive situated activity
analogy to counterpoint in composition, 1940/1982, contexts) and ontogenesis (development over the

290 th e c i t y as a si g n
life-course). Encounters develop microgenetically is regulated once a meaning of space is established.
(see Valsiner, 2007, Chapter 8, for methodological When we encounter space, we interpret it as some-
approaches to microgenesis; Wagoner, 2009, devel- thing (e.g., as an “urban street”). Our future relation
ops constructive microgenesis as an experimental to it as well as our memory of all past experience of
methodology). it is developmentally mediated and regulated by this
Thus, microgenesis is regulated by culture. Culture, newly emerged spatial sign—a mediating-regulating
however, is not a whole outside the individual (and sign that constitutes the meaning of place (or one of
thus having an objective reality qua Durkheim’s social several such signs). Space is identified as species.
fact), akin to society or economy. Culture in this sense “The Rue Vilin starts level with No 29 in the Rue
is personal (Valsiner, 2000, p. 55 ff.; Valsiner, 2007, des Couronnes, opposite some new blocks of coun-
p. 60) and is constituted by development of the per- cil flats, recently built with something old about
son and their prior experience in the realm of “inter- them already”—thus George Perec (1977/2008b,
personal signs-mediated communicative processes” p. 212) identified his object of interest, recogniz-
(ibid.; the latter forming collective culture having no ing it as a “member” of the species of “the street”
reality and causality outside these interpersonal com- (cf. his analysis of this species, 1974/2008a, p. 46 ff.).
municative semiotic processes).24 Accordingly, the Choosing his scale and applying boundaries to his
process of experience is developmentally regulated by object of interest (operations he did as a person—
culture through specific signs. and which regulated his further inquiry into this
street; what for us as geographers and sociologists is
Spatial Signs as Species of Spaces a matter of heated debates is resolved practically out
How does the organization of spatial experience there on a daily basis for us as persons), he proceeded
look in light of this framework? It is time to bring to meticulously record and describe six encounters
all elements of the framework together. A develop- with “Rue Vilin,” each connected to the previous
mental perspective entails assuming a processual and each organized by this sign.
vision of experience as emerging in irreversible
time. Experiential humanistic geography interprets Developmental Model of Experience
places as created and maintained by human spatial of Spatial Encounter
experience—as entities imbued with a certain This conceptual framework could be integrated
meaning. Encounter ontology presupposes that the into a microgenetic developmental model repre-
only reality spaces have is the reality they assume sented in Figure 13.2. At the center of the model
when humans exist and live in space, and places is encounter—the lived presence of the person in
are thus moments of encounter of organism with the spatial world. Experience of this encounter
environment. Finally, it follows from the notion is mediated and microgenetically organized and
of Umwelt and semiotic mediation perspective regulated by spatial signs and proceeds by way of
on microgenetic organization of experience that von Uexküll’s functional circle of perception and
through specific signs, personal culture regulates the action. Spatial signs emerge out of personal cul-
functional relation of organism and environment— ture and achieve a unique encounter-specific con-
environmental experience—and mediates it. figuration that defines that particular experience
(although it may bear resemblance, or similarity, to
The Nature of Spatial Signs other encounters). Through their promoter func-
Spatial experience is organized by specific cul- tion, spatial signs create grounds for future mean-
tural signs. What are these signs? They are precisely ing construction within the same encounters (at
what Perec’s (1974/2008a) species of spaces are for the very next moment) and beyond it. By the same
each of us. From the standpoint of individual expe- token, space is articulated into places, which enter
rience, signs that we draw from our personal culture memory as encounter fades into the past to form
and create on the basis of it function in the domain the foundations for future potential encounters in
of spatial experience as those meanings that space irreversible time. Thus the process of living in space
attains for us, thus becoming identified as meaningful is formed by a multitude of encounters that flow
place. It is on the basis of this identification that our into one another as we move through space in time
past experience of space is re-interpreted and future (or stand in one place while time goes by).
experience of space is projected. On the same basis, Thus my own experience of the road near Worcester
our cognitive and affective relation to environment Regional Airport is partly mediated and regulated now

kh a rl a m ov 291
Articulated Geography:
Abstract Geography: PLACES
SPACE (Moments of Encounter)
ENVIR
ONME
NT
Functional Circle:
Experience Mediated-
Regulated by Spatial Signs

st
Pa

Cr
of

eat
ion

ion
MEA
eat

of
NING
Cr

Fu
tur
e
PERCEPTION ACTION

PER
SON

Personal Culture

Past Experience: Encounter:


Future Experience:
MEMORY HERE-AND-NOW
POTENTIAL ENCOUNTER
BECOMING

DEVELOPMENT IN IRREVERSIBLE TIME

Figure 13.2 Microgenetic Developmental Model of Experience of Spatial Encounter

by the sign “Worcester Regional Airport”—and given fields feed on specific affective states (such as fear and
that whenever I was driving there I did not know or panic) and elevate these states into high-level regu-
remember the name of the road (as an anxious learner, latory signs such as “night,” associated with fear of
I was more concerned with making a smooth turn strangers and feeding into our perceiving the same
into the road without making my encounter with the places differently at night and during daytime. In this
nearest telegraph pole a bodily encounter than with way we can read, through developmental-experiential
reading the sign with the road’s name), this road is still lens, Williams (2008) excavation of night spaces as
identified for me by that sign in terms of its location. fundamental spaces in social life in terms of dynam-
Even as I write these words I have no map and no ics of territorialization (control by forces of govern-
Internet access to discover its true name. (Does it have mentality), deterritorialization (transgression and
any relevance for me though?) disruption of social order), and reterritorialization
But there are many other signs that regulate the (re-establishment of control).25 For example, the
experience of that road for me—some of those being same street in Moscow (Figs. 13.3 and 13.4, taken at
hypergeneralized affective semiotic fields (Valsiner, the same date) during daytime and nighttime exhib-
2007, pp. 51, 312 ff.) belonging to the upper levels its vastly different visual cues related to light, dark-
of affective regulation and only partially accessible ness, presence of people, speeds of cars, and others;
to my verbalizations of them. Those semiotic fields but importantly, we microgenetically make sense of
encompass my subjective, personal, private experi- all these visual cues here-and-now, in an encounter,
ence of driving the motor vehicle for the first time under the regulatory influence of night as an over-
myself and the associated combination of excitement, arching cultural meaning.
anxiety, and other feelings that will possibly reverber- Thus, “species of spaces” signs are only part of
ate in my memory for years to come. Other semiotic the story of semiotic mediation of environmental

292 th e c i t y as a si g n
Figure 13.3 Myasnitskaya Street, Moscow,
Russia, in daytime
(Photograph by author, 2006)

Figure 13.4 Myasnitskaya Street, Moscow,


Russia, at night
(Photograph by author, 2006)

experience. They are not the least important part, close to the city center and the Edinburgh Castle,
however, and this part is especially pertinent when yet hardly noticing it.
it comes to recognizing the city as a sign. An array of spatial signs such as “Edinburgh”
and “pedestrian walkway” regulates experience
The City As a Sign, or Recognizing of this walkway. One such sign is “city.” Indeed,
Species of Settlements although several parts of the walkway could appear
Water of Leith is a small river that runs through suburban (assuming that “suburbia” could be rec-
the city of Edinburgh. It ends in Leith, where it ognized visually through features such as single-
flows into the Firth of Forth. A pedestrian walk- family homes with lawns), knowing that the walk
way (Fig. 13.5) was constructed some years ago on goes through Edinburgh leaves its impression on
the bank of the river. On this walkway, a person experiencing this walk, depending on, for example,
can walk through Edinburgh starting in the sub- whether the person associates “danger of crime”
urbs and finishing the walk on the shore of the sea. (another regulating sign) with “the city.”
Depending on the exact starting location, an average Similarly, recognizing that some place is an
person could walk this route in about a day, passing “inner city” in the United States is enough to trigger
different parts of Edinburgh, for a while being very a panic affective response in many people, although

kh a rl a m ov 293
Figure 13.5 Water of Leith Walkway, Edinburgh, Scotland
(Photograph by author, 2007)

it may have nothing to do with whether this place experience as something other than urban—as with
is “objectively” an inner city (as defined by urban someone from Western Europe “failing to recog-
sociologists and demographers) or whether at the nize” a middle-sized American city as a “city” in the
given time of the day in the given place there is any sense that urban life has for them (Fig. 13.6).
“objective” (as defined by crime statistics) or “real” Developmental-experiential approach to mean-
(as defined by the actual presence of criminals look- ing of the city thus starts with the encounter and
ing for someone to mug or rape) danger of crime. emergence of experience. It is concerned with the
ongoing, here-and-now process of meaning-mak-
“The City”: Spatial Sign Designating ing, as opposed to relatively static representations
a Specific Species of Space of space that are supposed to have stability and
The story of Water of Leith indicates that for duration in human memory—such as cognitive
a particular person, the experience of encounter- maps and attitudes. The focus on meaning-making
ing space proceeds by way of semiotic regulation process means that task-performance fades into
before and partially independently from objective background, and non-pragmatic ways of meaning-
(physical, material) properties of that space. For the making, such as aesthetic judgment (beyond simple
meaning of the city—or for construing the city as a “good–bad” dimensions), emerge as visible to this
sign—this entails that “the city” is precisely a regula- approach. In short, “the city” is one of the spatial
tive sign that operates as a guide for the emerging expe- signs that we routinely employ as an organizing
rience. When this sign is activated in an encounter principle for our experience of environments where
with environment, it serves as a field-like promoter we live and travel.
sign that allows the entire setting and the experience
of this setting to be recognized as—and thus made Reversal of Objectivist Urbanism:
sense of as—urban setting and urban experience. It Exploring the Meaning of the City
follows that if the person is not equipped with a The concern with meaning of the city thus takes
sign that bears that meaning, meaning-making can the following form: What are the conditions for
proceed in a way that will not designate experience emergence of such a meaning attached to space, that
of place as urban experience. Similarly, if these signs places emerge as urban places? In other words, in
are not activated, meaning-making may organize which kinds of situations humans in their everyday

294 th e c i t y as a si g n
Figure 13.6 Dewey Street, Worcester, MA
(Photograph by author, 2010)

life understand their surroundings as being urban as that which humans create through experiencing
surroundings? general and unspecified space, the humanistic per-
Behind this simple wording, in fact, is a rever- spective on space and place allows us to approach
sal of the usual way of defining the city “from upside- the issue of ostensiveness of the city in a person-
down” typical of traditional urban disciplines such oriented processual way. Human geography and
as urban geography. These disciplines routinely urban sociology often work with defining the city in
specify physical characteristics of territories (e.g., an “objective” fashion (thus working in “space over
having dense built environment), social character- place” mode in terms of Agnew, 2005), through
istics of the population (e.g., size, density, perma- properties of physical distribution of things on a
nence, heterogeneity famously indicated by Louis territory. The city thus becomes a sufficiently dense
Wirth, 1938), economic functions (e.g., predomi- set of buildings, pavements, and human bodies. In
nantly industrial or service economy whether mea- contrast, from a humanistic standpoint, the urban
sured in terms of occupational structure or types is first and foremost a specific meaning attached to
of businesses), or similar characteristics that are these things.
located outside persons and are expected to project
urbanism onto persons living in these conditions. In Conclusions: Situating Human Life
that sense, it fundamentally goes against the simple in Settlement Space
spatial determinism characteristic of some strands Luhmann (1984/1995) famously started his
of urban planning (epitomized by utopian modern- theorizing of social systems from the assertion that
ism of Le Corbusier) and conceptions of ideal city his “considerations assume that there are systems”
whereby “good” urban life is determined by and (ibid., p. 12). His theory explicitly postulated that
consequently is achievable through “good” design social systems have communication as their basic
(Kharlamov, 2010). constitutive element—and that analysis of commu-
Simply put, the city is a meaning—and therefore nication in social systems can proceed without con-
exploring what is a city entails exploring the diver- sidering persons—as individuals or as selves—at all.
sity of meanings that ordinary people (rather than In fact, for Luhmann, social systems have nothing
what planners, administrators, or even depersonal- to do with people at all, even as groups or popula-
ized sciences classified as “urban studies” mean by tions. His systems theory suggests that selves and
it) create that allow them to qualify certain places as persons do not exist—rather, the domain of psychic
urban places, as well as the process of emergence of life should be reconfigured in psychology as a psy-
these meanings itself.26 chic system.
By bringing together the developmental nature This radical formulation illustrates very well what
of human psychic processes and the notion of place all the traditional ways of looking at cities share:

kh a rl a m ov 295
the tendency to look at wholes above individuals or of species of space (or settlement space, if we are
wholes to which individuals are entirely irrelevant as to borrow Gans’ term) could add to objectivist
the primary foci of inquiry. Built environment, econ- approaches that would classify places that people
omy, community, neighborhood—all are examples create and live according to their properties (social,
of such wholes. At best, persons get reduced to being economic, material, and other) is an insight into the
members of populations or communities. ordinary meanings that people routinely employ
Starting from the elementary encounter of an to make sense of their surroundings. These might
individual person with space requires reversing this or might not correspond to “objective” dimension,
kind of frameworks. This reversal task has particu- and it is this domain of correspondence-non-cor-
lar salience for urban studies as they struggle with respondence where most fruitful transdisciplinary
the evident failure of the rural–urban dichotomy on integration could be hoped for.
which they have constructed themselves. Presumably,
urban geography deals with urban space, and urban Future Directions: Integrating Cultural
economics deals with urban economy; however, in Psychology With Urban Sociology and
the world where regional economies take the form Geography
of urbanized regions without any discernible city The proposed developmental-experiential per-
center (Fishman, 1987; Dear & Flusty, 1998; Soja, spective on human spatial life opens up a number
2000), this self-definition loses all utility and serves of lines of future inquiry. At the center of this pos-
as a source of confusion. sible research program is, to draw on the title of
In fact, there is nothing very new about this; Milgram’s seminal article (1970/2010), the experi-
in 1976 Castells was already questioning whether ence of living in spaces, or, in terms of Soja (2000),
urban sociology had any salient subject matter. Thirdspace.
Thirty-three years later, Gans (2009) criticized the The first direction is to examine the immense
metro-centrism of American urban sociology, which variety of settlements that people create and inhabit.
concerned itself almost exclusively with a small More specifically, the issue is what spatial signs define
number of iconic cities such as Chicago, New York, these settlements. Recent calls for de-metrocentriz-
and Los Angeles. Gans’ choice of the central orga- ing urban studies (Bell & Jayne, 2009; Bunnell
nizing category to replace “urban” is settlement: & Maringanti, 2010; Gans, 2009) have forcefully
argued against limiting inquiries to a small number
A focus on settlements would suggest examining and
of paradigmatic metropoli—a tendency that could
comparing the interactions, routine and unusual,
be traced back to Simmel (1903/1997). A particu-
peaceful and conflict ridden, and competitive and
larly important issue that emerges is to closely study
cooperative among and between all the various
“the city” as one of the most prominent and salient
groups and institutions without concern as to
spatial signs, especially when it comes to differen-
whether they were urban or not but without losing
tiating cities. What could be “large” and “small”
sight of the fact that they are settlements.
for urban geography may not be the same as large
(Gans, 2009, p. 215)
and small for many people who simply live in cit-
What this proposal best captures is that wherever ies. Perhaps, personally and culturally specific tax-
humans live, they appropriate environment around onomies of settlements, dwellings, and other species
them as their Umwelt. They settle—or, in Ingold’s of spaces could emerge as the outcome, a la the
(2000) terms, dwell—in space: “it is through being Linnaeus standard biological classification system.
inhabited, rather than through its assimilation to a Second, models of individual development are
formal design specification, that the world becomes needed to account for the immense intrapersonal
a meaningful environment for people” (p. 173). variation in these “taxonomies of spaces.” In other
Hence the issue is to put a more nuanced concep- words, on a mesogenetic and ontogenetic level, each
tual system in place of the old rural–urban dichot- of us develops our spatial taxonomies over time, and
omy. In other words, it is necessary to de-essentialize these taxonomies serve as further repertoires of spa-
spaces, or territories (Brighenti, 2010) as well as the tial signs to regulate future experiences.
notion of “amorphous, non-differentiated space,” Third, on an interpersonal level, the important
which could have no more salience to a non- issue is how relatively stable shared cultural complexes
geographer and non-psychologist than “standard of spatial signs emerge in communicative processes
metropolitan statistical area.” What a psychology of collective cultures.

296 th e c i t y as a si g n
Fourth, it is important to understand what the tackled using this approach. Cities—and, for that
configurations that spatial signs enter are and what matter, all places—have identities that we recognize
are the regulative outcomes of these configura- as salient, and thus no matter how many skyscrapers
tions (e.g., coupling “inner city” with “danger of are there in the world, there is only one Manhattan,
crime” and the resulting affective reaction of “fear”). and no matter how many cities were built around
Further, it is important to study the specific char- medieval fortifications, there is only one Moscow
acteristics of these signs and configurations, such as with its Kremlin and only one Warsaw with its forti-
hierarchical organization and propensity to verbal- fications built anew after it was leveled by bombs in
ization and expression in other forms. World War II. Dresden, Coventry, Hiroshima, and
Fifth, situations of ambiguity and ambivalence Nagasaki, for that matter, did not lose their “souls”
are an important area of research, such as when with the destruction of material built environment
people employ different and/or conflicting spatial but, rather, solidified them and added new dimen-
signs in their ongoing meaning-making. Study of sions to them.
boundaries (such as boundaries between differ- Seventh, the presented developmental-experien-
ent city areas or boundaries associated with differ- tial approach to human spatiality should be taken
ent affective reactions—e.g., “ghetto begins on the further along the lines of accounting for time and
other side of this street”), boundaries, and their sociality. The temporal dimension emphasized by
maintenance and transgressions may be among the Castells with reference to social life in network
most fruitful areas in this respect (Brighenti, 2010; society (Castells, 1996/2010, Chapter 7) is fun-
Kaganskiy, 1983; Rodoman, 1983). One interesting damental for the approach and is reflected in the
concept to develop in this way is Foucault’s notion notion of irreversible time (Valsiner, 2007) in which
of heterotopias: development occurs. This dimension needs to be
coherently and thoroughly conceptualized, includ-
real places, effective places, places that are written
ing the personal perception of time and temporality
into the institution of society itself, and that are a
and the role of time in organization of experience.
sort of counter-emplacements, a sort of effectively
The social dimension should be integrated with the
realized utopias in which the real emplacements, all
spatial dimension, as many spatial encounters are
the other real emplacements that can be found within
also encounters with others (Amin & Thrift, 2002),
culture, are simultaneously represented, contested
and this bridging of the frameworks would allow
and inverted; a kind of places that are outside all
accessing the rich theoretical resources such as the
places, even though they are actually localizable.
work of Mead (1934) and Goffman (1974/1986).
(Foucault, 1967/2008, p. 17)
In particular, these two dimensions are indispens-
This notion has been developed in multiple ways able for accounting for the unique nature of city life
to account for ambiguous spaces, including some understood so well by Simmel (1903/1997). These
of the spaces that writers such as Sorkin (1992) dimensions could also add to the understanding of
and Davis and Monk (2007) classified, respectively, new role of virtual worlds, these “new fractal social
as theme parks and evil paradises (see collection spaces” (Urry, 2007, p. 181) that are enabled by com-
of applications of the concept of heterotopia in municative technologies creating “connections and
Dehaene & De Cauter, 2008). These spaces oscil- communities [that] are simultaneously private and
late between different spatial regimes and functions public, intimate and distant” (ibid.). Indeed, whole
and routinely misplace stable spatial orders in ways new social realms emerge in the virtual worlds such
reminiscent of keying and rekeying in Goffman’s as Second Life, and many of these at least attempt to
frame analysis (1974/1986). The enterprise of “het- simulate, emulate, and recreate the urban space and
erotopology”, the science of heterotopias, (Foucault, urban experience.
1967/2008), would benefit greatly from a personal Eighth, new methodologies need to be developed
perspective, a psychology of heterotopias and other that would grasp encounter in its microgenetic
strange places (cf. Edensor’s, 2005, analysis of indus- developmental unfolding. These methodologies
trial ruins as ambiguous spaces). might follow the track of controlled field experi-
Sixth, the questions first asked by Antsiferov ments (Ittelson, Franck, & O’Hanlon, 1976) and
(1925), on what defines the soul, the unique synthetic more generally the recent trend toward mobile
identity of the city, and Milgram (1970/2010), on methodologies (Büscher & Urry, 2009; Fincham,
the atmosphere of great cities, could be fruitfully McGuinness, & Murray, 2010; Büscher, Urry, &

kh a rl a m ov 297
Witchger, 2011) such as go-alongs (Kusenbach, Filippov and Nikita Pokrovsky helped me in many more ways than
2003). The notion of non-representational theory I can account for. I am grateful to the members of the Kitchen
Seminar at Clark University, on whose cutting board I was a happy
(Thrift, 2008) captures very well the methodologi- fish more than once. This research was presented at the Perceptive
cal necessity to go beyond assumptions of cognitive Minds and Affective Bodies in Urban Environment symposium at
representations (and the corresponding empirical Aalborg University in October 2010. This research was supported
reliance on laboratory experiments popular in cog- by the Oxford Russia Fund Scholarship (2005–2007), Oxford
nitive psychology) to grasp the affective, performa- Russia Fund Adam Smith Scholarship (2007), and Foundation for
Urban and Regional Studies Studentship (2009–2011).
tive nature of experience. Thus, Urry reminds that
the atmosphere of places is “in the relationship of
peoples and objects. It is something sensed often Notes
through movement and experienced in a tactile kind 1. I find strange the common (and dating back even to Sim-
mel and before) use of the adjective “psychological” to denote
of way, what Thrift terms ‘non-representational’ prac-
mental processes, whereas the adjective “psychic” is reserved
tices (1996)” (Urry, 2007, p. 73; see Jensen, 2009, for weird things such as telepathy. This use essentially suggests
for a conceptualization of ordinary urban mobility that what is happening in our heads exists only insomuch as it is
as a meaningful practice and a site for interaction). accounted for by professionally trained people graduating with
Although it may be wise—contrary to some propo- degrees in science of psychology. However, I am optimistic about
the propensity of humans to maintain active and healthy psychic
nents of non-representational theory—to retain the
life without the intrusion of white-coated and/or tie-wearing pro-
vision of theory as at least one of the outcomes of fessionals, at least most of the time—just as we seldom need soci-
inquiry. These new methodologies could be fruit- ologists to live active and healthy “social” lives. Hence, through
fully grounded in cultural-developmental psychology this chapter the term psychic, with the exception of quotations,
(Valsiner, 2007, Chapter 8). will be used to denote mental phenomena. The term psychological
will be reserved for those phenomena that are made accountable
Finally, integrative efforts should be directed
for by means of the science of psychology, or for the concepts and
toward recognizing the complexity and emergent char- standpoints used therein.
acter of life in space—which is impossible to account 2. In fact, the original German title of Simmel’s lecture,
for from any one standpoint including the experien- Die Gro βstädte und das Geistesleiben, could be translated as The
tial standpoint. Rather, it is important to establish metropoli and the spiritual life. Nikolai Antsiferov does not cite
Simmel, but given that a Russian translation (using the word
common grounds between different disciplinary
“spiritual” rather than “mental” in the title) was made shortly
efforts at understanding human life in space. Space, after the initial German publication, it is entirely possible that
its use, and experience of it all come together in the Antsiferov developed his notion of “soul of the city” and his pro-
complex interplay of affect, meaning, culture, social posal for urban psychology under Simmel’s influence.
relations, technologies, and environmental settings 3. Methodologically, the APA report hardly goes beyond calls
for mixing qualitative and quantitative approaches as well as calls
that human living is about. Hence, urban psychol-
for interdisciplinarity and using methods borrowed from other
ogy, or settlement psychology (not coterminous with disciplines (APA, 2005, pp. 45–48). One interesting proposal
either ecological or environmental psychology), contained in the report is to adopt a “strength-based approach,”
could complement settlement sociology and settle- recognizing that urban life is not all about decay and disorder,
ment geography in exploring—empirically as well and that in addition to infamous deficits and drawbacks, there
are unique strengths that urban individuals, families, communi-
as theoretically—the personal, psychic, existential
ties, and cultural groups have.
meaning of our habitats. This concerted effort is 4. “Urban” is defined in the report as “Settlements or
essential today if we are to revive utopian thinking localities defined as ‘urban’ by national statistical agencies”
and constructively assess what human life in spaces (UNFPA, 2007, p. 6). Its authors immediately explain them-
is and how to make it better and more just in face selves: “since mindsets, planning efforts and data are still com-
partmentalized, the rural-urban distinction is still necessary,
of the challenges of overpopulation, slumming, ten-
although imprecise . . . the deficiencies of . . . data are less sig-
sions and conflicts along identity lines, and global nificant when analyzing broad trends and prospects of urban
warming and resource exhaustion—challenges growth at the world and regional levels” (ibid., p. 7). Thus,
that target every city in the world today much as they imply that there is a tacit knowledge of what urban and
the individualist spirit of modernity, according to rural means, shared by professionals and laypeople alike.
5. The paradigmatic status of Los Angeles has been largely
Simmel (1903/1997), converged on the fin-de-siè-
crystallized through the efforts of the self-proclaimed “Los Ange-
cle Berlin. les School of Urbanism.” Michael Dear and Edward Soja are the
most prominent representatives of this group (the foundational
Acknowledgements works of the “school” are assembled in Dear, 2002, and Scott &
I am indebted to Svetlana Bankovskaya and Jaan Valsiner, Soja, 1996).
who have supported the development of the ideas presented in 6. The great urbanist Jane Jacobs (1961/1993) called diver-
this chapter in various contexts over the past 4 years. Alexander sity the main principle of the city: “This ubiquitous principle is

298 th e c i t y as a si g n
the need of cities for a most intricate and close-grained diversity away from anthropocentrism, evident, for example, in “animal
of uses that give each other constant mutual support, both eco- geographies” (Wolch & Emel, 1998).
nomically and socially” (p. 19). “City diversity itself permits and 11. It should be remembered that realities, in von Uexküll’s
stimulates more diversity” (ibid., p. 190), asserted Jacobs, and for theoretical biology as well as in phenomenology in general, are
her this was the diversity of uses of places coupled with the diver- multiple (Schuetz, 1945) and are different even in the subjective
sity of intentions people have for coming into a certain place (she experience of one organism, as well as between organisms and
was particularly hostile toward separating residential, leisure, and between species.
work functions of places). In the decades after her seminal book, 12. This is broadly consistent with a definition for person–
The Death and Life of the Great American Cities (1961/1993), environment–behavior research perspective offered by Amedeo,
this diversity has received many interpretations. Thus, Iris Mar- Golledge, and Stimson: “either a focused level of cognition acti-
ion Young (1990), in one of the most prominent treatments of vated and reflected on by an individual . . . and/or . . . a particu-
justice and social life, asserted that the good, just life is about lar reaction . . . undergone by an individual who may have been
elimination of institutionalized dominance and oppression, and aroused or stimulated by some environmental and/or spatially
affirming difference on multiple dimensions (such as race, sexu- related situation” (2009, p. 5). However, this latter definition
ality, etc.). She had an urban vision: the normative ideal she sug- gives primacy to environment and environmental stimulation,
gested for human living was the “city life,” which she defined as whereas, as von Uexküll’s framework suggests, the individual
the “being together of strangers” (p. 237). “Social justice in the phenomenal world is as much active as it is reactive. It is neverthe-
city requires the realization of a politics of difference” (p. 240). less instructive in that it both brings in more traditional psycho-
In a way, the concept of diversity—more recently conceptualized logical concepts (cognition, reaction) and further reinforces the
as difference—is one of the most articulated ways of interpret- argument that experience is fundamentally related to situation
ing the old dictum that “city air makes people free.” Friedmann and that situation always has an important spatial or environ-
(2000) names, among other things, human flourishing as a mental dimension.
foundational value and “multipli/city” as a primary good in a 13. Goffman continued this aim: “and to analyze the special
“good city.” Difference is also a founding element of Sandercock’s vulnerabilities to which these frames of reference are suspect”
Cosmopolis (1998/2003; Sandercock draws on the work of Iris (Goffman, 1974/1986, p. 10). Indeed, the bulk of his book is
Marion Young, 1990, in discussing this concept). devoted to exploring how definitions of situations get trans-
7. “Moral” could be added, although this word has lately formed, “keyed” and “rekeyed,” such as when a legitimate game
fallen out of fashion in human sciences, replaced by a blander is subverted to become a set up. This focus will not be followed in
notion of “values.” The word “moral”, however, links the con- the present inquiry, although it could serve as an inspiration for
cern with relations between people, the problem of social order, further exploration, for example, of the personal experience of
and the issues of justice and equity much better than “values” “theme park urbanism” characterized by disguising consumption
(but see Sandercock, 1998/2003, who names memory, desire, spaces as urban public space (Sorkin, 1992).
and spirit as important dimensions of urbanism—these three 14. Goffman draws on Gregory Bateson’s (1972) notion of
capture at least some of the spatial significance of moral orders frame. In the present context, “sign” is the correlate of the con-
of the city). cept of “frame” in relation to organization of experience.
8. Cf. the works of John Urry (2000; 2007), who proposed 15. Compare this to Herbert Gans’ “use-centered view” on
“mobility” rather than “society” as the central concept of sociol- sociology of space:
ogy concerned with social life today.
Natural space becomes a social phenomenon, or social
9. Highmore (2005) developed an interesting approach
space, once people begin to use it, boundaries are put on it,
grounded in Henri Lefebvre’s notion of “rhythmanalysis.” He
and meanings . . . are attached to it. Then the air-over-dirt
suggested that a study of urban culture could read the city as a
becomes a lot or a plot, and if residential users obtain control
text, but attempt first and foremost not to “make the urban leg-
over the bounded space, it becomes their place.
ible” but to “declare its object to be the social anxiety caused by
(Gans, 2002, p. 329)
the city’s perceived illegibility” (ibid., p. 7). In this way, for exam-
ple, he approached the material such as the movie The Matrix Gans’ use of “natural space” in this sense corresponds roughly
(1999) by reading it as a manifestation of network-connective to abstract space, although he leaves open the possibility that
urbanism. In Soja’s (2000) terms, however, this could still be some space would be natural because humans do not (or even,
considered a study of Secondspace. for some reason, cannot) use it, rather than because they do not
10. It should be noted that von Uexküll’s conception is not attach any meaning to it. Brighenti (2010) proposes a similar
anthropocentric. On the contrary, he powerfully asserts that understanding, suggesting that the notion of “territory” could be
Umwelten are species-specific, and therefore a dog inhabits a an all-encompassing term to denote what happens to space when
vastly different reality—and space—than a human. His A Stroll it is appropriated by humans and human social institutions. He
Through the Worlds of Animals and Men (von Uexküll, 1934/1992) also puts the notion of boundary forward as one of the crucial
is a picturesque statement to this effect, which, as Giorgio Agam- aspects of territory-making (cf. a cultural-developmental under-
ben (2002/2004, Chapter 10) reminds, has the potential of stop- standing of boundaries in Valsiner, 2007). Brighenti does not,
ping the “anthropological machine” that in our culture maintains however, provide a conceptual apparatus to approach the experi-
the distinction between humans and animals. Accordingly, it ence of territories and spaces. Nor this is a problem for Gans.
would be interesting to extend the arguments presented in this 16. Simmel himself made a seminal contribution to the
chapter outside the domain of Homo sapiens to other species nascent urban studies in his The metropolis and the mental life
and to question whether city has phenomenal salience for those (Simmel, 1903/1997), which, as Frisby and Featherstone
species’ relating to environments. For pragmatic reasons of sim- remind, could be “read in the context of his more systematic
plicity, this chapter does not make this move, but such a move explorations of social space and the social psychological impact
would entirely fit with the wide movement in human sciences of socio-spatial relations” (1997, p. 11). Simmel’s metropolis, the

kh a rl a m ov 299
spatial epitome of modernity (Kharlamov, 2009), was the form 23. Behaviorist doctrine of mechanism excluding any notions
of modern social life: of experience—especially private experience—”The behaviorist
finds no evidence for ‘mental existences’ or ‘mental processes’ of
An enquiry into the inner meaning of specifically mod-
any kind” (Watson, 1924, p. 2 n. 1)—was criticized by Mead
ern life and its products, into the soul of the cultural body,
(1934), for whom experience was the central matter of (social)
so to speak, must seek to solve the equation which structures
psychology. It is, however, strangely re-enacted by contemporary
like the metropolis set between the individual and the supra-
cognitive neuroscience, which ideally would reduce all “internal”
individual contents of life.
phenomena such as experience or consciousness to epiphenom-
(Simmel, 1903/1997, p. 175)
ena of neural processes in the central nervous system.
In that sense, Simmel’s ‘environmental-psychological’ remarks 24. It should be noted in passing that such formulation,
on intensity of nervous stimulation that urbanites face, picked up emphasizing the relative autonomy of personal cultures from
by latter observers such as Milgram (1970/2010, p. 12) in form collective culture (Valsiner, 2007, p. 61), avoids reifying the
of concepts such as “overload,” were only a starting position for a notions of group, community, and society, and assuming that
deeper philosophical inquiry into the essence of modern culture there are cultures as bounded entities projecting their essence
and its spatial condensation in modern metropolis. onto individual members of culture. As Urry (2000) shows,
17. Cf. the understanding of the “legibility of the everyday bounded “society”—and by extension “culture,” usually cotermi-
city” in the work of Ash Amin and Nigel Thrift (2002, Chapter 1) nous in social and human sciences with “society” or even “nation-
and the way Highmore (2005) discusses urban legibility and state”—is an inadequate concept for a highly mobile world of
illegibility. individuals constantly soaked in multiple settings.
18. There are few axiomatic, conceptual, and theoretical dif- 25. Cf. the way Amin and Thrift (2002, p. 119 ff.) conceptual-
ferences between frameworks developed for environments on ize night as one of “escape attempts” everyday life takes from the
different scale, and their discussion falls outside the scope of this controlling forces of governmentality, and how it is in turn put back
chapter. under control, for example through “theming” and consumerizing.
19. Cf. the notion of encounter as used by Goffman (1961), 26. This is not to say that planners and architects are not
whose focus is exclusively on human interaction, and more spe- people. Indeed they are—and it would be an interesting research
cifically, on focused interpersonal interaction with mutually sus- project to see whether planners and administrators employ their
tained attention. “professional” notion of “the city” when they drive their kids to
20. Von Uexküll’s theoretical biology thus allows us to turn the doctor or leisurely walk in the city park.
Amin and Thrift’s concern with de-humanizing knowing the city
(Amin & Thrift, 2002, p. 26) upside down—by asking whether
there is, and could be, such a thing, or such a meaning, as “the References
city” in the Umwelt of dogs and ticks, instead of trying to suggest Agamben, G. (2004). The open: Man and animal (K. Attell,
that human Umwelt is shared with them. Indeed—what is for Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. (Original
the subway rat that environment, which humans call Manhat- work published in 2002).
tan, and attribute unique meanings, a “soul” (Antsiferov, 1925), Agnew, J. (2005). Space : Place. In P. Cloke & R. Johnston
to it? (Eds.), Spaces of geographical thought: Deconstructing human
21. Goffman’s figure is illuminative in history of sci- geography’s binaries (pp. 81–96). London, UK: Sage.
ence and disciplinary traditions. Erving Goffman started his Amedeo, D., Golledge, R. G., & Stimson, R. J. (2009). Person-
career almost as an anthropologist, defending his dissertation environment-behavior research: Investigating activities and
(Goffman, 1953) on patterns of communicative conduct in experiences in spaces and environments. New York, NY: The
a rural community on the islands off the British coast. His Guilford Press.
dissertation—which was defended in Chicago as a disserta- American Psychological Association (2005). Report of the APA
tion in sociology—was completed under the guidance of Wil- Task Force on Urban Psychology Toward an urban psychology:
liam Lloyd Warner (himself an anthropologist and a student of Research, action, and policy. Retrieved from: www.apa.org/pi/
Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown) after 12 months of fieldwork ses/resources/publications/urban-taskforce.pdf (last accessed
using “observant participation” (ibid., p. 2). Goffman’s primary on August 22, 2011)
concern in his dissertation was with social order and social Amin, A., & Thrift, N. (2002). Cities: Reimagining the urban.
interaction. For him this was the beginning of a career-long Cambridge, UK: Polity.
conversation (cf. Goffman, 1983) with the work of Parsons Antsiferov, N. P. (1925). Puti izucheniya goroda kak sotsial’nogo
(1951), back then the bible of theoretical sociology. However, organizma: Opyt kompleksnogo podhoda [The ways of study-
his unique sensibility to the intimate complexities of human ing the city as a social organism: An attempt at a complex
everyday life and to its immense variation across humanity— approach]. Leningrad, USSR: Seyatel’.
reflected in the methodology of his dissertation fieldwork—was Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. New York, NY:
unquestionably anthropological. Ballantine Books.
22. Erving Goffman, in an otherwise rare homage to early Bell, D., & Jayne, M. (2009). Small cities? Towards a research
Durkheim’s vision of sociology, did not cover non-social expe- agenda. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research,
rience, and his primary interest in any situation was its social 33, 683–699.
nature. Similarly, Mead (1934), whose rethinking of behavior- Bhabha, H. K. (1990). The third space: Interview with Homi
ism introduced symbols and meanings as serving the mediating Bhabha. In J. Rutherford (Ed.), Identity: Community, culture,
function between the mind and the environment, was mostly difference (pp. 207–221). London, UK: Lawrence & Wishart.
focused on experience in social interactions (starting with elemen- Boesch, E. (2012). Culture: Result and condition of action. In
tary analysis of gesture). This is the essential obstacle in applying J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology
their theories to spatial experience. (pp. 347–356). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

300 th e c i t y as a si g n
Brighenti, A. M. (2010). On territorology: Towards a general sci- Goffman, E. (1953). Communication conduct in an island com-
ence of territory. Theory, Culture and Society, 27, 1–21. munity (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from ProQuest
Bunnell, T., & Maringanti, A. (2010). Practicing urban and Dissertations and Theses database. (UMI No. t-02149)
regional research beyond metrocentricity. International Goffman, E. (1961). Encounters: Two studies in the sociology
Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 34, 415–420. of interaction. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin University
Burgess, E. W. (1925). The growth of the city: An introduction Books.
to a research project. In R. E. Park, E. W. Burgess, R. D. Goffman, E. (1983). The interaction order. American Sociological
McKenzie, & L. Wirth. The city (pp. 47–62). Chicago, IL: Review, 48, 1–17.
The University of Chicago Press. Goffman, E. (1986). Frame analysis: An essay on the organization
Büscher, M. & Urry, J. (2009). Mobile methods and the empiri- of experience. Boston, MA: Northeastern University Press.
cal. European Journal of Social Theory, 12, 99–116. (Original work published in 1974).
Büscher, M., Urry, J., & Witchger. K. (Eds.). (2011). Mobile Golledge, R. G. (Ed.). (1999). Wayfinding behavior: Cognitive
methods. London, UK: Routledge. mapping and other spatial processes. Baltimore, MD: Johns
Calvino, I. (1974). Invisible cities (W. Weaver, Trans.). Orlando, Hopkins University Press.
FL: Harcourt. (Original work published in 1972). Golledge, R. G, & Stimson, R. J. (1997). Spatial behavior:
Carlson, L. A., Hölscher, C., Shipley, T. F., & Dalton, R. C. A geographic perspective. New York, NY: The Guilford Press.
(2010). Getting lost in buildings. Current Directions in Gottdiener, M. & Hutchison, R. (2006). The new urban sociology
Psychological Science, 19, 284–289. (3rd ed.). Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Castells, M. (1976). Is there an urban sociology? In C. Pickvance Gottdiener, M. & Lagopoulos, A. (Eds.). (1986). The city and the
(Ed.), Urban sociology: Critical essays (pp. 33–59). London, sign. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
UK: Methuen. Harvey, D. (1996). Justice, nature, and the geography of difference.
Castells, M. (2010). The information age: Economy, society, and Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
culture. Vol. 1: The rise of the network society (2nd ed., with Highmore, B. (2005). Cityscapes: Cultural readings in the material
a new preface). Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. (Original and symbolic city. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
work published in 1996). Ingold, T. (2000). The perception of the environment: Essays in live-
Chang, R. S. (2009). Relating to environments: A new look at lihood, dwelling and skill. London, UK: Routledge.
Umwelt. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers. Ittelson, W. H., Franck, K. A., & O’Hanlon, T. J. (1976). The
Davis, M. (2006). City of quartz: Excavating the future in Los nature of environmental experience. In S. Wapner, S. B.
Angeles. London, UK: Verso. (Original work published in Cohen, & B. Kaplan (Eds.), Experiencing the environment
1990). (pp. 187–206). New York, NY: Plenum.
Davis, M., & Monk, D. B. (Eds.). (2007). Evil paradises: Jacobs, J. (1993). The death and life of great American cities.
Dreamworlds of neoliberalism. New York, NY: The New Press. New York, NY: The Modern Library. (Original work pub-
Dear, M. J. (Ed.). (2002). From Chicago to L.A.: Making sense of lished in 1961).
urban theory. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Jazbinsek, D. (2003). The metropolis and the mental life of
Dear, M. J., & Flusty, S. (1998). Postmodern urbanism. Annals Georg Simmel: On the history of an antipathy. Journal of
of the Association of American Geographers, 88, 50–72. Urban History, 30, 102–125.
Dehaene, M., & De Cauter, L. (Eds.). (2008). Heterotopia Jensen, O. B. (2009). Flows of meaning, cultures of move-
and the city: Public space in a postcivil society. London, UK: ments—Urban mobility as meaningful everyday practice.
Routledge. Mobilities, 4, 139–158.
Edensor, T. (2005). Industrial ruins: Space, aesthetics, and materi- Kaganskiy, V. L. (1983). Geographical boundaries: Contradictions
ality. Oxford, UK: Berg. and paradoxes. Soviet Geography: Review & Translation, 24,
Filippov, A. F. (2008). Sotsiologiya prostranstva [The sociology of 39–48.
space]. Saint-Petersburg, Russian Federation: Vladimir Dahl. Kharlamov, N. A. (2009). O ‘Simmelevoi probleme’: Sovremennyi
Fincham, B., McGuinness, M., & Murray, L. (Eds.). (2010). Mobile mir i sreda bolshikh gorodov v ‘Bolshikh gorodakh i duk-
methodologies. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. hovnoi zhizni’ Georga Simmelya [On ‘Simmelian problem’:
Fishman, R. (1987). Bourgeois utopias: The rise and fall of subur- Contemporary world and the environment of large cities
bia. New York, NY: Basic Books. in Georg Simmel’s ‘The metropolis and mental life’]. In
Foucault, M. (2008). Of other spaces (L. De Cauter & Pugacheva, M. G., & Vakhstayn, V. S. (Eds.), Puti Rossii:
M. Dehaene, Trans.). In M. Dehaene & L. De Cauter (Eds.), Sovremennoye intellektualnoye prostranstvo. Shkoly, naprav-
Heterotopia and the city: Public space in a postcivil society leniya, pokoleniya. Vol. XVI. (pp. 295–307) Moscow, Russian
(pp. 13–29). London, UK: Routledge. (Original work pub- Federation: Universitetskaya Kniga.
lished in 1967). Kharlamov, N. A. (2010). Ideal city. In R. Hutchison (Ed.), The
Friedmann, J. (2000). The good city: In defense of utopian think- Sage Encyclopedia of urban studies (pp. 389–392). Thousand
ing. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 24, Oaks, CA: Sage.
460–472. Kitchin, R., & Blades, M. (2002). The cognition of geographic
Frisby, D., & Featherstone, M. (1997). Introduction to the texts. space. London, UK: I. B. Taurus Publishers.
In D. Frisby & M. Featherstone (Eds.), Simmel on culture: Kusenbach, M. (2003). Street phenomenology: The go-along as
Selected writings (pp. 1–28). London, UK: Sage. ethnographic research tool. Ethnography, 4, 455–485.
Gans, H. J. (2002). The sociology of space: A use-centered view. Luhmann, N. (1995). Social systems (J. Bednarz, Jr. & D. Baecker,
City & Community, 1, 329–339. Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. (Original
Gans, H. J. (2009). Some problems and futures for urban sociol- work published in 1984).
ogy: Toward a sociology of settlements. City & Community, Lynch, K. (1960). The image of the city. Cambridge, MA: The
8, 211–219. MIT Press.

kh a rl a m ov 301
Lynch, K. (1981). Good city form. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Sorkin, M. (Ed.). (1992). Variations on a theme park: The new
Press. American city and the end of public space. New York, NY: Hill
Magnus, R., & Kull, K. (2012). Roots of culture in the Umwelt. and Wang.
In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology Takooshian, H. (2009). Urban psychology. In R. Hutchison
(pp. 649–661). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. (Ed.), The Sage encyclopedia of urban studies (pp. 914–918).
McWilliams, C. (1973). Southern California: An island on the Los Angeles, CA: Sage.
land. Santa Barbara, CA: Peregrine Smith. Thrift, N. (2008). Non-representational theory: Space, politics,
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society: From the standpoint affect. London, UK: Routledge.
of a social behaviorist. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Tuan, Y.-F. (1977). Space and place: The perspective of experience.
Press. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Milgram, S. (2010). The experience of living in cities. In Blass, T. United Nations Population Fund. (2007). State of world popula-
(Ed.), Stanley Milgram. The individual in a social world: Essays tion 2007: Unleashing the potential of urban growth. Retrieved
and experiments (3rd expanded ed., pp. 11–28). London, UK: from: http://www.unfpa.org/webdav/site/global/shared/doc-
Pinter & Martin. (Original work published in 1970). uments/publications/2007/695_filename_sowp2007_eng.
Nasar, J. (1989). Perception, cognition, and evaluation of urban pdf (last accessed on August 22, 2011).
places. In Altman, I. & Zube, E. (Eds.), Public places and Urry, J. (2000). Sociology beyond societies: Mobilities for the twen-
spaces (pp. 31–56). New York, NY: Plenum Press. ty-first century. London, UK: Routledge.
Nijman, J. (2000). The paradigmatic city. Annals of the Association Urry, J. (2002). The tourist gaze (2nd ed.). London, UK: Sage.
of American Geographers, 90, 135–145. Urry, J. (2007). Mobilities. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
Parsons, T. (1951). The social system. Glencoe, IL: The Free Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and human development: An introduc-
Press. tion. London, UK: Sage.
Perec, G. (2008a). Species of spaces / Especes d’espaces Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies: Foundations of
(J. Sturrock, Trans.). In J. Sturrock (Ed.), Georges Perec. cultural psychology. New Delhi, India: Sage.
Species of Spaces and Other Pieces (pp. 1–96). London, UK: von Uexküll, J. (1982). The theory of meaning. Semiotica, 42,
Penguin Books. (Original work published 1974). 25–82. (Original work published in 1940).
Perec, G. (2008b). The Rue Vilin (J. Sturrock, Trans.). In von Uexküll, J. (1992). A stroll through the worlds of animals
J. Sturrock (Ed.), Georges Perec. Species of Spaces and Other and men: A picture book of invisible worlds. Semiotica, 89,
Pieces (pp. 212–221). London, UK: Penguin Books. (Original 319–391. (Original work published in 1934).
work published 1977). Wagoner, B. (2009). The experimental methodology of construc-
Perec, G. (2008c). Notes on what I’m looking for (J. Sturrock, tive microgenesis. In J. Valsiner, P. C. M. Molenaar, M. C.
Trans.). In J. Sturrock (Ed.), Georges Perec. Species of Spaces D. P. Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Dynamic process meth-
and Other Pieces (pp. 141–143). London, UK: Penguin odology in the social and developmental sciences (pp. 99–121).
Books. (Original work published 1978). Dordrecht, Germany: Springer.
Rodoman, B. B. (1983). Basic types of geographical boundaries. Watson, J. B. (1924). Psychology: From the standpoint of a behav-
Soviet Geography: Review & Translation, 24, 48–59. iorist (2nd ed.). Philadelphia, PA: J. B. Lippincott Company.
Sandercock, L. (2003). Towards cosmopolis: Utopia as construc- Werner, C. M., & Altman, I. (2000). Humans and nature:
tion site. In S. Campbell & S. S. Fainstein (Eds.), Readings Insights from a transactional view. In S. Wapner, J. Demick,
in planning theory (2nd ed., pp. 401–407). Malden, MA: T. Yamamoto, & H. Minami (Eds.), Theoretical perspectives
Blackwell Publishing. (Original work published in 1998). in environment-behavior research: Underlying assumptions,
Schuetz, A. (1945). On multiple realities. Philosophy and research problems, and methodologies (pp. 21–37). New York,
Phenomenological Research, 5, 533–576. NY: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Press.
Scott, A. J. & Soja, E. W. (Eds.). (1996). The city: Los Angeles and Werner, H., & Kaplan, B. (1984). Symbol formation: An organ-
urban theory at the end of the twentieth century. Berkeley, CA: ismic-developmental approach to the psychology of language.
University of California Press. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. (Original work
Simmel, G. (1997). The metropolis and mental life (H. Gerth, published in 1963).
Trans.). In D. Frisby & M. Featherstone (Eds.), Simmel on Williams, R. (2008). Night spaces: Darkness, deterritorializa-
culture: Selected writings (pp. 174–185). London, UK: Sage. tion, and social control. Space and Culture, 11, 514–532.
(Original work published in 1903). Wirth, L. (1938). Urbanism as a way of life. American Journal of
Simmel, G. (2009). Sociology: Inquiries into the construction of Sociology, 44, 1–24.
social forms (A. J. Blasi, A. K. Jacobs, & M. Kanjirathinkal, Wolch, J., & Emel, J. (Eds.). (1998). Animal geographies: Place,
Trans.). Leiden, Netherlands: Brill. (Original work published politics, and identity in the nature-culture borderlands. London,
in 1908). UK: Verso.
Soja, E. W. (2000). Postmetropolis: Critical studies of cities and Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton,
regions. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers. NJ: Princeton University Press.

302 th e c i t y as a si g n
CHAPTER

Modeling Iconic Literacy:


14 The Dynamic Models for Complex
Cultural Objects
Rebeca Puche-Navarro

Abstract
Paradoxical objects are everywhere in human lives—and they are used as a cultural scenario to capture
cognitive processes and trigger inferential operations. I look at how Nonlinear Dynamic Systems Theory
can be used to make sense of cognitive processes, as these are embedded within the environment of
cultural kind. Coordinating two different techniques—the minimae and maximae estimation, and the
wavelet techniques—allow researchers to capture the dynamic nature of the mind. The discovered
effectively inferential operations have a fractal structure. But perhaps more important is that the human
mind in varied contexts and disparate perspectives may be studied by these techniques from Nonlinear
Dynamic Systems Theory. The paradoxical objects—cartoons and other media—open a panorama for
the study of the mind. The mind—through dealing with paradoxical objects—is sensitive and open to
culture. It may be that cognitive and cultural psychology become united in the study of paradoxical
objects.
Keywords: paradoxical objects, nonlinear dynamic systems, fractals

The purpose of this chapter is to illustrate the Paradoxical objects can be understood through
approach from nonlinear dynamics to human cog- complex cognitive processes.
nitive development by using paradoxical objects The choice of paradoxical objects for the study
of an iconic nature in a cultural method. The of development from a cultural perspective begins
emphasis here is based on the idea that paradox- from the principle that these objects condense
ical iconic objects are by nature essentially cul- what is understood culturally. These are objects
tural. We encounter cartoons in everyday life, and that “make sense” (in immediate encounter) they
we smile or laugh. Why? After all, these are merely are not just perceived gestalts. Francastel argued
some drawn graphic images that are not even—and that the arts in general are the result of a vision
purposefully not—adequate replica of the objects of an era, of a time, of a geographical moment,
they depict. and of a world historically and culturally under-
The paradoxical objects with which our research stood (Francastel, 1970)—an idea that captures
program at University of Valle in California has the nature of paradoxical objects very well. In that
worked are exclusively of visual and iconic nature. sense, they constitute “a place of convergence”
At the same time, we want to emphasize that not between the author and the world that is being rec-
only verbal and argumentative procedures could get reated. Nonetheless, Barthes refers to some icons
us closer to deciphering some thought processes. as representing a kind of hallmark, a celebration,
The key to this chapter is dynamic systems as a a “spiritualization” of the object—not only as an
perspective that takes complex ideas into account. object but as a sense.

303
Paradoxical objects contain another privileged of cultural objects. That position gathers strength
relationship—that is, the relationship of the viewer when it comes to studying the cognitive processes
with the work. In any artwork, be it iconic or not, involved in understanding doubtful ambiguities
there are converging perspectives coming from dif- and evidently the little that is literal with para-
ferent sides, which overlap in shared meaning and doxical objects. The comprehension of paradoxical
significance. All art, says Barthes, has two dimen- objects plays on the unpredictable, on uncertainty,
sions: that of the work and that of the viewer. and the transgressions of the conventional, and all
Effectively, the work is “a meeting place for the of those are conditions for NLDS.
spirits of an era, they are a sign, not a building or However, it is necessary to elaborate a bit more
a painting can have an existence independent of on the implications of working on cognitive devel-
a double effort, that of the artist and that of the opment and specifically on the inferential elabora-
viewer that in meeting form it” (Francastel, 1970, tions involved in understanding paradoxical objects
p. 11). An exaltation is a joining “spiritualization” of from the perspective of NLDS. The first argument
the object that goes beyond it and returns not only rests on the idea that the chaotic phenomena stud-
as object but as a sense. From this perspective, the ied with NLDS are of qualitative kind. They are
paradoxical object includes the future or a linkage characterized by being in the middle of the road
of the past and future occurring in the present. In between the periodic and a-periodic, between the
effect, the fact that the author and audience share predictable and unpredictable (although they are
the sense of perspective despite differences in eras, deterministic), between the regular and the irregu-
geographies, and cultures is a living example of a lar, and between the systematic and the random. It
historicity that includes the future (Lyra & Valsiner, can be said that they do not conform to the distri-
2010). Needless to say, this intersection between bution of the Gaussian curve, although they present
cognitive development in a cultural approach, by a certain degree of consistency.
using paradoxical objects, is not a usual way that Working within the framework of these ideas, it
cultural psychological studies are covered. is not risky to postulate that many cognitive and
cultural processes, as well as cultural cognitive devel-
Nonlinear Dynamic Systems and Cultural opment, are phenomena of chaotic structure. They
Cognitive Development are unpredictable in the sense that the prediction
Nonlinear dynamic systems (NLDS) constitute thresholds are rather flexible and relative. As Rose
neither a dominant approach in developmental and Fischer have outlined:
psychological literature in general nor one in cul-
Developmental processes are highly nonlinear,
tural cognitive development, in particular. It is an
heterogenous and dependent on a wide factors.
approach that, despite being new and promising,
(Rose & Fischer, 2009, p. 417)
does not yet produce a large number of studies.
The analysis of the comprehension of paradoxical In the emergence of making inference, for
objects as a way to integrate cultural aspects and do example, we know that some categorical inferences
it from NLDS results in a doubly risky bet. Maybe must be present at the end of the first year, but the
these elements make the text provocative and then precise moment of their appearance is uncertain.
encourage the reader to become interested and join They show great irregularity and variability (Rose
the discussion. & Fischer, 2009; Adolph, Robinson, Young, &
In recent literature there have been many Alvarez, 2008; Combariza & Puche-Navarro, 2009;
authors who have claimed the use of NLDS for Puche-Navarro, 2009b; Yan & Fischer, 2002). This
the study of cultural developmental psychol- irregularity that psychologists study under the con-
ogy (Rose & Fischer, 2009; Fischer & Bidell, cept of variability—behaviors that appear and dis-
2006; Lewis, 2000; Fogel, Lyra, & Lewis, 2000.) appear, breaking the image of stable growth that
“Dynamic modeling offers tools to better under- has always been taken as the rule in developmental
stand development and learning in their full com- studies—has caused nightmares to the developmen-
plexity, integrating influences involving person, tal researcher (Smith & Thelen, 2003). In summary
context, and culture” (Rose & Fischer, 2009, and generally speaking, recent research is increas-
p. 417). The position defended is that from nonlin- ingly insistent in providing evidence to confirm the
ear and open conceptions, one would be in better chaotic nature of the operations and information-
shape to decode and make sense of the complexity processing mechanisms in cognition.

304 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


Some Terms of Dynamic Systems have provided evidence on development and emer-
Notions such as nonlinearity, self-regulation and gence of language in children. One such study
self-organization, multilevel, attractors, and fractals reports on the individual pathway of Helen, who
then emerge as more appropriate and relevant to after little more than 1 year of follow-up, shows
account for the nature of cultural psychological pro- that her performance is not described by ascending,
cesses (Lewis, 2000; Thelen, 1995; van Geert, 1998; cumulative linear trajectories. By contrast, they take
Smith & Thelen, 2003; van Geert, 1994, 1998, into account fluctuations that move within non-
2003; van Geert & Steenbeek, 2005a, 2005b). linear dynamics and in which variability is always
Taken together, these notions are information-bear- present (van Dijk, 2004). Studies such as these with
ing units on chaotic structure. Thelen, for example, clear empirical evidence constitute compelling rea-
approaches such developmental psychological phe- sons to consider that nonlinear systems are better
nomena in terms of components that interact with able to access the complexity of cultural cognitive
strong interdependencies among many variables, processes (for further elaboration of this point, see
breaking with the simplified conception between Cortés, Combariza, & Puche-Navarro, 2009).
an independent and dependent variable. Perhaps The second argument is the questioning of linear
his most famous work is the illustration of the methods for studying cultural cognitive processes.
emergence of walking as a simultaneous interaction Those who make this criticism criticize linear-
between multiple components with their respec- ity because it leads to a necessary simplification as
tive covariance in self-regulatory processes (Smith opposed to the complexity of psychological pro-
& Thelen, 2003). Fischer, for his part, suggests an cesses, in general, and cultural cognitive process,
original reconceptualization of development called in particular. The doubt that linear methods can
“dynamic theory of abilities,” from the NLDS. In preserve the basic properties of the complexity of
that conceptualization, self-organization has a spe- a system such as cultural cognitive development is
cific role in integrating the nonlinear dynamic with supported by accumulating developmental theories
his own concepts of development and explains vari- and methodologies that insistently raise this issue
ability as an indicator of the complex organization (Munné, 2005; Valsiner, 2004; van Geert, 2003).
of human activity (Yan & Fischer, 2007). From linearity, it is difficult to capture the com-
According to van Geert: plexity of psychological processes, such as cognitive
activity, and to obtain a meaningful understanding
Non-linearity means, among others things, that the
of the numerous relationships that hold in such a
effect of a dynamic process differs from the sum of
complex system.
its parts . . . ( . . .) An alternative and somewhat more
intuitive understanding way of defining the property
Tools for Analysis
of nonlinearity is to say that the effect of a factor that
As van Geert has emphasized:
influences the system is not (necessarily) proportional
to the magnitude of that factor. The adoption of linear statistical modeling enhanced
(van Geert, 2003, p. 657) the methodological rigor of research, but weakened
aspects of comprehensiveness and mutuality from the
As is known, linearity supposes only one
oldest conceptualizations of development.
solution—the implied cause-and-effect relation
(van Geert, 2003, p. 643).
only produces proportional effects. In contrast,
in a nonlinear system, bifurcations occur as the Without new tools, conceptualization from
causal relationships become more complex, lead- NLDS is not possible to study and to understand
ing to unexpected consequences and opening a information from new perspectives. Concepts such
range of possibilities with several possible alterna- as strange attractors, fractals, bifurcation, and itera-
tive solutions. In the development of mother– tion, besides being closely related, are the basis of
child interactions, many studies show how in the techniques and tools for NLDS.
observed trajectories, the emergence of patterns is The classic definition of strange attractors con-
not the result of accumulation, but precisely from siders them as a zone of turbulence (Combariza &
the combinations among many variables that inter- Puche-Navarro, 2009). Hence their capture shows
act over time (Hollenstein & Lewis, 2006; Lamey, a set of paths characterized by not repeating them-
Hollenstein, Lewis, & Granic, 2004; Lewis, 2000; selves, by not crossing with each other, and not
Lewis, Lamey, & Douglas, 1999). Other authors merging. Although it appears disordered, in reality

pu ch e- n ava rro 305


it is governed by an underlying order and regular- relationship between visual paradox and cognitive
ity not visible at first sight (Smith, 1998). A good exercise.
example is seen in the Rössel attractor (see http:// One of the most appreciated benefits of para-
commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Roessler_ doxical objects is precisely that they are just inef-
attractor.png). fable, they play in their own drawing, as Gombrich
One of the growing possibilities that are very says, “the drawings (by themselves) get much more
attractive to psychologists is to visualize the transi- than the words would ever do” (Gombrich, 1997,
tion from one state to another. In that sense, the p. 189). In the line of analysis of transgressions that
attractors are very useful in the study of cognitive embody different paradoxical objects, one can easily
change (Lewis et al., 1999; Spencer & Perone, transform it into a review of how the subject knows.
2008; Yan & Fischer, 2007). In addition to Fischer The diversity of paradoxical objects opens the spec-
(Yan & Fischer, 2002), they have also been used by trum of different inferential elaborations involved
Lewis et al. (1999), Hollenstein (2007), and more in comprehension.
recently by Spencer and Perone (2008). Studying The paradoxical objects are built on a transgres-
cultural cognitive activity and other developmen- sion of the logical and conventional structure that
tal processes starting with attractors has permitted subverts the shared meaning between those who
a visualizing of the change between states in the produce it and those who read it. It demands the
processes of developmental change from cognitive complicity of the spectator to be able to follow the
activity (Lamey et al., 2004). traces of intermittent transformations and unex-
Fractals, in turn, are defined as established by pected combinations before concluding and deriv-
Mandelbrot (2006) on the basis that they always ing consequences. Such a relationship between visual
repeat themselves on any scale. Munné (2008) objects and the cognitive activity of those who read
relates this self-similarity characteristic of frac- them perhaps have been clearer to drawing artists
tals to iteration to point out that fractals can be and art critics than to developmental psychologists.
understood as generated by rules that produce According to Gombrich, Steinberg was very con-
self-similar phenomena in differing spatial and scious of this, as evidenced by the following quote:
time-scales. Curiously, although attractors have “I appeal to my reader’s complicity to transform the
been frequently used by psychologists, as men- line into meaning by using our common cultural
tioned before, this has not similarly occurred with past, history, poetry. The contemporary, in that
fractals. sense, is a complicity” (Gombrich, 1997, p. 192).
It is therefore not surprising, although unusual, to
Paradoxical Objects and Cultural argue that visual objects constitute an ideal scenario
Development that fits well with the inquiry into the representa-
Any comprehension of humorous paradoxical tional activity of the young child.
objects constitutes a privileged scenario for capturing
the historical nature of culturally understood cogni- Semiological Analysis
tive development. Thus, the paradoxical objects are One tool that has contributed to this work is
spaces in which, to paraphrase Francastel, culture semiological analysis of such objects that permit
and society enter and leave, and some of its features the establishment of distinctions among them while
(geographical, scientific, economic, or of gender) deriving important differences as to what is being
establish themselves and leave traces, which is why referred to by the involved inferential elaborations
time in art does not remain fixed (Francastel, 1970, (Puche-Navarro, 2001, 2004, 2009b). Semiological
p. 195). Obviously, the relationship that arises analysis of the paradoxical objects offers a rigorous
between paradoxical objects and their perceivers is examination of the necessary requirements for their
not a new relationship; it was identified in the art understanding. The analysis of paradoxical objects
world long ago. According to Gombrich (1997), discovers the contradictions in which they are based,
for example, the entirety of visual contradictions as well as the conditions required by the subject to
suggested by paradoxical objects is highly illustra- resolve the proposed crossroads. In other words, it
tive of the processes of representation. For Magritte, allows for anticipating and controlling the explicit
they synthesize a “superposition from the thought responses of the interrogated subject. A clearly sub-
exercise to the revealing exercise of his painting” versive suggestion, even humorous, is to say that it
(Meuris, 1992). Both make explicit and play on the is based on alienation and/or ambiguity.

306 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


Our previous studies have used semiological such a magnitude that the objects cease to belong
analysis as a tool to distinguish among different to one class or species, and, from the effect of that
types of paradoxical objects. There is no doubt that change, it becomes part of another distinct species.
differentiation between visual objects derives from
“In the course of the inquiries I found a new
the nature of transgression. The semiologic analy-
possibility of things gradually becoming something
sis could characterize very precisely if the display of
different, an object becomes another ( . . . ) This
distinctive inferential functioning already evolved
means in my opinion, something very different from
is some kind of analyzing task used in psychology
the coincidence between two objects because there is
(Orozco, 2000; Pascual-Leone, 1991).
no break, no boundaries between the two materials.”
(Quoted by Meuris, 1992, p. 51; see illustrations of The
What Paradoxical Visual Objects Mean?
Boots of Magritte in http://cognitiva.univalle.edu.co/
The paradoxical object is presented as a problem
imagenes.htm)
to solve, a type of ambiguous enigma and at a cross-
roads for those observing it. Magritte refers to it as A second specific type of paradoxical object is
an ambiguity in which an object is transformed into when the drawing comes from the drawing, when
another (Meuris, 1992). It is treated as a deliberately the object is derived from the traces of the very
subversive suggestion that leads to an estrangement act of drawing. Magnificent examples of that type
that produces an enjoyment of the humorous. There of paradoxical objects are Escher’s The Drawing
is some consensus that paradoxical objects combine Hands or Steinberg’s Passport; the latter is certainly
possibilities for play, illusion, poetry, and humor. less transcendent but with a not insignificant dose
The work on the spatial aspects leads to traces of of wit and humor. Steinberg puts it well when he
illusions and to geometric shapes that break with says: “What draws is the drawing (and) drawing
convention to open the door to the imagination and comes from the drawing. My line wants to be con-
the unthinkable. stantly reminded that it is made of ink” (Rosenberg,
Perhaps the characteristics of uncertainty that cited by Gombrich, 1997, p. 189). (See Illustration
surround paradoxical objects make them very of Escher’s The Drawing Hands and Steinberg’s
diverse in nature and of different types. Magritte, The Passport at http://cognitiva.univalle.edu.co/
for example, draws attention to the different types imagenes.htm.)
of transformations that lead to a wide heterogeneity In the case of The Drawing Hands and The
of objects (Meuris, 1992). The nature of the subver- Passport, the author breaks down the barrier between
sive transformation (or of incongruence, as they’re that which draws and the action of drawing so that
called by psychologists like Bariaud, 1983; McGhee, therein is the contradiction. A different thing occurs
1979; and Schultz, 1996) would define different with mutations in that the transformation plays
types of paradoxical objects. Below is an incomplete between two different objects, producing a hybrid.
typology that characterizes some of them. In the work The Boots, the feet turn into shoes in the
In this classification, at a first and important presence of the spectator’s eyes. That which charac-
place are Mutations, characterized by a transforma- terizes this extraordinary mutation places it on the
tion undergone by an object in front of the eyes of road to the metaphor. It is the same case as those
the spectator. A second type concerns objects that paradoxical objects of Escher’s that are half-bird,
develop Recursions, which is the case for objects half-fish (extremes between two asymmetric animal
that break the distance between the author and his species, one aquatic and one aerial—not in vain
creation. Finally, there are the Mentalists: objects called Sky and Water) or as those found in Meeting,
that play on the contradictions of content that take where he plays with the variation between ape and
place in the mental states of the reader. Let us review man.
them in more detail. Finally, other paradoxical objects are termed
Magritte’s work by itself constitutes an excel- Mentalists. They have the specific feature of being
lent overview of many of these distinct paradoxical psychological; in other words, they are anchored
objects. In this wide range, specific types of para- in mental states. This is nothing other than what
doxical objects are called mutations, named as such is seen when a child interprets what occurs in the
by Magritte to refer to those objects that undergo image that alludes a mental state of the protago-
radical transformations. They are characterized as nist and in front of which the viewer can situate
such because the transformation they undergo is of themselves. Mentalist objects conciliate that early

pu ch e- n ava rro 307


capacity of children (or adults) to interpret and The Mentalist class of objects may also include
reproduce in their own emotional system the states, several different subclasses because they cover certain
intentions, beliefs, and assumptions identified in the heterogeneity in the use of mental states. Consider
paradoxical object. That projection destroys the lit- some of the following subclasses.
eral meaning of the object by discovering properties
that it did not have, by creating ironies, and by open- Mentalist 1
ing other senses to the content acted upon. The dog When the transgressive relationship that is pro-
sickness (Fig. 14.1) serves as a good example of this. posed transforms an object into another through
The paradox is built on the fact that the reader has to projection that alludes to a desire or a sentiment of
know, that the dog “knows” what sickness means. the protagonist. In the case of the object we have
It is intended in those ways to better locate the class called Cat in the Mirror, subversion is defined by
that we have named mentalists. It really is about these the functioning of a mirror that instead of reflect-
objects that our team has dedicated part of its work ing (its fundamental property) transforms whoever
and has gathered much information. In fact, some of is in front. What the reader must infer is the pro-
obtained results are used to account for the fertile and jection that is behind the relationship of “desired
beneficial implications of returning to the iconic. transformation.”
Paradoxical objects have a humorous side; in
addition to being objects with meaning, they add Mentalist 2
an element of fun, which is also a cultural phenom- The contradiction that this object proposes is
enon. In a way of understanding the complexity of based on a clearly identifiable mental state but one
relations of development in a cultural approach, it is that the protagonists cannot possess. It is clear that
not surprising to come to a comprehension of them. the television sets are discussing among themselves
No review of paradoxical objects would be complete and that the reader can identify this directly and
without pointing out, if even briefly, the fact that rapidly, but the contradiction is precisely that the
humor plays an important role. Not all paradoxical television sets do not have the property for discus-
objects are humorous, and not all visual humor pro- sion among themselves (i.e., they “can” not do it).
ceeds from paradoxical objects. In this latter case, Inferential demands that require an understand-
let’s just say, for example, a comic strip is some kind ing of the evidence that mentalistic objects provide
of iconic joke (Lozano & Puche-Navarro, 1998). In are not always the same. In some cases, the empirical
the first case, perhaps we can say that humor plays a evidence offered by this object is not direct (televi-
fundamental role in understanding the greater part sion sets), but they are necessary to deduce similar
of paradoxical objects. Gombrich claims that “may properties in the object. In the case of the Cat in
be not other artist alive (referring to Steinberg) Front of the Mirror, it is necessary to think and feel
knows more than this humorist about the represen- like the cat to understand the meaning of the lion in
tation of philosophy” (Gombrich, 1997, p. 188). the mirror.

Figure 14.1 The Dog’s Sickness

308 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


Humorous Objects It is equally important to note that in the case of
Perhaps it is time now to review some of the studies with children, the humorous ingredient of
findings from our studies on understanding objects the paradoxical objects is a component that facilitates
that have a clear humorous ingredient, to point out the child’s access to them. The young child’s ability
more precisely what is intended to be shown in this to understand the meaning embodied in the subver-
chapter. The spectators in our studies—the inter- sion of the humorous visual object is necessary when
preters of paradoxical objects—are children. The age it masters the double sense that it proposes. Such
range used in the study was from 3 years to 4 years. understanding assumes an inferential operation that
Another element is that this child–spectator idea when animated by the humorous ingredient moves
acts as a basic inquirer in the words of Karmiloff- the reader to decipher the meaning (see Table 14.1).
Smith (2002), as a subject that raises questions and Table 14.1 shows that children of about age 4
thus “reads the world.” It takes advantage of the years took the handling of mental states into account,
paradoxical objects posed as a riddle, precisely to which is the architecture required for understanding
trigger the child’s abilities to discover what is being the mentalistic object. This fact by itself is surprising
posed. In this exercise, one tries to understand what from the perspective of traditional child psychology.
the posed object accesses from the inferential opera- But equally interesting is the difference in the per-
tions involved in such attempts at understanding. formance of children facing the mentalistic object 1
The results of previous studies (Lozano & Puche- and the mentalistic object 2. Our semiological analy-
Navarro, 1998; Puche-Navarro, 2001; 2002, 2004, sis of the requirements for understanding one and
2009b) take into account such mental function- the other showed such differences. In one case the
ing required to make what is in the image explicit mental state is clearly identifiable, whereas with the
and find the original meaning that is implicit. The other it is necessary to discover it. That discrimina-
results are as surprising as they are diverse. tion that translates the different inferential operations

Table 14.1. Comparison of the Understanding of Two Mentalists Jokes in Children from 3 to 8 years
Percentages of children that
Mentalistic solve the problem

Mentalistic 1 37/50 = 74%


(T V)

Mentalistic 2 26/50 = 52%


(Cat in the Mirror)

pu ch e- n ava rro 309


shows them with relative transparency. Indeed, that objects, it may also be relevant to question these facts
the child discriminates between those two mentalis- differently. A very pertinent issue may be trying to
tic objects implies that they require inferential opera- find out what the structure is of the inferential oper-
tions at a different level of complexity. ations that are involved and to investigate emerg-
One of the most important pieces of information ing alternatives that adopt the NLDS perspective
collected shows that the understanding of different to try to establish if they take into account a cha-
humorous objects of the mentalist type occurs quite otic structure. Although the linearity of age-related
early—that is, around age 4 years (Puche-Navarro, behavior has been dominant, it is worth exploring
2002). Precociously then, the children pass in a what happens if one works from nonlinearity and
flexible and agile manner along the trajectory that bifurcation. The problem then would not be about
separates the original representation of the subverted the time of emergence of inferential operations nor
embodied in the iconic object. It is worth reiterating stratification in relation to age. From nonlinear-
how humor plays an anchoring role in the reception ity the issue would be to explore what the paths of
that the child makes from the paradoxical object. inferential operations over a span of several weeks
The very fact that the child discriminates involve to know what it is that these trajectories
between different paradoxical objects is a first-or- show. Paradoxical objects of the mentalistic type,
der fact to continue our study directed to delving others of the hyperbolic type, and, third, those of
deeply into the various classes of differential opera- the substitution type are again taken into account.
tions involved. It has been hypothesized that the The paradoxical objects identified as mentalistic are
understanding of paradoxical objects is played out characterized by a game of transgression based on the
on the unpredictable, on uncertainty, and on the use of mental states. Hyperbolic paradoxical objects
transgressions of the conventional. These doubtful are characterized as such because the transgression
ambiguities and the little literal evidenced by the takes place as a function of character exaggeration
paradoxical objects should be enriched by taking up (e.g., a quiet fisherman in a small boat catches a fish
a larger class of them and adopting NLDS to try to three times the size of the boat). The transgression
explain the nature of the inferential operations that that gives rise to a substitution object is character-
are derived. ized by transposition of a structural element of the
In the subject’s activity, one can then differen- image that completely transforms the meaning of it
tiate many kinds of inferences (although some of (e.g., a cow with the head of an orchid).
them are not included in our work). There are some The first objects that have been widely treated
that are of an inductive type (along the long-known throughout the text (the mentalistic) are character-
ideas of David Hume), as are many of those work- ized from the standpoint of inferential operations
ing on children’s ability to relate theory with evi- as demanding deductive inferences that require a
dence (Koslowski, 1996; Kuhn, 2002); there will second-order intentional system (Dennett, 1995).
be a relational or deductive type; and there will be That is, the subject needs to think or feel what
the abductive, as those working in the emergence the protagonist thinks or feels. The second objects
of metaphor (de la Rosa, 2006), to name but a few. of nature, hyperbolic, require inferential opera-
However, the important thing to consider is that tions of the inductive type to the extent that they
inferential operations cover a wide range. According derive from direct and concrete indications of the
to this idea, one the most recent studies by our team iconic object. Finally, the third type of operations,
worked on a task based on different objects requir- the substitution, pose a transductive inference type,
ing distinct operations. The study utilized condi- according to the classification of de Gortari (1969),
tions and the scenario favorable for differentiating who defines them as such for being of relational
them (Puche-Navarro, 2002, 2004, 2009b; Lozano character given that they extract knowledge from
& Puche-Navarro, 1998). among two or more elements. This can be seen in
It is necessary to contextualize that traditionally Table 14.2 with three paradoxical objects involving
the focus that has dominated the study of inferential three distinct inferential operations (Combariza &
operations has been that of pointing out an order Puche-Navarro, 2009).
of appearance (Mandler, 2007). Despite the impor- On the one hand and from what can be seen
tance of that work, and given the evidence that was in Table 14.2, it may be necessary to insist on the
just mentioned of the young child of around age benefit of speaking of inferential operations in the
4 years, discriminating between various paradoxical plural and not simply of inference in the singular.

310 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


Table 14.2. Relation between Paradoxical Objects and 3: mentalistic, and 4: substitution). This technique,
Types of Inferential Operations then, displays the temporal sequence of each choice
Type of inferential among the four scores along the 9 repeated experi-
Paradoxical objects operation ments (Combariza & Puche-Navarro, 2009).
In reality, rather than the technical specifica-
Hyperbolic Inferential operations of tions of the experiment that may be observed in the
the inductive type cited study, what we want to highlight here is that
Mentalistic Inferential operations of from the NLDS perspective, it sought to explore
the deductive type the performance of various inferential operations
involved in the three paradoxical objects utilized.
Substitution Inferential operations of Let’s look at some outcomes in an individual case
the transductive type
(Fig. 14.2).
Juan’s trajectory shows (Fig. 14.2) that much of
In the given study, we worked with a paradoxical the choices are scored as a 2. In the first 10 observa-
object situation on a problem-solving task with a tions, the scores ranged among 2, 3, and 4 options
branching structure. Faced with a board with three with a wide bandwidth. The same thing occurred
columns and four choices, the child could make in the last 20 observations, a segment in which the
three consecutive choices in sequences (which are largest number of option 4 appears. Between 10 and
given in the vertical columns) versus four options 45 the options are from 1, 2, and 3. A similar trajec-
from the paradoxical objects (three distracters and a tory is presented between observations 47 and 64, as
neutral option). In this way, we could keep itinerar- well as between observations 72 to 85. Another fea-
ies of the choices for each child. ture is that very few choices are recorded for option
The study was carried out with a time-series 4 because only 8 are counted. The bandwidth shows
design that allowed for obtaining 108 mea- that Juan’s scores range intermittently between the
sures by presenting the subject 9 sessions where four options. The picture shown in these trajecto-
each experiment collected 12 data units (12 x 9 ries is a rather incessant oscillation of choices. This
= 108). The data were treated with the graphic time-series technique results in highly irregular data
technique of minimae and maximae (van Geert & showing variability as a recurrent and a-periodical
van Dijk, 2002) applied to the individual perfor- process.
mances determined by the choices of the subject. What these data reveal is that the choices of
The result is a band with observational measures. the subject are marked by oscillations. It would be
The x-axis represents the period of 108 observa- expected that once the subject chooses the paradoxi-
tions and y-axis represents the scored choices of cal mentalistic object, it would continue doing so.
paradoxical objects (scale 1: control, 2: hyperbolic, On the contrary, the study found that the next time,

4 All data
Max
3 Min

0
1 6 11 16 21 26 31 36 41 46 51 56 61 66 71 76 81 86 91 96 101 106
Observations

Figure 14.2 Juan’s Performances of Various Inferential Operations Involved in the Three Paradoxical Objects along 108 Observations

pu ch e- n ava rro 311


a hyperbolic or a control may be chosen. There defi- Consider the wavelet of the same child, Juan,
nitely does not seem to be an order or a sequence whose data were seen with the graphical technique
between the various choices. of minimums and maximums in the Figure 14.3.
These three types of inferential operations do What does this image reveal? There are three
not show sequentially among themselves. It is not characteristics: the vertical axes show shapes as
recorded, for example, that the inferential opera- arcs diffuse; these arcs are self-contained; they
tions of the inductive type (hyperbolic) precede the represent lack of symmetry. These three charac-
deductive (mentalistic) nor those of the transductive teristics prove the multifractal nature of Juan’s
type (substitution), following a growing line of pro- response pattern.
gression. These three types of inferential operations The wavelet produced by the set of inferential
do not evolve in fixed sequences, but their develop- operations exposes a certain irregularity between
ment is interdependent. different arcs that seem self-contained. These forms
If there is no linear relationship among the vari- reveal the presence of different fractals in a multi-
ous inferential operations, then the next step is to fractal space. Based on this information, it can be
respond to whether they effectively have a fractal confirmed that the inferential operations studied
structure. To answer that question, it is necessary to mathematically correspond to a multifractal struc-
identify whether they behave as a transition region ture and to a strange attractor (Combariza & Puche-
and whether they might be treated as nodal points— Navarro, 2009). The wavelet indicates that the
that is, an area of attractors. This answer confirms trajectories studied belong to the same attractor.
the application of techniques such as the wavelet The wavelet shows evidence that allows us to
that was applied to the same data collected in the assume that the inferential operations constitute
same situation and under the same conditions. a system of coupled variables that control each
other and that act simultaneously, formally demon-
New Methods: The Wavelet Model strating the nonlinear nature of the phenomenon
The history of this technique is in itself remark- under study. The three types of inferential opera-
able because it was rediscovered several times tions belong to a region of attractors, which implies
(Mackenzie, 2001). The name wavelet is first that they change each other in an interdependent
found in an article by Morlet in 1984 (Goupillaud, manner. That is, if the inference involved in men-
Grossman, & Morlet, 1984). Technically speaking, talistic object grows, then the inferential operations
it is a transformed signal and of optimal visual rep- corresponding to the other two objects (hyperbolic
resentation with qualitative character and pattern and substitution) decrease. This type of interac-
productive. Its virtue is to identify within a cluster of tion would respond in the game between the three
data a code that allows for representing the facts in a objects in which one serves as a bridge between the
simple manner. One of its great virtues is to identify two other visual objects.
a-periodicity in chaotic systems. In this regard, it is The wavelet shows different patterns that emerge
a privilege to know if the paths that make inferential from the same model that underlies its functioning.
operations in the selections of the different paradox- Rose and Fischer pose the presence of “patterns of
ical objects correspond with chaotic systems. attractors” to refer to common values that would

Figure 14.3 Juan’s Performances Applied


to Wavelet

312 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


account for the connections between these different in classical proportional or sequential relations
domains (Rose & Fischer, 2009). These outcomes between a previous element and a posterior one—
would show these patterns of attractors between dif- but necessarily entails numerous bifurcated sce-
ferent functioning of inferences, derived rising from narios. Inferential operations fail to evolve in stages,
the various paradoxical objects. and their levels of complexity do not appear in a
The passage between successive micro-attractors stepwise fashion where the simplest precedes and
evidences that this is not a fixed sequence without is a condition of that which follows. Further, they
uniform order. In terms of inferential operations, this do not necessarily follow an unequivocal form not
implies that their evolution does not follow a pre- a single cause and effect chain. The role of multiple
established linear process. Rather, it is on a somewhat interactions of the components that comprise the
illogical path with no apparent order, similarly to subject’s relations with its environment is very pres-
the passage from one memory to another, but that ent. At least, perhaps the approach of Ilya Prigogine
behaves much as dynamic systems and therefore has that can be found in the reconstitution of his con-
an underlying structure of a chaotic nature. As Rose ference, L’homme devant l’incertain, is perhaps very
and Fischer exposed: “Dynamic modeling offers tools appropriate:
to better understand development and learning in
their full complexity, integrating influences involving The vision of an evolving and bifurcating world
person, context, and culture” (2009, pp. 417). requires a new rationality, a nature that invites us to
wonder, and that wonder is the common source of
Conclusions: Toward Exploration of the arts and science.
Nonlinearity in Mind and Culture
One of the aims of this chapter was to demon- Future Directions
strate the virtuosity of paradoxical objects in the Perhaps many more questions arise than answers
study of development from a cultural perspective. that have been able to be established from this
We believe that one is able to establish that they chapter. It is then worthwhile to focus on two issues
contain multiple paths of access to different levels on which this work is built: paradoxical objects,
for comprehension of the subject. The fact that a dynamic systems, and the role of both in a cultural
child can grasp the understanding of an object cre- approach to cognitive development.
ated in another distant place and in another century Paradoxical objects constitute, in themselves, a
is, as we said before, as much surprising as revealing great diversity and that diversity is what allows us to
of the object’s ability to interface between perspec- investigate the various kinds of cognitive activities,
tives and different times. culturally understood. The semiotic analysis of par-
However, another important conclusion is the adoxical objects complements this form of inquiry
pertinence of NLDS to account for the complexity by providing a map of the possibilities of the human
of inferential operations. Indeed, fluctuations and mind in varied contexts and disparate perspectives.
peculiarities of inferential functioning in understand- Being such a useful tool, the question is perhaps,
ing objects such as paradoxical ones requires a type “Why have paradoxical objects been used only by
of approach that is not schematic nor linear. In fact, art critics and journalists, not by psychologists?”
methodologically employing our graphic technique of Perhaps the simplest answer is found in the weight
minimae and maximae and the wavelets technique, of tradition. Psychologists are quite wedded to
we have been able to establish that human cogni- devices and tools that last and are reluctant to take
tive inferential operations have a fractal nature. They risks. However, to innovate and especially refresh
belong to a strange attractor zone. We can show the research when it offers interesting results is a task for
path from one attractor to another—yet without everyone. In the agenda of researchers in develop-
a steady sequence. It breaks the idea of an order in mental psychology from a cultural perspective, one
appearance of inferential operations development must see the needs for innovation with the use of
complexity. Wavelet shows that the distinctive infer- paradoxical objects (especially in a technological age
ential operations evolve in an interdependent way. where much of the information is imparted through
Multifractality found in inferential operations images) as another road with fertile results.
leads to the issue of evolution of cognitive func- It is also evident that there are not many authors
tions. This evolution is not necessarily from past– who have adopted the NLDS as a conceptual and
future relations as the sole and exclusive option—or methodological perspective in the study of the

pu ch e- n ava rro 313


development as a system that evolves under a con- niños pequeños [The wavelet use for the study of inferen-
text. Why? It seems that this alternative is quite risky cial functioning in children]. In R. Puche-Navarro (Comp.),
¿Es la mente no lineal? (pp. 111–133). Cali: Fondo Editorial
and requires the use of mathematical thought, which Universidad del Valle.
is a challenge for most psychologists. Nevertheless, Cortés, M., Combariza, E., & Puche-Navarro, R. (2009). Entre
in the future, there will be the capacity to build nubes, relojes y fractales: un acercamiento a las relaciones de
interdisciplinary teams composed by psychologists, los sistemas dinámicos no lineales y el desarrollo cognitivo
anthropologists, physicists and mathematicians that [Clouds, clocks and fractals: An approach to relationships
between nonlinear dynamical systems and cogni-
will be suited to approach the problem from the psy- tive development]. In R. Puche-Navarro (Comp.),
chology with the NLDS vision and methodology: ¿Es la mente no lineal? (pp. 45–72). Cali: Fondo Editorial
Universidad del Valle.
A dynamic approach can change the way you think
De la Rosa, A. (2006). Las figuras retóricas visuales: Apuntes
about development and it can change the way you para explorar la metáfora visual [Visual rethorical figures:
conduct research in development. Once we began to Exploring the visual metaphor]. Habladurías, 4, 66–83.
view development from a dynamic and selectionist Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea. New York: Simon
approach, we found the ideas so powerful that we & Schuster.
Eco, U. (1972). La estructura ausente. Introducción a la semiótica
could never go back to other ways of thinking. Every
(F. S. Cantarell, trans.) [The absent structure. Introduction to
paper we read, every talk we heard, every new bit of Semiotics]. Barcelona, Spain: Lumen.
data from our labs took on new meaning . . . The final Francastel, P. (1970). Etudes de Sociologie de l´art [Studies in soci-
test of dynamics in development, of course, is in its ologie of art ] Paris: Denoel Gonthier
usefulness to a wide range of scholars. We hope readers Gombrich, E. H. (1997). El Ingenio de Saul Steiberg [The Wit
of Saul Steiberg]. In E. H. Gombrich (Ed.), Temas de nuestro
will accept the challenge of the new way of thinking
tiempo. (pp.188–194). Madrid: Debate.
and working and we look forward to the report card. Gortari de, E. (1969). Iniciación a la lógica. [ An Introduction to
(Thelen & Smith, 1994, pp. 341–342) logic]. Mexico: Editorial
Grijalbo, S.A. Goupillaud, P., Grossmann, A., & Morlet, J.
What Thelen and Smith raised here about the (1984). Cycle-octaves and related transforms in seismic sig-
possibilities for the study of cognitive development nal analysis. Geoexploration, 23, 85–102.
from the perspective of NLDS can be applied with Hollenstein, T. (2007). State space grids: Analyzing dynam-
full force to the study of cognitive development ics across development. International Journal of Behavioral
Development, 31, 384–396.
from a cultural approach. Indeed, the dynamic Hollenstein, T., & Lewis, M. D. (2006). A state space analysis of
model can reconcile what appear to be disparate emotion and flexibility in parent-child interactions. Emotion,
aspects in development because of a whole range of 6, 663–669.
influences, both cultural and otherwise. It is fairly JETC7 - Texte reconstitué de la conférence du Professeur Ilya
safe to say that if psychologists look at the future, Prigogine Text of the conference of Prof Ilya Prigogine.
Retrieved January 25, 2010, from http://www.adelino-
the latter provides new opportunities. torres.com/filosofia/PRIGOGINE-C2%B4Homme%20
devant%20l%C2%B4incertain.pdf
Acknowledgements Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2002). Elementary, my dear Watson,
The author wishes to express her gratitude to professors the clue is in the genes - or is it? Proceedings of the British
Ernesto Combariza, and Mariela Orozco members of the Centro Academy, 117, 525–543.
de Investigaciones en Psicología, Cognición y Cultura, de la Koslowski, B. (1996). Theory and evidence. The development of
Universidad del Valle, for their help in for their careful, attentive scientific reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
reviewing, which allowed a significant improvement in the text. Kuhn, D. (2002). What is scientific thinking and how does it
Much of the information contained in this chapter is part of an develop? In U. Goswami (Ed.), Handbook of childhood cogni-
investigation project Cognitive development from dynamic non- tive development (pp. 371–393). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
linear systems. The empirical project was financed by internal Lamey, A., Hollenstein, T., Lewis, M. D., & Granic, I. (2004).
resources of the Vice-Dean of research of Universidad del Valle, GridWare (Versión 1.1). [Computer software]. http://
to the Center of Psychology and Cognition and Culture statespacegrids.org.
Lewis, M. D. (2000). The promise of dynamic Systems
approaches for an integrated account of human develop-
References ment. Child Development, 71(1), 36–43.
Adolph, K., Robinson, S., Young, J., & Gill-Alvarez, F. (2008). Lewis, M. D., Lamey, A. V., & Douglas, L. (1999). A new
What Is the Shape of Developmental Change? Psychological dynamic systems method for the analysis of early socioemo-
Review, 115(3), 527–543. tional development. Developmental Science, 2, 457–475.
Bariaud, F. (1983). La genèse de l´humour chez l´enfant [The Lozano, H., & Puche-Navarro, R. (1998). Paradigma y sin-
emergence of humor in young children]. Paris: PUF. tagma: chiste gráfico y tira cómica. Un estudio experimen-
Barthes, R. (1953). Lettres nouvelles. [New Letters]. Paris : PUF tal en el niño [Paradigmatic and syntagmatic axes: Joke and
Combariza E., & Puche-Navarro, R. (2009). El uso de la wave- comic strip. An experimental study]. Infancia y Aprendizaje,
let para el estudio de los funcionamientos inferenciales en 84, 99–113.

314 modeli ng i coni c li t e r acy


Lyra, M., & Valsiner, J. (2010) Historicity in development: Smith, P. (1998). Explicando el caos [Explaining chaos]. Madrid:
Abbreviation in mother-infant communication. Infancia y Gedisa.
Aprendizaje, Smith, L., & Thelen, E. (2003). Development as a Dynamic
Mackenzie, D. (2001). The Path from Research to Human Benefit. System. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 343–348.
National Academy of Sciences © U.S. National Academy. Spencer, J. P., & Perone, S. (2008). Defending qualitative
Mandelbrot , B. (2006). Los objetos fractales [The fractals objects]. change: The view from dynamical systems theory. Child
Barcelona, Spain: Tusquets. Development, 79, 1639–1647.
Mandler, J. M. (2007). The conceptual foundations of animals Thelen, E. (1995). Motor development: A new synthesis.
and artifacts. In S. Laurence & E. Margolis (Eds.), Creations American Psychologist, 50(2), 79–95.
of the mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach of the
McGhee, P. E. (1979). Humor: It’s origin and development. San development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman. Press.
Meuris, J. (1992). Magritte. Paris: Benedict Taschen. Valsiner, J. (2004). El desarrollo de las teorías del desarrollo: La
Munné, F. (2005). ¿Qué es la complejidad? [¿What´s “Hollywoodización” de la ciencia y su impacto [The devel-
Complexity?]. Encuentros de Psicología Social, 3(2), 6–17. opment of theories of development: the “Hollywoodization”
Munné, F. (2008). De la Globalización del Mundo a la of science and its impact]. Infancia y Aprendizaje, 27(2),
Globalización de la Mente [From the world’s globalization 147–154.
to the mind’s globalization]. Les Cahiers de Psychologie poli- van Dijk, M. (2004). Child language cuts capers. Variability and
tique, 13. ambiguity in early child development. Enschede: Print Partners
Orozco, M. (2000). El análisis de tareas: cómo utilizarlo en la Ipskamp.
enseñanza de la matemática en primaria [Task analysis: How van Geert, P. (1994). Dynamic systems of development:
to use it in teaching mathematics in elementary school]. Change between complexity and chaos. Hemel Hampstead:
Revista EMA, 5(2), 139–151. Harvester.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1991). The psychological unit and its role in van Geert, P. (1998). We almost had a great future behind
task analysis: A reinterpretation of object permanence. In M. us: the contribution of non-linear dynamics to develop-
Chapman & M. Chandler (Eds.), Criteria for competence. mental-science-in-the-making. Developmental Science, 1,
Controversies in the conceptualization and assessment of chil- 143–159.
dren’s abilities (pp. 153–187). New Jersey: Hillsdale. van Geert, P. (2003). Dynamic systems approches and modeling
Puche-Navarro, R. (2001). Mutaciones, metáforas y humor of developmental processes. In J. Valsiner & K. J. Conolly
visual en el niño [Mutations, visual metaphors and humor (Eds.), Handbook of developmental psychology (pp. 640–672).
in children]. In R. Rosas (Ed.), La mente reconsiderada London: Sage.
(pp. 181–202). Santiago de Chile: Psycke. van Geert, P., & van Dijk, M. (2002). Focus on variability: New
Puche-Navarro, R. (2002). El sentido del humor en el niño tools to study intra-individual variability in developmental
pequeño [A sense of humor in young children]. Bogotá: Siglo data. Infant Behavior and Development, 25, 340–374.
del Hombre. van Geert, P., & Steenbeek, H. (2005a). Explaining after
Puche-Navarro, R. (2004).Graphic jokes and children’s mind: An by before: Basic aspects of a dynamic systems approach
unusual way to approach children’s representational activity. to the study of development. Developmental Review, 25,
Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 45(5), 343–355. 247–251.
Puche-Navarro, R. (Comp.). (2009a). ¿Es la mente no lineal? [Is van Geert, P. & Steenbeek, H. (2005b). A complexity and
the mind non linear?] Cali: Fondo Editorial de la Universidad dynamic systems approach to developmental assessment,
del Valle. modeling and research. In K.W. Fischer, A. Battro, & P. Lena
Puche-Navarro, R. (2009b). From implicit to explicit representa- (Eds.), Mind, brain and education. Cambridge: Cambridge
tion in children’s response to pictorial humor. International University Press.
Journal of Behavioral Development, 33(6), 543–555. Yan, Z. & Fischer, K. W. (2002). Always under construction,
Rose L.T, & Fischer, KW. (2009) Dynamic Development A dynamic variations in adult cognitive microdevelopment.
neo Piagetian Approach In U. Muller, J.I.M. Carpendale & Human Development, 45, 141–160.
L. Smith, (Eds.). The cambridge companion to Piaget Yan, Z., & Fischer, K. W. (2007). Pattern emergence and pat-
(pp. 400–424). NY ; Cambridge University Press tern transition in microdevelopmental variation: Evidence
Shultz, T. R. (1996). A cognitive-developmental analysis of of complex dynamics of developmental processes. Journal of
humor. In A. Chapman & H. Foot (Eds.), Humor and Developmental Processes, 2(2), 39–62.
laughter: Theory, research and Applications (pp. 11–36). New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

pu ch e- n ava rro 315


CHAPTER

Existential Semiotics and Cultural


15 Psychology

Eero Tarasti

Abstract
Existential Semiotics is a new approach, or “school,” within the general semiotics and philosophy. It
tries to renew the epistemic foundations of the theory of signs, inspired by rereading the classics of
continental philosophy in the line of Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Jaspers, Arendt, and
Sartre and, on the other hand, the whole tradition of classical semiotics from Saussure to A.J. Greimas.
Yet, the new issue it offers is the revalorization of subject and subjectivity, and hence it opens the
field to psychological explanation and application as well. It launches new notions to the field, such
as transcendence, Dasein, modalities, values, Moi/Soi, and so forth. It constitutes a kind of ontological
semiotics starting from the modality of Being and shifting toward Doing and Appearing, as well. Many
concepts of various disciplines from representation and genre to dialogue and nature of communication
can be re-interpreted in its light. Albeit it also takes into account moral and axiological acts, it emphasizes
the transcendental aspect of value as virtual entities and hence does not belong so much to any post-
modern or post-structuralist thought; rather, it aims for what is called “neosemiotics,” philosophy, and
methodology of signification conceived in the 2010s.
Keywords: transcendence, subject, modalities, Being, Doing, Appearance (Schein), Dasein, Moi/Soi, sign
categories: pre-sign, act-sign, post-sign, neosemiotics, existentiality

The mere notion of “existential semiotics” in the of Kant, Schelling, Hegel, and thereafter the exis-
title evokes many issues in the history of ideas and tentialist line in the proper sense (i.e., Kierkegaard,
study of signs.1 As such, it is new theory of stud- Heidegger, Jaspers, Sartre, de Beauvoir, Arendt,
ies of communication and signification, as Eco has Wahl, Gabriel, Marcel, etc.). However, albeit this
defined the scope of the discipline of semiotics (Eco, new theory may get its inspiration from these clas-
1979, p. 8). But the attribute “existential” calls on a sical sources, one cannot return into any earlier
certain psychological dimension—namely, existen- historic phase, the theoretical thought in 2010 is
tial philosophy and even existentialism. In a broader definitely philosophy in our time and in our case is
sense one can ask, like once my publisher John enriched by the development of semiotic discipline
Gallman from Indiana University Press: Is it some- through the twentieth century particularly.
thing like existential life (this came to my mind
since the American transcendentalist philosophers, Return to Basic Ideas
Ralph Waldo Emerson, the writer Henry Thoreay These theoretical and philosophical reflections
and others can be considered a kind of pre-exis- have started from the hypothesis that semiotics
tentialist thinkers) On the other hand, it certainly cannot forever stay as the classics from Peirce and
carries a philosophical tinge at least and brings us Saussure to Greimas, Lotman, Sebeok, and others
back to German speculative philosophy, to the time have established it. Semiotics is in flux and reflects

316
new epistemic choices in the situation of sciences his/her speech providing it with his/her wishes,
in the 2000s. With existential semiotics, I by no hopes, certainties, uncertainties, duties, emotions,
means attempt any kind of return to existential- and so forth. They meant, in fact, a psychological
ism or to some earlier historic thinker, like Hegel, turn in the semiotics (even if it basically preserved
Kierkegaard, Sartre, or Heidegger. I have felt enti- its conceptual nature). Larousse’s French dictionary
tled to search for inspiration in these philosophers defines modality as:
because of the actuality of their ideas in the new
Psychic activity that the speaker projects into what
context.
he is saying. A thought is not content with a simple
Existential semiotics aims for discovering the life
presentation, but demands active participation by
of signs from within. It studies unique phenomena—
the thinking subject, activity which in the expression
unlike most previous semiotics, which have investi-
forms the soul of the sentence, without it the
gated only the conditions of such particular mean-
sentence does not exist.
ings. It studies signs in movement and flux, signs
(quoted from Tarasti, 1994, p. 39)
becoming signs (i.e., as pre-signs, act-signs, and
post-signs), as I have portrayed this process (Tarasti, Modalities appeared in the grammar of some lan-
2000, p. 33). It sees signs fluctuating between what guage as a special subjunctive verb form of sub-
I call by the German term Dasein—Being there (our phrase. In French, one says: “Il faut que j’aille à la
world with subjects and objects) and transcendence. banque,” or “J’espère qu’il vienne” (so not: “Je vais”
Completely new sign categories emerge in this ten- or “Il vient”). In Italian, one says: “Credo che questa
sion between reality and being beyond it. We have to sia possible.”
make a new list of categories in the side of that once
done by Peirce. Such new signs so far discovered are Dasein
a.o. trans-signs, endo- and exo-signs, quasi-signs (or Fundamental modalities were “being” and
as-if-signs), and pheno- and geno-signs. “doing.” Moreover. we can distinguish a third—
In my own previous theory of musical semiot- namely, becoming, referring to the “normal” tempo-
ics, which is my special field of empirical research ral course of events in our Dasein. Other modalities
(Tarasti, 1994, pp. 27, 38–43), I came to the con- are, in turn, will, can, know, and must plus believe.
clusion that the most important manner of music Importantly, here modalities are processual concepts.
to signify comes from its modalities. This evokes the Therefore, they are the element that is certainly pre-
background of my theories in the so-called “Paris served as valid from the “classical” semiotics, in the
School of Semiotics,” and particularly its founder, new existential semiotics, precisely because of their
the Lithuanian-born scholar Algirdas Julien dynamic nature.
Greimas. Before Greimas, I had studied with Claude They are very apt to portray what happens inside
Lévi-Strauss, but the Greimasian theory definitely what I call Dasein of the following model (Tarasti,
brought me into the core of the European tradition 2000, p. 10) in Figure 15.1.
of semiotics. Greimas started with his Sémantique The concept of Dasein (which I have left
structurale (1966) stemming from phenomenol- untranslated because of its strong philosophical
ogy, semantics, Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology, connotations) has been borrowed from German
and Levi-Straussian structural anthropology, not philosophy, Heidegger, and Jaspers (see also Jaspers,
to mention Saussure and Hjelmslev. He launched 1948, pp. 6–11, 57–66, 295); however, unlike in
new concepts such as semanalysis, actantial model, Heidegger, for whom Dasein in the first place meant
isotopies, and so forth. In the late 1970s, he put my existence, here it does not refer only to one
his thought into a generative course, fashionable subject, Me, but also to Others and likewise to the
model at that time (Greimas, 1979, pp. 157–164). objects that we desire. Yet, we have to notice that
However, the most radical of his innovations was there is something beyond the concrete reality in
just the discovery of modalities, to which he always which we live—namely, that which is called “tran-
referred to as the “third semiotic revolution” (the scendence.” The easiest definition of this intriguing
first being the invention of semantics by Bréal and notion, which certainly not all semioticians would
the second the structural linguistics by de Saussure). wish welcome to semiotic theory, might be the fol-
Modalities remained probably the most durable and lowing: Transcendent is anything that is absent but
innovative aspect of the Paris school. By modalities, present in our minds. Furthermore, in the model,
he meant the manners whereby a speaker animates a new element is introduced—namely, the subject.

ta ra sti 317
Negation
(“Le Néant”)

Dasein “Dasein” X

Affirmation
(plenitude)
Figure 15.1 The model of Dasein.

There is a subject dwelling in the Dasein, who willing, conceiving, and feeling being.” Accordingly,
feels it somehow deficient, not satisfactory, and so what Schelling did was to portray the world soul as
negates it. This is what Sartre called néantisation a “modal” entity, to use the semiotic vocabulary of
(Sartre, 1943, pp. 44–45), the lack of the existence the Paris School (Greimas, 1979, pp. 230–232).
that forces the subject to search for something else As early as here I want to emphasize that the
and more. But in the model, there are two tran- model is of conceptual nature and not of empiri-
scendental acts: first negation, followed by affirma- cal one. This, of course, does not exclude any kind
tion. As a result, we have the “existential style” in of subsequent psychological, anthropological, theo-
the Dasein x. That is what has been called also “exis- logical applications. Someone has proposed that
tential move.” “transcendental journey” means “a psychedelic trip,”
First our subject finds himself amidst the objec- some others have compared it to the act of a shaman
tive signs of Dasein. But then the subject recog- in which his soul after he has eaten mushrooms,
nizes the emptiness and Nothingness surrounding makes a transmundane wandering to other realities,
the existence from which he has come—that is, and so forth. However, the scheme itself is philo-
which precedes him and comes after him. The sophical and deals with what Kant called transzen-
subject makes a leap into Nothingess, to the realm dental rather than transzendent (Kant, 1787/1968,
of Le Néant, described by Sartre. In its light, the p. 379).
whole earlier Dasein seems to have lost its ground: We can, of course, provide the logical opera-
it appears to be senseless. This constitutes the first tions of affirmation and negation with a more psy-
act of transcendence, or the negation. Nevertheless chological content and distinguish within them
the movement of the subject continues further and subtle nuances of these acts. For example, negation
now follows the second act of transcendence: He means:
encounters the opposite pole of the Nothingness—
the universe that is meaningful but in some supra- • abandoning, giving up—that is, one is in a
individual way, independently of his own act of situation in which some x has appeared, the subject
signification. The act can be called affirmation; as has taken it into its possession but now abandons
the consequence of this act, he finds what Peirce it, and is “disjuncted” from it (formalized as S
called the Ground. For me, it was first difficult to V O, in the Greimassian semiotics; see Greimas,
find a suitable concept to portray this state, before 1979, p. 108)
I noticed, after reading the Russian philosopher • passing by: x appears but a subject passes by it
Vladimir Soloviev (1965, pp. 348–349), that it was • forgetting: x has appeared, but it is forgotten;
the same as what in the Gnostic philosophy was it does not have any impact
called pleroma or plenitude. This again evokes die • making a counter-argument: x appears, but
Weltseele, the world soul of Schelling (see also Ralph something totally different follows: y or x appears
Waldo Emerson), which he defined as follows: “The and it is followed by its negation (inversion,
soul of the world, anima mundi, is the unitary inner contrast, opposition or else) or this corresponds to
nature of the world, which is thought to be a living, Greimas’s semiotic square and its categories s1 and

318 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


s2, and non-s1 and non-s2 (Greimas, 1979, • transfiguration: x radiates something that
pp. 29–33) stems from it background, not from its own
• rejecting: x appears, but it is rejected power but as the weight of the invisible reality; for
• preventing: x is going to appear, but it is example, the bodies in El Creco’s paintings—in
prevented this case, we first encounter the negation: the body
• taking away the relations attributes: x appears, is portrayed as suffering, pining, but behind it
but one eliminates its seems x . . . xn where after looms some clarity
only it becomes acceptable • victory: x appears as the end of a long
• destroying: x appears, but it is destroyed struggle; for example, C major at the end of
• collapsing, vanishing: x appears, but it then Beethoven’s Fifth
disappears by itself, without our ability or will to • opening: the appearance of x means a gate to
influence it the world of possibilities, new universes open for
• concealing: the appearance of x is hidden, but us
altogether it “is” on a certain level • liberation: the appearance of x signifies
• parodizing: x appears, but it is not taken getting rid of the chains of y or x′.
seriously; it is taken as an “as-if sign”
However, one has to note two other aspects of
• mocking: x appears, but one jokes with it; it is
this model of how our psyche is adapted to his/her
ironized, made grotesque
existential situation and journeys. For the first, there
• dissolution: x appears, but it is reduced to
is one thing that is evoked by pondering negation as
smaller parts; when its total phenomenal quality
a kind of alienation, estrangement. Namely, when
is lost, one does not see the forest from trees. Or,
a subject temporarily exits his Dasein in his tran-
according to Adorno: “When one scrutinizes art
scendental act, he can naturally stay in this journey
works very close, even most objective works turn
one minute, hour, day, week, year, decades. In the
into confusion, texts into words . . . the particular
temporal sense, the journey can thus last whatsoever
element of the work vanishes, its abridgment
time span. Yet, it can occur that when he returns to
evaporates under microscopic glance” (Adorno,
the world of his Dasein, symbolized by a globe, it
2006, p. 209)
has changed, it has been all the time in motion by
• misunderstanding: x appears, but it is not
itself and completely independently of our subject,
interpreted as x but as something else.
it has perhaps turned around to some directions so
Affirmation means: that our subject does not return any longer to the
same world. There has been in-built in our model
• acceptance: x appear,s and we accept it as a kind of solipsist idea that Dasein exists only for
without intervening it; for example, we rejoice in one subject and that it changes its shape because of
others’ success his/her existential experiences. Yet it is not only so.
• helping: contributing to the fact that x During the transcendental journey, the world may
appears have in the meantime developed into a new direc-
• enlightenment: we see x in a favorable light tion. Subject does not return at home but to a quite
• revelation of the truth and disappearance of different world from that which he left. As far as
lie: x appears, it is recognized as Schein, lie, and we take Dasein as a collective entity, which consists
as its counterpole we do so that, or allow that x′ of subjects and objects, of Others, we encounter
appears the community and the autonomous development
• beginning: we start to strive for, we undertake of the collectivity, the change brought by the his-
an act so that some positive, euphoric x appears tory. Our subject can either accept this change and
• duration: we attempt to maintain the try to adapt to it or deny it. A special opportunity
appearance of x; for example, by teaching someone for semiotics of resistance emerges from the latter
• finishing: x appears as the end result of case. Progress does not mean to go along the normal
a process, as a reward of pain; the shine, the course of the journey, but to look at other alterna-
brilliance has been gained by labor (see later the tives, or what might have happened, what might
modality of appearing) have been possible (see Tarasti, 2009, pp. 51, 61–65)
• organic vitality: x erupts, appears as as shown in Figure 15.2.
consequence of an organic process, as abandoning In addition, there is another aspect at our model,
to it, as “striding at the top of a wave” which opens new avenues after the previous one.

ta ra sti 319
Le Néant

Dasein
Dasein

Affirmation Figure 15.3 The counter-current of the Dasein.

Figure 15.2 The turn-around of Dasein.


used by Greimas but appearing also in the phenom-
Namely, the arrows can go backward as well. enological theories by Roman Ingarden.
Our subject recalls how Dasein was before and Ultimately, this is an axiological problem of the
returns to it on the basis of his memory. His mem- existence of values. In the Saussurean tradition val-
ory has kept still some images and ideas from these ues are relative: they are determined only in their
previous worlds and their phases, as we can see in context as opposed to other values by the linguis-
Figure 15.3. tic community (Saussure, 1916/1995, p. 116). In
Some of them he may have already forgotten, my theory, values are transcendental but become
and similarly the Dasein may have forgotten him. signs via the activities of the subject. In the aes-
There is danger indeed that if he dwells too long thetical field such a view is of course problematic.
in his position of resistance and outside the Dasein, How can we say that the value of, say, a Beethoven
then he is forgotten—like a text that has to be sonata existed before its creation? Was it looming
destroyed and ignored from the collective memory somewhere and waiting for its actualization in the
of a culture. This leads to strong social implications Dasein? We may say that transcendental values do
of our theory. Real thinkers of resistance are always not become a manifest reality without an agent who
forgotten and suppressed. If they were accepted, actualizes them.
they would not be what they want to be. Thus, in When this occurs, such pre-signs can also become
our model the arrows go also to another direction: something different than they were thought to be
backward. This leads us to ponder the return of before, as mere pre-signs (Tarasti, 2000, p. 33).
signs and problems of history, determination and Without the help of other modalities, know, can,
optionality, causality, and communication. must, and will they are never concretized. Signs can
be also classified as endo- and exo-signs (Tarasti,
Values 2000, pp. 37–55)—that is, either something inter-
In the existential theory, regarding semiotics (one nal to our subject’s world or external to it.
may have already wondered what this has to do with Let us scrutinize this problem regarding moral
the theory of signs), signs are in constant movement values. If we would like to abridge what was said
between transcendence and Dasein. Depending on above, then we could present the following figure:
their distance to Dasein, whether they are approach-
values---------------> modalities-----------------> signs
ing it or distancing from it we indeed get new types of
signs. For the first, we have pre-signs—that is, ideas The movement would be from the left to the
or values that have not yet become concrete signs. right, when in the semiosis stepwise some abstract
Such signs are virtual. When they become manifest idea is condensed and crystallizes at the end into
as a sign object or “vehicle” or an act, they become a sign (see Tarasti, 2004, p. 39). The psychological
act-signs. Moreover, when they exercise their impact moment is situated at modalities and modaliza-
on receivers, they become post-signs. In their vir- tions. But can we call this process a semiosis? Shall
tual, potential state as transcendental entities, they we then not commit the error that we consider signs
can be called trans-signs. These three or four phases not straightly as values but at least value vehicles,
correspond to three activities of the human mind: and then we would correspondingly keep values as
virtualizing, actualizing, and realizing—not only signs? To some philosophers, to say that something

320 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


is “sign” is not any recommendation. But on which the responsibility of the person of Dasein whether
grounds could we reason that if something is of sign he/she believes in this and whether he/she lets them
character, then it would be less “real” and valuable? have any impact on his/her acts. This idea probably
Peirce’s way of thinking was that to become con- provides us with the key to the problem of how
scious of a sign is a second. The French novel writer to fit values into modalities and furthermore into
Le Clezio said that as soon as when reading a novel, signs—that is, how to act. I offer you now such a
we exclaim: “Oh this was well said!” it is a kind of proposal. No one can say that I pursue such and
sign, and it does not function any longer. The func- such an act because a transcendental value x requires
tionality of signs has become almost an aesthetic me to do so.” When I select value x as my ideal, it is
slogan in recent years. But this is the same as stated always my own choice for which I am responsible.
above—namely, the value reality escapes our hold This is my main argument against the argument
on it, and everything becomes only technical prob- most often used to attack the value realists—that
lems of functionality. Some may say that this was is, who and/or what guarantees that some person
the fault of the semioticians! They taught us that all does not start to enact some completely foolish
is only sign and semiosis: there can be disturbances transcendental value and even imagine to be right.
in its functioning, but they can be corrected with However, when I have picked up the value x, it falls
the technical knowledge of dominance that we have into the field of the modalities and passions of our
of the functioning of text. Thus, values remain com- Dasein, amidst our wanting, obligations, abilities,
pletely external, and transcendental, and one does and knowing. Then I make the act, x or non-x—
not need to believe in their existence: There are only that is, I fulfill an act following this value or I give
opinions, language, discourse, but no transcenden- it up, I do something against it, I negate the value
tal categories. Greimas (1979/1999) said: “Il n’y a by my act, see Figure 15.4.
pas de vérité, il n’y a que véridiction” [“There is no Hence, the signified of the act is the transcen-
truth, there are only statements about truth”]. dental value but only insofar as this, our subject, has
All moral philosophers have to deal with Moore the right value of competence for the code whereby
and Hume. The latter proposed as his thesis that he/she can connect such an act to the transcenden-
no values can be inferred from facts. From the state tal value under question.
of how things are, we cannot logically infer how At the same time this act further launches other
they should be. In my existential semiotics, I have acts, which either affirm or negate the act x/non-x.
defended the idea that values could be transcenden- Consequently, we can infer the crucial imperative
tal ideas in the side of other values that exist out- for any moral activity: If the act x=/non-x= causes in
side the Dasein. However, in some cases and under its Umwelt other negative acts, which are negative in
certain circumstances, they start to exercise their relations to other transcendental values, then such
influence within the Dasein, when some living sub- an act should not be committed. In other words,
ject therein—individual or collective—feels such a we have to apply there the postulate by Mackie that
value as his own, experiences it to oblige him/her says that we have to give up moral judgment and
into something and finally realizes this value as a activity. We might, for example, imagine that we
sign. The British philosopher John Mackie in his
work Inventing Right and Wrong (Mackie 1977),
has represented extreme value nominalism. Views X
of different cultures of what is right and wrong
are so different that no value facts exist. All moral
statements are thus untrue. Mackie’s idea is that all
objective moral theories make a mistake when they
say that man cannot step outside and above morals X’
if he/she wants to do so. In his mind, moral is a spe-
cial form of social life, which man and his commu-
nity creates and chooses. This sounds already rather
existential. He says: “If moral leads into quarrel and
dispute, then moral shall be forgotten!”
If, even after this, we keep on the point that
moral values exist in transcendence, it remains on Figure 15.4 The enactment of values.

ta ra sti 321
have the transcendental value of being honest or encyclopedia of values, then the reality of values is
keeping promises. However, somebody does some- not fulfilled at all.
thing contrary (e.g., breaks a contract). This nega- This model should likewise fit to other values, as
tive act enhances in its social environment reactions said, like the truth or epistemic values and the beauty
or other acts that can likewise be negative: non-y or aesthetic values. In any case, the subject of Dasein
punishing, non-p abandoning, exclusion outside is totally responsible for his value choices—that is,
the community, non-q hatred. All these reactive which value he metamodalizes from the encyclope-
value acts are, in turn, negations of some transcen- dia of values. Naturally when he is devoid of some
dental values, like indulgence, benevolence, abstina- value because of his education, for example, one
tion from violence, charity, look at Figure 15.5, and can say that also his community, “senders” (school,
so forth. parents, teachers), are responsible. Yet, he is existen-
In other words, if the correction of a negative tially responsible for which transcendental values he
value act causes more negative acts in its Umwelt selects, how he modalizes them into a value act, and
than the original negative act, then one has to give which kind of value acts and modalities they bring
up such a correction, being morally right and dis- about.
playing it. The intermediate phase of modalities is indis-
Two kinds of modalities function in such a pensable in making values and signs compatible. It
moral value act, like in any fulfillment of a value: also explains why some originally right value can,
(1) modalities that regulate acts and the behaviors when it is transformed into a value act, get distorted
of their agents in the Dasein, and (2) modalities into a caricature of itself: It is caused by modaliza-
that regulate the relationships of value acts to their tion, or in the transformation of the phase of actual-
transcendental values. This movement takes place in izing when the human passions intervene.
two directions: either it is manifesting, concretizing This explains the nature of meta-modalities:
values or the process in which, as Greimas states, They are altogether activities of a subject. Yet, how
virtual act changes into actual and sometimes even then do meta-modalities distinguish from ordinary
real - this takes place when we ‘return’ to the value modalities? They contribute to the particular act of
as it is in transcendence and compare the ‘actual’ signification in which a value is connected to a phys-
value to the ‘virtual value’, hence the transcenden- ical act or object of the sign vehicle. That implies the
tal value serves as the source of the actualized value following varieties of ordinary modalities:
in Dasein. These two acts of metamodalization, i.e.
making values concrete entities by actualizing them 1. want (vouloir): I want to connect value x to
and by comparing them to their transcendental the signified of act x. If subject would not want it,
and virtual sources, presuppose a particular value this value could not manifest. But another concern
competence. If our subjects do not possess the right is if such a wanting differs from that wanting and
codes to connect a potential, virtual value into an desire, whereby the subjects of Dasein look after
act that concretizes it and if they cannot decode each other or various value objects. Not even a
from an act its value content and compare it to the supporter of the psychoanalytic theory would
presume that the Freudian desire would as such
explain for example, artistic activity, ethical choice
X
or scientific theory. A special form of human
wanting is involved.
Y 2. know (savoir): I know that value x exists;
without such knowledge I cannot even want to
non-Y’ concretize it in my value act: But which kind of
P knowing is this? Is it quite similar information as
non-X’ the one we receive in our Dasein and that can be
non-Q’ measured by the information theoretical concepts
Q of enthropy and redundancy?
non-P’ 3. can (pouvoir): I am able to connect a value
x to an act x—for example, I want to help sick
people but to do something I have to master
Figure 15.5. Reaction to a value act. medicine; I want to help the poor, but unless I am

322 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


able to provide a property, then I cannot do it; I how such semiosis functions within an organism,
want to transmit artistic experiences, but if I do Uexküll uses musical metaphors; he says that every
not master good techniques, then I cannot produce organism surrounded by its Umwelt possesses its
any such emotions; and so forth. codes or something like a score, which determines
4)=must=(devoir): must means the which signs it accepts from Umwelt, and which it
internalization of values, so that we could rejects. This principle is called Ich-Ton, Me-Tone
experience that a value obliges us. But even then (see in music Tarasti, 2002, pp. 98, 109). Moreover,
the meta-modality must is our own existential Thure von Uexküll calls this process of signs intrud-
choice. ing the organism and functioning within it on vari-
ous levels from molecules to cells endosemiosis. On
New Types of Signs this basis, we can speak of two kinds of signs: endo-
The traffic between these instances of signs— signs and exo-signs, in these two states of being
that is, between transcendence and existence—is either in or out (Tarasti, 2000, pp. 37–56).
taken care of by meta-modalities, as we would call I have tried to bring the wonderful idea of
them. Altogether, signs have their situations—an Me-Tone back to music and art by arguing that
aspect found essential in the existential approach. If every composer, every composition, every artwork
we take this first model as a narrative structure por- also has its Me-Tone that determines its characteris-
traying human life, it radically differs from classical tics. In this new framework of existential semiotics,
story schemes, which are symmetrical. Following and its fundamental notions of Dasein and tran-
Greimas, any narrative starts with a situation in scendence, we can give it a Kantian interpretation
which we are hic, nunc, ego (or here, now, me), but so that Ich-Ton appears through Kantian categories
then something happens (the so-called “initial lack” of subject (actor)-time-space when some transcen-
in Vladimir Propp’s theory of Russian folk tales) dental idea is filtered into Dasein.
that causes a “disengagement” from this prial state Moreover, I distinguish as-if signs (i.e., signs that
into there, then, others. Yet, normally in a classical must not be taken quite literally in the Dasein, but
storytelling, we return back to the initial state—that rather as a kind of metaphors). All signs of artistic
is, we are “engaged” with it, and so the syntagmatic representation are of this nature any signs in cin-
line becomes symmetrical. However, in the existen- ema, theater that should never be blended with
tial semiosis, there is no return—what happens next reality. Furthermore we can distinguish pheno-
is always unknown, unpredictable. This evokes the and geno-signs. This has nothing to do with Julia
idea of Levinas in his theory of Totality and Infinite Kristeva’s geno- and pheno-text (Kristeva, 1969),
(Levinas, 1971). nor with Barthes’s pheno- and geno-song (Barthes,
Another new scientific paradigm that enters 1977, p. 182). Pheno-signs are simply traditional
into existential semiotics—perhaps paradoxically signs that refer to or stand for something else. When
to some minds—is the biosemiotics. Biosemiotics referring or standing for, the sign remains what it
is one of the new schools that have emerged in is—it is only a tool, a window to the world of sig-
the last 20 years within general semiotics, thanks nified. Instead in the case of geno-sign, the entire
to writings of Thomas A. Sebeok (see also Sebeok, process of signs becoming signs is included: the
2001, pp. 31–44), and above all to the discovery of whole generation of the sign with various phases
the founder of this doctrine, the Estonian Jakob v. is vividly evoked by the appearance of such a sign.
Uexküll (see also Uexküll, 1940). For the first, the For example, when we listen for the first time to the
surprise with this new issue is that it does NOT overture to Parsifal by Richard Wagner, it launches
mean that semiotic, symbolic processes and forms with a motif raising from the depths, as something
were reduced into something biological—for exam- solemn, sad, appealing, longing for something. It
ple, in sociobiological theories that say that society is a pheno-sign that by its mere musical qualities
at the end is nothing but biology. It is the other way evokes certain modal content (will, can, etc.). If
around: biology and vital processes are shown to be one is a perfect Wagnerian, then one may recognize
semioses. The son of Jakob, Thure v. Uexküll has it as the Abendmal motif, referring to Amfortas.
said that his father’s doctrine is particularly well- However, this motif, when heard at the end of the
compatible with Peircean semiotics (T. Uexküll et 6-hour-long opera, gets a turn into E-flat major
al, 1993), but nothing prevents us from using it in with a cadence, and has become a geno-sign. We
other conceptual frameworks as well. To illustrate feel that it contains the whole growth of Parsifal

ta ra sti 323
from a young ignorant foolish into the repemptor (I refer here to the modal logics developed by Greimas
of the Graal knights, Kundry included. It carries the and angloanalytic philosophers and Finnish scholar
whole story in it. Here again the essential is that Georg Henrik v. Wright). They are again subjected
signs are nothing fixed; they are always in the move- to communication process. Yet, transcendence rep-
ment of becoming something else. resents pure signification without narrativization.
However, in what follows, I want to scrutinize Therefore, one can say that when the boundaries
some new issues and concepts whereby existen- of the Dasein get vague or vanish, then starts the
tial semiotics tries to contribute to semiotics and real semiosis without narrativity. There is narrativity
humanities in general. These will be discussed under only in Dasein. When, in turn, some transcendental
the headings of Transcendence, Subject, Being, idea intrudes to the Dasein of a subject, it becomes a
Doing, and Appearing. sign, and it participates to the communication.
Now one has to ask, what is that force that makes
Transcendence a transcendental idea manifest in communication or
Transcendence is not a concept we are used to incarnate into a sign? Signs have a certain imperish-
encountering in the semiotic context. Dictionaries, able part. Goethe said: Kein Wesen kann zum nichts
encyclopedias and handbooks from Greimas and zerfallen [No being can disappear], and he certainly
Sebeok as well as Posner, Nöth, and Bouissac simply meant this. Nevertheless signs also have a perish-
exclude it from semiotic discussion. However, no one able, temporal spatial, and actorial part. From the
can deny its cogency and centrality in the German viewpoint of a subject, the manifestation of con-
philosophy from Kant to Heidegger. As far as this tent in the physical appearance of the sign vehicle
philosophical tradition, its idealist nature, rejected is involved. The essential point here is thus the con-
by most of semiotic theories, is more and more seen cept of a boundary. A transcendental idea has to
as a fertilizing seed to contemporary semiotics (like transgress the limit to become a sign.
the turn to phenomenology and hermeneutics in Ricoeur (1983, pp. 85–129) speaks about three
the European context and deconstruction in the kinds of mimesis. Could we not then say that the
American scene show), and we cannot any longer becoming of transcendence into a sign in a Dasein
ignore its existence. In the existential semiotics, the is the first mimesis? In other words, the Dasein of
life of signs is situated in their movement and traffic a subject can simulate transcendence: man wants
between transcendence and Dasein. by his act to change his Dasein according to some
To some, the mere introducing of such a notion idea. Every action is based on this: a contradiction
like transcendence has some kind celestial, almost prevails between an idea and the reality of Dasein.
theological tinge about it. If we go in this direction Subject wants to intervene the course of events.
(which would also be very Heideggerian as far as Existentially he can do so—that is, he is free to do
he considered the ultimate goal of every being and so. However, when a subject in his Dasein creates
Dasein its disappearance, Sein zum Tod), we can an artwork, which is like a model of his Dasein (in
notice that within existential semiotics we are able which case the world of a work imitates his living
to deal with even such profound and serious issues. world), then the second mimesis occurs. In the the-
In this framework, death means the disappearance ory of Ricoeur, the mimesis essentially belongs to
of the boundaries of the Dasein and the blending of the course of process of communication: mimesis1
a subject to transcendence. There the juxtaposition = production of sign, and mimesis2 = the manner in
of temporality of Dasein and atemporality of tran- which a sign simulates or portrays the living world
scendence (i.e., time and not-time) is reconciled. All (Dasein). Then, the third mimesis (i.e., mimesis3)
that has happened in the Dasein (according to cer- would be the same as aisthesis, the interpretation
tain narrativity, dynamism, and processuality) has of a sign.
accumulated into acts of this subject. They are signs Instead, in our own model, mimesis does not
left by him that fuse together with acts by other sub- take place horizontally, in a syntagmatic or linear
jects who have already moved into transcendence. way as a kind of narrative course from a sender to
This is irreversible; nothing can be changed any receiver, but vertically as a movement from tran-
longer therein. They can be naturally renarrativized scendence or a subject’s inner consciousness, from
and rendered to constitute a part of the pseudo- a transcendental subject toward his living world,
narrativity and temporality of history writing. In Dasein (by a transcendental subject, we then under-
such a case, a subject is able to “remodalize” them stand a subject who, by his thought, tries to conceive

324 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


the transcendence). Following this theory, I should Again, mimesis3 also may not be —that is, the
make a slight correction to my earlier model of subject does not accept the idea that he should give
transcendental journeys and acts (see Tarasti, 2000, up the positions and signs he has gained during the
p. 10). There are no two different transcendences, processes of communication. Yet, unless he does not
one empty and anguishing nothingness (le néant), understand to make the limits of his Dasein vis-à-
and the other rich and overwhelming plenitude, vis transcendence more transparent and thus expe-
full with meanings or the “world soul,” as Schelling rience the plenitude of the transcendence—what is
called it. There is only one transcendence, which the nothing else but the encyclopedia of the acts and
subject experiences as nothingness in his act of nega- ideas in the entire transcendence—he is left without
tion, when he clings to his Dasein in his fear of the this essential deliberating and positive experience,
experience transgressing the limits of the boundaries which can also change his attitude toward death, the
of his existence. This is caused by his unwillingness vanishing of his Dasein. In fact, in every temporal
to give up the merits, achievements, and signs he has artwork, such disappearance already takes place,
obtained and gained in the phases of his Dasein. In but still the subject is after such a mini-narration
front of the unknown atemporal and anti-narrative transfigured, because he has mirrored the imperish-
transcendence, he experiences anguish, and he feels able transcendental entities of his living world to the
the nothingness threatens the significations he has aforementioned model and become aware of them.
made in his Dasein, which he believes he has cre- In any case, there is only one transcendence, but
ated himself. All statements about the fact that life the individual who has clung to the communication
has went down the drain, the plans, and the noemas processes of his Dasein, as rich as they may ever be, is
of a subject not being realized in the narrative pro- blinded to its contents, to the true semiosis of ideas
cesses of the Dasein result from this metaphysical and acts and significations, and believes it is empty.
attitude. Instead, when the boundaries of Dasein get Therefore, only when he abandons the boundaries
blurred, the subject sees the connection of his signs of his Dasein or via an act of conception and is able
and acts to their proper timeless transcendence and to step over this borderline, does he realize the true
real signification. The subject has the liberty to pur- plenitude of the transcendence. This experience is
sue affirmation and negation as stated above. This connected with the existential experience that he is
means here that he/she can reject the processes of already waited for on the other side of the bound-
mimesis1 through mimesis3. When he opposes to ary. All that positive or negative, which he has left
mimesis1, he does not want to listen to the voice of in his life, waits for him in the transcendence. Thus
the transcendental subject within himself and does mimesis3 means transgressing the boundary, striv-
not transform transcendental ideas into signs. His ing to get beyond oneself and its realization.
existence does not reach the level of sign; it remains The continuous crossing-over limits of tran-
a series of detached moments in the process of com- scendence and Dasein is one of the most profound
munication without a real content. The aesthetician problems of existential semiotics. It manifests as
Kierkegaard, who gets lost in his hedonistic life, is many subproblems of the communication processes
such a person rejecting mimesis1. of the Dasein. Is it then so that it is not sufficient
The models that keep within the Dasein and that a subject hears inside the voice of a transcen-
emphasize its immanency, which claim that the dental subject that tells to him the right aesthetic
only reality is the Dasein itself, the body, the soci- resolution or ethical choice, but he has to manifest
ety as a continuous process, and that nothing this voice to others in the world of communication
else exists, is based on the rejection of mimesis1. (i.e., encounter a subject who is alien-psychic entity
However, a subject can also reject mimesis2 or the to him)? Such an encounter of the alien-psychic
idea that he would create intentional objects in the is again essentially an event of mimesis2—that is,
course of Dasein. He can stay without realizing our subject creates his model of “mini-Dasein” not
that he can, by his acts and signs (act-signs), imi- to himself but in a dialogue with someone else,
tate and simulate the narration of the Dasein. An and this other influences it essentially. Our sub-
artist again creates artwork, copies, and models of ject strives for anticipating such a transcendence of
his Dasein, in which, however, one can try to see the other—for example, to please him, to get his
the existential in the narration of his proper life. message understood. But why is this so terribly
Music serves as such a narration on a high level of important? Why does our subject want to commu-
abstraction. nicate? Communication is always crossing over the

ta ra sti 325
boundary, and in this sense it is a model of both in us, like Lacan postulated: Ca parle. However, in
mimesis1 and mimesis2. The subject wants to show poststructuralist and postmodern theories the sub-
by it that his message goes beyond the boundary. It ject re-entered. One may interpret existential semiot-
is supported by the authority of transcendence, but ics as one of these new revalorizations of subjectivity
he also wants by this communicative act to aban- in the history of ideas, but I would not call it any
don his own boundaries and taste in advance what “post”-phenomenonen any longer; rather, I would
the definite vanishing of such borderlines would call it “neosemiotics.” This paradigm is setting forth
mean. Communication on this level of transference something radically new, using freely from the clas-
or shifts of values and modalities means just such sical semiotics what it needs and combining these
a fusion with the Other. It is anticipating the final ideas to what is the most inspiring in the specula-
blending with the Other or the transcendence in the tive philosophy from Kant and Hegel to Sartre and
proper sense. Marcel. It never considers only the text but all its
In fact semiosis has two movements or “forces”: conditions, its whole Umwelt, its process of becom-
vertical and horizontal. Vertical force leads into the ing a text, the whole act of enunciation. There has
fulfillment of ideas of transcendence, to mimesis in been much talk about subjects and subjectivity in
the Dasein, in such a manner that they first become many neighboring areas of semiotics, like in psycho-
noemas of a subject. Thereafter the vertical move- analysis, gender theories, and cultural theories.
ment continues within the Dasein as its modeling However, without a more articulated vision of
and simulating in various texts and narratives. This how a subject appears in the enunciation and our
represents the second degree of mimesis. The third semiotic activities, such theoretical views remain at
phase is, in fact, already a kind of de-mimesis, or half of their goals, as laudable as their efforts as such
the return of the ideas back to the transcendence, might be. To do so, I need to make a short excursion
to which they are blended. Narrativity is a special to the roots of existential semiotics, which means to
kind of syntagmatic form, which appears first in the go back to Hegel and his logics. For some semioti-
living world of the Dasein and then in the world cians, Hegel is mere conceptual poetry, to someone
of text. In other words, they at the same time get he was only acceptable after a Marxist turn-around,
modalized and syntagmatized to participate to but to some like Arendt he was the most central
process of communication. This is the horizontal thinker of Western philosophy altogether, who
direction of semiosis, its temporalization. On this had compiled phenomena of nature and history as
basis, I have argued that both aspects of semiotics a homogeneous construction, of which, however,
are ultimately of transcendental nature: communi- one did not know whether it was a prison or a pal-
cation—every act of communication is the encoun- ace (Arendt, 2000, p. 111). To Arendt, Hegel was
ter of the Other, the alien psychic, a leap toward the last word of the Western philosophy. All that
the unknown; and signification—by signs we talk came after him was either his imitation or rebellion
about things that are not present. Therefore, both against him. The present schools of thought (i.e., in
essential sections of any semiotics, communication Arendt’s case, Husserl, Heidegger, and Jaspers) were
and signification represent for existential semiotics the epigones of Hegel. They all tried to reconstruct
the transcendental: when in Saussure’s picture of a the unity of thinking and being without reaching a
dialogue, Mr. A sends signs to Mr. B, the latter is a balance when they either privileged matter (materi-
transcendental entity to the former; there is a gap alism) or mind (idealism). It may be that Arendt was
between them, but in human communication it is right. I do believe that even the semiotic thought is
not empty: it is filled by modalities and modaliza- indebted to Hegel, whose traces we can follow both
tions by these subjects—that is, the destinator and in Peirce and Royce as well as in French structural-
destinatee. Furthermore, the signs used and emit- ists, the Tartu cultural semioticians—particularly in
ted here are transcendental entities because they are existential semiotics. Therefore, I take as my starting
aliquid stat pro aliquot—something standing for point only one detail from the Hegelian logic, the
something as the oldest scholastic definition of sign principle by which we construct further our theory
is put. of subject—namely, his categories of an-sich-sein
(Being-in-itself ) and für-sich-sein (Being-for-itself ).
Subject Reconsidered or BEING In the Hegel dictionary edited by Michael Inwood,
In the structuralist phase, subject was eliminated there is an entry in,for, and in and for, itself, himself,
in favor of systems and grammars that were talking etc.(Inwood, 1992, pp. 133–136).

326 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


Hegel used the terms an sich and für sich in being to für sich being corresponds to his becoming
their ordinary senses but also provided them with a sign to himself, or the emergence of his identity.
contrasting meaning. As finite a thing has a deter- Kierkegaard says: the task of a subject is more and
minate nature only in virtue of its relation with more to take off his subjectivity and become more
other things, in negation of, and by, them. This is and more objective. The objective being is the same
true not only of items within the world but also of as observing and being observed. But this observa-
Kant’s thing-in-itself, as it, too, is cut off from our tion has to be of ethical nature, in his theory.
cognition. Thus, a thing as it is an sich has no overt The next careful reader of Hegel (as well as of
determinate character: at most, it has potential Kierkegaard) was Jean-Paul Sartre, whose L’Être et
character that will be actualized only by its relations le néant was, to a great extent, based on Hegelian
to other things. An infant, for example, is an sich concepts of an sich and für sich or: être-en-soi and
rational potentially, not actually. A tailor is tailor an être-pour-soi. According to Sartre, being only is and
sich in the sense of having certain internal skills that cannot but be. But it has as its potentiality the fact
suit him for this role and of having certain overt that it becomes aware of itself via act of negation.
features that distinguish him from e.h. sailor. Being In other words, in Kierkegaardian terms the being
a tailor, or musician, thus involves an interplay becomes an observer of itself, and hence it is shifted
between being an sich and being for another. But into Being-for-itself. This is just transcending. The
a person is not simply a role occupant. He is also pour-soi as the outburst of negation forms the basis
an individual “I,” and as such can distance himself for the identity. It appears as a lack. According to
from his role and think of himself just as me or I. Sartre, this is the beginning of transcendence (as
When he does this, he is no longer for others but said above): human reality strives for something
for himself. For example, a bus driver has already that it lacks (Sartre, 1943, pp. 124–125). Man starts
left but notices one person still running to the stop. to exist when he realizes the incompleteness of its
Against the rules, he stops and takes the passenger being. Via this effort also the value enters human
because he feels compassion for him. Although his life. Value is the one to which one is aspiring. Being-
self-consciousness may presuppose recognition by in-itself precedes every consciousness, Being-in-itself
others, an “I” is not one of a system of contrasting is the same as what Being-for-itself was earlier. The
roles: Everyone is an I. essential change in Sartre’s theory regarding Hegel
Moreover, the idea that if something is for itself, is the movement between these two categories, and
it is aware of itself, leads to the further idea that a kind of subjectivization of them considering the
an entity may have in itself certain characteristics existence.
that are not for itself. A slave is, as a man, free in Now we need still one modernization of
himself, but he may not be free for himself. The stu- Hegel and his categories. It has been offered by
dent is future doctor and professor, but he does not Fontanille in his study Soma et séma. Figures du
know it. Finally, the terms an sich and für sich start corps (Fontanille s.d.). In fact, it deals with corpo-
to mean potential and actual and may be applied to real semiotics but presents the distinction between
the development. When a person becomes for him- categories of Moi and Soi in a fresh manner. As a
self what he is in himself, he usually recognizes his Greimassian semiotician, Fontanille starts from
identity: he becomes meaningful to himself to use actant and his/her body. He distinguishes between
semiotic vocabulary. But before we make an existen- body and form. We speak of body as such or flesh
tial-semiotic turn-around of Hegel, let us look what (chair), which is the center of all, the material resis-
Kierkegaard did with the notions of an sich and für tance or impulse to semiotic processes. Body is the
sich. In him, they turn into subjective and objec- sensorial motor fulcrum of a semiotic experience
tive being. In his chapter, Becoming a Subject, in his (Fontanille, op. cit. p. 22). Yet, on the other hand,
treatise, Unscientific Ending Postscript (Kierkegaard there is a body in the proper sense that constitutes
1993, the original in Danish Afsluttende uvidenska- the identity and directional principle of the body.
belig Efterskrift 1846), Kierkegaard speaks about an Body is the carrier of the “me” (Moi), whereas the
individual who is said to be a subject, or such an proper body supports the “self ” (Soi) (Fontanille,
individual “who is what he is because he has become op. cit. pp. 22–23). The Soi builds itself in the dis-
like it.” In the existential semiotics, such a sub- cursive activity. The Soi is that part of ourselves,
ject who has become himself could be considered which me, Moi, projects out of itself to create itself
a geno-sign. The advent of a subject from an sich in its activity. The Moi is that part of ourselves to

ta ra sti 327
which the Soi refers when establishing itself. The MOI
Moi provides the Soi with impulse and resistance being-in-myself being-for-myself
whereby it can become something. Again the Soi être-en-moi être-pour-moi
furnishes the Moi with a reflexivity that it needs an-mir-sein für-mich-sein
(“will ”) (“can”)
to keep within its limits when it changes. The Moi
resists and forces the Soi to meet its own alterity.
Hence they are inseparable. für-mich-sein an-sich-sein
Although Fontanille is a semiotician (and albeit être-pour-soi être-en-soi
he quotes here Paul Ricoeur), his reasoning fits well being-for-itself being-in-itself
(“know”) (“must”)
to the aforementioned Hegelian categories. A new
SOI
interpretation to an sich and für sich is involved, the
first corresponding to bodily ego and the latter its Figure 15.6 MOI/SOI
stability and identity and its aspiration outward, or
the Sartrean negation. The Soi functions as a kind
of memory of the body or Moi, it yields the form They can be interpreted in the following ways:
to those traces of tensions and needs that have been
1. Being-in-myself represents our bodily ego,
inserted in the flesh of the Moi.
which appears as kinetic energy, “khora,” desire,
In the light of Fontanille’s concepts, we could
gestures, intonations, Peirce’s first. Our ego is not yet
change the Hegelian Being-in-itself or Being-for-
in any way conscious of itself but rests in the naive
itself, the an-sich-sein and für-sich-sein, into
Firstness of its being; modality: endotactic, will.
an-mir-sein and für-mich-sein—Being-in-myself
2. Being-for-myself corresponds to
and Being-for-myself. Nevertheless, before we pon-
Kierkegaard’s attitude of an “observer.” Sartre’s
der which consequences this has in our existential
negation in which the mere being shifts to
semiotics, we can scrutinize the principles of Moi
transcendence notes the lack of its existence and
and Soi as such. Then anything belonging to the cat-
hence the being becomes aware of itself and
egory of mich, me, concerns the subject as an indi-
transcendence. The mere being of the subject
vidual entity, whereas the concept of sich has to be
becomes existing. This corresponds to the
reserved for the social aspect of this subject. When
transcendental acts of my previous model: negation
we think now again about Uexküll;s principle of
and affirmation. Ego discovers its identity, reaches
Ich-Ton, which determines the identity and individ-
a certain kind of stability, permanent corporeality
uality of an organism, we can distinguish in it two
via habit; modality: endotactic, can.
aspects: Moi and Soi. In “me,” the subject appears
3. Being-in-itself is a transcendental category. It
as such, as a bundle of sensations, and in the “self,”
refers to norms, ideas, and values, which are purely
the subject appears as observed by others or socially
conceptual and virtual; they are potentialities
determined. These constitute the existential and
of a subject, which he can either actualize or
social aspect of the subject or, rather, the individual
not actualize. Abstract units and categories are
and community side of it.
involved; modality: exotactic, must.
4. Being-for-itself means the aforementioned
Moi/Soi
norms, ideas, and values as realized by the conduct
I can now put together the most important ideas
of our subject in his Dasein. Those abstract
presented above. My intention was to specify the
entities appear here as distinctions, applied values,
category of being by providing this basic modal-
choices, and realizations that often will be far away
ity with new species from Kant and Hegel and
from original transcendental entities; modality:
to follow the phases of this concept further from
exotactic, know.
Kierkegaard to Sartre and Fontanille. When one
aims for more subtle tools in semiotics, one can still The essential aspect of the model is that it
find basic innovations at classics of the philosophy. combines the spheres of the Moi and the Soi, the
The Being-in-itself and Being-for-itself were turned individual and collective subjectivities. It portrays
into Being-in-and-for-myself in the existential semiosis not only as a movement of the collective
semiotics. When these notions are combined in the Hegelian spirit, but by adding the Being-in-and-
Greimassian semiotic square, one gets the following for-itself the presence of a subject via Being-in-and-
cases like in Figure 15.6. for-myself. Not only is the distinction of these four

328 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


logical cases crucial, but also the movement among MOI
them, the transformation of a chaotic corporeal ego
into its identity, the becoming of ego into a sign M1 M2
(S4) (S3)
to itself; furthermore, we have to take into account
the impact of such stable and completely respon-
sible ‘transcendental’ ego on the actualization of
transcendental values, in which the ego becomes a S2 S1
(M3) (M4)
sign to other subjects. In this phase, the Being-in-
and-for-myself meets the you or Being-in-and-for- SOI
yourself, Others. Behind thus created social field
looms the realm of transcendental, virtual values Figure 15.7 MOI/SOI
and norms, signs that have not yet become signs
to anyone. So what is involved is also a psychologi- put in a semiotic square, they partly overlap as we
cal model portraying the varieties of our individual can see in Figure 15.7.
and social being within the mind of a subject. It These cases would contain the following issues,
shows how the social intrudes our innermost being which are almost the same as above but are now
and makes us social “animals.” In the classical sense, seen from the standpoint of our semiotic subject
the semiotic sphere consists only of fields of Being- in general and not as his acts embodied in texts or
for-myself and Being-for-itself. The extremities of signs portrayed by Figure 15.8.
the semiotic square are the field of pre-signs, which There are two directions in the model: one from
surround from two sides the semiosis in the proper the pure corporeality and sensibility, (M1; le sen-
sense. However, in this semiosis, the process of act- sible by Lévi-Strauss), to permanent, stable body
signs cannot be understood without going outside (i.e. M2), and further to the social representation
of it, to the transcendence. The existential analysis of the body in social roles and professions (M3),
hence becomes a Kantian transcendental analytics and to abstract values and norms of a society (M4;
in these two phases. l’intelligible, l’abstrait). On the other hand, there is
Next we can start to elaborate this achronic struc- a movement from abstract norms to their exempli-
ture, a kind of semiotic square in the Greimassian fications or representations in certain social insti-
sense further. In fact, strictly speaking, it is no lon- tutions, and further their enactment via suitable
ger any Greimassian square with its rigorous logical personalities that these institutes recruit for their
relations of contrariety, contradiction, and implica- purposes, and ultimately certain corporeal entities.
tion. In what follows, I still go further away from Therefore, there is in every form of square, at the
the idea of such a square into a more dynamic and upper side of the Moi (as we call that part of the
flexible model in which everything is in motion—as “me” in the model), a tiny trace of the social; corre-
one of the fundamental theses of existential semiot- spondingly in even most abstract social norms, there
ics has tried to argue since its beginning. is a tiny trace of pure corporeality. The model itself
We can now improve the model and make it still takes place within the mind of a subject explaining
simpler by indicating those four cases of being by how the social is internalized in it, and so, why we
signs: M1, M2, M3, M4 and S1, S2, S3, S4. When behave socially (i.e., obeying the laws and norms);

Moi
Primary kinetic energy identity, personality,
desire, gestuality, khora, body habit, stability

Social roles, institutions,


norms, values, general codes
practices

Soi Figure 15.8. MOI/SOI

ta ra sti 329
it explains how the society keeps us in its hold. To within—that is how one feels to be in the position
say it in the way of Adorno, what is involved is the of S1 or S2, and so forth.
juxtaposition of Ich und Gesellschaft. As to the idea
M1: In the case of M1 one may ask: Who am
that it would serve as a Greimassian semiotic square,
I in my body perceived in its chaotic and fleshly
I have already in my previous studies made efforts to
Firstness? “I wake up in the morning, I breathe,
temporalize it viewing movements among its mem-
I do not feel in any pain, I exist, this is wonderful.”
bers. So I would now rather call it a “Z” model,
Avicenna, in his psychology, imagined a man
considering of its inner motions.
floating in the air without any external stimuli, and
Nevertheless, the model seems to offer almost
still being sure of its existence, this would equal to
any possible type of theory or approach to human
the state of M1. Yet, as early as this primary being
reality, depending on which aspect of the subjectiv-
has been modalized, with euphoric or dysphoric
ity, psychological, individual, or collective it empha-
“thymic” values as follows: which properties I have,
sizes. For example, L’esprit des lois by Montesquieu
what I am capable of, at which I am good —that
(S1); Culture in Minds and Societies by Jaan Valsiner
is, what is involved is my sensuality, sensibility, my
(2007; all M case in the light of the S:s); Philosophy
Sinnlichkeit, or to put it in terms of Lévi-Strauss,
of Flesh by Mark Johnson (M1); Dictionnaire du
this is the “concrete,” le sensible, this is the case
Corps (CNRS Editions 2008; all varieties of M);
of being in archaic societies, like Suya Indians
Characters by La Bruyère (M2); Wilhelm Meisters
in Mato Grosso, with a corporeal existence (but
Lehrjahre by Goethe, Dreams from My Father. A
in direct touch with myths—that is, beliefs in
Story of Race and Inheritance by Barack Obama
the case of S1; see particularly the studies and
(1995), and Bildungsroman in general shift from
video documents by the American anthropologist
M1 to S1 . We can also situate a lot of further
Anthony Seeger, 2004).
central concepts of existential semiotics into these
M2: How can I develop my properties so that
positions: dialogue, representation, and so forth. I
I become a personality, I assume an identity?
leave the transcendence here out, because the model
This is the idea of personality by Snellman
is still completely immanent—that is, it deals with
(1848/1982), or Goethean schöner Geist; how I can
phenomena of our empirical or phenomenal world,
get training and education whereby I sublimate my
Dasein (it will be an essential addenda later).
physical essence into a man/woman with a certain
However, the model evokes a lot of further elabo-
competence?
rations. For example, it is about four stable moments
M3: How I can obtain a job, position, role
of Being, but what if we consider the modality of
in a social institute that would correspond to
Doing? Are the four instances there to represent a
my personality, skills, and inclinations? How I
kind of “organic” growth from pure body to social
become that and that, manager, artist, politician,
norms? If yes, does this development take place by
administrator, teacher, professor, officer, priest, and
itself or by acts and activities of our subject? Is he/
so forth. How do I get a job and work that is equal
she able to promote or resist it—that is, affirm or
to my capacities? How I can act in the community
deny it? As Schelling put it: either we are only look-
so that I become an accepted member of it and
ing at and observing this process (i.e., we are in a
gain appreciation and success?
state of Schauen), or we can influence in it, cause it
M4: Can I accept the value and norms that
(i.e., we act via Handeln). How does the dialogue
are dominant in my community and society—if
take place as an autocommunication among those
yes, then how can I bring them on this level of
instances of subject? Which signs and texts repre-
‘Fourthness’ into their brilliance, and efficiency.I If
sent each moment? Which kinds of questions does
no (as we can always either affirm or deny), then
our subject encounter in each stage?
how can I become a dissident until the extreme
negation and refusal, withdrawal from those
Questions by a Subject: From BEING
values that I find inacceptable, and how can I then
to DOING
become a pacifist, ecologist, and so forth, with
In the aforementioned scheme, man poses ques-
extreme attitudes?
tions; in the cases of M, these questions are indi-
vidual, whereas in cases of S they are collective. This Here we see that we are dealing with quite con-
is very typical of existential semiotics, which always crete cases and positions of our subject, not only
tries to imagine and portray the life of signs from with theoretical ontological varieties of different

330 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


kinds of “being.” However, from the standpoint of 1. Every sign or text stems from its being,
the society, its members, individuals (its Mois) are or a certain being behind it: ontological
only carriers or vehicles of the Soi, its tools, and foundation. Hence, the basis of this theory is in
implementations. the modality of being or in the category of Sein in
Therefore equally from the Soi we can ask the the philosophical sense. In this sense the theory
following collective questions: proposed here is “realist” and not nominalist; the
latter would mean taking into account only what
S1: It represents the voice of the society, its
is in the discourse, textual level, whereas here
ideology, and its axiology, which appears in
we postulate an agent, subject from whom these
sanctified texts, myths. It represents the society as
texts and signs originate. This means that we can
a virtual belief system.
somehow scrutinize every species and form of signs
S2: Here, the norms and principles are shifted
in this framework as well as we can interpret every
into manifest laws, rules, and institutions. How
scientific theory and discourse about human life in
are the activities of individual members of the
this context.
society regulated, dominated, and ruled by norms
2. Each sign or text is either done by a
and social practices; how are they channeled into
subject in a given state of being or it emerges
acceptable form and genres of behavior? This is the
“organically” from it. This is one of the
same as Bourdieu’s notion of habitus.
fundamental issues of any semiotic theory—that
S3: To which extent can individual personal
is, whether signs are just pragmatic, changeable,
properties and characteristics serve the society—
and variable tools that are all the time criticized
that is, which personalities and person-types
and improved by our agents using them or whether
are proper material for its institutions? How
they exist objectively and independent of choices
are persons recruited into these practices? The
and acts of our semiotic subject.
interviews in job-hunting, for example, are
3. One mode of being transforms, changes
functional here.
into another. Hence, the shift from M1 to
S4: How does the society penetrate even to the
M4 can also be interpreted as a psychological
physical sensible behavior of an individual? How
development of a subject from childhood to adult.
are even gender distinctions partly constructed?
So it represents genetic course of it—noting,
Here, we encounter those modalities whereby a
however, that no achieved stage disappears from
Soi enacts its contracts, and those passions that
one’s life anywhere when reaching a new state:
make it real in the innermost individual core by
man is constructed as a multileveled psyche in
emotions and feelings of guilty conscience, shame,
the course of the life. Even in the body, M1
glory, duty, and their quasi-physical counterparts
changes physically when aging, and as Darrault
of the behavior.
has studied it, a young person or an aged one is
Involved here is the realization of Moi and Soi anguished in noticing these changes and has to
via four phases in two opposed directions, in the remodalize him/herself (Darrault & Klein, 2007).
Dasein; the questions are linked to this movement On the other hand, in a subjective microtime,
and its goal-directness, Kantian Zweckmässigkeit within 1 day, one has to give one part of its to
(1790/1974, pp. 322–325), hence this constitutes one’s corporeal existence (i.e., M1—eat, sleep,
the Schellingian action, Handeln. Yet each phase also etc.), one part to personal hobbies in M2, one part
has its existential side—that is, each phase can stop, it for salary work in M3, and maybe one part for
can cease moving automatically, organically forward general interests, public life in a society of activity
by stepping into transcendence, by reflecting on in some associations for universal values (i.e., in
each developmental stage from the viewpoint of its M4 = S1). Bertrand Russell recommended that
essence (i.e., that “idea” or “value” that tells us how with age the last part should become more and
things should be). However, as we know, from being more prominent when M3 action is finished with
itself we cannot infer in any way how it should be. a retirement. Yet this is valid in Western societies,
in archaic communities the division of daily
Consequences for the Varieties of routine is different, and the same in postmodern,
Our Subjectivity postindustrial society; an unemployed may be
I take the liberty to present these observations in deprived of levels M3 and M4 but he can focus
the form of 17 “theses:” in his M1 and M2. Different profiles of lifestyles,

ta ra sti 331
as Kristian Bankov has defined this concept in his 5. One mode of being transforms, changes
studies on consumer society, can thus be sketched into another. This is the principle of “unfolding”
on the basis of our ‘Z’ model. development, history both in individuals and
4. Different modes of being are in a dialogue societies. There are two major narratives of such
with each other. So far existential semiotics has metamorphoses, one stemming from M1 toward
mostly dealt with only one solipsistic subject S1 and the other from S1 reaching ultimately M1.
living its life in his/her Dasein and pursuing his/ The Finnish psychiatrist and writer Oscar Parland
her “transcendental journeys.” However, as much wrote a novel, Förvandlingar (Changes, Parland
as on his/her own choices, he/she is formed and 1945/1966), in which he, with astonishment,
constituted by his/her communication with scrutinized transformations of human life, in
other subjects. John Dewey said that the mere which new identities could emerge under the cover
communication is as such educative. Some scholars of the gastropod shell and a brilliant butterfly
have even argued that such a dialogue is the could come out. Or, as in Turgeniev’s novel, one
primary issue; in other words, communication person is portrayed in a heartbreaking incurable
and mediation—all our ideas, concepts, and sorrow and anguish at one moment and appears
values—are nothing but absolutizations of these in next, years after, talking and laughing cheerfully
experiences of dialogue. The best known theory in with others.
this field is the one by Mihail Bakhtin. An entire 6. Every mode of being has its history—that
school of psychology has been elaborated on his is, memory of what it was, and expectations of
theory by Hubert J.M. Hermans, who speaks what it will be. This means that the paradigms of
about “the dialogical self as a society of mind.” To memory and expectation are open at each moment
his mind, the dialogical self is inspired by William of the process of the horizontal appearance, but in
James in his classic distinction of “I” and “Me” the existential sense we are not bound with them.
(occurring also at George Herbert Mead) and by In his speech at La Coruna world congress of
Bakhtin in his theory of the polyphonic novel. semiotics (IASS), Salman Rushdie asked whether
Thus, for Hermans, “Self and society both function we are bound to our history or not. Expectation
as a polyphony of consonant and dissonant voices” is again based on the modality of “believe”
(Hermans, 2002, p. 148). Other scholars of the (Greimas) or the principle of hope (Ernst Bloch,
school has confirmed this (Paul and John Lysaker 1985). These again are close to the modality of
in their essay “Narrative structures in psychosis: “knowing.” Someone would say that hope is based
The self is inherently ‘dialogical’ or the product of on ignorance, the fact we do not know what
ongoing conversations both within the individual will probably happen. The life is a determined
and between the individual and others (op.cit semiosis in many respects; however, there is that
p. 209) . improbabilité infinite, the infinite improbable
The problem now here is whether we consider that can happen and that in fact really happens,
the dialogue as a disturbing element, (“noise”) in and causes huge empires to collapse; a person
our Z model that seems to be a relatively closed can achieve something against any estimates and
and autotelic process. Or, do we take dialogue evaluations. This was the idea by Arendt (1972,
as the precondition of any such process and p. 221). If all the signs obtain their power in the
shift from one phase to the other? If we adopt Proustian sense in their reference to the past by
the phenomenological point, then the only functioning of the unvolontary memory (Henri
certain thing is our own stream of consciousness; Bergson), they also can be re-articulated first by
anything that happens in other’s mind is only our reflection and thought in our presence, and then
hypothesis and constant source of frustrations in our textual and discursive activities, whereby
in our lives when these others do not behave as these intuitions are communicated to others,
we expected. Yet, the dialogue always constitutes and hence what was first totally private, unique,
the unpredictable element in our Dasein, it mental, becomes public, common, and ultimately
serves as the Freudian reality principle correcting a semiotic force in the sense of Umberto Eco
our otherwise chainless and sometimes wild reshaping our Dasein.
fantasies and conceptions. The other external 7. Every sign or text is considered an
provides us with standards, forcing elements is the appearance regarding its being; thus, being
transcendence. constitutes its truth. Can we then say that the

332 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


Z model describes the essence of the world, what her efforts to socialize, have a success in the social
and how the life really is in our Dasein, some life, and in its desire to become accepted (i.e.,
kind of ontological depth that then appears as our in its social needs)? On the other hand, how is
semiotico-symbolic activities? The whole theory M1 manipulated by S1 and S2 (see theories on
of Schein is extremely important here. Yet here manipulation by Landowski, 1989, pp. 250–253)
we speak of “vertical appearance.” To say that via its formation process, Bildung, Erscheinen,
the truth is always conditioned by history would development?
mean to deny this type of Schein (in the sense of Communication is a special type of appearance,
Kant: “. . . so kann man nicht vermeiden, dass nicht Erscheinen. We have there, in an ideal case,
alles dadurch in blossen Schein verwandelt werde”; two subjects, x and y (or Saussure’s Mr. A and
1787/1968, p. 116). Mr. B) in a dialogue. x sends a sign from his/
8. Dialogue between two subjects carrying, her M1 and y answers from the position of his/
“doing” them or how modes take place her M2—for example, a young artist or student
among their “levels” or modes. Who speaks with full enthusiasm but without techniques
in a dialogue? A subject who consists of various shows something he has written chaotically by his
portions or degrees of the principles M and S. That intuition and the other answers from his/her S3:
is why dialogue is transference (in psychoanalytic Do not try, you should first work and learn a lot!
sense) and it is helped or obstructed by similarity, But the answer can also arrive from the destinatee’s
identity, or difference, strangeness between the S2: you have to be first a professionally recognized
Moi and Soi. We can say that a dialogue exists artist. Or from S1: your expression has no aesthetic
(a) when within the same Dasein the two Mois, value whatsoever! The contact is not reached unless
MoiA and MoiB, share the same Soi or (b) when the subjects talk in the same level of their M/S
they share the same S and M (e.g., M = gender modes. This is one source of misunderstanding
and S = values, and these two actors, x and y, in among individuals and collective actors. In a
communication both have their own variants of therapy session, we listen to the signs of M in any
M1, M2, M3 . . . and S1, S2, S3 . . .). For the first case. In the real action in a society, we listen to the
the Italian scholars Gino Stefani and Stefania signs of S. If signs of M and S fall into conflict,
Guerra Lisi have in their pathbreaking treatise how do we judge? This is analogous to Husserl’s
on art therapy (Globalitá di linguaggi, see Guerra distinction of two types of sign: Bedeutungszeichen
Lisi & Stefani, 2006) have spoken about the and Ausdruckszeichen —that is, symbolic,
principle of contact in all communication. How conventional exo-signs as signs of S, and expressive,
we get a contact with other persons is certainly a endo-signs, often iconic, organic signs of M. The
fundamental issue in our Dasein, and negatively if third type of sign is transcendental signs, leading us
a speaker, performer feels he did not get a contact beyond both Moi and Soi. By them we reflect on
with his audience, or a teacher with his pupils, signs of M/S—that is, they form a kind of meta-
then the situation is lost. language whereby we talk about our situation in
Now following questions arise: (1) How does the Dasein and transcend it.
the dialogue intervene and influence our becoming 9. The real semiotic forces in the universe
and growth from M1 to S1? and (2) How does the occur in the two opposed directions: from body
dialogue intervene our becoming from the social to values, from concrete to abstract (M1–S1)
man into an individual who has a unique destiny or from values and norms to “khora” (S1–M1).
in the world, and who distinguishes him-/herself However, there the essential issue leading us
not only socially (Bourdieu) but also existentially? toward semiotics of action, toward what Habermas
We can say that in the first case, our subject-actor called “kommunikatives Handeln” (Habermas,
externalizes him-/herself, becomes manifest; he/she 1987), is whether we can trust that these forces
explains himself by getting involved in broader and function organically in any case, and look only if
broader circles and contexts (explaining according something goes wrong to correct the Z process in
to the genetic structuralist Lucien Goldmann), its right course like Zorro in the movies, or are we
whereas in the latter case, it is the society, S, that required in every shift from M1 to M2 to M3 =
understands itself by becoming more and more S2, and so forth, to do something, pursue a special
substantial and concrete. How does the subject semiotic act? If yes, what is the nature of such
in his/her state of M1 reach toward S1 in his/ an act whereby we intervene in the course of the

ta ra sti 333
events? Should it be studied like G.H. v. Wright idiolect language understood by one person only.
following his logic of action—that is, considering On the other hand, genres need to be attractive for
how the world p becomes q? Or should we adopt individual persons, M2s, which they try to recruit
the Heideggerian principle of Gelassenheit, or the for their purposes. In this sense, genre (or Gattung)
principle of letting things happen put forth by employs the third case of human activity called
Morris (Morris, 1956)? We can here turn to what Wirken (impact), which means acting according to
Arendt and Schütz have said about this problem— a certain plan (Entwurf; see Schütz & Luckmann,
without forgetting what Greimas first said in his 1994, p. 22). This plan again is very much the same
Dictionary about the semiotics of acts. as what is called in semiotics a “narrative program.”
10. The encounter or touch between Moi and We might as well portray the phases leading
Soi or body and society takes place between M2 our subject (internally) from one mode or phase
and S2. Therefore, the essential shift is from social to the others as: shift from S1 to S2 = virtuality;
practices to individual or already half-socialized from S2 to S3 (M2) = passage to an act; and from
identities and personalities. Yet this “bridge” from S3 (M2) to S4 (M1) = achievement, applying the
M to S or from S to M cannot be separated from narrative theory by Brémond ( 1973). Here, we
the whole “generative course” (NOT here in the may only ask how this is related to the demand of
linguistic sense!). We might say that there are two existentiality? Is existentiality present in phases M1
concepts that crystallize this encounter. One is and M2, giving thereafter a place for something
“gesture,” which characterizes the cases M1 and “social”—that is, Soi that would be then the
M2, in M1 “gesture” is still only on the level of original of semiosis? Then a semiotic act would
“behavior” or Verhalten, as Schütz and Luckmann be essentially of social nature, and we would from
have stated in their understanding sociology those phenomenological adventures return to the
(Verstehende Soziologie). Yet gesture can become Saussurean basis. However, if we conceive the
intentional in M2 when it is done by a person with semiotic act existentially as a transcendental act,
an identity, and then we reach the phase of “acting” we would rather think that our subject was able
or Handeln. Nevertheless, the other important to distanciate from all those four modes of being,
notion here is the one of “genre,” or Gattung, as a and even doings connecting them and putting
special type of social practice both in action and them into a developmental scheme from M1 to
text. All genre scholars admit that it is essentially S1 or vice versa, so to step outside of this process:
a social notion, based on a collective agreement, Then the real leap is just based on the liberty of
and presupposes a proper audience, receiver the subject to scrutinize his/her Dasein from a
community. For example, TV, cinema, and mass transcendental viewpoint and pursue thus what we
media genres have been formed for special types of earlier called a “transcendental journey.”
public, as Cobley has emphasized ( 2001, p. 192). 11. In the analysis of subjects (of Being and
In literature it is constituted by readers, in music it Doing) and their representations (Appearing),
is constituted by listeners. Therefore, the encounter the four modes can exist simultaneously; they
of Me and Society, Moi and Soi, takes place as the are looming behind each other.
meeting, blending together, or conflict between Valsiner quotes Lewin’s comparison between
gesture and genre. Regarding gestures, Adorno has American and German personality spheres and
said that they cannot be developed, only repeated how easily its borderlines can be crossed. The
and intensified (1974, p. 32). They have to be structure of intrapsychological borderline system
sublimated into expression—that is, they have to be is involved. Layer 5 is the utmost subjective,
put in expressive genres to be influential in cultural deeply intrapersonal level. In the American U-type
sense, and not remain on merely the psychological, personality, it is strongly protected by resistance
individual level. Sometimes it is the “me” who boundaries for outsider’s penetration, whereas
wants to impose its own new Soi; regarding avant- the other layers (1–4) can be crossed in the
garde artwork, it is said that they create their own interpersonal domain with relative ease. In German
audience. However, this may be difficult because G-type only, the outermost layer is easily crossed;
communication is possible only by accepting in other layers one is already more protected:
language (i.e., grammar as a social agreement Valsiner has concluded that each person creates
and construction). A single Moi cannot decide it one’s own personal-cultural structure of the self-
on his/her own unless he/she wants to speak an boundaries, and rules for entry into varied layers of

334 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


(a) (b) S1
S2
M2
1234 5 1234 5
M1

U-Type G-Type
Figure 15.10 Boundaries of the self, according to Valsiner
Figure 15.9 Kurt Lewin’s comparison of social relations in
(a) America and (b) Germany.
(Valsiner, 2007, p. 247)

one’s self for his various roles (2007, p. 247). We consciousness in Dostoyevsky’s novels based
could say the same about crossing the boundaries on simultaneity of its different narrator voices.
among M1 through S1 in circles. However, I consider this view as additional to the
Yet it is crucial to note that the boundaries basic phenomenological view of the fundamental
are not necessarily fixed but vary in different nature of our stream of consciousness, as Schütz
situations of dialogue with other persons in has proposed.
the community. Signs are used to mark these 12. Among the modes, there exists a process
spheres: clothes, such as uniforms, can signify of learning from a subject’s inner point of
the protection of the M1 and M2 in the social view (“know”) or of educating, teaching
role of a priest, solder, businessmen (nothing (“make known”). Learning and teaching are
else but Georges Dumezil’s [1971] three Indo- essentially dialogue, but the problem certainly
European mythological functions—war, religion, for every individual M1 is to become M2 and
government—transformed into a myth of our M3, and so forth, whereas from the viewpoint
time!). In the airplane, passengers quickly mark of culture, it is crucial that its values of S1 are
their spheres by leaving things around themselves. adopted, assimilated, maintained, and renewed by
If one lets another person intrude into one’s M2 institutions, personalities, and ultimately living
or even M1, it does not hold true in another. experiencing human subjects. So, for
Marshal Mannerheim could toast with a young example, if S1 = love for fatherland (Heimat),
solder in evening party, but the next day he was then S2 can = army, S3 = M2 = soldier and then
again in his high position. However, the dialogical S4 = M1 = a certain combination of qualities; or
self model questions the idea of a fixed core— S1 = love for beauty in communication;
assuming that as Hermans defines it (Valsiner, S2 = theater, M2 = actor, M1= certain physio-
2007, p. 149): “The dialogical self is conceived psychic qualities (remembering that theater
as social—not in the sense that a self-contained is always communication of communication;
individual enters into social interactions with other Ivo Olsobe); or S1 = love for beauty in sounds,
outside people, but in the sense that other people intonations; S2 = orchestra, S3 = M2 = musician,
occupy positions in the multivoiced self. The self is M1 = certain ability to hear and for corporeal
not only ‘here’ but also ‘there,’ and because of the movement, kinetics, psycho-physical “harmony”
power of imagination the person can act as if he (notion of the Russian school of music education).
or she were the other.” This was evident as early as Whether teaching occurs as a dialogue between a
in the early works of Bakhtin, when he discovered Master with high competence and younger pupil
the dialogical nature of any communication in the imitating him/her or as a self-teaching process in
disputes in Nääveli, after the Revolution (see Erkki a dialogical group or club (“Du är själv din bästa
Peuranen: “Semiotics of disputes”; Synteesi, 1982, lärare” [You are yourself your best teacher], said the
p. 45–46). This dialogical principle is organized Swedish music pedagogue Gunnar Hallhagen) is
into an “imaginary landscape in which “I” has an interesting educational challenge. On one hand,
the possibility to move as in space. This is exactly culture decides which texts and modalities are to
what Proust said about music and its capacity to be preserved and further transmitted to younger
teach people to see unknown realities through generations and which have to be forgotten.
others’ eyes. Bakhtin showed the polyphonic Ultimately the distinction between “culture” and

ta ra sti 335
“civilization” (see Elias, 1997) concerns putting the that and that.” Prophecies often realize themselves
emphasis either on S1 (as internal, interoceptive— but also cause counter-reactions that make an
like the Germans, der deutsche Geist) or M1 individual cross over his normal boundaries.
(as exteroceptive, sensual, pleasure—like the 16. Every mode of being is an actuality,
Mediterraneans, die Lateiner). but in a dialogue with others it becomes reality;
13. Every mode of Being and Doing as well yet, they originate from virtuality and they
as becoming has its own ambiance, atmosphere, are aiming for virtualities. Insofar as virtuality
Stimmung, how they feel in their positions. here is the same as transcendence, the problem
Such an emotional atmosphere emerges from is how do we communicate with such an entity
the isotopies, which are the basis of any action as transcendence? Is transcendental journey or
or decision making. The existential project just movement opposed to a dialogue in Dasein?
emphasizes this inner view of things. Dialogue can strengthen or criticize or weaken
14. From every stage or mode, there are Moi’s development. In fact, Moi is constituted by
open possibilities for reflection (Schauen), and in a dialogue only, but how can we be sure
distanciation, alienation, and existentiality, that there is a transcendental dimension in our
which means a shift to a metalevel, “meta- whole existence? What we consider the voice of
being” via affirmation/negation. Hence, the transcendence may be nothing but that impact
possibility of freedom opens in the side of of another subject on us, and via him/her the
necessity. Here, we have to ponder how the S1 what our surrounding community takes as
transcendence appears and manifests in the transcendental—that is, true, absolute, under all
Dasein; often, it occurs as a noise or disturbance circumstances. What is the difference and how
in the communication. Let us think of such do we distinguish between truth in Dasein and
value as goodness. How can we explain that truth in a transcendental sense? How do we talk
such things like goodness are a reality? Those with transcendence? Via meta-modalities? If I
who make good acts most often have to suffer want something in Dasein, how will that differ
from their consequences, not merely in the from the case where I want to strive for something
sense of ingratitude from the side of the objects transcendental? Does the latter mean an elevation
of goodness, but even their hostility, and even of something into a general and universal principle
becoming martyrs. Arendt has said that good acts for all others as well? Or if I know something in
have to be concealed, they can never be public. Dasein, how do I know in transcendence? The
However, that cannot always be avoided. How can latter may seem irrational, absurd in the light of
we explain that goodness makes people worse and the former (but: Credo quia absurdum).
not better? Because goodness means strength, by 17. Every mode of being has one dominant
helping others, one shows he/she is stronger than modality while organizing and subordinating
the other, so it becomes a form of subordination others. Thus, in M1 it is “will” that is the most
that people consider unbearable. Yet one can important, everything is in a tate of wanting
argue. Goodness makes the evil appear, and when to be actualized; in M2 “can” organizes all the
it is no longer imminent, when it is foregrounded, other modalities, which find their place in the
it can be more easily attacked and conquered. harmony or disharmony of thus organizing
Goodness may thus seem an anomaly and can—that is, what one realistically can do with
disturbance. Very often transcendence is felt one’s modalities, how they can be actualized. In
like that. M3, “know” gives further possibilities for enacting
15. One mode of being can compensate or and actualizing and realizing modalities; the
sublimate another. In the process of civilization, knowledge (Wissen) accumulated in a society in
certain basic qualities are, via training and its institution provides persons with their proper
education, elevated from their merely physical position in a society. In M4, “must” operates
qualities into most spiritual Thirdness-level (i.e., evaluates, orders, commands, subordinates,
phenomena and sign action. Yet there are limits: tempts previous modes—that is, sanctifies them).
the lack of certain M1 properties cannot be It seems to me that the modalities are built in
compensated by any strong belief in certain values order of their development upon each other so that
and cultural goals. A young person may hear in they accumulate and remain valid. So essentially
an entrance examination: “You will never become the “must” of S1 would never have any power

336 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


on subjects unless they would have internalized Vertical Appearance
it in their own “will.” Jaspers has written about The idea of the appearance of the Schein is not
phenomenology of the “will” (Jaspers, 1948, pp. quite a new finding: it dates back to German phi-
423–435). Thanks to will, the Dasein is not closed losophy. Kant spoke about it in his Kritik der reinen
in its own world but reaches beyond. There is Vernunft (1787/1969); in his Briefe über ästhetische
illusion and reality. Will tries to make illusions Erziehung, Schiller spoke about it (1795/2000).
concrete realities. Thanks to “will” the Dasein Kant ponders Schein in critique of the pure rea-
steps into history. With energy of will we strive in son in the chapter “Transcendental aesthetics.” He
our imaginary directive of interiority toward real argues how space and time determine all our per-
situations. So Jaspers conceives energy and power ception concerning both external objects and our
of “ ‘will as a kind thorough streaming force so own psychological states of mind; Greimas later
that it connects various modes of being M1-M2- coined terms interoceptive/exteroceptive (it is alto-
M3-M4. So will is not satisfied with satisfaction gether not difficult to turn Kant into semiotics
at one moment but it constitutes the ‘destiny’ and in the framework of Paris School). But then how
basis for the continuity of our existence” (Jaspers do the external and internal world appear to our
1948, p. 425). On the other hand “will” is at the senses? From this, one cannot yet reason that they
origin of our semiotic acts. It is as Jaspers well were mere Schein (ein blosser Schein). As early as this
says: “Duration as continuity of the sense” [Sie nuance represents the attitude that Schein is some-
ist Dauer als Kontinuität des Sinns] (Jaspers 1948, thing less real than objects.
p. 425) Yet also the first sign of functioning of a In any case, for Kant the term Schein always
“will” is bodily movement (gesture?), which should appears in the context of bloss or falsch—that is,
be seen as a continuation of our psychic events something apparent in a negative sense. Adorno
as it appears at a given moment (Augenblick). For inherited this view directly from Kant, Schein was
Jaspers, this is a truly magic moment because there illusion, phantasmagory, which art paradoxically
the spiritual directly intervenes the psychic and had to deny and abolish by its own Schein. Schiller
physical world and causes a change in our Dasein. became familiar with Kant’s thought immediately,
Therefore, “will” is the moment that then recruits and as one result we have his famous letters about
all other modalities for its fulfillment. It is the aesthetic education. Yet, the radical difference to
counterforce to the mere happening, organic, or Kant was that he speaks about the joy of Schein.
automatic course from M1 to S1. So, on one hand, Savage men became humans when they were so
we have growth and becoming, full and force; on detached from reality that they started to take it as
the other hand, we have doing and goals (Wachsen a play and as a Schein, which could be appreciated
und Werden, Fülle und Kraft; Machen und Zweck) as such. The dissolution from interests of the reality
(Jaspers 1948, p. 429). In this aspect “will” might toward the world of Schein was a decisive step of
even seem to be something uncreative, it can only progress for mankind. Consequently, we have two
“want” such things that are given in that automatic basic theories of Schein: one keeps it false, illusion,
process and set its goals according to the “know” of betrayal, and the other an independent, autonomous
S2 and “must” of S1. reality of its own, a great step of progress of human-
ity. How these theories have been inherited by later
Appearance or APPEARING discussion about Schein soon will be seen. Similarly,
In the side of the fundamental modalities of the French phenomenologist Etienne Souriau, who
“Being” and “Doing,” which we thus inherited also had an impact on early semiotic structural-
from Greimassian semiotics, to conclude, I want ism, like Sémantique structurale by Greimas, and
to ponder the modality of “appearing” (paraitre). whose monumental knowledge of the whole twen-
One structuralist reasoning to which grand part of tieth century was gathered in the collective work
semiotics has stayed faithful—is that the true reality Vocabulaire d’esthètique, gives new meanings to the
is not the one to be seen, heard, and felt, but the terms of apparence and apparition (Souriau, 1990,
structure behind it, which causes it. The surface of pp. 141–144).
the reality is only, as Greimas said “effet du sens”— The term apparence is defined by Souriau: an
that is, a meaning effect. In one word, the reality is aspect whereby an object manifests, insofar as this
only Schein, like as early as Schiller and Kant taught, representation then distinguishes itself from the
or appearance or illusion. object thus becoming manifest. From this definition,

ta ra sti 337
furthermore, three different nuances open, which In fact, it is already on this basis that we can
are: (1) the mere appearance of something to our sketch a theory of vertical Schein. We notice how
senses (i.e., a phenomenon); (2) precisely the illu- many topical problems of culture, art, and phi-
sory appearance or illusion; and (3) the appearance losophy find their proper place in this framework.
that presupposes some kind of judgment (i.e., is Regarding existential semiotics, a theory of Dasein
the same as vraisemblance, verisimilitude). As far as is involved. Lehto has proposed that Dasein is char-
what is involved is an illusion, we speak about the acterized by its particular Da-signs ( 2010, pp. 156–
illusion of reality in painting or theater. 165). But to what extent are they in reality Da-shine
The truth of theater is based on three kinds of in the sense of brilliance, virtuosity, and bravura of
illusions: representation of emotions of men, the this term? Although in shine there is always the same
illusion of time and place or diegesis, and presen- danger (as with Schein), or it is always under certain
tation of natural or supernatural phenomena to conditions the same as fake and illusions, the lie:
provoke strong emotions in spectator or to increase Not all is gold that glitters. Without love the words
the credibility of the events on stage in general. The are empty as it is said in the Bible.
latter case also leads to the term apparition, which Thus one has to distinguish between Pseudo-
thus means appearance of something surprising to shine, which belongs to the category of vanity, and
the spectator. What appears can be a real person the authentic shine or brilliance, which is always
who indeed appears at a right moment on stage— based on the truth of being. What is involved can
for example, the masked subscriber of Requiem in be shine, which has been gained by work accord-
the movie Amadeus by Forman; but it can also be a ing to the protestant ethics. We accept richness if
real person who is imagined to be present, or it can it has been obtained by striving or overwhelming
be in reality a supernatural being, such as Il com- talents but doubt nouveau riches. On a symbolic
mandatore at the end of Don Giovanni. It is evident level, in a symphony the law of thematic elabora-
that apparence corresponds to the German notion tion prevails: the victory finale of the end has to be
of Schein and apparition to Erscheinung. Altogether earned by the struggle of thematic actorial forces
these cases deal with Schein as a vertical phenom- in music in their Durchführung and in the whole
enon, in depth: it is something, somewhere, which structure; if in music there is shine without this
then is elevated to the surface of reality and mani- work, it is entertainment, lower level shimmer. Yet
fests. Also Greimas’s theory of paraitre is of this kind. there is also brilliance that is like a gift of nature,
In his well-known so-called “veridictory square,” proof of vitality, overwhelming energy, like in the
we act by categories of être and paraitre (Being and case of Australian aboriginal handicraft studied by
Appearing). When they are negated, we get four Hénault (2002). The problem of shine remains in
cases; Being, not-Being, Appearing, not-Appearing. the aforementioned distinction: from which signs
When they are situated in the square, we get four can we distinguish between pseudo-shine and real,
meaning effects: truth, untruth, lie, and secret, good shine?
always according to the relationship of these catego- To do this, we need to compare Schein to Sein—to
ries: truth is what appears and is what it appears; lie continue our playing with words. The appearance
is what appears but is not that; secret is something and being manifest in many forms and variations in
that is but does not appear in any way; and untruth the history of ideas. First, we have a pair of concepts
is something that neither is nor appears, as shown referring to this: structure and ornament. One thinks
in Figure 15.11. that structure “is”—that is, it is really, is something
permanent, whereas its decoration is merely the
quality of surface.
TRUTH Moreover, the whole theory of simulacra, copies
of reality as Schein belongs to this category. Here,
the doctrines of Jean Baudrillard get a new dimen-
to be to appear
LIE SECRET sion, just as Eco’s theory of forgery. The problem of
not-to-appear not-to-be a forgery is not only in comparison of two objects
on the same level but in the shift of levels—in the
UNTRUTH
dialectics of appearance and being, in the Kantian
sense. The whole network of these concepts can be
Figure 15.11 The veridictory square by Greimas seen in Figure 15.12.

338 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


SEIN SCHEIN SHINE SIGN

ETRE BEING APPARENCE BRILLIANCE


(APPARITION)
ERSCHEINEN
PARAITRE
APPEAR
ÉCLAT
VIRTUOSITÉ
BRAVOURE
morality:

GOODNESS EVILNESS
EVILNESS GOODNESS
ILLUSION
IMAGINATION
STRUCTURE ORNEMENT
SIMULACRA
FAKES/FORGERIES
DREAM
SUBJECT OBJECT or:
OBJECT SUBJECT (depending on epistemology)
CULTURE CIVILISATION
KULTUR
GEIST MATERIE
(MIND) (MATTER

life style:

IDENTITY FASHION KITSCH STYLE


SPIRIT BODY
(Earth spirit)
communication:

PHRASE GESTURE

TRANSCENDENCE DASEIN DASEIN TRANSCENDENCE.


(distinction) (being-there)
PROFOUND SUPERFICIAL
either: PSEUDO-SHINE:
vanity, illusion
or: AUTHENTIC SHINE
referring to the “truth of being”
SHINE as earned (Protestant ethics) Figure 15.12 Categories around the
SHINE as gift of nature appearance

Horizontal Appearance a time. So the reality all the time appears to us tem-
Nevertheless, in the aforementioned diction- porarily, it has a certain rhythm, which we caneither
ary by Souriau is a passage that opens a different retardate or accelerate, but which altogether pro-
view. Namely, we find the following definition for ceeds irrefutably. We are all the time going toward
the term apparence: “Certain art works never appear something unknown and imprevisible; we are all the
to the spectator entirely and by all parts simulta- time transgressing some boundary or moving toward
neously. The temporal arts like music, theater and transcendence. Schutz and Luckmann considered
cinema, are all based upon successive appearance” just such an idea of borderline essential in the idea of
(Souriau, 1990, p. 140). the transcendence. The thought could be resumed in
Hence, when we join the idea of temporality—of one phrase: the appearance (Erscheinen) is becoming
succession, linearity, syntagmaticity, seriality, unfold- of transcendence (Werden der Transzendenz). Yet not
ing, developing—to such a static concept like Schein whatsoever becoming is an existential revelation or
or being, we are lead to a radically new theory. A naive realization of the transcendence—that is, existential
fact is that we can live our lives only one moment at choice. There is also blind becoming, without any

ta ra sti 339
for a subject. Instead transcendence as a plenitude
means the virtuality of innumerous possibilities,
Dasein
omnitemporality (a concept by Karsavine, 2003),
Transcendence
which only artists have been able to conceive and
simulate: Wagner in the networks of his leitmotifs in
Appearance
his operas and Proust by the time dimensions going
Figure 15.13 Existential appearance to all direction in his novels. These simulacra mod-
els are Schein that correspond to the truth of being.
chosen direction, the principle of laisser-aller, which Its modus is appearance, linear and horizontal.
means throwing and abandoning into the power of
uncertain future, perhaps its narrative course lead- Conclusions and Future Directions
ing assumingly into good. The situation could be Existential semiotics emerged from several
illustrated with the scheme in Figure 15.13. sources, both semiotical and philosophical. If we
The modalities of existential appearance are: would try to situate it in the panorama of recent
becoming (necessity) and doing (freedom) and their trends in these fields, one might be tempted to clas-
alternation or balance. sify it among the so-called “post-structuralist” and
One could say that the existential appearance is “postmodern” issues. It is true that the heritage of
directed only by the Ich-Ton, the identity of a subject French semiotics has been so modified there that it
(the concept has been borrowed from v. Uexküll’s is in this respect a “post-Greimassian” theory. Also
biosemiotics), but we cannot know in advance how the concern of human subject and its living and
it reacts in each situation. Therefore, the Schein, acting in the world with all of its moral issues pro-
which manifests the truth of being as a kind of figu- vides it with a certain tinge, which some others have
ration of a structure, its ornamentation, is not yet called “semio-ethics” (like Deely, 2008 Bonfantini,
existential Schein in this new sense. Similarly, the Petrilli, & Ponzio, 2009). What it attempts to
brilliance of the appearance, which is realization of underline in this debate on the nature of values is
the structure of being, is of course a kind of bril- that values are not relative as Saussurean linguistic
liance but one has to distinguish from it the shine, theory proposed—that is, completely determined
which occurs in the choice at every moment, and by the position of a sign in a certain system. Rather,
the fact that we are truly free to choose and not values are considered virtual and transcendental
as predetermined by any structural or ontological entities waiting for their actualization in our living
principle. world. Altogether, the theory is definitely a product
These starting points have immediate conse- of our time, which perhaps is no longer any post
quences, even to such a far-seeming theory as semi- issue but rather something neo.
otics. Namely, when in semiotics communication Yet, it preserves the ties with the long tradi-
is the only properly dynamic temporal process in tion of Western thought and has not thrown itself
the mediation of message from destinator to desti- into purely contemporary doctrines of so-called
natee, we have here found a completely new deeper “innovation”—with commercial and technological
epistemic level: appearance. usefulness and direct applications. However, amaz-
Appearance as the existentiality of subjects and ingly even in this respect already existential value
appearance in general is a still more fundamental aspects are applied to the study of consumers’ values
category as communication. Which kind of semi- or comparison of law systems of various kinds.
otics might emerge if we would take this principle We could say first that the theory is not yet ready
of horizontal appearance as our fulcrum? Which and completed at all. But then, to what directions
kind of theory, which methods, which analyses? I should it be developed further? Should it become
already referred to the new research program of Eric a complete, coherent, maybe even axiomatic sys-
Landowski, the semiotics of life and irregularities, tem of human mind and its various activities in the
which are analogous to existential semiotics. But world? Then the goal of such science would be a
also new approaches may emanate. kind of system, or generative construction in which
Transcendence as nothingness is just such in concepts and levels are derived from each other, so
which the appearance has stopped, the time has been that it seems as if they were logically and organi-
finished, one is in a totally achronic state and one cally growing from the basic hypotheses. That
could not even imagine anything more anguishing would be something like Hegel Science of Logics

340 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


of McTaggart’s Nature of Existence (McTaggart, existential semiotics may lead not only the semiotic
1927/1988). On the other hand, one would then theory to new configurations but also change our
easily argue that the time of such big narratives has basic understanding of mind and culture leading
passed away and that the human mind, history, and perhaps into new discoveries.
experience in all its complexity and diversity can-
not be any longer captured into one unified sys- Notes
tem of thought. In such a case, the theory should 1. Since fifteen years ago I launched a new theoretical project
to renew the so-called classical semiotic approach and to rethink
unfold into a more fragmentary treatise, something its epistemological bases. So far I have published on this topics
like Schlegel’s Athenäum Fragmente or Ruskin’s a monograph Existential Semiotics (Bloomington, Indianapolis:
Modern Painters (Ruskin, 1843–1873/1987) as Indiana University Press 2000), and in addition several articles
its goal. Perhaps such a presentation would better in various journals and anthologies. Moreover the Belgian review
do justice to the contradictory nature of the world DEGRES published in 2003 a special issue on Sémiotique exis-
tentielle with some international reactions to these new theories.
or Dasein that it tries to portray and mirror. The Yet recently there have appeared two other volumes in Italian
time of clean and rational generative courses has and French in which the theory has become remarkably larger
gone. One would also develop it as a discourse into and aspired towards deeper epistemic levels. These were Fonda-
more figurative expressions, supposing that mean- menti di semiotica esistenziale transl. by Massimo Berruti (Bari:
ings are created in the language and texts. Yet, the Laterza Editore, Tarasti 2009a) and Fondements de la sémiotique
existentielle transl by Jean-Laurent Csinidis (Paris: L’Harmattan,
great difference to this structuralist views is that the Tarasti 2009b)
origin is definitely a theory of subject and a kind of
psychology. References
In this aspect, one should think that it would Adorno, T. (1973). Ästhetische Theorie. Frankfurt am Main,
grow into a direction of collective subjectivities Germany: Suhrkamp.
reaching the level of communities and cultures. For Adorno, T. (1974). Versuch über Wagner. Frankfurt am Main,
Germany: Suhrkamp Taschenbuch.
any cultural theory, it would provide a new type of
Airaksinen, T. (1993). Moraalifilosofia. Porvoo, Helsinki, Juva:
approach. It would, in this respect, have its impact, Werner Söderström.
not yet tried, on gender theories as well. Yet keeping Andrieu, B. & Boëtsch, G. (2008). Dictionnaire du Corps. Paris:
ourselves in the social sphere, it might next focus CNRS Editions.
on the modality of Doing if so far the being and Arendt, H. (2000/1946). Qu-est-ce que la philosophie de
l’existence? In La philosophie de l’existence et autres essais.
appearing have been focus. It might develop into a
Paris: Payot et Rivages.
theory of action, and even in its radical and politi- Arendt, H. (1972). La crise de la culture. Translated from the
cal sense, telling us What We Have To Do, like Leo original Between Past and Future, by Patrick Lévy. Paris:
Tolstoi once asked. Howeverit could also flour- Gallimard.
ish in the field of such an indefinable notion like Bakhtin, M. ( 1970). Le poétique de Dostoievski. Paris: Seuil.
Bakhtin, M. (1981). The Dialogic Imagination. Four Essays. Edited
transcendence. Even if this concept were originally
by Michael Holquist. Translated by Caryl Emerson and
conceived here as something purely conceptual and Michael Holquist. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
philosophical, it can certainly have psychological, Bankov, K. (2000). Intellectual Effort and Linguistic Work.
anthropological, and even theological repercus- Semiotic and Hermeneutic Aspects of the Philosophy of Bergson.
sions, like the Rumanian mathematician Solomon Acta Semiotica Fennica IX. Helsinki: International Semiotics
Institute.
Marcus, who has connected it to divinity (at a
Bankov, K. (2004). Infinite Semiosis and Resistance.I In E. Tarasti
roundtable on existential semiotics in Paris, October (Ed.). From Nature to Psyche. Proceedings from the ISI Summer
27, 2010). I am also convinced that once having Congresses at Imatra in 2001–2002. Acta Semiotica Fennica
reached such an epistemic status, the theory would XX. Imatra: International Semiotics Mihail Institute.
proceed into a new methodology of human sciences Barthes, R. (1977). The Grain of the Voice. In Image, Music, Text.
Essays selected and translated by Stephen Heath. New York:
and into a new type of analysis of human mind and
Hill and Wang.
its various signs. As one of the most tempting fields Barthes, R. (1978) Lecon inaugurale. Paris: Editions du Seuil.
here, it offers the artistic texts and signs, such as, Barthes, R. (1957) Mythologies. Paris: Editions du Seuil.
say, music: after the existential approach, one could Bergson, H. (1975/1938). La pensée et le mouvant. Paris: PUF.
not imagine any musical or any aesthetic utterance Bergson, H. (1982/1939) Matière et mémoire. Paris: Quadrige/
Presses Universitaires de France.
but is simultaneously corporeal (M1), expression
Bergson, H. (1992). Les limites de l’interprétation. Traduit de
of human personality (M2), manifesting certain l’italien par Myriam Bouzher. Paris: Bernard Grasset.
genres (S2), and fulfilling aesthetic values (S1). Bloch, E. (1959). Das Prinzip Hoffnung. Frankfurt am Main:
Accordingly, I believe the avenues opening from Suhrkamp.

ta ra sti 341
Bonfantini, M., Petrilli, S. & Ponzio, A. (2009) “Semiotics Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit. Heilbronn, Germany: Max
and dialogue between logic and ethics”. In E. Tarasti Niemeyer Verlag.
(Ed.) Communication: Understanding/Misunderstanding, Hénault, ZA. (2002). Questions de sémiotique (sous la direction
Proceedings of the 9th Congress of the IASS/AIS. Acta semi- de A.H.). Paris: PUF.
otica fennica XXXIV. Helsinki, Imatra: Semiotic Society of Hermans, H. ( 2001). The Dialogical Self: Toward a Theory of
Finland/International Semiotics Institute. Personal and Cultural Positioning. Culture and Psychology.
Brémond, C. (1973). Logique du récit. Paris: Editions du Seuil. 7(3), 243–281.
Cobley, P. (2001). Semiotics and Linguisticd. The Routledge Hermans, H. (2002). Special issue on Dialogical Self Theory and
Companion. London, New York: Routledge. Psychology. 12, 2.
Cobley, P., & Randviir, A. (2009). “Sociosemiotica”. Semiotica, Husserl, E. (2000). Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren
173, 1–4. Zeitbewusstseins. Tübingen, Germany: Max Niemeyer Verlag.
Danesi, M. (1998). Sign, Thought, Culture. A Basic Course in Inwood, M. (1992). A Hegel Dictionary. The Blackwell Philosopher
Semiotics. Toronto: Canadian Scholars’ Press. Dictionaries. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.
Darrault-Harris,I., & Klein, J.-P. (2007). Pour une psychiatrie de Jaspers, K. (1948). Philosophie. Berlin, Göttingen, Heidelberg:
l’ellipse. Les aventures du sujet en creation. Limoges, France: Springer-Verlag.
PULIM. Kant, I. (1787/1968). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Stuttgart,
Deely, J. (2001) Four Ages of Understanding. The First Postmodern Germany: Reclam.
Survey of Philosophy from Ancient Times to the Turn of the Kant, I., (1790/1968). Kritik der Urteilskraft. Werkausgabe Band
Twenty-First Century. Toronto, London, Buffalo: Toronto X. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp.
University Press. Karsavine, L. (2003). Le poème de la mort. Traduction, postface
Deely, J. (2008). From semiosis to semioethics. The Full Vista of et apercu biographique par Francoise lesourd. Lausanne,
the Action of Signs. In Sign System Studies 36.2, 421–437. Switzerland: Editions L’Age d’Homme.
Deely, J. (2009). Basics of Semiotics. Tartu, Estonia: Tartu Kierkegaard, S. (1846/1993). Päättävä epätieteellinen jälkikir-
University Press. joitus (Ending unscientific postscript). Original:Aflusttende
Dumézil, G. (1971). Mythe et épopée. Types éppiques indo-euro- uvidenskabelig Efterskrift. Finnish transl by T. Lehtinen. Juva,
péens. un héros, un sorcier, un roi. Paris: Editions Gallimard. Finland: WSOY.
Eagleton, T. (1996). Ideology: an Introduction. London, New York: Kristeva, J. (1969). Seemiootikee. Recherces pour une sémanalyse.
Verso. Paris: Seuil.
Eco, U. (1968). La struttura assente. Milano: Bompiani. Lévinas, E. (1971). Totalité et infini. Essai sur l’exteriorité. Paris:
Eco, U. (1976). A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana Kluwer Academic.
University Press. Lévi-Strauss, C. (1971). L’homme nu. Mythologiques IV. Paris:
Eco, U. (1992). Les limites de l’interprétation. Traduit de l’italien Plon.
par Myriam Bouzher. Paris: Bernard Grasset. Landowski, E. (1989). La société réfléchie. Paris: Seuil 1997
Eco, U. (1997). Kant et l’ornithorynque. Traduit de l’Italien par Présences de l’autre. Paris: PUF.
Julien Gayrard. Paris: Bernard Grasset. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics, Inventing Right and Wrong. London:
Eco, U. (1976). A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana Harmondsworth.
University Press. Marc-Lipiansky, M. (1973). Le structuralisme de Lévi-Strauss.
Elias, N. (1978). The History of Manners. The Civilizing Process: Paris: Payot.
Volume I. New York: Pantheon Books. Marcel, G. (1927). Journal Métaphysique. Paris: Gallimard.
Fontanelle, J. (s.d.) Soma et séma. Figures du corps. Paris: McTaggart, J. (1927/1988). The Nature of Existence. Vols I-II. Edited
Maisonneuve & Larose. by C.D. Broad. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Goldmann, G. (1956). Le dieu caché. Étude de la vision tragique Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
dans les pensées de Pascal et dans le théâtre de Racine. Paris: University Press.
Gallimard. Lõhmus, M. (2002). Transformation of Public Text in Totalitarian
Greimas, A. J. ( 1967) Sémantique structurale. Paris: Larousse. System. A Socio- Semiotic Study of Soviet Censorship Practices in
Greimas, A. J. & Courtés, J. (1979). Sémiotique. Dictionnaire Estonian Radio in the 1980s. Annales Universitatis Turkuensis
raisonné de la théorie du langage. Paris: Hachette. Ser. B, tom. 248. Turku, Finland: Turun Yliopisto (University
Greimas, A. J. (1979/1999) ALuennot Helsingissä 4.-5.5.1979” of Turku, Finland).
(Lectures in Helsinki in May 4–5, 1979). Edited and Morris, C. (1956). Varieties of Human Values. Chicago, IL:
translated into Finnish by E. Tarasti. Helsinki, Finland: Chicago University Press.
Semiotiikan Seura (The Semiotic Society of Finland). Nöth, W. (2000). Handbuch der Semiotik. 2. vollständig neu bear-
Hare, R. (1952). The Language of Morals. Oxford. beitete und erweiterte Auflage. Stuttgart, Weimar: Verlag J.B.
Hegel, G. F. W. (1838). Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Metzler.
Geschichte. Hersgg. v. Eduard Gans. Berlin: Verlag von Parret, H. (1994). Peirce and Value Theory. Amsterdam:
Duncker und Humblot. Benjamins.
Hegel, G. F. W. (1917). Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Parland, O. (1945/1966). Muuttumisia (Changes), the Swedish
Weltgeschichte. I. Band: Einleitung. Leipzig, Germany: Verlag original Förvandlingar. Helsinki, Porvoo: WSOY.
von Felix Meiner. Petrilli, S. (2009). Signifying and Understanding. Reading the
Guerra Lisi, S., & Stefani, G. (2006). Prenatal Styles in the Works of Victoria Welby and the Signific Movement. Berlin: De
Arts and the Life. Acta semiotica fennica XXIV. Imatra: Gruyter Mouton.
International Semiotics Institute. Peuranen, E. (1982). “Mihail Bahtinin polyfonia-käsityksestä”.
Habermas, J. (1997). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Synteesi 2–4: pp. 97–100 (Synthesis. Journal for Interrelationships
Band 1. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp. of Arts, Jyväskylä, Finland).

342 ex i stenti al se m i ot i cs a nd cult ur a l psych ology


Ponzio, A. (1993). Signs, Dialogue and Ideology. Amsterdam, Tarasti, E. (1979). Myth and Music. A Semiotic Approach to the
Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins Publishing Company. Aesthetics of Myth in Music, especially that of Wagner, Sibelius
Ponzio, A. (1999). La comunicazione. Bari, Italy: Edizioni B.A. and Stravinsky. The Hague, Paris, New York: Mouton
Graphis. Publishers.
Ricoeur, P. (1967). Histoire et vérité. Paris: Editions du Seuil. Tarasti, E. (1994). A Theory of Musical Semiotics. Bloomington,
Ricoeur, P. (2000). La mémoire, l’histoire, l’oubli. Paris: Editions IN: Indiana University Press.
du Seuil. Tarasti, E. (2000). Le secret du professeur Amfortas, roman traduit
Rossi-Landi, F. (1972). Semiotik, Ästhetik und Ideologie. du finnois par Mikko Kuusimäki. Paris: L’Harmattan.
München, Wien: Carl Hanser Verlag. Tarasti, E. (2000). Existential Semiotics. Indianapolis,
Rossi-Landi, F. (1973). Ideologies of Linguistic Relativity Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
(Approaches to Semiotics 4). The Hague, Paris: Mouton. Tarasti, E. (2002). Signs of Music. A Guide to Musical Semiotics.
Rossi-Landi, F. (1978). Ideologia. Milano: Istituto Editoriale Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Internazionale. Tarasti, E. (2004). “Ideologies manifesting axiologies”. Semiotica
Royce, J. (1998). Metaphysics. Edited by W.E. Hocking, 148(1/4) 23–46.
R. Hocking, & F. Oppenheimer. New York: State University Tarasti, E. (2005). Existential and Transcendental Analysis of
of New York Press. Music. In Studi Musicali,Accademia nazionale di Santa
Ruskin, J. (1843–1873/1987). Modern Painters. Edited and Cecilia, direttor Agostino Ziino, Firenze. Leo S. Olschki
abridged by David Barrie. London: André Deutsch. Editore, s. 223–266.
Sartre, J. P. (1943). Lêtre et le néant. Essai d’ontologie phenomé- Tarasti, E. (2007). An Essay on Appearance Or: The Present
nologique. Paris: Gallimard. Structure And Existential Digressions of the Subject. In
Saussure, F. (1916/1995). Cours de linguistique générale. Paris: J. Fujak (Ed.). Convergences and Divergences of Existential
Editions Payot. Semiotics. Nitra, Slovakia: University of Nitra, Slovakia.
Schelling, F. W. J. (1977). Philosophie der Offenbarung 1841/42. Tarasti, E. (2009a). Fondements de la sémiotique existentielle.
Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp. Transl. J.Laurent Csinidis. Paris: L’Harmattan.
Schiller, F. (2000). Ûber die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen. Tarasti, E. (2009b). Fondamenti di semiotica esistenziale. Transl.
Stuttgart, Germany: Reclam. M. Berruti. Roma, Bari: Edizioni Giuseppe Laterza.
Schütz, A. (1993). Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt. Ein Tarasti, E. (2009c). Communication. Understanding/
Einleitung in die verstehende Soziologie. Frankfurt am Main, Misunderstanding. Proceedings of the 9th Congress of the IASS/
Germany: Suhrkamp. AIS. Acta semiotica fennica XXXIV. Vols 1–3. Helsinki,
Schütz, A., & Luckmann, T. (1994). Strukturen der Lebenswelt Imatra: Semiotic Society of Finland/International Semiotics
I-II. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp. Institute.
Schopenhauer, A. (1859/1987). Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. Tarasti, E. (2010). I Segni della musica. Che cosa ci dicono i
Stuttgart, Germany: Reclam. suoni. A cura di Paolo Rosato, Transl. B. Waterhouse. Milano:
Sebeok, T. A. (1979). The Sign and Its Masters. Austin, TX & Ricordi/LIM.
London: University of Texas Press. Taruskin, R. (1997). Defining Russia Musically. Princeton, NJ:
Sebeok, T. A. (2001). Global Semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Princeton University Press.
Indiana University Press. von Uexküll, J. (1940). Bedeutungslehre. Leipzig, Germany: Barth.
Seeger, A. (2004). Why Suyà Sing. A Musical Anthropology of an von Uexküll, T., Geigges, W. & Herrmann, J. (1993).
Amazonian People. Urbana, IL & Chicago, IL: University of Endosemiosis. Semiotica 96(2), 5–51.
Illinois Press. Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in Minds and Societies. Foundations of
Snellman. J. W. (1848/1982). “Über die Idee der Persönlichkeit”, Cultural Psychology. Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, India:
Persoonallisuuden idea, in:Teokset II (Works). Jyväskylä, Sage.
Finland: Gummerus. Volli, U. (1992). Les limites de l’interprétation. Traduit de l’italien
Solowjew, W. (1965). Philosophie. Theologie. Mystik. Grundprobleme par Myriam Bouzher. Paris: Bernard Grasset.
und Hauptgestalten. Deutsche Gesamtausgabe der Werke. Volli, U. (2000). Manuale di semiotica. Rome and Bari: Editori
Sechster Band. Freiburg im Breislau, Germany: Erich Wewel Laterna.
Verlag. Wagoner, B. (2010). Symbolic Transformation. The Mind in
Souriau, E. (1990). Vocabulaire d’esthétique. Sous la direction de Movement Through Culture and Society. London, New York:
Anne Souriau. Paris: PUF. Routledge.

ta ra sti 343
This page intentionally left blank
PA RT
5
Action, Self, and
Narration
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Culture: Result and Condition


16 of Action

Ernest E. Boesch

Abstract
How to use human potentials constructively will be a major problem for a science of culture. This
chapter covers the key issues that follow from its author’s Symbolic Action Theory. That theory
(which has been developed since the 1960s) has been rooted in the work of Jean Piaget, whose
constructivism has opened my eyes for human creativity; Pierre Janet, whose theory of feelings started
me on action theory; Sigmund Freud, whose use of free association became an important method for
the study of symbols; Gaston Bachelard, with his books on the symbolism of the house, the Earth, the air,
and fire; Claude Lévi-Strauss, by his studies of South American Indian myths; Raymond Firth, whose work
on symbols was a great help; and the anthropologists Mary Douglas and Victor Turner, who contributed
importantly to the symbolic side of the theory. Gaining multiple insights into traditional Thai customs
provided the cultural contrast for the development of the holistic theory.
Keywords: culture, self, action

For one who has lived the horrors of the twen- The writing of the Bible was a cultural feat, but
tieth century, it is not easy to write about culture. using it to justify expulsion, slavery, executions, and
We tend to think of culture as a special, positive torture was no less cultural; the extermination of
endowment of the human species, and if we say whole non-believing communities of men, women,
that a man or a woman are cultivated, we mean children, and cattle had been at the origin of Jewish
that they show endearing human qualities. Yet, the civilization, a biblical command, contrary to the
depravations of the past century were, indeed, also ten commandments demonstrating the Janus face
a product of culture. The systematic killing of 6 of culture. The atomic bombs of Hiroshima and
million Jews, Gypsies, invalids, and others were Nagasaki were a feat of science and a crime in the
committed by science and weapons produced by name of culture. The large depletion of forests for oil
our culture, applied by its members and justified rather than food production is done with cultural
by a cultural ideology. And so were the Stalinist techniques and for cultural purposes. Religion, of
mass killings, or the extermination of almost half course, has benefited culture in many ways but has
of the Khmer population. Deeds, perhaps less also brought intolerance, war, cruelty, and suppres-
striking but still horrible enough, have accompa- sion. Science, equally, has largely improved human
nied the history of culture: The burning of heretics life; yet, it has also produced weapons with more
at the stake or the stoning to death of a woman and more destructive power and sophisticated poi-
presumed to be adulterous are cultural, as are the sons and, intentionally or not, a misuse of medical
modern terrorist killings of women and children knowledge; even art had to serve ideological indoc-
in market places. trination and commercial seduction. Culture shows

347
a double face. It is man-made and as conflictual as Culture: Basic Functions
the man himself (Boesch, 2005). Culture is man-made, of course, but for each
newborn child it is the existing world, firm but
A Terminological Note strange, full of things to discover and explore pro-
In the following, I will often speak of experience gressively. At first a child will discover persons, the
and action, so it might be helpful to explain from mother and other caretakers as sources of gratifica-
the outset my use of these terms. “Experience” is tion and pleasure. During the first months, the child
the larger one. It means everything that enters our will smile at any face entering its field of vision;
senses and our mind, be it conscious or uncon- later, distinguishing between familiar and strange
scious. I consider it as equivalent to the German faces, it will show pleasure seeing the first and will
word Erlebnis, meaning what we live. reject the second. This is a distinction between the
“Action” means striving for a result, there- familiar and strange, which, however primitive,
fore not all we experience is action—we perceive tends to remain with most people all their lives. Of
or feel the sun, the wind, the heat, the cold, the course, the number of familiar and strange faces
rain, sounds and noises, and the smile or anger in will increase, and the child will learn to differenti-
the face of a person. All these are not actions but ate between persons—yet the basic distinction will
influence our mood and our awareness of reality, remain.
and thus they may instigate or at least influence The child’s world, of course, consists also of
actions. objects, an unending realm of discovery. Objects
By action we experience our world, its attrac- form its space by their shape, color, weight, sound,
tions or threats, but at the same time we experi- smell, and taste; by variable illumination; and, of
ence ourselves, our strength, our abilities, and our course, by their different use. All this the child
weaknesses or vulnerability. This twofold experience discovers by acting on objects, experiencing curi-
makes action particularly important. As a student, I osity and pleasure related to attractive things and
learned from Pierre Janet that emotions and feelings places, but the child learns also to be cautious with
were regulators of action, which, by making actions unknown, possibly dangerous objects. Thus, the
as frequent as emotions, required us to define them child first structures the world along dimensions
anew. If even dreams were actions as Sigmund of attraction or avoidance; it starts being a valence
Freud had taught us, then we would have to accept world (1963). This first organization of the environ-
also unconscious actions, but what, then, were their ment is not yet culture—every animal also struc-
goals? I finally concluded that all we do for regu- tures its surroundings along the places and objects
lating our relationship with the environment and of positive or negative valence.
ourselves, be it physical or mental (with the excep- Yet, this world of valences—including objects,
tion of reflexes), is action. Thereby action became people, and events—will soon be connected with
one of the two main sources of self-evaluation (the rules: “Do this, don’t do that!” The child will dis-
other one being social feedback). The term, in this cover such rules by his/her own action, which reveals
large conception, allows us to better understand the quality and function, the use, and the beauty or
self-formation in relation to culture (Boesch, 1975, danger of objects. But rules result also from adults
1976, 1991). or older children, who demonstrate or teach appro-
In the following, the word meaning will also be priate behaviors. Important rules concern property:
used frequently. Meanings can be public and pri- “No, you can’t play with that, it belongs to your
vate. Public meanings concern generally accepted sister!” Property rules emphasize the I-vs.-you dis-
purpose, function, or sign quality of a thing or an tinction, and thereby the possession of things will
event. Private meanings consist of subjective evalu- soon manifest self-value. Although the correct use
ations such as beauty or ugliness, attraction, repul- of objects requires knowledge and skill, the rules
sion, hope, or fear. The distinction between public concerning property limit one’s action in a way that
and private meaning is not always easy, as they can cannot be overcome by skill. They demand new
blend, and language lacks sufficiently subtle terms. kinds of action obeying other social rules—begging
We will meet enough examples for illustrating both, or borrowing will have to replace the act of simply
but I tend to use the term meaning mainly in its taking. The child will have to learn that, which is
private sense. As to the term symbol, also frequently not easy, and so property will also give rise to new
used, it is explained in the text. emotions, jealousy, greed, and aggression. Conflicts

348 c ulture
about property tend to be most frequent already in controls; cotton wool is spun, woven, and sewn into
kindergarten and probably occupy the major time shirts, and the construction of automobiles is only
of civil courts. Without that, these conflicts can eas- a more complex transformation of natural materials
ily turn into hostility, with the loss of property felt and utilization of natural powers.
as a threat to one’s self. These transformations often require interaction
These initial actions, of course, are accompanied and cooperation, and this, too, the child will meet
by words. The child’s world soon will become a early. Wanting to construct a toy, the child will have
named world. Mother tells her boy: “Go to the baker to ask for the help of an elder brother who then will
to buy bread.” Here, the object is classified by nam- need material or tools from their father. Depending
ing, integrating it into a category of similar things, on the cooperation of others, the child discovers the
separated from “no-breads” as, for example, from need for action chains. In fact, culture consists of a
cakes. Or during a walk in the woods, the mother dense and complex web of action chains, of coop-
might instruct her boy who collects berries: “Take erating actors. This, besides the coordination of
only blackberries, leave raspberries, they are infested competences and means, also requires mutual trust.
with worms.” She classifies not only with relation Trust is an emotion without which no culture can
to other berries but also to clean or infected ones. exist.
Thus, naming facilitates orientation within one’s These are the basic functions of culture: struc-
known and knowable world. It refers to a structure turing the environment along positive and negative
existing prior to individual experience. Even should valences; inventing language to classify things and
a name be forgotten—for example, as with a tech- events and to communicate about them; establish-
nical term—we still know that the thing belongs to ing rules for regulating action and interaction; and
a named category. Language, a collective system of transforming nature to meet the desires and needs
signs, orders the world. Yet it does so only to the of people. And, finally, there is cooperation of actors
extent that it is understood, understanding language with different competences and means for pursuing
is as much part of cultural learning as is naming cor- common goals. These functions, of course, engen-
rectly. Both are needed for useful orientation. der consequences. The monkey who discovers the
Words do not simply classify things and events— breaking of nutshells instigates a corresponding
they also include qualities. “Don’t eat these black rhythm of seasonal behavior and fosters new hab-
berries, they are poisonous nightshades, you might its of eating and sharing; the baker who transforms
die of them”, the mother would warn her son. Words wheat into bread initiates a new breakfast culture
establish relationships between thing and actor— and, as a consequence, also transformations in the
perhaps correctly, perhaps erroneously, but in both environment—for example, wheat fields replacing
ways they constitute reality. Soon the world of the woods. Even more so the automobile makers, by
child will be somehow doubled by language, which introducing new habits and skills, have altered indi-
defines qualities, and thereby conducts action. viduals, society, and even nature and climate. The
There exists a further basic aspect of culture. hunter who blows into the hollow leg bone of a deer
Soon children will start acting on objects. As a boy, or perceives the humming of the bow string discov-
my grandfather taught me how to fashion a kind of ers new sounds and, playing with them, develops
flute from a hazelnut twig. Such transformations of musical instruments, which, simple at first, engen-
reality may begin even early in phylogeny. When a der progressively an almost entirely non-natural
chimpanzee mother takes a big stone, places on it a musical culture (Boesch, 1998). All that, from
nut, and knocks it open with a strong truncheon, she primitive beginnings, led to increasingly complex
uses elements present in her environment in a novel transformations of nature, accompanied by new
way. In other words, she transforms nature to con- habits, increased skills and knowledge, new social
form with her subjective intentions. Culture starts formations, and even a change in mentality—to our
with such transformations, subjecting nature to the benefit and peril as well.
wants and needs of individuals, for limited pur-
poses at first, sometimes for mere curiosity or play, Objective and Subjective Culture
but it will become more and more complex with All this relates to actions by which the child
individual growth or social development. The baker structures his/her world. Such actions not only form
transforms natural products into bread by making the environment but acquire meaning themselves—
use of fire, whose destructive power he tames and actions have their significance, otherwise one would

boesch 349
not perform them. There is nothing invented, con- school, as well as to cathedrals seen elsewhere, it
structed, sold, bought, used, exchanged, borrowed, reminds of sin and merit, of guilt and atonement,
given, stolen, or destroyed without a meaning to the of anxiety and hope. The cathedral, far from being
actor. By their meaning, things and actions become simply a particular building, becomes a symbol for
subjective realities. a whole complex of memories, feelings, and expec-
Yet, meanings can be expressed by language, and tations. And, of course, why, when, and to whom
then they belong to a mental system different from I speak of the cathedral has its own symbolic mean-
the inside experience. In other words, meanings ings. Let me emphasize, these meanings are not just
named differ from meanings felt. The sentence “I am appended to an object, an action, or a situation:
walking” says only that I move by feet somewhere they change its quality.
in space, in a way different, for example, from run- The two kinds of meaning determine the rela-
ning. It does not say how I walk, where to, why, nor tionship of citizens with their culture. The objective
what I see or feel while walking—language points meaning concerns material structure, factual events,
at categories of reality, not at specifics of experience. shared customs, myths, ideologies, and theories.
Adding more details, such as, “I am walking from Objectively, the Baroque cathedral stands for religious
home to office,” would clarify where I walk but still services, rituals, sermons, and their performance—in
nothing of the experienced meaning. short, for customs and creeds an anthropologist
Indeed, the experience of walking implies a might neutrally observe. The subjective meaning just
number of proprioceptive, physical sensations, and described relates somehow to identification with the
it includes the anticipation of a goal, related to place and to feelings of belonging, of being at home,
expectations, hopes, or concerns, and it is colored or, contrarily, of strangeness, even adversity. I may
not only by perceptions of the surroundings I pass describe my culture, may enumerate its character-
by but also by a general feeling of idleness or haste, istics, but I also feel at home in it, identify with its
by the weather, or by unarticulated memories of customs and values; identifying with one’s culture is
other walks, and even, unconsciously, by the style of very different from factual knowledge.
my walking—the gait of a soldier or the ambling of All this leads to the conclusion that the term cul-
a sightseer are obviously felt differently, but so are, ture has two meanings. On the one hand, it is objec-
even less consciously, the walking styles of a German tive. Our surroundings are factual. Of course, most
or of a Thai. In other words, naming the act places of it is created by individuals at a certain time. Yet,
it within objective categories, whereas performing it once produced, these creations become public facts
relates it to a net of connotations. Let us not forget of generally accepted qualities. Houses, individually
that this applies also to the very action of saying built, become parts of the common landscape; laws,
something; this, too, is subjectively experienced and individually conceived, regulate public life. Even a
has its own meanings, which, of course, differ from poem or a painting, once published or exhibited,
the content expressed: saying something addresses a belongs to the factual culture. Language, man-made
person, with expectations and feelings of sympathy too, is a pervasive element of objective culture.
or unease, we try to form our speech accordingly, But how about genuine nature—the hills and
being aware at the same time whether we do it well the forests, the rivers and lakes, the birds, wind,
or not. The addressee, on his side, will try to guess clouds, storm? Although not man-made, they are
the intentions behind the words. Language has to given a cultural significance by classification, use,
be understood semantically plus the meanings con- and interpretation. Trees are named, used for spe-
noted by the words spoken and by the act of speak- cific purposes, they may be inhabited by spirits one
ing them. must placate before falling them; wind, clouds,
This complexity of meanings, of course, is true thunder, and lightning may be attributed to gods or
for actions as well as for objects. By saying that in explained by science—both of course, being objec-
the center of my hometown stands a Baroque cathe- tive culture.
dral, I mention a specific category of buildings, and These factual elements of culture are connected
even adding more descriptions, my explication still with rules determining their use and function.
remains limited to the architectural structure and Those rules, too, are objective facts. Shops are for
objective function of the church. Although in the selling and buying, offices for working, schools for
individual experience, the cathedral relates to reli- learning, hospitals for curing, churches for services,
gious teachings and rituals at home, in church, in and so on; tools have to be used correctly, traffic

350 c ulture
codes have to be obeyed, and even forms of greeting In other words, she not only enjoys the garden, but
and other social rituals are objective culture. she lives with it. Her and my objective reality are,
Objective culture shapes the person to a large of course, identical, yet subjectively they differ. This
extent but not exclusively. Mountain peasants may difference is not easy to define, because it is not
be different from seaside fishermen, yet in each of simply conceptual but implies, more importantly,
these groups individuals differ, too, and will, as a difference of identification. For her, she looks at
far as circumstances allow, tend to select or shape plants, birds, or frogs with a kind of spontaneous
their own environment—their culture will turn empathy. I envy her, and I might, of course, try to
subjective. “My home is my castle” goes the British live up to her knowledge of the garden, but it would
saying—the home area is the center of each indi- remain a mere cognitive competence, devoid of the
vidual’s subjective culture, from here she or he will feelings of identification and empathy. Her culture
branch out and return again. Here, the objective and mine, objectively similar, differ subjectively.
constraints are minimal; the individual enjoys This difference, of course, has its history. My
freedom of action much more than in the outside wife spent her childhood and young years in a tropi-
world. cal country, surrounded by a nature full of life, with
Yet, this points at a subtle balance. The inside of plants growing almost at sight, producing fruits
the home may be a place of maximum individual- for food or enjoyment, with all kinds of animals,
ity, yet it is nevertheless also controlled by objec- snakes, geckos, bats, rats, fishes, birds, insects—in
tive culture. Furniture, decorations, curtains, and short, a nature that required continuous attention
even small gadgets in most homes correspond to but provided also a multitude of pleasures. And
public taste and fashion. Common rules of doing by her Buddhist education she was taught since
and acting also considerably influence personal early years, too, that all this life surrounding her
behavior at home. On the other hand, the outside was, essentially, a life similar to ours. Animals were
world is structured and interpreted subjectively, our relatives, and plants possessed a power of their
sometimes minimally, at other times considerably. own—not simply medical but magical, too.
The individual strives continuously at establishing This difference in subjective meanings can be
his or her balance between subjective and objective shown in more details with every object. Take the
culture. My Swiss dialect, for example, sounds typi- water lilies in our pond. For me, they are somehow
cally San Gallese, yet it still retains my own personal imbued with my recollection of the lotus flowers
tone and rhythm, distinguishable from other San in the pond near the house in which I lived for a
Gallese speakers. My language, which is objective, time in Bangkok; less consciously, they also recall
of course, still retains a subjective flavor. How such the beautiful reflections of the evening light on
balances are achieved remains enigmatic. The pro- the water surface. They might surreptitiously call
cess is mainly unconscious, but usually so are the up other memories, such as the strange snake with
rules along which an individual realizes the subjec- tentacles like a snail I had seen swimming there or
tive–objective balance in his home. the nightly concert of frogs and toads around the
Let me try a more detailed look at this subjective– pond. Occasionally, the water lilies remind me of
objective relationship. The pond in our garden is Buddha’s parable of the lotus bud striving out of the
surrounded by a lawn, and the whole site is enclosed deep water mud toward the sun. Unexpectedly even,
by big trees of various kinds. They somehow close I think of the lotus song my mother sang while as
off our private area from neighbors, and I enjoy the a boy I sat listening under the piano of my father.
quiet privacy and the soothing green scenery, but I And, of course, the water lilies imply not only mem-
have apparently not much interest in details; I never ories but also future anticipations—for example, the
can remember the names of many trees, cannot dis- hope to re-experience such beauty.
tinguish their foliage or bloom, and tend to con- For my wife, our water lilies also remind her of the
found, when mowing the lawn, kitchen herbs with lotus in her home nature, but her recollections are
weeds. My wife, obviously, also enjoys the green much richer, including her swimming in the nearby
surroundings, but in addition she observes each canals and the life of animals she observed there, but
smallest plant, watches their growth, knows almost they refer also to very different lotus flowers, related
personally the frogs and the newts in the pond, and to myth stories of Hinduism and Buddhism, as well
distinguishes not only the song of different birds as to religious rituals—lotus buds were offered to the
but even its change when a cat prowls in the garden. Buddha and to monks during religious ceremonies.

boesch 351
In other words, lotus plants were holy plants, and The example of the garden is a simile for the
therefore even the view of our water lilies appealed to intimate blend of objective and subjective culture,
very private religious feelings. Their subjective and but it demonstrates also another important aspect.
public meaning blended inextricably. When we built the house, the garden area was an
One might object that such memories connected uneven terrain of dirt and rubble. We had it lev-
with the garden in no way alter its factual reality. eled and planted the saplings with a vision of their
One can enjoy it, can work in it, but always only as growing big. Saplings, of course, symbolize the
far as its size, structure, and content allow. Whatever trees, but they symbolized as well a life in nature,
the different past experiences, action still remains with all that implies in memory and hope. Thus, we
determined by the objective reality. This is true only created objective culture, yet with a view on future
if one neglects the very different garden behavior subjective options. Those would be many years
of my wife and myself. Objective reality determines ahead—action is future-oriented. It may welcome
our action, but we select its relevant contents, which immediate reinforcements but as a confirmation of
thereby receives a meaning that is both subjective hope.
and factual. Again, the manner in which this blend Such distant goals require imagination, which, of
is achieved remains a puzzle. course, is fed by previous experience. Imagination,
Our life does not consist of disconnected events. however, is not simply repetitive: it expands or
We want ourselves to be a consistent continuity. strengthens our action potential and can do so in
Therefore, what I experience now will color com- quite novel ways. When we built the garden as an
ing moments. While driving, I pass near the scene objective structure, we imagined it to offer not only
of a car accident, with police and ambulances. Will different but also new opportunities to our every
that not affect the style of my further driving? The action—to anticipate newness can particularly
beatings I received as an unruly boy still somehow animate imagination. Thus, a concrete situation
influence my adult behavior, and the stories I was is always open; it allows individuals their private
then told even today color my imagination. To be a interpretations.
permanent self implies that experience, as different
as it may be, be tied by a thread of continuity— Factual and Imagined Reality
what this thread is, is difficult to tell; it corresponds Action, I said, is both real and symbolic. Besides
to our continuous construction of the self, but we its specific goal, it always pursues other related
ignore what directs this construction. interests—the polyvalence we already have met.
Thus, it is this thread of continuity that affects the We have also discussed the overdetermination,
different garden behaviors of my wife and myself. meaning that past experiences also enter the pres-
Yet, these differences remain at the subverbal level. ent motivation of action. Polyvalence and overde-
The thousand and thousand impressions that con- termination constitute a major part of the symbolic
stitute a life will only rarely be present in our mind; variance of action and experience. Symbolism
yet, there are reasons to presume that, although enriches the actual experience by relating it with
latent, they still remain active. An apparently long outside contents. Those may be directly tied to
forgotten memory may suddenly re-emerge at a par- present action (as polyvalence and overdetermina-
ticular moment, not in all details probably, but in tion), may be connected with conventional beliefs
some of its personally relevant features. Unnoticed, (such as the lotus buds), may recall some recollec-
it was here all the time and must have melted some- tion, or may be result from private imaginations,
how into the totality of our experience and view of some or all of those in combination. Symbolism,
life, I tend to think that this totality in some way thus, is complex and polyvalent itself. Although
constitutes a prism through which we perceive real- mostly unconscious, it serves an important func-
ity, thereby contributing to our action tendencies. tion: to relate actual with previous experience and
According to the angle through which we look, the to thereby guarantee the continuity of our self and
image perceived may change, but it still results from cultural belonging.
the same prism. Of course, that is only an image, By its symbolism, action necessarily includes
but it allows me to understand the continuous inte- imagination. Imagination, therefore, is omnipres-
gration of experience in an individual’s life. We not ent. It may confine itself to the already known, but
only act with regard to an actual situation but con- it can also reach toward the unknown. Even when
tinue always the thread of our life. weighing alternatives of an intended action, we

352 c ulture
imagine possible outcomes, some never experienced successful—lies can be profitable. Yet trust, neces-
before; imagination is a creative function. sary for any cultural community, is itself a belief
For me, the creation of language is a striking based on imagination.
example. Indeed, linking a sound with an object Trust is not only concerned with possible dis-
establishes a connection not present in reality. The honesty; one must also trust oneself. Let me recall
phome “fish” has nothing in common with the ani- an aspect of language touched upon earlier. A
mal; the sound “table” nothing with the material meaning said and a meaning felt, we found, are
object. Therefore, to believe that imagination results not identical. Expressing a thought or a feeling by
from language puts the cart before the horse: the words unavoidably curtails or even distorts them.
invention of language requires imagination. Therefore speech, for being understood, requires
However, language progressively becomes a completion by imagination, and one must be able
major vehicle for imagination. It opens, as I have to trust it. The speaker, on the other side, needs to
said, the realm of the unreal. And the unreal is pres- trust that his words truly express his intention. Both
ent at every moment. Whatever somebody says may be wrong, their trust unfounded—a cause for
refers to meanings that have to be imagined. But much misunderstanding, possibly even conflict.
imagination extends further. It works already in the Thus, pure imaginations, apparently unrelated
simple contemplation of a flower, an insect, or a to facts, are more than ineffectual creations of
bird; it colors our perception of a person, and from mind; they can persuade and can give rise to hope
anticipating the results of an action it leads up to the or despair, which gives them a strong emotional
most artificial and abstract constructions of mind. appeal. Imaginations not only make facts real, as
Facts, I said previously, become real only through we already found, but may constitute facts or sug-
the meanings attached to them, which implies that gest their existence. Aware of that, perhaps uncon-
it is imagination that constitutes the reality of facts. sciously, we often tend to believe imagination more
Therefore culture, consisting of meaningful facts, than facts. Love relationships, financial investments,
is also always imagined; it operates constantly on the down to the preference of certain foods rely exten-
two levels of concrete facts and imagination—the sively on imaginations, and multiple are the con-
two, of course, being inextricably interrelated. This flicts resulting from imagination more than factual
relationship constitutes reality. Each factual cre- reality. Indeed, in Europe, religious wars were prob-
ation results from imagination, and for achieving its ably more passionate and cruel than territorial ones.
effect, it needs imagination, too. On the other hand, The bloodiest war in history, World War II, had
imaginations strive at material reality. Artists paint many causes, but the ideological ones were promi-
or sculpt their inner images, the founders of religion nent. That was true as well for the crusades or the 30
mold their spiritual inspirations into words and Years War. In the United States, the Civil War was
materialize them in innumerable ways. Yet, despite fought over racial ideologies, and in our days reli-
their close alliance, concrete action and imagination gious zeal creates bloody terror. To fight and kill for
have to observe different rules. Objective action religious or ideological reasons seemed, up to our
requires close observation of matter and compliance days, to many people legitimate, or even required.
with its qualities. For imagination, on the contrary, Cruel punishments for real or suspected heresy
anything is possible; even the rules of consistency, were widely acclaimed, and lynch justice persisted
logic, and truth may often be disregarded. until recently. Now merely fictive imaginations can
Language, opening the dimension of the unreal, engender violence that is real.
permits invention and fiction but also lie and deceit. The relationship between imagination and vio-
Although invention and fiction enjoy much prestige lence leads to two overarching concerns of human
and lead to the highest creations in art, literature, beings: To know who we are, what is the meaning
religion, and science, the ever-present possibil- of our life, and in what kind of a world we live.
ity of untruth introduces suspicion and distrust. These are strange questions. Animals live from day
This ambivalence plays an important role in cul- to day without ever wondering about the sense of
ture. Imaginative creations, like religion or politi- their existence. Mankind, from as early times as we
cal programs, may positively influence culture, but know, unceasingly asks these questions. Dryness
they can also mislead and provoke dissent or even and floods, thunder, lightening, earthquakes, or
deadly conflicts. Therefore, any culture invents rules diseases disturb the routine of their lives, and they
that try to guarantee trust. These are not always start wondering about their causes. The world

boesch 353
seems to be full of enigmatic powers –and how to stark poverty who are apparently content with their
deal with them. This is an issue that appears to be sort. The impact of factual conditions varies accord-
the root of culture formation and has directed our ing to the meaning we attach to them. This meaning
evolution up to modern science. Our curiosity, the results, of course, from previous experiences, mean-
drive at increasing the transparency of our world, ingful in their own way but no less from the cultural
has brought us down to the depths of oceans, up answers to the existential questions. External objects
to the expanses of the universe and into the micro- and events are real as well as symbolic.
scopic insides of matter. It has not only immensely The cultural views on life and the world take
increased our knowledge and mastery but also our form in myths and theories; in minute details of
feelings of security—the enigmatic occurrences that fashion, taste, and customs; and, most strikingly, in
had threatened us have largely lost their power, concrete creations. A temple, a mosque, a church are
whereas the one of mankind has increased. not only material manifestations of cultural beliefs,
Yet, the question—Who are we?—still remains. but by their size and magnificence confirm them
We may live a longer, easier, and more pleasant life, impressively. The same is true for sports stadiums
but we still die, and for most of us, life still consists or race courts, for hospitals or universities—they
of struggle more than of pleasure. With luck, we all resulted from a cultural ideology. Imaginations
will reach an age of pension, allowing us (again with respond to facts and want to turn into facts them-
luck) a carefree life for a few years, not enough to selves—facts, as I said, become real by imagination,
compensate the toil of the preceding decades. What but imagination strives at factual concretization.
then were all our efforts and pains for? Some of us Thus, facts and imagination form that symbiotic
may have the means to eschew this question—at unity that we call culture.
least for a time—by accumulating pleasant expe-
riences. The meaning of life, they may find, is to A Note on Cultural Differences
enjoy it. However, for the majority, even nowadays, Cultures are different. That is a truism. But how
this remains utopian. So what, then, was the mean- and why do they differ? Not an easy question. The
ing of life? usual answer is that, living in different ecological
It is one of the main functions of culture to pro- surroundings, populations are forced to develop
vide answers to these questions. I don’t know of any different ways of coping. That is true, yet not a
culture that did not try to explain the world and sufficient explanation. Of course, peasant cultures
the universe and to define the role and destiny of in moderate climates, for example, resemble each
human beings. Mythology, religion, philosophy, art, other, without, however, being identical. Or let us
science—they all compete to offer answers. These look at an even more instructive example: the male
are manifold, varying from superstitious beliefs to and female cultures, which obviously differ all over
Indian cosmology, from Egyptian religion to Greek the globe. Men and women tend to differ in lan-
mythology, from medieval religions to modern sci- guage, movement, taste and body care; in social
ence. They may stress the worldly role of individu- and sexual behavior; and in emotional reactions,
als, their social contribution, and responsibility, or religious inclinations, art preference, and prob-
they may link man’s fate to metaphysical powers. ably many more ways. Ecological conditions, being
Such answers, whatever they say, turn to be collec- identical for both sexes, can of course not explain
tive creeds; they dispel doubts, provide security, and their difference. Therefore, it is usual to see the rea-
thus induce strong feelings of belonging. Although son in their unequal anatomical and physiological
pure imaginations, devoid of empirical proof, they constitution. That seemed plausible until recently
tend to be taken as factual truths, strengthening the but now appears less convincing. Women enter
self and its social bond. This explains why any attack professions and occupations previously reserved for
on such beliefs appears as an existential threat and males; they compete successfully in science, sports,
risks to provoke violent reactions. Imaginations, not and other fields. Of course, child bearing will nec-
only establishing the reality of facts, gain tremen- essarily remain female, but it seems to hinder less
dous power by constituting also our self. and less their full participation in the hitherto male
Of course, the impact of factual conditions on world. The difference between male and female cul-
human beings is evident. Poverty creates frustration, ture is on the wane, because of, let us not forget,
and frustration engenders anger and aggression. True. the creative opposition to the prevailing order by
Yet, there exist people living in what we would call individuals, both women and men.

354 c ulture
Future Directions They are subcultures within an all-encompassing
The conclusion appears evident: The difference cultural field with its own opportunities and
was to a large extent ideological. Cultures gave men demands. How can we maintain an individuality
and women a different answer to the basic question in balance with such diversity? Some may choose
“Who am I?” Without denying the importance of to howl with the wolves, to bark with the dogs, and
ecology in forming cultures, we have to accept, too, to sing with the birds, being content to be simply
that ideologies carry considerable weight. Why? what each situation requires. Himmler was, with-
The question “Who am I?” asks for evaluating out qualms, a family man, an amateur musician,
oneself. Self-evaluation derives mainly from two and a killer of Jews. Others may strive at an inde-
sources: action potential and social feedback. The pendent self, consistent over variable situations.
action potential results, as we know (1976, 1991), Such a self will, of course, not be culture-free but
from previous successes and failures, allowing the will integrate creatively diverse cultural elements.
individual to conceive future actions – the action For those, to maintain a balance between self and
potential is prospective. But what is a success; what diverse cultures requires creativity, critical under-
is a failure? We need criteria to evaluate them, and standing, and empathy. Such individuals, history
apparently it is social feedback to our behavior that tells, can influence their culture in important ways,
mainly provides these criteria. Yet, social feedback but on a more modest level, everyone may contrib-
is multiple and often contradictory, the one may ute to shape their close or even distant world. Each
praise what the other blames, and they may also dif- of us leaves his or her traces wherever we dwell and
fer from own evaluations. Therefore, the individual act—it is worth pondering about what kind of
will select among social reactions and form personal traces we wish to remain. Human beings, although
criteria of success and failure. Those, however, will products of their culture to a major degree, still
still result from cultural inputs. Thus, action experi- also shape or even transform it—some minimally
ence blends intimately with cultural evaluations. but some also with considerable impact. Science
Let us look again at female culture. Cultural may often prefer to neglect human creativity, look-
imprinting starts early. Soon the child will exhort: ing at individuals as mere results of outside forces.
“No, that is not for girls”; or “Don’t act boyishly”; Yet, without considering the balance people create
“A good girl will behave this way” and so on. Advice between mind and culture, we would never under-
and examples will lead the growing girl to identify stand the emergence of cultural differences. Let us,
with her female belonging and its appropriate behav- however, remain mindful. Human creativity, his-
iors. She will learn sewing, knitting, and cooking tory tells again, can benefit as well as harm our lives
rather than working wood or metal. She may rebel and world. How to use human potentials construc-
occasionally, may reject certain constraints, but on tively will have to be a major concern for a science
the whole will accept being a woman to be one of of culture.
her tribe with its particular culture. However, only
to be a woman is no sufficient answer to the ques- References
tion “Who am I?”. The individual wants to know Boesch, E. E. (1963). Raum und Zeit als Valenzsysteme. In:
“What kind of a woman am I?”. Within the con- Hiltmann & Vonesse (Eds.), “In Dialektik und Dynamik
fines of their culture, each person seeks to form and der Person”. (pp. 135–154) Köln: Kiepenheuer & Witsch.
(Reprint 1971).
define their particular identity. This may be easier in Boesch, E. E. (1966). Psychologische Theorie des sozialen Wandels.
some cultures than in others because cultural con- In: H. Besters & E. E. Boesch (eds.), “Entwicklungspolitik”.
straints vary. The cultural ideology provides security Handbuch und Lexikon. (pp. 335–416). Stuttgart/Mainz:
but limits also the individual’s personal way of life. Kreuz-Verlag/Mathias-Grünewald-Verlag.
To some, security counts more, for them culture is Boesch, E. E. (1970). Zwiespältige Eliten. Eine sozialpsycholo-
gische Untersuchung über administrative Eliten in Thailand.
a welcome stabilizer, which lets us understand that Bern: Huber.
many women at first resisted the feminist revolt. It Boesch, E. E. (1971). Zwischen zwei Wirklichkeiten. Prolegomena zu
threatened their self and the gratifications related to einer ökologischen Psychologie. Bern: Huber.
cultural identification. Boesch, E. E. (1975a). Zwischen Angst und Triumph. Über das Ich
We all belong to many cultures—national, sex- und seine Bestätigung. Bern: Huber.
Boesch, E. E. (1975b). La détermination culturelle du soi. In:
ual, religious, professional ones—each with their “Psychologie de la connaissance de soi”. Association de psy-
conditions for membership, their rules, benefits, chologie scientifique de langue française (ed.), (pp. 99–119).
prohibitions, rituals, even their particular language. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

boesch 355
Boesch, E. E. (1976): Psychopathologie des Alltags. Zur Ökopsychologie (eds.), “Social representations and the social bases of knowledge”.
des Handelns und seiner Störungen. Bern: Huber. (pp. 89–95). Lewiston, Toronto, Bern, Göttingen: Hogrefe
Boesch, E. E. (1980a). Kultur und Handlung. Einführung in & Huber.
die Kulturpsychologie. Bern: Huber. Boesch, E. E. (1993). The sound of the violin. The Quarterly
Boesch, E. E. (1980b). Action et objet, deux sources de l’identité Newsletter of the Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition,
du moi. In: P. Tap (ed.), «Identité individuelle et personnali- 15, I,. 6–16.
sation». Toulouse: Edition Privat (pp. 23–37). Boesch, E. E. (1994). La réalité comme métaphore. Journal de la
Boesch, E. E. (1982) Fantasmus und Mythus. In: J. Stagl (ed.), psychanalyse de l’enfant, 15, 155–180
“Aspekte der Kultursoziologie”. (pp. 59–86). Berlin: Dietrich Boesch, E. E. (1996). The seven flaws of cross-cultural psychol-
Reimer. ogy. The story of a conversion. Mind, Culture and Activity,
Boesch, E. E. (1983a). Das Magische und das Schöne. Stuttgart: 3(1): 2–10.
Frommann-Holzboog. Boesch, E. E. (2000). Das lauernde Chaos. Mythen und Fiktionen
Boesch, E. E. (1983b). The personal object. Education, 27, im Alltag. Bern: Huber. Boesch, E. E. (2001) Symbolic Action
99–113 (Translated from German). Theory in Cultural Psychology. Culture & Psychology, 7, 4,
Boesch, E. E. (1983c) Die Kulturbedingtheit des Menschen. In: Boesch, E. E. (2005). Von Kunst bis Terror: Über den Zwiespalt in
P. Gordan (ed.), Menschwerden, Menschsein”. (pp. 339–369). der Kultur. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck + Ruprecht.
Kevelaer: Butzon & Becker. Boesch, E. E. (2008). The subjective culture. Culture & Psychology,
Boesch, E. E. (1987). Cultural Psychology in action theoretical 14(4), 498–512
perspective. In: Ç. Kagitçibasi (ed.), “Growth and progress in Simão, L., et al. (2002). L. M. Simao, M. T. C. Coelho de Souza,
cross-cultural psychology”. (pp. 41–52). Lisse: International N. E. Coelho, Junior: “Noçao de objeto, concepçao de sujeito:
Association for Cross-Cultural Psychology. Freud, Piaget e Boesch”. São Paulo: Casa de Psicólogo.
Boesch, E. E. (1991) Symbolic action theory and cultural psychol- Lonner, W. J. and Hayes, S. A. (2007) Discovering Cultural
ogy. (p. 356). Berlin/New York: Springer. In French “L’action Psychology. A profile and Selected Readings of Ernest E. Boesch.
symbolique”, Paris, L’Harmattan (1995). Charlotte, N.C.: Information Age Publishing.
Boesch, E. E. (1992). Culture - individual - culture: The cycle
of knowledge. In: M. v. Cranach, W. Doise & G. Mugny

356 c ulture
CHAPTER

Culture-Inclusive Action Theory:


17 Action Theory in Dialectics and
Dialectics in Action Theory
Lutz H. Eckensberger

Abstract
The following chapter deals with the concept of Culture-Inclusive Action Theory (CIAT) and research
the author and his coworkers conducted primarily in Saarbrücken (and later in Frankfurt) over the last
35 years in two (complementary) subject areas, which also form the roots of the chapter: cross-cultural
research and development of moral judgment in the tradition of Piaget/Kohlberg. In cross-cultural
psychology, the duality “person versus culture” is unavoidable. In moral development, the dualities
“content versus structure,” “facts versus norms,” and “affects versus cognition” are likewise unavoidable.
In both research fields, the assumption of a dialectical relation between these dualities and the role of
action theory in relation to dialectics was and still is attractive. In the following this role is interpreted
also within Dynamic System Theory, by the concepts of upward emergence and downward selection,
which are synthesized by the human action. This theoretical orientation from the very beginning called
for its justification vìs-a-vìs mainstream psychology by implying meta-theoretical reflections. After a
short introduction into dialectics and action theory in psychology, a more detailed treatment of the two
research subjects are presented. The first step in both topics was (biographically) a systematic theoretical
analysis dealing with the meaning of culture for psychology and the deep structure of moral development.
In both topics the (descriptive) application of action theory and the (interpretative) appropriation of
dialectics was productive and lead to contextualized research by conceptualizing a “regional cultural
identity” on the one hand and formulating “types of everyday morality” on the other. This cultural
contextualization is the reason for calling our approach Culture-Inclusive Action Theory (CIAT). A later study
on the process of coming to terms with cancer was based on the same theoretical model; developed in
both fields (culture and morality), it was also methodically contextualized from the very beginnings.
Keywords: moral judgment, culture, action, dialectics, cross-cultural research

In cross-cultural psychology, the duality “person (Breit & Eckensberger, 2004b; Eckensberger,
versus culture” is unavoidable (e.g., Eckensberger, 1993a; Eckensberger, 2006a), as is the duality
1979, 1990a, 1990b, 1996a, 1996b, 2002a, of “affects and cognition” (Eckensberger, 1989a;
2010a; Krewer, 1990). It has a long tradition in Eckensberger & Emminghaus, 1982; Villenave-
culture and personality studies (for an overview, Cremer & Eckensberger, 1985). In both research
see Eckensberger & Römhild, 2000; for an early fields, the role of action theory in relation to dia-
critique, see Shweder, 1980). In moral develop- lectics in dealing with these dualities was and still
ment, the dualities “content versus structure” is attractive.
(Eckensberger, 1986; Eckensberger & Reinshagen, The first step in both topics of research was a sys-
1978, 1980; Eckensberger & Burgard, 1986), tematic theoretical analysis dealing with (1) the mean-
“facts versus norms” are likewise unavoidable ing of culture for psychology and (2) the theoretical

357
foundation of moral development. Both topics lead to distinction is made between dialectics as an inher-
contextualized research by conceptualizing a “regional ent aspect of things or thought (although this
cultural identity” on the one hand (e.g., Krewer & distinction is difficult to maintain under a con-
Eckensberger, 1990; Krewer, 1990) and formulating structivist perspective), but dialectics is also consid-
“types of everyday morality” on the other (see Breit & ered an assumed relation between concepts and an
Eckensberger, 1998; Breit, Döring, & Eckensberger, operation.
2003; Döring, Eckensberger, Huppert, & Breit, Dialectic thought exists both in the West and in
2008; Eckensberger, 2006; Eckensberger, 2010b; Eastern philosophies—for example, in Taoism (Lin
Eckensberger, Döring, & Breit, 2001). A later study Yuang, 1948). In the West it goes back to classi-
on the process of coming to terms with cancer was cal “old Greek” philosophy (Aristotle, Socrates, and
based on a theoretical model, which was developed Plato); it was a topic in medieval philosophy but
in both fields of research (culture and morality) (e.g., primarily in the modern philosophy of the nine-
Eckensberger, Kreibich-Fischer, Gaul, & Schnurre, teenth century. Here the outstanding figures are
1990). However, this study also contributed to the Hegel and Marx, whose political impact certainly
model itself, although it is not closed yet. The fol- did not contribute to an appreciation of dialectics
lowing chapter rests upon these studies. But the in science. Yet, later it played a role in the Frankfurt
action-theoretical orientation from the very begin- School (Horkheimer& Adorno, 1969). These
ning forced me to justify this approach in the con- authors already indicate that dialectics was/is not
text of mainstream psychology by “meta-theoretical” only relevant for psychological theorizing but also
reflections (Eckensberger, 1979, 2002, 2003, 2006, for sociology and, in fact, for all sciences that deal
2010a, 2011a, 2011b). This work will also be sum- with development/change and with dualities (e.g.,
marized in the following. Molz (2010) has recently nature vs. nurture; individual vs. society/culture;
reconstructed my work also by comparing it with the norms vs. facts; theory vs. practice, etc.) and thus
theories of Yrjö Engeström and Jacques Demorgon. also for biology (Levins & Lewontin, 1985) and
Although the Culture Inclusive Action Theory even physics (Cross, 1991).
(CIAT) is genuinely developmental, the chapter does
not intend to give an overview of action theory in Dialectical Thinking and Developmental
developmental psychology in general. Examples for Psychology
such overviews can be found in Brandtstaedter1 and As the work, summarized here, began in the
Lerner (1999) and with reference to social cogni- 1970s, a word about the “Zeitgeist” of that decade
tion in Eckensberger and Plath (2006a). Rather, the is in order. During that time, dialectics received
chapter by necessity has a historical (autobiographic) considerable attention in developmental psychology
dimension, which implies (1) that it not only rests (e.g., by Riegel, 1979; Rychlak, 1976; Schmidt,
on my recent work, but it also starts with its root in 1972; Datan & Reese, 1977; Buss, 1979). But the
the 70s; (2) it also sometimes refers to unpublished reception of dialectics in psychology was also quite
work like reports; and (3) to save space, sometimes critical. Psychology was—and still is—heavily influ-
larger chapters I contributed to handbooks or reviews enced by Popper’s (1959) critical rationalism, in
are referred to, which contain detailed literature dealt which the principle of falsification is crucial. It is
with in the following. plausible therefore that for Popper, contradictions
(antithesis in dialectics) cannot be logically accepted
Multiple Views on Dialectics in Psychology as valid. This argument is explicitly formulated
The term dialectical/dialectics has a long and in Popper’s early criticism of dialectics in a paper
complex history. Briefly characterized, dialectics can entitled “What Is Dialectic?” (Popper, 1937/1963).
be regarded as (1) a basic principle in dealing with There, he concludes that “two contradictory state-
dualities in development/progress (often) in form of ments can never be true together” (1963, p. 5). It is
a spiral (not helix), also known as the negation of important to realize, however, that basically Popper
negation; (2) dealing with (overriding, synthesizing) evaluates a “newly formulated” perspective by using
dualities, or contradictions (thesis, antithesis); and traditional criteria of Boolean two-valent logic—
(3) the transformation of quantity into quality that which the originators of dialectics Hegel and Fichte
implies nonlinear concepts of development. Often had left behind more than a century earlier.
it is understood as a principle of interpenetration or Baltes, Reese, and Nesselroade (1977) stated:
interdependency between dualities. Furthermore a “What the basic metaphor of dialectics is, is open

358 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


to question” (p. 26), and in the same year Baltes upon by the scientific community but, rather, a fam-
and Cornelius (1977) speculated that “many devel- ily of theories. Like dialectics, action concepts also
opmentalists . . . are attracted to dialectics as a phil- have a long and complex history, again going back
osophical theory or as a theoretical orientation . . . to the “old Greeks” (Aristotle) and existing since the
however, whether the convergence of research issues very beginning of the formal discipline of psychol-
in developmental research with the proposition ogy in the last century both in Europe and North
of dialectics is more than a temporary courtship America, although it varied in saliency during its
is another question” (p. 123). Hook (1957) and history. In the psychology in Germany in 1874,
Mehlberg (1955), like Popper, evaluate dialectics in Brentano, a teacher of Freud’s, focused on inten-
terms of a traditional scientific method, when Hook tionality as a basic feature of consciousness, leading
states: to the concept “acts of consciousness.” Ten years later,
Dilthey (1894/1968) distinguished between the
“the dialectic method can claim to have meaning
explanation of nature and understanding the mind/
and validity only when it is understood to be
soul, a duality that paved the way for the ongoing
synonymous with scientific method, and that
discourse on the duality of explanation and under-
therefore there is no need to talk about dialectic
standing (v. Wright, 1971). At the turn of the twen-
method at all.”
tieth century, Münsterberg, a disciple of Wundt and
(Hook, 1957, p. 27, quoted by Baltes and Cornelius,
one of the founders of an applied psychology, pro-
1977, p. 126)
posed action as the basic unit of psychology rather
In contrast, Baltes and Cornelius (1977) have than sensations. In North America, James devel-
discussed different aspects and levels of the prin- oped a sophisticated theory of action at the end of
ciples of scientific method much more moderately the nineteenth century, which anticipated a remark-
and in more detail. They claimed pragmatically or able number of action theory concepts (see Barbalet,
strategically: “In order to implement a dialectical 1997). These early traditions were, however, over-
perspective, pluralistic but systematic method- ruled by the neo-positivistic logic of explanation,
ological procedures are necessary” (p. 130). This expounded by the Vienna circle in philosophy that
argument is based on their effort to break the asso- was quite in line with behaviorism in psychology.
ciative link between the dialectical perspective and They were taken up in philosophy by Wittgenstein’s
paradigm as well as between paradigms and the sci- “language games,” which are assumed to be differ-
entific method. They argue, “A dialectical perspec- ent in natural science and the humanities. In 1920,
tive need not be linked with a specific metaphysical Stern criticized the mainstream psychology of the
. . . paradigm nor with a specific epistemological time because it neglected intentionality and also
model, but may be better implemented by the cultural change as a framework for human devel-
utilization of multiple world views or meta-para- opment. And it is probably no wonder that Bühler
digms” (p. 130). The same is true for “lower–level (1927) and Vygotsky (1927) both published on a
research methodologies” (p. 130). So these authors crises of psychology in the very same year.
somehow tried to eat the cake (take a dialectical
perspective) and keep it too (by sticking to tradi-
tional scientific methods). In other contexts Baltes, Action As the Basic Unit of Analysis
Reese, and Nesselroade (1977) used the term dia- When seen from our contemporary vantage
lectics at the same formal level as “mechanistic” point, action theory terms have increased in impor-
and “organismic” (p. 23 ff.), thereby suggesting a tance again during the last three or four decades.
specific paradigm (see p. 877 ff.). Yet, as will be Bruner’s (1991) “acts of meaning” elucidated the
shown, I have not only argued slightly differently difference between meaning and information and
(see Eckensberger, 1979), but I am still convinced focused on contexts. Freese and Sarbini (1985) pub-
that the assumption of dialectical relations is pro- lished on goal-directed behavior, whereas Martin,
ductive in science and psychology in particular. Sugarman, and Thompson (2003) discussed the
question of agency in psychology. In Germany,
The Action Theory Enters the Scene Boesch (1991) published a remarkable introduc-
Important aspects of action theory can be sum- tion to his Symbolic Action Theory (see also Boesch,
marized as follows (Eckensberger, 2001a): Action 2011). Its development was recently carefully recon-
theory is not a formalized and unitary theory agreed structed by Lonner and Hayes (2007). Groeben

ecken sberger 359


(1986) analyzed the relation between the concepts and practice, between general laws and contexts (see
of action, doing, and behavior (historically as well), also Eckensberger, 1979, 2003, 2004). In addition,
and Straub (2006) discussed action theory from a an action-based cultural psychology, for example,
linguistic and cultural point of view and published becomes an integrated enterprise that is develop-
an interdisciplinary discourse on action theory mental as well as cognitive, affective, and motiva-
(Straub & Werbik, 1999), to mention but some of tional (cf. Boesch, 1976, 1991; Cole, 1990, 1996;
these developments. In fact, the term action also has Eckensberger, 1990a, 1990b).2 Considering the
a long and controversial history in philosophy. At breadth of action theoretical frameworks, it is not
least Juarrero (1999) and her discussion of action surprising that neither are the issues studied similar
as a complex system is to be mentioned here, also nor is the terminology coherent or fully agreed upon
because some of her concepts will be used in the by different authors or traditions.
following as they are quite compatible with my own From an analytical perspective, to act does not
theoretical orientation. mean to behave (although some authors consider
actions as a particular subtype of behavior). To
speak of an action rather than of behavior implies at
Action Theory in Different Fields least the following features:
of Psychology
Although not a focus of mainstream psychology, 1. Broadly speaking, it means that sentences,
action theory is also applied (implicitly or explicitly) symbols, but also mental states refer to something
in a variety of its subfields. This is true for basic in the world (Searle, 1980). Intentionality basically
science—in theories of motivation (e.g., Heckhausen, means that a subject (called agency) refers to the
1989; Gollwitzer, 1990; Kornadt, 1982)—problem world. Intentionality, therefore, is intrinsically a
solving (e.g., Dörner & Kaminski, 1988), ontoge- relational concept. Agencies refer to the world by
netic development (e.g., Oppenheimer & Valsiner, acting with reference to the world, by experiencing
1991; Brandtstaedter & Lerner, 1998), social psy- it (they think, feel, perceive, imagine, etc.), by
chology (von Cranach, 1991), and particularly cul- influencing it (actions are genuinely contextual),
tural psychology (Boesch, 1971, 1991; Cole, 1990; and by speaking about it. The latter is called speech
Eckensberger, 1990a, 1990b). It is also true for edu- act. An intentional state thus implies a particular
cational psychology (Bruner, 1996), organizational content and a psychic mode (a subject can think that
psychology or psychology of work (Hacker, 1986) it rains, wish that it rains, claim that it rains, etc.,
sport psychology (Kaminski, 1982), and “applied where rain is the content and thinking, wishing,
domains”—for example, in clinical psychology or and claiming are modes). The intent of the action
counseling (Janet/Schwartz, 1951; Eckensberger & is the intentional state of an action; the intended
Kreibich-Fischer, 1994; Eckensberger & Plath, consequence or goal its content. This implies what
2006b; Plath & Eckensberger, 2008). is also called “futurity” (Barbalet, 1997) or future
Particularly the applied domain is of central orientation of an action. It follows that actions
importance here, because since the very beginnings are not necessarily observable from the outside. If
there has been a conceptual split between general they are, one also uses the term doing (Groeben,
nomothetic psychology and psychology as a means 1986). However, intentionally allowing something to
to solve individual and social problems. This tension happen as well as intentionally refraining from doing
is one reason for the development of an “ecological something are both actions (von Wright, 1971;
orientation” of the 1970s focused on the issue of Janich, 2006).3
“two realities” (Boesch, 1971) of real life and the lab- Furthermore, it is assumed that action involves
oratory. Therefore, I have proposed (Eckensberger, the subjective free choice of alternatives to do
1995a, 2003, 2004) to allocate two different types of something (A or B), to let something happen
actions to these fields (theory building and problem intentionally or to refrain intentionally from doing
solving) that have quite different criteria and impli- something. This condition is closely related to
cations. A similar distinction has been made recently the (subjective perception) of free will. Although
by Smedslund (2009), who additionally called for the control aspect is sometimes also expanded
taking problem-solving strategies more seriously in to include the intended effects of an action, these
science. But basically I (Eckensberger, 1989a) inter- two aspects should be distinguished, because the
preted action theory as a bridge between theory effects of an action can be beyond the control of

360 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


the agency, although the decision to act itself was 4. The tension between autonomy (free choice)
controlled by intentionality. and heteronomy (intuitive4 rule following) is basic
2. Actions in principle are potentially conscious to many action theories and is therefore also the
activities of an agency. But the consciousness focus in the social/cultural context of actions (cf.
of actions is discussed differently by different Parsons, 1937/1968). One can try to resolve this
authors. Whereas some authors claim that tension, however, by assuming that cultural rules
consciousness is a necessary aspect of an action and their alteration are also man-made, although
(which also implies the methodical possibility the implied intentionality of cultural rules/norms
of asking actors about their actions), I have may “get lost” over time. This is why Smedslund
claimed that only the potential self-reflectivity (1984) can understand culture as “the invisible
of an agency (and a specific action) is crucial obvious.”
(Eckensberger, 1979). This not only implies
In principle within this theoretical frame, an
that a self-reflective action may be a rare event
action links the actor/agency and his/her environ-
(e.g., during a day) but also that actions can
ment (see James, 1897). Intentionality is not only
turn into automatisms or habits, yet still remain
a core concept for understanding the individual/
actions. This rather tricky issue was a problem
agency (Eckensberger & Meacham, 1984), but at
in action theory from the very beginning. In
the same time it is also possible to conceptualize
Paris, Pierre Janet wrote his dissertation about
culture as being the result of actions and co-ac-
Automatisme psychologique (Janet, 1889) to deal
tions (Eckensberger, 1979, 1990a, 1990b, 1996b)
with non-consciousness in actions. This was the
or as an intentional world (Shweder, 1990).5 We
beginning of an elaborated action theoretical
(Eckensberger, Krewer, & Kaspar, 1984, p. 99)
system of neuroses (see Schwartz, 1951). Freud
elaborated on this issue by claiming that actions
(1923) of course chose a different solution of
result in material social and symbolic changes of the
non-conscious actions in conceptualizing a
environment on the one hand (this is why culture
dynamic unconsciousness, but he also postulated
is sometimes understood as “the man-made part
a “descriptive unconsciousness” (habits). This
of the environment,”; Herskovits, 1948), and they
implication, however, calls for the analysis of
result in the development of cognitive and affec-
the development of single actions. That is one
tive schemata in the subject on the other hand. The
reason why development is a genuine and crucial
specific cultural contents and rule systems consti-
dimension in many action theories (as micro-
tute both the cultural context, the external medium
process or actual genesis, as ontogenesis, and as
(Cole, 1996) in which development occurs, and
social/cultural change; see Fig. 17.1).
what is in the minds of members of a concrete cul-
3. Back in 1979, I therefore proposed
ture (D’Andrade, 1984). Most importantly:
interpreting action theories as a “theory family”
(Eckensberger, 1979) based on the potentially self- Both processes are preconditions, which are
reflective subject or agency (see p. 881). This position contextual conditions for further acts. It is this
relates to the basic issue of whether Homo sapiens dialectical interrelational process between material and
have a special position in nature, because this species ideal action contexts that is the key to understanding
is, as far as we know, the only one that can decide cultural change.”
to a certain extent not to follow natural laws in (Eckensberger, Krewer, & Kaspar, 1984, p. 99, italics LHE)
their actions but can intentionally and reflexively
We sympathized then with the work of Berger
follow cultural rules (e.g., of prudence, of social/
and Luckmann (1966), who relied extensively on
cultural conventions, morality, law, and religion)
human action to explain (or speculate about) the
as well, which (s)he also “created.” This intentional
development of society (culture). We specified:
rule following implies that although an agency is
in principle considered autonomous, actions are (1) Every human act is subject to habituation
not arbitrary. It is important that the term agency and each action solidifies into a model; (2) this
is not restricted to a single subject here, but it may habituation of actions is standardized reciprocally
also include others or even groups (Eckensberger, in the fundamental dyadic face-to-face situation
1990b, 1996b). Therefore we sometimes speak also with two actors; (3) if this standardization
of co-agencies or co-actions, which imply shared is communicated to a third member (e.g.,
goals and/or coordinated actions. socialization), this makes it possible to distinguish

ecken sberger 361


types of actors as well as types of actions and this in (variations in experiments), implying that the rela-
turn results in the formation of institutions. Thus tion of causality and finality is exactly the other way
institutions have a history, which creates them . . . around: finality is the precondition for defining
(but) the logic of institutions does not consist in its causality (von Wright, 1971). But actions cannot
external functionality, but rather consists in the way be explained by the same rational. Second, Malpass
it is reflected by their participants. and Poortinga (1986) have argued that “culture as
(Eckensberger, Krewer, & Kaspar, 1984, p. 100) the product of human actions transcends behaviour
as studied in psychology” (p. 29). I also have refuted
Similarly, White (1959) understood culture as this argument (Eckensberger, 1996a) by showing
a set of extra-somatic symbols (symbolates), which that behavior alone is too narrow an object of psy-
are ossified forms of human activities. This does not chology. Even in cognitive anthropology, culture is
mean that all historical changes are intended; they located in the heads of people (D’Andrade, 1984),
can, of course, also be unintended—an aspect that and behavior never occurs without a context.
Graumann (1996) underlined when he interpreted The course of actions is particularly relevant in
Wundt’s early ideas on historical change. So, cul- empirical contexts. Analytically, actions are divided
tural psychology does not focus on concrete cul- into action phases. The number and features of these
tures but on the general concept of culture and its action phases differ, however, according to one’s issue
relevance to psychology.6 And, as proposed, thereby of concern. Whereas Boesch (1976, 1991), in fol-
psychological and cultural concepts are intrinsically lowing Janet (Schwartz, 1951), distinguishes three
and mutually inter-connected. main action phases (beginning phase, its course,
Of course, this perspective poses a serious prob- and end), others (e.g., Heckhausen, Gollwitzer, &
lem for understanding psychology as a natural Weinert, 1997) later propose four phases (a pre-de-
science based on functional or (efficient) causal pro- cision phase, a pre-actional phase, the action phase
cesses. It was again Boesch (1971) who aptly pin- [doing], and a post-action phase) for Heckhausen’s
pointed this tension when he formulated: “It is the work on motivation. Here, the decision to act plays
dilemma of psychology that it deals as a natural sci- an important role (Heckhausen uses the meta-
ence with an object that creates history” (p. 9, trans- phor of crossing the Rubicon). We (Eckensberger
lated by LHE). It is evident that this leads to serious & Emminghaus, 1982) distinguished a total of six
(epistemological and methodical) problems, as long action phases in dealing particularly with “action
as psychology is understood as a natural science, barriers/impediments” (perception of the situa-
which basically tries to interpret events/processes in tion; attribution of the origin of a barrier, attribu-
terms of causes and/or functions. No wonder that tion of responsibility for the barrier; estimation of
this general action theoretical perspective (in my action possibilities; decision to act; post-decision).
version of 1979) was strongly criticized. Malpass and Kornadt (1982) also used six quite similar phases
Poortinga (1986), for example, argued like Popper for analyzing aggressive actions (analysis of the situ-
(1937) and Hook (1957) by basically understand- ation, activation of the aggression motive, evalua-
ing psychology as a natural (nomothetic) science tion of the action, decision to act, act, and action
and likewise by evaluating the self-reflective para- result). For a critique/refinement, see Eckensberger
digm from a mainstream perspective. Consequently, (1988). Within all these phases, there is an interplay
they first claimed that action theory concepts have between cognitive, affective (motivational), and ener-
to be “formulated in causal terms.” And, in fact, also getic aspects of the action.
some philosophers try to explain actions by inter-
preting beliefs and desires as causes of actions (e.g., Dealing With the Duality Personality
Goldmann, 1970). But there is more or less agree- and Culture
ment at present that actions cannot epistemologi- Toward a Dialectical Relation Between
cally be explained by (efficient) causes but have to be Personality and Culture
understood in terms of their reasons (cf. Habermas, The sub-branch in psychology that dealt with
1984; von Wright, 1971). Juarrero (1999) also criti- culture in the 1970s was cross-cultural research.
cizes the attempt to apply the deductive-nomolog- The International Association of Cross-Cultural
ical model to understanding actions. Additionally, Psychology (IACCP) was founded in 1972. Its
I (Eckensberger, 1996) have argued that causality members followed the experimental logic, which was
usually is empirically defined by intentional actions the methodical ideal of mainstream psychological

362 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


research at that time. Therefore, cross-cultural differ- “revolutions” because newly developed paradigms
ences were considered a consequence of an experiment are qualitatively different from or are incommen-
in nature. Consequently, culture was understood as surable with the former. The same applies to theo-
an independent variable having (a causal) influence ries, formulated on the basis of the new paradigm.
on practically all psychological constructs. Cross- Different theories can therefore not easily be evalu-
cultural psychology was thus understood primarily ated comparatively; they also cannot be evaluated
as a method (Berry, 1980; Boesch & Eckensberger, (traditionally) in terms of being right or wrong
1969; Eckensberger, 1969; Eckensberger, 1973; from this perspective but, rather, as being more or
Whiting, 1954). My own (contextualized) research less fruitful, depending on the issue of concern. It
in a foreign culture (Afghanistan) was also at first is important to note that the core of Kuhn’s argu-
undertaken from a mainstream (nomothetic) per- ment, the change of paradigms in psychology, was
spective (e.g., Eckensberger, 1968, 1972, 1973). neither followed7 by me nor by Reese and Overton
However, in the long run it resulted in critical reflec- (1970); rather, it was assumed that psychology is
tions on this mainstream approach (Eckensberger, a multiparadigmatic science. But the idea of the
1979), because I learned more about the limits than internal relationship of model, theory, and methods
possibilities of the traditional research strategies (for was maintained as well as the notion that science
a summary, see also Eckensberger & Plath, 2003) is a social process. Therefore, at first more attention
in dealing with foreign cultures. So fairly early, I was directed at the relationship/incommensurabil-
came to the conclusion that to really understand ity of paradigms, which were all evaluated accord-
the meaning of data collected in a foreign culture, ing to their fruitfulness in allowing the inclusion
one should develop a theory that not only explains of ontogeny and cultural change, and of culture
ontogeny of an individual but also culture and its into psychology in the sense that they could be
development (Eckensberger, 1979, 2003, 2010). This explained by the same theory. In the early analysis,
was in line with Riegel’s (1975) demand that devel- I proposed five paradigms that more or less covered
opmental psychology should aim at analyzing “the psychology (Eckensberger, 1979). Three paradigms
changing individual in a changing world,” but it was (quantification or multitude and extent [use of
more than that: it called for a theoretical inclusion of measurements and statistics], system theory [e.g.,
culture into psychology—particularly called for also by sociobiology], and the model of the potentially
Boesch (1991), Cole (1990), and Valsiner (1987), self-reflective individual [Boesch’s action theory])
whose biographical examination of the culture con- were added to the two Reese and Overton (1970)
cept in psychology was carefully reconstructed by distinguished (mechanistic [learning theory] and
Mey and Mruk (1998). He was probably the one organismic [Piaget’s genetic structuralism]).
who most explicitly argued that culture was not an Many of the following arguments basically start
independent variable (Valsiner, 1988). with the notion of a dualistic position. Therefore,
To check whether existing theories can meet at least a few sentences are necessary to justify this
this demand, I followed and extended the meta- decision because it is true that it became rather
theoretical perspective Reese and Overton (1970) unpopular in science for some time, particularly
introduced into developmental psychology. It was after Dennett published “Consciousness Explained”
based on Kuhn’s (1969/1970) ideas on the devel- (1991), in which he even accused the dualistic posi-
opment of science, which is well-known today (see tion of being antiscientific. A similar position is
Frezzo, 2004) but was new in those days. Kuhn held by Bhaskar (1999), who also “argued against
assumed (based on the reconstruction of physics) the dualism and splits that dominated the . . . con-
that science did not develop by a continuous pro- temporary human science”, and he proposed to look
cess of upholding or falsifying hypotheses/theories for “a third sublating position which could reconcile
but rather by a radical change in the perspective these stark polarities and oppositions, and which
(worldview) on the subject matter of the theory. could situate the two extremes as special cases of the
The underlying worldviews in theories define the more general subliming position,” thereby propos-
qualitative features of theory development as well ing in principle a dialectic (Hegelian) procedure.
as the questions that can be asked and the meth- Yet, I argue that this does not mean that dualities
ods that can be applied (exemplars). The scientific are generally not a fruitful starting point in science. It
community follows this paradigm. Kuhn there- may be sufficient in the present context only to refer
fore claimed that science evolves by discontinuous to the detailed discussion of psycho-physical duality

ecken sberger 363


by Meixner (2004). He has even distinguished 11 • The physical perspective: Most historical
arguments for dualism (pp. 122–158). Beyond that, reconstructions of psychology underline that
the four perspectives in psychology later proposed physics was the most attractive model for this
by Eckensberger (2002a, 2008a, 2009) were com- emerging new science at the end of the nineteenth
patible with Rychlak’s (1993) four “groundings” of century. This was strongly supported by Kurt
Physikos, Bios, Socius, and Logos in psychology. Lewin (1931), who, in a classical paper entitled
So it seems to be quite productive to start with “The Transition from an Aristotelian to the
the assumption of dualities and to discuss their inter- Galileian Worldview in Biology and Psychology,”
relationship by some general principles but by at the called explicitly for defining psychology as a
same time also keeping them (see p. 930). Beyond natural science and choosing physics as the proper
all efforts either to overcome dichotomies by reduc- model for psychology. To represent this perspective,
tionism or incommensurability and complementation he chose the Italian mathematician, physicist, and
(Eckensberger, 2002a) or to eradicate them by either astronomer Galileo Galilei (1564–1643), who not
subsuming one dichotomy under the other by for- only came into conflict with the church because
mulating a “more general sublimining position” he argued for a “heliocentric” worldview but also
one easily runs into the danger of getting a solu- discovered the law of “free fall.” Reese and Overton
tion that in a way is ontologically empty. Quantum (1970) named it the “mechanistic worldview”
Theory may serve as an example that demonstrates (e.g., Learning Theory). It represents the homo
the attractiveness but also difficulties and dangers mechanicus.
in that approach. Quantum Theory seems only to • The biological perspective: In 1980 Norbert
work as a regulative idea but not in the reality of Bischof, in his inaugural address at the German
science (Görnitz & Görnitz, 2010). I will return to Congress of Psychology in Zürich, agreed that
this central problem later. psychology is and should be a natural science, but
Figure 17.1 illustrates particularly the four he accused Lewin of having selected the wrong
perspectives distinguished as well as their inter- science to overcome Aristotelian thinking. Instead
relationship. of physics, he proposed biology as the proper

Teleologic/Self-reflective Cultural/Historical/Symbolic
reasons (Proximate) Reasons (ultimate)
Individual/Supra-individual
DESCARTES

VICO

Realm of REASONS

ic
Hu
man bol
Sym

Mental/ Culture/
Material Ani Nature
l mal
eria
Mat
DARWIN

Realm of CAUSES
GALILEO

Human = Part of nature

Mechanistic/Organismic
Material/Life
Physical/Causal Biological/Teleonomic/
(Proximate) Functional/Causal(Ultimate)

Figure 17.1 Distinguishing the four perspectives in psychology and their inter-relationship.
(after Eckensberger 2010a, 2010b, 2011b)

364 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


model for psychology and used Charles Darwin mathematician, and natural scientist René
(1809–1882) as the key thinker, who published Descartes (1596–1650), who counts as founder of
the “Origin of Species” in 1859, in which he modern rationalism (Cartesianism), was proposed
claimed that the existence of different species was to represent this perspective on humans. He is
not the act of God’s creation but the result of a famous for his dictum “cogito ergo sum” (“I think,
long process of natural selection. Interestingly, therefore I am”). Clearly in the present context,
Bischof did not refer to the discussion of Reese his dictum is used because it underlines the
and Overton (1970). But both perspectives importance of the principal ability of humans
represented a natural science perspective, both of to be self-conscious or self-reflective. Although it is
its representatives were involved in conflicts with argued (Fischer, 2003) that the famous cogito ergo
the church, because their theories and empirical sum is logically not compelling because thinking
work contradicted the worldview presented in as such is arbitrary in content like meditating or
the Bible, and therefore both contributed to the walking. The reflective action should therefore
Enlightenment (e.g., the organismic worldview/ not be thinking but doubting. Although one can
Piaget, sociobiology; Eckensberger 1979, 2002a). doubt everything, one can not doubt that one
It represents the homo sapiens sapiens. doubts. It is interesting that according to Fischer
• The socio-cultural perspective: In an earlier (2003), Descartes first used the phrase “dubito ergo
paper (Eckensberger, 1979), culture was used sum” (“I doubt, therefore I am”). It is claimed that
simply as a concept that had to be integrated under a dialectic perspective, only this self-reflected
into psychology. Later (Eckensberger, 2002) it negation leads to a logically compelling new stage
seemed justified or useful, even necessary, to of self-assurance. This topic also led Descartes
distinguish a cultural perspective in psychology as to distinguish two different substances: material
a perspective in its own right. This resulted from substance (res extensa) and mental substance (res
the conceptualization of a (sub)discipline cultural cogitans). He is therefore often referred to as one
psychology and the emergence of culture-bound of the founders of the duality of mind and matter
indigenous psychologies, which became salient in the (thus called “Cartesian dualism”). In any case,
late twentieth century, although their roots go back Descartes is responsible for an understanding
to the foundation of modern psychology at the end of human nature as radically reflexive, meaning
of the nineteenth century (Eckensberger, 2010a). that we are not only self-conscious in the usual
Ng & Liu (2002) have even spoken of a cultural sense but uniquely conscious of the fact that we
revolution in psychology. I have chosen Giovanni are able to reflect on the contents of our own
Battista Vico (1668–1744) as a representative of minds (Taylor, 1989). (Example: action theories,
this perspective, because he is considered one of Eckensberger, 1979, 2002a). It represents the homo
the first to have developed a systematic methodic interpretans,
approach to history. He called for an analysis of
the “birth” and development of human societies Figure 17.1 summarizes not only the four mod-
and institutions; proposed the study of language, els of man relevant to psychology but also distin-
myths, and tradition; and underlined the symbolic guishes the general relationships between the four
meaning of words. For Vico history was already a perspectives, particularly highlighting the classical
source to help understand humans because humans splits or incommensurability based on them. The
are the ones who create history and form human upper and lower parts represent the two cultures,
rule systems. This is in line, for example, with the differentiated by Snow (1959/1963) in his famous
anthropologist Geertz (1973), who understood Cambridge lecture (see also Frezzo, 2004). Whereas
culture as “a set of control mechanisms—plans the human/cultural perspectives basically deal with
recipes, rules, and instructions for governing created personal and cultural rules and therefore con-
behaviour” (p. 44). This understanding also stitute the “realm of reasons,” the natural sciences
defined the centrality of morality (our second perspective is based on natural laws and the “realm
concern) as one important rule system of culture. of causes”. Mack (2006), with reference to Dilthey
It represents the homo symbolicus (Cassirer, (1894/1968), recently distinguished between an
1921/1922; Deacon, 1997). “e- and u-type of thinking” (e is based on expla-
• The perspective of the potentially self- nation, and u is based on understanding). Within
reflective human being: The French philosopher, these two domains, in the realm of reasons the split

ecken sberger 365


between individual (agency) and supra-individual The earlier (Eckensberger, 1979) as well as the
(aggregate/culture) objects is evident, and in the much more sophisticated later analysis (Eckensberger,
realm of causes the difference between a mecha- 2002) showed that if the inclusion of ontogeny
nistic and an organismic worldview is illustrated. and cultural change as well as the interpretation
Additionally, one can see the splits between nature of agency and culture within the same theoretical
and culture but also the Cartesian split of mind and framework is aimed at, then only the paradigm of
matter. It is evident as well that the ontologies of the potentially self-reflective subject seems to meet
the perspectives themselves differ: material (physi- both criteria, when normative concepts (like moral-
cal) versus symbolic (cultural) and the basic distinc- ity) and the meaning of culture and cultural rules
tion between human (self-reflective) versus animal are of interest. In that early paper, not only the rela-
(biological). tion between person and culture was called a dia-
Because the perspectives themselves are under- lectical one because they were interpenetrating each
stood as ways of looking at the world, they are other, but the human action was located between the
considered epistemological. Therefore one can, at subject (agency) and culture, thereby qualifying what
present, not argue that they represent the sciences dialectical meant in this duality. Dialectics in this
of physics, biology, psychology, and anthropol- sense means that neither exists without the other.
ogy/sociology, which are primarily or historically It has been proposed that human action mediates
defined by ontological categories, like the three between the individual and culture as a synthesis of
worlds distinguished by Popper (1977). Rather, that duality.
the productivity of the argument is that one can, in In doing so, I also chose the intentional and
principle, take all perspectives in each science (see, potentially self-reflective agency as the model of man,
in detail, Eckensberger, 2002). Whereas in earlier which is fundamental to the psychological under-
times ontology was considered to lead epistemol- standing of the subject as agency (Eckensberger,
ogy in theory construction (because in empiricism 1979). This qualification of the human being is
the results of research corrected theories), nowa- nowadays called “the human kind”9 (Danzinger,
days, with the increasing relevance of constructiv- 1997; Martin, Sugarman, & Thompson, 2003;
ism (Mahoney, 2004), epistemology leads ontology Martin & Sugarman, 2009). Also Smedslund
in a way, because theories determine data collection (2009) has recently elaborated a similar model of
to a great extent and therefore the data themselves. man that is unique to humans. So intentionality and
One can even argue that ontology and epistemology self-reflectivity were considered the characteristics
are no longer separated (Gülerce, 1997). As will be of the model of man, which I later (Eckensberger,
seen, however, in the following a contextual con- 1993) called the “homo interpretans.” Differing
structivism (Eckensberger, 1990) is advocated. from Baltes and Nesselroade (1977), I considered
dialectics methodologically as equivalent to causal-
Personality and Culture: Action ity and functionality in the mechanistic and organ-
Theory in Dialectics ismic paradigm (see p. 868) inter-relating culture
In the early paper on the integration of culture and personality (agency) and not as a metaphor or
into psychology, I argued (Eckensberger, 1979) paradigm.
along the lines of the transformative method for- The relationship of the potentially self-reflective
mulated by the post Hegelian Ludwig Feuerbach and socio-cultural perspective, just elaborated, is
(1804–1872) and described by Buss (1979). illustrated in Figure 17.2 by using human action as
Feuerbach’s method was developed within his the genuine unit of psychology that mediates agency
critical thinking about religion.8 It basically entails and culture in both directions and thereby synthe-
reversing the subject and object of a statement, sizes them. The ring structure (Leontiev, 1977) of
thereby hoping to get closer to truth. I basically Russian activity theory is based on the same the-
used the transformative method in saying that the oretical model (Eckensberger, 1995), as is Haste’s
person is shaped by culture and culture is shaped by (2008) theoretical position, which also relies very
persons. So this duality was framed as a dialectical much on Vygotsky.
relation and it attempted to integrate person and The interpretation of agency as a potentially self-
culture. Similarly, Bandura (1997) claimed later reflective being who, in addition to reconstructing
that “people are both producers and products of the world (homo interpretans) and constructing
social systems” (p. 6). culture (homo faber) to a certain extent, also “creates

366 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


him- or herself ” (thinks of the person he or she meaning people attribute to a situation, and the
wants to be, develops norms about right and wrong, external action field or cultural factors include exist-
which more or less implies upholding one’s charac- ing shared cultural concepts such as shared interpre-
ter) calls for the integration of individual as well as tational patterns, scripts, and expectations. It is this
cultural rule and interpretation systems (Eckensberger, conceptual status of culture and human action that
1993a, 1993b, 1996a, 1996b). Humans create justifies the term culture-inclusive action theory.10
and shape culture (material, symbolic artifacts This approach not only results in construc-
and social rules), which are in turn preconditions tions and co-constructions of cognitive and affective
for their actions. This is why these conditions are (evaluative) schemata in subjects but also implies
always saturated with teleological structures. This results in symbolic, material, and social structures in
perspective also implies that they can be altered to a culture, which in turn form canalizing constraints
varying degrees. As mentioned, an action theory (ranging from inhibitions to taboos) and/or support-
that includes culture quite naturally implies a genu- ing encouragements or selective pressures (ranging
inely developmental perspective, because the inter- from support to duties) given in the cultural context
relationship between culture and individual is based or action possibilities (Eckensberger, 1990a, 1990b;
on intentional processes over time. But development Martin & Sugarman, 1999), which also become part
is conceptualized on different levels: On the phy- of the schemata. Also Poortinga recently (e.g., 2002,
logenetic level (phylogeny), the individual level p. 327) formulated this model by distinguishing
(ontogeny), the action level (actual genesis or micro constraints and affordances quite in detail, although
process), and the cultural level (history and cultural he does so in a different paradigmatic context. Yet
change). These developmental levels are illustrated in the following the term constraints is kept and
in Figure 17.2. the term “affordances” is “adopted” because of its
By placing action (co-action) between the sub- semantic convenience. But these aspects of culture
ject (agency) and the context (culture), two action are understood here as parts of a dialectical rela-
fields are formed: the external and internal action tion of emergence and selection: The basic idea is that
field (Boesch, 1976, 1991; Eckensberger, 1990a, culture emerges on the basis of human actions and
1990b). They overlap and are interconnected by reflections (upward emergence) but also has a selec-
the action, which is part of both, and which there- tive function/effect via actions on humans and their
fore acts as a bridge (or a pivot) between them. The development, which are called “downward selection”
internal action field encompasses the subjective in analogy of upward and downward causation in11 in

Ontogenesis Actual genesis Cultural change

Internal action field Eternal action field

Production
Selection Creation/control
reflection communication
Action
Actor/Agency performance culture
competencies Co-action
Construction Canalizing constraints
Co-construction Offers, Possibilities
Re-construction medium
(meaning)

Phylogenetic conditions = Cultural history =


enabling conditions enabling conditions
human capacities human resources

Figure 17.2 Different kinds and levels of development in an action theory framework.
(after Eckensberger, 1979, 1990a, 1990b, 2010a, 2010b).

ecken sberger 367


Complex System Theory (Campbell, 1974; Juarrero, standards and external (cultural) rules are criti-
1999). These terms are avoided here; rather, the cal attributes of action theory. It is postulated that
terms upward emergence and downward selection are both are inter-connected in this perspective by
preferred because the former still suggest a reduc- the culture-inclusive action. In doing so, one also
tionist worldview, which is, however, not intended integrates Shweder’s (1980) proposal of cultural
(Murphy, 2010, suggests downwards constraints, but rules and research on the domain specificity of
we want also to include downward affordances from human cognitions (differentiated by authors like
the culture point of view, hence we use the more Nucci, Smetana, and Turiel; for an overview, see
comprehensive term downward selection). But the Eckensberger & Plath, 2006a), which constitute
basic dialectical ideas formulated in my early writ- individual standards. They both shape the nor-
ings are quite compatible with this terminology, mative frameworks for actions in the internal and
which we therefore consider as being more precise external action fields (Eckensberger, 1990, 1993,
than just interpenetration or interdependence. But 1996a, 1996b; Eckensberger, Kapadia, & Wagels,
we are also aware of the fact that both (emergence 2000). It is claimed that both emerge from the same
and downward causation) are not fully agreed upon type of action, although culture is ontologically
(Davies, 2006; Stephan, 2002). A detailed discus- often understood as a supra-individual phenome-
sion of this discourse is, however, beyond the scope non (White, 1959), it is saturated with intentional-
of this chapter. We will come back to this terminol- ity. Things are, however, not only more complex but
ogy and its usefulness later. also more productive, because by partly following
Janet (Schwartz, 1951) and Boesch (1976, 1991)
Cultural Psychology different action levels are distinguished. Not only
In trying to integrate these concepts, one simul- primary and secondary actions (Janet, Boesch) are
taneously ends up understanding psychology in gen- differentiated but also tertiary actions (Eckensberger,
eral as cultural psychology, a concept that has regained 1990, 1996, 2003, 2006a, 2010a).
importance in the last decades. As mentioned, this These levels come about because it is quite
new branch of psychology (better: renewed branch; normal that barriers/impediments occur in every
see Stern, 1920) is partly rooted in the socio- action. One can almost regard them as the condi-
historical school (e.g., Branco & Valsiner, 1997; tion for or initiator of development (see particu-
Cole, 1990, 1996; Ratner, 1991; Rogoff, 1990; larly Boesch, 1976; Eckensberger & Emminghaus,
Valsiner, 1987; Wertsch, 1985 and Holzkamp12 1982; Eckensberger, Breit, & Döring, 1999; Martin
in Germany), and it is partly based on Piaget and & Sugarman, 1999; Ulich, 1987). These can only
Janet and even Lewin (Boesch, 1976, 1991; Bruner, be experienced, however, because every action
1990; Eckensberger, 1979, 1990, 1995, 2002; already implies normative frameworks, which serve
Greenfield & Bruner, 1966; Krewer, 1990; Straub, as standards14 for determining whether or not the
2006) as well as on some other traditions (Allesch & action was adequately accomplished. These barriers
Billmann-Mahecha, 1990; Gergen, Gülerce, Misra, lead to reflections, which by necessity occur from
& Lock, 1996; Price-Williams, 1980; Shweder, a higher level, which itself emerges through this very
1990). So I have already argued for some time that reflection. This is the basic idea of Piaget’s (1970)
action theory is not just the most adequate theory proposal of the notion of reflective abstraction,15
for the perspective of the potential self-reflective which is a genuinely dialectic operation because the
agency but for cultural psychology in general, pre- same phenomenon (the action) is at first the sub-
cisely because it allows one to synthesize agency and ject (“in operation”) and then is reflected on as an
culture in time (ontogeny and history).13 object (see Kesselring, 1982; Vuyk, 1981). Through
After having examined the role of action theory this operation, existing structures (levels/stages) are
in the dialectic inter-relation of agency and culture, transformed into new ones. So the same phenom-
the role of dialectics in Culture-Inclusive Action ena are at first structure and then content, which is
Theory will now be elaborated. logically contradictory but developmentally plausi-
ble. But the three action levels do not only emerge
Person and Culture: Dialectics in Action through abstractive reflections (which could end up
Theory—Action Levels in an infinite regression), but they additionally have
It has been argued that the potential self-reflec- different orientations: primary actions are world-
tivity of the agency as well as internal (individual) oriented, secondary actions are action–oriented, and

368 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


third-level actions are agency-oriented. This is the Piagetian model of an active subject is still consid-
reason that action barriers are of utmost importance ered productive, but it has to be complemented by
for the emergence and development of the action cultural content that appears to become ever more
levels (this issue will be taken up in discussing moral important as the concept of standard increases in
development). However, it is again assumed addi- complexity in the course of development, as research
tionally that new action levels do not just emerge on Piaget’s and Kohlberg’s theory shows (e.g., Dasen
through the process of reflective abstraction (upward & Heron, 1981; Eckensberger & Zimba, 1997,
emergence) but that these influence the lower level Snarey, 1985). There is an urgent need to comple-
via downward selection processes (constraints and ment Piagetian developmental concepts with more
supports) rather than by causal processes. But a pos- content-orientated concepts of development. This is
sible misunderstanding has to be clarified: As in the aimed at particularly by Boesch’s concept of “sec-
case of agency (see p. 873), the reflective abstraction ondary structures” (see p. 896, but it is also called for
should not be understood as being “firmly fixed on by Krishnan’s (1999) proposal to complement it by
the organism side” and therefore being “fundamen- research in the tradition of socialization processes.
tally a-cultural” (Glick, 1985, p. 106). To clarify this These should particularly include cultural rituals of
point, I tried (Eckensberger, 1990b, p. 48) to apply various kinds that are all normative in character.
this term to co-constructions by proposing a reflec- In the following, the action levels will be described
tive understanding and co-reflective understanding, according to their implied structure, interpretation,
thereby making it cultural or social. and experience of standards as well as their concomi-
This developmental principle is proposed for tant emotional processes. Although the methodologi-
both ontogeny (particularly the third level emerges cal status of the action levels is primarily theoretical
later in development) as well as for actual gen- they also represent a productive framework for empir-
esis. Although the action levels are formed in this ical work. They provide a psychologically useful
sequence, it is assumed that the older one gets, the scheme for organizing and inter-relating a variety of
more of these levels are more or less simultaneously psychological concepts; they therefore also enable links
active. In general, it depends on the number and to concepts that have not necessarily been defined
kind of barriers that occur in an action. The genesis originally in an action theory perspective. This is not
of the levels is bottom-up, but the interpretation only true for many cognitive constructs but also for
process has to be top-down because all levels are motivational and emotional processes and their inter-
necessary to understand a human primary action. relation (like motivation, emotion, control theories,
To understand a simple act (primary action like or self-concepts; see Bettingen, Eckensberger, Gaul,
writing a chapter), one has to know the immediate Krewer, Madert, & Prowald, 1993). The reflected
intentions of the writer (to make a particular point action levels were particularly productive in the con-
within the time span of the deadline given) but also textualized research on regional culture (Krewer 1990;
the standards or conventions (secondary actions) in Krewer, Momper, & Eckensberger,1984; Krewer
which the chapter has to be written (length, APA & Eckensberger, 1990), on moral development in
format) as well as the fact that the writer is aware of the context of education (Breit & Eckensberger,
deviating from some other theoretical positions. In 2004a, 2004b; Eckensberger & Breit, 2003, 2006;
addition, this may be essential for the self-identity Eckensberger, 2002b; Maslowski, Breit, Eckensberger,
as a psychologist, and so forth. (tertiary actions). & Scheerens, 2009; Eckensberger & Chang, in press)
Therefore CIAT not only helps to understand the pro- and ecological issues (Eckensberger, Döring, & Breit,
posed dialectics between the subject/agency and culture, 2001; Döring, Eckensberger, Breit, & Huppert, 2008;
but dialectics also help to understand assumed relations Eckensberger, 1993; Eckensberger, Kasper, Nieder,
within action levels. Schirk, & Sieloff, 1990; Eckensberger Sieloff, Kasper,
The standards themselves that are the precondi- Schirk, & Nieder, 1992), and particularly on cop-
tions to experiencing barriers are not only developed ing with cancer (Eckensberger & Kreibich-Fischer,
during internal processes in ontogenesis, but the 1993, 1994; Eckensberger, Kreibich-Fischer, Gaul, &
experiences of barriers also take place in a specific Schnurre, 1990, Eckensberger, Kreibich-Fischer Gaul,
cultural context, in which different expectations— Bettingen, Madert, & Prowald, 1993). But these
technical, social, or belief systems (customs, logical, studies also fed back into further developments of the
and ethical principles)—set the stage (Eckensberger, theoretical structure of the CIAT: Figure 17.3 presents
1979, 1985, 1996, 2003, 2010a, 2010b). Thus the an overview of the three action levels distinguished.

ecken sberger 369


Secondary Structuration Secondary Structuration
Primary Structuration Primary Structuration
SUBJECTIVATION OBJECTIVATION OBJECTIFICATION SYMBOLIZATION
Production
Ideal self Self concept Self-reflection Tertiary action Biographical
Existential Understanding Philosophical
Autonomy Co-reflection Agency-orientated Religious
concepts –Maintenance of Availability principles
“Relatedness” Ideological
(meaning of life, pers. standards
Anchor of Canalization Roles
morality, religion) –Devel. of identity
identity Co-agency Construction “Personhood”
–Self presentation Presentation Symbolism
Co-construction

RESISTANCE
BARRIER

Production
PHANTASMS Reflection Secondary a. Cultural (shared)
Normative systems Explanation MYTHS
of reference Regulation Action- patterns of
Security Availability
Co-regulation (growth,
Control (logical, technical, orientated interpretation
Canalization prosperity,
Autonomy ethical, esthetical, –removing
Construction Communication Rule systems health, harmony)
Health scientific)
Co-construction obstacles (science, law,
Complex emotions Consensus /
Good life Re-construction communicative Compromise conventions... )
EXPERIENCE
BARRIER

Production
Functional Goal systems Reflection
Primary action Nature / body Functional
Explanation
potentiality Basic motives Selection Situational
Pers. Preferences “World”orientated Availability
Construction –instrumental Canalization Social rites Social
Subjective self Primary emotions
Figurative schemata Co-construction –understanding
Communication Symbolism
Attachment Re-construction Understanding
Material culture

AGENCY ACTION CONTEXT

Internal Field of Action


External Field of Action

Figure 17.3 Three action levels: primary (world-oriented), secondary (action-oriented), and tertiary (agency-oriented) actions.
(after Eckensberger, 1989, 1990a, 1990b, 2010a, 2010b).

Primary (World-Oriented) Actions actions are directed at the social world—that is, at
Analytically, the basic structure of instrumental another agency B or group, they cannot (causally)
primary action aims at some effect (to bring some- bring something about in B, but it is B who has to
thing about). It is assumed that the means applied to decide to follow or not follow a request/demand by
carry out an action follow rationally (not causally) from agency A, which implies that B also has to under-
the intentions—that is, they can be justified or made stand A’s intentions. So A has to coordinate with
plausible by the agency. They are chosen on the basis B’s intentions, means, and even with evaluations
of finality (to reach a goal). If they are carried out, the of consequences. Thus agency B’s intentions have
result is some change, and this change leads causally to be understood (interpreted) by agency A. This
to some consequences. Those consequences of actions presupposes a communicative attitude (Habermas,
that represent the goal are intended, others are unin- 1984). This type of action is consequently called a
tended (to let fresh air into a room [intended goal], communicative action. If this orientation not only
one opens the window [does something], after hav- implies understanding B, but also respecting B’s
ing opened the window it is open [result] and lets intentions, means, and consequences, then this is
[causally] fresh air in [intended], but the room may clearly a moral action. Interestingly, in non-West-
become cold [unintended]; see Fig. 17.4). ern philosophies/religions (Taoism, Confucianism
It is useful, however, to at least differentiate two Hinduism, Buddhism17) this adaptive attitude and
types of primary actions.16 If directed at the physi- respect for the non-A is extended to include the
cal/material world, and aimed at bringing about plant and animal world or even the cosmos. So one
some effect (also “letting things [intentionally] can distinguish between two action types that aim
happen,” von Wright, 1971) or suppressing some at A’s control of the environment (instrumental and
effect, they are called instrumental actions. But if strategic) and two action types, in which A aims at

370 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


intentionally to bring something about,
to prevent something from happening,
to allow something to happen
EXPLANATION

intentional
reflects final implicative causal intended
Agency
goal means results consequences
A
U reflects functional not intended
N goal/coordination
D effect oriented: natural environment
E final
R means/communication
S
T
A logical/implicative intentionally to ask, urge, to allow somebody to
N encourage, invite someone act
result/communicated
D
I communicative
N understanding social environment
norm oriented action
G (goal A)

intentional intended
reflects final implicative causal
Agency
B goal means results consequences
not intended
functional

Figure 17.4 Two main action types: instrumental- and social/norm-oriented action
(after Eckensberger, 1993, 1996, 2010b; Eckensberger & Plath, 2006).

harmonizing with the environment (communicative status is primarily analytical again. So, agency is
and adaptive actions; Sinha, 1996). characterized by four relations: by being (1) reflex-
This clearly shows that understanding does not ively tied to one’s goal in the physical environment;
refer to causes but to reasons. So, basically under- (2) orientated at the social world by understand-
standing or communicative actions are appropriate ing the actions of others; (3) self-reflexively related
for the social world. to itself (the “Innenwelt” or “inner world”); and
This distinction, however, also depends on the (4) it is related contemplatively to some transcen-
relationship between the agencies A/B as defined dental or ultimate phenomenon (see Fig. 17.4).
in the cultural context. If there is no mutual In empirical research, these action types enable a
respect (e.g., if agency B is a servant who has to methodical distinction that is quite productive for
follow orders), then this can lead to an instrumen- the analysis of data (see Bettingen, Eckensberger,
tal interpretation of agency B by agency A, called Gaul, Krewer, Madert, & Prowald, 1993, for a
a strategic action by Habermas (1984). In other manual of data on cancer patients; Eckensberger,
words, agency A interprets B’s behavior as some- Karpadia, & Wagels, 2000, for rules in marriage
thing caused by the order, like a natural law with- in India). Empirically these two action types often
out any possibility of deciding not to do it (B has occur simultaneously (e.g., if somebody asks some-
to do it). This means that agency A treats agency B one for help), particularly in early childhood, when
as if (s)he were a part of nature that is governed by the physical world and the social world are not totally
causal laws. But the reverse can also occur: a person distinct yet. In developmental psychology, particu-
may speak to his car that is broken and ask it not to larly in early childhood, the concept of theory of
fail him but to make it for some more miles. Then, mind (TOM) is highly relevant to the development
in a way, the person treats the car as part of the of social cognition. Premack and Woodruff formu-
social world. Hence, the world is constituted by the lated this concept in 1978 for chimpanzees, to study
application of the respective action types. Whether the question of whether chimpanzees understand
or not something is part of the social or natural/ intentions or actions of another chimpanzee (see
causal world is thus a matter of interpretation on also Boesch18 & Tomasello, 1998). This concept not
the part of the agency. Clearly the methodological only triggered much research with primates other

ecken sberger 371


than humans but also became a broad research pro- can also be embedded in a larger set of goals (e.g., to
gram for human infants (understanding intentions get ahead in a career). These hierarchies are particu-
of another person is clearly an operation that is the larly elaborated in instrumental contexts, but they
precondition of primary communicative actions; are also relevant to communicative actions.
for more detailed information, see Eckensberger & The following discussion makes use of Boesch’s
Plath, 2006a). (1976, 1991) distinction of primary structurations,
Actions (goals and means) are selected by the which are cognitive, and secondary structurations,
agency from all possible actions on the basis of which represent affective structures/schemata. Yet
their personal preferences, called personal con- again this distinction is primarily analytical. But in
cerns in social cognition (proposed particularly fact the issue of how cognition and affect interact
by Nucci and Smetana; for detailed references, see or merge is probably more important. He presumes
Eckensberger & Plath, 2006a). Primary actions that an action (he usually refers to instrumental
form schemata (standards) of technical, logical, and actions) has two components: first, the instrumental
(instrumental) action competence as well as social component usually studied (e.g., one uses a ham-
competencies (social actions). Additionally, they are mer to drive a nail into the wall) and second, the
based on content knowledge/facts (what effects can subjective functional component. Here, Boesch
be produced) as well as the effectiveness of means (1976, 1991) applies Lewin’s (1951) concept of
(how can they be produced). So in primary actions, valence to action elements. Hammering may also
standards exist in preferences of goal and means and, be fun—one can let off steam or be proud of being
of course, in the expectation of action outcomes. able to hammer successfully. Therefore, Boesch pro-
Although people relate directly to their nonsocial, poses that action results (nail in the wall) lead to
material, or natural surrounding, this process also two simultaneous feedbacks: one—like in Piaget’s
takes place in a cultural context and/or together with theory—is descriptive and leads to cognitive structures
other subjects. Writing, for example, is inextricably (schemata, formal condensations of similar actions),
linked to the script that comes with a language— which represent primary structurations and there-
Latin letters differ strikingly from Hindu scripts, fore an objectivation of the action in the agency and
both diverge from Arabic ones, and they are all of material consequences of actions in the real world
totally different from Chinese characters. Thus, the (culture), which he calls “objectification” (Boesch,
cultural context already provides shared schemas of 1991). The other form of feedback is evaluative and
writing, including the semantic meanings that refer leads to affective structures (secondary structurations).
to the world. On the one hand, these schemas serve They are basically threefold: At this point, he talks
as a sort of template for individual and collective about the subject’s functional potentiality, which is
experience; on the other hand, humans themselves the positive valence for the agency itself. Second, a
constructed and modified them in the course of his- goal valence is also established, and finally the action
tory or, rather, cultural history (upward emergence). means (hammer)19 acquires an object valence and
They therefore represent the cultural resources (cf. thus an idiosyncratic meaning for the subject, a pro-
Fig. 17.2) individuals can rely on or choose from cess called subjectivation. However, at the same time,
(fashion, rationality, logic, technology, and econ- these valences virtually symbolize the action and the
omy and their implied standards), which again situation, a process that is therefore called symbol-
form the “downward selection” processes of cana- ization. This topic of personal meanings (valences)
lizing constraints and affordances (Eckensberger, of objects is notoriously undervalued in psychology,
1993a, 1993b, 1995, 1996a, 1996b, 2008a, 2010a, because of its more or less exclusive focus on general
2010b). laws and principles. Not surprisingly, suppositions
There is considerable agreement among research- in this domain are still rudimentary and have to be
ers that empirically actions do not just have one goal developed in more detail in future. But to me the
but many. They can be seen as forming a chain or a secondary structurations and its implications are the
hierarchy. To write an article may have the goal of core of Boesch’s Symbolic Action Theory (1991),
understanding and describing a particular problem and they are probably his most important and
and may be considered part of a primary action. unique contribution to the field.
Writing individual characters on paper may be It is evident that these secondary structura-
taken as subaction or elements of an action (called tions are derived from a depth-psychological body
actemes by Boesch, 1991). Yet, writing the article of thought, which is the second source of Boesch’s

372 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


theory besides Piaget (see particularly Simão’s [2002] idiosyncratic symbolic meaning for an agency and
comparison between Boesch, Freud, and Piaget). through which the affective core of the agency itself
Therefore, it is also evident that their empirical con- is also developed. This phenomenon is classically
firmation presupposes some psycho-analytical com- explained in psychology by the concept/theory
petence and should be done cautiously and checked of attachment (e.g., Bowlby, 1969; Ainsworth,
particularly by the inter-rater reliability of competent Blehar, Waters, & Wall, 1978),21 which has explicit
raters. Boesch’s examples mostly refer to successful, roots in phylogeny but also in psycho-analysis.
positively experienced actions, which are also emo- I have speculated how attachment to a specific per-
tionally balanced and imply emotions of joy and son can also be reconstructed in terms of action
triumph (pride). Eckensberger and Emminghaus theory. Since the beginnings of depth-psychology
(1982) and Eckensberger and Kreibich-Fischer in the nineteenth century, the empirical status of
(1993) called these emotions, which are closely hypotheses on the dynamics of early child devel-
related to the flow-concept (Csikszentmihalyi, opment and mothering has changed dramatically.
2000), emotions of fit between the expectancies of This can be credited to researchers like Beebe and
the course of action and action experiences (internal Lachmann (1994) and Stern (1985, 1995), who all
equilibrium). But again it is productive to follow have a depth psychological background, as well as
Boesch by assuming that actions are also affectively Trevarthen (1993), who is a child psychologist with
structured and lead to individual superordinate a biological/systemic approach. Their research and
affectively structured goal systems of actions, which theorizing has focused on early child–mother inter-
Boesch calls phantasms. These are not only affective actions. They have developed concepts, which can
but also content-oriented normative frameworks. be understood as aspects of secondary structurations
On the first action level, they include notions of in early communicative actions. First, all of them
functional potentiality, which means the feeling do not see the child in isolation; rather, all com-
of being the cause of some event, which not only municative principles are mutual between a care-
forms the basis for a subjective self but also for the giver and a baby. Second, they focus on the course
subjective valence of places and objects. Therefore, of the communicative activity (temporal feeling
this concept goes beyond the concept of self-efficacy shapes; Stern, 1995). Third, they integrate cogni-
that Bandura (1997) coined. tive and evaluative (emotional) aspects of the pro-
But Boesch’s (as well as Bandura’s) proposals cesses. The “schema of being with” (Stern, 1995),
primarily relate to instrumental actions because or interpersonal timing as matching and being
his analysis of subject–world relations primarily matched (Beebe & Lachmann, 1994), or the term
relates to subject–object relations, which are not affect attunement (Stern, 1985) between a child and
communicative/normative but can be interpreted a mother may serve as examples. Fourth, they study
as being instrumental/strategical. Therefore, Simão children before they are able to speak, beginning
(2001, p. 487) tried to add interaction to Boesch’s shortly after birth. Yet they interpret early gestures
theory, by treating Boesch’s object as a subject and mimicking as communication (Trevathen
(p. 488). But in a way, through this substitution, [1993] speaks of proto-conversation). At pres-
she remains on the level of instrumental co-actions: ent, the early proto-conversations on the basis of
coordination and cooperation with others (p. 490). gestures—particularly pointing—are interpreted as
Only the normative coordination of actions for the the basis for communication and also as founda-
benefit of (all) others would imply true interac- tional for the uniqueness of humans as a species,
tions and fall into the moral domain. This leads to because great apes generally fail to do that (Janik &
my research on morality (which particularly in the Zuberbuehler, 2009; Tomasello, 2001; Tomasello,
beginnings focuses primarily on primary structura- Call, & Hare, 2003; Tomasello, Carpenter, &
tions) by distinguishing different barriers and reac- Liszkowski, 2007).
tions to barriers and by reconstructing Kohlberg’s These mutual communication processes in a
moral theory by action theoretical terms20. I have close relationship not only reduce negative emo-
also argued in two contexts (Eckensberger, 2001b, tions (prominent in attachment theory) but also
2007b) that, to increase the fruitfulness of Boesch’s maximize positive feelings, which represent happi-
concept of the secondary structurations, its gen- ness or mutual fit of emotions (not just security),
eral idea, should also be applied to communica- if the attunement/mutual regulation of interaction
tive actions, in which other persons obtain their rhythms works. So the constructed schemata are not

ecken sberger 373


only cognitive but also evaluative and should lead to emotion is anger, wrath, or fear and one adequate
attributing a valence to a particular person within an regulation is to remove the problem. But they can
interaction in a situation. also be social; then the standard is social functioning
Of course, emotions that accompany actions (an unfulfilled expectancy concerning individual or
after early childhood can also be positive or negative, conventional behavior of the social support system
and they occur in different phases of the action. It is of the family, the staff of the hospital, or doctors),
interesting in this context that positive emotions are these barriers are called an interpersonal conflict or
mainly characterized as happiness and being satis- disagreement, and the accompanying emotion is
fied, but they are not as differentiated in language as embarrassment, shame, rage, or disappointment.22 The
negative ones (see also Smedslund, 1988). adequate regulation is conflict solution or communi-
cation. In the domain of logic, the standard is consis-
SECONDARY ACTIONS: ACTOR-ORIENTED tency, the barrier is contradiction, and the emerging
As mentioned, during the course of primary emotion is insecurity. The adequate solution is
actions, almost inevitably obstacles or barriers occur searching for a new logical path. In case of personal
that are accompanied by negative emotions and pro- concerns, the standard is goal hierarchy, the barrier
voke control efforts and reflections. It is of utmost is an intrapersonal goal conflict, the corresponding
importance to remember that every definition of a emotion is dissatisfaction, and the regulation is sub-
barrier or obstacle in the course of an action implies jective re-evaluation. In case of morality, the stan-
(analytical as well as psychologically) some standard dards are duty, respect, and fairness, the barrier is an
about how an action should be carried out). We call intrinsic (or intuitive) conflict between different inter-
these phenomena “action-guiding frameworks” or ests, values, or principles, the corresponding emotion
“normative rule systems” for actions. In concep- is guilt or shame (in case of observing a moral trans-
tualizing the relationship between the objective gression, it would be indignation), and the regula-
world (ontology) and the subjective understanding tion is avoidance of harm or consensus-orientation.
of the world (epistemology), I claimed, however Although the emotional terms suggest that they are
Eckensberger (1985, 1993a, 1995, 1996a), that situational, this is not intended; on the contrary,
these barriers (like the interpretation of the world elaborating emotions in action contexts implies that
in first-order actions) are intuitively and objectively they are automatically understood in time, and they
given in primary actions, but in secondary actions can easily change if the interpretation/meaning of
they are reflected and come about through inter- the situation changes.23
pretations in action contexts. Therefore, these stan- So secondary actions serve as frameworks to
dards are not only preconditions for defining the regulate barriers in primary actions, which means
barriers as barriers but also imply different ways of they re-establish an equilibrium between the agency
overcoming them that are more or less adequate. and cultural standards. They are formed by upward
Additionally, the different interpretations of barri- reflection (reflective abstraction), but they also form a
ers also imply different types of emotions: Although downward selection of primary actions. Following the
all these emotions relate to frustrations in a general fruitful terminology of Janet (Schwartz, 1951) and
sense, manifold shades of affects/emotions that Boesch (1976, 1991), these regulations are called sec-
emerge as reactions to differently interpreted barriers ondary actions because on the one hand they (just as
or experiences are distinguished (cf. Eckensberger, primary actions) basically also have the formal struc-
1993, 1985, 1996; Eckensberger & Emminghaus, ture of actions—they are future-oriented and have
1982). It is not so important that the chosen terms a basic teleological structure (they are goal-oriented
reflect everyday language exactly; the central point, because they are supposed to re-establish and adapt
rather, is to distinguish various emotional reactions primary actions, and they involve decisions and eval-
to frustrations by using different emotional con- uations of outcomes). On the other hand, however,
cepts, depending on the barrier’s interpreted source they are not oriented toward the world but toward
or origin. primary actions. Hence, they are also called action-
To give some examples from the cancer research: oriented actions. They form normative schemata
These standards may be technical (e.g., during the (conventions, morality, and law) as regulatory rule
process of cancer, some body function may be at systems in the agency as well as rules in culture.
stake or some kind of prosthesis should work), then A systematic depiction of the most important
barriers are called problems, and the accompanying types of rules, their distinctions, and inter-relations

374 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


is presented elsewhere (Eckensberger 1993b, 1995, growth, wealth, and health. In the cancer research
1996). More recently, a systematization in terms of (Eckensberger & Kreibich-Fischer, 1994), these
action types was even proposed (Eckensberger, 2008, phantasms are, for example, individual overarch-
2010b; Eckensberger, Kapadia, & Wagels, 2000).24 ing affectively satiated goals of health, which are
In a later section, the development of moral judge- embedded in a whole pattern of subjective theo-
ment in action terms will be considered in more ries about one’s own illness (e.g., Fillip & Ferring,
detail. 1998) and (corresponding) ideas about the proper
Of course, action regulations (secondary actions) means to re-establish health. They are also embed-
are not new in psychology; rather, they are similar ded in the immediate social context (social support
to coping processes (cf. Lazarus & Launier, 1978; system) as well as in cultural myths about cancer,
Haan, 1977) or control theories of primary or sec- its development (who gets it, and why), and proper
ondary control strategies (e.g., Heckhausen, 1997). treatment (what to do). Thus, all regulations aim at
But the control efforts distinguished were inter- re-establishing or coordinating actions—whether to
nally more sophisticated. Hence, a detailed internal continue or give up an action and/or how to rein-
structure of these processes and a scoring manual to terpret the situation, and so on. Apart from this, as
define different cases based on the internal structure outlined above, secondary actions also differ (just
of actions was elaborated (Bettingen, Eckensberger, as in case of primary actions) in the affordances
Gaul, Krewer, Madert, & Prowald, 1993). To at and possibilities a culture provides as well as in the
least give a rough idea, some examples are in order: canalizing constraints, prohibitions, and taboos
First, intrapsychic and actional regulations were dis- (the normative rule systems) that already exist. In
tinguished. Both can apply to goals and/or means. cancer, for example, culture offers (besides the tra-
The regulation of means can involve representa- ditional medical treatment) a variety of alternative
tions, evaluations, or reflections; they can refer to treatments that promise healing. In the cancer study
the social or material world. The goal is either reset (Eckensberger & Kreibich-Fischer, 1983) practically
or not. Actional regulations apply to doing or not no patient did without them. So, quite generally,
doing something; they also refer to the social or with reference to the social world, phantasms like
material world. Additionally, it is useful to differen- security or ideals of love develop.
tiate whether regulations are orientated toward the
barrier or away from it. Tertiary Actions: Agency-Oriented
The “social world” certainly also initiates co- It is only consistent to presume—especially when
regulations (support, help), which in turn influ- postulating that humans are “potentially self-reflec-
ences the emotional evaluation of the success or tive beings”—that impediments to or disturbances
failure of a regulation (e.g., if one succeeds, one of secondary actions inevitably compel the person
feels pride or triumph, one feels grateful toward to reflection or, rather, to self-reflection (see Piaget,
others or appreciates their help, etc.; cf. Valsiner, 1974). One asks questions like, “What goals do I
1987). Apart from knowledge systems, however, really have?”; “How important is a particular action
among other things, fashions, conventions, morals, outcome for me?”; “What does some moral insight
and laws as outcomes of time-tested ways of solv- mean to me?”; or “Is it important for me to ‘uphold’
ing problems/conflicts in a culture also exist. For my personal convictions or character?” which
example, in some parts of Africa, local chiefs decide finally raises the question “Who am I?” or “What
and moderate social conflicts, the West has devel- is the meaning of my existence?” Once again, the
oped a written law, Islamic cultures operate with barriers of actions (this time in secondary actions)
the Sharia law system, whereas in China a written provide the developmental potential for such ques-
law also exists, but conflicts there are preferably tions. They again emerge from upward (abstractive)
regulated by mediation (Ma, 1998). reflection, and they form downward selection pro-
Again in following Boesch, it is assumed that cesses onto secondary actions. At the level of tertiary
secondary actions are also affectively structured and actions, the process of primary structuration leads
lead to individual superordinate affectively struc- to role expectations or stereotypes of persons in a
tured goal systems called phantasms. They include culture or society (personhood) and to the devel-
general notions of control (or harmony), security, opment of the subject’s identity and how he or she
health, and good life. The corresponding myths in presents his- or herself to the outside world. These
culture (in the West) are the well-known ideals of identity structures also possess an action-guiding

ecken sberger 375


potential. They can be considered as developmen- 1985; Leahy, 1985; Loevinger, 1976) shared the
tally organized types of identity (stages), as outlined common feature of conceptualizing “the process of
by Kegan (1982), Blasi (1985), Erikson (1959), and identity formation towards higher or more mature
others. It is the ability to rise to a higher level of eval- stages as a process reflecting increase in abstract
uation to evaluate possible actions and the motives, and formalized competences or structures” (Krewer
emotions, and so forth, involved that allows for the & Eckensberger, 1990, p. 216). The other side of
development of moral responsibility, character, and becoming more and more complex (structurally)
eventually free will. For example, Kane (1989) has implies, however, that one loses more and more
argued that when two possible courses of action (everyday) content. This assumption not only con-
conflict, the resulting destabilization of brain states tradicts daily life experiences, but it also somehow
allows for genuine free will and that when we act neglects the fact that identity is rooted in the spe-
on the basis of such deliberation, we are engaged in cific biography and cultural context. So our goal
self-forming actions that create our character and was to contextualize identity formation by means
thus make us responsible in the long run for the of the elaborated three-level action scheme,25 which
people we are. included daily life activities (primary actions) as well
In the present framework, the development of as action control (secondary actions) and reflections
agency can itself be considered an action as a proj- (tertiary actions).
ect of identity development, which has a goal and The German region in which the University of
which may fail (Clemens, 2007; Brandtstaedter, the Saarland is located was ideal for such effort,
1998; Eckensberger, 2007, Krewer, 1990; Krewer because it has a unique history (at times it belonged
& Eckensberger, 1991). Also Simão’s (2005) dis- to France, at other times to Germany, and it was
cussion of self-formation from the perspectives of even a European protectorate), and hence devel-
Gadamer, Boesch, and Valsiner is relevant here. oped a unique regional culture. So daily life contexts
This implies that individuals constantly reconstruct relevant for that culture were investigated by my
and renew their understanding of their relationship coworker Bernd Krewer in his dissertation (Krewer,
to themselves and to the social and material world 1990): language (dialect) use, preference of regional
and thus the relationship between autonomy (inde- food, humor, and meaning of historical events of
pendence) and affiliation (interdependence) in the the region. A whole variety of methods was used
social world. Essentially, the subject reconstructs the to really capture the daily life context (biographi-
balance between fulfilling personal needs and those cal interviews, diaries, group discussions, video
of others. The relation of the subject to the natural tapes of language use). On the basis of this research,
world (aspects of culture) is also located here. Krewer (1990) formulated the term cultural identity
Methodically, it is important to note that indi- anchors for these cultural features of the region and
vidual goals are not as conscious as seems to be sug- a regional cultural identity, which used these features
gested here, and they are therefore sometimes rather as symbolic representations of one’s identity; this
naively investigated by applying questionnaires that was particularly true for the regional dialect.
ask explicitly for goals. In the longitudinal cancer The importance of the particular role of self-re-
research study (Eckensberger & Kreibich-Fischer, flections (third action level) in cancer was quite dif-
1993, 1994), using the action framework, it became ferent. The study was triggered by the observations
evident that the significance of barriers/impedi- of a practitioner (Kreibich-Fischer) that many of the
ments is also methodically highly relevant: people cancer patients stated sooner or later, and more or
do not speak as spontaneously about their goals as less pronounced, that becoming ill was good or ben-
much as they do about barriers. Empirically their eficial for them. At first this was shocking, but then
goals, in that sense, often have to be reconstructed it was not really so, as it seemed to result from the
from the barriers the subjects experience. increased self-consciousness and awareness of the
The research on regional cultural identity and value and importance of every minute of life under
cancer may serve as examples for the productivity the threat of a limited time perspective. Hence, the
of the proposed action levels. Although quite dif- goal of the study was twofold: to understand this
ferent in detail, both tackled the problem of iden- increase in self-reflection (acceleration of self-de-
tity development. Usually, in those days, theories velopment) in more detail and to examine whether
on ego, self, or identity development (Fillip, 1980; healthy people might be able to learn something
Habermas, 1976; Kegan, 1982; Lapsley & Power, from this attitude.

376 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


None of the research programs mentioned was Although data from 30 patients were collected,
cross-cultural26 or done in another culture than only 6 of them were analyzed because the analysis
Germany, yet culture served as a necessary context— of the material was extremely time-consuming and
that is, a cultural psychology was followed. Rychlak thus expensive (s. Eckensberger & Kreibich, 1993).
(1993) saw no methodical implications in his dis- But the results were quite promising. First, it was in
tinction of the four groundings, but we disagreed fact possible to score free utterances for every patient
explicitly with this (Eckensberger, 2002). In the in terms of the theory of developmental types and
contrary, in the cancer study we refused the demand to reconstruct possible qualitative change (this was
by the Ministry of Technology and Education to use quite unclear in the beginning). Second, four of the
scales and questionnaires; instead we tried to take patients oscillated between stressing intimacy and
the self-reflective active model of man as seriously as self-control, only one manifested the over-adapted
possible also methodically, by treating the subjects picture, which was drawn about cancer patients
with respect, care, and understanding. This was (mamma carcinoma) in the literature of the 1980s
exactly what Smedslund (2009, p. 792) also called (Vetter, 1989; Lerner, 1987; Canakis & Schneider,
for recently. Although data collection and interpre- 1989). Third and most important, two of the
tation varied between studies, data collection (sam- patients exhibited different developmental changes:
pling) basically followed the model of theoretical one patient, in fact, within 3 years, developed from
sampling (Glaser & Strauss, 1967) and ended up in an intimate self to a reflected egoistic and then to
formulating psychological types (Werbick, 1985). an autonomous self (which was particularly inter-
But differing from these authors, the resulting types esting for the question at hand). The other, however,
did not simply emerge from the qualitative data col- first had an intimate, relational self-concept, but
lection; rather, they were, like the sampling, (action-) regressed to an expressive egoistic self-orientation,
theory-driven. In this sense, every new person was which demanded support and attention from her
included in a sample with the aim of testing and, partner (social support system). In both cases, the
if necessary, correcting the theoretical framework. support systems (cultural setting) were attuned to
Data collection allowed the interviewees as much these structures of the patients. These differences
freedom as possible to keep data as authentic as pos- were also discussed in terms of their implications
sible. Data analysis was qualitative (hermeneutic), for therapy (Eckensberger, Kreibich-Fischer, &
but it was also guided by the action theoretical psy- Gaul, 1998), but this discussion is again is beyond
chological framework. the scope of the present context.
To be methodically as unobtrusive, contextual- Secondary structurations were also relevant to
ized, and as respecting of the patients as possible the results of both studies: affective bonds were
in gathering data, no questionnaires were applied; formed to the regional (concrete) culture. This was
rather, normal counselling sessions were taped and true for the landscape (homeland), the food, but
only short (selective) interviews were performed. particularly for the regional dialect. On the other
Of course, the patients had to give their consent hand, the cancer patients formed phantasms of
and could stop the taping whenever they wanted. autonomy and relatedness, which became part of
But that was extremely rare. The study lasted about their identity. Although investigated primarily in
3 years, and in the end, up to 30 tapes existed for early mother–child contexts (see p. 898), it is pro-
every patient over different time spans. Because the ductive to assume that these affective structurations
patients themselves decided what to talk about (a are relevant during the entire lifespan (e.g., in love
medical or practical or financial problem, a problem relationships) but also in therapist–client relations
with the family, etc.), the scoring manual had to cover (the counsellors in the cancer project remained close
an extremely broad range of topics and yet had to be intimate friends with the patients for as long as they
structured in great detail (Bettingen, Eckensberger, lived).
Gaul, Krewer, Madert, & Prowald, 1993). The three One barrier is of utmost importance on the third
action levels served as a framework, and it was, of level, and this is, in fact, the other side of the coin of
course, complemented and improved content-wise self-reflection. It is the knowledge of the end of this
during the project. The particular question of self- process—that is, of one’s death or existence on earth.
development was mainly covered by an adaptation Most religions (on the cultural side) offer the hope
of Kegan’s (1982) theory on the evolving self, which of an existence beyond biological death (although
also makes use of Piaget’s reflective abstraction. this may differ qualitatively and quantitatively in

ecken sberger 377


various religions, it can be paradise [Christianity/ Tomasello (2001). Greenfield’s (2002) ingenious
Islam] or rebirth [Buddhism/Hinduism] or only work on hand-looms in the Zinacateco Indians,
moderate pronouncements as in Judaism), thereby which are offered to children in an age-related increas-
outwitting death. Religion thus can be regarded as ing complexity and can be understood as adaptations
what most individuals believe so as to create hope to the sequence of the ontogeny of cognition a la
for a better state of existence after death. But all Piaget, may serve as an example.
religions also encompass rituals and have prescrip- This kind of theorizing may look idiosyncratic
tive components that regulate social life on Earth at first glance, but it is not. As mentioned, Russian
(Kimmel, 2010). This is actually an interpretation activity theory also uses action levels (but with a dif-
scheme in its own right; it usually implies an entire ferent rationale; see Eckensberger, 1995). Recently
theory of the structure of the world (relations among Molz and Edwards (2011) gave an overview of
men, animals, and plants) and its creation (created altogether 11 meta-theoretical approaches that use
and governed by one or more ultimate beings). It three hierarchical levels. Those of Bateson (1972),
also entails rules of conduct (what is right or wrong, Christopher and Bickhard (2007), Gülerce’s (1997),
what is a sin). Some kinds of regulation are even Kitchener (1983), and Sorokin (1958) come close
prescribed in or afforded by a religion. These may to my distinction of action levels. But Martin,
be purifying rituals, prayers, and so forth. Since the Sokol, and Elfers (2008) also distinguish three levels
Enlightenment, these knowledge and rule systems of reflection in social cognition (from prereflective
compete with science. And they still do, as we know interactivity through reflective intersubjectivity to
from the discourse between evolutionism and crea- meta-reflective sociality). However, here is not the
tionism. As noted by Oser and Gmünder (1984) or place to elaborate on similarities and differences of
Fowler (1991), religious structures are of an existen- these approaches in more detail.
tial nature and can also be described as stages (devel-
opmental types) that represent human’s relation to Dealing With the Duality “Content versus
the ultimate (see also Eckensberger, 1993b). Structure”27 in Moral Development
But again, a word of caution is in order: It is not If one defines the importance of a theory in
proposed that these various rule systems are recon- terms of the amount of theorizing and research it
structed or detected by the agency alone. Although triggers, then Kohlberg’s theory clearly is an impor-
single agencies can create rules for themselves, they tant one. Although things have changed much since
inevitably do so in a cultural context. In our research his death in 1987, his theory is still very much
on the development of understanding precursors of alive and productive (see the Association of Moral
law in children (Weyers, Sujbert, & Eckensberger, Development, AME, and the affiliated Journal of
2007), we created group situations (with restricted Moral Development). The amount of work, enthu-
action means), which by necessity had to end up siasm, as well as criticism this theory provoked (see
in distributive justice problems. In an analysis of Modgill and Modgill, 1986; Latzko & Malti, 2010
literally hundreds of video-taped action episodes, for the German context) is immense. But there is
only two situations were found in which only one no need to summarize it here. Instead, only our
child created a rule (upward emergence) that was own engagement with the theory will be focused
immediately followed by the group (downward on, which also began in the middle of the 1970s
selection). But not all rules are created or detected (Eckensberger & Reinshagen, 1978, 1980) and
by children alone—to a great extent, most cultural continues (e.g., Eckensberger, 2006a, 2010b). In
rules are co-constructed in the enculturation pro- this domain, the relation of action theory and dia-
cess (Glick, 1985) and happen to be reconstructed lectics was and is also crucial.
under “adult guidance or in collaboration with more The interest in moral development from the
capable peers” (Vygotsky, 1978, quoted in Valsiner, very beginning was also part of my interest in the
1987, p. 107). A very similar concept can be seen role of culture in psychology. Morality is clearly
in Feuerstein’s (1989) proposal of mediated learn- one of the most important cultural rule systems,
ing, which according to him is even constitutive for and its development in the individual therefore has
humans and forms the essence of culture (see also been central for a psychology that tries to include
Bruner, 1996). This viewpoint is also supported by culture (Eckensberger, 2006b, 2007a). Kohlberg’s
psychologists working with chimpanzees, like David theory was particularly appealing in this regard,
Premack (personal communication, 1984) and by because he claimed (Kohlberg, 1958), during the

378 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


value-relativistic orientation of the 1950s, that applied the complexity of role-taking (egocentric
morality (as the exemplar of cultural relativism at perspective, perspective of another, of a group,
that time) itself is a universal phenomenon in that generalized role taking) as stage structure, and
it develops in a transculturally invariant sequence. decisions in a dilemma as representing content
He holds that developmental progress always occurs (values/norms: life, property, authority, law, etc.).
in a non-reversible order—that is, no stages should Additionally he distinguished further ethical
be skipped and regression to former stages is theo- positions (elements like egoistic consequences,
retically excluded (e.g., Kohlberg, 1976, 1986). This utilitarian consequences, ideal or harmony-serving
strong claim is not only a strength of his theory but consequences, fairness) as content, which also
also the Achilles’ heel and a challenge. Even today it entered the scoring manual (although differently
is difficult for many cross-cultural psychologists to over time). When talking about “holding content
accept that this claim is not based on a biological constant” so as to examine structure (Kohlberg,
model (i.e., on biological universals) but rather on 1978, p. 55), structure and content were viewed
the assumption of a developmental logic that should as independent from one another. In fact, in the
apply cross-culturally (i.e., it is based on structural final versions of the theory, Kohlberg (1986; also
universals; cf. Eckensberger & Burgard, 1983). And Kohlberg et al. 1983) again followed Piaget (1932)
this claim came under attack again in the postmod- by assuming some mutual reference between content
ern orientation of the late 1980s. (values/norms) and structure; thereby he, in fact,
This assertion was at all possible, however, assumed a dialectical relationship between both.
because Kohlberg sharply distinguished between 2. The centrality of the justice principle:
content and structure of moral judgments and Beyond this, justice as the chosen ethical principle
because his universalism claim referred to structure. that guides the theory also came under attack.
This perspective was derived from Piaget’s structur- Gilligan`s (1982) formulation of an ethic of
alism, which is also not at all agreed upon in social care and responsibility has to be mentioned, a
sciences, where values and norms are still under- criticism which in some sense was supported and
stood as content or normative orientations (Nauck, even expanded later by cross-cultural research
2010)—these are either assumed as universals or as and theorizing (for an overview, see Eckensberger
culture-specific frameworks. Because of its impor- & Zimba, 1997). A variety of culture-specific
tance, in the following, reference will mainly be perspectives and principles have been proposed
made to the content versus structure duality. But that appear not to be covered by Kohlberg’s justice
it will be shown that this duality has many implica- perspective, which also cast doubts on the proper
tions for the whole theory. conceptualization of content and structure as well
as their operationalization in the manual—for
Toward a Dialectical Relation Between example, the Confucian principle of giri-ninjo
Content and Structure in the Development (obligation), which seems to be close to the Indian
of Moral Judgment ethic of duty (Miller, 1994; Shweder et al., 1987).
Before starting, it should be noted that it is Huebner and Garrod (1991) have pointed out that
extremely difficult to do justice to Kohlberg’s the- in some Hindu and Buddhist cultures, morality
ory, because it has been modified several times over is embedded in conceptions about the nature of
the last 30 years of his life.28 human existence itself. There, especially the law of
karma (i.e., the adding up of good [dharma] and
1. From independence to dialectics between bad [adharma] actions that may also have been
content and structure. Over time, not only the committed in earlier lives) is regarded crucial. It
definitions of structure (form) and content changed leads, according to the authors, to types of moral
but also the assumptions about their inter- reasoning totally different from the ones defined in
relationship. Originally, the stages were defined Kohlberg’s stage theory and manual. The Javanese/
primarily by the chosen content. Structure was Indonesian principles of hormat (respect for older
only inferred as an ideal type, which connected people) and rukun (harmonious social relations;
the normative content favored by the stage Setiono, 1994) and the principles of collective
(Kohlberg, 1958). Later, Kohlberg was convinced happiness in the kibbutz (Snarey, 1983) require
that he differentiated between the form of moral mentioning. Lei and Cheng (1984) noted that
judgments and the content norm chosen. He some of their Taiwanese interviews were difficult

ecken sberger 379


to analyze, because their subjects referred to the status of these substages was rather unclear
different types of collective conflict-solving strategies from the very beginning (cf. Eckensberger &
not mentioned by Kohlberg. Tietjen and Walker Reinshagen, 1980; Eckensberger 1984, 1986).
(1984) were faced with similar problems in Papua And although some researchers (Tappan et al.,
New Guinea. Similarly, Ma (1988) pointed to 1987) later seemed to conceive these substages
the Chinese (Confucian) principle of jen (love, as a further refinement of the theory, Gielen
benevolence, human-heartedness, man-to- (1991) rightly stated that Kohlberg’s moral types
manness, sympathy, perfect virtue), and the Indian (A and B) “do not exhibit the same logical tightness
principle of respect for all life (Vasudev, 1986), and inner consistency that his moral stages do since
which lead to the principle of nonviolence the types intermingle structure and content to a
(ahimsa) in Hinduism. considerable degree” (p. 34). I have demonstrated
In fact, a long-enduring discussion exists on the (Eckensberger, 1984, 1986) that the substages in
relation between justice and care (Kohlberg et al., the manual are highly correlated with main stages
1983) as well as between role-taking and empathy. (B substages increase and A substages decrease
Here it may suffice to say that one can interpret the continuously with main stages), and I have
tension between both as constituting a thesis and pointed to the fact that the substage B criteria
an antithesis. From this perspective, it is productive are barely discernible from criteria that define
that Kohlberg, Boyd, and Levine (1986) discussed principled (post-conventional) stages. Hence,
integrating (synthesizing) both orientations in both the main stages as well as the substages
a new formulation of stage 6, although that represent an increasing trend toward autonomy
theoretical work did not have any consequences for (see also Tappan et al., 1987), which serves as an
Kohlberg’s method either. integrative concept. Moreover, the incitement
3. Beyond justice operations and A/B – substages: conditions for substage B development are difficult
Additionally, Kohlberg added two concepts to discriminate from the ones hypothesized for
that also blurred the relation between structure conventional and post-conventional development
and content. First he added justice operations (institutions and societies emphasizing democracy,
(equality, equity, reciprocity) and the balance equality, cooperation, and mutual relationships; see
between the perspectives as a further criterion for Gielen, 1991).
structure (Kohlberg, 1985), which is analogous to 4. Stages and levels: As is well-known, Kohlberg
a synthesis. Second, in following Piaget’s (1932) not only proposed development of moral judgment
notion of the development from a heteronomous (structure) in six (later five) empirical stages
to an autonomous orientation, Kohlberg (1976) but also organized these stages into three levels
elaborated on A-/B-substages. He saw them “as (stages 1 and 2: pre-conventional; stages 3 and 4:
laying intermediate between content and form” conventional; stages 5 and 6: post-conventional).
(Kohlberg et al., 1983, p. 43). They referred to the If this classification has a developmental
equilibrated (B) use of a justice structure. Without psychological meaning, then development
going into details, substage A was more intuitive, between and within levels should differ in speed
and B was reflected and equilibrated. He first of development or in difficulty. Given the state of
distinguished these types by means of elements the empirical data in those days, this was, however,
(egoistic and utilitarian consequences counted rather doubtful. The main difficulty in progress
as A, ideal or harmony serving consequences seemed to exist from stages 3 to 4—that is, it cut
and fairness as B). Later Kohlberg et al. (1983) the second level of conventional thinking. In stage
explicitly used “Kantian” and “Piagetian criteria” 4, a system perspective was involved (Selman,
(which were not quite independent from one 1974; Kohlberg, 1976); formal logical operations
another) to score substages. If most criteria applied, seemed to be a necessary condition for stage 4
it was B; if not, it was A. rather than for stage 3 (Kuhn, Langer, Kohlberg,
By doing so, he somehow constructed two & Haan, 1977). The known cross-cultural data
developmental paths of moral development (summary in Eckensberger & Reinshagen, 1980,
(Eckensberger & Burgard, 1986; Eckensberger, p. 100 ff.) of the time suggested that stage 4 was
1986): one stage structure in terms of socio-moral difficult (improbable) in “face to-face cultures”,
role-taking (a Mead’ian path), the other in terms whereas stage 3 was common (particularly
of A- and B-substages (a Piaget’ian path). But Edwards, 1975).

380 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


Edwards (1986) and Ma (1988), for example, harmonious structures but on different levels of
raised questions about the strict definition of social abstractions.
Kohlberg’s stage 4 in terms of law and institutions.
From her investigations in face-to-face societies, Based on these ambiguities in Kohlberg’s theory,
Edwards concluded that the social perspective of an we speculated about a different internal order of
informal understanding of roles should be sufficient the stages. Partly following Piaget, we assumed that
for a scoring at stage 4. Nisan (Nisan & Kohlberg, instead of a one-dimensional order of six stages in
1982) also proposed guess scores for a transitional three levels, moral development happens like a spi-
stage between stages 3 and 4 for subjects’ reasoning ral in two levels of social spheres. The first sphere
based on either family tradition or relatedness of is called the “personal” or “interpersonal sphere.”
the actors. Ma’s (1988) formulation of Chinese Here, agencies or conflicting parties are viewed as
stages of moral development interestingly only concrete, more or less real people or subjects. This
began with stage 4 (the first three stages were social sphere encompasses stages 1, 2, and 3. A sec-
assumed to be identical in the West and in China) ond sphere, which developmentally follows the first,
and ended in higher principles of harmony. is called “transpersonal sphere.”29 Here, conflicting
Later, in following the German sociologist parties are primarily understood in terms of roles or
Toennies (1887/1957), Snarey and Keljo functions or even general positions (abstract prin-
(1991) distinguished a community perspective ciples). This sphere encompasses stages 4, 4 ½, and
(Gemeinschaftsperspektive) from a societal 5. Beyond these social spheres, we have proposed
perspective (Gesellschaftsperspektive). a philosophical sphere of ethical positions. Instead
5. Stage 4 ½: Finally, two studies (Kohlberg & of one post-conventional stage, we (Eckensberger
Kramer, 1968; Haan, Smith, & Block, 1968) led & Reinshagen, 1980) have proposed three ethical
Kohlberg to formulate a stage 4 ½ (between stages positions: rule ethics, act ethics, and consensual eth-
4 and 5). The reasons were different (regression ics. We have also speculated about decalages between
from 4 to 2, and rescoring of stage 2 as a stage these stages from a lower social sphere to a higher
that was post-conventional but not yet stage 5). one and have assumed a dialectical relation among
It was defined in terms of relative egoism and as the three stages on each level (1 and 4 thesis; 2 and
representing a “personal and subjective choice 4 ½ antithesis, and 3 and 5 synthesis). But we first
(which) is based on emotions and hedonism, since did not have a plausible reconstruction for this
conscience is seen as arbitrary and relative, as are assumption.
terms like ‘duty,’ ‘morally rights,’ etc.,” (Kohlberg,
1976, p. 17). As similar structures had also been Content versus Structure in Moral
found in studies of adolescence by Döbert & Judgment Development: Action Theory
Nunner-Winkler (1975), there was no reason for in Dialectics
treating this structure as an abnormality, as was Although some of the cited data were published
done in the tradition of Kohlberg (cf. Colby et al., later, they support the problems we (Eckensberger &
1983), but they could be included in the main- Reinshagen, 1978, 1980) ran into with Kohlberg’s
stage development. theory (in fact, only the last three problem areas—
6. Scoring: Finally in scoring, it turned out numbers 4, 5, and 6—formed the basis of our ear-
that it was not difficult to differentiate between lier discussion). A better understanding particularly
the adjacent stages; rather, sometimes stage 1 was of the role of dialectics in moral development was
similar to stage 4 (both have a heteronomous (and still is) called for: (1) a possible spiral in stage
core), similarly stage 2 and stage 4 ½ seemed to development, as well as (2) the dialectical relation
imply similar structures (after all, stage 4 ½ was (mutual reference) between structure and content.
the result of rescoring some stage 2 answers in We began (Eckensberger & Reinshagen, 1978,
the Haan, Smith, & Block [1968] study). They 1980) with the choice of the structure of an action
both had a liberal relativistic core, either regarding to define a new criterion for the structure of moral
actions means (stage 2) or personal choices in arguments. So a “paradigm shift” from role-taking
values (stage 4 ½). Stages 3 and 5 also had a (Kohlberg’s criterion of structure) to goal-taking was
similar core: focus on common interpersonal proposed (Eckensberger, 1977; Eckensberger and
expectations (stage 3) and social contracts based Plath 2006a). Instead of the classical social perspec-
on common values (stage 5), so both referred to tive taken on each stage, the perceived complexity of

ecken sberger 381


the actions involved in a conflict were applied as the that actions themselves are reflectively tied back to
leading criterion of stage structures, thereby applying an agency, which is itself potentially self-reflective.
action theory to dialectics. Later it was discovered that Actions can now be evaluated in two regards (see
in analytical philosophy, a similar logic is applied Fig. 17.3). First, they can be evaluated in view of
to the concept of understanding another person, their instrumental/functional adequacy. This means
when, for example, Meggle (1993) elaborates “to analyzing whether the chosen means are instrumen-
understand a person means to understand his/her tally adequate to realize a certain end or goal. Actions
actions.” Meanwhile this paradigm is also increas- can, however, also be evaluated from a moral point
ingly being used in the context of social cogni- of view. This is primarily made possible by the crite-
tion, where the concept of TOM refers precisely to rion of a potential self-reflexivity and reflection on the
understanding others’ actions (see p. 893 and, for an means. Although trivial, it is the principle choice
overview, see Eckensberger & Plath, 2006a). of the means, which implies responsibility for the
We (Eckensberger & Reinshagen, 1978, 1980) outcome. Second, the moral evaluation of an action
first analyzed Kohlberg’s manuals30 (which later implies analyzing whether different aspects or ele-
became the standard issue scoring; cf. Colby & ments of an action (goals, means, or various conse-
Kohlberg, 1987) and then collected empirical quences) possibly could or, in fact, do interfere with
(cross-sectional) data (Eckensberger, 1984; 1986; other actors’ interests (goals).
Eckensberger & Burgard, 1984, 1986). The justifi- Thus, to define the structure of a moral judg-
cation of the choice of human action as the candi- ment in this framework:
date for defining the structure of moral arguments
1. a given moral reasoning was analyzed in the
was, in fact, simple. It was first based on the fact that
light of the complexity and comprehensiveness of
the human action is the only way of defining and
the action structure elaborated by a subject (e.g.,
conceptualizing morality, because it implies a choice
whether a quasi-mechanistic relationship between
between alternatives and therefore a subjective deci-
ends and means is assumed, or whether the choice
sion, which is the precondition for the conceptual-
of means is considered to be a question of personal
ization of responsibility as a central moral category
choice, and hence, of personal responsibility, etc.).
(Eckensberger, 1986; Eckensberger & Reinshagen,
2. This reasoning was analyzed with reference to
1980); this is not true for role-taking. Second, it
where the subject locates the main conflict (whether
was based on the assumption that the human action
the conflict is located between the goals, means,
is intrinsically a universal framework (Eckensberger,
consequences or entire actions, and/or an existing
2006b).31 It is assumed that all humans experience
external rule).
agency, have goals, choose means, produce effects
3. A given moral reasoning was analyzed in view
and results by acting, and coordinate actions,
of the standard (or normative claim) being used by
although these activities may be context- or culture-
the subject either to prevent, to circumvent, or to
specific. So we still imply a universal framework also
solve a given or possible conflict.
for comparison, which again implies that action the-
4. In addition, to define the two levels, the
ory is a culturally informed theory.
action elements were generalized to values and
Generally speaking, any structure consists of ele-
principles, partly using Linton’s (1954) distinction
ments and their inter-relations. If this notion is
between conceptual values and instrumental values
applied to the human action, then the most simple
or Rokeach’s (1969) distinction between terminal
structure of an action can be defined by the elements
values and instrumental values, the former
of goals, means, results, and consequences and by
representing classes/abstractions of goals, the latter
different thought processes that form the relation-
classes/abstractions of means. It is important to
ship between these elements (see Fig. 17.3): final
realize that within this approach, content and
thinking (a means is applied in order to reach a
structure was not assumed to be independent but
goal), logical thinking (the choice of a means implies
norm/value preferences were intrinsic to structural
the result), and causal thinking relate the result with
(stage) development.32
the consequences of actions. Additionally, conse-
quences can (at least) be differentiated according to The subsequent higher stages can be recon-
their intentionality into intended and unintended structed accordingly with the same dialectical
ones, and both are also functionally related to the relationship (Eckensberger & Reinshagen, 1980).
results. Last but not least, it has to be remembered At the first (stage 1), actions and action rules are

382 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


primarily interpreted intuitively and as being quasi- is a young man who asks a druggist to get a drug,
mechanistic. The conflict is located between existing but the druggist refuses to give it.” Then the inter-
norms and action means, Consequently, unilateral viewee is requested to ask more questions about the
respect is expressed in the moral standard. The moral situation, because not much information has been
standard (content) that represents unilateral respect given yet. Then he may ask, “Why do I need the
and an intuitive rule orientation on stage 1 can be drug?” It is not immediately explained that his wife
understood as a thesis. Next (stage 2), the conflict is ill (like in the Heinz dilemma), but he is asked
is located between intentions and means, all inten- in return “Why is that important?” He may now
tions involved become important, and hence, means answer, “I am ill,” or “I am an addict.” Again, one
to realize all goals are focused on. The standard to inquires, “Where is the difference?” and so forth. So
realize all goals of the agencies and an instrumental the subjects create their own normative framework
and outcome orientation implied in a dilemma can and make-up cases, which are all highly relevant for
be understood as the antithesis. It is only thereaf- scoring. Only the highest score (in terms of action
ter (stage 3) that complete actions are analyzed and elements) counts as a stage score. This procedure
integrative moral standards are developed. These was developed on the basis of the underlying model
standards imply mutual respect and shared goals. of man, the self-reflective human being. By doing
These integrating moral standards, which imply so, we again admit Smedslund’s (2009) later claim
like harmony or consensus orientation, represent a of taking this model serious also in methods.
synthesis. Mainly for empirical reasons, the 11 stages were
The subsequent (transpersonal) stages can be “condensed” into two levels on both spheres, which
understood as follows: First, the concrete social represent a development from heteronomy33 to
interactions are transformed into a group structure autonomy. Therefore, an interpersonal trend from
that is regulated by social norms/laws as means heteronomy to autonomy is distinguished from a
(stage 4, thesis). Then this stage is replaced by a transpersonal one from heteronomy to autonomy.
standard that calls for efforts to order hierarchi- There are good reasons to argue that the second
cally the values involved in a conflict. It is this dimension of transformation of moral judgments is
hierarchical order of the value system as superin- still best summarized as a move from heteronomous
dividual goals that are used to define what is ethi- (intuitive reference to external behaviors, rules, sim-
cally right or wrong (antithesis). As before, the final ple interests of people) to autonomous moral judg-
stage (stage 5) is basically characterized by mutual ment (mutual respect), as proposed by Piaget as early
respect, which, at this point, is now generalized as 1932. This becomes obvious when looking at the
to all rational human beings and to abstract posi- standards (now called norms); the subject applies
tions (synthesis). So, altogether both dialectically when discussing a moral conflict. So the claim that
interpreted internal relations in the stage structure in moral development a “horizontal decalage” also
have been plausibly reconstructed by action theory occurs between the stages 1 and 4, 2 and 4½, as well
structures: (1) the spiral-shaped development (rep- as between 3 and 5 on the two levels has been sup-
etition of a dialectical sequence of thesis, antithesis, ported. The notion of a horizontal decalage implies
and synthesis on two levels of social reality) and that it is not assumed that two different dilemmas
(2) an internal mutual reference of action structures are discussed on the same stage, and hence stage
and normative orientations (values) in stages. regressions from the higher to the lower levels may
But these early proposals were supplemented also occur (Burgard, 1989; Eckensberger, 1989),
by additional stages between these Kohlberg- implying also a weakening of strict (internally con-
related stages that we (Eckensberger, 1984, 1986; sistent) level/stage concepts. We also argue that we
Eckensberger and Burgard 1986) formulated on escaped the problem Kohlberg ran into with his dis-
the basis of their own data. They ended up with 11 tinction into moral stages and A-/B-substages. The
stages, which, however, did not destroy the basic two developmental paths (Mead and Piaget) are
dialectical relation between the stages. integrated in this model.
These data were collected using a different method
than Kohlberg’s hypothetical dilemmas. Rather than Dualities in Moral Development:
presenting the whole text of a Kohlberg dilemma Dialectics in Action Theory
(e.g., the famous Heinz dilemma), only the nucleus Again, the role of dialectics in action theory as
or core of a dilemma is used. For example, “There applied to moral judgments will be discussed, first

ecken sberger 383


with reference to the action theoretically recon- (Eckensberger, 2010). After having defined what
structed stages, then for the contextualized everyday can be called a deep structure of the development
types of morality. of moral judgment by action theory structures, we
turned to real-life contexts step by step by analyz-
Dialectics in Stages Defined in Action Terms ing ecological issues (building a coal-fueled power
First, in a later paper (Eckensberger, 1984), a plant, water consumption, following conventional
dialectical relation between the three levels was even or “green” farming methods) but also issues of edu-
proposed in following Piaget’s proposal to interrelate cation of democracy. In a way moral judgments
cognition and affect. We interpreted concrete action were re-contextualized in this research. This was
elements (personal social realm) as a thesis, the values realized by the CIAT perspective, which theoreti-
on the transpersonal realm as antithesis, and prin- cally allows the integration not only of the subject
ciples on the philosophical level as a synthesis.34 (agency) and context (culture) but also of norms
There is, however, a second aspect in which dia- and facts, as well as cognition and affect, because
lectics contribute to the action theoretical recon- these dualities are part of the three action levels.
struction of moral stages (Eckensberger, 1986). This In doing so, methodically biographical data
is, as in the case of action levels, the concept of the rather than the dilemma core or hypotheti-
principle of reflective abstraction (upward reflection) cal dilemmas were used as a source of the data.
that explains the emergence of the stages that can also be Theoretically the four moral levels (derived from
applied here: Every new standard (n + 1) emerges from the 11 stages defined by action structures) were
a reflective abstraction triggered by impediments/ combined with the three action levels described
problems/conflicts of the standard (n) of the previ- above. The results were interpreted in terms of four
ous stage. Every standard (structure), x, is therefore types of everyday morality, which were still prescrip-
first operative on stage (n) then content of the abstrac- tive (deontological) in nature but at the same time
tion (n + 1). Again, this is logically contradictory but they were embedded in the everyday reality of the
developmentally plausible. However, once more also subjects. Two interpersonal types (heteronomous
the complementary process of a downward selection and autonomous) and two transpersonal types
process is assumed that regulates (re-evaluate) lower (heteronomous and autonomous) were defined
stages. These processes were not only speculatively (Breit & Eckensberger, 1998). The definition
assumed (after all, our data were cross-sectional) but of these types was based both on the theoreti-
also validated in interviewing. The content of lower cal model and the analysis of data obtained from
stages is explicitly discussed by the interviewer and 180 subjects, who were intensively interviewed
critically reflected on by the interviewee (Nieder, about ecological issues in their daily lives. The
Sieloff, Kasper, & Eckensberger, 1987). core of morality was defined by the complexity
and normativity of the implied action concept.
Contextualization of Moral Judgments Additionally the kind of respect implied was used
(More Dualities—Facts Versus Norms; as a moral criterion as was the appreciation of rules
Affects Versus Cognition) (see Table 17.1). Because of the combination of the
Contextualization is one particular feature of four types with the three action levels, normative
dialectics because contextualization can be under- concepts on the three action levels were also added:
stood as environment (Umgebung) coherence risk-taking on the first level, responsibility on the
(Zusammenhang) (Graumann, 2000). Basically, second, and solidarity on the third. Additionally,
Kohlberg (e.g., Kohlberg et al. 1983) was a Kantian on the first action level (world-oriented actions),
because he, like Kant (1966), wanted to keep moral- the perceived efficiency of actions as well as the per-
ity free from empirical facts. Kohlberg constructed ception of facts was analyzed.
hypothetical moral dilemmas, which were intention- On the second level (action-oriented actions),
ally decontextualized, whether he succeeded in doing understanding of control in moral contexts was
so or not. analyzed as well as the dominant usage of coping
or defence styles (Haan, 1977). This was established
Contextualized “Everyday Types” of Morality: Action using a particular text-analytic method (Sieloff,
Theory in Dialectics Schirk, Kasper, Nieder, & Eckensberger, 1988).
So, in following dialectically thinking, we Finally, on the third action level (agency-oriented
also tried to contextualize moral development actions), the basis of identity and concepts of

384 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


solidarity were analyzed. Beyond that the domi- Future Directions
nant affects were reconstructed within the four In closing this chapter, two aspects of action
everyday types. Because affects exist on all three theory will be discussed, which are quite basic. I
action levels, they differ in complexity. Hence, will argue that the concept of CIAT is relevant far
the dualities of facts and norms, cognition and beyond psychology. Therefore, the arguments would
affects, as well as content and structure were not deserve a much more detailed treatment, which
defined independently (and related to morality in would, however, demand a second chapter. Yet, I at
a second step), but from the very beginning they least intend to point to possible directions of think-
were defined within moral structures of the four ing. The following arguments will be developed on
types. Hence, content and structure were con- two levels: one that focuses on the epistemological
ceptualized as being mutually interdependent: power of the human action (and therefore of CIAT)
content feeds back into structure (Eckensberger, for science in general, and the other that focuses
1986; Piaget, 1932)—that is, the understanding on the four (ontological) perspectives.35 It will be
of facts also contributes to morality, and moral- shown that CIAT not only allows one to synthesize
ity contributes to the understanding of risks the self-reflective and the cultural perspective within
(Döring, Eckensberger, Huppert, & Breit, 2008; psychology but also allows one to inter-connect all
Eckensberger, Döring, & Breit, 2001). Particular four perspectives, which is not the same as integrat-
emotions also occurred (dominant) within the ing them but is more than treating them as comple-
types: rage and wrath in Type I, indignation in mentary (Eckensberger 2002).
Type II, the absence of affects (objectivity) was
the ideal in Type III, and hope was dominant in The Epistemological Power of
Type IV. Hence, the normative structure (moral- the Action Concept
ity) shapes/influences the descriptive cognitive The first level, from which the four perspectives
structures, but emotions also support both and can be inter-connected by CIAT, may seem a bit
are themselves triggered by them (Eckensberger, exaggerated and rather psychology-centered at the
2006a). In that sense, all these dualities form dia- first sight. But, in fact, the argument is quite sim-
lectic relationships, which can be understood in ple yet also quite evident in the present context:
terms of a CIAT. Table 17.1 describes the four as culture is understood as unique to humans and
types and should be self-explanatory. not only created by human actions but also trans-
mitted by human actions, the same is true for sci-
Contextualized “Everyday Types” of Morality: ence, because science is part of culture. This is true
Dialectics in Action Theory for the interpretation of nature and culture (homo
Empirically, the “everyday types” of morality interpretans) as well for the creation of culture (homo
were defined on the basis of data from adults. To faber) as man-made. Hence, the different sciences
be able to claim that they yet can be understood can be elaborated on the basis of different aspects
developmentally in terms of an increase in com- of actions (Eckensberger, 1993, 1995, 1996). This
plexity or maturity, again the concept of the reflec- idea is not new, however, it is elaborated in detail
tive abstraction (upward reflection) as a dialectical by Holzkamp (2006) in his book Science as Action.
principle was applied in this context analytically During recent years it has been explicitly elaborated
as well as methodically. It is assumed that every in the program of a “methodical culturalism” by
type n + 1 emerges on the basis of reflections on the philosopher Peter Janich and his group as well
type n. Also the downward selection processes are (Hartmann & Janich, 1996), called the Erlangen
assumed in type-development by devaluating type school. Finally, the “constructive realism” of the
n-1. Additionally in this research, this assumption Vienna group of Fritz Wallner (Wallner & Jandle,
is used productively in the process of interviewing 2006) requires mentioning. They all rest on the early
in that the interviewee is confronted with “lower work of Dingler (1936/1987), who differentiated
type” (n – 1) arguments as well—that is, s(he) is between pool (Bestand) of knowledge (Erkenntnis)
forced not only into reflection processes but also and acquisition (Aneignung) of knowledge, a per-
to re-evaluate the lower type. This method sup- spective that is equally central in Piaget’s theory. It is
ported our developmental understanding of the compatible with the definition of causality by hav-
types. This is illustrated by the backward arrows ing an impact on something by actions too, which
in Table 17.1. von Wright (1971) has convincingly demonstrated

ecken sberger 385


Table 17.1 Four Types of Contextualized Everyday Moral Judgments
Interpersonal heteronomous
Morality autonomous Transpersonal heteronomous autonomous

Action concept Intuitive, external additional evalu- Laws as means to Consequences for
flexible ation of action secure morality upholding self-respect;
understanding consequences/ (flexible rule, consequences for
and acceptance of shared goals exceptions) values, recognition of
other’s intentions principles as goals
Appreciation intuitive accep- shared rules rights and excep- morality and rights are
of rules tance of rules tions complementary
Respect one-sided mutual respecting social Universalized respect
and legal systems (respecting human-
kind per se)

Identity based on similar- relationships, functional roles good life (virtues)


ity tradition

A III Solidarity shared interests preservation of experts, power world of potential


group standards structure moral patients

C Affects not articulated not articulated not articulated hope

T Control external, co-control technological reflection of


– cognitive conformity, coping > defense realizability interests/goals
– affective defense > coping defense > coping coping > defense

i II Responsibility delegation of individual respon- legal responsibility moral responsibility of


power sibility for the of “expert-power” all people
group

N Affects not articulated indignation/guilt “objectivity” not articulated


(not articulated)

L Perception important, dependent on objectivity reflection of limitations


of facts individual group interests of knowledge

E Facts/norms norms as given norms recon- facts dominate Facts as such hardly
facts structed as norms norms as institu- exist, norms dominate
tionalized facts and evaluate facts

V I Risk individual, to lose to lose one’s repu- to lose wealth loss of justice for all
property/advan- tation, lifestyle, or the power of
tages group-related society

E Efficiency maximization exchange, functionality of the self-commitment


of benefits, reciprocity system (market,
adaptation technology)

L Affects rage/wrath not articulated not articulated not articulated

(see p. 876). Causality as one of the core concepts of precondition for defining causality (Eckensberger,
natural sciences can best be determined by producing 1996). In that sense, the physical as well as the bio-
effects through systematic intended variation of con- logical perspective are constructions based on and
ditions or by intentionally preventing things from derived from human actions/co-actions. It is non-
happening by means of human actions. So intention- trivial that the development of science is marked
ality (as a central concept in action theory) is the by outstanding humans (here by Darwin, Galileo,

386 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


Vico, and Descartes). That the entire discourse in Hartmann & Janich, 1996), and this may be sym-
science nowadays is based more on teamwork and bolized by Dingler’s notion that “in the beginning
interdisciplinary efforts (co-actions) is not a major was the act” (Dingler, 1928, p. 73).
argument against the present point of view: human Of course, this program is also criticized by criti-
action creates science. cal rationalism (Albert, 1991), which only means
Although there is much commonality among that at present, the ongoing discourse is necessary
the underlying action concepts, there are also differ- and hopefully fruitful.
ences among the mentioned schools–particularly to
CIAT. (1) The culture concept is not as elaborated Focus on the Four (Ontological)
as it should be, and (2) communicative actions are Perspectives in a Relational
not considered as important as the instrumental Meta-Perspective
ones. These, however, immediately connote human Overton (2007, p. 156) elaborated on the neces-
science and hermeneutics and understanding, rather sity of relational meta-theory recently when he
than explanation and experimental strategies. stated:
Symbolic dimensions (secondary structurations) are
“relational metatheories are post-Cartesian and
not part of these theories, hence aesthetics are also
inclusive. Relational metatheories aim to transform
not really part of the discussion. (3) Particularly, the
classically fundamental dichotomies into dissociable
three action levels are not distinguished. But doing
complementarities through the relational principles
so would be productive for reconstructing science as
of holism, identity of opposites, opposites of
well. After all, all scientific theories are formulated by
identities, and syntheses of wholes ( . . .) Relational
humans on the basis of empirical activities (primary
metatheories support holism, analysis in the
actions) and their reflections (secondary actions), but
context of synthesis, ontological spontaneous
self-reflective processes (identity questions of scientists
activity, dialectic and necessary change, necessary
and responsibility in science, tertiary actions) are also
organisation, additivity/non-additivity, and linearity/
highly relevant. This aspect particularly is often
non-linearity ( . . . ) there is no privileging of one
neglected or even denied or avoided when psychol-
side or the other, and no privileged explanatory
ogy is considered a natural science (Smedslund,
base; inside and outside, and, efficient, material,
2009). But within that perspective, no “research just
formal, final explanation all play necessary, not
for the sake of research” exists, because science has
epiphenomenal, roles in the full understanding of
a purpose that is bound to human (autonomously
any event.”
chosen) goals, which means that science defined as
action by necessity implies responsibility. On the But as mentioned earlier, these relational meta-
other hand, there are good reasons for being cautious theories cannot be formulated easily, because of the
about going from “is” to “ought” transformations danger of their becoming ontologically empty (as
(called the naturalistic fallacy; see Eckensberger & already argued with reference to quantum theory).
Gaehde, 1993). A good example for holding psy- Therefore, the goal of this final section is rather
chologists responsible is Narvaez, Panksepp, Schore ambitious despite its brevity. In a way, it attempts
and Gleason’s, (in press) demand for taking an ethical to square the circle because it tries to retain all four
responsibility based on the factual knowledge on early perspectives, yet to inter-connect them by CIAT as a
child development, including brain development. synthesizing principle.
In addition the normative consequences Narvaez The basic assumption is first specified by the two
(2008) draws from her proposal of triune ethics can mutually interacting concepts already developed and
serve as an example. However, it calls for a note of applied in many sections of the text. (1) Emerging
caution as well because she draws normative con- upward processes (in human competencies the reflec-
sequences from empirical facts that are themselves tive abstraction) and downward selection processes,
of a functional kind—but functional norms are not compatible with Dynamic System Theory (Juarrero,
ethical norms/principles. It is therefore important 1999), will be applied to the relationship among all
that within all action theoretical frameworks, the four perspectives. (2) Again it is proposed that the
relation between facts and norms can be fruitfully human action can be understood as the general syn-
discussed (Eckensberger, 2006) just as that between thesizing agent in these processes. (3) Yet, it is of an
application (praxis) and theory (Eckensberger, utmost importance that one not assumes that these
1989, 2003, 2004; Plath & Eckensberger, 2008; processes are of the same kind or ontological nature

ecken sberger 387


(Emmeche, Koppe, & Stjernfelt, 1997). Rather, all and nature. This is so because culture is explicitly
four perspectives have a particular inherent basis for understood as an achievement of humans that tran-
the kind and range of possibilities/facilities, that enable scends their mere nature, it is built onto nature, but
and limit development. They are therefore character- is not nature itself (Gehlen [1978] therefore called
ized by different possibility-concepts or “attractors” culture the “second nature” of humans; Dux [1994]
(Eckensberger, 2010a, 2011a, 2011b: The species speaks of culture as a “connecting organization” to
(gene pool) provides the capacity inherent in this phylogeny). For this reason, the classical perspec-
pool for phylogeny, which was already conceptual- tives, which represent the natural science perspec-
ized by Mead (1934). But we distinguish addition- tives, must also be maintained.
ally the individual body (particularly the brain) by In Figure 17.5, the action (or resp. the co-action)
its potential for ontogeny. The agency develops com- is (like in Fig. 17.3) located in the center but between
petencies (cognitive, energetic, and affective) under- all four perspectives. This means that the action/co-
lying its performance, and culture has resources to action is assumed to inter-connect all four perspec-
offer, developed throughout history that can be used tives, thereby forming a meta-system or a dynamic
in actions. The four perspectives also imply different whole, in which (upward) emerging processes and
kinds of interpretations: The species is reconstructed (downward) selection processes are active between
by ultimate causes, the body by proximate causes, the all perspectives. To paint an admittedly speculative
agency – by proximate reasons, and culture by ultimate picture, it is assumed in Figure 17.5 that no single
reasons. (4) From every perspective there exist mutual perspective can be used as a “reductive explanation”
arrows toward the neighboring perspective, which are for any other perspective; rather, they emerge from
mediated by human action showing the emergence of each other and feed back into each other, and they
these perspectives and a downward selection process. do so via actions/co-actions.
This argument transcends earlier proposals The relation of the self-reflective and the cultural
(Eckensberger, 2002) that treated the different per- perspective via actions/co-actions has already been
spectives just as complementary36. In a recent paper, described (p. 880). So I will begin with the relation
Martin (2003) has come close to our intentions. between nature (species) and culture (cultural rules).
Figure 17.5 tries to illustrate the assumed inter- Although it is often argued that it is not fruitful
relationships. to separate culture and biology because they inter-
Figure 17.5 once more shows the splits act, it is not explained how this interaction is to be
between the four perspectives and the two cultures understood. Instead, cultures are often interpreted
of humanities and science. Of course, humans can- in biological terms and are explained by their biolog-
not escape being dual creatures, belonging to culture ical adaptation as “man’s peculiar elaborate way of

Mind Cultural rules


Individual / supra-individual
(cognitive/affective
Resources
schemata) em
erg of a cultural group
en (social, material
ce l) t)
Competence do
wn of cul tiona or symbolic)
of an agency wa ture (inten upp
rd s Ultimate reasons
proximate reasons ts/
selectio rain
.

n (const
ct
ru

ool

tion
st

volu ce
e o ty

selection of gene p

n
n

ling ions merge


enc nali

i
selection of bra
f
itio g merg ntio

co-e

Action
e
n e inte

Mental/ culture/
material Performance nature
Co-action
en ndit
co blin

b
co
a
a

rd
nd
en

ar d

nwa
nw

Species
w
do

Brain
w

selection of gene
do

(network, cells, rd po (gene pool)


cognitive/affective nwa ol
w
processes) do of brain struc Capacity
ce tures
en of the gene pool
Potential erg
em Ultimate causes
of an individual
Proximate causes Figure 17.5 Action Theory as conceptual link
Material/life between all four perspectives.

388 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


expressing the vertebrate biogram” (Count, 1958, were maintained, but killing, reproduction, and
p. 1049) or as an “epiphenomenon” and as “a prod- nourishment were transformed by culture although
uct of selfish individuals, who are forced to live in nature forms the enabling conditions for cultural
groups” (Chasiotis & Keller, 1994, p. 77, translation transformations and variations (upward emer-
LHE). Thereby the specifics of culture(s) as unique gence). However, culture also works on the gene
to humans is lost. In contrast, it seems to be more pool by downward selection processes. This not
fruitful to argue that despite phylogenetic continu- only happens because of human actions of selec-
ity in species, there is a qualitative shift in phylogeny, tive mating strategies (based on affiliation to social
when it comes to humans (some behavior patterns structure, caste, or religion; Eckensberger, Kapadia,
in animals that look like cultures are rather proto- & Wagels, 2000) but also by the process of indus-
cultures from this point of view). Although there trialization and work distribution between man and
is no doubt that humans possess a phylogenetic woman and emerging (intentional) family planning
continuity with other species, this does not imply and establishing (intentionally) a legal framework
that humans’ achievements and potentialities can be for family responsibilities, marriage and divorce,
explained sufficiently by ultimate causes, by phyloge- and by various means (actions) of birth control in
netic explanations. In fact, logically epistemological history (from killing offspring’s to religious rules/
continuity does not follow from empirical phyloge- prohibitions and different kinds of contraception
netic continuity (that humans can be explained on strategies, family planning, genetic counseling,
the same level and by the same mechanisms as other etc.). “Culture–gene–pool co-evolution” can only
species; see Eckensberger, 1978). Whether this qual- be understood from this point of view.
itative shift is characterized by tool use, language, When we examine the relation between the
teaching, or empathy is at present a matter of debate. mechanistic (here restricted to the neurophysio-
Even if some of these criteria can be shown to exist logical perspective)37 and phylogenetic perspective,
in a simple form in animals (Boesch & Tomasello, then it is first clear that the phylogeny of the human
1998; Janik & Zurbuehler, 2009), their quantita- brain is a complex process, and its understanding is
tive developments in humans represent a qualitative by necessity still speculative (Learey, 1994). It can
change. Even Dawkins (1976), who can be consid- neither be separated from environmental condi-
ered one of the fathers of socio-biology, realized the tions like climate change (Calvin, 2000) nor from
danger of an exclusive application of this approach the development of the body (blood vessels, shape
to humans, when he wrote at the end of his book of the skull) nor from the development of the upper
The Selfish Gene: “Be warned that if you wish, as I limbs—particularly the hand (instrumentality and
do, to build a society in which individuals cooper- expression in gestures, leading finally to language;
ate generously and unselfishly towards a common Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia, 2008)—nor from cultural
good, you can expect little help from biological nature. achievements like hunting and use of fire nor from
Let us try to teach generosity and altruism, because the development of agriculture and a more and
we are born selfish” (p. 203). Some time later, he more complex tool use, ending in industrialization
formulates: “We, alone on earth, can rebel against (Learey, 1994). The assumption is that these physi-
the tyranny of the selfish replicators” (he obviously ological developments probably emerged on the basis
refers to the genes here) (Dawkins, 1989, p. 201). of the increasing flexibility of human actions/co-actions
Psychologically the biophysiological processes as well in context (their biotope and culture) representing
as phylogenetic processes obtain their relevance only the “upward emergence” principle.38 Davies (2006)
through their meaning in actions, developed and considers natural selection in evolution a prominent
existing in cultural contexts. example of downward causation: “Selection takes
So, at some time during phylogeny and the place at the level of the organism, but it is the genes
history of the species homo sapiens sapiens, killing (or base-pair sequences) that get selected” (p. 33).
became homicide, reproduction strategies became Beyond this, the development of the human
romantic love or arranged marriage; eating was cul- species is not only supported by brain develop-
tivated by table manners and cultural styles (like ment but also by social coordinations via language
using forks, spoons, and knives, chopsticks, or eat- (communicative actions), which in themselves were
ing with hands); and simple nourishment was trans- probably triggered and supported by cultural devel-
formed into “nouvelle cuisine” and McDonalds. Yet opment (Deacon, 1997) It is an empirical datum
the species survived and species-specific conditions that, apart from a basically similar structure of all

ecken sberger 389


human brains, at present not two brains are iden- They form an emergent meta-structure with a
tical. In recent discussions in neuroscience, it has unique ontology, which, however, also influences
therefore been understood that cultural content the brain via actions in a cultural context (Singer,
(experiences of meaning and rule systems) leads to 2008). In a similar vein, Narvaez (2008) recently
changes in the brain from the very first second of discussed the neurobiological roots of moralities and
life, which creates the differences in single brains. even related these to present moral developmental
Therefore, in that sense physiological processes in theories, including Piaget and Kohlberg. Narvaez’
the brain cannot be separated from culture, and at paper is remarkable because she first reminds us
the same time they are conditions for actions. Even that physiological brain development leads to a
the neurophysiologist Singer recently spoke of the hierarchical system that is maintained. In fact, evo-
brain as a social organ (Singer, 2008). 39 So the poten- lutionary older brain structures (reptiles, early and
tialities of humans allow them to create conditions late mammals) are still present (and working) in
of living that may or may not be biologically (!) the human brain. According to her theorizing, they
adaptive. In other words: The focus on culture as imply particular behavioral systems, which she calls
a unique human phenomenon does not deny the triune ethics (reptiles: the ethics of security; early
utmost importance of biological- and neurophysio- mammals: the ethics of caring and bonding; late
logical-enabling conditions for human actions and mammals: the ethics of imagination). She secondly
therefore also for culture. clearly applies the process of emergence (Varela,
Consequently, within an action theory approach, 1992/1999) to the development of human conduct,
I propose that the physical perspective as well as the and she thirdly very creatively draws analogies even
biological perspective in particular also form the to stages of Kohlberg’s theory (cf. also Krebs 2005).
roots as enabling and limiting conditions for human It remains unclear, however, what these analogies
actions. These conditions can also be understood as represent ontologically. It is claimed here that the
potentialities and capacities, which set limits and can causal influence of these ancient brain structures
be exhausted by humans. On the other hand, they may only dominate in doing, under highly exis-
can also be controlled and intentionally changed to tentially threatening conditions and time pressure
a certain extent. (Eckensberger & Emminghaus, 1982), and that
Recent neurophysiological interpretations of they are ontogenetically transformed into a qualita-
actions in the context of new brain research, which tively different ontology by the upward emergent
refer to (biological) proximate causes for human principles. In fact, the present discussion is really
activities (Singer, 2000; Roth, 1997), therefore do only at its beginnings.
not explain cognitive processes as such, although
they clearly form their basis. Physiochemical (brain) Acknowledgments
conditions as enabling conditions can also be fruit- The chapter is dedicated to my teacher and “intellectual
fully discussed within this scheme—for example, father,” Ernst E. Boesch. Since it deals with the development of
the heated debate on the existence of free will Culture-Inclusive Action Theory and research that I conducted
during the last 35 years, first in Saarbrücken and later in Frankfurt
(already mentioned) and its relation to brain struc- many colleagues contributed to its theoretical and empirical basis
tures in physiology (e.g., Libet 1999; Baumeister, over these years (in alphabetical order): Judith Bettingen, Heiko
2008; Habermas, 2004; Singer, 2000). Particularly Breit, Peter Burgard, Thomas Döring, Gabriele Gaul, Elisabeth
Gustafson’s (2007) discussion of Wegner’s (2002) Kasper, Renate Kreibich-Fischer, Bernd Krewer, Anita Nieder,
book, The Illusion of Conscious Will, formulates the Heide Reinshagen, Ulrike Sieloff, Susanne Villenave-Cremer.
Heidi Keller and Ype Poortinga basically took a nomothetic per-
important insight that the fact that the subjective spective on Psychology in long discussions and thus forced me to
experience of will (conscious decision) seems to qualify my arguments in favour of action theory tremendously.
come after physiological activities in the brain (and I thank Ingrid Plath for her constructive criticism of the chapter
therefore is not assumed to be the real cause of an and for improving its English, as well as Jaan Valsiner and Nancy
action) would only be a problem for action theory, Murphy for their very constructive critical comments.
if actions are interpreted causally.40 This is, however,
not what I consider as productive: Self-reflection Notes
1. These authors—particularly Brandtstaedter—also incor-
and the free will are, in fact, assumed to emerge
porate the cultural context into their theoretical arguments. But
from complex brain structures (upward emergence), this is not accidental, because Brandtstaedter also was a student
but they are not of the same kind as the physiologi- of Boesch and obtained his degree as well as his PhD in Saar-
cal structures (Murphy, Ellis, & O’Connor, 2009). brücken. But he only turned to action theory in the 1990s.

390 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


2. One should remember that a “second tradition” of Rus- 11. In our earlier analysis, we did not accept system theory as
sian activity theory exists, with Vygotsky, Luria, and Leontiev as a solution to integrating agency and culture, because it contains
its most famous representatives, which overlaps with Action The- functional but not intentional processes. Since then, I have come
ory to a great extent, but also has specifics. This relation cannot to know “Dynamic Action Theory”, which particularly Juarrero’s
be elaborated here (for details, see Eckensberger, 1995). (1999) also applied to action theory and intentions. Heylighen
3. This attitude is particularly cultivated in Taoism. (2011) even argues that the basic ontological categories for sys-
4. An intentionally reflected rule following would be auton- tems theory are agents and actions (pp. 6–8, italics LHE). It was
omous. Narvaez (2009) recently discussed the role of intuition- particularly the discussion with Nancey Murphy on an Inter-
ism in moral theories and actions critically. I basically follow her national Symposium «Research across boundaries. Advances in
criticism. But in following Bastik’s (1982) definition of intuitive Theory-building» University of Luxemburg, June 16–19, 2010,
judgments as immediate, spontaneous judgments that are certain which encouraged me to propose the following arguments.
but not based on substantiate thinking, then our theory allows 12. Although most of these authors are now known in the
for intuitive judgments in lower “stages” that are justified (if English-speaking community, Holzkamp probably is not. But
forced to in interviews) with reference to rules. And additionally Tolman (1994) provides a good introduction to his work.
we assume that in adults intuitive decisions/judgments also exist, 13. This basic integration/synthesizing of agency and culture
but adults can reflect on them (see model of action). In fact, one through action has been pursued in my writings since 1979, but
can also argue that even Piaget describes a lot of intuitive think- Kim, one of the leading figures in the movement of indigenous
ing on higher stages of cognitive development as well. psychology, also follows this interpretation now (Kim & Park,
5. Without going into any detail, it may be noteworthy that 2006).
in the 1970s, German psychology also discussed the emerging 14. Boesch uses the term “should values” in this context. He
field of an “ecological and/or environmental psychology”. So kept this term from his early cybernetic orientation We avoid this
the reflections summarized here, went hand in hand with the term because of its “mechanistic” connotation.
discussion of “ecological” approaches in psychology and of the 15. So I make extensive use of Piaget’s (1970) theory—
status of “ecology” as human context—particularly the tension particularly reflective abstraction (but also to a certain extent the
between ecology (as a biological approach) and culture (Eck- implied processes of assimilation/accommodation and decentra-
ensberger, 1976, 1979c; Eckensberger & Burgard, 1977). The tion) is advocated as developmental principle or process that
paradigms distinguished were also applied in later discussions leads to a qualitative transformation of these standards during
of environmental psychology (Eckensberger, 2008a). Biological development in the sense of levels. Reflective abstraction is not
perspectives in ecology were distinguished from human action just a speculative construct but can be discovered in “real” cog-
theories (Eckensberger, 1978, 1979, 2002a; Vogel & Eckens- nitive transformations; see the documentary movie by Thiel &
berger, 1988). Schönbein (2000).
The fruitfulness of Action Theory in this context was based 16. For pragmatic and methodical reasons, we only apply
on the “fact” that human environment cannot be described solely two types of primary actions in our research. The philosopher
by “if–then conditions” (causality) but also requires “in order Peter Janich (2006) is much more differentiated.
to” conditions (finality). The (cultural) environment is build or 17. Taoism: Lin Yuang (1948); Hinduism and Buddhism:
influenced by humans with a purpose. Sinha (1996), Ohashi (1994); Confucianism: Ma (1988),
6. Later I tried to differentiate indigenous psychologies Hwang et al. (2003)
systematically from cultural psychology within this theoretical 18. Christian Boesch, the son of my teacher Ernst E. Boesch
frame, although this cannot be elaborated here (Eckensberger, (see also chapter on Primate Cultures in this volume).
2010a). 19. In interviews of 30 hunters, I analyzed whether the gun
7. This is more or less agreed upon today also in science (which is proverbially the “bride” of the soldier) also has a per-
of science (Nancy Murphy, personal communication, She also sonal symbolic meaning for hunters that goes beyond its instru-
pointed to Conant & Haugeland [2000] for this discussion). mental purpose by asking them what they would do and feel if
8. Feuerbach transformed the statement “God created the gun were damaged. All of them would simply get a new one
humanity in his/her image” into “Humanity created God in its without emotions of sadness or a sense of personal loss. However,
own image” (Buss, 1979, p. 3). they would have exactly these feelings if they were to lose a trophy
9. Of course, this distinction is not commonly agreed (deer head or fur). So the emotional personal attachment (in this
upon by all social scientists and philosophers. Martin and Sug- case) does not develop toward action means but rather toward the
arman (2009) summarize and reflect on that issue in a detailed symbolic representation of action results. Much more research is
paper and basically agree that the subject matter of social sci- necessary to understand these processes of subjectivation.
ence is unique. Without going into details here particularly 20. It is not by chance that Boesch dealt only peripherally
the argument that not all actions are reflective, and therefore with symbolism in ethics (Boesch, 1998), rather emphasizing it
a legitimate demarcation between natural and social sciences in aesthetics (Boesch, 1983, 1993).
concepts cannot be drawn. Kuhn (1991) is the reason why 21. For a basic critique of the underlying assumptions from a
I speak of the “potential” self-reflectivity of the agency. But cross-cultural perspective, see Rothbaum, Weisz, Pott, Myake &
I also insist that natural science need interpretation (Eckens- Morelli (2000).
berger, 2011). 22. Depending on the situation and cultural meaning: Bed-
10. In fact, the decision to use that term is rather recent. ford & Hwang (2003) with reference to guilt and shame. Kor-
Earlier we also used the term cultural action theory, which sounds nadt, (2002) with reference to shame/guilt and anger.
rather clumsy in German. Hence, we borrow this term culture 23. Imagine a boy sees that his girlfriend is kissed by another
inclusive from Valsiner’s (1987) concept of a “culture-inclusive guy. This would immediately trigger jealousy. But imagine that
psychology,” which is conceptually equivalent and can also be he learns that this other guy is the brother of the girl. The emo-
used in German. tion would vanish.

ecken sberger 391


24. An elaboration of these recent proposals is beyond the 36. It was particularly the discussion with Nancey Murphy
scope of this chapter. on an International Symposium «Research across boundaries.
25. The action levels of those days differed slightly, but the Advances in Theory-building» University of Luxemburg, June
foundation of the later scheme was laid. 16–19, 2010, which encouraged me to propose the following
26. This is one of the misunderstandings of some discus- arguments.
sions in cross-cultural psychology: Cultural psychology is not 37. I restrict my argument to the neurophysiological perspec-
restricted to that sub-branch but represents a different psychol- tive, characterized as “physical/causal (proximate)” in Figure 17.1
ogy. For a distinction and interrelationship of cross-cultural and summarized as “brain” in Figure 17.5 because also classical
psychology, indigenous psychologies and cultural psychology see learning theory as an example of the “mechanistic perspective”
Eckensberger (2010a). is increasingly interpreted in terms of neurophysiology. A more
27. The duality facts versus norms and cognition versus basic discussion of the principles that explain the “self-organiza-
affects are only mentioned here shortly; they are extensively dealt tion of matter and the evolution of biological macromolecules
with elsewhere (Eckensberger, 1993, 2006). (Eigen, 1971) which nullifies the distinction of matter and life
28. Whereas the stage descriptions published in various tables is far beyond the scope and level of this chapter. By applying
were hardly altered, central theoretical positions have undergone the Darwinian principle of selection to matter, life is explained
remarkable changes (Kohlberg, 1976; Kohlberg, LeVine, & Hewer, (reduced) to matter.
1983; Kohlberg, 1986). With respect to the stage assumptions, 38. The anatomist Rolshoven, for example, in explaining the
Kohlberg in a way became more Piagetian than Piaget himself, morphological change/development of the tegmentum argued
because in the course of time, his stage concept grew more and already in the 1960s: “What happens in the periphery [in body
more strict. Therefore, deviating from Piaget, a very important cri- activities], you will recognize it in the centre” (personal com-
terion for the validity of theory and method is the internal consis- munication).
tency of the stages (Colby, Kohlberg, Gibbs, & Lieberman, 1983). 39. “Wir müssen das Gehirn als Teil seines soziokulturellen
Also with reference to his methods, he became more and more Umfelds verstehen. Unser Gehirn ist nicht nur von genetischen
strict: Although he began with an interview following the clinical Dispositionen geprägt, sondern auch von unserer Erziehung, den
method of Piaget rather closely, his interview became more and Werten und moralischen Kategorien, die uns vermittelt wurden,
more standardized over the years, as did his scoring procedures und der Wechselwirkung mit anderen Gehirnen. Das Gehirn ist
(Colby & Kohlberg, 1987a, b). ein soziales Organ – man kann es nicht isoliert von der Umwelt
On the other hand, his theoretical arguments, clarifications, verstehen” (Singer, 2008). [We have to see the brain as part of the
and corrections over the years somehow did not “get through” to social environment. Our brain is not only shaped by genetic dis-
the empirical level—for example, the justice operations that serve positions, but also by our education, values and moral categories
to define the structure more precisely in Kohlberg’s later writings that we were taught, and the interaction with other brains. The
did not enter the logic of the scoring manual, nor did the distinc- brain is a social organ—one cannot understand it in isolation
tion of A- and B-subtypes of stages; they were first included into from the environment.]
the manual than removed again. 40. Where else should free decisions be prepared for, if not in
29. Although this term triggers different associations of tran- the brain?
scendental level (Kochetkova, personal communication), this
is of course not intended. It was taken from Burgards (1986)
reconstruction of Piaget’s terminology to the elaborated stage
References
Adorno, T & Horkheimer, M. (1987). Dialektik der Aufklärung.
model of Eckensberger & Burgard (1986).
Philosophische Fragmente. In: Gunzelin Schmid Noerr (Hrsg.):
30. Mainly translated by Uta S. Eckensberger into German.
Gesammelte Schriften. Band 5 Dialektik der Aufklärung und
31. This aspect is interpreted differently by different “schools”
Schriften 1940–1950. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.
(for example, see Wallner & Jandle, 2006). However, we use the
Albert, H. (1991). Traktat über die kritische Vernunft. Tübingen:
structural aspects of actions for humans as axiomatic.
Mohr.
32. A similar logic was applied later by Keller & Reuss
Ainsworth, M. D. S., Blehar, M. C. Waters, E. & Wall, S. (1978).
(1984), but for the first three stages of moral development only.
Patterns of attachment: A psychological study of the strange situ-
33. Autonomy and heteronomy are strictly connected to free
ation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
choice or absence thereof. This implies that heteronomy is not
Allesch, C. G., & Billmann-Mahecha, E. (1990). Perspektiven der
understood as some enforcement by an authority or an external
Kulturpsychologie. Heidelberg: Asanger.
rule. Instead it is the absence of autonomy. This implies that
Baltes, P. B., Nesselroade, J. R., & Reese, H. W. (1977). Life-span
intuitive judgments are also heteronomous because they do not
developmental psychology. Introduction in research methods.
represent reflective free choices. But decisions that follow exter-
Belmont: Wadsworth.
nal rules by free choice can also be autonomous.
Baltes, P. B. & Cornelius, S. W. (1977). The Status of dialectics
34. Much later, this dialectical interpretation of the develop-
in developmental psychology: Theoretical orientation ver-
ment of moral judgement was taken up by Minnameier (2001),
sus scientific method. In N. Datan & H. W. Reese (eds.),
who based his argument on Piaget and Garcia (1989) distinction
Life-span developmental psychology. Dialectical perspectives on
of “intra, inter, and trans” (which is quite similar to our dialec-
experimental research (pp. 122–134). New York: Academic
tical position). But he used perspective taking rather than action
Press.
structures .
Bandura, A. (1997). Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. New York:
35. This term looks like an oxymoron, but the expression
Freeman.
is intended to keep a constructivist attitude (perspective) while
Barbalet, J. W. (1997). The Jamesian theory of action. The
holding onto the assumption that the four perspectives differ in
Sociobiological Review, 45(1), 102–121.
their ontological presumptions.

392 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


Bhaskar, R. (1999). Roy Bhaskar interviewed. Retrieved July 31, interactions. Psychology and Developing Societies, 9(1),
2009 from http://www.raggedclaws.com/criticalrealism/ 35–64.
archive/rbhaskar_rbi.html Brandtstädter, J. (1998). Action perspectives on human develop-
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind: collected essays in ment. In W. Damon & R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of
anthropology, psychiatry, evolution, and epistemology. Chicago: child psychology. Vol. 1: Theoretical models of human develop-
University of Chicago Press. ment (5th ed., pp. 807–863). New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psychology. Brandtstädter, J. & Lerner, R. M. (Eds.) (1999). Action and
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(1), 14–19. self-development. Theory and research through the life span.
Beebe, B. & Lachmann, F.(1994). Representation and Thousanf Oaks, CA: Sage.
Internalization in Infancy: Three principles of salience. Breit, H. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1998). Moral, Alltag
Psychoanalytic Psychology, 11, 127–165. und Umwelt. In G. de Haan & U. Kuckartz (Hrsg.),
Bedford, O. & Hwang, K. K. (2003). Guilt and shame in Umweltbildung und Umweltbewußtsein. Forschungsperspektiven
Chinese culture: A cross-cultural framework from the per- im Kontext nachhaltiger Entwicklung (S. 69–89). Opladen:
spective of morality and identity. Journal for the Theory and Leske & Budrich.
Social Behavior, 33(2), 127–144. Breit, H. & Eckensberger, L. H. (2004a). Demokratieerziehung
Berger, L. & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social construction of real- zwischen Polis und Staat. In DIPF informiert, Nr. 6. S. 6–11.
ity. New York: Doubleday. Frankfurt/Main: TZ Verlagsgesellschaft.
Berry, J. W. (1980) Introduction to methodology. In H. Triandis Breit, H. & Eckensberger, L. H. (2004b). Die Faktizität des
& J. W. Berry, (Eds) Handbook of cross-cultural psychology. Normenbewusstseins. Eine entwicklungspsycho-logische
(Vol. 2) Methodology. Boston: Allyn & bacon Perspektive. In Christoph Lütge & Gerhard Vollmer
Bettingen, J., Eckensberger, L. H., Gaul. G., Krewer. B., Madert. (Hrsg.), Fakten statt Normen? Zur Rolle einzelwissenschaftli-
K., & Prowald, M (1993) Handbuch zur Auswertung von cher Argumente in einer naturalistischen Ethik (S. 207–224).
verschrifteten Therapie-/Beratungsgesprächen. Saarbrücken/ Baden-Baden: Nomos Verl.-Ges.
Berlin. Report to the BMBT /Bundesministerium für Forschung Breit, H.; Döring, T. & Eckensberger, L. H. (2003). Politics,
und Technologie. law and citizens’ responsibility - Justice judgements in the
Bischof, N. (1980). Aristoteles, Galilei, Kurt Lewin - und die everyday reconstruction of environmental conflicts. In H.
Folgen [Aristotle, Galilei, Kurt Lewin – and the conse- Breit, A. Engels, T. Moss & M. Troja (eds.), How Institutions
quences]. In W. Michaelis (Ed.), Bericht über den 32. Kongreß Change. Perspectives on Social Learning in Global and Local
der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Psychologie, Zürich 1980 Environmental Contexts (pp. 179–203). Opladen: Leske &
[Report about the 32nd congress of the German Association Budrich.
of Psychology, Zurich 1980] (pp. 17–39). Göttingen: Verlag Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
für Psychologie. University Press.
Blasi, A. (1985). Identity and the development of the self. Paper Bruner, J. (1996). The culture of education. Cambridge, MA:
presented at the Max Planck Institute, Munich, FRG, Oct. Harvard University Press.
3rd. 1985. Burgard, P. (1986) Das Verhältnis von Recht und Moral in ent-
Boesch, C. & Tomasello, M (1998). Chimoanzies and human wicklungspsychologischen Strukturtheorien des moralischen
culture. Contemporary Anthropology, 30, 591–604. Urteils—eine piagetianische Analyse. Phil. Dissertation.
Boesch, E. E. (1971). Zwischen zwei Wirklichkeiten. Prolegomena Universität des Saarlandes, Saarbrücken.
zu einer ökologischen Psychologie. Bern: Huber. Burgard, P. (1989). Consistencies in inconsistencies in moral
Boesch, E. E. (1976). Psychopathologie des Alltags - zur Ökopsychologie judgments: Microanalysis of stage variations within moral
des Handelns und seiner Störungen. Bern: Huber. dilemmas. Poster presented at the poster session ‘Moral
Boesch E. E. (1983). Das Magische und das Schöne. Stuttgart: Development’ at the tenth biennial meeting of the ISSBD,
Frommann-Holzbrook Jyväskylä, Finnland.
Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychol- Bühler, K. (1927). Die Krise der Psychologie., Jena: Verlag Gustav
ogy. Berlin: Springer. Fischer.
Boesch, E. E. (1993). The sound of the violin. In The Quarterly Buss, A. R. (1979). A dialectical Psychology. New York: Irvington.
Newsletter of the Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition. Campbell, D. T. (1974). “Downward causation” in hierarchically
15, 6–16. organized biological systems In F. J. Ayala and T. Dobzhansky
Boesch, E. E. (1998)). Sehnsucht – von der Suche nach Glück und (Eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology: Reduction and
Sinn. Bern: Huber related Problems (pp. 179–186). Berkeley and Los Angeles:
Boesch E. E. (2011). Culture: Result and Condition of Action. University of California Press.
In: J. Valsiner (Ed.) Oxford Handbook of Culture and Calvin, W. H. (1999). Der Schritt aus der Kälte. Klimakatastrophen
Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, und die Entwicklung der Menschlichen Intelligenz. München,
Boesch, E. E. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1969). Methodische Wien: Hanser.
Probleme des interkulturellen Vergleichs [Methodical prob- Canakis, J. & Schneider, K. (1989). Krebs – die Angst hat nicht
lems of cross-cultural comparisons]. In C. F. Graumann das letzte Wort. Stuttgart: Kreuz-Verlag.
(Hrsg.), Handbuch der Psychologie. Band 7: Sozialpsychologie, 1. Cassirer, E. (1921/1922) Der Begriff der symbolischen Formen im
Halbband. Theorien und Methoden (S. 515–566). Göttingen: Aufbau der Geisteswissenschafte, In E. Cassirer (1956) Wesen
Hogrefe. und Wirken des Symbolbegriffs. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and loss: Vol 1. Attachment. New Buchgesellschaft.
York: Basic Books. Chasiotis, A., & Keller, H. (1994). Evolutionary psychology and
Branco, A. U., & Valsiner, J. (1997). Changing methodolo- developmental cross-cultural psychology. In A.-M. Bouvy,
gies: A co-constructivist study of goal orientations in social F. J. R. Van de Vijver, P. Boski & P. Schmitz (Eds.), Journeys

ecken sberger 393


into cross-cultural psychology (pp. 68–82). Lisse: Swets & Schriften: Die geistige Welt- Einleitung in die Philosophie des
Zeitlinger. Lebens: Abhandlung zur Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften
Clemens, I (2007). Bildung - Semantik – Kultur. Zum Wandel der (Bd. 5, S. 139–240). Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht: Göttingen.
Bedeutung von Bildung und Erziehung in Indien. Frankfurter Dingler, H. (1928). Das Experiment. Sein Wesen und seine
Beiträge zur Erziehungswissenschaft, Monographien 7. Wirklichkeit. München: Reinhardt.
Christopher, J. C.& Bickhard, M. H. (2007). Culture, self and Dingler (1987). Methodik und Erkenntnistheorie statt
identity: Interactivist contributions to a metatheory for cul- Wissenschaftslehre. In U. Weiss (Hg.), Hugo Dingler:
tural psychology. Culture & Psychology, 13(3), 259–295. Aufsätze zue Methodik. Hamburg: Meiner.
Colby, A., & Kohlberg, L. (1987). The measurement of moral Döbert, R.& Nunner-Winkler, G. (1975). Adoleszenzkrise und
judgment. Vol. II: Standard issue scoring manual. Cambridge, Identitätsbildung. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
MA: Cambridge University Press. Döring, T., Eckensberger, L. H., Huppert, A., & Breit, H. (2008).
Colby, A., Kohlberg, L., Gibbs, J., & Lieberman, M. (1983). Risk management and morality in agriculture: Conventional
A longitudinal study of moral judgment. Monographs of the and organic farming in a German region. In M. J. Casimir
Society for Research in Child Development, 48(1–2, Serial No. & U. Stahl (Eds.), Culture and the changing environment.
200). Uncertainty, cognition, and risk management in cross-cultural
Cole, M. (1990). Culture psychology: A once and future disci- perspective. (pp. 79–106) Oxford & New York: Berghahn.
pline? In J. J. Berman (Ed.), Nebraska symposium on motiva- Dörner, D. & Kaminski, G. (1988). Handeln - Problemlösen -
tion 1989 “Cross-cultural perspectives” (pp. 273–335). Lincoln, Entscheiden. In K. Immelmann, K. R. Scherer, C. Vogel &
NB: University of Nebraska Press. P. Schmoock (Hrsg.), Psychobiologie. Grundlagen des Verhalten
Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology. A once and future discipline. (S. 375–414). Stuttgart, New York: Gustav Fischer Verlag.
Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Dux, G. (1994). Die ontogenetische und historische Entwicklung
Press. des Geistes. In G. Dux & U. Wenzel (eds.), Der Prozess der
Conant, J. & Haugeland J. (2000). Editors’ Introduction to Geistesgeschichte (pp. 173–224). Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays 1970–1993. Eckensberger, L. H. (1968). Unterrichtsprobleme an technisch-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. gewerblichen Ausbildungsstätten in Entwicklungsländern
Count, E. W. (1958). The biological basis of human society. [Teaching problems at technical and vocational schools in
American Anthropology, 60, 1049–1089. developing countries]. Stuttgart: Klett.
Cross, A. (1991). The crisis in Physics: Dialectical Materialism Eckensberger, L. H. (1970). Methodenprobleme der kulturvergle-
and Quantum Theory. Social Studies of Science, 21(4), ichenden Psychologie [Methodical problems in cross-cultural
735–759. psychology]. Saarbrücken: Verlag der SSIP-Schriften.
Csikszentmihalyi, Mihaly (2000): Das Flow-Erlebnis. Jenseits Eckensberger, L. H. (1972). The necessity of a theory for applied
von Angst und Langeweile im Tun aufgehen. 8., unv. Aufl. cross-cultural research. In L. J. Cronbach & P. D. Drenth
Stuttgart: Klett, (eds.), Mental tests and cultural adaptation (pp. 99–107). The
Danziger, K. (1997). Naming the mind: How psychology found its Hague: Mouton.
language. London: Sage. Eckensberger, L. H. (1973). Methodological issues of cross-cultural
D’Andrade, R. G. (1984). Cultural meaning systems. In R. A. research in developmental psychology. In J. R. Nesselroade
Shweder & R. A. LeVine (Eds.), Cultural theory: Essays on & H. W. Reese (eds.), Life-span developmental psychology:
mind, self, and emotion. (pp. 88–119). New York: Cambridge Methodological issues (pp. 43–64). New York: Academic Press.
University Press. Eckensberger, L. H. (1976). Der Beitrag kulturvergleichender
Dasen, P. R., & Heron, A. (1981). Cross-cultural tests of Piaget’s Forschung zur Fragestellung der Umweltpsychologie [The
theory. In H. C. Triandis & A. Heron (Eds.), Handbook contribution of cross-cultural psychology to questions
of cross-cultural psychology (Vol. 4, pp. 295–342). Boston: of environmental psychology]. In G. Kaminski (Hrsg.),
Allyn & Bacon. Umweltpsychologie - Perspektiven, Probleme, Praxis (S. 73–98).
Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural Stuttgart: Klett.
selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for Eckensberger L. H. (1977). „Soziale Kognition” und „sozial ori-
life. London: John Murray. entiertes Verhalten”. – Der Versuch einer Interpretaton durch
Datan, N. & Reese, H. W. (1977). Life-span developmental das Konzeot der Handlung. Newsletter Soziale Kognition 1,
psychology. Dialectical perspectives on experimental research. C 68–90. TU-Berlin.
New York: Academic Press. Eckensberger, L. H. (1978). Die Grenzen des ökologischen
Davies, P. C. W. (2006) The physics of downward causation. In Ansatzes in der Psychologie. (Erwiderung auf die Beiträge
P. Clayton & P. Davies (eds.) The re-emergence of emergence. von C. Trudewind: “Die ökologische Perspektive in der
The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion. (pp. 3552) Entwicklungspsychologie” und E. E. Boesch: “Kultur und
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Biotop” [The limitations to an ecological approach in psy-
Dawkins, R. (1976). The Selfish Gene. New York: Oxford chology (A response to the contribution of C. Trudewind on
University Press. “The ecological perspective in developmental psychology”
Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford and E. Boesch’s contribution on “Culture and biotope”)].
University Press. In C. F. Graumann (Hrsg.), Ökologische Perspektiven in der
Deacon, T. W. (1997). The symbolic species. The co-evolution of Psychologie (S. 49–76). Bern: Huber.
language and brain. New York: W.W. Norton Company. Eckensberger, L. H. (1979). A metamethodological evaluation
Dennet, D. C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston/New York/ of psychological theories from a cross-cultural perspective.
London: Little Brown. In L. H. Eckensberger, W. Lonner & Y. H. Poortinga (Eds.),
Dilthey, W. (1894/1968). Ideen über eine beschreibende und zer- Cross-cultural contributions to psychology (pp. 225–275). Lisse:
gliedernde Psychologie. In W. Dilthey (Hrsg.), Gesammelte Swets & Zeitlinger.

394 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


Eckensberger, L. H. (1984). On structure and content in moral Eckensberger, L. H. (1995). Activity or action: Two different
development. (Arbeiten der Fachrichtung Psychologie No. 92). roads towards an integration of culture into psychology?
Saarbrücken, Germany: Universität des Saarlandes. Psychology & Culture, 1, 67–80.
Eckensberger, L. H. (1986). Handlung, Konflikt und Reflexion: Eckensberger, L. H. (1996a). Auf der Suche nach den (verlorenen?)
Zur Dialektik von Struktur und Inhalt im moralischen Universalien hinter den Kulturstandards. In A. Thomas
Urteil [Action, conflict and reflection: On the dialec- (Hrsg.), Psychologie interkulturellen Handelns (S. 165–197).
tics of structure and content in moral judgments]. In Göttingen: Hogrefe.
W. Edelstein & G. Nunner-Winkler (Hrsg.), Zur Bestimmung Eckensberger, L. H. (1996b). Agency, action and culture: Three
der Moral. Philosophische und sozialwissenschaftliche Beiträge zur basic concepts for cross-cultural psychology. In J. Pandey,
Moralforschung (S. 409–442). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. D. Sinha & D. P. S. Bhawuk (Eds.), Asian contributions to cross-
Eckensberger, L. H. (1987). Zur Dialektik von Form und Inhalt cultural psychology (pp. 72–102). New Delhi, India: Sage.
moralischer Urteile [The dialectics of form and contents in Eckensberger, L. H. (2001a). Psychology of action theory. In N.
moral judgments]. In P. Wapnewski (Hrsg.), Jahrbuch des J. Smelser & P. B. Baltes, (eds.), International Encyclopedia
Wissenschaftskollegs zu Berlin (S. 255–265). Berlin: Siedler. of the Social & Behavioural Sciences (vol. 1, pp. 45–49).
Eckensberger, L. H. (1988). Zur Rolle des moralischen Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.
Urteils im Aggressions- und Aggressions-hemmungsmotiv: Eckensberger, L. H. (2001b) The beginning of social cogni-
Eine Diskussion der Kornadtschen Zweikomponenten tion and self. Paper presented at the National Seminar on
Theorie der Aggression aus der Sicht der kognitiven “Theoretical Approaches to early Development: Implications
Entwicklungspsychologie [The role of moral judgments in for Intervention” January 09 – 11, 2001, Department of
the aggression motive and aggression inhibition motive: A Human Development and Family S, Faculty of Home sci-
discussion of Kornadt’s two-component theory of aggression ence. M.S. University of Baroda, Vadodara. India studies.
from a cognitive developmental perspective]. Psychologische Eckensberger, L. H. (2002a). Paradigms revisited: From
Beiträge, 30, 373–414. incommensurability to respected complementarity. In
Eckensberger, L. H. (1989a). A bridge between theory and H. Keller, Y. H. Poortinga, & A. Schölmerich (Eds.), Biology,
practice, between general laws and contexts? Psychology and culture, and development: Integrating diverse perspectives
Developing Societies, 1, 21–35 (pp. 341–383). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
Eckensberger, L. H. (1989b). Consistencies in inconsistencies in Press.
moral judgments: Microanalysis of stage variations within Eckensberger, L. H. (2002b). Bildungsziel Demokratie. Eine ent-
moral dilemmas. Poster presented at the poster session ‘Moral wicklungspsychologische Perspektive. In L. H. Eckensberger,
Development’ at the tenth biennial meeting of the ISSBD, B. Tröger & H. Zayer (Hrsg.), Erinnerungen – Perspektiven.
Jyväskylä, Finnland. 50 Jahre Deutsches Institut für Internationale Pädagogische
Eckensberger, L. H. (1990a). On the necessity of the culture Forschung (S. 94–117). Frankfurt am Main: DIPF.
concept in psychology: A view from cross-cultural psychol- Eckensberger, L. H. (2003a). Wanted: A contextualized psy-
ogy. In F. J. R. van de Vijver & G. J. M. Hutschemaekers chology. A plea for cultural psychology based on action
(eds.), The investigation of culture. Current issues in cultural psychology. In T. S. Saraswathi (ed.), Cross-cultural perspec-
psychology (pp. 153–183). Tilburg: Tilburg University Press. tives in human development. Theory, research, and applica-
Eckensberger, L. H. (1990b). From cross-cultural psychology to tion (pp. 70–101). Delhi, India: Sage.
cultural psychology. The Quarterly Newsletter of the Laboratory Eckensberger, L. H. (2003b). Kultur und Moral. In A. Thomas
of Comparative Human Cognition, 12(1), 37–52. (Hrsg.), Kulturvergleichende Psychologie (S. 309–345, zweite,
Eckensberger, L. H. (1993a). Normative und deskriptive, struk- erweiterte Auflage). Göttingen: Hogrefe.
turelle und empirische Anteile in moralischen Urteilen: Ein Eckensberger, L. H. (2004). Development applied: In search
Ökonomie-Ökologie-Konflikt aus psychologischer Sicht. of an applicable culture informed developmental theory:
[Normative and descriptive, structural and empirical parts Reflections prompted by four Bulletin articles. Cross-Cultural
in moral judgments. An economy-ecology-conflict from Psychology Bulletin, 38(1–2), 25–34.
a psychological perspective]. In L. H. Eckensberger & Eckensberger, L. H. (2006a). Contextualizing moral judgment:
U. Gähde (Hrsg.), Ethische Norm und empirische Hypothese Challenges of interrelating the normative (ought judgments)
(S. 328–379) [Ethical norm and empirical hypothesis]. and the descriptive (knowledge of facts), the cognitive and
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. the affective. In L. Smith & J. Vonèche (eds.), Norms in
Eckensberger, L. H. (1993b). Zur Beziehung zwischen den human development (pp. 141–168). Cambridge: Cambridge
Kategorien des Glaubens und der Religion in der Psychologie University Press.
[On the relationship between the categories of faith and religion Eckensberger, L. H. (2006b). The mutual relevance of indigenous
in psychology]. In Gramkrelidze, T.V. (Hrsg.), Brücken. Beiträge psychology and morality. In Uichol Kim, Kuo-Shu Yang &
zum Dialog der Wissenschaften aus den Partneruniversitäten Kwang-Kuo Hwang (eds.), Indigenous and Cultural Psychology.
Praha, Saarbrücken, Sofia, Tbilissi und Warszawa (S. 49–104). Understanding People in Context (pp. 225–245). Heidelberg:
[Bridges. Contributions to a dialog between the sciences of Springer (International and Cultural Psychology).
the partneruniversities Praha, Saarbrücken, Sofia, Tblissi and Eckensberger, L. H. (2007a). Morality from a cultural psychol-
Warszawa]. Tbilissi, Universitätsdruck. ogy perspective. In G. Zheng, K. Leung, & J. Adair (eds.),
Eckensberger, L. H. (1993c). Moralische Urteile als handlung- Perspectives and Progress in Contemporary Cross-Cultural
sleitende normative Regelsysteme im Spiegel der kultur- Psychology (pp. 25–34). Beijing: China Light Industry Press.
vergleichenden Psychologie [Moral judgments as normative Eckensberger, L. H. (2007b) Culture and self: An action theory
rule-systems for action as reflected in cross-cultural psychol- perspective. Invited lecture at the international conference.
ogy]. In A. Thomas (Hrsg.), Einführung in die kulturvergle- “The culturalization of the self.” University of Chemnitz, Nov.
ichende Psychologie (S. 259–296). Göttingen: Hogrefe. 28–Dec. 1.

ecken sberger 395


Eckensberger, L. H. (2008a). Kultur und Umwelt [Culture and und Präzisierung des Aggressionskonzeptes sowie einiger
environment]. In V. Linneweber & E.-D. Lantermann (Hrsg.), empirischer Befunde. In R. Hilke, & W. Kempf (Eds.),
Enzyklopädie der Psychologie. Serie IX Umweltpsychologie. Aggression. Naturwissenschaftliche und kulturwissenschaftliche
(pp. 237–272). Göttingen: Hogrefe. Perspektiven der Aggressionsforschung (pp. 208–280). Bern:
Eckensberger, L. H. (2008b). Werte und Moral. In J. Straub, A. Huber.
Weidenmann und D. Weidemann (Hrsg.), Handbuch für Eckensberger, L. H., & Gähde, U. (Eds.). (1993). Ethische
interkulturelle Kommunikation und Kompetenz. Grundbegriffe, Norm und empirische Hypothese. Frankfurt/M., Germany:
Theorien, Anwendungsfelder (pp. 505–515). Stuttgart: Metzler. Suhrkamp.
Eckensberger L. H. (2008c) Epilog. In Plath, I. Graudenz, I. Eckensberger, L. H. & Kreibich-Fischer, R. (1994). Affektive
& H. Breit (eds.). Kultur – Handlung – Demokratie. und kognitive Verarbeitung des Krankheitsgeschehens bei
(pp. 195–342). Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. krebskranken Patienten. Jahrbuch für Psychoonkologie, 1994,
Eckensberger, L. H. (2010a). Kulturvergleichende Psychologie, 41–76.
indigene Psychologien und Kulturpsychologie: Eine harmon- Eckensberger, L. H. & Meacham, J. (1984). The essentials
ische oder disharmonische Familienbeziehung? Bemerkungen of action theory. A framework for discussion. Human
aus Sicht der Entwicklungspsychologie. In: B. Mayer, & Development, 27, 166–172.
H.-J. Kornadt (Hrsg.) Psychologie – Kultur – Gesellschaft. Eckensberger, L. H. & Plath, I. (2006a). Soziale Kognition.
(pp. 175–212). Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. In Wolfgang Schneider & Beate Sodian (Hrsg.), Kognitive
Eckensberger, L. H. (2010b). Kontextualisierung moralis- Entwicklung (Enzyklopädie der Psychologie, C.V. Bd. 2,
cher Urteile – etwas anderes als moralische Urteile plus S. 409–493). Göttingen: Hogrefe.
Kontextvariablen. In B. Latzko & T. Malti (Hrsg.), Moralische Eckensberger, L. H. & Plath, I. (2006b). Beratung und Kultur.
Entwicklung und Erziehung in Kindheit und Adoleszenz In Christoph Steinebach (Hrsg.), Handbuch Psychologische
(S. 13–41). Göttingen: Hogrefe. Beratung (S. 70–95). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.
Eckensberger, L. H. (2011a). Cross-cultural differences as Eckensberger, L. H., & Plath, I. (2006c). Möglichkeiten und
meaning systems. In F. J. R. van de Vijver, A. Chasiotis, & Grenzen des ‘variablenorientierten’ Kulturvergleichs: Von
S. M. Breugelmans, (eds.), Fundamental questions in der Kulturvergleichenden Psychologie zur Kulturpsychologie
cross-cultural psychology. (pp. 407–441). Cambridge, UK: [Possibilities and limitations of a variable-based compari-
Cambridge University Press. son of cultures: From cross-cultural psychology to cultural
Eckensberger, L. H. (2011b) Culture inclusive human action in psychology]. In H. Kaelble & J. Schriewer (Eds.), Vergleich
psychological theorizing: Troublemaker and trouble-shooter und Transfer - Komparatistik in den Sozial-, Geschichts- und
- and beyond? Integral Review. Manuscript submitted for Kulturwissenschaften (S. 55–99). [Comparison and trans-
publication. fer— comparability in the social, historical, and cultural sci-
Eckensberger, L. H. & Breit, H. (2003). Kann das Schulrecht ohne ences]. Frankfurt am Main, New York: Campus.
Moral auskommen? In H. Döbert, B. von Kopp, R. Martini Eckensberger, L. H. & Reinshagen, H. (1978). Überlegungen
& M. Weiß (Hrsg.), Bildung vor neuen Herausforderungen zu einem Strukturmodell der Entwicklung des mor-
(S. 23–34). Neuwied: Luchterhand. alischen Urteils. In L. Montada (Hrsg.), Brennpunkte
Eckensberger, L. H. & Breit, H. (2006). Zur Förderung moralis- der Entwicklungspsychologie (S. 267–280). Stuttgart:
cher Haltungen in der Berufsbildung. Anregungsbedingungen Kohlhammer.
für die Entwicklung einer moralischen Haltung durch Eckensberger, L. H., & Reinshagen, H. (1980). Kohlbergs
Erziehung. In Fritz Oser, & Maja Kern (Hrsg.), Qualität der Stufentheorie der Entwicklung des Moralischen Urteils: Ein
beruflichen Bildung – Eine Forschungsbaustelle (S. 398–435). Versuch ihrer Reinterpretation im Bezugsrahmen handlung-
Bern: hep-Verl. (Berufsbildungsforschung Schweiz. Bd. 2). stheoretischer Konzepte. In L. H. Eckensberger & R. K.
Eckensberger, L. H. & Burgard, P. (1977). Ökosysteme in Silbereisen (Eds.), Entwicklung sozialer Kognitionen: Modelle,
interdisziplinärer Sicht [Ecosystems as viewed from an Theorien, Methoden, Anwendung (pp. 65–131). Stuttgart,
interdisciplinary perspective]. Arbeiten der Fachrichtung Germany: Klett-Cotta.
Psychologie, Universität des Saarlandes, Nr. 49. Eckensberger, L. H., & Römhild, R. (2000). Kulturelle Einflüsse
Eckensberger, L. H., & Burgard, P. (1983). The cross-cultural [Cultural influences]. In M. Amelang (Ed.), Enzyklopädie der
assessment of normative concepts: Some considerations on Psychologie. Band 4: Determinanten individueller Unterschiede
the affinity between methodological approaches and pre- [Enzyclopaedia of psychology. Vol. 4: Determinants of indi-
ferred theories. In S. H. Irvine & J. W. Berry (Eds.), Human vidual differences] (pp. 667–731). Göttingen, Germany:
assessment and cultural factors (pp. 459–480). New York: Hogrefe.
Plenum Press. Eckensberger, L. H., & Zimba, R, F. (1997). The develop-
Eckensberger, L. H. & Burgard, P. (1986). Zur Beziehung zwis- ment of moral judgment. In J. W. Berry, P. R. Dasen &
chen Struktur und Inhalt in der Entwicklung des moralischen T. S. Saraswathi (eds.), Handbook of cross-cultural psychology.
Urteils aus handlungstheoretischer Sicht [On the relation- Vol. 2: Basic processes and human development (pp. 299–338).
ship between structure and contents in the development of Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
moral judgment as viewed from an action-theoretical per- Eckensberger, L. H., Döring, T. & Breit, H. (2001). Moral dimen-
spective]. Arbeiten der Fachrichtung Psychologie, Universität sions in risk evaluation. In G. Böhm, J. Nerb, T. McDaniels
des Saarlandes, Nr. 77. & H. Spada (eds.), Environmental Risks: Perception, Evaluation
Eckensberger, L. H. & Chang S.-C. (in press). Education for and Management, Research in Social Problems and Public Policy
becoming a good citizen in the West and in Asia: An Action (vol. 9, pp. 137–163). Oxford: Elsevier.
Theory Approach. In U. Kim (Ed.) Asia’s miracle of education. Eckensberger, L. H., Kapadia, S. & Wagels, K. (2000). Social
Eckensberger, L. H., & Emminghaus, W. B. (1982). cognitive domains of thinking in marriage partner selec-
Moralisches Urteil und Aggression: Zur Systematisierung tion: The Indian context. Paper presented at a symposium

396 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


on the development of moral reasoning and diversity in the Feuerstein, R. (1989). Cultural differences versus cultural dep-
conceptions of the being. 16th ISSBD meeting, July 11–14, rivation. Invited lecture at the 2nd Regional (Circum medi-
Beijing. tarraneum) Conference of the International Association for
Eckensberger, L. H., Kreibich-Fischer, R. & Gaul, G. (1998). Cross Cultural Psychology. Amsterdam, June 27–July 1,
“Bewußtmachung eigenen Bedürfnisse” als Therapieziel 1989.
bei Krebskranken: Rechtfertigung von Egoismus oder Filipp, H.-S. (1980). Entwicklung von Selbstkonzepten.
Entwicklung von Autonomie? In: U. Koch, J. Weis (eds.) Zeitschrift für Entwicklungspsychologie und Pädagogische
Rehabilitation von Krebskranken (S. 447–458). Stuttgart: Psychologie, 2, 105–125.
Schattauer. Fillip, S.-H. & Ferring, D. (1998). Who blames the victim? –
Eckensberger, L. H., Krewer, B. & Kasper, E. (1984). Simulation Kausal und Verantwortlichkeitszuschreibungen im Umfeld
of cultural change by cross-cultural research: Some metame- einer Krebserkrankung. In U. Koch & J. Weis (Eds.),
thodological considerations. In K. A. McCluskey & Krankheitsbewältigung bei Krebs und Möglichkeiten der
H. W. Reese (eds.), Life-span developmental psychology: Unterstützung (pp. 25–36). Stuttgart: Schattauer.
Historical and generational effects in life-span human develop- Fischer, G. (2003) Dialektische Psychologie und Psychoanalyse.
ment (S. 73–107). New York: Academic Press. Journal für Psychologie, 1, 4–11.
Eckensberger, L. H., Kreibich-Fischer, R., Gaul, G. & Fowler, J. W. (1991). Stufen des Glaubens. Gütersloh: Mohn.
Schnurre, M. (1990). Affektive und kognitive Verarbeitung (Original 1981: Stages of faith. New York: Harper & Row.
des Krankheitsgeschehens krebskranker Patienten [Affective Frese, M. & Sabatini. J. (eds.) (1985) Goal directed behaviour.
and cognitive processes in coping with cancer]. In The concept of action in psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
U. Koch & F. Potreck-Rose (Hrsg.), Krebsrehabilitation und Freud, S. (1923). Das Ich und das Es. Leipzig, Wien, and Zürich:
Psychoonkologie (S. 157–174). Berlin: Springer. Internationaler Psycho-analytischer Verlag.
Eckensberger, L. H., Kasper, E., Nieder, A., Schirk, S. & Sieloff, Frezzo, M. (2004). The ambivalent role of psychology and
U. (1990). “Wes Brot ich eß . . . ” oder worauf Urteile beruhen. psychoanalysis. In R. E. Lee & I. M. Wallerstein (eds.),
Der Konflikt zwischen Ökonomie und Ökologie [The vested Overcoming the two cultures. Science versus the humanities
interests underlying moral judgments - conflicting interests in the modern world system (pp. 73–86). Boulder, London:
between economy and ecology]. Forschungsmitteilungen der Paradigm Publications.
DFG, 1, 23–24. [English: Vested interests or bases for judge- Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays.
ments: Conflict of economy and ecology. Reports of the DFG, New York: Basic Books.
3, 27–28] Gehlen, A. (1978). Der Mensch. Seine Natur und seine Stellung
Eckensberger, L. H., Sieloff, U., Kasper, E., Schirk, S., & Nieder, in der Welt (1940). Wiesbaden, Germany. [Mankind. Their
A. (1992). Psychologische Analyse eines Ökonomie-Ökologie- nature and position in the world].
Konflikts in einer saarländischen Region: Kohlekraftwerk Gergen, K., Gülerce, A., Misra, G. & Lock, A. (1996).
Bexbach. In K. Pawlik & K. H. Stapf (Hrsg.), Umwelt und Psychological science in cultural context. American
Verhalten. Perspektiven und Ergebnisse ökopsychologischer Psychologist, 51(5), 496–498.
Forschung (S. 145–168). Bern: Verlag Hans Huber. Gielen, U. (1991). Kohlberg’s moral development theory. In
Eckensberger, L. H. & Kreibich-Fischer, Gaul, G. Bettingen, L. Kuhmerker & U. Gielen & R. L. Hayes) (eds.), The
J. Madert, K., & Prowald, M. (1993). Affektive und kog- Kohlberg legacy for the helping professions (pp. 18–38).
nitive Verarbeitung des Krankheitsgeschehens bei krebsk- Birmingham, AL: R.E.P.
ranken Patienten: Detailergebnisse von fünf Einzelfällen. Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and
Saarbrücken/Berlin: Report to the BMBT /Bundesministerium women’s development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
für Forschung und Technologie. Press.
Edwards, C. P. (1975). Societal complexity and moral develop- Glaser, B. G. & Strauss, A. L. (1967). The discovery of grounded
ment: A Kenian study. Ethos, 3, 505–527. theory. Strategies for qualitative research. London: Aldine.
Edwards, C. P. (1981). The comparative study of the develop- Glick, J. (1985) Culture and cognition revisited. In E. D. Neimark
ment of moral judgment and reasoning. In R. H. Munroe, & J. L. Newman (eds.), Moderators of competence (pp. 99–115).
R. I. Munroe, & B. B. Whiting (Eds.), Handbook of cross-cul- Hillsdale. NJ: Erlbaum.
tural human development (pp. 501–528). New York: Garland Goldmann, A. (1970). A theory of human action. Englewood
STPM Press. Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Edwards, C. P. (1986). Cross-cultural research on Kohlberg’s Gollwitzer, P. M. (1990). Action phases and mind-sets. In
stages: The basis for consensus. In S. Mogdil & C. Mogdil E. T. Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino (eds.), Handbook of moti-
(eds.), Lawrence Kohlberg: Consensus and controversy vation and cognition: Foundations of social behavior (Vol. 2,
(pp. 419–430). London: The Falmer Press. pp. 53–92). New York: Guilford Press.
Eigen, M. (1971) Selforganzzation of matter and the evolution Görnitz, T. & Görnitz, B. (2010) Towards a new relation of
of biological macromolecules Die Naturwissenschaften, 58, mankind to science and spirituality. Paper presented in
465–523. Across boundaries. Advances in Theory Building. International
Emmerche, C., Koppe, S., & Stjernfelt, F. (1997) Levels, Symposium 16 – 19 June (2010) University of Luxemburg.
emergence and three versions of downward causation. In Graumann, C. F. (1996). Wollen und können – Überlegungen
P. B. Andersen, Emmeche, N.O. N. O. Finnemann & zu deren Wechselwirkung. In M. Cranach, & K. v. Foppa
P. V. Christainsen (eds.) Downward causation: Mind, bod- (Hg.), Freiheit des Entscheidens und Handelns. Ein Problem
ies, and matter. (pp. 13–34). Aarhus, Denmark: Aarhus der nomologischen Psychologie (S. 70–85): Heidelberg.
University Press. Springer
Erikson, E. H. (1959). Identity and the life-cycle. New York: Graumann, C. F. (2000). Kontext als Problem der Psychologie.
International University Press. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 208, 55–71.

ecken sberger 397


Greenfield, P. M. (2002). The mutual definition of culture and Integral Review, http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/Papers/ECCO-
biology in development. In H. Keller, Y. H. Poortinga, & A. paradigm.pdf. Manuscript submitted for publication.
Scholmerich (eds.), Between culture and biology: Perspectives on Hook, S. (1957). Dialectical materialism and scientific method.
ontogenetic development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Manchester, Eng. Special Supplement to the Bulletin of the
Press. Bulletin of the Committee on Science and freedom.
Greenfield, P. & Bruner, J. (1966). Culture and cognitive growth. Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. W. (1969). Dialektik der
International Journal of Psychology, 1, 89–107. Aufklärung. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt/Main.
Groeben, N. (1986). Handeln, Tun, Verhalten als Einheiten einer Holzkamp. K. (2006). Wissenschaft als Handlung. Schriften III.
verstehend-erklärenden Psychologie. Wissenschaftstheoretischer Hamburg: Argument Verlag.
Überblick und Programmentwurf zur Integration von Huebner, A., & Garrod, A. (1991). Moral reasoning in a karmic
Hermeneutik und Empirismus. [Action, conduct, behav- world. Human Development, 34, 341–352.
iour as units of an understanding/explanatory psychology. Hwang, K. K. Liu, T.-W. Han, Der-Yan, & Chen. Sue-Huel
A theory of science overview and programmatic state- (2003). Somatisation, emotional expression and confucian
ment on the integration of hermeneutics and empiricism] Ethics in Chinese culture. In W.-O. Phoon & I. Macindoe
Tübingen, Germany: Francke. (eds.), Untangling the thread: Perspectives on Mental health in
Gülerce, A. (1997). Change in the process of change: Coping Chinese Communities. Taiwan: Transcultural Mental Health
with indeterminism. In A. Fogel, M. A. Lyra, & J. Valsiner Centre.
(eds.), Process of Change and Indeterminism (pp. 39–64). James, W. (1897). The will to believe. New York: Longmans,
Hillsdale, NJ: Plenum. Green & Co.
Gustafson, D, (2007). Neuroscience of action and non-causal Janet, P. (1889). Automatisme. L’automatisme psychologique. Paris:
theories. Philosophical Psychology, 20(3), 367–374. Alcan (quoted after (Schwartz, 1951).
Haan, N. (1977). Coping and defending. Processes of Self- Janik V. M. & Zuberbuehler K. (2009) Vom Ursprung der
environment organization. New York: Academic Press. Sprache: Kommunikation im Tierreich. Lecture in the
Haan, N. Smith, M. B. & Block, J. (1968). Moral reasoning of Center for Advanced Studies in Berlin. 9. Dezember
young adults: Political-social behaviour, family background, Janich, P. (2006) Die Heterogonie der Zwecke als Problem der
and personality correlates. Journal of Personality and Social Psychologie. In G. Jüttemann (Hrsg.), Wilhelm Wundts
Psychology, 10, 183–201. anderes Erbe. Ein Missverständnis löst sich auf (S. 88–101).
Habermas, J. (1976). Moralentwicklung und Ichidentität. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht.
In J. Habermas (Hg.), Zur Rekonstruktion des historischen Juarrero, A. (1999) Dynamics in action. Intentional behaviour in
Materialismus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. complex systems. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Habermas, J. (1984). 11. Erläuterungen zum Begriff des kommu- Kaminski, G. (1982). What beginner skiers can teach us about
nikativen Handelns (1982). In J. Habermas (Hrsg.), Vorstudien actions. In M. von Cranach & R. Harré (eds.), The analysis of
und Ergänzungen zur Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns action (pp. 99–114). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(S. 571–606). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. Kane, R. (1989) The significance of the free will. Oxford; New
Habermas, J. (2004). Um uns als Selbsttäuscherzu entlarven bedarf York: Oxford University press.
es mehr. Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, am 15 Nov. 2004 Kant, I. (1966). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. In
Hacker, W. (1986). Arbeitspsychologie. Berlin: Deutscher Verlag H. Paton (ed.), The moral law. London: Hutchinson.
der Wissenschaft. Keller, M. & Reuss, S. (1984) An action theoretical reconstruc-
Hare, B. (2007). From nonhuman to human mind. What tion of the development of social cognitive competence.
changed and why? Current Directions in Psychological Science, Human Development, 27, 211–220.
16(2), 60–64. Kegan, R. (1982). The evolving self. Harvard: Harvard University
Haste. H. (2008). Constructing competence: Discourse, Press.
identity and culture. In Plath, I. Graudenz, I. & H. Breit Kesselring, T. (1981). Entwicklung und Widerspruch. Ein Vergleich
(Eds) Kultur – Handlung – Demokratie. (pp. 109–132). zwischen Piagets genetischer Erkenntnistheorie und Hegels
Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. Dialektik [Development and contradiction: A comparison of
Hartmann, D. & Janich, P. (1996). Methodischer Kulturalismus. Piaget’s genetic epistemology and Hegel’s dialetics]. Frankfurt
Zwischen Naturalismus und Postmoderne. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp.
Heckhausen, H. (1997). Developmental regulation across adult- Kim, U., & Park, Y. S. (2006). The scientific foundation of
hood: primary and secondary control of age related chal- indigenous and cultural psychology. In Kim, U., Yang,
lenges. Developmental Psychology, 33, 176–187. K-S., Hwang, K-K. (eds.), Indigenous and cultural psychol-
Heckhausen, H., Gollwitzer P. M. & Weinert F. E. (Hrsg.) (1987): ogy. Understanding people in context (pp. 27–48). New York:
Jenseits des Rubikon. Der Wille in den Humanwissenschaften. Springer.
Berlin: Springer. Kimmel, M. (2010). The arc from bodily experience to cultural
Heckhausen, H. (19892) Motivation und Handeln (2. Auflage). concepts. Paper presented in “Across boundaries. Advances in
Berlin: Springer Verlag Theory Building. International Symposium June 16–19, 2010.
Heron, A., & Kroeger, E. (1981). Introduction to developmental University of Luxemburg.
psychology. In H. C. Triandis & A. Heron (eds.), Handbook Kitchener, K. S. (1983). Cognition, metacognition, and episte-
of cross-cultural psychology (Vol. 4, pp. 1–15). Boston: Allyn & mic cognition. Human Development, 26, 222–232.
Bacon. Kohlberg, L. (1958). The development of modes of moral think-
Herskovits, M. G. (1948). Man and his works. New York: ing and choice in the years 10 to 16. Unpublished doctoral
Knopf. dissertation, University of Chicago.
Heylighen, F. (2011). Self-organization of complex, intelligent sys- Kohlberg, L. (1976). Moral stages and moralization: The cogni-
tems: The ECCO paradigm for transdisciplinary integration. tive-developmental approach. In T. E. Lickona (ed.), Moral

398 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


development and behavior: Theory, research, and social issues LatzkoB. & Malti T. (Hrsg.) (2010). Moralische Entwicklung und
(pp. 31–55). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. Erziehung in Kindheit und Adoleszenz. Göttingen: Hogrefe.
Kohlberg, L. (1978). The meaning and measurement of moral Lazarus, R. S. & Launier, R. (1978). Stress-related transac-
development. Invited address at the Convention of the American tions between person and environment. In L. A. Pervin &
Psychological Association, Toronto, Canada. M. Lewis (eds.), Perspective in interactional psychology
Kohlberg, L. (1986). A current statement on some theo- (pp. 287–327). New York: Plenum.
retical issues. In S. Modgil & C. Modgil (eds.), Lawrence Leahy, R. L. (1985). The development of the self. New York:
Kohlberg: Consensus and controversy (pp. 485–546). London, Academic Press.
Philadelphia: The Falmer Press. Leakey, R. (1994). The origin of mankind. New York: Basic Books.
Kohlberg L & Kramer, R. B. (1969). Continuities and disconti- Lerner, A. (1987). Krebs und Psyche. München: Goldmann.
nuities in childhood and adult moral development. Human Linton, R. (1954). The problem of universal values. In
Development, 12, 93–120. R. F. Spencer (ed.), Method and perspective in anthropology
Kohlberg, L., Boyd, D., & LeVine, C. (1986). Die Wiederkehr (pp. 145–168). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota
der sechsten Stufe: Gerechtigkeit, Wohlwollen und der Press.
Standpunkt der Moral. In W. Edelstein & G. Nunner- Lei, T., & Cheng, S. W. (1984). An empirical study of Kohlberg’s
Winkler (Eds.), Zur Bestimmung der Moral: Philosophische theory and scoring system of moral judgment in Chinese
und sozialwissenschaftliche Beiträge zur Moralforschung society. Unpublished manuscript. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
(pp. 205–240). Frankfurt/M., Germany: Suhrkamp. University.
Kohlberg, L., LeVine, C., & Hewer, A. (1983). Moral stages: The Lewin, K. (1930/31). Der Übergang von der aristotelischen
current formulation of Kohlberg’s theory and a response to critics. zur galileischen Denkweise in Biologie und Psychologie.
Basel: Karger. Erkenntnis, 1, 421–460 (= Annalen der Philosophie, Bd. 9).
Kornadt, H. J. (1982). Aggressionsmotiv und Aggressionshemmung. (Republished: Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft,
Band I. Bern: Huber. 1971).
Kornadt, H. J. (2002) Biology, culture and child rearing: The Lewin, K. (1951). Field theory in social science. New York: Harper
development of social motives. In H. Keller, Y. Poortinga and Brothers.
& A. Schölmerich (eds.). Between culture and psychology. Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness
(pp. 191–211). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Studies, 6, 47–57.
Krebs, D. L. (2005). The evolution of morality. In D. Buss (ed.), Levins, S. & Lewontin, R. (1985). The Dialectical Biologist.
Evolutionary psychology handbook. (pp. 747–774). New York: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wiley. Loevinger, J. (1976). Ego development. London: Jossey-Bass.
Krewer, B. (1990). Psyche and culture - Can a culture-free Lonner, W. J. & Hayes, S. A. (2007). Discovering cultural psy-
psychology take into account the essential features of chology. Advances in cultural psychology. Charlotte, NC:
the species homo sapiens ? Quarterly Newsletter of the Information Age Publishing.
Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognitive Development, Leontiev, A. N. (1977) Tätigkeit, Bewußtsein und Persönlichkeit.
12, 24–37. Stuttgart: Klett Cotty.
Krewer, B. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1990). Cultural identity and Ma, H. K. (1988). The Chinese perspectives on moral judgment
political events. In D. M. Keats, D. Munro & L. Mann development. International Journal of Psychology, 23, 201–227.
(eds.), Heterogeneity in cross-cultural psychology (pp. 216–231). Mack, W. (2006). Wundts programmatisches Erbe. In
Amsterdam/Lisse: Swets & Zeitlinger. G. Jüttemann (Hrsg.), Wilhelm Wundts anderes Erbe. Ein
Krewer, B. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1991). Selbstentwicklung Missverständnis löst sich auf (pp. 232–243). Göttingen:
und kulturelle Identität [The development of personal and Vandenhoek & Ruprecht.
cultural identity]. In K. Hurrelmann & D. Ulrich (Hrsg.), Mahoney, M. J. (2004). Constructivism and why is it growing?
Neues Handbuch der Sozialisationsforschung (S. 573–594). Contemporary Psychology, 49, 360–363.
Weinheim: Beltz. Malpass, R. S., & Poortinga, Y. H, (1986). Strategies for design
Krewer, B., Momper, M. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1984). Das and analysis. In W. J. Lonner & J. W. Berry (eds.), Field
Saarland war zumeist Objekt der Geschichte [For the most methods in cross-cultural research (pp. 47–83). Beverly Hills,
part, the Saarland has been the object of historical change]. CA: Sage.
Der Bürger im Staat, 34, 178–186. Martin, J. (2003). Emergent persons. New Ideas in Psychology,
Krishnan, L. (1999). Socialization and cognitve-moral influences 21, 85–99.
on justice rule preferences: The case of Indian culture. In Martin, J. & Sugarman, J. (1999). The psychology of human possi-
T. S. Saraswathi (ed.), Culture, socialization & human devel- bilities and constraints. New York: State University.
opment (pp. 188–212). New Delhi: Sage. Martin, J. & Sugarman, J (2009). Does interpretation in psy-
Kuhn, T. S. (1970a). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: chology differ from interpretation in natural science? Journal
University of Chicago Press. of the Theory of Social Behaviour, 39(1), 20–37.
Kuhn, T. S. (1991). The natural and the social sciences. In Martin, J., Sokol, B. W. & Elfers, T. (2008). Taking and coordi-
J. F. Bohrman, D. R. Hiley, & R. Shusterman (eds.), The nating Perspectives: From prereflective interactivity through
interpretative turn: Philosophy, Science, Culture. (pp. 17–249). reflective intersubjectivity to metareflective sociality. Human
Ithaka, NY: Cornell University Press. Development, 51, 294–317.
Kuhn, D. Langer, J., Kohlberg, L. & Haan, N. S. (1977). The Martin, J., Sugarman, J. H., & Thompson, J. (2003). Psychology
development of formal operations in logical and moral devel- and the question of agency. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
opment. Genetic Psychology Monographs. 95, 97–188. Maslowski, R., Breit, H., Eckensberger, L. H., & Scheerens, J.
Lapsley, D. K. & Power, F. F. (1985). Self, Ego and Identity. (2009). http://www.dipf.de/de/publikationen/publikationen
New York: Springer. datenbank/show/detail?string=dld_set.html%3FFId%

ecken sberger 399


3D7890. In J. Scheerens (ed.), Informal learning of active Ohashi, R. (1994). Kire: Das “Schöne” in Japan. Philosophisch-
citizenship at school (pp. 11–24). Dordrecht: Springer Science ästhetische Reflexionen zu Geschichte und Moderne. Köln:
+ Business Media. DuMont.
Mead, G. (1934). Mind, self and society from the standpoint of a Oppenheimer, L. & Valsiner, J. (1991). The origins of action.
social behaviourist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Interdisciplinary and international perspectives. New York:
Mehlberg, H. (1955) The method of science, its range and Springer.
limits. Science and Freedom. London: Martin Secker & Oser, F. & Gmünder, P. (1984). Der Mensch. Stufen seiner
Warburg. religiösen Entwicklung. Zürich: Benziger.
Meixner, U. (2004). The two sides of being. A reassessment of psy- Overton, W. F. (2007). A coherent metatheory for dynamic
cho-physical dualism. Paderborn: Mentis. systems: relational organicism-contextualism. Human
Meggle, G. (1993) Semantische, emoirische und normative Development, 50, 154–159.
Aspekte eines Begriffs des Kommunikativen Handelns. In Parsons, T. (1937/1968). The structure of social action. New York:
L. H. Eckensberger & U. Gähde (Hrsg.), Ethische Norm und Free Press.
empirische Hypothese (S. 197–212) [Ethical norm and empiri- Piaget, J. (1932/1965). The moral Judgment of the child. New York:
cal hypothesis]. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Free Press.
Mey, G. & Mruck, K. (1998). A traveller trough psychology. An Piaget, J. (1970). Piaget’s theory. In P. H. Mussen (ed.), Carmichael’s
interview with Jaan Valsiner. Cultural Psychology: Ideas and manual of child psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 703–732). New York:
scholars [Forschungsbericht aus der Abteilung Psychologie Wiley.
Band 1]. Berlin: TU Berlin. Piaget, J. (1974). La prise de conscience. Paris: Presses Universitaires
Miller, J. G. (1994). Cultural diversity in the morality of caring: de France.
Individually-oriented versus duty-based interpersonal moral Piaget, J. & Garcia, R. (1989). Psychogenesis and the history of
codes. Cross-Cultural Research, 28(1), 3–39. science. New York: Columbia University Press.
Minnameier, G. (2001). A new “stairway to moral heaven”? A Plath, I. & Eckensberger, L. H. (2008). Counselling as cul-
systematic reconstruction of stages of moral thinking based tural practice: Reflections on counselling across cultures
on a Piagetian “logic” of cognitive development. Journal of from the perspective of cultural psychology. Social Practice/
Moral Education, 30, 317–337. Psychological Theorizing, Article 8, http://sppt-gulerce.boun.
Modgil S. & Modgil C. (Eds.),(1986). Lawrence Kohlberg, edu.tr/article8.aspx
Consensus and controversy. Philadelphia: The Falmer Press. Poortinga, Y. H. (2002) Behaviour-culture relationships and
Molz, M. (2010). Toward an integral pluralism in sociocultural ontogenetic development. In: H. Keller, Y. H. P. Poortinga
research. Unpublished Doctoral Dissertation, University of & A. Schölmerich (eds.), Between culture and biology. perspec-
Luxembourg. tives on ontogenetic development (pp. 320–340). Cambridge,
Molz, M. & Edwards, M. G. (2011). Crossing Boundaries, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Stimulating Creativity: The Horizon of Integral Meta- Popper. K. (1937/1963). What is dialectics? In Karl K. Popper
Studies. In A. Giri (Ed.), Pathways of creative research: towards (ed.), Conjeczures and Refutations (pp. 312–335). London:
a festival of dialogues. New Delhi: Shipra. Manuscript sub- Routledge.
mitted for publication. Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic
Murphy, N. (2011) Non reductive physicalism. Integrating sci- Books.
ence, theology, and Philosophy of mind. Integral Review. Popper, K. R. (1977). Part I. In: K. R. Popper & J. C. Eccles
Manuscript submitted for publication. (Eds.), The self and its brain (pp. 3–223). Berlin, Germany:
Murphy, N., Ellis, G & O’Connor T. (2009). Downward causa- Springer-Verlag.
tion and the neurobiology of free will. New York: Springer. Price-Williams, D. R. (1980). Towards the idea of a cultural psy-
Narvaez, D. (2008). Triune ethics: The neurobiological roots chology: A superordinate theme for study. Journal of Cross-
of our multiple moralities. New Ideas in Psychology, 26, Cultural Psychology, 11, 77–88.
95–119 Ratner, C. (1991). Vygotsky’s Sociohistorical Psychology and Its
Narvaez, D. (2009). Truthiness is Fatal: The complexity of Contemporary Applications. New York: Springer/Plenum.
mature moral functioning. Association for Moral Education. Reese, H. W., & Overton, W. F. (1970). Models of development
Netherlands: Utrecht. and theories of development. In L. R. Goulet & P. B. Baltes
Narvaez, D., Panksepp, J., Schore, A., & Gleason, T. (in press). (eds.), Life-span developmental psychology: Research and theory
The Value of the Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness (pp. 115–145). New York: Academic Press.
for Gauging Children’s Well-Being. In D. Narvaez, J. Riegel, K. (1979). Foundations of dialectical psychology. New York:
Panksepp, A. Schore, & T. Gleason (Eds.), Evolution, early Academic Press.
experience and human development: From research to practice Rizzolatti, G. & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Empathie und
and policy. New York: Oxford University Press. Spiegelneurone. Die biologische Basis des Mitgefühls. Frankfurt/
Nauck, B. (2010). Fertilitätsstrategien im interkulturellen Main: Suhrkamp.
Bereich. Value of children, Ideale und angestrebte Kinderzahl Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking. New York: Oxford
in zwölf Ländern. In B. Mayer, & H.-J. Kornadt (Hrsg.), University Press.
Psychologie – Kultur – Gesellschaft (pp. 213–238). Wiesbaden: Rockeach, M. (1969). The role of values in public opinion
Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. research. The Public Opinion Quarterly, 32, 547–559.
Ng, S. H. & Liu, J. H. (2000). Cultural revolution in psychol- Roth, G. (1997). Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit: Kognitive
ogy. Asian Journal of Social Psychology, 3, 289–293. Neurobiologie und ihre Philosophischen Konsequenzen [The
Nisan, M., & Kohlberg, L. (1982). Universality and variation in brain and its reality. Cognitive neurobiology and its philo-
moral judgment: A longitudinal and cross-sectional study in sophical consequences] (5th ed.). Frankfurt am Main,
Turkey. Child Development, 53, 865–876. Germany: Suhrkamp.

400 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


Rothbaum, F. Weisz, J., Pott, M., Myake, K., & Morelli, G. Snarey, J. (1985). Cross-cultural universality of socio-moral
(2000). Attachment and culture: Security in the United development: A critical review of Kohlbergian research.
States and Japan. American Psychologist, 55, 1093–1104. Psychological Bulletin, 97(2), 202–232.
Rychlak, J. F. (1976). Dialectics: Humanistic rationale for behav- Snarey, J., & Keljo, K. (1991). In a Gemeinschaft voice: The
iour development. New York: Karger. cross-cultural expansion of moral development theory. In
Rychlak, J. F. (1993). A suggested principle of complementarity W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (eds.), Handbook of moral
for psychology. In theory, not method. American Psychologist behaviour and development, Vol. I: Theory (pp. 395–424).
Association, 48(9), 933–942. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Schmidt, H. D. (1972). Allgemeine Entwicklungspsychologie. Snow, C. P. (1963). The two cultures and the scientific revolution.
Berlin: VEB Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Schwartz, L. (1951). Die Neurosen und die dynamische Psychologie Sorokin, P. A. (1958). Integralism is my philosophy. In
von Pierre Janet. Basel, Switzerland: Schwabe. W. Burnett (Ed.), This is my philosophy. (pp. 180–189).
Searle, J. R. (1980). The intentionality of intention and action. London: Ruskin House.
Cognition Sciences, 4, 47–70. Stephan, A. (2002) Emergence, irreducibility, and downward
Setiono, K. (1994). Morality from the viewpoint of Javanese causation. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 65, 77–93.
tradition. Paper presented at the Symposium “Eco-Ethical Stern, D. N. (1985). Affect attunement. In J. D. Call, E. Galeson
Thinking From A Cross-Cultural Perspective” Kirkel, Germany. & R. L. Tyson (eds.), Pioneers of infant psychiatry. Vol. 2. New
Shweder, R. A. (1980). Rethinking culture and personality the- York: Basic books.
ory. Part III: From genesis and typology to hermeneutics and Stern, D. N. (1995). The motherhood constellation: An intensified
dynamics. Ethos, 8, 60–94. view of parent-infant psychotherapy. New York: Basic Books.
Shweder, R. A. (1990). Cultural psychology - what is it? In Stern, E. (1920). Probleme der Kulturpsychologie. Zeitschrift für
J. W. Stigler, R. A. Shweder & G. Herdt (eds.), Cultural psy- die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 75, 267–301.
chology: Essays on comparative human development (pp. 1–43). Straub, J. (2006). Understanding cultural differences: Relational
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. hermeneutics and comparative analysis in cultural psychol-
Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J. G. (1987). Culture ogy. In: J. Straub, D. Weidemann, C. Kölble, B. Zielke (eds.),
and moral development. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (eds.), The Pursuit of meaning: Advances in cultural and cross-cultural psy-
emergence of morality in young children (pp. 1–83). Chicago: chology (S. 163–213). Bielefeld: Transcript.
Chicago University Press. Straub, J. & Werbik, H. (1999). Handlungstheorie. Begriff
Sieloff, U., Schirk, S., Kasper, E., Nieder, A., & Eckensberger, und Erklärung des Handelns im interdisziplinären Diskurs.
L. H. (1988). Eine textanalytische Auswertungstechnik zur Frankfurt/Main: Campus.
Erfassung von Abwehr und Bewältigung beim moralischen Tappan, M., Kohlberg, L., Schrader, D., Higgins, A., Armon,
Argumentieren. Arbeiten der Fachrichtung Psychologie, Nr. C., & Lei, T. (1987). Heteronomy and autonomy in moral
118, Saarbrücken: Universität des Saarlandes. development: Two types of moral judgments. In A. Colby &
Simão, L. M. (2001). Boesch’s symbolic action theory in interac- L. Kohlberg (Eds.), The measurement of moral judgment. Vol.
tion. Culture and Psychology, 7(4), 485–493. I: Theoretical foundations and research validation (pp. 315–
Simão, L. M. (2002). Noção de objeto, concepção de sujeito: Freud, 380). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Piaget e Boesch. Lívia Costa Coelho de Souza, Nelson Ernesto Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Coelho Junior. (1ª ed.) São Paulo: Casa do Psicólogy. University Press.
Simão, L. M. (2005). Bildung, Culture and Self. A possible Thiel, T. & Schmidt-Schönbein, C. (2000). “From direct
dialogue with Gadamer, Boesch and Valsiner? Theory & encounter with objects to reflection on actions - A cinematic
Psychology, 15(4), 549–574. reconstruction of an individual cognitive process” Potsdam).
Singer, W. (2000). Vom Gehirn zum Bewusstsein [From brain Documentary movie presented at the Jean Piaget Society, June
to consciousness]. In N. Elsner & G. Lüer (eds.), Das Gehirn 1–3 Montréal. 2000.
und sein Geist [The brain and its spirit] (pp. 189–204). Tietjen, A., & Walker, L. (1984). Moral reasoning and leadership
Göttingen, Germany: Wallsteinverlag. among men in a Papua New Guinea village. Unpublished man-
Singer, W. (2008). Das Abenteuer unseres Bewusstseins. Frankfurter uscript, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada.
Allgemeine Zeitung, 29. April, Nr. 100: Feuilleton 37 Tolman, C. W. (1994). Psychology, Society, and Subjectivity:
Sinha, D. (1996). Cross-cultural psychology: The Asian scenario. An Introduction to German Critical Psychology. London:
In J. Pandey, D. Sinha, & D. P. S. Bhawuk (eds.), Asian Routledge.
Contributions to cross-cultural psychology (pp. 20–41). New Tomasello, M. (2001). Cultural transmission. A view from
Delhi: Sage Publications India Pvt Ltd. chimpanzees and human infants. Journal of Cross-Cultural
Smedslund, J. (1984). The invisible obvious: Culture in psychol- Psychology, 32(2), 135–146.
ogy. In K. M. J. Lagerspetz & P. Niemi (eds.), Psychology in Tomasello, M., Call, J. & Hare, B. (2003). Chimpanzees under-
the 1990th. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publisher. stand psychological states: The question is which ones and to
Smedslund, J. (1988). Psycho-Logic. Berlin: Springer. what extent. Trends in Cognitive Science 7, 153–156.
Smedslund, J. (2009). The mismatch between current research Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., & Liszkowski, U. (in press) A
methods and the nature of psychological phenomena. new look at infant pointing. Developmental psychology
What researchers must learn from practitioners. Theory & Trevarten, C. (1993). The function of emotions in early infant
Psychology, 19, 778–794. communication and development. In J. Nadel & Camaioni
Snarey, J. (1983). The social and moral development of Kibbutz (eds.), New perspectives in early communication development
founders and abras: A cross-sectional and longitudinal cross- (pp. 48–81). London: Routledge.
cultural study (Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University, Ulich, D. (1987) Krise und Entwicklung. Zur Psychologie der
1982). Dissertation Abstracts International, 43(10), 3416b. seelischen Gesundheit. München: PVU.

ecken sberger 401


Valsiner, J. (1987). Culture and the development of children’s Vuyk, R. (1981). Overview and critique of Piaget’s genetic episte-
action. New York: Wiley. mology. New York: Academic Press
Valsiner, J. (1988). Culture is not an independent variable: A Vygotsky, (1927/1987). The historical meaning of the crisis in
lesson from cross-cultural research for “mainstream” psychol- Psychology: A Methodological investigation. New York: Plenum
ogy. Paper presented at the symposium The contributions of Press
cross-cultural psychology to mainstream psychological the- Wallner, F. & Jandl, M. J. (2006). The importance of construc-
ory (convener W. Lonner) at 24th International Congress of tive realism from the indigenous psychology approach.
Psychology, Sydney, Australia, September 2. In U. Kim, K.-S. Yang & K.-K. Hwang (eds.), Indigenous
Varela, F. (1992/1999). Ethical know-how: Action, wisdom, and and Cultural Psychology. Understanding People in Context
cognition. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. (pp. 49–72). Heidelberg: Springer (International and
Vasudev, J. (1986). Kohlbergs Universalitätspostulat aus indis- Cultural Psychology).
cher Sicht. In W. Edelstein & G. Nunner-Winkler (eds.), Werbik, H, (1985). Psychonomie und Psychologie. Internal
Zur Bestimmung der Moral (pp. 145–177). Frankfurt/M., report No. 8, Psychologisches Institut, Üniversität Nürnberg.
Germany: Suhrkamp. Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of the free will. Cambridge, MA:
Villenave-Cremer, S. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1985). On the role MIT Press.
of affective processes in moral judgment. In M. W. Berkowitz Wertsch, J. V. (1985). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind.
& F. Oser (eds.), Moral Education: Theory and application. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(pp. 175–194). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Weyers, S., Sujbert, M., & Eckensberger, L. H.( 2007). Recht
Vetter, G. (1989). Krebs und Seele. Zürich: Oesch-Verlag. und Unrecht aus kindlicher Sicht. Die Entwicklung recht-
Vine, I. (1986). Moral maturity in socio-cultural perspective: Are sanaloger Strukturen im kindlichen Denken und Handeln.
Kohlberg’s stages universal? In S. Modgil & C. Modgil (eds.), Münster: Waxmann.
Lawrence Kohlberg: Consensus and controversy (pp. 431–450). White, L. (1959). The evolution of culture: The development of civi-
London, Philadelphia: The Falmer Press. lization to the fall of Rome. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Vogel, C. & Eckensberger, L. H. (1988). Arten und Kulturen - Whiting, J. W. W. (1954) The cross-cultural method. In
Der vergleichende Ansatz. In K. Immelmann, K. R. Scherer, G. Lindzey (ed.). The handbook of social psychology, vol.1
C. Vogel & P. Schmook (Hrsg.), Psychobiologie - Grundlagen (pp. 523–531). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
des Verhaltens (S. 563–606). Stuttgart: Gustav Fischer Verlag. Wright, G. H. v. (1971). Explanation and understanding. Ithaca,
von Cranach, M. (1991). Handlungsfreiheit und Determination New York: Cornell University Press
als Prozeß und Erlebnis. Zeitschrift für Sozialpsychologie, 22, Yuang, L. (1948). Taosim. Die Weisheiten des Laotse. Frankfurt/
4–21. Main. Fischer.

402 c ulture-i nclusi ve act i o n t he ory


CHAPTER

The Other in the Self: A Triadic Unit


18
Lívia Mathias Simão

Abstract
In this chapter, the notion of the other in the self is proposed as a triple holistic developmental structure. This
proposal aims to account for aspects that have not been considered for understanding the constitution
and maintenance of the self–other–culture processual structure yet. The structure here proposed is a
derivation of Herbst’s (1995) model of co-genetic logic. Additionally, it takes the self as an actional self
(Boesch, 1991) dialogically oriented by the other (Marková, 2003; Linell, 2009). From this perspective,
self–other interactions are approached under the focus of how the triple holistic developmental structure
tacitly (Polanyi, 1966/2009) constrains (Valsiner,1998) them in a feed-forward process. In this dynamics,
new forms of cultural fields for symbolic actions (Boesch, 1991) can emerge. Some concluding issues, an
illustrative analysis, and some future developments concerning the triple holistic developmental structure
approaching the other in the self are also presented.
Keywords: triple holistic developmental structure, self, other, culture, actional self, dialogism, constraints

“(. . .) Triste noção tem da realidade quem a limita ao


orgânico, e não põe a idéia de uma alma dentro das
estatuetas e dos lavores. Onde há forma há alma”

“(. . .) Gloomy notion about reality have those who


limited it [only] to what is organic, not putting a soul
inside the statuettes and handcrafts.
Where is a form, there is a soul”
—(Fernando Pessoa, 1997, “Livro do Desassossego”
[Book of Disquieting], 416)

The main proposal of this chapter is to discuss ever-changing movement, which makes it an always
the psychological notion of “the other in the self,” re-emerging structure.
arguing that it embraces a threefold relationship
among self, other, and culture. This relationship The Threefold Relationship of Self,
takes the form of a holistic developmental struc- Other, and Culture
ture. As belonging to the realm of developmental The notion of the self has a very broad and
phenomena, this structure is characterized for an long history in philosophy and psychology. The

403
vagueness and ambiguity of this notion can be con-
sidered very useful for heuristic purposes. However,
precisely because of its fuzziness, it is necessary
that one makes explicit the theoretical–conceptual
frame in which the term is being used (Stam, 2006).
Usually, in the domains of philosophy and human
sciences, the notion of self leads implicitly to the
notion of someone else, the non–self, who main- Figure 18.1 The form of primary distinction (extracted from
tains some relation with the self. However, although Herbst, 1995, p. 68).
conceived as partners in a relation, self and other are
usually treated as if they were independently sepa-
and the distinction made that is represented by the
rated instances at the organic and/or psychological
boundary. At this stage, we have nothing more than
levels.
a form in an empty space. In most general form what
Besides, the socio-cultural aspects of the self–
has become generated in this way is a unit consisting
other relation is conceived as a something outside
of not less than three elements (. . .) In this case,
of them, as if culture were a kind of independent
primary distinction that generates the form (the
variable directly influencing self and other, which
inside) together with the empty space (the outside),
are consequently taken as dependent variables.
and the boundary separating and distinguishing
Synthetically speaking, this view posits a dyadic rela-
inside and outside, is only one particular realization
tionship among the elements (e.g., self and other as
of the primary distinction (. . .).
dependent variables, and culture as the independent
(p. 67)
one); or even a triadic relationship (e.g., self and
other immersed in culture; or self and other creating Figure 18.1 shows Herbst’s form of primary
culture as well as being constrained by it). However, distinction.
none of them accomplish to consider self, other, The triadic unit so formed has the following
and culture in a co-genetic threefold relationship, properties:
as I am here proposing based on Herbst’s (1995)
1. It is Co-genetic: The three elements that are
co-genetic logic.
generated come into being together.
Taking into account the psychological notion of
2. It is Nonseparable: We cannot take the components
“the other in the self ” requires consideration that
apart (. . .) we cannot have them initially apart and
the relationship among self, other, and culture is con-
them put them together” (. . .).
formed according to one of the main characteristics
3. It is Nonreducible: There cannot be less than three
of the dynamically contextual human functioning.
components. If any one component (. . .) is taken
This dynamics can be accounted by a derivation
away, then all three components disappear together”.
of Herbst’s (1995) model of co-genetic logic. This
4. It is Contextual: None of the components have
logic, maybe as an alternative to the classical one,
individually definable characteristics. In fact, they
has not been considered for understanding the con-
have no intrinsic characteristics that belong to them.
stitution and maintenance of the self (other) cul-
(. . .) the components are individually undefined, but
ture processual structure until now. This alternative
each is definable in terms of the two others. (Herbst,
logic, by putting in relief the distinction among the
1995, pp. 67–68)1
parts of a structure while, at the same time, keep-
ing them joined as a triadic unit, may give us new
The Threefold Co-Genetic Relationship
ways of understanding the relationships among self,
of Self–Other–Culture
other, and culture.
The Actional Self
According to Herbst’s (1995) co-genetic logic,
Instead of being a static, crystallized entity, the
any structure is formed, from its very origin, by a
notion of self will be taken here as an actional self,
primary process of differentiation among its future
who is always in interlocution with someone else:
compounding relational parts. According to him:
the other, or the I itself, in the I–myself interac-
When a distinction is made, a boundary comes into tions. Therefore, there will always be someone else
being together with the inside and the outside of for me as an actional self: the one who has created
a form. What is generated in this way is a triadic the masterpiece that disquiets me, the one who has
co-genetic unit consisting of the inside and outside composed the music that now delights me, the one

404 th e oth er i n t he se lf
who directed the film that made me so anguished similarity and difference, even under the perceptive
yesterday, the one who gave me a gift, who made me human laws we are submitted to as belonging to the
angry, who sheltered me. The actional self is, then, same species (Crossley, 1996; Boesch, 2011).
someone who is always in companion of someone The perspective of the dialogism, which pre-
else, co-creating their cultural world in both time supposes the other orientation of the self as a basic
and place. Of course, as highlighted by Boesch assumption in human sciences, is certainly also
(2011), unfortunately this does not always happen implied here:
in an ethically promising world.
A definitional point in dialogism is the assumption
Fortunately, the companionship between self
that human nature and human life are constituted
and other keeps the proper tension of relation-
in interrelations with “the other,” that is, in other
ships among different participants, even when the
orientation. Humans are always interdependent
involved persons can neither realize nor admit their
with others, although the degree and kinds of
differences, nor feel the thusly created tension. I am
interdependence will of course vary with individuals,
using the term fortunately in aiming to highlight
cultures and situations.
the fact that thanks to the tension caused by the
(Linell, 2009, p. 13)
difference, the other may subvert the self ’s sym-
bolic actional contribution, and vice versa, may be Thus, a relationship of mutual constitutive
preventing each one of the presumptions of being interdependence is configured among the self, the
the only and sovereign actor in the process of the other—as representative of their culture—and the
meaning-making of personal and collective culture expectations they have one about the other, their
(Simão, 2011, in press). experiences diverging from the expected and the
relational meaning among them. In this dynamic
Culture and Other in the Self field of relationships, the self ’s and the other’s
Culture, on its turn, is taken here in a sense that meaning-making will occur according to the extent
channels our sight to some specific aspects of the to which they can position themselves in respect one
social life, which are directly related to the dynamics to the other as someone who gives opportunities for
of the I–Other relationship. The notion of culture is constructing new meanings, as well as supporting
concerned with the interactive social field, which, them in the social milieu (Simão, 2003).
par excellence, modulates symbolic actions in con- In such a co-genetic emergent processual struc-
textualized time and place. Culture allows some ture, the relationships are engendered thanks to the
persons’ symbolic actions, and prevents others, so I’s symbolic actions in its I–I and I–Other interac-
engendering a myriad of tensional situations in the tions in each particular and temporary socio-cul-
symbolic world. In such an extent, the self–other tural milieu. The I’s symbolic action, by selectively
relationships are understood as they act as modula- making distinctions from its experienced world,
tors, and are modulated by, the experiences of the generates, at each moment and place of its life,
actional self in its cultural field. These formulations diverse triadic units formed by the three elements
are based on Boesch’s (1991) notion of culture, that come into existence jointly and inseparably: the
which clearly and consistently backgrounds and self, the other, and the relationship between them.
pervades all his oeuvre (Boesch, 2011). It is in the core of this third element—the relationship
The relationship between culture and self occurs between self and other—that cultural objects (in the
through the figure of the other, this other being Boeschian broad sense) are engendered, through nego-
concretely present, distant, or even imaginary but, tiations in face of the tensional difference realized by
in any case, always the figure who makes remarks, the self and the other as differences between them, as
sings praises, reproves—in sum, acts in a multiplic- represented by Figure 18.2.
ity of contextual ways, verbally and nonverbally, As far as the social interaction is one of the main
directly or indirectly. In so doing, the other becomes sources of self-formation in culture (for example, see
the representative of, as well as the one who renders Boesch, 1991, 2011; Simão, 2005), and assuming
concrete, in each particular moment, the affective Herbst’s co-genetic logic as the way of functioning
and cognitive possibilities and limits for the actional of the triadic processual structure of self–other–
self in a given socio-cultural constellation (Simão, culture here proposed, I will now approach some
2000, 2008). All this is possible thanks to the ways by which this process works in the dynamics
nature of the dialogue as an intersubjective field of of self–other interactions.

sim ão 405
OTHER
OTHER

SELF

TURE
CULTURE
CULTU
Figure 18.2 The triadic processual structure of
self–other–culture, as it emerged according to the
co-genetic logic proposed by Herbst (1995), at
each time and place in lifetime during self–other
relationships.

How the Other Orientation by As far as relationships involve changes (i.e.,


the Self Happens movement), the quest for comprehension about
By proposing to discuss some ways of other movement and the consequent differentiation
orientation by the self, I will take into account according to these categories by the Ancient Greek
some inheritances from the tradition of Ancient philosophers interests us because they can raise
Greek thought, believing that these inheritances some reflections concerning the apprehension
are nowadays present in our personal process of and transformation in I–world (other) relation-
Bildung (Formation) in Western tradition. As any ships. These aspects, by their turn, are linked to
inheritance, it is not now present in its identical two inter-related aspects about the triadic struc-
Ancient form but in a transformative way. This ture of self–other–culture here proposed: (1) the
presence can be found in the ways we aim and ways by which it is formed and tacitly (Polanyi,
try to establish our interpersonal relationships, as 1966/2009) constrains (Valsiner, 1998) the self–
well as in the ways we evaluate and try to change other interactions in a feed-forward process, and
them in everyday life. The same applies to our psy- (2) allowing the emergence of new forms of fields
chological understanding and explanation about for symbolic actions (Boesch, 1991)—that is, new
them (Gadamer, 1959/1985; Taylor, 2002; Simão, cultural processual structures.
2005, 2008).
Among the Ancient Greek philosophers, one
The Issue of Transformation and the
of the most disquieting aspects in the nature was
Self–Other Orientation
movement. When they were trying to understand it,
Differentiating movements assumes that things
they arrived at distinguishing categories that made
may transform themselves during time, presenting
their conception of movement simultaneously more
themselves differently than they were. In such an
specific and broader than our modern concep-
extent, things are not (as if they had an intrinsically
tions of movement. Not one, but four categories
immutable state belonged to them), but they are tem-
of movement were conceived by the Ancient Greek
porarily in this or that way.
philosophers:
Among the categories of movement already men-
1. the local movement, concerning the tioned, those referred to as the qualitative and sub-
movement of things from one place to the other; stantial movements (more than the other two) lead us
2. the quantitative movement, concerning the toward reflections about temporality, multiplicity, and
increasing or decreasing of things; contradiction inhabiting the self–other relationships.
3. the qualitative movement, responsible for the Moreover, the category of substantial movement
changes in the nature of things; and puts in focus the generation and degeneration of
4. the substantial movement, concerning the things during time. Differentiating and recogniz-
generation and degeneration of things (cf. Marías, ing this category ends in bringing uncertainty over
2004, p. 14). to the very and real nature of things, also carrying

406 th e oth er i n t he se lf
the issue of how to state relationships with them. Transformation As Illusion, Uncertainty,
Recognizing the inconstancy of things in the world and Imperfection
brings disquieting feelings, preventing oneself of The pre-Socratic philosopher Parmenides (515–
ruling lines for self–other relationships that other- 440 BC) was intensely dedicated to the fundamen-
wise would be coherent with the tacit belief of sta- tal issue of the thing-in-itself. He argued that acting
bility. Generation and corruption imply that if there in a twofold way in inherent to human kind when
will be rules, they can only be addressed to the pro- surveying the nature of things. Both ways of act-
cesses of understanding transformation. ing are not excluding each other, leading to differ-
In the ambit of self–other relationships, a rel- ent places. On the one hand, there is the method of
evant issue for human affairs shifts its terms from thought, the only way for capturing the being in its
what is the real and veritable knowledge about our- certitude, uniformity, unity, and veracity. The way of
selves and the other to what kind of relationship we thought is, however, counterposed by that of the
can develop with ourselves and the other at the present senses, leading to the uncertain, changing, mutable,
circumstances. This issue poses the incessant quest heterogeneous, and multiple things. The way of the
for disclosing what is believed to be true behind the senses leads to grasping the things as if, simultane-
appearances of the other, who always seems change- ously, they are and are not.
able. All this means putting under suspicions the For Parmenides, the perception of the aforemen-
adequacy of self ’s and other’s ways of acting, as well tioned movements of generation and corruption of
as the possibilities of a “real” apprehension of the things are originated by the apprehension of things
one by the other. The expectation about the stabil- through the senses; these kinds of movements are,
ity of the self–other relationships becomes, then, however, mistakenly understood as true attributes
groundless. of things, as if one were grasping their come to be.
In the presumption that interpersonal relationships It is a way of apprehension that is inherent in the
are not safe and regular as they wish or expect, as for human condition, making the pursuing of the thing
the true person’s thoughts and desires may be hidden in itself tricked by the senses. However, it is an ines-
behind their appearances, self and other try to cre- capable condition of human beings. In conclusion,
ate relationships that will be patterned and ruled by for Parmenides, via the senses, the human being
ways of discovering and holding the unrevealed truth. goes pursuing something that can be rightly done
Culture, as a field is created at the frontiers of self– only by the way of thinking (Marías, 2004).
other relationships,-will be then less flexible and more Putting these ideas under the focus of self–other
ruling to guarantee the aims of safety in interpersonal relationships, the quest for grasping the other in his
relationships. permanence and unity (i.e., in what that other is in
In sum, as the self does not quit pursuing the his essence) should be done through the self ’s ratio-
true knowledge about the other, aiming to act on an nality, as the senses would only lead the person to
ever more safe ground, the person will then be faced encounter the inconstant and liable character of the
with one of the most important antinomies about other. Thinking the other, rather than feeling the other,
the self–other relationships, the one of stability versus would be the “golden rule” for the other orientation
transformation. in the self aiming to grasp the other’s essence behind
From this antinomy, we can differentiate two its appearances. This is the hallmark of a concep-
versants of other orientation in the self. In the first tion of self–other relationship settled in the dual-
versant that springs from the whole Ancient Greek ism between what is and what seems to be, but is not;
thought, the other orientation channels the self— between reality and illusion, veracity and falsity; a
tacitly or explicitly—according to the conceptions dualism between relationships ruled by the reasoning
of illusion, uncertainty, and imperfection as the of thought and those ruled by the emotion of sensibility.
hallmarks of self–other relationships. This chan- The cultural field so engendered will value reason to the
neling, as we will discuss, are linked to Plato’s and detriment of emotion.
Parmenides’ philosophical inheritances. The sec- Moreover, one of the consequences of this kind
ond versant of other orientation channels the self— of dualism is tacitly creating a synonymy between
tacitly or explicitly—according to the conceptions transformation and nonessentiality in the ambit of
of potentiality and becoming (the time to come); it the other orientation in the self. It is a dualism
can be linked to the inheritance of Aristotle’s and that opens the ground for self–other relationships
Heraclitus’ philosophical ideas. exclusively settled in rationality, taken it as the only

sim ão 407
essential and desirable via for self–other relation- our world; perfection inhabits only in their essence,
ships, whereas those involving feelings and emotions the ideas of others. The essence dwelled by the ideas
are considered as labile and less desirable. It is worth are, however, inaccessible through via the I’s experi-
noting that the desirability of the former seems to ence in our world, so remaining outside the ambit
be due to the fact that they intuitively believe in of the self–other relationships.
the possibility of objective interpersonal relation- Moreover, in Plato’s philosophy, the entity—
ships, letting self and other free from the onuses of understood as the thing in itself—is not only perfect
taking different perspectives as valid. Considering but also independent of its circumstantial predicates,
the assumption of the impossibility of the complete what makes it not changeable according to them. If
objectivity, the situation would require negotiation self–other relationships were framed accordingly, we
for creating a third or recognizing and validating its would have a self that would not be altered by its
impossibility. These situations that imply negoti- past or present experiences with the other, nor by
ation would also probably interfere in the already its future expectations about the other. The same
stated knowledge about the state of affairs, which is would be the case for the other. In this respect,
in focus during the interaction. In other words, the self and other would be above of their mutual
path of negotiation requires recognizing that there interference and evaluation; they would be enti-
is not only one valid apprehension and comprehen- ties exempted from imperfections and differences
sion of some reality, but many. If so, the co-genetic predicated by their mutual relationships. Here, we
unit of self–other–culture is kept, or is even unfolded have the emblematic perfection in the relationships
in other co-genetic units, by distancing and polari- to which the common sense wisely gives the label of
zation of its compounding parts. The non-negotia- “platonic.” There would be no tension, no necessity
tion method, on the contrary, puts the interlocutors of negotiation—in sum, no actual interactive con-
in the territory of the emblematic and chimerical tact. Again, and consequently, the co-genetic unit is
world of no tension. It is a world without place for broken down; also there is no place for movements
the creative symbolic action as the movement, par of differentiation, preventing cultural innovation in
excellence, of solving tensions (Janet, 1928, 1929; the sense here assumed.
Boesch, 1993). In such a way, the co-genetic unit of But there is something more to be said: in Plato’s
self–other–culture is broken down, and cultural inno- philosophy, perfection exists only in the realm of
vation is prevented. the ideas, not in the mundane real world of per-
The impasses created by the interplay of forces sonal relationships. In such a way, self and other can
between both ways can be viewed as a inheritance of then be mutually affected in their actual relation-
the aporia concerning making compatible the unity, ships. However, this affection still remains captive
immobility, and eternity of the thing in itself with the of the thing in itself, as the self will forcefully depend
multiplicity, variability, and perishing of the being in on some previous idea of the other, in expectation
Ancient Greek philosophy. This can be viewed as a or imagination, for realizing its mere presence, the
good inheritance, as for Aristotle suggests that the condition for any possibility of relationship. In
very point of departure in any inquiry should be such a way, the self should act symbolically at the
an aporia (Aristotle, 1979, p. 139, Metafísica, Da level of the ideal anticipation of the other’s actions,
Geração e Corrupção, I, 8, 325 to 13). thoughts, and feelings (i.e., at the level of the perfect
entity), for having the opportunity of encountering
The Perfection–Imperfection Dualism the real other (i.e., the imperfect being). All this
in Self ’s Searching for the Ideal Other leads to the following consequence: what the self
Concerning the aporia here in focus, we can now apprehends in its relationship with the other is not
turn ourselves to Plato’s (427–348/347 B.C.) phil- what the other is but only what the other almost is.
osophical ideas. Synthetically, they can be under- However, in Plato’s philosophy, the distance
stood as a permanent quest for complementing the between the idea of the other and the real other as
world of things, which is never perfect, to the ideas of encountered by the self gives rise to a further aporia:
things, in their perfection (Simão, 2010). Brought to if, on the one hand, for realizing and relating with
the issue of the self–other relationships, Plato’s per- anything we need previously have some idea about
spective points to the fact that we are always relating it and, if on the other hand, the idea is an event that
ourselves with a world of imperfect others, as the cannot come from direct experience in the world,
perfection is not lodged in the beings that inhabited then we will always have access just to things as

408 th e oth er i n t he se lf
imperfect instances of the ideas, never to the enti- process. For this purpose, I will analyze some of
ties in their perfection. In such a way, the terms of Boesch’s proposals, as I understood them from my
our former issue derived from the platonic aporia own perspective, taking them as a transformative
are shifted: Even without the possibility of having intellectual construction that contemplates aspects
access to the other as an entity in its absoluteness, of Plato’s philosophical conception.
the self needs to track the other at least as an idea in At this point, it is worth recapitulating two of
its perfection. This is the only possible way for the the main tenets of Plato’s philosophy as we have
self to try grasp the other. As far as it is impossible brought to our focused subject. First, the I–world
for the self reaching the other in its absoluteness, it relationship happens at the level of imperfection of
will forcefully reach the other only in its aspect of things, if considered the perfection of the absolute of
an imperfect other. the ideas. This means that the self can relate itself
In other words, the quest for perfection, for just with a world of imperfect others, as the perfec-
the essence (the entity), remains conditional to tion of the essence of beings is not accessible to its
the imperfection of the self–other relationship, the worldly experience. Second, as far as the I is imper-
only via for its access to the world, through the I’s fect in its humanity, because not naturally provided
symbolic action. It will always be, then, a distance of the Goodness and the Beautifulness, the self will
between the idea of other, in its perfection, and the try to accomplish Perfection through its relation-
other as the self can encounter it, what gives place ship with the other.
to the tension between what is planned, expected, At this point, it is important to listen to Gadamer.
and desired and what is effectively encountered by He points out that delineating the historic-cultural
the self concerning the other and their relation- place of the concept of Beautifulness in hermeneutic
ship. As culture is a field originated from the core of (among other aspects) to the tightly relation between
self–other relationship, it will be always a real (imper- the ideas of Beautifulness and Goodness in platonic
fect) construction of the humankind, aiming to solve philosophy, which are sometimes even interchange-
the gap between perfection and imperfection through able. Moreover, Goodness and Beautifulness are
symbolic action. In such a case, the self–other–cul- beyond the circumstantial conditions of the things,
tural co-genetic processual structure here proposed concerning what is unitary and unconditional in
could be kept and will always involve a struggle for their whole essence. Goodness and Beautifulness
perfection. are above all world circumstantialities (Gadamer,
However, as in the Platonic philosophical con- 1959/1985).
text, the major issue is the possibility of the human Nevertheless, Gadamer also warns that in pla-
being reaching Perfection and True, the other enters tonic philosophy, there is a deeper distinction
then only as an instrument for the I reaching those between Goodness and Beautifulness, as only the
absolute values, rather than being the other—inter- latter has the property of being showed by itself.
locutor. This is, indeed, the main role of the other This differentiated character gives to Beautifulness
in platonic dialectics (Voelke, 1961; Szymkowiak, the most important ontological function, that of
1999; Marková, 2003a).2 In this frame, identify- mediation between idea and phenomena (Gadamer,
ing and recognizing differences among beings, as 1959/1985).
between self and other, will only account for dis- If brought to the focus of the semiotic–cultural
placing them from the ambit of the essentiality of constructivism (Simão, 2005, 2007, 2010, in
the entities and not for approaching the subject press), these aspects of platonic philosophy appear
of differences concerning the “real and mundane in important transformative conceptions that are
world.” present in Boesch’s thought.

The Transformative Construction The Beauty of the Sound


of Ernst Boesch From a Platonic The human experience of questing for perfection
Inheritance: An Illustration of is clearly approached by Boesch in his oeuvre as, for
Culture in Psychology example, in one of his most important papers enti-
In this section, I will work mainly with two tled The Sound of the Violin (Boesch, 1993). Boesch
aspects of Plato’s philosophy inheritance, trying to reconstructs there the filogenesis and ontogenesis of
illustrate the transformative and creative psycholog- the violin and the violinist in their intimate rela-
ical thought about the self–other–culture structural tionship. At the very beginning of his paper, Boesch

sim ão 409
explains that the understanding of the term ontogen- in its perfection, bringing Goodness together; nei-
esis he invites us to take in its original sense—that ther, however, is ever attained in their plenitude. On
is, the sense of “what comes to be.” This means to the other hand, in Boesch’s semiotic-constructivist
take the term in the sense of potentiality and coming contemporary ideas, there are at least three recon-
to be, one of William James’ impacts on Boesch’s structive aspects that are far away the strict Platonism,
thought (Simão, 1999; Simão, 2002). In his own clearly illustrating the transformative process of cre-
words, “Indeed, a violin becomes really a violin only ation in tradition (Gadamer, 1959/1985; Taylor,
on being played” (Boesch, 1993, p. 72). The poten- 2002), as I would like to bring here in focus.
tiality, the come to being of the symbolic object, in First, in Boesch, the search for perfection is
its function and meaning, is then actualized only explicitly recognized as a transformative cultural
through the relationship with the subject. process in the self, putting the things nearer to
But this is not only for the object: the appren- Gadamer’s (1959/1985) conception of self-rela-
ticeship himself has also his genesis as such. The tionship with masterpieces. In Boesch (1983), the
eventual future violinist, through a challenging and violinist’s search for the Beautiful Sound requires a
painful process, faces himself, at once, with the dif- complex and subtle imbalance between the is value
ference between the sound he desires the violin pro- and should value (Boesch, 1991). Managing this
duces and the sound he realizes he reached that the requirements will challenge the self (the violinist), if
violin has produced. The violinist is so confronted he lets himself be challenged in the process of mak-
by the distance that separates him from what he is, ing art. In a similar vein, for Gadamer, the horizon
in his actual relationship with the violin, from what of the masterpiece interpellates who really looks for
he is not yet, what he desires to be and may be will its comprehension, who lets it be interpellated by it,
never be. In such an extent, the relationship with in ways that the self went out transformed in this
the violin, in the perspective of the violinist’s comes dialogue.
to be, confronts him with his own limits, transform- Second, the necessity and feeling of fulfillment,
ing him in some way. Therefore, Boesch brings to which is experienced in the process of a constant
discussion the issue of the emergence of symbol- search for perfection, is eminently dependent on
ism through the subject’s action in his relationship self–subjective processes. In this sense, Boesch’s
of tension and distension with the object. This is propositions seems nearer to the primacy of the self ’s
a process where the I (the violinist) searches in its inner resources than the mundane–ideal imbalance
relation with the other (the object violin) for the of forms, maybe putting his/her propositions nearer
Beautifulness as near as Perfection, although never from Augustine’s than Plato’s inheritance.
reaching them at all. Third, according to Boesch’s Symbolic Action
Boesch enters, then, in a Janetian way (Simão, Theory, in the self–other relationships, the self not
2003b), where the antagonism between perfection only continuously reconstructs the symbolic objects
and imperfection experienced by the self is clearly (the other here included) but also transforms itself,
present. From here comes the micro and ontoge- as in this process it experiences its action potential—
netic value of the quest for perfection, as it instigates that is, the experience of can or cannot reaches its
the self for continuing to want to be. For Boesch covet personal patterns (Boesch, 1991). This aspect
(1993), the reason for the maintenance of the puts Boesch’s reconstructive propositions about
young violinist, usually a child, in the activity as a Beautifulness and Perfection closer to the real self
violin apprenticeship is her search for her sound, that in its lived world. This keeps, at the same time, the
sound that only she can extract from the violin, that self ’s present experiences and the desire for tran-
she can recognize as her sound; it affects her, touching scending its experience at the heart of the self, not
her heart in un indefinable way, producing a content- in an external world. In such a way, Boesch reaches
ment and fulfilling in the few and liable moments to keep both worlds—the present and the desired,
she reaches the violin produces that sound (cf. imagined—together inside the self, rather than pla-
p. 74). This means, in Boeschian terms, the real cul- tonically interdicted in their communication.
tural quest for perfection, which is always a step fur-
ther from where we presently are (cf. Boesch, 1993, Transformation As the Potentiality
pp. 76–77). of Coming to Be
We are here clearly facing the human search In the domain of Ancient Greek philosophy, it
already announced in Plato’s philosophy: the Beauty, will be Aristotle (384–322 B.C.) who refused the

410 th e oth er i n t he se lf
synonymy between transformation and nonessenti- about its come to be or when it manifests what it
ality, inherited from Parmenides’ thought, attribut- presently is) (Marías, 2004).
ing a special place for the issue of mutability of the The importance of these pairs of modes to our
natural phenomena. focus is that they address to dual forms of self–other
Nevertheless, as highlighted by Marková (2003), relationships as, for example, the true versus false
it is important not to forget that despite the fact that friendship. These pairs of modes also address, con-
it was Aristotle who opened the place for the pair of sequently, the self ’s acts aiming the construction and
opposites potentiality and actuality in Ancient Greek maintenance of the true friendship, which according
thought, he still remained faithful to the canon of to Aristotle’s thought, is the main way for accom-
non-contradiction in Ancient Greek philosophy. plishing the human potential of being happy in life.
In such a way, potentiality and actuality remain In fact, the Aristotelian most important moral
as mutually exclusive in Aristotle’s philosophy, an value is the human constant search for the sovereign
inheritance that will preponderate in European Goodness of happiness. In Aristotle teleology, this is
thought until the advent of Hegel’s dialectic but the supreme goal, under which all other are subor-
has never completely disappeared until now (see dinated as means for reaching it (see Voelke, 1961).
Marková, 2003, pp. 34–37). Searching for happiness, in Aristotelian terms,
Although keeping this aspect in mind, we should be understood not as if it were an exceptional
can reflect about some particular implications of occurrence but a natural one. It is the natural way
Aristotle’s philosophy for the understanding of destined to the existence of the human beings in
the self–other–culture processual structure pro- their world, which should be reached through their
posed. The character of the other enters in Ancient effective actions. Bringing this philosophical frame
Greek philosophy only when Aristotle takes the to the self–other relationships, the cultural value of
phenomenon of friendship as paradigmatic for the friendship will be the principal method for the self ’s
comprehension of human relations. For Aristotle, attainment of happiness.
friendship is an event that touches the live beings The range of uncertainty will, then, fall over the
(humans and other animals). The condition for issue of skillfulness and perfection in the search for
considering that friendship exists in a particular happiness—in other words, I’s virtue in acting for
relationship is that the involved persons should be the perfect self-realization of coming to be happy,
capable of recognizing that they are the objects of the natural way for the human beings. However,
the other’s attachment, as well as being capable of according to Aristotle’s philosophy, even the virtu-
retribution (Szymkowiak, 1999; Voelke, 1961). ous person is not self-sufficient for her self-realiza-
Therefore, Aristotle’s conception of friendship tion in happiness, as the self never can prescind from
implies a preponderantly symmetrical self–other the other in this pursuit. In self ’s search for being
relationship. It is settled in the equalized appre- happy, different interconnected roles are reserved
hension of the nature of the ongoing relationship for the other.
by the involved persons, as well as their explicit Insofar as the attainment of happiness depends
reciprocity. on a continuous activity of the self in searching it,
This conception of friendship is clearly founded as uninterrupted as possible, its questioning is at
on the Aristotle’s Metaphysics, in which he postu- the level of the self virtues. According to Aristotle’s
lates that for each category of entity there is a set philosophy, it is easier to be virtuous in companion-
of essential properties and availabilities without ship than alone, as the other, through its actions,
which that entity ceases to exist. Variability from feedbacks the self ’s attitudes and paths.3 Besides, as
the essential properties is, by its turn, assumed as far as the other is someone who is demanding in
the different circumstantial modes through which the very convivial relationship, the I needs to make
essentiality can concretely be effective in each par- use of his virtues for being convivial with the other,
ticular case. Among these modes by which variability what makes him better by practicing a more enrich-
can express itself, two pairs of modes are especially ing activity concerning social interaction. Last but
important for our discussion: first, the pair veracity not least, the relationship with the other allows the I
and falsity (respectively, when the being shows his to exercise him-/herself in love. In Aristotelian phi-
own nature and when it shows a nature that does losophy, love is a Good in itself, as it touches to hap-
not belong to it); second, the pair potency and act piness and self-accomplishment, natural destinies of
(respectively, when the being manifests something the human beings.

sim ão 411
As should be expected, in face of the weight of Moreover, if the other as an alter ego is the mean for
the other’s role, this other must be someone who knowing oneself, then that other must be similar
fulfills some requirements to give the best oppor- and apprehensible by the I— as much as it is, the
tunities for the exercise of virtues by the self and best the I can fully know and feel itself and fully
should be someone who can give the best opportu- live. Happiness, then, is brought by similarity with
nities for a virtuous self–other relationship. As such, the other, accompanied by its consciousness.
the other must also be virtuous. These possibilities of self–other relationships as a
At first sight, then, the undifferentiated and, in way for the self-awareness and self-accomplishment
some sense, self-centered figure of the other, that is settled, in a great part, on the Aristotelian meta-
one who is “someone but not me” will become, physics about knowledge, where the fundamental
in Aristotle’s proposals, a very special other, the character of empeiria is to allow a kind of knowledge
fellow. However, the other as friend is still a self- that cannot be taught to another by the knower; the
centered figure, as he should be “someone as similar one who knows can only give conditions for the
in Virtues as possible to the self,” an alter-ego. The other to have similar experiences. Brought to our
other as friend will be, indeed, reduced to a subcat- context of discussion, the self–other relationships
egory of the self, a kind of self detached from the would allow the empeiria to the self, through the
I, with whom the relationships must be similar to individual, particular and circumstantial experience
those hold by the I with the self.4 of getting knowledge about oneself in the famil-
In sum, according to the Aristotelian philosophy, iarity with the other. It will be, then, through the
the human life is something naturally good and nice. mediated experience in self–other relations that the
It consists of feelings and thoughts that are actual- human being will search for the wisdom about him-
ized in activities, especially those about which the self, for the sophía.
human being is conscious. We will desire to live if As already noted by Cuvillier (1938), the basis
our consciousness is informing us that we are accom- for the Aristotelian conception of friendship is anal-
plishing our natural function of having a nice and ogy in its strict sense of the mathematical propor-
good life. The conscious activity is, however, more tion. However, in its extended sense, it concerns a
difficult when turned to oneself than when turned kind of reasoning in which one goes across some
to another, to the friend, that “myself detached from established similitude to other not yet established.
the I,” with whom the relationships are very similar Additionally, Marías (2004) explains that in the
to those of the virtuous I with himself. The friend, Aristotelian sense of analogy, many different things
the alter ego who amplifies the self-consciousness are connected thanks to a common aspect in their
and its living, will be, therefore, so necessary to the nature.
self-accomplishment (Voelke, 1961). In fact, for Aristotle, in a perfect friendship the
Besides, and maybe more relevant for our dis- attitudes the self has toward the other are analogous
cussion, the person’s consciousness about that alter to those he would have toward himself (cf. Voelke,
ego allows him/her, by contemplating the other’s 1961). This means that I would not conceive the
virtues, to contemplate the virtues in his-/herself other as identical, but analogous to itself; anyway,
easier than he/she could do if he/she had only it would always be a process of construction of
him-/herself for contemplating; to see oneself in self–other relationship by similitude, not by contra-
the mirror is easier than without it. In few words, position. Besides, as the direction of the process is
the virtuous man will need friends who resemble preponderantly from the self to the other—and not
him in virtues to contemplate himself. bidirectional—it transpires some omnipotence of
If the self needs the other for activities that allow the self in the course of the relationship.
him the search of Perfection in living—that is, for In Aristotle’s view, individualism and utilitarian
his self-accomplishment—this other should be a attitudes make unviable the attainment of the per-
virtuous friend as the self, an alter ego to whom fect friendship. However, friendship can embrace
the self can have a perfect and veritable friendship. imperfect aspects. In this case, because of its combi-
Therefore, in the Aristotelian philosophy, the access nation with altruism, the result will be that the very
to Goodness does not happen against a background friend would like to be useful and give pleasure to
of diversity but of similarity with the other; does not the other (Voelke, 1961).
happen against the background of difference and The perfect friendship will also embrace the
alterity but against that of the other as an alter ego. interplay between altruism and individualism in the

412 th e oth er i n t he se lf
context of approximation or distancing from suffer- of symmetry and equalization, and the purposes
ing. The paradigmatic situation in Aristotelian terms of each one should be convergent to the other’s.
is the one in which, if Friend 1 is suffering, the other Divergences will be indicative of imperfection and
(Friend 2) will try to share such a suffering with him lack virtuosity in the symbolic actions that construct
(Friend 1), believing that his attitude can relieve his the self–other–culture relationships.
friend’s pain. Almost paradoxically, Friend 1, on his
side, trying to be a real friend of Friend 2, would Heraclitus and the Unity in the Tension
try to avoid that such sharing because it could bring Heraclitus’ (approx. 550–480 B.C.) philoso-
pain for his Friend (2). phy inherits mostly the issues brought about by
In a coherent way, in the Aristotelian solution Parmenides’ philosophy, which had installed the
for this impasse, reason must prevail upon feel- antinomies of being and not being, unity and plural-
ings. According to this criterion, the very friendship ity, stability and changing. As we already mentioned,
among human beings will be distinguished from the these antinomies touch to another issue, that of the
vital communality among other animals, as well as transformation of things, to the one that becomes the
from the loving relationship. The way of reason will different. Heraclitus’ metaphysics relies on the idea
allow that the very friendship constitutes itself not of movement, of mutable reality, according to which
through the identity fusion, but through rational everything flows. This mutability expresses itself in
reciprocity. Reciprocity presupposes the vice versa, the duality of the being, who, as a creature of the
whereas rationality presupposes the awareness of world, while actually being, is already in a movement
reciprocity in the relationship. As such, the very of coming to be, of being no more what it just was.
friendship, although lived at the affective level, will According to Bréhier (1931/1988), there are
be known at the thought level (Voelke, 1961). four basic and inter-related themes in Heraclitus’
Aristotle gives, then, an integrative destiny to the meditations. These themes are directly related to
dichotomies of perfection–imperfection and individu- our discussion about transformations in the proces-
alism–sharing. The attributes that make the friend- sual triadic structure of self–other–culture.
ship perfect or imperfect (altruism vs. utilitarian The first Heraclitean theme is war, attributed by
feelings and self-pleasure) become, through the way Bréhier to the fact that Heraclitus lived in a time of
of rationality, a whole hierarchically more complex great civil catastrophes in Greece. In those times, the
than the former forms of relationship, which pre- birth and the conservation of beings were depen-
serves the primordial character of perfect friendship. dent on an imbalance of opposite forces in conflict.
This, however, makes it something hybrid, less pure, In such a perspective, the absence of conflict would
and maybe more real, as it also embraces some utili- cause the cessation of the universe. Conflict, there-
tarian attitudes and the pleasure in the relationship fore, is taken in its aspect of fecundity, where oppo-
with the other. Imperfection, by its side, becomes less site forces harmonize, “as the forces that maintain
imperfect in this new arrangement, because it is at the the tension of the strings of a bow” (Bréhier, 1931,
service of a virtuous relationship, through altruism. p. 62). We are, then, by other ways, very near to
This reorganization may open the doors for Boesch’s The Sound of the Violin . . .
transformation of the self and other involved in The second theme in Heraclitus’ philosophy is
the friendship. However, in face of the Aristotelian the unity of nature and of everything that inhabits
presumption of the other as an almost myself, where it. This unity is, however, hidden behind an appear-
the pleasure of the self and the other are barely dis- ance of multiplicity, making the former evident only
tinguished, that process, in principle a reorganizing through the intuition of the laws that rule trans-
process, ends in configuring a situation where, if no formation. In such a sense, wisdom means to grasp
one loses, also transforms himself. the general formula of the world changes, especially
About equality and inequality, the Aristotelian the ones related to the temporal cycles (see Bréhier,
perspective is that of proportional equality, in 1931, pp. 62–64).
which the merits of each person involved are con- The third Heraclitean theme—and proba-
templated: the most powerful, for example, should bly the most known—is the perpetual flowing of
receive honors proportional to the extent he/she has things, from which the being cannot be divorced.
helped the weakest (Voelke, 1961). Bréhier (1931) explains it by giving its paradig-
It is, then, a conception of self–other relation- matic circumstances of manifestation: “[T]he
ship where complementarities become synonymous young becomes aged; life gives place to death, the

sim ão 413
vigil to sleep; cold things come to be hot and the Among the philosophical perspectives here
wet dries” (p. 63). focused, Heraclitus’ philosophy is indeed the one
Finally, the fourth theme of Heraclitus’ phi- that opens possibilities for thinking the self–other
losophy concerns the fact that the things embrace relationship as a dynamic structure between genu-
the opposite of what they reveal about themselves. inely different parts producing a third member, the
Grasping their opposite side depends on the perspec- cultural field, which will be also active as symbolic
tive according to which one’s take them (Bréhier, field for action. The metaphor of the intense and
1931, p. 63). conflicting relationship in war is paradigmatic;
Among the fourth themes, it is the second that there, tension and conflict have a restructuring
interests us, especially in the present discussion. power, generating a new relational unity. Moreover,
Apprehending cyclical changes involves more chal- Heraclitean ideas also point to the fact that the rela-
lenges in approaching the phenomena than could tionship among different beings installs itself in the
appear at a first glance. It involves the conception core of the proper I as a dual being in a constant
of the Cosmos, which is a constant come to be movement of coming to be. This is the natural con-
and perishing, a kind of primary background from dition of the self in its constant flow. Simultaneously
which everything comes and returns to. However, and successively, the self is and it is not; it is itself
the so conceived Cosmos is not something out of now and its come to be. The impossibility of such a
the being, as a kaleidoscopic spectacle to be watched. duality is the impossibility of the existence itself.
On the contrary, the Cosmic event passes through- The same is true for the relationship among
out the being, it is linked to its soul. The human different selves in the self–other–culture triadic
being is a Cosmic being that should orient its life processual structure: the relational unity depends
according the Cosmic spirit—that is, the logos on the duality, without which the proper sense of
(cf. Jaeger, 1933/1942). In such a case, the constant relationship is voided. The conception of dual-
mutability of the human life is not a matter of indi- ity in Heraclitus’ philosophy also has important
vidual option but an unavoidable natural fact, as implications for the issues of meaning-making and
the being is part and parcel of the cosmic whole. contextual understanding in self–other–culture rela-
The issue to be put is, then, about the orientation tionships. Hans-Georg Gadamer approaches this
the person can or cannot give to her life toward the issue in his reflections upon aesthetic and religious
logos, integrating herself more or less harmoniously experiences, when talking about his comprehension
into the Cosmic unity. of sign:
Orienting one’s life toward the logos cannot
[A sign] is not something that everyone has been
be reduced, in Heraclitus, to the sense of logic–
able to see, not something to which one can refer,
rational understanding concerning some phenom-
and yet, if it is taken as a sign, there is something
enon external to the self, relating to which the self
incontestably certain about it. There is a saying of
should take a position. Orienting oneself toward
Heraclitus that illuminates this matter very well:
the logos is, otherwise, a constant movement of
“The Delphic god neither reveals nor conceals, but
fighting between being and coming to be. This
gives a sign”. One needs to understand what “giving
movement can be done only through self-investi-
a sign” means here. It is not something that takes the
gation. It is, indeed, an inner movement. In other
place of seeing, for what distinguishes it precisely
words, aside from sensitive intuition and rational
from all reports or from its opposite, silence, is the
thought about the world perceived as external of
fact that what is shown is only accessible to the one
the self, the investigation toward the logos means
who looks for himself and actually sees something
a self-investigation about inner experiences. To
there.
apprehend the logos is, therefore, mainly of an
(Gadamer, 1977/1986, p. 152)
imagetic nature (cf. Jaeger, 1933/1942). However,
although it requires turning to oneself, contem- In such a way, the constructive character of dual-
plating the self ’s particularities, the way toward ity in Heraclitus allows us to think that a message is
the logos cannot be tread out as an idiosyncratic born from something that, at the same time, is not
individual search. As the logos is unity and com- (does not reveal) and is (does not conceal), generat-
munality, this kind of search would end in putting ing a third thing, the meaning (the sign). Maybe it
the self away from the logos, breaking the unity of is not a coincidence that, curiously, Heraclitus was
the Cosmos (cf. Jaeger, 1933/1942). called, at his time, the obscure.

414 th e oth er i n t he se lf
But in Gadamer’s Heraclitus, there is something and Heraclitus’ philosophical conceptions, as we
more: The comprehension of the sign will be pos- have discussed here, the conditions for self–other
sible only if, at the beginning, the person who is relationships will happen in very different ways.
faced and confronted by the duality quests the unity From what we discussed about Aristotle’s phi-
of the meaningful third in her horizon; in other losophy, we could say that the idea of the “good
words, only if the self has the unity of the mean- form” (in the very later Gestalt sense) prevails. The
ingful third as a pre-comprehension. If we take this self–other relationship will reach the “good form”
third part as the cultural productions emerged from if there is reciprocity between self and other. In the
the core of self–other relationships, cultural demands, symbolic action field (culture, Boesch), engendered
prescriptions, and possibilities should be, by a process in the core of self–other relationship, the alter ego
of Bildung (Formation, Gadamer), as personal pre- will be the ideal other, with whom the self will pref-
comprehensions. In short, living in culture, as living erably develop symmetric and virtuous relation-
in the level of self–other core productions, demands the ships. In very few words, culture will be the field of
person’s availability for relationships with the other, harmony and virtuosity.
which will be, of course, always selective relationships With Heraclitus other possibilities for consid-
according to the person’s ever reconstruction in culture. ering self–other relationships were opened. The
unavoidable tension between opposites, which can
Some Concluding Issues be co-present or successive, allows a self–other rela-
From what we discussed until now, one main tionship that is in itself a process for solving that
issue emerges—that of the conditions under which tension. In this process, self and other transform
self–other relationships can develop. This main themselves in their search for mutual understanding
issue, by its side, unfolds in other that of the pos- in an always nonsymmetrical relationship (Marková,
sibilities for relationships among different selves, 1997; Rommetveit, 1979, 1991; Linell, 1995). It is
which allows cultural diversity. the self ’s search for the unity of the time to come in
From Parmenides’ and Plato’s philosophical con- its relationship with the other, never reached at all.
ceptions, as here discussed, emerges the suspicion Talking about self, other, and culture can bring
about the possibility of real relationships among dif- in its core a tricking statement. As far as culture is
ferent selves. Even if this possibility is admitted, it understood as people meaning constructions, which
still remains the question of the validated status of channels the person’s symbolic actions, we fall in a
the ways by which that relationship happens, touch- vicious cycle, instead of arriving to a productive cir-
ing the status of the proper relationship. In this sce- cle, as we can arrive through the ideas of the her-
nario, thought and rationality appear as safer ways meneutic circle (Gadamer), as well as in the idea of
for the self apprehending the essence of the other, the circle of knowledge (Boesch). The idea notion
whereas senses and sensibility would allow the self of a productive circle includes a movement of inter-
to apprehend the other only in its inconstant and change among self–other and culture from which a
runaway character. Culture will be, in very schematic new structure or state of affairs emerges. This new
ways, a predominantly rational matter. structure can be more complex than the former or
In such an extent, a dualism between true and not; the important feature is, however, that there
false in the apprehension of the world and, more is some change. In this sense, the productive circle
particularly, the other, is then installed. It means a involves—and makes more dynamic—the process
dualism between what is and what appears to be, but of differentiation and de-differentiation accord-
is not, because inconstant and mutable. In such a way, ing orthogenetic principle proposed by Werner
some questions can arise as, for example, “When I and Kaplan (1956).5 According to this principle,
have a relationship with myself as well as with other human development happens in ways of formerly
person, am I relating myself with the essentiality of nondifferentiated elements to their differentiation.
the other, with my essentiality, or just with some- Such a process of differentiation produces system-
thing transitorily?” or “Can interpersonal relation- atization, integrative hierarchical transformation
ships be real, truthful, or just illusory? “ and articulation among the involved parts, giving
The already mentioned synonym between nones- more autonomy to the system as a whole respect
sentiality and transformation pervades the self–other to its context. This process is possible only through
relationships, in which core cultural objects (in movements of distancing and polarization of the
Boeschian sense) are engendered. From Aristotle’s involved parts. All this means that development

sim ão 415
implies de-contextualization, concerning a multi- a momentary field for symbolic action—that is, a
linear process, resulting in qualitative reorganiza- cultural field—in Boesch’s sense. This is what was
tion of the whole. intended to be represented by the Figure 18.2 pre-
Bringing to the frame of the subject’s relation- sented at the beginning of this chapter.
ships in culture, the proposition here developed not
only keeps the advantages of above referred models, An Illustration of the Character of
even because it is in part based on them, however the Triple Processual Structure Here
strengthening more the figure of the other. This Proposed
alternative puts culture as a co-genetic construction, In what follows, I present an illustrative analysis
avoiding explanations that can fall into a vicious of a specific context of cultural production, taking
cycle. Thanks to the premises of the co-genetic logic advantage of some reports by the French plastic
(Herbst), the unity of self–other–culture comes to artist Pierre Soulages, when he talks about some
the existence at once, by the relationships among the aspects of his own work (Soulages, 1950/2009).
three elements, so preventing that one can explain Soulages’ reports were chosen for mainly because
the other in terms of its previous existence. they offer a rare and consistent published mate-
Besides, the co-genetic model here proposed rial of self-reports by someone who creates culture
allows for understanding how different relation- through reconstructions of a tradition in which—as
ships can bring about different cultural con- all of us—he is immersed, and most importantly,
structions, from the self–other feelings of great which directs him to the other as an active fellow in
similarities between them to the self and other feel- his cultural construction.
ings of dissimilarities that can cause stress, pain, and It is worth emphasizing that the aim of this illus-
disquieting. trative analysis is not to access or analyze Soulages’
In sum, the possibility of relationship between reports about his creative process in itself but to
self and other, mutually perceived as different one offer an opportunity for thinking about if and how
from the other, allows the eternal mutability in the the triadic processual structure of self–other–cul-
search of the unity, bringing the constant re-cre- ture here proposed (Fig. 18.3) can help to highlight
ation of their relationship, from which core culture some important aspects of the psychological process
emerges. Difference, tension, polarization, and dis- of cultural creation emerged from I–self and self–
tancing should be part of the processes of social life, other relationships.
requiring negotiation in self–other relationships, Excerpt7:
which opens doors for cultural channeling and cul-
tural innovation (Boesch, 1991; Valsiner, 1998)6 (1)8 The problems posed for a painter do not precede their
In schematic terms, from the core of this nature solutions. They are born from the oeuvre, together with it.
of relationship emerges some unity, a provisional I do not believe that I can learn what I look for but
solution for the tension that can be understood as by painting; (2) this does not exclude that my painting

the spectator (other)


4
4

the painter 2
(I-self) 1&3

the masterpiece (cultural object)

Figure 18.3 Representation of the analysis of the


excerpt according to the proposed triple holistic
developmental structure.

416 th e oth er i n t he se lf
can be preceded by a desire, a need of some kind of In (2) we see a proactive symbolic action from
form more than other, (3) yet it is not but in painting the artist’s self, settled in its desires and necessities,
that those forms let me know about that desire. It is which gains clearer contours while the self acts; yet,
the moment when I draw the changes, the details that these contours are always changing and never com-
seems to me necessary, and also the next forms that pletely achieved in the sense of completely fulfill-
oblige me to replace the former in question again. As ing the artist’s desires and quests (remember here
an artist, I believe in a continuous intervention: the Boesch’s The Sound of the Violin . . . ).
artist comes and goes of his creative impulse to the In (3) Soulages interacts with a cultural symbolic
interrogation about the form presented by his creative object (the canvas) at two intertwined and mutu-
impulse to himself. Truly speaking, the matter is not ally feeding levels. There is an objectified level of the
the isolated forms which are added one to the other, canvas, the tempera, or whatever he will use as instru-
but the elements that takes, step by step, the non disso- ments in their materiality for working. Yet, Soulages
ciable character of a synthesis: the accomplished canvas. uses them for producing his work that which makes
(4) In this way of painting, in which the artist’s them subjectified in his canvas, his tempera, and so
liberty is each moment at stake, the canvas itself is a forth. On the other hand, the subjective level in
whole engagement, a poetic testimony of a world where which the painting comes to the existence by the
the validity is abandoned to the spectator. He is not artist’s symbolic actions, becomes objectified in its
asked for re-finding a history, a landscape, a still life, materiality, allowing some relationships between
characters, animals or fragments of them; not even a him and his ongoing painting. During this rela-
state of soul experienced by them in front of the canvas, tional process, insofar as he is painting, changes may
in brief a romantic or an expressionist anecdote, or happen in the artist’s self. In such a way, there is a
whatever. (5) There is nothing required from the symbolic personification of the white canvas, as it
spectator: a painting is proposed to him, which he sees asks for a symbolic action from the artist’s self, the
all at once according to his whole liberty and necessity. very condition for the dialogue between the artist
(6) Yet, in this painting the spectator also finds himself and the canvas. This means a circumstantiation of
naturally engaged as a whole. The position adopted the self–other relationship with the unknown (the
by him in front of this kind of canvas depends on and white canvas asking for some action on it), which
answers his general attitude in the world; and this is so becomes, step by step, more familiar (less unknown)
much strong that the painting does send him to nothing while the artist goes on painting in it. The canvas is
that is external to himself. then becoming transformed in a painting. A sym-
N.B.: The painting as the highest I see it is not a bolic cultural object emerges, then, from the heart
«pure art» opposed to a «realist art». There is no gratu- of the relationship between the artist’s self with the
itous art; moreover there is no a pure play of forms. canvas as other (a symbolic object) in the perspec-
It is a walk that engages all at once the man and the tive of the artist’s come to be. The noncompleted
world. The man as the spectator and the artist as well. painting channels the artist’s self-symbolic actions,
(Soulages, 2009, pp. 12–13) in a back-and-forth movement, as referred by
Soulages himself (remember here Boesch’s Culture–
The triple holistic developmental structure here individual–culture: the cycle of knowledge).
proposed can be circumstantiated in Excerpt 1, as Passage (4) gives us the report of the unavoidable
well as the Excerpt can us to understand the dynam- moment in which the artist abandons his painting,
ics of the structure functioning. in a kind of donation to the spectator. Here (as we
In (1) Soulages put the métier of fine arts at the also see clearly later), the matter is not the self get-
level of the artist’s quest, in which there is no pre- ting rid of its symbolic production but allows it to
cedence of the problem or the solution either. They try to survive outside the isolation of the self–myself
are born together, and the solution comes as far as relationship. It is “as . . . if ” the artist’s self knew
he searches for it. This way by which things happen from the beginning that there were always a third
in everyday life of people interacting to themselves person (Marková) waiting for acting in their hori-
and others (as Soulages’ report clearly illustrates) is zon (Gadamer): the spectator. It will be him, by his
what I am proposing to grasp and trying to under- interactive symbolic action with the painting, that
stand (at the psychological level) with the above can validate it—or not—as a cultural object in its
presented and discussed triple holistic developmental full sense. This requires an openness from the paint-
structure. er’s self to the otherness of the spectator, letting him

sim ão 417
talk to the former through the art object. In such painting does not become art but from the moment
an extent, the spectator is, in fact, a participant. when it is viewed, it is saw by others; it is how it
Besides, as we shall see below, the artist’s self can becomes a masterpiece, that is, a thing that others
move—and usually does—from the author’s self- see and live in their own way.
position (Hermans, Kempen, and van Loon, 1992) (Soulages, 1973/2009, pp. 41–42)9
to the self-position of a privileged spectator of his
own painting. Future Directions
However, I will keep here the term spectator to Some future directions for semiotic-constructiv-
avoid diverting our attention from the main focus ist research in psychology can be foresighted from
of this chapter. the ideas here proposed and discussed.
Letting the spectator’s self talk requires neither First, we need to develop theoretical-
talking for him nor inducing him to talk. It implies methodological ways of better apprehending and
a necessary but not easy attitude of leaving aside comprehending the dynamics of how cultural con-
the idea of asking someone for symbolically acting structions emerge in the core of the relationship
in this or that way. This is the attitude reported by between self and other, according to the co-genetic
Soulages in passage (5). He wants to let his painting model here proposed. This involves account-
say something—if it can—to the spectator, which ing for, among other aspects, the great diversity
depends on the spectator’s willing of being touched and differentiation in the contemporary societies
by his painting. (Simão, 2010). In face of what we already have
In terms of our proposal, a painting is a poten- discussed about Herbst’s co-genetic logic, and also
tial cultural field for channeling symbolic actions. considering that social interaction is one of the
However, as Soulages’ himself suggests in passage main sources of self-formation in culture, it may
(6), the real symbolic actions will depend on the be productive pointing to some further implica-
spectator’s self ongoing constructions about and in tions of the self-other-culture co-genetic process
the world. In other words, we have here a circum- here proposed. As culture is a field originated from
stantiation of the process of bounded indetermi- the core of self–other relationship, it will be always
nacy (Valsiner) in self–other–culture relationships. a real (imperfect) construction of the humankind,
What will really happen in this relationship varies aiming to solve the gap between perfection and
not only from one spectator to another but also imperfection through symbolic action. In such a
from the different moments or occasions for the case, the self–other–cultural co-genetic processual
same spectator. structure here proposed could be kept and even
Being the painter consciously of all that, in increase in complexity, according to Werner’s and
the sense that his self-report is a testimony of his Kaplan’s (1956) orthogenetic principle.
concerns and even provisional answers about the Lawrence’s and Valsiner’s (2003) metaphori-
process of art creation, we can say that it indicates cal model of “membranes of meaning transitions,”
the ways in which the other in the self is present in accounting for the intra- and interindividual selec-
the process of cultural construction. Here also is tive movements of meaning-making in psychologi-
involved the process of distanciation and polariza- cal process should also be very promising integrated
tion in development, allowing the emergence of in the theoretical-methodological framework here
more complex structures (Werner & Kaplan, 1956). in focus.
This more complex structure, in the present case, is Second, we cannot lose our ethical sight from
the proper emergence of the masterpiece from the the discussions that can be unfolded from the pro-
painter’s production through the symbolic action of posal here focused. As already noted, the main char-
the spectator. The painted object will come to be art acteristic of the structure here in focus concerns
only when interacted with the spectator. In Soulages’ the fact that, from each instance of its occurrence,
own words: other more complex structures can unfold from the
present one. These new structures are never identi-
I am the spectator of what I do. I do realize that I am cal to the former, not even necessarily similar, but
a very particular spectator, very committed to what more complex in some sense. Their greater com-
I do. Yet I paint firstly for myself; I have no fear to plexity, however, does not mean that self, other, and
say that; it is what makes my life possible. I paint their cultural co-construction will allow account-
because I need to paint. But I consider that my ing for values and goals that are more engaged with

418 th e oth er i n t he se lf
ethical and social issues than the former structure les premières en question. Je crois que la part de l’artiste à une
(see Boesch, 2011). continuellle intervention: va-et-vient de son impulsion créatrice
à l’interrogation de la forme qu’elle lui apporte. À vrai dire, il
Third, the issue of temporality is now accounting ne s’agit pas de formes isolées qui s’additionnent les unes aux
for the co-genetic model here proposed for the self– autres, mais d’élements prenant peu a peu le caractère indisso-
other–culture relationships.10 Temporality embraces ciable d’une synthèse : le tableau achevé.
a movement of dual interplay between the intersub- Dans cette manière de paindre, la liberté de l’artiste étant a
jective time and the subjective duration, bringing chaque instant en jeu, le tableau lui-même est un engagement
total, témoignage poétique du monde dont on abandonne la
about by the other to the self. In such an extent, validité au spetacteur. On ne lui demande pas de retrouver une
it brings in its bulk the dual co-presence of the I histoire, un paysage, une nature morte, des personnages, des
and the other, in which the other inserts itself in animaux ou de fragments de ceux-ci, ni même un état d’âme
the I’s subjective life, demanding the duration to éprouvé devant eux, bref une anedocte romantique, expression-
be transformed in time and vice versa, in face-to- iste ou d’un autre ordre. (5) On ne demande rien au spectateur:
on lui propose une peinture qu’il voit à la fois en toute liberté et
face relationships and through cultural traditions as nécessité. Mais dans cette peinture le spectateur lui aussi se trouve
well. In such an extent, otherness requires changes naturellement engagé en entier. La position qu’il adopte devant
in the mediational strategies of expression and com- un tableau de ce genre dépend et répond de son attitude générale
munication by the subject, pushing him to create dand le monde, et ceci avec d’autant plus de force que la peinture
alternative forms for expressing his new experiences ne le renvoie pas à quelque chose d’exterieur à elle-même.
N.B. : La peinture telle que je l’envisage plus haut n’est pas
about temporality. These latter, on their turn, are un « art pur » opposé à l’ « art réaliste ». Ce n’est pas un art gra-
partially created exactly by the new forms of media- tuit, surtout pas un pur jeu de formes.
tion brought about by the otherness. C’est une démarche qui engage à la foi l’homme et le monde.
L’homme, auntant le spectaterur que l’artiste » (Soulages, 2009,
Notes pp. 12–13).
1. Concerning this fourth characteristic stated by Herbst 8. The numeration in the excerpt was inserted by the author
(1995) it is worth noting that I am using the model of his co- of this text.
genetic logic respect to the self as one of the elements of the triad. 9. The original text is French is:
I am not referring to the I. The discussion about the relation- « Je suis expectateur de ce que je fais. Je me rends bien compte
ships between I and self according to Herbst’s co-genetic logic que je suis un spectateur trés particulier, très compromis dans ce
certainly also merits to be done, but should be kept for other que je fais. Mais je peins d’abord pour mois; je ne crains pas de
opportunity. le dire, c’est pour que ma vie sa possible. Je pains pas que j’ai
2. This point is related to the important issue of Love in besoin de peindre. Mais je considère que ma peinture ne deivent
Plato’s philosophy which, however, will not be approached in de l’art qu’à partir du moment où elle est vue, oú elle est regardée
this chapter. par d’autres et oú elle est comme une oeuvre d’art c’est-à-dire
3. Being alone with oneself, however, is not the same of iso- comme une chose que d’autres regardent et vivent à leur manière
lation, as in Aristotle, existence includes the companionship of » (Soulages, 1973/ 2009, pp. 41–42).
oneself, which means otherwise the complete accomplishment of 10. Research Project supported by the National Council for
living in Virtue (cf. Aristotle, Ética a Nicômaco, Nicomachean the Scientific and Technological Development of Brazil – CNPq
Ethics, Book IX, 4, 1166a-b). (Process 302890/2009–2).
4. In the symbolic action space of culture, the value of the
“selected friendship” and the friend as alter-ego will lose impor- References
tance during the Middle Ages for regaining its strength in the Ariès, P. (1986/2006) Por uma história da vida privada [For a
Renaissance period, especially in face of the increasingly rupture history of the private life]. Em: P. Ariès e R. Chartier (Eds.)
between public and private spheres (Ariès, 1986 / 2006, p. 12). História da Vida Privada [History of the Private Life], 3,
5. For a discussion about the genesis of Werner’s orthoge- 9–19.
netic principle, remounting to Goethe’s biological ideas, see for Aristotle. (1979). Metafísica, Da Geração e Corrupção [Metaphysics,
instance Valsiner (2005) and Van der Veer (2005). on Generation and Corruption], I, 8, 325 to 13. Coleção
6. About the relationship of the issues here put in discus- “Os Pensadores”, São Paulo: Ed. Abril Cultural.
sion to some of our proposals about the notion of otherness, see, Aristotle. (1979). Ética a Nicômano [Nicomachean Ethics], Livro
for instance, Simão (2007); Simão and Valsiner (2007); Simão IX, 4, 1166 a – b. Coleção “Os Pensadores”, São Paulo: Ed.
(2011, in press). Abril Cultural.
7. The original text in French is: Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychol-
« Pour un peintre les problémes que se posent ne précèdent ogy. Berlin / Heidelberg/ New York: Springer.
pas les solutions. Ils naissent de l’oeuvre, avec elle. Je ne crois Boesch, E. E. (1993). The Sound of the Violin. Revue Suisse de
apprendre ce que je cherche qu’en peignant; cela n’exclut pas Psychologie, 52(2), 70–81.
que ma peinture soit précédée d’une envie, d’un besoin de cer- Boesch, E. E. (2011). Culture: Result and Condition for
taines formes plutôt que d’autres, mais ce n’est que peintes que Action. In: J. Valsiner (Ed.) Oxford Handbook of Culture and
ce formes me renseignent sur cette envie. C’ést à ce moment- Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
là que j’en tire les modifications, les précisions qui me paraissent Bréhier, E. (1931/1988). Historia de la Filosofía [History of
nécessaires, et aussi les formes suivantes qui m’obligent à remettre Philosophy]. Vol. I. Madrid: Editorial Tecnos.

sim ão 419
Crossley, N. (1996). Intersubjectivity – The Fabric of Social presented at the 3rd. Conference on Sociocultural Research,
Becoming. London: SAGE. Campinas, SP, Brazil.
Cuvillier, A. (1938). Manuel de Philosophie [Handbook of Simão, L. M. (2002). A noção de objeto e a concepção de sujeito
Philosophy], Tome II. Paris: Librairie Armand Colin. em Boesch [The notion of object and the conception of sub-
Gadamer, H-G. (1959/1985). Truth and Method. New York: ject in Boesch]. In: L. M. Simão, M. T. C. C. de Souza &
Lexington (Translated by G. Barden & J. Cumming). N. E. Coelho Júnior, Noção de objeto, concepção de sujeito:
Gadamer, H-G. (1977/1986). The Relevance of the Beautiful and Freud, Piaget e Boesch [Notion of object, conception of subject:
Other Essays. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Freud, Piaget and Boesch]. São Paulo: Casa do Psicólogo.
Herbst, D. P. (1995). What happens when we made a distinc- Simão, L. M. (2003a). Beside Rupture—disquiet; Beyond the
tion: an elementary introduction to co-genetic logic. In: other—alterity, Culture & Psychology, 9, 449–459.
T. A. Kindermann & J. Valsiner (Eds.) Development of Person- Simão, L. M. (2003b). Sociogênese e alteridade em Pierre Janet
Context Relations. (pp. 67–79). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence [Sociogenesis and alterity in Pierre Janet]. Paper presented at
Erlbaum. the 3rd. North-Northeast Congress of Psychology, João Pessoa,
Hermans, H. J. M., Kempen, H. J. G. & van Loon, R. J. P. Paraíba, Brazil.
(1992). The Dialogical Self: Beyond Individualism and Simão, L. M. (2005). Bildung, culture and self: A possible
Rationalism. American Psychologist, 47(1), 23–33. dialogue with Gadamer, Boesch and Valsiner?, Theory &
Jaeger, W. (1933/1942). Paideia – Los ideales de la cultura griega Psychology, 15, 549–574.
[Piadeia – The Ideals of Greeck Culture]. México: Fondo de Simão, L. M. (2007). Why Otherness in the research domain
Cultura Económica, vol. I. of semiotic-cultural constructivism? In L. M. Simão &
Janet, P. (1928). L´Évolution de la Mémoire et de la Notion du J. Valsiner (Orgs.) Otherness in Question: Labyrinths of the Self.
Temps [The Evolution of Memory and of Notion of Time]. Paris: (pp. 11–35). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
A. Chahine. Simao, L. M. (2010). Ensaios Dialógicos: compartilhamento e
Janet, P. (1929). L´Évolution Psychologique de la Personalité [The diferença nas relações eu-outro [Dialogical Essays: sharing and
Psychological Evolution of Personality]. Paris: A. Chahine. difference in I-other relationships]. São Paulo: HUCITEC.
Lawrence, J. & Valsiner, J. (2003) Making Personal Sense: Simão, L. M. (in press). Otherness. In M. Juergensmeyer &
An Account of Basic Internalization and Externalization H. Anheier (Eds.). The Encyclopedia of Global Studies. London:
Processes, Theory & Psychology, 13(6), 723–752. Sage.
Linell, P. (1995). Troubles with mutualities: towards a dialogical Simão, L. M. & Valsiner, J. (2007). Multiple Faces of Otherness
theory of misunderstanding and miscommunication. Em: within the Infinite Labyrinths of the Self. In L. M. Simão &
I. Marková, C. Graumann & K. Foppa (Eds.), Mutualities J. Valsiner, Otherness in Question: Labyrinths of the Self.
in Dialogue. (pp. 176–213). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge (pp. 395–407). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
University Press. Soulages, P. (1950/2009). Écrits et porpos [Writtings and propos-
Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking Language, Mind, and World als]. Paris: Hermann.
Dialogically. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Stam, H. J. (2006). The Dialogical Self and the renewal of
Marková, I. (1997). On two concepts of interaction. Em: Psychology, International Journal for Dialogical Science, 1(1),
M. Grossen e B. Py, Pratiques Sociales et Mediations 99–117.
Symboliques. (pp. 23–44). Bern & Berlin: Peter Lang. Szymkowiak, M. (1999). Introduction. In: M. Szymkowiak (Ed.).
Marková, I. (2003). Dialogicality and social representations: The Autrui—textes choisis et présentés par Mildred Szymkowiak
dynamics of mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University [Autrui—selected texts presented by Mildred Szymkowiak]
Press. (pp. 11–45). Paris: Flammarion.
Marías, J. (2004). História da Filosofia [History of Philosophy]. São Taylor, C. (2002). Gadamer on the human sciences. In
Paulo: Martins Fontes. R. J. Dostal (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer
Polanyi, M. (1966/2009). The Tacit Dimension. Chicago and (pp. 126–142). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
London: The University of Chicago Press. Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind: A sociogenetic approach to
Rommetveit, R. (1979b). On the Architecture of Intersubjectivity. personality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
In: R. Rommetveit & R. M. Blakar (Eds.), Studies of Valsiner, J. (2005). General Introduction: Developmental Science
Language, Thought and Verbal Communication. (pp. 93–107). in the making: The role of Heinz Werner. In J. Valsiner
London: Academic Press. (Ed.). Heinz Werner and Developmental Science (pp. 1–17).
Rommetveit, R. (1991). Dominance and Asymmetries in a New York: Kluwer.
Doll’s House. In: I. Marková & K. Foppa (Eds.), Asymmetries van der Veer, R. (2005). The Making of a Developmental
in Dialogue, (pp. 195–220). New York: Harvester. Psychologist. In J. Valsiner (Ed.). Heinz Werner and
Simão, L. M. (1999). Ação, interação, objeto e cultura: a con- Developmental Science. (pp. 75–105). New York: Kluwer.
tribuição de Ernest Boesch [Action, interaction, object and Voelke, A.-J. (1961). Les Rapports avec Autrui dans la Philosophie
culture: Ernst Boesch’s contribution]. Conference pronounced Grecque d’Aristote à Panétius [The Relationships with ‘autrui’ in
at the 1st North-Northeast Congress of Psychology, Salvador, Greeck Philosophy from Aristotle to Panetius]. Paris: Vrin.
Bahia, Brazil. Werner, H. & Kaplan, B. (1956). The developmental approach
Simão, L. M. (2000). The role of the other in the process of to cognition: its relevance to the psychological interpreta-
knowledge construction during interactions: developments tion of anthropological and ethnolinguistic data. American
from the Symbolic Action Theory of Ernst Boesch. Paper Anthropologist, 58, 866–880.

420 th e oth er i n t he se lf
CHAPTER

Dialogical Theory of Selfhood


19
Tiago Bento, Carla C. Cunha, and João Salgado

Abstract
Dialogism is presented as a relational paradigm in which intersubjective and communicational relationship
is considered the most appropriate to further explore and understand selfhood. In abandoning the
paradigm of self-awareness for the comprehension of selfhood, dialogism attempts to elaborate on
the importance of the intersubjective relationship to the constitution of the psychological domain. For
that, the relationship is grounded in the postulate of radical otherness. This means that the irreducible
asymmetry and difference between Self and Other is considered to open an ontological relational space
with logical and pragmatic qualities within which processes of subjective and intersubjective meaning
construction take place. The characteristics and processes inherent to this external communicational
and intersubjective space are considered to mold the internal domain of selfhood that is seen as
being structurally and functionally continuous and dependent on such external relational space and
processes. Selfhood is then conceived as a product of the continuous dynamic processes that are
established between the I (as center of experience), the other-in-me (as the background from which
the I experiences the world), and internal audiences that shape the specific positioning of content
and processes of subjectivity in the experiential and communicative moment. On this basis, the future
challenges faced by dialogical theory of selfhood are addressed.
Keywords: dialogism, dialogical self, alterity, selfhood, subjectivity, intersubjectivity

In the recent decades, we have been witnessing through an intellectual framework and orientation
an important discussion, across humanities and that emphasizes a social/relational and discursive/
social sciences, about the limits of modern epis- semiotic construction of reality and human phenom-
temology for the conception and comprehension ena and also reinstates the need to (re)situate and
of human processes. In psychology this has led to contextualize psychological knowledge. These plu-
the development and consolidation of new meta- ralistic movements have elicited prolific epistemo-
theoretical configurations, such as social constructiv- logical, theoretical, and methodological reflections
ism (Valsiner, 2007), social constructionism (Gergen, and discussions that defy the scientific assumptions,
1985a, 1985b, 1994), or dialogism (Marková, 2003; goals, and perspectives of traditional psychological
Linell, 2009; Salgado 2006; Salgado & Gonçalves, science. From these movements emerged a common
2007; Salgado & Valsiner, 2010), and to the explo- growing interest in the importance of social, com-
ration of the contrasts that emerge between them municational (e.g., Marcos, 2001; Mendes, 2001),
and other traditional frameworks (Ferreira, Salgado, hermeneutic (e.g., Bamberg, 2006), and inter-
& Cunha, 2006; Hibberd, 2001a, 2001b; Marková, subjective processes (e.g., Bråten, 1998; Stolorow,
2003). Although these recent movements do not Atwood, & Braudchaft, 1994; Zlatev, 2008) to the
share all assumptions, they are generally united constitution of the psyche in a multicultural world,

421
with expression in several areas of psychology like explanatory principle. In our view, it is the purpose
developmental psychology, psychology of self and of psychology to explain the human mind and not
identity, developmental psychopathology, psycho- only to take it for granted and to use it as an expla-
therapy, feminist psychology, or social and cultural nation for itself. To explain the mind, we need to
psychology. take into account not only its constituents and their
In this context, central to the dialogical approach relations, but the transaction between the mind and
to subjectivity and selfhood is the critique of the tra- the surrounding environment. In line with this, we
ditional approaches that tend to assume that subjec- follow Marcos (2001) in stating that “the figure of
tivity is manipulation of symbols and that think of the ‘relationship,’ in its logical complexity and in
human relations as something based on aprioristic its openness to novelty, is today the more appropri-
and isolated selves. On the one hand, we consider ate to think of rationality [and selfhood]. It is the
that any perspective stressing that subjectivity (and only way to prevent the affirmation of any absolute
intersubjectivity) is based on a prioristic and asocial (ontological or ethical)” (p. 23).
mind endorses an unnecessary and misleading sepa- Within this context, the developments for the
ration between mind and the process of relating with dialogical theory of selfhood suggested here are
the world, a typical mistake of some traditional the- based on an interval ontology —on the commu-
oretical frameworks of psychological tradition (e.g., nicational processes that take place on the space
cognitive models of information processing); on the (interval) between individuals. To be a self is a mat-
other hand, to assume the linguistic domain of signs ter of relating and contrasting with the social and
and symbols by themselves as the foundational basis material world. Therefore, this ontology is rooted
of human mind cuts the very possibility of discus- in the notion of irreducible difference between the
sion of a subjective mind, avoiding the discussion Self and the Other, which is taken as the institut-
of problems such as experiencing an individual ing and epigenetic operation of the psychological
agency or freedom of choice, while human relation- domain. The delivery and birth of a human mind
ships become a matter of sign- exchange devoid of is metaphorically and literally something involving
any subjective element. Dialogism appears precisely and contrasting at least two different people in rela-
from the discussion on the limits that arise in these tion within a social and material world that is even
kind of approaches (Ferreira, Salgado, & Cunha, larger than them.
2006; Salgado & Hermans, 2005).
Beyond Sameness
Arguing for a Relational Metatheory Deleuze (1994) has argued that representa-
In the field of psychological science, the proposal tional thought necessarily brings us to frameworks
of dialogism is for the development of an approach to in which sameness tends to acquire an ontological
human psychological domain based on a relational sense. The existence of something would be granted
ontology. In this context, the relationship within by its intrinsic or essential features, following the
the communicational space becomes an invaluable Aristotelian logic of identity. In that sense, what
notion because it is assumed to be the only rela- can be said to exist is what remains unchanged.
tionship able to prevent a return to representational This highlights the fundamental problem of self-
thought and to the figures of representation (sub- hood theories that, despite emphasizing relational
ject, concept, being; Deleuze, 1994, Deleuze & and intersubjective processes, consider the symbolic
Guattari, 2004) as the main or foundational mat- or representational activity as the ontological basis
ters of subjectivity and selfhood. Without disregard- of human beings. In other words, the representa-
ing the notion of representation, it is assumed that tional (or linguistic) ability would be the intrinsic
“referring to the world through representations” is and defining feature of the human mind—implying
part of the human mind, but it is not its fundamen- consideration of the mind as defined by a specific
tal or unique ontological element. Even if we would and self-contained property. Relations with the
consider the human mind as constituted only by world exist, but they are not defining features of the
representations (perceptions, memories, symbolic main substance (the mind and its symbolic activ-
symbols, etc.)—and this is the most common way ity). Dialogism is one of trends that refuses that
of thinking about psyche—an acceptance to explain ontological reasoning. Dialogical approaches attri-
the mind based on its elements would mean to bute otherness an ontological sense. Along with
take the mind as a self-explanatory concept or an other trends of thought in the twentieth century,

422 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


the human mind is, first of all, a matter of relating but “What do we do with signs?” The answer is:
with others. As George Herbert Mead put it in his We relate, we communicate, and this relation is
symbolic interactionist stance: something that transcends language itself (even if
it is partially enabled by language). The task is to
“[W]e do not assume there is a self to begin with.
obtain strong substantive theoretical and practical
Self is not presupposed as a stuff out of which the
consequences from the postulate that human beings
world arises. Rather the self arises in the world.”
are relational beings.
(Mead, 1992, p. 107)
What is suggested here, then, is that meaning-
Thus, the mind and its symbolic activities, making processes must be conceived in continuity
important as they are, will remain contingent on with the elementary structure of experience that is
intersubjective processes that shape them. In this considered intrinsically relational in its constitu-
type of account, the relation with the world and, ent terms and processes. It is in line with this that,
most of all, with other human beings becomes the throughout this chapter, communication and mean-
origin of the self. Difference becomes a corner- ing are elaborated as two asymmetric but intercon-
stone notion for dialogical approaches to selfhood nected axes, invaluable and fundamental to any
precisely because it suggests the need of something discussion on subjectivity and selfhood.
other than individual subjectivity for the under-
standing of its constitutive processes. Alterity and Tension
In recent decades, arguments have been put for- The Self–Other relationship has a tensional
ward regarding the need to move beyond a linguis- nature. Alterity or otherness processes involve the
tic or symbolic criterion for an intersubjective view simultaneous presence of different interpretations
of human beings (e.g., Habermas, 1992; Jacques, in confrontation. The underlying assertion is that
1985, 1991). In psychology, it is in the field of the “tensional nature of communication is its condi-
psychological development of newborns that tion of possibility” (Marcos, 2001, p. 22).
this approach seems to express itself more clearly, It should be emphasized here, on the one hand,
moving from a linguistic emphasis to a relational that to communicate is to share, co-reference, co-in-
emphasis. Trevarthen (1998) describes the theory vest, and make sense with relational space. To coor-
of intersubjectivity proposed in this area as follows: dinate with others, we need to achieve some mutual
“It is a theory about how human minds, in human understanding. However, this coordination is some-
bodies can intuitively recognize impulses from each thing that people struggle to find, and even when
other, with or without cognitive or symbolic elabora- it is achieved, mutual understanding is never “per-
tions” (p. 17, emphasis added). It is this project that, fect.” It should be emphasized that this understand-
we believe, should be pursued in other areas of psy- ing does not take the form of two minds merging
chology, and we will elaborate on that throughout into one—to dialogism, this dream (or nightmare)
this chapter. is never accomplished: the difference between agents
is the very possibility of their contact.
Relation, Experience, and Meaning Thus, on the other hand, this relational space is
The relational and communicational construc- always indeterminate. We must keep in mind that
tivism that characterizes dialogism (see Linell, the intersubjective relationship follows a principle
2009) as a consequence of its focus on the inter- of exotopy, in the words of Bakhtin (1984). As de
play between Self and Other does not imply that Man (1989) has noted, Bakhtin expresses with this
we abandon meaning-making as a central feature of notion the principle of radical otherness, taking it
a psychological understanding of subjectivity and as the principle of reality. Creating an analogy with
selfhood. Nevertheless, dialogism also stresses that Freudian notion, de Man has argued that it is within
“to put communication in the domain of sign (lin- the relation with others that a person confronts the
guistic, philosophical, theological or otherwise), is world—a socially articulated and regulated world
to set it up as an intellectual object, independent of (including its material dimension)—to which the
the act that confirms it as relationship, as alliance, human subject is “subjected.” The intersubjective
and as commitment; it is to isolate it and fix it as relation and the real that is built and negotiated
a mere representation, as a saying that does noth- within it depend on the irreducibility of its partici-
ing” (Martins, 2001, p. 98). The question is not pants. It is the indeterminate condition of the rela-
“What is language (or signs, or representations)?” tional space that makes it possible the emergence

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 423


of dialogical products of coordinated activities relationship is stressed by stating that all human
(cf. Shotter, 1997). The disorderly and unfinished processes (cognitive processes of knowledge con-
background of communicational and meaning- struction, emotional and identity processes, etc.)
making processes opens the possibility for unique are essentially relational in their origin. As a rela-
variations and novel associations to emerge and tionship involves at least two elements in interac-
be elaborated in the relational processes. Also, its tion, this issue is directly linked with the need to
unfinished condition feeds forward this constant define contrasts (1) between subjects; (2) between
movement of novelty emergence because the deter- each subject and a context or environment; and
mined, finalized remains static and stable. (3) between the constituent elements of this con-
Furthermore, dialogism—although emphasizing text, and so on. In this proposal, all human pro-
the role of the Other—does not mean to suggest nor cesses involve the presence of a figure-ground kind
elaborate on an imagined, represented, or generalized of relationship (see Holquist, 1990) that implies a
Other with general expected qualities (the Other as contrast that simultaneously unites and separates
role or trait). As Marcos (2001) has noted, this sec- the elements in relationship.
ond position consists in “representing difference as a Following the implications of this notion of
function of sameness. It consists, basically, in assign- contrast, we claim that a dialogical relation implies
ing not a difference but an indifference” (p. 77) to (1) different elements and (2) a zone of contact
the role of the Other. Similarly, the words of Jacques between them. Thus, this contrast demands a
(1991) are equally clear: “As long as the fact of differ- membrane (Salgado & Valsiner, 2010): a space
ence invites us to take a monadic Self as our point of of contact between the elements in relation that
departure, the other will be constituted with a mean- not only contrasts but also establishes a functional
ing that refers back to the Self” (p. xxii). As we will contact. Like a cell, there is not only a mutual
see later in this chapter, our proposal is the recogni- constitution of the person (the interior element)
tion of a real Other unavoidably different from the and the environment (the exterior element) but a
Self and, despite that, present and active in the psy- zone of exchange between them. These boundaries
chological space of the Self (see Salgado & Ferreira, delimit those elements, and these limits are specific
2005; Ferreira, Salgado, & Cunha, 2006). of the relational moment of those elements. As the
relationship unfolds through time, boundaries
Dialogism may change, and as they change, they also define
As we have noted, our proposal for the estab- the elements differently within the relationship. In
lishment of a post-rationalistic framework to the this sense, dialogism makes use of this notion of
description of psychological domain is based on the boundaries to underline that dialogical relation-
instituting nature of the intersubjective relationship ships are constituted through a process that, in
and on the correlative notions of difference and putting elements in relationship, both unites and
tension between two persons as their conditions distinguishes them.
of possibility. These are the organizing themes of a
meta-theoretical framework that we must now sys- Dialogicality and Monogicality
tematize and lay out in its general terms. The second principle is dialogicality (see also
Dialogism as a meta-theoretical framework is far Salgado & Valsiner, 2010). Human beings not only
from a robust systematization, and only recently relate with the surrounding material environment—
have some approaches to this issue emerged (Linell, more important, they also coordinate their actions
2009; Marková, 2003; Salgado & Gonçalves, 2007). with social others. It is through the development of
Nevertheless, the principles established by Salgado joint activities that we become capable of establish-
and Gonçalves (2007) allow us to lay out the key ing a minimal mutual understanding with others,
themes of this perspective (see Linell, 2009, for an enabling the development of actions that are social
expanded discussion on the axiomatic assumptions in their origin. Even instrumental actions are devel-
of dialogism). oped through social guidance and, therefore, involve
this coordination. It is our claim that such a scenario
Relationality and Boundaries illustrates precisely the principle of dialogicality—
The first of these principles is the relational that every human action, in its material and semiotic
principle. Here, the ontological position of the dimension, has always a communicative basis, placing

424 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


it as a form of social relation with others. Therefore, first, demands knowledge and active presence of
everything we do is dialogical: other elements external to the object and to the
relationship of knowledge (subject–object) so that
But if people are not simply putting their ideas
it may arise and be described; second, it involves
into words, what can they be said to be doing in
indeterminacy and originates what Bakhtin (1984)
their talk? Primarily, I suggest, they are materially
termed “surplus of vision,” the emergence of novelty
responding to each other’s utterances in an attempt
and of a more general framework involving Self and
to link their practical activities with those of the
Other’s visions. In monological communication, one
others around them; and in these attempts at
party tries to dictate his or her particular worldview,
coordinating their activities, people are constructing
without considering the other in his human full
one or another kind of living social relationship.
capacities. However, even when this happens, there
(Shotter, 1997, p. 11)
is a mutual relation, and therefore, a monological
With utterances and/or with practical activities, orientation still entails the principle of dialogicality
we are constantly producing something with poten- (it is addressed and it calls for an answer, even if
tial social meaning, and therefore, through those faked). Linell (2009) has a similar point:
words, we are constantly addressing others. Signs
All kinds of communication and thinking are
play an important role here, as it is through signs
arguably dialogical in terms of responsivity,
that we reach others—signs are placed at the mem-
addressivity, and genre-belongingness. At the same
brane of contact between Self and Other. These
time, there are many monologizing (“undialogizing”)
signs, by their turn, stand for something else (they
practices in the world, in which a speaker, author
refer to other objects) and stand for someone else
or sender tries to formulate a mono-perspectival
(they are addressed to social others and have a mean-
message which is aimed at imposing one specific
ing potential to others). Therefore, it is through
type of response from the addresse, in terms of his
sign-mediated activities that we reach others and
or her interpretation and responsive action. One
the world. However, this does not mean to reduce
might summarize the point by claiming that there are
the dialogical relationship to the sign properties; it
monological practices in our dialogically conceived
is the dynamic of sign-mediated activities that are
world.
relevant here, the constant process of relating and
(p. 408)
mutual positioning of Self and Other (Hermans,
2001a; Leiman, 2002, 2004). This apparent paradox is, then, solved with this
Dialogicality must be taken as a constant pro- distinction between two basic ways of approaching
cess. However, in the tradition of Bakhtinian dialo- communication: as a two-way, bidirectional activity
gism (Bakhtin, 1984, 1986), a distinction between between parties or as a single-way process of trans-
dialogical and monological relations is often mission. Thus, it is possible to treat the other in a
emphasized (e.g., Linell, 2009; Marková, 2003; monological way, just as it is possible to think about
Hermans, Rijks, & Kempen, 1993). However, this communication in a monological way. However,
adds some confusion to the field that needs to be communication, even when monologically ori-
clarified. As we will argue, this distinction does not ented, is always communication and, therefore,
depend on the nature of the components involved dialogical. As previously stated (Salgado & Valsiner,
(which will be always relational). It refers mainly, as 2010), we should not mix “orientations to the dia-
the authors point out, to the nature of the relation- logue” (that can be monological or dialogical) with
ship established between the elements—that is, to the general principle of dialogicality (that is perva-
the communicative responsiveness and intersubjec- sive and extends itself even to monological forms of
tive engagement of elements. Usually, this notion communication).
is used to distinguish types of communication: dia-
logical and monological forms of communication. Otherness and Communicative
In dialogical communication, the agents remain Constructivism
open to the otherness brought to the situation by Involving the relationship in the ontological
the interlocutors, and the dialogue evolves by a debate, dialogism is constituted by a third principle—
joint and common effort, whose final result is cre- that of otherness. Any human action (behavioral, intel-
ated by all parties. Thus, a dialogical relationship, lectual, emotional) is always addressed to an Other.

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 425


The Self and the Other are, therefore, two essential and mediated by signs. This also explains why we
poles for the emergence of any human process. It place the relation between Self and Other at the
should be made explicit that the claim here is that center of our reasoning—it does not imply that
there is no Self without an Other nor an Other the material is irrelevant, it simply means that the
without a Self, and it is in their figure-ground rela- experiencing of the world is regulated by the social
tionship that the possibility of emergence of a sub- coordination of the human subject with social oth-
jective psychological space is opened. Nevertheless, ers. The world is “revealed” or “touched” through
this emphasis on otherness and relationality does signs (see Leiman, 2002, on the “epiphanic” qual-
not intend to maintain the figures of relation and ity of signs), and these symbolic tools are not pas-
intersubjectivity at a purely conceptual level. On the sive or “neutral vehicles” (Linell, 2009) but, rather,
contrary, dialogism establishes that these notions active elements in those relationships. At the same
and the processes they circumscribe are on the basis time, they are also involved in forms of interaction,
of every particular action or cognition and should in which they gain their value and are not limited
be directly applied to their understanding. to the linguistic or semiotic realms. In fact, as we
In line with this, dialogism tends to endorse a have seen, any dialogical relationship refers both to
communicative constructivism: “[W]hen we construct itself in its constituent terms and to the exterior of
the world, it is a question of intersubjective co- itself. It is this reference to the outside that brings
construction with the help of others and artifacts” out a contextual environment to which it becomes
(Linell, 2009, p. 19). Basically, dialogism assumes dependent in terms of its processes and meanings.
the world is not even there to be constructed for an
isolated mind in any substantial psychological sense, Moderate Holism and Dynamism
nor would it be possible for such a mind to relate Dialogism therefore commits itself with a con-
with it. Therefore, the Other assumes a vital role. textual, interactional, and interdependent approach
At the same time, it should be highlighted that to psychological processes. Generally, as Linell
under the notion of constructivism, we are endorsing (2009) has noticed, this moves dialogism toward a
the tradition of thought that integrates action upon moderate holism in the sense of it assuming a “com-
the world with the representation of that world, mitment to preserve the integrity and complexity of
without giving primacy to any of them. The long phenomena, such as the context matrices, situations
philosophical debate around action and reflection as and activities, in which constituent acts or the use
the basis of our living in the world is dissolved here: of semiotic resources are embedded” (p. 18). This
We act upon the world, and through that action creates a constant tension between the particular,
we create an “image” of that world that guides our local, and momentary and the global, contextual,
future actions. Our constructions are ways of act- and developmental levels. Both levels are consid-
ing upon the world that seek our adaptation to the ered to be essential for an appropriate approach to
future circumstances. Communicative constructiv- phenomena that preserves their integrity as such.
ism adds something to the cognitive constructivism This also highlights dialogism movement toward
(e.g., Piaget, 1955), affirming the role of the Other complexity as it resists homogeneity, rigidity, and
in this process of construction. closure of phenomena.
Simultaneously, this focus on otherness and rela-
Contextuality and Mediation tionality separates dialogism from a conception of
The fourth principle of dialogism developed by phenomena as static, stable, or constant. Open to
Salgado and Gonçalves (2007) is the contextual- what is external to them and dependent on it for
ity of dialogical processes. Human actions, being their constitution, psychological phenomena are
addressed, are also involved in a specific cultural not defined on the basis of their identity, internal
matrix and depend on the semiotic tools available properties, or characteristics but, rather, on the
in this matrix. These semiotic tools are considered basis of the dynamic processes of constant change
to be the means by which it becomes possible to and transformation that they undergo. It is the pro-
contact with and know others and the world. Linell cess of transformation and the dynamics inherent
(2009) stresses that “our understanding of the world to it that is considered to be indicative or reveal-
come to us in a necessarily mediated form, never ing of the nature and characteristics of phenomena
immediately” (p. 19). Our relations with others and rather than predetermined properties they may be
the world are never direct, immediate but indirect assumed to have.

426 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


By the same token, this openness and constant identity is recognized, something more radical is
interaction with external elements also makes phe- reinforced: not only do we construct multiple self-
nomena permeable to those external elements or images or a diversity of stories where several roles
other phenomena. The dynamics inherent to the and actors play their part, we are also multiple
interactional processes determines how permeable authors, involved in internal and external dialogical
the frontiers between them are. These changes in the processes.
border of a phenomenon are what define the phe- To reach this conception so distanced from the
nomenon itself. This explains why dialogism resists monadic version of identity, so long disseminated
and tries to transcend oppositions and dualisms (see in psychology (cf. M. Gonçalves, 1995), Hermans,
Marková, 2003) such as individual versus social or Kempen, and Van Loon (1992) depart from the
culture X versus culture Y. The point is that culture X classic distinction of William James (1890/2007)
will appear in one way in relation to culture Y and between I and Me. To James (1890/2007), the Self
in another way in relation to culture Z. Therefore, has a dual nature. On the one hand, there is the I (or
culture X will be attributed different qualities Self as knowing) that refers to the agent responsible
depending on which other culture with which it is to a sense of experiential continuity, distinct from
compared. It is the specificity of the global pattern others and the world, with the consequent sense of
of its different qualities in different relations that volition and autonomy (Hermans, 1996). In other
defines culture X as culture X. words, according to James, the I is associated to
the construction of a subjective continuity through
The Dialogical Self Theory time, from which emerges a sense of personal iden-
Originally, the Dialogical Self Theory (DST) tity as a unique individual (Bertau, 2004; Hermans,
subscribes this relational framing by turning to the 2001a). On the other hand, the Me (or Self as object)
notion of dialogue to rethink the Self. We will now is related to the construction of a self-image and the
characterize this theory by elaborating, first, on the inclusion of objects/others in the world that become
pioneer work of Hermans and collaborators (cf. part of the Self in a physical and symbolic extension
Hermans, Kempen, & Van Loon, 1992; Hermans of what we are, what completes us, and what we
& Kempen, 1993; Hermans, 1996). These contri- call our own (such as objects in the world, signifi-
butions have been extensively debated in several spe- cant others, and personal history; Hermans, 1996;
cial issues in psychological publications (Hermans, Hermans & Kempen, 1993). Through these two
2001b, 2002, 2003, 2004b, 2008; Hermans & dimensions—I and Me—the Self conjugates two
Lyddon, 2006; Hermans & Hermans-Konopka, fundamental properties: a differentiation between
2008; Stam, 2010). Self and world and the construction of identity
in time.
Sources for the Dialogical Self Theory In this sense, for James (1890/2007), identity is
The first formulations of the DST (Hermans, constituted simultaneously from pairs of mutually
Kempen, & Van Loon, 1992; Hermans & Kempen, inclusive opposites: We are producers of images and
1993) had four main sources of inspiration: narratives of ourselves (as products of our semiotic
activity), but these self-images and self-narratives
1. The work of William James (particularly his
end up feeding our own subjective process. The
distinction between I and Me).
image of myself in the world (Me) is the base that
2. The metaphoric and narrative nature
allows the I (as subject) to be guided in action and
of cognition (highlighted by authors such as
semiotic activity in the world. Furthermore, what
G. Lakoff and M. Johnson) and human life
one thinks about oneself (as products or part of Me)
(particularly by T. Sarbin and J. Bruner).
reveals one’s own reflexivity and subjectivity—that
3. The approaches that underlie the multiple
is, the I as agent.
and multifaceted nature of the Self.
This original distinction between I and Me was
4. The dialogical thinking of Mikael Bakhtin.
later retrieved by Sarbin (1986) under the narrative
Combined together, these influences originate a framework. In this view, identity is seen not only
notion of identity as something that is constructed as a form of reflexivity but also the achievement
from the dialogical engagement between differ- acquired in the act of interpreting ourselves as social,
ent “voices” or positions of the Self. In this sense, historic, and contextual beings. As we exist in a given
although the multifaceted and narrative nature of socio-historic-cultural context, identity appears as a

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 427


narrative project (O. Gonçalves, 2000) that we share of narrating, which puts the Self (as interlocutor)
and co-construct with others. According to this, the facing an Other as an audience (either present or
I of James is seen as an author that organizes experi- absent, real or imaginary). In these suggestions, the
ence through a socially articulated narrative struc- influence of the Bakhtinian thought becomes clear
ture, from several biographic episodes where the Me and demarks its difference.
is both actor and protagonist (Sarbin, 1986).
Given these influences, Hermans and collabo- The Emergence of an Alternative
rators (1992) have conceived the Self as a specific View on Selfhood
organization of socially articulated meanings deriv- We consider that four central notions in the
ing from experiences lived in a temporal sequencing DST constitute it as an independent, unique alter-
of episodes, events, and actions. These narratives are native, distinguishing it from other perspectives on
both subjective and social products, because they selfhood:
put symbolic, discursive, and material resources
1. The centrality of dialogue and polyphonic
into play. Similarly, we can say that the initial move-
metaphor applied to the Self, both of Bakhtinian
ment of sense-making is both metaphoric (because
heritage.
metaphors use something to [re]present another),
2. The dynamic notions of positioning and
imaginative (because imagination allows us to con-
repositioning of the Self in time and space and
struct what is not yet present and project something
in relation to something/someone (in internal/
into the future), and relational (because sharedness
external dialogues that place the interlocutor in a
allows the co-construction of meaning).
specific relationship).
These original works from the beginning of the
3. The role of difference and tension in
1990s have traces of the zeitgeist of the moment.
dialogical processes (both in the differential
The emphasis on the complexity and multifaceted-
power acquired by parts of the Self and in the
ness of the Self, from a cognitive view, was also a
relationship between the Self and the world) for
marked influence on the earlier versions of the DST,
the construction of stability and sameness and the
because they were current efforts to surpass the tra-
creation of innovation and novelty.
ditional monadic, coherent, and stable view on the
4. The polyphonic metaphor that Bakhtin
Self (cf. Linville, 1987; Markus & Nurius, 1986;
applied essentially to distinguish the literary
Khilstrom & Cantor, 1984). Similarly, the move-
works of Dostoevsky, where the author is no
ments within “the linguistic turn” sought to deal
longer presented as an omniscient entity narrating
with the phenomenon of the multiplicity of the Self
the story. On the contrary, it is presented as
(especially the social constructionist movement).
multivoiced and internally controversial, by being
Despite the reference on these cognitive and
habited with multiple voices that defend different
narrative influences in the early works upon the
perspectives and worldviews in contrast with each
DST, they became less present in subsequent works
other (Hermans, 2001a).
(cf. Hermans, 2001a, 2004a). The main reason is
that narrative appears as an insufficient concept in Inspired by this, Hermans and collaborators
this theory, as we have argued. Thus, according to (1992) have claimed that the Self—more than an
Hermans (1996), self-narratives, as products of dis- internal multiplicity that results from different roles
course that usually privilege the temporal sequenc- and contexts—is a dialogic polyphony, where several
ing and coherence of episodes, do not fully consider voices are contrasted translating multiple experien-
the dialogue and the voices that become alive, there- tial positions that co-exist in simultaneity. In this
fore diluting the narrator in detriment to the story sense, the Jamesian view is radicalized: not only the
that is told. In other words, more important than stories are multiple, but the agent that constructs
the narrated content is the relationship between these stories is also diversified. Thus, even if self-
the author and the audience, established through narratives appear as a form to construct coherence
the narrative. Moreover, according to Hermans, and cohesion in identity, they no longer guarantee
Kempen, and Van Loon (1992), the more adequate the personal unity and continuity given that we live
way to acknowledge the question of the multiplic- with multiple authors that constitute our Self.
ity of the Self is through the use of the polyphonic How to explain, then, identity and sameness?
metaphor and the notion of co-construction—that The answer proposed arrives from the notion of dia-
is, narrative cannot be more prevalent than the act logue: through the dialogical articulation achieved

428 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


between different “voices” of the Self and from our (parts of the world that are identified with the Self;
interpersonal engagement with others in a cultural e.g., we can carry voices of significant others within
world (Hermans, 1996). Furthermore, a voice ourselves or even internalize specific generalized cul-
translates a specific point of view that emerges from tural voices upon a given subject) that contrast with
a given existential position from where the world is internal voices (relating to different roles or parts of
experienced and perceived, forming a unique gestalt the Self ).
of experience (Holquist, 1990). In this line of rea- Although the DST attempts to surpass old
soning, the dialogical Self is conceived as a tensional dichotomies in psychology (e.g., Self–Other,
and dynamic multiplicity of self-positions that are Individual–Social), given the acknowledgement of
occupied in an internal dialogical space that feed the constant trades and interconnections happen-
distinct and independent voices, within the same ing through the flexible and permeable frontier of
person: the Self, according to some authors (Bertau, 2004;
Salgado, & Hermans, 2005), it is precisely in this
. . . we conceptualize the Self in terms of a dynamic
social and cultural landscape of selfhood that we
multiplicity of relatively autonomous I positions in
find the constraints in the movements and mul-
an imaginal landscape. [ . . . ] The I has the possibility
tiplicity of the Self. Salgado and Hermans (2005)
to move, as in space, from one position to the other,
are not as optimistic toward the versatility of the
in accordance with changes in situation an time.
Self as the original definitions might convey: The
The I fluctuates among different and even opposed
potentialities of movement in the dialogical Self
positions. The I has the capacity to imaginatively
are generally linked to the possibilities allowed in a
endow each position with a voice so that dialogical
given society, which are always limited within cer-
relations between positions can be established.
tain confinements (e.g., constrained either toward
The voices function like interacting characters in a
the compliance and conformism or toward oppo-
story. Once a character is set in motion in a story,
sition and rebellion directed to the socio-cultural
the character takes on a life of its own and thus
milieu).
assumes a certain narrative necessity. Each character
has a story to tell about experiences from its own
Moving Forward: Critical Elements to the
stance. As different voices these characters exchange
Dialogical Self Theory
information about their respective Mes and their
Despite the developments that have been occur-
worlds, resulting in a complex, narratively structured
ring within the DST, it is also necessary to recog-
Self.
nize that some issues require a special analysis and
(Hermans, Kempen, & van Loon, 1992, p. 28)
further development. In our view, there are several
According to the Bakhtinian “law of place- aspects that should be clarified and problematized
ment,” the Self is always involved in these dynam- if we want to keep dialogism as the epistemological
ics of positioning and repositioning, expressing and ontological reference frame to the DST.
voices that are related to spatial and temporally
specific positions, from which emanate idiosyn- Exploring the Imaginal Landscape
cratic views of the world (Holquist, 1990). Voices and the Multiplicity of the Self
express meaning-making processes on experience, If we resume Hermans’ initial proposal of the
which are emotionally grounded (Josephs, 2000) DST, we may now state that in DST, the dimension
and embodied (Fogel, Koeyer, Bellagamba, & Bell, of experience is usually conceived as an imaginal
2002; Hermans, Kempen, & Van Loon, 1992). landscape in which different positions of the Self, or
This dynamic movement of the Self between voices I-positions, move and relate to each other by means
and positions emphasizes the role of internal alterity of dialogue. The imaginal landscape and the posi-
given the contrast between other (former and poten- tions of the Self are therefore the structural elements
tial) voices or positions different from the voice of of the experiential domain. As dialogism empha-
the experiential position that is occupied by the Self sizes addressivity as a fundamental characteristic of
in the here and now (Valsiner, 2002). selfhood processes, the location and movement of
In sum, the dialogical Self does not have a clear I-positions in the imaginal landscape of the Self are
frontier with its external surroundings. Its borders considered to be a function of the correlative posi-
are highly permeable. In fact, the outside world is tion of each one of them to the other I-positions in
also inside the Self in the form of external positions the system of Self.

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 429


It is considered that as two I-positions address The Process of Difference and
each other, they become juxtaposed, one in rela- the Other As an Irreducible
tion to the other. This process of juxtaposition has Ontological Element
been metaphorized as a dialogue (in opposition to The process of difference needs further explora-
a monologue). For an I-position to communicate tion. We need to develop implications from the
with another I-position and the world, it is endowed argument that the human psyche is ontologically
with a voice that later becomes inter-related with based on the difference between Self and Other. As
other voices immanent from other I-positions, as mentioned earlier:
in a dialogue. These narrative voices constitute the
The dialogical perspective is based on the
other dimension of meaning-making that is con-
fundamental assumption that human life is
ceived to be dependent on constant positioning and
permanently an addressed existence. It therefore
repositioning of I-positions.
attributes a fundamental role to the Other in the
In another way, we could say that the dynamics
constitution of the I - human existence is co-
inherent to positioning and addressing constantly
existence or is not human. Therefore, difference -
sets up an experiential and narrative configuration
the radical asymmetry between any two persons -
that defines the relevance and salience of certain
simultaneity - the necessary co-presence of I and
experiential and narrative contents in detriment
Other without which neither of them may exist - and
of others that are elaborated and exchanged in dia-
tension - emergent from the simultaneity of insoluble
logue with others (see Fig. 19.1).
differences - become invaluable concepts for the
As can be seen in Figure 19.1, the most frequent
dialogical project. [ . . . ] Relationship, elaborated
configuration of the dialogical Self assumes that the
upon those concepts, is conceived to be previous
audience of each I-position is another I-position
to (id)entity: there is no previous I and no previous
(e.g., Georgaca, 2001; Hermans, Kempen, & Van
Other to the relationship that makes them an I to an
Loon, 1992; Raggatt, 2000). This leads to a con-
Other and an Other to an I.
ception of selfhood that is centered on the dia-
(Salgado, Ferreira, & Fraccascia, 2005, p. 13)
logical relations between I-positions, usually as
dyads. However, the possibility has been explored In fact, the process of difference is revealed as
that “instead of a dialogue between an I-position the basis of the genetic code of human psychologi-
(a voice) and another, each I-position has dialogi- cal processes, with simultaneity and tension as the
cal relationships to its addressee(s)” (Leiman, 2002, parameters that guide them on their trajectories. It
p. 232; see also Leiman, 1992). This opens dialogism is the conception of the relationship as consisting of
to other, more complex, and dynamic perspectives these components that distinguishes the dialogical
on selfhood (see Ferreira, Salgado, Cunha, Meira, & approach from others that stress the importance of
Konopka, 2005, for a comparison of several dialogi- relational processes. The figure of the relationship
cal approaches). emerges as a gestalt, a configuration of the inter-
active processes of the elements that constitute it,
and not as an object of study, a property, or a trait.
However, we believe that this process of difference
Self has not yet been fully developed.
Difference, we would say, is also related with
continuous tensional process between Self and
Other. However, we need to ask: What are we talk-
Position’s
Voice ing about when we talk about an Other? Traditionally
dialogical proposals in psychology have assumed
that the Other could be conceived as a represented
Position other (Hermans, 2004a); a person, a group, or a
community (Marková, 2003); a socially indexed
fictional narrative (Wortham, 2001); or a part of
the Self (e.g., Hermans, 2001a). The status of the
Figure 19.1 Dialogical relations between positions of the Self Other seems rather unclear, and this vagueness may
as diads. reach a point that sometimes seems confusing, if

430 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


not misleading. Moreover, this also represents a dif- human mind in a self-encapsulated way. To describe
ficulty in taking into account otherness as a consti- it as an emergent social performance without inner
tutive element of otherness. qualities would be oblivious to the compelling attri-
On this basis, the remainder of this chapter fur- butes of inner experience of emotions. We propose
ther elaborates a dialogical proposal to attempts to to recycle these notions, articulating them simulta-
contribute to a more full development of a dialogi- neously. Therefore, dialogism argues that the only
cal approach to selfhood processes. way to look inside the Self and at the same time
preserve its dialogical integrity is precisely by taking
Redescribing Selfhood from a Dialogical into account dialogical processes that occur inside
Perspective and outside the Self.
In previous sections, our elaboration on the Under this perspective, a communicational
ontological value of the difference between Self and act implies: “(1) a speaker who is simultaneously
Other led to the proposal that dialogical relations addressing, (2) an object and (3) the subjective
are constituted by: the Self, the Other, and the rela- world of the listener” (Salgado & Ferreira, 2005,
tionship between them (Holquist, 1990). p. 145). This means that the act of addressing is
Dialogism defends the relation between Self and not a simple movement from the Self to the Other
Other as the realm in which those two poles of com- (or from one position of the Self to another) but
munication emerge as two distinct, yet bounded, actually a twofold movement from the world of the
agencies (Marková, 2003). Therefore, this implies Self to the “specific world of the listener” (Bakhtin,
defending an “exteriority” of the Self, because the 1981, p. 282) and, simultaneously, to the “world out
subjective experience of oneself is correlative with there.” This Bakhtinian heritage has been brought
the Other with whom the person relates. However, up by dialogical approaches to selfhood both within
this does not lead dialogism to claim, as some social clinical psychology (Leiman, 2002, 2004; Leiman
constructionists have been doing, that we should & Stiles, 2001) and social-cultural psychology
avoid descriptions and explanations of the inner (Marková, 2003; Valsiner, 2007; see Ragatt, 2010,
experience. Our claim, here, is that a dialogical for a general analysis of this issue).
account preserves this distinction between inner and In this context, we will develop in the next sec-
outer realms and that subjectivity is brought to being tions our previous attempts of giving a dialogical
in the borderline of contact of these two domains. account of selfhood. We will defend the description
Take an emotion, for example. On the one hand, an of a triad of communicational agencies within the
emotion is an inner and private experience. On the inner realm of selfhood: I (as a center of experience),
other hand, it also brings an outer expression that the other-in-me (as the constructed and addressed
if the person does not make an effort of dissimu- Other), and internal audiences that shape the spe-
lation, it will be apprehended by the surrounding cific positioning of the moment. Moreover, this
people given its communication value. It is inner Self inner dynamics is always connected with the
and it is outer. The production of an emotion, in external dialogical activity in the world, in which we
itself, is based on some interpretation of the pres- encounter real others and real objects.
ent situation based on the previous personal history
of socialization that took place within contextual The Felt I
and historical specific backgrounds. Thus, if we ask, As Jacques (1991) writes, “[T]o the person,
“What is the self-experience of this person at this being is a process of self-production by a gradual
moment?” and the answer is, “This person is feeling self-identification. It is a process that acts directly
a strong feeling of rage against his boss,” we are con- on the Self, an activity which refers to itself in
necting the interior and the exterior, the personal order to prevent us from making a substance of this
and the social, self and other. An emotion, then, is a self-activity” (p. 22). As we observe the approach
bodily-sign—referring to something else, involving of Jacques, it is close to that proposed by Damásio
a joint interpretation of its meaning, while giving an (1999), for example, in the sense that both have
embodied felt sense of the agent’s needs or wishes. as primordial and elemental matter of identity the
To describe it only as the activation of a self-sche- feeling that “whatever is happening is happening to
mata of inferiority, for example, would be to cut the me” (other authors would call this the experiencing
relation between self and other and to describe the self; Greenberg & Safran, 1987). Thus, the Self, the

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 431


feeling of being an I, does not emerge from the use constant novelties and tensions within the space
of the personal pronoun as suggested by the discur- of the Self.
sive approaches. This feeling that “what happens,
happens to me” sets up an experiential center that The Other-in-Me
positions itself correlatively to the other elements of Another issue that needs further clarification has
the structure of experience. The spatial metaphor to do with how the Other gets in touch with the
here is not insignificant. Self. We have just claimed their continual separa-
tion but in a way that maintains their mutual bond
The Other and definition. Then, the question is: From the per-
Returning to the previous question about the spective of the Self, how is possible to reach that
Other—What are we talking about when talking Other?
about the Other? First, as previously discussed, it A usual solution is to postulate representations
is necessary to remember that the Other is not only of significant others. However, this has the prob-
a representation—it is another human agency that lem of suggesting a self-enclosed mind. This hap-
transcends the Self. We are talking to you, and our pens in different theoretical postulates, like the
words come in touch with your inner realm, and in notion of internal objects in psychoanalysis (e.g.,
that way, we are an Other to you. We may be some- Klein, 2002) or the possible selves in cognitivism
how represented by you, but our words have an (e.g., Markus & Nurius, 1987). Therefore, we think
element of strangeness that does not fit completely that this does not completely answer the question
your representation. And this leads us to the second of how the Other is elaborated by the Self. Without
point: The Other remains separated from the Self. denying that we do represent other people, in accor-
We feel the Other, we address the Other, but the dance with the framework, we have been advocating
real Other always remain partially alien. However, here representations are only means to relationships.
it is in the dance between Self and Other that they More important, to have a representation of some-
become mutually defined: If the operative principle thing does not entail, by itself, the possibility of
is radical otherness, then we are led to the need of having a communicational joint activity with that
considering a real other to know and describe a par- something.
ticular Self and assume its positioning in the inter- In our view, this demands a semiotic stance,
nal space of subjectivity. defending that it is through signs or chains of signs
Nevertheless, it is also true that Self and Other that people get a mutual minimal coordination that
communicate by exchanges of signs or chains of enables meaning-making. The possibility of joint
signs. Therefore, the voice of these two bounded activity between two people implies the elaboration
and separated elements comes in material forms of signs that they may trade. Consequently, com-
that transports each stance regarding some specific municative action becomes possible, and Self and
objects—words, gestures, and signs that carry the Other relate to each other. Signs or chains of signs
perspective and purposes of the agents. Look to are vital tools for the dialogical involvement.
these words: You do not need to be here and now Therefore, in every communicative action—and
to hear what we are saying—we will read this in every action is communicative, as it is always leaves
someplace else and in an unknown future to us. a trace or a sign waiting to be interpreted—there is
Therefore, signs are the media through which Self an agent semiotically addressing the Other. Initially,
and Other relate with each other, and this enables and whenever we engage in some activity with other
the possibility of relating with unknown others. people, there is a real Other. However, when these
Who or what is this Other? We come close to sign-mediated actions become internalized, we no
Marková’s (2003) definition: a person, a group, a longer need a real Other. We use signs “as-if ” there
community—a communicational agency. However, was a real other waiting on the other end of our
familial values, cultural norms, fictional charac- actions, utterances, or gestures. Many times, there
ters, social discourses, and so on, often assume the is no one there.
function of an Other and are not directly linked We will say that from the perspective of the Self,
to a particular person. We could name them “col- the Other is always that potential addressee of his or
lective voices” (Hermans, 2001a). Additionally, her semiotic activities. At the same time, it is also
the representation of the Other created by the an Other constructed by the Self—it is an Other-
Self never exhausts the real Other, introducing in-me. As a potential addressee, this Other-in-me

432 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


can take varied forms: It can be the interlocutor then there is no absolute limit to what forms this
of a sign exchange taking place (“Tell me, where addressee may take—it may be virtual, fictional, or
have you been this morning?”); it can be the same even the own person. Therefore, this Other-in-me is
person, talking to herself or himself (“How stupid the opposite end of the road that leads the process
I am!”); it can be nobody—in that case, we would of inner dialogicality.
say that it is a virtual Other, an addressed agency
lying in the other end of the message (e.g., leaving Internal Audiences
a book you like in a public space to let someone else The Other-in-me is the constructed and
read it); and we also admit that this Other-in-me addressed Other. However, the person may have
can be a material object, constructed in a anthro- other audiences interfering with the addressed one.
pomorphic way. For example, our addressee may be a dear friend in
The way this Other-in-me is based on matching whom we trust but who also has a very intimate
together what is happening in the moment (e.g., relationship with someone we deeply distrust—Will
utterances from another person) with the personal we tell him our personal secret? This third party will
previous experiences of similar circumstances that be highly influential in the course of events, but it
create a specific pattern of expectations around par- is not the addressee of my actions. Thus, we need
ticular objects or themes. Returning to a Piagetian to take into account third parties in every situa-
reasoning, we may call this patterned activity a tion, beyond those that might be involved in the
“relational scheme,” in which this social circum- situation. We have been calling these third parties
stances activates specific purposes (needs, wishes) internal audiences that constrain internal dialogical-
and expectations, guiding our social action (e.g., ity and the actual intersubjective and communica-
Safran, & Muran, 2000). This scheme is associ- tional process. As we stated elsewhere, these internal
ated with specific implicit or explicit images of the audiences are conceptualized
Other, but it is not a static element—its value lies
as the global context of the subjective realm. In our
in its potential dynamics (creating needs, wishes,
view, its development is probably rooted in personal
strategical moves, etc.). However, there is some-
and cultural history of each human life. It has to
thing more: This scheme is always matched with
do with the accumulating experiences of being in
the “incoming” response from reality—the sign-
contact with the world, especially, the intersubjective
mediated account about what is happening in the
experiences. In some sense, it has to do with culture,
moment. Thus, there is always a possible mismatch
with all the semiotic devices that we come in contact
between the “expected” Other and the “incoming”
with. However, it is deeply idiosyncratic, since
signs, generating a dialogical activity of positioning
every utterance, sign, or exchange with someone
and repositioning.
or something else immediately creates a specific
Therefore, we postulate the existence of an Other-
positioning of the experiencing I.
in-me: a process of continuous re-elaboration of the
(Salgado & Ferreira, 2005, p. 149).
potentially addressed Other, which is put in motion
by the articulation of a relational scheme (form- These internal audiences are compounded by all
ing the “expected Other”) with the sign-mediated Others’ responses, beyond the ones coming from
account of the reactions coming from the world the addressee. Therefore, their presence within the
(forming the “incoming Other”). In situations in inner realm of the Self creates a complex dialogical
which the Other-in-me is no real human agency, we space, in which the person is polipositioned at every
may have no real answer, but we still have effects, moment—not only socially but also internally.
and these effects are interpreted as socialized signs.
They are understood given previous relations with Progressive Differentiation of the
real others. In simple terms, the Other-in-me is Selfhood Domain
the addressee of the communicative actions of the As we have been referring, the real other has
agent. this function of generating the difference between
In sum, we are assuming that within the Self the Self and the Other. In this, the Other simul-
inner space, there is a place to otherness. This is taneously constitutes herself or himself as an I for
opens a developmental route to accomplish a pro- himself and an Other to another I. This person also
cess of self-relating based on this other: If the Other- occupies a place in the system of Self, becomes an
in-me is a half-constructed and half-alien addressee, Other-in-me, generating the internal difference and

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 433


dialogicality of selfhood. The process of interper- the Self or externalizing; see Valsiner, 2007) move-
sonal relationship, or external dialogicality, is con- ments, occurring simultaneously. The movement of
tinuous with the elementary structure of selfhood addressing is, of course, a centrifugal movement, but
and its intrinsic dialogical processes. as the Self addresses the Other and the world, she or
It is in this difference between Self and Other, he brings back traces of them that are incorporated
and therefore in the interplay between internal in one’s own experiences and narratives (as meaning
and external dialogicality, that the possibility of contents) and serve as basis in future references to
self-consciousness and meaning (both personal the Other and the world.
and shared) is opened—as has been proposed, for The Self is therefore moving and positioning
example, by researchers in newborn development simultaneously in two different domains: one is its
(e.g., Hobson, 1998). Progressively, real others gen- relation with the objects in the world, and the other
erate increasing internal differentiation of selfhood is its relation with the Other. On this basis, perhaps
as new relationships are established, bringing with we could name the dimensions of the relation with
them new meanings, new ways of relating to others the world as interobjectivity (Moghadham, 2003)
and objects in the world, as well as new subjective and the dimension of the relation with an Other as
states. This increasing internal differentiation of sub- intersubjecitivity.
jectivity simultaneously makes possible the intrinsic The double directionality of the Self generates
dynamism of its processes and also the participation those two simultaneous and necessarily connected
in and intentional use of cultural semiotic systems. life dimensions. Objects are always constructed by
Moreover, from an ontogenetic point of view, the person as semiotic objects, and because they can
we argue that it is within interpersonal relation- only become semiotic objects in the context of dia-
ships that more complex forms of inner relations logical relations with others. Thus, interobjectivity is
are developed, such as thinking through symbolic a realm achieved through the development of joint
manipulation. Assuming a Vygotskyan perspec- activities. The domain of intersubjectivity is mutu-
tive, the tools that will enable self-reflection— ally and reciprocally generated. Self and Other, in
the ability of using signs and afterward the use of their process of positioning toward a specific object,
self-referential signs, enabling self-identification are also positioning themselves toward each other.
and self-differentiation—are established through It does not imply an explicit commentary on the
the social guidance and constraints introduced by other party, but at least implicitly each human agent
caretakers. The developing child climbs the ladder reveals himself or herself in the positions assumed
of the successive zones of proximal development toward something else. Thus, the Self obtains a
introduced by Others and then becomes capable of “surplus of seeing” through the Other—specifically,
internalizing these tools (Vygotsky, 1978; Valsiner, through the positions he or she assumes toward the
2007). When internalized, it becomes possible to object of the joint activity, something is revealed
use those tools to guide self-observation or any about the Self.
other form of self-consciousness. Thus, objects are placed at the core of the dia-
logical relation. Each rejoinder in a social activity
Dialogical Relations: Interobjectivity assumes a position toward that object that positions
and Intersubjectivity all the others involved in a certain way. These others
Bakhtin (1981) has emphasized double direction- will respond to this position with another position
ality of any utterance. He has also emphasized that around that object, introducing a new perspec-
the words used in an utterance are half authored by tive about it or introducing some new object that
the speaking subject and half given, as they carry refracts the previous one. And the dialogue keeps
with them the history of previous usages carried out on and on.
by other persons. This idea of double directional-
ity, emphasizing that utterances carry traces of the Spatiality of the Self
Other, not only suggests that the Other is brought In the Bakhtinian tradition (Bakhtin, 1984), a
inside the Self but also that the Self is constantly spatial metaphor is used as well as the notion of posi-
addressing, referring, to something outside of it. tion. If we assume that Self, Other, and the objects
This delimitates a central process of selfhood: the of their attention are disposed in a space, we may
constant interplay between centripetal (away from say that they have a co-relative position toward each
the Self or internalizing) and centrifugal (toward other. This metaphor thus defines the impossibility

434 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


of two identical perspectives regarding the Other or supports and expresses a given position of the Self
the world and the impossibility of a subject simulta- toward its environment. Thus, we do not mean
neously occupying two positions toward the world. to suggest that the Self is permanently multiposi-
However, it may happen that multiple social others tioned, revealing different simultaneous positions
are involved, and in that case the same position of toward the world. The Self does not possess multiple
the Self toward an object will create multiple co- positions, even if throughout time it becomes a mul-
relative positions I–Other. For example, if someone tiplicity of states and tendencies that are enacted in
defends a friend against some threatening stranger, different relational contexts along time. Therefore,
this person is assuming one single position but these positions (or configurations) of the Self are
implying two antagonic I–Other configurations global self-states constituted by affects and thoughts,
(protecting the friend, and attacking the stranger). desires, signs, cultural values, and practices that are
In other words, the specific position of the Self aggregated in a semi-stable global organization.
is determined by the combination of the several Temporality and spatiality appear in DST
co-relative positions I–Other involved. related to the functional and structural charac-
Thus, it seems that the DST gives the wrong teristics it attributes to selfhood. Although we are
impression when insisting in the polyphonic self. well-aware of the perils of such distinction (struc-
On the one hand, it is true that throughout time we ture and function) and we recognize that it is not a
may assume different positions regarding the same clear-cut distinction, it serves a descriptive purpose.
objects; on the other hand, the Self only occupies a However, despite this, it has led to an overemphasis
position in any single moment. on the description of the components of selfhood
in detriment of the development of its dynamic
Conclusion and temporal dimension. So, the relation between
As we emphasized throughout this chapter, dia- temporality and spatiality of Self is still under-
logism attributes to difference-in-itself an ontologi- developed. Moreover, it is not an easy question.
cal status (very much in the same sense philosophers DST does not favor a perspective on temporality
of difference like Deleuze do) and takes it to have that considers it as being continuous and a unified
a function of bridging opposing and asymmetric process. Both because DST is focused on the rela-
elements. Therefore, dialogism frequently considers tions between elements of Self and considers rela-
antinomies to have an explanatory value by them- tions with different natures at different levels, there
selves instead of trying to favor one of their poles in will probably be several temporal trends involved in
detriment of the other (see Marková, 2003, for an selfhood. However, generally, DST emphasizes Self
elaboration on this topic). to be oriented toward the future. The present does
The debate pertaining to the openness and clo- not exist as an extended and stable time; it exists
sure of Self is, in DST, a function of two proposals: only in its relation to the future and to its history
that the Self is bounded by a membrane that sepa- and, therefore, its past. The present of the Self is an
rates Self from non-Self, interiority from exteriority, unstable moment in its process of becoming; it can
and that the elements that internally and externally only be apprehended by conceptually discontinuing
constitute the Self are mutually dependent and a group of processes that are constantly on the verge
connected through referential semiotic processes. of change and becoming different.
In this sense, DST endorses neither an individual The debate around the unity or multiplicity of
constructivism nor a contextual or social construc- the Self is the last point we would like to stress. To
tivism. Both Self and the context in which it is summarize what we just argued throughout this
immersed are co-constructed, and DST is focused chapter, we could say that in DST the Self is nei-
on the processes by which it occurs and on what it ther one nor several, neither single nor multiple.
involves. It is considered to be a decentralized and hetero-
The experiencing-here-and-now-I, as Valsiner geneous multiplicity. This means that there is not
(2002) phrased it, is always configured as “I, Other- a central organizing element or a hierarchical chain
in-me, and internal audiences” and draws always a of elements of different orders; no predetermined
separation between itself and its environment. The process is thought to decide which positions will
basis through which the Self draws this separation emerge across time or how they will organize in
and addresses the Other and the objects is a specific relation to one another. This way, Self is like a rhi-
configuration of those elements. This configuration zome in the sense that Deleuze and Guattari (2004)

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 435


have described rhizomatic entities: The several posi- integrity between the worldview in which it is based
tions that come to constitute the Self throughout (dialogism) and its conceptual and methodological
its history constitute centers of significance and dimensions.
subjectification. These functions of significance and In this context, several general questions are yet
subjectification are distributed across positions and to be addressed. Two of them appear to be funda-
are not dependent on any process besides the ones mental at this point. First of all, we argue that cur-
inherent to internal and external dialogicality of rent descriptions of the dialogical self are still static
the Self; they are not subject to any pre-determined descriptions in the sense that they are focused on
paths nor hierarchy. structural and dimensional parameters describing
These antinomies to which we just alluded to the system of selfhood. But how does this structure
also help us to position dialogical perspective on behave in motion? It is the question of changes in
selfhood in the global context of selfhood theories. its configuration over the course of experiential and
Traditionally, theoretical models of Self tend to communicational time facing us. Specifically, it is
emphasize one the poles of each one of these antin- also, for example, the question of the self-and hetero-
omies while criticizing their competitor models for regulation in the Self. Although these are still overly
positioning on the other pole. Sometimes, they may conceptual questions, they stimulate researchers to
accept some minor characteristics of the other pole expand DST into a more comprehensive model of
but still emphasize that Self is essentially open or human psychological domain and to reach clear
closed, for example. Dialogism, in stating that self- applications of DST throughout subdisciplines of
hood is constitutively relational in its processes and psychology. In time, these developments will show
elements (even when we are referring to the phe- the limits of dialogism, as a meta-theoretical frame-
nomena of individual thinking), sustains that Self work, and will orient researchers to new theoreti-
is essentially open and closed, temporal and spatial, cal developments and, most of all, to new synergies
constructed through narratives and dependent on between dialogism and other general frameworks.
non-narrative processes. In this sense, dialogical Second, the present descriptions are construc-
theory of selfhood is a positive and heuristic proj- tions derived theoretically. This gives rise to several
ect in that it accepts and integrates constitutive methodological issues that relate essentially to the
characteristics and processes of selfhood that usu- need to specify the properties of the constituent ele-
ally remain in opposite sides of the academic and ments of the Self and the processes involved in their
scientific debate. relations and the problem of access to the domain
of experience. Specifically, this final issue will result
Future Directions in questions like: Is it possible to identify internal
Major changes in DST have taken place since the audiences, for example, in all activities (whether
initial proposal of Hermans and colleagues. Some behavioral, cognitive, or emotional)? Hopefully,
recent versions of it have made a long way from the these questions will press researchers to develop dia-
scheme of I-positions involved in mutual relations logically sound strategies and methods of analysis of
within the landscape of the mind and contain some dialogicality inherent to selfhood without returning
promises of reshaping the way selfhood is conceived to traditional ways of conceiving phenomena and
within a dialogical framework. This has happened doing research that are hardly compatible with a
as dialogism has evolved and been articulated fur- strong dialogical framework. Because within dialo-
ther as a global system of thought and as research- gism, theoretical and methodological developments
ers have applied it to conceive specific phenomena. have evolved at different rates, this discrepancy
Although these two forces have been promoting between theory and method runs the risk of becom-
further developments in dialogism and DST, their ing a conservative force to dialogism innovative
potential to generate novelty in the way psychol- potential. Specifically, because the discussion around
ogy approaches and conceives human phenomena what would be dialogically informed research prac-
is also potentially hindered by the use of concepts tices is still incipient.
like voices or positions in ways that may have lost
their relation to dialogism. A major global challenge
Acknowledgements
to DST, therefore, is to maintain itself as dialogical. Preparation of this chapter was supported by the Portuguese
As further developments and applications of DST Foundation for Science and Technology grant PTDC/PSI
are presented, it is important for it to maintain the PCL/103432/2008 (Decentering and Change in Psychotherapy,

436 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


2010–2013) and PhD grants SFRH/BD/30880/2006 and Greenberg, L., & Safran, J. (1987). Emotion in psychotherapy.
SFRH/BD/48266/200. New York: Guilford Press.
Hermans, H. (1996). Voicing the self: From information pro-
cessing to dialogical interchange. Psychological Bulletin, 119,
References 31–50.
Bamberg, M. (Ed.). (2006). Narrative: State of the art [Special Hermans, H. (2001a). The dialogical self: Toward a theory of
issue]. Narrative Inquiry, 16(1), 1–228. personal and cultural positioning. Culture & Psychology, 7,
Bakhtin, M. (1981). The dialogic imagination: Four essays by 243–281.
M. M. Bakhtin (C. Emerson & M. Holquist, Trans.). Austin, Hermans, H. (2001b). The dialogical self [Special issue]. Culture
TX: University of Texas Press. & Psychology, 7(3), 243–281.
Bakhtin, M. (1984). Problem’s of Dostoevsky’s poetics (C. Emerson, Hermans, H. (Ed.). (2002). The dialogical self as a society of
Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press mind [Special issue]. Theory & Psychology, 12(2), 147–280.
(Originally published 1929). Hermans, H. (Ed.). (2003). Dialogical self and psychotherapy
Bakhtin, M. (1986). Speech genres and other late essays [Special issue]. Journal of Constructivist Psychology, 16(2),
(V. W. McGee, Trans.). Austin, TX: University of Texas 185–269.
Press (Originally published in 1979). Hermans, H. (2004a). The dialogical self: Between exchange and
Bertau, M.-C. (2004). Developmental origins of the dialogi- power. In H. Hermans & G. Dimaggio (Eds.), The dialogical
cal self: Some significant moments. In H. Hermans, & self in psychotherapy (pp. 13–28). New York, NY: Brunner-
G. Dimaggio (Eds.), The dialogical self in psychotherapy Routledge.
(pp. 29–42). London: Bruner-Routledge. Hermans, H. (Ed.). (2004b). The dialogical self in a global digi-
Bråten, S. (Ed.). (1998). Intersubjective communication and emo- tal age [Special issue]. Identity: An International Journal of
tion in early ontogeny. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Theory and Research, 4(4), 297–405.
Press. Hermans, H. (Ed.). (2008). Research and the dialogical self
Damásio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion [Special issue]. Journal of Constructivist Psychology, 21(3),
in the making of consciousness. San Diego, CA: Harcourt. 185–269.
De Man, P. (1989). Dialogue and dialogism. In G. S. Morson Hermans, H., & Hermans-Konopka, A. (Ed.). (2008). The
& C. Emerson (Ed.), Rethinking Bakhtin: Extensions and dialogical self [Special issue]. Studia Psychologica, 6(8),
Challenges (pp. 105–114). Evanston, IL: Northwestern 5–253.
University Press. Hermans, H., & Kempen, H. (1993). The dialogical self: Meaning
Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and repetition (P. Paton, Trans.). as movement. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
New York: Columbia University Press (Originally published Hermans, H., Kempen, H., & Van Loon, R. (1992). The dia-
1968). logical self: beyond individualism and rationalism. American
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2004). A thousand plateaus: Psychologist, 47, 23–33.
Capitalism and Schizophrenia (B. Massumi, Trans.). New Hermans, H., & Lyddon, W. (Eds.). (2006). The dialogical
York: Continuum (Originally published in 1980). approach to counselling theory, research, and practice [Special
Ferreira, T., Salgado, J., & Cunha, C. (2006). Ambiguity and the issue]. Counseling Psychology Quarterly, 19(1), 1–120.
dialogical self: In search for a dialogical psychology. Estudios Hermans, H., Rijks, T., & Kempen, H. (1993). Imaginal dia-
de Psicología, 27, 19–32. logues in the self: Theory and method. Journal of Personality,
Ferreira, T., Salgado, J., Cunha, C., Meira, L., & Konopka, 61, 207–236.
A. (2005). Talking about voices: A critical reflection Hibberd, F. (2001a). Gergen’s social constructionism, logical
about levels of analysis on the dialogical self. In P. Olés, & positivism and the continuity of error. Part 1: conventional-
H. Hermans, H. (Eds.), The Dialogical Self: Theory and Research ism. Theory & Psychology, 11, 297–321.
(pp. 121–130). Lublin, Poland: Wydawnictwo KUL. Hibberd, F. (2001b). Gergen’s social constructionism, logical
Fogel, A., Koeyer, I., Bellagamtar, F., & Bell, H. (2002). The dia- positivism and the continuity of error. Part 2: meaning-
logical self in the first two years of life. Theory & Psychology, as-use. Theory & Psychology, 11, 323–346.
12, 191–205. Hobson, R. (1998). The intersubjective foundations of thought.
Georgaca, E. (2001). Voices of the self in psychotherapy: In S. Braten (Ed.). Intersubjective communication and emotion
A qualitative analysis. British Journal of Medical Psychology, in early ontogeny (pp. 283–296). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
74, 181–194. University Press.
Gergen, K. (1985a). The social constructionist movement in Holquist, M. (1990). Dialogism: Bakhtin and his world. New York:
modern psychology. American Psychologist, 40, 266–275. Routledge.
Gergen, K. (1985b). Social constructionist inquiry: context and Jacques, F. (1985). L’espace logique de l’interlocution. Paris: PUF.
implications. In K. Gergen & K. Davis (Eds.), The social con- Jacques, F. (1991). Difference and subjectivity: Dialogue and per-
struction of the person (pp. 3–18). New York: Springer-Verlag. sonal identity (A. Rothwell, Trans.). New Haven, CT: Yale
Gergen, K. (1994). Realities and relationships: Soundings in social University Press (Originally published 1982).
construction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. James, W. (2007). The principles of psychology (Vols. 1 & 2). New
Gonçalves, M. (1995). Auto-conhecimento e acesso introspective: York: Cosimo (Originally published 1890).
Do self reificado ao self narrativo [Self-knowledge and intro- Josephs, I. (2000). Feeling as movement from a person-cen-
spective access: From the reified self to the narrative self ]. tered standpoint: Going beyond Willem Stern. Theory &
Braga, Portugal: Instituto de Educação e Psicologia. Psychology, 10, 515–829.
Gonçalves, O. (2000). Viver narrativamente: A psicoterapia como Klein, M. (2002). Love, guilt and reparation: And other works
adjectivação da experiência [To live narratively: Psychotherapy as 1921–1945 (The writings of Melanie Klein, Vol. 1).
adjectification of experience]. Coimbra, Portugal: Quarteto. New York: Free Press.

ben to, cu n h a , sa lga do 437


Khilstrom, J., & Cantor, N. (1984). Mental representations of Raggatt, P. (2010). The dialogical self and thirdness: A semiotic
the self. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social approach to positioning using dialogical triads. Theory &
psychology. Vol. 17 (pp. 1–47). New York: Academic Press. Psychology, 20, 400–419.
Leiman, M. (1992). The concept of sign in the work of Vygotsky, Safran, J., & Muran, J. (2000). Negotiating the therapeutic
Winnicott, and Bakhtin: Further integration of objects rela- alliance: A relational treatment guide. New York: Guilford
tions theory and activity theory. British Journal of Medical Press.
Psychology, 65, 209–221. Salgado, J., & Ferreira, T. (2005). Dialogical relationships as tri-
Leiman, M. (2002). Toward semiotic dialogism: The role of sign ads: Implications for the dialogical self theory. In P. K. Olés,
mediation in the dialogical self. Theory & Psychology, 12, & H. J. Hermans (Eds.). The dialogical self: Theory and prac-
221–235. tice (pp. 141–152). Lublin, Poland: Wydawnictwo KUL.
Leiman, M. (2004). Dialogical sequence analysis. In H. Hermans Salgado, J., Ferreira, T., & Fraccascia, F. (2005). Il sè dialogico
& G. Dimaggio (Eds.), The dialogical self in psychotherapy come un sistema triadico: L’Io come una parte del Noi.
(pp. 255–270). New York, NY: Brunner-Routledge. Ricerche di Psicologia, 28, 13–38.
Leiman, M., & Stiles, W. (2001). Dialogical sequence analy- Salgado, J., & Gonçalves, M. (2007). The dialogical self: social,
sis and the zone of proximal development as conceptual personal and (un)conscious. A. Rosa & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The
enhancements to the assimilation model: The case of Jan Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 608–623).
revisited. Psychotherapy Research, 11, 311–330. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking language, mind and world dialogi- Salgado, J., & Valsiner, J. (2010). Dialogism and the eternal
cally: Interactional and contextual theories of sense-making. movement within communication. In C. B. Grant (Ed.),
Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Beyond universal pragmatics: Studies in the philosophy of com-
Linville, P. (1987). Self-complexity as a cognitive buffer against munication (pp. 101–121). New York: Peter Lang.
stress-related illness and depression. Journal of Personality and Salgado, J., & Hermans, H. (2005). The return of subjectivity:
Social Psychology, 52, 663–676. From a multiplicity of selves to the dialogical self. E-Journal
Marcos, M. (2001). Sujeito e comunicação: Perspectiva tensional of Applied Psychology: Clinical Section, 1, 3–13.
da alteridade. [Subject and comunication: Tensional perspec- Sarbin, T. (1986). The narrative as a root metaphor for psychol-
tive on alterity]. Coimbra, Portugal: Campo das Letras. ogy. In T. Sarbin (Ed.), Narrative psychology: The storied nature
Marková, I. (2003). Dialogicality and social representations. of human conduct (pp. 3–21). Westport, CT: Praeger.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Shotter, J. (1997). Artificial intelligence and the dialogical self.
Markus, H. & Nurius, P. (1987). Possible selves. American The American Behavioral Scientist, 40, 813–828.
Psychologist, 41, 954–969. Stam, H. (Ed.). (2010). Self and dialogue [Special issue]. Theory
Martins, M. (2001). A racionalidade da linguagem humana: and Psychology, 20(3), 299–460.
Aquilo que os discursos dizem e aquilo nós fazemos com eles Stolorow, R., Atwood, G., & Brandchaft, B. (Ed.). (1994). The
[The rationality of human language: What the discourses intersubjective perspective. Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson.
say and what we do with them]. Revista de Comunicação e Trevarthen, C. (1998). The concept and foundations of infant
Linguagens, 29, 87–104. intersubjectivity. In S. Braten (Eds.). Intersubjective communi-
Mead, G. H. (1992). Mind, self & society from the standpoint cation and emotion in early ontogeny (pp. 15–46). Cambridge,
of a social behaviorist (Edited by C. W. Morris). Chicago, IL: UK: Cambridge University Press.
University of Chicago Press (Originally published 1934). Valsiner, J. (2002). Forms of dialogical relations and semiotic
Mendes, J. (2001). Porquê tantas histórias: O lugar do ficcional autoregulation within the self. Theory & Psychology, 12,
na aventura humana. [Why so many stories? The place of 251–265.
the fictional in human adventure]. Coimbra, Portugal: Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies: Foundations of
MinervaCoimbra. cultural psychology. New Delhi, India: Sage Publications.
Moghadham, F. (2003). Interobjectivity and culture. Culture & Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher
Psychology, 9, 221–232. psychological processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Piaget, J. (1955). The child’s construction of reality. London: Press.
Routledge and Kegan Paul. Wortham, S. (2001). The narratives in action: A strategy for
Raggatt, P. (2000). Mapping the dialogical self: Towards a research and analysis. New York: Teachers College Press.
rationale and method of assessment. European Journal of Zlatev, J. (Ed.). (2008). The shared mind: Perspectives on intersub-
Personality, 14, 65–90. jectivity. Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.

438 dialogi cal t he o ry of se lfhood


CHAPTER

Narrative Scenarios: Toward a


20 Culturally Thick Notion of Narrative

Jens Brockmeier

Abstract
This chapter investigates the role of narrative in the relationship between individuals and their cultural
worlds. Drawing on assumptions of interpretive cultural psychology and a Wittgensteinian concept of
narrative as a cultural form of life, it proposes a culturally thick notion of narrative. At the heart of this
notion is the idea of narrative as a cultural practice, a practice of meaning construction. This argument
is developed in discussions of five traditions of research that have explored the nature of narrative
(1) in contexts of cultural traditions and (2) socialization, (3) as a “form of life,” (4) with respect to
fictional and nonfictional genres, and (5) as an instrument and practice of folk psychology. The resulting
outline of a culturally thick notion of narrative is further elaborated by arguments from narratology,
discussions on narrative in the light of evolutionary anthropology, and interpretive approaches to
narrative in philosophy and the social sciences.
Keywords: narrative, narrative psychology, narrative practice, meaning, intentionality, socialization, folk
psychology, narrative as a form of life

Introduction are pivotal in binding the individual into a cultural


An inquiry into the nature of narrative that world and in binding the meaning of this world into
aims to situate its subject in the context of culture the individual’s mind. To explore this dialectic is the
and psychology reasonably draws on two differ- main purpose of my inquiry.
ent families of theories. One is a family of cultural To do so, I first need to qualify the meaning of
approaches to human psychology, the other a fam- culture and narrative. As both are subjects of high
ily of psychological approaches to culture. Essential complexity, it is not surprising that they come with
to both is the effort to understand the relationship an array of different conceptual definitions reflect-
between individuals and the cultural worlds in ing diverse points of view from which they can be
which they live. In this chapter I make the case that considered. The point of view underlying my dis-
language—particularly narrative—plays a crucial cussion is that of a cultural psychology. Cultural
role in this relationship. I therefore also consider a psychology investigates the relationship between
third family of theories, namely, theories of narra- individuals and their cultural worlds from a per-
tive that emphasize its cultural nature and allow us spective that, in some respects, differs from, say,
to conceive of the great variety of narrative practices cultural or social and psychological anthropology. It
to be found in all human societies as a variety of also is different from sociology or social psychology,
cultural practices. cultural studies, narrative studies, and hermeneu-
There is a twofold reason why narrative practices tic philosophy. At the same time, however, cultural
play a central role in humans’ cultural existence: they psychology draws on all of these traditions and uses

439
their resources—and they all are, in fact, part of the to the “local” specifics of the cultural models and
theoretical landscape that I want to survey. What is vocabularies of self and identity on which these nar-
more, the understanding of cultural psychology that ratives draw. Further, we may recognize that their
I bring to bear on this relationship is not that of a narrators do not necessarily have “a sense of hav-
clear-cut disciplinary economy but rather that of a ing a narrative identity,” perhaps not even a sense
point of view, a perspective that cuts through several of having a personal identity at all. To be sure, even
disciplines and that will become sharper as my dis- most people in traditions as obsessed with self-talk
cussion proceeds. as European and North American ones would use a
The qualification of culture and narrative, outlined different language than that of “narrative identity” to
in the second section of this chapter, leads to what talk about themselves.
I call a culturally thick notion of narrative—a notion Yet the proposition of a culturally thick notion of
of narrative as cultural practice and performance.1 narrative does not only rely on the multidisciplinary
The notion of narrative as a cultural practice takes resources just mentioned. There are more traditions
up Geertz’s (1973) suggestion that an interpretive of knowledge and thought that have contributed,
study of humans’ cultural reality is to be based on in one way or another, to a notion of narrative as
experience-near concepts. Such concepts, sometimes a cultural practice, which will be reviewed in the
called emic, are as close as possible to the experiential third section of this chapter. But before that—in the
discourse of the individuals whose, in this case, nar- second part, after this Introduction—I outline three
rative practices are at stake. Of course, “closeness” assumptions about culture and narrative that orient
to experience is relative. All human experiences are my ensuing discussion of the scholarly and scientific
generalized, but some are more and some are less so; traditions relevant here.
some echo common sense and conventional every- The fourth section then takes a closer look at what
day psychology, others give way to more reflected, is the quintessence of the notion of narrative put for-
individual, and deviant ways of meaning-making. ward in this chapter: the idea of narrative as a cultural
The important point here is that emic concepts form of life. This idea centers on an emic notion of
are concepts of a cultural world seen from within. narrative that, rather than postulating universal com-
They reflect the subject’s point of view, the perspec- ponents or ontological characteristics of storytelling,
tive from which people themselves consider their is based on a culturally situated mode of meaning-
experiences to be meaningful. On the other hand, making. This notion also comprises how people give
we have experience-distant “or etic” concepts. Etic meaning to what they consider to be a “story.” The
concepts are used in the description and analysis of fifth and final section offers an anticipatory look at
emic experiences—for example, by psychologists, important developments in the field: prospects of a
philosophers, anthropologists, and narratologists. culturally thick notion of narrative that permits us a
When, in everyday life, people tell stories about fuller understanding of the intricate relations between
themselves, they are typically concerned with issues the actions and minds of individuals and the cultural
that matter to them, with things they did, or with worlds that they create, populate, and change.
events affecting their actions, thoughts, feelings,
and relationships with others. In telling their stories,
Culture and Narrative: The Basics
they are arguably not concerned with the distinc-
tion of “story” and “discourse,” as important as it Culture As Perspective
may be in narrative studies, or the way their “sto- In recent years, our concepts and theories of
rylines” and “plot structures” unfold and (together culture have undergone radical changes that also
with other narrative, discursive, grammatical, and affect our understanding of the cultural charge of
semantic registers) are shaped by and give shape to narrative. People have always been viewed as cul-
their sense of “narrative identity.” Giving center stage tural beings, yet today many theorists have come to
to experience-near concepts not only enables us to emphasize that people do not just live in a culture,
become aware that people engage in very different but in a variety of cultural worlds. They are simul-
stories about themselves (which is to say that there is taneously embedded and entangled in distinct cul-
no single “narrative identity” narrative)—irrespective tural realities, and these realities are often divergent
of the fact that these narratives can be subject to the and conflicting among each other.
same categorical distinctions of “story,” “discourse,” Take people in a so-called “individualist cul-
“plot,” and so forth. It also makes us more attentive ture” who, irrespective of this label, can live in a

440 narrative sce na r i os


very social and relational way—they may have a experience “their culture,” have thus come to prefer
supportive family, a close network of friends, and a view more sensitive to the polyphonic, fractured,
be good team players at work. Whereas people in contingent, and often disharmonic ways of life and
a so-called “collectivist culture” may not only work experience, a view that is more able to bring to the
on their own and are without a family, but they may fore what Valsiner (2007) calls “the heterogeneous
also behave and think in a self-centered and ego- multitude of human dramas of everyday lives”
istic way. In addition, social realities can be expe- (p. 87). Repudiating the imposition of a marked-
rienced differently by different people within the off unitary culture concept on a group of people, a
same cultural world and even by the same people in society, or civilization (typically alien and different
different situations. Obviously, “individualist cul- from the investigator), many theorists now tend to
tures” and “collectivist cultures,” terms widespread conceive of social order as an unstable accomplish-
in cultural and cross-cultural psychology (for exam- ment that may be enforced, explained, legitimized,
ple, see Kitayama & Cohen, 2007), are prototypical and exploited by some members of a society and,
experience-distant, or etic, concepts. at the same time, questioned, rejected, and resisted
Moreover, although in the history of anthro- by others.
pology the existence of cultural traditions was long On this view, today’s cultural worlds are increas-
viewed as constitutive of a culture, there can be ingly open, inter-related, and fleeting. Sociologists
circumstances that exclude the formation of tradi- speak of “liquid realities” (Bauman, 2000). Cultural
tions. A good example, elucidated by Mintz (1974; worlds are permanently under construction. They
Mintz & Price, 1992), is the socio-cultural world extend on trajectories that link the local to the
of the Caribbean in the extended period of con- global. They are dynamic both in terms of internal
flict between colonial and postcolonial regiments. differentiations and contradictions, and in terms
In this period many previous traditions came to of external (inter- and multicultural) relations.
an end without comparable new cultural conti- They are made up of processes whose dynamics go
nuities establishing themselves. Mintz’s findings far beyond the idea of general laws, structures, or
have also confirmed a general observation: cultural rules. Instead, to use the language of cultural the-
experiences are typically contested. Interlaced with orist Appadurai (1996), they consist of emergent,
divergent powers and interests, they are subject to fractal, and fragmentary configurations that follow
controversies and conflicts of interpretation that are nonlinear ways on which they temporarily overlap,
often at the very heart of societal life. interpenetrate, and again diverge.
All of these conflicts and complications, as well Drawing on these discussions, the understand-
as their underlying political forcefields of power and ing of culture that underlies my approach to the
economic interests, tend to be neglected when cul- inter-relation between individuals and their cultural
ture is meant to refer to a monolithic and bounded worlds is neither substantialist, nor does it depend
context—a meaning that has been, in fact, perva- on generic terms or collective categories of culture.
sive (not least, in quarters of cultural and cross- At stake, then, is not what is defined as culture by
cultural psychology). One reason for this is that traditional anthropology (and mutatis mutandis by
psychologists and social scientists in general, when psychology in the wake of Wundt) as “that complex
describing and investigating culture in terms of a whole which includes knowledge, belief, arts, mor-
homogenized social unit, typically approach their als, law, custom, and any other capabilities and hab-
subjects with concepts and models that reflect their its acquired by man as a member of society” (Tylor,
own cultural worlds or, more precisely, the hege- 1871, p. 1). Rather than based on the assumption of
monic theoretical assumptions of these worlds. such a “complex whole,” my understanding of cul-
This argument has been much discussed in the ture (and, as I will explain in a moment, my ensuing
wake of two influential books by George Marcus, understanding of narrative) is epistemologically and
one written with Michael Fischer (1986), the other hermeneutically motivated. I propose comprehend-
with James Clifford (1986). Marcus has argued ing the role narrative plays for our cultural being
that anthropologists have organized their observa- in the world by using the “cultural point of view”
tions of and thoughts about the people they study as a perspective. This perspective allows me to view
according to categories of their own cultural tradi- human action (and, in the wake of Wittgenstein
tions. Many anthropologists and cultural theorists, and Vygotsky, I also count language as a form of
discarding the idea that all people in any one society action) and other material and symbolic practices

brockm eier 441


in a context without which they would remain form of life (Wittgenstein, 1953) defies a number
unintelligible. of exclusionary oppositions, such as those between
It is important to see that the idea of the cul- the verbal and the nonverbal, between linguistic
tural as a point of view on the world does not imply and communicative practices, between speaking
culture as an institution, a force, or a power—that and acting (including bodily acting), and between
is, as “something to which social events, behaviors, linguistic and material action. With this in mind,
institutions, or processes can be causally attributed,” let me qualify my point. On the one hand, I argue
to put the matter in Geertz’s terms (1973, p. 14). that without narrative, these cultural webs of mean-
At stake is a context in the sense of a frame, a per- ing cannot be spun, which is to say that without
spective within which certain phenomena can be the use of narrative, human beings cannot commu-
intelligibly (or “thickly”) described. On this view, nicate, interpret their experience, and guide their
culture loses all folkloristic color. It turns into an actions, except in a restricted way.2 At the same
epistemological, hermeneutic, and semiotic per- time, I propose that without narrative, we cannot
spective: a way of interpretation that allows certain investigate these webs and the way they are spun—
phenomena to gain meaning that otherwise would that is, without the use and the analysis of narrative,
remain enigmatic. Geertz (1995) speaks of a ground we cannot scientifically and scholarly interpret peo-
against which a figure becomes visible, meaningful, ple’s cultural self- and world-interpretations.
understandable. The hermeneutic circle inherent to this approach
has often been explicated as unavoidable part and
Cultural Webs of Significance parcel of every effort to understand human action
What is called the “cultural context” of a phe- and mind (e.g., Gadamer, 1989; McDowell, 1994;
nomena thus refers to a symbolic fabric, to a mean- Ricoeur, 1981), and cultural life at large (Rorty,
ing context—that is, it is not ontological. It does 1979). Against the backdrop of this philosophical
not have, for example, a materially manifest exis- tradition of reasoning, the study of cultural worlds
tence like a castle, church, or parliament building. cannot proceed like a nomological and experimental
To say it is of semiotic nature means it is mediated science in search of laws but must be “an interpre-
by signs—that is, it is neither of ecological, socio- tive one in search of meaning” (Geertz, 1973, p. 5).
economic, ethical, or political nature, although all This idea of human beings as “reaching for mean-
these contexts (and many more) are relevant here. ing,” which I have discussed in more detail elsewhere
Geertz (and, before him, Weber and Cassirer) has (Brockmeier, 2009), has long been established in the
used a compelling metaphor for this cultural mean- human sciences. It also became the springboard for
ing context: that of humans as animals suspended in Bruner’s (1986, 1990) vision of narrative psychol-
webs of significance they themselves have spun. My ogy as a core area of cultural psychology. Bruner,
point now is that if we view the cultural context of one of the pioneers of cultural narrative psychology,
human action and mind in this sense as a semiotic saw this endeavor from the very beginning as closely
construction, as “the fabric of meaning in terms of connected to cultural anthropology.3
which human beings interpret their experience and
guide their actions” (Geertz, 1973, p. 145), then Functions of Narrative
the most complex and comprehensive sign system, What then, more exactly, is the general role of
language—and especially the most complex and language in the unfolding und understanding of
comprehensive form of language use, narrative— cultural meaning contexts? And what is the par-
plays a pivotal role in spinning these webs of ticular role of narrative, especially, when we bear
significance. in mind that an essential assumption of the just
I should mention that the concept of language mentioned project of a narrative psychology is to
(and, by inclusion, of narrative) that underlies this understand narrative practices as cultural practices?
argument is a Wittgensteinian notion of language as To explore this question, I take a socio-evolutionary
an open and fleeting form of life. This notion sug- and anthropogenetic vantage point. What charac-
gests a discursive and performative understanding terizes human activities on a socio-cultural level
of language as mingled with a broad spectrum of as specifically human is that they are mediated
other practices of life, which is in contrast with an through increasingly sophisticated forms of social
understanding of language lodged within an exclu- sharing, collaborative action, and cultural learning.
sively linguistic arena. The idea of language as a For Tomasello (2008), human beings have evolved

442 narrative sce na r i os


to coordinate complex activities. These activities some of what follows), combines and condenses all
comprise culturally essential forms of shared inten- options of language and, in doing so, creates novel
tionality such as “reading” the intentions of others, syntheses of meaning. No other sign system could
emotional interaction, pretending, playacting, and handle and communicate the complexity of these
gossiping. It is because they are adapted for such syntheses in such a comprehensive, economic, and
cultural activities—and not because of the cleverness effective manner.
of their individual minds—that humans are able to There is little doubt about the evolutionary
do so many exceptionally complex and sophisti- advantages of narrative, even in its most elemental
cated things. There is a hub to all these complex form as preverbal language of enactment, as Abbott
and sophisticated things that make human beings (2000) has stated (on the evolutionary origins of
unique: this is joint sign-mediated meaning con- narrative, see also Abbott, 2001, and Boyd, 2009).
struction and interpretation, with language being Performed storyworlds (i.e., enacted narrative sce-
the evolutionary and socio-historically most devel- narios) might have dominated an early evolution-
oped constructive and interpretive mode (Lock ary stage of narrative, which then, at the same time,
& Symes, 1999; Nelson, 1996; Tomasello, 2003, would also have been one of the early stages of
2008). It is in this sense that Jakobson (1960a) human cultural and intellectual history. Narrative,
pointed out that language “serves as a foundation for Abbott (2000), “is not a product of grammatical
of culture. We may go even further and state that language, but a preexisting condition for it that was
language is the necessary and substantial foundation later absorbed and enriched by language” (p. 255).
of human culture” (p. 107). Once fully developed, narrative becomes one of
those capabilities whose evolutionary and cultural
Narrative Complexity advantages so easily escape our attention because we
Yet this is not just about language or linguistic are, from early childhood on, used to taking them
practices. The more humans’ social and cultural for granted. We are immersed in it: we breathe it.
activities have become complex, both on an evolu- It has become our element. Borrowing an analogy
tionary and socio-historical plane—that is, the more from evolutionary niche theory suggested by Hutto
they are socially inter-related, are based on shared (2009), we can say “that narratives are a distinctive
intentionality, involve extended action sequences, and characteristic feature of human cultural niches,
and demand planning and anticipating—the more just as dams are for beavers” (p. 27).
they involve complex linguistic practices. Why do
we call these linguistic practices complex? Because Four Basic Functions
they afford humans the possibility to navigate spa- To get a clearer sense of this unique capacity, we
tial and temporal scenarios that go beyond the here can distinguish several basic functions of narrative; all
and now and encompass multiple events in several of which are at work in the example just quoted. All
forms of past and present. Moreover, they allow us of them are functions of action—that is, they are in
to look forward to and imagine future scenarios the service of human activities, which explains why
and hypothetical—subjunctive—events (Carrithers, they are as variegated as the forms of life which they
1992; Grodal, 2005; Nelson, 2007a). The overarch- realize. Building on Wittgenstein, we can view narrat-
ing form of discourse in which such complex linguis- ing as a way to do things with words. However (and
tic practices are organized is narrative. A great ape here this view diverges from that of Austin’s [1962]
may communicate, “I want that banana.” However, famous founding question of speech act theory How
a language at the complexity level of narrative is to do things with words?), narrating is not only a way
needed for the following sequence (taken from an to do things with words; it also involves an array of
ongoing conversation between a young couple): other linguistic and nonlinguistic means, of media
“I want that banana, but only if it is not from the or semiotic environments, and of social and institu-
fruit shop where you got those disgusting bananas tional constellations. It thus may be more appropri-
yesterday—probably because you thought, ‘Wow, ate to approach it as a means, or action, to carry out
this is an eco shop, the first one in our neighbor- certain functions under certain circumstances, rather
hood, terrific, terrific, and we must support it, and than by universally defining some structural proper-
so on and so forth.’ We really should throw those ties or basic elements. I will come back to this idea of
mushy bananas in the trash before they start to rot.” narrative as action in a moment, but first let me spell
Narrative, to make a long story short (and to foresee out narrative’s four basic functions.

brockm eier 443


First and most importantly, narrative, as already cultural identity. An essential element of one’s sense
indicated, is crucial in enabling developed forms of of cultural belonging is the inter-relation between
social sharing, coordinating joint actions, and inter- social inclusion and exclusion. Although the desire
subjective understanding. This is narrative’s com- for belonging seems to have developed one of the
municative function. Second, narrative is a force oldest, not to say archaic and most deeply rooted
to express and push forward particular views in the form of bonding, there have always been diverse,
service of particular interests. Narrating is humans’ even contradictory forms of belonging: practices
most powerful means to make one’s case—to of simultaneously localizing oneself in several cul-
explain, persuade, and defend something—against tural narratives and symbolic spaces of identity
the case of others. This is the rhetorical function of (Brockmeier, 2001). For most people, the wish of
narrative. Third, narrative not only allows people belonging to a society leads to what Valsiner (2007)
to share their emotional and intentional states with has called “a real effort at an impossible task,”
others, but also to make sense of the emotional and simply because a modern society has become too
intentional states of others as well as of themselves. decentralized and too heterogeneous a field to allow
That is, it affords them to become aware of, reflect for unambiguous identification. What further com-
on, and regulate their feelings and other mental plicates matters is that most modern social and per-
(and bodily) states. This is its empathetic or emo- sonal identifications refer to fictional units. A prime
tional function. And fourth, narrative has a cog- example is the nation state which, according to
nitive function, a term I use as a shorthand for its Anderson (2006), only exists as an “imagined com-
manifold intellectual (or reflexive) and imaginative munity” because the members of this community
potentials. cannot possibly know each other.
The cognitive function is manifest in narrative’s That cultural identity fans out in a network of
capacity to make sense of experience, to operate as often conflicting relations to other identities (and to
a way of problem solving, and to give shape to the other social networks) becomes particularly patent
most intricate thoughts, visions, and imaginings—in in the case of individuals’ sense of national iden-
fact, to have many of them come into existence in tity. In much of today’s world, a sense of national
the first place. The cognitive function comprises belonging means balancing a difficult to entangle
special forms and capacities, such as ability (quite array of plural identities that reflect a multitude
prominent in the quoted example) to construe mul- of inclusions and exclusions. One and the same
tilayered temporal scenarios and gestalts of time, be Belgian can be a Flame and a Huguenot, a native
they real or fictive, realistic or fantastic. These tem- speaker of French and Portuguese, an employee of
poralizations go far beyond the sequential ordering an U.S.-based multinational company who lives in
of events and individual actions; they extend to the the Netherlands and is married to an immigrant
lifetime of individuals and the historical visions of from India. We are all familiar with such or similar
communities. Narrative thinking enables us to fol- identity constellations that can be lived out in many
low a flow of events both in the here and now of different ways and described in terms of many dif-
our social and societal life, and within the broader ferent but inter-related personal and collective iden-
temporal horizon of history and evolution. Perhaps tities (Straub, 2002). But, and this is my point, if
the most powerful way, Bruner (2002) remarks, to they are to be articulated from a first-person point
distance ourselves from the immediacy of events of view (perhaps in view of life as a whole, as subjec-
and experiences is to convert what we’ve encoun- tively meaningful gestalt, or as the search for such a
tered into story form. And not least, the cognitive gestalt, in a word, as a relation of figure and ground),
function allows us to give shape to and reflect on the then it unavoidably takes the form of narrative. In
cultural dynamics mentioned above, the dynamics such a story, the four basic functions of narrative
ensuing from the fact that people live in more than merge. We still may call it a personal (or first-per-
one cultural world, which is especially manifest son) narrative and also a narrative of an “impossible
under conditions of modern globalization. task,” or a story that is supposed to impose order
and coherence on the inherent instability of a post-
The Case of Cultural Identity modern “messy self ” (Rosner, 2007), yet we should
An illuminating illustration of this aspect comes bear in mind that “the personal” here is a highly
with the thorny question of how we understand, cultural arrangement—and so are the models and
under modern and global conditions, an individual’s conventions of storytelling and autobiographical

444 narrative sce na r i os


narrative that bring about this arrangement. These documentarian. Using an expression by Goodman
models range from literary, philosophical, psycho- (1978), narrative has been conceived of as a “way
logical, and political genres to popular and everyday of worldmaking” (Brockmeier, 2005a; Bruner,
genres of narrating; they encompass the entire range 2001; Herman, 2009a). What Whorf (1956) wrote
of what has been called “narrative folk psychology” about the “background linguistic system” of each
(Bruner, 1990; Hutto, 2009). language in general also holds true for the narra-
tive registers of each language, namely, that it “is
Narrative As Action not merely a reproducing instrument for voicing
In line with most social scientists, psycholo- ideas but rather is itself the shaper of ideas, the pro-
gists have been interested in narrative first of all gram and guide for the individual’s mental activity,
as a method or methodology, as a way to find out, for his analysis of impressions, for his synthesis of
as a means to an end. The stories people tell in his mental stock in trade” (p. 212). Meanings are
research settings such as interviews are conceived neither incorporated in the material world nor an
of as providing access to either a given social or inherent quality of words; they are, as Wittgenstein
psychological reality or to the experience of such a pointed out, negotiated in interactions within a
reality. Specifically operationalized narrative meth- cultural community. Wittgenstein put particular
ods allow researchers to “collect data” and objectify emphasis on the language games emerging in these
them through coding systems and other elaborative interactions, with narrative as one particular lan-
techniques. This sort of research proceeds on the guage game (1953, § 23).
assumption that narrative represents social or psy- It is from within such a “cultural grammar,”
chological reality, that it offers a window on such an idea echoing both Wittgenstein’s and Whorf ’s
reality. What makes this assumption so persuasive thinking, that we mentally organize our being in the
is that it is well-articulated not only in the social world. “The categories and types,” Whorf (1956)
sciences, but also in narrative studies and criticism. wrote, “that we isolate from the world of phenom-
Many influential investigations of literary narrative ena we do not find there because they stare every
have privileged nineteenth-century realist novels, observer in the face; on the contrary, the world is
generalizing their role of mimesis (i.e., of simula- presented in a kaleidoscopic flux of impressions
tion, imitation, or representation), whereas they which has to be organized by our minds—and this
neglect the non-mimetic nature of much narrative means largely by the linguistic systems in our minds”
discourse, as critics like Richardson (2006) have (pp. 212–213). I take narrative to be one of these
argued. In more general terms, this view piggybacks Whorfian linguistic systems, even if we might be
on an understanding of language as representation more reluctant today in using the term “system” for
of reality or as the representation of the experience such an open and fleeting form of life. Wittgenstein’s
of this reality. Irrespective of a long tradition of cri- concept form of life also helps us to discern another
tique, this paradigm of language as a mirror of the essential quality of narrative discourse: its interwo-
world (Rorty, 1979) has proved to be most resilient venness with all kinds of actions, linguistic and not.
and continues to flourish not only in common sense, As ecological and cultural linguist Harrison (2007,
but also in many quarters of the social sciences and p. 205) has put the matter from the perspective of
humanities, from psychology to narratology. an empirical field researcher: languages exist and
One problem resulting from the focus on nar- evolve to interact, convey information, and shape
rative as representation is that it misses out much meaning “within a specific cultural matrix” that
of what else narrative discourse is about. Let me influences and permeates every level and aspect of
give prominence to just one further use to which them; they thus “must be studied holistically and
narrative can be put. As with all language, narra- in their natural – that is cultural – context.” When
tive not only represents (or re-presents, or reflects, languages die off, Harrison maintains, entire reali-
or expresses) reality, but also creates reality. It is a ty-models (most prominently, those embedded in
way not only of organizing experiences but also the lexical resources of a language) are lost forever
of making new experiences. Rather than simply (Harrison, 2011).
mirroring the world, it also invents the world; in It is against this theoretical and empirical back-
fact, it evokes many worlds, storyworlds—be they ground that my cultural-psychological perspective
fictional or factual, told by the liar, the poet, the gives center stage to narrative as action, as a cultural
visionary or by the accountant, the judge, the practice that is wider in scope, more differentiated

brockm eier 445


and powerful than what could be captured by a section, I flesh out this sketch by reviewing five tra-
cognitive, linguistic, narratological, or critical focus ditions of scholarship and research concerned with
alone. What could be seen as weakness turns out to the relationship between culture and narrative. All
be its strength: that the borders of a culturally thick of them have made, in one way or another, a sig-
notion of narrative are fuzzy because it is interlaced nificant contribution to the study of the cultural
with many other cultural practices, linguistic and nature of narrative and the role of narrative within
nonlinguistic. humans’ cultural worlds at large. Although some of
Another way to understand narrative as action these traditions have a remarkable history, which
is to see the point of storytelling not as a mode of would be a valuable subject in its own right, my
representing but of construing meaning. And this is interest is not primarily a historical one. Rather, I
an important difference. It is the difference between view these approaches as shedding light on impor-
an idea of narrative as a reified entity (something tant aspects of the cultural matrix of narrative I have
Rom Harré and I have expounded as the “ontologi- set out to explore.
cal fallacy”) and the idea of narrative as a discursive
or cultural process, as a mode of meaning-making Narrative and Cultural Tradition
(Brockmeier & Harré, 2001). Taking Bruner’s point One of these aspects is the role of narrative in
about narrative as meaning construction a step fur- creating, preserving, and transforming cultural tra-
ther, we have argued that a more appropriate way to ditions—that is, its importance as a bond of inter-
study the discursive reality of this mode than classi- generational and historical continuity. Within the
fying narrative structures or components is to exam- context of anthropological approaches, the study of
ine the ways in which people engage in the very this role goes back to Edward Sapir’s (1949/1933)
business of meaning-making and, in the process, idea of narrative as a “culture-preserving instrument.”
use stories. There are no forms of narrative that exist Sometimes, the origins of this line of thought are
as universal templates to be made concrete; instead, even traced back one more century to the linguis-
they are constrained to take the forms they do by tic and philosophical work of von Humboldt (e.g.,
the exigencies of the particular cultural situations in Jahoda 1992). To view publicly circulating stories
which they occur. Rather than conceiving of narra- of a community—myths, fables, fairytales, religious
tions as given ontological (or cognitive, or linguis- and historical legends, and other folk stories—as
tic, or metalinguistic) entities, we have described part of what Wundt (and Lazarus and Steinthal
them as modus operandi of some of our discursive before him) described as Völkerpsychologie, was not
practices or performances (Brockmeier & Harré, unusual among literary and cultural-history schol-
2001, p. 53). The question, thus viewed, is not how ars in the first half of the last century, the time of
people use narrative as a means to a representational Sapir and Whorf. In the 1920s and 1930s, classicists
end, but what are the concrete cultural conditions examined the transmission of ancient Greek narra-
under which they tell stories and in so doing implic- tives in a world of orality (e.g., Parry, 1971) and
itly define what they take to be narrative. This may early ethnographers of narrative and folklore such as
also comprise a view of narrative as representation.4 the Russian Formalists (e.g., Propp, 1968) investi-
It is in this fashion that the cultural study of narra- gated what they saw as culturally canonical patterns
tive practices becomes emic, in the sense outlined at of folk tales. Many works of the period were inspired
the beginning: it is based on experience-near stories by similar interest in the cultural nexus among social
of what people, at a certain point in time, consider life, language, narrative, and other semiotic envi-
to be meaningful in their lives. ronments. Much discussed examples are Benjamin’s
Archades Project (1999), never completed because
Exploring the Cultural Matrix of of his death in 1940, about the cultural world of
Narrative: Traditions Paris he called “the capital of the nineteenth cen-
In the last section I have sketched a culturally tury,” and Mikhail Bakhtin’s (1993) studies from
thick notion of narrative, localizing it on three dif- the 1930s and 1940s about the Renaissance and
ferent maps: as a mode of interpretation through “Rabelais’ world.”
which people try to understand their being in the Over the last decades, linguistic anthropolo-
world, as a cultural practice realizing several (com- gists and ethnographers of narrative in the wake of
municative, rhetorical, empathetic, and cognitive) Sapir and Whorf have extended the view of narra-
functions, and as a form of action. In this third tive as a “culture-preserving instrument.” The new,

446 narrative sce na r i os


extended view is meant to encompass not only the processes and fine tunes them, in a variety of inter-
function of narrative for a cultural tradition but also subjective practices, to culturally canonical require-
the function of a cultural tradition for narrative or, ments (Brockmeier, 2004). For Rogoff (2003,
more precisely, for the specific organization of nar- p. 282), the focus on this “guided participation in
rative “speech events,” storytelling performances, cultural endeavors” is at the heart of the Vygotskian
and other linguistic practices and discourses (e.g., vision of human development.
Bauman, 1986; Hymes, 1964; 1974; Duranti, Why is entering the world of narrative discourse
2006; 2009a). The idea of narrative practices as cul- such a crucial cultural endeavor? It induces the child
tural practices has led to the analysis of language- into discovering a new experiential space, a space
specific and culture-specific narrative forms, such as that opens to a symbolic universe with unprece-
genres, semantic and grammatical resources, indexi- dented social options, as Nelson (2004; 2007b) has
cal systems, situated contexts of communication, argued. In learning the rules of narrative language
and language socialization. games, children not only find out that stories can
fulfill several functions that all extend their horizon
Narrative and Socialization of agency, but also that the same event can be told
As we have seen, the interplay between narrative in different ways from different perspectives. This
and the cultural world can be approached from two narrative multi-perspectivalism comes in tandem
different angles: whereas narrative practices appear with a multicentered “theory of mind,” if we want
to be shaped and guided by cultural traditions, they to use this term to refer to the social and pragmatic
simultaneously play an important role in estab- skills of what, in an alternative view, has been called
lishing and transforming these very traditions. To humans’ “interpretive mind” (Brockmeier, 1996;
participate in social life it thus is essential for each Ricoeur, 1981). The multiple perspectives, and
individual to become a culturally competent story- the need to interpret them, that emerge in narra-
teller, which is encouraged by members of a cultural tive interactions help children to understand that
world who are deeply concerned with children’s able different stories often reflect different people with
participation in social life and command of cultural different minds; they articulate different beliefs and
knowledge. Central to both is language and the points of view on the world, and this includes the
skillful use of its registers, from grammar to nar- worlds and minds of others. Ultimately, under-
rative, conversational turn-taking (Ochs & Taylor, standing—interpreting—different stories is to
2001; Ochs & Schieffelin, 2006) and other forms of understand different minds. And this is not little.
“streetwise” language use (Zentella, 1997). How an It requires, Nelson (2007b) writes, “understand-
individual learns to actively participate in the nar- ing the sources of differences among people—their
rative language games of his or her cultural world background, personalities, relationships, histories”
is the central issue in a second field of research that (p. 219). There is abundant evidence from a vari-
I review in this subsection. This field has emerged ety of empirical fields suggesting that narrative is
from the study of language socialization and the pivotal for the emergence of this folk psychology of
developmental psychology of language. Influenced social understanding (e.g., Herman, 2009c; Hutto,
by the work of Vygotsky (1978, 1987)—another 2008, 2009; Nelson, 2009; Ornaghi, Brockmeier, &
contemporary of Sapir, Whorf, and Wittgenstein—it Grazzani, 2011).
has drawn attention to narrative and narrative prac- Drawing on Vygotsky’s theory of human ontog-
tices as an important way of integrating different eny as based on social-interaction, we can say that
strands of linguistic socialization. It is in fact a syn- language and, by inclusion, narrative can be con-
thesis of a broad spectrum of linguistic and psy- ceived of as the pivotal hinge between the child and
chological aspects of language development that is the cultural world within which he or she develops.
realized in narrative discourse. More than that, the Not least in view of narrative development, Nelson
implications and consequences of narrative devel- (1989a) has noted that we owe to Vygotsky the most
opment affect the entire cultural socialization of the profound explanation of the role of language in the
child (Daiute & Lightfoot, 2004; Miller, Fung, & development of the child—especially as far as his
Koven, 2007; Nelson, 2007b). Learning how to tell or her culturally shaped sense of self is concerned.
and understand stories in early childhood is a pro- Language, for Vygotsky, is characterized in a two-
cess that combines linguistic, social, and psycholog- fold way. It is operative as a societal semiotic system
ical (cognitive, emotional, and moral) development and, in and through the process of its individual

brockm eier 447


acquisition, as a mode of social, linguistic, and cog- mainly concerned with personal stories (as a partic-
nitive development that allows novices to enter a ular variation of cultural stories) and the discursive
linguistic and cultural community. In Vygotsky’s and social contexts of interaction in which they are
psychological semiotic, language is essential for all told, performed, and interpreted—as in the clas-
forms of what he called “higher mental or psycho- sic studies by Miller (1982), Nelson (1989b), and
logical functioning,” by which he referred to mental Ochs (1988).
processes that are mediated by tools, especially “psy-
chological tools” or signs, that is, cultural signs. Narrative as a Form of Life
This process gains a new quality as soon as chil- Traditionally, developmental psychology has
dren begin to understand and use narrative discourse revolved around the individual child, and from this
practices because it is these practices that offer them perspective, it also has viewed the development of
access to the manifold storyworlds of a cultural an individual’s linguistic and narrative “compe-
community. The child is entering what Nelson tence.” Yet Vygotskian perspectives, socialization
(2007b) calls a new experiential space: a community theories, pragmatic approaches, and other cultur-
of minds. Acting as a member of this community ally oriented investigations have shifted emphasis:
means “we learn to tell the stories that our social from the autonomous individual and his or her
world values, and our storied thoughts come to con- mental or cognitive life, to the intersubjective, con-
firm to the models of our society” (Nelson, 1996, textual, institutional, and socio-economical realities
pp. 184–185). In Nelson’s Vygotskian view, this of human development. In this way, narrative too
community is the core of cultural life. It encom- has been increasingly examined as a form of com-
passes cultural environments in which the child munication and co-construction of meaning. At the
begins to explore the intersecting complexes of same time, it has served as a method of investiga-
communication, narrative, conceptual knowledge, tion. This trend has been undergirded by disciplines
and memory. In these experiences, and theories from distinct backgrounds. Notably,
parts of sociolinguistics, linguistic anthropology,
the child begins to encounter and engage with
ethnography, discourse studies, auto/biographical
cultural knowledge systems beyond the personal
studies, life story research, and action and practice
range . . . Practices in cultural environments common
theory have all contributed to the formation of a
to life in the preschool years may be particularly
field that, by now, can be marked as a third over-
significant: symbolic play and games, and cultural
arching research approach to the cultural nature of
narratives—stories, myths, folktales . . . and so
language and narrative.
on—all contribute to narrative consciousness and
Bolstered by one of the most influential para-
thus to becoming a member of the community of
digms of modern philosophy of language—the
minds where these practices originate.
non-representational notion of language as com-
(Nelson, 2007b, p. 212)
municative and intersubjective form of action,
The implications of this view are far-reaching. To unfolded by Pragmatism, Wittgenstein, Austin,
assume that during their first 10 years children are Davidson, Habermas, Rorty, and others—many
developing toward membership in a human com- sociolinguistic and social-scientific-oriented stud-
munity of minds challenges the traditional concept ies have begun to explore narrative as a mode of
of theory of mind. It broadens the concept from interaction and, in the process, cast light on its cul-
something that children (in a developmental “mile- turally situated nature. Yet it is not only the orienta-
stone event”) invent for themselves or that emerges tion toward the contextually and culturally situated
from their cognitive development to a “cultural con- nature of narrative practices and the understand-
ception of what it is to be a person within a human ing of these practices as ways of meaning-making,
community” (Nelson, 2007b, p. 219). The point at it also is the recognition of their ubiquity in many
issue is no longer a single mind and its theory but cultural worlds that is a common feature in this
children—persons—and their minds, their interac- field. The notion of narrative emerging here might
tions, and interpretations according to the cultural therefore be best dubbed in a Wittgensteinian
conventions of a community. manner as a cultural form of life—or, to use a dif-
Whereas research in the first tradition, outlined ferent expression, as a language game “consisting of
in the previous section, has concentrated on cul- language and the actions into which it is woven”
tural narratives, the Vygotskian approach has been (Wittgenstein, 1953, §7).

448 narrative sce na r i os


There are several more currents of research that and conversational or face-to-face settings (includ-
have developed conceptual and analytical tools for ing those constituted by ethnographic and psycho-
the investigation of narrative as a cultural form of logical research interviews) that involve cultural
life. Let us begin with discursive psychology that contexts such as development and socialization (as
studies narrative as a form of intersubjective action just reviewed), home and family life (Heath, 2009;
or, to be more precisely, as discursive intervention in Ochs & Taylor, 2001), the workplace (Fasulo &
ongoing events (Edwards, 1997; Edwards & Potter, Zucchermaglio, 2008), health and illness (Hydén &
1992; Harré & Gillett, 1994). A case in point is Brockmeier, 2008b), psychotherapy (Fasulo, 2007),
positioning theory. It foregrounds the ways narrators politics (Andrews, 2007; Duranti, 2009b), cultural
carry out various actions by attributing certain posi- memory (Brockmeier, 2002), law (Amsterdam &
tions to characters in their stories, to the audience Bruner, 2000), science (Harré, Brockmeier, &
of their storytelling, to themselves, and in respect to Mühlhäusler, 1999), and sport (Smith & Sparkes,
the cultural world at large (Bamberg, 1997; Harré & 2009), to mention a few.
van Langenhove, 1999; Harré et al., 2009). In a sim- On a conceptual and epistemological plane,
ilar vein, other authors have emphasized the inher- however, this differentiation and diversification has
ently intersubjective dynamic of storytelling—of come at a price. The more social-scientific narra-
“narrative in interaction”—especially in everyday tive research has established itself as a major player,
encounters and conversational events (Bamberg & the more it has become elusive—at least it seems
Georgakopoulou, 2008; Georgakopoulou, 2007; so if viewed through the lenses of traditional meth-
Ochs & Capps, 2001). Similarly, in the wake of odologies that typically are appealed to in order to
Sacks (1992), sociolinguistic and conversation-an- warrant the scientificity of inquiry. “Unlike many
alytical approaches (e.g., Aronsson, 2001; Norrick, qualitative frameworks, narrative research offers
2000, 2007; Quasthoff & Becker, 2005) have devel- no automatic starting or finishing points . . .; there
oped what could be called a narrative pragmatics—a are no self-evident categories on which to focus, as
term originally coined by Chatman (1981). there are with content-based thematic approaches,
It is amazing in what a short period of time the or with analyses of specific elements of language,” as
use of narrative and discursive approaches in the Squire, Andrews, and Tamboukou (2008) explain
social sciences has become business as usual. From the dilemma of many social and cultural scientists.
an exotic outsider and underdog, narrative inquiry
In addition, unlike other qualitative research
has transformed into a respected member of the
perspectives, narrative research offers no overall rules
academic club—a taken-for-granted part of the
about suitable materials or modes of investigation,
standard spectrum of ethnographic and other qual-
or the best level at which to study stories. It does
itative methodologies (e.g., Atkinson, Delamont,
not tell us whether to look for stories in recorded
& Housley, 2008; Chase, 2005; Clandinin, 2007;
everyday speech, interviews, diaries, TV programs or
Elliott, 2005; Holstein & Gubrium, 2008, 2009;
newspaper articles; whether to aim for objectivity or
Horsdale, 2011; Quinn, 2005). For some time now,
researcher and participant involvement.
it has been safe to say that narrative inquiry in the
(Squire, Andrews, & Tamboukou, 2008, p. 2)
social sciences has entered a “post-polemical phase,”
as Freeman (2001) put it. The time Freeman made That being said, the same picture has also been
this comment, the very beginning of the twenty-first linked to an increasing fine-tuning of narrative
century, can indeed be seen as a watershed. Since research to a changing understanding of humans’
then, “[r]ather than proposing to do the desired work social and cultural reality, a reality that is intimately
or proclaiming the need for such work, it is simply mingled with narrative discourses which, however,
being done, constructively and vigorously” (p. 284). in order to be grasped, demand a new, more open
In the process, social-scientific narrative research and flexible view of narrative—that is, a second nar-
has become more differentiated, shifting from text rative turn.
and story-oriented paradigms to action and perfor-
mance-oriented paradigms and models of pictorial Two Narrative Turns
narrative (Brockmeier, 2005b; Hydén & Brockmeier, Approaching the field from a historical point
2008a; Kohler Riessman, 2007; Mattingly, 2007; of view, Gubrium and Holstein (2008, 2009) have
Peterson & Langellier, 2006). It also has become distinguished two narrative turns in social research.
wider in scope. Narratives are studied in institutional They discern the first narrative turn early in the last

brockm eier 449


century, launched by Propp (1968) and other social (Gubrium & Holstein, 2008, p. 247)
researchers of narratives and folklore. The tradition It is, as we can conclude with Gubrium and
of narrative ethnography initiated here also led to Holstein, the social, institutional, and cultural envi-
efforts to study ordinary peoples’ “own stories,” as ronment of storytelling that impacts on the con-
manifested in interviews and personal “documents tent and internal structure of narrative, just as the
of life” (letters, diaries, files)—material viewed as a strategies of positioning influence the social profile
window on distinctive social and cultural worlds. In of storytellers and the narrative scenarios within
the “Chicago tradition,” dominated theoretically by which they carry out actions. Thus, many narra-
George Herbert Mead (1934), early classics such as tive researchers have come to understand the per-
W. I. Thomas and Forian Znaniecki’s (1958) The formance and social organization of the storytelling
Polish Peasant in Europe and America on the immi- process as meaning-making activity in its own right.
gration experience in Chicago after the end of “Meaning-making,” write Gubrium and Holstein
World War I were followed by a stream of ethno- (2009), “is a practical activity that transpires in par-
graphic case studies of particular social and cultural ticular circumstances and puts into play the avail-
communities. Although such analyses concentrated able resources for constructing stories” (p. 57).
on the content of participants’ narrative accounts
and on the social and cultural life they depicted, this Fictional and Nonfictional Narrative
interest widened in what Gubrium and Holstein The study of the relationship between narrative
(2008) called the second narrative turn. This turn, and culture in the three traditions mentioned so far
within which Gubrium and Holstein associated has paid much heed to oral narrative practices. This
their own work, shifted the attention to the very is not to say that writing does not play a role in
practices of storytelling and the social and cultural the sphere of oral narrative; in fact, it does. Under
circumstances in which they occurred; we might conditions of cultural literacy, structure, usage, and
add that this second narrative turn already started understanding of language is profoundly influenced
in the 1960s and 1970s with ethnolinguistics, con- by the existence of writing and its various semiotic
versation analysis, and sociolinguistics entering the media, including those that have come into being in
scene of language analysis. It reaches beyond the the digital age (Brockmeier & Olson, 2002). Still,
first narrative turn in that it brings to the fore the psychological, social-scientific, and sociolinguistic
interplay between the content and internal organi- research on narrative has been concerned primarily
zation of narratives, and the concrete social and cul- with oral storytelling and their discursive or narra-
tural conditions, the “narrative environments,” that tive environments. In contrast (as if in an odd divi-
regulate the production, distribution, and circula- sion of labor), written narrative has been the subject
tion of narratives. of a distinct tradition of scholarship. The terrain
of this tradition is the storyworlds of fictional and
Although there is no strict line of demarcation
nonfictional literary narrative, complemented by
between . . . stories and storytelling, we need
the storyworlds of play and opera, film and tele-
to know the details and working conditions of
vision, photography, graphic novels, and digital
narrative occasions if we are to understand narrative
or virtual environments. Roughly, the distinction
practices. These details, in turn, can only be
between dominantly written and dominantly oral
discerned from direct consideration of narrative
storyworlds corresponds to what Hyvärinen (2006,
environments. Stories are assembled and told to
2010) has described as the two families of narrative
someone, somewhere, at some time, with a variety
studies: one, rooted in the humanities, represents
of consequences for those concerned. All of this
narratological and critical scholarship, the other
has a discernable impact on what is communicated
has emerged with the narrative turn (or turns) in
and how that unfolds. A life story might be told to
the social sciences. Hyvärinen notes that despite the
a spouse, to a lover . . ., to a therapist, to a son or
common interest in narrative, there are only very
daughter, or to a fellow team member, among the
few encounters between these two families.
huge variety of audiences to which narratives are
I use the terms storyworlds and literature to mark
conveyed. The occasion might be a job interview,
this fourth tradition of narrative research because I
part of a pickup line, a confession, or a recovery
think they are more appropriate for a discussion of
tale. The consequences might be amusing or life
the cultural nature of narrative than the more com-
threatening.
mon term fiction. From a cultural point of view,

450 narrative sce na r i os


the distinction between fictional and nonfictional same linguistic repertoire in arriving at a cultural
genres of narrative (and the derivative distinction code of aesthetic, moral, and political values.
of genres such as creative or narrative nonfiction A second reason why a clear-cut borderline
and docufiction) appears to be problematic for sev- between fictional and nonfictional narrative is prob-
eral reasons. One is that there are many forms and lematic is that the very idea of such a distinction
genres of narrative that simply ignore the borderline itself is a cultural one. It emerged as a convention
between fictional and nonfictional narrative and whose rationale and scope has depended on specific
cannot be understood by these categories. Consider discursive and narrative environments. Even within
“subjective” genres such as autobiographical nar- Western traditions, it has undergone considerable
ratives or first-person life stories, as we encounter change. For years, indeed centuries, these traditions
them, for example, when people review their lives did not specify any distinction between history and
in hindsight (Freemann, 2010). If the criterion for fiction. Even well into the eighteenth century, his-
nonfictional narrative is taken to be its truth value tory was a literary art and historians were consid-
(Lejeune, 1989), or its reference to the real world ered good historians because of their imaginative
(Cohn, 1999), or that it is falsifiable (Abbott, 2008), and inventive abilities, their qualities as writers of
what are we to make of, say, an autobiographical nar- narrative prose (Burrow, 2007). That empirical evi-
rator who offers possible interpretations of events in dence had to play a critical role became an academic
his or her life, events that so often happened coinci- conviction and culturally established rule only in
dentally? The narrator may be fully aware of that but the nineteenth century.
still might try to make sense of these events, perhaps The storyworlds of all three areas of literary fic-
by the help of Christian or Buddhist or Marxist or tion, nonfiction, and those narratives that defy
Existentialist assumptions. Who then would be able and go beyond this opposition are surrounded by
to judge, and by which standards, the truth value of discourses that meander in many public spheres.
these interpretations? And whether they refer to the They also comprise a vast literature that is critical,
real world? And are falsifiable? philosophical, and sometimes even narrative itself.
But the questions that ensue from a cultural This literature interprets and reflects on exactly
perspective for the fiction–nonfiction distinction the interfaces between life and language, tradition
are also evident in “objective” genres such as travel and the individual, and action and interaction
narratives. Pratt (1988) has noted that European where we have situated narrative practices as cul-
landscape narratives evoke a cultural system of rep- tural practices. This makes it even more difficult to
resentation that works across the fiction–nonfiction understand why social-scientific research has almost
line, which, in the traditional view, is supposed to entirely ignored the resources of critical knowledge
separate genres such as the novel from a nonliterary that have been accumulated in a long tradition of
genre like travel writing (what today would be called narrative scholarship. My argument is that the sto-
creative nonfiction). However, as Pratt has shown, ryworlds of fictional and nonfictional literature and
from at least the sixteenth century on (i.e., during the surrounding discourses of interpretation and
the epoch of colonialism), the two genres have com- critical reflection constitute the thickest narrative
pletely interpenetrated and mutually determined layer of our attempts to cultural self-interpretation.
each other. Drawing on a narrative analysis, “which In these attempts, we can explore in much detail
decenters the question of truth versus falsehood, what it means that narrative binds the individual
fiction versus nonfiction, literary genre versus non- into a cultural world while it binds the meaning of
literary genre, and focuses instead on generalized this world into the individual’s mind.
strategies of representation,” Pratt (1988, p. 22) has
found that what at first sight presents itself in both The Cultural Fabric of Life
genres as a neutral and realist narrative—in fact, as and Literature
a landscape description—functions as discourse of Narrative prose realizes functions of all three
domination. The landscapes described within both fields outlined above: the historical and intergen-
literary and nonliterary narrative scenarios are part erational, the individual and developmental, and
of a widespread cultural system of values in which the discursive and intersubjective. It furnishes the
nature is viewed first and foremost as a commod- discourses in these fields with genres, plots, sto-
ity, as something to be conquered and dominated. rylines, and models of reality, mind, and imagina-
Fictional and nonfictional authors alike employ the tion, whereas it, in turn, continuously soaks up the

brockm eier 451


linguistic and experiential resources of these dis- narratives is also investigated in traditional philo-
courses, as well as those of everyday life in general. logical and critical studies and in newer deconstruc-
What makes this mutual enrichment of life and lit- tionist approaches.
erature possible is that literary prose serves a variety Finally, there is a special focus on the interpen-
of cultural purposes. etration of narrative literature and the general cul-
Taking a closer look at these cultural purposes we tural dynamic beyond literary discourse. For many
find, not surprisingly, that there is first an aesthetic literary and cultural theorists, the only way to fully
intention. This intention and the way it is real- appreciate a literary work is to examine the cultural
ized is studied in poetics, stylistics, and criticism. world that it reflects and is embedded in, and this
One could go as far as to argue that the explicit or comprises the ethical value system, the “narrative
implicit aesthetic intention, the artistic vision of lit- judgements” (Phelan, 2007), which the literary
erary narrative, is the distinctive feature that sets it work (in fact, every narrative) implicitly asks its
apart from the rest of narrative. But then, its aes- audience to adopt while reading or listening to it.
thetic component is only one among several; which Greenblatt (1998) thus views what he calls “culture
is to say, there is more to literary prose than its as a complex whole” as both continuously articu-
poetic dimension. On the other hand, there also is a lated and transformed by literary texts. According
poetic component to everyday language, in fact, as to Greenblatt, an important task of cultural literary
Jakobson (1960b) said, to all language, even if this criticism is to investigate the rules of the cultural
component is rarely dominating. But it is enough to power games upon which literary works are predi-
assume a continuum of poetic qualities that reaches cated. This understanding, he believes, must begin
from ordinary to literary narrative. Whether it is with the acknowledgement that each cultural order
poetry or an everyday exchange on the bus, lan- organizes what appears to be opposite things: con-
guage inherently has an aesthetic dimension, and so straint and control versus mobility and openness.
have all cultural practices of narrative. Both are pervasive cultural forces that have become
Another cultural purpose of literary narrative internal operators of literary dynamics.
becomes evident when we consider it as strategy of
persuasion, as a way to convince others, and some- Bakhtin’s Novel
times even the tellers of the tale themselves. I have A case in point of the cultural charge of nar-
already alluded to this as one of narrative’s basic rative prose is the genre of the novel, especially as
functions. In the humanities, this is the subject of understood by Mikhail Bakhtin. In Bakhtin view,
rhetorical analysis. Like notions and standards of the novel is a polyphone creation that comprises, on
aesthetics, notions and standards of persuasiveness the one hand, all potentials of literature and, on the
are strongly culturally defined. other, all spheres of social and psychological life in
Further, literature sets up processes of mutual a given epoch. Like a human being always changes
interpretation between author and reader; this, too, and is never fully realized or fully known, neither to
piggybacks on an elemental function of narrative. himself or herself or to others, so are language and
In the realm of literary studies these processes are cultural life never fully realized and remain bound-
examined in reception-(or reader response)-theoret- less and interminable in their potentials. This makes
ical, discursive, interactional, pragmatic, rhetorical, the novel the prime venue to grapple with what
and cognitive narrative inquiries. Bakhtin calls the unfinalizability of human life, for
Next, narrative sets up processes of mutual inter- the novel is fundamentally concerned with all three:
pretation among texts from various cultural worlds, the individual and his or her experiential world, lan-
present and past, real or imagined, conjuring up guage, and humans’ cultural existence.
what cultural semiotician IUri Lotman (1990) has Bakhtin saw literature as the semiotic dimension
described as the textual “semiosphere,” the intercon- where an epoch comes to the most comprehensive
nected signs systems that as a whole constitute the and sophisticated notion of itself. This capacity is
cultural sphere. Within a semiosphere, distinct nar- due, not least, to the heterogeneous and open char-
ratives unfold networks of meaning relations among acter of novelistic discourse. The interplay in which
each other: through semantic and stylistic similar- the novel realizes the totality of language as a social
ities, explicit cross-references, ironic comments, system and, in this way, captures the totality of a
sarcastic allusions, friendly dialogues, and furious particular historical world was the stage of the cul-
clashes. This kind of intertextual interaction among tural dramas Bakhtin examined.

452 narrative sce na r i os


The novel can be defined as a diversity of social our cultural worlds not only contain narratives but
speech types . . . and a diversity of individual voices, are contained by narrative “in the sense that the idea
artistically organized. The internal stratification of of culture, either in general or in particular, is a nar-
any single national language into social dialects, rative” (p. 96).
characteristic group behavior, professional jargons, I take the arguments outlined in this section
generic languages, languages of generations and as supporting the claim that the storyworlds of
age groups, tendentious language, language of the fictional and nonfictional literature and the sur-
authorities, of various circles and of passing fashions, rounding sphere of critical discussion and reflec-
languages that serve the specific sociopolitical tion constitute an unrivalled enterprise of cultural
purposes of the day, even of the hour (each day has self-interpretation. Again, we may conclude that
its own slogan, its own vocabulary, its own emphasis) almost always the efforts of coming to terms with
– this internal stratification present in every language the cultural conditions of our existence transform
at any given moment of its historical existence is the into narrative efforts. And again, it is these narra-
indispensable prerequisite for the novel as a genre. tive efforts that permit us to scrutinize the multifold
The novel orchestrates all its themes, the totality interactions through which we are bound in a cul-
of the world of objects and ideas depicted and tural world and in which we create what makes up
expressed in it, by means of the social diversity of the meaning of our life.
speech types . . . and by the differing individual voices
that flourish under such conditions . . . Narrative and Folk Psychology
(Bakhtin, 1981, p. 263) In envisioning the meaning-constituent dimen-
sion of narrative, a further, final current of research
In studying the modern novel as the narrative comes to the fore. Emerged only recently, it has
amalgamation of a manifold of languages and sty- highlighted that narrative practices (and all the
listics that “orchestrate” a multivoiced cultural uni- more the traditions to which they belong) involve
verse, Bakhtin developed a theory of narrative as a not only linguistic and other symbolic and physical
hinge between the individual and his or her cultural activities, but also an accordant mental disposition,
world. Each voice in this cultural universe is taken as an intentional orientation. Often this is called folk
a particular point of view on the world, a point that, psychology. Bruner (1990) described folk psychology
at the same time, also reflects (and contributes to) as a cognitive system in the service of cultural func-
the consciousness of a particular individual. Both tions, a system that regulates how human agents
consciousness and cultural world are interlaced in a do things on the basis of their beliefs and desires,
text of sorts, a peculiar cultural “text of the mind” strive for goals, cope with trouble, and get a sense of
whose workings are at the core of Bakhtin’s investi- themselves. Folk psychology is about people orga-
gation (Brockmeier, 2005a). nizing their experience of, and knowledge about,
Such a comprehensive philological and cultural- the cultural worlds in which they act.
historical approach to narrative prose can be viewed
All cultures have as one of their most powerful
as part of the project of a cultural narratology (or
constitutive instruments a folk psychology, a set
cultural narrative theory).5 Currie (1998) has put
of more or less . . . normative descriptions about
forward two arguments in favor of a cultural narra-
how human beings “tick,” what our own and other
tology. One is narrative’s ubiquitousness in the con-
minds are like, what one can expect situated action
temporary world, a point already emphasized above.
to be like, what are possible modes of life, how one
Currie remarks that narratives are so commonplace
commits oneself to them, and so on.
that it would be difficult to consider any cultural
(Bruner, 1990, p. 35)
form or practice without encountering a narrative
context. Similarly, Jakobson (1960a) has stated that For the most part, Bruner’s cultural-psycholog-
“the principal way of diffusion for cultural goods ical explanation of folk psychology dovetails with
is through the word, through the medium of lan- Geertz’s (1983) notion of common sense as a cultural
guage” (p. 103). We may add that the more these system. But the intellectual history of this tradition
cultural goods are complex and semiotically medi- is longer. Bruner (1990) himself aligns the cultural-
ated practices and artifacts, the more their diffusion psychological concept of folk psychology with early
involves the language of narrative. This leads to twentieth century anthropology, the ethnomethod-
Currie’s (1998) second point, according to which ology of Garfinkel (1967) and Heider (1958), and

brockm eier 453


the phenomenological sociology of Schutz (1967). psychology—these developments are particularly
Still, Bruner’s own work is especially relevant here interesting.
because it gives center stage to one specific feature
of folk psychology: that it is organized in a narrative The Cultural Scope of Post-Classical
rather than conceptual or logical way. Narrative, in Narrative Theory
Bruner’s picture, is particularly important in mit- In contrast with classical narratology that was
igating between the exceptional and the culturally dominated by structuralist linguistics and its con-
ordinary. It links the normal with its break, the rule cern with the code structures of written and literary
with its violation. Folk psychology is about the cul- text, post-classical narrative theory has freed itself
turally canonical. It states not simply how things are from both structuralist and philologist constraints,
but how they should be. “When things ‘are as they extending its space of inquiry to the study of cul-
should be,’ ” Bruner (1990, p. 40) writes, “the narra- tural phenomena beyond the boundaries of litera-
tives of folk psychology are unnecessary.” That is to ture. In this way, a more comprehensive view of the
say, not only is most of folk psychology laid out in inter-relations between narrative and the mind has
narrative, stories also are the central instrument for emerged, elaborated especially in the work of narra-
folk psychology’s normative and regulative author- tive theorists who have explored how understanding
ity. Although a cultural world must contain a set literary prose requires making sense of how human
of norms, “it must also contain a set of interpre- minds work—both the minds of fictional and actual
tive procedures for rendering departures from those characters (e.g., Herman, 2009c, 2011a; Fludernik,
norms meaningful”; these procedures of “explicat- 1996; Palmer, 2004, 2010; Alber & Fludernik,
ing deviations from the ordinary in a comprehensi- 2011). This view complements the reverse assump-
ble form” are narrative (p. 47). tion (underlying, among others, my line of argu-
The assumption of an intrinsic link between nar- ment) that everyday narrative practices continuously
rative and the cultural templates of folk psychology absorb resources from literary, dramatic, and filmic
has been taken up by researchers in several fields. discourses and from the popular arts. This exchange
It has been elaborated, for example, in terms of a works so smoothly and indeed typically escapes our
socio-cultural developmental psychology of chil- attention because it involves on both sides the same
dren’s acquisition of folk psychological narrative by basic psychological abilities and practices.
Nelson (2007b; 2009), reformulated in the con- If we thus assume that a large portion of our
text of philosophy of mind debates as the “narra- experience is mediated through narrative, then
tive practice hypothesis” that helps us to understand Fludernik’s (1996) suggestion to consider narrative
the socio-cultural basis of how people make sense as a particular mode of experience or, as she calls
of intentional actions by Hutto (2008, 2009), and it, of human “experientiality” appears as an obvious
integrated into a narrative-theoretical alternative next step. Narrative, on this view, is not so much a
to mentalist explanations of “theory of mind” by plot or the representation of a sequence of events as
Herman (2008; 2009c). a human form of experiencing the world that has
To conceive of people’s ideas about what makes more to do with how our consciousness works than
human beings tick and what their own and other with linear, causal, and closed story structures. And
minds are like—that is, their theory of mind—as how does our narrative consciousness (or narrative
integral to an overall cultural system of folk psy- mind) work? My answer to this question is that it
chology supports the claim, delineated in the last works by entangling us with the cultural world in
section, that the distinction between fictional and which we live; that it entraps us in a human—that
nonfictional genres of narrative dissolves when is, intersubjective and interpersonal fabric web of
approached from a cultural point of view. Some concerns—of meanings, thoughts, intentions, and
recent developments in “post-classical” narra- emotions (Brockmeier, 2007). It is in this context
tive theory have further elucidated the common that I understand Fludernik’s view that narrative cen-
ground of both types of narrative, lending more ters on a human experience and that it operates by
narratologically refinement to a culturally situated means of a “projection of consciousness”—the con-
notion of narrative. Because my argument here is sciousness of the character in a story, of the narrative
that this common ground is essentially the cultural voice, or of the narrator or listener/reader. Hence I
fabric of folk psychology—with stories, at the same find it plausible, within the cultural and cultural-
time, serving as the principal instrument of folk psychological scope outlined in this chapter, when

454 narrative sce na r i os


Fludernik (1996) describes the crucial point of this the doing, the activity structure, of storytelling and
narrative projection in terms of “human immunda- interpretation” (Herman, 2008, p. 256). More pre-
tion” and “situational embodiment.” The important cisely, we face contexts of interaction that encompass
element in the context of this chapter is that the the story (in a particular medium), its narrator(s),
equalization of narrativity as experientiality spans and reader(s) or listener(s) or observer(s) involved
across a continuum of narrative practices from the in efforts of mutual interpretation. We have to be
everyday oral, performative, and pictorial to the aware, then, of what I would call an extended cul-
most sophisticated forms of written literary prose. tural framework of interpretative intersubjectivity,
In building on an argument that Herman if we want to understand how narrative and inten-
(2011b) has put forward in favor of an unified tionality are interlaced. While narrative is grounded
approach to either literary and everyday narrative, in cultural patterns of intentionality, as Herman
we might say that the vision of narrative as a psy- (2008, pp. 240–241) puts it, “intentional systems
chologically fundamental practice of human mean- are grounded in storytelling practices.”6
ing construction that cuts across the putative divide Viewed in this light, the study of the narrative
between fiction and nonfiction allows us to bring microstructures that interweave intentionality and
to bear on the study of this practice the full bat- folk psychology opens a direct route to a culturally
tery of investigative tools being developed in liter- sensitive notion of narrative. It has been from this
ary, narratological, art-theoretical, psychological, perspective that I have discussed this approach to
and anthropological research on the cultural nexus narrative and folk psychology, as I also have explored
of mind and narrative. To be sure, much of post- in this section four other traditions that have que-
classical narratological research on this nexus is not ried narrative practices—in contexts of cultural his-
overly interested in situating its subject within a tory, contexts of socialization, as a form of life, and
cultural framework; significantly enough, drawing with respect to the common ground of fictional and
on analytical philosophy of mind, cognitive science, nonfictional genres. I have selected these five tra-
and evolutionary psychology, it has become known ditions because they have contributed, in different
as cognitive narratology. I believe, however, that the ways, to the study of both the cultural nature of nar-
scope of issues being investigated here exceeds the rative and the role of narrative for humans’ cultural
somewhat narrow limits associated with the cogni- life. Hence, my overview has foregrounded aspects
tive focus in psychology. There is no doubt that it of these traditions that provide investigative lenses
can enable us to fuller comprehend a pivotal point: for this project. Using these lenses, I turn now to a
that at the base of both literary and everyday pro- more specific qualification of what is at the center of
cesses of meaning construction are the same nar- this project: the very notion of narrative as cultural
rative operations, realizing fundamental processes practice, its ways of application, and implications
of human understanding and intersubjectivity, for further research.
including affect and empathy (Keen, 2007). What
is more, it permits us to extend the implications of
Narrative As a Cultural Form of Life:
this comprehension toward a culturally rich notion
Applications
of narrative.
Consider Herman’s analysis of the inherent The Principle of Narrative’s Singularity
link between narrative and human intentionality. Considering the five traditions reviewed in the
Storytelling operations, he says (2008, p. 240), are last section that have enriched the culturally moti-
“irreducibly grounded in intentional systems,” which vated understanding of narrative that I want to
is to say that in understanding these operations we carve out in this chapter, we face this situation: both
employ concepts of intentionality that are part and in the humanities and in the social sciences, narra-
parcel of “culturally transmitted folk-psychological tive practices are conceived of as important cultural
templates” (p. 256). Now, how are we to understand practices. But as these practices are so multifarious,
“intentional systems?” Herman takes great pains to they are investigated by a perplexing multitude of
explain that they are all but merely cognitive con- different methods and techniques, developed in a
structions, introspectively to be localized in individ- great many distinct disciplinary contexts and from
ual heads like “mental models.” Rather, intentional a wide range of theoretical approaches and perspec-
systems are intersubjective contexts of operation: tives. Is there a method to come to terms with this
“intentionality in narrative contexts is built into large variety of narrative methods?

brockm eier 455


I believe it would not only be difficult to draw have categorical and analytical rigor? If all stories
generalizable conclusions about the nature of nar- are singular events (in the language of methodology,
rative and the methods that involve narrative, or single cases), and if the world is a field of differ-
examine it, or aim at both; it would be highly prob- ences, are there any general characteristics at all that
lematic to do so. There is an implicit presumption justify the use of a common category of narrative
in many discussions in literary theory and narratol- that is more than a metaphorical label? This is the
ogy, and this might be of even greater significance question I discuss in this section.
for psychology and social research: the methods of
each narrative investigation are to be sensitively Good Stories and Bad Stories
fine-tuned to its subject, a subject that is always par- It is fair to say that everyone working with and
ticular. Particularity has indeed been claimed to set on narrative has a working definition of narrative,
narrative apart from general explanations (Bruner, as intuitively and rudimentary as it may be. In view
1990; Herman, 2009b). And it seems that it has of the absence of a more than occasional dialogue
been this sensitivity for the particular that has made between the humanities and psychology (and the
narrative attractive not least for the social sciences, social sciences in general), it is all the more sur-
from the very beginning of their narrative turn. prising that there is widespread agreement in both
But then cannot general explanations also be for- literatures on what counts as narrative. I already
mulated in a narrative form? And does not narrative mentioned the axiom of narrative as representation
have many techniques and devices to present the and some of the problems resulting from it. Further,
particular as the general and the general in the par- most authors concur in assuming at least three
ticular? Hence I think, within a culturally reflected structural or inner characteristics of narrative. These
conceptual framework, we must go further and rec- three elements constitute, to use a term coined by
ognize narrative as something genuinely singular. Leitch (1986), a minimal narrative ontology defin-
One could call this the principle of narrative’s sin- ing the essential components that make up a story.
gularity, and I take it to complement the principle First, there is the idea of narrative as a sequence of
of narrative’s cultural ubiquity. action or events, which, second, is organized in time
In a momentous analysis of a literary text, and which, third, constitutes some kind of inner
Barthes (1974) made the case that stories are singu- structural coherence. The sequentiality of narrative
lar, in fact, individual events. They are as individual means that the succession of action or events implies
as their narrators and the situations in which they some kind of logical or intentional or psychologi-
are told. More than that, each narrative comes, in cal causality; the temporality of narrative means
principle, with a multitude of individual interpreta- that the sequence is temporally organized; and the
tions; these interpretations are not added to a story, coherence of a narrative implies that it is told as a
but are an essential part of it. The focus on singu- sound and plausible fashion story. Contributing to
larity thus implies confronting the world as a field narrative coherence are not only the first and second
of differences—a vision in which Geertz (2000) rec- features, sequentiality and temporality, but also the
ognized the essence of anthropology: “If anthropol- closure of its plot structure. At stake in this view,
ogy is obsessed with anything, it is with how much then, is the notion of a “good story,” with a marked
difference makes” (p. 197). Translated into narrative beginning, middle, and end—as it is classically
methodology terms, this is to say that the question defined as narratio in the Aristotelian tradition of
of what investigative procedure and analytical focus poetics.
is appropriate can only be answered vis-à-vis of the This reference reminds us that we deal here with
concrete narrative and the cultural environment in a tradition of literary poetics that has influenced not
which it occurs and within which certain interpreta- only classical (structuralist) narratology, but also
tions take shape. most of sociolinguistic and social-scientific narra-
Of course, the principle of narrative’s singularity tive research so far. Its criteria of a well-structured
raises another question—namely, what is (if there is story—reflecting the composition of classic Greek
anything at all) common to all those innumerable tragedy, the ancient dramatic art form that under-
cultural practices that are referred to by the fickle lay Aristotelian poetics—have been canonized in a
term narrative and approached with such manifold long and venerable history of drama, poetry, and
methods and techniques? Obviously, the term nar- narrative. Now, this tradition faces a serious prob-
rative itself has a metaphorical side. But does it also lem. Although the notion of narrative is modeled

456 narrative sce na r i os


on a “good story,” a well-structured narratio, not all a handle on, or pose a question to which we don’t
narratives are good stories. That is, not all narrative know the answer. Or we narrate because we try
practices produce Aristotelian plots. to hide embarrassment, insecurity, shame, or reg-
The problem is a historical one. It emerged ulate other emotions and mental states. We tell a
in modernity—particularly with modernism— story, as Mark Twain once put it, because we don’t
even if it became manifest only later in the twen- have anything to say. We also may share a story to
tieth century. In Modernism, literary narrators crack a joke, to make a point, or comment on last
began to employ new, non-Aristotelian forms and night’s TV show; or because we want to ridicule a
techniques of narrative, especially in discourses of politician or superior, pass on gossip, or excuse our-
consciousness. Later in the twentieth century, nar- selves for being late. All of these discourse genres,
rative research followed and also went beyond the and many more, make use of narrative forms that
borders of the traditional literary canon to exam- we have to add to the traditional list of established
ine narrative practices created not primarily with narrative genres, the “good stories,” with which the
aesthetic intentions but as part of naturally occur- “bad stories” are, of course, interlaced in manifold
ring everyday discourse. More precisely, then, the ways. Borrowing from them, challenging and can-
problem is that neither the modern and postmod- nibalizing them, sometimes the bad ones just want
ern narrative forms developed in literature, film, to be good ones. Still, whatever they are or are not,
theater, and other artistic venues, nor the narrative it is not because they comply or do not comply with
practices embedded in the cultural contexts of ordi- any general “narrative ontology.”
nary life can be captured by the traditional model In those narratives that I have described as a form
of a “good story.” Typically, our everyday narrative of social action, another precarious aspect of the
practices do not aim at closed and well-structured narrative ontology assumption comes to the fore.
stories. Forms of action that serve many purposes, Often there is no clear line between the narrator and
they have, as already noted, fuzzy borders. Often, the listener or reader of a story, as it is known from
“they are undecided, fragmented, broken, nar- genres of monologic storytelling. As a consequence,
rated by voices struggling to find words” (Hydén & the notion of a story continues to blur, and its
Brockmeier, 2008a, p. 2). Ochs and Capps (2001, putative ontology becomes even more elusive. Not
p. 3) call them the country cousins of well-wrought only that the audience (the listeners and readers of
narratives. Not surprisingly, these country folks do a story) always construct in their individual recep-
not bother about a proper narrative ontology (and tions their own versions of the original story; as we
likewise unsurprisingly, most narratologists have know, the story told by a narrator is rarely identi-
excluded them from their terrain). So what do they cal with the story that takes form in the listener’s
bother about? Why do we tell stories, even if they perception and imagination. To put it again from a
are bad stories? Wittgensteinian perspective, there is no meaning of
The reasons that we narrate are as variegated a narrative without the uptake of the addressee or, in
and as good and bad as the reasons why we act and Duranti’s (1986) terms, without “the community’s
live. We are entangled in countless narratives and testing and approval” (p. 240). For his part, Duranti
narrative events, and only rarely do these produce has argued that it is especially in storytelling where
the monologic, well-structured, and coherent sto- “the form and content of talk is continuously re-
ries that are the subject of standard definitions both shaped by co-participants” (1986, p. 242). Often
in narratology and the social sciences. If we would the audience already influence what is told during
rigorously apply these scholarly classifications and its very articulation. In turn, envisioning the pos-
their implicit narrative ontologies, we would have sible (desired or undesired) reception of the local
to conclude that most of the time we tell bad stories, addressee, the narrator can fit the narrative to the
or weird stories, or failed stories, or do not narrate at reaction of the listeners, be it manifestly demon-
all (Medved & Brockmeier, 2010). strated by their behavior and reactions (as in an oral
This is all the more the case when we interact narrative environment) or imaginatively anticipated
outside of institutionally regulated cultural and (as the “implied reader” in the writing of a story).
narrative environments such as schools, law courts, Finally, narrators and co-narrators can operate with
health facilities, and so forth. Take an inciden- different common sense notions of stories that they
tal encounter. We may tell a story to get in touch use as conversational (or rhetorical) acts: “This is
with someone, trace some trouble that we can’t get not the story here . . .” (Stokoe & Edwards, 2006).

brockm eier 457


All this comes together in what Norrick (2007, mode of representing but of construing meaning.
p. 127) has called genuine conversational narrative: What is taken to be a convincing story in one cir-
cumstance may be an incoherent, embarrassing, or
Genuine conversational storytelling is always
failed attempt at storytelling under different condi-
interactive, negotiated, and not simply designed for
tions. The joke told by the boss is confirmed by
a particular audience by a single teller; indeed, it is
his employees as a “funny story”; the illness nar-
often hard to determine who is the primary teller,
rative told by the patient is not registered by the
especially when the events were jointly experienced
doctor but immediately translated into “medical
or the basic story is already familiar. Conversational
data”; whereas the one-word sentence of the tod-
stories may be deeply contextualized, diffuse, and
dler is commented on by her parents as a won-
not easily detachable from the local conditions that
derful little story. Likewise, imagine how a school
occasion them.
teacher would mark a narrative essay of a student
This is most apparent in situations Bakhtin written in the experimental style of James Joyce’s
(1981) called polyphonic, where a non-hierarchical Finnegans Wake and—as we are in a thought exper-
narrative community acts at the same time as an iment—also imagine how Joyce might have retold
interpretive community that, claiming the same the teacher’s report. Many traditional narratives by
storytelling rights as the teller, is interrupting, eval- North or South American aboriginal people were
uating, and co-narrating. Norrick elucidates this as long classified by anthropologists as lists of names,
“many-voiced narration” in cultural contexts where descriptions of kinship relations, or ritual reports.
no single participant can control the course of the Only recently, ethnographers have questioned the
story, “and multiple voices vie for the right to for- appropriateness of Western concepts of narra-
mulate its point” (2007, p. 128). This brings us back tive to understand fundamentally different, non-
once more to the question: What, then, is the story? Aristotelian ways of storytelling—a problem that is
And how can we tell it from the contributions of the further complicated by the fact that many aboriginal
other voices in this polyphonic discourse? narrative performances cannot be isolated from the
presence of a specific local geography and from par-
Narrative and Meaning ticular cultural occasions (Basso, 1996; Chamberlin,
Numerous arguments have been put forward to 2004; Cruikshank, 1998). Often these occasions are
challenge the idea that there are universal compo- spiritual or even sacred in a markedly non-Western,
nents of a discourse genre “narrative” that exist prior indigenous sense (Benham, 2007).
to and independently from a culturally situated nar- What all these examples have in common is an
rative event. Rather than assuming the existence of implied notion of narrative that is only comprehen-
an abstract entity called “story,” the attention now sible if it is viewed in connection to a multitude of
has shifted to the concrete contexts of action and other stories. In the realm of written and literary
interaction in which a linguistic or otherwise per- stories, this phenomenon is known as intertextual-
formed action sequence is perceived as a story. Thus, ity: each narrative text refers to other narrative texts,
the question of what distinguishes a narrative from in this way widening its horizon of meaning and
other discourse genres, as Leitch (1986) concluded interpretation. In oral storytelling, a comparable
his review of possible distinctive criteria, is not to intertextual framework is evoked by the cultural
be answered by reference to the inner structure of and historical traditions to which a story belongs.
a story as such, but depends on how a discursive I already expounded the role of narrative for cul-
sequence is understood in a given situation. What tural traditions; at stake now are narrative tradi-
counts as a narrative arises from “the audience’s tions and, in tandem with them, the issue of the
perceptions, projections, and reintegrations” of the historical rootedness of all symbolic meaning con-
sequence (Leitch, 1986, p. 130). structions (Straub, 2005). In the case of the Joyce-
In this view, narrative is not constituted by a inspired student, these traditions comprise literary
set of given structural features such as sequential- modernism. In the case of the doctor’s version of the
ity, temporality, and coherence; rather, it takes on patient’s illness narrative, we face the institutional
its form in a context-dependent process of mean- and linguistic constraints of the medical appara-
ing attribution or, in Bruner’s (1990) terms, in tus. And in the case of aboriginal storytelling tradi-
an “act of meaning.” This links to the argument, tions, we are confronted with non-Western forms
made above, to see narrative not primarily as a of life, both narrative and non-narrative. Isolating

458 narrative sce na r i os


a story from its living context and reducing it to told,” their analysis cannot but give center stage to
an autonomous narrative structure means losing what Herman has described as their situatedness in
a constituent dimension of its meaning. For Gee, specific “narrative occasions” (2009b, pp. 37–74).
it is exactly this being steeped in cultural meaning “Narrative occasions” is taken in a double sense as
traditions that distinguishes narrative from other communicative (or narrative) environments “shap-
forms of discourse. A narrative, Gee (1991) wrote, ing how acts of narration are to be interpreted, and,
becomes “meaningless apart from a surrounding reciprocally, as contexts shaped by storytelling prac-
narrative context, connections to social memory, tices themselves” (Herman, 2009b, p. 37).
and the resources of a system of themes that can As a consequence of all this, even the concept of a
create (what counts in a given group as) a coherent “prototypical story” appears more and more difficult
(satisfying) pattern” (p. 13). to pin down—except as another narratological pro-
jection. Perhaps we should keep in mind an impor-
Beyond Narrative Ontology tant Wittgensteinian point of which Herrnstein
Viewed in this way, there is no need—indeed, no Smith (1981) already reminded us many years ago:
basis—for a normative model or a universal ontol- concepts such as “story” and “narrative” represent
ogy of narrative. In resisting this idea, as powerfully distinctions that “are drawn, not discovered, by nar-
as it has been elaborated in the narratological lit- ratologists” (p. 228).
erature, the focus shifts from the noun “narrative” Interestingly enough, despite poor communica-
as a monument of stable categorical identity to the tion between literary and linguistic narratologists,
“adjectival ‘narrative’ as an element of ongoing pro- and social scientific and psychological narrative
cesses,” as Hyvärinen (in press) puts it. What shapes researchers,7 they sometimes come to similar conclu-
the adjectival perception of a linguistic or otherwise sions, as when Gubrium and Holstein (2009) have
symbolic action as a story depends on local cultural suggested a “loose commonsensical” understanding
environments and traditions in which the rules and of narrative “as a basis for unpacking and paying
meanings of narrative practices have been formed, empirical attention to how story and storyteller are
where “particular audiences have accepted particular discerned, defined, and responded to in practice” (p.
discourses as stories” (Leitch, 1986, p. 25). Rudrum xviii). In other words, what stories amount to and
(2005) makes the same point on Wittgensteinian what other discourse forms (description, account,
grounds when he argues that the “form a narrative list, etc.) they may absorb and transform cannot be
ultimately takes—and, hence, the properties by defined axiomatically. It is a result and not a pre-
which one would attempt to define it—is as muta- condition of narrative analysis—that is, of cultural
ble as the uses to which it is put, making the task of narrative analysis. Patently, in this argument, the
neat definition a practically hopeless one” (p. 200). principles of narrative ubiquity and of narrative’s
To be sure, the hopelessness of defining narrative singularity are joined.
fiction is not a new experience. Rudrum himself
builds on the work of Iser (1989) who pointed out, Narrative Dimensions
“the more fiction eludes an ontological definition, If we view narrative as a quality attributed under
the more unmistakably it presents itself in terms of particular circumstances to discursive practices
its use” (p. 267). (which also include enactive or performative prac-
Narrative, then, is not an entity that can simply tices), several aspects of storytelling are cast in a new
be found in the everyday reality of our lives, not light. This light makes narrativity appear as a relative
even in a linguistic or textual reality. “As such,” quality that is displayed in numerous dimensions to
state Ochs and Capps (2001), “narrative bows to different degrees and in different ways. Ochs and
no simple generic blueprint that sets it apart once Capps (2001) have distinguished five such narrative
and for all from other forms of discourse” (p. 8). dimensions that structure what I have described as
In a similar vein, Herman (2009b) has observed culturally situated perception of narrative. Ochs and
that whatever counts as a “prototypical story” is per- Capps’s approach is especially fruitful if read from a
ceived “in a gradient, more-or-less way, and emerges cultural perspective because it promises to do justice
from the strategies on which people rely in their to both narrative principles, that of singularity and
everyday narrative practices” (p. 6). Because nar- that of ubiquity. Moreover, it offers a non-reductive
ratives “are both structured by and lend structure way to come to terms with narrative’s bewildering
to the communicative contexts in which they are cultural flexibility and adaptability.

brockm eier 459


Ochs and Capps (2001) propose to exam- my life, a sense of what I have become, which can
ine a sequence of discourse that is conceived of as only be given in a story” (p. 48).
narrative—as genre and activity—in terms of a set It is not difficult to see that these five narra-
of narrative dimensions that the sequence takes on tive dimensions enable us to categorize storytelling
along a spectrum of graduations. The first of these along a broad range of culturally situated discourse
narrative dimensions is tellership. It refers to the formats. These formats range from social activity to
extent and kind of involvement of different protago- a textual reality, from oral to written discourse, from
nists in the actual recounting of a story. The question virtuoso verbal performance to mundane everyday
here is: Who tells the story? The second dimension exchange, from naturally occurring conversation to
is tellability, which is related to the question of how literarily composed prose. To view in this way nar-
tellable and convincing a story is. How much is it rative activities as a heterogenous gamut of cultural
in accordance with the local cultural notion of nar- practices underscores once more the argument that
rative? In everyday interaction, personal narratives there is no boundary between everyday and liter-
can take different qualities of tellability, from high ary narrative discourse. Both are inter-related in
to low. If a discourse goes below a certain level of a myriad of ways, displaying the same narrative
tellability, then it is not perceived as a story any lon- dimensions of tellership, tellability, embeddedness,
ger. A third narrative dimension is marked by the linearity, and moral stance. Steeped in the same
embeddedness of a story in surrounding discourse cultural world, both take part in the same never-
and social activity, its being rooted in an narrative ending circulation of language; both have a say in
environment. This environment can be shaped by the endless conversation of storytellers.
institutional constraints. Yet it can also be shaped
in a more narrow discursive sense. For example, the Conclusions
extent to which a personal narrative is told and per- I started this inquiry with the claim, ensuing
ceived as a structured whole unto itself or as part of from an interpretive cultural psychology, that nar-
ongoing conversation is related to the organization rative practices are pivotal for human existence
of turn-taking (i.e., the sequence of the contribu- because they bind the individual into a cultural
tions) in a conversation, its subject or theme, and world while binding the meaning of this world
the way it is rhetorically structured. Linearity is the into the individual’s mind. I have explored this
fourth dimension. In personal narratives, it concerns interplay in developing a culturally thick notion
the extent to which events and actions are organized of narrative—of narrative as a form of life—that
along a single, temporal, causal, and closed path (as builds on Geertz’ cultural anthropology, Bruner’s
it is characteristic for an Aristotelian storyline with narrative psychology, and Wittgenstein’s philoso-
a clear beginning, middle, and end) or, alternatively, phy of language (which I zoomed in on narrative
in a nonlinear, intermittent, fragmentary, and open as a particular language game). To this end, I have
order. traced this notion from three different angles: as a
Finally, the fifth dimension: the moral stance mode of interpretation through which people try
that a narrative conveys. Typically, personal narra- to understand, and give meaning to, their cultural
tives do not pretend to present objective accounts being in the world; as a cultural practice realizing
of events or experiences but rather perspectives on several (communicative, rhetorical, empathetic, and
events and experiences. Central to these perspec- cognitive) functions; and as a form of action.
tives is the moral stance of the narrator. There is no My outline of a culturally charged notion of nar-
story that does not offer a perspective, if not several rative did not start from scratch. It has emerged from
perspectives, that explicitly or implicitly expresses the discussion of five research traditions that have
judgments and evaluations. The moral stance, the examined the nature of narrative: as an instrument
sense of right or wrong and good or bad, gives per- of cultural traditions and of individuals’ socializa-
sonal narrative its punch, its urgency, and its com- tion; as a form of life, with respect to fictional and
mitment. Ochs and Capps refer to Taylor’s (1989) nonfictional genres; and as a form and practice of
philosophical conception of narrative as a moral folk psychology. One conclusion drawn from these
framework for understanding human comport- discussions I called the principle of narrative’s sin-
ment: “Making sense of my present action, when gularity, which complements the principle of narra-
we are dealing with . . . the issue of my place relative tive’s cultural ubiquity. The principle of singularity
to the good, requires a narrative understanding of means that the ways narrative scenarios are to be

460 narrative sce na r i os


investigated are to be sensitively adjusted to the par- only a seismograph but in which it also is a most
ticular cultural (i.e., local) circumstances of their momentous factor.
occurrences. This also goes for the very understand- With this in mind, Rom Harré and I have argued
ing of what counts as narrative, an understanding that the culturally sensitive study of narrative unveils
that likewise depends on the contextual conditions a particularly flexible and open structure of action
under which the meaning of narrative is attributed and human agency; it allows us to explore precisely
to a discursive sequence. For this meaning—and this these fundamental aspects of human life, its open-
is the important point here—is not given. There is ness, and its flexibility – which often also means its
no such thing as a universal and pre-cultural defini- messiness – that are, for the most part, neglected by
tion of narrative. human sciences (Brockmeier & Harré, 2001). The
But make no mistake, there is an imposing con- practices of narrative are fleeting constellations of
cept or category of narrative, and this is solid and forms of life that can serve us as a guide to the vari-
stable enough. Well-established in countless dis- able and fluid nature of human reality because they
courses, it has foisted upon a vast variety of fluid are, in part, constitutive of it.
forms of life an illusionary identity and an onto-
logical weight that, as Rudrum (2005, p. 201) has Toward a Culturally Thick Notion of
remarked, narratives themselves, as dynamic acts of Narrative: Future Perspectives
meaning, do not have. Hence, if we want to avoid Much of what I have outlined is work in
falling in this ontological fallacy, we have to take progress—a research agenda that is, however,
a radical stance and understand each narrative as a already well underway in the shaping of a culturally
singular phenomenon, as an individual act of mean- rich notion of narrative. I want to end with offer-
ing in its own right. This inference is all the more ing three questions, delineating desiderata but also
stringent because each narrative practice is carried offering prospective vistas on further research in this
out within an intersubjective context of interpreta- hard-to-contain field. The first prospect is of narra-
tion. To be sure, this view challenges not only the tive as a cultural way of meaning-making. In repu-
idea of a narrative ontology but also research meth- diating a narrative ontology, the question of what
odologies in psychology and other social sciences makes up a narrative has not dissolved; rather, it has
based on principles of generalizability and nomo- shifted to an emic question: what do people do when
logical validity. But then, as we have seen, even they understand, in a specific cultural situation,
within today’s social-scientific narrative inquiries, a discursive sequence as a story, regardless of the
more and more attention is allotted to the concrete Aristotelian definitions of “good” and “bad” stories?
cultural contexts of action and interaction in which What practices does it take to constitute—and to
a discursive action sequence is perceived as a story. perceive—a narrative scenario? More exactly, how is
After narrative ways of knowing and inquir- a narrative act of meaning in which something takes
ing fell from favor early in the twentieth century’s on the meaning of a story carried out? To indicate
social sciences, they have begun to re-emerge over the routes possible answers to these questions might
the last decades as a legitimate and highly success- take, let me sketch three minimal conditions for an
ful way of investigating humans’ cultural existence act of narrative meaning constitution. With each
(Hyvärinen, 2006; Pinnegar & Daynes, 2007; of these three conditions, different, although inter-
Polkinghorne, 1988). Providing another strand to related, answers to the issue of what we do when we
the post-positivist paradigm and a further refine- tell and understand stories come into sight. For one,
ment of interpretive methodology in the human we bring a perspective to our experience, knowl-
sciences, they can be seen as propelling a shift that edge, thought, imagination, and much of our emo-
promises to overcome longstanding reductionism tional life, a perspective (the term is closely related
and open up a more comprehensive, differentiated, to what narrative theorists call “point of view”) that
and humanistic view of our being in the world. organizes how we face the world in which we live
All of this could also be framed in political terms; and how we position ourselves and others in this
indeed, as already emphasized above, it would be world. Second, we connect (not least through this
an unjustified reduction to see the cultural sphere perspective) several distinct elements to each other
without the forcefields of power and political and as to constitute a whole—that is, we create a synthe-
economic struggle that underlie most cultural sis of meaning, a gestalt that is more than the sum of
dynamics—dynamics of which narrative is not its isolated elements. And finally, narrative is a way

brockm eier 461


to do things. It is discourse in a strong sense, a mode unreduced access to the cultural nature of the nar-
of action and performance inextricably entangled rative mind.
with what Wittgenstein called the grammar of our
cultural world. In a nutshell, a discursive sequence
Acknowledgment
is configured as narrative in so far as it operates as a I would like to thank Molly Andrews, Alessandra Fasulo,
perspective, a synthesis, and a form of life. To inves- David Herman, Lars-Christer Hydén, Matti Hyvärinen, Maria
tigate these elemental conditions of narrative mean- I. Medved, and Jaan Valsiner for helpful comments on earlier
ing-making, as well as their interconnection, along a versions.
number of different “dimensions” (Ochs & Capps,
2001), will significantly deepen our knowledge of Notes
the narrative meaning construction of narrative. 1. Throughout this chapter, I use the terms practice and activ-
From here, the second prospect follows. It ity more or less interchangeably; performance refers to a particular
hinges on the question of how the meaning-making cultural practice or activity.
2. This is not to say that these constraints—as in individu-
options of narrative differ in various languages and
als suffering from diseases (e.g., Alzheimer’s), injuries (e.g., neu-
linguistic communities. After all, languages are the rotrauma), syndromes (e.g., autism), and (genetic) neurological
background systems of our cultural worlds, and disabilities—do not allow for specific forms of communication
the world’s thousands of distinct languages open and meaning construction. Of course they do. Yet the discussion
up thousands, at least in part, of distinct cultural of these forms is beyond the scope of this chapter.
3. For Bruner (1996), “The historical separation of anthro-
worlds. There is a first generation of pioneering
pology and psychology, whatever may have caused it, must surely
studies, some referred to above, tackling the impli- be counted as one of the most stunting developments in the
cations of this variety for narrative discourse. Yet history of the human sciences . . . In spite of their staking out
there can be little doubt that we will gain a fuller separate territories of inquiry, the two disciplines were never able
understanding of the cultural fabric of narrative, to ignore each other” (p. xiii). Bruner goes on to argue that the
“cultural study of man” requires a “consortium” of psychology
mind, and social life when a new generation of
and anthropology. On Bruner’s long and close relationship with
multilingual researchers, aware of the novel insights (social, cultural, and psychological) anthropology, see Mattingly,
associated with the narrative turn, go about these Lutkehaus, and Throop (2008).
issues—especially, in examining the make-up of nar- 4. The claim that an action- and performance-theoretical
rative scenarios in non-European languages. In the concept of language resonates with the culturally thick notion
of narrative put forward in this chapter does not reject the idea
introduction to this chapter, I mentioned Benjamin
that narrative has a representational side or can be used as a rep-
Lee Whorf, who persuasively argued that there is an resentation (e.g., a particular “representation” is offered as part
intrinsic connection between “multilingual aware- of a discursive or rhetorical move) and that, under certain cir-
ness” and the “culture consciousness” that he saw as cumstances, this side can be the dominant one. Understanding
necessary for the study of the relationships among narrative as a mode of representation seems to have been par-
ticularly plausible in contexts of literary, media-theoretical, and
language, thought, and reality (Darnell, 2006).
traditional narratological reasoning, where most cases of story-
This, I believe, holds particularly true for the cul- telling fall within the “scope of narrative viewed as a kind or
tural nature of narrative. category of text,” as Herman writes (2009b, p. 6); although the
A third prospect has emerged only recently with understanding of narrative as representation is also widespread
the increasing interest in the nexus of narrative and in the social-scientific literature. In fact, for narratologists from
Genette (1980) to Herman (2009b), representation is the “most
the mind in psychology, philosophy, narrative the-
universally accepted feature of narrative” (Ryan, 2007, p. 25; for
ory/cognitive narratology, narrative medicine, and a critical discussion, see also Rudrum, 2005). Although in inves-
related areas. Now, imagine a close and persisting tigating narrative as a cultural form of life I privilege an action-
dialogue—if not a joint investigative effort—would theoretical view of storytelling, this does not exclude the idea of
unfold and a bridge would span between this prom- narrative stretching along a continuum from action to represen-
tation, from text to performance, and from the storyworlds of
ising new area of research and the culturally oriented
fiction to the life worlds of everyday interaction—an argument
narrative inquiry with which this chapter has mainly that will be discussed in more detail in what follows.
been concerned. Would narrative not be a uniquely 5. Whereas in the past, the term narratology was mainly used
appropriate subject to overcome some longstanding in the context of structuralist narrative theory, today narrative
borderlines, questionable as they are anyway—such theory, narratology, and narrative studies have become synonyms
in much of the theoretical and critical literature, as in my discus-
as those between the cultural and the mental, as well
sion.
as between psychology, the social sciences, and the 6. Note that this view does not need the idea of narrative
humanities?8 It would not be hard to envision the representation. Herman (2008) makes clear that the understand-
outcome of this joint effort: an unrestricted and ing of what a story is about (i.e., its representational or referential

462 narrative sce na r i os


aspect) depends on the interactional context of communication Austin, J. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford, UK:
and interpretation in which the “intentional stance” of story- Clarendon.
tellers as well as the entire “intentional system” of their stories Bakhtin, M. (1981). The dialogic imagination. Austin, TX:
are grounded. It is this cultural context of communicative and University of Texas Press.
interpretive practice—which I have pointed out in terms of an Bakhtin, M. M. (1993) Rabelais and his world. Bloomington, IN:
action-theoretical concept of narrative—that gives shape to the Indiana University Press (Russian Original 1941).
representational side (or use) of narrative. Hence it seems to me Bamberg, M. (1997). Positioning between structure and perfor-
more appropriate to view the representational side as an aspect of mance. Journal of Narrative and Life History, 7, 335–342.
narrative “worldmaking”—that is, of cultural meaning construc- Bamberg, M., & Georgakopoulou, A. (2008). Small stories as
tions grounded in intentions, communicative interaction, and a new perspective in narrative and identity analysis. Text &
acts of interpretation that always remain defeasible. Talk, 28(3), 377–396.
7. There are only a few theorists who, like Jerome Bruner Barthes, R. (1974). S/Z. New York: Hill and Wang.
and David Herman, have systematically drawn on both fields of Basso, K. (1996). Wisdom sits in places: Language and landscape
research and scholarship. among the Western Apache. Albuquerque, NM: University of
8. Perhaps the current study of literary narrative could serve New Mexico Press.
as a model. James Phelan (2006, p. 86) notes that narrative Bauman, R. (1986). Story, performance, and event: Contextual
theory has so productively developed along various theoretical studies of oral narratives. Cambridge, UK & New York:
lines because the distinct approaches have remained in dialogue Cambridge University Press.
with broader trends in theorizing the human condition. Con- Bauman, Z. (2000). Liquid modernity. Cambridge, UK & Malden,
sequently, it is not dominated by a single view but, rather, is MA: Blackwell: Polity Press.
marked by a range of approaches: formalist, structuralist, phe- Benham, M. K. P. (2007). Mo’ōlelo: On culturally relevant story
nomenological, cognitive, rhetorical, psychoanalytic, feminist, making from an indigenous perspective. In D. J. Clandinin
marxist, and others. “What is especially striking about this vari- (Ed.), Handbook of narrative inquiry: Mapping a methodol-
ety,” Phelan remarks, “is that it has produced relatively little con- ogy (pp. 512–533). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
flict. Instead, practitioners of the different modes are generally Benjamin, W. (1999). The Arcades project. Cambridge, MA:
happy to learn from each other, and to use the insights of one The Belknap Press of Harvard University (German Original
approach to enhance the quality of their own investigations and 1983).
reach of their own conclusions” (2006, p. 86). Boyd, B. (2009). On the origin of stories: Evolution, cognition, and
fiction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brockmeier, J. (1996). Explaining the interpretive mind. Human
References Development, 39, 287–295.
Abbott, H. P. (2000). The evolutionary origins of the storied Brockmeier, J. (2001). Texts and other symbolic spaces. Mind,
mind: Modeling the prehistory of narrative consciousness Culture, and Activity, 8(3), 215–231.
and its discontents. Narrative, 8(3), 247–256. Brockmeier, J. (Ed.) (2002). Special volume on “Narrative and
Abbott, H. P. (2001). Special volume on “On the origins of fiction: cultural memory.” Culture and Psychology, 8(1).
Interdisciplinary perspectives.” SubStance, 94/95, 1–278. Brockmeier, J. (2004). What makes a story coherent? In
Abbott, H. P. (2008). The Cambridge introduction to narrative. A. U. Branco & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Communication and
2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. metacommunication in human development (pp. 285–306).
Alber, J. & Fludernik, M. (2010). Postclassical narratology: Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
Approaches and analyses. Columbus, OH: The Ohio State Brockmeier, J. (2005a). The text of the mind. In C. Erneling
University Press. & D. M. Johnson (Eds.), The mind as a scientific object:
Amsterdam, A. G. & Bruner, J. S. (2000). Minding the law. Between brain and culture (pp. 432–452). New York: Oxford
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. University Press.
Anderson, B. R. O’G. (2006). Imagined communities: Reflections Brockmeier, J. (2005b). Pathways of narrative meaning con-
on the origin and spread of nationalism. London & New York: struction. In B. D. Homer & C. Tamis-LeMonda (Eds.),
Verso. The development of social cognition and communication
Andrews, M. (2007). Shaping history: Narratives of political (pp. 291–313). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Brockmeier, J. (2007). Über narratives Bewusstsein [On the
Andrews, M., Squire, C., & Tamboukou, M. (2008). Doing nar- narrative mind]. In P. H. Breitenstein, V. Steenblock, &
rative research. Los Angeles: Sage. J. Siebert (Eds.), Geschichte, Kultur, Bildung. Philosophische
Appadurai, A. (1996). Modernity at large: Cultural dimensions of Denkrichtungen [History, culture, education: Philosophical
globalization. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Perspectives] (pp. 12–25). Hanover: Siebert.
Press. Brockmeier, J. (2009). Reaching for meaning: Human agency
Aronsson, K. (2001). Narrative, sociology of. In J. Smelser & and the narrative imagination. Theory and Psychology, 19(2):
P. B. Baltes (Eds.), International encyclopedia of the social 213–233.
and behavioral sciences (pp. 10,285–10,289). Oxford, UK: Brockmeier, J. & Harré, R. (2001), Narrative: Problems and
Pergamon. promises of an alternative paradigm. In J. Brockmeier &
Atkinson, P. & Delamont, S. (2006). Rescuing narrative from nar- D. Carbaugh (Eds.), Narrative and identity: Studies in
rative research. Narrative Inquiry, 16, 164–172. autobiography, self and culture (pp. 39–58). Amsterdam &
Atkinson, P. Delamont, S., & Housley, W. (2008). Contours of Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
culture: complex ethnography and the ethnography of complex- Brockmeier, J. & Olson, D. R. (2002). What is a culture of lit-
ity. Plymouth, UK: AltaMira Press. eracy? In J. Brockmeier, M. Wang, & D. R. Olson (Eds.),

brockm eier 463


Literacy, narrative and culture (pp. 1–15). Richmond, UK: Duranti, A. (Ed.) (2006). A companion to linguistic anthropology.
CurzonRoutledge. Oxford, UK & Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Bruner, J. S. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, Edwards, D. (1997). Discourse and cognition. London: Sage.
MA: Harvard University Press. Edwards, D. & Potter, J. (1992). Discursive psychology. London:
Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Sage.
University Press. Elliott, J. (2005). Using narrative in social research: Qualitative
Bruner, J. S. (1996). Foreword to B. Shore, Culture in mind: and quantitative approaches. London & Thousand Oaks, CA:
Cognition, culture, and the problem of meaning (pp. xii–xvii). Sage.
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Erickson, P. A. & Murphy, L. D. (2003). A history of anthro-
Bruner, J. S. (2001). Self-making and world-making. In pological theory, 2nd ed. Petersborough, ON: Broadview
J. Brockmeier & D. Carbaugh (Eds.), Narrative and iden- Press
tity: Studies in autobiography, self and culture (pp. 25–37). Fasulo A. (2007). Theories of self in psychotherapeutic narra-
Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins. tives. In M. Bamberg, A. De Fina, & D. Schiffrin (Eds.),
Bruner, J. S. (2002). Narrative distancing: A foundation of lit- Selves and identities in narrative and discourse. Amsterdam &
eracy. In J. Brockmeier, M. Wang, & D. R. Olson (Eds.), Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Literacy, narrative and culture (pp. 86–93). Richmond, UK: Fasulo, A. & Zucchermaglio, C. (2008). Narratives in the work-
Curzon Press. place: Facts, fictions, and canonicity. Text & Talk, 28(3),
Burrow, J. W. (2007). A history of histories: Epics, chronicles, pp. 351–376.
romances and inquiries from Herodotus and Thucydides to the Fludernik, M. (1996). Towards a “natural” narratology. London:
twentieth century. London: Allen Lane. Routledge.
Carrithers, M. (1992). Why humans have cultures: Explaining Freeman, M. (2001). From substance to story: Narrative, iden-
anthropology and social diversity. Oxford, UK: Oxford tity, and the reconstruction of the self. In J. Brockmeier &
University Press. D. Carbaugh (Eds), Narrative and identity: Studies in auto-
Chamberlin, J. E. (2004). If this is your land, where are your sto- biography, self and culture (pp. 283–298). Amsterdam &
ries?: Reimagining home and sacred space. Cleveland, OH: Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Pilgrim Press. Freeman, M. (2010). Hindsight: The promise and peril of looking
Chase, S. E. (2005). Narrative Inquiry: Multiple lenses, backward. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
approaches, voices. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Gadamer, H.-G. (1989). Truth and method. New York: Crossroad
The Sage handbook of qualitative research (pp. 651–680). (German Original 1960).
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood
Chatman, S (1981). Reply to Barbara Herrstein Smith. In Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
W. J. T. Mitchell (Ed.), On narrative (pp. 258–265). Chicago, Gee, J. P. (1991). Memory and myth: A perspective on narrative.
IL: The University of Chicago Press. In A. McCabe & C. Peterson (Eds.), Developing narrative
Clandinin, D. (Ed.) (2007). Handbook of narrative inquiry: structure (pp. 1–25). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Mapping a methodology. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic
Cohn, D. (1999). The distinction of fiction. Baltimore, MD: Books.
Johns Hopkins University Press. Geertz, C. (1983). Common sense as a cultural system. In
Cortazzi, M. (2007). Narrative analysis in ethnography. In C. Geertz, Local knowledge (pp. 73–93). New York: Basic
Atkinson, P. A. & S. Delamount (Eds.), The call of life stories Books.
in ethnographic research (pp. 384–394). London: Sage. Geertz, C. (1995). After the fact: Two countries, four decades, one
Cruikshank, J. (1998). The social life of stories: Narrative and anthropologist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
knowledge in the Yukon Territory. Lincoln, NB: The University Geertz, C. (2000). Available light: Anthropological reflections on
of Nebraska Press. philosophical topics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Currie, M. (1998). Postmodern narrative theory. New York: St. Press.
Martin’s Press. Genette, G. (1980). Narrative discourse: An essay in method.
Daiute, C. & Lightfoot, C. (2004). Narrative analysis: Studying Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
the development of individuals in society. Thousand Oaks, CA: Georgakopoulou, A. (2007). Small stories, interaction and identi-
Sage. ties. Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Darnell, R. (2006). Benjamin Lee Whorf and the Boasian foun- Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis, IN:
dations of contemporary ethnolinguistics. In C. Jourdan Hackett.
& K. Tuite (Eds.), Language, culture, and society: Key top- Greenblatt, S. (1998). Culture. In D. Keesey (Ed.), Contexts
ics in linguistic anthropology (pp. 82–95). Cambridge, UK: for criticism, 3rd ed. (pp. 477–492). Mountain View, CA:
Cambridge University Press. Mayfield.
Duranti, A. (1986). The audience as co-author: An introduction. Grodal, T. (2005). Evolution of narrative forms. In D. Herman,
Text, 6(3), 239–247. M. Jahn, & M.-L. Ryan (Eds.), Routledge encyclopedia of nar-
Duranti, A. (2009a). Linguistic anthropology: History, ideas, rative theory (pp. 152–154). London: Routledge.
and issues. In A. Duranti (Ed.), Linguistic anthropology: A Gubrium, J. F. & Holstein, J. A. (2008). Narrative ethnography.
reader, 2nd Ed. (pp. 1–38). Oxford, UK & Malden, MA: In S. Hesse-Biber & P. Leavy (Eds.), Handbook of emergent
Blackwell. methods (pp. 241–264). New York: Guildford.
Duranti, A. (2009b). Narrating the political self in a campaign Gubrium, J. F. & Holstein, J. A. (2009). Analyzing narrative real-
for US Congress. In A. Duranti (Ed.), Linguistic anthro- ity. Los Angeles: Sage.
pology: A reader, 2nd Ed. (pp. 245–271). Oxford, UK & Harré, R. & van Langenhove, L. (Eds.) (1999). Positioning theory:
Malden, MA: Blackwell. Moral contexts of intentional action. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

464 narrative sce na r i os


Harré, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. Thousand travelling concept of narrative (pp. 20–41). Helsinki: Helsinki
Oaks, CA.: Sage. Collegium for Advances Studies. Accessed on September 3,
Harré, R., Brockmeier, J., & Mühlhäusler, P. (1999). Greenspeak: 2011 from http://www.helsinki.fi/collegium/e-series/volumes/
A study of environmental discourse. Thousand Oaks, CA: volume_1/001_04_hyvarinen.pdf.]
Sage. Hyvärinen, M. (2010). Revisiting the narrative turns. Life
Harré, R., Fathali M. M., Pilkerton Cairnie, T., Rothbart, D., & Writing, 7(1), 69–82.
Sabat, S. R. (2009). Recent advances in positioning theory. Hyvärinen, M. (in press) “Against narrativity” reconsidered. In
Theory and Psychology, 19(1), 5–31. G. Rossholm & C. Johansson (Eds.). Disputable core con-
Harrison, K. D. (2007). When languages die: The extinction of the cepts of narrative theory.
world’s languages and the erosion of human knowledge. New Iser, W. (1989). Prospecting: From reader response to literary
York: Oxford University Press. anthropology. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins.
Harrison, K. D. (2011). My position as field linguist. Retrieved Jahoda, G. (1992). Crossroads between culture and mind:
September 1, 2011 from http://www.swarthmore.edu/ Continuities and change in theories of human nature. New York
SocSci/dharris2/. & London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Heath, S. B. (2009). What no bedtime story means: Narrative Jakobson, R. (1960a). Language and culture. In Jakobson, R.,
skills at home and school. In A. Duranti (Ed.), Linguistic Selected writings, Vol. 7 (pp. 101-–112). Berlin & New York:
anthropology: A reader, 2nd Ed. (pp. 343–363). Oxford, UK Mouton Publishers.
& Malden, MA: Blackwell. Jakobson, R. (1960b). Linguistics and poetics. In T. Sebeok
Heider, F. (1958). The Psychology of interpersonal relations. (Ed.), Style in language (pp. 350–377). Cambridge, MA:
New York: John Wiley and Sons. MIT Press.
Herman, D. (2008). Narrative theory and the intentional stance. Keen, S. (2007). Empathy and the novel. New York: Oxford
Partial Answers, 6(2), 233–260. University Press.
Herman, D. (2009a). Narrative ways of worldmaking. In Kitayama, S. & Cohen, D. (2007). Handbook of cultural psychol-
S. Heinen & R. Sommer (Eds.), Narratology in the age of cross- ogy. New York: Guilford Press.
disciplinary narrative research (pp. 71–87). Berlin, Germany Kohler Riessman, C. (2008). Narrative methods for the human
& New York: Walter de Gruyter. sciences. Los Angeles: Sage.
Herman, D. (2009b). Basic elements of narrative. Oxford, UK: Leitch, T. M. (1986). What stories are: Narrative theory and inter-
Wiley-Blackwell. pretation. University Park, PA & London: Pennsylvania State
Herman, D. (2009c). Storied minds: Narrative scaffolding for University Press.
folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and folk psy- Lejeune P. (1989). On autobiography. Minneapolis, MN:
chology (pp. 40–68). Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic. University of Minnesota Press.
Herman, D. (2011a). The emergence of mind: Representations of Lock, A. & Symes, K. (1999). Social relations, communica-
consciousness in narrative discourse in English. Lincoln, NB: tion, and cognition. In A. Lock, A. & C. R. Peters (Eds.),
University of Nebraska Press. Handbook of human symbolic evolution (pp. 204–235).
Herman, D. (2011b). Introduction. In D. Herman (Ed.), The Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
emergence of mind: Representations of consciousness in narra- Lotman, IU. M. (1990). Universe of the mind: A semiotic theory of
tive discourse in English. Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska culture. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Press. Marcus, G. E. & Clifford, J. (1986). Writing culture. Berkeley,
Herrnstein Smith, B. (1981). Narrative versions, narrative theo- CA: University of California Press.
ries. In W. J. T. Mitchell (Ed.), On narrative (pp. 209–232). Marcus, G. E. & Fischer, M. M. J. (1986). Anthropology as cul-
Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. tural critique: An experimental moment in the human sci-
Holstein, J. A. & Gubrium, J. F. (2008). Handbook of construc- ences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
tionist research. New York & London: Guilford Press. Mattingly, C. (2007). Acted narratives: From storytelling to
Horsdal, M. (2011). Telling lives: Exploring dimensions of narra- emergent dramas. In D. J. Clandinin (Ed.), Handbook of
tive. New York: Routledge. narrative inquiry: Mapping a methodology (pp. 405–425).
Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocul- Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
tural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Mattingly, N., Lutkehaus, C. & Throop C. J. (2008). Special
Press. volume on “Troubling the boundary between psychology
Hutto, D. - (2009). Narrative and folk psychology. Exeter, UK: and anthropology: Jerome Bruner and his inspiration.” Ethos,
Imprint Academic. 36(1).
Hydén, L.-C. & Brockmeier, J. (2008a). From the retold to McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
the performed story: Introduction. In L.-C. Hydén & University Press.
J. Brockmeier (Eds.), Health, illness and culture: Broken nar- Medved, M. I. & Brockmeier, J. (2010). Weird stories: Brain, mind,
ratives (pp. 1–15). New York: Routledge. and self. In M. Hyvärinen, L.-C. Hydén, M. Saarenheimo, &
Hydén, L.-C. & Brockmeier, J. (2008b). Health, illness and cul- M. Tamboukou (Eds.), Beyond narrative coherence (pp. 17–32).
ture: Broken narratives. New York: Routledge. Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Hymes, D. (1974). Foundations in sociolinguistics; an ethnographic Miller, P. J. (1982) Amy, Wendy, and Beth: Learning language in
approach. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania South Baltimore. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
Press. Miller, P. J., Fung, H., & Koven, M. (2007). Narrative rever-
Hymes, D. (1964). Language in culture and society: A reader in berations: How participation in narrative practices co-creates
linguistics and anthropology. New York: Harper & Row. persons and cultures. In S. Kitayama & D. Cohen (Eds.),
Hyvärinen, M. (2006). Towards a conceptual history of Handbook of cultural psychology (pp. 595–614). New York:
narrative. In M. Hyvärinen & J. Mykänen (Eds.), The Guilford Press.

brockm eier 465


Mintz, S. W. (1974a). Caribbean transformations. Chicago, IL: (Ed.), Handbook of narrative inquiry: Mapping a methodology
Aldine. (pp. 3–34). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Mintz, S. W. & Richard Price (1992). The birth of African- Plummer, K. (2007). The call of life stories in ethnographic
American culture: An anthropological approach. Boston, MA: research. In Atkinson, P. A. & Delamount, S. (Eds.), The call
Beacon Press of life stories in ethnographic research (pp. 395–406). London:
Nelson, K. (1989a). Introduction: Monologues in the crib. Sage.
Narratives from the crib (pp. 1–23). Cambridge, MA: Harvard Polkinghorne, D. E. (1988). Narrative knowing and the human
University Press. sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Nelson, K. (Ed.) (1989b). Narratives from the crib. Cambridge, Pratt, M. L. (1988). Conventions of representation: Where dis-
MA: Harvard University Press. course and ideology meet. In van W. van Peer (Ed.). The tam-
Nelson, K. (1996). Language in cognitive development: The emer- ing of the text: Explorations in language, literature, and culture
gence of the mediated mind. New York: Cambridge University (pp. 15–34). London: Routledge.
Press. Propp, V. (1968). Morphology of the folk tale. Austin, TX:
Nelson, K. (2004). Construction of the cultural self in early University of Texas Press (Russian Original 1928).
narratives. In C. Daiute & C. Lightfoot (Eds.), Narrative Quasthoff, U. M. & T. Becker (2005). Narrative interaction.
analysis: Studying the development of individuals in society (pp. Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins
87–110). London: Sage. Quinn, N. (2005). Finding culture in talk: A collection of methods.
Nelson, K. (2007a). Developing past and future selves for time New York: Palgrave MacMillian.
travel narratives. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 327–328. Richardson, B. (2006). Unnatural voices. Columbus, OH: The
Nelson, K. (2007b). Young minds in social worlds: Experience, Ohio State University Press.
meaning, and memory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Ricoeur, P. (1981). Hermeneutics and the human sciences.
Press. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University.
Nelson, K. (2009). Narrative practices and folk psychology: A per- Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development.
spective from developmental psychology. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Narrative and folk psychology (pp. 69–93). Charlottesville, VA: Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton,
Imprint Academic. NJ: Princeton University Press.
Norrick, N. R. (2000). Conversational narrative: Storytelling Rosner, J. (2007). Introduction. In J. Rosner (Ed.), The messy self
in everyday talk. Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John (pp. xiv–xix). Boulder & London: Paradigm Publishers.
Benjamins. Rudrum, D. (2005). From narrative representation to narrative use:
Norrick, N. R. (2007). Conversational storytelling. In D. Herman Towards the limits of definition. Narrative, 13(2), 195–204.
(Eds.), The Cambridge companion to narrative (pp. 127–141). Ryan, M.-L. (2007). Toward a definition of narrative. In
Cambridge, UK & New York: Cambridge University Press. D. Hermann (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to narrative
Ochs, E. (1988). Culture and language development: Language (pp. 22–35). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
acquisition and language socialization in a Samoan village. Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation. Oxford, UK:
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Blackwell.
Ochs, E. & Capps, L. (2001). Living narrative: Creating lives in Sapir, E. (1949/1933). Language. In D. G. Mandelbaum (Ed.),
everyday storytelling. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Selected writings of Edward Sapir in language, culture, and
Press. personality, 2nd ed. (pp. 7–32). Berkeley, CA: University of
Ochs, E. & Taylor, C. (2001). The “father knows best” dynamic in California Press (1st ed. 1933).
dinnertime narratives. In A. Duranti (Ed.), Linguistic anthro- Schutz, A. (1967). The phenomenology of the social world.
pology: A Reader (pp. 431–449). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press (German
Ochs, E. & Schieffelin, B. (2006). The impact of language Original 1932).
socialization on grammatical development. In C. Jourdan & Smith, B. & Sparkes, A. C. (2009). Narrative inquiry in sport
K. Tuite (Eds.). Language, culture, and society (pp. 168–189). and exercise psychology: What is it, and why might we do it?
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Psychology of Sport and Exercise, 10(1), 1–11.
Ornaghi, V., Brockmeier, J., & Grazzani Gavazzi, I. (2011). The Squire, C., Andrews, M., & Tamboukou, M. (2008).
role of language games in children’s understanding of mental Introduction: What is narrative research? In M. Andrews,
states. Journal of Cognition and Development 12(2), 239–259. C. Squire, & M. Tamboukou (Eds.), Doing narrative research
Palmer, A. (2004). Fictional minds. Lincoln, NB: University of (pp. 1–20). Los Angeles: Sage.
Nebraska Press. Stokoe, E. & Edwards, D. (2006). Story formulations in talk-in-
Palmer, A. (2010). Social minds in the novel. Columbus, OH: The interaction. Narrative Inquiry, 16(1), 57–65.
Ohio State University Press. Straub, J. (2002). Personal and collective identity: A conceptual
Parry, M. (1971). The making of Homeric verse. The collected analysis. In H. Friese (Ed.), Identities: Time, difference, and
papers of Milman Parry. A. Parry (Ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford boundaries (pp. 56–76). New York: Berghan Books.
University Press. Straub, J. (2005). Telling stories, making history: Toward a nar-
Peterson, E. E. & Langellier, K. (2006). The performative turn in rative psychology of the historical construction of meaning.
narrative studies. Narrative Inquiry, 16(1), 173–180. In J. Straub (Ed.), Narration, identity, and historical conscious-
Phelan, J. (2006). Rhetorical aesthetics and other issues in the ness (pp. 44–89). New York: Berghan Books.
study of literary narrative. Narrative Inquiry, 16(1), 85–93. Taylor, C, (1989). Sources of the self: The making of the modern
Phelan, J. (2007). Experiencing fiction. Columbus, OH: The identity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ohio State University Press Thomas, W. I. & Znaniecki, F. (1958). The Polish peasant in
Pinnegar, S. & Daynes, J. G. (2007). Locating narrative inquiry Europe and America. New York: Dover Publications (First
historically: Thematics in the turn to narrative. In D. Clandinin published 1918–1921).

466 narrative sce na r i os


Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a language: A usage-based Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher
theory of language acquisition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard psychological processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
University Press. (Russian Original 1930, 1933, & 1935).
Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). Thinking and speech. New York: Plenum
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Russian Original 1934).
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. Whorf, B. L. (1956). Language, thought and reality. Cambridge,
(2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins MA: MIT Press.
of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford,
675–735. UK: Blackwell.
Tylor, E. (1871). Primitive culture. London: John Murray. Zentella, A. C. (1997). Growing up bilingual: Puerto Rican chil-
Valsiner, J. (2007). Cultures in minds and societies: Foundations of dren in New York. Malden, MA: Blackwell 1997.
cultural psychology. Los Angeles: Sage.

brockm eier 467


CHAPTER

Culture in Action: A Discursive


21 Approach

Kyoko Murakami

Abstract
The overall aim of this chapter is to discuss an approach to studying culture by drawing on the project
of remembering and reconciliation from a discursive psychology perspective. I demonstrate discourse
analysis from research using a case of the Anglo-Japanese reconciliation. I provide a brief overview of the
development of discourse analysis and discursive psychology and highlight key philosophical foundations
and theoretical assumptions on which discursive psychology and practice of discourse analysis are
based. As the examples of discourse analysis, I will demonstrate how culture can be studied as a topic
of members’ concern. In this view, culture is not a matter of the researcher’s concern to handle as
a causal factor or independent variable. Discursive psychologists study culture as a resource for the
participants. Finally, I will discuss the implication of the discursive approach and its far-reaching challenges
for advancing the methodology of studying time-relevant phenomena of people’s experience as a matter
of duration and transformation.
Keywords: discourse, culture, discursive psychology, cultural psychology

Introduction The overall aim of this chapter is to introduce


Since the discursive turn in social sciences, dis- a concept of discourse and discuss an approach
course has become a common currency. For one to studying culture by drawing on a project of
thing, critical movement in psychology and other remembering and reconciliation from a discursive
social disciplines promoted a rapid development psychology perspective. I shall demonstrate dis-
of discourse theory and discourse-based studies. course analysis from the research using a case of the
There are many versions of discourse-based stud- Anglo-Japanese reconciliation (Murakami, 2001a,
ies and discourse analysis at present. Those include 2001b, 2007; Murakami & Middleton, 2006) and
namely, but not exhaustively, Critical Discourse discuss the relevance, implications, and challenges
Analysis (Fairclough, 2001; Wodak & Meyer, of discourse analysis for research in exploring the
2009), Sociocultural Discourse Analysis (e.g., Gee, relationship between culture and psychological
1999; Gee & Green, 1998), Foucauldian Discourse phenomena. In the following, I will provide a brief
Analysis (e.g., Burman, 1996; Hook, 2001; Hook, overview of the development of discourse analysis
2005; Parker, 1997; Parker, 1999; Parker, 2002), and discursive psychology to highlight key philo-
and other discourse theories (e.g., Bakhtin, 1981). sophical foundations and theoretical assumptions
Because of its large variety of discourse studies of social sciences disciplines on which discursive
and analysis, I shall not attempt to chart compre- psychology and practice of discourse analysis are
hensively the variations in these discourse-related based. Using examples of discourse analysis, I shall
approaches. demonstrate how culture can be studied as a topic

468
of members’ concern using an analytic concept interviewer, were doing the remembering of the
called “membership categorization device” (Sacks, past events and actions. Such remembering is a
1989, 1992). Membership categorization device is socially organized communicative action situated
a discursive resource for the participants in talk-in- in an inter-/cross-cultural social setting. To study
interaction to do social action and perform social this inter-cultural phenomenon within the project
accountability. Therefore, culture is not a matter of of remembering and reconciliation, I use discourse
the researcher’s concern to handle as a causal factor analysis using the perspective taken from discursive
or independent variable to bring about differences psychology.
in behavior, perception, and attitude—discursive
psychologists study culture as a resource for the Discourse Analysis
participants. Finally, I shall discuss the implica- The term discourse has been used in a number of
tion of the discursive approach by referring to other different ways within the community of discourse
approaches that forefront culture as a main research analysts and scholars of social sciences (Heath,
object and its far-reaching challenges for advancing 1997; Potter, 1998; Potter & Wetherell, 1987).
the methodology of studying time-relevant phe- The general consensus is that discourse analysis is
nomena of people’s experience as a matter of dura- a study of language in use and refers to a field of
tion and transformation. research encompassing a broad range of research
drawing on the philosophical and methodologi-
The Project of Remembering and cal traditions in linguistics, psychology, sociology,
Reconciliation and anthropology and cultural and literary stud-
Toward the end of World War II, 16 British pris- ies. For discursive psychology, the term discourse,
oners of war (POWs) died in a labor camp located in in a least limited sense, is used “to cover all forms
the mountains of central Japan. The cause of death of spoken interaction, formal and informal, and
derived from illness induced by malnutrition, severe written texts of all kinds” (Potter & Wetherell,
climate, and living conditions in the previous camps 1987, p. 7). Discourse analysis deals with naturally
in Singapore and Thailand. Initially, British soldiers occurring talk and text, including interview tran-
were captured by the Japanese army in Singapore in scripts and other forms of both spoken and written
December 1941 and worked on the construction of communication.
the Thai-Burma Railway from 1942 to June 1943. Discourse analysis, a method of analysis of dis-
Three hundred British POWs were then transferred course, was born out of a synthesis of contempo-
to Japan to work in a copper mine until the end rary critical movements in psychology—particularly
of the war in August 1945. During the captivity, a social, cognitive, and experimental psychology as
grave for the dead POWs was built by fellow British well as other social science disciplines. Discursive
POWs. After the war, local Japanese villagers refur- psychology might be construed as one of those sep-
bished the grave and erected a memorial. In October arate strands as the application of discourse theory
1992, 47 years after the war, 28 former POWs and to the classic questions of psychology, but discursive
their family members returned to Japan and visited psychology itself has grown to be a complex field,
this grave on a reconciliation trip. upheld by a multiplicity of different ideas and argu-
In the spring of 1999, I set out to interview ments (Edley, 2001). For the purpose of this chap-
surviving POWs and family members who took ter, rather than offering an account of the various
part in this reconciliation trip. The key interview latest developments within discursive psychology,
question was: Why had they decided to go on the I shall underline key features and assumptions for
reconciliation trip? This question was designed to grounding the ensuing discourse analysis that I shall
elicit their accounts of wartime captivity and post- present as the illustration of how culture in psycho-
war experiences of living and coping with difficult logical phenomena can be studied.
times—war-related illnesses and disease, trauma,
and presumably any other medical problems. Also, Language as Social Action
the interview invited them to share their views on Among the principal features of interview as
reconciliation with the troubling past. The occa- social practice of reconciliation, action orientation
sion of the interview created a participatory frame- to talk, joint construction of meaning, social actions
work of revisiting the past. That is, the participants, of blaming, justifying, forgiving, and apologizing
being engaged in a conversation with a Japanese are performed. Rather than treating reconciliation

m u ra ka m i 469
as an interior psychological phenomenon of con- reconciliation is achieved and how language in use
flict being resolved, reconciliation is researched as is observed.
the social relationship, as a practical interactional To further explain the discursive approach to
business that interview participants attend to and language as social action, let me now trace the con-
accomplish. Similarly, the central focus on studying temporary development of linguistics and philoso-
reconciliation rests on the intercultural communi- phy of language. Chomsky’s theory on the nature of
cation, how cultural differences are brought off as a language development and acquisition features what
problem or posed as an obstacle for achieving recon- is termed as generative grammar, a set of underlying
ciliation, and these cultural issues were analyzed as a linguistic rules that innately exist in the form of deep
members’ practical concern that was accomplished structure (Chomsky, 1965). Among the critique of
interactionally. Chomsky’s theory and its approach to underlying
There are several principal features of discourse cognitive psychology is that it tries to separate the
analysis that are relevant to the study of inter-/ issue of linguistic competence from linguistic per-
cross-cultural communication in an Anglo-Japanese formance. Linguistic performance and competence
reconciliation practice. First, discourse analysis are not easily separable, being intricately related to
is concerned with the content of talk, its subject one another. Chomsky’s empirical work is taken
matter, and with its social organization rather than from speech data that is idealized compared with
linguistic system, structure, and grammatical rules ordinary speech (Potter & Wetherell, 1987). Such
(e.g., syntax, phonetics, semantics). Second, dis- data are so far removed from the natural speech,
course analysis has a threefold concern with action, with errors, hesitations, self-corrections, and so
construction, and variability. Simply put, in talk- forth, that they do not capture the interactional fea-
ing (and written communication), people perform tures of natural speech (Potter & Wetherell, 1987).
social action. Third, discourse analysis examines the In contrast, discourse analysis attends to the perfor-
rhetorical organization (argumentative) of everyday mance of naturally occurring speech to determine
talk and thought, revealing the dilemmatic nature how people use language in the course of different
of discourse attending to potential versions of kinds of interactions.
argument (Billig, 1997; Billig et al., 1988). Finally, The second feature of discourse analysis pertains
discourse analysis is concerned with the cognitive to the way in which the relationship between the
issue of reality and mind—particularly with how object (reality) and language is accomplished (Potter
cognitive issues such as knowledge, belief, fact, & Wetherell, 1987; Silverman, 1997, p. 115). This
truth, and explanation are handled in talk and text. point refers to the notion of sign (the signifier and
This reflects its origins in the sociology of scientific the signified) as to how such an arbitrary relation-
knowledge (e.g., Mulkay, 1979) and the reworking ship between the object and the linguistic labeling
of psychological categories of memory, attitude, is established. This notion of sign derives from a
learning, and so on (e.g., Harré & Stearns, 1995; Saussurean approach to signification and semiol-
Middleton & Edwards, 1990; Potter & Wetherell, ogy and heavily depends on the larger structure of
1987). society. Whereas discourse analysis is interested in
The development of discourse analysis centers the local production of meaning and knowledge,
on language as a main focus of psychological inves- Saussurean linguistic approach links its analysis
tigation. It derives from philosophy, linguistics, to an abstract level of social structures and other
and literary and cultural studies as to how we view broader concerns of the society such as power, hier-
and understand the function of language. The dis- archy, class, race, gender, and so forth. In semiology,
cursive approach is premised on an action orienta- theory of society is generated independently from
tion of language, especially on the language use in what meanings are locally produced within a given
context and materialized in social relations, within linguistic and cultural community. In other words,
which such a context allows. Therefore, language is semiology does not necessarily account for the local
not treated as merely a tool or medium to repre- meaning making process as it “tends to produce . . .
sent the inner states of the mind. Language takes static idealized analysis” (Potter & Wetherell, 1987,
up a larger and more central role in our everyday p. 31). The emphasis is placed on “looking at struc-
communication and social interactions, and it is in ture (“la langue”) rather than specific uses (“parole”),
the social interaction where the remembering and along with a focus on examining meaning at a

470 c ulture in act i on


single instance rather than processes occurring over a way of validating their categorization of speech
a period of time, ruling out a number of impor- acts. This shortcoming is complemented by the per-
tant and interesting questions” (Potter & Wetherell, spective developed by ethnomethodology and its
p. 31). For the discourse analysis, this means that it branch entitled conversation analysis, by which the
should focus on how members in a particular cul- ensuring discourse analysis is influenced.
tural community establish the social relations and Discursive psychology acknowledges and draws on
moral order of the group using language (Edwards, contributions made by Vygotsky and Wittgenstein,
1997; Potter & Wetherell, 1987). Discourse analy- as they both emphasized an importance of the role
sis aims to explicate the process of producing and of language in the development of knowledge,
changing meanings at the time of their occurrence. thought, memory, and cognition. Vygotsky’s the-
Studies of the function of language from linguis- ory, or what is known as Socio-Cultural Theory
tic philosophy are also concerned with examining (or other labels of cultural-historical theory), fore-
the processes of labeling and pointing as language fronts concepts such as mediation and cultural
functions, how the meaning (a set of relations tools and artifacts and their relation to human
between the object and the language) is produced activity (Harré, 2011, Chapter 9; van der Veer,
over time. Speech Act Theory (Austin, 1975 [1962]) 2011, Chapter 3). The theory influenced the early
moves away from the idea that the primary function development of the discursive movement. Equally
of language is to describe some state of affairs, some influential to the contribution to development
aspect of reality. The most useful distinction Speech discourse analysis is Wittgenstein in his famously
Act Theory makes on language use is between doing known notion of “language-games” (Wittgenstein,
and stating, specifically the ways in which people 1968 [1958])—the role of language in shaping
use language to perform social actions. To illus- thoughts and other cognitive functions and the
trate this point further, let me use some modified action-orientation of language. He states, “[T]he
examples cited in the work of Potter and Wetherell term ‘language-games’ is meant to bring into
(1987). For example, the sentence: prominence the fact that the speaking of language
is part of an activity, or of a form of life” (para. 23).
I declare war on terrorism.
Regarding the problem of categorization in social
is not a description of the world that can be seen sciences, he comments:
as true or false. Rather it accomplishes some practi-
When philosophers use a word—“knowledge,”
cal action and brings about specific consequences
“being,” “object” (etc.) . . . —and try to grasp the
when uttered in appropriate circumstances. This
essence of the thing, one must first ask oneself: is the
example illustrates an action-orientation to lan-
word ever actually used in this way in the language-
guage—that is, language is performing an action:
game which is its original home?—What we do is to
request, declare, agree, disagree, and so forth. This
bring words back from their metaphysical to their
view of language underlines the key foundation of
everyday use?
discourse analysis.
(Wittgenstein, 1968, para. 116)
One of the main difficulties with Speech Act
Theory, however, is that it tends to deal with ideal- Wittgenstein’s critique, similarly applied to semi-
ized linguistic phenomena or “made–up” sentences ology, refers to a problem of our understanding of
taken outside the context of use or highly ritual- the relationship between language and context. It
ized speech forms. This problem is common to the reveals the taken-for-granted nature of social scien-
Chomskian approach. Studying these idealized, tists’ producing arbitrarily constructed operational
made-up examples poses another challenge. Often definitions of phenomena without ever studying
we hear a single utterance that performs a num- the “language-game” in which the phenomenon
ber of acts at once, or acts may be spread out in has its everyday home (Wittgenstein, 1968).
more than one sentence including a question and Discourse analysis, in line with Wittgenstein’s cri-
response sequence. As Potter and Wetherell argue, tique, problematizes the analysts’ production and
“[i]n practice the decision about what act an utter- superimposition of their categories on the social
ance is performing is often made by referring to the phenomena. In its distinct epistemological posi-
response rather than to any features of the utterance tion, discursive psychology’s practice of discourse
itself ” (1987, pp. 29–30). Speech Act Theory does analysis aims to explicate how members produce
not consider the sequential feature of interaction as them and make them relevant in talk.

m u ra ka m i 471
The aforementioned points suggest that analy- or interactional work being done in the discourse”
sis should be focused on the language in use, not (Edwards & Potter, 1992, p. 2). Moreover, its inter-
on excavating formal rules embedded in language est is the nature of knowledge, cognition, and real-
and the underlying cognitive processes. This means ity as to how events are described and explained, in
that the study of language does not confine itself to the forms of factual reports, or narratives, and how
formal linguistic analysis as in the transformational cognitive states are attributed. Instead of assuming
grammatical approach and analysis of sentences the speaker’s (or writer’s) underlying cognitive states
that the analyst himself/herself generated to prove in such discursive constructions, they are “examined
their point. Nor does it mean a diachronic approach in the context of their occurrence as situated and
of studying the history of the word meanings and occasioned constructions” (p. 2).
explicating the process of change. Drawing on the
arguments by Wittgenstein, Austin, and Vygotsky, Action Orientation, Construction,
discursive psychologists point out that language Variability in Mundane Settings
in use, including communication and interaction, The view of language as social action is also com-
is itself a form of practice. Language is used to do monly shared in the sociological tradition of eth-
things in everyday communication—giving orders, nomethodology (Garfinkel, 1967). It refers to “the
making promises, and thinking and arguing. From investigation of the rational properties of indexical
this view of language, reconciliation comes to be expressions and other practical actions as contin-
understood as something that is done or accom- gent on-going accomplishments of organized artful
plished in the course of social interaction, in which practices of everyday life” (p. 11). As the term sug-
discourse is observed. In this view, language is a tool gests, ethnomethodology is concerned with the study
to be used for the accomplishment of social action of (-ology) ordinary people’s (ethno-) methods. It
(Middleton & Edwards, 1990, p. 36), steering away is the study of the methods that ordinary people
from the notion of the representational instrumen- use to produce and make sense of everyday life.
tality of language seeing versions of events as prag- Ethnomethodological research seeks to learn about
matically variable accomplishments. the activities of everyday life as phenomena in their
own right. According to Sacks and Garfinkel (1967;
Discursive Psychology: Principles Heritage, 1984), founders of ethnomethodology,
for Discourse Analysis talk is considered as an activity and “doing” talking
Discursive psychology is the culmination of a provides ways of understanding as to how common
number of independent developments in psychol- sense views about the world and practical reasoning
ogy, sociology, linguistics, anthropology, and phi- in a given situation get produced and shared.
losophy. More specifically, it was born out of the The treatment of language as action is a com-
critiques of traditional psychological methods— mon concern for discursive psychologists and
behaviorism and positivism (Gergen, 1978; Harré, ethnomethdologists. This implies that language is
1979) and also the critique of psychological the- a constructive medium that people use resource-
ory, cognitivism, which favors explanation in terms fully to accomplish things. The discourse analysis
of mental states or processes. Roots of discursive is aimed at explicating “the constructive and flex-
psychology go as far as a number of independent ible ways in which language is used should them-
developments, including the work of Mead and selves become a central topic of study” (Potter &
Vygotsky (Harré & Gillet, 1994). In particular, it Wetherell, 1987, p. 35). The present study of iden-
incorporates contemporary movements such as tity and accountability fully exploits this feature of
ethnomethodology (Garfinkel, 1967; Garfinkel, language. It also follows that our position on the
1974; Heritage, 1984), social constructionism (e.g., role of language allows us to see the variability of
Gergen, 1997; Shotter, 1990; Shotter, 1991), and people’s views and opinions in talk (and texts).
ethnogenics. Edwards and Potter (1992) have pro- Ethnomethodology’s concerns with the way mem-
filed key features of discursive psychology in terms bers’ knowledge and understanding get produced
of action-orientation, construction of knowledge reflect discursive psychology’s interests in people’s
about reality, and variability of versions of reality. pragmatic use of language in terms of talk as action
The focus of discursive psychology is the action- as practical accomplishment. Thus, the focus on
orientation of talk and writing. “For both participants variability yields analytical resources for studying
and analysts, the primary issue is the social actions, accountability.

472 c ulture in act i on


In the next section, I shall show what makes dis- The contribution of CA to discursive psychology is
course analysis a viable approach for the concerns of that CA provides evidential basis, or a proof proce-
the research on remembering and reconciliation. In dure of how speakers establish intersubjectivity, shared
doing so, I shall elaborate on the features of action understanding of reality in interaction. The analysis of
orientation, construction, and variability to identify the interview talk is empowered by the conversation
a body of influence—namely, ethnomethodology analytic principles, and relevant issues to illustrate the
and conversation analysis—which would lead to performative nature of identity and constitutive pro-
another important notion called accountability of cess of accountability as action were examined.
social action. The aforementioned features of discourse analy-
sis and discursive psychology—action orientation,
Accountability construction, and variability—have important
The project from which the discourse analysis implications for studying culture in terms of cul-
was conducted makes a major emphasis on the tural membership in the project of remembering
centrality of accountability for making sense of and reconciliation. The discursive approach (i.e.,
the participants’ discourse. Mainstream psycholo- the umbrella term for the methodological approach
gists also have paid close and systematic attention used in discourse analysis) attends to the particu-
to one level of accountability, specifically where lar analytic concerns—our identities and cultural-
people attribute responsibility for events. Another ness arising out of interactions with other people.
level of accountability is that of the speaker who Cultural identity or what it means to be a particu-
is producing the report, or the description of the lar member of a culture is constituted in interac-
world, from which the causal inferences are sup- tion, and it resources to perform social actions
posed to be drawn: such as invitations, agreements and disagreements,
blamings, displays of neutrality, and so forth. Thus
[T]he discursive approach where versions of events,
cultural membership is achieved discursively by
things, people and so on, are studied and theorized
mobilizing the members’ knowledge and under-
primarily in terms of how those versions are
standing of social categories (e.g., class, ethnicity,
constructed in an occasioned manner to accomplish
gender, age, etc.)—what it means for the partici-
social actions.
pant to be a member of a given community. The
(Edwards & Potter, 1992, p. 8)
discursive approach does not take these categories
Conversation analysis (CA) helps translate this per- as provided by the analysts without looking at what
spective to systematic analytical procedures in study- is actually produced in talk. People orient to these
ing naturally occurring conversations. Conversational categories in talk and construct what they mean to
analysis is focused on the sequential organization of them, rather than how those categories are shaping
conversation—the ways in which people take turns the way they think about their identities. The consti-
in conversation, the management of repair, and tutive process of cultural membership is important
the analysis of the topic organization. The mean- to the studies of social remembering and reconcili-
ing and interpretation of the first speaker’s utter- ation. People do not consistently produce the same
ance is examined in the second speaker’s utterance. version of the past when accounting for a problem-
Heritage (1984) terms it as intersubjectivity and atic past, especially when the events relate to vio-
explains as follows: lence and other unpleasant acts committed during
the war. People fashion talk (and texts) about the
[S]ome analysis, understanding or appreciation of
wartime past, orientating to identities of the speak-
the prior turn will be displayed in the recipient’s
ers and the hearers and perform social actions in
next turn at talk . . . Conversational interaction is
making his or her claim of the past. Hence, a multi-
structured by an organization of action which is
tude of discourses are constantly at work construct-
implemented on a turn-by-turn basis. By means of
ing and producing our identity. Variability of views,
the organization, a context of publicly displayed and
opinions, and identity descriptions, therefore, work
continuously up-dated intersubjective understanding
to be the analytical resource for discourse analysts.
is systematically sustained . . . It is through the
“turn-by-turn” character of talk that the participants
display their understanding of “the state of the talk” Discursive Approach to Studying Culture
for one another. Language users engage in talks and texts not only
(Heritage, 1984, p. 259) as speakers, writers, and listeners or readers but also

m u ra ka m i 473
as members of groups, professions, organizations, on cultural models in cultural anthropology (e.g.,
communities and societies, and cultures. As mem- Holland & Cole, 1995), cultural script in pragmat-
bers of given groups, they interact in complex com- ics (e.g., Nelson, 1981, 1986; Wierzbicka, 1994) and
binations of social roles and cultural identities. In ethnographic conversation analysis (e.g., Moerman,
participating in discourse, members (i.e., language 1973). The discussion is guided by two analytic
users) display roles and identities, which become concepts—membership categorization and eth-
visible for discourse researchers as a dynamic, flex- nification processes. The analysis concludes that
ible category that the participants use. Thus social the ways in which cultural knowledge is socially
categories such as gender, age, class, and ethnicities constructed—negotiated and shared—are discur-
and cultural background alike are relevant resources sive accomplishments of the veterans’ social action
for members to use to accomplish social action. of accounting for the wartime past and their dealing
Power dynamics and asymmetries can be observed with the problem attributed to cultural differences
in a given interaction as part of the participant’s and misunderstanding.
concern and orientation to the talk at hand and
work within the interactional order and hierarchy of Ethnification As a Topic
power positions (Linell & Luckmann, 1991). Below This particular example analysis explores the
I will present a few extracts and demonstrate the notion of ethnification: how people ethnify others
discursive approach to analyzing interview materi- in talk in a cross-cultural context (Moerman, 1973).
als, especially how a cultural marker (whether one Taking a discursive approach informed by discursive
is British or Japanese) is treated as a member’s topic psychology (Edwards & Potter 1992), ethnomethod-
of concern, rather than an independent variable ology (Garfinkel, 1967), and conversation analysis
assigned by the researcher. The analysis is guided by (Atkinson & Heritage, 1984), I will look at how
the analytical concept of membership categoriza- cultural otherness is marked, constituted, and put
tion and ethnification processes, which I discussed to use in talk. Also, I will show ways in which a par-
earlier. The analysis will illustrate the ways in which ticular cultural aspect of others is made to be a topic
the participants’ claim of difficulty with a rice diet of concern in interaction and establish its relevance
is addressed in the interview where participants’ and to accomplishing social actions. Discourse examples
the interviewer’s orientation to culture becomes at are taken from interviews with British World War II
issue. Let us now look at the examples of such talk. veterans, who were taken as POWs by the Japanese.
During the interviews, they gave accounts of the
Culture and Membership Category wartime past and shared their views and experiences
What does it mean to say one is treating cul- of reconciliation. The analytical task is twofold:
ture as a topic of its “members?” Discourse analysis first, to illustrate how rice is rendered as a member’s
examines the member’s notion of culture and seeks category relevant to the interview talk and how it
to address how the concept of culture is put to use in becomes a discursive resource; second, to examine
talk in interaction and negotiate and forge meaning a process of ethnification, defined as “ethnic iden-
to it. With this approach, culture is considered as a tity as a situated accomplishment of interlocutors”
dynamic concept, not a fixed, stable category that (Day, 1994, 1998; Moerman, 1974). Finally, I will
members in conversation/interlocutors use. Culture discuss the methodological payoff of the discursive
is always on the move and in action. I shall hereby approach as a way of studying culture and cross-
present an example of discourse analysis from previ- cultural issues.
ous research that examines the ways in which people
talk about others of different culture or ethnic ori- Ethnification Process
gin (Murakami, 2001b). I now introduce the analytic concept of “eth-
I analyzed interview talk of the British World nification processes,” with which the use of iden-
War II veterans about their experiences of captiv- tity categories in ethnic (and linguistic) group
ity in the POW camp in Japan and their recent categorizations have been explored (Day, 1994).
activities of reconciliation nearly 50 years after the Ethnification processes are defined as “processes
war. Proposed is a discursive approach (a discourse through which people distinguish an individual
analysis by discursive psychology) to the study of or collection of individuals as a member or mem-
culture and cross-cultural communication. This bers respectively of an ethnic group” (Day, 1994,
approach is sharply contrasted with work drawing p. 154). Arguably Day’s study takes a discursive

474 c ulture in act i on


approach and views “ethnic identity as a situated and transformations in relations to other peoples”
accomplishment of interlocutors” (Day, 1998, (Ohnuki-Tierney, 1993). The work is based on
p. 151). The important distinction is that the dis- the notion of “a presentation and representation
cursive perspective does not ask how someone’s of the self, using food as metaphor of self ” (p. 4)
ethnic background shapes or determines what they and explores how the Japanese people use the meta-
say, but, rather to ask how this ethnicity becomes a phor of rice to think about themselves in relation to
resource for them—and others to use (Day, 1998). other peoples (e.g., ethnic groups or nationalities).
Within this view ethnicity, identity is a topic in It aims:
its own right, and its relevance for interlocutors
to show how the Japanese notion of the self has taken
becomes an empirical question (Day, 1998).
on a different contour as a different historical other
From a systematic observation of a large cor-
has emerged and rice and rice paddies have served
pus of data gathered for the study, it became clear
as the vehicle for deliberation, although not always
that certain topics and experiences were recurrently
conscious, in these process.
talked about by the veterans in the interviews. Such
(Ohnuki-Tierney, 1993, p. 5)
topics included food and eating practices in the
camps, especially a rice diet in the Japanese camp. She acknowledges a methodological challenge in
Their experiences related to rice were central to studying collective representation of consciousness
the life as POWs, and rice was emblematic of the as follows:
culture of the camp. The topic of food and hunger
In a broader framework it is a question of the
during any war is a universally poignant theme. For
development of a powerful representation of the self
example, the autobiography titled The Railway Man
by the people themselves, on the one hand, and of
by Eric Lomax (1996) depicts the eating regime
how to reconcile a dominant representation with
in the prison camp—not only rice but any eating
apparent multiplicity within a culture, on the other
incidents—at length and with fine details dur-
hand.
ing his captivity in Singapore and other locations
(1993, p. 6)
in Asia during World War II. The selected extracts
used for this chapter concern conversational topics The discursive approach differs from her approach,
of rice and a rice diet. The discourse analysis reveals focused on representation of self through the object
a nuanced way of talking about their problem of a such as rice. Instead of looking at a multiplicity of
rice diet. The ex-POWs’ accounts of rice and rice voices, selves, and variability of people’s views, opin-
diet mark the Japanese as cultural other and display ions, and positions as something to be reduced to a
their understanding of the Japanese people and their model or fit to a conceptual category as a manifested
cultural practices in the interview while they recall form of collective representation, the discursive
how the POWs viewed the rice diet at the time. The approach views them as a members’ topic, discur-
aim is to produce some empirically grounded analy- sive resources for the purpose of achieving social
sis and discuss how the topic of rice and rice diet is actions such as arguing, justifying, agreeing and
constituted as a culturally emblematic category of disagreeing, and claiming differences and similari-
membership and used to accomplish specific social ties in representing culture of their own and others.
actions—that is, to claim and account for their dif- Therefore, tensions between individual and collec-
ficulty with a rice diet in the POW camp. tive representations and between heterogeneity and
homogeneity are not treated as a problem and are
Marking the Cultural Other: to be resolved in terms of contested or negotiated
An Anthropological Approach meanings and symbolic interpretations in studying
I consider two studies in anthropology to see culture and self. In this vein, the task here is to show
how culture is studied in various social science and demonstrate what people “do” with culture,
disciplines. Ohnuki-Tierney’s work on rice as self the ways in which they make cultural difference an
(1993) is the most relevant work on rice here. It issue, and attend to the issue of self-representation
typifies an anthropological approach to cultural vis-à-vis cultural others. This analysis proposes that
knowledge and the symbolic representation of self the discursive approach provides a basis for showing
through food. She takes a view that food is a way people’s (members’) moment-by-moment and here-
of marking cultural other and examines collective and-now sense-making of their culture, and others,
representations of self, change, continuity, structure in relation to the past, present, and future.

m u ra ka m i 475
Culture As Local Production of Meaning Extract 21.1 Souvenir from the Camp
Equally relevant to the present chapter is the eth-
1. Ted: I’ve got all sorts of souvenirs.
nographic and conversation analytic study of Thai
culture by Moerman (1973). Writing of his approach, 2. Int.: Hummm.
he comments that “culturally contexted conversa-
3. (.)
tion analysis tries to limit the ingredients of inter-
pretation, the components of meaning” (Moerman 4. Ted: >got a< little or- a little box of
1973, p. 7). This is a modified adaptation of the that we used to you know.
ethnomethodological stance, which “treats members’
5. We got breakfast out o’ a little
inquiries as locally occasioned, managed and accom-
brown bowl (2.) pap rice.
plished, within and with reference to the ‘here-and-
now’ circumstances of their production” (Hester 6. [(.)a uh and it was rice (.)
& Eglin, 1997, p. 2). Branching off the orthodoxy crushed ((clapping sound))=.
of conversation analysis (e.g., Schegloff, 1992),
7. Charlie: [aye.
Moerman analyzes talk between villagers and an offi-
cial and highlights some instances of locally triggered 8. Int.: =um huh.
significance of cultural systems in which rice (and
9. Ted: in water (.) and they called it
other food) as an identity marker or a member’s cat-
like porridge [you know.
egory do the business of labeling ethnicity. Also the
interactional use of the category “rice” invokes social 10. Int.: [Yeah
relations of power and authority of state, which con-
11. Ted: Just a little brown bowl like
stitute the dominant and dominated in a particular
that. That’s what we got.
social setting (Moerman, 1973). Such conversation
analysis permits us to see the active situated use of 12. That was at five o’clock in the
cultural ideas and local production of meanings morning.
accomplished in interaction. In what follows, I shall
13. [was it six o’clock about.
illustrate discourse analysis and its approach to study-
ing culture as discursive accomplishment by using the 14. Charlie: [ye that was six o’clock.
research on remembering and reconciliation.
15. Ted: at six o’clock then you went.

Interviews With British Prisoners 16. [( ) then you got a (.) your little
of War Veterans box (.)
Two extracts were selected from a transcript of 17. Int.: [hummm.
a 5-hour recording of a group interview with those
veterans who agreed to take part in the research. 18. Ted: your bento, was it?
They were asked to share and discuss their views and
19. Int.: hum, lunch [box.
post-war experiences of reconciliation with respect
to their captivity in the POW camps in Thailand 20. Ted: [and they used
and Japan. The interview was conducted in a partic- [to put rice in there.
ipant’s home in a northeastern city in England. The
21. [((clapping noise))
participants included four former POWs who took
part in the reconciliation trip in 1992 and two of 22. Int.: [uh huh≠
their spouses. Two spouses did not accompany their
23. (.)
partners on the reconciliation trip. The interviewer
was the researcher herself. 24. Ted: and maybe if you’re lucky a
little bit of uh Soya sauce or.
Analysis: Rice in the Prisoners of War Camp 25. something in it.
Talk of Rice As Discursive Resource for
Accountability of Actions 26. Sidney: aye if you were lucky.
Extract 21.1 below exemplifies an analytic view
27. Mary: °(hhhhh)°.
that rice is a members’ category with which the

476 c ulture in act i on


Extract 21.1 (Continued) both personal and shared meanings of the past in
the present interactional circumstances. A tangible
28. Int. if [you’re lu(h)cky(h).
object such as a lunch box, which represents a par-
29. Ray: [(the first time) the first ticular past at issue, becomes an aid for recalling past
[time (when). events that are relevant to a particular conversational
setting and organization of social relations. In other
30. ?: . . . [lucky.
words, the objects work as discursive resources for
31. Int.: . . . [( ) just plain rice. entering into a particular moment in the past and
establish its relevance in interaction. In this extract,
32. Ray: The first time we got those
“rice” is treated as a common reference point, and
boxes they had been varnished.
the talk about rice establishes a mutual understand-
33. or something [hadn’t they. ing of what it was like to live with a rice diet and
other related cultural practices that were markedly
34. Charlie: . . . . . . . . . . . . [( ) they
different from and unfamiliar to their own.
were quite.
In this extract, “rice” deserves a term that
. . . . . . . . . . . . [no they denotes something more than a simple reference
35. Sidney:
hadn’t. point. I suggest that it is a membership category.
The membership category refers to classifications or
36. Ray: You couldn’t eat the rice.
social types that may be used to describe persons in
37. (.) its original definition (Sacks, 1992), but it is later
extended to collectivities and non-personal objects
38. Charlie: [O≠hh
(Hester & Eglin, 1997). Descriptions of objects
39. Int.: [( ) and events provide for the accountability of actions;
they are used to generate excuses and generally deal
(Italicized words are of Japanese origin; names used are pseudonyms.) with “attributional” issues of cause, intention, and
responsibility (Edwards & Potter, 1992). A fine-
grain analysis of the organization of turn-taking and
participants display their cultural understanding uptakes unveils the ways in which various descrip-
of rice and a rice diet and establish its relevance in tions as to how rice was cooked and served in the
talk. Prior to this interview segment, they trace their camp are produced in situ interactionally. These
experience of being transported from Thailand to descriptions ascribed to the category “rice” consti-
the camp in Japan. They speak of a drastic change of tute a claim for the participant’s difficulty with a
diet. What is demonstrated here is that the partici- rice diet, and they are subsequently formulated as
pants used rice as a category, which is emblematic a problem.
of life at the Japanese POW camp. Rice, as being
central to the life at the camp and to the very basic The Cultural Practice of a Rice
need for survival, is brought up as a conversational Diet in the Prisoners of War Camp
resource, whereas the participants account for what In the opening sequence, a reference to sou-
it was like to be in captivity and live and work in venirs is specified in Ted’s utterance, “a little box
a Japanese POW camp. The ex-POWs’ work of to put in a little brown ball (2.) pap rice and eat
managing accountability entails the presentation of with” (ll. 4 & 5). He gives a detailed and animated
a rice diet as an unfamiliar cultural practice of the description of what the box is and how it was used
Japanese, as well as a claim for the POWs’ difficulty for eating rice (ll. 4–6 & 9). The term souvenir,
with such a diet. as referred to things that the POWs brought back
The analysis of this extract focuses on the ways from the POW camp, seems to be ironic consid-
in which cultural otherness is constituted through ering the context in which the interviewees reflect
telling about items that the POWs used to use in the about their experiences of captivity and reconcili-
camp and later brought back to Britain as memora- ation. “Souvenirs” are, in a conventional sense, a
bilia and produced as souvenirs (line 1). The word reminder, a token, or memento of a place one vis-
“souvenirs” refers to the things they brought back ited in the past, but in this case the experiences may
and they form the object of remembering the camp not necessarily be pleasant. Rather than speculating
days. Stories produced about these items give rise to the intention of the speaker, Ted, let us look at how

m u ra ka m i 477
this is received in the next turn. Does the inter- another example of discursive accomplishment
viewer treat this as irony? Here, the interviewer’s with a resource of the membership category “rice.”
receipt and the brief pause (l. 3), albeit not actively, The difficulty of eating rice is discursively formu-
solicit and encourage the speaker Ted to continue. lated by the description of the box, a container used
The descriptions make reference to a mealtime and to serve and transport rice at the Japanese camp. In
crockery with which to serve rice, including details addition to the descriptions given by the partici-
as to how rice was prepared and how it was served pants with reference to how the box was used, the
and eaten in the camp. For example, the exact meal- speaker’s embodied action—for example, the clap-
time is debated among the participants, Ted and ping sound of simulating a packing of rice in the
Charlie, marking some significance of the time of box (ll. 6 & 21)—demonstrates a cultural practice
breakfast (ll. 12–15). This exchange makes a point of what to do with rice in the Japanese camp.
(and even a complaint) of how little and infrequent Now I would like to focus on the latter part of
the POWs ate at the camp. Issues dealing with food the conversation (ll. 24 onward) and discuss how
shortage, scarcity, and constant hunger are talked talk of the box mediates further telling of difficulty
about later in the same interview (see the discussion with a rice diet and affords the speaker Ray’s claim
in Extract 21.2). of difficulty with rice (l. 36, “You couldn’t eat the
rice”). How is this claim formulated as being sen-
Ethnification and Shared Understanding sible and legitimate without making an explicit
of the Past blame? Clearly, the generic pronoun “you” is used
Let us look at how the researcher–interviewer’s to distance the speaker from the claim of difficulty
identity as Japanese is marked and made relevant in with a rice diet. The problem is attributed to two
talk. In line 18, Ted actively seeks the interviewer’s features of rice and its cultural practice. First, the
response by checking his memory of a Japanese term tastelessness of rice is invoked in Ted’s description
for lunchbox that is at issue (ll. 16 & 18). First, after in line 24 (“and maybe if you’re lucky a little bit
the debate over the breakfast time, Ted refers back of uh Soya source or something in it”). This for-
to the topic “little box” in line 1. 16 (“then you got mulation seems to be ironic, for “maybe if you’re
(.) your little box (.)”) and a brief pause at the end lucky” orients to the opposite of being lucky, and
for his pursuit of the interviewer’s response. Then, in it is offered as a mitigated claim of the extremity of
line 18 he specifically asks the interviewer to reply hard conditions in the camp. This claim is endorsed
to his question (“your bento, was it?”). This formu- and warranted in the way in which Ted’s utterance
lation needs unpacking. Along with the pronoun is duly picked up—that is, the affiliational uptakes
“your” predicated to the lunchbox, the way to which of the other speakers such as Sidney’s recitation of
this is responded by the interviewer indicates that the utterance (l. 26), followed by Mary’s laughter
Ted’s question, using the Japanese word “bento” has (l. 27), and the interviewer’s recitation and interpo-
a direct relevance to the interviewer and therefore lated laughter (l. 28). The interviewer’s summation
interactionally nominates the interviewer to take in line 31 (“just plain rice”) displays her understand-
the next turn. The Japanese word bento, the English ing of the nature of the problem and aligns herself
equivalent of lunchbox, ethnifies the interviewer with the other speakers.
as Japanese, someone who is assumed as culturally The second feature of the difficulty is the unusual
informed and linguistically competent on the topic appearance of the box. This is registered in Ray’s
in progress. Joint construction of what bento means description of the box in line 32 (“The first time we
is interactionally accomplished: The interviewer dis- got those boxes they had been varnished or some-
plays her knowledge by offering a gloss in English thing hadn’t they”). The emphatic reference to the
(l. 19, “hum, lunch [box]”), which is completed rice holder as being “varnished,” as well as the rice
by Ted with his embodied action (l. 21). This joint being served in a little box, exoticises the cultural
construction of what bento means not only ethnifies practice of how rice was eaten. All these allusions as
the interviewer but also constitutes a mutual under- to how food was prepared in the Japanese camp have
standing of the particular past at issue (ll. 16–23). bearings on the speakers’ normative expectations
of how to prepare food in their own culture. Ray’s
Claiming Difficulty With a Rice Diet claim of difficulty with the rice diet as something
The talk in this extract illustrates how Ray’s prob- legitimate and warrantable is achieved by how he
lem with a rice diet is worked up, which warrants describes the preparation of the rice. In the ensuing

478 c ulture in act i on


section, I further examine the ways in which this
50. Charlie: But we got inferior rice as the
claim of difficulty with rice is handled interaction- prisoners of war.
ally and discuss the interactional consequences of it.
To this end, I will use an analytical concept of mem- 51. Int.: oh ye[ah?
bership categorization device (Sacks, 1992). I will
52. Ted: .[oh:::h
argue that culture is treated as a topic of talk and a
members’ concern, rather than it being presumed 53. Charlie We didn’t get the best rice.
an a priori concept. I will then consider the useful-
54. Int: hu[mmm
ness of such a concept in analyzing discourse.
55. Ray: . . . .[well the first rice you got
Rice As a Membership Category it had been treated with lime
In the next extract, the participants are dis-
56. hadn’t [it? Really for sowing.
cussing their experiences of and displaying their
knowledge of rice. Various descriptions regarding 57. Charlie: ..[it ha:d aye
the category “rice” have emerged and are attrib-
uted to a particular ethnicity or culture of other. 58. Ted: We had lime rice (.) I think it
In Sacks’ terminology, describing can be consid- 59. [was used for plantin’ the rice.
ered a “category-bound activity” (1972). Sacks
notes many activities are common-sensically asso- 60. Int.: [what’s that?
ciated with certain membership categories (1972). 61. Int.: Oh.
Considering that the interview pertains to the
war-time events such as captivity in a POW camp, a lime rice and what was that the
62. Ted:
what has been brought off as part of a members’ other one? (.)
category can be highly consequential to the future 63. °Lime and something else°
trajectory of interaction and become a source of
potential conflict among the interlocutors. We 64. Ray: The lime (was to:) with the
now look at how those categories and descriptions preserve it er::
are introduced and worked up and identify what 65. [as: a: seed rice you see?
are interactional upshots as part of managing a deli-
cate nature of the interaction. 66. Ted [(it was another kind) and it was
This extract is rich with a collection of descrip- a [horrible
tions (or subcategories) regarding the category 67. Int. [It’s a brown rice?

68. Ray: Pardon?


Extract 21.2
69. Int.: Brown rice? It’s like uh (.)
40. Ray: Cos anyway, all our cooks didn’t
know how to cook rice did 70. Ray: Oh yeah [( )

41. they? . . . .[with the rusk on


71. Charlie:
you mean
42. Charlie: Well er:: they’re quite . . . -
72. Int.: [Not- not refined rice
43. Ted: no::: [(unless)]
73. Charlie: [ah we used to get that sometimes
44. Charlie: [ they’re] quite- canny.
74. Ted: We used to fight for rice polishers
45. Ray: Some of the rice was er: (.) didn’t we
46. (.) 75. Charlie: [aye
47. Charlie: Not as good as the Japanese rice 76. Sidney: [rice polisher(h)
(.) the rice (.) Japanese
77. Ted: You know when you polish the
48. is flaky (a bit) innit, [you know. rice- the-
49. Int.: [um ummm
(Italicized words are of Japanese origin; names used are pseudonyms.)

m u ra ka m i 479
rice—the Japanese rice, flaky rice, the inferior rice, the Japanese at the camp for their differential treat-
the best rice, rice for sowing, lime rice, planting rice, ment of the POWs. In addition, he suggests that
seed rice, brown rice, and unrefined rice. How do it may have been done deliberately on the part of
the varying descriptions of the category rice work in those Japanese who treated the POWs. The ascrip-
relation to Ray’s earlier claim of the difficulty with tion of the rice with the adjective “inferior” appeals
a rice diet in the camp? The focus of the analysis of to the morality (or lack of by the Japanese) in such
this extract is to ask how Ray’s claim is handled in treatment and thus makes the criticism legitimate.
the interaction. Let us focus on the ways in which With all the possible ways of talking about differ-
the speakers (Ray, Charlie, and Ted) bring up the ential treatment, this could be said, for example, to
category rice and see what they accomplish inter- be “different” rice rather than “inferior.” The point
actionally. The problem of a rice diet is formulated here is that the analyst is making a judgment about
as a legitimate problem for the POWs. Here the how it should be said, or in this case, what adjective
ex-POW speakers do not make an explicit criti- should have been used. It is the way in which the
cism of the Japanese rice diet, nor do they implicate category rice was used to perform a social action of
the interviewer into the problem of this cultural blaming the Japanese at the camp and how such a
practice. recollection was shared and established as to what
In the opening sequence, Ray goes on to elabo- happened at the camp.
rate on his problem with a rice diet. By formulat- The interviewer responds to this problematic
ing in this way, Ray implies that a rice diet is not attribution as a dispreferred answer, seeking fur-
just his problem but that it is also problematic for ther explanation (l. 51, “oh yeah?”). Ted’s emphatic
the other prisoners, including experts such as cooks response in line 52 overlapping with the interviewer
(ll. 40–41, “all our cooks didn’t know to cook rice also seems to attend to Charlie’s problematic state-
did they?”). Here, as the speaker is normalizing the ment. Charlie’s reformulation (l. 53, “we didn’t
problem, he offers further descriptions of rice (l. 45, get the best rice”) is elaborated by Ray, who offers
“some of the rice was er:”). This is followed by a brief more category-related terms: “treated with lime”
silence (l. 46), indicating his pursuit for comments and “rice for sowing” (ll. 55–56). Additional cat-
from others. Charlie takes over from Ray, providing egories mitigate Charlie’s charge (and suspicion)
a description of rice that elaborates on Ray’s point. that the POWs were served with the inferior rice
Here, two descriptions of rice become available (ll. on purpose. Following from Charlie’s agreement
47–48): one is the rice that was eaten by the POWs (l. 57), Ted endorses this category (l. 58) and offers
(“not as good as Japanese rice (.) the rice (.) Japanese another category “[rice] used for plantin’ the rice.”
is flaky (a bit) innit”), and the other is Japanese The descriptions of both speakers, Ted and Ray, in
rice that, by implication, is of better quality and is lines 62 through 65 seem to be ensuring that they
presumably eaten by the Japanese. This contrasting stay on the topic of the lime [rice] with preserva-
set of descriptions of rice made by the speakers sug- tives and seed rice. The upshot of these categories
gests that the problem of a rice diet is linked to their hearably works as a repair of Charlie’s earlier prob-
being British POWs. What is more, the problem of lematic formulation, by emphasizing the technical
a rice diet, originally attributed to the food having properties of rice, rather than judgmental or moral
no substance and taste (from Extract 21.1) is now attribution.
being reformulated as implicitly having to do with Not only the ex-POW participants but also the
a differential, possibly discriminatory, treatment at interviewer participate in talk about rice. How
the POW camp. does the interviewer handle the series of formula-
Let us examine line 49 onward to see how the tion and reformulation of the problem? When Ted
participants and the interviewer handle this state- speaks of lime rice in lines 55through 56, the inter-
ment. In doing so, we can examine how multiple viewer actively seeks an explanation (l. 57, “what’s
categories of rice, brought off interactionally, con- that?”) and acknowledges Ted’s explication (l. 59) as
tribute to accounting for the troubling past. In a news receipt (l. 61, “Oh”). The category that the
Charles’ statement (l. 49, “but we got inferior rice interviewer offered, “brown rice” (l. 67), matches
as the prisoners of war”), the use of “we” as a col- up with a collection of categories for rice—rice for
lective voicing of the problem of discrimination is planting and sowing, or seed rice. The interviewer
now attributed to the discriminatory practice of makes claim to her understanding of rice served in
being fed the inferior rice. Charlie implicitly blames the camp by producing the category brown rice as

480 c ulture in act i on


part of the collection of category rice. Brown rice resource. Certain descriptions and properties of rice
is accepted by Ray in line 70 and Charlie with his and the rice diet were predicated and established as
reformulation as “[rice] with rusk on you mean” legitimate interactionally. This was done as perform-
(l. 71). The interviewer has another go at produc- ing accountable actions, accountability—claiming
ing “not not refined rice” for reassurance, and this the participants’ difficulty with the rice diet in the
is ratified by Charlie (l. 73). As shown here, the Japanese camp. Notably, rice itself is not bound to
interviewer produces a few categories, displaying an intrinsically fixed symbolic meaning, as shown in
her cultural knowledge that is relevant to the topic the participants’ talk about their experiences of rice
of rice. She is not a passive hearer of the talk about and the rice diet. Cultural anthropologists would
rice but takes part in the ongoing talk, signaling her treat rice in terms of a symbolic representation of
participation. The turn-taking and production of self and society at large. The researchers subscrib-
categories of rice illustrate the ex-POWs’ work of ing to the cultural model/script might look for an
accountability to addressing the difficulty of the rice underlying cultural model implied in the rice and
diet in the camp—what it was like to live in extreme rice diet. Here, however, rice is treated as a mem-
circumstances, in which food and eating become a ber’s concern and is used as a discursive resource
crucial, daily concern for survival. The interviewer’s in performing social action with which interlocu-
role is noteworthy here; her participation in the talk tors orient to what it is to live in a culture of oth-
about rice collaboratively accounts for the problem ers. Cultural otherness is constructed through such
of the rice diet. The ex-POW participants manage talk.
to talk about the problem vis-à-vis the Japanese Rice and its related activities are central to the
interviewer without becoming hostile and making life of the POWs and therefore are emblematic of
an overt criticism of the cultural practice of eating the culture of the camp. The talk offers a reference
rice. point and context, in which the participants discur-
sively manage the sensitive issues of talking about
Summary of the Analysis difficult experiences without having to be hostile
The extracts analyzed in this chapter illustrate or aggressive to the interviewer, who represents
the way in which cultural issues were addressed in the nationality of the perpetrator. This point is evi-
the research interview between the British veterans denced by the ways in which ex-POW participants
and the Japanese researcher concerning the rice diet and the interviewer display their understanding and
at the Japanese POW camp during WWII. The affiliation to an argumentative position in situ as
Japanese rice diet emerged as a key conversational discursive accomplishment. The analysis takes place
topic in the interview with the ex-POWs, and in at a microlevel, focusing on turn-taking and how
the unfolding interaction the veterans expressed sequential organization unravels the ethnification
their views and experiences of reconciliation. As process by which the participant ethnifies the inter-
demonstrated in the analysis, a close examination viewer and seeks her alignment to undertake work
of talk allows us to see what people do with a seem- on a potentially problematic statement and claim.
ingly mundane conversational topic such as a rice In turn, the interviewer’s accommodation to the
diet and how the unfolding talk brought about a ethnification is registered as part of the interactional
cross-cultural tension in this interactional setting, upshot, collaborating to the interviewees’ account-
where the groups of two different nationalities ability work.
talked face-to-face. The rice diet was discussed as Production of cultural knowledge and its devel-
seemingly mundane but then was elevated to differ- opment and dissemination is often a principal
ent kinds of rice, which led to an implied criticism academic concern for some anthropologists, soci-
against the Japanese for discriminatory practice at ologists, philosophers, and psychologists. Their aca-
the camp. The problem with the rice diet was con- demic endeavors are invested to explicate forms of
structed as such that it linked with the way in which cultural knowledge in terms of folk theories, folk
the POWs were treated in the camp. This discursive psychology, and cultural models. Discursive psy-
process of construction was guided by the analyti- chologist Derek Edwards states that “approaches
cal concepts of ethnification and membership cat- to categories and categorization are closely linked
egory. The analysis illustrated the ways in which a to notions of cultural knowledge” (1997, p. 250).
culturally emblematic category of rice was made use Cultural knowledge is considered in “the ways in
of by the ex-POW participants as an interactional which ordinary people categorize and understand

m u ra ka m i 481
things and events, including human actions and Cultural Scripts and Cultural Models
mental experiences” (ibid.). Edwards argues that The body of work pertaining to studying inter-
much of the analyst’s discussions on these forms of or cross-cultural communication (including mis-
cultural knowledge are based on analytical categories communication) has well-established traditions
in which analysts themselves conceptualize the cul- and perspectives that are commonly taken by socio-
ture they are set to investigate (ibid.). Consequently, linguists and linguistic anthropologists. Nelson
“important features of common-sense understand- (1981) and Wierzbicka (1994) are well-known for
ing are systematically obscured, such that we are left their work on the concept called “cultural script.”
with nothing but abstracted cognitive sense-making The objective of their research is to extract the cul-
to explain the data” (ibid., p. 251). tural script in cross-cultural communication—and
Drawing on this discursive approach to study- it can involve miscommunication. According to
ing culture, I argue that the ways in which cultural Wierzbicka (2004), ‘‘[c]ultural scripts are formulae
knowledge is constructed, established, and shared written in very simple words that attempt to articu-
is a discursive accomplishment. Discursive psy- late, on the basis of linguistic evidence, tacit cultural
chologists and discourse analysts are concerned rules” (p. 576). Also, cultural scripts are formulated
with explicating how cultural knowledge becomes in words that have the exact semantic equivalents in
available to people—the ways in which the partici- all languages.
pants in conversation topicalize culture and work Similarly to cultural script, cross-cultural psy-
with categories and categorization in interaction. A chologists and cognitive/psychological anthropolo-
discursive approach provides an analytical tool to gists have devoted themselves to producing a cultural
investigate what it is to be (or not to be) a cultural model in a context of the practice. For example, the
member of a community in a given moment and cultural model of success (Kim, 1993) is focused on
setting. It does not impose the analyst to generate the adaptation pattern from a migrant/immigrant
conceptual categories beforehand and apply a stan- of Korean background to a successful person inte-
dardized coding technique to analyze the data. This grated into a mainstream American culture. This
approach provides an empirical basis for studying cultural explanation is a strategy of attributing the
the constitutive nature of emerging forms of cultural success or failure of people to cultural compatibil-
knowledge. This epistemic stance is one of the most ity and discontinuity. Then they break the model
distinctive features of the discourse analysis that sets down to constituent categories such as cultural val-
it apart from other forms of qualitative analysis. In ues and communication styles as part of operation-
the following, I take this point further by discussing alization. Rooted to cross-cultural psychology, the
two bodies of work pertaining to studying culture cultural explanation relies on Confucian tradition,
within psychological phenomena. and so forth. as a background to this psychologi-
cal phenomenon of adaptation and integration. To
Whose Culture? what extent do we move inward and outward from
As demonstrated in the above analysis, the rice a person/individual? How does the social matter in
diet and eating regime in the Japanese POW camp working up to a cultural model and cultural expla-
is one of the topics that were most commonly to nation of successful integration? In the following, I
be recalled and reminisced by those ex-POW vet- will discuss a socio-cultural perspective, a perspec-
erans. I showed that within the interview talk on tive similar to the cultural model to understand
Anglo-Japanese reconciliation, the members’ (for- the major body of work in studying cultural issues
mer POW British veterans’) main concern over within psychological phenomena.
the hardship and other difficult experiences of the By tracing the changes of the word meaning over
prison camp in Japan was addressed as an issue of time, the socio-cultural discourse analysts insist that
intercultural communication difficulty and lack of cultural models are not fixed but are open to mod-
knowledge about rice as a normal Japanese diet. The ification, expansion, and revision by members as
above discourse analysis demonstrated that the issue they interaction across time and events. This per-
of intercultural communication was discussed in spective also suggests that “cultural models (whether
the specific cultural practice of a rice diet in Japan. local or broader framing models) constitute a set of
In appraising the significance of this analysis, I refer principles for actions in particular cultural domains
to two other popular approaches to studying culture and for particular cultural processes” (Gee & Green,
and intercultural communication. 1998, p. 124). And “the dynamic process involved

482 c ulture in act i on


in constructing a cultural model can be seen if we might have a view/position that the context and
consider how notions of ‘coffee’ have changed in the history of the events involving this case of Anglo-
last decade” (Gee & Green, p. 124). The idea that Japanese reconciliation over World War II should be
the cultural model is constantly changing strikes foregrounded. If those men had been made familiar
a chord with the key assumption of the discursive with a rice diet as the norm of the Japanese diet and
approach, but the socio-cultural perspective indi- that the diet they were exposed to was inevitable
cates that the socio-culturally informed “cultural under the time of war, would their life in the prison
model” perspective needs to design research that camp be remembered differently? Although discur-
incorporates an empirical task of examining changes sive psychologists would not pose such a question, as
over time. it is beyond their remit of studying culture as being
Both approaches to studying culture by focus- a topic of concern of the participants, some linguists
ing on cultural model and script—a socio-cultural and cognitive/psychological anthropologists would
perspective or cognitive anthropological—tend find this issue of intercultural communication quite
to emphasize the importance of cultural models/ important. In the following, I review the alternative
scripts as the researcher’s pre-established object for approach to studying culture-related phenomena
investigation. The discursive approach differs on for a cultural script or cultural model.
this ground. Evaluating my analysis presented in
this chapter, I am not suggesting that those partici- Future Directions: Implications for
pants did not learn the norms and routines of the Discourse in Culture and Psychology
camp because of the lack of a cultural model (or Studies of culture and cross-cultural communi-
script) relevant to the context of the camp. Neither cation have traditionally concentrated on classify-
would I suggest that the interaction in the inter- ing and interpreting features of data taken from a
view is devoid of the cultural model. I question how particular culture. The researcher then puts forward
the cultural model is generated and by whom. The a universal model, script, or set of explanations of
difference in approach between discourse analysis the culture through his or her theorizing cultural
and the other research traditions I referred to is phenomena and the application of researcher’s cri-
epistemic. This epistemic stance leads to another teria and categories in abstracted cultural models or
aspect of discourse analysis regarding how to treat cultural scripts. In contrast, the discursive approach
the context of the research. commits to explicating locally produced and situ-
Within the discursive psychological community, ated meaning in the making—illustrating the ways
to what extent does the analysis presume and take in which members handle cultural issues and estab-
in and foreground the context and any other avail- lish their significance interactionally. The discur-
able information beyond what is represented in sive approach employed in this analysis provides a
the transcripts? Some are more vigilant about the viable tool, as it makes visible the very moment-by-
importation of the context and other ethnographic moment process in talk where people’s cultural
information and argue that the analysis should understanding and knowledge are displayed, shared,
refrain from considering a larger context and the and established as relevant. Membership categories
circumstances. However, I would say that the con- such as rice are discursive resources used to achieve
text of the interview as well as the history in which social actions of accountability of the past in social
those British men in captivity endured a deprived practices of reconciliation and other socially orga-
and extreme condition and were subjected to forced nized sense-making activities.
labor is important. Within the discourse analytic I suggest that the discourse analysis produces
community, including that of ethnomethodological a theoretical critique to a notion of culture and
and conversation analytic orientations, there is an its methodological orientation regarding how to
ongoing debate about what constitutes the context study culture. Also pertinent is culture and its role
and to what extent the analysis takes it into consider- in psychological research. Culture demonstrated in
ation (Billig, 1999a, 1999b; Schegloff, 1997, 1999; the discourse analysis in this chapter is treated as
Wetherell, 1998). The debate allows me to nestle a topic for the participants (i.e., the veterans and
my analysis in a spectrum of positions, whether the research interviewer); cultural difference and
the analysis should look at only the utterances or at intercultural understanding is central to discur-
the immediate context of the interviews as a back- sive reconciliation—the argument I put forward is
ground. In addition, the other end of the spectrum that reconciliation is not a static concept in which

m u ra ka m i 483
opposing, multiple views are unified and harmo- phenomenon in duration while the same phenom-
nized, and differences between persons are to be enon is constantly in motion and defies the notion
extinguished. In talking about rice, the British vet- of stability and permanence?
eran participants’ views on rice as a cultural issue To understand any experience such as the
at the time of their captivity in a Japanese prison POW’s experience of captivity and post-war expe-
camp as a POW is brought off as a relevant topic rience of struggle and reconciliation over decades
of concern, rather than as a cultural script, so as to in this chapter, it is imperative for the researcher
iron out and erase differences between two national to sensitize himself/herself to different concep-
groups. tions of time and to consider a methodology that
In the remaining section, as I draw this chap- uses an account of transformation of the British
ter to a close, I wish to address far-reaching impli- veterans. The idea that the cultural model is con-
cations and unresolved challenges and issues for stantly changing (like a river) resonates with the
studying culture in psychology and offer a call for a key assumption of the discursive psychological
special and, if possible, concerted effort to advance approach to discourse analysis. Furthermore, the
the discourse-based methodology. It is becoming socio-culturally informed “cultural model/script”
clear that culture has “the constructive openness in perspective seems to require a research design that
using it as an intellectual catalyst in psychology con- incorporates an examination of changes over time.
tinues” (Valsiner, 2009, p. 7). Despite many break- But what interval of time is appropriate to be able
throughs in recent years in psychology and other to observe changes as discernable and significant to
social sciences, understanding culture in psycho- the researcher? The decision over a research time
logical phenomena continues to pose challenges to has been somewhat underexplored by the socio-
psychologists and researchers alike. The discursive cultural and cross-cultural psychologists as much
approach acknowledges culture as a dynamic, unsta- as the discursive psychologist tends to see instances
ble category for the interlocutors as it is in the social of turn-taking and overlooks a longer time frame.
interaction where the meaning of being in a given Culture might be considered as the ecology in
culture gets nominated, accepted/disagreed, and which psychological phenomena such as people’s
negotiated to reach a consensus (albeit it is not per- transformative experiences can be studied in terms
manently settled). This implies that the research on of a dynamic flow of meanings.
culture in psychology is fundamentally designed to
be impossible because of “[t]he Bearable Vagueness Appendix
of Culture” (Valsiner, 2009, p. 7). The research and
the researcher’s position and his/her value system [ Overlap begins
affect the way the research questions are phrased
around the issues of culture. Culture then seems to ↑↓ Vertical arrows precede marked
be inflected in the inception of the research as “the pitch movement, over and above
projection of social values into the term—culture is normal rhythm of speech.
not a neutral term” (Valsiner, 2007, p. 7). Research Underlining Signals vocal emphasis
on culture in psychology therefore is a value-laden,
moral project of the academics (see a similar argu- °I know it° “degree” signs enclose obviously
ment in Brinkmann, 2006, 2009). quieter speech
Following the above, it may be fair to say that () Inaudible, indecipherable utter-
our quest for methodology, whether via discourse or ance, uncertain hearing
otherwise, continues. One far-researching challenge
I see at present is how to approach discourse beyond (0.4) Pause (in seconds and/or tenths of
the research object. The metaphor river might bet- a second)
ter describe our relationship to discourse, which (.) A micropause, hearable but too
moves and has some properties, patterns, and rules short to measure.
so that we can make them visible and therefore be
able to describe them. Yet, the minute we capture ((text)) Additional comments from the
transcriber, e.g., gesture, context
the phenomena, it becomes already obsolete, as the
or intonation, comments by the
experience we capture is in irreversible time (Sato &
transcriber
Valsiner, 2010). How can we come to understand a

484 c ulture in act i on


discourse practice: From regulation to resistance (pp. 1–14).
(Continued) London: Taylor & Francis.
Day, D. (1994). Tang’s dilemma and other problems: Ethnification
she wa::nted Prolonged syllable or sound
processes at some multicultural workplaces. Pragmatics, 4,
stretch 315–336.
Day, D. (1998). Being ascribed, and resisting, membership of
hhh audible aspiration or laughter
an ethnic group. In C. Antaki & S. Widdicombe (Eds.),
.hhh audible inhalation Identities in talk (pp. 151–190). London: Sage.
Edley, N. (2001). Analysing masculinity: Interpretive repertories,
bu-u- hyphens mark a cut-off of the ideological dilemmas and subject positions. In M. Wetherell,
preceding sound S. Taylor & S. J. Yates (Eds.), Discourse as data: A guide for
analysis (pp. 189–228). London: Sage.
>he said< “greater than” and “lesser than” Edwards, D. (1997). Discourse and cognition. London: Sage.
signs enclose speeded-up talk. Edwards, D., & Potter, J. (1992). Discursive psychology. London:
Sage.
<he said> the other way round of the sings Fairclough, N. (2001). The discourse of new labour: Critical dis-
enclose slower talk. course analysis. In S. Yates, M. Wetherell & S. Taylor (Eds.),
Discourse as data: A guide for analysis (pp. 229–266). London:
solid.= =We latched utterance (no interval Sage.
said between them) Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Sto(h)p i(h)t. Laughter within speech is signaled Gee, J. P. (1999). An Introduction to Discourse Analysis: Theory
by h’s in parentheses, audible and method. London: Routledge.
aspiration within a word Gee, J. P., & Green, J. L. (1998). Discourse Analysis, Learning,
and Social Practice: A Methodological Study. Review of
Research in Education, 23, 119–169.
Gergen, K. J. (1978). Experimentation in social psychology:
Note A reappraisal. European Journal of Social Psychology, 8,
The transcription convention used in this paper has been devel- 507–527.
oped by Gail JEFFERSON for the purposes of conversation analy- Harré, R. (1979). Social being: A theory for social psychology.
sis (see ATKINSON & HERITAGE 1984). The exact transcription Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
notation employed in the extracts is listed in the appendix. Harré, R. (this volume 2011). Positioning Theory: Moral
Dimensions of Social-Cultural Psychology. In J. Valsiner
References (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology.
Atkinson, J. M., & Heritage, J. (Eds.). (1984). Structures of Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
social action: Studies in conversation analysis. Cambridge, UK: Harré, R., & Gillet, G. (1994). The discursive mind. Thousand
Cambridge University Press. Oaks, CA: Sage.
Bakhtin, M. M. (1981). Discourse in the novel (M. Holquist & Harré, R., & Stearns, P. (1995). Discursive psychology in practice:
C. Emerson, Trans.). In M. Holquist (Ed.), The dialogic imagi- Sage Publications.
nation: Four essays (pp. 259–422). Austin, TX: University of Hester, S., & Eglin, P. (Eds.). (1997). Culture in action: Studies
Texas Press. in membership categorization analysis. Washington, DC:
Billig, M. (1997). Discursive, rhetorical and ideological Messages. International Institute for Ethnomethodological and
In C. H. McGarty, Alexander S. (Ed.), The message of social Conversation Analysis: University Press.
psychology: Perspectives on mind in society (pp. 37–53). Holland, D., & Cole, M. (1995). Between Discourse and
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. Schema: Reformulating a Cultural-Historical Approach to
Billig, M. (1999a). Conversation analysis and the claims of Culture and Mind. Anthropology & Education Quarterly,
naivety. Discourse & society, 10(4), 572–576. 26(4), 475–489.
Billig, M. (1999b). Whose terms? Whose ordinariness? Rhetoric Hook, D. (2001). Discourse, Knowledge, Materiality, History.
and ideology in Conversation Analysis. Discourse & Society, Theory & Psychology, 11(4), 521–547.
10(4), 543–558. Hook, D. (2005). Genealogy, discourse, ‘effective history’:
Billig, M., Condor, S., Edwards, D., Gane, M., Middleton, D. J., & Foucault and the work of critique. Qualitative Research in
Radley, A. R. (1988). Ideological dilemmas: A social psychology Psychology, 2(1), 3–31.
of everyday thinking. London: Sage Publications. Kim, E.-Y. (1993). Career Choice among Second-Generation
Brinkmann, S. (2006). Mental Life in the Space of Reasons. Korean-Americans: Reflections of a Cultural Model of Success.
Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 36(1), 1–16. Anthropology & Education Quarterly, 24(3), 224–248.
Brinkmann, S. (2009). A normative sociocultural psychology? Paper Linell, P., & Luckmann, T. (1991). Asymmetries in dia-
presented at the FUROR 1: Futures of Research – Advancing logue: Some conceptual preliminaries. In I. Markovà &
sociocultural psychology in Europe, The University of K. Foppa (Eds.), Asymmetries in dialogue (pp. 1–20). Hemel
Neuchâtel, Swizerland. Hempstead, U.K.: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Burman, E. (1996). Psychology discourse practice: From reg- Lomax, E. (1996). The Railway Man. London: The Vintage Books.
ulation to resistance. In E. Burman, G. Aitken, P. Alldred, Middleton, D., & Edwards, D. (Eds.). (1990). Collective remem-
R. Allwood, T. Billington & B. Goldberg (Eds.), Psychology bering. London: Sage.

m u ra ka m i 485
Moerman, M. (1973). Talking culture: Ethnography and conver- Sacks, H. (1989). Lecture Six: The M.I.R. Membership
sation analysis. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Categorization Device. Human Studies, 12, 271–281.
Press. Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation (edited by Gail
Moerman, M. (1974). Accomplishing ethnicity. In R. Turner Jefferson; introduction by Emanuel A. Schegloff). Oxford, UK:
(Ed.), Ethnomethodology: Selected readings (pp. 54–68). Blackwell.
Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin Education. Sato, T., & Valsiner, J. (2010). Time in life and life in time:
Murakami, K. (2001a). Revisiting the past: Social organisation Between experiencing and accounting. Ritsumeikan Journal
of remembering and reconciliation, Unpublished PhD thesis. of Human Sciences, 20(1), 79–92.
Loughborough, U.K.: Loughborough University. Schegloff, E. A. (1992). In another context. In A. Duranti &
Murakami, K. (2001b). Talk About Rice: A discursive approach to C. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language as an
studying culture. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung / Forum: interactive phenomenon (pp. 193–227). Cambridge, U.K.:
Qualitative Social Research [On-line Journal], 2(3), 48–59. Cambridge University Press.
Murakami, K. (2007). Positioning in Accounting for Redemption Schegloff, E. A. (1997). Whose text? Whose context? Discourse &
and Reconciliation. Culture & psychology, 13(4), 431–452. Society, 8(2), 165–187.
Murakami, K., & Middleton, D. (2006). Grave Matters: Schegloff, E. A. (1999). ‘Schegloff’s texts’ as ‘Billig’s data’: A criti-
collectivity and agency as emergent effects. Ethos, 34(2), cal reply. Discourse & Society, 10(4), 558–572.
273–296. Valsiner, J. (2009). Cultural Psychology Today: Innovations and
Nelson, K. (1981). Cognition in a script framework. In Oversights. Culture & Psychology, 15(5), 5–39.
J. H. Flavell & L. Ross (Eds.), Social cognitive development. van der Veer, R. (this volume 2011). Cultural-historical psychol-
Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. ogy. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Culture and
Nelson, K. (1986). Event knowledge: Structure and fucntion in Psychology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
development. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Wetherell, M. (1998). Positioning and interpretative repertoires:
Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1993). Rice as self: Japanese identities through conversation analysis and post-structuralism in dialogue.
time. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Discourse & Society, 9(3), 387–412.
Parker, I. (1997). Discourse analysis and psychoanalysis. British Wierzbicka, A. (1994). “Cultural Scripts”: A Semantic Approach
journal of social psychology, 36, 479–495. to Cultural Analysis and Cross-Cultural Communication.
Parker, I. (1999). Introduction: Varieties of Discourse and Analysis. In L. Bouton & Y. Kachru (Eds.), Pragmatics and Language
In I. Parker & Bolton Discourse Network (Eds.), Critical Learning (pp. 1–24). Urbana-Champaign, IL: University of
Textwork: An Introduction to Varieties of Discourse and Analysis Illinois.
(pp. 1–12). Buckingham, U.K.: Open University Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1968 [1958]). Philosophical investigations (The
Parker, I. (2002). Critical discursive psychology. Houndmills, English text of the third edition) (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.).
U.K.: Palgrave Macmillan. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Potter, J., & Wetherell, M. (1987). Discourse and social psychology: Wodak, R., & Meyer, M. (Eds.). (2009). Methods of critical dis-
beyond attitudes and behaviour. London: Sage Publications. course analysis (Second ed.). London: Sage.

486 c ulture in act i on


CHAPTER

Social Representations As
22 Anthropology of Culture

Ivana Marková

Abstract
The Theory of Social Representations studies formation and transformation of meanings, knowledge,
beliefs, and actions of complex social phenomena like democracy, human rights, or mental illness,
in and through communication and culture. This chapter examines the nature of interdependence
between social representing, communication, and culture. It first explains differences between mental,
collective, and social representations with respect to culture and language. It then focuses on two
meanings of social representing: first, on representations as a theory of social knowledge and second,
representations as social and cultural phenomena and as interventions in social practices. Rationality
of social representations is based on diverse modalities of knowing and believing shared by groups and
communities; it is derived from historically and culturally established common sense. This perspective
justifies the claim that social representations should be treated as anthropology of contemporary culture.
Finally, the chapter discusses main concepts linking social representations, language, and culture.
Keywords: two meanings of social representations; rationality of social representations; polyphasia
in knowing, believing and communicating; figures, metaphors and myths; communicative and cultural
themata.

In this chapter we explore interdependencies phenomena requires researchers’ and practitioners’


between social representing, language, communi- creativity in broadening and deepening the scope of
cation, and culture. In contrast to individual rep- their disciplines. This involves a scholarly interest in
resentations, social representations are dynamic the ways in which traditions and novel ideas enrich
phenomena that are embedded in culture and each other, in the ability to understand how the rel-
formed and transformed in and through language atively stable and new phenomena struggle for dom-
and communication. The researchers of social rep- inance and transform one another and how these
resenting aim to understand how citizens think, tensions and conflicts are reflected in thought and
feel about, and act on phenomena that are in the language. The Theory of Social Representations, we
center of societal, group, and individual interests shall argue here, provides researchers and practitio-
and discourses, be they political, health-related, ners with the means of coping with such challenges
environmental, or otherwise. Such phenomena and so ensures the credibility of social psychology as
pose significant challenges for social psychology a scientific discipline.
generally and social representing specifically. Their Because the concepts of “representation” and
understanding cannot be fitted within narrow “representing” are used in different fields of social
and static frameworks, which still dominate large sciences and psychology, the study of social repre-
parts of social sciences. Instead, the study of social senting must dispel confusions between social and

487
individual representations, the problem or ratio- influential book Reason and Culture, Gellner (1992)
nality and irrationality, and misunderstandings of claims that human reason is innate and universal
meanings of concepts linking social representing and that it exists independently of culture. On the
with cultural anthropology. Such issues also pose one hand, it can be argued that this idea expresses
challenges for social psychology as a social scientific an essential presupposition that all humans have the
discipline: Can we make it theoretically convincing same potential for rationality and for the develop-
and useful in practical interventions? ment of intelligence and so that it mitigates rac-
ism. Gellner insists that culture and common sense
Representation and Culture knowledge hinders this universal human potential:
During its long history in European scholarship, “reason is latent in us all,” but “most cultures fail to
the meaning of representation has undergone con- promote it” (Gellner, 1992, p. 53). On the other
siderable changes and diversification. Today, there hand, we shall see later, to ignore culture in the
are three main meanings of representation in human growth of human intelligence leads to a paradox:
and social sciences and in philosophy. They stem any human individual always belongs to one culture
from diverse epistemological traditions, address dif- or other, and it remains questionable what it could
ferent levels of analysis, and imply contrasting rela- possibly mean to claim that reason can be explored
tions with respect to culture and language. independently of culture or that culture fails to pro-
mote reason.
Mental Representation, Culture,
and Language Collective Representation, Culture,
The first meaning refers to mental representa- and Language
tions. It has been associated, at least since the sev- A different meaning of representation was held
enteenth century with philosophers René Descartes by the sociologist Emile Durkheim who, despite
and John Locke, with glorification of the cognition remaining philosophically within the framework
of the individual and with mirroring of the objec- of Descartes and Kant, dramatically altered the
tive reality. According to this tradition, the self ’s concept of representation. First, Durkheim (1898)
cognition is the only source of certain knowledge or sharply distinguished between individual and col-
representation of reality. lective representations. Individual representations
The concept of mental representation as a mir- are of physiological and neurological nature and do
ror of objective reality has nothing to do with cul- not have much to do with knowledge. In contrast,
ture. The proponents of this perspective attribute collective representations do not originate in single
any mistaken representations to the influence of minds but arise directly from social structures. They
other people and, indeed, of culture. As Descartes are generated in social life and in social groups,
(1637/1985) put it, true knowledge cannot be institutions, and cultures. For Durkheim, represent-
pursued by an “example and custom.” Whereas ing referred to various forms of thinking—whether
Descartes did not say much about language, the scientific, religious, social, or ideological—rather
philosopher John Locke (1690/1975) argued that than to specifically defined objects. Such meaning
the perfection of knowledge could be hindered was fully in agreement with the French use of the
or facilitated by incorrect or correct use of words. word representation in arts, literature, and daily dis-
Although views of these philosophers were highly course as well as in social sciences.
original in the context of philosophy and science of Collective representations are social facts, and
the seventeenth century, they have become a hin- as such, they form the basis of all understanding,
drance in social sciences of the twenty-first century. knowledge, and logic. Durkheim’s ambition was to
Their variations with respect to representations, develop the idea of collective representations as a
culture, and language still play a significant role in theory of sociological knowledge. Being social facts,
contemporary cognitive sciences and in philosophi- collective representations impose an irresistible
cal traditions based on foundational epistemology pressure on individuals who yield to their coercion,
(for criticism of foundational epistemology, see internalize them, and so perpetuate specific forms
Rorty, 1980; Taylor, 1995). Reflecting on views of thinking, feeling and acting. For something to
of foundational philosophy, the anthropologist be knowledge, it must be stable. Durkheim held
Gellner (1998, p. 3) characterizes them by saying: the position that representations change very slowly
“We discover truth alone, we err in groups.” In his during the historical journey of mankind from

488 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


religion to science and from less to more adequate in various social, political, health-related, and other
representations. kinds of phenomena preoccupying the minds and
In Durkheim’s time, social and cultural phenom- discourses of general public (for a comprehensive
ena were understood as intertwined and Durkheim’s review, see Wagner & Hayes, 2005).
concept of collective representations formed an
interface between culture and society; he used the The Dynamic Nature of Social
term social both for social and cultural systems. Representing
Representations included religion, normative con- Moscovici’s social representations, in contrast to
straints of society, moral orders, social solidarity, Durkheim’s collective representations, are dynamic:
as well as systems of beliefs and knowledge. Being they arise and are maintained and transformed
social facts, collective representations are external to through interaction and different forms of commu-
individuals who acquire them through internaliza- nication between the established social structures—
tion. Language, too, is a social fact. It circulates in for example, traditions, on the one hand, and the
society, forms the individual’s social environment, individuals’ and groups’ mental and social activities
and imposes itself on the individual. When the indi- and social practices on the other. From the incep-
vidual acquires language, he/she adopts the whole tion of the theory, language and communication
system of social thoughts, their classifications, and have been vital features of representing, and this is
evaluations. Words fix ideas and transmit them already expressed in La Psychanalyse. As Moscovici
from generation to generation. Therefore, language explains, a representation is always directed at oth-
is a social thing (Durkheim, 1912/2001; Marková, ers: it speaks through pointing something to some-
2003/2005). one; it communicates through mediating meanings
and symbols to someone. Representing and com-
Social Representations, Culture, municating is jointly generated by human sub-
and Language jects and groups that have different histories and
Having considered relations between mental and experience. Their interaction does not follow the
collective representations with respect to culture Durkheimian path of the progress from less ade-
and language, in the rest of this chapter we turn to quate (e.g., religious representations) to more ade-
social representations. quate (e.g., scientific representations). Arising in
Building on the ideas of Durkheim and Piaget, traditions, social experience, and communication,
Serge Moscovici has proposed an original Theory social representations are discontinuous; emotions,
of Social Representations and developed it, both contents of beliefs, and images are sensitive to socio-
conceptually and empirically, in La Psychanalyse: cultural changes and to tensions and preferences of
Son Image et Son Public (Moscovici, 1961/76). This the Zeitgeist.
book was published in English as Psychoanalysis: Its In contrast to collective representations that refer
Image and Its Public (2008). This classic explores to various ideas and forms of thinking, social repre-
transformations of professional and scientific knowl- sentations refer to specific objects or specific social
edge of psychoanalysis into everyday thinking and phenomena. For example, the way citizens think,
discourse of various social groups, and the mass feel, and act (or represent) democracy depends on
media reporting, in a specific socio-political culture their historical and cultural experience as well as on
in the late 1950s in France. But we need to make a their knowledge of, beliefs, and images about con-
general point: it would be a mistake to understand temporary socio-political circumstances as well as of
the transformation of professional and scientific their expectations of the future. What is important
knowledge into everyday thinking as a naïve form to emphasize, however, is that it is not the object
of thinking and developing simplified lay theories. that is social. On the contrary, social representations
Instead, these transformations into common sense arise from the fact that objects or phenomena are
thinking and knowledge are accomplished and socially shared (Moscovici, 1988; Wagner, 1998;
enriched through different means of communica- Wagner et al., 1999).
tion and images; they involve arguments based on Unlike Durkheim’s time, contemporary mean-
trust and distrust of others, collective memories, ings of the notions “social” and “cultural” are not
conscious and unconscious beliefs, myths and meta- synonyms, although the boundaries between them
phors, fears and hopes. Following the publication of are not always clear. The notion social ranges from
La Psychanalyse, social representing has been studied usages in social sciences and their subdisciplines (e.g.,

m a rková 489
economics, sociology, social psychology, politics, etc.) Duveen, 2002; Marková, 2003/2003). First, the
to professional fields like social security, health ser- Theory of Social Representations is a theory of
vices, social work and social practices, among many social knowledge. As such, it establishes networks
others. Numerous attempts and failures to define of concepts and figurative schemes that are gen-
culture as an entity point to inherent difficulties erated in and through tradition, common sense,
of this notion, and these difficulties also transpose daily knowledge, and communication and that are
themselves with respect to their relations to social shared by particular groups and communities. The
representations (Duveen, 2007). These problems theory of social knowledge enables the researcher to
are raised by Jodelet (2002) in her article, “Social define research problems. Second, social representa-
Representations in the Field of Culture.” The author tions or social representing refers to concrete social
draws attention to the changing relations between phenomena and to forms of apprehending and cre-
psychology, anthropology, and culture in the course ating social realities in and through communica-
of the last two centuries, arising both from diversifi- tion, experience, social practices, and interventions
cations within human and social sciences and from (Jodelet, 2006a; in press) and semiotic mediation
the more recent cognitive revolution, among other (Valsiner, 2003). This also enables the researcher
factors (see also Valsiner, 2003). to understand problems posed by the theory and
During the five decades after the publication to attempt their answers. Let us consider these two
of La Psychanalyse, the explorations of social rep- meanings in some detail.
resentations have become widely differentiated. A
large volume of research has been carried out in Social Representations As a Theory
different social and cultural conditions. Individual of Social Knowledge
researchers have subscribed to divergent underlying There is a fundamental difference between what
epistemologies, and numerous studies have been is considered by knowledge in cognitive sciences
performed on different topics, contents, and struc- and in the Theory of Social Representations. In
tures. As a result, some researchers (e.g., Wagner the former, building blocks of epistemologies are
et al., 1999; Wagner & Hayes, 2005; Palmonari & knowledge and justified beliefs arising from the
Emiliani, 2009) speak about social representational cognition of the individual. In parallel with this, in
approaches—or schools of social representations— social sciences, epistemologies are often considered
rather than about a single theory. For example, as paths from beliefs to knowledge, implying a grad-
these authors refer to the Aix-en-Provence school ual progress in intellectual development (for a his-
based on structuralistic approach that emphasizes torical account of these ideas since ancient times, see
central nucleus and periphery of representations Lovejoy, 1936). Such was the position, for example,
(e.g., Abric, 1994a, 2001; Flament, 1994a, 1994b; of Jean Piaget whose epistemology focused on trans-
Guimelli, 1994), whereas the Genevean school of formations of less adequate patterns of thought to
Doise specifies organizing principles of social repre- more adequate ones. In his studies of moral devel-
sentations (Doise, 1985, 1986). Jodelet’s approach opment, Piaget (1932) conceptualized this path as a
is anthropological and cultural (e.g., Jodelet, gradual transformation of beliefs into knowledge or
1989/1991, 2002, 2006a, 2008); Wagner, Duveen, as a transformation of the morality of constraint to
and their collaborators (Wagner et al., 1999, 2000; the morality of cooperation. Asymmetric relations—
Duveen, 2007) bring to attention the role of social say, between a child and an adult—imply constraint
construction and discourse; and Valsiner draws on and, therefore, only the possibility of belief or com-
the role of semiotic mediation and social experience pliance resulting from the authority of the source.
(e.g., Valsiner, 2003). In addition, one can hardly In contrast, symmetric relations in terms of social
discuss social representations and culture without status and influence between individuals allow for
foregrounding language, communication, and, co-operation and, therefore, for the mutual con-
more specifically, dialogicality as a major feature of struction of knowledge (Duveen, 2002). As we have
the relation between social representations and cul- already seen, Durkheim’s ideas concerning the trans-
ture (Marková, 2003/2005; Valsiner, 2003). formation of less adequate to more adequate collec-
Within these diversities in focus, we can nev- tive representations throughout human history take
ertheless distinguish between two fundamental a similar path. The Piagetian and Durkheimian way
meanings of the concept of social representations of progress in the intellectual development relies on
that underlie all approaches (Jodelet, 1989/1991; classical—that is, the Kantian form of—rationality.

490 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


This means that the action of reason and of intel- Ego–Object, in which the Ego is taxonomically
lect excludes partly or totally those actions based on undifferentiated, by the triad Ego–Alter–Object.
motives, desires, or emotions—that is, on irrational Once we introduce the Ego–Alter, we are imme-
activities (Kant, 1788/1873). The Piagetian rational- diately in the realm of language, communication,
ity (1970), like the Kantian rationality, is universal. and culture. The Ego–Alter are not undifferen-
All children pass through the stages of operational tiated and undetermined subjects; they interact,
development, and through these stages they acquire, communicate, and speak. As it is already clear in
step by step, higher forms of intelligence. La Psychanalyse, representing takes place in com-
Although informed and inspired by Durkheim munication. If knowledge is generated neither
and Piaget, Moscovici takes a different route: by the Ego nor by the Alter alone, but jointly
by the Ego–Alter, then the minimum unit in the
The proper domain of our discipline is the study
formation of knowledge cannot be expressed as
of cultural processes which are responsible for the
a relation between the Ego–Object but as a tri-
organization of knowledge in a society . . . In parallel
adic relation, the Ego–Alter–Object (Moscovici,
more attention should be paid to language which has
1970, 1972/2000, 1984; Bauer & Gaskell, 1999;
not until now been thought of as an area of study
Marková, 2003/2005; Jesuino, 2009). But who is
closely related to social psychology.
it that stands behind these abstract notions, the
(Moscovici, 1972/2000, pp. 55–56)
“Ego” and the “Alter?” Although in this general-
But how can one link, epistemologically, cul- ized model the “Ego–Alter” could mean an inter-
ture, language, and knowledge, in and through action between any kind of the self and other(s), in
social representations? concrete and contextualized dialogical situations,
there is always the specific Ego and the specific Alter
From Taxonomic Psychology of the Ego-Object to (or the self–other[s])—for example, “I–you,” “minor-
Representing Through the Ego–Alter–Object ity–majority,” “I–group,” “group–another group,”
Moscovici’s (1970, 1972/2000) analysis and crit- “I–culture,” and so on. Indeed, these specific Ego
icism of what he called a “taxonomic” social psy- and Alter are embedded in other dyadic Ego–Alter
chology is instructive. It will lead us to overcoming interactions. For example, a mother–child interac-
problems of taxonomic psychology and to under- tion (Ego–Alter) takes place in a specific culture; this
standing the fundamentally important link between means that we can conceptualize this mother–child
culture, language and knowledge. The study of the dyad as the Ego within a particular culture (Alter),
relation between the Ego and the Object in social or that this same dyad can be conceived as the Ego
psychology refers to no more than classification—or within a specific social group (Alter), and so on. Or
taxonomies—of stimuli or variables. For example, a conversation between two individuals is not just
in taxonomic social psychology that is undertaken an exchange of words between I and you that takes
in numerous laboratory experiments, the Ego is place in a specific here-and-now, but it has its past,
treated (or classified) as undifferentiated and unde- present, and future. Moreover, parents, leaders of
fined; it is a subject without culture. The aim of political groups, friends, the “generalized other,” and
such experiments is to discover how social stimuli so forth, speak through the mouth of each conver-
affect classes of variables like perception, attitudes, sational partner. All these social and language-based
judgment, and so on. But humans live in societies interdependencies make the dyadic relations between
and are differentiated from one another in many the Ego–Alter dynamic, with implicit and explicit
ways; they live in cultures and they communicate. meanings affecting their discourses and contributing
Therefore, “others” are not “other subjects” with to transformation of representations in all dialogical
whom humans compare themselves—for example, participants. They all contribute to different dialogi-
as in Festinger’s (1954) social comparison theory— cal perspectives and create tensions among them.
in order to reduce uncertainty with respect to what Language and communication as a point of
is right and wrong, or good or bad; neither are they departure in epistemology of social representations
subjects whose presence facilitates the Ego’s activ- has yet another implication: to communicate means
ities, as in Zajonc’s (1965) social facilitation the- to take diverse routes, leading once to intersubjec-
ory. Instead, the Ego and the Alter communicate tive understanding between individuals or between
and jointly generate knowledge and social repre- groups or cultures, once to conflict; to negotia-
sentations. Therefore, we must substitute the dyad tion, to compromise, or to a firm self-positioning.

m a rková 491
Therefore, communication does not necessarily always judgmental, evaluative, and orientated to
lead to a better understanding and “true knowl- creating new meanings.
edge.” In contrast to the ascent theory of knowl- Bakhtin expressed this idea pertinently in his
edge toward science and true knowledge that was analysis of Dostoyevsky’s novels. Consciousness
adopted by Durkheim and Piaget, the Theory of must be in interaction with another consciousness
Social Representations does not presuppose pro- to achieve its proper existence: “justification can-
gress toward higher forms of knowledge or toward not be self-justification, recognition cannot be self-
more adequate representations. Instead, it presup- recognition. I receive my name from others, and
poses transformation of one kind of knowledge into it exists for others (self-nomination is imposture)”
another one; transformation of different kinds of (Bakhtin, 1984, pp. 287–288).
knowledge is pertinent to specific socio-historical
and cultural conditions. This is why the triangu- Social Representations As Phenomena
larity of the Ego–Alter–Object forms the basis of and As Interventions
linking language and communication, culture, and The second meaning of social representations
social representation. refers to the ways in which humans apprehend,
interact with, and create their social reality. As
The Dialogicality of the Ego–Alter they attempt to orientate themselves and create
in Mikhail Bakhtin meanings of events in their lives, humans form
We can arrive at the triangularity of the Ego– representations of complex social phenomena that
Alter–Object from a different theoretical perspec- are in the center of social life and social disputes,
tive, like the dialogicality of the Ego–Alter in whether they are political, ecological, or health-
Voloshinov’s (1929/1973) and Bakhtin’s (1981) or community-related. Resources for generating
approaches to language and communication. For social representations are phenomena that dis-
these scholars of the early part of the twentieth rupt routines, turn them upside down, and call
century, alike, social knowledge and social reality for action. Specifically, firm or irresistible beliefs
is jointly created by the Ego–Alter. In Voloshinov’s (see below) concerning, say, democracy, manage-
and Bakhtin’s work, too, the Ego and Alter dialogi- ment of banks, social responsibility, mental ill-
cally co-constitute one another in a dynamic figure- ness, distrust, freedom of speech, and so forth, are
ground set-up. I am using the term dialogicality to sources of action, and they instigate social change.
characterize the fundamental capacity of the Ego Complex phenomena obtain their specific and
to conceive, create, and communicate about social multileveled meanings in interdependence with
realities in terms of the Alter. What the human indi- culture and in relation to other representations
vidual has become through the work of the past, within that culture and community. For example,
and what his/her prospects are for the future, results the representation of freedom of speech would be
from dialogicality (Marková, 2003/2005). related to other social representations and actions
To my mind, these two epistemological within that particular culture, like political protests
approaches, the one stemming from Moscovici and against terrorism, expressions of abuse of the dom-
the other arising from Bakhtin (1981, 1979/1986), inant political Party, censorship of any dissent, of
enrich one another and provide potential, in the the media, and the like. Thus, freedom of speech
Theory of Social Representations, for a more would have different meanings in relation to dif-
focused study of relations between knowing, believ- ferent semiotic networks and social phenomena.
ing, language, and speech. In both epistemologies, Two points should be mentioned as fundamental
the Ego and the Alter transform one another’s rep- with respect to culture: social representations are
resentations in and through dialogical and sym- phenomena in the making and representing can
bolic interactions. The concept of transformation take part of action and intervention.
in both approaches is characterized by tension and
by multifaceted and heterogeneous relationships Social Representations Are Phenomena
between the Ego and Alter. There can be no sin- in the Making
gle mind without other minds: they dialogically In emphasizing relationships between social
co-constitute one another. Neither for Bakhtin nor representations and communication, Moscovici
for Moscovici can dialogue be neutral. Neutrality (Moscovici & Marková, 1998, pp. 393–394) draws
can be only artificially imposed but daily speech is attention to viewing them “in the making, not as

492 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


already made.” This characteristic is essential both become a kind of dead psychology” (Moscovici &
historically and developmentally. Social repre- Marková, 1998, p. 394).
sentations are not quiet things (Howarth, 2006); Thus we arrive at an important feature of rep-
being phenomena in the making, social represen- resentations as phenomena in the making: Social
tations are formed and transformed in and through representations are structured semiotic media-
asymmetries, conflict, discontinuities, and tension. tors that are constantly in the process of innova-
Representing, like communication, requires commit- tion, created in and through conflict and tension
ment. For example, one cannot study influence and (Valsiner, 2003). In experiencing tension, humans
innovation processes between majorities and minori- attempt to construct a predictable world out of
ties by removing tension and engagement: “Whether great diversity and regulate their conduct. Referring
in conversation or in influence processes, one deals to Moscovici’s back-and-forth movement between
with change, with negotiation between two oppos- experiencing and representing Valsiner (2003,
ing partners—one cannot exist without the other” p. 73) concludes: “representing is needed for expe-
(Moscovici & Marková, 1998, p. 394). riencing, while experiencing leads to new forms of
Interdependencies between communication representing.”
and different social groups can be illustrated by
Duveen’s analysis of communication systems in Representing As Action and
Moscovici’s (1961/1976) La Psychanalyse: Son Image Intervention
et Son Public. Specifically, Duveen (2008) analyzes Another feature of representing, Valsiner (2003)
Moscovici’s thoughts about social groups in relation maintains, is its implication for action and social
to different communicative systems through con- change, or its function as intervention. Jodelet
tent analysis of the French press. Focusing on dif- (in press) characterizes intervention as a practice
ferent types of social groups in relation to the three involved in an “explicit and intentional project of
genres of communication—that is, diffusion, propa- a deliberate act of change.” Intervention encour-
gation, and propaganda—Duveen identifies specific ages transformation of knowledge and behavior
forms of affiliation corresponding to each commu- of individuals and groups toward better standards
nicative genre and consequently also to different of living. Jodelet specifies three forms of activities
representations of the members of the in-group and interconnecting social representations and interven-
the out-group in each instance. He characterizes dif- tion: first, social representations can modify think-
fusion as the voluntary association of the members ing of individuals or groups about a practical issue;
of in-group who possess a skeptical intelligence, second, they can transform practices, and these, in
whereas the out-group embraces forms of dogma- turn, can lead to transformation of representations;
tism. Duveen describes this kind of group in terms and finally, intervention of social representations
of sympathy. Propagation, on the other hand, refers is intentionally directed at producing changes in
to groups in which a central authority sets limits activities of individuals and groups concerned.
to creativity or intellectual curiosity. The out-group The relation between intervention practices and
does not share the belief in the legitimacy of such social representations is itself an object of research
authority or the relevant ideology. Duveen calls this practice (Abric, 1994b), in particular in health
kind of group a communion. Finally, propaganda research (Jodelet, 2006a; Jovchelovitch & Gervais,
is used by groups whose political commitment and 1999; Morin, 2004) or in education (Garnier
organization defines the way of conduct of in-group. & Rouquette, 2000). For example, intervention
In contrast, the out-group is either committed to a should allow for exchanges between traditional and
different kind of ideology or simply does not share new forms of knowledge (Quintanilla, Herrera, &
the ideology of the in-group. Duveen characterizes Veloz, 2005), the preservation of culture, and its
such group in terms of solidarity. His analysis shows negotiation with emerging alternatives in society
that commitment to a particular kind of ideology (Jodelet, 2006b). Doise (2002) regards social rep-
elicits a particular kind of communicative genre. It resentations of human rights as interventions into
illustrates that communicative genres of groups are social relations, whether these concern relations
part of their particular cultures and that, therefore, between individuals and groups, or individuals and
representing, like communication, is never a neutral institutions. Human rights must be clearly defined
exchange of information. Moreover, if we attempted precisely because they are interventions of one kind
to remove tension from communication, “it would or other.

m a rková 493
Culture and Social Representations There is yet another implication of the concept
Are Relational Phenomena of structured field. Just like when speakers com-
Referring to two ways of studying social rep- municate, they select different ways of expression
resentations (which basically correspond to the with respect to one another depending on their
two main meanings as discussed in this section), relations, status, experience, and otherwise, so when
Jodelet (1989/91) emphasizes that when we focus they represent a phenomenon they are in an inti-
on positions held by individuals and groups with mate complementary relation with culture. In other
respect to objects, representations are treated as words, it is not the case that the same culture would
structured fields. By “structured fields,” she means be in relation with a set of different social represen-
relations between contents contributed by sub- tations. Such a position would be something like
jects (or the Ego and Alter) and principles that Piaget’s mountain seen from different perspectives.
organize contents, like cultural schemata, norms, In this case, the mountain remains the same, but
and so forth. This perspective draws attention, the child’s position is different and through the
again, to the relation between social represen- growth of intellectual development, the child learns
tations and culture. I suggest that this does not to understand this. In contrast, the relation between
mean to consider a social representation on the social representation and culture is unique. Each
one hand, and culture as its context on the other social with culture in a specific manner; it selects
hand, and to ask how they are related. Equally, it different aspects of that culture because not all
would be wrong to consider culture as a container aspects are relevant in the same way for each social
within which one can identify a set of specific representation. Consequently, the forces of interac-
social representations. tion between them imply that for each representa-
Jodelet’s concept of a structured field, I sug- tion we have a slightly different meaning of culture.
gest, can be viewed as something like the concept If we return to communication between groups and
of an electromagnetic field in physics of relativity. their communicative genres, propaganda and prop-
Electromagnetic field is a totality of forces that agation view different aspects of culture. The former
exists “between the two charges and not the charges places emphasis on authoritarian aspects of the cul-
themselves, which is essential for an understanding ture, whereas the latter focuses on more democratic
of their action” (Einstein & Infeld, 1938/1961, features.
p. 151). Thus “force between particles,” rather We need to view forces as both constraining
than “behavior of single entities” defines the field. and stimulating. In Moscovici’s words, “society is
Equally, we cannot understand the specificity of an institution which inhibits what it stimulates. It
the Theory of Social Representations without tak- both tempers and excites . . . increases or reduces the
ing on the concept of the force of interaction that chances . . . and invents prohibitions together with
binds elements to one another as complements, the means of transgressing them” (Moscovici 1976,
rather than as behavior of single entities (indi- p. 149).
viduals, groups) that come to interact with one
another. Taking Jodelet’s concept of the structured Social Representations As Anthropology
field, individuals and groups are not undifferen- of Contemporary Culture: The Case of
tiated subjects as in the taxonomic psychology Rationality
(see above), but their meanings are defined in and Throughout his career, Serge Moscovici (e.g.,
through concrete society or culture. Their inter- 1987, 1993a, 1988/93; Moscovici & Marková, 1998,
nal interaction (in contrast to external interac- 2006) has persistently insisted that the Theory of
tion; e.g., in the analysis of variance) constitutes Social Representations is—or should be treated—as
a new reality: the interacting components define anthropology of contemporary culture. Cultural
one another as complements, whether this involves anthropologists are concerned with the totality of
institutions vis-à-vis environment, institutions vis- life of social groups under study—that is, with beliefs
à-vis groups, one group vis-à-vis another group, or and knowledge, myths, images, as well as with social
social representation vis-à-vis culture (see above, practices in daily living. To understand these phe-
the Ego–Alter). Like an electromagnetic field, nomena, anthropologists study them in relation to
the structured field of social representations is one another, like meaningful wholes, rather than as
dynamic. It is open to participants’ new experi- independent elements that, if need be, could either
ences and to social change. be joined together or disjoined. In the previous

494 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


section, I touched several times on the problem of irrational beliefs. Rationality as opposed to relativ-
rationality, culture, and social representations. This ism even forms titles of classic volumes like those by
issue is significant in contemporary social sciences, Wilson (1970; Rationality) and by Hollis and Lukes
and it raises specific questions in relation to social (1982; Rationality and Relativism). The contribu-
representing; therefore, in this section, I turn atten- tors to the latter volume suggest that the problem of
tion to this issue in some detail. understanding relativism and irrational beliefs arises
from the fact that different cultures, languages, and
Rationality and Irrationality in the minds of others can be understood only within
Social Sciences their own idiosyncratic socio-historical situations,
Whatever we can say about rationality and irra- rather than universally. Can we, therefore, identify
tionality of, and within, social sciences, it is nec- anything transcultural among humans? Does cul-
essary to place this issue in the context of natural ture challenge “the very idea of a single world” (ibid,
sciences. Since the end of the seventeenth century, p. 1)? The dichotomy between the presupposition
natural sciences have been based on “knowledge of universal rationality and questions concerning
which eliminates mystery. In contrast to Greek sci- the sources of irrational beliefs as well as their rich
ence it does not end in wonder but in expansion of and extensive presence in different cultures have led
wonder,” as says Michael Foster (1957, p. 53) in his to the search for different forms of relativism. For
treatise of “Myth and Philosophy.” Since the seven- example, researchers have been concerned with weak
teenth century, natural sciences have prided them- and strong forms of relativism, types of representa-
selves on being rational disciplines. tional beliefs (convictions, persuasion, opinions),
In contrast, social sciences started their scien- and different kinds of translation, interpretation,
tific career as irrational disciplines. As Moscovici and explanation of beliefs.
(1988/1993) reminds, they originated in the study Yet such questions can hardly be settled by aca-
of phenomena like nationalism, religion, myth, and demic discourses about rationality and relativism.
beliefs. For example, Weber and Durkheim com- Cultures are no longer isolated in their geographi-
menced from religion, Simmel from the relativity cal ghettos. Therefore, Harris (2009) argues that it
of values, and Marx from a kind of the Hegelian would be less misleading to abandon the notion of a
concept of historical forces. Vico, Herder, Hamann, singular rationality and speak, instead, about ratio-
and Humboldt were developing ideas of relativism nalities in the pluralistic sense. The contemporary
and cultures. Other social scientists, like Le Bon, world of societies is opened to other cultures and
Ortega y Gasset, or McDougall, preoccupied them- it set the stage for permanent situations of uncer-
selves with the study of collectives and crowds in tainty moving cultures in different directions. In
which rational individuals turned themselves into this situation, reason is not a private domain of
irrational beings. the individual but it must be negotiated (Rosa &
Since the nineteenth century, the ideas of rela- Valsiner, 2007, p. 697). A narrow rationality of the
tivity, variability, and the evolution of species have individual defined in formal terms cannot meet the
been drawing attention to the importance of per- world of ambiguities of the contemporary world,
spective-taking in the growth of knowledge. Yet and it transcends not only individual reason but
perspective-taking has influenced natural sciences also a particular cultural reason. In these circum-
and social sciences differently. Natural sciences, stances, judgments of what is right and wrong and
despite the influence of theories of evolution and what is and is not ethical guide any kinds of prefer-
relativity, defined these scientific discoveries in ences, control the individual and social choices, and
rationalistic manner and so remained rational dis- confront different reasons for choosing something
ciplines; in social sciences, however, we can observe rather than something else. In these confrontations,
a split between rationalistic and less rationalistic (or “Reason then turns into Rationality” (ibid, p. 697),
non-rationalistic) approaches. giving rise to Ethics and to Objectivity that emerges
In social sciences—specifically in anthropol- in and through transformations of rules and new
ogy and social psychology—the meaning of ratio- norms. As Rosa and Valsiner (ibid, p. 698) argue,
nality has become a subject of keen interest. This “Rationality, Ethics and Objectivity” (all with capi-
has led to the search for universals that apply to all tal letters) cannot be disentangled from one another.
humans and to all cultures. Consequently, this has It is in this sense that we shall view rationality and
raised questions about the sources of relativism and social representations.

m a rková 495
Reason and Cultures Three Paradoxes of the Individual
The interdependence between culture, rational- and Collective Mentality
ity, and social representations is perhaps most clearly Moscovici (1993a) identifies three historically
expressed in Moscovici’s (1993a) lecture on Razón y established paradoxes with respect to individual
Culturas (Reason and Cultures). One could say that and collective mentality; both Durkheim and Lévy-
the red thread through this lecture is an ethical con- Bruhl struggled against them in their particular
cern of culture and social representations. Moscovici ways. Therefore, Theory of Social Representations,
notes that the Cartesian approach discarding exam- to fulfill its role as anthropology of contemporary
ple and custom has also led to discarding culture, culture, needs to address these paradoxes.
whether religious or profane, and substituted it by The first paradox concerns individual rationality
a narrow concept of rationality. However, to ratio- and collective irrationality. As we saw at the begin-
nalize in this narrow way, Moscovici argues, means ning of this chapter, for Descartes and Locke, only the
to ignore moral and ethical values of traditions in individual was rational whereas culture and language
human histories and cultures as well as their sym- were sources of error. Yet no individual starts think-
bolic values. He raises the question as to whether ing and talking from nothing like the biblical Adam;
this narrow approach means that social psychology each individual lives in a culture and in language.
has nothing to say about arts or literature or whether Durkheim acknowledged this paradox, and there-
this means that humans are satisfied with perceiving fore, for him, all representations were rational beliefs;
others, making judgments about objects, or looking however, as mankind progressed from religion to sci-
for motivations of their conduct. Moscovici notes ence, some became closer to true knowledge than
that humans have deep experiences in and through others. Collective representations are socially true, as
living in their cultures; they read novels, appreciate Durkheim (1912/2001) states in “The Elementary
arts, listen to music, and experiment with ethical and Forms of Religious Life.” They are founded in the
moral values. These issues that have been neglected nature of things and they hold to and express reality.
by social psychology are brought back to life by the Religions, too, express reality, and therefore, all are
Theory of Social Representations. Moscovici draws true in their own fashion: there are no religions that
on three fundamental concepts: social representa- are false. All religions respond, although in different
tions, anthropology, and culture. ways, to the given conditions of human existence,
The lecture on Razón y culturas was written and this is why for Durkheim a collective representa-
at a time when it became clear that the cognitive tion is a rational belief. In contrast, and as Moscovici
revolution failed to cope with complex human and (1998a, p. 134) analyzes this question, Lévy-Bruhl
social phenomena. In the late years of the twenti- showed that members of different cultures did not
eth century, cultural psychology gained importance view rationality of social representations in the same
because it was thought that it would solve questions way. He has studied throughout his life the ways of
of economic, educational, and political psychology thinking of primitive cultures and tried to under-
as well as of child development and transformations stand why it was not possible to explain one form of
of mental faculties in adulthood, migration, and thought by another one.
nationalism, among others. Cultural psychology The second paradox to which Moscovici refers
was seen as a plausible alternative to individualis- concerns the presupposition of “the mental unity of
tic and mechanistic approaches (e.g., Bruner, 1985; mankind” that contradicts with the observation that
Jodelet, 2002; Valsiner, 1987; 1989, 1998; Valsiner local cultures are very diverse. This paradox leads to
& Lawrence, 1996) in focusing on intentionality, the question as to whether it is possible to find any
indigenous psychologies, language and commu- commonalities within these diversities. It is this ques-
nication, and on semiotic and symbolic practices. tion that is being vehemently discussed by social sci-
But, Moscovici points out that even if cognitive entists and particularly by social psychologists and
revolution were to succeed, these phenomena could anthropologists, as we indicated above.
be understood only with reference to culture. But The difficulty of resolving this paradox might
instead, as we have seen in the previous section, be magnified by ancient beliefs that were clearly
contemporary social psychology and anthropology expressed in Darwin’s assumption that all species
are still disputing problems of rationality and the could be placed on an upward continuum and that
relation between universality and cultural relativ- humans differed from animals in degree but not
ism. These problems are not new. in kind (Lovejoy, 1936; Ingold, 2004). As Ingold

496 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


explains, for Darwin, “the evolution of species in or explicit ethnocentric beliefs. These beliefs, on the
nature was also an evolution out of it” (Ingold, 2004, one hand, are based on assumptions of superior-
p. 210, his emphasis) as the mind progressively lib- ity of the own group, and at the same time, groups
erated itself “from promptings of innate disposi- propagate multiculturalism.
tion.” This means that ancestors of humans became How does the Theory of Social Representations
humans gradually, in stages, rising from primitive respond to these three paradoxes? The first paradox,
savages to humans, developing (in degrees) reason arising from treating the individual and group as
and language. But at what point does an animal independent entities is being resolved by treating the
become a human? Ego–Alter as interdependent. The second paradox,
arising from the narrow treatment of rationality, is
If no organic being excepting man had possessed any
substituted by fiduciary rationality (see below). The
mental power, or if his powers had been of a wholly
third paradox can be surmounted by the reflection
different nature from those of the lower animals, then
of the group on the existing incommunicability and
we should never have been able to convince ourselves
attempting to improve communication. Yet over-
that our high faculties had been gradually developed.
coming this paradox remains one of the challenges
But it can be shown that there is no fundamental
for social representing. In conclusion, all paradoxes
difference of this kind . . . yet this interval is filled up
arise from the difficulty to overcome the traditional
by numberless gradations . . . Differences of this kind
epistemology based on reasoning capacities of the
between the highest men of the highest races and the
individual, the narrow concept of rationality, and
lowest savages, are connected by the finest gradations.
the treatment of groups as independent categories.
(Darwin, 1859/1874, p. 157)

Darwin stated that in The Origin of Species he aimed Fiduciary Rationality


to show this continuous development of species Interdependence between the social representa-
toward perfection (compare this with Durkheim’s tion and culture of a group also makes the com-
and Piaget’s ideas toward progress). Thus the idea munication within a group preeminent above the
of gradual perfection might have led to an implicit communication with outsiders. I suggest that to
assumption that cultures could be at different stages understand the nature of this preeminence, we need
of their development, and it seems that this assump- to return to the epistemic question of rationality in
tion is implicit in the ideas of rationalists and rela- the triad Ego–Alter–Object. The Ego–Alter dialogi-
tivists that we discussed above. cal relation within a group comes from the ethics of
The third paradox concerns the difficulty of inter- common sense pertaining to social representations
group or intercultural communication. Moscovici of that group. Social representations captured by
notes that groups or cultures in general believe that common sense within a group, Moscovici argues,
others understand their point of view but, in fact,
are analogous to paradigms, which, contrary to
others are not always capable of understanding oth-
scientific paradigms, are made partly of beliefs
ers. Groups are often closed to the perspective of
based on trust and partly of elements of knowledge
other groups, and communication between groups
based on truth. In as much as they contain
is absent even if groups occupy the same pub-
beliefs, validating them appears a long, uncertain
lic space. This incommunicability affirms mutual
process, since they can be neither confirmed nor
incompatibility between different social represen-
disconfirmed.
tations and diverse forms of communication, and
(Moscovici & Marková, 2000, p. 253)
it characterizes our present society, which consists
of numerous groups with noticeable antagonistic Within the epistemological triad of Ego–Alter–
representations. For example, Europeans can hardly Object, relations between these components can
understand exotic beliefs of primitive assumptions. take on different forms and strengths. For example,
Moscovici maintains that a question like, “What if the Ego searches for knowledge of this or that, he/
objects constitute the world around us?” cannot be she might pursue the route of own discovery and
answered otherwise than by specifying the frame- autonomous thought, focusing, within this trian-
work of a particular representation to which it is gularity, more strongly on the Object than on the
pertinent. Loyalty to certain values makes groups Alter. In this case, the Ego would examine, in a step-
insensitive to values of others (Geertz, 2000, p. 70). by-step strategy, dispassionately and systematically,
The third paradox results in incompatible implicit the object of knowledge. Dispassionate knowledge

m a rková 497
can be expanded by new learning, or it can be sus- that arise from within, from trust and loyalty, rather
pended, resisted, or ignored. Moscovici (1993b) than from an outside pressure. Fiduciary rationality
calls such kinds of knowledge (or beliefs) resistible. functions like irresistible beliefs. It is rooted within
For example, if the knower does not care about the group and it binds groups together. Rationality
certain facts like “The Earth is not flat,” or “AIDS is of the common sense, too, is based on fiduciary
caused by a virus,” then he or she might ignore, not rationality.
think about, or suspend such facts and substitute We need to view social representations of vari-
them by others that appear more convincing. In a ous dependencies within a group—for example,
way, in such cases we can say that we possess beliefs rules and norms of acting and constraints of group
just like other kinds of possession; if we do not need members and solidarity and sympathy as established
them any longer, then we can dispose of them. in and through tradition, history, and culture. They
Another kind of relation within the triangular- are present already in informal organizations that
ity of the Ego–Alter–Object could be based on a develop from within the group, before any more
strong relation between the Ego and Alter, whereas formal organization is formed. Similarly, commu-
the relation between the Ego and Object would be nication is based on an inner contract among the
treated as secondary. In this case, knowledge/beliefs in-group members. A contract is an ethical require-
can range from those that Moscovici calls irresistible ment for communication (Rommetveit, 1974), and
to those that would function as constraints—be it we can say with Mikhail Bakhtin that there is no
compliance, conformity, or obeisance. Let us con- alibi for communication.
sider the latter, irresistible beliefs. Such beliefs can
hardly be changed through evidence to their con- Concepts Relating Social Representations,
trary, by facts, or by persuasion. Irresistible beliefs Language, and Culture in Empirical
can lead to self-sacrifice and other-sacrifice of indi- Research
viduals and groups, rather than to their change. The term culture permeates a great deal of empir-
Such strong beliefs within a group are often based ical research on social representations—particularly
on trust and trustworthiness of the other. Irresistible the research that aims to separate itself from nar-
beliefs “are like perceptual illusions: we are not a lib- row rationalistic and cognitive perspectives. This
erty to dismiss them, to have them or correct them research examines diverse topics ranging from
if need be. Like many ideas, memories, or rituals, political, ideological, and historical issues to men-
they take possession of us and are . . . independent of tal health, illness, social services, and child develop-
our reasoning” (Moscovici, 1993b, p. 50). ment, among others. As one would expect, in many
The rationality of these forms of relations in the studies the terms social representations and culture
epistemological triad is based not only on knowl- are rather nonspecific and could be easily replaced
edge and justified beliefs but on the totality of by other terms like opinions, attitudes, stereotypes,
human experience embedded in, and accumulated or prejudice in the case of the former, and context,
through, history and culture. It includes the strug- situation, or community in the case of the latter. In
gle for social recognition, desires and their sym- view of this, in this section I focus only on those
bolic transformations, ethics and morality, myths studies that theoretically enrich this growing field
and metaphors, judgments and evaluations of the addressing relations among culture, language and
self/other relations, and objects of knowledge. It is communication, and social representations. To do
the epistemology of living experience and of daily this, I focus on three fundamental concepts of the
thinking rooted in common sense, which is being Theory of Social Representations that make such
transformed into new social representations when contributions—specifically on cognitive polypha-
conditions for them are obtained. sia; figures and metaphors; and communicative and
In his analysis of Razón y culturas, Moscovici cultural themata. These concepts, we shall see, are
(1993a) argues that what makes one group distin- not mutually exclusive or exhaustive, and I can do
guishable from another one is “the act of privileging no more than to draw attention to them.
a type of representation and as a result, a form of
communication” with other members of that group. Cognitive Polyphasia and Heterogeneity
He calls this kind of group loyalty the fiduciary in Thinking and Dialogue
rationality. As I understand it, fiduciary rational- One of the basic features of the Theory of Social
ity is a form of dependency among group members Representations from the beginning has been the

498 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


focus on dynamic co-existence of distinct modal- among villagers, and Jodelet examines in these con-
ities of thinking and communication in common texts the production of social representations from
sense knowledge (Moscovici, 2008). These distinct communication, different modes of thinking, and
and rich modalities of thinking and communicat- knowledge. She shows that cognitive polyphasia
ing co-exist in communicative actions, contribute emerges from the villagers’ necessity of coping with
to viewing the issue in question from different per- fear of mental illness and enabling villagers to live
spectives, and so enable formulation of diverse argu- together with patients. At one level, most villag-
ments. They originate from knowledge and beliefs ers do not believe in medical dangers coming from
shared by social groups, and they have been estab- mental patients. They know that mental illness is
lished through their cultural and historical experi- not contagious and that the lodger with mental ill-
ences. Such communication-centered thinking is ness does not transmit germs or microbes as in the
directional and controversial, although it checks case of tuberculosis. At another level they believe in
and validates its normative coherence (Moscovici, contamination, but these beliefs remain unspecified
2008, p. 168). It forces humans to take up their because they are difficult to articulate. Beliefs take
own positions in social situations and defend them; form of folk-fantasies, superstition, and convictions
it is the thinking that judges, evaluates, criticizes, of a magic power. Jodelet emphasizes the persistence
and makes proposals for action. Moscovici coined and forms of dual appeal in speech and actions of
these diverse modalities of thinking and communi- villagers, ranging from “biological and social, to
cating as cognitive polyphasia. ancestral, indeed archaic, representations of insanity
It is not that humans change their ways of think- with their magic contents borrowed from the realms
ing according to their mood, temporary prefer- of animism and sorcery” (Jodelet, ibid, p. 300). At
ences, or personality characteristics. The concept the same time, villagers pride themselves on living
of cognitive polyphasia is inherently dialogical. The in modern ways, on using advanced technology
divergent modalities of thinking are articulated as like fast trains or television, and on being aware of
specific Ego–Alter communications. This point is new means of medical treatment. Jodelet raises the
important: We relate to others dialogically, which question as to how can archaic beliefs retain their
means that we express our thoughts as it is specif- power in the face of modern medical treatment. She
ically pertinent with respect to this or that Alter. comments:
Whereas a Cartesian scholar would expect that the
The embedding of these beliefs in the language codes
thought of the individual should be rigorous and
which are transmitted by communication and the
should follow an identical logical route from one
everyday acts which are transmitted by tradition,
moment to the next, in the Ego–Alter dialogical
both conditions of collective memory, suffice to
communication, different cognitive and emotional
explain their permanence, not their intensity of
goals employ heterogeneous modes of thinking. To
character or the veil of secrecy with which they are
think means to pursue diverse mental routes. These
covered.
may range from scientific to religious, from literal
(Jodelet, ibid, p. 300)
meanings to metaphoric interpretations, from jokes
to formal expressions, and so on. They are suited to Such diverse meanings and beliefs are usually
and articulated in different contexts of which they implicit and hidden in linguistic codes and in mean-
are parts. Speakers create links to others’ communi- ings of words. One may guess that they have been
cations, anticipating their responses, reactions, and unconsciously transmitted for generations and that
feelings. Moreover, the speakers’ dialogues are also the contradictory forms of knowledge and belief
filled with ideas of absent others; in communica- have their specific expressions in particular social
tion, speakers express commitment and loyalties to situations.
views of those who are not physically present in dia- Other researchers have presented many examples
logue or they object to, reject, or contest opinions of cognitive polyphasia in common sense thinking,
of absent “others.” and we can find excellent reviews of these studies (for
Probably no other work has provided a deeper example, see Duveen, 2007; Jovchelovitch, 2007;
insight into cognitive polyphasia than Jodelet’s Wagner & Hayes, 2005) showing diverse forms of
(1989/1991) research on social representations of thinking in different social and cultural settings and
madness. We can see here that cognitive polypha- among different groups. Numerous studies show
sia dominates different kinds of communication that different cultural communities—for example,

m a rková 499
in India (Wagner et al., 1999), in Chinese immi- that from science into common sense, involves cre-
grants in the United Kingdom (Jovchelovitch & ating metaphors, figures, and myths. Scientific dis-
Gervais, 1999), or citizens in Turkey (Narter, coveries diffuse themselves into common sense not
2006)—think about health issues both in terms of as simplified versions of science; transformation of
traditional ways of thinking and modern medicine. scientific knowledge into common sense knowledge
Cognitive polyphasia also dominates new and old is accompanied by creating figurative schemes and
ways of thinking about environment and science metaphors. It is well-documented that the science
(Castro & Lima, 2001). Psaltis (2011) is concerned of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries has had a
with diverse forms of thinking between Greek and profound effect on literature, art, and public imag-
Turkish Cypriots, relating them to varying mean- ination (e.g., Beer, 1993). For example, the discov-
ings, emotions, distrust, and threat. These forms ery of X-rays at the end of the nineteenth century
of thinking about the Cyprus issue express cogni- has led to artists’ and public’s images of the invis-
tive polyphasia when groups consider solutions to ible world and to fantasies and occult ideas. More
the problem from the point of view of the past, the recently, metaphors of illnesses like cancer, tubercu-
present, and the future. losis, and HIV/AIDS in language and thought and
Research on cognitive polyphasia directs atten- their transformations in public representations were
tion to shifts and changes in societies that experi- captured by Sontag (1978, 1989). Political, eco-
ence movement from traditional forms of thinking nomic, and educational changes, too, are accompa-
toward modern forms. Yet it shows that traditional nied by new images and metaphors. The collapse
elements of representing, for example, mental ill- of the Soviet bloc was marked by creating new
ness, are deeply embedded within the communal life symbols in re-emerging states. For example, Baltic
and are drawn “into a more active form of reflection States, in designing their new banknotes, chose
and change through this process of cultural contact, symbols that represented preferred values of the
communication, and exchange” (Duveen, 2007, newly created free nations (Mathias, 2008). Images,
p. 557, his emphasis). Moscovici (2007, p. 9) maintains, speak to the pub-
Wagner and Hayes (2005, p. 235) have argued lic and accelerate communication. In her chapter on
that the concept of cognitive polyphasia highlights “Crossing Latin America: Two French perspectives
two research areas. Instead of treating language and on Brasil and Mexico,” Jodelet (2007) shows that
thought as independent, “representations are social since ancient Greece, alterity or others have always
because of their articulation within the context of played crucial roles in imagination. The discovery
their genesis and enactment.” The other research of the New World has created, from the beginning,
area places attention on the processes of change and rich forms of imagination of indigenous peoples in
transformation in representational systems. Just as a Latin America by European intellectuals, arts and
contemporary society’s culture is constantly in flux literature, as well as social scientists and has con-
and transformation and rarely in the state of equi- tributed significantly to generating social represen-
librium, so are the modes of thought and represen- tations filled with imaginary others.
tations within it. Wagner and Hayes observe that If we turn to the research on figurative schemes,
cognitive polyphasia emerges primarily when mem- metaphors, and images in social representations, we
bers of groups are coping with new conditions dur- find that it has considerable methodological impli-
ing their lifetime and that transformations in forms cation. To access processes of thinking and commu-
of thinking and communicating continuously run nication, questionnaires and scales are substituted
between different generations. by other means such as drawings, analyses of the
media images, posters, and by studies of semiotic
Figure, Myth, and Metaphor contents of these.
From the outset, the Theory of Social Represent-
ations included the figurative dimension—or images Representing in Drawings of Maps
and metaphors—as features of representing. The One of the first studies of figurative schemes was
term figure is preferable to image because imaging the exploration by Milgram and Jodelet (1976) of
could be confused with mirroring or with a pas- drawings representing mental maps of Paris. The
sive reflection (Moscovici, 2008, p. 20). I wish to study showed that subjects were not drawing maps
emphasize once more that the transformation of based just on their personal experiences but that they
one kind of knowledge into another one, including were transmitting images of certain subcultures and

500 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


ethnic groups to which they belonged. For example, determined (Jodelet, 2005; Wagner & Hayes, 2005),
certain places were drawn only by those belong- historical and cultural events (e.g., Sen & Wagner,
ing to special professions—for example, slaughter 2005; Wertsch & Batiashvili, 2011). Kalampalikis
houses were drawn by butchers but scarcely by (2007) analyzes symbolic conflicts embedded in
anybody else. Other places, such as the icons of the social representations of two interpretations of his-
town like Notre Dame, Place de la Concord, or the tory that are embedded in the name of Macedonia.
Eiffel Tower, were drawn by nearly everybody. We Equally, images and metaphors in social repre-
can say that drawings express historical-cultural sentations have been explored across cultures or in
networks of meanings that are part of subjects’ and specific groups. In the 1980s, De Rosa (1987) car-
subgroups’ experiences, knowledge, and feelings ried out a multimethod research on the social repre-
about the place where they live (Guerrero, 2007). sentation of mental illness. In this research, children
Institutions that societies create are nourished by and adults were asked to draw images in connection
collective memories, myths, national identities, and with madness; their drawings suggested the presence
imagination (Banchs et al., 2007). of ancient images of madness (see also Schurmans &
Imagining based on drawings of maps inspired de Rosa, 1990).
extensive studies in Latin America (Arruda & de Visual images in the press, advertisements, and
Alba, 2007). In her study of maps of the city of campaigns are used to influence or change social
Mexico, De Alba (2007) shows that the symbolic representations of political or health issues (De Rosa,
construction of the city is an imaginary sphere in 2001; Joffe, 2008). Intentions of the producers of
which mythical references, mystical beliefs, reveries, posters, on the one hand, and images of the public,
and urban legends have no correspondents in the on the other hand, could be quite divergent. For
real world. An interesting theoretical issue discussed example, some posters produced on behalf of peo-
in Arruda and Ulup’s (2007) research of mental ple with mental disabilities sometimes confirmed,
maps of Brazil is the presence of blank spaces in the rather than changed, the existing representations
center or center-west region. The authors maintain (Marková & Farr, 1990). Visual images in the press
that void spaces coincide with the colonial occupa- have been particularly influential in staged photo-
tion of these territories and that drawings some- graphs capturing public images about genetic engi-
times reproduce the ancient images of isolated and neering as injecting tomatoes with genes that make
dangerous places. The authors observe that although them grow bigger (Wagner et al., 2002). Wagner
one might consider empty spaces on maps as signs and Hayes (2005, p. 181) comment that images of
of lack of knowledge, it is more likely that these dis- tomatoes injected with genes remind inoculation
tant places in the center of Brazil express strangeness and injecting foreign materials into bodies known
from which subjects wish to dissociate. These empty from medicine and chemistry. There is also an asso-
places may also serve as reminders of the past and ciated belief of infection that passes from one organ-
collective memories of occupation. Thus, emptiness ism to another:
does not always mean nonexistence but a choice or
Finally, the monstrosity of genetically engineered
a defense (Arruda, Gonçalves, & Mululo, 2008).
organisms is related as well. The topic of ‘Frankenstein
In contrast, seaside spaces were filled with images.
foods’ is not far from these ideas and in fact frequently
They were inhabited by Europeans and civilized
came up in interviews. Just as tomatoes are good to
local people. In addition, the authors found that the
eat, they are also good to think with. These images
participants from northern Brazil represented south
and metaphorical projections capture the ‘What
as a very different region because of its temperate
is it’ and the ‘How does it work’ part of popular
climate and its population of the European origin.
imagination about ‘genetic engineering.
(Wagner & Hayes, 2005, p. 181)
Figurative Schemes in Comparative
Research These examples show how the two opposite yet
A considerable amount of research has been car- complementary explanations of phenomena in the
ried out to compare figurative schemes and images in world of reason and myth, or logos and mythos, mix
different fields like health and illness (e.g., Herzlich, to generate social representations. Nevertheless, it
1973; Joffe, 2003, 2008; Joffe & Haarhof, 2002), would not be correct to say that sciences are guided
biotechnology (e.g., Wagner et al., 2002), the body by logos (see Moscovici, 1992, on “scientific myths”)
(Jodelet, 1984), the body and hygiene as culturally and common sense by mythical thinking.

m a rková 501
A recent volume on Mythical Thinking and Social representations (Moscovici, 1993c; Moscovici &
Representations forms a true dialogue between anthro- Vignaux, 1994/2000).
pology and the Theory of Social Representations Many antinomies are implicitly present in our
(Paredes & Jodelet, 2009). The contributions to common sense thinking for centuries, and they may
this volume show that mythical thinking does not never be brought to explicit awareness. This is so,
disappear with scientific progress, technology, and because there may never be any reason—or at least
mass education but that it continues to be present there may not be any reason for many generations—
in everyday reasoning and that it permeates daily for them to become problematized and thematized.
practices. Jodelet (2009, p. 31) observes that there For example, logos and mythos could be viewed
are least three central aspects that relate social rep- throughout history as complementary antinomies
resentations and mythical thinking. There is an until, for one reason or other, logos become a supe-
instrumental aspect of common sense that utilizes rior and rational way of explanation of phenomena,
certain mythical thinking in the construction of whereas mythos is degraded as irrational thought
social life. Furthermore, production of common (Moscovici, 2009). In principle, all antinomies can
sense re-activates ancient myths with requirements become themata—that is, issues for public debates
of contemporary cultural identities. Finally, through and disputes—but many of them do not rise to that
functional aspect of common sense, the formation status.
of myths facilitates interpretations of events or Themata that generate most social representa-
objects in social life and in social relations. tions are those pertaining to the Ego–Alter, like
private/public, morality/immorality, justice/injus-
Communicative and Cultural Themata tice, and freedom/oppression, among others. Such
In contrast to cognitive polyphasia, figura- themata are in the heart of social sciences, and
tive schemes, metaphors, and myths, the concept they generate social representations of phenom-
of themata has entered into the Theory of Social ena like democracy, citizenship, quality of life,
Representations more recently (Moscovici, 1993c; and health and illness, to name but a few. How
Moscovici & Vignaux, 1994/2000). It has since and in what ways themata become problematized
become one of the most important theoretical con- and which meanings become foregrounded is spe-
cepts in social representations with respect to cul- cific to the structured field in which a social rep-
ture and communication. Let us explain. resentation in engaged. A social representation is
One of the fundamental features of human rarely generated from a single thema. If we con-
thinking is making distinctions and understand- sider, as an example, a social representation of
ing phenomena as antinomies. For example, we HIV/AIDS and its vicissitudes over the last three
understand freedom in contrast to what we con- decades in different parts of the world, we find
sider to be a lack of freedom; justice is understood that re-thematization of morality/immorality has
through what is considered to be an absence of been associated with re-thematization of social
justice; logos as contrasted with mythos, and so values related to sexuality, promiscuity in the
on. Antinomies are features of thinking, language, general public, discrimination of minorities, and
and communication in all cultures, but different social recognition, among other issues (Marková
cultures and societies employ their capacity of et al., 1995). Although the antinomy morality/
making distinctions and thinking in antinomies immorality itself has not been questioned, the
in specific ways. We find them throughout eons content and context of morality/immorality has
of human history both in scientific and in com- been differently thematized in different structured
mon sense thinking, although very often they are fields in which the social representation of HIV/
present implicitly without becoming an explicit AIDS has been engaged. For example, the ques-
topic of discourse. Socio-cultural changes, how- tion of personal and social responsibility, medi-
ever, may bring implicit antinomies to the public cal confidentiality, and human rights all became
awareness and into discourses, reflecting socie- part of discourse in such specific structured fields.
tal tensions and conflicts. This means that from Communicative processes, through which these
that moment on, they turn into themata, whether changes in meanings are usually achieved, carry
in scientific thinking where they generate scien- symbols and images, which not only circulate in
tific theories (Holton, 1975, 1978) or in com- public discourses but also organize and generate
mon sense thinking where they generate social discourses; they shape common thinking, language,

502 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


and behavior; and provide grounds for the forma- Declaration of Human Rights. This strong coher-
tion of new social representations. ence disappears, however, when subjects respond
Liu (2004) describes themata as “deep struc- to specific contexts in which human rights are pre-
tures” of social representations. In his research on sented. Having examined theories and practices in
rapid changes of social representations of the quality relation to human rights, Doise concludes that the
of life in China, he identified two themata that, in basis of legal thinking on human rights is not to
contemporary society, compete with one another: be sought in their institutional expression, but it is
“to be” and “to have.” Being prioritizes traditional profoundly anchored in normative social represen-
Chinese values like the authentic relation between tations. Doise traces the origin of normative social
subject and object, a union between self and others, representations of human rights in communication
and their rootedness, connectedness, and mutual and human interactions. Communicative contracts
commitment. Having, on the other hand, gives carry implicitly ethical norms (Rommetveit, 1974;
priority to how subject instrumentalizes object as a Bakhtin, 1979/1986) that regulate our mutual inter-
resource to be possessed and consumed. Possession actions, mutual commitment, and social recognition
has become a new value in the rapidly changing of one human by another. These contracts are then
China, whether it is the possession of money and built into social norms and social representations.
material objects or of symbolic objects like social In a similar manner, Mead (1915) drew atten-
status and power. Neither having nor being exist tion to the error in the assumption of theorists who
in pure forms, but they are both dynamically inter- were convinced that individuals had originally pos-
related into the meaning of the quality of life in sessed their natural rights before any formal societal
contemporary China. organizations existed. He was critical of those who
In their research on social representations of thought that formal organizations had to be estab-
Roms, Peréz et al. (2007) identified two underlying lished to protect those natural rights. Mead argued
themata. One of them highlights nature versus cul- that, on the contrary, already in informal organi-
ture. This polarity emphasizes the superiority of cul- zations that developed within groups, the rights,
tured European majorities over natural minorities rules, norms of acting, and constraints had already
of Roms. The second thema, human versus animal, existed. Mead specifically referred to philosophers like
represents Roms as having deficits in human quali- Hobbes, Spinoza, and Locke who were not aware of
ties. Drawing on his socio-anthropological research, this fact. Thus, he said that if Locke had the knowl-
Moscovici (2011) shows that in the case of Roms edge of the contemporary anthropologists, then he
themata are also articulated along the extensive his- would have recognized that people had been orga-
torical narratives artistic/criminal. nized in informal groups from which governmental
Research on social representations of genetically institutions later developed. Governmental institu-
modified food as presented in the press shows that tions arose out of communities that already had for-
these are underlain by themata of health versus dis- mulated their customs. In other words, rights were
ease and risk versus safety (Castro & Gomes, 2005). already in existence, and they were recognized by
The already noted research by Wagner et al. (2002) group members, although in a different form than
implies that social representations of genetically in governmental institutions. No special introduc-
modified tomatoes, both in the press and in inter- tion or special instruments were required to estab-
views with citizens, are triggered by themata like lish them in formal institutions.
natural versus unnatural. Doise has maintained that although norms do
not translate themselves automatically into insti-
Morality of Human Rights As a Thema tutional expressions, they remain to be the shared
Although Doise (2002) does not use the con- references to which victims can appeal (Doise,
cept of thema, we can subsume his work on human 2002, p. 25). Concerning the issue of how to assess
rights as social representations under this concept. whether human rights are upheld by different coun-
Moral universality of human rights codified itself in tries, normative social representations are used as a
societies as a basic thema, although naturally, it has tool of evaluation. Countries use their own norms
been thematized differently in specific cultures and and ethnocentric social representations of human
societies. Doise’s own empirical research shows that rights to evaluate different countries with respect
participants in different countries express consis- to discrimination and prejudice in others, and they
tent attitudes on general principles or articles of the commonly overvalue their own morality. Doise has

m a rková 503
analyzed contemporary trends and habits of speak- that have followed Jodelet’s research have provided
ing about different kinds of human rights—for accounts of groups’ representations in which history
example, individual rights, socio-economic rights, and collective memory have mixed and organized
the self-determination rights of ethnic groups, and and have transformed these representations. Such
rights for natives to maintain special ties with the accounts are never neutral cognitive narratives but
land of their forefathers. Variability in dealing with dialogical evaluations and justifications of history;
human rights is great and anchored in different they are forging many ethnic, social, and national
kinds of beliefs that are rooted in histories, politics, identities and pose questions about how histories
and in common sense. could be re-interpreted and rewritten on the basis of
politics and ideology (e.g., Liu et al., 2009; Lastrego
Conclusion: Toward Theoretical and & Licata, 2010; Paez, 2010). Raudsepp, Heidmets,
Empirical Diversity in Social Representing and Kruusvall (2008) have explored social represen-
After World War II, the social sciences exerted a tations of collective memory in their study of the
strong effort to establish their places in reconstruct- socio-cultural context of Estonia during the tran-
ing the world and to coordinate themselves inter- sition from a post-Soviet republic to a liberal State
nationally. Among these efforts was the UNESCO in the European Union. They have analyzed explicit
research of the roles of social sciences in higher edu- and implicit socio-cultural regulative principles,
cation. Social psychology was grouped together with and they have explored how these principles have
cultural anthropology and sociology because it was transformed in the course of the transition period,
assumed that this was its proper place (Moscovici & focusing on the changed roles of Russian minori-
Marková, 2006). But the UNESCO research ties and Estonian majorities during that time. Social
showed that the position of social psychology was representations of collective memories of daily life
split between psychology and sociology. In the years during communism in Rumania have been cap-
to come, social psychology leaned toward experi- tured by Neculau (2008) and those of the Cyprus
mental psychology and its methods, and the rela- conflict by Psaltis (2011). Findings of these substan-
tion to culture considerably diminished or totally tial empirical studies feed back to the theory.
disappeared. Equally, language and communication
played only a minimal role in social psychology, the Future Directions
situation that Moscovici (1972) and Rommetveit The growing interest in theoretical and empiri-
(1974) deeply regretted. cal research in social representations also highlights
In contrast, we have seen in this chapter that from challenges and problems for the future. Among
its beginning, the Theory of Social Representations these I mention the following.
has been conceptualized within culture, language, and First, despite the fact that strong emphasis on
communication. In this chapter I have discussed three language and communication was already part of
concepts: cognitive polyphasia; figurative schemes, La Psychanalyse, this remains a neglected area of
myths and metaphors; and themata. These three studies of social representations. Language and com-
concepts have made most significant contributions to munication are usually taken for granted as essential
the Theory of Social Representations. However, there features of human interactions but rarely studied as
is also substantial empirical research in social repre- phenomena that require a specific exploration. We
sentations that covers diverse topics in education, only see beginnings of such research in dialogical
politics, environmental problems, health, mental studies of different kinds of discourse (e.g., conver-
health, and aging. There is growing research on social sation and dialogue, polylogue, inner speech, focus
representations of otherness or alterity, everyday life groups studies) that have been recently emerg-
(Haas, 2006), identity (Moloney & Walker, 2007), ing. They include analyses of various grammatical
and historical events. Jodelet (1992) has initiated structures like modalizations, positioning, deontic
the study of collective memories as an important claims, and other means by which speakers take dis-
aspect of social representations. Examining histor- tance from or express closeness to objects of social
ical perspectives of collective memory in the work representations (e.g., Harré, this volume; Salazar
of social scientists like Halbwachs and Douglas, Orvig, 2007; Marková et al., 2007; Salazar Orvig &
she has analyzed the process with the Nazi Klaus Grossen, 2008; Linell, 2009). In addition, what par-
Barbie that took place in 1987 in France. Numerous ticipants communicate to one another is not pro-
studies of social representations of historical events duced solely by them; they necessarily draw on their

504 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


cultural resources, on perspectives of the parties that diversity is studied, for example, by structuralist,
are not present in discourse (third parties), and on discourse, anthropological, phenomenological,
groups to which they belong or which they reject. narrative, and other approaches (Jodelet, 2012).
For example, absent others could become, directly Among all of these, what specific contributions
or indirectly, participants in talks among villagers in can the Theory of Social Representations make that
Jodelet’s (1989/1991) research on madness, because will differentiate it from other approaches? This is a
absent others could become invisible or semi-visible challenge in the world of rapid changes that is char-
judges of relations between villagers and patients. acterized by a series of “trans-”processes (Jodelet,
Groups do not live in a vacuum but are part of a ibid) What different forms will transformation of
broader community. Outsiders coming to the village knowledge take in these changes where the local
are not neutral onlookers but they communicate competes with the global and crossbreeding think-
with in-groups: they can make flattering as well as ing produces new kinds of cognitive polyphasia?
damaging comments about relations between villag- Finally, there are theoretical challenges concern-
ers and patients. A close association with mentally ing the epistemological status of social representa-
ill patients could downgrade, in the eyes of others, tions. Both knowing and believing co-constitute
the villagers’ social identity. These different circum- social representations, although some social rep-
stances involving numerous communicating parties resentations are based primarily on knowledge
reflect themselves in diverse modalities of thinking. or factual beliefs and others mainly on passionate
Participants in interactions may jointly con- beliefs and convictions. Knowledge and beliefs are
struct utterances that may suggest that they transmitted in and through culture, language, and
share—or assume sharing—a social representation. communication, as well as through learning (tacit
Alternatively, in and through a joint construction or explicit) by repeating and changing others’ activi-
of utterances, they may question limits of their ties. But what status can be attributed to knowledge
shared knowledge (Marková, 2007). They may generated from trust in authority of other individu-
refer to beliefs, to a super-addressee (god, general- als or institutions and of collective norms? Can these
ized other, consciousness), the law and its different serve as preconditions of rationality and coherence
kinds, rules and norms, morality and ethics, tradi- of reasoning?
tions, habits, and stereotypes. There are countless No doubt there are other theoretical and empiri-
examples of the interdependence among language, cal challenges. The theory is now 50 years old, and
communication, and social representations that over these long years it has undergone transforma-
have not been explored or have only just become tions and has become gradually enriched by differ-
subjects of research interest. ent cultures all over the world as it has spread from
Another challenging issue was implied earlier in Europe to other continents—particularly to Latin
this chapter. It concerns the fact that cultures live no America and most recently to Asia.
longer in isolated ghettos, and rather, the contem-
porary world of societies is open to other cultures Acknowledgements
and they “set the stage for permanent situations of I am very grateful to Denise Jodelet for her generous help
in providing ideas and references to research on social represen-
uncertainty,” moving cultures in different directions tations and culture and to Angela Arruda for references to the
(Rosa & Valsiner, 2007). This is also the issue that research in Latin America. This chapter was written during the
Moscovici expressed in his third paradox concern- period of my Emeritus Fellowship awarded by the Leverhulme
ing incommunicability among different groups (see Trust, and I wish to acknowledge the Trust’s generous support
above, p. 497). The challenge for the Theory of Social for this project.
Representations concerns the issue of studying eth-
ical problems arising from the growing uncertainty References
Abric, J.-C. (1994a). L’organisation interne des représenta-
in the world of increasing complexity; and with tions sociales: système central et système péripherique.
problems how to establish reflective communica- In C. Guimelli (ed.). Structures et Transformations des
tion in intergroup and intercultural relations. Such Représations Sociales (pp. 73–84). Neuchâtel, Switzerland:
issues concern the future developments of relations Delachaux et Niestlé.
Abric, J.-C. (1994b) Pratiques Sociales et Représentations. Paris:
between the Theory of Social Representations and
Presses Universitaires de France.
culture (Permanadeli et al., 2012). Moreover, the Abric, J.-C. (2001). A structural approach to social representa-
Theory of Social Representations is only one psycho- tions. In K. Deaux and G. Philogène (eds.). Representations of
logical approach that focuses on culture. Cultural the Social (pp. 42–47). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

m a rková 505
Arruda, A. & de Alba, M. (2007). Espacios imaginarios y repre- & D. Murdoch) (Vol. 2). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
sentaciones sociales. Aportes desde Latinoamérica. Barcelona, University Press.
Spain: UAM-Anthropos. Doise, W. (1985). Les représentations sociales. Definition d’un
Arruda, A. & Ulup, L. (2007). Brasil imaginado: representaciones concept. Connexions, 45, 243–253.
sociales de jovenes universitarios. In A. Arruda, A. & M. de Doise, W. (1986). Levels of Explanation in Social Psychology.
Alba (Eds.). Espacios imaginarios y representaciones sociales. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Aportes desde Latinoamérica (pp. 165–198). Barcelona, Spain: Doise, W. (2002). Human Rights as Social Representations.
UAM-Anthropos. London, UK: Routledge.
Arruda, A., Gonçalves, L. V. P. & Mululo, S. C. C. (2008). Durkheim, E. (1898). Représentations individuelles et représen-
Traveling with students through Brazilian varieties: social tations collectives. Revue de la metaphysique et de morale, 6,
representations and stereotypes. Psicologia em Estudo, 13, 3. 273–302.
http://www.scielo.br/revistas/pe/paboutj.htm/. Accessed on Durkheim, E. (1912/2001) The Elementary Forms of Religious Life
28 August 2011. (Trans. C. Cosman). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Bakhtin, M. M. (1981). The Dialogic Imagination. Four Essays Duveen, G. (2002). Construction, belief, doubt. Psychologie &
by M. M. Bakhtin. M. Holquist (Ed.). C. Emerson and Societé, 5, 139–155.
M. Holquist (transl.) Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Duveen, G. (2007). Culture and social representations. In
Bakhtin, M. M. (1984). Problems of Dostoyevsky’s Poetics. J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.). The Cambridge Handbook of
C. Emerson (Ed. & Trans.). Manchester, UK: Manchester Sociocultural Psychology (pp. 543–559). Cambridge, UK:
University Press. Cambridge University Press.
Bakhtin, M. M. (1979). Estetika Slovesnovo Tvorchestva. Moskva: Duveen, G. (2008). Social actors and social groups: a return to
Bocharov. Speech Genres and Other Late Essays (1986). heterogeneity in social psychology, Journal for the Theory of
C. Emerson & M. Holquist (Eds.). V.W. McGee (Trans.) Social Behaviour, 38, 369–374.
Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Einstein, A. & Infeld, L. (1938/1961). The Evolution of Physics.
Banchs, M. A., Agudo Guevara, A. & Astorga, L. (2007). London, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Imaginarios, representaciones y memoria social. In Festinger, L. (1954). A theory of social comparison processes,
A. Arruda, A. & M. de Alba (Eds.). Espacios imaginar- Human Relations, 7, 117–140.
ios y representaciones sociales. Aportes desde Latinoamérica Flament, C. (1994a). Aspects péripheriques des représentations
(pp. 47–95). Barcelona, Spain: UAM-Anthropos. sociales. In C. Guimelli (Ed.). Structures et Transformations des
Bauer, M. W. & Gaskell, G. (1999). Towards a paradigm for Représations Sociales (pp. 85–118). Neuchâtel, Switzerland:
research on social representations. Journal for Theory of Social Delachaux et Niestlé.
Behaviour, 29, 163–186. Flament, C. (1994b). Structure, dynamique et transformation
Beer, G. (1993). Wave theory and the rise of literary mod- des représentations sociales. In J.-A. Abric (Ed.). Pratiques
ernism. In G. Levine (Ed.). Realism and Representation Sociales et Représentations (pp. 37–57). Paris: Presses
(pp. 193–213). Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Universitaires de France.
Bruner, J. (1985). Actual Minds, Possible Worlds. Cambridge, Foster, M. B. (1957). Mystery and Philosophy. London, UK: SCM
MA: Harvard University Press. Press.
Castro, P. & Lima, M. L. O. (2001). Old and new ideas about the Garnier, C. & Rouquette, M. L. (2000). Représentations sociales et
environment and science: an exploratory study. Environment éducation. Montreal, Canada: Editions Nouvelles.
and Behaviour, 33, 400–423. Geertz, C. (2000). Available Light: Anthropological Reflections
Castro, P. & Gomes, I. (2005). Genetically modified orgqanisms on Philosophical Topics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
in the Portugese press: thematisation and anchoring. Journal Press.
for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 35, 1–17. Gellner, E. (1992). Reason and Culture. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Darwin, C. R. (1859). The Origin of Species. (2nd ed. 1874). Gellner, E. (1998). Language and Solitude. Cambridge, UK:
London: John Murray. Cambridge University Press.
de Alba, M. (2007). Mapas imaginarios del Centro Histórico de Guerrero, A. (2007). Imágenes de América Latina y México a
la Ciudad de México: de la experiencia al imaginario urbano. través de los mapas mentales. In A. Arruda & M. de Alba
In A. Arruda, A. & M. de Alba (Eds.). Espacios imaginar- (coords). Espacios imaginarios y representaciones sociales
ios y representaciones sociales. Aportes desde Latinoamérica (pp. 235–284). Aportes desde Latinoamérica. Barcelona,
(pp. 285–319). Barcelona, Spain: UAM-Anthropos. Spain: UAM-Anthropos.
de Rosa, A. S. (1987). The social representations of mental ill- Guimelli, C. (1994). (ed.). Structures et Transformations des
ness in children and adults. In W. Doise & S. Moscovici Représations Sociales. Neuchâtel, Switzerland: Delachaux et
(Eds.) Current Issues in European Social Psychology (Vol. 2, Niestlé.
pp. 47–138). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Haas, V. (2006). (ed.) Les savoirs du quotidien. Rennes, France:
de Rosa, A. S. (2001). The king is naked. Critical advertisement PUR.
and fashion. The Benetton phenomenon. In K. Deaux & Harris, R. (2009). Rationality and the Literate Mind. New York
G. Philogene (Eds.) Representations of the social (pp. 48–82). and London: Routledge.
Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Herzlich, C. (1973). Health and Illness. London and New York:
de Rosa, A. S. & Schurmans, M. N. (1990). Immaginario e follia Academic Press.
nelle rappresentazioni sociali di bambini e adolescenti di due Hollis, M. & Lukes, S. (1982). Rationality and relativism.
paesi europei. Rassegna di Psicologia, 3, 297–340. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Descartes, R. (1637). Discourse on Method. In The Philosophical Holton, G. (1975). On the role of themata in scientific thought.
Writings of Descartes (1985). (Trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff Science, 188, 328–334.

506 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


Holton, G. (1978). The Scientific Imagination: Case Studies. Kalampalikis, N. (2007). Les Grecs et le mythe d’Alexandre. Paris:
Cambridge, UK: New York: Cambridge University Press. L’Harmattan
Howarth, C. (2006). A social representation is not a quiet thing: Kant, I. (1788/1873). Critique of Practical Reason. T. K. Abbott
exploring the critical potential of social representations the- (Trans). London, UK: Longsman, Green.
ory. British Journal of Social Psychology, 45, 65–86. Lastrego, S. & Licata, L. (2010). “Should a country’s leaders
Ingold, T. (2004). Beyond biology and culture. The meaning apologize for its past misdeeds?” An analysis of the effects
of evolution in a relational world. Social Anthropology, 12, of both public apologies from a Belgian official and percep-
209–221. tion of Congolese victims. Revista de Psicología Social, 25,
Jesuino, P. (2009). L’evolversi della teoria. In A. Palmonari, A. & 61–72.
F. Emiliani (Eds.). Paradigmi delle rappresentazioni sociali Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking Language, Mind and World
(pp. 113–146). Bologna, Italy: Il Mulino. Dialogically. Charlotte, NC: Information Age.
Jodelet, D. (1984). The representation of the body and its Liu, J. H., Paez, D., Slawuta, P., Cabecinhas, R. Techio, E.,
transformations. In R. Farr and S. Moscovici (Eds.). Social Kokdemir, D., et al. (2009). Representing World History in
Representations (pp. 211–238). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge the 21st Century: The Impact of 9/11, the Iraq War, and
University Press. the Nation-State on Dynamics of Collective Remembering.
Jodelet, D. (1989/1991). Madness and Social Representations. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 40, 667–692.
G. Duveen (Ed.), T. Pownall (Trans.). London: Harvester Liu, L. (2004). Sensitising concept, themata and sharedness: a
Wheatsheaf. dialogical perspective of social representations. Journal for the
Jodelet, D. (1992). Mémoire de masse: le côté moral et affectif de Theory of Social Behaviour, 34, 249–264.
l’histoire. Bulletin de psychologie, XLV, 239–256. Locke, J. (1690/1975). An Essay Concerning Human
Jodelet, D. (2002). Les représentations sociales dans le champ de Understanding. Ed. and Introduction by Peter H. Nidditch.
la culture. Social Science Information, 41, 111–133. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Jodelet, D. (2005). Imaginaires érotiques de l’hygiène féminine Lovejoy, A. O. (1936). The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge,
intime. Approche anthropologique. Connexions, 87, 105–127. MA: Harvard University Press.
Jodelet, D. (2006a). Culture et pratique de santé. Nouvelle Revue Marková, I. (2003/2005). Dialogicality and Social Representations.
de Psychosociologie, 1, 219–239. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Jodelet, D. (2006b). Place de l’experience vécue dans les proces- Marková, I. (2007). Themata in dialogue: taking social knowl-
sus de formation des représentations sociales (pp. 235–255). In edge as shared. In I. Marková, P. Linell, M. Grossen & A.
V. Hass (Ed.) Les savoirs du quotidien. Rennes, France: PUR. Salazar Orvig. Dialogue in Focus Groups. Exploring Socially
Jodelet, D. (2007). Traversias latinoamericanas: dos miradas Shared Knowledge (pp. 167–193). London, UK: Equinox.
francesas sobre Brasil y México. In A. Arruda, A. & M. de Marková, I. & Farr, R. M. (1990). Representations of Health,
Alba (Eds.). Espacios imaginarios y representaciones sociales. Illness and Handicap. Chur, Switzerland: Harwood.
Aportes desde Latinoamérica (pp. 99–128). Barcelona, Spain: Marková, I., McKee, K., Power, K. & Moodie, E. (1995), The
UAM-Anthropos. self, the other and perceived risk: Lay representations of HIV/
Jodelet, D. (2008). Social Representations: The Beautiful AIDS in Scottish prisons (pp. 111–129). In I. Marková &
Invention. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 38, pp. R. M. Farr, (Eds.) Representations of Health, Illness and
411–430. Handicap. New York: Harwood.
Jodelet, D. (2009). Introdução. In Paredes, E. C. & Jodelet, D. Marková, I., Linell, P. Grossen, M. & Salazar Orvig, A. Dialogue
Pensamento mitico e representações sociais (pp. 27–32). in Focus Groups. Exploring Socially Shared Knowledge.
Cuiabá, Brazil: EdUFMT. London, UK: Equinox.
Jodelet, D. (2012). Social representations study and interlocu- Mathias, E. (2008). Economic success and social trust: Evidence
tion of knowledges in a globalized space. In R. Permanadeli, from the Baltic States. In I. Marková & A. Gillespie, A. (Eds.):
D. Jodelet & T. Sugiman (Eds.). Alternative production of Trust and Distrust: Sociocultural Perspectives. (pp. 219–245).
knowledge and Social Representations. Yogyakarta, Indonesia: Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.
Center of Research and Social Partnership. Universitas Mead, G. H. (1915). Natural rights and the theory of the politi-
Dhama. cal institution. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and
Jodelet, D. (in press). Interconnections between social repre- Scientific Methods, 12, 141–155.
sentations and intervention. In A. S. de Rosa (Ed.). Social Milgram, S. & Jodelet, D. (1976). Psychological map of Paris.
Representations in the Social Arena. London, UK: Routledge. In H. Proshansky, W. H. Ittelson & L. G. Rivlin (Eds.).
Joffe, H. (2003). Risk and ‘The Other’. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Environmental Psychology: people and their physical set-
University Press. tings. (2nd ed., pp. 104–124). New York: Holt, Rinehart, &
Joffe, H. (2008). The power of visual material: persuasion, emo- Winston.
tion and identification. Diogenes, 217, 84–93. Moloney, G. & Walker, I. (2007). Social Representations and Identity.
Joffe, H. & Haarhoff, G. (2002). Representations of far-flung New York and Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
illnesses: the case of Ebola in Britain. Social Science and Morin, M. (2004). Parcours de santé. Paris: Armand Colin.
Medicine, 54, 955–969. Moscovici, S. (1961/1976). La psychanalyse: son image et son pub-
Jovchelovitch, S. (2007). Knowledge in Context: Representations, lic. Paris: PUF.
Community and Culture. London & New York: Routledge. Moscovici, S. (1970). Préface. In D. Jodelet, J. Viet, & P. Besnard
Jovchelovitch, S. & Gervais, M.-C. (1999). Social representa- (Eds.). La psychologie sociale, une discipline en mouvement
tions of health and illness: the case of Chinese community in (pp. 9–64). Paris-La Haye: Mouton.
England. Journal of Community and Applied Social Psychology, Moscovici, S. (1972). The Psychosociology of Language. Chicago,
9, 247–260. IL: Markham.

m a rková 507
Moscovici, S. (1972/2000). Society and theory in social psy- Narter, M. (2006). The change in daily knowledge in Turkey.
chology. In J. Israel & H. Tajfel (Eds.). The Context of Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 36, 409–424.
Social Psychology (pp. 17–68). London and New York: Neculau, A. (2008). (ed). La vie quotidienne en Roumanie sous
Academic Press, Reprinted in S. Moscovici, S. (2000). communisme. Paris, France: L’Harmattan.
Social Representations: Explorations in Social Psychology. In G. Paez, D. (2010). Official or political apologies and improvement of
Duveen (Ed.) (pp. 78–119). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. intergroup relations: A neo-Durkheimian approach to official
Moscovici, S. (1976). Society Against Nature. London, UK: The apologies as rituals. Revista de Psicología Social, 25, 101–115.
Harvester Press. (Trans. S. Rabinovitch from La société contre Palmonari, A. & Emiliani, F. (2009). Paradigmi delle rappresen-
nature. Paris: Seuil, 1992/1994). tazioni sociali. Bologna, Italy: Il Mulino.
Moscovici, S. (1984). Introduction: le domaine de la psychologie Paredes, E. C. & Jodelet, D. (2009). Pensamento mitico e repre-
sociale. In S. Moscovici (Ed.). Psychologie sociale (pp. 5–22). sentações sociais. Cuiabá, Brazil: EdUFMT.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Pérez, J. A., Moscovici, S. & Chulvi, B. (2007). The taboo
Moscovici, S. (1987). Answers and question. Journal for the against group contact: hypothesis of Gypsy ontologization.
Theory of Social Behaviour, 17, 513–529. The British Journal of Social Psychology, 46, 249–272.
Moscovici, S. (1988). Notes towards a description of social Permanadeli R., Jodelet, D. & Sugiman, T. (2012). Alternative
representations. European Journal of Social Psychology, 18, Production of Knowledge and Social Representations. Yogyakarta,
211–250. Indonesia: Center of Research and Social Partnership.
Moscovici, S. (1988/1993). La Machine à faire des dieux: soci- Universitas Dhama.
ologie et psychologie. Paris: Fayard. Translated by W. D. Hall Piaget, J. (1932). The Moral Judgment of the Child. London, UK:
as The Invention of Society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Kegan Paul
Moscovici, S. (1992). The psychology of scientific myths. In Piaget, J. (1970). Structuralism. New York: Harper & Row.
M. Cranach & W. Doise (Eds.). Social Representations and Psaltis, C. (2011). Trust and Distrust of Contact and the Contact
the Social Bases of Knowledge (pp. 3–9). Lewiston, Toronto & Hypothesis in Cyprus. In I. Marková & A. Gillespie (Eds.).
Bern: Hogfere & Huber. Trust and conflict: Representation, culture and dialogue.
Moscovici, S. (1993a). Razón y culturas. In: S. Moscovici & S. (pp. 83–104). London, UK: Routledge.
Barriga. Arte la Nueva Europa (pp. 30–62). Sevilla, Spain: Quintanilla, L., Herrera, V. And Veloz, V. (2005). Nutrir el
Mimeo. desarollo comunitário con representaciones sociales, Mexico.
Moscovici, S. (1993b). The return of the unconscious. Social Prometeo, 42, 22–31.
Research, 60, 39–93. Raudsepp M., Heidmets, M. & Kruusvall, J. (2008). Changing
Moscovici, S. (1993c). Introductory address to the First patterns of trust: the Estonian case. In I. Marková &
International Conference on Social Representations in A. Gillespie (Eds.). Trust and Distrust: Sociocultural Perspectives
Ravello, 1992. Papers on Social Representations, 2, 160–170. (pp. 247–264). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.
Moscovici, S. (1998a). Social consciousness and its history. Rommetveit, R. (1974). On Message Structure. London & New
Culture & Psychology, 4, 411–429. York: Wiley.
Moscovici, S. (l998b). The history and actuality of social rep- Rosa, A. & Valsiner, J. (2007). Rationality, Ethics and Objectivity.
resentations. In U. Flick (Ed.) The Psychology of the Social In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.). The Cambridge Handbook
(pp. 209–247). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. of Sociocultural Psychology (pp. 692–707). Cambridge, UK:
Moscovici, S. (2007). Un largo prefacio. In A. Arruda & M. de Cambridge University Press.
Alba (coords). Espacios imaginarios y representaciones sociales Rorty, R. (1980). Philosophy & the Mirror of Nature. Oxford,
(pp. 7–13). Aportes desde Latinoamérica. Barcelona, Spain: UK: Basil Blackwell.
UAM-Anthropos. Salazar Orvig, A. (2007). Who is speaking in focus groups? The
Moscovici, S. (2008). Psychoanalysis: its Image and its Public. dialogical display of heterogeneity. In I. Marková, P. Linell,
Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. M. Grossen & A. Salazar Orvig. Dialogue in Focus Groups.
Moscovici, S. (2009). Prefácio. In Paredes, E. C. & Jodelet, D. Exploring Socially Shared Knowledge (pp. 103–129). London,
Pensamento mitico e representações sociais (pp. 11–23). Cuiabá, UK: Equinox.
Brazil: EdUFMT. Salazar Orvig, A. & Grossen, M. (2008). Le dialogisme dans
Moscovici, S. (2011). An essay on social representations and l’entretien clinique. Langage et Société, 123, 37–52.
ethnic minorities. Social Science Information, 50, 442–461. Sen, R., & Wagner, W. (2005). History, emotions and hetero-ref-
Moscovici, S. & Vignaux, G. (1994). Le Concept de Thêmata. erential representations in intergroup conflict: the example of
In C. Guimelli, Structures et transformations des représenta- Hindu-Muslim relations in India. Papers on social representa-
tions sociales (pp. 25–72). Neuchatel, Switzerland: Delachaux tions 14, 2.1–2.23.
et Niestlé. Reprinted in S. Moscovici. Social Representations. Sontag, S. (1978). Illness as Metaphor. New York: Farrar, Straus
(2000). (pp. 156–183). In G. Duveen (ed.). London, UK: and Giroux.
Polity Press. Sontag, S. (1989). AIDS and Its Metaphor. New York: Farrar, Straus
Moscovici, S. & Marková, I. (1998). Presenting social represen- and Giroux.
tations: a conversation. Culture and Psychology, 4, 371–410. Taylor, C. (1995). Overcoming Epistemology. In C. Taylor (Ed.),
Moscovici, S. & Marková, I. (2000). Ideas and their development: Philosophical Arguments (pp. 1–19). London & Massachusetts:
a dialogue between Serge Moscovici and Ivana Marková. In S. Harvard University Press.
Moscovici. Social Representations. (pp. 224–286). G. Duveen Valsiner, J. (1987). Culture and the Development of Children’s
(Ed.). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Action. Chichester, UK: Wiley.
Moscovici, S. & Marková, I. (2006). The Making of Modern Valsiner, J. (l989). Human Development and Culture. Lexington,
Social Psychology. Cambridge, UK: Polity. MA: D.C. Heath.

508 social repre se ntat i ons as a nt hropology of cu ltu re


Valsiner, J. (1998). The Guided Mind: A Sociogenetic Approach Wagner, W., Duveen, G., Verma, J. & Themel, M. (2000).
to Personality. Cambridge, MA & London, UK: Harvard I have some faith and at the same time I don’t believe’ –
University Press. Cognitive Polyphasia and Cultural Change in India. Journal
Valsiner, J. (2003). Beyond social representations: a theory of of Community and Applied Psychology, 10, 301–314.
enablement. Papers on Social Representations, 12, 7.1–7.16. Wagner, W., Kronberger, N. & Seifert, F. (2002). Collective
Valsiner, J. & Lawrence, J. A. (1996). Human development symbolic coping with new technology: knowledges, images
across the life-span. In J. W. Berry, P. R. Dasen, & T. S. and public discourse. British Journal of Social Psychology, 41,
Saraswathi (Eds.). Handbook of Cross-cultural Psychology: Vol. 323–343.
2 Basic Processes and Developmental Psychology (pp. 69–106). Wagner, W. & Hayes, N. (2005). Everyday Discourse and Common
Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Sense. The Theory of Social Representations. Basingstoke, UK:
Voloshinov, V. N. (1929/1973). Marxism and the Philosophy of Palgrave.
Language. L Matejka and I. R. Titunik (Trans.). New York Wertsch, J. & Batiashvili, N. (2011). Mnemonic Standoffs in
and London: Seminar Press. Deep Memory: Russia and Georgia. In I. Marková & A.
Wagner, W. (1998). Social representations and beyond—brute Gillespie (Eds.). Trust and conflict: Representation, culture and
facts, symbolic coping and domesticated worlds. Culture and dialogue (pp. 37–48). London, UK: Routledge.
Psychology, 4, 297–329. Wilson, Bryan R. (1970). Rationality. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Wagner, W., Duveen, G., Themel, M. & Verma, J. (1999) The Zajonc, R. B. (1965). Social facilitation. Science, 149, 269–274.
modernisation of tradition: Thinking about madness in
Patna, India. Culture & Psychology, 5, 413–445.

m a rková 509
This page intentionally left blank
PA RT
6
Tools for Living:
Transcending Social
Limitations
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Life-Course: A Socio-Cultural
23 Perspective

Tania Zittoun

Abstract
This chapter characterizes a socio-cultural psychology of the life-course, and shows how it differs from
other approaches of the life-course. General principles for such a psychology are highlighted, and a
particular attention to ruptures, transitions, and the processes these involve, is proposed. Such a basic
“grammar” enables us to highlight a few dynamics of development; empirical situations chosen along
typical life-courses exemplify them. Issues to be further examined can thus be highlighted.
Keywords: development, socio-cultural perspectives, life-course, transitions, ruptures

The possibility shadows every single person and speak (in a secret roll, in our genes, or in our social
changes the nature of his life; for (and this is another class)? Or on the contrary, can we “make ourselves”
well-known axiom of existential mathematics) any as we wish? What is our margin of freedom, how
new possibility that existence acquires, even the least much can persons become who or what they want
likely, transforms everything about existence. to be? The reflection on the nature of life-course
(Kundera, 1996, p. 36) finds multiple roots in old philosophical questions
and has found beautiful forms in arts and literature.
The study of the life-course, an important issue in Life trajectories became the object of systematic sci-
the social sciences and psychology since the 1970s, entific investigation relatively recently. In psychol-
can also be considered as the effort to understand the ogy and social sciences, reviews usually consider as
mutual constitution of a developing person and her first life-span studies these of Charlotte Bühler and
changing cultural environments. It is easy to admit Erik Erikson’s analyses of biographies. In the 1950s,
that there is no human life outside of a culture— a certain number of longitudinal studies were pub-
one can thus speak of the “cultural nature” of human lished in the United States, and these gave a new
development (López, Najafi, Rogoff, & Arauz, 2011; grounding for the research on how people develop
Rogoff, 2003) or of the “cultivation” of humans over a life (see Giele & Elder, 1998, for a review).
(Josephs & Valsiner, 2007)—yet how culture medi- Currently, two disciplinary traditions have
ates development demands explanation. The current emerged and have been given contrasting appella-
Oxford Handbook offers various ways of advancing tions. On the one hand, the orientation in psychol-
such understanding; here, I propose to focus on the ogy that considers the development from infancy
person’s changes through his/her life-course. to old age and death calls itself life-span psychol-
ogy (Baltes, Staudinger, & Lindenberger, 1999;
The Study of the Life–Course Overton, 2002). On the other hand, the sociologi-
Why does a person become who he/she is? Is it cal orientation that examines life trajectories con-
true that our fates have been sealed before we even siders itself as developing a life-course theoretical

513
perspective (Elders, 2004). Because these two fields cultural mediation different in a 5-month-old than
of investigation develop in different disciplines, they in a 90-year-old person?
have deepened different questions:
Life-Course Sociology
Life-span psychologists typically begin with
On their side, sociological approaches to the life-
psychological functions and ask questions about
course have been struggling for accounting both
change and stability, individual differences, and
for social and historical effects on personal trajec-
intraindividual plasticity. Life course sociologists
tories and individual agency (see Mayer, 2009, for
typically begin with social change and ask how it
a review). Elder, Kirkpatrick Johnson, and Crosnoe
influences communities and families, and, in turn,
(2004, pp. 11–14) have highlighted five paradig-
trajectories of development. For all their significant
matic principles in life-course theory:
theoretical commonalities, the two perspectives often
begin the research process by asking distinct types of 1. The principle of life-span development:
questions. human development and aging are lifelong
(Shanahan & Porfelli, 2002, p. 399) processes;
2. The principle of agency: individuals construct
Life-Span Psychology their own life-courses and the choices and actions
Since the 1990s, the life-span approach to they take within the opportunities and constraints
development has made itself known thanks to its of history and social circumstance;
elegant propositions. First, it has proposed meta- 3. The principle of time and space: the life-
theoretical principles according to which the role of courses of individuals are embedded and shaped
natural growth and culture vary through life. From by historical times and places they experience over
this perspective, the person’s natural capacities and their lifetimes;
cultural mastery initially grow, until at some point 4. The principle of timing: the developmental
of one’s development, his/her biological capaci- antecedents and consequences of life transitions,
ties start to decline. At this point, culture plays a events, and behavioral patterns vary according to
growing role in one’s life. For example, when sight their timing in a person’s life; and
diminishes, one starts to use glasses; when one gets 5. The principle of linked lives: lives are lived
to the limits of his/her memory, online reference interdependently and socio-historical influences
completes the amount of available information, are expressed through this network of shared
and so forth. However, at some point, the biologi- relationships.
cal state of person declines so much that culture
cannot compensate it anymore. Second, life-span Mainly based on large samples over long peri-
psychology proposes that development is regulated ods, life-course studies have developed complex
through selection, optimization, and compensation methodological strategies enabling combination
(SOC): people first select a certain number of of quantitative and qualitative data so as to show
skills, competencies, or relationships on which they the interacting effects of context and biography,
will invest efforts; they then optimize these selected structure, and agency. They have tried to capture
fields of activity; they finally compensate, in the the commonalities of people born and developing
limits given by the meta-theoretical model, their under comparable socio-historical circumstances—
weaknesses by other means (Baltes, 1986; Baltes, for example, with the help of the notions of cohort
Staudinger, & Lindenberger, 1999). Studies in life- effect “when historical change differentiates the lives
span psychology have particularly explored aging of successive birth cohorts” and period effect, “when
and old age, yet many other researchers over other the impact of social change is relatively uniform
periods of the life-course have been inspired by the across successive birth cohorts” (Elder, Kirkpatrick
model. However, the generality of these principles Johnson, & Crosnoe, 2004, p. 9). However, it is not
does not allow for a more fine-grained analysis of certain that people from a given cohort, in the same
the processes of development nor the specific role period, develop along the same line. Researchers
of culture in these dynamics (Gillespie & Zittoun, have used the notions of social pathways¸ trajectories,
2010). How can we describe the process enabled careers, and navigation to describe the individual
by culture, in what sense does cultural production life-courses people trace within a given social and
participate to development, and in what respect is historical structure (Furlong, 2009). Scholars also

514 l i fe-cour s e
seem to agree on the importance of studying tran- Levy, Ghisletta, Le Goff, Spini, and Widmer (2005,
sitions within trajectories; they have acknowledged p. 365).
their role as turning points—events that “involve
a substantial change in the direction of one’s life, General Principles for a Socio-Cultural
whether subjective or objective” (Elder, Kirkpatrick Perspective on the Life-Course
Johnson & Crosnoe, 2004 p. 8)—and have tried to As much as there is life, there is change: things
capture their long-term consequences. move, evolve, are constructed, become organized,
If we accept the five principles above and retain decompose, and perish. Galaxies dilate and suns
the importance of transitions in a life-course, how die; it rains, water evaporates; our bodies grow and
can we account for the processes whereby a person become weaker; we inhale and exhale; the seasons
might decide the course of his/her life within a given pass. As humans, we perceive discourses and infor-
sets of constraints and relations? How can we account mation, we think and dream, we communicate with
for what is unexpected? And how is this connected to others, and as William James (1892) wrote, our
the cultural means at his/her disposal? consciousness flows—it flows, as one might say it
rains, or it snows. Human perception of these pass-
Using Traditions—Studying Transitions ing events, realized thanks to various social and cul-
Research from the two traditions of life-course tural markers, produce time—as a personal sense, or
and lifespan studies have been published in separate as a collective history.
journals, and researchers have presented their stud- Cultural psychology tries to account for the
ies in different conferences and have developed their experience of humans in time and in social and cul-
own research traditions. Only on rare occasions do tural environments. A person’s birth takes place in
they attempt to see their contributions as comple- a certain moment of history (of the group within
menting each other (Levy, Ghisletta, Le Goff, Spini, he is born), and from that moment on, his/her life
& Widmer, 2005), then facing complex meth- will unfold as times goes on. It also takes place in
odological as well as theoretical issues. These two a family, with its beliefs, located in an area of the
traditions have also kept their distances toward the town, in a country that has current policies—that
current developing field of cultural or socio-cultural is, in a social, material, and symbolic environment.
psychology (and reciprocally)—even if their object As the person develops, she will explore that sphere
is ultimately the same. Indeed, from a socio-cultural of experience, its boundaries, and explore other
perspective, it is clear that it would be absurd to spheres. Finally, each of the others met by the per-
consider human development out of its cultural, son are changing him or her, the mutual relation-
social, and historical constraining and enabling ships of persons, environments, societies, with their
conditions; yet for various reasons, socio-cultural own rhythm and periodicities, produce the com-
psychology neither developed models enabling us plex environment in which a person’s life occurs.
to fully understand the nature of “cohort effects” Hence, cultural psychology examines the ongoing
over individual trajectories (but see Sato, Yasuda, transactions (Dewey & Bentley, 1946) or mutual
Kido, Arakawa, Mizogushi, & Valsiner, 2007) nor adjustments between developing persons and their
gave much attention to the evolution of the bio- changing environments.
logical constraints of development. In that respect, One of the specificities of human life, over other
both lifespan and life-course studies might contrib- forms of organisms, is to be found in the central
ute to our enquiry. However, the core issue of socio- role of meaning making (Bruner, 1990). Young
cultural psychology is to account for the life of humans not only perceive their environment, they
humans as meaning-makers. Here, we first need to also feel it, develop memories and expectations.
define the specificities of a socio-cultural approach Their environments not only provide them with
to the study of the life-course, which is open both food and warmth but also with lullabies, rhymes,
to the multilinearity of development and to the cen- and fairytales. Children learn to read other people’s
trality of human meaning-making in their worlds of intentions, and they make themselves understood;
culture. We will thus propose a theoretical model for as they grow older, they learn to use and produce
exploring the life-course, drawing on various studies words, toys, colors, and ideas, to understand what
of different traditions, using the notion of transi- occurs around them, to represent their ideas of
tion as transdisciplinary “analyzer” as proposed by the world, and to create alternative realities. On

z it tou n 515
the other hand, the experience of human groups is In psychology, there has been for many years a
deposed and registered in concrete objects—a car is tendency to identify structures of personality, and
the result of many generations’ experience of how to types of character, as if these were acquired once for
facilitate human locomotion—and in cultural ele- all—one believed that if Paul was an introvert he
ments primarily meant to carry meaning, such as would remain so, or that if he had a low IQ he just
chronicles, novels, psychological textbooks, and car- had to live with it. Other parts of psychology have
toons that convey, under a semiotic form, people’s in contrast tried to account for how these structures
experience of life. have developed through time—what is the genesis
A core idea of cultural psychology is that each of cognitive structure (Piaget, 1967), how a per-
person, as one particular instantiation in time and son’s identity matures over years (Erikson, 1959).
space of the infinities of shape that can take humans, Finally, recent approaches have proposed models
is absolutely unique. That person, exposed to the that emphasize the mutability of humans—Paul is
discourses, shapes, and rites of his/her environment, not a father and a plumber, he is doing the father or
is likely to understand them in a sufficiently shared positioning himself as a father in a specific sequence
manner so as to remain in interactions with others; of dialogue with his son’s teacher, which vanishes as
but these discourses, rites, or lullabies will also find he is doing the soccer fan with his friends 2 hours
a form of unique understanding, and translation, in later (Harré & Davies. 1990). Similar debates have
her mind—where it will integrated with other traces been legion in life-course studies: Is it true that a
of experiences, bring to psychological reorganiza- child’s fate is defined by the first 3 years of his/her
tions, and so forth. Such process of internalization life (e.g., by the attachment style developed, or by
thus brings the person to develop his/her own “per- the mode of resolution of his oedipal conflict?), or
sonal culture” (Valsiner, 1997). On this basis, he/she by the profession, income, and numbers of books
will also be able to communicate, make his-/herself read—that is, social class—of his/her parents?
understood, move, take specific postures, by which Whether we change or remain the same through
he/she externalizes (translates unto a semiotic form) time, whether we are constrained by the hazards of
what occurs in him/her, or within specific interac- our birth or whether we can develop in any direc-
tive dynamics (Lawrence & Valsiner, 2003; Valsiner, tion, is a recurring question in human history. It
2000). Internalization and externalization can thus has been treated as a philosophical question (about
be seen as the core processes by which meaning can freedom and determinacy) and as a political issue
be produced, individually and collectively. Cultural (whether we are produced by our class, can eman-
psychology examines human development with a cipate, or can determine our own fate). As cultural
specific attention to the dynamics of meaning-making psychologists, we can take a nuanced position.
in which groups and individual are engaged.
With the help of other sciences, cultural psychol- Transitive and Intransitive Change
ogy has developed a theoretical basis, notions, and Drawing on dynamic system theory, cultural
models to account for human development, its trans- psychology can distinguish between sorts of change.
actions with environments, and dynamics of mean- In an open system, some changes are quasi-circular:
ing-making (especially Boesch, 1991; Cole, 1996; people eat cakes, digest them, eliminate them, and
Josephs & Valsiner, 2007; Valsiner 1997, 1998, 2007; eat again. Students read books, write notes, raise
Valsiner & Rosa, 2007; Wertsch, 1991). questions, check references, and borrow more books
in the library. There is a “virtuous circle”; even if
Life-Course As Lifelong Development each book is different from the other, it remains
Stating that everything constantly changes is of a book that will be borrowed, read, and serve as a
course just a starting point. It is clear that change source of questions. Such changes are called transi-
occurs only within a constant tension between con- tive, in the sense that the circle is “symmetrical”—it
tinuity and change. Our bodies remain “the same” can be considered from any point, and the other
even if each of the cells of our organism is replaced points will be found (this is what van Geert [2003]
every year. Paul can cut his hair, change jobs, and has called a “level 1 change”). Of course, transitive
divorce, but he remains Paul—for himself and for changes can also involve slight displacement and
his mother, and even for his ex-wife, even if she has evolution—if Paul and Mary have the habits of
fallen out of love. How can we account for the fact swapping novels they have read and liked, then they
that we are both the same and not the same? are in an transitive movement; yet one day Paul can

516 l i fe-cour s e
propose to Mary not a book, but a DVD, which Ruptures are what life-course researchers call
will also bring Mary to propose a Paul a DVD she “turning points” or “critical moments” (see above).
liked (it can be distinguished from the former form They usually constitute bifurcation points in a trajec-
of transitivity by being called a level 2 change: here, tory – some pathways are opened, others are closed,
the structure remains the same even if some com- and generally their outcomes are not yet decided
ponents vary). Other changes lead to total new (unless the rupture is one’s own death). Hence,
forms of conduct or situation, from which there is Paul’s new degree opens the possibility of work-
no coming back: if Paul has an accident and loses a ing as a lawyer, but also of starting full-time studies
leg, then he will not recover it, and he will have to again; his accident forbids him to play soccer but
reorganize his life accordingly; if Paul goes to eve- instead, after re-education, brings him to kayaking,
ning classes and gets a degree in law, then he will which he always wanted to do.
not “unlearn” what he as acquired, and this can also The interesting thing is that ruptures experi-
open new life possibilities. Such no-return changes enced by a person demand substantial, intransitive
can be called intransitive (or a level 3 change); these changes—processes of adjustment, or adaptation,
require real re-elaboration of one’s understanding, between him/her and his/her environment. It is
means of actions, or relationship to the environ- these processes that we will call transitions. From a
ment. From such a perspective, it is clear that these life-course perspective, then, ruptures followed by
different sorts of change also have various degrees of transitions are moments of accelerated or catalyzed
freedom—transitive changes do not enable radical changes. For researchers, they offer the opportunity
innovation, whereas intransitive require them. And, to study substantial, observable development, and
in turn, intransitive changes are sometimes imposed this probably explains the current popularity of
but can also be deliberately provoked. studies on transitions.
Change occurs in continuous forms, as slow In life-course research, the notion of transition
accumulation of reconfigurations of person–world– has been used to designate moments of change
others dynamics, or through events that appear as either from the perspective of a person’s life trajec-
caused by or causing discontinuities. Continuous tory or from an observer’s perspective. Adopting
change has been described as processes of matura- such second perspective, the studies on the
tion, growth, increase of expertise, and so and so “school-to-work transition,” for example, exam-
forth, which have been privileged in the studies of ine the fact that groups of students end school
child learning and development. Events bringing and enter the labor market. Such a perspective
discontinuities specifically call for change. Studies has enabled researchers to distinguish “norma-
on youth and adult life have mainly focused on tive transitions,” which are expected to be expe-
these. rienced by certain group of persons of a certain
age in a given society, from non-normative transi-
Ruptures and Transitions tions (Elder et al., 2004), which affects the way in
Not every change has durable consequences— which individuals perceive changes as ruptures or
this appears very clearly once we replace types of not. It is usually easier to engage in a transition
changes within a person’s life trajectory. From that in a normative way than non-normative, because
perspective, transitive changes are part of the daily one is more likely to find appropriate social sup-
transactions between the person and his/her envi- port and acceptance: for example, when a young
ronment, whereas intransitive changes are linked graduate applies for his first job, his lack of experi-
to more clear-cut changes that we can call ruptures. ence is likely to be tolerated as part of a “normal”
Ruptures are moments in which existing modes of school-to-work transition, whereas if Paul applies
progressive adjustment are interrupted. A rupture for a first job after his studies in middle life, he
can result from internal factors or causes (as when might be considered as too old for too little expe-
Paul decided to leave his wife after a long period of rience. Hence, the normative nature of a transi-
doubt, or when he decided to take evening classes) tion might facilitate the processes of change in
or by external ones (as when he lost his leg); they which a person is engaged, whereas non-norma-
can be expected by the person, as when a nurs- tive transitions might be experienced as stronger
ery child is anticipating and imagining his first subjective ruptures. More generally, such studies
day at primary school, or not (Winther-Lindqvist, highlight certain of the structure of constraints
2009). within which change takes place.

z it tou n 517
In contrast, when we focus on ruptures actually and how we experience the world. It is thus impor-
perceived as such by people, as we do when we focus tant to emphasize that if it is clear that biology sets
on meaning-making, we observe that socially observ- important constraints in human development and
able ruptures are not always felt as such (Zittoun, change (Baltes, 1987), then its action always already
2006a); also, people experience as ruptures and is in great part mediated, if not guided, by individual
engage in transitions for events that are not visible and collective semiotic dynamics.
for an observer (e.g., a grandmother died, a close On the other hand, human development is also
friendship ended, or the person developed some new canalized by social or cultural conditions. But what
self-awareness). do we mean by that? The social is so much “every-
where” that talking about the “influence” of the
Limited Plasticity social is as absurd as talking about the influence
From a socio-cultural perspective, we need to of “matter” on cells—cells are made out of mat-
propose a model accounting for the ways in psycho- ter, matter circulates through their inner and outer
logical change is enabled and constrained by bio- membranes, it is around them . . . More interesting,
logical and social situations. and more difficult, is to define ways of describing
On the one hand, it is clear that one cannot speak the multiples modalities through which the social
of meaning-making without considering the person’s and cultural becomes psychological and back.
embodied existence. Any meaning-making is just one Many authors have proposed such descriptions
part of the ongoing processes of perceiving, moving (see Valsiner & Van der Veer, 2000, for a review;
in, understanding, acting in an environment that we Valsiner 1998, 2007; Zittoun, Valsiner, Vedeler,
constantly experience. In that sense, experience seems Salgado, Goncalves, & Ferring, in press).
enabled and limited by our senses, the capacities of Here, building on the socio-cultural tradition,
our bodies and minds—which are plastic to some I will distinguish five modalities on a continuum
extent only. However, these capacities are them- through which the social and the person interact.
selves mediated by our own meaning-making (we First, the social and the cultural is already “in the
overhear advices that we do not like, or hormonal mind” of each person. Since birth, each instant
processes are modified by moods or achievements) through interactions with the world, the person
and by our understanding of our social and cultural internalizes portions of discourses and signs that
environment (that valorizes certain capacities rather will participate to the development of his/her
than others, encourage us to develop other, and cure thinking and acting possibilities. This constitutes
and replace further ones). For example, we can imag- the mind—as always already social (see below).
ine that Paul developed a good memory as a con- Second, every time a person interacts with another
sequence of his interest in soccer and his intention person, there is the construction of the social—as
to be acknowledged as expert; this memory then coordinated perspective, which is eventually desig-
helped him as he started his late studies, even if his nated by symbolic meaning exchanged (Gillespie,
bad hearing could have limited his participation to 2010). Third, every time a person interacts with or
seminar discussion. Also, we can imagine that Paul creates an artifact, the person is actually interact-
is a rather handsome slim man and that his usual ing with a symbolic object—an object that desig-
facility to charm people enabled him to develop a nates a world of shared meaning in a social group
sense of self-confidence; hence, received for a job on the one side, and his own life on the other
interview, he might have made a good impression (Zittoun, 2005, 2010). Fourth, each sphere of
in an environment that valorizes self-confidence and experience in which people are located are socially
slimness. Hence, our bodies are important in sense- structured and organized according to rules,
making as it is as embodied person that we experi- which allocate them rights and mutual positions;
ence ourselves, the world, and others, and through it is supported and usually reinforced by material
these bodies that we make sense of our experiences; arrangements (it is often called a “social frame”).
also, it is as embodied beings that we are recognized Hence, a school in a closed environment, such as
by others and addressed and treated by our societies. a boarding school, creates a total institution that
Indeed, it is also clear that our societies, with the gives quite clear indications to people about what
quality of the environment it creates, the modes of can be done, or not (Goffman, 1958). Fifth, the
life it encourages, its industries and medical systems, social and cultural is pervasive; present in the daily
shape the changes of our bodies, as other perceive us, organization of the public and mediatic space; it

518 l i fe-cour s e
imposes, on the fringe of our consciousness, cer- stories of colleagues “turning green” or scientists
tain messages, values, and beliefs that constitute abandoning their universities to live on sailing boats.
our belonging to a social world. For example, the At every step of our lives, social discourses, fictions,
smoking bans in most north European towns have narratives, and gossips present us with alternative
created zones for smokers separated by a yellow lives. Nourished by these semiotic means, but also
line on the floor and glass boxes in airports, and by our own past, affective lives, and our imagina-
they impose smokers to freeze in front of restau- tion, we constantly explore the possible outcomes of
rants while their beer warms up inside, repeatingly situations, alternative choices, new versions of the
making smokers feel unwanted, and non-smokers past, or possible futures. Each moment, we engage
learn to see them as deviant (see Zittoun, Valsiner in an action by closing down an alternative.
et al., in press). In addition, the world in which we live is not
Meanings move from one modality to the predictable, neither at an individual level nor at a
other. The meaning of the smoker–non-smoker collective one. Cohort- studies retrospectively show
segregation is that “smoking is bad,” which even- how a given generation went through comparable
tually becomes internalized and guides the action events—for example, very old people in Switzerland
of the not-yet-smokers who hesitate to buy a first all experienced two World Wars, years of crises, and
pack of cigarettes. The issue of the smoking ban years of economical optimism (Lalive d’Epinay &
can also become an object of discussion between Spini, 2008), yet how these events have affected
peers. The famous Marlboro poster is an artifact each life is not predictable. Hence, if sociologists
that now crystallizes these many meanings for a thought that in the 1960s (an until the mid-1980s)
middle-aged viewer: the imaginary freedom asso- work trajectories were quite linear (e.g., a middle-
ciated with smoking, now overwritten by the fact class young worker would enter in a company,
that “Mr. Marlboro” had cancer, by the scandals of make his way through the hierarchy, and have a
tobacco companies manipulating public opinion, good retirement), then retrospective analysis have
and the present smoking ban. Interacting with the shown that unexpected events (such as an evolu-
social and cultural around us, more or less reflec- tion of the market’s needs), disturbed predictions,
tively, we constantly internalize and revise our ear- and personal crises brought people to have very per-
lier understanding and our systems of orientation. sonal trajectories, not so much depending on their
In turn, we can also externalize our opinions, make social or economical background or initial train-
our friends change their views, produce discourse ing as on a synthesis of unexpected opportunities,
or art pieces that will be seen by others, and use luck in meeting others, accidents, random injustice,
various means to reshape our environment; we personal imagination, re-examination of one’s situa-
can smoke out of the smoker zone, move coun- tion, and moments of personal decisions (Goodwin
try, or, like in certain parts of Switzerland, use our & O’Connor, 2009). Hence, if life trajectories were
democratic rights to show that the smoking ban is never fully predictable (i.e., people always had acci-
unconstitutional and suppress it. dents the day before graduation, fell in love with a
person from a different social class, or experienced
Multilinearity, Unpredictability a war), then our contemporary society brings us to
Life is not a quiet river. It is a tortuous torrent, deal with a much more generalized uncertainty.
full of surprises. It can be characterized in two The second characteristic of life trajectory is
ways. their multilinearity: there is always more than one
First, the development of a child or a person is way to get to comparable points in the life-course.
not linear and therefore cannot be predicted. Our Studies classically have shown that children can
contemporary societies encourage people to travel, start walking after crawling or might just stand up
work or study abroad, or meet foreigners in their and walk (Bottos et al. 2008; Valsiner, 2000); one
office or in their street; we are exposed to a wide can become a lawyer studying straight after college
variety of information about alternative life choices, or as a mature learner; one can have children early
other countries, and innovative professions; we live in life and then establish oneself as a professional,
in a world that has lost its economical and ecologi- or one can acquire a professional stability and then
cal stability; we know that every other marriage will have children; and one can learn the violin as an
end up in a divorce; we are offered ways to alter our adult. This has two implications. First, not everyone
bodily appearance and physical strength; we hear develops skill A in the same spatio-temporal place

z it tou n 519
(e.g., in the classroom, third grade); very often, skill as when I consider what if I would have another cup
A is developed in other circumstances. Second, the of coffee, or can imply major construction, as when
so-called “learning disabilities” often more result what if I gathered the best scientists in the world and
from the fact that a person might be engaged in a we would build a spaceship that could bring a coun-
pathway that does not enable him/her to change or try to the next liveable planet. Considering imagina-
develop that particular understanding or skill—an tion, one can understand why very old people, with
alternative way might enable the person to develop limited mobility and reduced social networks, still
in such way that the disability is suppressed or consider themselves as happy as years earlier (Lalive
avoided (Vygotsky, 1929). d’Epinay & Spini 2008) or how people in very hard
Unpredictability and multilinearity always char- detentions conditions could actually survive thanks
acterized human lives; only our current society to the powers of their mind—living in faith, explor-
constantly reminds us of multiple choices we have, ing their past, or living alternative lives (Bouska &
the ambivalence in which we live (Sato, Fukuda, Pinerova, 2009). Such hypothesis is also needed to
Hidaka, Kido, Nishida, & Akasaka, 2011), and the understand why, in all times of visible or invisible
uncertainty that we have to tolerate in daily lives. oppression, some people are taking the risk to object
Do we have more freedom, or are we more slave of to absurd rules or engage in changing the society.
our own fears? Imagination is usually accompanied by a good dose
of forgetting—forget that we are on Earth just for a
Freedom in the Life-Course minute and that our action will not change much
Life-courses depend on many personal choices, (something that depressive people usually cannot for-
social forces, and random events; they are not pre- get anymore). Of course, some people might object
dictable in a strict sense. Studies that have used that surviving in a situation of oppression thanks to
mainly “objective” data (i.e., income, health assess- a world of one’s own or to minute degrees of free-
ment, and standardized tests of well-being) have dom is still a form of alienation; but actually, who
tended to show, initially, the structuring effect of can say whose alienation is bigger, that of the bank
the social or the irresistible effect of biological con- director who plays golf, flies first class, and eats sushi
straints on human lives; this has then been debated (as it is expected) or the street cleaner who writes
by others who have wanted to confer some agency absurd novels after work?
to actors (Furlong, 2009; Goodwin & O’Connor, The freedom of imagining is made possible
2009; Levy et al., 2005). However, if one consid- through the mediation of signs, and so it intervenes
ers that human lives are as much made by what is at each of the modalities of our encounter with the
invisible (i.e., what people believe in, who matters social; we can imagine on our own, we imagine
to them, how they find the world meaningful or as we discuss with others, we enter in imaginary
absurd, how the enjoy the sunset or an illegal copy worlds when we read novels, and we can continue
of an alternative music band) than by what is visible being surprised at our environment and remember
(i.e., their income or their ability to run 100 meters) how it was and how it could be. We are infinitely
then the discussion takes another dimension. constrained by our social and cultural environment
Indeed, within and beyond the modalities of and yet very free from it. However, sometimes, it
social constraints as defined above, people have becomes harder to imagine, and this we have to
various means to expand their life worlds. People account for. In what follows, I propose concentrat-
engage not only in reasonable or practical activities, ing on two of the five modalities of the social and
they are also constantly imagining—beyond consid- cultural as part of our lives: how we encounter it in
ering what is, they engage in thinking what if (the our immediate environment, and how it is already
distinction comes from Vaihinger, 1924; Josephs, in our mind, as part of our personal cultures, con-
Valsiner, & Surgan, 1999). Imagination—that is, stituting a system of orientation.
thinking beyond the here and now—takes various
directions: remembering, which is an imagination A Sketch of a Theory of Transitions
of the past, thinking alternatives in the present in the Life-Course
(I am sitting here at my desk, but what if I were The Plurality of Spheres of Experiences in
now at the movies or walking the dog or visiting Contemporary World
Tunisia), and anticipation, which is imagining the In our complex worlds, we participate in various
future. These imaginations can be minimal loops, social and material settings, which are structured by

520 l i fe-cour s e
certain rules and organized through specific webs is perceived as having some stability is dynamic. If
of meaning, that participate to the allocation of the person is essentially a meaning-maker and grows
mutual social positions and define ranges of possi- and develops through culture, then the mind has
ble, encouraged, or forbidden actions. Typically, a to be described as a semiotic system, producing
child participates in family life, classroom interac- sense about real and possible worlds. In psychol-
tions, playground during school time, family life, ogy, various models are based on similar premises.
and perhaps going to football rehearsals, visiting The model of the psyche promoted by Freud pre-
his cousins, or gaming on the Playstation®. Each cisely describes how streams of thought transit
of these settings creates, for the person, a specific through layers of consciousness and undergo vari-
sphere of experience. These spheres of experiences, ous semiotic transformations, under the constrain-
partly defined by the environment (as affording ing forces of internalized cultural rules on the one
certain actions and thoughts rather than others) side and biological needs and strives on the other
and by the person, have been described in different (see Salvatore & Zittoun, 2011). The “dialogical self
traditions (as social frames, microsystems, commu- model” represents dynamics taking place between
nity of practices, symbolic contexts, etc.) that meta- various I-positions, resulting from internalized posi-
phorically consider that each sphere is “bounded” tions developed in specific social situations, within
(socially and/or personally perceived as different the “imaginal landscape of the self ” (Hermans &
from another one). Kempens, 1993). Here, we follow the idea that as
Ruptures, as what generate transitions processes, humans develop in cultural world and internalize
sometimes are caused by the passage of one per- signs under some form of translation, these become
son from one sphere of experience to another one; progressively organized, differentiated, and hierar-
sometimes ruptures occur within a given sphere chized (Valsiner, 1998, 2007; Werner & Kaplan,
of experience; and sometimes what causes them 1963). We learn to identify some experiences as
is more general (e.g., a war) and therefore might “sweet” and “likeable”; we organize them in classes
be experienced in parallel in different spheres of of experiences, which we then prefer or avoid; our
experiences. general beliefs (i.e., that people are good) guide each
There has been abundant research on various of our actions—for example, trusting unknown per-
forms of transitions between spheres of experiences sons, and so on.
(these are often perceived as problematic and are Some of our experiences get organized and clas-
socially more visible). Authors sometimes distin- sified into formal categories, which are usually
guish vertical transitions, which suppose a devel- called “concepts” and are the basis of scientific rea-
opment through time (such as the passage from soning—hence, from that perspective, we say that
primary school to secondary school for children, what a dog, a cat, and a mouse have in common
which is actually an intransitive change), from hor- is that they are mammals. However, we also have
izontal transitions, the daily passage from home other, more experience-based modes of organizing
to school, and back (which is a transitive change). experiences: one might also say that a mouse, a cat,
Given our observations above, we will not call and a dog have in common the fact that they live
the daily passage from home to school and back a at my grandmother’s or that they run after each
transition, although the question of how a person other in some cartoons. Developmental psychology
manages these passages (sometimes thematized as has usually considered such grouping of experience
boundary crossing) is a relevant question from a life- as preconceptual (Nelson, 2007; Vygotsky, 1934),
course perspective. In effect, it raises the question of as a step to acquire the mode of organization of
transfer of knowledge or, rather, moments in which experience required by our society (and schooling
a skill typical for one sphere of experience, a way system). It is also typically the mode of organiz-
to present oneself, can be used in another sphere of ing experience observed by psychologists study-
experience—what we have called boundary crossing ing the modes of memory of various indigenous
events (Grossen, Zittoun, & Ros, 2012). groups that had no formal education (Cole, 1997).
However, such more intuitive, affective-based orga-
The Mind As a Meaning System nization of experience remains active and can easily
What is it of the self that remains self while be convoked in daily lives (Zittoun, 2010); their
changing? In the dynamic perspective outlined logic is not conceptual, but affective, based on per-
above, we need a working model in which even what sonal relevance.

z it tou n 521
Preferred associations between components of temporality to one’s time perspective (Green,
experience can be said to be grouped in semiotic 2000; Salvatore & Zittoun, 2011). Hence, the
sets, often in prereflective ways; hence, a person can same experience of meeting a deer in the fields
think herself to be a “decent woman,” because she can on the one side feed my experience of wild
does not go out with foreigners, she has good cook- animals, my knowledge about deer inhabiting
ing skills, and she expects a decent man to marry this countryside, and complete my personal nar-
her (Zittoun, Avelling, Cornish, & Gillespie, 2011). rative; in parallel, it might enter in more floating
Such semiotic sets are partly organized according to and much less conscious fantasies about wildlife,
one’s experience and partly caused by the internal- entrapment, or cannibalism.1
ization of shared values or social representations. Examining daily reasoning as a socially situated
They constrain one’s actions and feeling about practice, the facility with which some signs are
one’s actions; they can be reshaped through experi- made socially available, internalized, and acquired
ence (self-reflection, or psychotherapy, see Zittoun, a power to reorganize a person’s life is at times
Valsiner et al., in preparation) and they slowly striking. For example, it is very easy for a teach-
evolve. They also can be the object of progressive ers’ committee to jointly consider that a series of
distantiations and reorganizations. disconnected actions of a little girl actually belong
Progressively, certain zones of one’s personal to the same semiotic set conventionally designated
culture acquire some stability because they are as attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD)
recurrent, efficient, and enable a good enough (Hjörne & Säljö, 2004). In turn, offering a girl to
understanding of one’s environment. People hence be treated as ADHD might be extremely conve-
define their version of a “system of orientation”—a nient for her, as it brings adults to be more toler-
sort of meaning-producing system that renders ant of her actions; this might bring her to more or
the world intelligible and actionable, made out less deliberately act as-if she were an ADHD child
of semiotic sets and concepts (Zittoun, 2006a). (Abbey & Valsiner, 2003). Such processes might
A system or orientation is produced through pro- durably shape the life-course of a person. Such
gressive distantiation from experience, its differ- analyses also suggest that it does not take much to
entiation in more or less formal classes (semiotic attribute different values to one’s experience and to
sets, categories, scientific concepts) and progres- reshape a life-course!2
sive distantiation. Distantiation enables us, on a In summary, a person’s view on the world is a
first dimension, to transform more concrete, spe- randomly stabilized system of orientation, and
cific, embodied experience into abstract and more bases for sense-making processes, resulting from
general values and to have the latter to guide and the internalization of various socially situated and
channel concrete experiences. Of course, these shared experiences, as well as from the responses her
can be more or less mutually adjusted: it is quite externalizations find in the world. Systems of ori-
often the case that young people have certain entation are the basis through which a person con-
values of being “good students,” which is con- fers sense to his/her experience, which includes the
tradicted by poor school results, for example, or affective valuation of experience, its semiotization,
that they decide to become “non-violent vegetar- turning it into possible narratives, and the basis of
ians” yet find difficult to refuse a nice steak. On development of more generalized beliefs and values
what can be seen as second dimension, distan- guiding one’s life.
tiation enables us to organize experiences along The study of the life-course can thus be seen as
what people feel to be a time perspective—some the study of the slow evaluation and variation of
experiences are connected to earlier ones, others people’s systems of orientation, which are likely to
are felt as oriented toward future—although it is require reorganization of semiotic sets or transfor-
clear that any new experiences bring a reorganiza- mation along the two dimensions of distantiation
tion of past experiences. However, in parallel to and time. Of course, what the metaphorical notion
these processes of differentiation, hierarchization, of system of orientation designates cannot be stud-
and time orientation, other links organize traces ied directly; it can be only inferred on the basis of
of experiences according to logics of affective or people’s externalization. In what follows, I propose
subjective similarity. Such affective logic enters in to examine of transitions in people’s lives, as these
dynamics of free association, can connote different offer occasions of changing and to elaborate new
zones of experience, and superimpose a different meanings.

522 l i fe-cour s e
Ruptures and Transitions valuation of the situation, working through affects,
Psychology, as well as many other developmental or the linking of a situation to one’s own experience
sciences, has been looking for moments of progres- and in one’s time perspective (Perret-Clermont &
sive evolution as well as of sudden change, called Zittoun, 2002; Zittoun, Duveen, Gillespie, Psaltis, &
alternatively “irritations,” “disequilibration,” “turn- Ivinson, 2003; Zittoun, 2005, 2006a).
ing points,” “conflicts,” and so forth (see Zittoun, Learning processes have been widely studied by
2009). Although there is something structurally researchers focusing on transitions between institu-
comparable in all these developmental studies, it is tions, or from school to work (see below). Learning
important to see that what is considered as changing designates the acquisition of knowledge and skills,
or being re-equilibrated or re-elaborated after a dis- which are often identified through the fact that a
rupting event depends on the theoretical perspec- person can actually solve a problem or handle a situ-
tive envisaged, the object of study, and the models ation. Identity processes, including the elaboration of
used to represent its usual functioning. social identities, issues of positioning and recogni-
In a psychology focused on the development of tion, or self-definition, have been the focus of stud-
persons through the life-course, the object of study ies of life changes, but also have more recently been
is the person. Because we consider persons as mean- included in studies in adult learning and learning in
ing-makers, we have to consider ruptures perceived sensitive populations. Identity processes are engaged
as such (and not, for example, the reorganization when a person is required to define who he/she is
of schemes involved as a child realized that a quan- (in a job interview, in a questionnaire) or when he/
tity of liquid remains the same even if it changes she has to stand for what he/she believes he/she is
glass; Piaget, 1941). Hence, the notion of transition (often because he/she is treated in a different man-
designates here the processes triggered by a rupture ner). Sense-making dynamics have been approached
experienced by a person and that lead to a progres- through studies on narratives, biographical elabora-
sive, new adaptation between the person and his/ tion in the life-course, or representation of the future
her environment. (It is, of course, clear that the new (Bruner, 1990; Dominicé, 2007; Mc Adams &
“adjusted” situation still involves changes but only Logan, 2006; Masdonati, 2007), but within transi-
the smooth transactions of transitive changes.) But tion and life-course research, rarely as an overarch-
what is re-elaborated during transition dynamics? ing process. In some studies, sense-making processes
How can this adjustment be made? and learning, or identity and learning, are seen as
At one level, it is the system of orientation of the mutually dependent. However, our proposition is
person that has to be reconfigured. But this con- that sense making, a direct production of what we
struct is extremely abstract, phenomenologically have called a system of organization, plays a central
inaccurate, and difficult to operationalize. Actually, role both in identity changes and in learning.
our system of orientation and semiotic sets appear to
us in some forms of stabilized configuration, which Uses of Resources in Transitions
people and social scientists identify under different People experiencing ruptures in their life-course
labels in different contexts. Hence, identity (what a might use any available information or help to facil-
person thinks she is, or how others recognize her) is itate processes of transitions. Beyond the umbrella
a stabilized or recurrent sets of beliefs and meaning notion of “copying”, it is possible to study what
about oneself. We can thus define a model that is resources people find in themselves or in the envi-
closer to data and phenomenological experience—a ronment and how they use them to facilitate these
midrange model (Zittoun, 2008). Research in devel- processes. Many of these resources play an impor-
opment and the learning sciences have developed, tant role in facilitating the process of imagination,
through numerous studies, notions that enable us to enabling the consideration of alternative options,
capture some aspects of the person’s changing activ- reconsidering personal narratives, or opening pos-
ity after ruptures. Hence, at another level, grouping sible futures.
these analyses, we have proposed to consider that One important class of resources is institutional;
ruptures in the life-course lead to three mutually many social settings are actually meant to facilitate
dependent lines of change: processes of identity transition processes in the life-course. Vocational
definition, perception or positioning; processes of trainings, birth preparation courses and groups of
learning or definition of modes of understanding or parents, alcoholic anonymous, and religious con-
acting; and processes of sense-making, linked to the gregations are such settings, which might more or

z it tou n 523
less tolerate exploration and offer a safe space for processes, and it might also offer entry points for
try-and-fails, and support identity changes, sense- practitioners (teachers, parents, counsellors) who
making or the question of skills. Then, people often accompany people in different moments of transi-
activate interpersonal relationships, which might play tions in the life-course.
an important role in offering a protected space to The three types of changes—learning, identity
experience sharing, dialogue, mutual perspective- and sense-making—are deeply related and mutu-
taking, and distantiation from experience, whether ally dependent. In most cases, changing one of
it is friendships or family or professional “transition- these aspects will imply changes in one of the other
helpers” such as counsellors, priests, and psycholo- aspects, in the shorter or longer term (see Fig. 23.1).
gists. People also might look for, and more or less For example, an adult that takes language classes
deliberately use semiotic resources—social knowl- (learning) might progressively feel more competent
edge, information, scientific knowledge, (includ- and, consequently, take more initiative in his/her
ing what can be more specifically called symbolic workplace, where he/she might then be given new
resources)—cultural elements that primarily demand responsibilities, which changes his/her social and
an imaginary experience, such as films, novels, arts, personal definition (identity); in turn, the person
and poems (Gillespie & Zittoun, 2010; Zittoun, might then imagine new options for his/her life—
2006a). Symbolic resources might play important for example, further studies or a professional change
roles of mediation of transition and processes, first (sense).
because they support and guide affective imagi- From this follows that when a person who has
nary experiences (isolated from daily constraints), experienced a rupture seems to resist one of these
and second, because their semiotic form provides changes required by a new situation, the problem is
people with means to contain, take distance from, often that one of the two other changes is impeded.
and transform personal experiences. Finally, people For example, if after arrival in a new school, a for-
might simply use their own reflective ability, and in merly good student does not learn anymore (NO
a less mediated way draw on their past experiences learning), it might be that he/she cannot tolerate
to establish links between situations, take distance, the position of a newcomer he/she has in this new
and redefine problems—what we might call per- school (NO identity change); or perhaps the family
sonal resources. of the young person plans to soon return to a for-
As a contribution to a life-course socio-cultural eign country where he/she would anyway take on
psychology, it is very fruitful to describe the pro- the family company for which this knowledge is not
cesses whereby uses of various resources support required (NO sense).
transition processes (for such analysis, see Zittoun, Then, as noted above, each person participates
2006a, Zittoun, Cornish, Gillespie, & Aveling, to a plurality of spheres of experiences. It is very
2008). As we will see in the examples below, it is often the case that transition processes start in one
possible to show how each resource used by a per- of the spheres of experience only; yet these can
son facilitates (or not) playful exploration, and extend beyond these boundaries, to others’ spheres
consequently, identity changes, the acquisition of of experiences, which might then evolve at vari-
knowledge, or sense-making processes and thus, the ous speeds. The plurality of spheres of experiences
transformation of one’s system of orientation. has interacting effects, which can be stabilizing or
destabilizing, facilitating transition processes or
Dynamics and Variations in the impeding them. A teenager finishing compulsory
Life-Course
The study of the life-course has to account for the
complex interplay of social changes, the constrain- Knowledge
ing role of culture, psychological development,
and the margin of freedom of each person in given
circumstances. Identifying spheres of experiences, Identity
ruptures, processes of transitions, resources used by
persons, and the work of imagination, one might Sense
attempt to capture some of the dynamics of the life-
course. Rendering visible such dynamics might be
useful for the identification of further comparable Figure 23.1 Mutual dependency of dynamics of transition.

524 l i fe-cour s e
school might experience a rupture in his educa- Finally, to generate change in any of these
tional trajectory; yet he might, in parallel, still reg- aspects, a person has to engage to some degree in
ularly attend his piano classes, his theatre activities, exploration, try-and-fail, and approximations; it is
and his informal gathering with his friends. There by acting “as-if ” one is qualified that one can have
is thus a transition in one sphere of experience but the experience of being treated as qualified; it is
not in the others. However, the older person who by accepting to be treated “as-if ” one were igno-
enters in a pension might at once experience a rup- rant that one can learn; and, most of all, it is by
ture in the sphere of daily life but also put an end to exploring possible explanation, narrative, moods,
her weekly meetings with neighbors, her attendance possible outcomes, and preferred lives that one can
to church, and the monthly visit of her grandchil- develop and confer sense to a situation. Hence,
dren; here, rupture diffuse in many spheres of expe- each of these processes demand the work of imagi-
rience and demand numerous transitions at once. nation, through which a zone is created for poten-
In addition, this multiplicity is co-evolving. Often, tial actions and thoughts not-yet possible. Very
key events in one’s sphere of activity result from often, these explorations are rendered possible by
events in others—a professional transition might the immediate social environment, which accepts
be caused, or facilitated, by a coincidental meeting a student’s wrong answer, an adult’s divorce, or a
with an uncle at a family dinner, or a person’s abil- period of confusion in a young woman’s life (Hviid
ity to deal with the demands of a new job might be & Zittoun, 2008).4
facilitated by his weekly discussions with childhood Many of the surprising curves and bends in a life-
friends in a local pub. course simply result from the multiplicity of a per-
In addition, each sphere of experience is socially son’s spheres of experiences, their mutual dynamics,
structured and sets precise demands on people; con- and the dynamics of transitions, and so these have
sequently, for different reasons, the system of ori- to be studied if one wants to address life-course
entation of a person and, following from them, the development.
sense a person is prone to confer to a situation, her
ways of defining skills and identity, can at times be Current Issues in Life-Course Transitions
consonant, yet also extremely dissonant within a In this section, and based on the framework
given sphere of experience. The experience of dis- defined above, I use a series of empirical to high-
sonant demands might thus be the cause of a felt light four inter-related issues that could be further
rupture within a given sphere of experience. For analyzed in the study of the life-course.
example, religious young men who have developed First, the processes suggested here are meant
a meaning system in a religious environment, which to account for any transition, at any age, in the
is extremely functional within that sphere of experi- life-course, including very young children. Paying
ence, might precisely feel that they do not have the attention to such experiences of transition is a first
means to deal with daily events once they are in a step to develop a life-course analysis. Second, the
secular context, because their values and semiotic principle of plurality of sphere of experience might
resources are dissonant there (Zittoun, 2006b). help us to understand dynamics traditionally stud-
It then seems that people can more easily engage ied in isolation, such as the school-to-work transi-
these processes of change when they can work tion. Third, the question of what changes as persons
through one of these aspects at the time, leaning get older and accumulate experience through life
on at least another, more stable one. Hence, when has to be raised; and fourth, transitions of one per-
a person changes country and sees her whole life son are likely to influence others, especially in inter-
questioned, having with her personal objects or generational relationships. If the first two issues are
pictures can offer a sense of personal continuity currently being at the heart of a growing number of
beyond the rupture, on the bases of which she can studies, the latter two are still to be explored.
initiate other changes (e.g., learn the new language)
(Habermas, 1996; Zittoun, 2006a). Similarly, in Transitions to New Spheres of
some cases, a person who is living through a rup- Experiences: Childhood
ture in one sphere of activity can, under some con- Although the interest for the study of transitions
ditions, use resources coming from other past or in the life-course has mainly focused on youth and
present spheres of experiences to facilitate these aging population, transitions as defined here obvi-
transitions3. ously start very early, and birth is probably one of

z it tou n 525
the first substantial transitions a human person Benjamin and Mark are drawing at the table with
has to go through.v Without going that far, we will the adult Mia. All children are supposed to make
examine early childhood experiences. The passage a drawing for Liva as it is her birthday. Benjamin
from home to kindergarten, or from kindergar- concentrates and works with commitment on the
ten to primary school—even if usually prepared task.
by adults through different techniques—is lived Mark: I am done (stands up).
by every child as a particular transition (Lam & Mia: But Mark you only just arrived! When you
Pollard, 2009) depending on his past experience, his start school you can’t just quit when you feel like
preferences, his social insertion, and his ability to it . . . Draw some more . . . .
play with reality. Even if very young children do not Mark: (grabs the pen and draws for 10 more seconds
have the capacities to develop long-term time per- without sitting down) Now it is done!
spectives, research documenting children’s external- Mia: Mark, you know in school there is no such
ization have shown their ability to reflect on what thing as not being bothered! (Sighs) Alright, this will
happened to them and what might soon happen have to do then.
(even as young as 2 years old; Nelson, 2006). For (Winther-Lindqvist, 2009, p. 134)
example, Ditte Winther-Lindqvist (2009) followed
James seems to be positively anticipating school,
two groups of children for 8 months, before the
and playing as-if he would be already at school. He
end of nursery school and after the entrance at pri-
is actively creating a zone of proximal development,
mary school, and before and after their move from
with the help of a book, and his experience devel-
primary school to secondary school. Here, I report
oped in another sphere of experience—knowing his
some of the observations of children age 5 years and
father’s phone number. Benjamin is not reported in
analyze them with the notions proposed above.
such active explorations, even if he is part of inter-
James is a popular child in the nursery school.
actions that signal him what is expected in the pri-
In that social frame, children are free to organize
mary school.
their time as they please, and the most valued activ-
After having changed school, things appear
ity by the boys is soccer. As James is very good at it,
quite differently. James is put in a different class
he is recognized as very competent by his peers and
than his good friends. Soccer is not the main activ-
himself feels quite content. In contrast, Benjamin
ity anymore and is even difficult to practice: it can
is friends with girls and is bad at soccer; the other
be played only during breaks, yet the sport ground
children consider him incompetent, and he says he
is far and always very busy. Eight weeks after the
doesn’t like them; he often withdraws, and seems
beginning of the school year, the researcher writes
bored when adults do not organize time for him; his
the following:
main commitment is in adult-conducted activities.
Before changing schools, both children construct (protocol notes from the school interview). James
anticipations of what might happen: draws an unhappy face to the general question: How
do you like school? And the class teacher asks him
James is sitting in the couch reading when Ollie
what it is about school he does not like. He shrugs
asks him if he is coming outside to play soccer.
and cannot tell her. “Is there something you miss
“Yes, when I have finished reading this book,”
from day care?” she asks him. “I miss my friends,” he
he says. I sit down next to him. It is a spelling-
says. “But you have nice friends, also in school, don’t
pointing book. He pronounces every word carefully
you?” He shrugs. Regarding the questions about
as he points at it. Sometimes he asks me to read a
scholastic activities, James also says that lessons are
word aloud if he is not certain. He sits a long time
boring, and learning rhymes and singing is dull.
concentrating with the book. “I know my dad’s
(Winther-Lindqvist, 2009, p. 138)
telephone number,” he says and recites it for me.
“I am attending school next Friday,” James says. In contrast, Benjamin seems to do fine: “in school
“Only after the holidays,” I correct him. “No we he is not supposed to decide for himself what to
are to visit them next Friday and they will show us do with his time, an he is engaged in the project of
around and everything,” he says with excitement. learning and being a good student, recognized by
“That is why I rehearse reading,” he says, as he all teachers and peers for his hard work with draw-
puts the book away and joins his friends in the ing, counting, writing letters, remembering rhymes
playground. and lyrics, putting his hand up when wanting to
(Winther-Lindqvist, 2009, pp. 134–135) speak, etc.” (Winther-Lindqvist, 2009, p. 138). He

526 l i fe-cour s e
still does not have many friends, but this fact seems of experience, where relevant social others play an
to worry his teacher and his parents more than him, important role. Others acknowledge or not, vali-
as he seems to enjoy schoolwork. date or ignore, a child’s externalization; this might
The examples enable Winther-Lindvist (2009) facilitate or hinder the exploration or the change in
to highlight how, in different spheres of experi- which the child is engaged—his attempt to under-
ence, children’s “orientation” and social identity stand something he did not, his work of conferring
are welcome or not and lead to integration versus sense to a situation, or of redefining himself.vi In
disintegration. In our terms, it seems that in the addition, the role of these others might be guided
new school, James was relying on his good identity by institutional rules: a kindergarten teacher can let
as a good soccer player, reinforced by his friends’ children play, why a primary teacher has to bring
acknowledgement and supported by the related them to read according to a certain agenda. Hence,
skills; in the new sphere of experience, there is no to actually observe dynamics of transition, one has
occasion to practice these skills and to reactivate his to consider not only the person’s actions and exter-
friends’ admiration so as to support his own iden- nalizations but also how these enter in interpersonal
tity. The expectations he had for school, through dynamics, in a given socially defined setting.
which things could have acquired a personal sense
(e.g., reading and knowing telephone numbers), on Youth Transitions—Relationships Between
the other hand, have not been met by reality: so far, Spheres of Experiences
children do “boring” things like rhymes and sing- Typically, youth (including adolescence and what
ing, which are much less grown up activities than is at times called “emerging adulthood”) is a period
writing phone numbers! Hence, the whole activity of many transitions; several changes of spheres of
seems devoid of sense, which is suggested by the experience might occur in a short period, each of
general emotional tone of James’ externalizations them creating experience of ruptures and subsequent
(his unhappy face, his comments on missing friends readjustments. This partly results from the fact that
and finding things boring). James has thus experi- young people often involve more time in the social
enced the school change as rupture, and it seems world and in imaginary worlds than children do,
that he could rely on none of the dimension iden- through their leisure and because of training and
tified above: identity is questioned, skills become economical reasons. For example, a study on sec-
redundant, and the sense degrades. In contrast, ondary school students’ uses of symbolic resources
Benjamin was described as having had difficulties (SYRES) has shown that many young people spend,
establishing a strong positive identity, and his skills besides school and schoolwork, up to 20 hours a
enabled him to execute what was asked from him. week in playing music, working out and combat
The entrance in the primary school enables him to sports, pocket bikes, art school, and in addition,
actualize such skills in an environment where it is during weekend, mixing to earn some money, or
valued, and where he becomes acknowledged as a investing online. Each of the spheres of experience
good pupil; in turn, one might think that through to which a person participates can involve processes
this, and perhaps, through a genuine epistemic of transitions. These spheres of experiences might
pleasure hence generated, Benjamin seems to confer be felt as more or less connected or disjointed, and
some sense to school as a place to learn—manifested young people might seem to experience a plurality
by his enthusiasm. Here, some pre-existing skills are of identities, might create boundary-crossing events
reinforced and support an identity in the making. between these spheres of experiences (Grossen,
Hence, in the new sphere of experience, the pro- Zittoun, & Ros, 2012), or might reflect these in a
cesses of transition in which James engages seems to rather unitary way. In the frame of this study, inter-
take an involutive shape, whereas it is more genera- views were made with 20 young persons regarding
tive in the case of Benjamin. their leisure time and their relationship to school
In this example, we see the intricateness of learn- knowledge (Zittoun, Padiglia, & Matthey, 2010).
ing, identity processes, and sense-making, ranging The data that follow comes from an interview with
from affective connotation to anticipation of the Marc, a young man engaged in vocational train-
future and evaluation of the adequacy of the situ- ing. His interview enables us to show relationships
ation, as these might take place at any moment between spheres of experiences.
of the life-course. We also see that such mutually In the sphere of school experience, Marc pres-
dependent dynamics take place in specific spheres ents what is initially an involutive circle, because of

z it tou n 527
what he considers a lack of skills: “[School] is very to read and question a text. Marc realizes that he can
demanding for me, I need to work a lot, I am dys- read despite his dyslexia and that complex texts can
lexic and things are very difficult for me. I never make sense. He explains how, through his activities
liked school . . . That is also why I trained as a carpen- in the worker’s union, he came to think again about
ter”. Dyslexia, a learning difficulty, is for Marc an the novel Germinal, by Zola, that had been read
identity, and it seems to limit his engagement in fur- and analyzed at school. In other words, in the new
ther learning. On this basis of such negative identity, school, Marc can engage in French learning, confer
Marc seems to have engaged in a negative choice, sense to it, and, possibly, change his identity into
choosing to study the less demanding trade: that of a competent student.
Contrasting with his school experiences, Marc
I did a CFC [diploma] of carpenter [a few years ago]
is very assertive about his skills and identity in the
and ( . . . ) I worked 6 months in a company, and
sphere of musical activities:
I didn’t correspond to me at all, the work . . . It was
not the act of working, it was the relation to the I started to play in a brass band [13 years ago],
trade, the stress, and also the workshop chief was a I started to play drums; after [3] years of training I
bit lunatic, and as I was all the time with him it was could have the costume and of on parade, and soon
too heavy. ( . . .) Then I worked with another boss this was not enough for me anymore, I went to the
( . . . ) someone I knew personally, a friend of the conservatory, I played a lot of drum, I made few
family. And there the atmosphere was nice, much years of xylophone which I had to stop because of
nicer. But I wanted something else, to work alone in the vocational training, and then I concentrated on
the workshop didn’t correspond to me. percussion (..) and suddenly the director of the brass
band left and I took it on. Now I play less, I direct,
Marc seems unable to define a positive sense in a and I am still at the conservatory. ( . . .) I compose
trade chosen as a consequence of negative self-def- pieces for concerts, I have a team of 114 young
inition. This experience led him to change his ori- people, I have to teach them, manage the team, last
entation. In the first company, Marc disliked the week we were second at the [regional] competition
work and the other persons, which prevented him with the percussion.
from developing a vocational identity—he felt as not
“corresponding.” Marc then changes place—that is, Music is a strong component of Marc’s life; the mem-
sets a relationship to examine “what if ” would then bers of his family play music and most of his friends
happen, exploring ways to generate more sense. were known through the band. Now, with the prize
However, even in the new, supportive environment, obtained, Marc feels also the public acknowledg-
the work still does not make sense, and Marc decides ment of his work. As musician, Marc’s legitimacy is
to go back to school to re-orient his professional self-evident. Marc listens to a lot of music; he devel-
pathway. Marc engages in a vocational bachelor after oped over the year his personal taste, he is actively
difficult entrance tests. Suddenly his relationship to exploring the musical field, attends concerts, and
learning changes, which surprises Marc himself: shares his interests with friends. Identity as musician
and learning go hand-in-hand. In terms of personal
It is funny at the beginning of the school year, sense, Marc is also aware of the way in which music
because French has always been the discipline that is personally meaningful to him. On the one hand,
I don’t link, because of dyslexia, spelling mistakes. music can be directly resonating with personal expe-
It never worked for me. But coming here, riences. Hence, asked whether music he listened to
surprisingly, my grades became very quickly quite could be related to his mood, Marc answers about
good. And I don’t have the same relationship with his experience as adolescent using music to regulate
the discipline than in compulsory school. his emotional state:
The interviewer asks him about this sudden change, Very much so. There was a period in my
and Marc answers that he believes that the teacher adolescence, during which I was . . . a bit in love
played a role. First, the teacher often talks about with a girl and it didn’t go, and it is true that
things that are external to the course, and stu- I turned to music which were revolting or a bit
dents feel that it increases their general knowledge. hard. (..) it makes the energy go out. In general it
Second, French is taught in a different way: it is for easily calms me down. ( . . .) There was also a song,
the first time that the construction of a text is ana- where the text corresponded really to what I was
lyzed and discussed, and Marc discovers a new way living, and I listened a lot to it . . .

528 l i fe-cour s e
Playing has various other benefits: (Interviewer: as you were doing in the brass band?)
Yes, that is what was missing on the professional
Playing enables me to cut from everything that is
plane.
going on ( . . . ) when I play I don’t think about what
is going on anymore, it also enables to let the steam Hence, it seems that Marc could connect his experi-
off, especially drums, sometime it hits hard, and now ences in the sphere of school and in the sphere of
what I like is to be able to transmit to younger ones music playing: having the identity, the skills, and
in the band. And this concourse . . . is also a bit ( . . . ) the reasons to “transmit what one knows to younger
an acknowledgement. ones” is something that can occur in both spheres of
activity. It can be read as a specific semiotic set, crys-
Marc gives a narrative account of his changing rela-
tallized enough to cross boundaries. Thanks to it, the
tionship to music through time, and of the evolu-
identity of self-as-teacher comes to enrich the iden-
tion of its use as symbolic resource. In the past, he
tity of self-as-learning-a-manual-trade; and the expe-
used music for emotional regulation and to reflect
rience of being skilled in teaching, what is socially
about a love affair. In the present, music can be used
acknowledged, and the sense it has for self can now
to create intergenerational relationships in teaching;
support the vocational sphere of experience.
and played in public, it can produce social acknowl-
Note that not all young people have to develop
edgement. Other people’s recognition (students, the
convergent understanding of different spheres of
public, juries) comfort Marc in his competent musi-
activity. Some young people develop parallel, but
cian identity. Sense follows: through these activities,
disjointed, skills in their spheres of music-mixing
one can also share his pleasure and expertise and
or Asian film watching and at school; others might
enjoy the satisfaction of doing so. The transmitting
in contrast have a clear unifying definition of their
activity becomes very important in Marc’s present
activity through different spheres, as Mara, who is
life. He enjoys it, and his comments show how seri-
interested in visual arts and uses every information
ously he reflects about the didactics of music in his
provided by the school to develop her own explora-
ensemble:
tion of arts, art books, and her practice of painting
It is really interesting, the youngest is 10 years old. in an art school or in her daily life (Zittoun, Padigia
So, to teach them, is quite interesting. (..) I compose & Matthey, 2010). There is still a tendency in psy-
most pieces, it is easier for me because I can write chology to claim what sort of life configuration is
according to their level, I can make voices which are “better”—predictive of better social integration, or
progressive and not too difficult. more well-being, and thus emphasizing the impor-
tance for people to elaborate more “integrated per-
Hence, for Marc, in the musical field, an identity
sonalities” (Erikson, 1968), or on the contrary, more
of musician, the learning it engages, and the sense
diversified, multifaceted self-definitions (Proulx
that one can extract from it are mutually support-
& Chandler, 2009; Moshman, 2009). Given the
ive and generative. That music makes personal sense
open-ended nature of these processes, it is not possi-
supports engagement in learning, which supports
ble to say whether some of these modes of joining or
social recognition, which supports identity and
maintaining disjointed various spheres of experience
enables transformation of the sense one finds in it,
is “good” or “not good” for facilitating development
until it changes the activity of learning, now ori-
over time. One might even say that for some people,
ented toward the development of teaching skills.
under some circumstances, some modalities might
If we now consider Marc as a whole, we see that
be better than others. Hence, for a young woman
he developed in one sphere of experience an identity
enrolled in the war effort, working in the fields with
of incompetent learner, bringing inadequate learn-
no possibilities to change activities, it might be good
ing and meaningless activity, whereas in another
to have leisure experiences felt as very disconnected,
sphere of experience, learning, identity, and sense
such as Walt Disney film-watching, whereas at other
are united positively in music. The key point is that
moments, reading botanic books and literature about
Marc, after his second work experience in the work-
life in nature can serve as a symbolic resource that
place, realized what was missing:
enriches daily practice (Zittoun, Cornish, Gillespie,
I wanted to be able to transmit what I head learned, & Aveling, 2008). In the state of our society, it might
and there I thought that teacher of handcraft, simply be good to find, when necessary, the psycho-
this would be a good think, yes, to be able to logical and social conditions permitting playfulness,
transmit, and to be in contact with other persons.

z it tou n 529
imagination and explorations of alternatives; these In this passage, a present moment—linked to a
conditions are extremely variable. dramatic transition in Czech’s people’s lives, the
end of socialism in 1989, 75-year-old Hrabal as
Moving Through Life: Experience narrator sees the situation through the eyes of
in Transitions someone who has experienced similar events and
As people advance through life, they also are their meanings —1939 and the transition of
likely to accumulate experience from transitions. Czech people under the German occupation but
Hence, if transitions lived by older persons might also 1968 with the arrival of the Russian tanks
still be similar in kind with those experienced by leading to a totalitarian state. Hrabal’s description
young people, they might simply have known of the past events, his fellow students’ arrest, is
more of them and learned from them or about already interpreted through the lenses of the pre-
them. Personal experience is not the simple accu- sent: in 1939, Hrabal did not know that they were
mulation of distinct moments; it implies the con- sent to Sachsenhausen. The emotional intensity of
stant re-elaboration of one’s system of orientation. that excerpt seems to be result from the fact that
With it, not only do people have the ability to use it is not a simple experience of a transition; it is
more resources in new transitions, but also, the vibrant of all the traces of comparable, past transi-
modalities of experiencing these transitions might tions, with their various meanings and longstand-
be different. ing consequences on the narrator’s life and on
In the following sequence taken from an essay that of a nation. In that sequence, then, these past
called “November Hurricane,” the Czech writer events and the lessons learned by the narrator are
Bohumil Hrabal,vii age 75 years, describes how, also questioned and reread, for, if past November
seeing the crowds getting organized in Prague in events lead to dramatic events, the present one,
November 1989, he reminisced about dramatic past full of dignity, will actually see the “victory of the
experiences that occurred in November 1939 (on people,” demanding a radical rereading of the past:
reminiscence in old age, see Coleman, 2005): hence past deaths, which seemed meaningless in
the past, seem now to find a meaning in the new
So there I stood in front of the pub in my Russian
freedom acquired.
fur hat, while all the people who’d been in Wenceslas
This active work of understanding, linking, and
square streamed past me, shouting and carrying
working through experience, takes place all through
placards – I watched them, astonished as this May
life, yet gets depth with experience (of course, in the
Day parade on Eastern Monday, still without it
case of a writer, the effect of experience goes hand-
customary whipping and lashings . . . I’d never seen
in-hand with the development of creative skills).
so many beautiful unblinking people, I’d never
seen such solemnity in young people . . . I walked
along with them, and I came to my old Law Intergenerational Relationships
Faculty, where across the bridge the white helmets and Transitions
gleamed and shone, proclaiming no entry—and Finally, it might be worth returning to the prin-
I stood where fifty years ago I saw the Army and ciple of inter-related lives; in effect, very often, how
the SS-Waffe hounding my fellow-students out a person lives and experiences (or has experienced)
of the Faculty – it was morning, my friends from transitions affects other persons living their own
the University were forced at rifle butt into army transitions. Intergenerational relationships affect,
trucks with green tarpaulins, while I stood on the among others, nuclear families, teacher–students
corner of Bílkova and saw what I saw . . . And as the interactions, as well as grandparent–grandchild
side-flaps were slammed shut, and those lorries set exchanges.
off, making for Sachsenhausen, I heard my fellow- The fact that people’s lives are inter-related has
students singing . . . Kde domov můj . . . our national been largely shown by systemic psychotherapists.
anthem . . . Today I stood there and saw young men Trying to understand how interactions taking place
in jeans bending their knees and squatting down on with one or members of a family could have an effect
a patch of lawn to light candles by a little memorial on other members of a family beyond the therapeu-
I’d never spotted before . . . ( . . .) [where was a marble tic encounter, Dreier (2008) has proposed a com-
tablet in the memory of a young man fallen for plex ideographic study of a family, where not only
freedom in 1945] a session with one or more members of the family
(Hrabal, 1998, pp. 111–112) are registered but also where the family members

530 l i fe-cour s e
are interviewed at home. Hence, the study enables Finally, studies on grandparenthood have sug-
us to see how, for a person, transitions in one sphere gested that although dynamic of experiences of
of life (e.g., therapy) are linked to changes in other reactivation of past transitions in the present of
spheres (e.g., family encounters); it also examines interactions with grandchildren, the different posi-
how transitions in the life of one person affects the tioning gives occasion of creative re-invention. First,
lives of others and conversely, how the resistance to grandparents are not stressed with their children’s
engage in developmental transitions hinders daily troubles as they used to be as parents (Attias-Donfut
transactions in the other family members’ lives. & Segalen, 2007; Cesari Lusso, 2004); but second,
Such study enables us to advance in the understand- intergenerational exchange allows for an explicit
ing of the mutual relationships between transitions transmission of experience, with grandchildren
that are synchronic, affecting various persons, in being more likely to accept to learn from elders—
and through various spheres of experiences. especially, but not limited to, their grandparents—
A second type of mutualities are those affecting than from the generation of their parents. Today, as
transitions lived in the past by an adult and the ones longevity increases, the co-existence of three to four
experienced by younger persons with which the generations becomes common in some families;
adult interacts—that is, interacting with a child, the at the same time, the drop of birth rates produces
adult is in the position of the adult who was played many elder persons without offspring. Researchers
by another person as he was in the position of the and policymakers have called for a “new intergener-
child. Such position exchange (Gillespie, 2011) ational pact” so as to allow the establishment of new
and reactivation of old transitions can bring the relations between generations (Fragnière, 2010)—
adult either to simply exchange position (become within or across family lines. As traditions, which
the adult that once dealt with him) or, having the usually provided semiotic resources to guide most
possibility to reflect on that situation, transform the of life transitions, tend to erode, one might won-
situation. In either case, young people or children der whether such trans-generational transmission
are confronted to some respect, to a re-actualization might bring the emergence of new forms of crystal-
of a drama that already happened. Hence, psy- lized experience—that is, the embryo of traditions.
chologists call the “Pygmalion effect” the tendency In the future, such studies should pay attention to
of teachers to treat students as small themselves the role of mutually dependent transitions in inter-
or modeling them in that direction (Rosenthal & generational dynamics.
Jacobson, 1968); and conversely, it is part of the
hard work of teachers or parents to realize that their Conclusion: Life-Course Dynamics
children or students are not the sorts of students or The study of the life-course is an old project in
children they once used to be and that the transi- the social sciences. Given the research methods that
tions experienced by younger persons are different have been privileged so far, wide groups meant to
(see, for example, Hatchuel, 2007). This tendency to be representative of some universal beings have been
align present transitions with old ones in which one considered; this has led researchers to focus on what
had a different position can typically be identified is general among trajectories—either the impact of
in the adult’s constant complaint that “youth is not social and historical events affecting many people at
anymore what is used to be”—less well-educated, once, or the biological necessities of aging. From a
less politicized . . . To advance our understanding of socio-cultural psychology perspective, the core issue
such dynamics, in the study on secondary school is elsewhere: it is located where people render their
students mentioned above, we interviewed teach- experience significant—be it in the here-and-now
ers about their past transitions, and their modalities of the emerging moment, or when 2 weeks or a
of uses of symbolic resources then, and we exam- whole life is examined at once. It seems reasonable
ine how, in classroom interactions, teachers tend to to ground such a socio-cultural study around the
promote, in their students, the same sorts of uses study of transition, as this notion might facilitate
of resources, and through that, a similar transition trans-disciplinary synthesis.
experience; we then compare this with the students’ In this chapter, I have retraced the main theoreti-
discourses on their transitions. This type of study cal assumptions of a socio-cultural perspective on
can thus participate to a better understanding of the life-course, and I have in particular proposed to
the mutualities between transitions in people whose focus on two of four aspects through which human
lives are inter-related. “cultivation” occurs (Josephs & Valsiner, 2007): in

z it tou n 531
the constant evolution of one’s system of orientation, creativity—not only that which brings some of us
and in the interactions that take place in various to engage in a craft or an artistic creativity, but a
spheres of experiences. Using a deliberately limited daily ability to question the obvious, to explore the
number of processes, I have tried to highlight basic possible, and to see what is not yet the case.
dynamics taking place as people experience transi- A psychology of the life-course should give
tions through their life-course as many occasions for means to advance the understanding of humans in
development. In the last part of this chapter, I have the contemporary world. I have attempted to high-
also suggested some issues for systematic studies, light a few ideas toward that goal; yet this explora-
such as the evolution of people’s modalities of expe- tion also leaves us with open issues: How can the
riencing transitions and using resources to facilitate theoretical ambition to develop a psychology aware
them, as they gain more life experiences, and the of the complexities of dynamics of the person in
inter-relations of people’s experiences transitions. context really be translated in empirical work, and
From what precedes, it becomes clear that to how can this empirical work be generalized? How
move toward the construction of a more general can the notion of transition really become an “ana-
socio-cultural psychology of the life-course, less lyzer” by which advances in various sciences might
wide-samples studies are needed than well-thought contribute to such complex understanding? Then,
case studies (or ideographic approaches). Beyond how can a knowledge that emphasizes dynamic
the strategies evoked here (quasi-ethnographic processes offer tools for teachers and practitioners?
work, interviews, use of personal writings), there is And more generally, how should we define human
a current scientific effort to rediscover and empha- choice and responsibility in a changing world? How
size methods that would be adequate and to which can our society, which educational institutions
the reader might refer (Abbey & Surgan, 2012; tend toward self-maintenance, facilitate the devel-
Toomela &Valsiner, 2010; Valsiner, Molenaar, Lyra, opment of persons who are equipped to deal with
& Chaudhary, 2009). More generally, we can invite unpredictability?
the reader to be creative—as long as data collection
respects the basic theoretical principles exposed Notes
here (and by others) and preserves the unexpected 1. Hence, three modes of organizing one’s experience can be
dynamics of the life-course. proposed: first, the organization of experience according to for-
mal logic and that tends toward scientific knowledge; it involves
causal reasoning and temporal succession, and it refuses contra-
Future Directions: Life-Course in diction. It is what we usually call “rational” thinking. A second
the Twenty-First Century mode, which we have here associated to the creation of semiotic
The study of the life-course presents new chal- sets, is experience-based and as such might engage reasonable,
lenges in contemporary times. The acceleration of yet not rational, reasoning—what one might call “common
time perceived by more and more humans—both sense” thinking (with all its positive and negative connotations!),
which is highly sensitive to cultural variation and is typically
resulting from actual technical, political, ecologi- displayed in narrative accounts of one’s lives. The third mode is
cal changes, and to the information about these— the logic of affective dynamics, which are much more embodied
changes the perceived stability of human life. More and ignore time and causality. We have very little control over it,
and more people become migrants or feel nomadic, yet it might infuse other modes of thinking, especially common
and experience frequent transitions. In this moving sense. The first and third modes have been described by psycho-
analysis, as resulting from conscious versus unconscious logics,
environment, the strong social or cultural canaliza- secondary processes, and primary processes (Freud, 1898) or as
tion becomes less visible—we live with the illusion “asymmetrical thinking” versus “symmetrical thinking” (Matte
of being free, when we are not. With less explicit Blanco, 1998; Salvatore & Venuleo, 2010). The first mode is
cultural guidance, people would have to rely more also privileged by learning and developmental psychology. The
on their personal system of orientation and on the third mode has been explored by psychoanalysis but is still widely
ignored by psychology, with the exception of some streams of
resources they are able to find in themselves, with social psychology (Moscovici, 2000). The second mode is the
the help of others, or around them. Learning from preferred object of study of social psychology and “folk psychol-
experience is vital, and for those who, in rich soci- ogy” (Bruner, 1990) yet has the less clear status of all. It is often
eties, do not have to focus on daily survival, learn- seen as a combination of the two other modes of thinking (it is
ing from experience involves mainly being able to close to Freud’s “preconscious” thinking, it demands a combina-
tion of symmetric and asymmetric thinking) but has still received
reflect on one’s experience and to develop strong very little attention in itself. However, it is quite likely that this
basis of usable knowledge mobilizable in unex- mode of thinking groups a large number of identity dynamics,
pected situations. This also requires an enhanced cultural experiences, and daily thinking, which participate in

532 l i fe-cour s e
what we call sense-making—and that is the object of study of Attias-Donfut, C., & Segalen, M. (2007). Grands-parents: La
cultural psychology. famille à travers les générations (2nd ed.). Paris: Odile Jacob.
2. It is to this sort of goal that some forms of meditative practice Baltes, P. B. (1987). Theoretical propositions of life-span devel-
tend to orient people and reveal the random nature of the world in opmental psychology: On the dynamics between growth and
which we believe and, therefore, its vanity (in a Pascalian sense). decline. Developmental Psychology, 23, 611–626.
3. This raises the complex issue known under the idea of Baltes, P. B., Staudinger, U. M., & Lindenberger, U. (1999).
“transfer of knowledge” or of “use of resources” from one sphere Lifespan psychology: Theory and application to intellectual
of experience to another (see Zittoun, Valsiner et al., in press, for functioning. Annual Review of Psychology, 50, 471–507.
a discussion). Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychol-
4. Such explorations take place in what Vygotsky had called a ogy. Berlin: Springer Verlag.
zone of proximal development (as it is created in children’s play, or Bottos, M., Dalla Barba, B., Stefani, Daniela, Gianna, P.,
in adult–children interactions, see Van der veer & Valsiner, 1991) Carmela, T., & D’Este, A. (2008). Locomotor strategies pre-
or as transitional phenomena in the sense given by Winnicott— ceding independent walking: Prospective study of neurologi-
between what is and what is yet to be (Helson, 2009; Winnicott, cal and language development in 424 cases. Developmental
1971). Medicine & Child Neurology, 31(1), 25–34.
5. It is not only a biological change but also and imme- Bouska, T., & Pinerova, K. (2009). Czechoslovak political pris-
diately a symbolic one: a child enters in the world of culture. oners. Life stories of 5 male and 5 female victims of stalinism
All traditional cultures accompany birth with actions aiming (Europe of Citizen programme). Education and culture pro-
at facilitating the cultural birth of the child, such as circumci- gramme.
sion, baptism, or name-giving rituals. Humans, who are used to Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The Ecology of Human Development:
reasoning in terms of transitions, are pushed to question where Experiments by Nature and Design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
these children were before being there. The question, “Where University Press.
do children come from?” is a classical anthropological and reli- Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge: Harvard
gious question; raised by most children, it is quite likely to be University Press.
present in many people’s minds, even if in a very unconscious Cesari Lusso V. (2004). Il mestiere di . . . nonna e nonno. Trento,
form. Parental theories (ethnotheories) about how to accompany Italy: Erickson.
the child’s progressive mastery of biological functions (progres- Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology. A once and future discipline.
sive sleeping hours, whining, sphincter control) can also be seen Cambridge, MA/London: The Belknap Press of Harvard
as actualization of implicit knowledge about transitions: people University Press.
might act as if it were better to accompany self-generated tran- Coleman, P. G. (2005). Reminiscence: Developmental, social
sitive changes, eventually bringing more substantial changes (as and clinical perspectives. In M. L. Johnson, V. L. Bengtson,
when parents decide to follow the child’s sleeping rhythm); on P. G. Coleman, & T. B. L. Kirkwood (Eds.), The Cambridge
the contrary, they might privilege clear transitions by imposing handbook of age and ageing (pp. 301–309). New York/
a rupture to the infant and having the child adjust to it (as when Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
parents decide to have their child learn to “make their hours”). Crosnoe, R., & Elder, G. H. (2002). Life Course Transitions,
Whether one believes in the importance of early experience or the Generational Stake, and Grandparent-Grandchild
not, it is probably the case that these first handling of experi- Relationships. Journal of Marriage and Family, 64(4),
ence of ruptures in children might constitute a basis for further 1089–1096.
handling of ruptures and transitions. However, as humans are Dewey, J. & Bentley, A. F. (1946). Interaction and Transaction.
extremely plastic—especially in early age—and because of the The Journal of Philosophy, 43(19), 505–517.
multiplicity of experience and the multilinearity of development, Doise, W. (1982). L’explication en psychologie sociale. Paris: Presses
it is quite likely that some experiences of demanding transitions Universitaires de France.
might be compensated by later experiences, and memories of the Dominicé, P. (2007). La formation biographique. Paris:
one and the other revised accordingly. L’Harmattan.
6. The model of the semiotic prism, proposed elsewhere, Dreier, O. (2007). Psychotherapy in everyday life. New York:
enables to capture these dynamics of recognition in sense-mak- Cambridge University Press.
ing (e.g., Zittoun, 2006a). Duveen, G., & Lloyd, B. (1990). Social representations and the
7. The text of Hrabal belongs to a series of “letters to development of knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
Dubenka”—although they are very written, they have the speci- University Press.
ficity of having the form of a freeflow of consciousness—with Elder, G. H. J., Kirkpatrick Johnson, M., & Crosnoe, R. (2004).
Hrabal (2008) explaining that his work consists in absorbing The emergence and development of life course theory. In J.
during the whole day experiences and situations, and emptying T. Mortimer & M. J. Shanahan (Eds.), Handbook of the life
himself on the paper afterward; his work has been qualified as course (pp. 23–50). New York: Springer.
“total realism” (Naughton, 1998). Engeström, Y. (1999). Activity theory and individual and
social transformation. In Y. Engeström, R. Miettinen, &
R. -. Punamaki (Eds.), Perspectives on activity theory.
References Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Abbey, E., & Surgan, S. (2012). Developing Methods in Psychology, Engeström, Y. (2005). Developmental work research: Expanding
series “History and Theory of Psychology,” New Brunswick, activity theory in practice. Berlin: Lehmanns Media.
NJ: Transaction Publishers. Erikson, E. H. (1959). Identity and the life cycle. Selected papers.
Abbey, E., & Valsiner, J. (2003). Going to no-where: the role (1959th ed.). New York: International Universities Press.
of diagnosis in educational practice, Paper presented at the Retrieved August 4, 2009, from http://www.archive.org/
EARLI conference, Padova, Italy. details/identityandtheli011578mbp.

z it tou n 533
Erikson, E. H. (1968). Identity: youth and crisis. London: Faber & Josephs, I. E., & Valsiner, J. (2007). Developmental science
Faber. meets culture: Cultural developmental psychology in the
Fragnière, J.-P. (2010). Solidarités entre les générations. Lausanne: making. European Journal of Developmental Science, 1(1),
Ed. Réalités sociales. 47–64.
Furlong, A. (2009). Revisiting transitional metaphors: reproduc- Josephs, I. E., Valsiner, J., & Surgan, S. E. (1999). The process
ing social inequalities under the conditions of late modernity. of meaning construction. Dissecting the flow of semiotic
Journal of Education and Work, 22(5), 343–353. activity. In J. Brandstädter & R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Action &
Giele, J. Z., & Elder, G. H. J. (1998). Life course research. Self-development. Theory and research through the life-span (pp.
Development of a field. In J. Z. Giele & G. H. J. Elder (Eds.), 257–282). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Methods of life course research. Qualitative and quantitative Kundera, M. (1996). Slowness. (L. Asher, Tran.). London:
approaches (pp. 5–27). Thousand Oaks, CA/London: Sage. Faber & Faber.
Gillespie, A. (2011). Position exchange: the social basis of agency. Lalive d’Epinay, C., & Spini, D. (2008). Les années fragiles: La
New Ideas in Psychology. vie au-delà de quatre-vingts ans. Québec: Presses universitaires
Gillespie, A., & Zittoun, T. (2010). Using resources: de Laval.
Conceptualising the mediation and reflective use of tools and Lam, M. S., & Pollard, A. (2006). A conceptual framework
signs. Culture & Psychology, 15(4), 1–26. for understanding children as agents in the transition from
Goffman, E. (1997). The mortified self. From the characteris- home to kindergarten. Early Years: An International Journal
tics of total institutions. In C. Lemert & A. Branaman, The of Research and Development, 26(2), 123–141.
Goffman reader (pp. 55–71). Malden/Oxford: Blackwell Lawrence, J. A., & Valsiner, J. (2003). Making personal sense:
[original publication 1958]. An account of basic internalization and externalization pro-
Goodwin, J., & O’Connor, H. (2009). Whatever happened to cesses. Theory & Psychology, 13(6), 723–752.
the young workers? Change and transformation in 40 years Levy, R., Ghisletta, P., Le Goff, J., Spini, D., & Widmer, E.
at work. Journal of Education and Work, 22(5), 417–431. (2005). Incitations for interdisciplinarity in life course
Green, A. (2000). Le temps éclaté. Paris: Editions de Minuit. research. In R. Levy, P. Ghisletta, D. Spini, & E. Widmer
Grossen, M., Zittoun, T., & Ros, J. (2012). Boundary crossing (Eds.), Towards an Interdisciplinary Perspective on the Life
events and potential appropriation space in philosophy, lit- course (pp. 361–391). Amsterdam, etc.: Elsevier.
erature and general knowledge. In E. Hjörne, G. van der Lopez, A., Najafi, B., Rogoff, B., & Arauz, R. M. (2011).
Aalsvoort, & G. de Abreu (Eds.), Learning, social interac- Collaboration and helping as cultural practices. In J. Valsiner
tion and diversity—exploring school practices (pp. 15–33). (Ed.), Oxford Handbook of Psychology and Culture. New York:
Rotterdam/Boston/Taipei: Sense Publishers. Oxford University Press.
Davies, B., & Harré, R. (1990). Positioning: The Discursive Matte Blanco, I. (1998). The unconscious as infinite sets: An essay
Production of Selves. Journal for the Theory of Social in bi-logic. London: Karnac Books.
Behaviour, 20(1), 43–63. Mayer, K. U. (2009). New directions in life course research.
Habermas, T. (1996). Geliebte Objekte. Symbole und Instrumente American Review of Sociology, 35, 413–433.
der Identitätsbildung. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter. Mortimer, J. T., & Shanahan, M. J. (2004). Handbook of the Life
Hatchuel, F. (2007). Savoir, apprendre, transmettre. Une approche course. New York: Springer.
psychanalytique du rapport au savoir. Paris: La Découverte. Moscovici, S. (2000). Psychologie sociale des relations à autrui
Helson, C. (2009). L’adulte face à son âge: dénis et défis du vieil- (2nd ed.). Paris: Nathan Université.
lir jeune. In J. Boutinet, & P. Dominicé, (Eds.). (2009). Où Moshman, D. (2009). Identity, morality, and adolescent devel-
sont passés les adultes ? (pp. 17–40). Paris: Téaraèdre. opment. Human Development, 52, 287–290.
Hermans, H. J. M., & Kempen, H. J. (1993). The Dialogical Self: Naughton, J. (1998). Translator’s note. In B. Hrabal (Ed.), Total
Meaning as movement. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. fears. Letters to Dubenka (p. 203). Prague: Twisted Spoon
Hjörne, E. & Säljö, R. (2004) “There is something about Julia”: Press.
Symptoms, categories, and the process of invoking Attention Nelson, K. (Ed.). (2006). Narratives from the crib (2nd ed.).
Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder in the Swedish School: A Case Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
study, Journal of Language, Identity & Education, 3(1), 1–24. Nelson, K. (2007). Young minds in social worlds. Experience,
Hrabal, B. (1998). November Hurricane, In Total fears. Letters meaning, and memory. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard
to Dubenka (J. Naughton, Tran.) (pp. 83–112). Prague: University Press.
Twisted Spoon Press. Overton, W. E. (2002). Development across the lifespan. In
Hrabal, B. (2008). Pirouettes on a postage stamp: An interview- R. M. Lerner, M. A. Easterbrooks, J. Mistry, & I. B. Weiner
novel with questions asked and answers recorded by Laszlo (Eds.), Handbook of Psychology, (Vol. 6, pp. 13–42). New
Szigeti. (D. Short, Tran.) (1st ed.). Prague: Karolinum Press, York: John Wiley & Sons.
Charles University. Perret-Clermont, A. (2004). Articuler l’individuel et le collec-
Hviid, P., & Zittoun, T. (2008). Editorial introduction: tif. Nouvelle Revue de Psychologie sociale/New Review of Social
Transitions in the process of education. European Journal of Psychology, 3(1–2), 94–102.
Psychology of Education, 23(2), 121–130. Perret-Clermont, A.-N., & Zittoun, T. (2002). Esquisse d’une
Rosenthal, R., & Jacobson, L. (1968). Pygmalion in the classroom. psychologie de la transition. Education permanente, 1, 12–14.
New York: Rinehart & Winston. Piaget, J. (1941), (with B. Inhelder). Le développement des quan-
James, W. (1892). The stream of consciousness. The Stream of tités chez l’enfant: conservation et atomisme. Neuchâtel/Paris:
Consciousness. Psychology (chap. XI), Cleveland & New Delachaux et Niestlé.
York: World. Retrieved January 27, 2010, from http://psy- Piaget, J. (1967). Six psychological studies. New York: Random
chclassics.asu.edu/James/jimmy11.htm. House (original publication 1964).

534 l i fe-cour s e
Proulx, T., & Chandler, M. J. (2009). Jekyll and Hyde and me: Wertsch, J. V. (1991). Voices of the mind. A sociocultural approach
Age-graded differences in conceptions of self-unity. Human to mediated action. London, etc.: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Development, 52, 261–286. Winther-Lindqvist, D. (2009). Children’s development of social iden-
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. tity in transitions. PhD Thesis, University of Copehnagen.
New York: Oxford University Press. Zittoun, T. (2005). Donner la vie, choisir un nom. Engendrements
Salvatore, S., & Venuleo, C. (2010). The unconscious as symbol symboliques. Paris: L’Harmattan.
generator: A psychodynamic-semiotic approach to meaning- Zittoun, T. (2006a). Transitions. Development through sym-
making. In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic Transformations. The bolic resources. Coll. Advances in Cultural Psychology:
mind in movement through culture and society (pp. 59–74). Constructing Development. Greenwich (CT): InfoAge.
London & New York: Routledge. Zittoun, T. (2006b). Difficult secularity: Talmud as symbolic
Salvatore, S. & Zittoun, T. (2011). Cultural Psychology and resource. Outlines. Critical Social Studies, 8(2), 59–75.
Psychoanalysis in Dialogue. Issues for Constructive Theoretical Zittoun, T. (2008). Children’s uses of cultural objects in their life
and Methodological Synergies. Charlotte, NC: Information trajectories. In S. Salvatore, J. Valsiner, S. Strout-Yagodzynski,
Age Publishers. & J. Clegg (Eds.), YIS. Yearbook of ideographic science (Vol. 1,
Sato, T., Yasuda, Y., Kido, A., Arakawa, A., Mizogushi, H., & pp. 361–370). Rome, Italy: Firera Publishing.
Valsiner, J. (2007). Sampling reconsidered: idiographic sci- Zittoun, T. (2009). Dynamics of life-course transitions—a meth-
ence and the analysis of personal trajectories . In J. Valsiner & odological reflection. In J. Valsiner, P. C. M. Molenaar, M. C.
A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of socio-cultural Lyra, & N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Dynamic process methodology
psychology (pp. 82–106). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge in the social and developmental sciences (pp. 405–430). New
University Press. York: Springer.
Sato, T., Fukuda, M, Hidaka, T., Kido, A., Nishida, M., & Zittoun, T. (2010). How does an object become symbolic?
Akasaka, M. (2011). The authentic culture of living well. In Rooting semiotic artefacts in dynamic shared experiences.
J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford Handbook of Psychology and Culture. In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic Transformations. The mind in
New York: Oxford University Press. movement through culture and society (pp. 173–192). London:
Shanahan, M. J., & Porfelli, E. (2002). Integrating the Life Routledge.
Course and Life-Span: Formulating research questions with Zittoun, T., Aveling, E.-A., Gillespie, A. & Cornish, F. (2011).
dual points of entry. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 61, People in transitions in worlds in transition: Becoming
398–406. a woman during WWII. In A. C. Bastos, K. Uriko, & J.
Toomela, A. & Valsiner, J. (2010). Methodological thinking in Valsiner (Eds.), Cultural Dynamics of Women’s Lives. Trieste,
psychology: 60 years gone astray? Charlotte, NC: Information Italy: Edizione Carlo Amore.
Age Publisher. Zittoun, T., Cornish, F., Gillespie, A., & Aveling, E. (2008).
Van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky. Using social knowledge: A case study of a diarist’s meaning
Oxford, UK: Blackwell. making during World War II. In W. Wagner, T. Sugiman, &
Valsiner, J. (1997). Culture and the development of children’s action K. Gergen (Eds.), Meaning in Action: Constructions, Narratives
(2nd ed.). New York: John Wiley & Sons. and Representations (pp. 163–179). New York: Springer.
Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind: a sociogenetic approach to Zittoun, T., Duveen, G., Gillespie, A., Ivinson, G., & Psaltis, C.
personality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (2003). The uses of symbolic resources in transitions. Culture
Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and Human Development. Thousand & Psychology, 9(4), 415–448
Oaks, CA: Sage. Zittoun, T., Grossen, M., Lempen, O., Matthey, C., & Padiglia,
Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies: Foundations of S. (2008). Usage de textes littéraires et philosophiques comme
cultural psychology. New Delhi, India: Sage. ressources symboliques: socialisation et développement de jeunes
Valsiner, J., Molenaar, P. C., Lyra, M. C., & Chaudhary, N. personnes au secondaire II. [Uses of literary and philosophical
(2009). Dynamic process methodology in the social and develop- texts as symbolic resources: socialization and development
mental sciences. New York: Springer Verlag. in young people in upper secondary school]. Rapport inter-
Valsiner, J., & Rosa, A. (2007). Handbook of Sociocultural médiaire. Neuchâtel et Lausanne, Switzerland: Université de
Psychology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Neuchâtel et Université de Lausanne.
Valsiner, J., & Van der Veer, R. (2000). The Social Mind: Construction Zittoun, T., Padiglia, S. & Matthey, C. (2010). La culture per-
of the Idea. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. sonnelle des élèves et leurs relations aux textes lus en classe de
Van Geert, P. (2003). Dynamic systems approaches of modeling philosophie, littérature et enseignement général. [Students’ per-
of developmental processes. In J. Valsiner & K. J. Conolly sonal culture and their relationships to texts read in philoso-
(Eds.), Handbook of developmental Psychology (pp. 640–672). phy, French literature and General culture classes]. Rapport
London: Sage. de recherche SYRES n°4. Lausanne/Neuchâtel, Switzerland:
Vygotskiĭ, L. S. (1986). Thought and language. (A. Kozulin, Ed.). Universités de Lausanne & Neuchâtel.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press [Original publication, 1934]. Zittoun, T., Valsiner, J., Vedeler, K., Salgado, J., Goncalves, M. &
Werner, H., & Kaplan, B. (1963). Symbol formation. An organ- Ferring, D. (in preparation). Melodies of living: Developmental
ismic-developmental approach to language and the expression of science of the human life-course. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
thought. New York: John Wiley & Sons. University Press, 2012.

z it tou n 535
CHAPTER

Being Poor: Cultural Tools


24 for Survival

Ana Cecília S. Bastos and Elaine P. Rabinovich

Abstract
Poverty has been a subject of interest in psychological theorization and research, inasmuch it is related
to many problems and fields with which psychologists deal. Nevertheless, the narratives on poverty
available in psychological research and theory are not enough: one might say there exists a “poverty
of psychology” regarding this condition, which is a quotidian reality for the majority of the world’s
population. In this chapter, we intend to approach the reality of being poor as a living experience in
process, by addressing several considerations: What does it mean to be poor in the perspective of the
poor? How can the relation poor versus non-poor be understood? Which cultural tools are employed
in the struggle for survival? This chapter analyzes the historical emergence of the notion of poverty and
its uses in research and social policies, identifying the different discourses related to it, the official, the
activist, and the discourse of living experience. The approach on cultural tools highlights the concepts of
collective memories and resilience, presenting relevant features concerned to them: folk and oral culture,
group identification (belongingness and spirituality), hope, and destiny.
Keywords: cultural tools, poverty, otherness, collective memory, resilience

I remember your words very well, Your Excellency: our


misery is profiting well. In order to live in a country of
beggars, one needs to show the wounds and the boys’ salient
bones. ( . . .). This is the current word: gather the debris to
easy the view of the disaster. The outsider should be able
to contemplate all that “poorness” without making too
much effort.
—Mia Couto, 200. (Mozambique)

It has always been the main European argument to colonize


other nations the right to compare cultures in a hierarchical
way that gave them tranquility of spirit to proclaim they
were bringing civilization to the non cultivated, barbarian
and savage Indians. How to compare past and experiences?
—Pepetela, 2009 (Angola)

536
The idea of a “poverty of psychology” is not new. In to as the expectation of the other’s addressivity to
1970, Arthur Pearl wrote a chapter with this title, oneself, have emphasized the dialogical form that
remarking: characterizes the dynamics of selfhood: “the dialogi-
cality of the self is defined in terms of a dynamic
“psychologists as a group, along with other social
multiplicity of I-positions which can be endowed
scientists, have been guilty of refusing to accept
with a voice in the landscape of the mind” (p. 5).
the challenges that poverty presents to a society of
Thus, the Other can be an external voice inside the
unparalleled affluence”
self, yet a voice personally signified:
(Pearl,1 1970, p. 348; Harper, 2003, p. 185)
This dynamic perspective on selfhood has proven
Representations of poverty throughout history
itself to be one of the most promising ways to surpass
have been complex and multidimensional in their
the old static conceptions of self which viewed the
nature. Such representations need to be understood
self as a monadic structure capable of relating with
in their socio-historical contexts, rather than treated
other monadic structures (Sampson, 1993), but still
as homogenizing stereotypes. The approaches to the
each independent from the other. The reality of the
topic of poverty vary, of course, according to the
individual self was, in this sense, different from the
culturally and historically situated place and time
reality of relationships.
and their prevailing philosophical and theoretical
(Bertau & Gonçalves, 2007, p. 5)
assumptions. The condition of living in poverty
implies that the poor, as a social category, do not Perhaps this claim can also be applied in broader
usually have the opportunity to produce academic spheres (as done by Hermans & Dimaggio [2008],
knowledge about their reality from their own per- when bridging dialogicality and globalization)
spective. Studying poverty is possibly one of the inclusive of the relationships between social classes,
greatest epistemic and ethical challenges concern- inasmuch as, besides material constraints, complexes
ing the I–Other relationships in a multicultural of meanings sustained by poor and non-poor build
world that increasingly needs to learn about the and maintain poverty as a social reality. No under-
complex dynamics of otherness. When it comes to standing of poverty is possible without taking into
poverty, the very possibility of the social visibility of account this social-psychological dimension, and it
the other is the first problem: the poor as agentive is better if done from a dialogical standpoint, which
people become invisible. The academic, political, implies:
and financial centers of decision-making, from the
Human expressions are in interrelationships with
outside, study, evaluate, make diagnoses, and imple-
other’s expressions: any single expression, such as a
ment programs that still relate to the poor in a con-
spoken utterance, a written text, a thought (even if
descending or patronizing way, offering explanations
not yet exteriorized) is a reply to other’s utterances,
and solutions that hardly fit the reality of poverty as
texts or ideas. In this sense, dialogicality refers to
an ongoing process of living experience—just like
a property that is essential in all human meaning-
other human conditions. In doing so, those institu-
making processes. ( . . .). Linell (in preparation) goes
tions, scholars, and technicians implicitly deny, to
beyond the level of expression and addresses the
the people and communities living in poverty, the
human condition: “The term dialogicality ( . . . ) refers
possibility of expressing their own voice.
to some essence of the human condition, notably that our
Alternatively, we want to adopt in this chapter a
being in the world is thoroughly interdependent with the
different perspective on poverty, a perspective capa-
existence of others.”
ble of revealing the cultural tools that the poor wield
(Bertau & Gonçalves, 2007, p. 6, emphasis added)
for survival, and the developmental poetics present
under adverse and paradoxical circumstances. Such Therefore, if dialogically considered, alterity or
an approach aims to overcome the blindness—still otherness (Simão, 2008) is itself constitutive; the I
present in psychological research—toward the broad depends on the view of the Other. For our purposes
variability of modes of living, and in doing so, allow in this chapter, the I and the Other are historical and
us to dialogically consider diversity and otherness. culturally context-situated. The poor is “the other” in
our discussion—the other to whom the I is related.
The Dialogical Perspective In this relationship, I and Other need to be mutu-
Bertau and Gonçalves (2007), accepting the ally recognized in his/her otherness as being part, at
Bahktinian idea of dialogicality as a potency referred the same time, of an equal human condition. If the

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 537


poor cannot be seen from this relational standpoint, Poverty was quite broadly defined. A pauper was
then there is not complete consideration of his/her a person who permanently or temporarily found
reality; then there is not an encounter between dif- himself in a situation of weakness, dependency and
ferent objective and subjective realities from which humiliation, characterized by privation of the means
a new understanding can emerge. Which kind of to power and social esteem (which means varied with
relationship does psychological research put in period and place): these included money, relations,
motion when studying, approaching, and interven- influence, power, knowledge, skill, nobility of birth,
ing on poverty? physical strength, intellectual capacity, and personal
This chapter intends to approach the reality freedom and dignity.
of being poor as a living experience in process by (Mollat, 1986, p. 5)
addressing several considerations: Which cultural
tools are employed in the struggle for survival? How The image constructed about the poor at different
do meaning-making processes inform and direct life times is connected to social goals and varies through-
trajectories under poverty? What does it mean to be out history, ethically and aesthetically, according to
poor from the perspective of poor persons? How do the values of the time (Geremek, 1995). This image
we approach the relation poor versus non-poor as a can carry notions and experiential realities that are
social relationship? What can the non-poor world basically similar, but the relationships between the
learn from the lives of the poor? concept and the living situations are difficult to
The literature in psychology, history, and social apprehend (Mollat, 1986). Mollat’s assertion takes
sciences has been screened to select studies where into account the Middle Ages but could perfectly fit
the perspective of the communities and persons contemporary times.
under focus is effectively considered. Special atten- Examination of Mollat’s classical study in social
tion has been given to studies that illuminate pro- history, The Poor in the Middle Ages, not only verifies
cesses, mechanisms, and cultural tools involved in the polysemy of the concept of poverty, considering
facing the reality of poverty. its several dimensions (biological, economical, and
cultural) but identifies the historical roots of signs
that are still associated with the poor—in addition to,
Meanings of Poverty: Historical Roots of course, the array of conditions that enhance pov-
Seeing so much poverty everywhere makes me think that erty: from material deprivation and social inequalities
God is not rich. He gives the appearance of it, but I to war and violence. All these dimensions should be
suspect some financial difficulties. considered in any discussion about the poverty line,3
—Victor Hugo, Les Misérables, 1862 which indicates the existence of degrees of poverty.
As a reality, poverty is known in every society and They are also intertwined: poor hygiene and health
time throughout history; yet noteworthy is Mollat’s appear linked to the lack of economic resources and
claim (1986) that the word “poverty” only became are used to generate social exclusion:
diversified and part of the vulgar languages in the In the Middle Ages, to suffer a loss of status meant
13 and 14 centuries. Etymologically, poverty comes literally to fall from one’s estate, to be deprived
from Old French poverte, Latin paupertatem.2 The of its instruments of labor and of the marks of
word “poor” comes from Latin “pauper,” meaning its condition. For a peasant this meant the loss of
“small” and “to give birth.” Originally, it was used farming implements and animals; for an artisan, loss
to refer to unproductive land or cattle. The main of the tools of his trade; for a merchant, loss of his
feature here is the idea of infertility: something that shop; for a cleric, loss of his books; for a noble, loss
is small and cannot generate (give birth); gradu- of his horse and arms. Without these things a man
ally, the term began to be used as an attribute of ceased to be anything, because he no longer possessed
people. the means to carry on a social existence. Stripped of
The study of poverty must be approached from his social position and excluded from the community,
each of the two poles that support it: the process of he was forced into emigration and vagabondage. The
being poor and social conditions (objective and sub- poor man was uprooted and alone.
jective). According to Mollat (1986), “poverty refers (Mollat, 1989, pp. 6–7)
initially to the quality, and later the condition of a
person from any social status struck by privation” However, starting from the sixteenth century, there
(p. 2), and also: were changes in the image of the poor. The term

538 bei ng poor


poor has begun to refer to the person that cannot The historic roots of charity offer another good
maintain him-/herself: the beggar, the sick person, example in explaining the ambiguities of poverty as
the old, the widow, the landless farmer, the aban- a concept and as a reality. In the Christian tradi-
doned child, the soldier with no war to fight. The tion, as in other more ancient religions, being poor
epidemics turn out the beggar as a factor of popu- appears as a virtue. In the Middle Ages, Mollat
lar disorder. The poor have become a social danger. (1998) reports the honorific use of poverty in the
To control these “marginal” people, society has expression “pauper of Christ,” initially applied to
based itself on moral arguments. (Petit journal de monks who chose poverty for love of God, and later,
l’exposition. 1997). with Saint Francis and Saint Benedict, with the con-
One could identify here some roots of the current notation of a means of perfection or a virtue in itself
discussion on the concept of poverty, but should it (the poor hold an inherent dignity and it is a social
emphasize economic indicators or social exclusion? duty to restore this dignity if broken). Starobinski
The social construction of the image of the poor (1994) highlighted that the role of “poor” as repre-
entails process and steps. In this way, the term poor senting the salvation of souls through charity turned
is historically employed, first as an adjective with out to be indispensable to distinguish between
several connotations (e.g., condescendence, disdain, “good” and “bad” connotations of the word: the
contempt, repugnance, fear), then as a substantive one that worked and the one that did not. The first,
and only later in its plural form, acquiring here an the “poor for Christ,” needed to be helped admin-
abstract dimension: the poor, charged by feelings of istrating charity (and not giving alms in the streets)
pity and/or social disquiet. In his description of this so the new urban order could be maintained. Later,
process, Mollat (1989) recognizes: with Illuminism, poverty became an issue of politics
and government, no longer of charity.
The word poor in an abstract sense [is used to] evoke
As Mollat’s perceptive analysis has noted, the
not only an image of the afflicted individual and
central ambivalence lies in considering poverty as
the state of his or her affliction but also an affective
“a form of spiritual sublimation” or “a permanent
component of compassion or horror, which carries
disgrace” (p. 9):
with it considerable potential to provoke rebellion
or social fear. The idea, derived from the Gospels, that the pauper
(p. 2) was created in the image of Christ the Redeemer was
frequently contradicted for brutal contempt for the
From a cultural-semiotic perspective, the word “poor”
peasant ( . . .).
can be seen as a hypergeneralized sign (Valsiner, 2007),
. . . the misery of the pauper is often described
a semiotic regulator that orients important psycholog-
dispassionately and with the purpose of reminding
ical mechanisms that contribute, on a personal and
society of its duties towards the poor. But what was
social level, to maintain or modify the social status
proposed? Resignation in anticipation of consola-
quo. Just as other conditions of being in the world,
tion in the hereafter? A social upheaval that would
the image of the poor has the power of a hypergen-
humble the proud and exalt the humble without
eralized sign, presenting a dense, dynamic, social and
changing the structure of society? A balance between
personal quality, likely to interact with affective-se-
rights on the one hand and duties on the other,
miotic fields set up by feelings of empathy-repulse,
based on some notion of mutual charity?”
inclusion-exclusion, compassion-indifference and
(pp. 9–10)
from which emerge complex attitudes and responses
to poverty—keeping in mind Mollat’s claim that As also stressed by Starobinski, here Mollat refers
“evidence concerning these attitudes and responses to a notion of the “true poor,” whose belongingness
generally exhibit only one point of view, that of the to a group implies living on scarce resources gen-
non-poor casting their gaze upon the poor” (1998, erated by humble work, in contrast with the false
p. 2). Considering that the Other carries what Souza one, the vagabond, wanderer, the beggar. The latter
(2009) refers to as “a way of perceiving the future as could be seen as a rebel, likely to disseminate social
a possibility (p. 104),” the images of the poor con- disorder and epidemics. Using these polarities as a
structed by non-poor are, on the other hand, just as basis, Ezequiel (1998) has commented on the many
other social realities, value-laden and may underesti- nuances around the subject of poverty and the
mate or excessively idealize poverty and poor people, image of the poor, which need to be studied over the
as this author emphasizes. course of history. Only by the late Middle Ages was

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 539


the notion of the poor as a social group established, of pauperization directly: he was interested in the
with important social and moral implications: mechanisms that generated this reality. The Marxist
analysis is structured around three main axes: the
What had been an individual affliction became a
mismatch between labor income and purchasing
social scourge. Poverty, once seen as a consequence
power; the industrial reserve army (mechanism
of, and punishment for, individual sin, was later
of the capitalist system that has control over the
considered a form of social parasitism or even (as in
establishment of a constant distinction between the
the case of beggary) a crime. (. . .) Humanist praise
mass of wages and productivity); and the structural
for success, with its concomitant exaltation of wealth,
unemployment (with the decrease in the elastic-
eventually contaminated the poor themselves, who
ity of the industrial army reserve). The changes in
were rightly or wrongly accused of giving in to the
these three areas lead to increased illegal economic
natural tendency of the poor man to envy or desire
activities, institutionalized drug trafficking, under-
the comforts of the rich.
employment, piracy, and informal trade.
(Mollat, 1998, p. 297)
The much-discussed crisis of capitalism and the
And he continues: demands and realignment that it brings on a global
level have revived the discussion on the issue of poverty,
A new word came into use as a rival to charity
by scholars and international agencies. Governments
and mercy: beneficence (with its equivalent in
create ministries and special offices for dealing with
other languages), a precursor of the more modern
poverty (e.g., the Brazilian Department of Solidarity-
benevolence, which first came into use (in French)
Based Economy). This conjuncture allows the emer-
in the eighteenth century, along with philanthropy.
gence of new concepts (or new emphasis) around
(. . .) And meanwhile, governments guided by the
poverty as an international reality, such as the ideas
principle of raison d’état invented the idea of policing
of Amartya Sen (1999) on “development with free-
the poor – an idea more rational than it is charitable.
dom”. He highlighted the idea that development is
(p. 298)
not possible in a socio-economic model that excludes
The contemporary meanings of being poor refer human life as a value by itself.
to social conditions of social disqualification Eventually, initiatives characterized by solidarity
(Paugam, 2003), stigmatization, and criminalization or community life introduce new perspectives that
(Wacquant, 1999). To deal with those conditions, consider the voice of the poor man himself. From
the poor develop cultural tools for survival: it is not the standpoint of the poor, considering their living
only the lack of food and not having somewhere to reality, the process of globalization entails displace-
live and a job. According to Paugam (2003), under- ments and realignments with deep and as yet poorly
standing social disqualification demands for us understood impacts on the self. These are some of
the consequences of belonging to an industrial army
“to study the diversity of statuses which define
reserve that, in the words of Serge Paugam (2003),
[people living under this condition], their personal
is not more “reserve” ’ but “obstacle.”
identities, i.e., the subjective feelings around
To understand how these concepts impact the
the situation experienced by these individuals
research, be it through scholars’ ideological and
along their social experiences and, finally, the
epistemological biases or through the measures the
social relationships they hold with other people,
studies adopt, let’s consider the three different kinds
inside the same social condition and in different
of narratives on poverty that can be currently iden-
situations.”
tified: the official discourse, and the discourses of
(p. 47)
activism and of living experience. The critical point
As a social category, connected to the Marxist here is that the official discourse is structured upon
notion of class struggle, the contemporary concept the naturalization of social inequality: two different
of poverty comes from mercantilism, incorporat- kinds of logic are accepted and taken for granted—
ing the French Revolution’s claim of liberté, egalité, one for the rich, another for the poor (Fonseca,
fraternité, and the fight for living with dignity— 1987; Chaves, 2009).
the latter, according to Mollat (1998), originat-
ing from one of the conceptions of poverty within Poverty According to Official Policies
Christendom, well-expressed by Saint Francis. Marx The understanding of poverty that prevails
(1890/1968) himself did not approach the subject contemporarily in academic and political spheres

540 bei ng poor


is based on some central ideas, which come from prevailing in the society to which they belonged. In
the end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the this sense, people are suffering from relative depri-
twentieth centuries. The first concerns the criteria to vation when they cannot get nourishment, ameni-
identify a poverty line and classify families accord- ties, standards, and services that allow them to play
ing to their position relative to this line. social roles, participate in relationships, and have
The first of these criteria is subsistence. Families the normal behavior as members of a given society.
were defined as in poverty when their income was People can suffer from relative deprivation in any
not “sufficient for maintaining mere physical effi- country—even the more developed ones—and it
ciency” (Rowntree, 1901, p. 86). Food, rent, and may concern one or more spheres of life (Townsend,
clothing were taken into account as indicators. If 1985, 1992; Desai & Shah, 1988; Sen, 1983, 1985;
the family income minus rent was not sufficient for Lister, 1991).
the consumption of the items above, the family was Therefore, the policies to eradicate poverty have
classified as under the poverty line—Rowntree’s con- been highly influenced by these conceptions. More
struct. After Rowntree’s studies in England (in 1901 recently, a dialogue between the so-called “official”
and 1918) and the policies on Social Security in the discourses and policies have begun to benefit from
1940s (Beveridge, 1943), the poverty line concept the discussion on poverty as social exclusion, elabo-
greatly influenced the scientific research and such rated mainly by French social scientists as Bourdieu
national and international policies and agencies as and Paugam (Ezequiel, 1998).
the World Bank. In the United States, the idea of As the recent report on the world social situation
subsistence predominated in governmental policies by the United Nations (2010) stresses, there is not
for poverty reduction until the late 1970s (Usdhew, a single criterion that separates the poor from the
1976). This conception can be found updated in non-poor. The experience of poverty is multifaceted
Gazeley and Newell (2000). and multidimensional, encompassing dimensions
Basic needs constitute the second criterion. The of time and relativity. Therefore, multiple indicators
concept of subsistence was criticized as long it was are needed to capture its scale and dimensions (p. 3);
built exclusively on physical needs, without consid- there exists, recognizably, a “poverty of poverty mea-
eration of social ones (Rein, 1970; Townsend, 1979). sures” (p. 45) to be overcome. The study “Voices of
In the 1970s, the International Labor Organization the Poor”, conducted by World Bank, is also a good
(ILO) argued that basic needs should include two example of a new research direction (Carr, 2003b;
components: (1) minimal consideration of con- Spink, 2003; Eyber & Ager, 2003).
sumption: adequate food, habitation and clothing,
and minimum housing and furniture; (2) access to The Discourse of Activism
community services in general, such as water, sanita- The Brazilian scholar Pedro Demo, synthesiz-
tion, public transport and health services, education, ing the discussion around poverty and inequality,
and culture (ILO, 1976, 1977). This framework has poverty and social exclusion, avers that “the most
a very important role in the international scenario, obstinate center of poverty is its political nucleus
strongly influencing the public policies for fighting of social exclusion, in addition to material depri-
poverty for all nations that sign the multilateral pro- vation” (p. 9): and here the “poverty politic” finds
grams of ILO (Brandt, 1980). Broadly understood, fertile ground to develop, having an impact also in
this concept also produces a frame of reference not the “poverty” of many studies of poverty, marked
only for survival but also for the prosperity of popu- by the same “political naiveté”—not to mention the
lations in all countries. researchers that benefit and draw prestige from the
Relative deprivation, which has been a very poverty of the majority.
popular concept in psychological research related Activists criticize welfarist policies, as long as
to poverty in the 1960s and 1970s (Carr, 2003), they consider that these policies delegitimize com-
resulting from the emphasis on prosperity over sur- munities’ political and emancipatory initiatives. The
vival, guided social scientists to formulate the third argument has been clearly exposed by Demo:
contemporary conception of the meaning of pov-
erty. In such a case, poverty applies not only to the [Public] assistance is a radical citizenship right
victims of poor income distribution but, in a more concerning material survival, linked to democratic
precise way, to the people whose resources do not ethics and, thus, independent of the market. The
allow them to satisfy the demands and social norms right to survival cannot be determined by insertion

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 541


in the market, because this would destroy ipso facto human complexity to its material face, despite of
the notion of subject implied in the law. This is the important scholars as Sen, who overcame this barrier.
problem: how to do assistance in such a way that (Demo, 2003, p. 37)
the beneficiary is not reduced to a recipient target of
In psychological research, a counterpart of the activ-
minimal and minimalist material aid, thwarting his/
ist discourse can be found in the intervention stud-
her emancipatory horizon?
ies, particularly when it comes to action-research.
(2003, p. 10)
In the United States, the work of Garbarino (1992,
In the context of developing countries, welfarist 1992b, 2008) and Kozol (1992, 2005) has illustrated
policies represent part of the solution but also part this trend, as have Latin American studies in educa-
of the problem, as much as the social projects so tion and social inclusion (Lacerda & Guzzo, 2010;
characterized can weaken civil society and promote Ferreira-Santos, 2009; Iriart & Milani, 2009) and
the depoliticization of the social question: the so called “psychologies of liberation” (Watkins &
In this context the poor are renamed by their Shulman, 2008). Thus, Villarreal and Díaz (2009)
fragilities, and not for their effective or potential have stressed that, in place of the “real plans of
strength. In technocratic discourse, they arise death” that the Mapuches sustain to be imposed by
decontextualized and de-historicized, reconstructed the Occident on indigenous people, a “plan of life”
by a new kind of surveillance, which disregards the should be proposed. And from Algiers, Mekideche
social values that allow solidarity, spontaneous (2009) asks: Does territory, as designed by the North,
cooperation and fraternity in daily life constitute a concept and a reality connected to the
(Ribeiro, 2005, pp. 20–21) economic contexts of the South? Her answer is that
this must be epistemologically questioned.
The issue of the political approach to poverty is
complex; let’s just emphasize its insufficiency, ambi-
The Discourse of Living Experience
guity, orientation for social control and the fact that
Saint Bernard would have said that “no man
the poor are rendered invisible as agentive persons.
should commend poverty unless he is poor.”4 The
The activist discourse is relevant as much it draws
analysis of famine in Africa made by de Waal (2005)
attention to this. However, it is possible that the real
illustrates the gap between the poor and non-
movement of the crowd—those anonymous people
poor world, evident through the many contrasts
so important in history (de Certeau, 2001)—be
between the concepts of famine held by European
kept out of reach.
and American scholars and those held by the peo-
Demo (2003), inspired by French literature
ple who actually suffer famines. His exemplar
on the matter, defines poverty as social exclusion,
analysis, considering Africa’s situation, identifies
characterized thus by “non-belongingness, social
how the difference between economic indicators
irrelevance, weak identity, mental depressions and
and being poor as a living experience impacts the
discriminatory nature” (p. 33). Here, instead of
efficiency of programs meant to diminish famine
centering the discussion on income levels (material
in the world.
basis for poverty), the author stresses the increasing
de Waal’s claims that the notion of famine could
vulnerability of the vast majority (social exclusion),
be better understood “if we discard the English
whose condition becomes more visible and global-
notion of ‘famine,’ and instead adopt the concepts
ized. According to Demo (2003), it is necessary to
used by the people who have experience suffering
realize that social exclusion cannot be reduced to
famines” (p. 24). An interesting example for illus-
the lack of essential goods but is, mainly, the situa-
trating this point comes from the different words
tion of someone unable to raise him/herself to the
used to refer to the experience of famine, as happens
status of controlling his/her destiny. Here, what is
in Bangladesh: there are akal (scarcity, when times
denied is emancipatory autonomy.
are bad), durvicka (famine, when alms are scarce),
Close to social exclusion stands social inequality,
and mananthor (famine widespread in the whole
on the basis of the unfair distribution of the income.
nation, bad times). These ideas go far beyond the
Poverty arises when scarce goods become privileged international definition commonly adopted:
goods, in a material and immaterial sense. At its heart
. . . widespread food shortage leading to a significant
is the removal of political content-an imposed, unfair
regional rise in death rates.
condition, historically produced and maintained.
( . . .) The economist approach persists in reducing (de Waal, 2005, p. 9)

542 bei ng poor


Indeed, the words above indicate several layers of (income poverty, food poverty), the new construct
complexity involved in the experience of famine, its of a subjective poverty has been proposed and val-
extension, and its diverse causality. ued inasmuch it gives the word to the poor so that
In the current world scenario, the case of fam- they can express their own suffering and expecta-
ine, analyzed by de Waal, is a good example also tions (Ferroukhi & Bedrani, 2009). That concept
to demonstrate the conflicting interests involved in is grounded on a non-utilitarist perspective from
initiatives to eradicate poverty, especially consider- which these authors, based on Sen’s work, accept
ing relations between rich and poor countries. the idea that maximizing personal reasons is not
More than famine is at stake: the only individual leit motiv: therefore, individ-
ual action can be motivated by compassion or social
This work should be seen in the context of other
commitment. Improving other people’s well-being
work which centered on starvation and the command
can improve one’s own well-being. This approach
over food for the starving, for example that of
implies the valorization of abilities and the under-
Sen (1981). The implication in Sen’s work is that
standing that having resources is not enough unless
command over food is the overwhelming, even the
the aptitude for using them well is also active.
only concert of famine victims. The implications of
The meaning of “being poor” varies widely accord-
the anthropological studies are that even when people
ing to the particular experiences individuals and soci-
are dying from starvation, the “conceptual centre”
eties go through. Hundeide (1999) has evinced how
of famine, for both the victims and people studying
this meaning is cultural and historically situated, con-
it, may not necessarily be that same starvation. The
sidering four different communities living in poverty:
experience of a threat to a way of life may be more real
Begumpur (slum-dwellers of Patna, India); Simpruk
than the experience of the threat of starvation.
(slum-dwellers of Jakarta); the homeless poor in
(p. 29, emphasis added)
the United States; and Jews of Eastern Europe. The
The imposed aid may be a burden, inasmuch as it author observes:
overlooks the perspective of the starving. Many
These four communities gave four different
times it is based on inconsistent constructs and tech-
reconstructions of their similar situations. The
niques, such as “child’s thinness,” “anthropometric
Begumpur population believed that everything in
surveillance:”
life happens according to a predestined pattern
The development of techniques such as nutritional leaving no room for individual effort. For the
surveillance creates a “citadel of expertise” (often Simpruk slum dwellers fate determines the
inappropriate expertise) which prevents dialogue possibilities of life and the fulfillment of these
with lay people, including the famine victims. It depends upon personal effort. The Western slum
also reinforces the “otherness” of famine, and its dwellers, with their individualist and materialistic
isolation from ordinary life (Hewitt, 1983). “Famine” orientation, put great emphasis on individual effort
has become a technical malfunction, not a human and personal success. Their failure in this context
experience. gives rise to a combination of guilt, resignation,
(p. 29) inferiority feelings and hatred towards authorities.
The East European Jews are more pragmatic in their
Furthermore, the recipients of this imposed aid only orientation. They face the challenges of everyday
rarely have the power to decide what this aid is and living through a practical tradition of skills in
how it can be used. Thus, trade and economy and a literary tradition of
The concept of poverty is bound to what we (the non- transcendental reconstructions.
poor) can do to alleviate it, rather than what they [the (p. 143)
poor] can do to alleviate it. The point of this is not to
pronounce upon the ethics of the aid business, but to
Esquit (2009) has studied the relationship between
place famine relief in the context of power relations
political action and the formation of the Indian
between rich and poor countries.
Guatemalan Kaqchikel’s concepts of meb’ail (“pov-
(de Waal, 2005, pp. 31–32, emphasis added)
erty”), qawinaq (“our people”), poqonal (“suffer-
ing”), and consciousness (“politically positioned”).
Although shy, new measures emerge in social For him, the Indians’ notion of poverty—through
research to approach the reality of living in pov- which they define their social relations—can be
erty. Aside from the traditional measures of poverty understood when we examine their language and

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 543


the discourses about history and daily life. This Individual trajectories through poverty can be illus-
analysis has shown that qawinag is a category that trated by the French example, where social policies,
defines the Indian being and the solidarity kept meant to integrate people under the welfare system,
because of meb’ail and distress they suffer facing establish three conditions: the assisted (depending
the hegemonical culture. He has emphasized that on welfare services), the fragile (still distant from
to be poor and Indian are kind of synonymous welfare services), and the marginalized (who had
because the differences between the Kaqchikel severed social bonds). This system contributes also
group and the dominant one always showed them to stigmatization (each condition in a different way)
as not having “house, food, clothes.” and sets up conditions for a broad array of personal
experiences and cultural tools for survival under
Poverty as a Process poverty.
According to Véras (2003), Paugam’s system
And one would not have given a fair representation
shares some of Robert Castel’s description of the
of a world that, as the social cosmos, has the
process of disaffiliation, which starts from the desta-
peculiarity of producing numerous representations of
bilization of the stable, who become vulnerable and
itself, without a place in the space of views for these
settle down in precarious conditions (long-term or
groups particularly exposed to little misery which are
recurrent unemployment). It is followed by the
all professions that have the task to treat or speak of
absence or deficit of places to be occupied in the
their great misery, as all the distortions related to the
social structure (social uselessness).
peculiarity of their views.
Paugam has worked on the concept of disquali-
(Bourdieu, 1997, p. 13)5
fication, related to social status and identity. One
The approach to poverty developed by contemporary could say it is his way to approach poverty as a living
French sociologists is very relevant for understand- experience:
ing being poor as a living experience. Embracing
the road opened by Bourdieu, Paugam can be rec- To study disqualification, the discrediting of those
ognized as the one who has developed a proces- who, at first glance, do not participate fully in
sual approach to poverty, as much as he focuses economic and social life, means to study the diversity
on trajectories built across ages and contexts where of status that defines personal identities, that is, the
there is an increasing social disqualification. Taking subjective feelings about their own situation along
into account the case of welfare policies in France, diverse social experiences, and finally the social
Paugam has worked with the notions of trajectory, relations that hold among themselves and with
identity (positive, negative), and territoriality (the others.
spatial basis that houses socially excluding processes, (Paugam, 2003, p.47)
such as segregation).
In the psychological field, diverse representations
One could say that Paugam’s analysis is based on
of poverty are present, sometimes implicitly, but
categories that assume the standpoint of the poor:
nevertheless orienting the view and choices of the
the kind of processes and situations people experi-
researcher. Obviously, these representations imply a
ence when crossing the several layers that constitute
certain concept of the psychologist as a scientist and
life in poverty.
as a practitioner. It is therefore possible to identify
The concepts involved in this debate often refer the social activist as the one who practices charity
to job insecurity, lack of qualification, uncertainty and philanthropy; the other who consents to work
toward the future, finally, to pauperism, coupled on explaining—for example, delinquency—for pur-
with the crisis of industrial society (from the poses of social control; and employees at institutions
nineteenth century to today) and the exclusion and funding agencies. These institutions and agen-
itself. Both refer to moral degradation as the new cies are oriented by specific goals and adopt images
condition of material deprivation ( . . .). There is a of poverty from an outsider perspective, hardly tak-
process which is progressively pushing to outside ing into account the poor’s own goals.
of the productive population those segments less Ezequiel’s report on Geremek’s account of the
qualified. It is, indeed, the disillusionment representation of poverty between the years 1400
in the belief that progress would bring and 1700 recognizes that “the constructions of
prosperity for all. the cultural elite regarding the marginal elite were
(Véras, 2003, p. 14) absorbed by the social elite as answers to its need to

544 bei ng poor


be horrified in front of the dirt and the unknown. Although providing relevant cues, these images
Such a strangeness was useful for praising their val- still do not fill in the blanks regarding being poor
ues and legitimizing the existing rules through the as a living experience. To consider just one of these
reversal of the discourse” (1998, p. 109). portraits, social disqualification based on disaffilia-
Therefore, a curious mosaic of intertwined tion, it is necessary to analyze the diverse statuses
meanings is set up: representations and explana- and personal identities involved in impoverishment
tions of poverty are available that do not consider (Paugam, 2003); the personal feelings concerning
the needs and goals of those who live in poverty. one’s own situation, the social relationships.
The actions generated by the studies on poverty, for In the field of cultural history, being poor as a liv-
their part, are directed to the poor, offering them ing experience can be described by specific features:
solutions that they internalize, and then comes the
Thinking of a cultural history of society, Chartier
moment where the well-known questions on the
(1990:19) states that its subject is the understanding
ability of the poor for a subjective life, for agency,
of shapes, motifs and representations of the social
emerge in the field of psychological studies and
world, which, despite of social actors, reflect their
practices (“Are the poor ready to go through psy-
interests and describe the social world as they think
chotherapy?”, “Are they able to maintain autono-
it is, or how they would like it to be. In consequence,
mous thinking?” or “Are they condemned to be in a
the values, the conceptions of the self and the
subordinated position?”). These kinds of questions
world and the images of the poor should be studied
appear with much distance and strangeness, as if
because they are constituents of the past as much as
referring to a different humankind, and are not
quantifiable information.
without consequences, inasmuch as they regulate
(Ezequiel, 1998, p. 104)
decisions and choices in the process of researching
and intervening on human lives. Balsa, Boneti, and Souler (2006) argue that the
Actually, sociological thinking registers different socio-anthropological analysis of poverty, unlike a
images of poverty, connected to different times and historical and socio-institutional approach, is sup-
paradigms, related to different dimensions of the posed to focus on
process of being or becoming poor, and also present
“The ways in which situations are rooted and
in the field of psychology. Bajoit (2006) offers the
the particular contexts and trajectories can be
following sketch of these images:
approached through the use of individual, family or
1. “The poor as marginal: he is poor because of his group life histories. The goal here is to examine how
bad socialization, or as he comes from a subculture poverty and its dimensions are grounded in personal
different from that of the majority of persons. So, biographies or how people experience and handle the
he cannot succeed because he is stigmatized (and events that lead to poverty and exclusion”.
cloistered inside his culture and his stigma by the (p. 22)
view of the others). (Oscar Lewis, Richard Hoggart,
A similar direction can be found in some psycho-
G. Simmel);
logical studies, moving—more or less resolutely—
2. The poor as exploited: he is poor because he is
toward constructing process models. For example,
exploited by the upper class/ruling class, because
in Garbarino’s (1992) claim of the need to consider
he is alienated, impoverished, excluded by the way
the “phenomenology of deprivation” (p. 231) start-
capitalism works, and he cannot succeed as he is
ing from the evaluation all human beings do of their
not protected and is not aided (Jean Labbens, Paul
situation, comparing it with their surroundings.
Vercauteren);
Therefore, to impoverish at recession times assumes
3. The poor as dependent: he is poor because he has
specific connotations: “It leads to a growing sense
no autonomy and no success, and cannot succeed
of deprivation that stands in stark contrast to the
because he does not have sufficient capital – as-
‘objective’ facts of modern affluence (pp. 230–231).”
sociability, information, training, trust, autonomy
Garbarino concludes:
(Klinsberg, Tomassini, Putnam).
4. The poor as disaffiliated: he is poor because he is “The phenomenology of poverty is dominated by
isolated, fragmented, and discouraged and he the experience of deprivation and exacerbated by
cannot succeed because he does not participate in widespread promulgation of highly monetarized
organized forms of solidarity (R. Castel, S. Paugam).” affluence as the standard. Low-paying jobs can come
(p. 92) to be interpreted as an affront in such a context,

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 545


the accoutrements of affluence a right. None of this meaningful number of subjects relevant to analyze
contributes to the well-being of young children. the scope and directions of psychological research
All of it sustains rage and despair.” and intervention addressing poverty—power and
(p. 231) justice, place and community, wealth and crisis,
psychopathology, and unemployment. We (Bastos
Undoubtedly, variables linked to poverty as a
& Rabinovich, 2009), in Living in Poverty—
situation (income, socio-economic status, envi-
Developmental Poetics of Cultural Reality, cover the
ronment, unemployment) have been exhaustively
results of investigation of social realities and their
measured in psychological research, as predicting
public representation in Brazilian poor communi-
outcomes. Carr (2003) has presented an interest-
ties, with a particular emphasis on the use of cul-
ing synthesis of some milestones relevant to under-
tural tools to survive and create psychological and
standing the relationship between psychology and
social novelty under conditions of severe poverty.
poverty since the late 1950s. He starts with the
sociological account of poverty represented by the
notion of a “culture of poverty” of Oscar Lewis and
Cultural Tools for Survival
“The miserable ones are those who confess to be de-
considers that a more psychological approach can be
feated. However, poor people do not surrender. Every
identified during the 1960s:
day they find out unprecedented/novel ways to work
During the 1960s, the field moved toward a much and fight. Thus, they face their difficulties and search
more psychological approach, captured most to overcome them. Having to be constantly alert,
succinctly in the concept of a Need of Achievement they do not have an intellectual rest. Memory would
(McClelland, 1961). In a similarly psychological way, be their enemy. The heritage of the past is flavored by
the 1970s were largely focused on attribution theory, the feeling of urgency, this awareness of novelty that
and in particular on how the comparatively wealthy is also an engine of knowledge”.
view the causes of poverty amongst the relatively —Milton Santos, 2000.7
deprived (Feagin, 1972). The 1980s, in turn,
The analysis of cultural tools for survival entails
witnessed something of a crisis of confidence in this
various conceptions about what survival is: What
type and level of analysis, culminating in suggestions
does it mean to be poor, to remain in poverty,
that psychology may be doing more harm than good
to overcome poverty? In which directions and
(for examples, see Sinha & Holzman, 1984). During
with which characteristics are cultural tools to be
the 1990s however, tentative calls that psychology
utilized?
might be able to make a difference began to appear
When it comes to survival and to coping with
(e.g., Sloan & Montero, 1990; Carr & MacLachlan,
poverty, two relevant alternatives are in place: sur-
1998). Bye the new millennia, we are witnessing
vival and coping. They need to be understood in
a renewed debate about the role of psychology in
the direction of adaptation: is the desired goal con-
fostering critical awareness of the causes of, and
forming to or overcoming poverty? In each case,
solutions to, poverty (Cohen, 2001).
which cultural tools are available and likely to be
(p. 2)
handled?
In the particular field of developmental psy- The concept of cultural tools comes originally
chology, we can see socio-economic variables often from Vygotsky and, from the beginning, has been
correlated to measures of development, with a defined by the quality of signs projected to master
predominance of linear, one-dimensional explana- and improve natural human psychological processes.
tory models. Some efforts, however, rely on differ- Signs are included in psychological operations just
ent, more systemic grounds, such as Bornstein and as tools are included in a work operation, and the
Bradley (2003) and Tudge (2008),6 who take into metaphor of tools is just as appropriate (Valsiner &
account the need of understanding the multiple lev- van der Veer, 1996). Cultural tools are, therefore,
els of organization involved in human development. media of transformation (Cole et al., 2001; Wertsch,
New trends exemplifying processual approaches 2002). To properly understand them, studies need
are also reflected in Poverty and Psychology—From to focus on processes and not on outcomes. Using
Global Perspective to Local Practice, edited by Carr cultural tools entails a focus on psychological dis-
and Sloan (2003). This pioneer work, coming from tancing, through the use of semiotic mediation for
what the authors name a positive and critical psy- overcoming, temporal and spatially, the particular
chology, has to be considered and encompasses a here-and-now situation.

546 bei ng poor


Collective Memory< seen as mediators affording people the capacity to
Collective memory is among the most widely create distinct versions of their collective past and to
usable cultural tools. It is a concept originally devel- share these versions that construct their “collective
oped by Maurice Halbwachs (1990), who claimed memory.” These memories are not about the past
that there are as many collective memories as col- but about present interests and conflicts (p. 113).
lectives. This concept contrasts with that often Belelli and Leone (2007) have argued that com-
employed in psychological studies on memory, munities “have a memory” only in a metaphorical
linked to the assumption that memory is a distinct sense; still, collective memories can be a marker of
phenomenon that can be studied isolated from other community life, favoring belongingness.
mental functions. Usually, it is studied as an indi- As a kind of cultural tool, collective memory
vidual phenomenon. Studies on collective memory, implies the possibility to organize and direct the
on the contrary, have the guiding assumption that it struggle for survival, which has important political
is a complex setting always bound with something consequences.
else (Wertsch, 2009, p. 122). It is also seen as in the
service of providing a usable past that serves some Resilience
group identity (p. 123), and this has led to a view Many studies centered on poverty have focused
of remembering as contestation and negotiation in cultural tools from a conceptual perspective broadly
social and political spheres (p. 124). Because of the called resilience. Resilience has been generally defined
issues involving memory in the group and memory as overcoming adversity and seen through different
of the group, Wertsch (2009) proposes the concept lens, disciplines, and theory approaches. For exam-
of a “distributed version” of collective memory: ple, Adger (2000), a geographer, has emphasized the
connection between social and ecological resilience,
From this perspective, memory is viewed as being
pointing that the demand for diverse and resilient
distributed: (a) socially in small group interaction;
resources partially determines location for a settle-
(b) “instrumentally” in the sense that it involves both
ment. But for Unger (2004, p. 344), a social worker
active agents and instruments” (p. 119). Cultural
and a family therapist, there are two discourses
tools belong to instrumental distribution. The author
on resilience: a positivist one, the ecological model,
suggests two forms of mediation: explicit linguistic
that defines resilience as “health despite adversity”,
forms, especially narratives, and forms of mediation
and a constructionist approach that defines it as “the
that rely more on embodied practices. Narratives
outcome from negotiations between individuals
are a crucial cultural tool for representing the past
and their environments for the resources to define
(APUD Bruner, 1990) and what makes collective
themselves as healthy amidst conditions collectively
memory collective is the fact that members of a
viewed as adverse.” And Payne’s methodological
group share the same narrative resources.
critics (2008) have highlighted the importance to
(p. 120)
capture the phenomenology of the studied person,
Wertsch (2009) proposes the concept of sche- which is not usually taken on account in studies
matic narrative templates as they concern abstract about resilience.
and generalized functions. The organizing form is a Other concepts to describe correlate phenomena
narrative, and these abstract structures can underlie are vulnerability, risk and protective factor, coping,
an entire set of specific narratives (p. 129). These and empowerment. Risk may be defined as statuses
narratives operate at a level that can be called “deep that increase the probability of failure as a conse-
collective memory” because they: quence of the imposition of structured constraints
(O’Connor, 2002). Constraints are practices that
“function to exert a conservative, yet unrecognized
systematically and/or institutionally limit the life
force on collective memory, making it resistant to
chances of particular groups of people. However,
change. This reflects the fact that they are deeply
Shih (2004, p. 180) opposes coping models to
embedded, both in the sense of being transparent
empowerment model: in the first, individuals are
and unconscious, and in the sense of being part of
motivated to avoid negative consequences rather
deeply held identity commitments.”
than to create positive ones; the second one pro-
(p. 130)
poses that overcoming adversity is not a depleting
Thus, cultural tools (either narratives or other process but rather a replenishing and enriching
means such as calendars, computers, etc.) can be process. In the same direction, Nicolas et al. (2009)

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 547


have used the concepts of strengths and resistance— their children in enriching activities, and maintained
not of resilience—to refer to active coping strategies family cohesion (Black & Lobo, 2008).
that youths learn to use to alter environments or However, framed within a positivist paradigm,
their reactions to adverse environmental contexts. most of these studies choose arbitrary distinctions of
Nevertheless, one important notion is that of what are to be accepted. “Such arbitrariness is more
opportunity: it signifies the availability of specific the result of ethnocentricism than of cross-cultural
institutional, material, or human resources that study that questions the hegemony of Western mid-
might be employed in the negotiation of structured dle class norms” (Ungar, 2004, p. 345).
constraints. Opportunity can be registered through Payne has highlighted this issue (2008, p. 5),
the availability of institutionalized and non-insti- studying “street people” (Black men) and noting
tutionalized resources. Institutionalized resources that traditional literatures on discussions of resil-
reflect systematic and structured supports that coun- iency are typically grounded in four problematic
teract or circumscribe constraints. In contrast, non- assumptions: (1) a middle-class and upper-middle-
institutionalized resources reflect those supports class orientation, (2) an a-historical stance, (3) an
that mitigate the impact of circumstances but are individualized perspective that often holds the per-
acquired through idiosyncratic or informal mecha- son solely responsible for the development of resil-
nisms. (O’Connor, 2002). iency, and (4) a refusal to consider the overall social
As a consequence of opportunity social differ- structural impact of economic conditions in the
entiation, Schoon et al. ( 2004, p. 399) concluded lived experiences.
from their study about levels of adult adapta- Therefore, in contexts such as poverty, the sig-
tion that for the socially disadvantaged, secondary nificance of societal context has been minimized
school adjustment was a more important predictor in resilience research (Bottrell, 2009a). Recently,
of successful adult adjustment than for their more research has centered on understanding processes to
privileged peers. Young people from disadvan- account for the complexity of factors and their corre-
taged backgrounds have to have the necessary cre- lated interactive effects (Abelev, 2009; Adger, 2000;
dentials to succeed, whereas for their privileged Bottrell 2009b; Brown, 2008; Gomes, Rabinovich,
peers, other factors, such as existing social networks & Bastos, 2005; Hernández, 2002; Jones, 2007;
and familial resources, might be more important. Payne, 2008; Seginer, 2008). That which may con-
Bronfenbrenner’s idea of a structure of opportuni- stitute risk in one cultural context may not apply
ties and its components—mainly the differentiated to another or elsewhere may constitute a protective
degree of permeability at each level of the context factor or process, based in specific conditions, cul-
and the differentiation by forms of social integration tural values, and norms (Ungar, 2004; Bastos et al.,
and participation (Goodnow, 1996)—was utilized by 2008). Moreover, criteria for assessment of positive
Bastos, Iriart, Alcântara, Milani, and Ferreira Santos or maladaptation may be embedded in socio-cul-
(2008) to analyze mechanisms for social inclusion of tural assumptions and historically specific societal
Brazilian adolescents living in poverty. expectations.
The study of resilience started from an individu- Bottrell’s study (2009b) has revealed that resil-
alistic approach to a much more complex and social ience goes beyond the protective factors currently
one. Historically, researchers relied on deficit mod- highlighted within the resilience literature, noting
els (Ceballo, 2004, p. 172). Poor families were seen that all her respondents also benefited from access
as potentially confronting multiple stresses, such as to the habitus of the middle class, without which
unemployment, substandard housing, lack of health they would not have exhibited the same level of
care, crime, violence, and substance abuse (Black & resilience. So, to become a middle class can be
Lobo, 2008). Poverty was considered a risk factor for understood as one way to surpass the difficulties of
a multitude of reasons, including family exposure to being poor—even if it can conduct to other kinds of
parents with higher stress and greater propensity for poverty, considering the restricted worlds and hori-
negative parenting, and neighborhood factors, such zons of some typical middle classes.
as crime, violence, drug use, peer influences, and Besides social class, gender and ethnicity have
cultural pressure (Abelev, 2009). Despite these pres- been related to poverty (Campbell, 2008; Hartman
sures, many low-income families not only met basic et al., 2009). O’Connor (2002, p. 878) has shown
needs, but were able to avoid violence and crime how constraints were expressly linked to the wom-
involvement, kept their children in school, engaged en’s positioning as Blacks and women, as well as to

548 bei ng poor


how the intersection of race, class, and space deter- rich lives within the context of a poor and environ-
mined their access to educational opportunity. This mentally degraded place “is not a naïve story about
point of view suggests the importance of resources poor people content with their low station in life.
to enhance both resilience and social capital because Such an interpretation would serve only the inter-
options and opportunities are constructed out of the ests of those who wish to retain the inequities of the
unequal resources of multiple interdependent capi- status quo” (Driskell, Bannerjee, & Chawla, 2001,
tals (O’Connor, 2002). The role of social structure p. 80). Driskell’s account of India Sathyanagar’s
in risk decision making has been extended beyond young people spoke of young people living under
social factors to include notions of power, opportu- difficult circumstances: of 6- and 7-year-olds thrust
nity, and constraint—for example, social exclusion, into adult roles; of hours spent each day in house-
access, and use of social networks, and the range of hold chores such as fetching potable water; of chil-
“social capital” available to the decision maker to dren exposed to open sewer drains in their daily
include the structure of opportunity itself and the play; of people’s lives cut short by disease and vio-
range of choices and resources genuinely available lence; and of social and political injustice. Yet they
(Kemshall, 2008). Therefore, Bottrell’s (2009b) also spoke of young people with an astonishing
study about Black student girls has shown that the degree of resilience. In many cases, the children of
students thrive on recognition within their own Sathyanagar could be described as confident, con-
networks, but “their pride can readily transform to nected, and happy—words seldom used to describe
shame and anger in the face of outsider” (p. 499). young people in many other cities that enjoy much
These two levels of focus (individual vs. collec- higher relative levels of well-being.
tive) may not always be exclusive and contradictory. Some approaches to Black and Native American
Stigmatized individuals who adopt an empowerment studies have turned their focus to cultural dif-
model tend to engage in efforts aimed at removing ferences. Brown (2009, p. 45) concludes that the
stigma at the collective level (Shih, 2004, p. 183). cultural practices of some Black American fami-
Those individuals believe that the stigma associated lies and communities may have a significant role
with the identity is unjust, and consequently, they in their resiliency. Having the support of another
are often spurred into action to remove the stigma person (e.g., family, peer, and community mem-
from the identity. ber) can be advantageous for African-Americans
Besides pride and relations of recognition that (Utsey, Bolden, Lanier, Williams, 2007, p. 77). The
close down opportunities and resources for some worldview of African-Americans is grounded in a
and open them for others differentiating types of strong spiritual/religious belief system, extended
networks and their capacities for facilitating accrual familial and fictive kinship bonds, a collective social
of social rewards and resources, social institutions orientation, and affective expressiveness. Studying
are subject to external pressures and shocks associ- the continuity as resistance of the Native American
ated with both political and economic change. The family, Gross (2003) has shown that “memory is a
ability to absorb these changes depends on social key source of self-destructive behavior, as well as of
capital but also on the role of surprises and the char- cultural resilience” (p. 31). So, cultural factors can
acteristics of the resource system (Adger, 2000). At a have a significant impact on the level of resilience
still broader perspective, Saint-Arnaud and Bernard reported by participants.
(2003) have accrued another perspective includ- The study of a gifted Black child living in rural
ing welfare regimes. The authors have concluded poverty (Hébert & Beardsley, 2001, p. 98) also
that the stability of the welfare regimes reflects the showed that the boy, besides solitude, “found that his
strength of their resilience when confronted with quiet surroundings gave him high-quality thinking
the effects of the economic transformations caused time and inspiration for his creative writing.” The
by globalization. authors note that educators need to appreciate and
So, either focusing on individual or social respect the cultural qualities of rural life to people
resources, the deficit model prevailed. More inter- born and raised in a rural culture. Related to an edu-
estingly, the concept of paradoxical poverty has cation process, Sartorello (2009) has proposed col-
been used to refer to places that are poor in material laboration, interlearning and co-theorizing to arrive
resources yet rich in social, cultural, or environmen- at a new curriculum in Chiapas, an Amerindian
tal resources (Driskell, Bannerjee, & Chawla, 2001). Mexican region. New Amerindian social movements
The paradox of people’s culturally and emotionally related to education can be seen in Chiapas but also

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 549


in the whole Mexico and in Latin America. These identifies. That is, stories of individual experience
new movements look for ethnic and solitary citi- are frequently employed in direct reference to the
zenship, supported by Amerindian cultures against content or structure of family trauma experiences or
the domination–submission balance between the oral history (p. 406).
national-mestizo culture and Amerindian cultures. Based on these considerations, our understand-
He insists that educators must listen to the voices ing of cultural tools and resilience related to poverty
of their Indian collaborators and let themselves at made us highlight the following features: belong-
some measure be guided by them so they can con- ingness; hope; destiny; cultural beliefs and values;
struct and express their educational proposal. spirituality; and strategic interpretations of social
environment.
Folk and Oral Culture
Santos (2009, p. 143), discussing the effects of Group Identification: Belongingness
globalization, opposes the resistance of the previous and Spirituality
culture to the mass culture, dominated by the inter- Individuals that are highly identified with their
national market. This folk culture outlines the daily group, despite the negative meaning associated with
life of the poor people using the mass media tools. it, are more likely to be empowered. They inter-
Even so, its content is not “global” because its base act with others from the same group and are more
is grounded on the territory and on the traditional aware of the positive aspects of their group member-
and local culture (p. 144). For this author, scarcity ship. As a result, they are less likely to buy into the
is again the main issue; as “the poor” do not have negative messages received from society about their
the instruments (material and others) to partici- negative public identity (Shih, 2004, p. 181).
pate in the modern mass culture, their own culture, Hernández (2002) has defined autogestión as
based on territory, work, and daily life, becomes
“the name in Spanish to the processes in which
strengthened and finds its way out. So, territoriality
communities develop agency and organize themselves
is important to consider how poor people manage
to demand the fulfilling of their rights, restructure
to find solutions to their challenges. This is culture
relationships of power within the community, or
and how they do it, cultural tools.
become political in society.”
Martins (2000) also stresses that poor people’s
(p. 343)
common sense is socially related shared knowledge
(p. 59). Meaning comes before the relationship Social networks in communities living in poverty
“because without shared meaning there is no interac- can be seen as a survival mechanism. Informal kin-
tion” (p. 59). Meaning is reciprocally perceived and ship is another manifestation of the value of inter-
negotiated by the participants. So, new meanings are connectedness and authenticity, present in the
continually re-invented and not only merely copied. Afrocentric belief system. It is a manifestation of
An important contribution to understand cultural the collective social identity whereby one has a view
tools related to poverty comes from Denham (2008). of oneself as part of a community. As a result, the
His study focused on narratives of resilience of one microsystem expands to include more than imme-
Indian American family to understand historical diate and extended family members (Jones, 2007).
trauma. Owing to the manner in which memories Driskell et al. (2001) have shown that the children
and ancestral identity are transmitted to future gen- of Sathyanagar had the advantage of being part of a
erations, family members constructed their sense generally cohesive culture steeped in tradition, myth,
of self from a network or chain of intergenerational and ritual that gave them a strong sense of identity.
memories and narratives situated within the larger They knew who they were and had a strong sense of
socio-cultural, political, and historical context. belonging, partly because of their extended family
Children are told: “Never forget who you are and networks, strong ties of kinship, and a vibrant social
where you come from.” The author concludes that and cultural context in which interaction with com-
the resilient dimensions of the narrative praxis of munity members of all ages was an integral part of
the family—that is, the active employment, telling, daily life. Analogous trends have been analyzed by
and interpretation of narratives—illustrate how per- Mahfoud and Massimi (2009), in a Brazilian semi-
sonal situations or experiences are given meaning rural community that stands on religious traditions,
and often interpreted in relation to a specific narra- particularly celebrations (“festas”) to relate with
tive or an ancestor with whom the individual closely modernization without losing the sense of identity,

550 bei ng poor


keeping the autonomy for making choices and posi- Hope and Destiny
tioning themselves. Belongingness and celebration Lothe and Heggen (2003), after their study in
of the history and the artistic resources of the com- Ethiopia, raised the question: “Is resiliency suf-
munity were found by Ferreira Santos (2009) to ficiently differentiated to fit cultural setting in the
be the most important strengths in the struggle to countries of the South? (p. 319), based on a possible
survive for adolescents living in a slum of Salvador, cultural bias of the lack of attention paid to the sig-
Brazil. nificance of hope that “emerges as the most signifi-
Historically, spirituality has been defined as a cant source for survival” ( p. 320). For Hernández
search for universal truth and meaning or a form of (2002), studying the meaning of hope and solidar-
belief that connects an individual to the world and ity in Colombia Latin American context facing war
provides meaning to one’s existence (Jones, 2007, and political repression, the locus of hope is located
p. 131). Cultural resources are sources of external in the building of social networks and promoting
support, such as religion and spirituality and avail- agency. From Israel, studying the psychological fac-
ability of extended family networks (Nicolas et al., tors that facilitate adolescent future orientation in
2009). The term religiosity historically has been asso- times of political violence, Seginer (2008) has out-
ciated with functional, institutionalized behaviors lined an integrated model positing that the effect of
associated with religion. More recently, researchers challenge/resilience on future orientation is medi-
have begun to minimize the polarized nature of these ated by hope. She has defined hope as “a positive
definitions and consider a more integrated definition emotion specifically related to the feeling that things
of spirituality. Jones (2007) focused cultural beliefs will turn for the best, and close to the meaning yet
and values that are used as coping mechanisms in the distinguished from optimism” (p. 277). Finally,
context of specific African-Americans. Participants Payne’s (2008, p. 9) project has provided a social
in the study included 71 African-American children psychological examination of how street life as an
between the ages of 9 and 11 years who lived in a ideology and set of relations and networks operate in
high-crime, high-poverty community in Houston, the lives of low-income Black men as a space within
Texas. The results indicated that formal kinship and which hope, friendships, violence, terror, risk, opti-
spirituality, along with high levels of combined sup- mism, and struggles for survival are displayed.
ports, demonstrated buffering effects on exposure to A very interesting way of looking to des-
violence. Utsey et al. (2007) concluded that spiri- tiny and to its underlying processes is proposed
tual and collective coping were statistically signifi- by Chaturvedi, Avinish, Chiu Chi-yue, and
cant predictors of quality-of-life outcomes above and Viswanathan Madhubalan (2009) by using the con-
beyond the traditional predictive factors for African- cept of negotiable faith belief. This model accepts
Americans from high-risk urban communities. that the individual does not have direct control over
In Driskell’s et al. study (2001) in India, reli- one’s fate and at the same time maintains that the
gion, with its symbols and rituals, also played an individual can negotiate control with fate for bet-
important role in community life. From Brazil, ter personal outcomes (p. 882). They differentiated
people living on the border of the Amazon River it from disjoint agency “which boasts the ability of
emphasized the importance of family, nature, self-determine one’s course of action and outcomes
work, and religiosity (Vasconcelos, 2009). The unconstrained circumstances” and from “fatalism,
religiosity in this context legitimated the family which holds that all events are predetermined by
and work relationships and demonstrated it to fate.” Negotiable fate recognizes fate as a powerful
be strongly tied to the regional traditional values. causal agent through agentic actions (p. 881).
And Terena (2009), a great Brazilian Indian leader, In their study, among relatively low literacy in
has said that spirituality is a criterion shared by Indians, the belief in negotiable fate was linked to
every Amerindian together with oral, historical, a greater tendency to engage in decontextualized
and ancestral wisdom, which maintain the balance judgment and rule bases categorization (p. 890).
and the quality of life. This thinking style is privileged by Western culture
Spirituality is a broader term than religiosity, and not in societies where contextualized, intui-
but both seem important when we consider them tive thinking is emphasized. They “speculate that,
as cultural. Both also are related to belonging to among these individuals, the belief in negotiable fate
a group, either transcendental or more socially and its associated thinking style may support a focus
based. on their personal agency despite the environmental

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 551


constraints. Specifically, this belief may help these to dissociate research, theoretical understanding,
individuals to identify the critical factors that cre- and social change when it comes to poverty; sim-
ate and remains the major constraints in their life” ilarly, poverty is a phenomenon that entails eco-
(p. 891) and motivate them to identify rules to max- nomic, social, psychological, cultural, and ethic
imize personal control without directly confronting dimensions. No wonder that so many initiatives to
the “nonmalleable” social reality. reduce or alleviate poverty fail. However, there are
There is a Brazilian’s expression, jeitinho (literally, signs that justify some optimism.
“little way”), which is difficult to be translated but To recognize this mixed, complex nature of pov-
means “that a problem should be accepted as given” erty and the trials for interdisciplinary and inter-
(Torres & Dessen, 2006, p. 262) but that at the end cultural approaches is an important, positive sign.
some solution will be anyway achieved. This expres- The initiative of United Nations inviting 10 inter-
sion is similar to the concept of negotiable faith national journals of psychology to elaborate special
belief in the sense that, even if fate exists, agency issues on the subject of poverty is an interesting
also plays a role and results depend on both. example in the search of a more complex, integrated
Besides, there are other processes to overcome view in the development of policies and strategies
stressful poverty situations related to strategic inter- for poverty reduction. However, as Tripathi (2010)
pretations of social environment. Individuals may has observed, the possibility of halving poverty in
switch their identity orientations across situations the world in 2015, as a Millennium Development
to strategically emphasize identities that are valued Goal, is not likely to be achieved then.
and de-emphasize identities that are not in any An effective criticism about conceptual perspec-
given social context. Work on identity adaptiveness tives on poverty has to be centered on the question
has found that individuals orient themselves more of its relation with alterity. Everything is preceded
positively toward identities that are adaptive in any by how poverty is perceived and by the way one
given situation (Shih, 2004, p. 179). In a broader relates to it (de Waal, 2005; Bastos, Rabinovich,
sense, orientation to the future and human capa- & Almeida, 2010). Here, we need to consider the
bility of psychological distance respond for survival diverse discourses and to situate ourselves in relation
under adversity, as exemplified in the experience of to them. This challenge requires basic changes in the
Brazilian families living in poverty. There is a poetic way of feeling, thinking, and acting of researchers
dynamics involved here, in every shift that chal- and practitioners. The issues discussed in this chap-
lenges what is and clearly promotes moving into the ter can help to delineate the nature and directions of
direction of what could be and should be (Bastos & these changes, and it may be worthy now to single
Rabinovich, 2009). out some of them.
Individuals can manipulate their interpretations The first issue concerns the cleavage between
of their environment to protect their sense of self- being poor as a living experience and as a focus for
worth. By changing their standards of comparison, study and intervention, and the epistemic and ethic
individuals are able to ameliorate perceptions of challenges to build different basis for the relation-
inequity and relative deprivation (Shih, 2004, p. ships I–Other, in a globalized world and at multiple
179). They also may manipulate the kind of attri- levels—the person, the family, the community. New
butions they make to explain social events. developments in the conception of poverty and in
These could be cultural tools that underlie some research methods are needed, articulating the study
processes by which poor people manage to survive. of micro- and macro-level processes and fostering
As Kumar (2010, p. 16) has concluded, cultures the voices of the poor to be heard, taking advantage
remain an important variable in explaining phe- of cultural diversity.
nomena linked to poverty and development, but Besides the two psychological models in under-
daily culture is majorly responsible for structuring standing poverty presented by Tripathi (2010), dispo-
the responses to real-life situations. sitional (where the poor are held responsible for their
fate and fall victim to stigmatization and prejudices
Future Directions that are based on social class or a social category)
The issue of poverty, broadly considered, and for and situational (that holds the social, economic, and
its implications for human lives in several senses and political conditions responsible for the emergence
at multiple levels, cannot be reduced to a research of the social class of the poor), it is also needed a dif-
topic or to a technical problem. It seems impossible ferent perspective on poverty, a perspective capable

552 bei ng poor


of revealing the cultural tools that the poor wield the poetry of a diversity of ways of life that still, in
for survival, and the developmental poetics present a certain measure, escape from homogenizing and
under adverse and paradoxical circumstances. Such impoverished models as, for example, the limits,
an approach aims to overcome the blindness—still paradoxes, and suffering of consumer society.
present in psychological research—toward the broad In this context, it is worthy to have in mind the
variability of modes of living, and in doing so, allow goal stated by the United Nations—even if inscribed
us to dialogically consider diversity and otherness. in the official discourse, which needs to fight very
A third set of questions is directly related to cul- much to be recognized and legitimated from the
tural tools, as we understand here. Which cultural standpoint of people living in poverty:
tools are employed in the struggle for survival, and
Promoting inclusion and reducing deprivation
how does it happen? Cultural tools are media of
strengthens democratic institutions and processes,
transformation (Cole et al., 2001; Wertsch, 2002)
making social and economic relations more
and media for understanding social change itself.
harmonious, and provides a firm foundation for
Research should also focus on the new cultural tools
long-term development and prosperity.
that continuously emerge from the struggle of the
(UN, 2010, p. 7)
human being to survive, living in a world of poor
and non-poor people, full of heterogeneous and
ambivalent social directions. Notes
We agree with Tripathi when he says that “pov- 1. Pearl, A. (1970). The poverty of psychology: An indict-
ment. In V.L. Allen (Ed.). Psychological factors in poverty (pp.
erty reduction requires approaches which are trans-
348–364). Chicago, IL: Markham.
disciplinary. Poverty alleviation cannot be left to be 2. Retrieved October, 6, 2009, from Online Etymology Dic-
dealt with by any single discipline” (pp. 216–217). tionnary. http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?search=povert
Furthermore, we would say that poverty reduction y&searchmode=none
requires intercultural and intersectorial approaches, 3. It is interesting to note that the idea of a poverty line was
present then: Mollat reports the medieval French expression saying
far beyond of the academics and governmental
of a man “that he ‘fell’ into servitude or misery, or that he could not
walls. Nothing will happen without the effective ‘maintain his estate,’ much less ‘rise again’” (1989, p. 5).
and agentic participation of the poor, at the social 4. In: The Free Dictionary by Farlex. Retrieved April 6, 2010,
level and at the personal level as well. Whatever from http://www.thefreedictionary.com/poverty.
should be the role of the researcher in this process, 5. E não se teria dado uma representação justa de um mundo
que, como o cosmos social, tem a peculiaridade de produzir
he/she must be aware of the political implications
inúmeras representações de si mesmo, se não se tivesse feito seu
of every decision and step taken. These implications lugar no espaço dos pontos de vista para essas categorias par-
start from the conceptions he/she holds about pov- ticularmente expostas à pequena miséria que são todas as profis-
erty and the relationship with the poor. In a cer- sões que têm por missão tratar a grande miséria ou falar dela,
tain way, we must also consider that the researcher com todas as distorções ligadas à particularidade de seu ponto de
vista” (Bourdieu, 1997, p. 13).
has necessarily a political and a social inclusion
6 These authors study, respectively, parenting and child devel-
that participates in his/her research. The possibil- opment and culture, class, and child-rearing in diverse societies.
ity of investigating poverty depends on an honest, 7 Miseráveis são os que se confessam derrotados. Mas os
intense, and open practice of reflexivity consider- pobres não se entregam. Eles descobrem cada dia formas inéditas
ing the place occupied by the researcher allied to de trabalho e de luta. Assim, eles enfrentam e buscam remédio
para suas dificuldades. Nessa condição de alerta permanente, não
intervention as a way of knowledge. The participant
têm repouso intelectual. A memória seria sua inimiga. A herança
of the research also must occupy the place of the do passado é temperada pelo sentimento de urgência, essa con-
knowledge constructor. sciência do novo que é, também, um motor do conhecimento”.
Finally, an intercultural perspective is impor- Milton Santos, 2000.
tant to identify general patterns of conditions, con-
texts, and ways of feeling, thinking, and acting that References
produce specific ways of survival. It would favor a Abelev, M. (2009). Advancing out of poverty: social class world-
broad vision of poverty as part of human experi- view and its relation to resilience. Journal of Adolescent
ence—to be transformed toward dignity—but still Research, 24(1), 114–141. Retrieved April 27, 2009, from
a source of psychological and socio-cultural novelty http//www.jar.sagepub.com.
Adger, W. N. (2009). Social and ecological resilience: are they
and concerning every human being, poor and non- related? Progress in Human Geography, 24(3), 347–364.
poor, for its multiple implications. Poverty must not Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.phg.sagepub.
be a stigma that superposes itself to richness and to com.

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 553


Bajoit, G. (2006). Olhares Sociológicos, Rostos da Pobreza e Carr, S.C. (2003a) Poverty and Psychology. An Introduction. In:
Concepções do Trabalho Social. In: C. Balsa, L.W. Bonete, S.C. Carr & T. S. Sloan (Eds.) Poverty and Psychology. From
& M.-H.Soulet (Eds.): Conceitos e Dimensões da Pobreza e da Global Perspective to Local Practice. (pp. 1–15). New York:
Exclusão Social. Uma Abordagem Transnacional. (pp. 91–102). Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.
Ijuí, Brazil & Lisboa, Portugal: Editora Unijuí/CEOS – Carr, S.C. (2003b). Poverty and Justice. In: S.C. Carr &
Investigações Sociológicas. T. S. Sloan (Eds.) Poverty and Psychology. From Global
Balsa, C., Boneti, L. & Souler, M-H. (2006). Conceitos e dimen- Perspective to Local Practice. New York: Kluwer Academic/
sões da pobreza e da exclusão social. Uma abordagem transnacio- Plenum Publishers.
nal. Ijuí, Brasil/Lisboa, Portugal: Editora UNIJUÍ/CEOS. Ceballo, R. (2004). From Barrios to Yale: The role of parenting
Bastos,A.C.S.; Iriart,M.F.S. ; Alcântara,M.A.R. ; Milani, F.M ; strategies in Latino families. Hispanic Journal of Behavioral
Ferreira-Santos, J.E. (2008). O risco e a possibilidade: ser Sciences, 26(2), 171–186. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from
adolescente em contextos brasileiros.. In: L. R. de Castro and http://www.hjb.sagepub.com.
V. Besset. (Org.). Pesquisa-intervenção na infância e juventude. Chaturvedi, A., Chiu C.-Y., & Viswanathan, M. (2009).
(pp. 567–586). Rio de Janeiro: NAU Editora/FAPERJ Literacy, negotiable fate, and thinking style among low
Bastos, A.C.S. & Rabinovich, E.P. (2009). Living in Poverty. income women in India. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology,
Developmental Poetics of Cultural Realities. Charlotte, NC: 40(5), 880–893.
Information Age Publishing. Chaves, A. M. (1998). Crianças abandonadas ou desprotegi-
Bastos, A.C.S. & Rabinovich, E.P. (Eds). (2009) Living in Poverty. das? Unpublished dissertation presented to the Institute of
Developmental Poetics of Cultural Realities (pp. 237–252). Psychology, University of São Paulo, São Paulo
Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers. Chaves, A. M., Borrione, R. T., & Mesquita, G. R. (2009).
Bastos, A.C.S., Rabinovich, E.P. & Almeida, M.B. (2010). Protection Offered to Poor Children by the Holy House of
Living the World of Poverty: The Researcher as Participant/ Mercy in Bahia During the 19th Century. In A.C.S.
Apprentice. Psychology and Developing Societies. The Poor in Cole, M., Gay L., Glick, J. A., & Sharp, D. W. (1971). The cul-
Developing Societies, 22(2) (Special Issue), 221–247. tural context of learning and thinking: an exploration in experi-
Belelli, G., Curci, A. & Leone, G. (2007). Social and Cognitive mental anthropology. New York: Basic Books.
Determinants of Collective Memory for Public Events. In. Cole, M. (1995). Culture and Cognitive Development: From
J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds). The Cambridge Handbook of Cross-Cultural Research to Creating Systems of Cultural
Sociocultural Psychology. (pp. 625–644). Cambridge, UK/ Mediation. Culture & Psychology, 1, 25–54. Retrieved February,
New York: Cambridge University Press. 2010, from http://cap.sagepub.com/cgi/reprint/1/1/25.
Bertau, M-C. & Gonçalves, M. (2007). Looking at “Meaning Couto, M. (2005). O último vôo do flamingo. São Paulo:
as Movement” In Development: Introductory Reflections Companhia das Letras.
on the Developmental Origins of the Dialogical Self. De Certeau, M. (2001). A invenção do cotidiano. Petrópolis: Vozes.
International Journal for Dialogical Science, 2(1), 1–13. De Waal, A. (2005). Famine that kills. Darfur, Sudan. New York:
Beveridge, W. H. (1943). The Pillars of Security. London: Allen Oxford University Press.
& Unwin. Demo, P. (2003). Pobreza da Pobreza. Petrópolis: Vozes.
Black, K., & Lobo, M. (2008). A conceptual review of family Denham, A. R. (2008). Rethinking historical trauma:
resilience factors. Journal of Family Nursing, 14(1), 33–55. Narratives of resilience. Transcultural Psychiatry 45(3),
Retrieved April 27, 2009, from http://www.jfn.sagepub. 391–414. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.
com. tps.sagepub.com.
Bornstein, M. H., & Bradley, R. H. (2003). Socioeconomic Status, Desai, M., & Shah, A. (1988). An Econometric approach to
Parenting and Child Development. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence the measurement of poverty. Oxford Economic Papers, 40(3),
Erlbaum Associates, Publishers. 505–522.
Bottrell, D. (2009). Dealing with disadvantage: Resilience and Driskell D., Bannerjee K., & Chawla, L. (2001). Rhetoric, reality
the Social Capital of Young People’s Networks. Youth & and resilience: overcoming obstacles to young people’s par-
Society, 40(4), 476–501. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from ticipation in development. Environment and Urbanization,
http://www.yas.sagepub.com. 13(1), 77–89. Retrieved April 27, 2009, from http://www.
Bottrell. D. (2009). Understanding ‘Marginal’ Perspectives: eau.sagepub.com.
Towards a Social Theory of Resilience. Qualitative Social Eyber, C. & Ager, A. (2003). Poverty and Youth. In: S.C. Carr
Work, 8, 321–330. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http:// & T. S. Sloan (Eds.) Poverty and Psychology. From Global
www.qsw.sagepub.com. Perspective to Local Practice. (pp. 229–250). New York:
Bourdieu, P. (1998). A Miséria do Mundo. Petrópolis, RJ: Editora Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.
Vozes. Esquit, E. (2009). Historias sobre la opresión y la lucha política
Brandt, W. (1980). North-South: a Programme for Survival. entre los kaqchikel, en Guatemala, siglo XX. Annals of the
London: Pan. XIIème Congrès de l’ARIC (Association Internationale pour la
Brown, D. L. (2008). African American resiliency: examining Recherche Interculturelle)
racial socialization and social support as protective factors. Ezequiel, M. (1998). Pobreza como Objeto Histórico: Problemas
Journal of Black Psychology, 34(1), 32–48. Retrieved October Empíricos e Teóricos. Diálogos, 2, 95–112.
6, 2009, from http://www.jbp.sagepub.com. Ferreira-Santos, J.E. (2009). Transitions through Adolescente in
Campbell, W. S. (2008). Lessons in resilience. Undocumented Novos Alagados : Reflections on an Experienc Report. In:
Mexican women in South Carolina. Affilia: Journal of Women A.C.S. Bastos & E. R. Rabinovich (Eds). Living in Poverty.
and Social Work, 23(3), 231–241. Retrieved October 6, Developmental Poetics of Cultural Realities (pp. 237–252).
2009, from http://www.aff.sagepub.com. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.

554 bei ng poor


Ferroukhi, A., & Slimane, B. (2009). Perception de la Pauvreté International Labour Organization. (1976). Growth and Basic
par les Agriculteurs Beneficiaires des Soutiens Fnrda. Les Needs: a One-World Problem. Genebra.
Cahiers du CRÉAD, 87, 137–154. International Labour Organization. (1977). Meeting Basic Needs:
Fonseca, C. (1987). O internato do pobre: Febem e a organiza- Strategies for Erradicating Mass Poverty and Unemployment.
ção doméstica em um grupo Porto-alegrense de baixa renda. Genebra.
Temas IMESC, Sociedade, Direito, Saúde, 41(1), 21–39. Jones, J. M. (2007). American children exposure to chronic
Garbarino, J. (1992a). The Meaning of Poverty in the World of community violence: resilience in African American chil-
Chidren. American Behavioral Scientist. 35 (3), 220–237. dren. Journal of Black Psychology, 33(2), 125–149. Retrieved
Garbarino, J. (1992b). Children and Families in the Social October 6, 2009, from http://jbp.sagepub.com.
Environment (2nd Edition). New York: Aldine de Gruyter. Kemshall, H. (2008). Risks, rights and justice: understanding
Garbarino, J. (2008). Children and the Dark Side of Human and responding to youth risk. The National Association for
Experience. Confronting Global Realities and Rethinking Youth Justice, 8(1), 21–37.
Child Development. New York: Springer Science + Business Kozol, J. (1992). Savage Inequalities. Children in America’s Schools.
Media. New York: Harper Perennial.
Goodnow, J. J. (1996). Differentiating among social contexts: by Kozol, J. (2005). The Shame of the Nation. The Restoration
spatial features, forms of participation, and social contracts. of Apartheid Schooling in America. New York: Crown
In P. Moen, G. H. Elder Jr. & K. Lüscher (Eds.), Examining Publishers.
lives in context. Perspectives on the ecology of human develop- Krumer-Nevo, M. (2002). The arena of othering. A life-story
ment. Washington, DC: APA. study with women living in poverty and social marginality.
Gomes, M. C. C., Rabinovich, E. P., & Bastos, A. C. S. (2005). Qualitative Social Work, 1(3), 303–318.
A resiliência em mulheres de um bairro popular de Salvador, Lacerda, F., & Guzzo, R. (2011). Psicologia e sociedade: interfaces
Bahia: recursos pessoais e contextuais. Revista Brasileira no debate da questão social. Campinas, SP: Alínea.
Crescimento Desenvolvimento Humano, 15(3), 49–56. Lister, R. (1991). Concepts of poverty. Social Studies Review 6,
Gross, E. R. (2003). Native American family continuity as resis- 192–195.
tance. The Indian Child Welfare Act as legitimization for an Lothe, E. A. (2003). A study of resilience in young Ethiopian
effective social work practice. Journal of Social Work 3(1), famine survivors. Journal of Transcultural Nursing, 14(4),
31–44. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://jsw.sagepub. 313–320.
com. Lynn McIntyre, L., Officer, S., & Robinson, L. M. (2003).
Halbwachs, M. (1990/1950) A memória coletiva. São Paulo: Feeling Poor: The Felt Experience Low-Income Lone
Vértice. Mothers. Affilia, 18(3), 316–331.
Hartman, J. L., Turner M. G., Daigle, L. E., Exum M. L., & Mahfoud, M. & Massimi, M. (2009). Cultural Dynamics in a
Cullen F. T. (2009). Exploring the gender differences in Brazilian Community> Representation and Re-elaboration
protective factors implications for understanding resiliency. of Meaning in Morro Vermelho. In A.C.S. Bastos &
International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative E.R.Rabinovich (Orgs). Living in Poverty. Developmental
Criminology, 53(3), 249–277. Retrieved February 11, 2010, Poetics of Cultural Realities (pp. 237–252). Charlotte, NC:
from http://ijo.sagepub.com Information Age Publishers.
Harper, D.J. (2003). Poverty and discourse. In Carr, S.C. Marx. K. (1890/1968). O capital (Crítica da economia política).
(2003). Poverty and Justice. In: S.C. Carr & T. S. Sloan Livro 1: O processo de promoção capitalista. (R. Sant´Anna,
(Eds.) Poverty and Psychology. From Global Perspective to Trad.). Rio de Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira. (original in
Local Practice. (pp. 185–204). New York: Kluwer Academic/ Geman Das Kapital).
Plenum Publishers. Mekideche, T. (2009). Le paradigme territorial en économie
Hébert, T. P., & Beardsley, T. M. (2001). Jermaine: A critical case à l’épreuve des réalités du sud. Vers de nouveaux para-
study of a gifted black child living in rural poverty. Gifted digmes : la niche territoriale. Annals of the XIIème Congrès
Child Quarterly, 45(2), 85–102. Retrieved October 6, 2009, de l’ARIC (Association Internationale pour la Recherche
from http://gcq.sagepub.com. Interculturelle).
Hernández, P. (2002). Resilience in families and communi- Moll, I. (1995). Cultural People and Cultural Contexts: Comments
ties: Latin American contributions from the Psychology of on Wertsch (1995) and Cole (1995). Culture & Psychology, 1,
Liberation. The Family Journal, 10(5), 334–343. Retrieved 361–171. Retrieved February, 2010, from http://cap.sagepub.
April 27, 2009, from http://www.sagepublications.com. com/cgi/reprint/1/3/361.
Hugo, V. Les Misérables. Retrieved from Online Etymology Mollat, M. (1986). The Poor in the Middle Ages. An Essai in Social
Dictionary, Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www. History. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.
etymonline.com/index.php?search=poverty&searchmode=nl Nicolas, G., Helms, J. E., Jernigan, M. M., Sass, T., Skrzypek,
Hundeide, K. (1999). Four Different Meanings of “Being A., & DeSilva, A. M. (2008). A conceptual framework for
Poor”. Psychology Developing Societies. Retrieved February understanding the strengths of Black youths. Journal of Black
11, 2010, from http://pds.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract Psychology, 34(3), 261–280. Retrieved October 6, 2009,
/11/2/143 from http://www.jbp.sagepub.com.
Ian, G. & Andrew Newell. (2000). Rowntree Revisited: Poverty O’Connor, C. (2002). Black women beating the odds from one
in Britain, 1900. Explorations in Economic History, 37(2), generation to the next: How the changing dynamics of con-
174–188. straint and opportunity affect the process of Educational
ILO Brazil (2006). Agenda Nacional de Trabalho Decente. Resilience. American Educational Research Journal, 39(4),
Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.oitbrasil.org. 855–903. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.
br/info/downloadfile.php?fileId=237. aerj.aera.net.

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 555


Paugam, S. (2003). Desqualificação social: ensaio sobre a nova Terena, M. (2009). Espiritualidad y conocimiento tradicional
pobreza. São Paulo: Educ/Cortez. indígena. Annals of the XIIème Congrès de l’ARIC (Association
Payne, Y. A. (2008). “Street life” as a site of resiliency: how street Internationale pour la Recherche Interculturelle).
life–oriented black. men frame opportunity in the United Torres, C. V., & Dessen, M. A. (2006). The Brazilian jeitinho:
States. Journal of Black Psychology, 34(1), 3–31. Retrieved Brazil’s sub-cultures, its diversity of social contexts, and its
October 6, 2009, from http://www.jbp.sagepub.com. family structures. In J. Georgas, J.W. Berry, F.J. R. van de
Pepetela (2009). O planalto e a estepe. São Paulo: Leia. Vijver, Ç. K., & Y. H. P. (Eds.), Families across cultures. A
Rein, M. (1970). Problems in definition and measurement of pov- 30-nation psychological study (pp. 259–266). Cambridge,
erty in The concept of poverty. Peter Townsend (Org.). London: UK: Cambridge University Press.
Heinemann. Townsend, P. (1979). Poverty in the United Kingdom. London:
Ribeiro, A.C.T. (2005) Introdução. In V. Victor, E.N. Stotz, & Allen Lane.
E.B. Algebaile (Eds.) Para compreender a pobreza no Brasil. Rio Townsend, P. (1985). A sociological approach to the measure-
de Janeiro: Escola Nacional de Saúde Pública Sergio Arouca/ ment of poverty: a rejoinder to professor Amartya Sen.
Fiocruz/Ministério da Saúde—Editora Contraponto. Oxford Economic Papers 37, 659–668.
Rowntree, B.S. (1901). Poverty: a Study of Town Life. London: Townsend, P. (1992). The International Analysis of Poverty.
Macmillan. London: Simon & Schuster.
Rowntree, B.S. (1918). The Humans Needs of Labour. London: Tripathi, R.C. (2010). Poverty Alleviation: Is It Only Tilting at
Longmans. the Windmills? Psychology and Developing Societies. The Poor
Saint-Arnaud, S., & Bernard, P. (2003). Convergence or resilience? in Developing Societies, 22(2) (Special Issue), 201–220.
A hierarchical cluster analysis of the welfare regimes in advanced Tudge, J. (2008). The Everyday Lives of Young Children. Culture,
countries. Current Sociology, 51(5), 499–527. Retrieved Class and Child Rearing in Diverse Societies. Cambridge, UK/
October 6, 2009, from http://www.sagepublications.com. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Santos, M. (2009). Por uma outra globalização: do pensamento único Ungar, M. (2004). A constructionist discourse on resilience:
à consciência universal (18ª. ed.) Rio de Janeiro: Record. multiple contexts, multiple realities among at-risk children
Sartorello, S. C. (2009). Colaboración, inter-aprendizaje y co- and youth. Youth & Society, 35(3), 341–365. Retrieved April
teorización en un proceso intercultural de construcción cur- 27, 2009, from http://www.yas.sagepub.com.
ricular en Chiapas (México). Annals of the XIIème Congrès United States Department of Health, Education and Welfare
de l’ARIC (Association Internationale pour la Recherche (1974). The Measure of Poverty: a Report to Congress as
Interculturelle). Mandated by the Education Amendments of 1974. Washington,
Schoon, I., Parsons, S., & Sacker, A. (2004). Socioeconomic DC: Government Printer.
adversity, educational resilience, and subsequent levels Utsey, S. O, Bolden, M. A., Lanier, Y., & Williams III, O.
of adult adaptation. Journal of Adolescent Research, 19(4), (2007). Examining the role of culture-specific coping as a
383–404. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.jar. predictor of resilient outcomes in African Americans from
sagepub.com. high-risk urban communities. Journal of Black Psychology,
Seginer, R. (2008). Future orientation in times of threat and 33(1), 75–93. Retrieved April 27, 2009, from http://www.
challenge: How resilient adolescents construct their future. jbp.sagepub.com.
International Journal of Behavioral Development, 32(4), 272– Valla, V. V., Stotz, E. N., & Algebaile, E. B. (Orgs.) (2005).
282. Retrieved April 27, 2009, from http://www.sagepubli- Para compreender a pobreza no Brasil. Rio de Janeiro: Escola
cations.com. Nacional de Saúde Pública Sergio Arouca/Fiocruz/Ministério
Sen, A. (1983). Poor relatively speaking. Oxford Economic Papers, da Saúde—Editora Contraponto.
35, 153–169. Valsiner, J. & Rosa, A. (2007) The Cambridge Handbook of
Sen, A. (1985). A reply. Oxford Economic Papers, 37, 669–676. Sociocultural Psychology. New York: Cambridge University
Sen, A. (1999). Desenvolvimento como liberdade. São Paulo: Press.
Companhia das Letras. Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and Human Development. London:
Shih, M. (2004). Positive stigma: Examining resilience and Sage Publications.
empowerment in overcoming stigma. The ANNALS of the Valsiner, J. (2001). Comparative Study of Human Cultural
American Academy of Political and Social Science, 591(1), Development. Madrid: Fundación Infancia y Aprendizaje.
175–183. Retrieved October 6, 2009, from http://www.ann. Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in Minds and Societies. New Delhi,
sagepub.com. India: Sage.
Silva, M. A. da. (2005). Encontro com o pensamento de Milton Valsiner, J. (2009). Cultural Psychology Today: Innovations and
Santos: o lugar fundamentando o período popular da história. Oversights. Culture & Psychology, 15, 5–39.
Salvador, Brasil: Empresa Gráfica da Bahia. Valsiner, J. & van der Veer, R. (1996). Vygotsky. Uma síntese.
Souza, J.C. (2009). The Wealth Poverty and the Poverty of [Copyright 1991, Understanding Vygotsky—a Quest for
Wealth. In A.C.S. Bastos & E. P. Rabinovich (Eds.). Living in Synthesis.]. São Paulo: Unimarco Editora/Edições Loyola.
Poverty. Developmental Poetics of Cultural Realities. Charlotte, Vasconcelos, V. O. (2009). O fundamental na tradição: histórias
NC: Information Age Publishing. de vida de populações ribeirinhas da Amazônia. Annals of the
Spink, P. (2003). Poverty and Place. In S.C. Carr & T. S. Sloan XIIème Congrès de l’ARIC (Association Internationale pour la
(Eds.) Poverty and Psychology. From Global Perspective to Recherche Interculturelle).
Local Practice. (pp. 103–120) New York: Kluwer Academic/ Véras, M.P.B. (2003). A Desqualificação Social. In S. Paugam:
Plenum Publishers. Desqualificação Social. Ensaio sobre a Nova Pobreza. (Preface
Starobinski, J. (1994). Largesse. Paris: Editions de la Réunion des to the Brazilian edition, pp. 13–29). São Paulo: EDUC/
Musées Nationaux. Cortez Editora.

556 bei ng poor


Villarreal, J., Díaz, R. A. (2009). “Plan de vida” versus desarrollo: Wertsch, J. V. (2002). Voices of collective remembering. New York:
disputas en torno a la sustentabilidad. Annals of the XIIème Cambridge University Press.
Congrès de l’ARIC (Association Internationale pour la Recherche Wertsch, J.V. (2009) Collective memory. In P. Boyer. &
Interculturelle). J. Wertsch (Eds.) Memory in mind and culture (pp. 117–137).
Watkins, M. & Shulman, H. (2008). Toward Psychologies of Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Liberation. London/New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

ba stos a n d ra bin ovich 557


CHAPTER

Cultural Psychology of Racial


25 Ideology in Historical Perspective: An
Analytic Approach to Understanding
Racialized Societies and Their
Psychological Effects on Lives
Cynthia E. Winston and Michael R. Winston

Abstract
Race as a label and idea has developed over time as part of science, philosophy, psychology, and other
areas of scholarship. Its social uses have been notable—and often notorious—leading to treating race as
a “thing.” Such ideological use of race as a “thing” has been discredited in our century. Nevertheless, the
residual reality is that socially destructive ideological concepts of race have been embedded in racialized
societies to varying degrees through social, economic, and political institutions and their practices. This
reality has psychological consequences for human personality development, identity formation, and lives.
Varied cultural historical conditions have buttressed systematic and institutionalized agents of power.
This has motivated, manufactured, and sustained new forms of racial thinking and ideology. The goal of
this chapter is to develop an analytic framework for cultural psychology that penetrates the historical
surfaces of racialized societies so that the interactions among race, culture, and racist ideologies may be
understood as a dynamic, rather than static, multidimensional system that varies over time and place.
Although modern scholarship on race across the disciplines is vast and more than a century old, the
Winston Framework provides a new organization and synthesis of cultural psychological concepts that
operate at multiple systems and interindividual levels across time and different racialized systems of
domination. It is proposed that a cultural historical psychology of race analytically requires a synthesis
of race concepts appropriately placed in their historical context, including the dynamics of individuals,
institutions, and societies.
Keywords: race, racialized societies, racial ideology, identity, master narratives, cultural historical, cultural
psychology, comparative

Contemporary biological and social sciences especially in Europe and in the Americas. In those
recognize that human beings are a single spe- societies in which dominant and subordinate
cies and that observable physical differentiations groups were classified racially, economic and social
among them are not markers for traits, abilities, institutions were structured to maintain the exist-
or intelligence. Moreover, genomic research has ing disparities in power, wealth, and social devel-
found that all humans are approximately 99.9% opment. Those aspects of the social structure in
the same genetically (Collins, Green, Guttmacher, turn shaped patterns of behavior, forming cultures
& Guyer, 2003). Since the end of World War II, of dominance and subordination. Within such
an international scientific consensus has dismissed societies, behavior coded and regulated by race
the idea of superior and inferior races as a myth. and or color became an integral component of the
For more than 200 years, however, such ideas were psychological development of dominant as well as
a dominant although often challenged ideology, subordinate groups.

558
In this chapter, we propose an analytic frame- facilitated colonial exploitation by the British system
work for penetrating the historical surfaces of of “divide and rule.” In other instances, such as Brazil,
racialized societies for cultural psychology. It would color and class replaced the legal status of slavery as
enable researchers to view interactions between race, markers for social and economic subordination. In
culture, and racist ideologies as a dynamic, rather such a system, the cultural dimensions of class became
than static, system that varies over time and place. A a major component of the system of racial subordina-
cultural psychology of race conceptualizes culture as tion, enabling supporters of the system to argue that
central to the psychological meaning of race. Race’s it was not based on race or former slave status, but
meaning is both constituted by and constitutive class.
of culture. A cultural psychology of race fuses sys- Another example of a comparability measure
tems and identity development dynamics through is the degree of urbanization and proximity to
mechanisms that are political, social, economic, seaports (e.g., coastal versus interior [Africa,
and personal. It includes history as a tool to specify Latin America, Caribbean]). For example, in pre-
empirically the psychological mechanisms of domi- industrial societies, seaports were “zones of racial
nation, subordination, and equality. juxtaposition” because they attracted popula-
There are several factors that distinguish our ana- tions involved in various aspects of trade. These
lytic framework from others within the field of psy- included slaves, textiles, spices, tobacco, and other
chology and other social sciences. Our framework commodities in trade between tropical areas,
allows for comparative analysis of racial systems across Europe, and the Americas. As cities grew in the
cultures and social types in different countries—such coastal areas of the Americas, England, Europe,
as the United States, South Africa, the Dominican Africa, and Asia, work and commercial opportu-
Republic, and Brazil. As such, it allows for very spe- nity attracted populations that were highly differ-
cific factors to be compared across systems and cul- entiated racially.
tures. For example, the date of emancipation varies The Winston Framework also allows for empirical
across the British colonies (1834), the United States data to be interpreted within a dynamic and scalable
(1865), and Brazil (1888). In some instances, emanci- framework referring to linked concepts and phenom-
pation precipitated a search for other racial sources of ena that vary in their expression and intensity from
labor, as in the case of the British Empire, where Asian society to society. The Winston Framework identi-
(Chinese and Indian) contract labor was imported to fies such concepts as color coding, technology, and
replace local Black labor. The racial-cultural dynamic master narratives of race as being mutually relevant
was thus made only more complicated but actually (see Fig. 25.1). Therefore, empirical data on the race

Social
Matrix

Economic Institutions
Political
Institutions
SYSTEMS Social Institutions

Disposition
al Traits
The Narrative
Symbolic Identity
Dimension Master Characteristic
Adaptations
Narratives
of Race
Color Coded
Dynamics
Social
Matrix Technology
Innovation & Interindividual
Access Personality

Figure 25.1 The Winston Framework for


Distinctively Salient Mechanisms OF Racialized Societies
the Cultural Psychology of Race in Historical
Perspective (2010)

w in ston , w in ston 559


and or color and status or role of a particular racial ideology—the transcendental, unique essence of the
group in a technical field may be examined as part of German soul (Mosse, 1964, pp. 3–30); and Yamato
a socio-cultural system, rather than isolated demo- minzokuism—the Japanese as the pure “leading
graphic and employment data. It was the pattern in race” (Dower, 1986, pp. 204–207).
racialized societies, for example, for newly emerging The ideological use of race as a “thing” has been
technical fields of scientific importance or social pres- discredited in science and scholarship. The ideologi-
tige to exclude racially targeted groups. Aerospace cal manipulation of race, however, has often adapted
programs, organ transplant programs in their early to new social and political conditions, sometimes
development, and militarily significant research pro- using politically potent proxies for race such as reli-
grams (such as the development of nuclear weapons) gion or immigration status. Despite the steadily nar-
are all examples of this phenomenon. Limiting the rowing appeal of overt racism since World War II, a
access of targeted groups to the relevant education residual, institutionalized reality continues to exert
and training is also, of course, a part of the institu- significant psychological influence on lives. Ideas,
tional means for making some fields more exclusive, attitudes, and values now known to be erroneous
prestigious, and Whiter than others. have an embedded life in the economic and cultural
patterns that continue to shape the interactions of
Race As a Biological and Historical people of different racial identifications in what the
Phenomenon Winston Framework conceptualizes as “racialized”
The Basic Dualism of Race societies. This has psychological consequences for
The term race has been used for centuries to cate- individual personality development (Winston, in
gorize human groups. If it were no more than a con- press a) and for the study and understanding of lives
venience for generalizations about human variations, affected by subsurface social ideologies from earlier
then it would have had no more historical or social periods of history (Drake, 1987).
significance than different classification systems in
botany and zoology. Origins of Racial and Racist Thinking
Analysis of race is often marred by confused rea- The physical differences among humans noted in
soning caused by the tendency in some academic early civilizations were variously explained by cre-
disciplines, and in certain aspects of public policy, to ation myths and legends. Claims to superiority were
discuss race as if it were a concrete “thing.” On one usually rooted in a belief that a given civilization or
level of analysis, “race” is a label with no universal culture was superior to all others (e.g., Greece and
definitions or intrinsic substance. On another level, China), which were characterized as “barbarian,” but
race is implicated in a vast system of social and eco- not because of the physical differences themselves.
nomic control and subordination. An understand- As early as the time of Aristotle (384–322 B.C.),
ing of these two aspects of race necessarily involves physical and temperamental differences were some-
the history of how the use of the term race evolved times explained naturalistically as a result of climate
and how it became more than a neutral label. In and culture (Aristotle, Politics, Book X 1327b).
fact, it became a major social, political, and cultural When Christianity emerged as a syncretistic reli-
force. The key distinction is between what race “is” gion of the Roman Empire, transcending tribal and
objectively and what race “means” in different cul- sectarian traditions, it acknowledged human differ-
tures and periods of history. ences but emphasized St. Paul’s statement that God
Just as there is a basic dualism in the concept of “hath made of one blood all nations in the earth to
race, as a label and a “thing,” there is also a fundamen- dwell” (Acts of the Apostles 17:26). Later, in the early
tal dualism in the history of race. On the one hand, fifth century, St. Augustine argued (in The City of
race as a label, as a means of classifying humans, God) that differences in color or “quality of nature”
has continued to evolve over centuries in both sci- did not mean that human beings did not all derive
ence and scholarship. On the other hand, race has from the same divine source (Gossett, 1965, p. 9).
evolved as a component of various ideologies— The spread of explicitly racist views is linked
some explicitly racist, others more nationalistic historically to the European conquest of large ter-
or cultural but with a strong racial element—for ritories inhabited by non-White populations. It
example, American White Supremacy, (Fredrickson, was observed initially in the Spanish conquest of
1981, pp. 136–179), Russian Slavophilism, Peru and Mexico in the sixteenth century, when
(Riasanovsky, 1963, pp. 401–404), German Volkish Indians were enslaved to provide free labor for

560 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


mining and agriculture. Countering religiously Europeans, Asians, Americans, and Africans). By
based objections to slavery, most significantly those mid-century, some writers in this camp ventured
of Bartolome de Las Casas (1474–1566), defend- a stratifying notion of “the races” in a hierarchy,
ers of the system asserted that Indians were inferior with Europeans at the apex and Africans at the
to Europeans, not because of climate or culture but base (Cohen, 1980). Equally prominent was their
because of unchanging “racial” differences. As other attempt to associate “character traits” with nations
Europeans—notably the English, the French, and as well as races, identifying some as uniformly clever
the Dutch—vied for the opportunity to extract or dull, courageous or servile, militaristic or passive.
wealth from their colonies in the Americas, racist The opposite approach, based on a broad concep-
ideas took firmer root with the expansion of the tion of the formation of human cultures and societ-
African slave trade. As late as the seventeenth cen- ies, posited that there is a single “human nature”
tury, these ideas were still far from systematic and that is expressed variously in different cultures. Its
did not generally have the sanction of the learned. adherents also argued that civilizations or societies
As Thomas Gossett has pointed out, as slavery evolved over time, from simpler forms and struc-
expanded as a system driven by economic gain, tures to more complex, with the range and varia-
“there was a minimum of theory” (Gossett, 1965, tion in human behavior attributable to the type of
p. 29). When slavery began to be attacked more society in which individuals and groups lived. The
frequently as immoral by Quakers, and contrary to first approach tended toward a racial determinism
Christian teaching by some Protestants, explicitly in human behavior, expressed as unchangeable
racist theory began to be developed in defense of racial superiority or inferiority, whereas the second
the system (Frederickson, 2002). recognized human differences but left open the pos-
Race gradually became more than a device for sibility of “savage” peoples evolving into “civilized”
classifying human beings. Under the pressure of peoples. Two of the most prominent philosophers
controversy, it evolved into something new, in which of the century, Immanuel Kant and David Hume,
its social meaning was more important than any adopted the racialist approach. The opposite view
biological variations. Variations in physical appear- was prominently advanced by J. G. von Herder,
ance (phenotype) were interpreted to be markers for Adam Smith, and Adam Ferguson (Broadie, 2003,
unchangeable abilities, temperaments, and traits. pp. 88–90).
It was claimed that just as human groups differed A vehicle for systematizing and disseminating
in color, physical stature, and facial features, they knowledge was the creation of encyclopedias, the
differed fundamentally, as groups, in their “capacity most influential of which were the Encyclopédie
for civilization,” their intelligence, general educa- ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts, et
bility, capability in mathematics and the sciences, des métiers, edited by Denis Diderot and Jean
character traits such as industriousness, adaptability, d’Alembert (published in parts, 1751–1772) and
as well as motor skills, sexual behavior, tolerance for the Encyclopaedia Britannica (published in three
particular diseases, pain thresholds, and aesthetic volumes in 1771). What these works had to say
sensibilities (Hall, 1905, pp. 95–107). about race reflects a distinct stage in its evolution as
an organizing idea or concept in society and among
The Enlightenment Sources of Modern the learned. The French Encyclopedie said that not
Racist and Anti-Racist Ideology only did color and facial traits distinguish Negroes
During the eighteenth century, intensified con- from other men, but they “appear to constitute a
tact among Europeans with Asians, Indians in the new species of mankind.” The first American edi-
Americas, and Africans aroused increasing interest tion of the British version (1798) claimed that
in the subject of human variations. Over the course Negroes were “a variety of the human species” and
of the century, two contrasting intellectual responses identified them as Homo pelli nigra—black-skinned
to the new information about non-European pop- man (Eze, 1997, p. 91). After describing the color
ulations emerged. One approach continued the and physiognomy that was supposedly distinctive of
effort in botany and zoology to develop a scheme Negroes, it ascribed to them a remarkable catalog of
for classifying populations. This strain of thought implicitly hereditary traits:
was a type of proto-racial theory, classifying humans
according to color or geography (usually white, “Vices the most notorious seem to be the portion
red, yellow, brown, and black; or, alternatively, as of this unhappy race: idleness, treachery, revenge,

w in ston , w in ston 561


cruelty, impudence, stealing, lying, profanity, Such a uniform and constant difference could not
debauchery, nastiness and intemperance, are said to happen, in so many countries and ages if nature had
have extinguished the principles of natural law, and not made an original distinction between the breeds
to have silenced the reproofs of conscience. They are of men.”
strangers to every sentiment of compassion, and are (Eze, 1997, p. 33)
an awful example of the corruption of man when left
to himself ” The claims of Kant and Hume were countered by
(Eze, 1997, pp. 91, 93–94) James Beattie (1735–1803) in his Essay on the Nature
and Immutability of Truth, in Opposition to Sophistry
Although it might be thought that such notions
and Skepticism (1770) on logical grounds: the only
were more likely to flourish in societies heavily
way to prove an inherent inferiority of Africans and
involved in the African slave trade, some of the
American Indians would be to introduce arts and sci-
most influential debates about race biologically and
ences among them to see whether they were “unsus-
socially occurred in Germany, which had no colo-
ceptible to cultivation.” “The inhabitants of Great
nial assets at the time and was only marginally in
Britain and France,” he wrote, “were as savage 2,000
contact with non-White populations.
years ago as those of Africa and America are to this
The most important German racial theorist was
day.” Adam Smith, another member of the Scottish
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), whose influence
Enlightenment, argued in The Wealth of Nations
as a philosopher was of European—not simply
(1776) that geography, not individual abilities, was
German—significance. Kant introduced a course
the underlying cause of the social and economic dif-
on anthropology at the University of Königsberg
ferentiation that led to personal achievement. All of
in 1772, the first in any German university. Over
the inland areas of Africa and Asia, he wrote, were
the course of his career, Kant offered at least 72
in a “barbarous and uncivilized state” because they
courses in anthropology (compared with 28 in eth-
lacked waterways that supported internal “commerce
ics and 54 in logic). The ideas developed in these
and communication,” whereas all the civilizations of
courses became embedded in European racial
the past (his examples were Egypt, India, China)
theory for more than a century. In one early essay,
were built around great river systems. He added that
“On National Characters” (1764), Kant wrote, for
Europe followed this pattern, with inland and other
example, that “the Arab [is] the noblest man in the
isolated areas having less developed populations than
Orient,” whereas “the Persians are the French of
the sea coasts or the river systems (Smith, 1776,
Asia.” By contrast, he wrote:
Chapter III, Section 8).
“the Negroes of Africa have by nature no feeling The large shifts in racial populations occasioned
that rises above the trifling. Mr. [David] Hume [in by slavery, contract labor systems, and the mobil-
his essay, Of National Characters, (1754)] challenges ity associated with intensified transnational and
anyone to cite a single example in which a Negro intercontinental trade after the sixteenth century
has shown talents . . . not a single one was ever found resulted in vast increases in mixed race populations.
who presented anything great in art or science or In the ancient and medieval worlds, such popula-
any other praiseworthy quality . . . .So fundamental tions were clustered mainly on the Mediterranean
is the difference between these two races of man rim (the Maghreb, Egypt, Western Anatolia, Sicily,
[blacks and whites] it appears to be as great in mental Southern Italy, and Spain). In the early modern
capacities as in color.” period, mixed race populations grew rapidly in the
(Eze, 1997, p. 55) West Indies, Latin America, and North America. In
some social systems of the Spanish Empire, the term
In the same essay, Hume had also written that he
mestizo included mixtures of Indians, Whites, and
was “apt to suspect” that there were four or five “spe-
Africans, whereas in others there was an attempt to
cies of men” who were naturally inferior to Whites.
place racially mixed groups in a hierarchy based on
“There never was a civilized nation of any other the observable “amount of their White blood.” The
complexion than [W]hite, nor even any individual Spanish colonies generally developed systems of psy-
eminent either in action or speculation . . . .On the chological advantage and prestige attached to peo-
other hand, the most rude and barbarous of the ple of “pure Spanish blood” as the number of mixed
[W]hites, such as the ancient Germans, the present race people grew, in most cases to a clear majority of
Tartars, have still something eminent about them . . . . the population. In such a triadic system (e.g., Cuba,

562 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


Puerto Rico, the Dominican Republic, Mexico), as a matter of biology wholly African. Because the
Whites were at the top of the hierarchy, mixed race racial system in the United States was regulated by
people in the middle, and dark-skinned or Black- law and the usual violence of slave societies, the
skinned people at the bottom, although some of racial definition of these populations became a mat-
them were indeed of mixed race. Thus, color became ter of law rather than custom, cultural preference,
a major part of the psychosocial matrix affecting or individual decision. Popularly known as “the
the distribution of education, occupations, wealth, one drop rule” because the legal and social defini-
and social prestige. Language also played a cultural tion as a Negro could be made if a person had any
role, with a premium placed on “correct speech” as African ancestry, no matter how remote (see Frazier,
opposed to the Creolized or pidgin speech associ- 1949). As a result, in the racial system in the United
ated with the lower classes and darker segments of States, many individuals who would have been clas-
the population. sified as Whites in the West Indies, Brazil, or other
The French colonies of the West Indies and parts of Latin American were classified as mulattos
North America followed some of the same mixed (one-half White), quadroons (one-fourth White),
race and color-graded patterns of the Spanish but or octoroons (one-eighth White). In the nineteenth
developed different attitudes about the acknowl- century, they were generally called “people of color”
edged mulatto children of wealthy Whites. Those but remained legally an undifferentiated part of the
children, at times, inherited property, were provided “American Negro race”. From 1890 until 1920, there
educations in France, and returned to the colonies was a mulatto category in the U.S. Census. After
as a privileged segment of the population (e.g., Saint that category was eliminated in the 1930 Census,
Domingue [later Haiti], Martinique, Guadeloupe, some of those formerly identified as mulatto simply
and Louisiana before 1803). As in the Spanish case, became White, as they were not counted as Negroes.
color was an important feature of the cultural matrix Although color played a personal role in cultural
in the racial systems of the French colonies. preference among American Negroes, the fixed legal
The British developed racial policies and prac- status of the race had the effect of creating a social
tices in their colonies that varied. In India, racial and political solidarity that had no analog in Latin
theory was used as a dividing technique, classify- America or the West Indies. By contrast, in the South
ing some groups as “martial races” (e.g., Sikhs and African system of Apartheid, laws succeeded in cre-
Gurkhas, although Sikhs were not racially different ating a system in which Whites, Coloreds, Indians
from Hindus or Muslims) and others as “backward.” (and other Asians), and Africans developed as sepa-
Racial or “color bars” were imposed in establishing rate populations in the racial system. The opposi-
residential areas and clubs. In the settler colonies of tion to Apartheid eventually included members of
Africa, such as Kenya and Rhodesia, racial segrega- all of these groups, but there was never the degree of
tion and racially limited educational opportuni- solidarity between Black Africans and Coloreds as
ties followed the South African pattern, whereas in there was between those of various racial mixtures
Egypt, Aden, and other places, racial discrimination among American Negroes. This is mainly attribut-
was more muted. Theories of racial inferiority were, able to the fact that the Coloreds had privileges as a
however, an essential part of the British, French, matter of law that were denied to Africans, whereas
Dutch, Belgian, Spanish, and Portuguese systems of in the United States there was no legal or political
rule and the maintenance of White dominance. difference based on racial mixture.
In the United States, the juxtaposition of White,
Black, and Indian populations resulted in a large The Consolidation of Race Theory in
mixed race population from the early seventeenth the Era of Scientific Racism
century to the end of the mid nineteenth century. From Racial Ideas to Racial Ideology
This occurred, of course, before the U.S. Congress The transformation of eighteenth-century specu-
passed an Indian removal bill, signed into law by lations about race into an ideology that was regarded
President Andrew Jackson in 1829, that mandated as solidly based knowledge and sound science was
the forced removal of the Indians (principally in a process that stretched from the mid-nineteenth
the Southeast) to territory west of the Mississippi century to the early twentieth century. In this
River. Most demographers concluded by the early period, several developments accelerated interest
twentieth century that only a tiny fraction of the in racial theory. One was the dramatic expansion
Negro population in the United States remained, of European imperialism in Africa and Asia. By

w in ston , w in ston 563


the end of the century, only two African countries Chinese are glad to vegetate, as well as to the strict
remained independent: Ethiopia and Liberia; all despotism which is the only way of governing the
the others were direct colonies of Britain, France, Negro.”
Germany, Belgium, Portugal, Italy, and Spain or (Gobineau, as in Biddiss, 1970, pp. 136–137)
were controlled less directly by European pow-
In Gobineau’s theory, Northern Europeans
ers (e.g., Egypt and the Sudan). Holland, Britain,
were regarded as superior, intellectually and physi-
and France directly controlled colonies in Asia
cally (the “Nordics” of Scandinavia and the “Celtic
(e.g., Indonesia, India, French Indochina) and had
Germans” of Central Europe), whereas Slavs in
spheres of influence in China. Another develop-
Central Europe and Eastern Europe were “demon-
ment of profound importance was the abolition
strably” inferior, as shown by their often subordinate
of slavery in the United States after the Civil War
status in peasant societies. Those Europeans on the
(1861–1865) and the creation of a system of gov-
Mediterranean rim, southern Frenchmen, Spaniards
ernment-enforced White Supremacy in the South
who were not “of pure blood,” Greeks, and Italians
and various types and degrees of segregation in the
were inferior. In the evolving racial theory of the
North, all of which were sanctioned by the U.S.
nineteenth century, there were as many as 30 differ-
Congress, the Presidents of the United States, and
ent “races” or “racial types” of Europeans, including
the U.S. Supreme Court.
a religious minority—Jews (Snyder, 1939).
Both European Imperialism and White Supremacy
Gobineau’s ideas were further popularized by
in the United States (and South Africa) were but-
Richard Wagner’s version of racism allied with
tressed by racial ideologies that posited the inher-
German nationalism (his “Teutonism”), and by
ent inferiority of Africans, Asians, and American
Wagner’s son-in-law, Houston Stewart Chamberlain
Negroes. Although it is an exaggeration to call Count
(1855–1927). Chamberlain’s two-volume, Founda-
Arthur de Gobineau (1816–1882) the “Father of
tions of the Nineteenth Century (1899), fused racism
Racism,” as he often is, he was the European thinker
with anti-Semitism, an amalgam exploited politi-
in the nineteenth century who wrote the most influ-
cally by Adolf Hitler in Germany (and enacted into
ential racist book of the era, the Essai sur l’inégalité
law in 1934) and by the anti-immigration move-
des races humaines (1853–1855). He borrowed the
ment in the United States (enacted into law in the
racial classification schemes of the eighteenth cen-
immigration quota system in 1924 and “the national
tury and followed the usual Hume–Kant hierarchy,
origins plan” of 1929).
placing Blacks at the lowest level and Whites at the
An important stage in the consolidation of
highest. New in Gobineau’s ideology was his appli-
race theory in the nineteenth century was the
cation of these ideas to a racial interpretation of all
skewed importation of Darwin’s biological ideas
history, explaining the rise and fall of civilizations on
(e.g., natural selection) into social theories in the
the grounds of supposedly racial migrations, traits,
newly developing social sciences. Herbert Spencer
and degrees of “purity.” Gobineau also popular-
(1820–1903), for example, argued that just as
ized the idea that among Whites there were various
there was a struggle for existence between animals
“races,” with the “Nordics” being the most superior,
in nature, there was a struggle between classes in
whereas the Mediterranean and Slav groups were
society, between nations and between races. As
inferior. Of “the [W]hite races” as a whole, he wrote
in nature, he maintained, these struggles had the
that they “are gifted with reflective energy, or rather
result that the strongest triumphed, and this was
with an energetic intelligence.” He added the fol-
the key to overall human progress—the “survival
lowing details:
of the fittest.”
“They have a feeling for utility, but in a sense far Social Darwinism became not only an approach
wider and higher, more courageous and ideal, than to society but was embedded in the social sciences
the yellow races; a perseverance that takes account of as the most “realistic” way to think of the disparities
obstacles and ultimately finds a means of overcoming in education and wealth in industrial societies and
them; a greater physical power, an extraordinary between Europe and other parts of the world. From
instinct for order, not merely as a guarantee of peace this perspective, social inequality was a natural phe-
and tranquility, but as an indispensable means of nomenon, based on biological facts that could not
self-preservation. At the same time, they have a be changed by education or other variables. It was,
remarkable, and even extreme, love of liberty, and therefore, a “sentimental delusion” to believe that
are openly hostile to the formalism under which the the “lower orders” of humanity could be improved

564 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


by better education, health services, or other social The most active and influential of Agassiz’s suc-
policy interventions. cessors in this area of research was Robert Bennett
In the same era, medical and physical anthro- Bean, a professor of anatomy at the University
pological research attempted to establish an ana- of Virginia Medical School. The “Negro brain,”
tomical and physiological foundation for theories he wrote in 1908, developed normally as far as
of racial inferiority, especially of Blacks. The most perception, memory, and motor responses were
consequential and prestigious American scientist to concerned, but logical critical thinking or the
adopt rigidly racist views was Professor Louis Agassiz comprehension of abstract ideas were beyond its
(1807–1873) of Harvard University. He was the grasp because of “arrested physiological develop-
founding scientist of Harvard’s Lawrence Scientific ment” (Bean, 1906, pp. 353–432). The signifi-
School (1848), the first school in the United States cance of this development in science was, first,
to train scientific researchers. His popularity as a the assumption that it was objective and correct,
public lecturer and writer on scientific subjects pro- and therefore not a matter of controversy, but fact.
pelled him to unprecedented influence as a shaper of Second, its application to public policy had far-
scientific knowledge and public opinion. Supported reaching consequences, especially in education
not only by Harvard but by substantial research and employment.
funds from the Massachusetts legislature (for his
Museum of Comparative Zoology), Agassiz’s work From “Race Science” to Racialized Public
was influenced by Samuel George Morton, the lead- Policy and Institutions
ing American anthropologist, who believed that on The United States had the most sophisticated
the basis of his examination of human skulls, he had system of racial domination in the world. As a hard
shown that Whites had the largest skulls, whereas system, the United States maintained a structure
Blacks and American Indians had the small- of racialized power through legislation and judicial
est skulls, proving to his satisfaction that Whites opinion. This distinguished it from European sys-
had more intellectual ability because of their pre- tems in which claims of racial difference were made,
sumptively larger brain size. Morton’s results were for example, about Italians, Germans, Poles, or Jews.
achieved in part by arbitrary racial classification, When members of these groups immigrated to the
deciding for example, that the ancient Egyptians United States, those European racial distinctions
were Caucasians. In his first year as Lowell Lecturer, virtually vanished, as they were identified by U.S.
Agassiz lectured in Charleston, South Carolina and law as White. As a result, the social use of race was
maintained that as a matter of science, Negroes were redefined because of the use of the legal system to
a distinct species. Using Morton’s work, Agassiz said maintain a racial hierarchy after the abolition of slav-
that the “brain of the [adult] Negro is that of the ery (Mangum, 1940). The question became, Who is
imperfect brain of a 7-month’s infant in the womb Black and who is White? At the same time, in Europe,
of a White” (Stanton, 1960, p. 100). race theory was still based on the idea that there were
Agassiz developed his ideas into a theory, poly- multiple “races” within Europe (Goldstein, 2006).
genism, that maintained that all of the races were In England and Ireland, there was the develop-
separate creations and in an immutable hierarchy ment of the idea of an “Irish Race.” Maintaining the
of abilities. Polygenism was a theory especially European distinctions would not only have been too
congenial to defenders of slavery. Agassiz’s theory complicated legally but would have worked against
meant that the abolitionist and humanitarian the assimilation of immigrants so they could become
views on slavery were false, because Negroes were “Americans,” pure and simple.
not fully human and could not be included in the Because of its size and distribution, the Negro
natural rights doctrine announced in the American population of the United States was always of public
Declaration of Independence or ever be entitled to policy importance, during the slave era and after-
citizenship or constitutional protections. Agassiz’s ward. Constituting about one-fifth of the national
ideas about race retained their scientific authority in population in 1790, it remained a much larger pro-
the United States far beyond the slavery controversy portion of the population in the southern states. By
and the Civil War because they became the founda- 1880, Negroes were 13% of the national population
tion of the American School of Anthropology and but in some southern states comprised as much as
part of standard medical research and teaching in 50% or more of the total population (Bureau of the
the United States (Menand, 2001, pp. 97–116). Census, 1918, pp. 46–49).

w in ston , w in ston 565


The Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth including the military, the United States developed
Amendments to the U.S. Constitution, and the separate social and cultural environments that not
Congressional policy of Reconstruction, had been only limited the development of the Black popula-
intended to be the basis for the Freedmen to be tion but affected them psychologically. Race became
citizens and participants in a democratic society. a determinative aspect of the economic and social
Although no government measures were taken realities that shaped most Black lives, irrespective
to secure an economic base for the ex-slaves, the of the frequently enunciated egalitarian aspects of
Freedmen’s Bureau (a part of the War Department) American ideals and democratic constitutional the-
was the government agency created to provide ory. The United States became a racialized society
the recently emancipated slaves with education, at the same time that the country rose to become
health care, and other forms of assistance. With the one of the most powerful countries in the world, a
defeat of Reconstruction (1876), southern Whites social fact that did not begin to change until after
attempted to erase the progress that had been World War II.
achieved by Blacks in the decade since the end of
the war through Black Codes, Ku Klux Klan terror- The Scientific Error of Eighteenth- and
ism, and other violence. These methods were grad- Nineteenth-Century Race Theory
ually superseded by changes in state constitutions The fundamental error of eighteenth- and
and federal policy, principally by the U.S. Supreme nineteenth-century race theory, as science, was the
Court, which removed Negroes from political par- assumption that naming a race and then attributing
ticipation in the South. Southern and northern fixed abilities, behavioral traits, and physical charac-
Whites then created a system of legalized racial seg- teristics to it was logically or empirically adequate.
regation and economic exploitation (Logan, 1954, However, the intellectual weakness of this approach
pp. 3–11). as science did not lessen the hold such ideas had on
Between the 1880s and 1920s a new type of social thought, public policy, or popular culture. It
society was structured, one that was “modernizing” was not, strictly speaking, an issue of science but
with respect to industrialization, commercial devel- of power and a need to find a cultural and social
opment, urban growth, expanded transportation, means to unify a majority of the people of the
communications networks, and a rapidly growing United States, even if at a terrible cost to the minor-
system of public education, including higher edu- ity that was not White. The multiple traumas of the
cation. At the same time, disparities based on race Civil War placed in high relief the divisions among
in education, income, and access to social resources the White population—by region, class, immigrant
were institutionalized through segregation laws and status, religious domination—so that hatred and
other forms of public policy that made it possible exclusion of Blacks (to the extent possible) became
to limit the development of Negroes (segregated a kind of social adhesive for people who increasingly
schools, libraries, hospitals, racial classification thought of themselves as “White” rather than as eth-
of jobs as “White jobs” and “Black jobs”) while nic immigrants, class opponents, or former enemies
advancing Whites at public expense. on the Union or Confederate side of the war.
The fusion of racial theory and institutional
development made it possible to perpetuate inequal- A Racialized Society
ities based on race from generation to generation. The racial ideas of the eighteenth century did
An illustration of this trend is the expenditure of not, of course, independently create the racialized
funds for education of Whites and Negroes in those societies of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
states maintaining racial segregation of schools (the In their time, they were primarily speculative con-
most crucial institution for social mobility in the jectures. They gained importance later, when race-
American social system). Charles H. Thompson, based systems of dominance operationalized them
head of the Bureau of Educational Research at by the application of governmental power and pri-
Howard University, pointed out that in 1900 the vate institutions.
disparity in per capita educational expenditures for A “racialized society” develops over time. It is not
the two racial groups was 60% in favor of Whites, simply a society in which there is a sudden or transi-
but by 1930 had increased to 253% (Thompson, tory contact between different racial groups through
1935, pp. 419–434) As such disparities were con- conquest or immigration. In a racialized society,
solidated in all social and economic institutions, different groups that have been socially identified

566 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


as “races” are limited to social and economic roles the prejudices of the private realm are extended by
according to their racial identification. custom to the employment and civic realms, so that
Racialized societies are historically a phenom- persons of the less socially privileged racial groups
enon of the early modern world (beginning in the would not be absolutely barred from certain occu-
sixteenth century) when western Europeans devel- pations or public offices but would attain them very
oped the technical and military means to conquer rarely. In “harder” systems designated as “racist,” in
societies in Asia, Africa, and Latin America and the “racialized society” continuum, racial groups are
extract mineral wealth and other natural resources defined formally by law. Limitations in the educa-
from some of those areas using native labor. During tional, economic, and political freedoms of those
a second stage, millions of laborers, either through proscribed racial groups then become enforceable
slavery or contract labor systems, were moved to by law, including regulation of such private rela-
frontier societies, such as those in North and South tions as marriage (Higginbotham, 1978; Mangum,
America, the Caribbean, East Africa, and South 1940).
Africa. There, Europeans imposed a caste system Historically, the societies of Latin America and
in which race was made a functional boundary for the Caribbean were racialized but not racist in the
economic and social roles (Du Bois, 1945; Frazier, sense defined here. In the United States and South
1957). Africa, the societies were racist as defined here
The concept of a racialized society does not apply because the status of racial groups was fixed and
to all multiracial societies. In the ancient African enforced by the power of the State through the for-
and Mediterranean world (e.g., in Egypt, the Greek mal mechanisms of legislation, judicial proceedings,
or the Roman Empires), Africans, West Asians, and and executive force. In the case of those regimes
Europeans were significant demographic compo- developed by such colonizing powers as the Dutch,
nents of those societies, making them multiracial. the Portuguese, the English, and the French, racial
But there was no systematic or strict determina- policies and the distribution of educational and
tion of social and economic roles by what would economic opportunities in the colonies were reg-
be later called race (Snowden, 1970, 1983). In the ulated by colonial administration, whereas in the
ancient world, slavery was a result of conquest, as it metropolitan area such laws did not apply. Thus
was in the Medieval Muslim and Christian realms, France, for example, maintained a racially strati-
but slavery was not the product of a racialized eco- fied regime in its African and Caribbean colonies
nomic system, as it would become in the era of the but provided legal equality in France itself for all
Indian Ocean Slave Trade, the Atlantic Slave Trade, racial groups. In such a system, it was possible for
and European colonization. Status as a slave or free Negroes (as defined in the United States; in France
person was not tied in the earlier historical periods they were mulatto), such as the Chevalier de St.
to racial or ethnic identity. The mere existence of Georges (1745–1799) and Alexandre Dumas Père
several races in the same society does not, therefore, (1802–1870), to become famous and distinguished
make it conceptually a “racialized society.” “Frenchmen” in music and literature (Banat, 2006;
Is there a distinction to be drawn between a McCloy, 1961).
“racialized” society and a “racist” society? The The analytical significance of these distinctions
Winston Framework uses “racialized” to designate derives from the fact that societies that may be classi-
societies in which race is used as a socially differenti- fied along the “racialized–racist continuum” adapted
ating marker. Societies may use such markers in vary- different kinds of institutions and cultural systems
ing degrees. In “softer” systems, race and color may to perpetuate racially stratified social and eco-
have more importance in the private than the public nomic differentiations. Those differences, between
realm and historically were linked in some societ- customary regimes on the one hand and legalistic
ies to class hierarchies. In such systems neither race ones on the other, had varying kinds of impact on
nor color may have formal legal significance. The those who were within the racial nets maintained
absence of a legalized, state-imposed racial regime by political and social elites. Institutional and cul-
does not, of course, mean that there is no racial prej- tural variations, in turn, had different types and
udice or virtually hereditary racial stratification in a degrees of psychological and social consequences for
society, as was claimed by scholarly apologists for individuals in those societies. By conceptualizing a
the Brazilian racial class system (Fernandes, 1969; “racialized–racist continuum” as a framework, it is
Freyre, 1946; Ramos, 1939). In “softer” systems, possible to compare very different racial systems

w in ston , w in ston 567


across time and geography, one of the most difficult cultural racism (see Jones, 2003) can be combined
analytical problems in studies of the intersections within master narratives of race that reflect their
between race, culture, and society. influence on both social structures and individual
cognitive structures. In many ways, they come to
Master Narratives of Race provide a distorted justification for the racial dis-
Within racialized societies, master narratives of parities that emerge not from individual sources but
race emerged as a cultural psychological mechanism from collective constructions of institutions, sys-
to “story” dominance, subordination, and equality tems, and customs.
ideology. Master narratives of race are dominant The form that master narratives of race takes
cultural stories and discourses that reflect racial can be varied and complicated. Master narratives
ideas and ideologies within a racialized society. of race can present themselves as ideologies, plot
These stories include plotlines, characters, settings, constructions, storylines, and discourses. Plotlines
and other narrative features that create a framework for master narratives of race for African-Americans,
that individuals draw upon in thinking about the for example, have been up from slavery/sharecrop-
meaning of race within lives. Master narratives of pers’ child, affirmative action unqualified, and
race function as societal, symbolic meaning systems Black exceptionality of excellence. These master
of culture. In a sense, they have a dramatic qual- narratives of race plotlines evolve over time, retain-
ity like all narratives that are constructed over time ing the central essence of their meaning, grounded
(see Bruner, 1990). Moreover, often based on the in racial ideas and ideology that are prevailing at
“point-making” motivation (see Bamberg, 2004) of a particular point in time. Characters in master
the master narrative speaker or writer, only selected narratives of race are contextualized in the for-
narrative features of the story are emphasized. mat of exemplary actions by exemplary characters
Although master narratives of race may at times that are appropriated to act out and make relevant
appear to be elusive, they are omnipresent, produc- the claim. For example, Sterling A. Brown (1933,
ing images, symbols, storylines, and caricatures that 1937, 1966) identified seven stereotypical char-
reflect dominant racial ideas and ideologies within a acters that were prominent in fiction of the late
racialized society. This can include storylines about 1800s and early 1900s which included the con-
the meaning of racial group membership, as well as tented slave, the wretched Negro, the comic Negro,
explanations for racial group disparities. There is a the brute Negro, the tragic mulatto, the local color
rapidly growing body of research on implicit racial Negro, and the exotic primitive. More contempo-
bias in social psychology that provides an example rary characters in master narratives of race include
of how these master narratives of race can work to the hip hop icon, the superhuman athlete, and the
shape unconscious bias at the interindividual level highly successful exception whose achievement,
(see Goff, Eberhardt, Williams, & Jackson, 2008). therefore, is not to be considered important vis-à-
In this research, the symbolic meaning of race is vis the low-achieving stereotype by its very excep-
often induced using cues associated with a particu- tionality (Rice, 2010).
lar group membership or stereotyped characteristic Master narratives of race act with storylines
of racial group members. that have both static and dynamic features, mak-
Master narratives of race serve the function of ing the master narrative of race a cultural historical
configuring power dynamics through distortion construction that is recombinant at the level of the
of reality, gross overgeneralization, and extension individual and society. Master narratives are tem-
of the ideas with origins or roots in scientific rac- porary, like other narratives, of course. Bamberg
ism, racial thinking, and ideologies associated with (2004) asserts:
racist and antiracist movements. In other words,
within racialized societies, master narratives of race “[L]ooking at narrative at a different angle . . .
to varying degrees provide one of the most impor- there seems to be something special in their
tant mechanisms through which racialized habits of implementation, even at the level of mundane,
thinking are sustained and reinforced. The key vital- conventional everyday interactions, because
ity and sustainability of these master narratives of narratives order characters in space and time and
race is a pervasiveness of thickly embedded racism therefore, as a format, narrative lends itself not only
in American society and culture. Discourses, poli- to connecting past events to present states (as well
cies, and practices of individual, institutional, and as imagined, desired states and events) but also to

568 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


revealing character transformations in the unfolding are left intact, whereas others are reshaped and
sequence from past to future.” reconfigured. To extend this idea further to a coun-
(Bamberg, 2004, p. 354). ter-narrative of race, the master narrative of race is
reflected in the construction of counter-narratives of
The master narrative of race about the alleged
race, making it not a “simple counter-story”; rather,
intellectual superiority of White Americans and
these counter-narratives juggle several story lines
alleged intellectual inferiority of Black Americans
simultaneously (see Bamberg, 2004). The degree of
is an illustration of one of the main features of
psychological interactivity required to negotiate the
master narratives of race. Within American society
meaning of race between the level of society and the
and culture, there is a master narrative or common
individual is complex. As such, precise determina-
“story” whose main characters are individuals who
tion of the shifting meanings of race is analytically
are Negro, Black, or African-American as well as
challenging given the current state of research in the
typically White characters. One storyline develops
field, the quality of the conceptual tools developed
the plot that intelligence is an exceptional or genetic
thus far, and the inadequacy of the research instru-
impossibility for individuals who are non-White
ments and methods.
and particularly for those who are Black. A con-
temporary example of the plotline of exceptionality
occurred when early in the 2008 U.S. Presidential Human Personality Development
Campaign, Senator Joe Biden referred to then With Racialized Societies and the
Senator Barack Obama as “articulate” (see http:// Centrality of Identity
www.cnn.com/2007/POLITICS/01/31/biden. The complexity of master narratives of race
obama). inhere in their fusion of interindividual dynamics
From a cultural-historical perspective, typi- and systems level racial ideology that are within
cally when the word “articulate” is used to describe economic, social, and political institutions. Within
someone who is Black, it may be interpreted as a the field of psychology, individuality is most often
coded way to indicate that he is an exception to the conceptualized in terms of the concept of personal-
socially scripted inarticulate stereotype for Blacks in ity and focuses on those psychological forces within
this race and intelligence master narrative. In other the whole person.
words, although the speaker’s motivation may be to The development of personality within all soci-
pay a compliment, the symbolic meaning of the dis- eties, racialized and non-racialized, involves the
course is interpreted in the resonant context of the dynamic interplay between phenomena on three
master narrative of race and intelligence. levels: (1) dispositional traits or the broad indi-
In response to this master narrative about the vidual differences in behavior, thoughts and feelings
alleged intellectual inferiority of individuals who that have longitudinal consistency across situations
are Black and African-American, powerful counter- and developmental time; (2) characteristic adapta-
master narratives have also emerged in American tions or goals, values, motives, coping strategies,
society and culture. These counter-narratives have and stage specific tasks that are contextualized in
been developed primarily among individuals who time, place, and social role; (3) narrative identity or
are the targets of the master narrative of intellec- internalized and evolving narratives of the self that
tual inferiority. This counter-narrative script is that reflect the meaning of life experiences in time and
Black people are intelligent and at least equally as culture. In fact, McAdams and Pals (2006) have
capable as their non-African-American counter- argued that any science of the person should include
parts. These counter-master narratives have evolved conceptualization and corresponding methodologi-
over time as part of a response to the ideologically cal approaches of personality as “an individual’s
driven, institutional, and culturally crafted explana- unique variation on the general evolutionary design
tions for structural disparities across racial groups, for human nature, expressed as developing patterns
particularly related to public policy debates about of dispositional traits, characteristic adaptations,
compensatory education and affirmative action and integrative life stories complexly and differen-
(e.g., Jensen, 1969, Hernnstein & Murray, 1994). tially situated in culture” (p. 212).
Within the counter-master narrative of race, Culture impacts these different levels of per-
there are features that act like other types of counter- sonality in different ways. For example, different
narratives. For example, there are some elements of cultures may emphasize distinct characteristic adap-
dominant narratives that Bamberg (2004) suggests tations, with individualistic cultures emphasizing

w in ston , w in ston 569


independent self-construals, in contrast to collec- most often require individuals to reconcile psycho-
tivist cultures that stress goals and values of inter- logically contradictory characterizations of who they
dependence (Markus & Kitayama, 1991). The are in terms of a personal sense of self as persons, as
most profound influence of culture on personal- well as with respect to their collective attachments
ity is arguably reflected within the psychological within social, religious, and national groups. The
repertoire from which a person draws in making narrative features of these master narratives of race
sense of past, present, and anticipated future expe- are often omnipresent because they are reinforced
riences that comprise that person’s identity con- by the economic, political, and social systems of
struction. In answering the question Who am I?, society.
people have agency in choosing from competing The human development of identity has a pro-
internal and external stories while rejecting many found impact on all other aspects of a person’s
others. McAdams and Pals (2006) have described life-course. To understand comprehensively the
this process and the relation of culture and iden- magnitude of this impact, imagine if human beings
tity as self and culture coming together through did not strive to achieve and restory their identity.
narrative. This process of self-exploration occurs in There would be no posing of questions and striving
the context of a person’s dispositional trait profile for answers to the question of Who am I? at any
and adaptive states. As such, it highlights the cen- developmental stage of life, including adolescence
trality of the identity dimension of personality in and later adulthood. In this sense, all of the psy-
understanding the psychological effects of living in chosocial tasks associated with resolving conflict,
a racialized society. achieving psychological balance, developing trust,
and choosing a life’s occupation would be elimi-
Identity nated from what it means to be human.
Within racialized societies, persons construct the The experiential elements specific to living in a
personal, collective, and cultural dimensions of their racialized society contribute to a person’s identity
identity, in part, within the context of the racial construction in the form of autobiographical mem-
ideologies that present themselves in master narra- ories of race (Winston, in press a; Winston, in press
tives of race. The narrative features of these master b). In her theory of race self complexity, Winston
narratives are reinforced by the institutional and (in press a) argues that the meaning of race is pro-
structural features of society, as well as through the cessed narratively, and as such, there is a complex
political and economic realities that automatically process of the self-system by which autobiograph-
create limited opportunities distributed by race. ical memories of race are recalled and narratively
A person’s identity is a psychological dimen- organized. In the construction of autobiograph-
sion of personality that functions to integrate past, ical memories of race experiences, encoding of
present, and anticipated future life experiences to remembered emotion launches two core processes
answer perplexing and complicated questions: Who of the self-system: narrative processing and autobio-
am I as a person? What does my life mean in the overall graphical reasoning (Mangum & Winston, 2008;
structure of the cultural contexts in which I live? How Winston, 2011). This processing engages narra-
do I bring unity and purpose to my life through how I tive sequencing and emotion. The processing also
think about self and who I am? And how do I fit into is triggered at different times across the life-course,
the adult world? and in various roles and environments. The nar-
Identity is at the same time personal, social rative processing of autobiographical internal and
(Tajfel & Turner, 1979), hierarchical (Markus, external race-related stimuli requires channeling of
1977), storied (e.g., McAdams, 1985), and cultural a stream of thought into prescribed, narrative race
(Erikson, 1968). Such simultaneously constructed meaning sequences. These narrative sequences rely
elements make its development across the lifespan on both cultural and personal templates, as well as
complex and both a product of and producer of the stimulation of affect. Often the stimuli and cul-
culture. Within any type of society, identity drives tural templates are in the form of master narratives
psychological attachments to the values, attitudes, of race. Such dominant narratives in society serve
customs, cognitions, affect, and views of the self, as a mechanism for drawing up a personal mean-
others, and the world. Racialized societies present ing of race. Also, the human nature of individuals
unique contexts in which complicated forms of to categorize phenomena, objects, and people serves
identity develop, because master narratives of race as a culturally universal mechanism that individuals

570 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


use in racialized societies to cultivate the meaning of whose findings had the single most important social
race within their lives. science impact on the U.S. Supreme Court decision
Emotion is an adaptive characteristic of personal- Brown versus Board of Education (1954), which held
ity that is also a core part of the narrative process- that the racial segregation of public education by
ing of race in identity construction (Mangum & law was unconstitutional (Kluger, 1976). Although
Winston, 2008). Emotion enhances memory encod- the validity and reliability of these findings were
ing and therefore serves to launch a person’s narra- later questioned, on interpretive and methodolog-
tive processing and autobiographical reasoning of ical grounds (Baldwin, 1979), this body of research
race experiences, including those that are personal as continues to have a profound impact on the debate
well as those that are at the level of master narratives about the role of Black culture in the development
of race within the larger racialized society. In the pro- of an identity that is not self-hating.
cess of identity construction, these experiential affect During the Black consciousness movement that
cues give rise to one of the psychological functions of began in the 1960s, Cross (1971) introduced his the-
autobiographical memories of race—to aid a person ory of Nigrescence (the process of becoming Black)
in organizing events of past life experiences of race in to explore the stages of racial identity development
a temporal sequence and meaningful internal portrait shifts from an unhealthy sense of self as a Black per-
of people, places, and events (Winston, in press a). son in the United States to a healthy identity. The
In this regard, narrative is an organizing structure of impact of this stage model of identity development
personality, an idea advanced by both Singer (1995) has been great. It has continued in various forms for
and McAdams and Pals (2006). Self-protection, self- more than 40 years, largely pursued by scholars who
enhancement, and psychological balance (see Rice, were students or collaborators of Cross (Parham &
2008) are forms of self-regulation of the internal and Helms, 1981). More recently, Black identity theo-
external stimuli that operate within racialized societ- rists, building on previous research, have shifted
ies. These three motives of the self serve important their focus from an emphasis on trying to under-
psychological functions of constructing autobio- stand the content of a “healthy” identity in a racist
graphical memories of race in the process of identity society to a focus on mental health correlates of the
development. dimensions of racial centrality, racial regard of the
Because identity is selective and constructed public toward individuals who are Black, as well as
rather than fixed and genetically based, like other Blacks’ own regard for their group, racial salience,
features of human personality such as dispositional and racial ideology—mainstream, assimilationist,
traits, individuals within racialized societies have a nationalist, and oppressed minority (see Sellers et.
wide range of ways they can choose to configure al, 1998; Shelton & Sellers, 2003).
their identity. As a narrative of self, identity devel- Another recent development in the study of
opment within “harder” racialized systems may, for identity within the United States has been to shift
example, include elements of counter-racial or anti- terminology from racial identity to ethnic identity
racist ideology that have been influenced by familial for two reasons. One is to be more politically cor-
and other primary socializers. This can be the social- rect in the use of the term race, because the fallacy
izing agenda for families from both dominant and of its biological basis is widely recognized, and the
subordinate groups. For members of groups that are second results from the racial and ethnic diversifi-
subordinate within a racialized society, the intended cation of the participants in psychological studies
result of such socialization is to help foster identity beyond White male college students.
development that is adaptive and functional. For The complexities of identity construction within
members of the dominant group, the function of racialized societies have been formalized in the most
such socialization is to normalize the presumption sophisticated way in theories that focus on the psy-
of privilege. chological impacts of racially determined disadvan-
Within the field of psychology, for example, there tage on people of African descent. Jones (2003), for
has been a long history of debate about whether indi- example, has proposed a theory of Time, Rhythm,
viduals who are Black living in the United States can Improvisation, Orality, and Spirituality (TRIOS)
form a healthy identity, given the pervasive racism to explain the cultural dimensions of African cul-
within society. This debate began with the pioneer- ture that individuals of African descent use to adapt
ing doll study research of Ruth Horowitz (1939), and cope with living in a universal context of rac-
Mamie P. Clark and Kenneth B. Clark (1939), ism. In so doing, his model identifies individual,

w in ston , w in ston 571


institutional, and cultural levels of racism that indi- new narrative theory of personality that posits that
viduals have to negotiate in cultivating a sense of the meaning of race can be processed narratively
self and other. This negotiation can be linked to (Winston, in press a). Within the framework of this
both self-enhancement and self-protective factors. theory, narrative theories of personality are inte-
Similarly, Boykin (1986) has proposed a theory grated with psychological significance of race the-
of identity dilemma in which individuals of African ories to describe and explain the nature, form, and
descent have to negotiate simultaneously three psychological function of autobiographical memo-
realms of psychological experience: the mainstream, ries of race specifically, and race narratives gener-
minority, and Afro-cultural orientation. Harrell ally, across critical life periods within the lives of
(1999) also has provided a theoretical orientation individuals in racialized societies. In other words,
for describing the psychological consequences of this theory provides a theoretical and accompanying
racism on the minds of people of African descent. methodological orientation to study, understand,
He describes three forms in which these conse- and transform an individual’s identity construction
quences take shape: standards of beauty, European process that includes making sense of race within
ideals, and miseducation. There are many other racialized societies across critical life episodes. This
theorists who focus more explicitly on the psy- allows for the incorporation of cultural psychologi-
chological impacts of early forms of domination cal mechanisms through which systems and identity
and oppression (particularly slavery) on the iden- interact, change, or stabilize.
tity development of individuals of African descent In sum, identity construction is fundamentally
(Akbar, 1984; Kambon, 2002; Cress-Welsing, 1991; a cultural process. The amount of identity work
Nobels, 1991). in which a person engages shifts in developmental
Within the field of sociology, there is a class of time, place, and role and in cultural dynamics that
theories called “Whiteness” theories (see Anderson, are made even more psychologically complicated by
2003; Bonnett, 1996; Lewis, 2004; Murano, 2004; living within racialized societies. The demands of
Roediger, 2002) that posit a relationship between ideo- the broader cultural contexts in which the mean-
logical and material components of race that afford ing of self and life experiences are cultivated may
individuals who are White automatic privileged represent maneuvers simultaneously between com-
social status within a societal racial hierarchy. Lewis plicity in and countering established master narra-
(2004) asserts, “whether Whites have self-conscious tives of race. Those narratives give guidance to one’s
racial identities may or may not matter as much actions, but at the same time constrain and delin-
for their life chances as external readings of them as eate a person’s agency—where, for example, laws or
White” (p. 624). Thus, she asserts, the social category entrenched customs prohibit access and movement
Whiteness cannot be divorced from its role as a force to key institutions and opportunities of the society.
of domination and subjugation. Moreover, whiteness Erik Erikson, psychology’s most influential identity
theories suggest that the psychological negotiation theorist, has suggested that identity is “a process
that Whites must do in constructing their identity located at the core of the individual, and yet also in
and corresponding behaviors and feelings is based on the core of his communal culture, a process which
notions of privilege and entitlement. establishes, in fact the identity of those two identi-
Taken together, these theories about the psycho- ties” (Erikson, 1968, p. 22).
logical significance of race within lives suggest that
the context of the racism within racialized societ- The Winston Framework for Inquiry: The
ies and the simultaneous demands of psychological Cultural Psychology of Systems and Human
negotiation create complexities in a person’s quest to Personality Within Racialized Societies
formulate answers to identity questions. Such com- The concepts presented thus far comprise the
plexities make it very challenging for researchers to Winston Framework for Inquiry. Racialized soci-
uncover the meaning of race within lives. In addi- eties have specific generic features whose particu-
tion, these theories and their important ideas have, lar details will vary by culture, historical period,
for the most part, not been integrated theoretically and the structure of political power and economic
or methodologically in the discipline of psychology development. The Winston Framework is a concep-
and related fields. tual framework for inquiry about the cultural his-
To address this gap, the theory of race self com- torical intersection of interlocking societal systems
plexity was developed. Race self complexity is a and interindividual personality adaptations within

572 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


racialized societies (Fig. 25.1). It identifies, defines, Racialized culture is learned. A racialized soci-
and explains a collection of linked core concepts at ety’s institutional arrangements, structured by racial
both the macro- and micro-levels of reality within a stratification, induce the development of types of
racialized society. Regardless of discipline, these con- racially mediated, learned behavior—that is, they
cepts are inherent and fundamental for all inquiry generate cultural mechanisms to perpetuate patterns
about or related to the meaning and impact of race of racial dominance and subordination. An example
on lives within racialized societies. of this is the routine deference that a member of the
Although at one level the Winston Framework subordinate group is expected to show to a mem-
is systems-oriented, there is no intention of sug- ber of the dominant group, whether it is expressed
gesting that what we describe as “racial systems” are in the once entrenched southern custom of Blacks
mechanical, deterministic, or permanent. They are being expected to yield the sidewalk to Whites in
systems in the sense that they have structure, form, small towns and cities during the segregation era or
and stability across varying periods of time. Another the cultural expectation in certain contemporary
characteristic of these systems is that they have iden- academic or corporate environments that the pro-
tifiable uniformities and patterns. Moreover, a sys- fessional judgment of a member of a racial minority
tem itself is not necessarily a racial system per se. should count for less than a White colleague of the
A system that is theoretically “race neutral” may same training, experience, rank, or status.
be used for a racial purpose. This phenomenon is A racialized society requires unwritten cultural
seen, for example, when the law is used to segre- codes because human institutions are not perpetu-
gate schools, hospitals, or other public facilities or ally renegotiated in day-to-day living by individuals
to use the power of eminent domain to eliminate but fit, for the most part, into patterns that are gov-
the neighborhoods or businesses occupied or owned erned more by implicit than explicit assumptions,
by disadvantaged racial groups. Another example beliefs, and habits (Doyle, 1937). These racialized
would be the “special attention” policing applied to cultural prisms of lived experience naturally refract
the non-White “Bidonvilles” of Paris or Marseilles or psychological consequences. With some notable
the immigrant slums of Manchester and Leeds. In exceptions, scholars have focused more on the leg-
other words, all societies have multiple systems that islative, judicial, and public policy formulations of
allow them to function as a whole, including eco- racial dominance and have given scant attention to
nomic, social, and political systems. In a racialized the cultural plasma that allows racialized societies
society, these systems operate differentially accord- to actually work and escape socially paralyzing vio-
ing to race. That is, those in a subordinate position lence and disorder most of the time.
do not benefit from the system in the way that indi- In a racialized society, culture also has the
viduals who are racially privileged have a probability immensely important function of normalizing and
of doing. Many debates have been launched about rationalizing inequality and other aspects of the
the greater significance of class to race, as well as racial system, whether in a modern industrial state
arguments about race being more important than or, historically, in colonial environments as large
class in determining life experiences, as well as as India or as small as the Caribbean islands. In all
socio-economic outcomes (see Wilson, 1980). of these cases, the individual in the target group(s)
At another level, the Winston Framework iden- must learn how to adapt psychologically to these cul-
tifies processes used by the targets of racialized tural imperatives. These adaptations assume a range
societies to establish their own identities, modes of forms, depending on the individual’s personality
of independent action, and human flourishing. and access to a repertoire of coping resources and
These processes of race self complexity include psy- strategies. Within the limits imposed by a racialized
chological manipulation of the plotlines of master society’s institutions and culture, such individuals
narratives of race in the form of self-protection, engage in an evolving process of generating ways to
self-enhancement, and psychological balance. give their own lives frames of meaning and signifi-
In other words, there is a intra-active process by cance that the dominant society’s racial postulates
which meanings and personal actions are guided. and practices deny or attenuate. Formation of such
The individual’s actions and internal processing meaning-making resources is both a psychological
have some degree of autonomy, but that autonomy and cognitive process that varies through an indi-
has boundaries within the context of the intercon- vidual’s life span and differs in its details, but not in
nected systems of racialized societies. its function as a way to attain agency, integrity, and

w in ston , w in ston 573


personal fulfillment in the distorted social arrange- salient feature in multiracial English-speaking colo-
ments and cultural habits that characterize all racial- nies such as Jamaica, Trinidad, and British Guiana,
ized societies. or Spanish-speaking colonies such as Cuba, Puerto
The most challenging element in developing Rico, and the Dominican Republic. Within racial-
the Winston Framework as a robust and appropri- ized societies, these types of color-coded calibrated
ate model for inquiry is to make the connections social dynamics provide a mechanism for the social,
between the social, cultural, political, and economic economic, and political institutions and interindi-
contexts and the individual without being simplis- vidual personality development to interact in ways
tic or without denying agency to the individuals that provide a multidimensional constellation of
affected. This is a classic social science problem— lived experiences.
filling the gap between what sociologists and histo-
rians do and what psychologists and others do who The Symbolic Dimensions of
focus their research on individuals. Racialized Societies
The Winston Framework serves as a heuristic Modernization as a phenomenon always affects
device for researchers, practitioners, and the public the mode of transmitting racial meaning in a racially
to guide inquiry about racialized societies in terms stratified society. In pre-modern systems, force is
of both systems and interindividual variables. It more important than social or cultural systems. In
does so with an emphasis on global, complex, and modern systems (characterized by industrialization,
cultural-historical conceptualization of the concept, urbanization, and the spread of mass media), racial
structure, and psychology of race. symbols have become a primary cultural means
There are several key mechanisms that link sys- for stabilizing a racial system. Thus, the portrayal
tems and interindividual personality development of subordinate racial groups in mass circulation
within racialized societies. These include transporta- newspapers, magazines, radio, television, and films
tion, mass communications, color-calibrated social becomes a cultural mechanism for embedding ste-
dynamics, master narratives of race, hierarchies of reotypes in a society. As those images become a sta-
cultural prestige, access to technology, and academic ble form of representation, all racial groups in the
scholarship. society begin to accept those stereotypes as repre-
sentations of reality for interindividual personality
Distinctively Salient Mechanisms of development and description. For the subordinate
Systems and Interindividuality racial groups, this has an effect on motivation,
Personality Development education, standards of beauty, and achievement,
Color-Coded Calibrated Social thus reinforcing its racial stratification (see Harrell,
Dynamics of Racialized Societies 1999).
There are color-coded calibrated social dynamics
of racialized societies in which race and color shape Technology Innovation and
social experience and become a part of a society’s Access in Racialized Societies
culture. Although laws are used in some systems Technology innovation and access tend to desta-
(e.g., the United States and South Africa) to estab- bilize racial systems. Historically transportation was
lish racial and color boundaries, most systems func- the first important change, as railroads, and later
tion through culture and custom. In some systems, automobiles, enabled subordinate racial populations
such as Brazil’s, there has been more sensitivity to to migrate readily from rural to urban areas, from
color and social class than to race (as defined in the agricultural labor to industrial enterprise and better
United States). There were, for example, more than a educational opportunities. As print media technol-
dozen color classifications that calibrated skin shades ogy became more widespread, independent news-
between blanco (white), pardo (brown), and preto papers and book production by subordinate racial
(black). Such color stratification affected employ- groups became possible, enabling them to mobi-
ment opportunities; access to public spaces such as lize for political and social action and to develop
beaches, schools, and nightclubs; and were cultural a counter-cultural racial consciousness (Winston,
rather than legal boundaries for the marriagability of 1982). As mass media, like television, accelerated
women (Pierson, 1942, pp. 111–156). Similar cul- the spread of images and information, the shift-
tural coding of color and physical appearance was a ing imagery of Blacks and other racial groups

574 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


destabilized racial attitudes and cultural boundar- Counter-Cultural Racial Consciousness:
ies (e.g., televised coverage of the U.S. civil rights The Intellectual Reconfiguration of Race
movement of the 1960s versus earlier and limited and Social Action
print coverage, 1890s to 1950s). There was a group of exceptionally well-trained
Negro scholars who were clustered (although not
Master Narratives of Race exclusively) on the faculties of Atlanta University,
Master narratives of race as dominant cultural Fisk University, and Howard University. They ini-
stories and discourses are a mechanism connecting tially used the definition of race (of their time) and
systems-level racial ideas and ideologies to interindi- developed it as a mobilizing device. Many also rede-
vidual processing of the meaning of race. Most often, fined the concept of race and its consequences on
this kind of processing is required of the individual in lives. The trajectory of this change can be traced
developing motives, goals, and coping mechanisms, from Du Bois’s work in the 1890s, in which “blood”
as well as in constructing an identity. In large part, was still a component of the concept of race, through
these personality dynamics are adaptive responses to Alain Locke’s Race and Inter-racial Relations (1916),
living in a racialized society and can work to create in which it was argued that race is a socially con-
a continuum from psychological depletion to psy- structed, malleable concept, to the consensus views
chological stamina in overall well-being and func- of E. Franklin Frazier and the United Nations state-
tioning. Master narratives of race serve the function ment on race in 1950.
of maintaining power dynamics through distortion In the United States, the foundation for anti-
of reality, gross overgeneralization, and extension racist thought and action was created immediately
of the ideas with origins in scientific racism, racial after the Civil War when the Freedmen’s Bureau,
thinking, and ideologies associated with racist and under the leadership of General Oliver Otis Howard
antiracist movements. In other words, within racial- (1830–1909) established a complete educational
ized societies, master narratives of race to varying system from kindergarten to higher education for
degrees provide one of the most important mecha- the former slaves (Bond, 1934; Holmes, 1934).
nisms through which racialized habits of thinking This was the first such system of education in the
are sustained and reinforced. American South, where educational opportunities
It is important conceptually to delineate the con- among Whites were limited and prohibited by law
gruity between the political institutions of racialized for slaves and for Free Negroes. No similar system
societies and the dynamics of how master narratives was created in any other former slave society. Spread
of race are used. In the United States, for example, over an area larger than Western Europe, these col-
public opinion had an increasingly and at times leges and universities prepared generations of teach-
decisive role in shaping race relations because elec- ers, doctors, lawyers, and other professionals who
tions are a fundamental part of the American politi- became the core of a new middle class in the 1870s
cal/power process. Although the defeat of federal and 1880s. It is significant that the most impor-
Reconstruction policies enabled the White South tant of the counter-cultural, antiracist intellectuals
to disenfranchise the Black population in those and scholars, W.E.B. Du Bois (1868–1963), was a
states, the continued national acquiescence in that graduate of Fisk University in Tennessee. Fisk was
system (supported by the U.S. Congress, the U.S. one of the institutions assisted by the Freedmen’s
Supreme Court, and the presidents) depended on Bureau and the American Missionary Association,
national public opinion, not only public opinion a key educational agency founded and operated by
in the southern states. Therefore, the hostile por- northern White missionaries.
trayal of Blacks in developing a national market for In his influential paper delivered to the American
mass circulation of newspapers and magazines was a Negro Academy, the Conservation of Races (1897),
significant component of the racial system and the Du Bois argued that American Negroes were the
master narratives of race that stabilized between the “advance guard of the Negro Race,” whose mission
1880s and 1950s (Logan, 1954; Winston, 1982). it was to counter White racist thought, achieve racial
This is the reason that the most important intellec- equality within the American system, and ultimately
tual and psychological response to scientific racism, liberate non-White colonies from European and
White supremacy, and imperialism developed in the American domination. Du Bois (Ph.D., Harvard,
United States. 1895), the fifth American Negro to earn a Ph.D. at an

w in ston , w in ston 575


American University (the first was Edward Bouchet produced nearly half of the Black physicians in the
in Physics from Yale, 1876), virtually created the United States (the bulk of the other half was pro-
field of objective science-based Negro Studies in the duced by Meharry Medical College in Nashville,
Atlanta University Studies (1896–1913). Tennessee) and more than 90% of the country’s
DuBois’s evolving racial theory converted the Black lawyers, engineers, and architects. In the
biological elements of Euro-American race theory twentieth century, its faculty in the natural sciences,
into a historical-social construct that posited a social sciences, and the humanities included the
global Negro race. In his view, Africans, all North highest percentage of nationally recognized Black
Americans, and Latin Americans of any African scholars and scientists of any institution of higher
descent (no matter how minute), as well as the education in the country. The law and social sci-
mulattoes of the Caribbean and Latin America, ence faculty (and their graduates) from the 1930s
constituted one race as a result of the shared histori- through the 1960s provided most of the intellectual
cal experiences of slavery, emancipation, and eco- leadership of the Civil Rights Movement. Equally
nomic exploitation. important was the impact of the published scholar-
A founder of sociology in the United States, ship of its leading faculty, which was instrumental
Du Bois’s Philadelphia Negro (1899) demonstrated in changing the global consensus on race, racial seg-
that social conditions, rather than innate traits, regation, and White Supremacy (Winston, 1971).
accounted for much of the observed behavior in Howard University is an example of the institution-
urban Blacks. His work became the inspiration for alization of a counter-racist micro-environment.
a generation of Black scholars in history and soci- Functionally, such an environment normalizes and
ology (notably Charles S. Johnson, E. Franklin legitimizes intellectual opposition to the prevailing
Frazier, and Horace Mann Bond). Du Bois had social and cultural order. It also creates expectations
a clear concept of the intellectual mobilization of of intellectual performance and achievement that are
American Negroes to fight racial segregation, eco- the opposite of the cultural stereotypes and expecta-
nomic exploitation, and political domination by tions that reinforced the racial system imposed by
Whites. Carter G. Woodson (1875–1950), another Whites. An institution functioning in this way is
early Harvard Ph.D. in History (1907), founded the one of the components for effective mobilization
Association for the Study of Negro Life and History of a targeted racial group in a sophisticated system
in 1915 and the Journal of Negro History in 1916, of racial dominance of the type developed in the
both cornerstones of the Negro History Movement, United States.
perhaps the most effective fusion of scholarship and
popular participation in the counter-cultural move- The Establishment of Black, Asian
ment against racial ideas and policies. Through his American, and Latino Psychology as
books and other publications as well as his support Counter-Counter-Cultural Racial
for a younger generation of Negro historians (e.g., Consciousness Movements
Charles H. Wesley, Rayford W. Logan, Luther P. Within the field of psychology, a group of well-
Jackson, John Hope Franklin), Woodson decisively trained Black scholars cultivated a paradigm and
answered Hume’s question about what Negroes had associated publication outlets to counter the rac-
achieved over the centuries. ist ideology that permeated much of the empiri-
By the 1940s, Negroes in the United States had cal science of mainstream psychology. In so doing,
developed a national network of Civil Rights orga- they established what has been recognized over
nizations; more than 100 accredited institutions of time as the field of Black Psychology, the Journal
higher education; hundreds of newspapers; profes- of Black Psychology, and the Association of Black
sional organizations of teachers, doctors, and law- Psychologists.
yers; and a growing body of scholarship in the social The development of a new field of Black
sciences and humanities that was unparalleled in Psychology was stimulated by a desire of a group of
other racialized societies. Black psychologists “to move away from the pathol-
The largest and best supported of the Negro insti- ogy-oriented notions about the behavior of black
tutions of higher education was Howard University people and toward creating, interpreting, and rein-
in Washington, DC, founded in 1867 with a mul- terpreting the psychological literature on Blacks”
tiracial administration, faculty, and student body. (Jones, 1972, p. xi). In 1972, Black Psychology was
From Reconstruction to the end of the 1960s, it edited by Reginald Jones and was the very first

576 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


volume to bring together in a single volume writ- work through the graduate and professional train-
ings of black psychologists. Prior to this publica- ing of others:
tion, the feasibility of developing a journal of Black
“In particular, we hope this book will serve as
Psychology was discussed among this same group of
an impetus to students and behavioral scientists
Black psychologists at the Annual Meeting of the
to embrace research as one means of alleviating
Association of Black Psychologists in 1970 (Jones,
oppressive life conditions of Black people, and
1972). This book included both philosophical and
we visualize it as being especially encouraging to
empirical chapters that were designed to highlight
Black graduate students interested in pursuing
re-interpretations and clarifications of the psycho-
systematically the difficult questions of ethnic
logical literature on Black people related to the
pertinence so often confronted in professional
following topics: racism, psychological assessment,
training. Moreover, we expect to provide thesis
personality, motivation, counseling, education, and
advisors with a frame of reference for counseling
the training of Black psychologists for work in the
students who adopt research proposals with themes
Black community.
that emanate from their professional interests and
In June 1974, a group of Black psychologists
concerns about life conditions of Black people.”
held the first Conference on Empirical Research in
(Boykin, Franklin, & Yates, 1979, p. xiv)
Black Psychology at the University of Michigan in
Ann Arbor. This conference was stimulated by the Within the field of psychology, a small group of
Association of Black Psychologists’ charge to Black well-trained Asian-American and Latino scholars
psychologists to focus their professional contribu- organized through regional and later national con-
tion toward service to the Black community. The ferences in ways similar to Black psychologists to
primary purpose of this small conference, which counter the racist ideology that permeated much of
currently continues in another form, was to cul- the empirical science of mainstream psychology. In
tivate in-depth exchange among Black psycholo- a recent article on the History of Asian American
gists whose primary interest was empirical research Psychology, Leong and Okazaki (2009) have iden-
(Boykin, Franklin, & Yates, 1979). The University tified the pioneering Asian-American psychologists
of Michigan conference (and the second in 1975 at and described the events that led to the founding
Teachers College, Columbia University) resulted in of the Asian American Psychological Association.
the publication of a collection of revised and edited Similarly, Padilla and Olmedo (2009) have recently
papers. Publication of Research Directions of Black published a chapter on the History of Latino
Psychologists (by the Russell Sage Foundation) was a Psychology in the Handbook of Latino Psychology
significant advancement toward establishing a field of that describes the founding of the Association of
Black Psychology. It is also significant that this book Psychologists por la Raza in 1969 and the founding
was edited by three early career psychologists—A. of the National Hispanic Association in 1980.
Wade Boykin, Anderson Franklin, and J. Frank There were several significant historical events
Yates. Their careers had the potential to demon- that created the momentum necessary for the
strate the verifiable validity and research fruitfulness establishment of a national movement for Latino/a
of the new modes of conceptualizing the field and Psychology. After 1969, when Edward Casavantes,
its major research problems. The volume included an educational psychologist who worked for the U.S.
sections on methodology, identity and adjustment, Civil Rights Commission, founded the Association
cognitive abilities, motivational issues, and prob- of Psychologists Por La Raza, an annual meeting of
lems for future research. These chapters were writ- this association was held in conjunction with the
ten by a collection of Black psychologists who later annual American Psychological Association meet-
became some of the field’s most influential theorists ing. The first was held in Miami in 1970 and led to
and researchers, including the following scholars: organization of a symposium for the following year
Oscar Barbarin, A. Wade Boykin; William Collins; that was to be the first on Chicano Psychology at
William Cross, A.J. Franklin, James Jackson, James APA (Padilla & Olmedo, 2009). In 1979, a National
M. Jones, William Lawson, Diane Pollard, and J. Conference of Hispanic Psychologists was held at
Franklin Yates. The goals of the book as described the University of California Residential Conference
by the editors were held together by an interest in Center at Lake Arrowhead. This conference was
empirical research in psychology but also included funded by a grant from the Division of Manpower
a concern for the growth and sustainability of this and Training and the Center for Minority Group

w in ston , w in ston 577


Mental Health at the National Institutes of Mental Despite the widespread impact of this national
Health. The goal of the conference was twofold: organization of Asian American Psychologists that
(1) to share information on needed training, ser- was stimulated largely by these two conferences,
vices, and research from a Latino perspective; and it was not until 2010, that The Journal of Asian
(2) to determine if there was universal agreement American Psychology was established and published
to establish a national Latino association. This con- by the American Psychological Association.
ference was significant in the history of Latino/a
Psychology because it was the first time that a large Future Directions
number of Latinos/as representing different geo- The human mind has the unique capacity of
graphical regions, national origins, and disciplinary agency and adaptation. Racialized societies are com-
interests converged in a single location to develop an plicated contexts in which the mind is called on
alliance for the empowerment of Latino/a psycholo- to make these shifts of adaptation. The Winston
gists and their communities (Padilla & Olmedo, Framework as a cultural psychology framework for
2009). More recently, the name of the National analysis of systems level and interindividual level vari-
Hispanic Association was changed to the National ables within racialized societies creates new opportu-
Latino/a Psychological Association. nities for theoretical and methodological innovations
Like the Black Psychology and Latino/a Psycho- within future research. Although clearly not an easy
logy movements, there were a few key historical undertaking, scholars of the future will have unprec-
events important to the momentum of Asian edented opportunities. They will have a new ease in
American Psychology. In 1972, a group of psy- gaining access to digital information across disci-
chologists who lived in the San Francisco Bay area plines that provides insight into the economic, social,
(including Derald Due, Stanley Sue, Roger Lum, political, historical, and psychological dimensions
Marion Tin-Loy, and Tina Tong Lee) founded the of human life. This, coupled with the relative ease
Asian American Psychological Association. The of travel, compared to the past, creates new ways
first national conference on Asian American men- to begin to formulate theories within the Winston
tal health was held in San Francisco, California, Framework. Technological advances in digital data
and funded by the National Institutes of Mental collection tools, all used within appropriate cultural
Health. The conference was attended by more than boundaries, provide new opportunities to collect
600 individuals from a wide diversity of Asian eth- first-person accounts (see Winston in press b) with
nic groups and types of organizations, including more ease in crossing geographic location, time, and
grassroots organizations, academia, and private resources to collect, process, and analyze the fusion of
practice. Leong and Okazaki (2009) have described systems and interindividual personality data.
how this diversity of backgrounds, views, and A derivative effect of the expansion of opportu-
agendas led to some tensions and debates about the nities for theory development and methodological
most pressing issues for a national Asian American innovation are new emphases in research related to
psychological association to address. In 1976, Asian a cultural psychological analysis of race in histori-
American psychologists organized a second confer- cal perspective. For example, future research should
ence in Long Beach California with the following examine the relationship between personality traits
objectives: and identity construction within racialized socie-
“(a) to gain a sense of mental health service needs ties. It is likely that racialized constraints within a
of Asian Americans from individuals with active society, driven by law or custom, for example, can
engagement with them; (b) to identify and recognize cause tension and conflict if a person has personality
salient issues for various Asian American groups; traits that are more expressive or demanding than
(c) to abstract from participants’ backgrounds and the system accommodates, making it more difficult
experiences both instances and preparation that to construct a balanced and adaptive identity.
would facilitate work with Asian Americans and
instances of inadequate or counterproductive The Significance of Comparative Analysis
training for such work; and (d) to organize of Racial Systems
information gathered into a series of It is now understood that race is a socially con-
recommendations for improving the training structed category whose significance varies histori-
of Asian American psychologists.” cally, socially, and psychologically by era, types of
(Leong & Okazaki, 2009; p. 356) social and economic structures, cultures, and the

578 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


dynamics of individual and group adaptations to Appiah, K. A. (1992). In my father’s house: Africa in the philosophy
imposed racial boundaries. As scholarship about of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.
Baldwin, J. (1979). Theory and research concerning the notion
slavery, racial segregation, and personality devel- of Black self-hatred: A review and reinterpretation. Journal of
opment has matured, the importance of compara- Black Psychology, 5(2), 51–77.
tive studies has emerged, principally as a means Bamberg, M. (2004). Narrative discourse and identities. In
of grasping the essential social and psychological J. C. Meister, T. Kindt, W. Schernus, & M. Stein (Eds.),
mechanisms that perpetuate or destabilize racial Narratology beyond literary criticism. Berlin & New York:
Walter de Gruyter.
regimes, and to separate fundamental structure Banat, G. (2006). The Chevalier de Saint-Georges, virtuoso of the
from merely idiomatic or cultural features of sys- sword and the bow. Hillsdale, New York: Pendragon Press.
tems of racial dominance (Holt, 2000). This real- Bean, R. B. (1906). Some peculiarities of the negro brain.
ization underscores the importance of developing American Journal of Anatomy, 5, 353–432.
a provisional framework for the analysis of racial Biddiss, M. D. (Ed.) (1971). Gobineau: Selected political writings
[Essay on the inequality of the human races, 1853]. New York:
systems, regardless of geographic area, historical Harper & Row.
period, or the methods used to enforce dominance Blakely, A. (1986). Russia and the Negro: Blacks in Russian history
(e.g., a “hard” approach via government power or a and thought. Washington: Howard University Press.
“soft” one utilizing culture and private prejudices). Blakely, A. (1993). Blacks in the Dutch world: The evolution of
This chapter has posited the elements of a com- racial imagery in a modern society. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
parative framework for the analysis of racial systems Bond, H. M. (1934). The education of the Negro in the American
but has deliberately avoided a purely schematic or social order. New York: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
theoretical approach, anchoring the framework in Bonnett, A. (1996). White studies: The problems and projects
a historical, cultural, and psychological continuum. of a new research agenda. Theory, culture and society, 13(2),
Thus, the core racist ideas have been identified, the 145–155.
Bose, S. (2006). A hundred horizons: The Indian Ocean in the age
process of their becoming embedded in institutions of global empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
and culture described, and some of the social pro- Boykin, A. W. (1986). The triple quandary and the schooling
cesses and intellectual movements mentioned that of Afro-American children. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The school
destabilized the late nineteenth- and twentieth-cen- achievement of minority children (pp. 51–92). Mahwah:
tury racialized society system. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Boykin, A. W., Franklin, A. J., & Yates, J. F. (1979). Research
The Winston Framework emphasizes the issues directions of Black psychologists. New York: Russell Sage
of power, wealth, social development, and psycho- Foundation.
logical adaptations because all racialized societies— Brendon, P. (2008). The decline and fall of the British Empire,
regardless of culture—operated to reserve power, 1781–1997. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
wealth, education, prestige, and social development Broadie, A. (2003). The Cambridge companion to the Scottish
Enlightenment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
to a dominant racial group, while systematically dis- Brown, S. A. (1933). Negro character as seen by White authors.
advantaging a subordinate racial group (or groups). Journal of Negro Education, 2, 179–203.
It is the nexus between material advantages and Brown, S. A. (1937). The Negro in American fiction. Washington,
racial identification that entrenched racial ideas in D. C.: The Associates in Negro Folk Education
societies. Although the racist ideas themselves have Brown, S. A. (1966). A century of Negro portraiture in American
literature. The Massachusetts Review, VII, 73–96.
been discredited, and the legal framework for racial Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
segregation and other state-enforced discrimination University Press.
has been destroyed, all societies with a racialized Bureau of the Census (1918). Negro population 1790–1915.
past or with later and weaker derivative variations Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office.
have cultures and social habits that continue to have Clark, K. B., & Clark, M. P. (1939). The development of con-
sciousness of self and the emergence of racial identification
negative impacts on lives. The Winston Framework in Negro pre-school children. Journal of Social Psychology, 10,
enables scholars and scientists to identify more 591–599.
readily the evolving adaptations of racially identi- Cohen, W. B. (1980). The French encounter with Africans: White
fied individuals to less racially restrictive (not “post- response to Blacks, 1530–1880. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
racial”) societies. University Press.
Collins, F. S., Green, E. D., Guttmacher, A. E., & Guyer, M. S.
(2003). A vision for the future of genomics research. Nature,
References 222, 835–847.
Akbar, N. (1984). Chains and images of psychological slavery. Cress-Welsing, F. (1991) The Isis Papers; The keys to the colors .
Tallahassee, FL: New Mind Productions. Chicago, IL: Third World Press.
Anderson, N. B (2003). Emotional longevity: What really deter- Cross, W. E. (1971). The Negro-to-Black conversion experience.
mines how long you live? New York, NY US: Penguin Press. Black World, 20, 13–27.

w in ston , w in ston 579


Crummell, A. (1898). The attitude of the American mind toward Harrell, C. J. P. (1999). Manichean psychology: Racism and the
the Negro intellect [American Negro Academy Occasional Paper minds of people of African descent. Washington, D.C.: Howard
Number 3]. Washington: The American Negro Academy. University Press.
Dickson, D. (2001). The Supreme Court in conference (1940–1985): Hernnstein, R. J. & Murray, C. (1994). The bell curve: Intelligence
The private discussions behind nearly 300 Supreme Court deci- and class structure in American life. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
sions. New York: Oxford University Press. Herskovits, M. J. (1928). The American Negro: A study in racial
Dower, J. W. (1986). War without mercy: Race and power in the crossing. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Pacific War. New York: Pantheon Books. Higginbotham, A. L., Jr. (1978) In the matter of color: Race and
Doyle, B. (1937). The etiquette of race relations in the south. the American legal process. New York: Oxford University
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Press.
Drake, S. C. (1987). Black folk here and there: An essay in Holmes, D. O. W. (1934). The evolution of the Negro college.
history and anthropology (2 Volumes). Center for African New York: Columbia University Press.
American Studies, University of California, Los Angeles. Holt, T. C. (2000). The problem of race in the 21st century.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1897). The Conservation of Races [American Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Negro Academy Occasional Paper Number Two]. Washington, Horowitz, R. (1939). Racial aspects of self-identification in nurs-
D.C.: The American Negro Academy. ery school children. Journal of Experimental Education, 7,
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1899). The Philadelphia Negro: A social study. 133–140.
Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania. Jensen, A. R. (1969). How much can we boost I.Q. and scholas-
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1945). Color and democracy, colonies, and tic achievement? Harvard Educational Review, 33, 1–23.
peace. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company. Jones, J. M. (2003). TRIOS: A psychological theory of the
Erikson, E. H. (1968). Identity, youth, and crisis. New York: African legacy in American culture. Journal of Social Issues,
Norton. 59(1), 217–241.
Eze, E. C. (Ed.). (1997). Race and the Enlightenment: A reader. Jones, R. (1972). Black Psychology. New York: Harper & Row.
Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers. Jordan, W. D. (1968). White over Black: American attitudes toward
Ferguson, A. (1966). Essay on the history of civil society, 1767. the Negro, 1550–1812. Chapel Hill, NC: The University of
Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press. North Carolina Press.
Fernandes, F. (1969). The Negro in Brazilian society. New York: Kambon, J. (2002). Cultural misorientation among Africans in
Columbia University Press. America. Chicago, IL: Burnham.
Frazier, E. F. (1949). The Negro in the United States. New York: Kluger, R. (1976). Simple justice: The history of Brown v. Board of
Macmillan Company. Education and Black America’s struggle for equality. New York:
Frazier, E. F. (1957). Race and culture contacts in the modern Alfred A. Knopf.
world. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Leong, F. L., & Okazaki, S. (2009). History of Asian American
Frederickson, G. M. (1971). The Black image in the White mind: psychology. Cultural Diversity and Ethnic Minority Psychology,
The debate on Afro-American character and destiny, 1817–1914. 15(4), 352–362.
New York: Harper & Row. Lewis, A. E. (2004). What group? Studying whites and white-
Frederickson, G. M. (1981). White supremacy: A comparative ness in the era of color blindness. Sociological Theory, 22,
study in American and South African history. New York: 623–646.
Oxford University Press. Locke, A. L. (1916,1992). Race contacts and interracial relations:
Frederickson, G. M. (2002). Racism: A short history. Princeton, Lectures on the theory and practice of race.[Delivered in 1916],
NJ: Princeton University Press. edited by Jeffrey C. Stewart (1992) Washington, D.C.:
Freyre, G. (1956). The masters and the slaves: A study in the devel- Howard University Press
opment of Brazilian civilization. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Logan, R. W. (1954). The Negro in American life and thought, The
Gerzina, G. (1995). Black London: Life before emancipation. New nadir, 1877–1901. New York: The Dial Press.
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Macmillan, M. (2001). Paris, 1919: Six months that changed the
Goff, P. A., Eberhardt, J. L., Williams, M. J., & Jackson, M. C. world. New York: Random House.
(2008). Not yet human: Implicit knowledge, historical dehu- Markus, H. (1977). Self-schemata and processing information
manization, and contemporary consequences. Journal of about the self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Personality and Social Psychology, 94(2), 292–306. 35(2), 63–78.
Goldstein, E.L. (2006). The price of whiteness: Jews, race, and Markus, H., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self:
American identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation.
Press. Psychological Review, 98(2), 224–253.
Gossett, T. F. (1965). Race: The history of an idea in America. Mangum, C. S. (1940). The legal status of the Negro. Chapel Hill,
New York: Schocken Books. NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Gould, S. J. (1981). The mismeasure of man. New York: W. W. Mangum, A.M. & Winston, C.E. (2008, August). Race self
Norton & Company. complexity and emotion: How does it feel to be African?
Graubard, S. R. (Ed.). (1965). The Negro American. Daedalus: Paper presented at the meeting of the Association of Black
Journal of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Psychologists, Oakland, CA.
743–1163 95. McAdams, D. P. (1985). Power, intimacy, and the life story:
Graubard, S. R. (Ed.). (1967). Color and race. Daedalus: Journal Personological inquiries into identity. New York: Guilford
of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 279–626 96. Press.
Hall, G. S. (1905). A few results of recent scientific study of the McAdams, D. P., & Pals, J. L. (2006). A new big five: Fundamental
Negro in America. Proceedings of the Massachusetts Historical principles for an integrative science of personality. American
Society, Second Series, 19,95–107. Psychologist, 61(3), 204–217.

580 c ultural psycho log y of r aci al i de o logy in h istorica l perspective


McCloy, S. T. (1961). The Negro in France. Lexington, KY: The Singer, J. A. (1995). Seeing one’s self: Locating narrative mem-
University of Kentucky Press. ory in a framework of personality. Journal of Personality, 63,
Menand, L. (2001). The metaphysical club. New York: Farrar, 429–457.
Straus and Giroux. Smith, A. (1976 ). An inquiry into the nature and cause of the
Miller, K. (1897). A review of Hoffman’s race traits and tendencies wealth of nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
of the American Negro [American Negro Academy Occasional Snowden, F. M. (1970). Blacks in Antiquity: Ethiopians in
Paper Number One]. Washington, D.C.: The American the Greco-Roman experience. Cambridge MA: Harvard
Negro Academy. University Press,
Mosse, G. L. (1964). The crisis of German ideology: Intellectual Snowden, F. M. (1983). Before color prejudice: The ancient view of
origins of the Third Reich. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. Blacks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Murano, J. (2004). Roots of “Whiteness”. Labour/Le Travail from Snyder, L. L. (1939). Race: A history of modern ethnic theories.
http://www.historycooperative.org/journals/llt/54/munro. New York: Longmans, Green.
html Stanton, W. (1960). The leopard’s spots: Scientific attitudes toward
Murray, P. (Compiler) (1950). States’ laws on race and color. race in America, 1815–1859. Chicago, IL: University of
Cincinnati: Woman’s Division of Christian Service, Chicago Press.
Methodist Church. Stoddard, L. (1920). The rising tide of color against White world
Newby, I. A. (1965). Jim Crow’s defense: Anti-Negro thought in supremacy. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
America, 1900–1930. Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State Tajfel, H., & Turner, J.C. (1979). An integrative theory of inter-
University Press. group conflict. In W. Austin & S. Worchel (Eds.), The social
Nobels, W. (1991). African Psychology: Toward its reclamation, psychology of intergroup relations (2nd ed., pp. 7–24). Chicago,
reascension and revitalization. Oakland, CA: Black Family IL: Nelson Hall.
Institute Publications. Thompson, C. H. (1935). Court action the only reasonable
Padilla, A. M., & Olmedo, E. (2009). Synopsis of key persons, alternative to reducing immediate abuses of the Negro sepa-
events, and associations in the history of Latino psychology. rate school. Journal of Negro Education, 4, 419–434.
Cultural Diversity and Ethnic Minority Psychology, 15(4), Todorov, T. (1993). On human diversity: Nationalism, racism,
363–373. and exoticism in French thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Parham, T. A., & Helms, J. E. (1981). The influence of Black University Press.
students’ racial identity attitudes on preferences for counsel- UNESCO (1961). Race and science: The race question in modern
or’s race. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 28, 250–257. science. New York: Columbia University Press.
Pierson, D. O. (1942). Negroes in Brazil: A study of race contact in Wilson, W. J. (1980). The declining significance of race: Blacks
Bahia. Chicago, IL: The and changing American institutions. Chicago, IL: University
University of Chicago. of Chicago Press.
Pittard, E. (1924). Les races et L’Histoire. Paris: La Renaissance Winston, C. E. (2011, August). Race Self Complexity and human
du Livre. personality: Can the meaning of race be processed narratively?
Ramos, A. (1939). The Negro in Brazil. Washington, D.C.: The Paper presented at the meeting of the American Psychological
Associated Publishers Association, Washington, D.C.
Riasanovsky, N. V. (1963). A history of Russia. New York: Oxford Winston, C. E. (In Press a). Human Personality: Race Self
University Press. Complexity and Symbolic Meaning of Persons Living Race in
Rice, D. W. (2010, August). Race Self Complexity and identity American Society and Culture. In A. U. Branco & J. Valsiner
balance: Black boys, black men and identity orchestration in the (Eds.) Cultural psychology of human values. Charlotte, NC:
age of Obama. Paper presented at the American Psychological Information Age Publications.
Association, 118th Annual Conference, San Diego, CA. Winston, C. E. (In Press b). Biography and Lifestory. In S.
Rice, D. W. (2008) Balance: Advancing considerations of self and Lapan, M. Quartaroli & F. Riemer (Eds.) Qualitative research:
identity by engaging the Black male adolescent. Lanham, MD: An introduction to designs and methods. Englewood Cliffs,
Roman Littlefield. New Jersey: Jossey-Bass.
Roediger, D. R. (2002). Colored white. Transcending the racial Winston, M. R. (1982). Racial consciousness and the evolution
past. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. of mass communications in the United States. Daedalus:
Sellers, R. M., Smith, M. A., Shelton, J. N., Rowley, S. A. J., & Journal of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 111(4),
Chavous, T. M. (1998). Multidimensional Model of Racial 171–183.
Identity: A reconceptualization of African American racial Winston, M. R. (1971) Through the back door: academic rac-
identity. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 2(1), ism and the Negro scholar in historical perspective. Daedalus:
18–39. Journal of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 100 (3),
Shelton, J., & Sellers, R.M. (2003). The role of racial identity 678–719.
in perceived racial discrimination. Journal of Personality and Yolton, J. W. (1991). The Blackwell Companion to the
Social Psychology, 84(5), 1079–1092. Enlightenment. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

w in ston , w in ston 581


CHAPTER

Belonging to Gender: Social


26 Identities, Symbolic Boundaries
and Images
Ana Flávia do Amaral Madureira

Abstract
Symbolic boundaries mark the differences between individuals and social groups in daily life. These
symbolic boundaries are deeply connected with the feelings of belonging to specific social groups. What
does belonging to gender mean? Social control related to the feminine body and sexuality is a field in
which the study of reproduction of inequalities in the domain of gender relations is of interest. It is
necessary to construct creative analytical and methodological strategies to investigate gender issues
inserted in broad cultural meaning systems, historically constructed. In this paper, I consider the analytical
and methodological relevance of images as data sources in the context of psychological science.
Keywords: gender, social identities, symbolic boundaries, meaning-making processes, images as cultural
artifacts

. . . To affirm the identity means demark boundaries, associated to femininity and masculinity as “lin-
means make distinctions between what is inside and guistic atoms” (Madureira, 2007a). Therefore, it is
what is outside. The identity is always connected necessary to construct creative analytical and meth-
within a strong separation and distinction, supposes odological strategies that emphasize the importance
and, at the same time, affirms and reaffirms power of images, as cultural artifacts, in the inquiries about
relations. ‘We’ and ‘they’ are not in this case only meaning-making processes and the construction of
grammatical distinctions . . . . social identities.
(Silva, 2000, p. 82)

What does it mean to be a man or to be a woman? The Construction of Symbolic


What does belonging to gender mean? These ques- Boundaries and Feelings of Belonging
tions are important in the analysis about the com- to Specific Social Groups
plex relations between the collective culture and the From a cultural psychology framework, human
psychological development of each person. From a conduct is conceived as behavior reorganized by
cultural psychology framework, this chapter focuses semiotic mediation that is used by the intentional
on the construction of symbolic boundaries that are and active mediator, the person oneself (Valsiner,
deeply connected with the feelings of belonging to 2005, 2007a). Consequently, understanding human
specific social groups. More precisely, our story is conduct is essential to considering the central role of
about symbolic boundaries related to the construc- semiotic mediation. Nevertheless, our relating with
tion of gender identities. the world is not just a rational enterprise mediated
It is not possible to properly understand the pro- by signs expressed by verbal language. Therefore,
cesses of the construction of gender identities from an important theoretical and analytical challenge
an isolated approach that treats cultural meanings is the overcoming of rationalistic and linguistic

582
reductionisms in the inquiries of social and psycho- processes of meaning making in daily life, and sym-
logical phenomena (Madureira, 2008). In this direc- bolic boundaries have an important role in these
tion, the concept of symbolic boundaries could be a processes. Tensions, ambiguities, and differences
useful conceptual tool that expresses the necessity to are in the heart of the meaning-making processes
construct an integrative view, a systemic approach that involve the constant using of signs through the
that articulates cultural, affective, and cognitive flow of personal experiences. It is important to stress
aspects in the inquiries of important issues for psy- that signs, visual and verbal, present a hybrid and
chology and social sciences in general. recursive nature that increase the complexity of the
In this chapter, I focus on the process of social meaning-making processes (Valsiner, 2007a). After
identities. More precisely: the focus is on the con- all, there are many possible combinations between
struction of gender identities. In this sense, it is icons, indices, and symbols.
important to stress that social identities are always Making distinctions is important at different
constructed on the ground of collective memories, levels of analysis, including the biological level—
historically situated. When we intend to analyze for example, the differentiation of organ systems in
the construction of social identities, we move our- embryogenesis, the “self/other” distinction in our
selves into the direction of crossing the boundaries immune systems (Valsiner & Rosa, 2007). In the
between psychology and social sciences. After all, biological sense, boundaries work as membranes.
as Rosa, Bellelli, and Bakhurst state, the concept of After all, “Boundaries as structures that unite
identity “. . .is not a concept that pertains exclusively standard in the biological world. All membranes
to psychology, but it is part of the heritage of all are boundaries—and the livelihood of organisms
social sciences . . .” (2000, p. 57). Therefore, in order depends on how well appropriate transpositions
to understand the construction of symbolic bound- of chemicals through these membranes work”
aries and the feelings of belonging to specific groups (Valsiner, 2007b, p. 221).
present in our societies, it is necessary to establish From a biological level to a sociological level of
interdisciplinary dialogues. analysis—considering the societies as dynamic and
open systems—we can notice that in diverse soci-
Social Identities: The Construction eties around the world, there are always symbolic
of Affective Bridges between Individuals boundaries that delimit the differences between
and Social Groups individuals and social groups in a semipermeable
The metaphorical image of a boundary as semi- way. Some of them do not present meaningful
permeable membrane (Valsiner, 2007b, 2009) is a implications, but others present deep implications
promising path to study diverse phenomena like, in different levels of analysis: (a) macrosocial level;
for example, the construction of social identities (b) interpsychological level (social interactions);
and the related dynamics (and tensions) between and (c) intrapsychological level (Madureira, 2008,
in-group and out-group, stereotypes, prejudices, 2009a).
and discriminatory practices, as prejudices in action The color of skin, for example, illustrates how
(Madureira, 2008, 2009a). symbolic boundaries can present relevant and con-
From a cultural psychology framework, it is crete implications in daily life. This arbitrary cri-
central to recognize that without differences and terion has been considered culturally meaningful
ambiguities, meaning-making processes are impos- to split individuals into different and hierarchical
sible (Ferreira, Salgado, & Cunha, 2006; Valsiner, social domains in different societies. This arbitrary
2007a). In other words, the differences are cen- criterion is in the base of racism, a kind of prejudice
tral elements of classificatory systems through the that, frequently, is associated with elitism (contempt
meanings that are created (Woodward, 2000). for poor people) in countries with slavery as a social
Therefore, meaning-making processes are deeply practice in their past. There is obviously a long his-
related to the tension between sameness and dif- tory of oppression and resistance in the process of
ference. As Ferreira, Salgado, and Cunha (2006, the transformation of the arbitrary criterion “color
p. 28) state: “ . . .Human meaning, in that sense, is of skin” into a culturally meaningful recognition of
brought to being by difference, contrast, tension, differences, which become connected with social
disagreement.. . .In other words, meaning is always power issues, understood as the relation between
dependent on the play between sameness and dif- forces of oppression and resistance (Foucault, 1996).
ference.” Thus, marked differences are central in the In few words, differences become inequalities.

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 583


When semipermeable symbolic boundaries the far away”: adventure, encountering novelty and
become cultural barriers—understood as rigid, non- also risks). In general terms, while the perception of
permeable boundaries—and come to qualify some risks and dangers are related to the promotion of the
groups at the cost of disqualifying others, we can Heimweh process, the feelings of pleasure and curios-
perceive different kinds of prejudices in action (rac- ity are related to the promotion of the Fernweh pro-
ism, sexism, homophobia, elitism, xenophobia, reli- cess. As we encounter in daily life many ambiguous
gious bigotry, and so on). When these rigid symbolic situations, one possible solution could be avoided
boundaries are targets of transgression, we see the the experiences that put in risks the sense of sta-
violence and the intolerance underlying diverse dis- bility of self-system, especially our personal values
criminatory practices. For the constant reproduction (Madureira, 2007b, 2007c). As Joerchel affirms,
of social inequalities and hierarchies, there are many
. . . the relation between ‘home, secure’ and the
social mechanisms that, in different ways, inform
‘strange, unfamiliar’ is a key element in developing
that these boundaries should be respected, whatever
a self system. . . . Thus, the self concept is comprised
the cost in terms of psychological suffering: depres-
both of the familiar, the home environment, as well
sion, anxiety, shame, and so on (Madureira, 2007a,
as of the strange and the unknown. It is within this
2007b, 2007c, 2008). In extreme cases, when the
tension that humans develop a self concept: the
symbolic boundaries become more rigid, the “oth-
secure home environment provides the base for self
ers” (they) are socially perceived as enemies that
confidence and self actualization, the strange and
should be eliminated. Figure 26.1 shows a didactic
the unknown provides a platform for hopes, dreams,
view of the transformation of symbolic boundaries:
and desires, for potential actions and potential self
(a) from differences to inequalities; and (b) from
concept as well as a platform for fears and threats to
inequalities to intolerance.
the self system. . . . In this respect the construction of
a social barrier can be seen as defense mechanisms in
The Feelings of Belonging to a Specific
reaction to a perceived threat to the self concept.
Group: The Tension between the
(2007, p. 257)
Heimweh and the Fernweh Processes
The feelings of belonging to a specific group pro- Therefore, when the Heimweh orientation is pro-
vide a familiar and secure basis to face the ambi- moted, the symbolic boundaries between “us” and
guities present in ordinary situations in our lives “others” tend to become rigid. It is important to
(Madureira, 2008, 2009a). In this direction, it is clarify that we are not talking about a linear causal
relevant to mention the notion of tension between relation. Instead of we are talking about a tendency.
two general processes, specified by Ernest Boesch, In this sense, when the Heimweh orientation is pro-
Heimweh (“homeward road”: striving toward the moted, a cultural barrier tends to be erected and the
known and the secure) and the Fernweh (“road to others come to be perceived as inferiors or enemies

We They

A: They are different...

We
Χ They

B: They are inferior...

We
Χ They

Figure 26.1 Prejudices as rigid symbolic


C: They are enemies. Therefore, they should be eliminated. boundaries: from differences to inequalities,
from inequalities to intolerance.

584 belongi ng to g e nde r


who put at risk ourselves and, in a broader sense, practices that mark what is socially expected regarding
the status quo. More than seeking strategies to deal men and women. These social expectations delimit the
with ambiguities from a secure and familiar basis, symbolic boundaries of masculinity and femininity.
what emerges is the desire to eliminate all ambi- Frequently, masculinity and femininity are conceptu-
guities, and all differences, to eliminate the others, alized by the logic-exclusive separation. As Watzlawik
perceived as the source of uncomfortable feelings (2009) demonstrated, the constructs of masculinity
(Madureira, 2008, 2009a). and femininity—based on the oversimplification and
An example can illustrate the discussion above: overlapping between different levels of analysis—are
from (a) the secure basis of religious beliefs, values fragile in scientific terms. In this sense, to be a man or
and practices in the case of religious individuals who a woman is not a “natural fact.” Instead, belonging to
respect other religious beliefs distinct of their reli- gender is a cultural construction.
gion; to (b) religious bigotry based on fundamen- In the cultural construction of gender identi-
talist mentality (e.g., ones’s belief that everybody ties, an important domain entails the beliefs, val-
outside of the symbolic boundaries of his/her own ues, and practices related to sexuality (Blackwood,
religion is “unfaithful” and should be converted or 2000). Thus, in this paper, we pay a special atten-
combated and eliminated (Sim, 2004). Therefore, tion to the interfaces between gender and sexuality
differences become inequalities, and intolerance, that issues, including the deep connections between sex-
underlying prejudice, becomes explicit through dis- ism and homophobia, which constitute boundary
criminatory practices against different social groups phenomena (Madureira, 2007b). The maintenance
(Madureira, 2007c, 2007d, 2008). of gender inequalities in daily life is sustained by a
To summarize—the study of boundary processes complex power system (Foucault, 1996). Women,
challenge us in the direction of an integrative view that frequently, have a strategic and important position
articulates cultural, affective, and cognitive aspects in in the maintenance of this complex power system.
the research of important issues for psychological and The scornful talk among women about the sexual
social sciences as, for example, social identities, stereo- behavior of other women is, for example, a pow-
types, prejudices, and discriminatory practices. erful informal social control strategy concerning
From the previous discussion, it is possible to feminine sexuality. More precisely, the social control
conclude that when we talk about the construction related to feminine sexuality is a meaningful field
of social identities, we are talking about affective to study hierarchical gender relations. In this sense,
bridges (feelings of belonging) between the individual the feminine body, sexual pleasures, and desires play
and the social groups present in society (Madureira, a strategic role in the context of the “power games”
2000, 2008, 2009a; Madureira & Branco, 2007). occurring within cultural contexts.
These processes are a political arena where tensions
and contradictions are not the exception, but a com- Gender Identities: We Are Not Talking
mon characteristic. In this sense, gender, class, and about “Natural Boundaries”
race become important interdependent axes in the The interdisciplinary studies of gender have
approaches on social identities, as powerful social questioned the biological essentialism diffused in
organizers in different societies (Barcinski, 2008; daily life, and in scientific approaches based on the
Oliveira, 1998). Therefore, the construction of gender traditional biomedicine model (Costa, 1996). As
identities always happens in connection with other previously mentioned, the construction of gender
social identities. Moreover, identity processes present identities is permeated by beliefs, values, stereotypes,
a clear political dimension (Silva, 2000). Surely, we prejudices, and practices that mark what is socially
are not analyzing a neutral domain of social life. expected regarding men and women in specific
sociocultural contexts. These social expectations,
with historical roots, are the “collective ground”
What Does Belonging to Gender Mean?
where the symbolic boundaries of masculinity and
Social Identities, Symbolic Boundaries,
femininity are delimited in daily life. In this sense,
and Cultural Canalization
we can say that gender identities are:
Between the (biological) concept of sex and the
(cultural) concept of gender, there is a long way to (a) constructed not only in the relations
be covered by each person. This “long way” is always between men and women, but also intragender
covered from particular socio-cultural contexts, per- relations from the cultural models and antimodels
meated by beliefs, values, stereotypes, prejudices, and of masculinity and femininity (Parker, 1991);

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 585


(b) constructed in an articulated way within Sexism and Homophobia: When Prejudices
power relations that permeated our societies in Meet Each Other and Become Stronger
their different levels, relations of force, oppression, Since the beginning of Christianity, coherent
and resistance (Foucault, 1996). with the ancient Greek one-sex model, and dur-
ing all the medieval period in the Western Europe,
The development of the gender concept, from the “. . .the woman was defined from her deficiencies in
1980s, expresses the important exchange between relation to the human nature, that is was accom-
the scientific enterprise and the feminist movement, plished in the most complete form in man” (Zuber,
which as a social and political movement, has fought 2002, p. 144). The adopting of the two-sexes
against the sociohistorical inequalities between men model, at the end of eighteenth century and during
and women in different domains of life (Louro, the nineteenth century, was not just a consequence
1998). According to Joan Scott, “ . . . Gender is the of “medical scientific progress”, but resulted from
social organization of sexual difference. The concept deep social and political changes. As Costa claims:
[gender] is not a reflection of biological reality, but “. . . From the ‘inverted man’, the woman became the
gender constructs the meaning of this reality . . . ” ‘inverse of man’, and the cause was in her sex. Firstly,
(Scott, 1995, p. 115). the production of social and political inequalities
Therefore, as an analytical and political tool, happened, between men and women, legitimated
the concept of gender helps us to reject the by the natural norm of sex. Then, what is effect
assumptions—underling discourses about the became cause. . .” (1996, p. 85, italics added).
“natural” inequalities between men and women— The maintenance of a deep gap between mascu-
that are based on biological differences. In this linity and femininity has a strategic role in political
sense, the concept of gender has an important terms, in order to reproduce the hierarchical struc-
heuristic value concerning the understanding of ture between men and women. The transgression
the cultural and psychological basis of the pro- of symbolic boundaries related to gender is socially
cess of becoming a man or a woman (Madureira, perceived as a threat to ordinary flow of life. For
2007b). We can say that gender issues have an example, homosexuality is traditionally perceived as
important role concerning individual psychologi- a defect of gender identity, as if gays and lesbians
cal development, in terms of cultural canaliza- are men and women that “fail” in the construction
tion (Golombok & Fivush, 1994; Madureira & of their gender identities. In the cases of transgen-
Branco, 2004). Gender is, therefore, an interdis- der, the transgression of the gender boundaries is
ciplinary analytical tool that makes it possible to socially perceived as an even greater threat, because
understand diverse phenomena studied by human these cases question the existence of a “natural link”
sciences. Gender is a relational concept—best between biological sex and gender identity. It does
viewed as a field (Madureira, 2007b). not cause surprise that the amplification of differ-
When we focus on identity processes and power ences between men and women is in the basis of
relations, it is essential that we pay special attention sexism and homophobia.
to the role of scientific discourses in contemporary Sexism corresponds to an exclusive separation
societies. As Foucault (1996) analyzed, there are (dualistic conception) of genders, prioritizing one
intrinsic connections between scientific knowledge over the other, and associating pejorative meanings
and power relations in our disciplinary Western soci- to the other. In didactic terms: sexism = rigid distinc-
eties. Historically, modern sciences broke the ancient tion of genders + unequal power relations + constructed
distinction between episteme (theoretical knowledge) prejudice to mark the unequal relation (Madureira,
and téchne (applied knowledge) (Marcondes, 2000). 2007a, 2007b, 2009b). If we focus on the macroso-
Thus, modern sciences are not a kind of contempla- cial level of analysis, we observe the reproduction
tive knowledge. In fact, the socially spreading myth of a hierarchical structure of gender that expresses
of scientific neutrality hides this “practical” aspect inequalities between men and women in different
of the production of scientific knowledge (Chauí, domains, as autonomy, prestige, status, and so on
1995). From the noticing that science is power in (Bourdieu, 2005).
our societies, we should develop ethical and politi- However, it is essential to recognize that sexism,
cal reflections concerning our researches and recog- as a kind of prejudice, is not present just “in men’s
nize that we are not constructing neutral knowledge minds.” It can be found in institutional and informal
(Madureira, 2009b). practices, in different social relations in daily life. The

586 belongi ng to g e nde r


empirical example presented in this paper will illus- their desires and their access to other sexual partners.”
trate the importance of the adoption of a relational In fact, the label of promiscuity is a real danger for
perspective in gender studies. Beyond that, as recent women in some contexts, especially where the tra-
studies have demonstrated, there are deep connec- ditional gender ideology is strong.
tions between sexism and homophobia (Andersen, Sexual violence, more precisely, rape, does not
2000; Lionço & Diniz, 2009; Madureira, 2007b; correspond with a simple “individual pathology,”
Welzer-Lang, 2001). Sexism—as a rigid and hierar- completely dissociated of power relations, beliefs,
chical gender distinction—is directly related to the values, and cultural practices regarding gender
reproduction of nonpermeable boudaries between issues. In this sense, it is pertinent to mention the
masculinity and femininity, between the heterosex- research coordinated by the anthropologist Rita
ual population and the Lesbian, Gay, Bissexual, and Segato (2003) about gender structure and sexual
Transgender (LGBT) population. violence, from the analysis of interviews with prison-
ers of Complexo Penitenciário da Papuda (Distrito
The Traditional Dualistic Gender View: Federal, Brazil) who committed crimes against sex-
Cultural Meanings Associated to ual freedom. This research shows that, in the rap-
Masculinity and Femininity ists’ discourse, it is commonly a “moralizing accent”
There is a historical-cultural dualistic gender concerning the women’s behavior that is considered,
view in Brazilian society, like other Latin American, in some way, immoral. Segato stresses that the rape
Mediterranean, Middle Eastern, and North African is perceived by rapists:
societies (González-López, 2005). According to this
. . . as a punishment or revenge against a generic
dualistic gender view, we can perceive strong con-
woman who goes out of her place, that is, her
nections between:
subordinate position and ostensibly tutelage by a
(a) femininity, sexual passivity, and the value of status system. . . . ‘Only the protestant woman
female virginity versus [in Portuguese: mulher crente, evangélica] is good’,
(b) masculinity, sexual activity, and the value of said to us a prisoner, which means: ‘only she does
diverse and precocious sexual experiences. not deserve to be raped.’
(2003, p. 31)
According to this dualistic meaning system, the
antimodel of masculinity is the “passive man,” and According to the analysis carried out by Lloyd
the antimodel of femininity is the “active woman” Vogelman with rapists in South Africa (as cited in
(promiscuous) (Parker, 1991). The traditional Segato, 2003, p. 30): “women who are not propriety
cultural discourses about sexuality in Brazil have of a man . . . are perceived as propriety of all men. In
structured from this traditional dualistic gender essence, they lose their physical and sexual auton-
view: masculinity—activity in social and sexual omy.” Therefore, in traditional hierarchical gender
domains—versus femininity—passivity in social structure, the notion of propriety of a man does not
and sexual domains. involve only material possessions, but also the pos-
Therefore, the “major problem” concerning female session of women. In other words, the woman is
sexuality would be the active conduct by women, not socially perceived as citizen of her own sexual-
many times perceived as a sign of promiscuity. In ity and body, but as an object/property of the man:
this sense, it is curious to note that of the women an “honorable” woman would be a possession of a
who participated in a qualitative research about the unique man.
construction of nonhegemonic sexual identities in Without any doubt a rape is a case of extreme
Brasília, Brazil (Madureira, 2000), all of them argued violence. However, it reveals subjacent cultural
for a clear-cut difference between gays (out-group) meanings associated to traditional gender relations
and lesbians (in-group). In their opinions, compar- in our societies. As it was analyzed by Segato (2003),
ing to men, women are more affective. Moreover, the rapist fulfills a kind of mandate of society: the
they claimed that men are totally sex-oriented, and “deviated” women must be punished! They should
depict men as promiscuous (out-group) whereas they not circulate freely in spaces designated to men,
are not. As Blackwood (2000, p. 232) claims: “. . . By such as the public space of streets at “inappropriate
establishing certain ideas about who and what men times.” Indeed, as men socially perceived as “closer
and women are, gender ideologies create different to women,” gays are also victims of sexual vio-
possibilities for men’s or women’s understanding of lence. The maintenance of rigid symbolic boundaries

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 587


between masculinity and femininity does not only 2007a). It is an insightful example to analyze how
imply “bad jokes” against the supposed transgressors, women, frequently, put in action the mechanisms
but also implies, in extreme cases, acts of physical vio- of social control on the feminine body and sexual-
lence against women and men who do not “respect” ity. These mechanisms of social control are deeply
their biological sex. As if biological sex completely connected within archaic cultural meanings about
determines their actions, their thoughts, their feel- femininity, as it will be discussed later. Moreover, it
ings, their desires. As if the biological sex traces an illustrates the importance of adoption of a relational
inexorable destiny that must be respected. and political perspective (Louro, 1998; Scott, 1995)
when we focus on gender issues.
Social Control on the Body and Example extracted from individual interview:
Sexuality of Other Women: An Interviewee: Joanna (fictitious name).
Empirical Example Age: 34 years old.
. . . Because gender includes beliefs about sexual Religion: Catholic.
behaviour, it is one of the primary crucibles within
Ana Flávia (interviewer): Do you think today’s
which sexuality is produced. Sexualities are informed
society expects different things from men and
by and embedded in conceptions of gender; that is,
women? Why?
they are embedded in gender ideologies that enable
– Joanna: I think that too much equality, also, is not
and structure differential practices for women and
good, you know?
men . . . .
– Ana Flávia: What do you mean? So I can better
(Blackwood, 2000, p. 229)
understand what you’re saying . . .
This topic focus on the interfaces between gen- – Joanna: Well, I guess, like, too much equality, then
der and sexuality issues from an empirical example we’d go like, then I don’t know. I’m going . . . I’m
extracted from a broader research (Madureira, going . . . for instance, uh, the same rights. When you
2007a). The main objective of the research in focus say, like, that women want to have the same rights as
was to analyze teachers’ beliefs and conceptualiza- men, and everything. But then you have the sexual
tions within the context of Brazilian public middle thing. You know, it’s too cheap, you see, like, what’s
schools, located in Distrito Federal (DC, Brazil), the problem if I go out with a guy this weekend and
about gender and sexuality issues, especially those then with another in the next? You see? Because if
concerning sexual and gender diversity. These issues all rights are the same, everything the same, at work,
were analyzed from the integration of different things are like this, you see? Then you have an equal-
methods: (a) questionnaire; (b) individual semistruc- ity, a sexual freedom, you know? A sexual freedom
tured interview; and (c) focus group. One hundred that I, like, sometimes I think that, it’s not worthy,
twenty-two teachers (n = 122) from seven different you know?
public schools in Distrito Federal participated of – Ana Flávia: This sexual freedom you’re saying it’s
the first phase of the research (questionnaire). Ten not worthy, what do you mean by that?
teachers (n = 10), from two different schools that – Joanna: I mean promiscuity.
contributed in the first phase, participated in the sec- – Ana Flávia: In relation to whom? Men or women?
ond phase (individual semistructured interview and – Joanna: To women.
focus group). The age of their students was between
In this excerpt of the interview with Joanna, she
the range of 11 to 15 years old. In the process of
says that she disagrees with the idea of men and
analyzing the “empirical indicators,” it was central
women having the same rights in all domains of life.
to interpret the implicit connections between: (a)
She agrees about the same rights in the professional
individual beliefs and values concerning the issues
domain, but she really disagrees about the same
in focus; and (b) the broader cultural meanings sys-
rights concerning the sexual domain. Her position
tem of gender and sexuality, historically established.
is made clear when she says:
In other words, it was central to construct analytical
strategies to integrate different levels of analysis in order But then you have the sexual thing. You know, it’s too
to elaborate a more general understanding about the cheap, you see, like, what’s the problem if I go out with
subject of the target research. a guy this weekend and then with another in the next?
The following empirical example was extracted You see? Because if all rights are the same, everything
from the individual interviews carried out at the the same, at work, things are like this, you see? Then you
second phase of the broader research (Madureira, have an equality, a sexual freedom, you know? A sexual

588 belongi ng to g e nde r


freedom that I, like, sometimes I think that, it’s not “controlled” by each woman, by other women, and
worthy, you know? by society in general. The pejorative view about the
female body and sexuality is fed by social imaginary.
According to Joanna, sexual freedom is a real
The ways that each woman deals with her sexuality
problem for women, but that is not so for men.
and body in daily life are socially interpreted from
Here we observe, in her discourse, the links
symbolic boundaries. These symbolic boundaries
between: (a) same rights for men and women in
split women in two different social groups: “honorable
the sexual domain; (b) [women] become cheap;
women” and “nonhonorable women.” A central issue
(c) [women’s] sexual freedom; (d) [women’s] pro-
is: the honor of a woman is focused on her private life
miscuity. Thus, we can conclude that, for her, the
while the honor of a man is focused on his public life.
same rights between men and women at the sexual
domain are not desirable; instead, it seems that the
same sexual rights can be “dangerous.” After all, The Feminine in the Medieval Christian
for women, sexual freedom is interpreted by her as Iconography: The Woman as a Devil
a sign of promiscuity. The personal values system When we focus on the construction of gender
seems to express a central role in the interpreta- identities, it is necessary to promote interdisciplin-
tion of what “sexual freedom” means. For example, ary dialogues between psychological science and
for some women sexual freedom is interpreted as a social sciences in general. For example, the current
sign of individual rights, while other women inter- historical analysis about social imaginary in the
pret sexual freedom as a sign of promiscuity. A sign Middle Ages can be a fertile ground for psychol-
that can present concrete implications in some ogy. Jacques Le Goff and Jean-Claude Schmitt,
contexts (especially sexist contexts): women who two important contemporary historians, stress the
were marked with this sign (seen as promiscuous) necessity of integrating “. . .in our analyses and in
become less worthy in the community’s eyes. our reflection a new orientation in history so pres-
What is particularly interesting here is that such ent in the view of historians nowadays: the history
a position was presented by a woman. Again, in of imaginary. . .” (2002, p. 14). In other words, it is
order to develop our analytical strategies to inter- important to articulate the analysis of the “historical
pret gender issues it is essential to go beyond generic facts” and the representation of these “facts.” The
assumptions about the “masculine oppression authors note that “Around twenty years, an impor-
against women.” Gender inequalities are sustained by tant part of these new ways appears under the label
a complex power system that is built on cultural mean- of ‘historical anthropology’ ” (Le Goff & Schmitt,
ings and practices where women, frequently, have a 2002, p. 18).
strategic and important position in the maintenance of In this sense, the present topic analyzes some
the oppression system. For example, the scornful talk historical clues about the cultural pejorative view
among women about the sexual behavior of other about the sexuality of women from the image of the
women is a very powerful social control strategy feminine in the medieval Christian iconography.
concerning feminine sexuality. After all, our personal imagination is constantly fed
Here we have an example of the strong relations by the images that circulate in social imaginary, and
between gender and sexuality issues. More precisely, we should not disregard the force of the Christian
the social control (by men and women) related to cultural tradition in Western societies.
feminine sexuality is a meaningful field to study The European Middle Ages is, traditionally,
hierarchical gender relations. The feminine body, divided in the following way: it began in the fifth-
sexual pleasures and desires play a strategic role in century, with the disintegration of Western Rome
the context of the “power games” occurring within Empire in 476 AC, and continued until the fifteenth
cultural contexts. Therefore, it is essential to inte- century, with the Turkish capture of Constantinople
grate a critical view about gender relations with the in 1453 (Pratas, 2009). It is important to remember
interdisciplinary studies of sexuality, as illustrated in that Catholic Church was the most powerful social
this empirical example. institution in this historical period, especially dur-
For example, the pejorative view of Joanna about ing the last centuries of the Middle Ages (tenth to
the “sexual freedom” of women (understood by her fifteenth centuries), when its economic, political,
as a sign of “promiscuity”) is inserted in the long and cultural power reached its peak. The Earth was
Christian tradition that presents feminine sexual- considered the center of universe, and the universe
ity as potentially dangerous. Thus, it should be was considered as finite and unchanged. The image

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 589


of God was in the center of medieval societies and, the expulsion from the paradise and the establish-
therefore, philosophy and arts were simple servants ment of original sin” (Gomes, 2009, p. 262). In
of theology. the New Testament, the third important element of
From the conception that images are cultural religious doctrine related to femininity is the figure
artifacts, this topic focuses on some elements of of Mary, mother of Christ, who is in opposition to
medieval Christian iconography1 in order to seek Eve. Although Eve has a sin essence, Mary receives
clues about the historical roots of archaic meanings the Holy Spirit. The Virgin Mary “. . .is the unique
about femininity. These meanings are still present woman in the Christian ideology who is not essen-
in the social imaginary in Brazil, a country with a tially sin and of which the body is not vehicle of
strong Catholic tradition, but are also present in sin” (Gomes, 2009, p. 263). Moreover, the figure of
other Western countries. Mary is perceived as something extraordinary, as an
ideal of chastity and purity that transcends the real-
Misogyny in the Medieval Social imaginary ity of concrete women.
Misogyny, or hatred of women, was widespread Between the fourth and sixth centuries, spread
in European medieval societies. Misogyny did not a literature for men, inspiring the practice of soli-
begin with Christianity in the Middle Ages; it cor- tary life that already had been happening among
responded to an appropriation of conceptions and Eastern Christians since the third century. It was a
beliefs that were already presented in the Ancient literature that presented accounts about the life in
world. On another hand, misogyny became a pro- monasteries with the objective to persuade men to
ject “. . .in the sense to encrust in the popular imag- seek to chastity. For example, Athanasius (295–373
inary the belief in the inferiority of woman and AC), archbishop of Alexandria, found refuse among
femininity. In Western history, the period when the monks before writing his famous Anton Life
this procedure was the most obvious was during (Vainfas, 1992). In this work, a “crowd of feminine
the Middle Ages.” (Gomes, 2009, p. 261). In this faces and bodies, that assaulted the monks’ imagina-
sense, some meaningful examples will be presented tion, is associated to devil. It was another image of
in order to illustrate how the social imaginary in this woman that emerges in these works: the diabolic,
historical period was full of hostile images concern- fleshly, that must be execrated of the spirit . . . demo-
ing women. niac mask.” (Vainfas, 1992, p. 16).
As the start point, we will focus on the holy In the novel The Name of the Rose by Umberto
book for Christianity, the Bible that comprised the Eco2, the plot of the novel happens in the last week
Ancient (Old) and the New Testament. Then, other of November 1327 in a Benedictine monastery in
examples will be presented. The Bible presents at medieval Italy. Although the work was fictional in
least three essential elements of the religious doctrine nature, the author reconstructs in detail the atmo-
associated with femininity: (a) as the man and the sphere of this historical period. In this sense, there
woman were created (Ancient Testament, Genesis); are parts of this novel that express some of the images
(b) the figure of Eve (Ancient Testament, Genesis); about women that circulated in medieval monaster-
and (c) the figure of Mary, mother of Christ (New ies. In general lines—with the exception of Mary,
Testament) (Gomes, 2009; Pratas, 2009). mother of Christ—the images of other women are
According to Genesis, concerning the way that extremely pejorative (Eco, 1983). 3
the man (Adam) and the woman (Eve) were created, From the previous examples, it is possible to
it is interesting to note that “. . .the man is a direct deduce that there is no salvation for women out of
descendent of God—a divine being—although the the model of chastity and purity that were personi-
woman is a descendent of man’s rib—a flesh being fied by the image of the Virgin Mary. In this sense,
and, therefore, closer to what is profane, sensorial women should sublime their femininity, essentially
and corporal” (Gomes, 2009, p. 262). Thus, the marked by the original sin introduced by Eve in par-
human tendency to commit sins is interpreted by adise. Mary and Eve are, therefore, biblical figures
Christianity as stronger in women than men. In a that personalized the strong moral dualism regard-
similar way, the figure of Eve per se also expresses ing women present in Christian imaginary (Gomes,
this pejorative view of femininity. More precisely, 2009; Pratas, 2009). This dualism is inserted in
Genesis stresses “the incapacity of Eve to resist the the long Christian historical tradition of pejorative
temptation, the woman is also responsible to induce meanings associated with the body and pleasures
Adam to eat the forbidden fruit, which resulted in (Vainfas, 1992; Delumeau, 1990).

590 belongi ng to g e nde r


In this direction, Vainfas—after the accomplish- The Gothic cathedrals illustrate how the architec-
ment of historical analysis of marriage, love, and tonic structures can make real in their “rocks” all of
desire in the Christian West (since the beginning the symbolic universe that embody some beliefs, val-
of Christianity until the end of the Middle Ages)— ues, narratives, and cultural practices that populated
states that, although the moral diversity concerning the medieval imaginary. In a social world where the
sexual issues during many centuries of Christianity, analphabetism was the reality of the great majority
if there was a characteristic trade of all these morals of the population, the sculptures, the paintings, the
was: “. . .the refuse of pleasure . . . that presupposes stained glass windows, and the tapestries in the Gothic
that the pleasure is an evil itself and also is an obsta- cathedrals fulfilled a didactic function: telling, through
cle to eternal salvation. . .” (1992, p. 81). Therefore, images, biblical stories. Thus, these different forms of
we find a true “angelical anthropology” (Delumeau, art have become more concrete and palpable beliefs
1990) between the lines of the Christian religious and values coherent within the Christian view of the
tradition, based on the conception that human world. There is a rich iconographic tradition in the
beings should get closer to angels, who would be West that was legated by Christianity. The Christian
celestial beings without body and sex. It is possible medieval iconography fulfilled, therefore, a strategic
to deduce that, concerning the Christian ideal of function in a historical period when the participa-
asceticism, women—as “Eves in potential”—would tion in the symbolic universe of reading and writing
already have been born in disadvantage. was not a right of each citizen, but a privilege of a
reduced part of the population.
Telling Stories through Religious Images It is important to mention that the artistic style
Marked by the original sin introduced by Eve, named “Gothic” developed in Europe between the
women, in principle, would be more distant from thirteenth and fifteenth centuries, in the period of
the Christian ideal of renunciation of body and transition between the Middle Ages and the Modern
pleasures of “the profane world” (in opposition to Age (Strickland, 1999). In the Gothic style, that suc-
“the spiritual world”). As “Eves in potential,” the ceeded the Romanesque style, the sacred became,
women should be the target of a strong social con- gradually, closer to human reality through a more
trol. Their actions, their body, and their sexuality naturalistic representation. According to León
should be keep guard over with rigidity. Because (2006), a common characteristic of Gothic paint-
of the supposed feminine proximity to diabolic ing was the increasing naturalism, stimulated by
forces, women were forbidden to cure diseases and the scholastic philosophical though, that had as one
their transgressions were to be punished with sever- of the most representative name: Thomas Aquinas
ity (Dall’Ava-Santucci, 2005). Thus, thousands of (1225–1274). He introduced a Christian version of
women were burned alive during the Inquisition. the works by the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–
The Christian ethos of refusal of pleasures, perme- 322 BC), focusing faith issues through the “light
ated by misogyny, found in the universe of visual4 arts of reason” and defending that philosophy helps the
an important ally in doctrinaire terms. In the Western work of theology (Marcondes, 2000). The scholasti-
history of arts, in the period of transition between the cism promoted an approximation between human
Middle Ages and Modern Ages, the Gothic cathedrals beings and the surrounding world, seeing the reflex
occupied a space of prominence. As Strickland (1999) of God in each creature. This approximation stimu-
stresses, the Gothic cathedrals were true “Bibles in lated the analysis of the details of nature and also
rock,” wonderful architectonic structures: a narrative sense in the different plastic manifesta-
tions of Gothic style (León, 2006).
. . . In fact, these ‘Bibles in rock’ overcame Around 200 years after the death of Thomas
even the classical architecture in terms of Aquinas, western Europe passed through a deep
technological audacity. . . . The medieval revolution called cultural and artistic Renaissance,
theologians believed that the beauty of church directly related to the increase of mercantile bour-
inspired the meditation and faith of believers. geoisie and the increase of cities (urban Renaissance).
Consequently, the churches are more than a A new view of the world started to delineate.
simple combination of spaces. They are holy Nevertheless, this Renaissance did not imply a
texts, with volume[s] of ornaments preaching radical rupture within the medieval mentality. For
the salvation way . . . example, the diffusion of the international Gothic
(Strickland, 1999, pp. 28–29) style—that happened at the end of the fourteenth

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 591


century and the first half of the fifteenth century— sin is introduced in the world. According to Torviso
resulted in the development of Flemish painting and Marías, Bosch “ . . .did not more than repro-
in northern Europe (Léon, 2006). Although the duce plastically what the theologians and poets were
italian Renaissance sought inspiration from classi- writing during the fifteenth century, following the
cal ancient works, the Flemish Renaissance sought medieval patristic, ‘culpa of Eve’. . .” (1982, p. 163).
inspiration from nature (Strickland, 1999). Both of If we “read” the images—from the paradise into
them, however, followed a tendency present since direction to hell (from left to right, like a text)—we
the end of the Middle Ages: despite the increased can see the development of a religious narrative in
naturalism in the plastic expressions, the majority of front of our eyes, a religious narrative with moral-
the themes represented were still religious. izing function that alerts individuals to the tragic
We find the most original expression of the consequences of sin and, especially, the luxuriance
Flemish tradition in the paintings by Hieronymus sin (Torviso & Marías, 1982).
Bosch (1450–1516), an artist considered to be the Between the historical period when Bosch lived—
precursor of the surrealistic movement of the twen- around 1450–1516 (Charles, Manca, McShane, &
tieth century (Strickland, 1999). The principal Wigal, 2007)—and the beginning of twenty-first
interest of Bosch was shown in his paintings, with century there are, surely, innumerable economic,
irony, the passions and vices of his epoch (León, political, and cultural differences. However, the
2006). Underlying his work, there is a moralizing social imaginary in the contemporary Christian
discourse connected within the medieval imaginary, Western societies are still marked, in different ways,
permeated by misogynic images that remitted to by archaic images about women that are reproduced,
original sin and the punishment of hell. One of the reactualized, and contested in daily life. In some
most notorious paintings by Bosch is the triptych sense the moral dualism expressed by the strong
The Garden of Earthly Delights.5 opposition between Mary and Eve is still alive. In
the promotion of gender equality, in diverse social
There is no other Renaissance panel painting like
spaces (including relations in the private domain),
so-called Garden of Earthly Delights. . . , Bosch’s
an important challenge is, exactly how to overcome
best-known work. When opened, the triptych
this strong moral dualism about women. As we see
reveals three scenes that, at first glimpse, present
in this topic, this complex challenge is articulated to
a straightforward Biblical account. Adam and Eve
the long Christian iconographic tradition that has
appear in the left panel, their many children in
marked, in deep ways, the social imaginary in the
the centre, and a monstrous scene of hellfire and
West.
damnation in the right. However, upon closer
inspection, things are not as they should be. To begin
Culture, Semiotic Mediation, and
with, no descendants of the first parents ever lived so
Images: Cultural Canalizations of Human
well! Instead of the thorns and thistles the Bible says
Experiences through Visual Signs
were food for Eve’s children, who were consigned to
lives filled with pain and work, Bosch’s handsome Since the prehistoric period, people have been
young people feast with abandon on huge berries practicing painting. Through colors, light, and
and frolic naked among giant birds. They seem more shapes, artists have expressed the conception of the
like children at play, innocently taking exuberant world that surrounds them; they have become closer
advantage of a world devoid of any hint of danger to the immaterial and have understood, controlled,
or evil. and appreciated everyday life.
(Dixon, 2003, p. 227) (León, 2006, p. 6)

As commented by Dixon, on the left panel we From the image of the feminine in the medieval
see the representation of paradise. On the central Christian iconography, some historical clues on the
lamina, we see the representation of the Garden of pejorative view about women’s sexuality were ana-
Earthly Delights. Finally, on the right panel, Bosch lyzed in the previous topic. Surely, psychological
has represented hell. There is a clearly narrative sense science should not disregard the historical force of
in this painting: a story is narrated through images different religious traditions in the construction of
based on Christian doctrine. In the representation of social imaginary in diverse cultural contexts around
paradise, the Creator gives Eve to Adam (left panel). the world. In the context of Western societies, for
Thus, it is through the feminine figure of Eve that example, the long Christian cultural tradition, and

592 belongi ng to g e nde r


its rich iconography, can offer meaningful clues focus is on the human experience instead of the
about different social and psychological phenom- behavior itself (Valsiner, 2007b). The focus on
ena. After all, our personal imagination is constantly human experiences—which always happen in
fed by the images that circulate in social imaginary. culturally structured contexts—expresses the phe-
As Silva claims: “To affirm the identity means nomelogical approach present in researches car-
demark boundaries, means make distinctions ried out in the cultural psychology framework
between what is inside and what is outside. . .” (2000, (Valsiner, 2007a)—a cultural phenomenology of
p. 82). In the flow of everyday life experiences, each human experience.
person uses implicit criterions to include or exclude In the context of theoretical and empirical
in the symbolic boundaries of a particular group his/ researches on the construction of human experience,
herself or other individuals. These implicit criterions we are in front of an important challenge: improving
are connected within the personal values system that our analytical capacity in order to integrate biolog-
involves beliefs with deep affective roots (Branco & ical, cultural, and subjective dimensions. After all,
Madureira, 2008; Branco, Branco, & Madureira, human experience, as cultural organized, is the result
2008). From a cultural psychology framework, the of a long Homo Sapiens phylogenesis (Rosa, 2007a,
personal values system is not perceived as a simply 2007b). Thus, human senses have a clear biological
individual creation. Instead, a personal values system basis. At the same time, human senses are deeply
is created and changed by the tension between collective changed from the individual immersion in a specific
culture (and its complex mechanisms of canalization) cultural context that promotes a constant and, fre-
and the active and intentional role of each person. In quently implicit, “education of senses” (Madureira,
other words, even the most “personal” values have cul- 2007a). In this sense, it is not exaggeration the meta-
tural roots. phorical statement: social control penetrates in the mind
The construction and maintenance of these through the body and its sensations. Therefore, “the
diverse symbolic boundaries is directly related to dis- body is the intimate place where nature and culture
tinction, fluid or rigid, between insider and outsider meet each other” (Nightingale & Crombyas cited in
(Kim, 2007). Who is responsible for “gatekeeping” Araiza & Gisbert, 2007, p. 115).
of these symbolic boundaries? If we focus on the As it was analyzed by Louro (1998, 1999, 2003),
macrosocial level of analysis, we can suppose the fun- social institutions in general, and schools in par-
damental role of social institutions (e.g., religion, ticular, promote a continuous cultural education of
media, science, schools, laws, etc.) in “gatekeeping” senses in agreement with hegemonic social values.
the symbolic boundaries between insiders and out- Thus, individuals present on their bodies the “marks”
siders (Kim, 2007; Madureira, 2007c). An important of years of schooling. It was not just their minds that
strategy used by social institutions is the materializa- were modified by schooling, but also their bodies.
tion of some conceptions, beliefs, values, and world According to Le Breton (2007), the sensory
views through images. Our distant ancestors in the perceptions correspond to an ambitious and orig-
prehistoric period already used images to become inal research field that remains almost unexplored
closer to the immaterial (León, 2006). in social sciences. If we consider that: (a) the
In this sense, we can suppose that visual signs Western societies present a long and rich tradition
have fulfilled a strategic role in the processes of cul- of images; (b) in our contemporary societies, we
tural canalization of human experiences in different are living a true “invasion of images” in daily life
historical periods and different cultural contexts. through outdoors, television programs, movies (in
Thus, the present topic focuses on the analytical 2D and 3D), Internet, sophisticated video games,
and methodological relevance of images, as cultural and so on; and (c) through vision, individuals clas-
artifacts, in psychological science. sify other individuals in different social groups,
then we can conclude that the sense of vision—
Semiotic Mediation and Visual Signs: organized through stereotypes—has a special value
Beyond the Verbal Language in the in the study of social identities, personal values,
Study of Human Experience prejudices, and discriminatory practices. After
A central issue for cultural psychology is the all, in ordinary situations in daily life, individu-
relevance of individuals’ experiences in their rela- als classify other individuals in different social
tions with the social world and with themselves groups from their first impression6. Frequently,
(Valsiner & Rosa, 2007). In other words, the that classification is not based on more accurate

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 593


information. The first impression is enough to signs and expressed by verbal language. Beyond this
construct symbolic boundaries that split people in reductionistic concept, our relating to the world and
different domains: man, woman, white, black, het- to ourselves is affective embodiment (Madureira,
erosexual, homosexual, rich, poor, and so on. 2007a, 2007b; Madureira & Branco, 2005b). Thus,
Surely, there are particularities related to the affect, cognition, and action form a whole and
processes of classification concerning different complex unit, and human beings are semiotically
social groups. Some social groups present clear mediated: “. . . the role of language-mediated relat-
“marks” on their bodies, although other groups do ing with the world is not [the] highest level in the
not present these marks in a clear way. For exam- semiotic mediation hierarchy—but an intermediate
ple, as analyzed by Bourdieu (2005), the symbolic one . . .” (Valsiner, 2003, p. 156). In other words:
domination against gays and lesbians is related to the processes of semiotic mediation go beyond verbal
a specific stigma that, unlike the color of skin or language.
femininity, could be hidden or revealed. However, Human experience, culturally structured, is based
there are strong social expectations that work as on complex recursive semiotics processes: semiosis
cultural canalization into the direction of dissimu- (Rosa, 2007b). Iconic signs, because of their simi-
lation and/or discretion concerning nonhegemonic larity to objects, are powerful signs in terms of cul-
sexual orientations. Compared to sexism and rac- tural canalization. Contexts that involve specific
ism, a specific feature of homophobia is the demand activities—as, for example, religious rituals—are
that all nonheterosexual people keep his/her sexual used in order to promote the generalization of some
orientation secret. The rescue of legitimated public feelings, beyond the immediate contexts, “here and
existence, including the domain of laws, is a relevant now” (Valsiner, 2005). Architectural structures, paint-
mark of homophobia (Madureira, 2007c). ings, sculptures, and visual arts in general also fulfill
The maintenance of this secret includes also other certain functions in this direction, working as a “social
aspects related to personal sexual orientation, like the technique of feelings” (Vygotsky, 1970/2007). They
sexual and affective relationships. Frequently, it is a promote more general and abstract levels of cultural
complicated task for nonheterosexual people to deal mediation connected, in different ways, within the
with the social expectation to maintain this secret. symbolic universe in which they are inserted. The
Therefore, there are deep connections between the raw material of social identities, personal values,
social invisibility and the psychological suffering, and prejudices are not only verbal languages, but
expressed in feelings of discomfort, like anxiety, fear, also images.
depression, guilt, and shame by people who present
nonhegemonic sexual identities (Madureira, 2000, Images as Cultural Artifacts and Their
2007a, 2007b; Madureira & Branco, 2007). Thus, Methodological Potential in Psychology
social invisibility is one of the mechanisms of social Through the centuries, images have been cre-
exclusion that ensures the maintenance of hierarchi- ated to fulfill diverse functions (religious, aesthetic,
cal relations between different groups in society. political, entertainment, etc.). Thus, as researchers,
In sum: we should not disregard the corporal sen- we should not ignore the force of images in terms
sations and emotions embodied when we focus on the of cultural canalization of human experience. It is
cultural and psychological basis of different phenom- important to recognize the methodological poten-
ena like identity processes, values, and prejudices. The tial of images in our researches. In contemporary
accomplishment of theoretical and empirical studies societies—marked by a true “invasion of images”7
of psychological functions as embodied processes— in our daily life—we can mention, as an example of
that is, integrated biological, cultural, and subjective a broad and fertile field of investigation in human
aspects—is a central challenge for contemporary sciences, the cultural meanings, beliefs, and val-
psychology. In order to deal with this complex chal- ues expressed by media. Through advertisements,
lenge it is necessary to find some general mechanism. television programs, magazines, journals, etc., the
From cultural psychology framework, this general hegemonic cultural meanings related to feminin-
mechanism is found in semiotic mediation (Vygotsky, ity, masculinity, and sexuality are continuously (re)
1978/1991). appearing. According to the analyses carried out
In order to avoid any linguistic reductionism, by Sabat (2001), media presents, in its majority,
it is central to recognize that our relating with the images and texts that reinforce a stereotypic view
world is not just a rational enterprise mediated by of gender.

594 belongi ng to g e nde r


For example, in an essay about the content of Therefore, the arts involve diverse social tech-
masculine magazines, Nogueira (1986) analyzes niques of feelings that promote new levels of cul-
the image of man expressed in these magazines: tural mediation of affective and emotional processes,
a “victorious man,” rich, surrounded by beautiful integrated with cognitive processes. In other words,
women, without existential problems and sadness. the artistic objects are cultural artifacts that medi-
“Words as glory, successful, and power are the most ate, especially, human feelings and emotions. Thus,
found [in these magazines] . . .” (Nogueira, 1986, we can say that the artistic object is a cultural artifact
p. 61). We can even conclude that the anguish and produced to the creation of aesthetic experiences, to the
sadness would be the marks of “losers,” men who contemplation. The artistic object would correspond to
were at fault concerning the project of a success- feelings incarnate in forms (A. Rosa, personal com-
ful masculinity, men who are closer to women, munication, 2008). It is important to stress that in
and their “emotional problems” and “unnecessary order to contemplate, for example, a painting, it
affective and relational demands.” After all, from is necessary to have a cultural education of vision
the images and texts presented in these masculine that involves cognitive and affective aspects, as well
magazines, happiness could be translated as: having aspects related to the knowledge actively internal-
a lot of money, expensive cars, beautiful and sen- ized by the person along his/her life. The interpreta-
sual women. Therefore, the “masculine happiness” tion of a painting, as a cultural artifact, demands an
would correspond to the possession of socially val- elaborate process of apprenticeship that orients our
ued “power signs,” including beautiful and sensual look (Franz, 2003). After all, images are signs to be
women, according to the models of masculine desire interpreted (Lonchuk & Rosa, 2008).
stimulated by these magazines. The colors, shapes, and composition of a paint-
As previously discussed, the feelings of belonging ing bring in itself some social conventions that are
to gender are directly related to the identity pro- culturally and historically situated. Moreover, it is
cesses, to symbolic boundaries that delimit who per- important to not forget that there is “. . . a narrow
tains to the group of “men” and who pertains to the connection between vision and power. The act of
group of “women.” Moreover, inside the boundar- looking—that involves what we select to see and
ies of femininity and masculinity, there are implicit how to see—produces effects on the person, pro-
boundaries that mark who are the “honorable men” duces power relations, many times, in a subtle and
(focus on public life) and who are the “honorable seductive way . . .” (Loponte, 2002, p. 290). In this
women” (focus on private life). When we talk about sense, the use of images can be a fertile tool, in
identity processes (including gender identity), we are analytical and methodological terms, in researches
talking about boundary phenomena. about gender and sexuality issues inserted in broad
It is pertinent to note that arts are a fertile cul- cultural meaning systems, historically constructed.
tural domain to the study, especially, affective and Broad cultural meaning systems are those that sup-
emotional aspects involved in human experience. If port and are supported by power relations that
we promote a closer relation between sciences and permeated all levels of society (Foucault, 1996). In
arts, we will see a fertile (and less explored) ground sum: images as cultural tools (paintings, photographs,
that integrates cultural and affective aspects in drawings, etc.) can be used as an insightful method-
inquiries on theoretical and socially relevant issues. ological resource in empirical researches on diverse
Concerning the articulation between sciences and subjects, like identity processes, personal values, and
arts, Del Río and Álvarez stress the importance of prejudices.
the broad formation of Vygotsky—his intellectual
and humanistic formation, his scientific formation Images as Methodological Resources
allied with his artistic sensibility—in the establish- in Psychology: An Example
ment of the double challenge faced by Vygotsky Historical images can be an interesting method-
along his life: “. . . reach an objective knowledge ological resource in empirical researches on iden-
about human beings without resigning its subjec- tity processes. In this direction, we can mention
tive knowledge. Or vice-versa . . .” (2007, p. 11). the PhD studies carried out by María Fernanda
Vygotsky proposed as a central idea of psychology González (Carretero & González, 2006; González,
of art “ . . . the recognizing of the overcoming of 2005). This research focused on the construction
material by artistic form . . . the recognizing of art as of national identities from a sample formed by
social technique of feeling . . .” (1970/2007, p. 160). participants of different ages and from different

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 595


countries: Argentina (n=80), Chile (n=80), and identity processes. In other words, the actuations of
Spain (n=80). identification (Rosa & Blanco, 2007) are not ori-
The author used, as a methodological resource, a ented by cognitive processes alone. The emotions,
historical image: a drawing by Theodore de Bry called feelings, ambiguities, and conflicts are presented at
“Disembarkation of Columbus in Guanahani,” one time to choose the social groups for whom we
included in the work “The Great Voyages.” It was have sympathy and the social groups with whom
one of the first works with illustrations about the we identify ourselves. The sympathy concerning
colonization of America by Catholic and Protestant marginalized groups does not imply, necessarily,
countries. From the size of this work (13 volumes personal identification with them. Surely, there are
edited between 1590 and 1634) and its broad div- deep connections between identity processes and
ulgation, this work corresponds to an “iconographic power relations. Connections that also foment prej-
invention” of America (Bucher, as cited in González, udices concerning some groups present in our soci-
2005). The historical image selected was the base for eties. There are implicit connections between: (a)
the interviews with the participants. The interviews the inequalities among different social groups, in a
were analyzed from a quantitative approach (statis- macrosocial level of analysis; and (b) discriminatory
tical analysis) and qualitative approach. practices and the reproduction of psychological suf-
It is interesting to note that historical images fering, in interpsychological and intrapsychological
tend to rouse some “affective looks” (in the original: levels of analysis (Madureira, 2007a).
“miradas afectivas”). As González (2005, p. 106)
claims: “In this way, we can sustain that historical Images as Methodological Resources
images produce and convoke some affective looks in Psychology: Other Possibilities
that are linked with the definition of who we are, In researches on identity processes, personal val-
where we are pertained, who is part of our group ues, and prejudices it is necessary to construct ana-
and who is not . . .”. Historical images, such as the lytical strategies to interpret cultural, affective, and
drawing by Theodore de Bry, can be promising cognitive aspects—all of them. Therefore, we are
methodological resources in the studies on affective in front of a challenge: create new methodological
aspects concerning identity processes. resources in order to find meaningful clues concern-
More precisely, the analysis of affective aspects ing the subjects under scrutiny. This is an invitation
concerning the construction of national identities to our analytical and methodological imagination.
among the participants from Argentina, Chile, and After all, as Alves (1993, p. 39) claims: “. . . the sci-
Spain disclosed interesting issues. For example, it entist is a hunter of the invisible.”
was asked for the participants that choose one group It is possible, for example, to construct two
between the two groups that appeared in the image images: (a) one image formed by different photos
(Natives and Spanish people) that they have more of men (different social classes, ethnicities, ages,
sympathy, and choose the group that they identify and so on); and (b) one image formed by different
themselves with, they fell closer, resembling. Beyond photos of women (different social classes, ethnici-
that, participants were asked to justify their choice. ties, ages, and so on). Then, these images could be
The results showed that: used in inquiries about the construction of gender
identities and their connections within other social
. . . The image of the Pacific native, innocent, linked
identities from questions like: (a) Who do you like
to earth and his/her traditions; selvage and backward,
to be? Why? (b) Who do you not like to be? Why?
but respectful concerning his/her surroundings,
It is also possible to investigate the interfaces
convokes sympathy of the majority of participants.
between religious values, political ideology,8 and
However, at time to seek references about identity
gender issues from a different version of the famous
the references related to European and Hispanic
religious image of The Last Supper, with Marilyn
cultural heritage are stronger, in this way 48% of
Monroe at the center—at the position of Jesus
sample is situated in this crossroad: sympathize
Christ—and actors of Hollywood at the right and at
with somebody [Natives] and identify with
the left of the image—at the position of the apostles
another [Spanish people].
(see Fig. 26.2).
(González, 2005, p. 143)
After the presentation of this image (see Fig. 26.2),
This result is meaningful because it demonstrates it would be interesting to ask: (a) What do you see
clearly the presence of ambiguity and conflicts in in this image? (How the participant describes this

596 belongi ng to g e nde r


Figure 26.2 Photo of one version of The Last
Supper, with Marilyn Monroe at the center
(Image on display in a café, close to a movie
theater in Madrid, Spain).

image); (b) Do you like this image (or not)? Why? important to notice that without a serious political
(How the participant values this image—in terms analysis about gender issues: (a) in theoretical terms,
of positively, neutrally, or negatively valued). In we tend to develop a naïve approach and reinforce
research on gender and sexuality issues, it is impor- conceptions based on a biological determinism; and
tant to investigate religious values of the participants (b) in practical terms, we lose a fertile opportunity
(Madureira, 2007a), and how these values orient to contribute, in different ways, with the elabora-
their views about the feminine, the masculine, and tion of concrete strategies against social inequalities.
about sexuality. The knowledge produced from our theoretical and
Figure 26.2 presents a possibility, among oth- empirical researches can contribute to public poli-
ers, to focus on participants’ religious values at the cies in order to promote gender equality in different
beginning of an investigation about identity pro- domains of our societies.
cesses (especially about gender identities) in a more The studies of social identities (gender identi-
fertile way than asking direct questions about the ties, sexual identities, ethnic identities, etc.) are a
religion of participants. Beyond that, it is possible promising field to understand the complex con-
to analyze the motives why a participant may like nections between individuals and social groups.
or dislike the image presented. Thus, the valued Therefore, in terms of future theoretical develop-
dimension implicit in identity processes is also con- ment, the present author suggests the construction
templated. Surely, this is just one methodological of “conceptual bridges” between social-identity
suggestion; there are many other possibilities. The approaches and dialogical self-theory (Ferreira,
most important is: the creation of fertile methodologi- Salgado, & Cunha, 2006; Hermans, 2001; Rosa,
cal ways to properly investigate the phenomena in focus Duarte, & Gonçalves, 2008). As a cultural con-
in our researches. textualized theoretical model of self, dialogical
self-theory can provide insightful conceptual tools
General Conclusion to better understand the development of the self-
“A scientist without imagination is like a bird system in its psychological and sociological dimen-
without wings.” sions. Both of these dimensions are also essential
(Alves, 1993, p. 43) in the construction of social identities. From the
tension between the particular and the general, we
Throughout this chapter, I focused on the
are in front of a relevant challenge: improving our
construction of gender identities, as a boundary
capacity to consistently integrate different levels
phenomenon, with special attention regarding the
of analysis regarding the development of the self-
interfaces between gender and sexuality issues within
system and social identities.
a cultural psychology framework. The feelings of
belonging to a specific gender are constructed from
the beliefs, values, practices, stereotypes, and preju- Future Direction
dices that culturally delimit the symbolic bound- Concerning the theoretical implications of the
aries between femininity and masculinity. It is inquiry in focus, it is important to mention the

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 597


relevance of future researches on how the cultural the fertile discussions about social imaginary and images in
meanings concerning gender and sexuality are psychology.
integrated in broader cultural meaning systems,
historically constructed. In a metaphorical sense, Notes
meanings are not “linguistics atoms” that can be 1. In an etymologic sense, the word “iconography” is derived
from the Greek “eikon” (image) and “graphia” (description). See:
properly analyzed in an isolated way (Madureira,
http://www.etymonline.com/. This site was visited 01/20/2010.
2007a). Instead, if we intend to improve our 2. Umberto Eco is Professor of Semiotics at the University
understanding concerning the multiple connec- of Bologna in Italy. His first works focused on medieval aes-
tions of cultural meanings about gender and sexu- thetics, especially in the works of Thomas Aquinas (thirteenth
ality, we should investigate them from a systemic century). The Name of the Rose, published firstly in 1980, was
his first novel.
approach.
3. “. . . Eco’s celebrated story combines elements of detec-
These multiple connections are inserted in the tive fiction, metaphysical thriller, postmodernist puzzle and
context of broader meaning systems marked by the historical novel in one of the few twentieth-century books that
tension between stability and change. This tension can be described as genuinely unique. Set in Italy in the Middle
has always been present in the cultural develop- Ages, this is not only a narrative of a murder investigation in
a monastery in 1327, but also a chronicle of the fourteenth-
ment of societies throughout history (Madureira
century religious wars, a history of monastic orders, and a com-
& Branco, 2005a). The continuous construction pendium of heretical movements.” See: http://www.umbertoeco.
and reconstruction of cultural meanings is con- com/en/the-name-of-the-rose-1983.html. This site was visited
nected within hierarchical structures of power 01/19/2010.
between different social groups present in any 4. “. . . In fact, concerning the medieval Christianity, the
notion of “image” seems to be a singular fertility notion even
society. These hierarchical structures have histori-
that we understand little every senses related to the Latin term
cal roots that should not be disregarded by cultural imago. This notion is, with effect, in the center of medieval con-
psychology. ception of world and man . . . . The notion of image is concerned,
There are diverse methodological ways to inves- in short, to Christian anthropology as a whole, because is the
tigate meaning-making processes regarding the con- man . . . that the Bible, since its first words, qualify as “image”:
Yahweh says that make the man ‘ad imaginem et similitudinem
struction of different social identities. Therefore,
nostram’ (Gênesis 1:26). “ (Schmitt, 2002, p. 592–593).
the use of images, as methodological resources, is 5. See: http://arteuniversal.wordpress.com/2010/06/16/
just one possibility that seems fertile. The most bosch-hieronymus/bosch-hieronymus-the-garden-of-earthly-
important is to constantly feed our methodologi- delights-triptych/. This site was visited 08/15/2010.
cal imagination in order to construct creative ways 6. Stereotype is a “belief about the personal characteristics of
a group of people. Stereotypes can be super generalized, impre-
to investigate the phenomena under focus in our
cise and resistant to new information.” (Myers, 1995, p. 346).
researches. Sometimes, we find interesting clues The stereotypes are not prejudices, but they can work as a base
to do that in our everyday life: in the architectural to development of prejudices (Myers, 1995). On the one hand,
constructions on the street, in famous paintings, in the stereotypes offer a base, even super generalized, to the future
anonymous images in books, cafes, bars, and so on. development of a deeper understanding about individuals of a
specific social group. On the other hand, the stereotypes can
At the most ordinary places and moments, we feed
promote prejudices especially when [they] ‘close the doors’ to
our imagination. the appropriation of new knowledge that contradict[s] what the
stereotypes inform about the social group in focus (Madureira,
Acknowledgments 2009a, 2009b).
I want to thank the National Committee for Scientific and 7. New technologies of images have been developing faster
Technological Development—CNPq (Brazil) for the finan- nowadays. The new generations already born in a world with
cial support of my PhD studies, including the period that I computers, Internet, sophisticated video games, and other tech-
was Visiting Student of the Psychology Department at Clark nologies. At the end of nineteenth century, cinema appeared
University in Worcester, MA (USA). I also want to thank the (images in movement). In modern times, the accomplishment
National Committee for Academic Support—CAPES (Brazil) of 3D movies has been stimulated by the success of the creative
for the financial support of my postdoctorate at Universidad movie Avatar. It is not an exaggeration to affirm that we are living
Autónoma de Madrid (Spain). This chapter brought some a “true invasion of images” in our daily life. Psychology should
contributions from both my PhD and postdoctorate studies. I not ignore this aspect of our contemporary societies.
am grateful to Prof. Dr. Angela Branco (University of Brasília, 8. In Latin America countries, because of the cultural coloni-
Brazil), Prof. Dr. Jaan Valsiner (Clark University, USA) and Prof. zation by the United States since the second half of the twentieth
Dr. Alberto Rosa (Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Spain) century, there are social groups, especially groups that identify
for their important theoretical contributions and for their rele- themselves with the left political ideology, that cultivate a mis-
vant role in my academic trajectory. I also thank Juliana Garcia trustful attitude regarding the movies produced by Hollywood.
Pacheco (PhD in Psychology, University of Brasília, Brazil) for In this sense, cultural products, like movies, can be an interesting

598 belongi ng to g e nde r


methodological resource to investigate political ideology and its González, M. F. (2005). Representationes de narrativas e imágenes
relationship to personal values. históricas en la construcvión de la identidad nacional: Un estu-
dio comparativo entre Argentina, Chile y España. Resumen
de la Tesis Doctoral. Universidad Autónoma de Madrid,
References Madrid, España.
Alves, R. (1993). Filosofia da Ciência: Introdução ao jogo e suas Hermans, H. J. M. (2001). The dialogical self: Towards a theory
regras. São Paulo: Brasiliense. of personal and cultural positioning. Culture & Psychology,
Andersen, M. L. (2000). Thinking about women: Sociological per- 7(3), 243–282.
spectives on sex and gender. Needham Heights, MA: Allyn and Joerchel, A. C. (2007). A dance between the general and the spe-
Bacon. cific: Implications for the self concept. Integrative Psychological
Araiza, A., & Gisbert, G. (2007). Transformaciones del cuerpo en & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 254–261.
psicología social. Psicologia: Teoria e Pesquisa, 23(1), 111–117. Kim, S. (2007). Gatekeeping and homophobia: From bouncers in
Barcinski, M. (2008). The identity construction process of a bars to the macro-social, interpersonal, and intrapsychological
woman involved in drug trafficking: A systemic approach. practices of homophobia. Integrative Psychological &
In S. Salvatore, J. Valsiner, S. Strout-Yagodzynski, & J. Clegg Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 303–307.
(Eds.), Yearbook of Idiographic Science (pp. 107–134). Rome: Laqueur, T. (2001). Inventando o sexo: Corpo e gênero dos gregos a
Firera & Liuzzo Group. Freud. Rio de Janeiro: Relume Dumará.
Blackwood, E. (2000). Culture and women’s sexualities. Journal Le Breton, D. (1992/2007). A sociologia do corpo. Petrópolis, RJ,
of Social Issues, 56(2), 223–238. Brasil: Vozes.
Bourdieu, P. (2005). A dominação masculina. Rio de Janeiro: Le Goff, J., & Schmitt, J. C. (1999/2002). Prefácio. Em J. Le
Bertrand Brasil. Goff & J. C. Schmitt (Eds.), Dicionário temático do ocidente
Branco, A. M., Branco, A. L., & Madureira, A. F. A. (2008). Self- medieval (Volume I) (pp. 11–18). Bauru, SP: EDUSC / São
development and the emergence of new I-positions: Emotions Paulo, SP: Imprensa Oficial do Estado.
and self-dynamics. Studia Psychologica (Bratislava), 8, 23–40. León, P. G. P. (2006). Breve historia de la pintura. Madrid:
Branco, A. M., & Madureira, A. F. A. (2008) Dialogical Self Editorial LIBSA.
in action: The emergence of self-positions among complex Lionço, T., & Diniz, D. (2009). Homofobia, silêncio e natural-
emotional and cultural dimensions. Estudios de Psicología, 29, ização: Por uma narrativa da diversidade sexual. In T. Lionço
319–332. & D. Diniz (Eds.), Homofobia & educação: Um desafio ao
Carretero, M. & González, M. F. (2006). Representaciones y silêncio (pp. 47–71). Brasília: LetrasLivres / Editora da
valoración del “Descubrimiento” de América en adolescentes Universidade de Brasília.
y jóvenes de Argentina, Chile y España. In M. Carretero, Lonchuk, M., & Rosa, A. (2008, September). Graphic images
A. Rosa, & F. González (Eds.), Enseñanza de la Historia y as semiotic means for moral action. Paper presented at 2nd
Memoria Colectiva (pp. 115–145). Buenos Aires: Paidós. ISCAR Congress. San Diego, CA.
Charles, V., Manca, J., McShane, M., & Wigal, D. (2007). 1000 Loponte, L. G. (2002). Sexualidades, artes visuais e poder:
obras-primas da pintura. São Paulo: Martins Fontes. Pedagogias visuais do feminino. Estudos Feministas, 7(2),
Chauí, M. (1995). Convite à filosofia. São Paulo: Ática. 283–300.
Costa, J. F. (1996). O referente da identidade homossexual. In Louro, G. L. (1998). Gênero, sexualidade e educação: Uma per-
R. Parker & R.M. Barbosa (Eds.), Sexualidades brasileiras spectiva pós-estruturalista. Petrópolis, RJ, Brasil: Vozes.
(pp. 63–89). Rio de Janeiro: Relume Dumará. Louro, G. L. (1999). Pedagogias da sexualidade. In G. L. Louro
Dall’Ava-Santucci, J. (2005). Mulheres e médicas: As pioneiras da (Ed.), O corpo educado: Pedagogias da sexualidade (pp. 9–34).
medicina. Rio de Janeiro: Ediouro. Belo Horizonte, Brasil: Autêntica.
Del Río, P., & Álvarez, A. (2007). La psicología del arte en la psi- Louro, G. L. (2003). Currículo, gênero e sexualidade: O
cología de Vygotski. In L. S. Vygotski, La tragedia de Hamlet “normal”, o “diferente”e o “excêntrico”. In G. L. Louro,
& psicología del arte (pp. 7–38). Madrid: Fundación Infancia J. F. Neckel, & S. V. Goellner (Eds.), Corpo, gênero e sexu-
y Aprendizaje. alidade: Um debate contemporâneo na educação (pp. 41–52).
Delumeau, J. (1990). Sin and fear: The emergence of a Western guilt Petrópolis, RJ, Brasil: Vozes.
culture 13th–18th centuries. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Madureira, A. F. A. (2000). A construção das identidades sexuais
Dixon, L. (2003). Bosch. London: Phaidon. não-hegemônicas: gênero, linguagem e constituição da subje-
Eco, U. (1983). O nome da rosa. Rio de Janeiro: Nova Fronteira. tividade. (Dissertação de Mestrado). Instituto de Psicologia,
Ferreira, T., Salgado, J., & Cunha, C. (2006). Ambiguity and Universidade de Brasília, Brasília.
the dialogical self: In search for a dialogical self. Estudios de Madureira, A. F. A. (2007a). Gênero, sexualidade e diversidade
Psicología, 27(1), 19–32. na escola: a construção de uma cultura democrática. (Tese
Foucault, M. (1996). Microfísica do poder. Rio de Janeiro: Graal. de Doutorado). Instituto de Psicologia, Universidade de
Franz, T. S. (2003). Educação para uma compreensão crítica da Brasília, Brasília.
arte. Florianópolis: Letras Contemporâneas. Madureira, A. F. A. (2007b). The psychological basis of
Golombok, S., & Fivush, R. (1994). Gender development. New homophobia: Cultural construction of a barrier. Integrative
York: Cambridge University Press. Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 225–247.
Gomes, J. N. (2009). Reflexões sobre o desejo e a ideologia na Madureira, A. F. A. (2007c). Homophobia as a boundary
misoginia medieval. Aedos, 2(2), 261–267. phenomenon: The dynamic dance between different
González-Lopes, G. (2005). Erotic journeys: Mexican immigrants tensions. Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science,
and their sex lives. CA University of California. 41(3–4), 326–342.

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 599


Madureira, A. F. A. (2007d). The self-control ethos as a mech- Rosa, A., Bellelli, G., & Bakhurst, D. (2000). Representaciones
anism of social exclusion in western societies. Culture & del pasado, cultura personal e identidad nacional. In A. Rosa,
Psychology, 13(4), 419–430. G. Bellelli, & D. Bakhurst (Eds.), Memoria colectiva e identi-
Madureira, A. F. A. (2008). Invisible boundaries with con- dad nacional (pp. 41–87). Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva.
crete implications: Meaning-making processes and Rosa, A., & Blanco, F. (2007). Actuations of identification in the
symbolic boundaries. In S. Salvatore, J. Valsiner J., S. Strout- games of identity. Social Practice / Psychological Theorizing.
Yagodzynski, & J. Clegg (Eds.), Yearbook of idiographic sci- Retrieved from http://www.sppt-gulerce.boun.edu.tr/.
ence (pp. 233–248). Rome: Giorgio Fireira. Rosa, C., Duarte, F., & Gonçalves, M. (2008). Self and dialogical
Madureira, A. F. A. (2009a). Social identities, prejudices and articulation of multivocality: Proposal of an analysis model.
symbolic boundaries: Contributions from sociocultural psy- In S. Salvatore, J. Valsiner, S. Strout-Yagodzynski, & J. Clegg
chology. In E. P. Lamont (Ed.), Social psychology: New research (Eds.), Yearbook of idiographic science (pp. 163–189). Rome:
(pp. 81–104). New York: Nova Science Publishers. Firera & Liuzzo Group.
Madureira, A. F. A. (2009b). When stereotypes become “scien- Sabat, R. (2001). Pedagogia cultural, gênero e sexualidade.
tific” statements: Dealing with gender. Integrative Psychological Estudos Feministas, 9(1), 9–21.
& Behavioral Science, 43, 138–148. Schmitt, J. C. (1999/2002). Imagens. In J. L. Goff &
Madureira, A. F. A., & Branco, A. U. (2004). Coconstruction of J. C. Schmitt (Eds.), Dicionário temático do ocidente medieval
gender identity in social interactions: The role of communi- (Volume I) (pp. 591–605). Bauru, SP: EDUSC / São Paulo, SP:
cation and metacommunication processes. In A.U. Branco Imprensa Oficial do Estado.
& J. Valsiner (Eds.), Communication and metacommunica- Scott, J. (1995). Gênero: Uma categoria útil de análise histórica.
tion in human development (pp. 151–189). Greenwich, CT: Educação & Realidade, 20(2), 71–99.
Information Age Publishing. Segato, R. L. (2003). Las estructuras elementales de la violencia:
Madureira, A. F. A., & Branco, A. U. (2005a). Construindo com o Ensayos sobre género entre la antropología, el psicoanálisis y los
outro: Uma perspectiva sociocultural construtivista do desen- derechos humanos. Buenos Aires: Universidad Nacional de
volvimento humano. In M. A. Dessen & A. L. Costa Júnior Quilmas.
(Eds.), A ciência do desenvolvimento humano: Tendências atuais Silva, T. T. (2000). A produção social da identidade e da diferença.
e perspectivas futuras (pp. 90–109). Porto Alegre, RS, Brasil: In T. T. Silva (Ed.), Identidade e diferença: A perspectiva dos estu-
Artes Médicas. dos culturais (pp. 73–102). Petrópolis, RJ, Brasil: Vozes.
Madureira, A. F. A., & Branco, A. U. (2005b). A noção de sujeito Sim, S. (2004). Fundamentalist world: The new dark age of dogma.
na ciência psicológica: Linguagem e constituição da subjetiv- Cambridge, UK: Icon Books.
idade em discussão. In F. González Rey (Ed.), Subjetividade, Strickland, C. (1999). Arte comentada: Da pré-história ao pós-
complexidade e pesquisa em psicologia (pp. 127–153). São moderno. Rio de Janeiro: Ediouro.
Paulo: Pioneira Tomson Learning. Torviso, I. B., & Marías, F. (1982). Bosch: Realidad, símbolo y
Madureira, A. F. A., & Branco, A. U. (2007). Identidades sexuais fantasía. Madrid: Silex.
não-hegemônicas: Processos identitários e estratégias para Vainfas, R. (1992). Casamento, amor e desejo no ocidente cristão.
lidar com o preconceito. Psicologia: Teoria e Pesquisa, 23(1), São Paulo: Ática.
81–90. Valsiner, J. (2003). Sensuality and sense: Cultural construction
Marcondes, D. (2000). Iniciação à história da filosofia: Dos pré- of the human nature. Human Affairs, 13, 151–162.
socráticos a Wittgenstein. Rio de Janeiro: Jorge Zahar. Valsiner, J. (2005). Affektive Entwicklung im kulturellen
Myers, D. G. (1995). Psicología Social. México: McGraw-Hill. Kontext [Affective Development in Cultural Context].
Nogueira, R. (1986). Revistas masculinas ou de macho? In In J. B. Asendorpf (Ed.), Enzyklopädie der psychologie
Macho, masculino, homem: a sexualidade, o machismo e a crise (Vol. 3). Soziale, emotionale und persönlichkeitsentwicklung
de identidade do homem brasileiro (pp. 61–63). Porto Alegre/ (pp. 677–728). Göttingen: Hogrefe.
São Paulo: L&PM. Valsiner, J. (2007a). Culture in minds and societies: Foundations of
Oliveira, P. P. (1998). Discursos sobre a masculinidade. Estudos cultural psychology. New Delhi: Sage.
Feministas, 6(1), 91–111. Valsiner, J. (2007b). Looking across cultural boundaries. Integrative
Parker, R. (1991). Corpos, prazeres e paixões: A cultura sexual no Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4), 219–224.
Brasil contemporâneo. São Paulo: Editora Best Seller. Valsiner, J. (2009). Integrating psychology within the globaliz-
Pratas, G. M. D. L. (2009). O feminino na arte medieval. ing world: A requiem to the post-modernist experiment with
Mandrágora, 15(15), 117–124. Wissenschaft. Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science,
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. 43(1), 1–21.
New York: University Press. Valsiner, J., & Rosa, A. (2007). Editors’ Introduction:
Rosa, A. (2007a). Acts of psyche: Actuations as synthesis of semio- Contemporary socio-cultural research: Uniting culture,
sis and action. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge society and psychology. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), The
handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 205–237). New York: Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 1–20).
Cambridge University Press. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rosa, A. (2007b). Dramaturgical actuations and symbolic com- Vygotsky, L. S. (1978/1991). A formação social da mente: O
munication: Or how beliefs make up reality. In J. Valsiner desenvolvimento dos processos psicológicos superiores. São Paulo:
& A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural Martins Fontes.
psychology (pp. 293–317). New York: Cambridge University Vygotski, L. S. (1970/2007). La tragedia de Hamlet & psicología
Press. del arte. Madrid: Fundación Infancia y Aprendizaje.

600 belongi ng to g e nde r


Watzlawik, M. S. (2009). When a man thinks he has perspectiva dos estudos culturais (pp. 7–72). Petrópolis, RJ,
female traits—Constructing femininity and masculin- Brasil: Vozes.
ity: Methodological potentials and limitations. Integrative Zuber, C. K. (1999/2002). Masculino / feminino. In J. L. Goff
Psychological & Behavioral Science, 43. & J. C. Schmitt (Eds..), Dicionário temático do ocidente medi-
Welzer-Lang, D. (2001). A construção do masculino: Dominação eval (Volume II) (pp. 137–150). Bauru, SP: EDUSC / São
das mulheres e homofobia. Estudos Feministas, 9(2), 460–482. Paulo, SP: Imprensa Oficial do Estado.
Woodward, K. (2000). Identidade e diferença: Uma introdução
conceitual. In T. T. Silva (Ed.), Identidade e diferença: A

an a fl ávia do a m a ra l m a du reira 601


CHAPTER

Risk and Culture


27
Bob Heyman

Abstract
This chapter explores the interrelationships between risk and culture with particular reference to ‘late-
modern’ societies. In such societies, the benefits of technological progress are no longer taken routinely
for granted, and the human predicament is understood in relation to the ‘lens of risk’. The chapter homes
in on the taken-for-granted presuppositions which underpin this interpretive framework. Following a brief
mapping of leading social scientific risk theories, the chapter will address still neglected definitional issues.
Risk-thinking will be considered as a specific way of constructing contingency; and contingency thinking
as derivative from a universal human tendency to view events in relation to the potential infinity of what
might happen. The unlimited scope of possibility will be contrasted with the necessary cultural selection
of a small number of contingencies, viewed mostly as risks in late-modern societies, which become
objects of organized concern. The lens of risk will then be unpacked by recasting each of the elements in
a standard definition of risk (The Royal Society, 1992, with present author’s additions in parentheses) as:
the probability (3) that a particular adverse (2) event (1) occurs during a stated period of time (4a),
or results from a particular challenge (4b).
Each numbered element will be reframed in order to bring out its concealed interpretive underpinnings:
events as categories; adversity as negative valuing; probabilities as rule-of-thumb derived expectations; and
‘stated’ time periods as time frames (indefinite and therefore incalculable in the case of condition 4b). It will
be argued that societies and social groups must attempt to align their interpretations of the above elements
in order to make organized risk management possible. It will be further argued that this interpretive work
tends to be pushed to the background of social consciousness through a tacit process of ‘deletion.’ Without
such unspoken but collective direction of attention away from the indefinitely large set of what might
happen, social orders organized around selective attention to particular risks could not be sustained.
Keywords: probability, risk, culture, interpretation, escalation

Anthropological observations of the warning this bizarre yet taken-for-granted world. Readers are
signs which festoon the environments of full-blown invited to guess the location of the signs reproduced
risk cultures provide an instructive introduction to in Figure 27.1, below.

WARNING CAUTION

This Facility Contains This toilet is fitted


Chemicals Known to with a random
the State of California jack-in-the-box
to Cause Cancer and cleansing system
Birth Defects or Other
Reproductive Harm.

Figure 27.1 The weird and wonderful world of risk and its linguistic relatives.

602
The left sign (in tasteful pale blue) guards attention below. The term culture will be defined
the entrance to one of the apparently most dan- more cursorily as:
gerous places in the world—an up-market San
the set of shared attitudes, values, goals, and practices
Francisco hotel! Its purpose is clearly to fend off
that characterizes an institution, organization or group.
potential litigation, rather than to warn individu-
(Wikipedia, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/culture)
als considering entry about consequential risks. In
contrast, the third sign (in harsh yellow, nature’s The chapter will home in on one critical form
danger signal) was placed on a building site for an of this wide-ranging and ubiquitous phenomenon,
office block being erected in the City of London namely the shared but unspoken presuppositions
prior to the financial crash of 2007. It may well on which risk perceptions are unavoidably predi-
have been designed to discourage entry to a loca- cated. Unarticulated assumptions provide the bur-
tion which contained a large amount of expensive ied, although by no means secure, foundations on
machinery. The middle sign could be observed in which the vast edifices of cultures are built. They
toilets on London to Brighton trains in 2009. Its can be uncovered fairly easily, but only if attention
pragmatic purpose is hard to fathom. But this sign is directed away from concrete cultural products
shows up the esoteric nature of risk microcultures, and received problematics, toward the barely con-
since nobody appeared to have considered the sign’s cealed collective mental processes which underlie
impact on users of the facility in question! The three their creation, maintenance, and dissolution. The
signs also illustrate a small part of the rich linguistic material which follows will address these processes
family, of warnings, dangers, hazards, vulnerabili- after a brief context-setting foray into social scien-
ties, alarms etc., in which risk-thinking is embedded tific theories of risk.
(Heyman et al., 2010, pp. 25–28). All are oriented
in implicitly different ways toward possibilities of Social Scientific Theories of Risk:
unwanted events, and convey unstated attitudes, A Brief Introduction
for instance that hazardous environments should Major social scientific theories of risk offer dis-
be made safe, or that vulnerable persons ought to tinctive, although not necessarily incompatible,
be protected. Such lexical choices are used pragmat- analyses of why risk concerns have taken centre
ically, albeit unreflectively, in attempts to influence stage in contemporary developed societies. Despite
decision-making, rather than to merely describe their differences, these theories all point to com-
contingencies. plex organizational processes which the authors
The present chapter will analyze the relationship consider to be unrecognized by social actors who
between risk and culture, focusing on late-modern focus on particular risks. By way of background to
developed societies in which contested issues of risk the analysis offered in the present chapter, thumb-
affect every sphere of organized life (Beck, 1992, nail sketches of four such approaches are offered
2009). It will be argued that this pervasive risk con- below. For full accounts of risk society, cultural,
sciousness stands out historically and culturally from systems theory, and governmentality theories, see
a much more general human concern with contin- Zinn (2008).
gency (i.e. selective, symbolically mediated concern One variant, at least, of Beck’s risk society thesis
with what might, and by extension, what might (Beck, 1992; 2009) anticipates that:
not happen). The present preoccupation with risk is
in its mere continuity industrial society exits the stage of
bound up with one particular approach to contin-
world history on the tip-toes of normality, via the back
gency which draws on probabilistic reasoning and
stairs of side effects.
the metaphor of randomness. It is found primarily
(Beck, 1992, p. 11)
in rich, science-based countries whose citizens can
afford to invest the required resources into precau- This vision of history sees developed societies
tion (Bujra, 2000). gradually undermined by the cumulative force of the
The author cannot offer anthropological exper- interacting, unintended consequences of technolog-
tise, a more general shortcoming of the risk social ical development. The striking quotation suggests
science literature (Caplan, 2000), but the chap- that accumulating ecological risks are backgrounded
ter will address risk from a cultural perspective. until they can no longer be ignored. Their pressure
The definition of risk will be given considerable stimulates a transformation from modernity to late

h eym a n 603
modernity in which the benefits of technological themselves voluntarily in designated higher risk
‘progress’ become contested. categories such as obesity or illicit drug-taking, and
Cultural theory, as developed by Douglas to be morally accountable for officially disapproved
and colleagues (Douglas, 1966, 1992; Douglas ‘choices’.
& Wildavsky, 1983), equates risks with dangers, The above brief sketch will hopefully give read-
and views their collective selection as serving the ers unfamiliar with risk social science a sense of the
function of buttressing structural weaknesses of a diverse ways in which the relationship between risk
particular culture such as internal contradictions and culture has been theorized. Conjointly, the
and unclear external boundaries. Although most four outlined approaches outlined can be used to
apparent in small, undifferentiated and there- construct a gloomy picture of near future risks for
fore fragile ‘primitive’ societies, this analysis can the prevailing science-based civilization and the
be applied to late-modern hang-ups, for example billions of human beings who rely on it. In this
in relation to hostility toward immigrants, and envisaged future, the combined impact of runaway
panic about mentally disordered violent offend- global warming and resource depletion overwhelms
ers and paedophiles. In contrast, risks which cause increasingly complex, interdependent and therefore
far greater total harm, such as those arising from fragile socio-economic systems. At the same time,
traffic pollution and accidents, tend to be calmly raw cultural sensitivities, competition between
accepted because they do not challenge the under- nation states and the prevailing neo-liberalism pre-
lying cultural order. clude effective prophylaxis.
Risk systems theory accounts for heightened soci- Some such hefty social scientific machinery is
etal risk consciousness as an unintended and unrec- required to explain the yawning contrast between
ognized consequence of the ever-increasing role the vast resources spent fighting the ‘war on ter-
differentiation which results from societies becom- ror’ and the feeble global response to the loom-
ing progressively more and more complex, special- ing catastrophe of human-induced climate change
ized, and interdependent (Luhmann, 1993; Japp combined with unmanageable resource depletion.
& Kusche, 2008). Each subsystem creates its own The risk of human activity causing catastrophic
primary risk ‘object’ (e.g., loss of profit or patient climate change has been much debated. Resource
safety failures), while decentring from those of oth- depletion has received less media attention. With
ers. The consequent multiplicity of risk orienta- respect to peak oil, for instance, according to
tions generates unrealized differences of perspective one senior whistleblower from the International
which make the organized coordination of social Energy Agency, this organization has presented
action more difficult to achieve, and more vulner- unduly optimistic accounts of future supplies
able to breakdown than in less differentiated forms. because the truth would destabilize stock markets
According to this theory, heightened generic sensi- (The Guardian newspaper, November 11, 2009).
tivity to risks in highly developed societies reflects Risk arising from systems complexity is illustrated
the insecurity which arises from the increasing frag- by analysis of the impact of severe solar storms
mentation required to carry an ever-expanding cul- (Marusek, 2007). The event of September 2, 1859
ture by means of indefinitely increasing levels of role caused telegraph systems to collapse, with rela-
specialization. tively trivial consequences. An equivalent event in
Finally, governmentality theory treats risk the twenty-first century could bring about millions
consciousness as a historically novel method of of deaths through the simultaneous destruction of
transmitting social power (O’Malley, 2008). The electricity substations resulting in a lengthy loss of
mechanism for social control becomes internal- usable supplies and ensuing chaos. This example
ized within individual minds through acceptance illustrates the potential for failure of a mundane
of the imperative to manage risks responsibly, for but vital component of complex socio-technical
instance by adopting a healthy lifestyle. This partic- systems to crash an entire civilization. The four
ular form of governmentality carries the concealed processes of runaway global warming, resource
function of promoting a neoliberal social order in depletion, systems failures and political paralysis
which responsibility for avoiding adverse outcomes may feed off each other with devastating conse-
is individualized. Within a Governmentality1 quences. Readers will share this doom-laden con-
framework, individuals are deemed to have placed struction to a greater or lesser extent. What cannot

604 risk and c ult ure


be disputed is that many different possible futures 1998; Heyman et al., 2010). The present chap-
can be targeted for organized attention, the issue ter hones in particularly on the interrelationships
picked up below in relation to the key importance between risk and culture. An adequate account
of contingency visualisation. of these relationships must illuminate both the
As noted above, the four major theories outlined generic existence of risk as a cultural phenome-
above share one common feature despite their dif- non, and the construction and selection of partic-
ferences, namely the identification of key drivers for ular risks such as climate change or terrorism for
risk concerns which are claimed to operate outside organized collective concern.
the awareness of social actors: whether cumulat-
ing side effects of technological development (risk The Definition of ‘Risk’
society theory); structural weaknesses in prevailing A Tendency toward Non-definition
social orders (cultural theory); unintended conse- The idea that risk-thinking now influences
quences of increasing role differentiation (system all life domains in modern developed societies
theory); or the insidious operation of social power has acquired almost platitudinous status in the
in a new form driven by individualized risk con- social science of risk, although its impact on
sciousness (Governmentality theory). Together, public attitudes can sometimes be exaggerated
such work provides a rich and potentially comple- by over-enthusiastic social scientists2. Indeed, it
mentary analysis of concealed societal processes. has become more interesting to comment on the
However, on the whole, social scientific theories do contexts in which risks are apparently ignored, by
not systematically dissect risk thinking itself. Social mountaineers and other (fool)hardy adventurers,
scientists have, perhaps, been more concerned to people ruining their livers with alcohol, or enjoy-
highlight insight deficits than to analyze what peo- ing condomless sex with multiple partners. Such
ple do know, or at least believe, when they think seeming exceptions must all be qualified in vari-
about a risk. ous ways. Mountaineers are expected to take high
risks responsibly, particularly when their actions
Goals for the Rest of the Chapter cause further risks for rescue services (Simon,
The remainder of the present chapter will not 2003). Alcohol and sex are peddled by ruthless
pursue the rich lines of analysis offered by social commercial interests, exposing potential consum-
scientific theories of risk. Instead, the chapter will ers to profoundly conflicting cultural messages.
address the culturally mediated presuppositions Nevertheless, such behaviour appears to stand
which are carried by risk-thinking itself. The anal- out as apparently anomalous in relation to the
ysis will take off from the position that theories assumption of a pervading risk consciousness in
such as those presented above tend to take ‘risk’ late-modern societies.
for granted, and that this lacuna reflects more than The very ubiquity of risk-thinking in modern
a scholarly shortcoming, but derives from a wider cultures challenges definitional efforts. It can be
cultural reflectivity shortfall. A degree of prevail- argued that use of the term has become stretched so
ing collective reticence about defining risk at all far that it has lost much of any definitional purpose
will first be diagnosed and accounted for in terms which it might once have possessed. Garland (2003)
of the ambiguous ‘reality’ of risks. Risk-thinking has eloquently noted that the wide range of substan-
will then be depicted as one historic form of a tive social domains in which risks are considered is
general human tendency to view events as contin- cross-cut by a variety of approaches to risk, which
gent. A definition will be offered which allows risk can be applied in any domain.
to be decomposed into four components—events/
categories, adversity/values, probabilities/uncer- Today’s accounts of risk are remarkable for their
tain expectations, and time periods/time frames, multiplicity and for the variety of senses they give to the
all influenced by cultural interpretive processes. It term. Risk is a calculation. Risk is a commodity. Risk
will be argued that risk differs from other forms is a capital. Risk is a technique of government. Risk is
of contingency thinking only in one respect: the objective and scientifically knowable. Risk is subjective
grounding of uncertain expectation in the meta- and socially constructed. Risk is a problem, a threat, a
phor of randomness. These complex issues been source of insecurity. Risk is a pleasure, a thrill, a source
discussed in more detail elsewhere (Heyman, of profit and freedom. Risk is the means by which we

h eym a n 605
colonize and control the future. ‘Risk society’ is our late widely diverse social contexts, including business,
modern world spinning out of control. insurance, sport, weather, health care, crime pre-
(Garland, 2003, p. 49) vention, child protection, war, and many others.
The above quotations offer a debunking challenge
In this respect, risk may not differ from other to a mindset which connects the multitudinous
widely used symbolic tools which acquire their use- contexts of late-modern life through the notion
fulness because of their plasticity rather than their of risk. An alternative view is that the same term
precision. is used across social domains because it references
Philosophers tell us that nouns are misleading because a shared meaning which can be articulated. From
they suggest that a clear object exists when this is often this starting point, a social scientific failure to
not the case. In the case of ‘risk’ and ‘risk management’ carefully consider what members of modern soci-
we would do well to heed their advice. However, this eties are actually doing when they use the term
book [Organized Uncertainty: Designing a World of ‘risk’ to link together a vast range of organized
Risk Management] takes as its point of departure the activities can be diagnosed. Luhmann (1993)
surely uncontestable fact that the noun has grown in use criticized “carelessness in concept formation”. Rosa
and significance in organizational life. (2003) went further, identifying “an intentional
(Power, 2007, p. 3)
silence about defining risk at all.” Most risk texts
take the meaning of this heavily used term for
Similarly, another major contributor to the granted, as documented by Heyman et al. (2010).
social science of risk, Hansson (2005) dismisses Even a sharp, much-needed contribution to the
as the “first myth of risk”, the idea that risk “must “sparsely populated” field of risk philosophy,
have a single, well-defined meaning”. Althaus (2005) Lewens launches into a discussion of risks with-
has argued persuasively that risk is conceptualized out reflecting on what the term refers to.
differently in a wide range of academic disciplines
Decision-makers of all kinds frequently face
and subdisciplines, including economics, sociol-
situations where they must choose one of several
ogy, anthropology, psychology, medicine, legal
risky options.
studies, the arts, and philosophy. For instance, a
(Lewens, 2007, p. 2)
long-standing line in economics, a discipline which
took on risk much earlier than other social sciences, But what is a risk? And where do menus of “risky
relates risk and uncertainty to entrepreneurship, options” come from? Reticence about the mean-
with the successful entrepreneur ‘beating the odds’ ing of the term ‘risk’ can be detected in the wider
through innovation (Knight, 1921). Medicine, in society as well as among social scientists who have
contrast, seeks to make practice evidence-based in tended to remain immersed in this unreflective
line with empirically derived probabilities, turning conspiracy of silence. Definitional absence stands
conformity to statistical messages into the primary in sharp contrast to extended usage in every sphere
professional virtue. Such differences remain virtu- of modern life. An extra-planetary anthropologist
ally unexplored because scholars tend to confine might be struck by the amount of energy invested
themselves to the voluminous but narrowly focused by some of its wealthier inhabitants in manag-
universe of their home discipline. A little discussed, ing a phenomenon which they cannot specify. An
embarrassing consequence of this breadth of focus apparently sloppy or even conspiratorial approach
is that not even the slickest polymath can internal- to the concept of risk may be driven by its very
ize more than a small fraction of the current stock ubiquity. Risks have become so much a part of
of risk knowledge on which the late-modern world the fabric of everyday life that they have acquired
turns3. the aura of a fundamental natural force which can
Students of risk should not naively assume that be directly observed. However, when attention is
this word necessarily indicates the presence of a directed away from the practical management of
single entity possessing the same attributes. On particular risks toward the attributes of riskiness,
the other hand, members of cultures in which its elusiveness becomes apparent. Probing the
risk-thinking plays a strategic role tend to implic- meaning of risk has a gently subversive effect, shak-
itly presuppose that the term does possess a com- ing the foundations of taken-for-granted cultural
mon core of meaning; that it somehow connects assumptions on which analyses of specific risks are

606 risk and c ult ure


predicated. In particular, as argued in the next sec- view that an uncomfortably close supernova might
tion, careful reflection about the core of meaning wipe out all life forms on earth refers to a contin-
carried by the term ‘risk’ demonstrates that risks can gency even though little or nothing could be done to
never exist as material entities independently of an prevent such a catastrophe. Similarly, at the personal
observer who has learned to view the world through level, a patient waiting to hear whether a suspicious
the lens of risk. Definitional reflection undermines lump is benign or malignant confronts a contingency
the apparent material substantiality of risks, and specifying two alternative futures, but cannot influ-
thereby opens up the indefinite number of alterna- ence which one will have their name written on it
tives which might become the focus of risk concern. because the cancer process has already either started
Because the coordination of human action requires or not started. Contingency, as already argued, rests
a limited number of risks to be selected from the solely in an observer’s uncertainty as to which of two
infinity of possibility, such challenges threaten the or more outcome categories will hold true5.
underpinnings of organized risk societies. The proposed separation of contingency from
agency allows two interesting alternatives to be spec-
On Contingency ified: contingencies perceived by some observers and
The best starting point for a conceptual analysis not others; and contingencies which some observ-
of risk is consideration of its relationship to contin- ers, but not others, regard as fully or probabilisti-
gency (Luhmann, 1993; Renn, 2008), the idea that cally controllable. With respect to global warming,
one of two or more outcomes might happen (or for instance, an observer might hold that this future
might have happened while remaining unknown). will simply not occur, or is too unlikely to be worth
Carefully uncoupling contingency and risk allows the considering; or they could agree that global warming
latter to be put in its historical place as merely one might occur while asserting that any such trend will
variant, however currently significant, of the former. be unconnected with human activity. As discussed
Risk-thinking can be distinguished from other ways further in the next section, contingencies cannot
of viewing the world contingency through its reliance be thought about without categorization which
on the metaphor of randomness, as argued below. requires boundaries to be set (e.g., warming above
A contingency exists when an observer thinks two degrees centigrade)6. Furthermore, value must
that an event will fall into one of two or more cat- be assigned to outcomes, allowing further differ-
egories4. For example, a child born on January 1st ences of opinion—for example the view that global
2012 might or might not be alive 70 years later, and warming will confer as much benefit as cost. These
one and only one of these alternatives must hold and other potential areas of disagreement open up
true. An observer’s sense of contingency is dissolved many challenges to the coordination of social action
by eventually finding out the actual outcome, nec- among observers who construe a contingency differ-
essarily after, but perhaps not immediately after, ently. They can be distinguished from the condition
an event has happened. In the practical, cookbook where a contingency which might be considered
world of culturally mediated decision-making, con- simply has not been thought about, a point taken up
tingency derives ultimately from uncertainty, not below and illustrated in Box 27.1 (p. 610).
from indeterminacy, as demonstrated by the fol-
lowing consideration. An event which has already Some Esoteric Properties of Contingency
happened, and therefore is wholly determined (e.g. The culturally universal ubiquity of contingency
a sport outcome), can still be considered contingent conceals the non-obviousness of its nature. As with
by an observer who does not know what occurred. gravity and time, its familiar practicality is mislead-
Conversely, for an observer who mistakenly believes ing. Three important issues—the need for prior
that a particular outcome has already happened, the categorization, the infinite scale of possibility, and
turnout no longer appears contingent. the creation of non-events—will be discussed here,
Although contingency specification is mainly before being taken up below in relation to risk.
motivated by a pragmatic desire to influence out-
comes, the concept can be logically uncoupled from Contingency and Prior Categorization
perceived or actual prospects for human control. The formulation of a contingency requires a prior
Contingency indicates merely a belief that specified interpretive act of categorization, without which mul-
outcomes might or might not happen. Thus, the tiple possible outcomes could not even be conceived

h eym a n 607
of. Outcome categories such as winning games or what might/might not happen, or might have hap-
elections may be constituted by rule systems, or may pened/not happened while remaining unknown.
be mapped onto qualitative disjunctions like death A long-term cigarette smoker might or might not die
or heart attacks. Nevertheless, every individual event of lung cancer, for instance. Thinking contingently
is unique. Classification transforms this natural var- by no means requires a risk-based interpretive frame-
iability into identical, distinctive, symbolic packages work which draws upon the metaphor of random-
(Bowker & Star, 2000). ness. Thus, some religious belief systems hold that
The infinite diversity of nature can be squeezed human beings are bound for either heaven or hell
into an indefinite variety of category sets, yielding after death, with the outcome of this contingency
an unlimited number of potential contingencies. To determined by faith, repentance, or predestination.
count as a contingency, a category set must possess Two possible outcomes (or three if limbo is included)
the three properties of possibility, exclusivity, and are specified. Every individual to whom the contin-
universality. For example a presently live person gency applies must experience one of the specified
aged under 70 years might or might not die before trajectories generated by a chosen category system,
their 70th birthday (possibility), can only experi- but remains suspended between the constructed
ence one of the two or more categorized alternatives alternative categories until their fate becomes a mat-
(exclusivity) and must undergo one or the other ter of known historical fact.
(universality). These properties do not appertain If the Aztecs did carry out human sacrifices
intrinsically to events, but arise from socially orga- before dawn every day in order to appease the
nized interpretive action. Many category schemes sun god (Meyer, Sherman, & Deeds, 2003), their
can be applied to the same domain of events. For view can be represented as a contingency. From
instance, just considering binary distinctions for the this point of view, either the sun will rise following
sake of argument, deaths might be viewed as prema- the present night or it will not, with the latter out-
ture/of at least normal length, achieving/not achiev- come potentially leading to eternal darkness if the
ing salvation, painful/peaceful, or brave/cowardly, sun god decided to depart for good (a second-order
depending upon the culturally mediated concerns of contingency). Similarly, at least with respect to its
those applying a contingency. Once a contingency focus on what might happen, Tony Blair, the prime
has been constructed, slotting cases into its alter- minister who took the UK into the second Iraq
natives requires simplification through the conjoint war (testimony to the Chilcot Inquiry, January 29,
processes of homogenization within, and differenti- 2010, quoted in the Guardian newspaper, January
ation between, categories (Heyman et al., 2010, pp. 30, 2010), retrospectively accounted for this deci-
39–43), discussed further below in relation to risk sion by appealing to contingency. He argued that
categorization. These two processes direct attention “What is important is not to ask the March 2003 ques-
away from both intracategory variability and inter- tion, but to ask the 2010 question. Supposing we had
category similarity. This price must be paid in order backed off this military action . . . ?”. Blair maintained
to drive the diversity of events into unified alter- that the “crucial thing after September 11 was that
native packages which can be generalized about. the calculus of risk changed”. This instructive phrase
Allowing for a larger number of categories mitigates distinguishes risk-thinking from other ways of rea-
the distorting process of homogenization-differenti- soning contingently by attaching an aura of prob-
ation, but at the price of extra complexity, and may abilistic scientific rationality to the mental activity
fail pragmatically. For instance, screened individuals of analyzing the inherently ethereal multiverse of
must either be offered or not offered further expen- possibility.
sive and invasive diagnostic tests. In the practice of Examples drawn from cultures which seem
screening, the continuous scale of probability tends exotic from a current science-based cultural per-
to be reduced to the two alternatives of higher and spective illustrate the infinite scale of the possible
lower risk linked pragmatically to the action/inac- particularly well, showing that, in principle, any-
tion binary (Heyman, 2010). thing might happen. Even the laws of physics do
not curtail the potential bounds of contingency
Possibility Creation which require only that an observer should believe
A second, crucially important property of all that a categorized outcome might possibly occur.
forms of contingency, not just risks, is that they Culture plays the crucial roles, firstly, of shap-
conjure up possibilities through contemplation of ing how contingency is understood (e.g., as risk

608 risk and c ult ure


through the metaphor of randomness or as the will smokers would have died prematurely. These events
of the gods); and secondly, of specifying which small simply happened without becoming bound up with
number of possibilities out of the infinite number of the machinery of what might be, or might have been.
those which might be contemplated become foci of But smoking could have been, and sometimes still is,
organized concern. Variants of contingency, in both viewed contingently in many other ways (e.g., as an
its form and substance, should be located in the aid to digestion, an identity statement, or a facilita-
human mind, not in externally observable events tor of social bonding). Once a contingency has been
which merely happen. constituted through outcome categorization, it auto-
matically generates a counterpart type of non-event.
The Curious Reality of Non-events Occurrence and non-occurrence are bound up in a
In addition to selectively addressing what might figure-ground relationship in which each requires the
or might have happened, thinking contingently other, although their dividing line may shift dynam-
allows the observer to ‘see’ an imagined outcome ically (Josephs, Valsiner, & Surgan, 1999, p. 265).
such as eternal darkness or runaway global warming Furthermore, the occurrence/non-occurrence binary
‘not happening’. To an observer who is not think- structures time through differentiating an elusive pre-
ing about a contingency, the absence of an imagined sent in which an outcome might or might not occur
possibility will simply not register. Thus, members from a future in which one of these possibilities can
of societies which recognize the risks of smoking be ruled out (Heyman et al., 2010, pp. 118–120).
can see a heavy lifetime smoker ‘not dying’ from a After an event, possibility immediately resolves itself
smoking-related disease, but this (non)event could into history, inviting retrospective forensic account-
not be ‘observed’ before smoking risks were flagged ing, for instance if a serious accident has occurred.
up. Non-events do not register to the senses or any To recap, contingency thinking depends upon
measuring instrument, but cultural distancing is the shoehorning of events into two or more possi-
required for their ghostly nature to be recognized. In ble, exclusive, and universal categories. Each con-
relation to an unmet expectation, non-occurrence is tingency, realized as a category set, solidifies one
experienced as tangible. However, since anything issue from the unlimited fluidity of possibility. The
might happen, the number of possible non-hap- notion that an outcome is contingent derives from
penings is unlimited. The infinity of possibility, a observer uncertainty, not from the material exis-
crucial starting point for the analysis of contingency tence of alternative trajectories, as does the remark-
thinking, was emphasized by the nineteenth cen- able but usually unnoticed human capacity to
tury philosophical psychologist Alexius Meinong7 ‘observe’ what has not, but might have, occurred.
(Dölling, 2001, p. 63): The crucial analytical step which enables the
relationship between risk and culture to be
In developing his theory of objects, Meinong was guided
adequately understood involves uncoupling the
by the insight that the totality of what exists, including
idea of contingency, originating in the human
what has existed and will exist, is infinitely small in
capacity to imagine possibilities, from its par-
comparison with the totality of the objects of knowledge.
ticular culturally derived forms, such as belief
This fact easily goes unnoticed, probably because the
in divine justice or literal use of the randomness
lively interest in reality which is part of our nature
metaphor.
tends to favour that exaggeration which finds the
The process through which imagining a contin-
non-real a mere nothing.
gency conjures it into existence, although without
Meinong’s assertion that there are “objects of a guarantee of a lengthy or vigorous cultural life, is
which it is true to say that there are no such objects” illustrated in Box 27.1, on p. 610, below.
caused considerable contention at the time (Dölling,
2001 p. 64), perhaps because it subverted the The Problematic Status of Utility
taken-for-granted assumptions of empiricist sci- Calculation in Relation to Possibility
ence. Contingency identification requires a semiotic The above analysis raises the question of whether
“preadaption” (Josephs, Valsiner, & Surgan, 1999, some possibilities (e.g., the end of the world
p. 258) involving categorization, as argued above. through divine retribution, invasion from another
For example, before smoking came to be viewed as a planet, a situation in which the UK or France
health issue, smoker longevity would not have been would and could credibly threaten to use nuclear
particularly noted, although, needless to say, many weapons independently of the United States) can

h eym a n 609
Box 27.1 A Contingency Miscarriage
In 2009, an email concerning possible risks from compact disks (CDs) was circulated among forensic
mental health service providers11. A patient had pointed out that CDs could be turned into sharp weap-
ons, an outcome which the email writer had not previously considered. The email requested information
from elsewhere as to whether others shared this concern, or knew of it happening. Nobody involved in the
discussion group had come across a single case, but writers expressed concern that CDs or DVDs might
be used as weapons in the future. Despite this fear, participants agreed that they should not be banned.
This example illustrates the risk-management implications of the conjectural status of contingency.
Until the risk was envisaged, it could not be managed. Once articulated, it stimulated worry, which was
not alleviated by recognizing that no cases had been locally recorded. Their absence did not preclude
the possibility of adverse events having taken place elsewhere, or occurring subsequently. However, if
preventative action had been initiated, patients would have been deprived of one of the few forms of
recreation open to them, possibly generating new risks. At the same time, the overt contemplation of this
contingency made those who considered it vulnerable to blame if the now imagined but never observed
outcome actually occurred in the future.

rationally be given more or less weight than others. differ, such comparisons can always be contested.
The present author has reviewed this complex ques- Fortunately, the question posed above can be largely
tion elsewhere (Heyman et al., 2010, pp. 65–76). ducked in the present analysis of risk and culture on
In brief, the issue corresponds to that of measuring the grounds that social groups respond to the con-
expected value, which has received gargantuan aca- tingencies which they collectively prioritize, usually
demic attention, particularly within the discipline unreflectively, regardless of any utilitarian calcula-
of economics. The answer to the question posed tions or accusations of non-equivalence which crit-
above carries fundamental importance in science- ics may throw at them.
based societies in relation to one of their principal
strategic stumbling blocks, that of applying empiri- The Concept of Risk
cal methods outside the laboratory in conditions of Uncoupling the ideas of contingency and
real life complexity. Claims to rational grounding in risk makes it possible to view risk as the label for
risk-oriented societies depend heavily on the valid- merely one way of thinking contingently, which
ity of utility quantification. It is easy to be mesmer- has acquired quasi-universalistic status in the mod-
ized by the sheer volume of empirical work which ern, science-based world. This crucial step pre-
relies on the assumption that expected value can be vents the absurd conclusion, sometimes found in
accurately measured. the risk literature, being drawn that only modern
Although not futile, the calculation of expected peoples have attempted to control the future. Risk-
value can at best generate a variety of different, thinking provides a historically novel formulation
crudely plausible answers depending upon starting of contingency as governed by the combination
assumptions, for example about trade-offs between of empirically established causal factors and ran-
multiple values and about the temporal horizon to domness. (However, the notion of randomness will
be taken into account (Peterson, 2007). Because be demoted in the next section to a merely meta-
expected value is so elusive, evidence for the charge phorical status at least in the domain of everyday
of irrational contingency selection often draws objects.) The origins of the risk-based approach to
upon the calibration of non-equivalence. For exam- contingency are associated with the linked devel-
ple, the contrast between the urgency given to the opments of science and capitalism in Europe from
2010 oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico and the long the time of the Renaissance (Bernstein, 1996).
period of calm indifference to larger annual leak- Hacking (1975/2006) locates the birth of the mod-
ages in Nigeria and Ecuador can be used to support ern concept of probability precisely in the Europe
the view that environmental harm counts for more of the 1650s.
if it occurs in the United States than if it happens One way to explore the shared but tacit men-
in a developing country. Since circumstances always tal work underpinning the cultural presence of a

610 risk and c ult ure


risk is to expose the implicit assumptions buried in section. The risk observer cannot avoid implicitly
standard definitions, which are themselves scarce. or explicitly:
As presented in the Abstract and repeated here for
1. Categorizing the contingent outcomes which
the reader’s convenience, the Royal Society (1992,
become a selected focus of risk analysis;
p. 2, with present author’s additions in parentheses)
2. Making value judgments about these
defined risk as:
outcome categories;
3. Developing expectations about the likelihood
the probability (3) that a particular adverse (2) event
of these consequences, using the past as a
(1) occurs during a stated period of time (4a), or results
guide to the future;
from a particular challenge (4b).
4. Placing temporal boundaries around a
risk, without which it cannot be assessed.
The two variants of the fourth risk ingredient,
(Condition 4b in the Royal Society definition
which refer to limited and indefinite time periods
precludes quantification because it encompasses
respectively, both address the temporal aspect of
consequences extending toward infinity.)
risk. This formulation was designed to justify the
objective measurement of risks. However, each of The bottom part of the table draws attention to
the four elements of risk enumerated above can be the interpretive work which underpins standard
reframed in a way which brings out the implicit risk management steps such as drawing practice
processes of interpretation that underpin them. conclusions from evidence, reframed as “encoding”
This reframing is summarized schematically in (Alaszewski, 2010). Risk management will not be
Table 27.1, below, which also includes a similar considered further in the present chapter. However,
reframing of risk management. it should be noted that the crucial question of what
The four enumerated elements of risk tend to be to do about a risk cannot arise until it has been con-
projected onto the external world, so that features stituted, as shown in the first part of the table, and
such as adversity come to be experienced as intrin- that this sort of question can only arise in cultures
sic attributes of events themselves. A person con- which frame contingencies as risks. The four ele-
sidering a risk plays an active, culturally mediated, ments of the risk compound will be considered fur-
judgmental role, which can sometimes be obscured ther in the second part of the chapter.
by habit and social consensus, illustrated in the next
Four Components of Risk Thinking
As discussed in the previous section, perception
TABLE 27.1 Two Views of Risk Elements of any contingency entails four usually implicit
interpretive steps involving categorizing, valuing,
Naturalistic view Interpretative view
of risk of risk
expecting, and time-framing. Risk-thinking is dif-
ferentiated from other ways of envisaging contin-
RISK CONSTITUTION gency only with respect to the third ingredient,
through drawing upon the metaphor of random-
(1) Event Category
ness. These four components of risk-thinking have
(2) Adversity Value been analyzed at length elsewhere (Heyman et al.,
(3) Probability Uncertain expectation 2010). For the present purpose, each will be briefly
(4) Time period Time frame illustrated with particular reference to the interrela-
tionship of risk and culture.
RISK MANAGEMENT

Service delivery Service organization The Categorization of Events


Evidence-based practice Practice encoding
Management of a particular risk will mostly be ori-
ented not toward single outcomes, but toward con-
Information giving Information
stellations of linked predictive and causal antecedents
representation
and consequences. Regardless of the web of relation-
Regulation and safety Control
ships in which any event will be enmeshed, risk man-
Adapted from Heyman et al., 2010 with the permission of Oxford agement attention tends to foreground one negatively
University Press. valued antecedent or consequent. For instance, a focus

h eym a n 611
on cigarette smoking as a risky behaviour would link awareness of dissimilarities between cases (homog-
this presumed causal antecedent to a greater chance enization), and the exaggeration of boundaries
of experiencing various diseases, directing attention between cases and non-cases (differentiation). The
away from benefits of smoking such as stress man- woman quoted below challenged the homogeniza-
agement and weight reduction. Alternatively, a neg- tion of Down’s syndrome as a risk category (Heyman
ative outcome such as coronary heart disease might & Henriksen, 2001, p. 41).
be considered in relation to multiple risk factors. The
Pregnant woman: And it doesn’t help, again, people
variable architecture of risk constellations has received
making comments like, what he [acquaintance] just
little analytical attention, perhaps because the natural
said, ‘You could be changing someone’s nappy at 21.’ I
attitude toward risk does not lend itself to consider-
mean, not all Down’s syndrome are like that, are they?
ation of the socio-cognitive processes through which
I have seen them walking around the town. And, apart
a risk is mentally carved out from the tangled web of
from their visual looks, they are very intelligent, some
causation.
of them. (Research interview with pregnant woman,
Regardless of their position in a risk constella-
aged 39 years, who opted for amniocentesis)
tion, its constituent objects cannot exist without
prior categorization, which will be considered in Although the cause of Down’s syndrome, three
relation to a foregrounded outcome deemed adverse. copies of the twenty-first chromosome instead of
Because events never repeat themselves identically, two, can be specified, its precise configurations
outcomes must be neatly packaged before they can and clinical manifestations vary immensely. The
become available to generalized risk analysis. This quotation points to a tension between the men-
process entails three conjoint sub-processes, the tal construction ‘person with Down’s syndrome’,
selection of an outcome as worthy of attention, the which enables its probability to be computed
homogenization of cases, and their differentiation through counting its rate of occurrence, and the
from non-cases. For example, research into the risk variability within this category, which its classifica-
of ‘depression’ is predicated on the assumption that tion directs attention away from. In contrast, the
this state can be clearly differentiated from every- next quotation from the same study (Heyman &
day ‘sadness’ (Robertson, 2008). At the same time, Henriksen, 2001, p. 163) fends off challenges to
estimating the probability that an individual will the differentiation of Down’s syndrome from the
experience depression requires cases to be treated as absence of the condition.
equivalent so that their frequencies can be counted.
Woman who had terminated pregnancy: I read a
But this step requires attention to be directed away
story [magazine article]. Reading this story has helped
from differences within a risk category, at least tem-
me cope with it [opting for pregnancy termination
porarily. McCormack, Levine, and Rangno (1997)
after Down’s syndrome diagnosed] . . . I think they
provide “simple nomograms”, essentially graphs with
[couple depicted in story] are bloody stupid . . . They
correction factors which doctors and patients can use
look like they are really over the moon because they are
to calculate a patient’s probability of experiencing a
having this Down’s baby.
“cardiovascular event” over 5- and 10-year periods
Husband: I mean they will have been explained the
in terms of known risk factors. These authors define
same as everybody else as to what can happen, or what it
“cardiovascular events” as including “angina, unstable
is going to be like, and what it means for the future.
angina, myocardial infarction or death from coronary
Woman: They can have chest infections . . . I mean
artery disease.” Thus, in order to quantify the chance
they are laughed, and they are scorned at. (Research
of this ‘event’ occurring over a given time period,
interview with woman aged 46 years and her
it must first be marked out by lumping together a
husband after pregnancy termination for Down’s
diverse range of phenomena, as the above quotation
syndrome)
demonstrates. However, this manoeuvre is not itself
debated in the paper. Discussing category creation This couple had been undergoing fertility treat-
would direct attention toward the potential exis- ment for many years, and had given up their last
tence of alternatives which would generate different opportunity for biological parenthood, a loss which
risk entities and probabilities of occurrence. still distressed them deeply a year after the abortion
Inevitably, the categorization of risks generates had taken place. Understandably, they objected
dissonances in relation to the privileging of one con- vehemently to a representation of Down’s syn-
tingency over another (selection), the suppression of drome which undermined its differentiation from

612 risk and c ult ure


non-cases, and thereby stimulated doubt about that adversity can be located in events rather than
their painful personal decision. their perception arises from the projection of taken-
The third conjoint component of risk construc- for-granted, culturally shared values onto the external
tion alongside homogenization and differentiation, world, an unarticulated mental manoeuvre which
the selection and non-selection of outcome catego- leads to adversity being experienced as an intrinsic
ries, can only occur for a risk category which has attribute. The Royal Society definition adopts this
been created through homogenization and differ- natural attitude, which unreflectively directs attention
entiation. Otherwise, there is nothing to accept. away from value questions.
At the same time, the homogenization and differ- The inescapable role of the observer in judgments
entiation of a risk category entails its selection as a about outcome adversity can be seen most clearly
candidate, at least, for organized concern. Hence, when the humanistic assumptions taken for granted
these three processes must operate together in order (but not acted upon) in modern, developed societies
to bootstrap a risk into existence. Risk selection is are suspended. Aliens from another galaxy might view
illustrated in Box 27.2, below, in relation to a noto- the demise of the entire human species as a positive
rious case of risk blindness. event, a theme explored in countless science fiction
In conclusion, outcome homogenization, differ- movies. For racists, the destruction of ‘inferior’ eth-
entiation, and selection are undertaken conjointly. nic groups is to be welcomed; whilst various religious
Mental representations of what might happen are groups have positively valued the destruction of the
simultaneously foregrounded, bestowed with com- unfaithful. Conversely, believers in animal rights
mon attributes and marked out from ‘the rest’. This reject an implicit starting point in which humans are
complex mental activity must be aligned for organized privileged above other species (Singer, 1990), thereby
social interaction to be possible, but its grounding challenging the justification for animal experimenta-
always remains fragile because outcome categorization tion. Such examples expose the unexamined presup-
can never capture the individuality of actual events. positions which any utilitarian calculation requires.
Even within the frame of Western liberalism,
Value Judgments about Adversity risk analysis is built upon many value assumptions
The second component of risk-thinking mentioned which remain mostly unexamined. For the present
in the Royal Society (1992) definition is reframed in purpose of exploring the interrelationships between
the second column of Table 27.1 as negative valuing. culture and risk-thinking, one illustrative example
The notion of a “particular adverse event” locates nega- of alternative values will have to suffice. Maternity
tivity in an observable property of the external world, services in the UK and many other countries are ori-
like mass or temperature. However, badness can never ented toward preventing the birth of children with
reside in events themselves, but only in the percep- severe disabilities through screening and offering
tions of individuals who singly or collectively attribute the option of pregnancy termination. Many parents
negativity to outcomes (Rescher, 1983). The illusion wish to exercise this option, but some do not, and

BOX 27.2 An Example of Organized Risk Selection


The Butler Inquiry (The Home Office/Department of Health and Social Security, 1975) dealt with a
striking case of risk blindness, arising from selective risk perception, which stimulated the development
of medium-security forensic mental health units in the UK. While confined to a high-security institution,
Graham Young actively and openly pursued his interest in poisoning, for example borrowing library books
on the topic. After being released, he promptly resumed his career as a poisoner. Physically and socially
remote from wider society, staff working in high-security institutions may have become oriented toward
internal risks such as patients harming themselves or others on the ward. They simply did not visualize an
outcome which appeared glaringly obvious from outside the social system in which they were immersed.
Systems theory of risk (Japp & Kusche, 2008), outlined above, envisages endemic social disarray aris-
ing as an unintended consequence of increasing role differentiation. The Young case illustrates potentially
tragic, but also blackly comical, consequences which can result when social actors selectively address dif-
ferent risk objects without appreciating their discordance.

h eym a n 613
experience may stimulate reappraisal. Oulton and than the other three ingredients of risk-thinking.
Heyman (2009) found that some parents of chil- Reflecting its importance to risk, the Royal Society
dren with severe and profound intellectual disabili- (1992) document immediately followed the defini-
ties did not view their existence as an adverse event, tion of risk with a statement about probability.
a value judgment vividly illustrated by the following
As a probability in the sense of statistical theory risk
quotation.
obeys all the formal laws of combining probabilities.
Her every little step she makes is just so phenomenal.
This awkward, elliptical sentence uninten-
And what grace she’s got. And, ah, she’s just a complete
tionally conveys the writers’ unease whilst invok-
delight all the time. (Research interview with mother
ing abstruse mathematical “laws” as legitimation.
of daughter with severe learning and physical
Non-mathematicians, including the present author,
disabilities)
tend to defer to such authoritative assertions which
Another quotation from the same study specifically invoke a prestigious, mysterious world of science.
articulates resonances, normally concealed, between Mary Douglas (1992, p. 50), challenged the prevail-
outcome evaluation and wider cultural issues. ing official assumption that “the ordinary lay person,
the man in the street, is weak on probabilistic think-
There aren’t many opportunities in twentieth century
ing”, arguing that human beings intuitively appre-
life in England to be a good person unless you seek it
ciate probabilities. Common mistakes in everyday
out. And, like a missionary or something, so caring for
probabilistic reasoning can indeed be diagnosed
somebody, and the experience of loving somebody who
(Breakwell, 2007), for instance overgeneralizing
is different, and damaged, and has certain problems
from single cases, but should not distract attention
is a very rewarding experience for me personally . . .
from questioning this way of thinking, as the fol-
it’s a bit like Calvinism. You actually begin to feel as
lowing quotation illustrates.
if you’re of the elect, and of a very small banded set of
special people who are different from everybody else . . . Once upon a time I was an undergraduate majoring in
It’s very dangerous to feel superior to other people. That’s mathematics and statistics. I attended many lectures on
why you have to fight it. (Research interview with the probability theory, and my lecturers taught me many
father of a daughter with severe learning and physical nice theorems involving probability . . . One
disabilities) day I approached one of them after a lecture and
asked him . . . “What is probability?”. He looked at me
The brief exposition offered in this section has
like I needed medication, and he told me to go to the
done no more than scratch the surface of the many
philosophy department.
complex value questions which underlie even the
(Hájek, 2008, quoted author’s emphasis)
apparently simplest risk issue. That risk managers
are not, like Shakespeare’s Hamlet, paralyzed by This anecdote nicely captures the cultural pro-
doubt, attests to the quietly effective accomplish- cess of deletion, discussed in the final main section
ment of their culture, which supplies prepackaged, of the chapter, through which unspoken shared pre-
if not uncontested, answers to value pre-questions. suppositions are kept away from reflective scrutiny.
The face validity of pragmatic assessments of ‘what It will be argued below that probabilistic thinking
works’ depends on such matters not being opened draws upon the metaphor of randomness, and that
up to scrutiny and debate. its use to approximate the unknown but determi-
nate carries very important consequences. Before
Probabilities/Expectations this task is attempted, three ways in which quali-
Probability is the third of the four components tative or quantitative probabilities can be generated
of risk-thinking alluded to in the Royal Society will be briefly distinguished, namely inductive rea-
(1992) definition. It is reframed in Table 27.1 from soning, modelling, and motivation assessment.
an interpretive perspective as one approach to devel-
oping expectations. Categorization, valuing, and Three Modes of Probabilistic Reasoning
time-framing can be found in all forms of viewing Firstly, when outcomes occur frequently, their
possible events contingently. Probabilistic reasoning, probability can be estimated inductively, by using
in contrast, marks out risk-thinking as distinctive their past rate as a guide to the future. For instance,
from other ways of viewing the world contingently. the chance of an individual dying from coronary
For this reason, it will be discussed in more detail heart disease (CHD) can be computed by counting

614 risk and c ult ure


the number of such deaths in the recent past as the derive from expectations which can be grounded in
numerator, the total number of deaths as the denom- diverse epistemological procedures.
inator, and then calculating their ratio. More sophis-
ticated conditional probabilities can be worked out Probability and the Metaphor
for subcategories such as men versus women, or for of Chance
different socio-economic strata. This rough and ready Risk-thinking invites its users to view the deter-
approach to grounding expectations directly in previ- minants of a negatively valued outcome as parti-
ous experience is not available for unusual events like tioned between risk factors and a residue of chance;
nuclear accidents, which do not happen frequently and to regard this residue as resulting from inde-
enough to be reliably counted. In such cases, the terminacy rather than from prognostic limitations.
quantification of probability, for instance the scien- Thus, uncertainty arising from lack of knowledge
tific consensus that there is a 90% chance of human is projected onto events as the attribute of ran-
activity causing catastrophic global warming during domness, a process which parallels the perceptual
the present century, is based on mathematical model- metamorphosis of negative valuing into inherent
ling, a second mode of probabilistic reasoning. adversity. The merely metaphorical status of chance
Thirdly, when contingency involves voluntary in risk-thinking can be demonstrated through its
action, expectation can be expressed in terms of a application to historic but unknown events. For
numerical probability, as when an individual asserts example, people who are screened for a condition
that he is 90% sure that he will turn up for a social such as colorectal cancer will be told their probabil-
event. ity of experiencing an adverse outcome which has
Expectations can be represented through numer- already occurred. ‘Randomness’ in such cases can
ical probabilities in each of these three strikingly only refer to the projection onto the external world
different forms of reasoning, a difference which of observer uncertainty about an outcome which
their common numerical representation obscures. has happened and is therefore utterly determined.
Furthermore, their interrelationships, particularly The same analysis can be applied to future out-
that between statistical and psychological probabil- comes which are clearly generated from the com-
ities, are difficult to conceptualize. Human action plex interactions of simpler forces, for instance,
can itself become the object of risk analysis at the the end position of a spun roulette ball. Certain
collective level. Aggregate statistics such as an indi- internet vendors claim to be able to provide sys-
vidual’s chance of being a crime victim in a partic- tems of concealed cameras and computers which
ular locality remain remarkably constant from year predict roulette outcomes with sufficient accuracy
to year despite resulting from countless individual to beat the house odds, thus diminishing ‘random-
decisions. Similarly, the probability of an individ- ness’. In principle, there is no reason why such a
ual taking a risk-reducing action such as giving up system should not provide perfect accuracy, thereby
smoking can itself be estimated inductively. The banishing the scope for metaphorical randomness.
issue of genetic predisposition in relation to the In consequence, the probabilities of particular out-
attribution of criminal responsibility well illustrates comes will change for anyone who is using this sys-
the murkiness of the connection between volun- tem. Meanwhile the roulette ball, although not the
tariness and randomness. Knowledge of statistical casino owners, will carry on blissfully unaffected by
relationships between gene variants and crime rates the changes to its chances of coming to rest on a
can be used to argue either that the genetically pre- particular number.
disposed should be given shorter sentences on the This outline of a classical closed causal system
grounds that they cannot be blamed for their inher- needs to be modified in two respects to take into
itance, or that they should be given longer sentences account quantum uncertainty, and the indefi-
on account of their presumed greater propensity to niteness of open systems such as the human body
offend (Farahany & Bernet, 2006). which are affected by an indefinitely large number
The following discussion of probabilistic think- of causal influences. Physics teaches that an irre-
ing will focus on the first of the three forms of ducible randomness operates at the smallest scales
probabilistic reasoning outlined above, inductive of magnitude; and that, therefore, merely observ-
inference from frequently occurring events. But ing an attribute of a particle changes its behaviour
consideration of the very different cases outlined so as to prevent the observer from obtaining ‘for-
above demonstrates that probabilistic propositions bidden’ knowledge. Quantum processes may well

h eym a n 615
contribute to risk, for instance by tipping a cell into all members of a category, with each case deemed
a cancerous state which the immune system fails to to ‘carry’ the same aggregate chance of incurring
check. However, more generally, quantum effects the predicted outcome. Refinement of predictive
and risks are connected only tenuously through models can allow such demarcations of chance to
shared use of the concept of chance. As argued in be modified. For instance, personalized medicine,
the next subsection, risk analysis, stripped of its if its promise were ever met (Petersen, 2009), would
pretensions, offers no more than useful cookbook allow those who will suffer side effects from a partic-
pragmatism, and operates on a macro scale where ular drug to be identified through genetic markers.
quantum uncertainty can be ignored. Classical ran- At present, the chance of this undesired outcome
dom systems and the more complex events which is attributed to randomness equally affecting the
risk analysis addresses must be distinguished in one entire population of medicine users. However, until
important respect, however. Whereas, the behaviour perfect prediction is achieved, and risk thereby ban-
of a roulette wheel is determined by a small number ished, a residue of unexplained variance will remain
of interacting forces, social and health phenomena to be mopped up through tacit acceptance in prac-
are influenced by the interactions of a vast num- tice of the ecological fallacy that all members of a
ber of processes. Empirically grounded expectations nominated category share its aggregate statistics.
about the latter can only be developed selectively. It Two types of pragmatic gain can result from this
is never possible to measure more than a small pro- usually unnoticed cognitive manoeuvring. Firstly, if
portion of directly or proximally influential factors, presence in a marked risk category results from a
and many different models with some predictive causal link with the defining category attribute, as
purchase can be put forward. with smoking/lung cancer, and perhaps with obe-
sity/coronary heart disease, modification of the risk
Consequences of Adopting the factor will reduce the incidence of the risked condi-
Metaphor of Randomness tion in the sub-population flagged up as at higher
A number of practically important consequences risk. The belief that a causal connection, however
follow from the projection of uncertainty as ran- imperfect, exists motivates the direct preventa-
domness. Their combined impact is not always tive endeavour targeted at the attribute category.
appreciated because it is obscured by the tendency The anticipated gains will only be achieved if the
to take the metaphor of randomness literally. These assumption of causality is correct. Secondly, even if
consequences (Heyman et al., 2010, Chapter 5) no causal significance is attached to a category, its
are outlined in Table 27.2, and briefly illustrated markers can be used predictively to target a class of
below. individuals at greater risk for other forms of pre-
Acceptance of the ecological fallacy: The paradigm vention, as with screening tests. However, such
case of probabilistic reasoning involves counting risk management gains come at the price of con-
rates in categories and attributing these statistics to flating the aggregated properties of a category with
future members, although, as discussed above, prob- attributes of its individual members. Some further
ability estimation does not always take this form. ramifications of this useful but crude heuristic (rule-
It, in effect, ‘spreads’ the calculated rates among of-thumb) are briefly outlined below.
The ecological prevention paradox: The ecologi-
TABLE 27.2 Some Implications of Probabilistic
cal prevention paradox (Davison, Davey-Smith &
Reasoning Frankel, 1992) arises because every individual in a
delineated category is deemed to possess the over-
1. Acceptance of the ecological fallacy all probability of experiencing the negatively val-
2. The ecological prevention paradox
ued outcome of concern, and, therefore, to merit
the same risk management response. Moreover, this
3. Multiple probabilities way of thinking is often applied even when high rel-
ative risk is combined with low absolute risk, indi-
4. The informational management of “personal”
probabilities
cating that a large majority of those in the higher
risk category will not be affected. For instance,
5. Acceptance of the inductive fallacy the finding of a raised rate of future hospitaliza-
tion for schizophrenia among cannabis consumers
6. The inductive prevention paradox
(Zammit et al., 2002) has been employed to justify

616 risk and c ult ure


its criminalization, even though the vast majority Down’s syndrome can chose to leave their proba-
of users and non-users alike will not experience bility at this level. Alternatively, they can choose to
this outcome. Zammit et al. concluded that self- undergo a test which will either increase or decrease
reported heavy cannabis users were 6.3 times more their risk. However, they cannot know in advance
likely than self-reported non-users to be hospitalized which of these probabilities will apply to them.
for schizophrenia over a 25-year period. However, The woman quoted below (Heyman & Henriksen,
3.8% of heavy users, compared with 0.6% of non- 2001, p. 153) had ruled out diagnostic tests and
users, were found to have been hospitalized. High abortion, but, nevertheless, managed her personal
risk categorization spreads ‘the problem’ among the probability (expectation) by gambling that a nega-
vast majority who are unaffected one way or the tive screening test would bring reassurance.
other.
And if I had the serum screening test, that would let
Multiple probabilities: Because risks are attributed
me know when it was a high risk or a low risk. And
to individuals on account of their category member-
if it were a low risk, well, I could practically rule out
ship, it follows that changing either the specification
having a Down’s baby anyway. So that was brilliant
of categories or the assignment of individuals to
anyway because that give me peace of mind. (Research
them will alter ‘personal’ probabilities. In relation to
interview with pregnant woman, aged 37 years,
category specification, for example, recent research
who accepted serum screening for chromosomal
has suggested that obesity risk is better captured
anomalies)
by waist circumference than by the more widely
used body mass index (BMI). BMI lumps together Although unusual, this way of responding illustrates
highly fit muscular individuals with those carrying the possibilities for informational probability man-
larger amounts of fat (Janssen, Katzmarzyk, & Ross, agement particularly well. Since about 5% of women
2004). The category of persons with high BMIs who underwent this form of screening were judged
may experience a higher aggregate rate of health to be at higher risk, her strategy yielded a 95%
problems despite including some very fit persons. chance of relocating her to a lower risk status. But if
Although the choice of risk markers can be empir- she had screened at higher risk, she would have had
ically grounded in selection of the most accurate to live with this status until the birth because she
predictors, suboptimal risk models may provide suf- had ruled out invasive diagnostic testing.
ficient predictive purchase to justify their adoption. Acceptance of the inductive fallacy: Probabilistic
Until perfect prediction is achieved, banishing risk, reasoning based on frequency observation requires
stronger predictive models will remain to be discov- more than working acceptance of the ecological fal-
ered. Many alternative models may offer a similar lacy. In addition, a conceptual leap must be made
degree of prognostic power while marking different from the past to the future. Without this assump-
attributes as markers of risk. Each will assign differ- tion, expectations cannot be grounded in empiri-
ent probabilities to at least some individuals. cal observation. But its adoption requires pragmatic
The informational management of ‘personal’ prob- acceptance of the inductive fallacy. What happened
abilities: Individual location within an established in the past will not necessarily recur in the future, as
set of risk categories will depend upon the availabil- the European discovery of black swans in Australia
ity of information which assigns individuals to one during the nineteenth century illustrates8.
or other alternative. Hence, individuals can change Mortality risks provide a good example of famil-
their risk status by deciding whether to inquire fur- iar statistical ‘facts’ which contain implicit induc-
ther (Heyman, Henriksen, & Maughan, 1998). For tive assumptions. Individuals in marked categories
instance, the children of a parent with Huntington’s such as those of gender, social class and lifestyle,
disease may opt to undergo a genetic test which will are deemed to carry their aggregate rates of occur-
establish with certainty whether or not they will rence as personal probabilities, as discussed above9.
develop the disease, or may choose not to be tested, But these statistics can only be estimated induc-
leaving their probability at 50%. Some individuals tively through extrapolation into the future from
make this choice because they do not want to risk the longevity of those who have already died.
having to live with knowing that they will definitely Direct extrapolation carries the fundamental limi-
develop the condition in later life (Leontini, 2010). tation that it does not allow for historical increases
Similarly, pregnant women who are informed of or decreases in life expectancy. Even if such trends
their age-related probability of carrying a fetus with are taken into account, some sort of extrapolation

h eym a n 617
from the past to the future is inescapable. Observed cervical cancer vaccination has been recently intro-
regularities provide a practically indispensible rough duced in the UK and elsewhere alongside the estab-
guide to expectations. However, a price has to be lished technology of screening. Whether screening
paid for heuristic simplification, as with acceptance will become unnecessary in a population with a
of the ecological fallacy, discussed above. If the past high vaccination rate cannot be easily assessed as
ceases to provide a guide to the future because some long as both are being provided (Kiviat, Hawes, &
unknown causal condition has changed, inductive Feng, 2008). But the termination of screening pro-
inference will systematically mislead. grammes can hardly be contemplated because their
It will be argued in the next section that this lim- withdrawal might generate serious consequences.
itation becomes inherently inescapable when pre- This section has analyzed the complex, implicit
ventative efforts have themselves potentially altered structure of probabilistic reasoning, identifying
the circumstances surrounding a risk. counterintuitive implications such as multiple prob-
The inductive prevention paradox: The inductive abilities, informational probability management and
prevention paradox arises when preventative efforts preventative inductive loops.
remove from sight the pristine conditions which
existed previously, precluding assessment of their Time Periods/Time Frames
future necessity. This predicament arises regardless The analysis presented so far has attempted to
of whether the harm-reducing measure is presently unpick the interpretive work entailed by three
efficacious, as long as those managing a contingency embedded elements in risk-thinking: the categori-
think that it might be. If the Aztecs did carry out zation of contingent outcomes; negative valuing of
human sacrifices before dawn every day in order at least one of the categorized alternatives; and the
to appease the sun god, then their action would development of probabilistic expectations based on
have prevented them from observing whether the heuristic acceptance of the ecological and inductive
sun would have risen regardless, as modern readers fallacies. The final main section of this chapter will
may suspect. Furthermore, their belief system about consider the fourth necessary component of risk-
this contingency would have prevented them from thinking, the segmentation of time within temporal
putting the efficacy of human sacrifice to the test horizons, without which probabilities could not be
on account of the irreversible damage which they calculated.
feared might have resulted if the sun god had taken The Royal Society (1992) definition refers to a
umbrage and departed. Certainty is not required, risk spanning a “stated period of time,” recast in Table
merely fear about what might happen (i.e., about 27.1 as a time frame. The definition also offers a
contingency). variant on time periods, adverse events which result
Regardless of its historical accuracy, this esoteric “from a particular challenge”. The latter implies an
example illustrates a predicament which equally open time frame encompassing all the future con-
affects modern risk management at both the indi- sequences of a risk. Given that consequences can
vidual and collective level. To illustrate the former, extend indefinitely into the future through chains
a frail older person who is injured in a fall outside of causation, removing the outer limit would ren-
their home might decide that they cannot risk going der the inductive estimation of probabilities impos-
out again. By staying at home, this person cuts off sible. For instance, radiation from nuclear waste
the supply of evidence which might have suggested might harm health directly for many thousands of
that such precautions were unnecessary. Similarly, years, but its consequences could extend even fur-
patients with long-term conditions taking prophy- ther through reproductive transmission of genetic
lactic drugs, for instance controlling Crone’s disease damage. Not surprisingly, the nuclear industry
with anti-inflammatory drugs, cannot know whether has favoured assessing the health impact of storing
experimentally stopping their consumption would radioactive waste over a relatively short 500 year
trigger irreversible flare-ups. At the collective level, period (Atherton & French, 1999), thereby placing
the ‘war on drugs’ continues to be fought despite longer-lasting radioactivity outside the temporal
its evident failure, in case its abandonment would horizon for risk assessment, and reducing its appar-
trigger an irreversible explosion of addict numbers ent net disutility.
(Califano, 2007). However the impact of decrimi- The metaphor of a temporal horizon suggests
nalization could only be observed if the present legal a boundary beyond which consequences become
regime were to be suspended10. In the same way, invisible. However, the distance to the horizon is

618 risk and c ult ure


set by the observer’s focus, which is determined by a through the relatively ineffective method of post-
mix of cultural, organizational, and personal influ- approval adverse reaction reports. For instance,
ences (Heyman et al., 2010, Chapter 5). Although an annual recurrence rate of 1–2% after 10 years
easy enough to recognize when attention is drawn has been found for one form of testicular cancer
in that direction, awareness of the unavoidable arbi- (Dearnaley, Huddart, & Horwich, 2001).
trariness of time frames is particularly susceptible to In the UK, confidential inquiries into untoward
collective taking for granted. Unless social actors are deaths such as suicides of former mental health ser-
oriented toward similar time frames, organized coor- vice users are undertaken if the person had been
dination of their risk management efforts becomes in contact with health or social care professionals
almost impossible. In particular, those who set dif- less than a year before their death. Again, a cut-off,
ferent time frames will draw different utilitarian however necessary, interpretively dismembers the
conclusions even if they share the same values and chain of causation at an arbitrary point. A mental
probabilistic expectations, as illustrated above in health service manager (personal communication
relation to nuclear waste. However, this requirement to the author) indicated that his trust would prefer
to segment time in order to estimate expected value a shorter risk ownership period, of 6 months. This
flies in the face of multiple causal pathways which shift would narrow the scope of service risk ‘owner-
do not fit into single time segments. For instance, ship’, thereby reducing the number of adverse events
women who decline prenatal screening for Down’s for which they would be held accountable. The
syndrome in order to avoid the stress of being tested probability of discharged patients being involved in
can argue that this stress would itself cause long- adverse events would be reduced, although, unfor-
term risk to the baby on account of the link between tunately, patient welfare would not be improved.
pregnant women’s emotional well-being and fetal Any apparent risk reduction would result solely
health, a concern illustrated by the following quota- from changing the temporal boundaries within
tion (Heyman & Henriksen, 2001, p. 150). which probabilities were calculated.
Finally, UK smoking cessation programs have
Interviewer: How did you feel in the weeks that you
adopted a de facto time horizon of 2 weeks for iden-
were waiting for the results?
tifying “successful” quitting (The NHS Information
Pregnant woman: Oh it was awful. The result,
Centre, 2008). This temporal cut-off ensures a
waiting . . . Cos I was saying, “Ee, this baby will come
high success rate because it excludes anyone who
out miserable little” . . . I mean, when you read the books
relapses more than 2 weeks after the outcome is
and that, you think, “Oh well, you know, three, four
assessed, thereby potentially inflating the ‘chance’
weeks”. But, like, you’re wishing your life away, and it’s
of success’.
awful, you know. (Research interview with pregnant
The micro- and macropolitics of temporal hori-
woman aged 40 years who opted for amniocentesis)
zon setting can easily be identified when attention
The juxtaposition of multiple time frames in is drawn to them. Although shorter time frames do
the above quotation well illustrates the heuristic not necessarily generate substantially different risk
simplification required to confine outcome scan- assessments, they do work against questions about
ning within a particular time period. For the pre- longer term consequences being asked. Despite its
sent purpose of reviewing the relationship between significance, time framing remains largely invisi-
risk and culture, three further examples of time- ble. Indeed, the collective de facto failure to extend
framing drawn from the field of health care will global time framing beyond the next few decades
be outlined below: randomized controlled trials; is condemning the entire human species to almost
confidential suicide inquiries; and smoking cessa- certain disaster (hardly risk) through runaway cli-
tion programs. mate change and resource depletion.
Randomized controlled drug trials for curative
cancer treatments usually measure clinical effective- Risk, Culture, and Collective Deletion
ness through 5-year survival rates. Adoption of this The final step in the present analysis of the
time frame makes research comparable, provides a interrelationships between risk and culture will
cut-off which limits research costs, and allows timely gingerly explore one important implication of iden-
product development. But a price has to be paid for tifying the unexamined shared presuppositions on
this and any other time frame, in that it excludes which all societal manifestations of risk must rest.
longer-term effects which can only be identified Although more assumed than discussed in the social

h eym a n 619
sciences, the presence of a collective silencing pro- recurrence. Overwhelming non-urgency about the
cess is implied by all interpretivist theories which looming catastrophe of human induced runaway
point to concealed presuppositions at the heart of global warming provides the most alarming exam-
any social order. This issue is discussed below in ple because of its historic imminence and long-term
relation to the idea of collective “deletion” (Law, disastrous consequences. In relation to public health,
1995; Van Loon, 2002). despite strong evidence from migration studies that
Risks, like all forms of contingency, are located myopenigenic urban environments greatly increase
in the minds of observers, in contrast to particular the prevalence of short-sightedness (Morgana &
events which merely happen. Because absolutely Rose, 2005), this now common childhood condi-
anything might occur, individuals cannot avoid tion is not viewed as a risk to be managed. In these
choosing which possibilities to concern themselves and many other cases, the absence of high level con-
with. However, societies and social groups could not cern or resource mobilization provides false reassur-
function if their members attended to wholly dif- ance that there is not a contingency to be managed.
ferent risks. Cultures protect their members from Unfortunately, however, for this line of reasoning,
this chaotic fate by encouraging them to share their what appears entirely rational from one cultural
orientations toward what might happen. Such align- perspective will look insane from another. A snake-
ments, however fragile and temporary, bestow an handling preacher in Tennessee, shocked that the
aura of materiality on the collective selection of some author of Salvation on Sand Mountain did not have
but not other contingencies. Social actors managing any snakes in his car, asked, “What’s the matter with
a particular risk tend to adopt the “natural attitude” you boys? . . . Are you crazy?” (Covington, 1995).
(Schutz, 1962), treating it as a material entity, while Qualitative research offers more direct glimpses
directing attention away from the culturally shared of the postulated deletion process at the individual
interpretive steps without which it could not ‘exist’. level through inviting reflectivity. The following
Van Loon (2002, p. 54), drawing on Law (1995), extract from a research interview with a doctor who
has argued that the societal establishment of a risk advised pregnant women about prenatal screen-
requires a collective deletion process which dis- ing for Down’s syndrome (Heyman & Henriksen,
tances the necessary interpretive foundations from 2001, p. 42), unusually, captures the deletion pro-
conscious scrutiny. Deletion transforms a small cess in an answer to a thought-provoking question
selection from the unbounded realm of possibility about clinical practice.
into ‘real’ and controllable risks, which are therefore
worthy of organized attention, while background- Interviewer: Do you talk to them [pregnant women]
ing all others as either invisible or inevitable and so about Down’s syndrome, about what Down’s
unmanageable. For a risk to acquire the status of syndrome is?
an (apparently) material entity, the societal deletion Doctor: No, I don’t actually . . . interesting. And
process must itself be deleted, and so on, creating a yet, of course, that is addressed in the film [provided
fragile spiral of shared silence. for pregnant women], isn’t it? Perhaps I should do.
This analysis raises the further question of how (Research interview with doctor who advised women
deletion might be detected. Unfortunately for social about chromosomal screening)
scientists, the postulated silencing process works Another doctor working at the same hospital
against its direct observation. Although inevitably appeared more resistant to undeletion of questions
controversial, it is possible to point to breathtak- about the nature of Down’s syndrome (Heyman &
ing risk blindness as evidence of culturally fuelled Henriksen, 2001, p. 42).
deletion on the grounds that individual human
beings, left to themselves, could not display the Interviewer: Do you talk about Down’s syndrome?
required levels of stupidity! To put this point less Doctor: No.
pugnaciously, an observer who detects massive dis- Interviewer: What Down’s syndrome is?
crepancies between social actors’ goals and utili- Doctor: No. I assume that they understand, and
tarian calculations might infer collective deletion. they’ve read the leaflet before they came to see me,
For instance, during economic bubbles, including because we see about eight or nine new bookings every
the one which collapsed in 2007, financial play- clinic. We don’t really have time to go through this.
ers appear idiotically impervious to the inevitable (Research interview with doctor who advised women
credit crunch end-point, despite their historic about chromosomal screening)

620 risk and c ult ure


As these quotations illustrate, the cultural exis- contingency would not matter), and analysis con-
tence of a risk depends as much on what is kept off fined within a time frame which makes it quantifi-
the agenda as with what is articulated. able and manageable. Risk-thinking, the currently
dominant approach to contingency, differs from
Conclusions others not in these three respects, but through its
This chapter has explored the relationship use of probabilistic reasoning. The universal numer-
between risk and culture. Given the vast scope of the ical expression of probability as a proportion of
latter, the analysis has been confined to late modern unity conceals a variety of inference forms such as
societies in which contested risk issues take centre modelling and motivation assessment. The present
stage The discussion has focused on one aspect of chapter has focused on a third form, induction from
culture, the implicit and partly shared presupposi- observed frequencies, the most important method
tions on which risk understandings are predicated. for grounding probabilities in health and other
A concern with low visibility processes can be seen fields which deal with large numbers of cases. The
in major social scientific theories of risk, although ubiquity of probabilistic reasoning conceals its eso-
conceptualized differently. Late-modern risk con- teric but required working assumptions: that mem-
sciousness, has been variously viewed as resulting bers of an assigned category ‘carry’ its aggregated
from struggles over recognition of the ecological rate of risked outcome occurrence; that currently
crisis (Beck, 1992), the vulnerabilities of particular unpredicted variance within a category results from
cultures (Douglas & Wildavsky, 1983), systemic randomness; and that past patterns provide a reli-
role fragmentation (e.g., Japp & Kusche, 2008) and able guide to the future.
the evolution of a new mode for transmitting social This interpretive architecture involves more
power (O’Malley, 2008). The present chapter has than a cultural curiosity. It has important implica-
homed in on the shared but unstated presupposi- tion for fields such as health and social care. Many
tions underlying risk-thinking itself. probabilities of an outcome category can be derived
The best starting point for the analysis of risk- from empirical observation, making chance itself
thinking is contingency, a universal, linguistically (the merely metaphorical projection of uncertainty
mediated human capacity to envisage multiple in the non-quantum world at least) open to man-
possible future, or past but unknown, outcomes. agement. Individuals can acquire higher risk status
Although experienced as real, contingencies can- and all that may go with it, including anxiety, stig-
not exist in nature where events simply happen, matization, and moral imperatives, simply by being
but must be located in socially constituted minds. assigned to a category. Preventative endeavours can
Given the unlimited scope of what might come to create self-sustaining epistemological loops. These
pass, cultures have to coordinate contingency selec- and no doubt other non-obvious consequences of
tion in order to make coherent organized social risk-thinking can easily be observed, but remain
interaction possible. This collective feat of align- largely unexamined.
ment tends to be achieved outside conscious scru-
tiny, which would undermine the prevailing social Future Directions
order by invoking the infinity of possibility. The An interstellar journalist depicting life on early
forging of sets of shared, although always fragile, twenty-first century earth might point out that a
working assumptions about contingencies occurs small proportion of its rampantly dominant species
at two levels: firstly, the formulation of contin- enjoy pampered lives, while many others struggle
gency itself (e.g., as the outcome of divine justice, in abject poverty, and other forms of life become
predestined fate or quasi-random processes); and, extinct at an ever-increasing rate. He might note the
secondly, the construction of specific contingencies widespread although not globally universal influence
within a generic interpretive framework. In relation of risk consciousness, but then contrast huge invest-
to the present focus, the study of risk as a type of ment in warding off military threats with organized
contingency can be differentiated from the study of indifference toward looming climate change and
particular risks. resource depletion catastrophes.
For events to be viewed contingently, the unlim- Delving into human history, he might com-
ited variety of nature must be interpretively reduced ment wryly on the well-known but ignored exem-
to a small number of homogenized and differenti- plar of Easter Island, whose inhabitants chopped
ated categories, these categories valued (otherwise a down every tree, thereby depriving themselves of

h eym a n 621
a life-supporting environment, and even a means a focus on risk-thinking does draw attention to one important,
of escape. Finally, he would look to explain this available interpretive slant with the potential to shape experience
and decision-making about foods. Only in risk-oriented cultures
breathtaking injustice and short-sightedness, point- is it even possible to actively take risks.
ing to the might of organized commercial interests 3. Professor Sir Roy Meadow was initially struck off the UK
and the collusion of both lobbied politicians and medical register for making gross statistical errors which led
the prosperous minority. Seeking to illustrate his to the unsafe murder conviction of Sally Clark. Meadow had
report with a topical story about ecological reck- advised the court that the chance of a second, unexplained nat-
ural cot death in a family was about 73,000,000:1, but a case
lessness combined with global injustice, he might review concluded that this probability was actually 200:1. He
compare the justifiable outrage which greeted a cat- was reinstated after appealing on the grounds that his expert tes-
astrophic 2010 oil spill in the US waters of the Gulf timony was given in good faith (Samanta, 2006). Meadow was
of Mexico with relaxed indifference to much larger considered to have erred by straying from medical to statistical
routine annual spillages in poor countries such as matters about which he lacked competence. This tragic example
illustrates the quagmires which all self-proclaimed risk ‘experts’,
Nigeria and Ecuador. including critical social scientists, get themselves into. The above
Such gloomy reflections appear to overshadow judgment also raises questions about the status of medical exper-
the interpretive niceties analyzed in the present tise itself since probabilistic reasoning plays a fundamental role
chapter, making the latter appear trivial by compar- in its knowledge base.
ison. However, these soft considerations are directly 4. Readers who have undergone elementary statistics courses
may recognize the term ‘contingency table’ in relation to the chi-
connected to hard material realities. Looking at risk square test. A two-dimensional contingency table relates two or
thinking as a form of contingency thinking reveals a more categories of two variables, allowing conditional probabil-
fundamental contrast between the infinity of possi- ities to be inductively estimated (e.g., the chances of men versus
bility and the organized selection of a few outcomes women living beyond their 70th birthday). The computational
for organized attention. Analysis of the metaphor- simplicity of such calculations belies the complex and problem-
atic tacit categorisation processes on which they are predicated..
ical lens of risk can draw attention to the narrow- 5. Luhmann (1993, p. 23) takes a different view, arguing
ness of the light beam shed on possibility by any that, “Only in the case of risk, does decision making (that is to
form of collectively activated risk management. It say contingency) play a role”. One difficulty with this analysis is
thereby serves a constructively anarchic function, that it generates borderline cases which might or might not be
transmitted via the potentially explosive power of awarded the status of contingency because opinions can differ as
to whether outcome probabilities can be influenced. Luhmann
ideas. Subversive questions can be asked about the (1993, p. 26) has to insist rather primly that this attribution does
ontology of risk objects (e.g. depression, terror- not depend “on the whim of the observer”. Such awkwardness can
ism), the value judgements implicit in perceptions be avoided in a way which remains true to the experience of con-
of adversity (e.g. the birth of a disabled child), the tingency, for example, of somebody waiting to hear whether or
soundness of probabilistic reasoning (e.g. the cal- not they have terminal cancer, by separating a sense of alternative
outcomes being possible from views about their controllability;
culation of life expectancy) and the setting of time and by insisting that contingency is properly located in the mind,
frames (e.g. 5-year survival for drug treatments). not in events, which merely happen.
The considerations outlined in this chapter, and in 6. Although not uncontroversial, this widely accepted bound-
more detail elsewhere (Heyman et al., 2010) point ary is empirically fragile, since nobody knows the point at which
to important issues about risk, which the social global warming will become self-sustaining and beyond human
control. Boundary-setting, however dubious, provides the neces-
sciences have neglected, perhaps because even the sary starting point for the challenging task of mobilizing inter-
gurus of this field have tended in practice to neglect national prophylaxis. This coordinating function can only work
the prior question of what risk is. effectively if doubts, however obvious, are tentatively set aside.
7. The present author is indebted to Jaan Valsiner for draw-
ing his attention to this historical connection. The analysis of
Notes contingency also resonates with Sartre’s Nausea (1938/2000) and
1. O’Malley (2008, p. 56) usefully distinguishes ‘governmental- Being and Nothingness (1943/2003), but the present author does
ity’ from ‘Governmentality’. The former generic term refers to the not feel sufficiently knowledgeable to risk pursuing these con-
many interpretive frameworks within which social power is or has nections.
been transmitted (e.g. public torture and executions in medieval 8. Surprise may arise from event rarity (e.g., a large aster-
Europe). ‘Governmentality’ depicts a specific late-modern mode in oid colliding with Earth), or from sampling limitations, as with
which social power revolves around the internalization of risk-based Europeans not observing black swans before they discovered
moral imperatives directed at the behaviour of individuals. Australia. (However, the notion that all swans are white might
2. A distinction needs to be made between the ubiquitous be conserved through the classificatory manoeuvre of defining
presence of risk-thinking in every domain of late-modern life and black swans as a separate categorical entity.) Both kinds of jolt to
the variability of its influence. For example, the existence of risk expectation arise from practical limitations to inductive reason-
prescriptions for eating does not mean that all individuals will ing, which can never show that non-observed events might not
view eating primarily or even partly from this perspective. But happen in the future, or be discovered elsewhere.

622 risk and c ult ure


9. For example, people living in areas of greater socio- statistical inference. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
economic deprivation can obtain better annuity rates because Press.
they are assigned the lower life expectancy associated with their Hájek, A. (2008). A philosopher’s guide to probability. In
locality. G. Bammer, & M. Smithson (Eds.), Uncertainty and risk:
10. Recent press reports (e.g., Scientific American, 7/04/09), Multidisciplinary perspectives. London: Earthscan.
have drawn attention to the decriminalization of previously ille- Hansson, S. O. (2005). Seven myths of risk. Risk Management:
gal drug consumption in Portugal. As this example illustrates, the An International Journal, (7), 7–17.
inductive prevention paradox can be broken, but only through a Heyman, B. (Ed.) (1998). Risk, health and health care: A qualita-
leap into the unknown, which may be justified through theoreti- tive approach. London: Edward Arnold.
cal analysis. Others can then learn from the pioneers. Heyman, B. (2010). Editorial: Screening for health risks I:
11. The author is indebted to Lisa Reynolds of City Univer- A social science perspective. Health, Risk & Society, (12), 1–6.
sity for this instructive example. Heyman, B., & Henriksen, M. (2001). Risk, age and pregnancy.
A case study of prenatal genetic screening and testing.
Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.
References Heyman, B., Henriksen, M., & Maughan, K. (1998).
Alaszewski, A. (2010), Information about health risks. In Probabilities and health risks: A qualitative approach. Social
B. Heyman, M. Shaw, A. Alaszewski, & M. Titterton (Eds.), Science & Medicine, (9), 1295–1306.
Risk, safety and clinical practice: Health care through the lens of Heyman, B., Lewando Hundt, G., Sandall, J., Spencer, K.,
risk. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williams, C., Grellier, R., & Pitson, L. (2006). On being
Althaus, C. E. (2005). A disciplinary perspective on the episte- at higher risk: A qualitative study of prenatal screening for
mological status of risk. Risk Analysis, (25), 567–588. chromosomal anomalies. Social Science & Medicine, (62),
Atherton, E., & French, S. (1999). Valuing the future: A MADA 2360–2372.
example involving nuclear waste storage. Journal of Multi- Heyman, B., Shaw, M., Alaszewski, A., & Titterton, M. (2010).
Criteria Decision Analysis, (7), 204–321. Risk, safety and clinical practice: Health care through the lens of
Beck, U. (1992). Risk society: Towards a new modernity. London: risk. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sage. Janssen, I., Katzmarzyk, P. T., & Ross, R. (2004). Waist circum-
Beck, U. (2009). World at risk. Cambridge: Polity Press. ference and not body mass index explains obesity related
Bernstein, P. L. (1996). Against the gods: The remarkable story of health risk. American Journal of Clinical Nutrition, (79),
risk. New York: John Wiley & Sons. 379–384.
Bowker, G. C., & Star, S. L. (2000). Sorting things out: Classification Japp, K. P., & Kusche, I. (2008). Systems theory and risk.
and its consequences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. In J. O. Zinn (Ed.), Social theories of risk and uncertainty.
Bujra, J. (2000). Risk and trust. In P. Caplan (Ed.), Risk revisited. Oxford: Blackwell.
London: Pluto Press. Josephs, E. I., Valsiner, J., & Surgan, S. E. (1999). The process
Califano, J. A. (2007). Should drugs be decriminalised? No. of meaning construction: Dissecting the flow of semiotic
British Medical Journal, (335), 967. activity. In J. Brandtstädter and R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Action
Caplan, P. (2000). Risk revisited. London: Pluto Press. and self-development: Theory and research through the life span.
Covington, D. (1995). Salvation on Sand Mountain: Snake han- Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
dling and redemption in Southern Appalachia. Reading, MA: Kiviat, N. B., Hawes, S. E., & Feng, Q. (2008). Screening for
Addison-Wesley. cervical cancer in the era of the HPV vaccine: The urgent
Davison, C., Davey-Smith, G., & Frankel, S. (1992). Lay epi- need for both new screening guidelines and new biomarkers.
demiology and the prevention paradox: The implications Journal of the National Cancer Institute, (100), 290–291.
of candidacy for health education. Sociology of Health and Knight, F. (1921). Risk, uncertainty and profit. Boston: Houghton
Illness, (13), 1–19. Mifflin.
Dearnaley, D. P., Huddart, R. A., & Horwich, A. (2001). Law, J. (1995). Organization and semiotics: Technology, agency
Managing testicular cancer. British Medical Journal, (322), and representation. In J. Mouritsen, & R. Munroe (Eds.),
1583–1588. Accountability, power and ethos. London: Chapman and Hall.
Dölling, E. (2001). Alexius Meinong’s life and work. In Leontini, R. (2010). Genetic risk and reproductive decisions: Meta
L. Albertazzi, J. Dale, & R. Poli (Eds.), The School of Alexius and counter narratives. Health, Risk & Society, (12), 7–20.
Meinong. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Lewens, T. (Ed.) (2007). Risk: Philosophical perspectives. London:
Douglas, M. (1992). Risk and blame: Essays in cultural theory. Routledge.
London: Routledge. Luhmann, N. (1993). Risk: A sociological theory. New Brunswick,
Douglas, M. (1966). Purity and danger: An analysis of concepts of NJ: Aldine Transaction.
pollution and taboo. London: Routledge. Marusek, J. A. (2007). Solar storm threat analysis. Impact.
Douglas, M., & Wildavsky, D. (1983). Risk and culture: An essay Available online at http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/dow
on the selection of technological and environmental dangers. nload?doi=10.1.1.129.6527&rep=rep1&type=pdf.
Berkley, CA: University of California Press. McCormack, J. P., Levine M., & Rangno, R. E. (1997). Primary
Farahany, N., & Bernet, W. (2006). Behavioural genetics in prevention of heart disease and stroke: A simplified approach
criminal cases: Past, present, and future. Genomics, Society to estimating risk of events and making drug treatment
and Policy, (2), 72–79. decisions. Canadian Medical Association Journal, (157),
Garland, D. (2003). The rise of risk. In R. V. Ericson, & A. Doyle 422–428.
(Eds.), Risk and morality. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Meyer, M. C., Sherman, W. L., & Deeds, S. M. (2003). The
Hacking, I. (1975/2006). The Emergence of probability: A phil- course of Mexican history (7th ed.). New York: Oxford
osophical study of early ideas about probability induction and University Press.

h eym a n 623
Morgana, I., & Rose, K. (2005). How genetic is school myopia? Sartre, J. P. (1943/2003). Being and nothingness. London:
Progress in Retinal and Eye Research, (24), 1–38. Routledge.
O’Malley, P. (2008). Governmentality and risk. In J. O. Zinn (Ed.), Sartre, J. P. (1938/2000). Nausea. London: Penguin Modern
Social theories of risk and uncertainty. Oxford: Blackwell. Classics.
Oulton, K., & Heyman, B. (2009). Devoted protection: How Schutz, A. (1962). Collected papers, volume 1: The problem of
children with severe learning disabilities manage risks. social reality. The Hague, Netherlands: Martins Nijhoff.
Health, Risk & Society, (11), 313–319. Simon, J. (2003). Risking rescue: High altitude rescue as moral risk
Peterson, M. (2007). On multi-attribute risk analysis. In and moral opportunity. In R. V. Ericson & A. Doyle (Eds.),
T. Lewens (Ed.), Risk: Philosophical perspectives. Abingdon Risk and morality. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Oxford: Routledge. Singer, P. (2002). All animals are equal: Or why the ethical prin-
Petersen, A. (2009). The ethics of expectations: Biobanks and the ciple on which human equality rests requires us to extend
promise of personalised medicine. Monash Bioethical Review, equal consideration to animals too. Originally printed 1990
(5),1–12. and reprinted in R. Chadwick & D. Schroeder (Eds.),
Power, M. (2004). The risk management of everything: Rethinking Applied ethics: Critical concepts in philosophy. London:
the politics of uncertainty. London: Demos. Routledge.
Power, M. (2007). Organized uncertainty: Designing a world of Home Office/Department of Health and Social Security (1975).
risk management. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Report of the committee on mentally disordered offenders.
Renn, O. (2008). Risk governance: Coping with uncertainty in a London: HMSO.
complex world. London: Earthscan. The Royal Society (1992). Risk: Analysis, perception and man-
Rescher, N. (1983). Risk: A philosophical introduction. Washington: agement. Report of a Royal Society study group. London: The
University Press of America. Royal Society.
Robertson, M. (2008). The loss of sadness: How psychiatry Van Loon, J. (2002). Risk and technological culture: Towards a
transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder. Acta sociology of virulence. London: Routledge.
Neuropsychiatrica, (20), 168–169. Zammit, S., Allebeck, P., Andreasson, S., Lundberg, I., &
Rosa, E. A. (2003). The logical structure of the social amplifica- Lewis, G. (2002). Self reported cannabis use as a risk factor
tion of risk framework (SARF): Metatheoretical foundations for schizophrenia in Swedish conscripts of 1969: Historical
and policy implications. In N. F. Pidgeon, R. E. Kasperson, cohort study. British Medical Journal, (325), 1199–1123.
& P. Slovic (Eds.), The social amplification of risk. Cambridge, Zinn, J. O. (Ed.) (2008). Social theories of risk and uncertainty.
UK: Cambridge University Press. Oxford: Blackwell.
Samanta, A. (2006). Medical experts, the law and professional
regulation. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, (99),
217–218.

624 risk and c ult ure


CHAPTER

Constructing Histories
28
Mario Carretero and Angela Bermudez

Abstract
In this chapter we discuss how people in present societies construct historical narratives. This
topic, related to the field of the teaching and learning of history, extends to the debates in the last
decade about the “history wars” maintained in numerous societies. All these cases share a process of
consumption and production of historical narratives. To this respect, school history master narratives
are analyzed in terms of six common features. On the other hand, a theoretical distinction between
Romantic and Enlightened functions of teaching of history is presented. From this point of view, significant
educational developments and research in this field are analyzed, showing the limitations and possibilities
of both functions. Finally, the relevance of socio-cultural theories for the field of learning and teaching
history is also presented, along with future developments in this area of study.
Keywords: learning history, historical narratives, national identities, constructivism

Questions regarding how people construct his- throughout the last decade (see Carretero, 2011,
torical narratives in current societies have taken a and Nakou and Barca, 2010 for comparative stud-
center stage in recent public and academic discus- ies of different countries). As it will be shown below,
sion. Intense debates are taking place in different these debates in different parts of the planet are the
countries about the kind of historical contents that result of social and political changes related to the
should be taught in the schools and through other increasing globalization process and their implica-
formal and informal educational devices (Seixas, tions on national identities (see Carretero, 2011,
2004). These debates started in the mid-1990s and for Europe and Latin America; Eklof, Holmes,
are still alive in many countries. A vivid example & Kaplan, 2005 for post-Soviet Russia; and The
is found in the recent controversy around the dic- Academy of Korean Studies, 2005, for African and
tates of the Texas Board of Education in the United Asian countries).
States. As a recent article in the New York Times
(February 11, 2010) reports, Inventing the Nation: Tailoring the Past
It is by no means casual that in a short span
“Conservative activists on the Texas Board of
of time, the teaching of history—a topic often
Education say that the authors of the Constitution
reserved to experts—became a prominent issue in
intended the United States to be a Christian nation.
furious public debates across the globe. History
And they want America’s history textbooks to say so.”
wars have led to the revision of the historical nar-
(Shorto, 2010)
ratives in which, as Hobsbawm said, “the nation
The saliency and significance of this issue is revealed in is invented” (1990; see also, Berger, Eriksonas, &
the “History Wars” sustained in numerous societies Mycock, 2008). Research conducted in several

625
countries in the last 10 years has documented production of a national rhetoric that homogenizes
how the production of school historical narratives popular views despite the complexities of the lived
is closely related to the construction of national past. Wineburg explains how, “In a curious twist
discourses (Carretero, 2011; Carretero & Kriger, of historical revision, Vietnam, in the eyes of these
2011; Van Sledright, 2008). Interestingly, this revi- young people, had become a war waged without
sion of historical narratives coincides with, and supporters,” and uses the concept of “occlusion” to
probably originates from, the intensification of the describe the process by which “stories, images, and
globalization process and its social, political, and cultural codes . . . become muted in the transmission
economic effects. Profound transformations such from one generation to the next” (Wineburg et al.,
as the crisis of political identities, the emergence 2007, pp. 65–66).
of new discussions about nationalisms, and the That the history taught to young people is tai-
re-signification of the question “Who are we?” in lored to fit with current national discourses had
any society affect the history that is taught to young already been evidenced in comparative analyses of
people. In the context of the European Union, for the history curricula. Several of these studies show
example, several countries have undertaken a rein- that the versions of the recent past taught to the
terpretation of the “national histories” taught in citizens of historically related societies could not
schools in light of the need to promote the notion differ more from each other. In some cases, man-
of a common future. In a different context, Russia datory school contents are presented in an outright
and the United States offer two salient examples of biased way and full of inexactitudes or falsities. In
similar dynamics. other cases, the interpretation of the past presents
Within a very short period of time, from 1991 to a vision that is hardly acceptable to the country
1992, all the history school contents in the former to which the comparison is made. For example,
Soviet Union, as well as in many communist coun- Spanish school textbooks have traditionally omit-
tries that were under its influence, were drastically ted essential issues on the American colonization,
modified (Ahonen, 1992, 1997). This entailed, such as the subjugation of indigenous people or
among other things, that millions of students of slavery as generalized social and economic practices.
different ages received a radically different version In contrast, such issues are highlighted in Mexican
of their national past, and of the past in general, or Brazilian textbooks (Carretero, Jacott, & López-
than what they had been taught in school up until Manjón, 2002). Similar findings are reported for
then. After one decade and a half of introducing France/Algeria, Great Britain/India, China/Japan
a liberal view of history in the schools, Russia is (Ferro, 1984/2002) and Korea/Japan (The Academy
now again reconsidering its position about essential of Korean Studies, 2005).
issues as Stalinism, in order to provide the Russian These different cases reveal intellectual and edu-
students a more positive view of their own past. cational movements in which a reconsideration of
Dramatic controversies have taken place in the last the past is emerging, favoring the profound revision
5 years about the educational decision, originated of national and local histories both at the academic
in Vladimir Putin’s office, to require the use of an level and at the school level. Despite the particu-
obligatory history textbook in any Russian second- larities of each case, they have certain features in
ary school (Halpin, 2007; Maier, 2005; Piattoeva, common:
2009).
In the United States, the neoconservative elite, a) The search for a significant relationship
which seized power in the 2000 and 2004 elections, between the representation of the past and
impugned the new school-taught history contents, formation of identity, whether national, local, or
which had been designed by numerous special- cultural;
ists as a result of a meticulous, professional, and b) The conflict between mythical and
widely democratic work (NCHS, 1994; Symcox objectified histories;
& Wilschut, 2009). The above-mentioned debate c) The social need to reelaborate past conflicts
about the Texas Board of Education (Shorto, 2010) in function of the undertaking of future
is clearly a continuation of these heated debates. projects, and
Uncovering a new angle of this issue, Wineburg’s d) The still incipient utility of generating a
study on the communication across generations comparison between alternative histories of the
about the Vietnam War shows the process of same past.

626 construct ing hi stor i e s


Evolving Approaches to the Study of the & Jacott, 1997). The goal of the study was to deter-
Production of Historical Narratives mine if college students were able to understand
Scholars in the field of history education have significant historical events based on abstract socio-
approached these phenomena in varied ways. economic and political causes, as opposed to per-
Ferro’s seminal study (1984/2002) on how the past sonalized motives that tend to be more concrete and
is taught to children around the world introduced typical of younger students. The interviewer asked a
the important distinction between official and unof- group of college students to explain what led to the
ficial histories, the first being the narratives con- defeat of the Arabs in the battle over Granada in
structed and maintained by the Nation-State and 1492, when the last Muslim ruler surrendered his
the second being the counter-narratives of minority kingdom to Ferdinand II of Aragon and Isabella I
groups. Further studies have examined this distinc- of Castile. This victory, which led to the definitive
tion in more depth. The recent history wars revived expulsion of the Arabs from the Iberian Peninsula
an interest in studying the processes of ideological (the territory that is Spain and Portugal today), is
production and distribution of official histories, considered an essential moment in Spanish his-
revealing through the analysis of curricula, text- tory because it represents the starting point of the
books, and the narratives of teachers and students Spanish Empire, followed soon after by Columbus’
how a hegemonic social and cultural device—the “discovery” of America, in an expedition financed
school history—contributes to create the cognitive by the aforementioned king and queen.
and affective foundations of “imagined communi- Pablo, one of the interviewees (21 years old),
ties” (Wertsch & Rozin, 2000). Wineburg and col- provided an account of the victory of the Catholic
leagues (2007, p.70) in turn, discuss this in terms monarchs that included most of the staple facts and
of Michael Schudson’s (1992, p. 64) distinction motifs of current historiographic research that has
between, interest theories, in which cultural mean- made its way into high-school and college history
ings are predetermined by an underlying economic courses. Dissecting the various pieces of his exten-
and political agenda, or semiotic theories, in which sive account we learn that:
cultural products become, by definition, expressions
• The Arabs first arrived in 711 and expanded
of the search for meaning (see also Valsiner, 2010).
throughout the peninsula within a few years.
Building upon and extending this tradition of
• They encountered a collection of disparate
research, a new and important line of questioning
medieval Christian kingdoms that where
has emerged: How do the conflicting narratives
establishing in the Iberian Peninsula since the
found in academic and public debates and in school
collapse of the Roman Empire.
textbooks, manifest in students’ minds? How do the
• There were many and frequent fights among
features characteristic of the process of social pro-
Christians rulers, who on occasions allied with
duction of historical narratives translate into the
Muslim rulers in an attempt to defeat their
processes of individual consumption of historical
opponents and conquer their territories.
narratives? This paper expands on this last line of
• At other times Arabs, Christians, and Jews
inquiry.
coexisted and developed peacefully.
• The frontiers of Arab and Christian domains
The Consumption of Historical Narratives
ebbed and flowed as different kingdoms expanded
Pablos’ Construction of the Reconquest:
and contracted throughout the 800 years in which
An Example
the Arabs resided in the Iberian Peninsula.
The following example of a historical narrative
• The Catholic king and queen where
offered by a Spanish college student illustrates the
monarchs of the Kingdoms of Aragon and Castile,
depth of these emerging questions. We will draw
respectively.
upon this example to discuss different layers of the
problem, and corresponding lines of inquiry about Pablo’s account displayed a relatively well-
the processes of production and consumption of developed capacity to form complex causal expla-
historical narratives. The narrative in this example nations, which is not uncommon among students
was collected during an interview conducted by one of his age and background. He considered multiple
of the authors as part of a research project investi- social, economic, and political factors, he weaved
gating the development of understanding of causal together long-term and mid-term processes with
explanations in history (Carretero, López-Manjón, more immediate events, and he kept an accurate

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 627
record of the chronology of key events and turning Reconquista was to retrieve something that was mine
points. Yet, shortly after completing this account and had been forcibly taken away.
Pablo paused for a few seconds and then offered an
On logical grounds, the first narrative under-
epilogue to his explanation that caught the atten-
mines the second: The Christian kingdoms did
tion of the interviewer: “Well, at any rate, the most
not have control over the whole territory, and they
important thing, which I didn’t mentioned before, is
did not conform to any sort of united entity. Thus,
that nobody likes his own nation to be invaded.” The
Spain, the historical subject of the Reconquest, did
interviewer probed what he meant: “Which nation
not exist when the Arabs arrived in 711, nor dur-
are you thinking about?” to which Pablo replied:
ing the hundreds of years when they occupied the
“Spain! The Muslims had invaded Spain since 711. So
Iberian Peninsula. In consequence, strictly speak-
really, what the Catholic King and Queen did was to
ing, there was no territory to be reconquered. The
finish up the Reconquest.”
first portion of Pablo’s account reflects this under-
Pablo’s epilogue revealed two competing narra-
standing. However, the very use of the concept of
tives that coexisted in his mind. At this point, the
Reconquista, prominent in the more traditional
narrative of the “Reconquest,” (or the Christian
historiography, determines how Pablo ultimately
reconquering of the Iberian Peninsula from the
makes sense of the past. He draws upon the “natural
Muslim invaders) displaced the more current his-
anger” that anyone would experience when “hav-
toriographic version that organized the first part of
ing one’s nation invaded” to explain the moral force
his interview. Interested by this apparent contradic-
that drove the Catholic Queen and King to the final
tion, the interviewer probed further (see Carretero,
victory. Then, he redefines the unsteady and conflic-
Kriger, & Lopez, 2010; Lopez, 2010).
tive expansion of the Christian kingdoms as a long
Interviewer: Why did this happen (the Reconquest)? and concerted effort on the part of the Christian
Pablo: Well, because the Arabs had wounded, so to rulers guided by the shared ontological purpose of
speak, the Spanish Christian pride. Then, as usual, you “recuperating” their vast territory lost to the Arabs
have to recover something that was taken away, at least since 711.
you have to try, it doesn’t matter how long it takes.
Interviewer: And the area that you have drawn as al Contradictions and Ruptures in the
Andalus [Arab territory, about one-third of the Iberian Construction of Historical Narratives
Peninsula] was it, at that time, rightfully Arabic? What How can Pablo sustain a complex causal explana-
do you think? tion of this historical event together with a mythical
Pablo: Well it is true that several centuries had passed, account of it? The coexistence of these two compet-
and it might be that they (the Arabs) had persuaded ing historical narratives in Pablo’s mind suggests that
themselves that they had the same right as the Chris- the process of consumption, and the related attempts
tians, or even more. But I still think that if that was at of meaning making, involve perhaps inevitable con-
first a Christian territory . . . what happened is that tradictions and ruptures. How do these happen?
it took them a long time to regain their territory. I still Where do they arise? How does the individual man-
think it’s legitimate Christian territory. age them? How do we account for them? These ques-
Interviewer: OK, we’ve been using about the word tions are central to the purpose of this paper, and the
‘Reconquest.’ Tell me a little about what that term following pages discuss different approximations to
means to you? them. Some emphasizes the socio-cultural processes
Pablo: Well, for me, to reconquer is to recover a territory that shape the individual’s construction of histori-
that it was assumed it was mine. You know, if I have cal narratives, while other approximations empha-
this whole table and I’m studying in it, and if you, or size the individual cognitive processes involved. We
another guy comes along and . . . if you ask me, then search also for interaction between the two.
maybe I’d say half and half, maybe . . . But if you just
come and take over, pushing me out bit by bit, little by The Pervasiveness of Ontological
little . . . if I put my books here but you still come a little Narratives
closer . . . Well, there has to come a time when Although Pablo demonstrates a rather abstract
I get angry and say: ‘Hey, what are you doing! Let and well-organized understanding of the past that
me . . . !’ But what we are talking about now is derives from the recent circulation of a new his-
something of much more importance, because what’s toriographic narrative in school textbooks and
mine is mine! Then, in my view, the goal of the public discourses, he simultaneously reveals a deep

628 construct ing hi stor i e s


internalization of an ontological and essentialist con- territory). Both elements are rooted in an ontolog-
cept of the Spanish nation that is pervasive in his ical assumption: Spain, the essential national spirit,
society. The following excerpt from a classical text- preexisted to the foundation of the nation itself and
book (Alvarez, 1965/1997) captures that view that led the actions of its people toward a predefined
once dominated the teaching of history in Spain, and destiny. Once the central motif of the Reconquest
still today has a strong hold on a variety of cultural is introduced in the account of the 800-year pres-
artifacts such as popular literature and movies, mon- ence of the Arabs in the Iberian Peninsula, the past
uments, and casual conversations. See Box 28.1. is reorganized in such way that serves to justify past,
Demonstrating the pervasiveness and importance present, and future actions. In a mere chronological
of this narrative of the Reconquista, former Prime sense, 800 years is quite a long process to “recuper-
Minister Jose María Aznar, claimed in a recent speech ate” a territory. Still, national narratives tend to use
“the Arabs never apologized for having invaded Spain time in such a mythical way2.
13 centuries ago” (El Pais, September 23, 2006).
Content analysis of Spanish textbooks and their Narratives as Cultural Tools
changes in the last decades (Carretero, 2011; Valls, Socio-cultural analyses of school history contents
2007) coincide on the importance and ubiquity of show how closely these constitute “official narra-
the Reconquest narrative as a central constituent of tives” that purposefully seek to determine subjects’
the national identity. The construction of Spain and representations of the past. The nation’s past, pre-
the Spaniards as heroic subjects, opposite to, and sent, and future are organized in official versions of
able to overcome the Arabs, is a purposeful cultural the so-called “nation’s history” that are distributed
production. Spanish collective memory was first by schools. These official versions carry an argumen-
created during the eighteenth and nineteenth cen- tative continuity: an “identitary us” is constituted,
turies as a basic support for the construction of a and the typical nineteenth-century conception of
national identity, and it has since been maintained the “nation” as a community of destiny (Smith,
on a basic opposition to the Arab identity (Alvarez 1991) is transmuted into new imagined communi-
Junco, 2011; Boyd, 1996). Within it, the notion of ties. Hobsbawm (1990) defined this as “the nation’s
“reconquering” serves to organize the past in a narra- programmatic mythology.”
tive structure that defines a heroic character (Spain) “National histories” were born to be taught. They
endowed with an intrinsic purpose (recuperating its are contained in a variety of records such as monu-
ments and patriotic celebrations. Patriotic rituals
play an important role in many countries. The case of
Box 28.1 The Reconquest: Asturias, Latin America is telling. In countries like Argentina,
León, and Castile Brazil, Chile, or Uruguay, at least four historical and
patriotic commemorations take place in school every
The Reconquest: this is how we recall the
year. They consist of dramatizations and discussions
struggle sustained by Christians during almost
about the events, battles, and national heroes related
eight centuries against the Arabs in order to
to the processes of independence of each of these
expel them from Spain.
countries. In the United States we find these kinds
Spain is among the nations that have con-
of activities in many historical sites and monuments
tributed the most to the world’s civilization and
(Beckstead, 2012), besides the activities performed at
had greater influence in world history.
schools. These scenarios, rather ignored until now by
To prove this, it is enough to mention: its
researchers, convey an important amount of histor-
defense of Europe during the Reconquest,
ical content that influences students’ understanding
when she stood between Europe and the Arabs;
of the history contained in the formal curriculum
the discovery, colonization and civilization of
and textbooks (Carretero, 2011). Students consume
America, as well as the heroism she deployed in
and use national historical narratives that they learn
the Independence War, which contributed to
not only from the history textbooks but also from
Europe’s salvation from Napoleon’s Caesarism.
these kinds of events, in and out of the school. The
This Spain is your Motherland. Know her
school record contained in textbook narratives is
history. Always take from her the virtuous and
probably one of the most important and effective
heroic examples offered to you by your ancestors
means in determining how people consume the nar-
and try to be their continuator at all times.
ratives produced in their respective societies. School

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 629
versions, usually heroic and celebratory, unite stories results in greater difficulty in understanding, and
with different degrees of importance in a long narra- lower levels of student motivation. As pointed
tive chain that links them by virtue of the role they out by Barton and Levstik (2004) these individ-
play in the construction of what we might call the ual narratives have the power to humanize his-
nation’s “saga.” Most of these sagas adopt a teleolog- torical contents. However, this kind of narrative
ical form; destiny is already contained in the origins, greatly influences the way students understand
and knowledge of the “roots” of a nation is indis- and analyze information about the past, and they
pensable for knowing how to act in the future. As may result in a series of typical biases that hinder
Alridge (2006) and Straub (2005) have shown, these a more complex understanding. When the nar-
“master narratives” pervade underneath a variety of ratives are purely personal or individual, there is
specific contents and through time. Although spe- an absence of structural causal explanations based
cific narratives may change frequently, these under- on social, political, or economic factors. In many
lying master narratives rarely change, and manifest instances they personify a historic event in a par-
once and again in subsequent revisions. From the ticular character, which is represented as the main
perspective of socio-cultural psychology, official nar- actor and the cause of its development (Carretero
ratives on the nation’s origin constitute cultural tools et al., 1994; Hallden, 1994). We find examples of
(Wertsch & Rozin, 2000) that configure schematic such embodiment in the “discovery” of America
templates in students’ minds. These schematic tem- by Christopher Columbus, or the emancipation
plates define the underlying structure of historical process by Abraham Lincoln (Alridge, 2006). This
narratives and of people’s understanding of them. simplification of historical contents decontextual-
izes the events of the past, and relegates to oblivion
Uses and Consequences of Individual other characters or social groups that participated
and National Formats of Historical in them.
Narratives National narratives are another type of narra-
Although historical knowledge does not only tive frequently found in schools and in daily life.
occur in a narrative format, it often does. Barton and In schools across the world, the study of history
Levstik (2004) distinguish two specific types of nar- often focuses on the history of their own coun-
ratives that appear prominently in education (and in try. This is not surprising if we consider, as we will
other cultural practices): individual narratives and discuss later, how the teaching of history emerged
national narratives. The typical uses of these narra- at the end of the nineteenth century. National nar-
tive formats have profound implications for students’ ratives diminish the importance of other stories:
construction of historical understanding. Students do not have access to the most contro-
Individual narratives focus on the personal lives versial aspects of history, hindering their under-
of important historical figures, as opposed to those standing of conflicts, dilemmas, and ultimately,
whose focus are more abstract entities and events the reality of democratic societies in which they
such as economic systems, civilizations, processes of live (Barton & McCully, 2010). In this way, they
social change, and impersonal concepts of this kind. determine the type of explanations that students
We can all recall these individual narratives from give to critical historical events. For example, in
our own school experience: stories about Columbus, American textbooks, the vast majority of national
Julius Caesar, or Napoleon would be classic exam- narratives are organized around the concepts of
ples. Paxton (1999) and Alridge (2006), in com- progress and freedom, and students reuse these
prehensive analyses of American textbooks, show motifs to explain past events (Barton & Levstik,
that the narratives about “great” men and events 2004). Thus, the resistance of Native Americans in
that led America to an ideal of progress and civiliza- the face of waves of European settlers is seen as an
tion continue to be the prototypical way in which obstacle to achieve progress, and the Vietnam War
many historians and textbooks spread knowledge. is justified as an American response to the need to
Frequently, these figures are studied in isolation bring freedom to that country. In relation to other
from other individuals and events that constitute countries, where also native history is also part of
its historical context, while the more controversial the culture, similar contents can be found in both
aspects of their lives are not reflected. textbooks (Carretero, 2011; Clark, 2007) and stu-
The use of these types of individual narratives is dents’ minds (Carretero, Gonzalez, Rodriguez, &
justified with the idea that a more abstract content Carreño, 2010).

630 construct ing hi stor i e s


Features of the Production and Exclusion-Inclusion as a Logical
Consumption of Historical Narratives Operation that Contributes to
Several studies (Carretero, 2011; Carretero & Establish the Historical Subject
Kriger, 2011; Van Sledright, 2008) describe the A salient feature of this example is the mas-
features and functioning of historical narratives and tery of the distinction between “we” (in this case
explain their presence in the production of school “Argentineans,” but of course the historical subject
history textbooks and other cultural artifacts that could be of any nationality) and “the others” that
support the Nation-States. We can distinguish six the child shows. As different studies have shown,
salient characteristics: this distinction concerning the national “we” is
already mastered by children between 6 and 8 years
1) Exclusion-inclusion as logical operation of age (Barret & Buchanan-Barrow, 2005), even
contributing to establish the historical subject. though children are not able at that age to define
2) Identity as both cognitive and affective precise attributes of this category. In our exam-
anchor. ple, it is interesting to note that this national “we”
3) Mythical and heroic character. is not only social and political, but also historical
4) Simplification of historical events around the (Carretero, 2011). The very explicit “not you, but
main motive of search of freedom. we, the Argentineans” evidences that Federico is
5) National narratives offer fundamental moral already making a basic distinction based on a logical
examples and directions. operation of inclusion vs. exclusion, which he will
6) Ontological and essentialist conception of probably continue to use in his learning of history,
the nation and its nationals. in and out of school. Typically, this logical opera-
Most of these features have been identified and tion is performed in such a way that positive aspects
explained in the process of production of historical are almost always assigned to the national “we,”
narratives by cultural media (school history text- while any critical or negative aspects are assigned
books among others). What is less clear is how they to “the others” (Todorov, 1998). Likewise, negative
manifest in minds of citizens who appropriate these features of the national “we” tend to be ignored o
narratives. A brief example will assist us in elucidat- justified. It is reasonable to presume that historical
ing these features, both in the production and the master narratives will be learned and developed later
consumption of these narratives. on based on this fundamental distinction (Barton
Consider the following excerpt from a dialogue and Levstik, 1998), where the national “we” is being
between Federico, a 6-year-old Argentinean boy used as very well-defined category.
who describes to a Spanish interviewer a school
activity in which he and his friends dramatized Identity as Both Cognitive and
the events of May 25th, celebrated in the coun- Affective Anchor
try as the day of Independence from Spain. After The distinctions concerning a national “we” vs.
recounting several details of their reenactment, the the “others” is probably based on emotional and
interviewer asked: “But, what was the celebration affective features as much as on cognitive ones
about?” to which Federico answered, “Well, I do (Barret & Buchanan-Barrow, 2005). This emotional
not know really, but I think it was when we were dimension facilitates a strong identification process.
able to be free.” Probing his thinking, the Spanish In this example, Federico uses the narrative in such
interviewer paraphrased his words asking: “When way that includes him in a particular community,
we were able to free?” Immediately, Federico cor- the Argentinean one. In this regard, it is also inter-
rected “well . . . .you were not. We were. This is to esting to notice how the process of categorization
say, we, the Argentineans.” “Oh, well, it is true,” the in Federico’s mind draws no distinction between
Spanish visitor conceded, “you, the Argentineans, past and present times: the “we” of the present that
were free, but why, how did it happen?” Federico includes him (Argentineans) is the same “we” of
responded, in a very frank manner, “Well, I am not the past (the patriots of the Virreinato del Rio de la
sure if I understood well the whole thing. I better Plata). This overlap, which makes no sense from a
ask the teacher again . . . but I think we were free historical point of view (Argentina did not exist at
when . . . we, the Argentineans, escaped from the the time of independence. Sensu strictu they were
Pharaoh” (Carretero, 2007, p. 127). inhabitants of the Virreinato del Rio de la Plata,

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 631
not Argentineans), makes perfect sense to Federico theories would predict the gradual disappearance
because, as the master narrative dictates, the essence of mythical elements. For example, well-established
of the Argentinean nation pre-existed the facts. theories of narrative development (Egan, 1997)
In order to fully understand how historical nar- claim that human beings develop a narrative ability
ratives are constructed it is essential to know much that goes through a number of stages: somatic (0 to
more precisely how these emotional and affective 2 years of age), mythical (3 to 6 years), heroic (7 to
components of historical contents influence stu- 10 years), philosophical (11 to 15 years) and ironic
dents’ minds from an early age, and in particular, (15 years of age and onward). Thus, if national his-
how they provide support to the logical distinctions torical narratives often maintain their mythical and
of exclusion and inclusion. heroic components even during adolescence and
adulthood, times at which individuals should be
Mythical and Heroic Characters able to generate philosophical and ironic histori-
One of the main differences between historical cal narratives, it is worth investigating what kind of
and mythical explanations is precisely the absence of socio-cultural mechanisms yield this result.
time in the latter. It is totally irrelevant, for example,
to know Oedipus’ date of birth or any other spe- Simplification of Historical Events
cific temporal markers. Myths and mythical figures around the Main Motive of Search
and narratives are usually free of time restrictions. for Freedom
In contrast, one can say that history is making its National narratives tend to simplify the enor-
appearance when time and its constraints are intro- mous complexity of historical processes and events
duced into a narrative. In our example, it is clear around core common moral themes. These moral
that Federico’s understanding of Argentinean inde- themes typically relate to the sense of destiny por-
pendence events does not include a firm grasp of the trayed in teleological accounts of the past. Several
temporal dimension. Pharaoh’s intrusion aside, it is studies have documented how this feature mani-
telling that he links elements from a narrative of lib- fests in students’ thinking. For example, Barton
eration in ancient Egyptian times with a narrative of and Levstik (2004) and Penuel and Werstch (2000)
liberation of the Latin American bourgeoisie during studied how students understand the process of
the nineteenth-century revolutions. In fact, this is a independence of their own nations, drawing upon
common characteristic of historical understanding a historical master narrative in which the search for
at this age, in which children find it very difficult freedom is the core theme, and the starting point of
to understand and use chronologies and other con- the new community. Their representations consist of
ventional representations of time in history (Barton, a network of rather concrete concepts. Independence
2002; Carretero, Asensio, & Pozo, 1991). The appeal resulted from the intention of a group of individuals
of mythical national narratives probably builds on to be free from some form of domination. In the
this developmental trait. Usually, children are not case of many American, African, and Asian coun-
able to master chronological aspects of historical time tries, the independence narratives obviously relate
until they are approximately 12 years of age. to the domination of one of the European nations:
One could hypothesize that as students grow Spain, the United Kingdom, France, and so forth
and improve their understanding of historical time, (The Academy of Korean Studies, 2005; Ferro,
core mythical elements of their historical narratives 1984/2002). Abstracts and complex causal factors,
would subside. However, if we recall Pablo’s account such as economic relationships and interests, polit-
of the Reconquest of Spain from the Arabs, it is clear ical developments, and international influences
that mythical features remain in the historical narra- are basically absent of these narratives, even in the
tives of children older than 6 years old. Although the case of adolescents and adults (Carretero, López
temporal frame may adjust to disciplinary canons, Manjón, & Jacott, 1997). The following examples
the heroic tone and the essentialist understanding (Carretero, Gonzalez et al., 2010) illustrate this fea-
of the nation evidence the permanence of mythical ture as interviewees explain how the independence
narratives’ core elements. This is, indeed, a striking of their respective countries came to happen:
permanence, at least from a developmental perspec- 12-year-old Dario responded that: “Yes, the Spanish
tive. Besides the cognitive-developmental models dominated . . . It was when they used us as slaves, wasn’t
of historical understanding, other developmental it? And we wanted independence.”

632 construct ing hi stor i e s


Guillermo, one of the adult subjects interviewed the national “we,” and the second one is related to
expresses: “Well, we said to ourselves, this is enough. “they.” Thus, the logical and moral truth is always
And we were able to say this to the Spanish.” on the “we” side. For example, in our research
Moreover, it is common to find in such histori- (Carretero, Kriger, & Lopez, 2010) we have found
cal narratives that social groups and social condi- how young adolescents considered that Christians
tions that put into question the central theme of the have the right to “recuperate” the territory, inhabited
narrative are excluded or represented in misleading by the Arabs for 800 years, because it was consid-
ways. For example, although a significant number ered “Spanish territory.” On the contrary, according
of Argentinean children and adolescents think that to the same students, the Christians have no right
Spaniards treated the American “colonists” as slaves, to conquer the American territories because they
at the same time they ignore the enormous economic belonged to the natives.
significance of the slavery of the AfricanAmerican Second, master narratives offer living examples of
population, which, in all countries, was main- civic virtue, particularly of loyalty. As it can be easily
tained by the colonists well after the independence inferred, this loyalty function was essential in the
(Carretero, 2011). construction of the nation, and it can still be found
Along similar lines, in the United States the in many symbolic forms. For example, if we con-
historical master narrative of search for freedom sider the way that the World Soccer Championship
organizes around the theme of progress (Barton is followed by any citizen in the world, it would be
& Levstik, 1998). This tendency to consider that inconceivable that a citizen could support any team
society undergoes ever-increasing progress—both belonging to a different nation, even though that
technological and in regards to the standards of team may play better.
living—is quite naïve and gives rise to oversimplifi-
cation in historical understanding. Insofar progress Ontological and Essentialist
is deemed as the teleological direction of a society, Conception of the Nation and
the complexity of a nation’s experience must be Its Nationals
disguised. In their effort to simplify the account of events,
national narratives also reduce the subject of his-
National Narratives Offer Fundamental tory to particular groups who participated in the
Moral Examples and Directions events and achieved the predestined goals. This is
The moral dimension of historical master narra- an extension of the function of master narratives
tives is quite an obvious one, but unfortunately it discussed earlier. The subject of national narratives
has not been explored enough, particularly from an may well be a collective one, but its features coin-
empirical point of view (Barton & Levstik, 2004). cide with those of one single and particular group.
Interestingly enough, on the classical debates on the We can anticipate that in the studies discussed
nature of historical knowledge, the view of White above, the historical subjects of students’ narra-
(1987) about historiography as a production of nar- tives of Independence are influential Caucasian
ratives having an important moral component has colonists, most of them established merchants and
had an increasing influence. But this idea has not landowners. They are the sole protagonists of the
received much attention as an inspiring hypothesis narrative because they embody the struggle for
in order to test if school master narratives are pro- freedom or progress. Interestingly, students tend
ducing moral interpretations in students’ minds. To to identify this generic and idealized subject with
this respect, our expectation would be a positive one the present whole population of the nation, simi-
because historical contents are presented very often lar to what we saw earlier where students identify
to students in a way closer to moral stories than to the “we” of the past with the “we” of the present.
historiographical explanations. A clear example of this effect can be found in the
National historical narratives, both in and out historical meaning of the statement “We the peo-
of school, play an important role as moral vectors, ple . . .” in the U.S. Constitution. Probably most
because they are designed with that goal in mind. students think that this subject included each
This purpose is accomplished in at least two ways. and every inhabitant of the new nation, missing
First, the master narrative establishes the distinction its rather restricted meaning that excluded the
between “good” and “bad” options, people, and African American and Native American popula-
decisions. Typically, the first one is associated with tion, along with women.

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 633
Similarly, the end result or main achievement or in educational practice. The inconsistencies and
portrayed in these narratives is represented in onto- ruptures present in Pablo’s account of the victory
logical terms. This end result is the creation of of the Catholic King and Queen over the Arabs
the nation, but the nation is understood by most in the Iberian Peninsula in 1942 are an eloquent
of the subjects as an essentialist entity that preex- example of the deep contradictions that define the
ists the very process of creation. Pablo’s account construction of historical narratives in the minds of
of the Reconquista, and Federico’s account of individuals. In order to better understand this phe-
the Independence, both illustrate this feature. nomenon, we must take a closer look at how histor-
Respectively, they consider that Spain and Argentina ical knowledge became part of the school contents,
existed much before the historical formation of each and the kind of transformations that occurred to
nation. The national essence exists independently of them since.
historical developments. Thus, in one of our stud-
ies (Carretero, Gonzalez, et al., 2010), Argentineans The Coexistence of Goals
(young students and adults) were asked if the colo- History has been part of the national curricula
nists who participated in the first political demon- since the late nineteenth century in almost any
stration in favor of a broader political autonomy by country that established a public educational sys-
1810 were Argentineans. As a matter of fact, and tem. In fact, the constitution of history as an aca-
sensu strictu they were not Argentineans yet, because demic discipline occurred very close to its presence
they were colonists questioning the political power in the school curriculum. What was the purpose
of Spain. Thus, taking into account that this event of such early inception in the educational system?
happened 8 years before the Independence took Most nations considered, since their very origins,
place, our participants considered those colonists as that learning history was an essential part of the for-
definitely Argentineans because, as some expressed, mation of their future citizens. History education
they think Argentina and the Argentineans always was one of the pillars in the foundation of mod-
existed. Thus, it can be concluded that the historical ern nations. However, from early on, this ultimate
process of being member of a Nation-State tends to purpose of shaping the desired citizens translated
be seen as something that is already predetermined, into two parallel goals that generated and developed
in an ontological and essentialist way, and not as competing views of school history still present in
a result of different political, social, and economic today’s practice and discourse.
influences (Leinhardt & Ravi, 2008). Different researchers have considered the exis-
tence, implicit or explicit, of competing objectives
The Hidden Tension of Romantic and of school history (Barton, 2008; Carretero, 2007;
Enlightened Goals of the Teaching of Cuban, 2002; Wineburg, 2001) In this chapter we
History redefine those objectives as Romantic and Enlightened
So far we have discussed the construction of because their features and functions stem from their
historical narratives, emphasizing the function they respective intellectual roots in Romanticism and the
serve in supporting the construction of national Enlightenment. In other words, history is taught
identities. We have highlighted the mythical for- in any national school system attending to two dif-
mat that these narratives often adopt as they rely ferent goals: to make students “love their country”
on ontological and essentialist concepts of the (Nussbaum and Cohen, 2002) and to make them
nation, and the resulting discursive functions they “understand their past.” Based on this distinction,
serve. But if national narratives were the only ele- we analyze the continuous and seemingly irreduc-
ment in the picture, we would not see a rupture in ible tension that exists between the identity-forma-
Pablo’s account, and in fact the process of construc- tion function and the critical function played by
tion of narratives would be far less interesting and historical knowledge in the construction of histor-
intriguing. ical narratives (see Carretero, 2011 for an extended
What is interesting is the combination of dis- development of this idea). Can these two goals be
courses in his account, which reveals, among other simultaneously achieved? Can people love their
things, that despite the pervasiveness of national own country, and at the same time develop a crit-
historical narratives, and the influence they have ical understanding of its functioning? This chap-
in shaping peoples’ understanding of the past, they ter attempts to make a contribution to understand
have not gone uncontested in academic reflection these issues.

634 construct ing hi stor i e s


The Romantic Goals one essential component of that Romantic ideal.
From the very beginning, school history was Secondly, the Romantic goal of history education
inspired in the Romantic Goals of creating and is achieved through an intense and rapid process
maintaining a cohesive national identity that sup- of identification with one’s own nation through
ported the emerging centralized political project of emotional, affective, and social-interaction mecha-
Nation-States. According to Anderson (1983), this nisms. To love a country is certainly an expression
process required the constitution of imagined com- that does not denote specific reasoning or cognitive
munities whose members’ uniform stories, symbolic processes, but mainly affective ones. As a matter of
representations, and abilities superposed to the ter- fact, national identification processes and their final
ritory and state administration. History education results are considered by political forces, such as
was a singular but fundamental strategy used to nationalism or patriotism, as the necessary prereq-
achieve this goal, and it is still today. uisites to be willing, in case of necessity, to die for
Research on the history of history education and the motherland (fatherland).
school textbooks (Carretero, 2011; Ferro, 1984/
2002; Foster & Crawford, 2006; Nakou & Barca, The Enlightened Goals
2010) shows that history has been recurrently posi- Aside from the Romantic focus, history educa-
tioned in the school curriculum to instill in the tion has also pursued enlightened goals of fostering
future citizens, from a young age, the symbolic critical citizens capable of informed and effective
representations, the sentiments, and the values that participation in the progress of the nation, including
guarantee: a possible criticism to the own local or national com-
munity (Adorno & Horkheimer, 2002; Habermas,
a) A positive assessment of their own social 1990). From this perspective, the specific capacities
group’s past, present, and future; both local and that develop through the disciplined understand-
national. ing of the past and its relations to the present are
b) A positive assessment of the country’s important contributions to the cultivation of a
political evolution. democratic mind that has great civic value in liberal
c) Identification with past events and characters societies. Barton and Levstik (2008) review several
and national heroes. contributions that have been often attributed to the
teaching and learning of history: The ability to form
Barton and Levstik (2008) synthesize the differ-
well-documented and plausible critical interpreta-
ent ways of achieving these goals, by selecting topics
tions based on reasoned considerations of evidence
that focus only on the groups with which students
from multiple sources, an understanding of societal
should identify, focusing the content of teaching on
systems of relationships and dynamics of continu-
establishing a common origin, developing imagined
ity and change, the possibility of tracing the origins
communities around which such loyalties should
and evolution of current issues, the capacity to con-
form, glorifying the country’s past, and providing
sider the value dimensions of public issues, and the
historic models of civic virtue (pp. 358–361). As the
ability to contextualize the differing perspectives of
French historian M. Ferro, author of a pioneering
people (pp. 355–356). This Enlightened tradition
work in this field, has sentenced sparing no clarity:
places at the forefront the development of rational
“The image of other people, or of ourselves for that
abilities; and it displaces the management of identi-
matter, reflects the history we are taught as children.
ties, values, and emotions that may cloud a critical
The history marks us for life” (1984, p. IX).
understanding.
Why should these goals of history education
In its most current manifestation, Enlightened
be considered “Romantic”? There are at least two
goals translate in several countries into disciplinary
important reasons. First, because the emergence of
and cognitive objectives that generally consist of the
the Nation-States cannot be fully understood with-
following:
out the influence of the Romantic ideas and their
intellectual context. The whole idea of the nation a) To understand the past in a complex
as a specific ethnic group that is under a process of manner, according to age and educational level,
awakening and finally it constitutes itself in a com- which usually implies mastering the discipline’s
munity of destiny, cannot be conceived without conceptual categories (Carretero & Voss, 1994).
the contribution of the Romantic ideal. Precisely b) To distinguish different historic periods,
historical narratives, in and out of schools, express through the appropriate comprehension of

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 635
historical time, in order to understand social the darker episodes of the national past, and chal-
problems and issues, situated at different periods lenged the celebratory narratives (Barton & Levstik,
and having distinct characteristics (Carretero, 2008, p. 361). Taken as a whole, the Enlightened
Asensio, & Pozo, 1991; Barton, 2002; Lee, approach highlights reasoning and the development
2005). of thinking skills, and the mastery of explanation
c) To understand the complex historical and plausible argumentation.
multicausality, in which individual and collective
motivations interact with causal factors in intricate Different Ways of Explaining Ruptures
ways (Carretero et al., 1997; Bermudez & The evolution or transformations in the goals of
Jaramillo, 2001; Perkins, 2008). history education explain how we account today for
d) To relate the past with the present and the the ruptures and contradictions in the construction
future; this entails an important link with other of historical narratives.
social sciences and also with civic education (Von
Borries, 1994). The Early Version
e) To approach the methodology used by Early manifestations of the Enlightened goals
historians in ways that allow the student to learn appeared during the first decades of the twentieth
history in an intellectually active way and to century in Europe and the United States. In the
understand historical knowledge as a depository of spirit of progressive movements it was proposed
problems that can be solved with objectification that history education should serve purposes other
systems (Perfetti, 1994; Wineburg, 2001). than furnishing the cultural memory of youth with
glittering heroes, robust political landmarks, and
These Romantic and Enlightened goals of history other patriotic symbols. The idea of developing a
education coexisted from the very beginning and rational understanding of the past through school
developed over time. Often, when Romantic goals curriculum and pedagogical practice were part of
took the center stage, the Enlightened goals receded the progressive effort to open the classroom to the
to a side stage, and vice versa. Yet, this ebb and flow pressing complexities of social life (industrializa-
defined a long century of pedagogical practice and tion, urbanization, and immigration at that time)
academic reflection, that help us understand how and to reframe the role of schooling (the teaching of
citizens in present societies consume and construct history and social studies included) as the formation
historical narratives, and how we understand and of habits of mind and thinking skills necessary for
explain that phenomenon. a reflective engagement in democratic citizenship
The Romantic approach to the teaching of his- (Dewey, 1910/1933, 1916; Rugg, 1921; Osborn,
tory was the dominant discourse and practice in 1939; Griffin, 1942).
different countries up until the postwar era. As we In the late 1950s and 1960s several programs
discussed at length earlier, this approach placed at for the teaching of social studies and history were
the forefront of the teaching and learning of history developed following these Enlightened goals. Two
the management of values and sentiments for the prominent influential forces shaped this. In the
sake of building homogeneous national identities. United States, new developments in the social sci-
Simultaneously, it displaced the idea of fostering ences made their way to the school context, when
through the teaching of history any form of critical the “new social studies movement” engulfed the
rationality that threatened the cohesiveness of the teaching of history. By and large, this approach saw
national projects. the discussion of controversial issues as the necessary
Beginning in the 1970s an Enlightened approach strategy to educate reflective citizens, and grounded
reemerged and dominated the field for the next three its practical models on an inquiry-based pedagogy.
decades, installing a new perspective on the nature The emerging discourses of the “new social
of historical knowledge and the purposes of teaching studies” recommended practices for teaching that
and learning it. Countering the Romantic tradition, proposed to help students acquire the knowledge
Enlightened approaches in different countries advo- and methods of inquiry of the social sciences. For
cated from early on for a teaching of history that example, the now classical work of Hunt & Metcalf
explored the complexity of historical developments, (1955, 1968) outlined a curriculum for a “rational
recognized divergent experiences and multiples inquiry on problematic areas of culture.” Massialas
perspectives, contested national myths, scrutinized and Cox (1966) insisted on an “emphasis on ideas

636 construct ing hi stor i e s


and hypothesis,” “a stress on analytical rather than hand in hand with the development of constructiv-
descriptive processes,” and “the functional use of ist and developmental theories of learning and edu-
facts.” Terms like “value analysis,” “evaluation of cation. Importantly, the decades of 1980s to 1990s
data,” “skills of definition, classification, and gen- saw not only new pedagogical practices and curric-
eralization” were the typical language of proposals ulum developments based on Enlightened goals,
that claimed that these were the kind of abilities that but also a developing research program. Research
competent citizens would need in a democracy, and on history teaching and learning flourished during
the teaching of history and other social studies could these last two decades. A significant body of litera-
and should develop those capacities in citizens. ture emerged on how children and youth come to
“The revolution in education has at last reached understand the complexities of the past and how
the field of social studies,” wrote Massialas and Cox they make sense of the process of knowing history.
(1966)—with great enthusiasm. In their view, “the For the most part, this work was influenced by
conditions of the society made it imperative that the developing research in cognitive and develop-
the schools accept as its role the ‘progressive recon- mental psychology. Basic psychological principles
struction’ of the culture” rather than affirm itself as and concepts imported from Piagetian theory influ-
“a conserving agent of the past achievements of the enced research on the process of understanding his-
culture” (p. 21). “Today’s society presents the school torical knowledge (Burston & Thompson, 1967;
with conditions of change, instability, and disjunc- Carretero, Asensio, & Pozo, 1991; Coltham, 1971,
tion. Although many of these conditions have his- Hallam, 1967, 1970; Peel, 1967). For example:
toric roots, many others are new configurations,
1) Research was aimed to describe the
which are direct products of industrialization and
development of underlying cognitive structures
technology” (p. 6). In the face of these challenges,
(general structures across disciplines, not specific
they questioned the conservative Romantic approach
to history).
because “this position minimizes or totally discounts
2) Phenomena were analyzed as to how
cultural changes or the growing edge of the culture
structures of reasoning support or create obstacles
in deference to that which is traditionally good,
to mature understanding of core concepts (Time,
classical, or ‘established truth.’ ” Instead, the school
abstract categories, hypothesis testing).
should be “deliberatively critical and creative in its
3) The stress was on the difficulties of teaching
selection and examination of the values of the soci-
abstract history at young ages.
ety, carefully avoiding an over-identification with
4) The importance of developing general
any segment of the culture” (p. 21). Accordingly,
cognitive skills that could transfer and be applied
the function of social studies instruction should be
to the learning of history was emphasized.
to “furnish the forum for the analysis and evaluation
5) Advanced research on common
of normative propositions or value judgments about
misinterpretation and challenges of conceptual
man and society,” and the end result of such practice
change in history and social sciences contexts was
of inquiry should be “the production of a body of
carried out.
tested principles and generalizations about human
relations and societies” (p. 24). These constructivist and developmental views of
Similar proposals in the fashion of the Enlightened the teaching and learning of history had an influen-
perspective can be found in other contexts, but this tial impact on the Enlightened research program.
example from the American context suffices to illus- This, however, involved important debates and
trate the tension existing from early on between the transformations. Already in the mid-1970s, but
Romantic and the Enlightened goals of the teaching most consistently throughout the 1980s and 1990s,
and learning of history. research that had begun in Britain established
what is commonly known as the discipline-specific
Constructivist Developments approaches that advocated for a constructive teach-
Despite the early appearance of these and other ing of history that is organized around core historical
critical efforts, an Enlightened approach to the concepts, and recognizes the particularities of his-
teaching of history only began to settle in a more tory as a discipline that has developed specific ways
generalized way in the 1970s. Exploratory and of knowing society and knowing the past. Much of
innovative pedagogical practices transcended to the this work wanted to challenge the overbearing gen-
wider curricular frameworks in several countries, eralization of Piagetian models as proposed by Peel

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 637
(1967) or Hallam (1967, 1970). This discussion is Romantic narratives, and advocated for more inclu-
evident in work by Dickinson and Lee (1978) or sive, pluralist, and critical accounts. Adding to this,
Booth (1987). Based on this claim about the epis- constructivist and developmental research emerg-
temological specificity of historical knowledge and ing in the 1970s provided a psychological rationale
inquiry, research in this tradition investigated how that supported the proposal of Enlightened goals,
young people learn to master core historical con- and questioned the notions of a passive consumer
cepts such as causality, time, change, or empathy, of social narratives and the unidirectional process of
and learn to think about the past in disciplined ways meaning making that typically underlies to much of
(Dickinson, Gordon, & Lee, 2001; Lee, Dickinson, the Romantic tradition. Furthermore, advocates of
& Rogers, 1984; Lee, Dickinson, & Ashby, 2001; the Enlightened goals increasingly pushed for school
Portal, 1987; Shemilt, 1980, 1984, 1987) history contents that adopted a “scientific” explana-
Simultaneously, research in other countries in tory and expository format. To be sure, these expos-
Europe and in the United States progressed in a itory accounts are also cultural artifacts, socially
somewhat different direction. Influenced by cog- produced and transmitted by the schools. Yet, they
nitive research, studies on how students come to distanced the Enlightened pedagogy from the use
understand the complexity of historical knowledge of the traditional personal and national narratives
tracked changes in students’ ideas typically repre- typical of the Romantic approach, forever changing
senting intellectual growth as a progression from our understanding what it means to construct his-
naïve to expert models of reasoning (Carretero & torical narratives.
Voss, 1994; Leinhardt, Stainton, Virji, & Odoroff,
1994; Limón & Carretero, 1999). For example, as Limitations of the Enlightened Approach
it has been well-established in this research pro- to Teaching and Learning History
gram, adolescents develop their causal explanations The wealth of constructivist research on the pro-
going from intentional and concrete forms to more gression of historical thinking provides us with valu-
abstract ones where political and socio-economic able conceptual tools to examine Pablo’s account of
aspects play a more important role. Also, early ado- the defeat of the Arabs in Granada in 1492, and
lescents tend to consider only one or two causes to understand the strengths and limitations of his
in order to explain a historical problem, whereas explanation. Based on this research we can say that
young students and adults usually are able to pro- Pablo has the precise chronology of the changing
vide more complex multicausal explanations of his- occupation of the Iberian territory by Christians and
torical phenomena. Muslims, holds a fairly sophisticated understanding
These different traditions within the Enlightened of the interplay of multiple causal factors leading to
research program have established some dialog and the final expulsion of the Arabs, and reconstructs
basic consensus. Three decades of international the changing power dynamics. It is also clear that
theoretical reflection and empirical research have what happens in Pablo’s case is that he superposes
left us with rich models of how children and ado- an expository account focused on causal factors to
lescents develop the competencies needed to engage a narrative account focused on the motivations that
in “rigorous historical inquiry,” including an under- lead the Christians to victory. But, why does Pablo,
standing of the intricacies of historical evidence, the who demonstrates a fairly sophisticated critical abil-
differences and similarities between past and pres- ity, ultimately resorts to an essentialist narrative
ent, the short- and long-term processes of social that, in its very basic assumptions, contradicts the
change, the layered webs of historical multicausality, logical argument of his “historiographic account”?
and the contextual meaning of beliefs and practices Constructivist research falls short when it comes
that appear foreign today (Carretero & Voss, 1994; to make sense of this kind of incongruence. The
Stearns, Seixas, & Wineburg, 2000). argument put forward from this perspective would
These constructivist developments contributed typically be that the previous ideas and misconcep-
to the growing tensions between the Romantic and tions derived from cultural narratives stand in the way
the Enlightened views of the teaching and learning of effective conceptual change needed to construct
of history, and the construction of historical nar- accurate representations (Limón & Carretero,
ratives. Different progressive movements in the 2000). In fact, in much of the research on the devel-
social sciences were already questioning the elitist opment of historical thinking capacity, the intro-
and biased representations of the past contained in mission of values and emotions that emanate from

638 construct ing hi stor i e s


these narratives are regarded as cognitive obstacles the constructivist paradigm rests on its capacity to
that hinder the development of explanatory com- describe the cognitive or logical structures underpin-
plexity, and ultimately stagnate the development of ning a historical account (e.g., number of causal fac-
a mature understanding of the past. tors considered, accurate representation of change
To be sure, throughout the transformations and continuity, coordination of a variety of sources,
described above, values, emotions, and identity dis- etc.), and to map the pathways of transformation
courses continued to be inseparable ingredients of they undergo as they develop. In order to capture
the historical contents taught in the classroom, but these structural features, and the similarities, dif-
exactly how they appeared was open to change. In ferences, continuities, or transformations between
the curricular domain, positions were split. Several them, constructivists separate form from content,
constructivist curricular reforms in the fields of and the structures of logical reasoning from the sub-
social studies and history continued to justify their stance of meaning making. As a result, the process
new approaches by stressing civic value of historical of reasoning is abstracted from the social and cul-
thinking skills. The belief was that students would tural context in which the individual reasons.
develop critical attitudes and commitment to dem- Indeed, the selective focus on the cognitive
ocratic values such as supporting judgments with or logical structures underpinning a historical
evidence or considering different perspectives that account allows us to grasp its disciplinary adequacy.
would then apply to their action as citizens (Barton However, in doing so, it overlooks three important
& Levstik, 2008, Oliver & Shaver, 1966, 1974). dynamics of meaning making: (a) how individu-
To a certain extent, values and emotions become als draw upon narratives available in their society
objects of rational analysis. Yet, others argued that and culture in order to make meaning of the con-
the purpose of the history curriculum should be cepts and facts learned in school (Haste, 1992) ; (b)
the development of historical understanding rather how they engage in a variety of discursive activities
than any current civic purpose (Barton & Levstik, through which they negotiate the implications of
2008, p. 362; Lee, 1984) The rationale for this posi- new historical knowledge for their personal and
tion is that if history is taught for the sake of pres- collective identities, and for the interpersonal and
ent purposes, history may be instrumentalized and social relationships they participate in (Antaki &
denaturalized. An unqualified integration of moral Widdicombe, 1998; Billig, 1987, Harré & Gillet,
questions may distort both the authenticity of his- 1994; Harré & van Langehnove, 1999), and (c) how
torical experience, and the rigor of historical think- they mobilize and manage a host of values and sen-
ing. These concerns are long-lived among historians timents that link the process of knowing to the pro-
who coined two terms to name the greatest sins that cess of negotiating identities and social positions in
a historian may be tempted to commit: presentism a particular context. The constructivist research for-
and anachronism. mula lacks the conceptual tools necessary to explain
The situation in the field of research was differ- the role that socio-cultural context, identity, values,
ent. Questions about the role of values, emotions, and sentiments play in historical understanding.
and identity lost prominence in a research program Within this paradigm, we are at a loss when we
concerned with the reconstruction of the cognitive try to understand why Pablo does not extend his
structures and processes that underlies to the devel- critical skills to examine the narrative of reconquest
opment of understanding (or misunderstanding). that was socially transmitted to him. This is not a
With few exceptions (see for example Von Borries, minor limitation if we consider that much of the
1994; Hahn, 1994), researchers in the Enlightened constructivist paradigm rests on the assumption that
tradition displaced these themes to the backstage, students will transfer the thinking skills developed
when they did not entirely dismiss the role they play in the history classroom to real-life situations in
in learning and knowing the past. which a disciplined historical perspective can afford
The constructivist claims may hold some truth, them a better understanding of the social issues
but they still cannot explain why individuals reach and questions they encounter in their daily lives. In
these obstacles and struggle to overcome them. In fact, there is no empirical evidence that shows that
our view, the problem lays in that the theoreti- the transference of skills from the classroom to the
cal apparatus of constructivist research is limited. everyday life actually happens (Barton & Levstik,
Interestingly, it is precisely the features that define 2008). Despite the efforts of teachers and researchers
its strength that also constrain it. The strength of to engage students in the mastery of core historical

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 639
concepts, this does not effectively lead students to the narrative structure of historical knowledge,
change the historical narratives they bring to school. they stress the connection between the processes of
In fact, people do not change their theories but rather knowing the past and constructing identities in the
pick and choose conveniently. Evidence shows that present, and they reposition sentiments and values
students do not readily modify their prior narrative at the core of knowing the past. Yet, they do so from
understanding when they encounter new or con- very different perspectives and with significantly
flicting information (Limón & Carretero, 1999). different implications.
For example, Barton and Levstik (1998) have found
that U.S. students, who struggle to reconcile their Romantic Goals in a Neoconservative
knowledge of topics such as the Great Depression, Tradition
the Vietnam War, and continuing instances of rac- In the neoconservative tradition, the reemer-
ism and sexism with the overarching historical nar- gence of Romantic goals continues to be coupled
ratives of progress, tend to reinterpret such events to with patriotic and nationalist concerns that empha-
more closely match the broad theme that dominates size issues of loyalty, attachments, and unity. For
American culture. Similarly, research conducted by example, in recent years in the United States, sev-
Barton and McCully (2005) shows how students in eral authors have argued that the liberal views of
Northern Ireland draw selectively from the curricu- teaching history (i.e., the constructivist views), in
lum in order to bolster the sectarian narratives that which the past is made object of critical analysis,
they encounter outside of school. Other authors have eroded the cultural literacy that is the basis of
point to the similar conclusion that students use cohesion of a national identity and the sense of civic
religiously grounded narratives to ignore, reinter- virtue (Bloom, 1987, Hirch, Kett, & Trefil, 1988;
pret, or distort historical information so that it does Cheney, 1988; Ravitch & Finn, Jr., 1988) In their
not conflict with the prior ideas (Mosborg, 2002; view, the renewal of the nation depends on reestab-
Porat, 2004). lishing a shared historical narrative and on enacting
Where do we go from here? What are we left the values that this narrative embodies. Such reaffir-
with? Are the identity and the critical dynamics in mation of national unity is deemed fundamental in
construction of historical narratives irremediably the face of external threats, as well as internal threats
antagonistic? Are the Romantic and Enlightened such as the challenges brought by ethnic and lin-
traditions necessarily at odds with each other in guistic pluralism. This approach is generally didac-
their efforts to explain how and why historical nar- tic, and students are told what traits are embodied
ratives are constructed? The body of research on by historical figures and why they are good (Barton
historical understanding has generated a number of & Levstik, 2008). Here again, there is little room
questions about the knowing of history and the con- for interpretation or ambiguity, and little role for
struction of historical accounts/narratives that can- critical rationality that is repelled for having scruti-
not be addressed from within its own Enlightened nized and destroyed the creeds that sustained com-
paradigm. However, in our view, the latest wave munity and nation.
of research informed by a variety of socio-cultural
perspectives in psychology and social sciences chal-
Romantic Goals in a Critical
lenge these dichotomies and open new possibilities
Socio-Cultural Tradition
for research and understanding.
The socio-cultural approach contrasts with the
conservative version in at least four important
The Reemergence of Romantic Goals
ways:
After three decades in which Enlightened goals
and assumptions extended throughout pedagogi- (a) It tends to portray historical narratives
cal practice and constructivist research, the interest as cultural artifacts rather than as essential
in the Romantic themes of identity and the role of distillations of national character, or a set of basic
values and sentiments is moving back to the center objective facts.
stage of the current research agenda. (b) Because of that, it usually recognizes diverse
Not surprisingly, these interests have reemerged and contentious views of the past rather than
in two different ways: within a neoconservative tradi- positing the existence of one shared narrative.
tion on one hand and within a critical socio-cultural (c) It claims an active rather than a passive role
tradition on the other. Both approaches highlight for the individual in the process of constructing

640 construct ing hi stor i e s


historical narratives, and locates this process in its ideas and their ongoing attempts to make sense of
socio-cultural context. the world (Levstik & Barton, 2001). A student’s
(d) Because of that, it tends to examine the historical understanding, then, is not simply a mirror
interplay of rationality, values, and emotions, of external information but a unique set of mental
rather than dismissing one or the other. schemata resulting from the interaction between
the individual and environment. Yet, socio-cultural
Interestingly, some of these characteristics also
theory emphasizes that this process is necessarily
explain that the current socio-cultural approach has
situated in social contexts, and that the information
new tools that constructivist views lacked, which
to which students are exposed has been historically
afford the possibility of solving some of its limita-
and socially constructed.”
tions. In the pages that remain we will discuss some
(2005, p. 90)
of these features in terms of the potential contri-
butions that the current socio-cultural approach to
The recognition of the active role of the individ-
the Romantic goals of teaching history can make
ual in the process of construction of historical nar-
to the research on the construction of historical
ratives has important implications. For one thing, it
narratives.
has propelled the distinction between the processes
of production and consumption of historical nar-
Contributions of the Socio-Cultural
ratives (Wertsch, 1997). The former refers to how
Approach to Romantic Goals
history textbooks, mass media and other sources
The latest generation of research and discussion
deliver official history versions (Ahonen, 1997;
on the teaching and learning of history is marked
Luczynski, 1997) and the latter has to do with the
by a strong influence of socio-cultural theories.
process by which individuals appropriate those his-
Recasting history to a narrative format, emphasizing
torical narratives, even though their narratives may
the connection between the processes of knowing
not necessarily be identical to those produced.
the past and the processes of constructing identi-
Research conducted in different countries in the
ties, and repositioning sentiments and values and
last 10 years has documented, along these lines, how
the core of historical consciousness, socio-cultural
students engage with a variety of historical narra-
approaches come as a refreshing force, raising new
tives in active processes of negotiation that involve
questions, shedding light on new phenomena, fore-
stances of endorsement, resistance, or challenge—as
grounding new controversies, and suggesting new
they construct the meaning and of their own iden-
dilemmas.
tities. In the work cited, Barton and McCully call
Interestingly, much of this transformation in the
into question any simplistic notion of the relation-
research agenda has been propelled by the adop-
ship between historically grounded identities and
tion of socio-cultural approaches without abandon-
formal study at school: “students neither reject
ing the basic constructivist tenets, either because
school history outright nor use it to replace prior,
researchers draw upon a Vigotskian tradition that
community-based historical narratives. Rather, they
organically integrates both, or because constructiv-
draw selectively from the school curriculum (and
ist researchers migrated, bringing some of their con-
other sources) to support a range of developing his-
ceptual heritage. For example, Barton and McCully
torical identities” (2005, p. 85).
discuss one of their recent pieces of work in the fol-
While recognizing an active role for the indi-
lowing terms:
vidual in the process of constructing historical nar-
“This study is grounded in a constructivist and ratives, socio-cultural research also addresses the
socio-cultural perspective on historical social and cultural processes involved in learning
understanding. For most of the last two decades, history, knowing the past, and constructing histori-
theory and research in history education has been cal narratives.
part of the larger constructivist tradition in education Haste (1993), in her research about people’s
and psychology. From this perspective, neither construction of notions of self and morality, makes
children nor adults passively absorb information, an argument that proves helpful here. In her view,
whether at school or elsewhere. Rather, they engage “there is a major, and for some irreconcilable debate
in a process of active construction in which they in developmental psychology . . . between those who
interpret new information—encountered in a variety search for the basic process of morality inside the
of formats and settings—in light of their prior head of the individual and those who search for it

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 641
in the interaction between persons, between those the construction of historical narratives, and we
who assume that meaning is constructed by the have begun to see work emerging in some of these
individual and those who assume that it is a social areas:
construction transferred to the individual” (p. 175).
“No one denies that there is interaction,” Haste a) How individuals draw upon social and
clarifies, but in the face of debate there is “a funda- cultural narratives in order to make meaning of
mental, almost ideological, division between those the concepts and facts learned in school, as shown
who view the individual as the phenomenon to be in the works of already cited authors as Barton,
explained and those who treat the individual as the Seixas, Van Sledright, Wineburg, and others.
end of the social process” (p. 184). In our opinion, a number of aspects of school
Constructivist models in the research of history history narratives need to be studied more deeply
teaching and learning, which tend to adopt the first in the future not only in school settings but in
position in this conflict, assume indeed that other informal learning environments, particularly
individuals play a role in providing challenges and museums, exhibitions, TV shows, etc. Particularly,
generating disequilibrium. However, such “inter- in relation to the six features presented in this
actions among individuals” are not analyzed as chapter. For example, we do not know in detail
embedded in social and cultural processes. In fact, what is the influence of cognitive development on
social and cultural context are seen as unproblem- the processes of construction and consumption
atic. In contrast, conservative and neoconservative of historical narratives. It could be hypothesized
approaches to the study of history education rest that older students could understand and use
on principles akin to the second position described historical narratives in a more complex manner
by Haste. These traditions tend to conceptualize than younger ones, following a progression from
the self and knowledge as products of socialization, mythical and concrete narratives to ironic and
and therefore, argue that the primary process to be abstract ones. To this respect, also teaching and
explained is “that of inculcating the growing child learning factors should be taken into account.
into a socially constructed world of meaning.” As Thus, it is important to consider that very often
Haste explains, “the social context provides frame- school history education is carried out in order to
works for concepts and values, and this is regarded promote Romantic and patriotic values and not
as sufficient explanation of an individual’s develop- really historiographical understanding. This implies
ment, with no need to address actual processes at the possibility of not having a real disciplinary
the individual level” (Haste, 1993, p. 176, 182). progress in student’s minds. To this respect, it
Among other things, the dichotomy described would be very important to study in a very detailed
by Haste helps to explain why plain constructiv- way the possible influence of social and cultural
ist research has had little room to consider that factors in the process of interiorization of the
“ Identity matters” matter when it comes to con- mentioned narratives. Particularly the influence of
structing histories. Likewise, it sheds light on why the Nation-States educational policies, which are
the traditional Romantic perspectives rarely recog- very often interested in developing just mythical
nize that historical narratives have an active mind and heroic historic representations.
behind them. In contrast with the limitations of the b) How citizens mobilize and manage a host
Romantic and Enlightened traditions of research in of values and sentiments that link the process
their conventional forms, it becomes clear that what knowing to the process of negotiating identities
is needed to understand the construction of histori- and social positions in a particular context. To
cal narratives in its full complexity is a synthesis that this respect, we think the moral dimensions of
renders as problematic, or in need of explanation, historical master narratives should be explored in
both the process of individual active consumption more detailed way, particularly in relation to the
of historical narratives, and the social and cultural consumption process. A number of theoretical
processes of production of those historical narra- (White, 1987) and empirical contributions permit
tives and their meaning. to expect a strong influence of moral issues on
the way citizens consider historical narratives. It is
Future Directions plausible to expect that this moral influence would
Our synthetic approach implies the investigation be very much related to the process of belonging to
of three important dynamics of meaning making in a certain national, ethnic or cultural group. To this

642 construct ing hi stor i e s


respect, the relation between national or cultural Alridge, D. (2006). The limits of master narratives in history
identity and citizens’ moral interpretation of textbooks: An analysis of representations of Martin Luther
King, Jr. Teachers College Record, 108(4), 662–686.
historical issues is, in our opinion, a very promising Alvarez, A. (1965). Enciclopedia escolar. Tercer grado. Madrid.
hypothesis to be explored in the future. Reproducción facsimilar, 1997. (School encyclopedia. Third
c) How individuals engage in a variety of grade) Valladolid (Spain), Miñón. Reprinted, Madrid, EDAF,
discursive activities through which they negotiate 2003.
the implications of new historical knowledge for Alvarez-Junco, J. (2011) Spanish Identity in the Age of Nations.
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
their personal and collective identities, and for Anderson, B. (1983). Imagined Comunities: Reflections on the ori-
the interpersonal and social relationships they gins and spread of nationalism. London: Verso.
participate in. Coming back to the example of Antaki, C., & Widdicombe, S. (1998). Identities in talk. Thousand
Pablo´s narrative about the Reconquest in Spain, Oaks, CA: Sage.
presented above, we think much more work is Barrett, M., & Buchanan-Barrow, E. (Eds.) (2005). Children’s
understanding of society. London: Taylor & Francis.
necessary about how the interaction between Barton, K. (2002). “Oh, That’s a Tricky Piece!”: Children, medi-
production and consumption of school historical ated action, and the tools of historical time. The Elementary
narratives is being produced. A recent paper School Journal, 103 (2), 161–185.
(Hammack, 2010) considers the strong influence Barton, K. C. (2008). Students’ ideas about history. In
of these narratives on youths’ collective identity, L. S. Levstik & C. A. Tyson (Eds.), Handbook of research in
social studies education (pp. 239–258). New York: Routledge.
suggesting that identity is both a burden and a Barton, K. C., & Levstik, L. S. (1996). Back when God was
benefit at the same time. This shows how complex around and everything: Elementary children’s understand-
and counterintuitive the mentioned interaction ing of historical time. American Educational Research Journal,
could be. 33(2), 419–454.
Barton, K. C., & Levstik, L. S. (1998). It wasn’t a good part
The location of individual meaning within socio- of history”: National identity and students’ explanations
cultural contexts affords these new approaches the of historical significance. Teachers College Record, 99(3),
possibility of examining the interplay of rational- 478–513.
Barton, K., & Levstik, L. (2004). Teaching history for the common
ity, values, and emotions, rather than dismissing good. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
one or the other. Hence, a salient contribution of Barton, K. C., & Levstik, L. S. (2008). History. In J. Arthur,
the socio-cultural approaches is its potential to C. Hahn, & I. Davies (Eds.), Handbook of education for citi-
explore a variety of possible interactions between zenship and democracy. London: Sage.
Romantic and Enlightened traditions and goals Barton, K. C., & McCully, A. W. (2005). History, identity, and
the school curriculum in Northern Ireland: An empirical
that have largely been kept separate in previous study of secondary students’ ideas and perspectives. Journal
work. of Curriculum Studies, 37, 85–116.
Barton, K. C., & McCully, A. W. (2010). You can form your own
Notes point of view: Internally persuasive discourse in Northern
1. This chapter was written with the support of Projects Ireland students’ encounters with history. Teachers College
PICT 2005–34778 and 2008–1217 (Agencia de Investigacion Record, 112(1), 142–181.
de Argentina), and Projects SEJ2006–15461 and EDU2010– Beckstead, Z. (2011). Crossing thresholds: movement as a means of
17725 (Agencia de Investigacion, Spain), and the Fellowship at transformation. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture
the D. Rockefeller Center for Latin American Studies (Harvard and psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
University) to the first author during 2009–2010. We would like Bermudez, A., & Jaramillo, R. (2001). Development of his-
express our gratitude for that support. torical explanations in children, adolescents and adults. In
2. Consider, for example, the Israeli narrative about Palestin- A. K. Dickinson, P. Gordon, & P. J. Lee (Eds.), International
ian territories arguing the need to recuperate a land from where review of history education—Rising standards in history edu-
the Israeli people were expelled 2,000 years ago. Sand (2010) has cation (vol. 3) (pp. 146–167). London: Woburn Press.
brilliantly studied the “invention of the Jewish nation.” Billig, M. (1987). Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach
to social psychology (2nd ed., 1996). Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, Editions de la Maison des sci-
References ences de l’Homme.
Adorno, T., & Horkheimer, M. (1944/2002). Dialectic of enlight- Bloom, A. (1988). The closing of the American mind. New York,
enment. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. [Original NY: Simon and Schuster.
edition in German, 1944]. Booth, M. (1987). Ages and concepts: A critique of the Piagetian
Ahonen, S. (1992). Clio sans uniform. A study of the post-Marxist approach to history teaching. In C. Portal (Ed.), The history
transformation of the history curricula in East Germany and curriculum for teachers. (pp. 22–38). London: The Falmer
Estonia 1986–1991. Helsinki: Pekka Suvanto. Press.
Ahonen, S. (1997). A transformation of history: The official Boyd, C. P. (1996). Historia patria: Politics, history, and national
representations of history in East Germany and Estonia, identity in Spain, 1875–1975. Princeton: Princeton University
1986–1991. Culture & Psychology, 3(1), 41–62. Press.

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 643
Burston W.H. & Thompson, D. (Eds.) (1967) Studies in the Dewey, J. (1916). The democratic conception in education.
nature and the teaching of history. London: Routledge and In W. C. Parker (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind
Kegan Paul. (pp. 25–43). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Berger, S., Eriksonas, L., & Mycock, A. (Eds.) (2008). Narrating Dewey, J. (1910, 1933). How we think: A restatement of the rela-
the nation: Representings in history, media and the arts. New tion of reflective thinking to the educative process. New York:
York : Berghahn Books. D.C. Heath & Company.
Carretero, M. (2007). Documentos de identidad. La construccion Dickinson, P., Lee, P. J. (Eds.) (2001). Rising standards in his-
de la memoria histórica en un mundo global. Buenos Aires: tory instruction. International review of history education,
Paidós. (Documents of identity. The construction of histori- Volume 3. London: Woburn Press.
cal memory in a global world). Dickinson, P. Lee, P. J., & Rogers, P. (Eds.) (1984). Learning his-
Carretero, M. (2011). Constructing patriotism. Teaching history tory. (pp. 1–19). London: Heinemann Educational.
and memories in global worlds. Charlotte, NC: Information Egan, K. (1997). The educated mind. Chicago: The University of
Age Publishing. Chicago Press.
Carretero, M., Asensio, M., & Pozo, J. I. (1991). Cognitive Eklof, B., Holmes, L. E., & Kaplan, V. (Eds.) (2005). Educational
development, historical time representation and causal reform in post-Soviet Russia: Legacies and prospects (Vol. 20).
explanations in adolescence. In M. Carretero, M. Pope, New York: Routledge.
R.J. Simons, & J.I. Pozo (Eds.), Learning and instruction, Ferro, M. (1984). The use and abuse of history: Or how the past
Vol.III., European research in an international context. Oxford: is taught to children. London: Routledge. French Edition:
Pergamon Press. Comment on raconte l’Histoire aux enfants à travers le monde
Carretero, M., Gonzalez, M. F., Rodriguez, M., & Carreño, L. entier. Paris: Payot, 1983. New and revised version in French,
(2010, October 28–30). Is the “nation” an historical concept 2002.
in students’ minds? Paper presented at the international seminar Foster, S. J., & Crawford, K. A. (Eds.) (2006). What shall we tell
on understanding history and the construction of identities in a the children? International perspectives on school history text-
global world. De-nationalizing history teaching, UAM, Madrid. books. Charlotte, NC: Information Age.
http://www.uam.es/otros/history/abstracts/abs-carretero. Griffin, A. (1942). Teaching in democratic and authoritarian
pdf. Retrieved, November 5, 2010. states. In W. C. Parker (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind
Carretero, M., Jacott, L., Limón, M., López-Manjón, A., & (pp. 79–93). Albany, NY: State University of New York
León, J. A. (1994). Historical knowledge: Cognitive and Press.
instructional implications. In M. Carretero, & J. F. Voss (Eds.), Habermas, J. (1990). The philosophical discourse of modernity,
Cognitive and instructional processes in history and the social sci- Boston: MIT Press.
ences. (pp. 357–376). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Hahn, C. (1994). Controversial issues in history instruction. In
Carretero, M., Jacott, L., & López Manjón, L. (2002). Learning M. Carretero & J. F. Voss (Eds.), Cognitive and instructional
history through textbooks: Are Mexican and Spanish stu- proceses in history and social sciences (pp. 221–233). Hillsdale,
dents taught the same story? Learning and Instruction, 12(6), N.J.: Erlbaum.
651–665. Halpin, T. (2007). Textbooks rewrite history to fit Putin’s vision.
Carretero, M., & Kriger, M. (2011). Historical representations The Times. http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/news/world/
and conflicts about indigenous people as national identities. europe/article2163481.ece. Retrieved October 8, 2010.
Culture & Psychology, (2), 177–195. Hallam, R. N. (1967). Logical thinking in history. Educational
Carretero, M., Kriger, M., & Lopez, C.(2010, July 7–10). Review, 19, 183–202.
Historical representations and conflicts about first origins and Hallam, R. N. (1970). Piaget and thinking in history. In: Ballard
national identities. International Society of Political Psychology (Ed.) New movements in the study and teaching of history
33rd Annual Scientific Meeting, San Francisco, p. 45. (pp. 162–178). London: Temple Smith.
Carretero, M., López-Manjón, A., & Jacott, L. (1997). Explaining Hallden, O. (1994). Constructing the learning task in history
historical events. International Journal of Educational Research, instruction. In M. Carretero, & J. F. Voss (Eds.), Cognitive
27(3), 245–253. and instructional processes in history and social sciences
Carretero, M., & Voss, J. F. (Eds.) (1994). Cognitive and instruc- (pp. 187–200). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
tional processes in history and the social sciences. Hillsdale, NJ: Hahn, C. (1994). Controversial issues in history instruction.
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. In M. Carretero, & J. F. Voss (Eds.), Cognitive and instruc-
Clark, A. (2007). Representations of Aboriginal people in tional processes in history and social sciences (pp. 201–220).
English Canadian history textbooks: Toward reconciliation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
In E. Cole (Ed.), Teaching the violent past: History education Hammack, P. L. (2010). Identity as burden or benefit? Youth.
and reconciliation (pp. 123–153). Lanham, MD: Rowman Historical narrative, and the legacy of political conflict.
& Littlefield Publishers in cooperation with the Carnegie Human Development, 53(4), 173–201.
Council for Ethics in International Affairs. Harré, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. Thousand
Cheney, L. (1988). American memory: A report on the humanities Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
in the nation’s public schools. Washington, D.C.: Government Harré, R., & Van Lagenhove, L. (1999). Positioning theory: Moral
Printing Office. contexts of intentional action. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Coltham, J. (1971). The development of thinking and the learn- Haste, H. (1993). Morality, self and sociohistorical context: The
ing of history. London: Historical Association, Teaching of role of lay social theory. In G. G. Noam, & T. Wren (Eds.),
History Series No. 34. The moral self (pp. 175–208). Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Cuban, L (2002). Foreword. In B. Van Sledright (Ed.), In search Press.
of America’s past : Learning to read history in elementary school Hirsch, E., Kett, J., & Trefil, J. (1988). Cultural literacy: What
(pp. vii–x). New York: Teachers College Press. every American needs to know. NY: Vintage.

644 construct ing hi stor i e s


Hobsbawm, E. (1990). Nations and nationalism since 1780: Mosborg, S. (2002). Speaking of history: How adolescents
Programme, myth, reality. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge use their knowledge of history in reading the daily news.
University Press. Cognition and Instruction, 20(3), 323–358.
Hunt, M. P., & Metcalf, L. E. (1955). Rational inquiry on society’s Nakou, I., & Barca, I. (Eds.) (2011). Contemporary public debates
closed areas. over history education. International review of history education.
In W. C. Parker (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind Charlotte, CT: Information Age Publishing.
(pp. 145–170). Albany, NY: State University of New York NCHS (National Center for History in the Schools) (1994).
Press. National standards for world history: Exploring paths to the
Hunt, M. P., & Metcalf, L. E. (1968). Teaching high school social present. Los Angeles, CA: University of California.
studies. Problems in reflective thinking and social understanding Nussbaum, M., & Cohen, J. (Eds.) (2002). For love of country?:
(2nd ed.). New York: Harper & Row. A new democracy forum on the limits of patriotism. Boston,
Lee, P. J. (1984). Why learn history? In A. Dickinson, P.J. Lee, MA: Beacon Press.
& P. Rogers (Eds.), Learning history (pp. 1–19). London: Osborn, W.W. (1939). An experiment in teaching resistance to pro-
Heinemann Educational. paganda. In W. C. Parker (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind
Lee, P. (2005). Putting principles into practice: Understanding (pp. 61–78). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
history. In M. Donovan, & J.D. Bransford (Eds.), How stu- Oliver, D. W., & Shaver, J. P. (1966). Using a jurisprudential
dents learn history in the classroom. Washington, DC: The framework in the teaching of public issues. In W. C. Parker
National Academies Press. (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind (pp. 145–170). Albany,
Lee, P. J., Dickinson, A. K., & Ashby, R. (2001). Children’s NY: State University of New York Press.
ideas about historical explanation. In A.K. Dickinson, Oliver, D. W., & Shaver, J. P. (1974). Teaching public issues in the
P. Gordon, & P.J. Lee (Eds.), Rising standards in his- high school. Logan, UT: Utah State University Press.
tory instruction. International review of history education Paxton, R. J. (1999). A deafening silence. History textbooks and
(Vol. 3, pp. 97–115). London: Woburn Press. the students who read them. Review of Educational Research,
Leinhardt, G. & Ravi, A.K. (2008). Changing Historical (69)3, 315–339.
Conceptions of History. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.) International Peel E. A. (1967). Some problems in the psychology of history
Handbook on Research on Conceptual Change (pp. 328–341). teaching. In W. H. Burston, & D. Thompson (1967). Studies
London: Routledge. in the nature and teaching of history (pp. 159–172). London:
Leinhardt, G., Stainton, C., Virji, S., & Odoroff, E. (1994). Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Learning to reason in history: Mindlessness to mindfulness. Penuel, W. R., & Wertsch, J. V. (2000). Historical representation
In M. Carretero, & J. F. Voss (Eds.), Cognitive and instruc- as mediated action: Official history as a tool. In J. F. Voss,
tional processes in history and social sciences (pp. 131–158). & M. Carretero (Eds.), Learning and reasoning in history:
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. International review of history education (Vol. 2, pp. 23–37).
Levinson, M. (2009). “Let us now praise . . . ?” Rethinking role London: Routledge.
models and heroes in an egalitarian age. In Y. Raley, & Perfetti, C., Britt, M., Rouet, J., Georgi, M., & Mason, R.
G. Preyer (Eds.), Philosophy of education in the era of global- (1994). How students use texts to learn and reason about
ization (pp. 129–161) New York: Routledge. historical uncertainty. In M. Carretero, & J.F. Voss (Eds.),
Limón, M., & Carretero, M. (1999). Conflicting data and Cognitive and instructional processes in history and social sci-
conceptual change in history experts. In W. Schnotz, ences (pp. 257–283). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
S. Vosniadou, & M. Carretero (Eds.), New perspectives on Perkins, D. (2008). Making learning whole. How seven principles
conceptual change (pp. 137–160). Amsterdam: Elsevier. of teaching can transform education. New York: Wiley.
Limón, M., & Carretero, M. (2000). Evidence evaluation and Piattoeva, N. (2009). Citizenship and nationality in chang-
reasoning abilities in the domain of history: An empirical ing Europe: A comparative study of the aims of citizenship
study. In J. F. Voss, & M. Carretero (Eds.), Learning and education in Russian and Finnish national education policy
reasoning in history. International review of history education texts. Journal of Curriculum Studies, (41)6, 723–744.
(Vol. 2, pp. 252–271). London: Routledge. Porat, D. (2004). It’s not written here, but this is what happened:
Lopez, C. (2010, October 28–30). The Spanish nation in stu- Students’ cultural comprehension of textbook narratives on
dents mind: An ontological concept or a disciplinary one? the Israeli–Arab conflict. American Educational Research
Poster presented at the international seminar on understand- Journal, 41(4), 963.
ing history and the construction of identities in a global world. Portal, C. (Ed.) (1987). The history curriculum for teachers.
De-nationalizing history teaching,, UAM, Madrid. http:// London: The Falmer Press.
www.uam.es/otros/history/abstracts/pos-lopez.pdf. Retrieved Ravitch, D., & Finn, C. (1987). What do our 17-year-olds know?
November 5, 2010. New York: Harper & Row.
Luczynski, J. (1997). The multivoicedness of historical repre- Rugg, H. (1921). Reconstructing the curriculum. In W. C. Parker
sentations in a changing sociocultural context: Young polish (Ed.), Educating the democratic mind (pp. 45–59). Albany, NY:
adults’ representations of World War II, Culture & Psychology, State University of New York Press.
(31)1, 21–40. Sand, S. (2010). The invention of the Jewish people. London:
Maier, R. (2005). Learning about history and the world: Schools, Verso.
teachers, and textbooks in Russia after 1991. In H. Schissler, Schudson, M. (1992). Watergate in American memory: How we
& Y. S. Soysal (Eds.), The nation, Europe and the world. New remember, forget and reconstruct the past. New York: Basic
York: Berghahn Books. Books.
Massialas, B. G., & Cox, C. B. (1966). Inquiry in social studies. Seixas, P. (Ed.) (2004). Theorizing historical consciousness. Toronto:
New York: McGraw Hill. University of Toronto Press.

c a r re t e ro , b e r m u d e z 645
Shemilt, D. (1980) History 13–16: Evaluation Study. Edinburgh: Valsiner, J. (2010, October 28–30). Monuments in our minds:
Holmes McDougall. Historical symbols as cultural tools. Paper presented at under-
Shemilt, D. (1984). Beauty and the philosopher: Empathy in standing history and the construction of identities in a global
history and the classroom. In A. K. Dickinson, P. J. Lee, & world. De-nationalizing history teaching, Madrid. http://www.
P.J. Rogers (Eds.), Learning history (pp. 39–84). London: uam.es/otros/history/abstracts/abs valsiner.pdf. Retrieved
Heinemann Educational. November 5, 2010.
Shemilt, D. (1987). Adolescent ideas about evidence and meth- Van Sledright, B. (2002). In search of America’s past: Learning to
odology in history. In C. Portal (Ed.), The history curriculum read history in elementary school. New York: Teachers College
for teachers (pp. 39–61). London: The Falmer Press. Press.
Shorto, R. (2010). How Christians were the founders? New York Van Sledright, B. (2008). Narratives of Nation-State, histori-
Times Magazine, page MM32 Sunday Magazine. cal knowledge, and school history. Review of Research in
Smith, A. D. (1991). National identity. Reno, NV: University of Education, (32), 109–146.
Nevada Press. von Borries, B. (1994). Moral judgment: On relationships
Stearns, P. N., Seixas, P., & Wineburg, S. (2000). Knowing, teach- between interpretations of the past and perceptions of the
ing, and learning history: National and international perspec- present. In M. Carretero, & J.F. Voss (Eds.), Cognitive and
tives. New York: New York University Press. instructional proceses in history and social sciences (pp. 339–
Straub, J. (Ed.) (2005). Narration, identity, and historical con- 356). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
sciousness. New York: Berghahn Books. Wertsch, J. W. (1997). Narrative tools of history and identity.
Symcox, L., & Wilschut, A. (Eds.) (2009). National history stan- Culture and Psychology, (3)1, 5–20.
dards. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Wertsch, J. V., & Rozin, M. (2000). The Russian Revolution:
The Academy of Korean Studies (2005). Nationalism and history Official and unofficial accounts. In J. F. Voss, & M. Carretero
textbooks in Asia and Europe. Seoul, Korea: Editor. (Eds.), Learning and reasoning in history: International review
Todorov, T. (1998). On human diversity: Nationalism, racism, of history education (Vol. 2, pp. 39–59). London: Routledge.
and exoticism in French thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard White, H. (1987). The content of the form: Narrative discourse
University Press. French edition : Nous et les autres. La réflex- and historical representation. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins
ion francaise sur la diversité humaine. París: Seuil, 1989. University Press.
Valls, R. (2007). The Spanish civil war and the Franco dicta- Wineburg, S. (2001). Historical thinking and other unnatural acts.
torship: The challenges of representing a conflictive past in Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
secondary schools. In E. Cole (Ed.), Teaching the violent Wineburg, S., Mosborg, S., Porat, D., & Duncan, A. (2007).
past: History education and reconciliation (pp. 155–174). Common belief and the cultural curriculum: An intergenera-
Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers in coopera- tional study of historical consciousness. American Educational
tion with the Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Research Journal, 44(1), 40–76.
Affairs, MD.

646 construct ing hi stor i e s


PA RT
7
Emergence of Culture
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Roots of Culture in the Umwelt


29
Riin Magnus and Kalevi Kull

Abstract
This chapter begins by introducing the background, basic constituents and principles of the umwelt model
and theory developed by the Baltic German biologist Jakob von Uexküll (1864–1944) in the first decades
of the twentieth century. This is followed by a discussion of the features of the umwelt concept that
has provided the impetus for interpretations of human activities and cultural processes. The once
biology-bound model has by now found its way into very diverse traditions of thought. We concentrate
on four major trends in interpreting cultural phenomena with the help of umwelt theory: (1) the
Uexküllian functional circle model of perception and action as a predecessor of models that couple
human forms of impression and expression; (2) the mediated versus immediate character of human in
contrast with animal worlds; (3) the bridging of natural and cultural phenomena via semiotic processes;
(4) the integration of the cognitive and the social interpretations of (human) mind via two facets of
umwelt. The chapter includes some hints on the aspects of the umwelt model that could be elaborated
further in the analysis of culture.
Keywords: functional circle, impression and expression, modeling systems, semiosphere, Uexküll,
umwelt

Culture, Semiosphere, Umwelt interweaving in a common semiotic space is named


According to the semiotician and culturolo- the semiosphere (Lotman 2005).
gist Juri Lotman, cultures have a structure that is The semiosphere is a necessary medium for all
analogous to individual human minds in several sign processes as well as the totality of sign processes
of its fundamental features. In some of their gen- itself. Like the biosphere, which is the organic totality
eral structural aspects, as well as in some rules of of living matter as well as the precondition for the
their dynamics, these complex semiotic systems are persistence of life, the semiosphere is the result as well
isomorphic to each other (Lotman, 1984,1990). as the precondition for the development of culture
Both a culture and an individual world are fields (Lotman, 2000, p. 125). Departing from Thomas
of sign processes. Both entail many codes, several A. Sebeok’s (1920–2001) thesis, according to which
sign systems, translation processes, heterogeneity, the origin of semiosis (sign process) coincides with
asymmetry, borders, center and periphery, continu- the origin of life, we can assume that sign processes
ity and discreetness, unpredictability, and a certain (as the basis of recognition, discrimination, signifi-
processual logic. Both are embedded and molded cation) characterize human minds as well as animal
by communication and dialogue, which are primary minds. We can therefore describe the semiosphere
in respect with individual languages. The general of the worlds of organisms, all living organisms
model Lotman proposed for describing personali- included. This is how the concept of semiosphere
ties, texts, and cultures as semiotic systems and their is used in contemporary biosemiotics—the branch

649
of semiotics dealing with the organic part of the food and the destroyer of food, enemy and prey, and
semiosphere (Cobley, 2010; Hoffmeyer, 2008). above all, male and female in astonishing variations.
A predecessor of such a semiotic view in biology
That semiosic systems are simultaneously
was the Baltic German biologist Jakob von Uexküll
modeling systems was also emphasized in the 1960s
(1864–1944) with his concept of umwelt. Umwelt
by the Tartu-Moscow School of semiotics (Lotman,
is the world an organism creates, in which it lives. It
1967; Levchenko & Salupere 1999; Kull, 2010a).
is the meaningful world based on sign relations. A
Here modeling systems (which encompassed
quite common definition states that umwelt is the
languages as well as arts) were understood as the
personal world of an organism, or a self-centered
structure of elements and the rules of their com-
world, “the world as known or modelled” (Cobley,
bination that stood in an analogical relationship to
2010,p. 348). This definition, although correct
some object of cognition (Lotman, 1967, p. 130).
in itself, may not emphasize the relational aspect
Modeling systems provide the means for com-
of the umwelt concept enough. Therefore we can
prehending the outside world and yet, they are
also complementarily define umwelt as a set of sign
themselves the primary sources of world formation.
relations an organism has in an ecosystem (as in a
Connecting the ideas of Jakob von Uexküll and
semiosphere) (Kull, 2010b).
Juri Lotman, we could also say that culture is contin-
Thus, if umwelt is made of relations, of semiosic
uously created via human umwelt making. Cultural
bonds, we can conclude that organisms are deriva-
modeling as umwelt making includes all of the
tives of (sign) relations. Umwelt (as a relational, i.e.,
building, shaping, and design humans do in their
a meaningful world) exists even prior to the capacity
surroundings (i.e., besides “texts” in a narrow sense,
to use representations, since organisms can often be
also clothes, tools, technologies, architecture, and
involved in sign processes without building repre-
landscape). The umwelt-based semiotic approach to
sentations. Conversely, of course, there cannot be
culture may further widen the understanding of the
an umwelt without life. Life is centered on orga-
borders of culture by including semiosic processes
nisms, in their agency; therefore, umwelten are also
of an ecosystem into a single whole with human
individual and individualized.
culture proper. This means widening the basis of
All organisms participate in the construction
culture from language to semiosis.
of their umwelten. Organisms participate in
A semiotic interpretation, to which we will come
making their umwelten because this is generally a
back later, is just one way of linking the idea of umwelt
communication (including autocommunication)
with culture-specific constructions. In order to bring
process that modifies and constructs umwelten.
forth the variety of those links, we will further sketch
Building and modifying one’s umwelt is simulta-
the chief impetuses the umwelt idea has provided for
neously a communicative process and a modeling
interpretations of human activities and cultural pro-
process.
cesses. We shall demonstrate how different interpreta-
As Thomas Sebeok has pointed out regarding
tions of the umwelt concept allow the integration of
the scientific use of the term “umwelt,” “the closest
otherwise contradictory approaches to culture.
equivalent in English is manifestly “model” (Sebeok,
2001, p. 75). The description of a particular umwelt
Jakob von Uexküll’s Umwelt Model and Its
will mean the demonstration of how the organism
Constituents
maps the world, and what, for that organism, the
Although the common German word “umwelt”
meanings of the objects are within it. How the
is traditionally translated into English as “environ-
formation of individual worlds entails meaning-
ment,” its use as a loanword refers to the specific
ful operations was likewise described by Jakob von
concept worked out by Jakob von Uexküll in the
Uexküll in his Theory of Meaning (Bedeutungslehre)
first decades of the twentieth century.1
(Uexküll, 1982 [1940], pp. 64, 69):
Umwelt is the world as accessed and formed
Meaning in nature’s score serves as a connecting link, by the organism via its specific sensory and motor
or rather as a bridge, and takes the place of harmony devices. The section of reality that a biologist should
in a musical score; it joins two of nature’s factors. [ . . . ] describe, according to Uexküll, is thus of the organ-
Each meaning-carrier was always confronted with ism’s own making. In other words, umwelt is the set
a meaning-receiver, even in [ . . . ] earlier umwelten. of perceptual and action-based distinctions, shared
Meaning ruled them all. Meaning tied changing in a large extent by the members of one species and
organs to a changing medium. Meaning connected described by an external observer.

650 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


Umwelt as the world of meaningful objects, is When in contact with some object, a particular
always paired by its intraorganismic counterpart— perceptual sign (e.g., a sweet taste) is first received
Innenwelt (inner world). If umwelt denotes the by the organism and then projected to the outside
outside world as it appears to the animal via its world as a perceptual cue of that object (the sweet-
perceptual and motor apparatus, then Innenwelt ness of a fruit). The complex of the perceptual sign
refers to the experience side of the phenomena as and perceptual cue further induces the formation
experienced by the organism. However, the organ- of an effector sign. The effector sign is the image of
ism never feels itself as such. What is felt is some the action that is to be carried out in respect with
object of the umwelt, which indirectly refers to the the object (e.g., biting the fruit). Like the percep-
subjective center of world formation via the mean- tual sign, also the effector sign is projected outside
ing it carries to the animal. It is also the external as a cue or property of the object (the “bitability” of
object that serves as a ground for the species-specific the fruit). If the necessary action is accomplished,
coordination between the perceptual and motor a new perceptual sign can emerge and a new circle
apparatus. “Just like the factors of umwelt are will begin. The circles of perception and action fol-
objective, also the effects that they bring about in low one another until the need that initiated them
the nervous system have to be treated in the same has been satisfied (e.g., until the animal has satisfied
manner. These effects are also organized and regu- its hunger).
lated by the building plan. They together form the The model can also be seen as a hybrid of reflex
Innenwelt of the animal”2 (Uexküll, 1909, p. 6). arc schemes from biology and later communica-
The overarching principle that binds umwelt with tion models. At first glance, the Innenwelt part of
Innenwelt is mentioned here as Bauplan (building Uexküll’s model could be interpreted as a unifica-
plan)–—the specific anatomical and physiologi- tion of the afferent and efferent pathways of the
cal structure of the animal. The Bauplan concept reflex arc. The perceptual and motor cues, in turn,
encompasses both the developmental pathways of could be termed as equivalents of stimuli, initia-
the organism as well as the functional aspect of the tors of irritation. As a remarkable difference from
organism’s perceptions and actions. Although the the reflex arc scheme, linear logic models do not
focus for this umwelt concept is on the operation of work here. The explanation needed is therefore
sense organs and motor systems, when the forma- closer to the one used by complex systems theory,
tion of the umwelt is described, these systems are where downward and upward causation have to be
always to be seen as embedded in the totality of the accounted for simultaneously (see Gilbert & Sarkar,
organism itself. The key elements and characteristics 2000). Incorporating all elements of the functional
of the umwelt formation process were modeled by circle under the word welt denotes that the depar-
Uexküll as a schema, which he called a functional ture point for the observer of the animal’s behavior
circle (Funktionskreis) (see an adaptation of Uexküll’s should be the whole set of meanings with all the
schema in Figure 29.1). characteristic relationships between them just as
well as particular acts of perception and action.
Individual causes and effects, and the extraction of
single stimulus and response pairs, can be derived
only from an already understood set of possible
meanings, but the world-formation is itself observ-
Perceptual sign Perceptual cue able and accessible only via the individual acts. We
will return to this principle of part-whole mutual
Subject Object conditioning when describing the Romantic
philosophical roots of Uexküll’s umwelt theory.
Effector sign Effector cue Comparing the functional circle model with
classical models of communication3, may allow us
to see the subject as both a sender of messages about
its physiological state to the outside world and as a
receiver of responses to those states by the object-as-
Innenwelt Umwelt a-sender. However, the functional circle model does
not articulate the difference between the active and
Figure 29.1 An adaptation of Jakob von Uexküll’s functional passive object in the process. It does not therefore
circle model.

m agn u s, ku ll 651
permit a distinction between the acts of perception psychology and philosophy (esp. pragmatism) (cf.
and communication. Phillips, 1971; Bredo, 1998).
John Dewey’s 1896 article “The reflex arc con-
From Reflections to Coordination: How the cept in psychology” identified the persistence of two
Umwelt Concept Emerged kinds of older dualisms in the dominant models of
In order to track the road from umwelt to cul- the reflex arc: (1) the dualism between sensation and
ture and to explain how some principles of cultural idea—as being repeated in the dualism of peripheral
existence are to be viewed if umwelt is seen as their and central structures, and (2) the dualism of body
predecessor, we need to visualize the road leading to and soul—as still present in the dualism of stimulus
the basic model of umwelt theory itself. Jakob von and response (Dewey, 1896). Dewey argued against
Uexküll started his career by researching the physi- the separation of stimulus-response as two distinct
ology of marine invertebrates. While working in the physical absolutes, tied to sensation and reaction
physiology laboratories in Heidelberg and Naples, respectively.
he concentrated on the muscular movements of
What shall we term that which is not sensation-
sea urchins, brittle stars, octopuses, etc. (cf. Rüting
followed-by-movement, but which is primary;
2004, p. 39; Mildenberger, 2007). It is exactly here
which is, as it were, the psychical organism of which
that the empirical grounds of the developed umwelt
sensation, idea and movement are the chief organs?
theory are to be found: in those early works on
Stated on the physiological side, this reality may most
muscular tonus accompanied by research on reflex
conveniently be termed coordination.
movements and the nearly 200 years of debate about
(Dewey, 1972 [1896], p. 97)
the exact mechanisms behind them.
The eighteenth-century explanations of invol- Coordination is always present in each act of sen-
untary movement that preceded the nineteenth- sation or reaction as an “ideal” from which the two
century reflex concept, exhibited disagreements have deviated as conflicting parties and try to regain
on several grounds. One set of disagreements con- the initial state of coordination. Coordination is
cerned the (in)applicability of optical theories of thus presented by Dewey as a process whereby the
reflection to the biological relations of irritation dynamic stability of the organism is achieved.
and movement. Georges Canguilhem has dem- Jakob von Uexküll and his colleagues Theodor
onstrated how the period encountered on the one Beer and Albert Bethe published in 1899 an arti-
hand convictions that the irritation-movement pair cle where they suggest a new objective nomencla-
functions according to the mirror law.4 According ture for physiology. In the article they claim that
to this principle, the texture of the medulla serves physiology should be purified from the ambiguous
as a “mirror” upon which the incident irritation terms like “light” or “sound” and terms indicating
falls and reflects back to the motor nerves. Those the physical origin and properties of objective stim-
claims were countered by authors (e.g., George uli should be used instead (Beer, Bethe & Uexküll,
Prochaska and Robert Whytt) who denied the suf- 1899). Here they seem to identify themselves with
ficiency of optical parallels for explaining medullar the tradition of a physics-bound physiology rather
mediation of irritation and movement and who than with the more organism-specific perspective.
asked for the formulation of specific biological laws Solely because of the position presented in this arti-
in order to clarify the issue (Canguilhem, 1994, pp. cle, Uexküll’s research was received as a representa-
179–202). tive of the mechanistic-behaviorist physiology, even
Several classical models of a reflex arc in the in his later career when he distanced himself from
second half of the nineteenth century followed the his earlier theoretical grounds (see Mildenberger,
physicalist line of thought while explaining the 2006; Mildenberger, 2007, p. 58).
organism as a thing among things, comparable to Closer examination reveals that even this objec-
a physical body by which the same impulses always tivist manifesto already contains ontological threads
result in the same reaction. Reflex arc models, leading to the later umweltlehre. What is lacking in
which depicted the nervous system as a mecha- the latter and saliently present in the manifesto is
nism of simple motion transfer (cf. Bains, 2006, a significant discrepancy between the ontological
p. 61), received significant criticism already at the and the epistemological standpoints. While propos-
time of their wider distribution. The earlier critical ing a new nomenclature for sensory physiology, the
fronts came not just from physiology, but also from authors differentiate between the objective stimulus,

652 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


the physiological proceeding, and the eventual sen- superimposition of one of the systems on the other.
sation. The footnote to the objective stimulus, how- On the contrary, the central concept for describing
ever, states: these relations is punctus contra punctum—they have
to match like two notes in a chord. The principle
We admit that the stimulus is nothing but an
of responsive, counterpoint-like correspondence is
objectified sensation, but we stay by the conviction
central for understanding how it is possible to pro-
that natural scientists, in order to retain a stable
ceed from the perceptual systems to the commu-
ground, should take an unbiased standpoint, from
nicative, dialogical ones. This key factor also opens
where one could observe the outwards projected
up the possibility for umwelt-based research to serve
Erscheinungswelt5 as materially present. (Beer, Bethe
not just as a descriptive system, but also as a tool for
& Uexküll, 1899, p. 517)
understanding. The animal in this case is not merely
The new nomenclature is therefore suggested an object of scientific observation but a response
because of merely heuristic reasons; the authors to the research question posed by the researcher’s
attempt to deny asserting any reality to the objec- own perceptual and cognitive schemes. Partaking
tive stimulus. Uexküll’s later writing on umweltlehre in the communicative act provides the researcher
resolved this former discrepancy by adjusting the with as much knowledge about his own mind as it
theoretical framework according to his ontological does about the communicatively observed animal.
axioms. And the more conscious one becomes of one’s own
How could such a step be taken? What enabled perceptual restrictions, clarifying thus the structure
the initially self-determined scientific methodology of one’s own research tools, the more the under-
to be attuned to the “demands” of biological standing of the other will correspond to the features
reality? of the other. Scientific truth in this case does not
Above all, this leap in Uexküll’s ontological com- need to choose sides between idealistic or realistic
mitments is caused by the synthesis of philosophical premises—it is formed only while participating in
and scientific standpoints. The philosophical per- the mutual exchange of information, where the
spective, traditionally bracketed out from strictly object explicates the subject’s characteristics and
scientific investigations, was brought in to take part vice versa.
in the explorations of the living world. Only through
the coordination and integration of ideas belonging Umwelt Theory as a Springboard for Models
to different realms of human knowledge (either of Culture
to scientific, philosophical, or artistic) could orga- Uexküll himself did not provide significant
nisms be understood as entities who themselves base reflections on how his umwelt theory could be
their existence on coordination and integration.6 applied particularly to human beings (setting aside
This synthetic understanding of human knowl- his constant reminder that all researchers are bound
edge, which formed the epistemological founda- with their own perceptual boundaries, even when
tion of the umwelt idea, was the legacy of Romantic talking about the umwelt of another species, and
theories of human mind. First, it followed the his rather loose transfer of the umwelt concept to
Romantic ideals of the entwined architectonics of describe the characters of his friends). But Uexküll’s
human comprehension. Secondly, it considered the writings on the umwelt concept have served as an
principle of the isomorphic relations between the impetus for later philosophers and representatives of
object and the tools of research. Goethe figuratively other humanities to delve on the issue of its applica-
expressed the latter in the introduction to his Colour bility to human beings.
Theory (Zur Farbenlehre), quoted also by Uexküll: For the sake of conciseness, we are not aiming at
“If the eye were not sun-like, it could never behold describing all directions of influence, as the idea has
the sun. If the sun were not eye-like, it could not found its way into very diverse traditions of thought
shine in any sky,”7 and in his statement that “simi- (for overviews see Kull, 2001; Mildenberger, 2007; on
lar can be recognized only by a similar” (nur von the additional aspects, see Berthoz & Christen, 2009;
Gleichem werde Gleiches erkannt) (Goethe, 1810, Chang, 2009; Kliková & Kleisner, 2006; Magnus,
p. xxxviii). The structural principles of the object 2008). We therefore focus on four kinds of topics
and the descriptive system have to match with each in umwelt theory that have triggered discussions
other. Such matching and likeness of the observer on the question of specifically human umwelten:
and the observed does not require an overlap or (1) the perception-action pairing as a fundamental

m agn u s, ku ll 653
property of “being alive” and as a source for the fur- activities of an organism, rely on the encoded differ-
ther developments of human-specific impressions ence between its perception and action, impression
and expressions; (2) the immediacy vs. mediated- and expression. The latter principle—the necessity
ness of animal and human action; (3) the semiotic of twofold activities for the preservation of complex
embeddedness of all living beings, which leads to phenomena or forms—is a topic that has provided
the view of life as the primary threshold of semiotic common discussion ground for the philosophy
activity; (4) the integration of the perspective of the of biology on the one hand and phenomenology
subject and the perspective of the system. of perception and philosophy of art on the other.
One of the central authors uniting those two fields
The Principle of Counterpoints: is Maurice Merleau-Ponty who also found a strong
Relating Impression with Expression impetus from Uexküll’s umwelt theory, particularly
Let us first examine the first of those four—to for his courses on nature held at the Collège de
what extent is the basic model of the functional cir- France from 1956 to 1958.
cle applicable to human sensations and expressions? Merleau-Ponty’s idea about the compulsory two-
According to Uexküll, all objects enter the animal’s fold nature of the body as a perceiver and as per-
umwelt via their perceptual as well as effector cues ceived can be summed up with his central motive of
by inducing clearly distinguished perceptual and the “double sensation,” when my one hand touches
effector responses. Such a twofold process of receiv- my other hand (see Merleau-Ponty, 2002 [1945], p.
ing information followed by returning it reworked 106, 1968 [1964], p. 141, 2003 [1995], pp. 74–75).
in an organism-specific form is characteristic for all It explains how one and the same body serves as a
living beings. Although there is a long evolution- ground for acting and being acted upon and yet can
ary distance between the recognitions carried out never be in the two positions simultaneously. This
by the cellular receptor proteins and signaling mol- temporal hiatus between the always reversible states
ecules (as perception), and corresponding genetic of touching and being touched, seeing and being
expressions, metabolic changes, or apoptotic beha- visible, as Merleau-Ponty explains, does not result
vior (as effects), and the orientation of vertebrates in an ontological void between the two states, but
via highly differentiated sense organs (as receptors) “is spanned by the total being of my body, and by
and the limbic system (as effectors), both systems that of the world, it is the zero of pressure between
involve the establishment of a coded correspon- two solids that makes them adhere to one another”
dence between the receptor and effector activities as (Merleau-Ponty, 1968 [1964], p. 148). Merleau-
their basis. This does not amount to stating that the Ponty further postulated that the principle of
same impulse always results in the same response. reversibility does not reside just in one’s own body,
The organism with its specific form and current but also among different organisms, which he des-
physiological state serves as a translation matrix that ignated with the word intercorporeity. By perceiving
uses the correspondence between the perceptual we thus also perceive the others as perceiving, as far
and the motor systems in order to preserve its own as sensibility is unbound from its belonging to one
organic form with each object-oriented functional and the same consciousness. This sort of a possibil-
circle. The coded duality of perception and action is ity for the perception of the other as a perceiving
simply a device via which the organism encounters subject is absent in the Uexküllian umwelt model.
meanings essential for its specific form of existence. Here, the reversibility of umwelt and Innenwelt, of
Interpreting the organism as a translational matrix the perceived objects and the perceiving subject, is
means that it provides an interpretational frame- not possible, as the subject’s identity is solely based
work, in which all perceived objects are approached on the specific contacts with the objects as counter-
as actionable and actioned objects as perceivable. structures. All objects in the world of an animal
We may thus infer from this that the specific are directed toward its own existence; there is no
linkage between what the organism perceives about object for another. Uexküll thereby remained true
the environment and how it responds can be formed to the Kantian treatment of the subject, where “I
only via a common meaningful framework between can grasp the unity of the I only through its pro-
the two. Further, it is important to note that once ductions” (Merleau-Ponty, 2003 [1995], p. 22). In
such a relation has been established, its functioning the Uexküllian approach, there is a correspondence
becomes a necessity for preserving the meaningful between the different umwelten, but it is not caused
framework itself. Thus the particular form, as well as by the subject’s perception of the other as a subject

654 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


and an object simultaneously, but it is caused by a prior to feeling adhered perception to action, feeling
general, supra-subjective plan of nature. then becomes attached to its reverse in the form of
The function of presenting oneself as a perceiv- expression. This kind of a “felt life” unites and serves
able object can be elaborated by special organs as a foundation both for biological expressions such
which exteriorize the organism in the same manner as gestures, postures, etc., as well as for artistic pre-
as the sense organs interiorize the world. This is sentational symbols (see Weber, 2002). The latter
the manner in which the Swiss zoologist Adolf are distinguished from discursive symbols, as they
Portmann discussed the function of the skin and express not merely ideas, providing access to the
other body surfaces as phenomena that have devel- more basic levels of organic existence.
oped with the potential of being perceived by Biological expressions as well as presentational
someone else (Portmann, 1990; cf. Kleisner, 2008). symbols both express a certain significance and value
Firstly, the merely physiological function of several that impressions have for the particular form of life.
morphological traits has been enriched with a com- By filtering and sorting out only those bits of infor-
municative function during evolution. The hair and mation that are meaningful for the particular living
plumage of warm-blooded animals became organs being, the peripheral organs already act toward the
of communication besides their initial role of fix- preservation of the form of which they constitute a
ing stable body temperature; the skin’s capillary part. Langer (1988 [1972], p. 55) has noted:
network intensifies the color of the skin and thus
[ . . . ] The primary characteristics which animals see
serves as a sign for the psychosomatic state of the
are values, and all the qualities of form, color, shape,
animal (Portmann, 1961, pp. 77–97). Secondly,
sound, warmth, and even smell, by which we would
there are multiple examples of morphological
naturally expect them to recognize things, enter into
features that have never served any specific physio-
their perceptual acts only as they enter into their
logical function for the organism at all and to which
overt behaviour as values for action.
Portmann attributes the role of the “self-expression/
or presentation” of the organism. Those traits may Susanne Langer’s philosophy of presentational forms
also attain a communicative function in the course highlights the role of perception in opening up the
of time, as is the case with some color patterns world for signs, taking sense-data as receptacles of
that acquire a mimetic value or begin to operate as meaning (Langer, 1956 [1942]). “Eyes that did not
warning signals. see forms could never furnish it [the human mind]
Yet another variation on the topic of the antici- with images; ears that did not hear articulated
pation of action in perception (and vice versa) as a sounds could never open it to words” (Langer, 1956
binding phenomenon of humans and other living [1942], p. 73). However, in the Uexküllian umwelt,
beings is provided by the American philosopher of the meanings occur always together with forms. As
art, Susanne Langer. Like Merleau-Ponty, Langer far as all forms are functional and function is based
turned to biophilosophical questions in her later on meaning, there is no before or after the meaning,
works while also integrating critical accounts of the as those categories are already abstractions unattain-
umwelt theory (Langer, 1986 [1967]). The central able to the animal itself.
notion upon which Langer builds her theory of the
rootedness of artistic expression in the biological Poor Animals and Deficient Humans
experience is “feeling.” As for an organism, what is Both Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Susanne
felt is an action in the organism, either in the form Langer had explicated a particular organism-centric
of an impact or as autogenic action (Langer, 1986 mode of existence that opens the organism up for
[1967] pp. 23–24). Prior to the arousal of feelings, the world and yet, at the same time, encloses the
the simpler organisms already based their exis- organism in its specific modes of appearance. Both
tence on perception containing “values for action.” had stressed the importance of seeing the anticipa-
With the development of the nervous system, feel- tion of action in even the most primitive perceptual
ing arises not as a property, but as a phase of vital contacts with the world; perception was understood
activity (like ice is a phase of water), providing thus as already being attuned to the behavioral setting
several physiological processes with the new status and to the set of possible actions, (Merleau-Ponty,
of “being felt.” The arousal of the domain of feeling 2002 [1945]; cf. also Harney, 2007) or carrying
is necessarily accompanied by its transfiguration values for the subsequent activities (Langer, 1988
into an expression. Thus if the organism’s condition [1972]; cf. Weber, 2002).

m agn u s, ku ll 655
The umwelt theory provided quite a different is characteristic to all nonhuman worlds (Heidegger,
impetus for two other thinkers—Martin Heidegger 1983), is echoed also in the work of his other-
and Arnold Gehlen. Although using different argu- wise critical student, Czech phenomenologist Jan
ments and bodies of knowledge, they both main- Patočka (Patočka, 1998 [1995]). Patočka contrasts
tained the impossibility of departing from the the animal, embedded in the relations of immedi-
notion of umwelt while tackling any of the essen- ate relevancy, forced into the constraints of constant
tial questions concerning human beings. They both presence, with the human, who is open not just to
appreciate Uexküll’s contribution to the descrip- the domains of past and future, but also to all pos-
tion of the fundamental conditions of “being an sible forms of past and future, which he calls quasi-
animal,” but demand a new contrastive principle for structures (quasi-future, quasi-present) (Patočka,
the explication of human conduct. 1998 [1995], p. 32).
Gehlen found that human imperfection (der Excluding the aspects of past and future from the
Mensch als Mängelwesen) in relation to any specific activity of any living being is highly problematic if
environmental condition is striking when compar- the preservation of organic form is to be explained.
ing it with the perfect matching of the animal and Each act and activity of an organism already antici-
its environment.8 He traced the idea of the deficient pates some further biological state, thus contribut-
human being, lacking all means that would allow ing to the presence of the specific organic form in
him to attach, to fix himself to any environmental the future. Each value and meaning that an animal
affordances, back to J. G. Herder’s reflections on the encounters in the objects of its environment is at
origin of culture (Gehlen, 1997 [1940]). Inapt to the same time an encounter with a possible future
face any demands of the environment by means of state. The “not yet” of the organism is touched
specialized organs, humans had to choose a different upon with each perceptual act, giving way to the
strategy for getting by. Culture was thus established continuation of the self without reducing duration
as a compensatory mechanism for biological insuf- to an extracted present. A living being, therefore, is
ficiencies. In the biological sense, man is not yet never a point in space, but an ontogenetic as well as
ready, according to Gehlen; he is a task for himself. phylogenetic extension, without a fixed moment of
Unlike Arnold Gehlen, Max Scheler, and Adolf beginning and end, but with definite choices for the
Portmann, philosophers Martin Heidegger and self-specific persistence.
Ernst Cassirer9 did not take specific morphological All interpretations of Uexküll’s umwelt concept
traits of man nor the adaptive inaptness accom- introduced in this chapter, refer to it as a model that
panying them as a departure point for describing explicates the strict adaptations and deterministic,
man’s exceptional position among other living although species-specific, attachment of animal to
beings. Both Cassirer and Heidegger focused more its environment. In the next chapter, we return to
strictly on man’s specific mental modes of relating the semiotic interpretations and see how the above-
to the outer world. In broad terms, they both dis- mentioned versions were challenged by a number
closed the semiotic or symbolic hiatus between man of authors who questioned the claim that mediated
and animal, the human escape from the restraints access to the world is a privilege of humankind.
of immediate physiological reactions. In his “An
Essay on Man: An Introduction to a Philosophy Across the Semiotic Pass
of Human Culture,” Cassirer, when discussing the A new merging of umweltlehre and the humani-
human entrance to the world of symbolic forms, ties in the form of a semiotic synthesis took place
also considers the new coercion that is thereby set in the mid-1970s. It was a time when the language-
on man (Cassirer, 1944). Once the novel sphere of and culture-bound discipline of semiotics started to
symbolic interactions is opened up, man becomes seriously question its scope and extent. The coming
fully enmeshed and enclosed in it. From then on, years featured intensive discussions on the need to
symbolic filtering becomes the single pathway lower the semiotic threshold, i.e., to realize that the
leading from the self to the world, although, in human mind and language are not the first instances
essence, it always results in auto-communication, of semiotic activity, but that animals, plants and in
with man being caught in the forms of knowledge fact the whole living domain is based on the use of
that establish his own identity. signs and the functioning of sign processes. Those
Martin Heidegger’s concern with the human new questions and research perspectives led to the
world, free from the captivity of the immediacy that establishment of a field called biosemiotics, which

656 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


concentrates specifically on the semiotic character The Integration of Two Meanings
of various biological processes (from immunological of Umwelt
recognition to animal communication). Despite centuries of debate, contemporary
As the establishment of any new field is accom- sciences of man still find themselves in what have
panied by the awakening and construction of its been called the “turf wars between sociology and
dormant historic background, so was the case for psychology” (Watson & Coulter, 2008, p. 2), i.e.,
biosemiotics. After clarifying its basic principles, the debates between the social versus cognitive
biosemiotics began with a search for the confir- interpretations of the human mind. Whereas the
mational past. One of the founders of biosemiot- contradiction inside the humanities has gained
ics, Thomas A. Sebeok, with his primary interest in further support from a corresponding institutional
animal cognition and communication, found his segregation, a number of philosophical endeavors,
predecessors mostly from ethological circles (Heini from phenomenology to pragmatism, have aimed
Hediger, Jakob von Uexküll) (Sebeok, 1999, 2001). at undermining the battleground. Extending and
The list of forefathers grew with the expansion of contextualizing the problem of mind, incorporating
the field itself to include scientists from a number knowledge from areas separated by disciplinary bor-
of subfields of biology; for example the embryolo- ders, and inventing fully novel research arenas have
gist Karl Ernst von Baer and the psychologist James all granted some assuagement, to a certain extent at
Mark Baldwin. This biosemiotic quest for ancestors least. Seen in the light of these developments, the
stemming from biology ran parallel with the reread- theory of umwelt and its later cultural theoretical
ings of the classical authors of semiotics. Although adaptations also face two alternatives—to join the
American pragmatist philosopher Charles Sanders debaters on either side of the cognitive-social divide
Peirce was to become the historical mentor for a or to adhere to the challenging efforts.
significant part of biosemiotic research (Thomas The umwelt concept could contribute to either
Sebeok had called him the loadstar of semiotics (cf. one of the sides, if suitable threads of thought are
Deely, 2004)), it is perhaps even more interesting extracted from the full web of the theory. Thus the
to see how authors strictly bound to the humanities cognitive enclosure of an animal (including humans)
were linked to discussions of biosemiotics and to results in fully one-sided construction of all objects,
biological umwelt models. unless the organism itself is simultaneously explained
Thus Jakob von Uexküll’s son, Thure von Uexküll as a product of the constitutive ecological or social
(1908–2004), who related the umwelt theory to relations. On the other hand, the (biological) sub-
very different models of semiotic processes, linked ject’s meaning-initiated activity dissolves into a chain
it even with a theory that is otherwise considered of causal reactions to environmental stimuli, unless
to be in opposition with biosemiotic principles. He the role of the organism as an active center of mean-
explicated a homomorphic relationship between the ing formation is taken into account. In order to not
principles of Jakob von Uexküll’s umweltlehre and thereby tear apart the subject-as-meaning-provider
the structural semiotics of Ferdinand de Saussure.10 and subject-as-relations-induced, it is essential to
According to T. von Uexküll, Saussure’s distinc- find a framework of analysis that would maintain
tion between the abstract language system (langue) the two meanings of umwelt: as a world initiated and
and the concrete speech acts (parole) (Saussure, comprehended by the subject and as a node in the
1998 [1916]) might be seen as corresponding to set of ecological relations encompassing the whole
Jakob von Uexküll’s differentiation between plan biosphere. Those two could also be referred to as the
of nature and its concrete realizations in life activ- phenomenological and ecological facets of the the-
ity (T. v. Uexküll, 1992, pp. 4–6). T. von Uexküll ory of the umwelt. Only the simultaneous presence
made an important distinction between biological and usage of the two can guarantee a steady position
and linguistic sign systems, however, naming the outside the above-mentioned dilemma.
former perceptual or monological systems (based on The essential question therefore is whether we
innate codes) and the latter dialogical systems (based could indicate some primary integrative mecha-
on learned cultural codes). The classical authors of nism that guarantees and produces the coherence
semiotics whose ideas Thure von Uexküll integrated of the two, and that logically explains their simulta-
with those of Jakob von Uexküll, included Charles neous presence? Uexküll himself has suggested what
Morris, Gottlob Frege and C. S. Peirce (T. von he called planmässigkeit, as a ground for the syn-
Uexküll, 1982, 1992, 1999). thesis (Uexküll, 1927, 1973 [1928]). As the word

m agn u s, ku ll 657
seems to hint to a metaphysical grounding based two constancies calling forth one another. The self-
on a preestablished harmony, preformationism, tel- regulative and self-maintaining capacities of the
eology, and an idealized state of affairs, it has not organism had been a research interest of physiolo-
found many elaborations by later authors (although gists at least since the works of Claude Bernard in
see Hoffmeyer, 2004, 2008, pp. 172–173; Cheung, the mid-nineteenth century. Observations and dis-
2004). However, several additional processes have cussions about the corresponding properties of eco-
been suggested for what could also ground the systems, however, were just emerging in the 1920s
integration of the phenomenal and the ecological and 1930s (in the works of, e.g., Frederic Clements,
in umwelt theory, irrespective of whether planmäs- John F. V. Phillips, Victor Shelford), at the time
sigkeit is accepted or not. They can all be seen as Uexküll wrote his major works. As the theories of
mechanisms capable of establishing the relative the self-regulation of ecosystems were still in their
autonomy of some entity, applicable at the same outset in the first decades of the twentieth century,
time to a number of natural and cultural phenomena it may have been one of the reasons why Uexküll,
(thus the phenomena of mind just as well as cells, in an organicist manner, used at some occasions the
organisms, and whole ecosystems can be included). metaphor of the organism for describing the regu-
Frederick Stjernfelt, for example, has used subject- larities in whole ecosystems, instead of discussing
dependent categorical perception as a bonding the characteristics of the ecosystems proper (cf.
mechanism between different species-specific phe- Uexküll, 1909, p. 196).
nomenal worlds:
Conclusion
[ . . . ] the condition of possibility for nature to link We indicated a variety of ways in which Jakob
up in these strange ‘harmonies’ between different von Uexküll’s theory of the species-specific umwelt
species’ umwelten depends precisely on categorical has been thus far applied to the analysis of culture
perception: the perceptual categories form the tones and the human mind. These concrete derivations
in the metaphor, and it is their categoricity only that have departed from different aspects of the theory
permits them to enter into counterpoint between the while using it as a springboard for inferences con-
single umwelten. (Stjernfelt, 2007, p. 236) cerning man. The following associations between
umwelt theory and its cultural implications can
The traces of categorization and the complemen-
hence be brought out:
tarity of the categories of different species are
observable by any kind of spatial and temporal 1. If umwelt theory is interpreted as a
discreteness. Unless the form and expressions of demonstration of how biological form and
one species and the perception of another—e.g., behavior expose the sensory impressions an
the movement speed of the prey animal and the organism is capable of receiving, it may also
predator animal’s perceptual time-sectioning, the draw attention to questions of the coupling of
resolution of the insect’s eye and the size of its food artistic forms of expression and the underlying
object, the sound range of the male bird’s voice impressions;
organs and the female’s hearing range—correspond 2. If umwelt theory is read as a theory of ideal
to each other, the two species or organisms lack the biological adaptations and specialization of all
means to enter one another’s umwelt. The depen- living beings, except man, then culture appears to
dence of ecological relations on perceptual units be an extension of the same vital need to cope with
and categories appears thereby evident. the environment, although of a different kind than
Individual percepts and categories never operate all the previous morphological and physiological
as individual units, as though demanding some ones;
extra mechanism for their integration. They never 3. If we direct attention to the questions of
appear outside of the regulative and homeostatic meaning and sign-relations as expressed in the
self-maintenance process of the whole organism. concept of umwelt, then research on the common
Although the latter terms are mostly used for semiotic footing of all living beings is to follow;
describing how the ontogenetic continuity of one 4. If umwelt theory is seen as a way of
organism is preserved in the fixed limits of certain integrating the subjective and the systemic
parameters, self-regulation of the individual orga- perspectives, then a possible solution to the
nism would not be possible unless it is supported cognitive-social divide in humanities may be
by the coupled constancy of the environment, the suggested.

658 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


All this has given umwelt theory a remarkable into consideration for whom else may the object in
place in several approaches to culture. The funda- question be valuable. The acknowledgement of the
ments of umwelt theory have passed through signif- interest fields that surround the objects should not
icant transformations every time they have entered be seen as a source of competition, though. That
a new cultural theoretical paradigm. In the face of might rather lead to the establishment of shared
this, we don’t see a reason to strive for a purified interests and to a search for creative solutions for
essence of the theory, independent of all its inter- how the interest fields could further accommo-
pretations and therefore suggest that umwelt theory date the diversity of subjects that they attract. That
itself can be seen as a good indicator of cultural would also mean seeing other subjects behind one-
theoretical change. It offers a number of culture- self ’s actions, to the recognition that no activity can
bound elaborations, the character and concrete be only self-directed.
realization of which is specified by the cultural and
philosophical environment where it finds itself. Acknowledgements
This research was supported by the European Union through
Future Directions the European Regional Development Fund (Center of Excellence
Bearing in mind what we inferred in the con- CECT) and by the Estonian Science Foundation Grants ETF
8403 and SF0182748s06.
clusion, we can only rather generally suppose, what
could further be the culture-bound questions,
whereby umwelt theory can be employed. Notes
1. The term “umwelt,” if used as a loanword in English,
First, there is still enough work for cultural may also refer to the milieu concept of the French philosopher
studies to be done on how language itself func- and historian Hippolyte Taine (as the outer world that affects
tions as a system of perception and action and what the organisms) and to the modern common-sense meaning of
are its relations to other sign systems that humans umwelt in German (Sutrop, 2001, p. 458). For the historic over-
possess. A number of studies belonging to the field view of the development of the terms “milieu,” “environment,”
and “umwelt” see, e.g., Canguilhem (2001 [1948]) and Chien
of embodied cognition, situated cognition, enactiv- (2005).
ism that have in the past decades demonstrated the 2. “Ebenso objektiv wie die Faktoren der Umwelt sind, müs-
sensorimotoric embeddedness of linguistic catego- sen die von ihnen hervorgerufenen Wirkungen im Nervensystem
ries provide a strong foothold for further studies aufgefaßt werden. Diese Wirkungen sind ebenfalls durch
that might also encompass the principles Jakob von den Bauplan gesichtet und geregelt. Sie bilden zusammen die
Innenwelt der Tiere.”
Uexküll delineated in respect with sensorimotoric 3. Under the classical models we understand here the linear
coupling and its role in the formation of meanings. models of communication (e.g., Wilbur-Shramm’s, Shannon-
All those theories have paid attention to how the Weaver’s, and Jakobson’s communication models). Although we
symbolic domain of language is strongly tied with are aware of the differences between them, such differences may
the human bodily reactions and perceptions and be discarded in the context they are used here.
4. The mirror law or the law of reflection in physics charac-
Uexküll’s contribution might help to clarify how terises specular reflection, where the angle of incidence equals the
the connections of the latter are brought about in angle of reflection.
the first place. 5. Erscheinungswelt (the world of appearances) is the world of
Another possible future investigation thread may meaningful objects as it appears to the subject. Unlike umwelt, it
lead to the questions about the transitions from per- is not accessible to the external observer.
6. From Uexküll’s legacy, we find a significant number of
ception to communication. Is Jakob von Uexküll’s articles and essays on philosophical issues in science. These writ-
model of the functional circle still applicable, when ings touch first and foremost on the differences in the physi-
the two interconnected entities are mutually “talk- ologist’s and the biologist’s approaches to living phenomena. As
ative,” both carrying their own values and mean- Uexküll described the physiological approach as a mechanical
ings? To think that there is always another who has one, he identified his own position with the one of biologist.
7. Wär’ nicht das Auge sonnenhaft / Wie könnten wir das
a say toward a subject’s actions, does not concern Licht erblicken? (Goethe, 1810, p. xxxviii).
only situations where two or more living beings are 8. Max Scheler (1874–1928), who like Gehlen, belonged
directly involved. It comprises any situations where to the circles of German philosophical anthropology, reflected
interests are in play. The other may therefore be upon the same principle of nonadaptation as a biological
present only indirectly, through the claim he may impetus for the evolution of human species. Scheler called the
latter an organological dilettantism (organologische Dilettantismus).
have for the same thing the subject is striving for. He relied hereby on the evolutionary theories of the German
This means while making a choice (whether it’s a physical anthropologist Hermann Klaatsch (1863–1916)
living place, a piece of food or something else) taking (Scheler, 2001).

m agn u s, ku ll 659
9. For in-depth studies on the relations of Uexküll’s umwelt Harney, M. (2007). Merleau-Ponty, ecology, and biosemiotics.
theory and Cassirer’s philosophy see Chien (2006), Krois (2004), In S. L. Cataldi, & W. S. Hamrick (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty
Heusden (2001), Weber (2004); for the relations of Uexküll and and environmental philosophy: Dwelling on the landscapes of
Heidegger, see Buchanan (2008), Chien (2006). thought (pp. 133–146). Albany, NY: State University of New
10. Thure von Uexküll defines homomorphic relations as York Press.
based on “[ . . . ] a fundamental conformity repeated on various Heidegger, M. (1983). Gesamtausgabe. Abteilung II, Vorlesungen,
levels of complexity, each time in a different way, but basically 1923–1944. Band 29/30, Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik:
always in the same form [ . . . ]” (T. v. Uexküll, 1982, p. 5). Welt – Endlichkeit – Einsamkeit. Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann.
Heusden, B. v. (2001). Jakob von Uexküll and Ernst Cassirer.
References Semiotica, 134(1/4), 275–292.
Bains, Paul (2006). The primacy of semiosis: An ontology of Hoffmeyer, J. (2004). Uexküllian Planmässigkeit. Sign Systems
relations. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. Studies, 32(1/2), 73–97.
Beer, T., Bethe, A.. & Uexküll J., von (1899). Vorschläge zu Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics: An examination into the
einer objectivierenden Nomenklatur in der Physiologie des signs of life and the life of signs. Scranton, PA: University of
Nervensystems. Biologisches Centralblatt, 19, 517–521. Scranton Press.
Berthoz, A., & Christen, Y. (Eds.) (2009). Neurobiology of “umwelt”: Kleisner, K. (2008). The semantic morphology of Adolf
How living beings perceive the world. Berlin: Springer. Portmann: A starting point for the biosemiotics of organic
Bredo, E. (1998). Evolution, psychology, and John Dewey’s form? Biosemiotics, 1, 207–219.
critique of the “reflex arc concept.” The Elementary School Kliková, A., & Kleisner, K. (Eds.) (2006). Umwelt: Koncepce
Journal, 98(5), 447–466. žitého sveta Jakoba von Uexkülla. Prague, Czech Republic:
Buchanan, B. (2008). Onto-ethologies: The animal environments Pavel Mervart.
of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze. New York: Krois, J. (2004). Ernst Cassirer’s philosophy of biology. Sign
Suny Press. Systems Studies, 32(1/2), 277–295.
Canguilhem, G. 1994. A vital rationalist: selected writings. New Kull, K. (2001). Jakob von Uexküll: An introduction. Semiotica,
York: Zone Books. 134(1/4), 1–59.
Canguilhem, G. (2001 [1948]). The living and its milieu. Grey Kull, K. (2010a). Umwelt and modelling. In P. Cobley (Ed.),
Room, 3, 7–31. The Routledge companion to semiotics (pp. 43–56). London:
Cassirer, Ernst (1944). An essay on man: An introduction to a philos- Routledge.
ophy of human culture. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Kull, K. (2010b). Ecosystems are made of semiosic bonds:
Chang, R. S. (Ed.) (2009). Relating to environments: A new look Consortia, umwelten, biophony and ecological codes.
at umwelt. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Biosemiotics, 3(3). 347–357.
Cheung, T. (2004). From protoplasm to umwelt: Plans and Langer, S. (1956 [1942]). Philosophy in a new key: A study in the
the technique of nature in Jakob von Uexküll’s theory of symbolism of reason, rite, and art. New York: New American
organismic order. Sign Systems Studies 32(1/2), 139–167. Library.
Chien, J. A. (2005). Umweltforschung as a method of inquiry: Langer, S. (1986 [1967]). Mind: An essay on human feeling (Vol.
Jakob von Uexküll’s ‘semiotics’ and its fortune home and away, I). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
1920–2004. (Dissertation, National Taiwan University). Langer, S. (1988 [1972]). Mind: An essay on human feeling (Vol.
Chien, J. (2006). Of animals and men: A study of umwelt in II). Baltimore, MD and London: Johns Hopkins Press.
Uexküll, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Concentric: Literary and Levchenko, J., & Salupere, S. (Eds.) (1999). Conceptual diction-
Cultural Studies 32(1), 57–79. ary of the Tartu–Moscow Semiotic School. (Tartu Semiotics
Cobley, P. (Ed.) (2010). The Routledge companion to semiotics. Library, Vol. 2.) Tartu, Estonia: Tartu University Press.
London: Routledge. Lotman, J. (1967). Tezisy k probleme “Iskusstvo v ryadu mod-
Deely, J. (2004). Thomas Albert Sebeok, Biologist Manqué eliruyuschih sistem”. Sign Systems Studies (Trudy po znakovym
(Sebeok Memorial Essay). International Association for sistemam), 3, 130–145.
Semiotic Studies, 2004 World Congress, Lyon. Lotman, J. (1984). Kultuur ja organism. In T. Tiivel,
Dewey, J. (1972 [1896]). The reflex arc concept in psychology. K. Kull, T. Neuman, & U. Sutrop (Eds.), Teooria ja
In A. Boydston, & F. Bowers (Eds.), The early works of John mudelid eluteaduses (pp. 215–220). Tartu, Estonia: Eesti
Dewey, 1882–1898 (pp. 96–110). Carbondale: Southern Looduseuurijate Selts.
Illinois University Press. [First published in Psychological Lotman, J. (1990). Universe of the mind: A semiotic theory of
Review 3(4), 357–370.] culture. London: I. B. Tauris.
Eickstedt, E. F. v. (1959). Stammesgeschichte des Seelischen Lotman, J. (2005 [1984]). On the semiosphere. Sign Systems
(Paläopsychologie). In G. Heberer (Ed.), Die Evolution der Studies, 33(1), 215–239.
Organismen: Ergebnisse und Probleme der Abstammungslehre Magnus, R. (2008). Biosemiotics within and without biologi-
(2te Auflage) (pp. 1192–1242). Stuttgart, Germany: Gustav cal holism: A semio-historical analysis. Biosemiotics, 1(3),
Fischer Verlag. 379–396.
Gehlen, A. (1997 [1940]). Der Mensch: Seine Natur und seine Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968 [1964]). The visible and the invisible.
Stellung in der Welt. Wiesbaden, Germany: Quelle & Meyer. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Gilbert, S. F., & Sarkar, S. (2000). Embracing complexity: Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002 [1945]). The phenomenology of percep-
Organicism for the 21st century. Developmental Dynamics tion. London: Routledge.
219(1), 1–9. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003 [1995]). Nature: Course notes from the
Goethe, J. W. von (1810). Zur Farbenlehre. Erster Band. Collège de France. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Tübingen: J.G. Gotta’schen Buchhandlung. Press.

660 roots of c ult ure i n t he um we lt


Mildenberger, F. (2006). The Bethe/Beer/Uexküll paper (1899) Uexküll, J. v. (1909). Umwelt und Innenwelt der tiere. Berlin: J.
and misinterpretations surrounding ‘vitalistic behviorism’. Springer.
History and Philosophy of Life Sciences, 28, 175–190. Uexküll, J. v. (1927). Die Einpassung. In A. Bethe, G. v.
Mildenberger, F. (2007). Umwelt als vision: Leben und werk Bergmann, G. Embden, & A. Ellinger (Eds.), Handbuch der
Jakob von Uexkülls (1864–1944). [Sudhoffs Archiv, Heft 56]. normalen und pathologischen Physiologie: Mit Berücksichtigung
Stuttgart, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag. der experimentellen Pharmakologie (Vol. 1) (pp. 693–701).
Patočka, J. (1998 [1995]). Body, community, language, world. Berlin: J. Springer.
Chicago: Open Court. Uexküll, J. v. (1973 [1928]). Theoretische Biologie. Frankfurt a.
Phillips, D. C. (1971). James, Dewey, and the reflex arc. Journal M., Germany: Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft.
of the History of Ideas, 32(4), 555–568. Uexküll, J. v. (1982 [1940]). The theory of meaning. Semiotica,
Portmann, A. (1961). Animals as social beings. New York: The 42(1), 25–82.
Viking Press. Uexküll, T. v. (1982). Introduction: Meaning and science in
Portmann, A. (1990). Essays in philosophical zoology: The living Jakob von Uexküll’s concept of biology. Semiotica, 42(1),
form and the seeing eye. (Carter, R. B., trans.). Lewiston, NY: 1–24.
Edwin Mellen Press. Uexküll, T. v. (1992). Introduction: The sign theory of Jakob von
Rüting, T. (2004). History and significance of Jakob von Uexküll Uexküll. Semiotica, 89(4), 279–315.
and of his institute in Hamburg. Sign Systems Studies, Uexküll, T. v. (1999). The relationship between semiotics and
32(1/2), 35–72. mechanical models of explanation in the life sciences.
Saussure, F. d. (1998 [1916]). Course in general linguistics. Semiotica, 127(1/4), 647–655.
London: Duckworth. Watson, R., & Coulter, J. (2008). The debate over cognitivism.
Scheler, M. (2001). Schriften zur Anthropologie. Stuttgart, Theory, Culture & Society, 25, 1–17
Germany: Reclam. Weber, A. (2002). Feeling the signs: Organic experience, intrinsic
Sebeok, T. A. (1999). Editor’s note: Towards a prehistory of teleology and the origins of meaning in the biological phi-
biosemiotics. Semiotica, 127(1/4), 1–3. losophy of Hans Jonas and Susanne K. Langer. Sign Systems
Sebeok, T. A. (2001). Biosemiotics: Its roots, proliferation, and Studies, 30(1), 183–200.
prospects. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 61–78. Weber, A. (2004). Mimesis and metaphor: The biosemiotic gen-
Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on eration of meaning in Cassirer and Uexküll. Sign Systems
the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Studies, 32(1/2), 297–307.
Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Springer. Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes
Sutrop, U. (2001). Umwelt—Word and concept: Two hundred and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality.
years of semantic change. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 447–462. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125.

m agn u s, ku ll 661
CHAPTER

Culture and Epigenesis: A


30 Waddingtonian View

Iddo Tavory, Eva Jablonka and Simona Ginsburg

Abstract
The relationship between biology and socio-cultural phenomena can be studied within either causal
or metaphoric frameworks. Although causal analyses try to isolate biological factors and processes
associated with cultural phenomena and work out how they bring them about, the metaphoric approach
uses models and metaphors in one field to advance the other. This chapter outlines a metaphoric
approach to studying socio-cultural phenomena that is based on the epigenetic landscape model
developed by Waddington. The dynamic stability of socio-cultural phenomena is seen as a result of
interrelated patterns of plasticity and canalization operating at different levels of organization and
working through different mechanisms: social-structural, cultural, and biological. The chapter begins by
distinguishing our view from other prevalent approaches, and then proceeds to explain Waddington’s
epigenetic approach and apply it to a well-researched sociological question—the reproduction of urban
poverty.
Keywords: cultural evolution, epigenetic landscape, canalization, plasticity, Waddington

The relation between biology and culture—the face an extremely complex system of relationships.
effect of human culture on human biology, and the In both cases, from an array of contingencies and
effect of human biology on human cultures—has interacting processes, a relatively coherent complex
received a great deal of attention in recent years. A of phenomena emerges. For example, although both
cluster of approaches, differing in some ways, yet all developmental biological and socio-cultural systems
inspired by biological evolutionary theory, is partic- are in permanent flux, there is also a great deal of
ularly influential (see Richerson & Boyd, 2005). Far stability—what sociologists have been calling, for
less attention is given to analogies between develop- quite some time, “the problem of order.” We sug-
mental (e.g., embryological) processes and cultural gest that recent changes in the way biologists regard
processes. The open-ended nature of cultural trans- development—a greater stress on open-ended plas-
formations and the highly constrained, seemingly ticity on the one hand, and on processes of canali-
deterministic nature of developmental processes zation on the other (West-Eberhard, 2003)—make
seem at first sight to make such an analogy inap- such biology “good to think with,” as Levi-Strauss
propriate and no less problematic than that offered would have put it.
by approaches that stress specific genetic bases In this paper, we outline such an approach
for culture. However, the problems facing studies inspired by developmental epigenetic research, and
of culture and society, and those facing studies of use insights from this field as metaphors that may
biological development are often similar. be useful for thinking about some socio-cultural
Researchers studying embryological develop- dynamics. We suggest that a nonreductive analysis
ment, like those who study the dynamics of culture, of cultural phenomena can benefit from using

662
Waddington’s (1957, 1968) view of developmental the reproduction of complex behaviors—we focus
dynamics. We use Waddington’s schema as a gen- on the processes that generate trajectories that lead
erative metaphor for socio-cultural dynamics; we do to the reproduction of the same social-cultural state,
not assume that embryological dynamics can be seen even when these trajectories and many of the spe-
as causal agents for cultural determination. Rather, cific social products that are generated are variable.
we argue that, confronted by similar questions, soci- Thus, we see Wimsatt and Griesemer as providing a
ologists and cultural anthropologists may benefit view that complements our own by specifying one
from the schema developed by Waddington. class of stabilizing mechanisms.
We start by presenting and criticizing some of Our view is, however, different from the domi-
the most influential ways of thinking about the nant evolution-inspired approaches to culture,
relation between biological determinants and socio- which we discuss in the sections below, so we first
cultural configurations. We then move to define key need to clearly distinguish it from them. In each
concepts developed within the framework inspired case, having summarized the views put forward by
by Waddington and discuss their application to cul- the advocates of other approaches, we point to the
tural processes, focusing on a particular case—the kind of problems that make that view, in our eyes,
reproduction of poverty. Throughout this chapter partial, problematic, or even untenable. We differen-
we make the point that since the relationship tiate between three major evolutionary approaches:
between the biological and socio-cultural levels is
a. A memetic approach, which regards cultural
complex, “plastic,” and based on many (non-linear)
evolution as the result of the selection of memes,
feedbacks, any direct determination of a causal link
units of culture that are analogous to genes
from the biological to the cultural would be very
(Dawkins, 1976; Blackmore, 1999);
partial, and often theoretically reckless. Biological
b. The massive modularity view, which sees
and socio-cultural studies should, however, trade
culture and cultural processes as powerfully
metaphors. Because they are engaged with similar
influenced by preexisting mental cognitive and
dynamics—a study of multiple causes, of regulari-
affective modules (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992,
ties and changes in a complex system—such trade,
1995; Pinker, 1997). This approach, which
as we demonstrate, would be a fruitful endeavor.
takes several forms, assumes strong, domain-
specific, and partially encapsulated psychological
Causal and Metaphoric Links between processing devices, which are evoked by external
Culture and Biology social inputs;
Our approach stresses the “metaphoric links” c. The dual inheritance population approach—an
between culture and biology. Although we agree approach that focuses on selection by individuals
that specific causal relationships between biology of cultural variants, inspired by population
and culture may exist (in both directions) and genetics and quantitative genetics models, but
although it is both clear and trivial that biology not committed to distinct replicatable cultural
offers a template upon which culture evolves, this units (Cavalli-Sforza & Feldman, 1981; Boyd &
template is itself far from rigid, primarily provid- Richerson, 1985; Richerson & Boyd, 2005). It
ing a set of affordances that people socially and cul- uses general social-cognitive biases, such as the
turally mold in a variety of ways (Gibson, 1977). tendency of people to follow the majority habit
We argue that even in those cases where biological or copy prestigious individuals, as important
factors are to be taken into consideration as caus- determining factors of cultural dynamics.
ally relevant for enabling cultural dynamics, they
should be considered as inputs into a rich web of
relationships in which they do not have a privileged The Memetic View of Cultural Evolution
status. Our approach is therefore close to that recently This evolutionary approach is inspired by
developed by Wimsatt and Griesemer (2007), who Dawkins’ selfish gene idea and can be seen as an
advocate a view of culture that focuses on processes (analogical) extension of this view into the cul-
of reproduction and co-reproduction among bio- tural domain (Dawkins, 1976; Blackmore, 1999).
logical agents and cultural artifacts, rather than pro- According to this view, cultural units, memes, are cul-
cesses of replication and diffusion. Although they tural replicators, and cultural evolution is governed
use the metaphor of scaffolding—social processes by the selection of memes. Memes are determined
and embodied products that support and facilitate by cognitive neural processes within individuals,

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 663


which may control the evolution of their carriers in 1983). Modules are assumed to be functionally and
a way similar to that in which viruses control their neurologically distinguishable from each other, with
hosts. Like the selfish gene approach, where genes each module having its own database, its own set
are the units of analysis, the memetic view suggests of inputs that is specific to a particular empirical
that ideas are the replicatable units for the analysis domain and that acts as a trigger, often during a crit-
of culture, and people are but the carriers of such ical period of development. In addition, modules
“replicators.” have dedicated processing procedures, and domain-
This metaphor, however, has several serious prob- specific outputs (Fodor, 1983; Sperber, 2005).
lems. First, the nature of the memes is extremely Evolutionary psychologists generalized this view,
fuzzy—memes are sometimes thought of as trans- so that every strong behavioral human-specific ten-
missible behaviors, sometimes as cultural products, dency or behavioral bias is referred to as a module.
and sometimes as circuits in the brain. Secondly, and Humans are supposed to have modules for humor,
most importantly, the idea that cultural behavior is for mate choice, for food sharing, for cheater detec-
“replicated” involves unrealistic assumptions about tion, and so on. According to this massive modu-
the way cultural meanings are acquired, a view that larity thesis, then, the reaction to inputs is a process
sees learning as a simple process of imitation, rather of evocation rather than construction (Tooby &
than as a pragmatic reworking of a given problem. Cosmides, 1992). The specificity and number
This approach is therefore misleading—cultural of modules is the weakest point in this thesis (for
behaviors are not replicated. Rather, culturally detailed criticisms, see Karmiloff-Smith, 1994; Uttal,
meaningful behaviors are developmentally acquired 2003; Sterelny, 2003; Jablonka & Lamb, 2005).
and constructed during individual ontogeny and Although some domain-general mechanisms (e.g.,
social history. Since we regard developmental con- working memory) are accepted as important, and
struction and reconstruction as an elementary aspect it is acknowledged that modules may have complex
of culture and socio-cultural processes, disregarding interactions with environmental inputs (see Buss
it means, in our opinion, that the meme theory & Reeve, 2003; Sperber, 2005), the assumption of
cannot properly explain the most fundamental facts massive modularity is maintained. In other words,
about cultural dynamics—innovation, dynamic evolutionary psychologists resist the idea that many
stability, and change (for detailed critiques see Sperber, of the “modules” they posit can be the effects of an
1996, 2011; Avital & Jablonka, 2000; Jablonka & interaction between a small number of domain-
Lamb, 2005). general procedures with socially constructed stimuli
and processes. According to the massive modularity
Evolutionary Psychology and the Massive approach, instead of the interactions, the modules
Modularity Thesis themselves are understood as specific.
The second approach is held by most twenty- Although the modular organization of some bio-
first-century evolutionary psychologists. On the logical structures is not in doubt (West-Eberhard,
basis of widespread similarities in human behavior 2003), this does not mean that specific psychological
across different cultures, this view holds that “human regularities must result from a specific modular
nature” is reflected as a large collection of specific cluster, or that these clusters have the properties
psychological adaptations that evolved about two assigned to them by such evolutionary psychology.
million years ago, when our ancestors appeared The metaphor of the brain as a collection of modular
and lived as hunter-gatherers (Pinker, 1997, p. 21). “organs” is associated with several problematic
Following James (1890), who thought that human assumptions. First, the difference between a spe-
beings are flexible and intelligent because they cies-specific organ-like module that requires little
have more, not fewer, instincts than other animals, learning (such as inborn fear of snakes in some
evolutionary psychologists believe that the variety of birds), and a module that requires substantial active
problems faced by our ancestors led to the evolution learning is not very clear (Mameli & Bateson, 2006).
of many specific modules: “hundreds or thousands Most normal people exposed to schooling who can
of modules,” to quote Tooby and Cosmides (1995, read and write develop what may be viewed as a
p. xiii). “literacy module” which can be selectively impaired,
The idea that biological biases in psychological as cases of dyslexia prove; however, it is clear that
processes are organized as modules is taken from “triggering” and “evoking” cannot describe the com-
Fodor’s treatment of perceptual modules (Fodor, plex and learning-dependent process of constructing

664 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


literacy practices. There was no genetic evolution modify it (either accidentally or deliberately), and
specific to literacy, and this is clearly a case of a spe- transmit it to others, both kin and nonkin. Some of
cific interaction between more general cognitive- the cultural information is beneficial or gratifying
biological affordances and a specific social situation. at some level, and persists. Other types of informa-
Secondly, it seems that entrenched individual habits tion are deleterious and are weeded out. However,
may have a cognitive structure which is quite similar simple benefits that enhance biological fitness are
to that attributed to a module. For example, a not sufficient, for there are additional processes that
chess master may develop something resembling a affect cultural dynamics, such as the tendency to act
“chess module”, and a professional football player as the majority of people do (a conformity bias),
can be said to develop a “football module.” In fact, and the tendency to imitate powerful individuals (a
every learned habit or cognitive obsession, with its prestige bias).
developmentally constructed semispecialized and The evolutionary effects of culture according to
semilocalized brain mechanisms, can be described DIT are modeled by using (appropriately modified)
as a module, with more or less genetically guided population and quantitative genetics models. A
aspects. Assuming that these modules are all specifi- well-known example is the selection of the alleles for
cally evolved is an unwarranted stretch of the imagi- breaking down the lactose sugar in milk, a trait that
nation. Finally, the evidence from neurobiology for was favored in some human populations following
the existence of innate specialized cognitive mod- the domestication of cattle (for a basic review, see
ules is almost nonexistent. The only good example Jablonka & Lamb, 2005, Chapter 8; for a recent
is the “language module”, and this too can be inter- ramification, see Tishkoff et al., 2007). According
preted in less rigid terms than required by a massive to the DIT theorists, the basic cognitive archi-
modularity view, stressing the emotive, social, and tecture of human beings constrains culture, but
learning-dependent aspects of language evolution this constraint is far looser than that suggested by
(Tomasello & Slobin, 2005). evolutionary psychologists. Instead of an encap-
In short, the hypothesis that there are cognitive, sulated module in the massive modularity model
sensory, and motor biases in humans, as in other sense, it is a bias or an affordance.
animals, seems valid and nonproblematic (although, The DIT approach assumes that culture and
of course, such biases cannot be invoked at will); genetics act upon each other, rather than that there is
the assumption that they must be organized as dis- a uni-causal direction from genes to culture, and it
tinct modules—with all the baggage that the term uses population genetics models for thinking about
carries—is, however, unwarranted. The massive cultural diffusion. Although we sympathize with
modularity approach downplays the significance of both of these positions, we believe that as far as the
the formation of a vast number of new and chang- metaphor goes, the DIT model can be improved.
ing neural connections between different areas in Population genetics models do indeed throw light on
the brain during conscious behavior, the great open- some aspects of cultural dynamics, but they provide
ended plasticity of human behavior, and the major only a partial account. The assumption that meaning
role of social factors. diffuses because it is better “adapted” at the biological
or cultural level is debatable. It seems to overlook some
Dual-Inheritance Theory (DIT) Approaches of the important ways through which cultural diffu-
A third approach, which is related to the view sion has worked throughout history—through forced
we take in this chapter, stresses mostly the analo- diffusion, coercion, and conquest. Catholicism, for
gies between the dynamics of social and cultural example, is not better “adapted” than Incan religion;
change and biological-genetic population pro- it did, however, use guns—something that had a very
cesses. The proponents of this view (see Cavalli- tangential relationship to Catholicism. Although
Sforza & Feldman, 1981; Boyd & Richerson, 1985; DIT theorists accept force (and other macrosocial
Richerson & Boyd, 2005), revive parts of the dif- phenomena) as the initial context for change in pop-
fusionist approach to cultural evolution, which was ulations, they analyze it in terms of within-popula-
prevalent during the late nineteenth century, but tion dynamics and not in terms of global politics and
add to it a rigorous methodology and a theoretical macroeconomics, a perspective that is undoubtedly
rationale. They argue that population thinking of importance for such cases.
is the key to understanding cultural dynamics. In other words, the mapping of the relation
Individuals acquire and use cultural information, between cultural “parents” and cultural “offspring”

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 665


provides only a partial view of cultural dynamics: Waddington’s Epigenetic View
the way that institutional practices, social prod- The term epigenesis, which is the inspiration
ucts, political coercion, and economic constraints for the modern term epigenetics, refers to the
affect individual behavior is not just a background Aristotelian view (although Aristotle himself never
and a “selective environment.” These structural used it) that the characteristics of offspring are not
constraints are produced by individuals but can preformed in the material transmitted by their par-
also direct and overwhelm transmission biases. ents, but rather arise sequentially during embryo-
Macroevolutionary processes like wars and global logical development through qualitative changes in
political processes are ever-present, always affecting both material and organization. This approach was
the microevolutionary processes of diffusion within an alternative to what became known as the pre-
populations. Although DIT theorists focus on the formationist view, which posited that development
diffusion of practices, propensities, etc. within consists of an unfolding of preexisting organization
populations, with the large-scale economic and (Fry, 2000).
political processes being construed as a background In the 1940s and 1950s, Waddington (1940,
of necessary initial conditions, it may be more use- 1957) in Great Britain, and Schmalhausen (1949)
ful to situate the economic and political factors in the Soviet Union, initiated studies of develop-
in the foreground as dynamic processes, no less ment and evolution that were centered on the
important than the mechanisms of transmission of complementary aspects of developmental canaliza-
cultural practices among individuals within a pop- tion and phenotypic plasticity, two processes that
ulation. Indeed, although the diffusion of cultural decouple genetic and phenotypic variations. This
meaning cannot be reduced to political/economic view is known as an epigenetic view. The term
conditions (see Alexander, 2003), these conditions epigenetics was suggested by Waddington who
always co-constitute the processes of diffusion. wrote in retrospect:
Thus, although the dynamics of transmission/
Some years ago (i.e. 1947) I introduced the word
acquisition are, as the DIT theorists claim, a con-
‘epigenetics’, derived from the Aristotelian word
stitutive part of cultural processes, they are one set
‘epigenesis’, which had more or less passed into disuse,
of mechanisms, interacting in complex ways with
as a suitable name for the branch of biology which
other factors and mechanisms.
studies the causal interactions between genes and their
products which bring the phenotype into being.
Summary of Criticisms
(Waddington, 1968, p. 12)
In summary, we regard the lack of a develop-
mental perspective in the memeticists’ and most The “genetics” part of “epigenetics” points to
evolutionary psychologists’ approaches as a serious Waddington’s awareness of the crucial role of genes
flaw. We sympathize with the DIT approach, and in development, while the “epi” part of the term,
think that many of the insights and methodologies which means “upon” or “over,” reflects Waddington’s
it offers are useful, but we do not think that a popu- intention to study developmental processes that go
lation view is sufficient for explaining cultural phe- “over” or “beyond” the gene.
nomena and processes. Although, as we explain in This epigenetic approach, which was somewhat
the next section, processes of selective stabilization neglected during the 1970s and 1980s, has recently
are central to our development-oriented approach, been revived and expanded by a growing number
Darwinian population genetics describes only one of theoretical and experimental biologists. Modern
type of such stabilization, and is not sufficient for epigenetic approaches stress the importance of the
the explanation of cultural dynamics. Indeed, in developmental dynamics of cellular and intercellular
many situations it may be detrimental, leading us to networks of interactions during the individual’s
think about adaptability of meaning where no such development, and sometimes also between genera-
adaptive edge exists. In some ways our view is close tions of individuals. In addition to the emphasis on
to Sperber’s, although we do not subscribe to his development and on the relation between genetic
massive-modularity assumption. In order to explain and extragenetic factors, the current epigenetic
our view, we start by presenting Waddington’s approach is guided by a set of heuristic concepts
epigenetic approach to the development of orga- that are associated with Waddington’ views. The
nisms and the assumptions underlying his model of most important of these include “plasticity,” “canal-
an “epigenetic landscape.” ization,” and “phenotypic accommodation.” Since

666 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


our approach to culture should be seen in the light injuries, cortical areas devoted to certain functions
of these, we first define and describe them. undergo rearrangements, as is found after limb
Plasticity is defined in biology today as the amputation or stroke episodes. In stroke patients,
ability of a single genotype to generate variant forms measurements employing brain imaging techniques
of morphology, physiology, and/or behavior, in during finger movements in a previously para-
response to different environmental circumstances. lyzed hand have demonstrated complex patterns
The responses can be reversible or irreversible, adap- of brain reactivation; activity in certain areas of the
tive or nonadaptive, active or passive, continuous or cortex increases (Weiller, Chollet, Friston, Wise, &
discontinuous (West–Eberhard, 2003). The reper- Frackowiak, 1992; Weiller, Ramsay, Wise, Friston,
toire of alternative plastic responses to new condi- & Frackowiak, 1993), as changes follow rehabilita-
tions may be limited and predictable, as it is, for tion treatments (Liepert, Bauder, Miltner, Taub, &
example, with seasonal changes in the color and Weiller, 2000).
patterns of butterflies’ wings. Plasticity can also be, Moreover, the plasticity mechanisms that enable
however, broad and relatively open-ended. Such brain reorganization have more than compensatory
open-ended plastic responses include unpredict- functions. Novel functional organization, which
able, novel adaptive responses, as seen when animals has never been seen in the ontogenetic or phylo-
learn new behaviors through trial and error, or when genetic past of the individual, can become evident.
humans engage in cultural behaviors such as building The set of developmental processes that lead to
cathedrals or writing novels. Such open-ended plas- novel phenotypic outputs has been called pheno-
ticity is of central importance for understanding typic accommodation (West-Eberhard, 2003, pp.
cognitive and cultural behaviors. 140, 146). The notion is perhaps best exemplified
The mirror image of plasticity is canalization. by a morphological example, the case of a two-
Canalization is defined as “the adjustment of devel- legged goat that was described by Slijper in 1942.
opmental pathways so as to bring about a uni- This goat was born without forelegs, and with the
form result in spite of genetic and environmental help of a caring farmer adopted a semi-upright
variations” (Jablonka & Lamb, 1995, p. 290, based posture, ending up hopping, kangaroo-like, biped-
on Waddington, 1957). In other words, canaliza- ally and independently, on its hind legs. After its
tion leads to the production of a stable output death, postmortem examination revealed many
despite changes in inputs and/or in developmental coordinated changes in its morphology, which were
trajectories. It leads to robustness and stability in the consequence of its unusual mode of locomo-
a “noisy” world in which both the genetic milieu tion. In addition to a changed hind leg and pelvic
and the external environment are constantly chang- structure, it had a curved spine, an unusually thick
ing. A single typical phenotype is generated by and large neck, and various functionally corre-
many different underlying genotypes and in many lated changes in its skeleton and musculature (see
environmental conditions. West-Eberhard, 2003). Less spectacular, but still
Canalization and plasticity are closely and inti- striking examples of phenotypic accommodation are
mately related: almost every case of canalized devel- found in normal subjects challenged with unusual
opment (in the face of genetic and environmental tasks: for example, in the case of skilled string
“noise”) assumes plasticity at underlying or overlying players, who use their left hand in playing music,
levels of organization. There are many examples of the sensorimotor cortical areas in the right (but not
this. Thus, to take an example from neurobiologi- in the left) hemisphere are enlarged (Elbert, Pantev,
cal research, it has been established that inputs from Wienbruch, Rockstroh, & Taub, 1995). Similarly,
other brain areas during early embryonic develop- expanded sensorimotor cortical finger areas are seen
ment, influence the formation of specific cortical in healthy Braille readers (Pascual-Leone & Torres,
areas. For example, if retinal input is rerouted to the 1993).
auditory cortex, the latter develops visual properties Phenotypic accommodation is a consequence
(Roe, Kwon, & Sur, 1992). Similarly, the ability of of general biological properties such as mechanical
the adult neocortex to change its structure during flexibility—the many partially overlapping regula-
the lifespan of an individual is also quite striking, tory elements—and, crucially, processes of “explo-
and many examples of experiential modifications in ration” and “selective stabilization,” not only at the
the organization of the brain have been reported, cellular and physiological levels, but also at behav-
in both normal and sick subjects. Following various ioral and social levels. Exploration and selective

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 667


stabilization processes are based on a common the movements of the stem of a plant that is grown
principle—the generation of a large set of local in the dark are erratic, and growth only becomes
variations and interactions, from which only a directional when the plant encounters the directing
small subset is eventually stabilized and manifested. stimulus (light in this example), which leads to the
Which particular output is realized depends on the stabilization of growth in the direction of the light
initial conditions, the ease with which develop- (West-Eberhard, 2003, pp. 38–39). Other examples
mental trajectories can be deflected away from their are the selective stabilization of synaptic connec-
current paths, and the number of possible points tions during development and learning (Changeux,
around which development can be stably organized. Courrege, & Danchin, 1973; Edelman, 1987), and,
Following convention, we refer to these points as at the behavioral level, trial-and-error learning in
“attractors,” since they are stabilizing end-states animals. Sperber highlights the role of attractors—
toward which the system seems to “strive.” This, both cognitive biases, and cultural structures and
of course, should not be understood as a classical products—in the evolution of culture (Sperber, 1996,
teleological view, because the end points do not 2005, 2011; Claidière & Sperber, 2007). He argues
literally attract the processes leading to it. Rather, that attraction can lead to cultural stability even in
“attractor” is a shorthand to describe a process in the face of variations and a low fidelity of copying.
which a large number of interacting factors tend The dynamic stability of the macrolevel in the
to co-regulate and to reinforce each other in ways face of microlevel variations and processes is the
that regularly produce a specific end point. There key feature of canalization and is best understood
could be different permutations and plastic shifts through Waddington’s diagrams of his “epigenetic
in many of the underlying processes, creating a landscape” model of development (Waddington,
number of variations in trajectories, but the end 1957; see Fig. 30.1 and Fig. 30.2).
point would be similar. Put concisely, the selec- Development is represented as a ball rolling down
tive stabilization processes that lead to an attractor a tilted landscape, with many hills and branching
involve both canalization (at the output level) and valleys descending from a high plateau, which rep-
extensive plasticity manifested as extensive explora- resents the initial state of the fertilized egg (Fig.
tion and trajectory variability. 30.1). The attractor toward which the ball rolls is
An example of a selective stabilization is the a morphological, physiological, or behavioral state,
exploratory behavior of unicellular organisms, like which is relatively stable: A functioning heart, a
bacteria or paramecia. A paramecium that has its functioning eye, locomotor ability in a human child
path blocked starts moving in random directions. (see Thelen, 1995). The downward slope represents
Its movement is only stabilized and directed when temporal movement, with the bottom representing
it encounters an attracting stimulus, such as light or the final state of affairs and the top representing the
food. Exploratory, initially random, behavior is also initial state. The steepness of a valley can be thought
observed in plants’ growth trajectories: for example of as biases and propensities, constraints and specific

Figure 30.1 An epigenetic landscape.


Taken from Figure 4, entitled “Part of an
Epigenetic Landscape” on p. 29 of Wad-
dington’s The Strategy of the Genes (1957).

668 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


affordances, and it indicates how much the system outcome of development, can be altered through
can vary—how well-buffered it is. natural selection. In other words, attractors, and
The landscape is underlain by a network of inter- the ease or difficulty of reaching them, can change
acting elements (Fig. 30.2). It is shaped by the ten- during evolution.
sion of guy ropes that are tied to pegs in the ground.
As can be seen in the figure, which is like an X-ray Social Landscapes and Cultural Attractors
picture of the hidden dynamics below the surface, We can use this visual model to describe the
the topological relations of the interacting pegs and formation of new behavioral and cultural attrac-
guy ropes determine the architecture of the visible tors. We must, of course, spell out what this social-
undulating landscape (Figs. 30.1 and 30.2). These epigenetic landscape may stand for, what the time
interactions could be described by network-theory axis is, and what the underlying interacting factors
models, in that the different pegs are themselves are. Unlike the embryological landscape, the social
related to each other in complex ways that make landscape in Figure 30.1 is not one of unfolding dif-
some pegs more “central” than others, because they ferentiation from a relatively simple to an increas-
have connections with many other pegs, while other ingly differentiated state, but rather the outcome of
pegs are more “redundant.” As stressed in network the dynamics of the processes underlying it. Unlike
theory, it is not only the number of different pegs the pegs in Waddington’s picture, which are usually
(different interacting units) that is important, but different from the guy ropes emanating from them
the way they interact (see, for example, Bonacich, (in Waddington’s landscape, pegs are genes and guy
1987; Brandes & Erlebach, 2005). In Waddington’s ropes are proteins and different types of regulatory
schema, the pegs represent genes, and the guy ropes elements), there is no such clear distinction between
represent their biochemical and regulatory effects. social pegs and their effect. For example, if the qual-
The specific developmental trajectory toward the ity of the school in a poor neighborhood is a “peg”
attractor can change—there are many routes that in a landscape that depicts the reproduction of
can be taken, processes of exploration generate poverty (see next section) the behaviors of the pupils,
alternative routes that stabilize once the attractor is their parents and their teachers both constitute the
reached, whatever the route and trajectory taken and peg and are the guy ropes emanating from it. Figure
whatever the precise initial conditions. Although in 30.2 shows just part of a larger network (aspects
certain circumstances the existing biases and pro- of the social environment in the wide sense). The
pensities may be overcome and a different attractor inclining slope leads to several large attractors (not
may be reached, this requires that a new challenge seen in the picture) that are different socio-cultural
(e.g., strong stress) alters the multiple interactions phenomena. Depending on the initial conditions
among the elements, and generates a new network and the specifics of the landscape from which it
of interactions that divert the ball from its normal starts, an individual is likely to reach one particular
course. The steepness of the valleys, and hence the attractor state.

Figure 30.2 The networks underlying and


constructing the landscape.
Taken from Figure 5, entitled “The complex
system of interactions underlying the epige-
netic landscape” on p. 36 of Waddington’s
The Strategy of the Genes (1957).

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 669


As a preliminary example, let us look at the cul- selection for genes coding for proteins that are
tural stability of a particular hypothetical culinary related to the reaction to food intake.
culture. Imagine a society with a culinary tradi-
The example above already includes some of
tion in which salty and spicy, well-cooked food is
the elements of a metaphoric use of Waddington’s
strongly preferred, and assume that in this society
schema. Clearly, and contrary to Waddington’s own
the tradition, which involves the preparation and
use of the model, we do not assume that the pegs are
consumption of specific dishes, has been stable for
all genetic. Rather, the pegs are the interacting pro-
many generations. What are the interacting factors,
cesses and factors (in which individuals and groups
and why does the network they form lead to a sta-
are active agents) that lead, in this example, to cul-
ble, persistent, tradition? In this case the interact-
tural stability. Some of these may be the ecological,
ing factors are likely to be ecological, social, and
epigenetic, and genetic factors that biologists feel
biological:
comfortable talking about, but others are symbolic,
a. Ecological factors: The area is hot, food spoils economic, and social aspects that cannot be reduced
easily and the well-cooked, salted, spicy food is to the biological. What ties them together in an epi-
safer than food prepared differently. Plants from genetic-like landscape is that these are all mutually
which spices can be made grow in the area, and the reinforcing mechanisms that lead the individual to a
use of spices, and the cooking methods, enhance shared outcome (or “attractor”), namely eating spicy
the safety of the consumed food. food. We can imagine a situation in which an indi-
b. Social factors: Spicy food has come to be vidual leaves the community, breaking with the sym-
identified with this society, and begins to identify bolic aspects of liking spicy food (even thinking that
individuals as members of this particular group. it is silly to treat spicy food as a symbolic bound-
Specific dishes come to have important social- ary), but nevertheless still likes spicy food because
symbolic (e.g., religious) meaning, being eaten of the preferences garnered in utero and early life.
during festivities or other important occasions Similarly, we can imagine an individual who abso-
(weddings, funerals). Eating very spicy food gives lutely detests spicy food, but will still eat it, because
an individual special prestige, as does preparing she wants to be considered a competent member of
spicy dishes. The food is therefore related to a the community. In both examples, the underlying
whole network of significant social activities variability in preferences and specific behaviors is
and processes, which are mutually dependent. still strongly canalized, leading to the attractor.
Economic activities that are centered on the In the example above, the attractor state has
growth, selling/buying, and preparation of the biological adaptive significance for the individ-
food used for cooking reinforce its value. Some ual because we assumed that the ecological factors
spices that are not readily available are imported make the consumption of the food beneficial (it is
from several other localities. Economic activity “healthy”). However, it is easy to relax this assump-
is also associated with medicinal practices, since tion, by assuming, for example, that a group of
the spices have, or are believed to have, specific immigrants from the locality settled down in a dif-
medicinal effects, used in the local physicians’ ferent place, where medical care renders the con-
practices. sumption of spices completely irrelevant for health.
c. Biological and psychological factors: Young But even though the spicy food is no longer ben-
children are exposed to the food during early eficial, the tradition will still persist. In fact, one
childhood, and develop a lifelong preference for it. of the interesting aspects of the landscape model is
Moreover, pregnant women transmit food traces to that it can be used to interpret not only cases where
their offspring through the placenta and through there are some benefits to the outcome (when the
milk, and the offspring develop food preferences attractor provides a positive selective advantage at
similar to those of their mothers (Mennella, Jagnow the physiological level, the cultural level, or both).
& Beauchamps, 2001). Exposure at early stages Rather, it can also be used to interpret cases where
(in utero, as neonates, during early childhood), the attractor is clearly nonadaptive. The regulatory
reinforces the same food preference, which becomes architecture of the dynamic network may have
dominant (for a review of animal examples, see properties that overwhelm the chances of reaching
Jablonka & Lamb, 2005, Chapter 5). It is possible alternative, more adaptive attractors. A representa-
that in some populations, where the culture has tive case that can be interpreted in these terms is
persisted for a long time, there has been some the reproduction of urban poverty.

670 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


Realizing the Metaphor: The Case of will remain there as adults (Herz, 2006), and this
Urban Poverty percentage is higher if we make our scale finer, and
We now move to consider ways in which thinking go lower down the socioeconomic status ladder.
in epigenetic terms—specifically through In other words, remaining poor can be seen as a
Waddington’s epigenetic landscape metaphor— strong attractor, a dynamically stable point people
may help sociologists and anthropologists who deal tend to reach if they are born into a specific eco-
with meaning and social structures to make sense nomic stratum—although replication is not perfect,
of the patterns of action that people construct and poverty is a strong attractor.
decode, and into which they find themselves born. Why, exactly, poverty is such an end point is of
One thing that makes Waddington’s model useful is course a matter of some debate. Some aspects are
its similarity to current thinking about stability and obvious. Poorer people don’t have the family con-
change. Thus, whereas order was once seen as a non- nections that often provide good jobs, they usually
problematic social point of reference, and change live in blighted areas in which the only available
and conflict were seen as the phenomena we needed jobs are rotten, the schools are bad, and children are
to explain, current theorizations of social life focus expected to be working-class when they grow up,
on the dynamics of both change and stability. As rather than being expected to go on to be lawyers,
in Waddington’s model, the assumption is that any businessmen, etc. The parents’ position also affects
outcome is an end point in a long series of interac- their children through education. Thus, if there are
tions, many of them highly contingent. Structure no books in the home, or if parents cannot (or do not
is not something that exists independent of these have time to) help children with their homework,
contingent interactions, and indeed, if struc- and do not have the money to have them tutored,
ture “exists,” it exists as a process (Bourdieu, the effects can be predicted. Systematic discrimina-
1977; Giddens, 1984; Sewell, 1992). Thus, like tion, where it is harder for blacks to even obtain
Waddington, sociologists have moved to think jobs, does not help (Pager & Shepherd, 2008).
about the dynamics of stability as much as about the Other aspects that work into the reproduction of
dynamics of change. poverty are less widely recognized. Wilson (1987),
Thinking along these lines, we take one general for instance, argued that the low socioeconomic
problem that has been central to urban anthro- mobility of poor blacks in the United States is
pologists and sociologists—the reproduction of directly related to the decisions of the few that actu-
urban poverty. This is a potentially useful topic to ally “make it out” of the ghetto. Simply put, they
think through, because, as will become apparent, disappear. They move out to middle class neighbor-
it displays the two “Waddingtonian” dynamics we hoods, and often sever the friendships (and kinship)
have presented above: A highly complex system and ties they had with their poorer social network.
that is constantly shifting, and a relatively stable In effect, there is no collective efficacy, and the poor
outcome. Additionally, the question of urban pov- are now worse off, as those elements in their social
erty has received sustained attention, which allows network that could have helped them gain mobility
us to bring together different claims made in this are no longer there.
context. So far, the evidence for canalization is clear, but
Although some mobility exists, and people do the evidence for plasticity is missing—the stability
move from one socioeconomic category to another, of poverty seems inevitable and mostly divorced
urban poverty can be thought of as “hereditary.” from the question of meaning. A series of studies
This “heredity” does not work in any biological of the black ghetto and other working-class con-
sense, but simply in the sense that people who grow texts, however, shows how poor urban blacks and
up poor tend to stay poor, the myth of the self-made other working-class residents attempt to “make it”
man notwithstanding. Indeed, the degree of income in their environment; how they imbue their sur-
correlation between generations is extremely high roundings with meaning, and try to make sense of
in the United States, and children born in the low- themselves as actors in such an environment. Thus,
est quintile (20%) of the socioeconomic ladder Newman (1999) shows that many residents in these
have only a 1% chance to end up in the highest blighted neighborhoods try to yank themselves
5% (Herz, 2006). This is compounded in the case up by their bootstraps, fostering a middle-class
of poor blacks in the United States, where 63% of ethic of work, which they put into the worst jobs
black children born into the lower-income quarter, available—the “McJobs” at food establishments.

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 671


Other studies (Bourgois, 2003) show how drug The striking point in all these cases is that diffe-
dealers are attempting to realize a dream of mobility rent strategies and contingencies end up reproducing
through their dealings, while simultaneously foster- a specific socioeconomic position. In Waddington’s
ing a street “savvy” that gains them respect on the terms, the variations among the cases show that
streets (see also Anderson, 1999). there is a high degree of plasticity, but the emergent
People also try to cope with the poverty, con- consequences are strongly canalized. The “lads” in
structing “niches” of respectability within it. Thus, Willis’ work remain working-class, the unhoused
for example, Duneier (1999) shows how homeless remain poor, and those who develop a “code of the
men and women in New York’s Greenwich Village street” often find this code to be highly problematic
make sense of their surrounding, selling magazines when they look for jobs outside the ghetto; each of
that they pick up from the trash of others, building these strategies ends up flowing into the same set
up an ecology in which they can both survive and of conditions. On a larger structural level, urban
make sense of themselves as moral individuals. In poverty is reproduced. But the point is not only that
other words, the end point of poverty is dealt with without reorganization “from above” poverty will
in different ways; there is quite a lot of plasticity end up reproducing itself (cf. Wacquant, 2002), but
and variation in the ways that people deal with their that urban poverty is overdetermined, and—at least
surroundings. on a statistical level—each of the permutations ends
However, what makes Waddington’s metaphor up flowing to the same attractor: urban poverty.
“work” in this context is that these different strat- Using Waddington’s metaphor, we then shift the
egies are all canalized. Thus, workers in McJobs, way we think of the “pegs” from genes to different
where there is very little occupational mobility (in this case almost exclusively social) processes and
between ranks, remain poor. They may get a sense mechanisms. Thus, in the case of urban poverty,
of themselves as decent breadwinners, or see their we can distinguish between at least three diffe-
jobs as “slaving” (Newman, 1999, p. 133), but rent kinds of pegs. First, there are social-structural
they will almost certainly remain poor, with jobs pegs. These include the kinds of jobs available, the
that pay minimum wages. On the other hand, education of parents, the quality of schools in the
upon close inspection the “lucrative” allure of drug inner city, the structure of the state welfare system.
dealing turns out to be a myth. Not only is there A second order of pegs includes the meaning-mak-
the constant danger of being shot or arrested, but ing processes people use in order to make sense of
most drug dealers, if they carefully counted their the conditions they find themselves in, their ways
earnings, would realize that they make little more to define themselves and their relationships. These
than the minimum wage. Drug dealers’ illusions pegs are not uniform and range from the rebellion of
that they make “fast cash” stem from the fact that teenagers and selling drugs to the attempt to find
their work involves sudden cash flows, but this is steady employment in a McJob and other ways
punctuated by long lulls where they make nothing. of handling the situation. Where the first kind of
Although the lives of drug dealers and McWorkers pegs relates to social structures, the second denotes
are different, both “plastic” adaptations are thus local cultural and subcultural meaning structures.
canalized into the same general socioeconomic Another set of “pegs,” which is probably not very
outcome. salient in this case, may include some biological
This relationship between plasticity and canaliza- factors—e.g., where the cheapest food is junk food,
tion can perhaps be best seen in Willis’ (1981) study mothers’ and even fathers’ poor nutrition may have
“learning to labor.” One of the poignant points a lasting effect on the life chances of their children.
in Willis’ work is that the sons and daughters of Of course, sociologists know this. Using dif-
working-class families often rebel at school. Knowing ferent vocabularies—of “overdetermination of
that their life trajectories are predetermined (and causes,” to take one example—they make a very
overdetermined), they try to kick in all directions, similar point. Why then would the Waddingtonian
flunking school and fostering a masculine image schema be useful? We think it is useful in several
of themselves as rebels in the process. Yet, without ways. First, thinking through this metaphor would
having a high school diploma or credentials, they are force researchers to explicitly study the complemen-
doomed to follow in the footsteps of their parents; tary dynamics of change and stability. Adopting
it is exactly through their attempts to rebel against this viewpoint, “the problem of order” is not seen
their condition that their condition is reproduced. as somehow opposed to the constant dynamics of

672 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


change. Rather, in a complex system, certain out- align with their project. The Waddingtonian land-
comes are reproduced both in situations where scape may be seen as a further specification of this
one mechanism works against others (as when theoretical thrust in two ways. First, the networks
poor people try to “better themselves” through we are led to think about through this metaphor
minimum-wage labor), but also through changing are networks of relationships, not actors. Secondly,
internal dynamics. These dynamics of stability are not focusing on the temporal movement toward an
deterministic, so that although canalization means attractor, and on the complementary nature of plas-
that certain social conditions (“genotypes”) tend to ticity and canalization, moves us to think not only
produce the same social “phenotypic” outcome, this about process, but about the kinds of regularities
is not necessary. This probabilistic view needs to be that appear in overdetermined, canalized, structural
kept in mind especially in the social world—where dynamics.
63% of reproduction is considered very high. Lastly, thinking about social phenomena in
Secondly, students of culture are often seeking terms of plasticity and canalization would be useful
for the “golden practice”—the piece of the puzzle in providing a spectrum of different conditions—a
that would explain the difference between condi- scale that goes from the well-canalized process (such
tions. Raised on Mill’s (1843/2002) “method of as the reproduction of poverty) to more precariously
difference,” they (like other scientists) often look canalized phenomena that are thus reproduced
for the one practice that would account for the with less fidelity. Thinking along this continuum
difference between conditions. Thinking through would allow sociologists to create a scale of effect-
Waddington’s metaphor, however, would make this canalization, and thus a comparative tool, without
project highly dubious. If indeed sets of practices making the unrealistic assumptions that Mill’s
are canalized toward a specific outcome, then the method of difference implies; at the very least, it
comparative study of meaning should not focus on would take this question of difference to a higher
specific practices, but rather on the system of cana- level of organization.
lized relationships, and the combinations that may
subvert a well-canalized attractor. Although one Discussion and Conclusions
well-placed change can cause a different course to We have suggested linking biological and socio-
be more common, this would be rare. In most cases, cultural processes through the developmental meta-
it is only a combination of changing relationships phor of the epigenetic landscape. This bridging
that produces change. The task shifts from a spec- metaphor allows us to consider the many factors
ification of cause, to thinking about networks of and processes that make up the social landscape
relationships that produce a similar effect. A good without a priori granting a privileged position
example of the need to think in terms of networks of to one type of factor or process. We do not wish
interacting processes that can lead to change (rather to downplay the role of biological factors, as they
than of a single “major” cause) is the dynamics may indeed be important in some circumstances,
of persistence of famine in Northern Ethiopia. providing “a difference which makes a difference”
In this case, described and analyzed by De Waal (Bateson, 1979). However, in most cases these fac-
(1997, Chapters 5 and 6) complex political/reli- tors may play only a very minor role. This role,
gious struggles for power play a decisive role in the when there is one, is overwhelmed by more domi-
maintenance of famine; sadly and ironically, for- nant social factors. In fact, even when the existence
eign aid, which may be naively seen as a measure to of specific biological biases in a certain direction is
relieve famine, has been used to sustain the political demonstrated, it is still a long way from explaining
interactions that maintain the famine state. symbolic culture. Indeed, an analysis of cultural
The interactive, network-focused aspect of processes may show that many aspects of culture go
Waddington’s schema resembles recent develop- against the grain of our biological-cognitive biases.
ments in “Actor-Network Theory” in the sociology Our approach therefore incorporates these aspects,
of science. Latour (1987) and others (e.g., Callon, but does not prejudge their significance. Crucially,
1986) focus on networks of relationships among the adoption of the model is not intended to suggest
different actors as the basis of their analyses. Within a causal analysis of culture starting with genes and
each specific situation, actors pursue their own ends cellular epigenetic regulation processes, but its use
through constructing a network of other actors as a metaphor highlights the similarities between the
(both human and nonhuman) that they manage to processes described by developmental biologists and

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 673


those described by anthropologists and sociologists the dizzying array of social mechanisms come to
(see also Wimsatt & Griesemer, 2007). reproduce relatively stable social phenomena.
We use Waddington’s model of epigenetic land- Although the landscape metaphor is a very
scape as a way of thinking about the dynamics of sta- general way of thinking about cultural development,
bility and change in complex sociocultural matrixes. a particular social landscape (such as that underlying
Like Waddington, we assume that there is very the reconstruction of urban poverty) provides a
rarely, if ever, a situation in which an attractor, or a framework for hypotheses about the particular
recurrent state of affairs, is underlain by one causal nature and interactions among the underlying fac-
process. Waddington’s schema assumes that any sta- tors. A hypothesis has to account for the observed
ble attractor is the effect of a dynamic network of specifics of the architecture of the particular land-
processes. This schema describes the dynamics of scape, and for the specifics of its observed temporal
social structures as a pattern of interactions among dynamics (in the case of urban poverty—its dynamic
pegs supporting a landscape. The regulatory struc- stability). The landscape metaphor, like any other
ture of these interactions raises the chances of a par- good metaphor, therefore provides a framework for
ticular outcome, so that even if any one of the pegs articulating and testing hypotheses.
changes or disappears altogether, and even when
the landscape changes (in the sense that the ridges
Future Directions
and valleys are altered), the final stable state will
In this chapter we have taken first steps toward
nevertheless be reached.
translating Waddington’s epigenetic approach in a
As we pointed out, the pegs and guy ropes in the
way that makes it suitable for tackling questions in
social landscape belong to different domains, and
the study of culture. In order to further develop this
what the pegs are in a given landscape depends on
approach, there are several questions that need speci-
the kind of question we want to ask. If our question is
fication and other areas that need to be addressed.
about why spicy food is preferred in a certain society,
Although we are sure that more issues will come up
we will have one attractor, and set of specific pegs
as researchers use the metaphor, some preliminary
(including possibly but not necessarily some genetic
questions include the following:
pegs, some epigenetic pegs, some ecological pegs, and
many social/symbolic and economic pegs). In the case • What is the strength of canalization for
of the reproduction of urban poverty, our pegs would different phenomena? This is a question that needs
be very different, with no genetic pegs and with very to be addressed both for every particular case,
different sets of social and economic pegs. Moreover, and comparatively. On the comparative level, are
something that is an attractor for one question may there regularities in the strength of canalization
be a peg for another. For example, in the case of the of particular kinds of phenomena (such as
cycle of poverty we described, we could conceivably inequality)? Is there a relationship between the
ask a question regarding the culture of masculinity in structure of the landscape and the constraints on
the ghetto. In this case, the cycle of poverty will be its change across different kinds of phenomena?
considered a peg (albeit a very central one). • What is the relative closure, or the relative
We believe that the epigenetic landscape meta- autonomy of the part of the global landscape
phor can be useful for thinking about cultural and we focus on? In many cases we may find that
social relations. By providing a landscape model of within the immense, global network of social
dynamic stability, we suggest a way for thinking mechanisms, which are all interconnected to some
about the relative stability of social and cultural phe- extent, there are areas with a lot more interactions,
nomena as an emergent property of different mech- clusters that lead to a specific attractor. What
anisms working simultaneously. We do not assume might these areas be?
that processes are necessarily complicit, in the sense • What are the relative effects of different kinds
that they strengthen one another or depend on one of pegs and what do they depend on? In what
another to work (see Bourdieu, 1984), nor that any conditions are different types of pegs (social-
one mechanism, or a priori assigned category, holds structural elements, cultural meanings, ecological
primacy over the social process. Both for questions of constraints and affordances, epigenetic inheritance,
change and of stability, the interaction and dynamic and genetic inheritance) more important than
stabilization of multiple processes, occurring at dif- others? This question needs to be answered
ferent levels, provides a tool for understanding how empirically for different domains.

674 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


• How are the pegs themselves constructed Avital, E., & Jablonka, E. (2000). Animal traditions: Behavioural
and how do they change? The pegs may be inheritance in evolution. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
University Press.
composite and have their own construction rules. Bateson, G. (1979). Mind and nature, a necessary unity. London:
What are they? Wildwood House.
Blackmore, S. J. (1999). The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford
This chapter suggested a metaphor that research- University Press.
ers of sociocultural phenomena may find useful Bonacich, P. (1987). Power and centrality: A family of measures.
in tackling the kinds of questions they routinely American Journal of Sociology, 92(5), 1170–1182.
face—questions regarding the intersection of dif- Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge,
MA: Cambridge University Press.
ferent mechanisms, and regarding the dynamics of Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A social critique of the judgment
reproduction and regularities they observe. Like any of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
metaphor, its usefulness lies in orienting researchers Bourgois, P. (2003). In search of respect: Selling crack in El Barrio.
to specific kinds of problems. Like the “tool-kit,” New York: Cambridge University Press.
the “network,” or the “game,” the strength of a met- Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and the evolutionary
process. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
aphor is not in providing answers, but as a way to Brandes, U., & Erlebach, T. (Eds.) (2005). Network analysis:
provide more, and hopefully better, questions. Methodological foundations. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Buss, D. M., & Reeve, H. K. (2003). Evolutionary psychology
Glossary and List of Abbreviations and developmental dynamics: Comment on Lickliter and
Attractor: The set of properties that the system tends to reach Honeycutt. Psychological Bulletin, 129(6), 848–853.
(the state it tends eventually to settle in), regardless of the Callon, M. (1986). Some elements of a sociology of translation:
conditions from which it started and the specific trajectory Domestication of the scallops and the fishermen of St. Brieuc
taken. Bay. In J. Law (Ed.), Power, action and belief: a new sociology
Canalization: The adjustment of developmental pathways so as of knowledge (pp. 196–233). London: Routledge & Kegan
to bring about a uniform result in spite of genetic and envi- Paul.
ronmental variations. Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., & Feldman, M. (1981). Cultural transmis-
Dual-Inheritance Theory (DIT) approach: A theoretical approach sion and evolution: A quantitative approach. Princeton, NJ:
to evolution and cultural diffusion that assumes a two-way Princeton University Press.
causal relationship between culture and genetics, and that Changeux, J-P., Courrege, P., & Danchin, A. (1973). Theory of
takes population genetics as its model for cultural diffusion. epigenesis of neuronal networks by selective stabilization of
Epigenetic Landscape: A visual model suggested by C. H. synapses. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA,
Waddington to describe the dynamics of embryological 70(10), 2974–2978.
development and its underlying genetic network of interac- Claidière, N., & Sperber, D. (2007). The role of attraction in cul-
tions. tural evolution. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 7, 89–111.
Exploration and Selective Stabilization: The generation of a Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford
large set of local variations from which only a small subset is University Press.
eventually stabilized. Selective stabilization occurs when the De Waal, A. (1997). Famine crimes: Politics & the disaster relief
system reaches an attractor. industry in Africa. London: African Rights & the International
Massive-Modularity Thesis: The view that the mind is made up African Institute.
of many different, innate, domain-specific computational Duneier, M. (1999). Sidewalk. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.
mechanisms or “modules.” Edelman, G. M. (1987). Neural Darwinism: The theory of
Memetic View: The view that culture can be conceived as a set of neuronal group selection. New York: Basic Books.
replicatable units, analogous to genetic replicators, and that Elbert, T., Pantev, C., Wienbruch, C., Rockstroh, B., & Taub, E.
selection of memes underlies cultural evolution. People are (1995). Increased cortical representation of the fingers of the
seen as “carriers” of replicatable cultural “memes.” left hand in string players. Science, 270(5234), 305–307.
Phenotypic Accommodation: The set of developmental processes Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA:
that lead to novel phenotypic outputs. Phenotypic accom- MIT Press.
modation is based on the plasticity of existing biological Fry, I. (2000). The emergence of life on earth: A historical and scien-
affordances interacting with (physical, biological, and social) tific overview. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
environmental inputs. Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J.
Plasticity: The ability of a single genotype to generate vari- Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting and knowing (pp. 67–82).
able forms of morphology, physiology, and/or behavior in Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
response to different environmental circumstances. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society: Outline of the
theory of structuration. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
References Herz, T. (2006). Understanding mobility in America. Center for
Alexander, J. (2003). The meanings of social life: A cultural sociol- American Progress working paper.
ogy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (1995). Epigenetic inheritance
Anderson, E. (1999). Code of the street: Decency, violence, and the and evolution: The Lamarckian dimension. Oxford: Oxford
moral life of the inner city. New York: W.W. Norton. University Press.

tavory, ja blon ka , gin sbu rg 675


Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2005). Evolution in four dimen- Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of
sions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in human cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
the history of life. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Thelen, E. (1995). Motor development: A new synthesis.
James, W. (1890/1950). The principles of psychology. New York: American Psychologist, 50(2), 79–95.
Dover. Tishkoff, S. A., Reed, F. A., Ranciaro, A., Voight, B. F., Babbitt,
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1994). Beyond modularity: A developmen- C. C., Silverman, J. S., Powell, K., Mortensen, H., Hirbo,
tal perspective on cognitive science. International Journal of J. B., Osman, M., Ibrahim, M., Omar, S. A., Lema, G.,
Language & Communication Disorders, 29(1), 95–105. Nyambo, T. B., Ghori, J., Bumpstead, S., Pritchard, J. K.,
Latour, B. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and Wray, G. A., & Deloukas, P. (2007). Convergent adapta-
engineers through society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University tion of human lactase persistence in Africans and Europeans.
Press. Nature Genetics, 39(1), 31–40.
Liepert, J., Bauder, H., Miltner, H. R., Taub, E., & Weiller, Tomasello, M., & Slobin, D. I. (Eds.). (2005). Beyond nature-
C. (2000). Treatment-induced cortical reorganization after nurture: Essays in honor of Elizabeth Bates. Mahwah, NJ:
stroke in humans. Stroke, 31(6), 1210–1216. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Mameli, M., & Bateson, P. (2006). Innateness and the sciences. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological founda-
Biology and Philosophy 21(2), 155–188. tions of culture. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby
Mennella, J. A., Jagnow, C. P., & Beauchamps, G. K. (2001). (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and
Prenatal and postnatal flavor learning by human infants. the generation of culture (pp. 19–136). New York: Oxford
Pediatrics 107(6), e88. University Press.
Mill, J. S. (1843/2002). A system of logic: Ratiocinative and induc- Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1995). Foreword. In S. Baron-Cohen,
tive. Honolulu, HI: University Press of the Pacific. Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind (pp.
Newman, K. S. (1999). No shame in my game: The working poor xi–xviii). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
in the inner city. New York: Alfred A. Knopf and Russell Sage Uttal, W. R. (2003). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing
Foundation. cognitive processes in the brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Pager, D., & Shepherd, H. (2008). The sociology of discrimina- Press.
tion: Racial discrimination in employment, housing, credit, Wacquant, L. (2002). Scrutinizing the street: Poverty, morality,
and consumer markets. Annual Review of Sociology, 34, and the pitfalls of urban ethnography. American Journal of
181–209. Sociology, 107(6), 1468–1532.
Pascual-Leone, A., & Torres, F. (1993). Plasticity of the senso- Waddington, C. H. (1940). Organisers and genes. Cambridge,
rimotor cortex representation of the reading finger in Braille MA: Cambridge University Press.
readers. Brain, 116(1), 39–52. Waddington, C. H. (1957). The strategy of the genes. London:
Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: W. W. Allen & Unwin.
Norton. Waddington, C. H. (1968). The basic ideas of biology. In
Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How C. H. Waddington (Ed.), Towards a theoretical biology (Vol. 1,
culture transformed human evolution. Chicago, IL: University pp. 1–32). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
of Chicago Press. Weiller C., Chollet, K. J., Friston, K. J., Wise, R. J. S., &
Roe, A. W., Kwon, Y. H., & Sur, M. (1992). Visual projections Frackowiak, R. S. J. (1992). Functional reorganization of
routed to the auditory pathway in ferrets: Receptive fields the brain in recovery from striatocapsular infarction in man.
of visual neurons in the primary auditory cortex. Journal of Annals of Neurology, 31(5), 463–472.
Neuroscience, 12(9), 3561–3664. Weiller, C., Ramsay, S. C., Wise, R. J. S., Friston K. J., &
Schmalhausen, I. I. (1949). Factors of evolution. Philadelphia, PA: Frackowiak, R. S. J. (1993). Individual patterns of functional
Blakiston. reorganization in the human cerebral cortex after capsular
Sewell, W. H., Jr. (1992). A theory of structure: Duality, agency, infarction. Annals of Neurology, 33(2), 181–189.
and transformation. American Journal of Sociology, 98(1), West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolu-
1–29. tion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Willis, P. (1981). Learning to labor: How working class kids get
Oxford: Blackwell. working class jobs. New York: Columbia University Press.
Sperber, D. (2005). Modularity and relevance: How can a mas- Wilson, W. J. (1987). The truly disadvantaged: The inner city,
sively modular mind be flexible and context-sensitive? In the underclass and public policy. Chicago, IL: University of
P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate Chicago Press.
mind: Structure and content (pp. 53–68). New York: Oxford Wimsatt, W. C., & Griesemer, J. R. (2007). Reproducing
University Press. entrenchments to scaffold culture: The central role of devel-
Sperber, D. (2011). A naturalistic ontology for mechanis- opment in cultural evolution. In R. Sansom & R. Brandon
tic explanations in the social sciences. In P. Demeulenaere (Eds.), Integrating evolution and development: From theory
(Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 64–77). to practice (pp. 227–323). Cambridge, MASS: The MIT
Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Press.

676 c ulture an d e pi g e ne si s: a waddi ng ton ia n view


CHAPTER

From Material to Symbolic Cultures:


31 Culture in Primates

Christophe Boesch

Abstract
Recent wild animal studies have led to the realization that some of the population differences observed
in some species possess close similarities to human cultures. This has inflamed a long-standing debate
about the uniqueness of human cultural abilities. The accumulation of such detailed observations from
wild animal populations has provided more and more convincing details about the cultural skills in
different animal populations, which has resulted in a shift away from the question, “do animals possess
culture?” to the question, “what differentiates humans’ cultural abilities from other animals’?” The growing
body of evidence of cultural differences, not only in chimpanzees but also in macaques, capuchin monkeys,
orangutans, and other primate species, opens the way to a precise ethnography of culture in different
species. Chimpanzee culture is observed as well in the material domain as in the symbolic and social
ones and is disseminating by social-learning mechanisms, allowing in some cases for cumulative cultural
evolution. To further a precise understanding of the social-transmission mechanisms involved in cultural
transmission combining detailed field observations with ecologically and socially valid experimental
studies would be timely and welcome.
Keywords: Culture, symbols, cooperation, cumulative cultural evolution, ecological validity, chimpanzees,
humans, primates.

Culture is probably the single most central con- culture applies only to human beings, and, there-
cept in twentieth-century anthropology, as noted fore, a direct reference to ourselves is often implic-
by the Oxford Encyclopedia of Social and Cultural itly made when defining the concept (e.g., Barnard,
Anthropology (1996). Although not wanting to 2000; Kuper, 1999; Galef, 1992; Tomasello, 1999;
attempt to formally define “culture,” this encyclopedia Povinelli, 2000). For many others, however, culture
mentioned that “culture is what a person ought to is first and foremost a social process and should be
acquire in order to become a fully worthwhile moral defined as such without reference to any particular
agent” (p. 136). This illustrates one side of the cul- species (e.g., Borner, 1980; Kummer, 1971; Boesch
ture debate, which has been raging for decades as & Tomasello, 1998; Whiten & Boesch, 2001).
a consequence of the increasing number of obser- The tone of the culture debate has, in a sense, been
vations of behavioral differences seen between set by Marshall Sahlins, in his famous 1976 book titled
populations in different primate species. Although The Use and Abuse of Biology, in which the reluctance
these have been labeled as “cultural differences” of some in the human sciences to discuss humans with
by primatologists (Goodall, 1970; Boesch, 1996, an open comparative eye was clearly formulated. This
2003; McGrew, 2004; Panger et al., 2002; Perry & seems to reflect some people’s fear that by opening
Mason, 2003; Van Schaik et al., 2007; Whiten et al., anthropological concepts to other species, human
1999), for many anthropologists and psychologists, beings might be “threatened” in their humanity. For

677
example, when the famous anthropologist Louis small islet in the Japanese archipelago. This troop
Leakey learned about spontaneous tool use in wild was provisioned by animal keepers, who threw sweet
chimpanzees in the early 1960s, he remarked, “Ah, potatoes on the beach for them daily. The macaques
now we must redefine tool, redefine man—or accept rapidly learned to come to the beach and eat the
chimpanzees as humans!” A century earlier, after potatoes, and at the same time tolerated the close
learning about Darwin’s theory of evolution, the wife presence of human observers. One day, Imo carried
of the Bishop of Worcester said, “Humans descended a sweet potato from the sandy beach into the water,
from the apes! My dear, let us hope that it is not true, and after washing the sand off the potato, ate it.
but if it is, let us pray that it will not become gener- This new behavior, which resulted in sand-free and
ally known.” Interestingly enough, this view was still saltier-tasting potatoes, was performed by Imo again
expressed in a paper published in Science in 2009 the next morning. Interestingly, until this time, the
when White et al. (2009) wrote that a new description macaques avoided the water, but this new innova-
of Ardipithecus ramidus showed that “humans did not tion required that they now, at a minimum, come
evolve from chimpanzees.” However, this is a view that into contact with water. The peer playmates of Imo
biologists have never expressed. As Desmond Morris were the first to copy her behavior, and next were
said so wisely in his book The Naked Ape, humans’ the infants in the troop. Later, the mothers of the
“climb to the top has been a get-rich-quick story, and, different potato washers also learned the behavior.
like all nouveaux riches, we are very sensitive about In the end, other than some of the large adult males
our background.” At the same time, we may very well from the troop, everyone acquired Imo’s innovation.
be the only species that is curious to know what makes Remarkably, while potato washing, the macaques
us different from other species, and, therefore, many started to enter deeper and deeper into the water,
biologists and anthropologists feel that it is important so that the newborn babies lost any kind of aversion
to keep an open approach. Only in this way can we to the water, and started to play and swim. A few
progress in answering the question, “what makes us years later, the same Imo invented a new behavior:
human?”—instead of relying on just-so stories that do she collected a handful of wheat grains that the care-
not reflect our humanity. takers were throwing on the sand and carried them
to the water where she threw them all in. Only the
Culture as It Happens wheat grains floated on the surface of the water and
I shall adopt this last attitude in the present she was able to eat them much more rapidly than if
chapter and will present some of the knowledge that she had had to sort them from the sand, as before.
has been gained in the last three decades, as a result This new invention also propagated to the majority
of field studies of primates in their natural environ- of the group. Thanks to Imo’s innovations, sev-
ments. For the first time in history, this research has eral new cultural traits, including potato washing,
allowed us to gain a detailed view of what primates wheat grain throwing, and bathing, playing, and
really do in the wild. For this purpose, following a swimming in water, spread through the troop.
broad consensus, a behavioral trait is considered to When reporting these observations as far back as
be cultural once we have shown it to be a group- the 1950s, the Japanese observers did not hesitate
specific socially acquired trait (e.g., Kummer, 1971; to use the word “culture” without limiting its appli-
Bonner, 1980; Galef, 1992; Kuper, 1999; Barnard, cation to humans (Imanishi, 1952; Kawai, 1965;
2000). It is often also required that these behavioral Kawamura, 1959, 1965). This was because they
traits should be independent of any genetic and were less affected by the anthropocentric glasses that
ecological factors; however, if the first aspect make we tended to wear in the occidental world (de Waal,
sense, the second is never required when talking 2001). They were not disturbed by the fact that such
about humans and its relevance to the cultural changes resulted from human interventions, as, for
debate should therefore be questioned (Boesch, generations, the macaques had been living in contact
1996, 2003; Laland & Hoppitt, 2003). The example with humans in Japan and they had become part of
of potato washing in Japanese macaques will nicely the Japanese culture. To them and to many others in
illustrate this aspect of the cultural debate. the fields of anthropology and psychology through-
out the world, Imo and her playmates’ behavior
Imo the Culture Wall-Breaker opened the door to discussions of culture in ani-
Imo, a juvenile female Japanese macaque, was mal species other than humans for the first time.
a member of the Koshima troop, which lived on a However, not everybody shared our enthusiasm!

678 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


Some recent reviews of the concept of culture in group (e.g., Kawai, 1965; Whiten, 2005; Boesch,
the field of anthropology do not even mention 1996; Leca et al., 2007).
these observations, and consequently, there is also From another perspective, some psychologists
no hint of a discussion about the possibility that have argued that cultural transmission requires faith-
cultures might be observed in other animal species ful copying of the behavioral trait and have claimed
(Kuper, 1999; Barnard, 2000). Others have looked that this can only be guaranteed through imitation
carefully at the speed of acquisition of these new or teaching (Galef, 1992; Heyes, 1994; Tomasello
behaviors and have suggested that the transmission et al., 1993). They argued that other social-learning
was too slow to warrant the designation of cultural mechanisms, such as social facilitation or emulation,
transmission (Galef, 1990, 1992; Heyes, 1994; whereby individuals copy the context or the way
Tomasello, 1999; Laland & Hoppitt, 2003; but see objects are used but not the behavior itself, might
McGrew, 1992; Boesch, 2003 for alternative social lead to the acquisition of a behavior but with much
explanations for this). less fidelity. In their view, neither had been shown
It remains impressive that Imo invented two new in the case of the Japanese macaques and, therefore,
techniques that spread through her social group and that although the acquisition of potato washing was
that resulted in a series of behavioral changes related impressive, it could not be labeled as “cultural.”
to water. If precise analyses of the spread of the Others rapidly argued that human data did not
behavior are important to characterize how inno- show that cultural transmission required either of
vation spreads in macaques, it should not distract these mechanisms but, instead, that other forms of
us from the fact that macaques have this ability to social learning equally contributed to cultural trans-
learn from others, and totally new behavior patterns missions (Boesch, 1996; Waal, 2001). Following the
can be acquired by most group members within a arguments of the Japanese researchers, biologists, on
few years. These observations show that macaques the other hand, have argued that the sheer presence
exhibit important behavioral flexibility that was of such invention and propagation within a social
previously thought to be restricted to humans. To group is strong evidence of the cultural abilities of
many, this is a nice example of cultural change! this species (Bonner, 1980; Waal, 2001).
More generally, psychologists tend to argue
The Cultural Debate after Imo’s that animals’ abilities to adapt to the ecological
Breakthrough constraints they face in their daily life are well-
Although the primatological community reacted documented, and that both present and past small
positively to such new developments, some psychol- ecological factors could have affected the occurrence
ogists adopted a more critical stance and reminded of specific behavioral patterns. Furthermore, they
us that, as cultural traits disseminate within social suggest that, in natural settings, it would be almost
groups through a social-learning process, we should impossible to exclude such ecological effects and
expect this to happen “relatively” quickly (Galef, that natural observations, therefore, do not allow us
1990, 1992; Heyes, 1994). This has led to end- to make any claims about the cultural abilities of
less discussions about how quickly a behavioral animals (Galef, 1990, 1992; Heyes, 1994; Tomasello,
trait should spread within a social group when it 1990, 1999). This view has become dominant in
is supposed to be cultural transmission, and how some circles of experimental and comparative psy-
we can differentiate such a social-transmission chology and has led to an increase in studies done
mechanism from a pure individual learning process in captive settings.
(e.g., Lefebvre, 1995; Boesch, 1996; Tomasello,
1999; Laland & Janik, 2006). It should come as Problems with “Culture outside of
no surprise that in the absence of any rational argu- Culture” Studies
ment about the expected speed of such a spread, However, such studies of “culture outside of cul-
opinions would diverge; some believed that the ture” falter on their two key assumptions. First, they
macaque observations show that the speed of spread assume that captive animals face the same social-
indicates the absence of cultural transmission (e.g., learning challenges as their wild counterparts, and
Galef, 1990, 1992; Heyes, 1994; Tomasello, 1990), second, they assume that all behavior patterns are
while others saw it as strong support for a cultural learned via the same learning mechanism, indepen-
spread as the spread followed precisely the social dent of the ecological relevance of the behavior. For
interactions network prevailing within a macaque example, they would argue that captive macaques

boesch 679
would learn to rake food within arm reach of a between chimpanzee and human cultures. This has
human model based on the same copying mecha- been mainly possible thanks to the special treatment
nism and motivation as Imo’s playmates learn to of chimpanzee studies in primatology; because of the
wash potatoes. The stance a scientist takes toward genuine interest we have in our closest living relatives,
experimental data with captive animals is a func- more different populations living in diverse habitats
tion of their stance on these two assumptions. have been studied in chimpanzees than in any other
For a number of experimental psychologists, these primate species.
assumptions are perfectly reasonable and broad It is important to realize from the start that the
claims made from such experimental studies have study of culture in chimpanzees has followed a differ-
been thought to reveal limitations in the cultural ent approach than the one adopted with macaques;
abilities of different animal species. if a dynamic diffusion approach based on the acquisi-
On the other side, the validity of this “culture tion of novel behavior caused by human intervention
outside of culture” approach has been viewed much was central to the study of culture in macaques, an
more critically by the majority of behavioral ecolo- ethnographic approach, in which established behavior
gists, anthropologists, and philosophers, and the patterns in different populations were compared, has
broad claims made from such artificial studies with been taken with the study of culture in chimpan-
animals who are often socially impaired are greeted zees. Such an ethnographic approach to culture pro-
with skepticism (Byrne, 1995, 2007; de Waal, ceeds by exclusion, whereby ecological and genetic
2001, 2006; Bekoff et al., 2002; Allen, 2002, 2004; influences must be excluded before any behavior is
Boesch, 2007, 2008; McGrew, 2004). For one, the proposed to be cultural (see Goodall, 1973; Nishida,
“artificial” nature of the ecology of captive settings 1987; Boesch & Boesch, 1990; Nishida et al., 1993;
has no parallel in nature and, therefore, no one can Boesch, 1995, 1996, 2003; McGrew, 1992; Boesch
really assess the “ecological validity” of such studies. & Tomasello, 1998). The main rationale for utilizing
To some, this renders captive experiments use- such a different approach lies in the fact that, since
less. Furthermore, the artificial nature of the social wild animal populations live in stable ecological
groups in captive settings is patent and the effect conditions, it is extremely rare to see the acquisition
of this is again very difficult to assess, although we and dissemination of new behavior elements within
know that early social upbringing conditions have a a social group. Hence, the ethnographic approach is
large influence on later cognitive development. At often the only one available.
the very least, this should require one to carefully In the case of the chimpanzees, this approach
assess the validity of captive studies in contributing has proven very successful, in the sense that it
to our understanding of the culture phenomenon has allowed for the first time to gain more pre-
in primates. cise knowledge of important characteristics of the
cultural phenomenon in this species. Here, I will
Chimpanzees as Culture Generalists go through what researchers have seen as some of
As this debate was developing, new data was being the key elements of the culture phenomenon in
published on what has emerged as the most major chimpanzees over the years:
discovery in chimpanzee behavior of the two last
decades, namely the unexpectedly large behavioral 1) Large cultural repertoire: First, field researchers
diversity observed among different wild populations. have started to compare aspects of the behavioral
This was observed in a diverse assortment of contexts, repertoires of their study populations with the
including the sexual, social, demographic, tool-use, knowledge gained by others on other populations
and hunting contexts. This important dimension of and have proposed an ever-growing list of potential
chimpanzee behavior was the center of three interna- cultural elements (Goodall, 1973; McGrew, 1992;
tional conferences, which each resulted in an edited Boesch, 1996). Then, in an attempt to understand
volume. These were titled Understanding Chimpanzees the breadth of the variability in the cultural reper-
(Heltne & Marquardt, 1989), Chimpanzee Cultures toire of each population, field workers who followed
(Wrangham et al., 1994), and Great Apes Societies eight different populations of wild chimpanzees
(McGrew et al., 1996). This has progressively placed in different regions of Africa gathered together
the chimpanzee in a special position, as the more to compare their knowledge about chimpanzees.
we are learning about wild chimpanzee popula- This resulted in a preliminary list with 38 behav-
tion diversity, the more similarities we are finding ioral traits that were proposed to be cultural in the

680 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


species and independent of any ecological influences example, Taï chimpanzees exhibit 26 of the 38 cul-
(Whiten et al., 1999, 2001). At the time of writing, tural traits, while Gombe chimpanzees perform 24
a second similar exchange between field workers is of them, but only 16 of these are shared with the Taï
underway. This meeting includes the addition of chimpanzees. Similarly, the Bossou chimpanzees,
researchers who study three new chimpanzee popu- whose territory is only 200 kilometers north of the
lations, so that a much more extensive list of puta- Taï forest, exhibit 11 of the 38 elements, and share
tive cultural elements is been produced (Whiten only six with Taï and four with Gombe chimpan-
et al., in prep.). zees. So, each population of chimpanzees is charac-
The main lesson to be taken from such a listing terized by multiple different cultural elements, and
exercise is that, in chimpanzees, each population can it is this mix that is population-specific.
be distinguished from the others thanks to a specific The second point is that cultural differences are
cultural repertoire, which always includes a mul- not merely a question of presence or absence of a
tiple complex of different behavioral elements. Like trait, but also a question of the form and context
a fingerprint, knowledge of these elements makes it under which the trait is performed in each popula-
possible to determine the population origin of any tion. For example, ant dipping (the third icon from
individual chimpanzee with certainty. The map of the top of the map, in the left column of each popu-
the original publications presented here illustrates lation cultural card) is performed with short sticks
the distribution of the 38 cultural elements across and one hand in Taï chimpanzees, but with lon-
six wild chimpanzee populations (Fig. 31.1). For ger sticks and both hands in Gombe chimpanzees

Figure 31.1 The cultural repertoire of six


different chimpanzee populations (Whiten
et al., 1999). For each population, the rep-
ertoire is synthesized on a card with the 38
potential behavior elements, where each ele-
ment present in that population is earmarked
with a colorful icon; a square icon stands for
the element being observed in the popula-
tion, a circle icon stands for an alternative
form of the behavior element, and a blue cir-
cle indicates the element was not seen in the
population with no obvious ecological reason.
When a clear ecological reason explained the
absence of the element, a horizontal minus
bar is marked in the blue circle.

boesch 681
(Goodall, 1968, 1970; Boesch & Boesch, 1990). behavioral differences that persist despite the very
This is illustrated by the icon on the map with a close proximity of the two groups, and exchanges
squared or round shape, as can be seen for ant-dip. of individuals between the two groups have been
On the other side, for example, leaf-clip (the second recorded. As such groups are neighbors, we can be
to last icon from the right in the third row from certain that genetic differences do not explain these
the top) is performed in a very similar way in each observations, and additionally, it is straightforward
population but the context and its attached mean- to control for possible ecological differences. This
ing varies extensively (see below). has allowed researchers to make strong claims about
cultural differences (Boesch, 2003, in press; Whiten
2) Cultural fidelity: In some limited instances, et al., 1999; Langergraber et al., 2010).
researchers have followed and made detailed obser- In the Taï forest, three neighboring communities
vations about two neighboring chimpanzee groups have been followed and reveal strikingly important
living in the same forest block. For example, in the cultural differences in 11 behavior elements. These
Mahale Mountains of Tanzania, field researchers behavior elements have been seen as well in the
followed two neighboring chimpanzee communities, material domain, related to the acquisition of food,
the K- and the M-Group, and the larger of the two, as in the symbolic domain, related to courtship and
the M-Group, was seen to push the smaller K-Group play initiation (Fig. 31.2) (Boesch, 2003).
out of their range during certain seasons of the year The important aspect here is that, in chimpan-
(Kawanaka & Nishida, 1968). They have found zees, cultural transmission and fidelity within groups

20 25 30
Divergent cultural traits between neighbours in the Taï forest

65
North group:
- Driver ants deep-dig
- Termite mound pound
- Knuckle-knock courtship
- Day-nest rest 60

Middle group 55
N Ta ï Culture:
- Young pith eaten
- Ant dip
- Leaf swallow
- Crack Coula Nuts
- Decayed Strychnos 50
South group:
- Driver-ant surface-dig
- Mature pith chew
- Musanga leaf swallow
- Day-nest courtship
45
- Day-nest playstart
- Fresh Stry chnos
- Stone-hammer choice

Figure 31.2 Map of the territories of the three neighboring chimpanzee communities in Taï National Park, Côte d’Ivoire,
with a preliminary list of their specific cultural elements (Boesch, 2003). In addition to the general specific cultural elements
shown already in Figure 31.1, Taï chimpanzees possess community-specific cultural elements, both in the material and social
domain, that show a high level of conformity, being observed in all community members, and a strong level of fidelity, prevailing
for many years.

682 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


persist for extended periods of time, despite females shelters, have maintained themselves for numerous
transferring between communities at menarche. This generations in human groups. However, detecting
dispersal pattern could lead to a homogenization of the age of a behavior pattern is impossible, unless
the behavior patterns across neighboring communi- it produces long-lasting artifacts. The nut-cracking
ties over a very short period of time, as females who behavior of chimpanzees may well be the only pri-
transfer from their natal community to a new one, mate behavior that might allow for such a study, as
at an age when they have already acquired the full it is a cultural behavior in which chimpanzees often
behavioral repertoire of their natal group, could con- use stone hammers or anvils to crack nuts.
tinue to perform it in their new group. However, the To answer the question of how long nut-cracking
opposite was observed in both Mahale and Taï chim- behavior has been present in chimpanzees, we ini-
panzees, in the sense that community-specific culture tiated an archaeological project with the hope of
elements remain extremely stable and the new immi- uncovering some old nut-cracking sites (Mercader
grants adapt rapidly to the culture of the new group et al., 2002, 2007). By applying traditional archaeo-
(Luncz & Boesch, in prep.). It is too early to say any- logical methods to a Panda tree, where we had seen
thing about either the mechanisms making the immi- regularly chimpanzees crack nuts, we could show
grant females adopt the behavioral culture of their that they had been cracking at that particular tree for
new community or about the benefits of doing so. over 150 years (Panda 100 in Fig. 31.3), and had left
In conclusion, high fidelity to group-specific cultural hundreds of stone flakes behind. In a closely adja-
traits and conformity to new group-specific cultural cent area, we were able to reach old soil layers dated
habits are characteristics of chimpanzee culture. to 6,000 years old, and found stone artifacts pro-
duced by cracking nuts in layers that were between
3) Cultural history: An important part of culture 2,200 and 4,300 years old (site Noulo in Fig. 31.3)
is its historical dimension as this also emphasizes (Mercader et al., 2007). These artifacts were found
the social transmission aspect of the behavior trait. mixed with some typical Iron Age human artifacts
Many of the claims about human cultural fidelity and the older samples were found below the human
rest on archaeological studies that have shown that occupation layer. This represents a first estimate that
some cultural products, like arrows, hammers, or could be shifted back in time once excavations are

Culture history in nut-cracking in Taï chimpanzees

Panda 100 Noulo


(Mercader et al. 2002) (Mercader et al. 2007)
Age (yrs BP)

Chimpanzee
0–150

No Cultural
Remains

No Cultural
Remains ~2200
Human
Iron Age

Chimpanzee
Late Paleolithic Stone Age
~4240

No Cultural
Remains

~6290

Figure 31.3 Stratigraphy of two excavation sites in the Taï Forest.The first on the left represents a known recent Panda nut-cracking
site (Panda 100), and the second is at an old nut-cracking site (Noulo), where chimpanzee stone artifacts that were uncovered were partly
mixed with and below human artifacts typical from the Iron Age (after Mercader et al., 2002, 2007).

boesch 683
done on older soil layers. However, this result already by adult males just before a display to signal their
shows that, in the case of nut cracking, chimpanzees intention; in Bossou chimpanzees, it is often used
have used a cultural behavior in a very similar way by youngsters to get others’ attention and invite
for over 200 generations. To give an idea of the time others to play; and in Mahale chimpanzees, it is
interval this represents, the human Iron Age began used by sexually active males to attract estrus female
in this region of Africa about 2,500 years ago, and so to mate with them (Nishida, 1987; Sugiyama &
the Chimpanzee Stone Age predated the Human Iron Koman, 1979; Boesch, 1995) (see Fig. 31.4). So,
Age by some thousands of years. within a group, one behavioral element can acquire
This behavior remains the only cultural behavior a specific meaning that is shared between all mem-
trait where it is possible to show that chimpanzee bers, although the form of the behavior and the
culture has been transmitted over hundreds of gen- sounds produced remain exactly the same and
erations. However, that simple observation suggests do not refer to the meaning. In other words, the
that the ability to copy a behavior pattern over meaning of a behavior element results from a social
generations is present in chimpanzees and may be construct that is shared between group members in
observed in many other cultural traits. chimpanzees.
The flexibility of these social meanings in chim-
4) Symbolic culture: Communicative behavior panzees is further revealed by the fact that a similar
elements are used to convey information between meaning can be expressed by different behavior
social group members and, therefore, by definition elements in different social groups (Fig. 31.4). For
are based on some shared meaning if they are to be example, although leaf-clip means “I want to have
of any use. In chimpanzees, some communicative sex with you” in Mahale chimpanzees, this specific
traits follow some group-specific norms, by which meaning is expressed by knuckle-knock in Taï chim-
it is the meaning of the trait that differs and not the panzees. Leaf-clip in Taï chimpanzees means some-
form (Boesch, 1995, 1996, 2003, 2008). The most thing different than in Mahale chimpanzees, while
complex example is the leaf-clipping behavior ele- this last meaning is performed by knuckle-knock.
ment that is present in three of the six well-studied To complicate this further, leaf-clip in Bossou chim-
populations: In Taï chimpanzees, leaf-clip is used panzees, which means “I want to play with you” is

Sign code in
chimpanzees

I am going to display

Taï

Leaf-clip Bossou Taï Knuckle-knock

I want to have sex with you


Mahale

Taï Ground nest

I want to play with you

Figure 31.4 Symbolic culture in wild chimpanzees. The three behavioral elements performed by chimpanzees in three populations
are framed in bold with the name of the population indicated on the arrow specifying the meaning the element has in this population.
Two of the meanings have been seen to be supported by different signs in different populations.

684 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


also used by Taï chimpanzees, but is expressed by 5) Cumulative cultural evolution: Some of the
making a coarse day-nest on the ground (Boesch, cultural elements proposed in chimpanzees are char-
1995, 2003). acterized by a relatively high level of technological
Arbitrary shared meanings that are group-spe- complexity, in the sense that they incorporate differ-
cific are obviously among the main characteristics ent elements that each produce a behavior element
of human language, and it is very intriguing to that fulfills a function on its own and is seen to be
find that behavior signs in wild chimpanzee pop- used in only some populations. For example, all
ulations have similar properties. If the example of chimpanzees in all studied populations pound hard-
leaf-clip is still a long way from being a language, shelled fruits against hard surfaces in order to break
we need to keep in mind that uncovering such a them open and get at the seeds or the flesh found
“sign code” (see Boesch, in press) in another species inside. Some chimpanzee populations in Western
requires from the human observers an expertise in and Central Africa have incorporated the use of a
this code, something no one anticipated to be pres- hard tool in this universal behavior pattern, whereby
ent. In other words, if it was hard for Europeans the tool is hammered against the hard-shelled fruit to
to decipher Egyptian hieroglyphs, doing so for sign pound it open (Fig. 31.5) (Boesch & Boesch, 1984,
code differences between Taï and Gombe chim- 1990; Morgan & Abe, 2006). The integration of a
panzees may prove even harder. Thus, the leaf-clip second object in the pounding movements, as seen in
sign codes might be just the tip of the iceberg in a Bossou and Taï chimpanzees, allows the chimpanzee
new dimension of chimpanzee communication still to crack open much smaller and harder fruits that
unknown to us, or it may remain what it appears would not have been accessible with the first, sim-
to be now—an intriguing sophistication that never pler technique. Finally, in regions where roots, which
developed. Until specific studies comparing chim- are used as anvils, are hard to find, as in Bossou,
panzee populations are done with expert eyes, we chimpanzees have been seen to place nuts on mobile
will not know. stone anvils instead (Fig. 31.5) (Matsuzawa, 1999).

The way to nut-cracking


Cumulative cultural evolution

Cumulative
Flail
elements
(conspecific, snake,…)

Club
(conspecific)
Detached tool
Pound
(Hard fruits, termite mound)
Populations

Hammer Mobile Anvil Universal


Combine tools
(hammer nuts on anvil) (hammer nuts on anvil)
Gombe

Bossou
Serial tools Extract Stabilisor
(stick for almond) (support anvil ) Taï

Figure 31.5 Cumulative cultural evolution in chimpanzees: All chimpanzees in all wild populations have been seen to use branches, clubs,
or saplings to hit at conspecific or dangerous species, such as snakes or wild cats. This object can be attached or detached from their substrate.
As a second innovation, a food source could directly be pounded against a hard surface, as seen in Gombe, Bossou, and Taï chimpanzees.
Third, a hammer has been added to the behavioral sequence to pound harder food sources in Bossou and Taï chimpanzees, while only Bossou
chimpanzees have been observed to use mobile anvils that they can transport to the nut-producing trees. Furthermore, chimpanzees in Taï
and Bossou have been seen to use other tools to either extract more of the kernel out of the shell or to stabilize the mobile anvil.

boesch 685
But from there on, we saw two additional incorpo- It follows then that ideas about the uniqueness of
rations that are possible, either the use of sticks to human culture have lost some of their preeminence,
empty nuts as seen in Taï chimpanzees, or the use of and in their place, the urge to understand the distri-
a second stone to stabilize mobile anvils in Bossou bution of different animal species’ cultural practices
chimpanzees (Fig. 31.5). has arisen. The legitimacy of culture in animals was
An additional, very complex example of cumu- gained through an ethnographic approach, by which
lative cultural evolution in chimpanzees is seen the behavioral repertoire of different populations
in the honey-extracting techniques performed by within one species was compared to the ecological
Central African chimpanzees (see review Boesch et conditions they were facing. By excluding ecological
al., 2009; Sanz & Morgan, 2009). Here, different factors, the ethnographic approach suggested that
elements have again been progressively integrated the potential differences were of a cultural nature.
in the technique, so that each step in this cumula- The main requisite to the implementation of such
tive process produces an efficient technique seen to an approach is the necessity of detailed studies on
be used in some chimpanzee populations (Boesch enough different wild populations in a given species.
et al., 2009). As seen in the nut-cracking example, Even today, this situation exists for only a handful of
chimpanzees add innovations to a universal tech- species, and, therefore, our understanding of the real
nique, in this case, the common behavior for chim- distribution of the cultural phenomenon in animals
panzees extracting a food resource from a hole in remains limited by definition.
either a tree trunk or the ground with their hands. The ethnographic approach applied to wild pop-
In some chimpanzee populations, we observed the ulations has uncovered fascinating new facts about
first incorporation of a tool in the technique, either important population differences that exist within
a twig for ant dipping in Gombe, Goualougo, and a species, and cultural abilities have been proposed
Taï chimpanzees, or a sturdy branch, a pounder, in such diverse species as orangutans (van Schaik
to break open bee nests for honey in Goualougo, et al. 2001), capuchin monkeys (Perry & Manson,
Loango, and Taï chimpanzees. Then, after they suc- 2003; Panger et al., 2002; Visalberghi et al., 2007),
ceeded in breaking open the nest with the first tool macaques (Leca et al., 2007), as well as in whales
to extract tree honey, a second tool, a collector, was and dolphins (Rendell & Whiteside, 2001). Not
added by the Loango and Goualougo chimpanzees. only does the ethnographic approach stimulate the
This was not, however, seen in Taï chimpanzees. incorporation of a comparative approach in different
Finally, a third tool can be incorporated for large animal species, but, when observing one population,
nests. In Loango, the accumulation of elements can such approaches allow us to discover what is popu-
go in another direction for terrestrial bee nests. The lation-specific and what is representative of the spe-
Loango chimpanzees use a perforator, a complexity cies as a whole. This further stresses the complexity
not seen in Goualougo chimpanzees, to extract of the interactions between ecology and culture.
honey (see Boesch et al., 2009). Capuchin monkeys are particularly interesting
New observations of nut cracking and honey as, in some ways, they present very similar patterns
extraction present some of the most detailed cases to the ones observed in chimpanzees. A handful of
of cumulative cultural evolution in chimpanzees, wild-bearded capuchin monkey (Cebus libidino-
analogous to those proposed for human artifacts, sus) populations have been seen to crack wild nuts
such as the hammer or a screwdriver. Boesch (in in Brazil, while this behavior pattern is absent in
press) has emphasized the fact that such cumu- others (Visalberghi et al., 2007; Canale et al.,
lative processes were also apparent in different 2009). In another species, the white-faced capu-
communicative cultural traits. chins (Cebus capucinus), a series of differences have
been observed between three populations in the
Orangutans, Capuchins Follow way they process 20 food species before eating them
the Culture Track (Panger et al., 2002). In addition, a certain number
Once described only in macaques and chimpan- of social behavioral traits have also been observed to
zees, the idea of animal culture has gained credibility differ between populations, such as hand sniffing of
in larger circles in science, and biologists have gar- others, sucking on the body parts of others, and the
nered the courage to look for culture in other animal “finger-in-mouth” game (Perry & Manson, 2003).
species and have adopted a similar approach by com- Some cases of new social games were invented when
paring behavior patterns in different populations. researchers were around and the diffusion within the

686 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


group could be followed (Perry & Manson, 2003). culture between Eskimos and Pygmies are, first and
From these and other primate species observations, foremost, because of the drastically different eco-
we see that some of the simpler forms of cultural logical conditions that they face. It is important to
abilities seem to have been present very early on in bear in mind that if we want to compare cultural
our evolutionary history and that abilities proposed abilities between different species, we need to use
to be uniquely human in the past are possibly shared the same set of criteria to define culture. Sadly, such
with many in the primate family lineage. an aspect has rarely been considered in the conclu-
sions made when comparing the cultural abilities of
The Cultural Debate after the Wild humans with other species.
Animal Culture Explosion Two ways of progressing toward a fairer compar-
The important progress made in recent years to ison have been pursued. The first solution to nar-
our understanding of the cultural phenomenon in rowing this gap was to address the sample size issue
different animal species has led to a second shift, one by studying more and new groups of wild popula-
that is still in progress. The central question in the tions belonging to species known for their cultural
culture debate has become, “what distinguishes the abilities. The gaps in our knowledge in chimpanzees
cultural practices in different species?” rather than, have been especially dramatic, as the largest popula-
“is culture a uniquely human ability?” This shift in tion of this species lives in Central Africa, and they
focus in the culture debate has been enthusiastically have been totally neglected for decades. It is only
adopted by primatologists and some behavioral ecol- very recently that two long-term studies have been
ogists, while contemplated with more skepticism in initiated to fulfill this gap, the first in the Goualougo
some human science circles (Boesch, 2003; Whiten Triangle in the Republic of Congo (Sanz & Morgan,
et al., 2003; Laland & Janik, 2003; Byrne, 2007). 2007, 2009; Sanz et al., 2004) and the second in
This shift in trying to understand the width of the Loango National Park in Gabon (Boesch et al.,
cultural diversity in different species is still under- 2007, 2009). Both have already unraveled surpris-
way but there are many stumbling blocks. The first ing new and sophisticated forms of tool use that
is sample size, as this differs dramatically between have not been described before. This nicely illus-
species. In humans, we have access to observations trates how much our knowledge of chimpanzees, a
from hundreds of different populations or more, species who we have studied so much, is still very
while we have detailed observations from only 12 fragmentary. Similarly, new studies with capuchin
populations of chimpanzees, the second-most-stud- monkeys have adopted a much more comparative
ied animal species. There are only six populations approach and included many more populations
of orangutans, the third on the list. In other words, (e.g., Canale et al., 2009).
because of the terrible paucity of data on nonhu- The second solution directly addressed the short-
man animal species, cultural breadth and abilities comings of experimental approaches. For many
might by definition be much less-developed. psychologists, a transmission mechanistic approach
An additional hurdle to comparing cultural should be favored over the ethnographic approach,
abilities across species is that, since adaptation to based on the argument that what counts in the cul-
ecological conditions has long been observed in ture phenomenon is not necessarily the end result of
animal species, including insects and fish, ecologi- population-specific behavioral patterns but, instead,
cal influences must be excluded for a behavior to be how a behavior is transmitted between individuals.
recognized as cultural in nonhuman animals (Galef, Furthermore, they argue that only an experimental
1992; Tomasello, 1990; Laland & Hoppitt, 2003). approach is able to identify such a mechanism,
The addition of this criterion, never considered in as individuals in the wild are exposed to so many
humans, has by definition decreased the number of simulations and experiences that it would be almost
potential behavioral elements that could be consid- impossible to identify the precise mechanisms at
ered as cultural in animals (Boesch, 1996; Boesch & work (Galef, 1992; Heyes, 1994; Tomasello & Call,
Tomasello, 1998; Whiten et al., 1999; Van Schaik et 1997). However, it has been difficult to interpret
al., 2003). However, we all know that a vast part of the results of experimental studies on social learning
human culture includes artifacts, clothes, foraging of novel behavior patterns, which showed strong
tools, and many other items that are all related to limitations in this ability in captive chimpanzees
the specific ecological conditions a population faces. (Tomasello et al., 1987; Heyes, 1994; Povinelli &
For example, many of the differences in material Vonk, 2003). The favored experimental procedure

boesch 687
was to present a single individual in an isolated as a result of imitation, as this was suggested to
room with a demonstrator located in another be the only social-learning process that guaran-
room through a window. To prevent any uncon- teed a high level of fidelity in the copied behavior
trolled influences, the social dimension of cultural (Galef, 1990, 1992; Heyes, 1994; Tomasello, 1990;
learning was completely excluded. Furthermore, Tomasello et al., 1993). However, in the absence of
the novelty of the tasks was more important than a complete theory as to when and why imitation
their ecological validity, so individuals were tested should be used within a species, experimenters have
with artificial tasks such as throwing sand or raking been looking for imitative evidence with behav-
food (Tomasello et al., 1987). Nevertheless, to ioral tasks selected randomly with mixed results.
some, a consensus developed that such experiments Although the results of group diffusion experiments
were enough to prove that culture, as understood have convincingly shown that imitation is not
in humans, was not present in nonhuman pri- required to reach a high level of fidelity in copying
mates and that the population-specific behavior a behavior pattern in chimpanzees, it was found
observed should be based on a totally different that chimpanzees copy more by imitation when the
process (Povinelli, 2000; Tomasello & Call, 1997; individual cannot understand all the physical com-
Tomasello, 1999). However, such a conclusion plexities of a task (e.g., when copying the way to
remained in strong contrast to observations in the get access to food contained in an opaque version
wild and no attempt was made to explain the differ- of a box), while they will use more individual skills
ences between the ethnographic approach and the if they can understand them (e.g., when facing a
captive experimental studies. similar but transparent version of a box with food
The impressive array of cultural behavior dif- inside) (McGuigan et al., 2007). In both cases, the
ferences documented in wild primates concerning demonstrator was the highest-ranking female of the
group-specific socially learned behaviors has led group and therefore a trustful social partner. This
other psychologists to question the validity of the convincingly showed that imitation and transmis-
above-mentioned experimental procedures and sion are social behaviors and that chimpanzees are
to develop alternative ones, in which some of the very sensitive to this. Without taking great care to
aspects presented to the tested individuals would be preserve the social dimension, the results of experi-
as similar as possible to the situations faced by wild ments are not very helpful.
animals in the cultural domain. One of the most The main lesson about such studies is that cul-
innovative procedures was done by keeping the indi- ture is a social phenomenon and that the “culture
viduals within their normal social setting during the outside of culture” approach adopted in so many
experiments rather than isolating them. In this way, captive studies has shown very strong limitations
the social transmission of a novel behavior as well as in its ability to understand the cultural abilities in
the development of group-specific traditions could nonhuman animal species (Boesch, 2007, 2010; de
be mimicked in captive social groups (see Whiten et Waal, 2001). The main progress to experimentally
al., 2005, 2007, 2009; Horner et al., 2006; Hopper understanding some aspects of cultural transmis-
et al., 2007, 2008; McGuigan et al., 2007). This sion was achieved when the social dimension could
proved to be very successful as it was possible to be reintroduced into the experiment paradigm. This
follow the whole chain of social transmission from social approach was so successful that it could be
one expert individual to all group members and then replicated in other primate species, such as capuchin
from one group to up to four different neighboring monkeys (Dindo et al., 2009). Field studies remain
groups. Such dispersal of novel behavior was accom- the prime source of information about the breadth
panied by a strong fidelity to the expert’s behavior, of the culture spectrum and the cultural abilities.
which maintained itself over long periods of time
and during the dispersal process between groups. Conclusion
In other words, some of the key aspects of cultural Being as selfish as we are, the question of human
transmission could be reproduced in such innovative uniqueness has always drawn a lot of attention and
cultural diffusion experiments. been an area with numerous unsupported strong
This success has led the team to explore another claims (e.g., de Waal, 2001; Whiten et al., 2003;
aspect of culture that was proposed to be unique to Boesch, 2009). To avoid such well-known pitfalls, I
humans, namely the ability to imitate one another. shall try to limit myself to comparisons between spe-
Some have proposed that culture can develop only cies for areas where direct observations are available,

688 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


as reviewed above, and avoid anthropocentric claims that such a statement is very frustrating, as all pri-
as much as is humanly possible. The newest data on mate species are threatened in one way or another,
wild animals reveal that, in many species, cultural and because of this, we may never fully know how
differences are present. Such cultural traits that are similar our abilities are.
concentrated on feeding techniques and therefore Wild animal studies have led to the realization
contribute directly to an individual’s survival repre- that some of the population differences observed in
sent important characteristics of life. In other cases, some species possess close similarities to human cul-
cultural traits are also observed in the social and tures. The accumulation of such detailed observa-
communicative domains but these tend to be less tions from wild animal populations have provided
common than those seen in the material domain more and more convincing details about the cul-
(Boesch, in press). For the first time, this progress tural skills in different animal populations, which
offers some hope toward a resolution of what parts has resulted in a shift away from the question, “do
of the culture phenomenon are uniquely human. animals possess culture?” to the question, “what
This review would open the way to distinguishing differentiates human cultural abilities from other
some of the differences observed between animal animals’?” The growing body of evidence of cul-
species in their cultural abilities. To do this, I tried tural differences, not only in chimpanzees but also
to include all we know about wild animal cultural in macaques, capuchin monkeys, orangutans, and
behavior as well as some important experimental other primate species, opens the way to a precise
results. This review allows us to propose that, at a ethnography of culture in different species.
minimum, humans share the following attributes By turning away from wild animal studies,
with many animal species: comparative psychology faces the risk of eventu-
ally reaching an impasse, as only experimental
• Acquisition of spontaneous group-specific
studies with captive animals are considered with-
behavior traits,
out any concern for the ecological validity of such
• Presence of cultural traits that are not
approaches. Luckily, studies have recently been
influenced by ecological and genetic conditions,
started that will, in complement to wild animal
• Social learning of cultural traits from group
studies, help us to address the question of animal
members,
cultural abilities. However, time is running out and
• Persistence of cultural traits for extended
all primate species suffer from habitat degradation
period of time,
and direct hunting against them, which could pre-
• Presence of nonadaptive cultural traits.
vent us from collecting enough data on them before
In addition, I propose that the overlap between we can determine the specific cultural abilities of
human and chimpanzee cultural abilities is larger, as human and nonhuman primate species.
they include the following attributes:
Future Directions: Toward a Resolution of
• Cultural cumulative evolutions in material
Understanding Human Uniqueness
and social domains,
One way to find a provisional answer to the ques-
• Multi-generational history in cultural traits,
tion of human uniqueness is to look for cognitive
• Faithful copying from dominant prestige-
abilities unique to humans that are important for
carrying models,
cultural transmission and acquisition. This would
• Conformity to new social groups,
include speech, which is notably absent in other
• Active teaching and imitation of cultural
animal species, as well as modern human means of
traits,
communication like writing, radio, and Internet.
• Symbolic social norms in cultural behavioral
These communication media allow for the trans-
traits.
mission of cultural traits between individuals who
At this stage, it would be tempting to argue that do not meet face-to-face, either because they are not
those cultural abilities not listed here are uniquely visible to one another or because one of them might
human. This may be true, but we should not for- already be dead (Boesch, 2008). In addition, even in
get that our knowledge of other animal species a face-to-face situation, such improved communica-
fares very poorly compared to what we know about tion permits the cultural transmission of skills out of
humans, and, therefore, more observations will cer- context, namely without having to demonstrate or
tainly increase the list of similarities. I fully realize practice the skill. Such cultural transmission modes,

boesch 689
which are not available to any other animal species, Boesch, C., & Boesch, H. (1984). Mental map in wild chim-
would facilitate the transmission of more complex panzees: An analysis of hammer transports for nut cracking.
Primates, 25, 160–170.
cultural traits. Boesch, C., & Boesch, H. (1990). Tool use and tool making in
Another possible way to answer such a question wild chimpanzees. Folia primatologica, 54, 86–99.
will come from careful and ecologically valid compar- Boesch, C., & Tomasello, M. (1998). Chimpanzee and human
isons between how chimpanzees and humans learn cultures. Current Anthropology, 39(5), 591–614.
social skills from group members. Recent work on Boesch, C., Head, J., Tagg, N., Arandjelovic, M., Vigilant, L.,
& Robbins, M. (2007). Fatal chimpanzee attack in Loango
imitation reveals that, although both species readily National Park, Gabon. International Journal of Primatology,
imitate, humans have a much stronger tendency to 28, 1025–1034.
overimitate than chimpanzees, in the sense that they Boesch, C., Head, J., & Robbins, M. (2009). Complex toolsets
will faithfully copy unnecessary or irrelevant actions for honey extraction among chimpanzees in Loango National
(Lions et al., 2007; Whiten et al., 2009). This ten- Park, Gabon. Journal of Human Evolution, 56, 560–569.
Bonner, J. (1980). The evolution of culture in animals. Princeton,
dency to blindly imitate irrelevant actions in adults NJ: Princeton University Press.
might contribute to a stronger tendency in humans Byrne, R. (1995). The thinking ape. Oxford: Oxford University
to adopt irrelevant and maladaptive cultural traits Press.
(Whiten et al., 2009). In a process similar to mate Byrne, R. (2007). Sociality, evolution and cognition. Current
choice in birds, where individuals have been seen to Biology, 17, R714–R723.
Canale, G., Guidorizzi, C., Kierulff, M., & Gatto, C. (2009).
simply copy the choice of others rather than to select First record of tool use by wild populations of the yellow-
the best mate, humans may be copying what they breasted capuchin monkey (Cebus xanthosternos) and
see group members doing without going through new records for the bearded capuchin (Cebus libidinosus).
the time-consuming process of evaluating the ben- American Journal of Primatology, 71, 366–372.
efit of each cultural trait, and thereby nonadaptive Dindo, M., Whiten, A., & Waal de, F. (2009). In-group confor-
mity sustains different foraging traditions in capuchin mon-
or opaque cultural traits can spread more readily in keys (Cebus apella). PLoS ONE 4(11), e7858.
humans than in chimpanzees. Galef, B. (1990). Tradition in animals: Field observations and
laboratory analyses. In M. Bekoff, & D. Jamieson (Eds.),
References Interpretation and explanation in the study of animal behavior
Allen, C. (2002). A skeptic’s progress. Biology and Philosophy, 17, (pp. 74–95). Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
695–702. Galef, B. G. (1988). Imitation in animals. In B. Galef, &
Allen, C. (2004). Is anyone a cognitive ethologist? Biology and T. Zentrall (Eds.), Social learning: Psychological and biological
Philosophy, 19, 587–607. perspectives (pp. 3–28). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Earlbaum.
Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (2007). Animal minds, cognitive Goodall, J. (1968). Behaviour of free-living chimpanzees of
ethology and ethics. Journal of Ethics, 11, 299–317. the Gombe Stream area. Animal Behaviour Monograph, 1,
Barnard, A. (2000). History and theory in anthropology. 163–311.
Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Goodall, J. (1970). Tool-using in primates and other vertebrates.
Barnard, A., & Spencer, J. (Eds.) (2002). Encyclopedia of social In D. S. Lehrmann, R. A. Hinde, & E. Shaw (Eds.), Advances
and cultural anthropology (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge. in the study of behavior (Vol. 3) (pp. 195–249). New York:
Bekoff, M., Allen, C., & Burghardt, G. (Eds.) (2002). The cogni- Academic Press.
tive animal: Empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal Goodall, J. (1973). Cultural elements in a chimpanzee com-
cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. munity. In E. Menzel (Ed.), Precultural primate behaviour,
Boesch, C. (1995). Innovation in wild chimpanzees. International Fourth IPC symposia proceedings (Vol. 1) (pp. 195–249).
Journal of Primatology, 16(1), 1–16. Basel, Switzerland: Karger.
Boesch, C. (1996). Three approaches for assessing chimpanzee Heltne, P., & Marquardt, L. (1989). Understanding chimpanzees.
culture. In A. Russon, K. Bard, and S. Parker (Eds.), Reaching Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
into thought (pp. 404–429). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge Heyes, C. M. (1994). Imitation, culture and cognition. Animal
University Press. Behaviour, 46, 999–1010.
Boesch, C. (2003). Is culture a golden barrier between human Horner, V., Whiten, A., Flynn, E., & de Waal, F. (2006). Faithful
and chimpanzee? Evolutionary Anthropology, 12, 26–32. replication of foraging techniques along cultural transmis-
Boesch, C. (2007). What makes us human (Homo sapiens)? The sion chains by chimpanzees and children. Proceedings of the
challenge of cognitive cross-species comparison. Journal of National Academy of Science, 103(37), 13878–13883.
Comparative Psychology, 121(3), 227–240. Hopper, L., Spiteri, A., Lambeth, S., Schapiro, S., Horner, V., &
Boesch, C. 2008. Taking development and ecology seriously when Whiten, A. (2007). Experimental studies of traditions and
comparing cognition: Reply to Tomasello and Call (2008). underlying transmission processes in chimpanzees. Animal
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 122(4): 453–455. Behaviour, 73, 1021–1032.
Boesch, C. (2010). Away from ethnocentrism and anthro- Hopper, L., Lambeth, S., Schapiro, S., & Whiten, A. (2008).
pocentrism: Towards a scientific understanding of “what Observational learning in chimpanzees and children stud-
makes us human.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2/3), ied through “ghost” conditions. Proceedings of the Royal
26–27. Society, series B. doi:10.1098/rspb.2007.1542

690 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


Imanishi, K. (1952). Evolution of humanity. In K. Imanishi Morgan, B., & Abwe, E. (2006). Chimpanzees use stone ham-
(Ed.), Man (pp. 36–94). Japan: Mainichi-Shinbunsha. mers in Cameroon. Current Biology, 16(16), R632–R633.
Kawai, M. (1965). Newly acquired precultural behavior of Nishida, T. (1987). Local traditions and cultural transmission. In
the natural troop of Japanese monkeys on Koshima islet. S. S. Smuts, D. L. Cheney, R. M. Seyfarth, R. W. Wrangham,
Primates, 6,1–30. & T. T. Strusaker (Eds.), Primate societies (pp. 462–474).
Kawamura, S. (1959). The process of sub-culture propagation Chicago, MI: University of Chicago Press.
among Japanese macaques. Primates, 2, 43–60. Nishida, T., Wrangham, R. W., Goodall, J., & Uehara, S. (1983).
Kawamura, S. (1965). Sub-culture among Japanese macaques. In Local differences in plant-feeding habits of chimpanzees
S. Kawamura, & J. Itani (Eds.), Monkeys and apes—Sociological between the Mahale Mountains and Gombe National Park,
studies (pp. 237–289). Tokyo: Chuokoronsha. Tanzania. Journal of Human Evolution, 12, 467–480.
Kawanaka, K., & Nishida, T. (1974). Recent advances in the Panger, M., Perry, S., Rose, L., Gros-Louis, J., Vogel, E.,
study of inter-unit-group relationship and social structure of MacKinnon, K., & Baker, M. (2002). Cross-site differences
wild chimpanzees of the Mahale Mountains. In S. Kondo, in foraging behavior of white-faced capuchins (Cebus capuci-
M. Kawai, A. Ehara, & S. Kawamura (Eds.), Proceedings of nus). American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 119, 52–66.
the 5th Congress of the International Primatological Society Perry, S., & Manson, J. (2003). Traditions in monkeys.
(pp. 173–185). Tokyo: Japan Science Press. Evolutionary Anthropology, 12(2), 71–81.
Kummer, H. (1971). Primate societies: Group techniques of Povinelli, D. (2000). Folk physics for apes: The chimpanzee’s theory
ecological adaptation. Chicago: Aldine. of how the world works. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kuper, A. (1999). Culture: An anthropologist perspective. Boston: Povinelli, D., & Vonk, J. (2003). Chimpanzee minds: Suspiciously
Harvard University Press. human? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(4), 157–160.
Laland, K., & Hoppitt, W. (2003). Do animals have culture? Rendell, L., & Whitehead, H. (2001). Culture in whales and
Evolutionary Anthropology, 12, 150–159. dolphins. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(3), 309–324.
Laland, K., & Janik, V. (2006). The animal cultures debate. Sanz, C., Morgan, D., & Gulick, S. (2004). New insights into
Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 21(10), 542–547. chimpanzees, tools, and termites from the Congo Basin.
Langergraber, K., Boesch, C., Inoue, E., Inoue-Murayama, M., American Naturalist, 164(5), 567–581.
Mitani, J., Nishida, T., Pusey, A., Reynolds, V., Schubert, Sanz, C., & Morgan, D. (2007). Chimpanzee tool technology
G., Wrangham, R., Wroblewski, E., & Vigilant, L. (2010). in the Goualougo Triangle, Republic of Congo. Journal of
Genetic and “cultural” similarity in wild chimpanzees. Human Evolution, 52, 420–433.
Proceeding of the Royal Society, B. Sanz, C., & Morgan, D. (2009). Flexible and persistent tool-
Leca, J., Gunst, N., & Huffman, M. (2007). Japanese macaque using strategies in honey-gathering by wild chimpanzees.
cultures: Inter- and intra-troop behavioural variability of International Journal of Primatology, 30, 411–427.
stone handling patterns across 10 troops. Behaviour, 144, Schaik van, C. P., & Knott, C. (2001). Geographic variation in
251–281. tool use on neesia fruits in orangutans. American Journal of
Lefebvre, L., Whittle, P., Lascaris, E., & Finkelstein, A. (1997). Physical Anthropology, 114, 331–342.
Feeding innovations and forebrain size in birds. Animal Schaik van, C. P., Ancrenaz, M., Brogen, G., Galdikas, B.,
Behaviour, 53, 549–560. Knott, C., Singleton, I., Suzuki, A., Utami, S., & Merrill,
Lions, D., Young, A., & Keil, F. (2007). The hidden structure of M. (2003). Orangutan cultures and the evolution of material
overimitation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, culture. Science, 299, 102–105.
104(50), 19751–19756. Schaik van, C. (2007). Culture in primates and other animals.
Matsuzawa, T. (1999). Communication and tool use in chim- In R. Dunbar & L. Barrett (Eds.), Oxford handbook of evolu-
panzees: Cultural and social contexts. In M. Hauser, & tionary psychology (pp. 103–113). Oxford: Oxford University
M. Konishi (Eds.), The design of animal communication Press.
(pp. 645–671). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Sugiyama, Y., & Koman, J. (1979). Tool-using and -making
McGrew, W. (1992). Chimpanzee material culture: Implications behavior in wild chimpanzees at Bossou, Guinea. Primates,
for human evolution. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University 20, 513–524.
Press. Tomasello, M. (1990). Cultural transmission in tool use and
McGrew, W. (2004). The cultured chimpanzee: Reflections on communicatory signaling of chimpanzees? In S. Parker, &
cultural primatology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University K. Gibson (Eds.), Comparative developmental psychology of lan-
Press. guage and intelligence in primates (pp. 274–311). Cambridge,
McGrew, W., Nishida, T., & Marchandt, L. (1996). Great apes UK: Cambridge University Press.
societies. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (1997). Primate cognition. Oxford:
McGuigan, N., Whiten, A., Flynn, E., & Horner, V. (2007). Oxford University Press.
Imitation of causally opaque versus transparent tool use Tomasello, M., Davis-Dasilva, M., Camak, L., & Bard, K.
by 3- and 5-year-old children. Cognitive Development, 22, (1987). Observational learning of tool-use by young chim-
353–364. panzees. Journal of Human Evolution, 2, 175–183.
Mercader, J., Panger, M., & Boesch, C. (2002). Excavation of a Tomasello, M., Kruger, A., & Ratner, H. (1993). Cultural
chimpanzee stone tool site in the African rainforest. Science, learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16(3), 450–488.
296, 1452–1455. Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origin of human cognition.
Mercader, J., Barton, H., Gillespie, J., Harris, J., Kuhn, S., Tyler, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
R., & Boesch, C. (2007). 4,300-year-old chimpanzee sites Visalberghi, E., Fragaszy, D., Ottoni, E., Izar, P., Oliveira, M.,
and the origins of percussive stone technology. Proceedings of & Andrade, F. (2007). Characteristics of hammer stones
the National Academy of Science, 104(9), 3043–3048. and anvils used by wild bearded capuchin monkeys (Cebus

boesch 691
libidinosus) to crack open palm nuts. American Journal of C. (2001). Charting cultural variations in chimpanzee.
Physical Anthropology, 132, 426–444. Behaviour, 138, 1489–1525.
Waal, F. de (2001). The ape and the sushi master: Cultural Whiten, A., Horner, V., & Marshall-Pescini, S. (2003). Cultural
reflections of a primatologist. New York: Basic Books. panthropology. Evolutionary Anthropology, 12, 92–105.
Waal, F. de (2006). Primates and philosophers: How morality Whiten, A. (2005). The second inheritance system of chimpan-
evolved. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. zees and humans. Nature, 437, 52–55.
White, T., Asfaw, B., Beyene, Y., Haile-Selassie, Y., Owen Lovejoy, Whiten, A., Spiteri, A., Horner, V., Bonnie, K., Lambeth, S.,
C., Suwa, G., & WoldeGabriel, G. (2009). Ardipithecus Schapiro, S., & de Waal, F. (2007). Transmission of multiple
ramidus and the paleobiology of early hominids. Science, traditions within and between chimpanzee groups. Current
326, 75–86. Biology, 17, 1038–1043.
Whiten, A., & Boesch, C. (2001). The cultures of chimpanzees. Whiten, A., McGuigan, N., Marshall-Pescini, S., & Hopper, L.
Scientific American, 284(1), 48–55. (2009). Emulation, imitation, over-imitation and the scope
Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W., Nishida, T., Reynolds, of culture for child and chimpanzee. Philosophical Transactions
V., Sugiyama, Y., Tutin, C., Wrangham, R., & Boesch, C. of the Royal Society, series B, 364, 2417–2428.
(1999). Cultures in chimpanzee. Nature, 399, 682–685. Wrangham, R., McGrew, W., de Waal, F., & Heltne, P. (1994).
Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W., Nishida, T., Reynolds, Chimpanzees Cultures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
V., Sugiyama, Y., Tutin, C., Wrangham, R., & Boesch, Press.

692 f rom materi a l to sy mb o li c cult ure s: cu ltu re in prim ates


PA RT
8
Human Movement
Through Culture
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Encountering Alterity: Geographic


32 and Semantic Movements

Alex Gillespie, Irini Kadianaki, and Ria O’Sullivan-Lago

Abstract
This chapter analyzes the semantic consequences of crossing national borders. When crossing borders,
identities change, and alterity is encountered. We ask: what are the semantic structures, or meanings,
that enable alterity to be either embraced or resisted? We start by distinguishing between movements
in geographic space and semantic movements of meaning. Our aim is to link geographic movements to
semantic movements, but not in a linear way. The semantic consequences of geographical movement
can be diverse and reverberate for many years. We draw upon empirical examples from studies of
immigration in Greece and Ireland to show how alterity is resisted, how representations of nationality
and belonging are used to stabilize identities, and how feelings of being stigmatized can be deflected
without leading to reciprocal denigration. We speculate about the potential role of geographic movement
in providing people with externality over their own experiences, as it enables them to step out of
themselves and see themselves from the perspective of others. The chapter concludes with suggestions
for future research.
Keywords: Immigration, dialogism, identity, semantic barriers, movement

Humans move. They move from one place to our concerns. Movement between geographic loca-
another, from one job to another, from one social tions is mutually exclusive: our bodies cannot yet
group to another, from one life stage to another. It is be in two places at once. Meanings, however, even
therefore overly simplistic to consider contemporary when contradictory, are rarely mutually exclusive:
society as a collection of people and groups belonging our thoughts can be in many places at once. In the
to mutually exclusive identities. Movement can present chapter we will examine how the multiple
make locals become migrants and in-groups become meanings are not only present within the thoughts
out-groups. The present chapter analyzes the relation of people who move, but also how these multiple
between geographic movements on the one hand, meanings interact.
and the meanings that such movement generates Starting with a discussion of the extent to which
on the other. This relation is complex because geo- people travel across national borders, we move on
graphic movement does not have a linear effect on to the impact of those movements on how people
the way in which self and other are re-represented. are identified and identify themselves. We then
Movement across national borders usually has dif- introduce data from two studies and demonstrate
ferent meanings for the people who move compared the ways in which crossing national borders disrupts
to those who are either left behind or those in the and redraws identity boundaries. Our analysis places
host community. The extent to which people who emphasis on the way in which geographic movement
move are aware of these different meanings and leads to encounters with alterity: other individuals
integrate them into more general meanings is one of and other groups. We analyze semantic structures

695
(i.e., at the level of meaning and not discursive the social-psychological impact of such move-
practice) that enable alterity to be resisted, iden- ment? From a social-psychological point of view,
tity boundaries to be stabilized, and also those that geographic movement is interesting because it is a
create an openness to alterity. Our key question is: basis for encountering alterity, that is, other people
what are the semantic structures, or meanings, that and alternative ways of viewing the world and ones
enable the alterity encountered through geographic own position within it. Theories of human devel-
movement to be either resisted or embraced? opment and identity put significant emphasis on
interactions with alterity. Researchers developing
People on the Move the work of Mead (Hobson, 2002; Gillespie, 2006;
Commercial aircraft transport over one billion Martin, 2006), Vygotsky (Valsiner, 1998; Wertsch,
passengers per year. Most of these passengers are 1991), and the early Piaget (Perret-Clermont, 1980;
making trips of relatively short duration, with over Psaltis & Duveen, 2007) have argued and shown
922 million international tourist arrivals worldwide that social relations are central to the development
in 2008 (UNWTO, 2009). However, some interna- of higher mental functions, the capacity for self-
tional travelers have one-way tickets. Although it is regulation, and the transition to more differentiated
difficult to estimate the exact number of migrants in and integrated psychological processes. In addition,
the world today, a recent UN report (UNDP, 2009) researchers working in the field of identity have
has estimated that there are over 190 million world- argued, on the basis of countless studies, that alter-
wide. Clearly, geographic movement is an impor- ity is central to the emergence and transformation of
tant phenomenon for a large portion of humanity. self-definitions (e.g., Howarth, 2002; Jovchelovitch,
Moreover, a recent survey by Gallup (Esipova & 2007). If we accept that encountering alterity is a
Ray, 2009) indicates that 16% of the world’s popula- basis for human development, what implications
tion, or 700 million people, would move to another does the unprecedented movement of people across
country permanently if they had the chance. Actual national borders have for how people think about
geographic movement must be considered along- themselves and others?
side the larger pool of hopes, dreams, and fears that There is an established body of research examin-
motivate people to actually move, whether for tour- ing the relation between geographic movement and
istic pleasure or making a new life. identity. Encountering the other, particularly cul-
While geographic movement may have reached tural others when individuals relocate, is not a simple
new heights, the phenomenon is not new. For task for the self. Be they immigrants, asylum seek-
example, the heterogeneous makeup of people living ers, refugees (O’Sullivan-Lago, Abreu, & Burgess,
in the so-called “New World” is evidence of a long 2008; Kadianaki, 2010a), tourists (Gillespie, 2006),
history of movement. According to the U.S. Census or international students (Märtsin, 2009), the action
Bureau (Luke, 2004), the U.S. population is made of moving in geographic space and coming into
up of 70% non-Hispanic European descent,12.5% contact with alterity forces individuals to construct
Hispanic descent, 12.3% African descent, 3.8% new identities (Moghaddam, 2002) and engage
Asian descent, and over 2% mixed descent. Less in processes of identity negotiation. This is caused
than 1% of the population are of Native American by their encounters with novel social others, and
descent. What this latter fact also reveals is that even also because of direct or indirect encounters with
if one does not move, the geographic relocation of their home communities (Bhatia & Ram, 2001;
others can have an enormous impact. The Native Kadianaki, 2010a, 2010b). As they move, individu-
American group became “natives,” hosts to those als must come to terms with the identity transitions
that migrated, and later, because of the volume of from being a “local” in their home culture to being
individuals who arrived, a minority group in their a “foreigner” and “immigrant” in the new culture.
own land. How they are positioned in their home communi-
ties is also altered, however: there is, as such, “no
Social Psychological Consequences home to go back to” (Hall, 1987, p. 44).
The movement of people across national and Because of their geographic movement, indi-
cultural borders has been shown to have large- viduals encounter previously unfamiliar identities
scale social and political consequences (Mountz, that are often racialized and devalued in the par-
2004; Ellis, 2005; Hubbard, 2005; Abu-Laban & ticular social context (Deaux, 2006). Yarbrough
Garber, 2005; MacÉinrí, 2006). But, what about (2009) describes how migrants coming from Latin

696 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


American countries to Atlanta, USA, encounter a in geographic space and the movements of self and
previously unfamiliar identity, that of Hispanic/ other at the level of meaning and representation.
Latino(a), in their everyday social interactions While it is accepted that identities are bound
with native-born residents. Physical characteris- into geographic and social contexts (Dixon &
tics and language accent are often used by native- Durrheim, 2000), it does not follow that as people
born residents to build racialized assumptions move from one context to the next they take up new
about the new migrants, which lump together all identities and completely disregard their previous
Latin American nationalities into an overarching identities. While bodies can be only here or there,
identity or misattribute all of these nationali- at the level of identity and representation we can
ties as being Mexican. In the new situation, the occupy multiple and even contradictory positions.
migrants also move into positions of “immi- For example, before immigrants-to-be actually
grant” or “asylum seeker,” identities that are often move, they think about moving, they imagine their
highly stigmatized and laden with social meanings possible future in another country, and thus before
that need to be negotiated (O’ Sullivan-Lago & they have physically moved they have engaged in
Abreu, 2009; Kadianaki, 2010a). Verkuyten and semantic movements. Instead of describing people
Steenhuis (2005) point out that although the as moving from one identity to the next, it has been
“asylum seeker” category is often misinterpreted, argued that it is more accurate to describe them as
it is very socially meaningful, featuring in every- accumulating identities that, in relation to each
day thinking and raising emotional reactions. other, stand in various states of tension and har-
Often, particularly in the case of “asylum seekers,” mony (Gillespie, 2007a). The self stretches back to
the label is applied to, and must be negotiated encompass all the positions we have occupied and it
by, individuals who do not even belong to that can stretch forward to imagine future ones we may
category (O’Sullivan-Lago, 2009). occupy. For example, in his analysis of Malcolm X’s
Immigrant identity can be seen to be caught dialogical identity, Gillespie (2005) has shown that
between asymmetrical social discourses and stigma- in his trajectory through the social world and move-
tized representations in the community of residence ment between different social contexts, Malcolm
and “contradictory discourses related to home, tra- X accumulated the identities of being oppressed, a
dition, community, nation and loyalty” to the com- hustler, minister, and human-rights activist. Toward
munity of origin (Bhatia & Ram, 2001, p. 304). the end of his life, it was the interaction between
The immigrant self often constitutes ambivalent these accumulated identities that characterized his
and conflicting identity positions (Bhatia, 2002; uniqueness.
Hermans, 2001). In the next section we ana- In further opposition to the geographic body,
lyze more closely the relation between geographic the semantic world enables us to move between
movement and the semantics of identity. and occupy many social, temporal, and imagined
geographic positions simultaneously or in rapid
Theorizing Geographic and Semantic sequence. At a semantic and psychological level,
Movement the past, present, and future can coexist along
Our distinction between geographic and semantic with counterfactual presents, imagined pasts, and
movements is based on Koffka’s (1935) differentia- wished-for or feared futures. For example, tourists
tion of the geographic and behavioral environment in Northern India have been shown to inhabit a
of organisms. Koffka pointed out that there can be semantic world in which what is observed and expe-
a difference between the geographic environment rienced merges with what has been seen in films and
(the physical environment as it is independent of books (Gillespie, 2007b).
its perception) and the routines and meanings that In the geographic world, the difference between
organisms associate with that environment. The self and other is absolute because self and other
behavioral environment refers to the meanings, that occupy mutually exclusive space-time trajecto-
is, semantic associations, that organisms have with ries (Mead, 1932). However, at a semantic level,
the geographic environment. In what follows we the oppositions between self and other; between
develop Koffka’s distinction to theorize movement us and them; between me and you; can shift and
within the geographic and behavioral, or semantic, slide, sometimes collapse or even reverse (Gillespie,
environments. Simply put, we want to theorize the 2007a). We live in a perspectival social world:
relation between the movement of human bodies a world in which other people and groups have

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 697


different ideas and identities, and what is key is that Crossing Greek and Irish Borders
as social actors, we are to some extent aware of their In order to examine the relation between geo-
different ideas and identities. The difference is not graphic and semantic movement empirically, we
only “out there;” it is also within us. Humans expe- draw upon research from two studies. These proj-
rience alterity, represent it, and position themselves ects share their focus on the encounters between
in relation to it. people of different cultural worlds in one place as
a result of geographic movement across borders.
The Relation between Self and Other Our aim is not to introduce new data, but rather
The distinction between geographic and seman- to integrate existing data from these two previ-
tic environments provides conceptual clarity when ously published studies in order to develop more
talking about the relation between self and other. generalizable theory.
While self and other are fundamentally distinct in The first corpus of data is from a project on
the geographic world, they are inter-related in the immigrants living in Greece conducted by the
semantic world, gaining meaning through their second author of this chapter (Kadianaki, 2010a;
relationship. At a semantic and psychological level, Kadianaki, 2009). Immigrants who participated in
others are an important part of the self: this includes the project came from a variety of countries, mainly
not only one’s friends but also one’s enemies. Insofar South American and African. All participants were
as the self is defined in dialogical relation to the other living in Athens, their residence in Greece spanning
(Marková, Chapter 22), the other is an essential part from 2 to 30 years. The data presented comes from
of the self. To make the same assumption of groups, individual in-depth interviews, group discussions
that the out-group exists “out there,” apart from the and ethnographic observation in three immigrant
in-group, is to commit the psychologist’s fallacy and communities from August 2007 to April 2008.
confuse what is in the mind of participants with The second data corpus comes from research by
what is in the mind of researchers (James, 1890). the third author of this chapter with immigrants,
In a context of intergroup conflict, the out-group asylum seekers, and Irish locals living in Ireland
is central to the in-group’s identity: it structures the (O’Sullivan-Lago, 2009; O’Sullivan-Lago & Abreu,
way in which in-group members think about them- 2009, 2010). The immigrant participants were
selves and their world. Within the dialogical self, mainly from European countries. The asylum seekers
the other is a central counterpoint: not only a point were mainly from Africa and the Middle East. The
of comparison, but also a perspective from which to participants had resided in Ireland for very varying
view the self (Simão, Chapter 18). lengths of time: from a matter of months to over
Thus, at a semantic level the other can be within 20 years. All of the participants, including the
the self. At an empirical level this manifests when Irish locals, were residents in Cork in the South of
someone refers directly or indirectly to the point of Ireland. The data presented comes from in-depth
view of another. For example, “my mother thinks individual interviews that were conducted between
I am a good student, but I’m not sure I am.” In July 2007 and February 2008.
such an instance, we can see the mother refracted In both of these comparable empirical contexts,
semantically within the student. Yet, we must also geographic movement put people with different
be aware that at a semantic level the individual languages, accents, physical characteristics, eco-
has a self-concept that will often exclude not only nomic and symbolic power, beliefs, values, habits
their enemies but also their friends. Returning to and so on, into contact. Both empirical contexts
the example of the student, she would likely dis- are thus instances in which alterity is encountered
tinguish herself from her mother yet, these are her and identity transformation is likely. While the Irish
ideas about her mother (her mother might think locals may not have moved geographically, we will
differently). That is to say, people tend to see them- demonstrate that the movement of the other has an
selves as isolated and fail to see that the others with impact on their identity, as contact with migrants
whom they interact and continue various dialogues forces the recognition and evaluation of cultural
with, are in fact, part of their own selfhood at a identities.
semantic level. The present chapter aims to explore Our analysis focuses upon discursive data in
in detail exactly how alterity, encountered through terms of the identity positions being sustained
geographical movement, enters into and transforms (i.e., local, immigrant, asylum seeker, cheater, con-
the self. tributor, and so on), and any movement within the

698 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


discourse between these identity positions. This self-representation that she resists. The underlined
analysis of movement at a semantic level led us to text indicates the intrusion of the alternative self-
also analyze the ways in which movement in the representation (self as immigrant) into Helén’s dis-
representation of self and other can be both blocked course. The alternative self-representation, initially
and facilitated. given voice to by Helén’s mother, is that Helén is
Throughout the presentation of the excerpts we an immigrant who has gone abroad out of a tragic
use the following transcription conventions: square financial necessity. Helén vehemently resists this
brackets ([]) are used to insert explanatory text, being represented in that way, arguing that she is
pauses ([pause]) and the removal of some utter- not an immigrant “in that way.” Each time the alter-
ances ([ . . . ]). Underlining indicates the presence of native self-image intrudes, she resists it, counter-ar-
alterity, usually alternative representations, which is guing that she is different because she has moved
being encountered and negotiated in the excerpts. out of choice and does not see the move as sad.
In this resistance, however, we can also see that
Geographic Movement: Semantic the geographic movement to Ireland has reposi-
Consequences tioned Helén. She admits she is an immigrant in
The representations of immigrant/local usually some ways: she does come from a different country,
entail a rigid self/other opposition that are rein- she has left her family behind and has a different
forced by such things as language barriers, skin culture, but she still resists the categorization. Thus
color, and cultural practices. The distinction can also we see that although the geographic move from
be reinforced by commonplace beliefs about com- Spain to Ireland is absolute, the semantic movement
petition for economic and social resources. Despite into the identity position of immigrant is not.
the rigidity of this self/other differentiation, it is Moreover, the semantic movements occasioned
geographic movement that has brought about the by the geographic movement to Ireland do not end
distinction: all immigrants were locals before they with a self-representation of being an immigrant.
left. Although the movement from the geographic After a certain number of years, some immigrants
location where they were “local” to the geographic feel, and want to be seen as locals. For how many
location where they are an “immigrant” might only years one has to live in a country to become “local”
take a few hours, the semantic movement into a is contested, and often self-identifications come into
self-representation as an immigrant usually takes conflict with the way in which they are identified
much longer and is often resisted. Consider the fol- by others. Consider the following from Antonia, a
lowing excerpt from Helén who moved from Spain refugee from Romania:
to Ireland:
People will ask me, even after 7 years, ‘where are you
My mother used to say, she used to cry a lot, ‘why from?’ and I get so bothered, I’m becoming bothered
don’t you come home?’ always the same question, and tired after seven years to say ‘oh I am originally
‘why don’t you come home?’ And one time she from Romania’ and I will say sometimes to joke, ‘I’m
mentioned the word immigrant and I thought, Irish, I’m from Carrigaline’ and they say ‘ok, you
‘but I’m not an immigrant’ because before, their are from Carrigaline but where are you from?” ’ All
generation, the generation before, they were the time people will see me as being from another
immigrants in my view because they had to go abroad country. So that’s a little bit, you know, not such a
because of money, because of circumstances, being good feeling. But I have to get used to this because
poor or whatever [pause] I didn’t consider myself an this is it, what I am in the Irish eyes, I will never be
immigrant because I didn’t really have to leave my one of the Irish even though I consider myself and I
family and go because I needed a better life or money say, ‘come on, I’m an Irish citizen now.’
or anything like that, I just went because I wanted (Antonia, 41 years old, Romanian, living in Ireland for
to [ . . . ] so I know very much that I’m not Irish and 7 years)
never will be, but I’m not an immigrant in that way.
There is a disjunction between Antonia’s self-
(Helén, 45 years old, Spanish, living in Ireland for 21 years)
representation and how the Irish locals see her.
Helén has been living in Ireland for 21 years and in The (underlined) alterity she encounters punc-
a technical and legal sense, Helén is an immigrant. tures her thoughts and discourse. Antonia wants
However, she does not consider herself to be one. to represent herself as Irish, but she is blocked by
The idea that she is an immigrant is an alternative the views she encounters—her desired identity is

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 699


not recognized. Having moved 7 years earlier, she empirical examples of how these barriers work to block
now asserts her Irish citizenship and belonging, alternative representations.
but because her nationality and accent remain, the In the encounter between immigrants and locals,
people she meets see her first and foremost as a there are many examples of semantic barriers being
foreigner. What is central to the semantic conse- used to dismiss or block the alternatives presented.
quences of geographic movement is encountering In the following excerpt Aidan, an Irish local, gives
alterity, other people and alternative representa- his rather blunt justification for not engaging with
tions: as with Helén, it is in the eyes of the other asylum seekers:
that the semantic consequences of geographic
I just don’t like to talk to most asylum seekers, like,
movement become salient.
especially you know that most of them are either
Movement in the geographic environment does
on the run from the law in their own country and
not lead straightforwardly to repositioning of iden-
if they go back to their own country they’ll get
tity at the semantic level of representation. There
prosecuted for this or that, and our country doesn’t
can be issues of lag, of coming to terms with a
wonder why they’re so afraid to go back to their own
new identity position, and even acts of resistance
country, ‘oh they’ll probably get killed’ or something
and discrepancies between the identity positions
like that, you know they make up all these excuses.
that are claimed and the ways in which one is posi-
Why can’t they request their criminal background
tioned. People are rarely free to choose their identity
from that country? This person could have been
positions, and recognition from others is essential
just saying this and this and this and like, ‘I’ll go
(Howarth, 2002). An overarching semantic conse-
back and I’ll get killed’ and this, but they never look
quence of geographic movement is a disjunction
past that and think they could have got in trouble
between how people see themselves and how they
with the law. The possibility of them being done for
are seen. Geographic movement brings people into
kiddy-fiddling, kidnapping, rape, anything—you
contact, and in that contact each discovers that they
could number a list of things that they’d be nervous
have a relevancy or surplus meaning (Gillespie,
about going back for because he doesn’t want to go
2003) for the other that is somewhat at odds with
back to jail, so he makes up an excuse and how’s our
the way in which they have previously represented
government supposed to check up on that?
themselves.
(Aidan, 23 years old, Irish local)

Semantic Barriers: Resisting Alterity In this explanation for his avoidance of asylum
It is not sufficient simply to be in the geographic seekers, Aidan represents them as having an ulte-
presence of alterity to actually encounter alter- rior motivation for being in Ireland, namely, to
ity. Encountering alterity necessitates being open escape legitimate punishment for grievous crimes.
unto the other (Levinas, 1991), that is, represent- The alternative representation (underlined) is that
ing the other as beyond self and representing self the asylum seekers can’t go back to their country
as potentially transformed by the other. However, of origin because “they’ll probably get killed.” Even
because of threat of change, there is often a seman- though this fear of persecution is the definition of
tic effort to deny alterity and stabilize preexisting what an asylum seeker is, it gains no traction with
representations of self and other. Aidan. He constructs a powerful semantic barrier
Moscovici (1974/2008) and Gillespie (2008) to block the alternative representation of these
have begun to identify the semantic barriers used individuals seeking asylum for genuine reasons.
to resist alternative representations. Semantic bar- The extreme case formulation of his semantic con-
riers are ways of speaking and thinking that block struction (Pomerantz, 1986) leads him to distrust.
transformative engagement with alterity. Semantic Indeed, the vigor of their protestations could even
barriers, including creating rigid oppositions, nega- be interpreted by Aidan as further evidence of their
tive associations, prohibitions, clear-cut separations, horrendous crimes and desire to escape punish-
stigmatizing the other, undermining their motive, ment. The implication is that people who have com-
or presenting the other as having mere “beliefs” mitted grievous crimes will say anything to escape
and “thoughts” about the world (rather than valid prosecution and thus nothing said can be believed.
experiences), can all inhibit transformational inter- Dialogue with the other is accordingly presented as
action between ideas, representations, and per- a waste of time for an honest person, which is why
spectives. In the following analyses, we present he doesn’t “like to talk to most asylum seekers.” In

700 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


the absence of trust it is impossible to have open in the utterance “but we know it is a general thing
dialogical communication because what the other they feel.”
says and does loses value because of the possibility If one tendency in the face of alterity is to resist
of an ulterior motive (Marková & Gillespie, 2007). and stigmatize, as Aidan does, then it will be the
Another common alternative ulterior motive, case that in encountering alterity, one is likely to
voiced by the Irish locals, is that immigrants and encounter stigma. While an easy response might be
asylum seekers are only in Ireland for generous to counter with reciprocal resistance and stigmatiza-
social welfare payments. In both cases the represen- tion, such a response is a likely basis for escalating
tation creates a fundamental distrust of the other, semiotic barriers. The alternative representations of
which not only ossifies the self/other boundary but self and other are threatening, and thus both parties
makes it very difficult for the other to challenge tend toward protective stigmatization of the other,
the distinction: their protestations, no matter how making the alternative representations of self and
sensible, are not given any credence because of the other more threatening, and so the cycle continues.
block, boiling down to a suspicious, “they would
say that, wouldn’t they?” This powerful semantic Nationality and the Representation
block halts further elaboration of the justification of Difference
(Valsiner, 2002), because nothing said is trusted. In order to block out alterity, it is necessary to
Openness to dialogical engagement entails per- create a rigid opposition between self and other.
ceptions of mutual trust and respect. It is difficult Many strategies can be used to achieve this end, but
to be open unto the other if one perceives the other particularly salient are representational resources
to be stigmatizing, distrustful, or dismissing. This is that bring into play ideas of nationhood, belonging,
particularly evident among migrants who feel that and “essential” difference. These representations,
their new community of residence is closed to them; which are fundamental to our culture, are “ready-
this representation in turn, closes them to their new made” templates for stabilizing self/other difference.
community of residence. Consider the following In the following excerpt one can see how an Irish
excerpt from Alike, who came to Ireland from local uses multiple semantic barriers, and especially
Nigeria to seek asylum: the idea of belonging, to block out the egalitarian
point of view that “they’re just like us.”
They think of us as pests, as bodies. That’s what they
think of us. At times when I go to the post office Ireland is mostly just a place for foreigners. Everywhere
to pick up my weekly payment I feel ashamed of you go you see a black person or a colored person
myself because even if they are not looking at me, I or a Chinese or refugee or something. You see them
feel their eyes on me saying, ‘Look at them, they are everywhere you go. Inside in Dunnes, especially up
one of those people who come.’ So we are bodies to in Lidl’s [supermarkets]. I was out there yesterday: it’s
them. That is my belief. In as much as I know that just all them. Too many of them are coming in, so
not all of them think that of us, but we know it is a it’ll be us leaving. And then our country will just be
general thing that they feel. They feel that the asylum all colored, and no more Irish, we’ll all be gone. Too
seekers are no good [ . . . ] that we are bodies who many of them are coming in and they’re all just leaving
have come to use up their tax-payers’ money without them come in. It’s not fair on us. It’s alright to be
contributing anything. saying that they’re just like us, that’s alright, but they
(Alike, 32 years old, Nigerian, 1 year in Ireland) have their own country, they don’t belong here.
(Sinéad, 19 years old, Irish local).
This quotation illustrates how stigmatization and
overgeneralization (“that’s what they think of us”) Despite not relocating herself, the geographic
inhibit dialogue with alternative points of view movement of immigrants into Ireland has caused a
that might lead to a more nuanced conception. change for Sinéad. Using an example of her recent
According to Alike, all Irish people see asylum seek- visits to supermarkets as representative of societal
ers, including her, as “pests” and mere “bodies.” The changes (Bowen, 2008; O’Sullivan-Lago & Abreu,
alternative representation (underlined) of the Irish, 2010), she relays her fears of being outnumbered
that “not all of them think that of us,” makes a brief (and therefore other) within her own country.
appearance, and if elaborated, it might have cre- Again we see that geographic movement can, at a
ated points of commonality, but it is cut short by semantic level, reverse seemingly rigid identity posi-
an overgeneralized feeling (Valsiner, 2002) reflected tions. Sinéad reacts to these changes by creating a

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 701


rigid opposition between “foreigners” and the Irish. Your land carried you, rose you up [ . . . ] You are
Using words and phrases like “everywhere,” “all,” not Greek.’ ‘Yes I am Greek.’ I told him, ‘I have the
“just,” “too many,” and “no more Irish” to create a Greek nationality, but I was born in Colombia and
catastrophic representation of the situation. These I am Colombian until I die.’
extreme case formulations (Pomerantz, 1986) legiti- (Celia, 54 years old, Colombian, 31 years in Greece).
mize claims of complaint, accusation, justification
In this excerpt, the (underlined) alternative rep-
and defense and can also be used in negotiating
resentation is presented at the outset, namely the
claims about identity and category labels (Verkuyten
idea that one can be born in Chile and call one-
& de Wolf, 2002; Figgou & Condor, 2007).
self Greek. Celia is incensed by the idea. Powerful
Toward the end of the quotation, an alternative
semantic barriers are used to block the alternative
representation (underlined) makes an appearance:
representation of either Manuel or Celia as Greek.
“they’re just like us.” As was the case with Alike, if
According to Celia, the self cannot and should not
this representation were expanded, it could lead to
give up the identity given by birth. Self and other
a collapse of the distinction between self and other,
are represented as “essentially” different by birth.
but it is quickly silenced and blocked by the stron-
Celia’s argument is so strong that we can sense a
ger representation of nationalistic belonging. First,
prohibition at work blocking certain thoughts:
the alternative is bracketed: it is presented as some-
claims of being Greek are presented as an unthink-
thing that people are “saying.” Opinion is not to be
able betrayal to one’s nationality. A powerful meta-
taken as fact. Second, the idea that everyone has a
phor of kinship is introduced here in order to seal
country to which they “belong” is used to establish
the argument of national distinctions: the country
a rigid opposition. Within the logic of such “banal
is the mother who carries and raises her children.
nationalism” (Billig, 1995), an individual can only
Celia has Greek citizenship in a legal sense, but this
belong to one country and this belonging cannot
is overshadowed by her representation of nation-
change. Thus, it is argued, even if “they’re just like
hood and belonging.
us” it does not matter because “they don’t belong”
In both excerpts above, there is a representation
in Ireland. Nationhood, in Sinéad’s (and in Celia’s
of nationality at work, which creates a self/other dif-
words below), is discursively represented as a natural
ference that is primary to any legal documentation,
category. National distinctions are talked about as
personal experience, or preference. In both excerpts
essentially autonomous and unproblematic, repro-
we can see a similar representation of nationhood
duced through mundane phrases such as the use of
acting as a semantic barrier inhibiting any dissolu-
“us” and “them” so that the speaker does not feel the
tion of the asserted self/other difference. This type
need to explain (Billig, 1995).
of semantic barrier, what could be called a repre-
sentation of essential differences, has been discussed
Essentially Different by Raudseep and Wagner (in press) in their study
The idea of nationhood and belonging to one’s
of the intergroup tensions between Estonians and
place of birth is not only used by locals to differenti-
Russians. If one considers the way in which the
ate immigrants, but it is also used by immigrants
discourses of genetics, race, and culture are often
to differentiate themselves from locals. Consider
deployed, it seems reasonable to assume that any
the following quotation from Celia, a Colombian
representation which posits an essential or natural
who immigrated to Greece, following her Greek
difference will serve to reinforce self/other distinc-
husband. She relates a conversation she had with a
tions. However, representations of essential differ-
Chilean immigrant in Greece:
ence coexist with representations that all people are
I met this man from Chile and he said, ‘I am Greek “essentially” the same.
but I was born in Chile . . .’ [pause] I told him, ‘You
are either Chilean or Greek: you have to choose. If Counterpoint: Essential Sameness
you like more Greece, you can say you are Greek, In the same way that representations of an
but let me tell you one thing—what’s your name?’ “essential” difference between groups can act as a
‘Manuel.’ ‘Let me tell you one thing, Manuel: the powerful enforcer of difference, it is equally the
person who denies his land denies his mother—so case that representations of “essential” sameness can
why? Chile might have this name of pickpockets, promote identification and movement between self
of this and that, but no, my friend: you have to and other positions. The idea of “essential” sameness
love your land because this is where you were born. and how it is able to overcome the representation of

702 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


“belonging” to a nation is illustrated in the follow- loss of his friendships because of his “difference,” on
ing exchange: the basis of an essential sameness—people are from
the same world; despite religious and cultural dif-
O’Sullivan-Lago (ROS-L): What does that mean to
ferences, everyone still prays to God. The idea that
you? Being Irish?
all humans are essentially the same protects Janári
Aidan: It means fuck all really—let’s be honest. I’m
from being more deeply affected by the stigma he
going to be truthful with you—it means fuck all.
perceives.
Jesus, if I was born in Spain I’d be Spanish, if I was
Both Janári and Aidan invoke the idea that the
born in Italy I’d be Italian, if I was born in America
differences between people are inconsequential
I’d be American, or if I was born in England I’d be
and humans are essentially the same. They present
English. All it is that it kind of gives you a place in
a contrast to the previous excerpts, which showed
the world. It’s that people are all ‘oh I’m from here’
people talking about essential difference. That said,
and ‘oh what are you?’ Well, I’m from Corcaigh—so
however, it does not follow that differentiating is in
what? It’s not where you come from, it’s who you
any way connected with being closed unto alterity,
are—that’s what matters over all.
and “sameness” or identification implies being
(Aidan, 23 years old, Irish local)
open to alterity. In the next section, we see how
Aidan quotes other people as voicing an alterna- immigrants often invoke differentiations (albeit
tive representation (underlined) of nationalistic nonessentializing ones) in order to avoid stigma and
and cultural belonging: “I’m from here” and “what thus remain open unto local communities.
are you?” This representation, however, is blocked
and dismissed by saying, “I’m from Corcaigh—so Deflecting Stigma, Remaining Open
what? It’s not where you come from, it’s who you In our discussion of the resistance people often
are.” Aidan’s basic idea is that nationality is happen- enact when encountering alterity, we pointed out
stance and that people should focus on who people the potential for mutually escalating stigmatizing
are as individuals. This is oppositional to the idea representations, as each side tries to protect them-
of nationality as an essential difference. It is also selves from the views they attribute to the other.
oppositional to his previous idea of the ulterior In this section, we examine the ways in which the
motivation of immigrants for being in Ireland (i.e., stigmatizing views attributed to the other can be
escaping severe crimes). Thus Aidan seems to move blocked, or rather quarantined, so as to prevent
between quite different orientations, unaware of the an escalation. The basic strategy is to isolate the
potential contradictions. stigma either in a minority of the out-group or as an
Asylum seekers in Ireland also use the idea of obvious misperception.
essential sameness to resist the way in which some The following excerpt demonstrates how immi-
Irish locals perceive asylum seekers as different. grants in Greece try to differentiate Greeks who
Consider the following utterance from Janári who are respectful from those who are stigmatizing and
moved to Ireland from Albania: racist. This excerpt is from a conversation with
I have been to friends’ houses, but I can’t bring Maria and Celia from Colombia and Elvira from
them here [to the accommodation center for asylum Santo Domingo:
seekers]. I can’t tell them where I live because I know
Kadianaki (IK): Many people now learn Spanish
I’m going to lose them. So that’s not good, that’s bad.
here in Greece and learn how to dance, how do you
Just I hope people understand that all the people are
see this?
from one world, you know? So, all the people have
Maria: It is very nice!
one God. You might pray like that, I might pray like
Elvira: One feels as if . . . [pause]
that, but all of us pray to God, you know?
Maria: I feel proud that they want to learn the lan-
(Janári, 31 years old, Albanian, 2 years in Ireland)
guage and the culture.
Janári is aware of essentializing representations that Elvira: Because I always, one has felt all this rejection
would posit him as essentially different if he were of our traditions, of the tradition we have and now
identified as an asylum seeker. Despite being famil- that they see it and it is pleasant and they like it and
iar with these representations, he does not agree they say, ‘Look—Jennifer Lopez.’ I remember many
with them. Janári resists the differentiating repre- times they have told me, ‘Oh, shit, look—Beyoncé!
sentation that would mean being ostracized and the Did you see that?’ Well, so, these things they please

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 703


you, because they see you and they compare you becomes neutralized and nonthreatening. This pro-
with somebody, you see? With something, with a cess is evident in the following excerpt, which is a
person who is something, important, they don’t see part of a group discussion with women from a vari-
you as trash, like they have always wanted to see you, ety of African countries. Here, Lysette from Sierra
like for the floor, like very low, like you are nobody. Leone explains during a group discussion:
Like you came to this place and you are an unhappy,
You know in Greece they have mythology, we were
dying from hunger, and you came to eat. Like many
taught a lot in the school in my country, I learnt a
have told me, ‘you came to take our food.’
lot of myths about Greece and I was thinking, how
Maria: What happens is [pause] sorry for interrupt-
can they be like that?! [Everyone laughing] I was
ing you [pause] what happens and I have seen it too
thinking of them as mythical beings, they had the
[unclear] the Greeks, not all of them, [pause] but
twelve Gods, and all this made me see Greeks when
some are racists.
I was there, like that, mythical, it is the same with
Elvira: Not everybody, yes.
those who believe that Africans are cannibals. We
Celia: There are racists everywhere.
learnt about Hercules, about the twelve Gods, about
(Maria, 52 years old, Colombian, 17 years in Greece;
Athena, it seemed like another world to us, you see
Elvira, 52 years old, Santo Dominican, 18 years in
what I mean? That is why I can’t be concerned with
Greece; Celia, 54 years old, Colombian, 31 years in
people who believe that Africans are cannibals.
Greece).
(Lysette, 43 years old, Sierra Leonean, 24 years in Greece)
The fact that some Greek locals learn to speak
Lysette gives voice to the idea that Africans are
Spanish and learn Latin American dancing gives
cannibals. What is interesting is that this alterna-
Maria, Elvira, and Celia confidence that they are
tive representation gains no ground; it is treated as
respected by Greek people. Elvira comments on
ridiculous and is therefore laughed away and poses
how proud she has felt when she was identified with
no threat. Being attributed to a minority of people
Latin American superstars like Jenifer Lopez and
neutralizes this potentially stigmatizing represen-
Beyoncé. In explaining her enthusiasm, she raises
tation. Lysette raises herself above it through her
the alternative representation (underlined) that
construction of it as a phantasmagorical illusion.
the Greeks have “always” seen Latin Americans as
Indeed, the presentation of this particular alterna-
“trash” and as “nobody.” The stigmatizing alterna-
tive seems to reverse the trajectory of the stigma
tive representation gains traction for Maria, and
such as it falls back upon the stupidity of anyone
she expands upon it saying that not all, but some
who held such a view.
Greeks “are racists” and Elvira agrees.
Encountering alterity can be threatening, and
While Alike and Aidan, discussed above, homog-
semantic barriers provide a means to dismiss alter-
enize their respective out-groups and refuse to make
ity and maintain existing ideas about self and
differentiations within the out-group, Maria and
other. However, if discriminating representations
Elvira are able to engage with the idea that there
are elaborated on both sides, then there is likely
is racism within Greece without it becoming over-
to be mutual escalation as the challenge posed by
whelming, which would lead them to take an iden-
the other becomes exacerbated. This is not a neces-
tity position firmly opposed to Greeks. The way in
sary outcome, however, and in the present section
which they achieve this is primarily through differ-
we have shown how semantic barriers can also be
entiating between the Greeks—“not all of them” are
used to silence discrimination, quarantine stigma,
racist. Celia also achieves the same end by declaring
and thus diminish the challenge of alterity. In this
that “there are racists everywhere”—the implication
way semantic barriers can be used to remain open to
being that the women should not feel threatened by
transformation by alterity.
Greeks in general. By constructing racism as par-
ticular to a minority of Greeks on the one hand and
commonplace on the other, these women manage Unplanned Semantic Movements
to maintain a sense of pride and recognition in the Geographic movement is usually intentional and
eyes of the Greeks in general. planned, but semantic movement is often uninten-
An additional means of silencing stigma is to tional and sometimes not even noticed. The adjust-
understand the source of the discrimination, and ment of the representation of self and other to the
to forgive it. By claiming to understand the source changed geographic circumstance is a gradual pro-
of the discrimination, the perceived discrimination cess. Moreover, representations of self and other are

704 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


context-specific, and accordingly, insofar as people the shared “immigrant” identity of self and other.
occupy multiple contexts, they participate in mul- The collapse is uncomfortable and Eoin rebuilds the
tiple representations (Wagner, Duveen, Themel, & differentiation in a new way:
Verma, 1999). Consequently, movements of migra-
So as I said, I know a few of them alright and they’re
tion can lead to semantic reverberations years later,
getting along ok, and there are a few, the ones that
when disjunctions can result in unplanned semantic
come over and try to scam everyone and that just
voyages.
bugs the shit out of me. I don’t know: it’s like why
Consider the following excerpt from Carla, a
come over and rip people off? You’re coming over
Peruvian immigrant in Greece. She is talking about
to have a better life and all you do is rip people off.
the places she has lived in Athens and particularly
But as I said, those that go away and get a job and
why she moved out of an area of predominantly
do everything right, I’ve no problem with. It’s just,
immigrant inhabitants:
you know, the ones that scam off everything and just
IK: How long have you been living here? try and try, you’ll hear them, “Oh my brother went
Carla: It’s about 2 to 3 years, and [pause] I liked it, over and got this, that and the other thing, so I’m
because I wanted my children to learn Greek from going to go over.” Now, fair enough, the Irish do it
Greeks, because I was living in Aharnon [an area near all the time, we go over to America. A friend of mine
the center of Athens] where there are many migrants. went over to America [ . . . ] went over with a sleeping
It is not that I discriminate, everybody, myself I am bag and got over, “right, where am I staying?” [ . . . ]
a immigrant too, but next to me there were some They’re over illegally as well, like, so they just go ship
Albanians, and on the other side some Romanians, to ship, making their money. Now there are people
so my son, what was he going to listen to? It would over here doing the same thing, I’ve no problem with
be Greek that no [pause] so I didn’t want a place that, but if my friend went over to America and said,
like that. “Right, I can get a free house and free this, I can get
(Carla, 40 years old, Peruvian, 10 years in Greece) free that.” There’s no, there’s no, it’s just sickening.
(Eoin, 24 years old, Irish local)
Carla says that she left an area where “there are
many migrants” because she wanted her children to Initially, Eoin discusses some immigrants he knows
grow up among locals. As she speaks she becomes who are “getting on ok” in Ireland, but also points out
aware of a potential contradiction: not only might that there are many who are “scammers” that are “rip-
she be perceived to be discriminating against immi- ping people off.” In short, as discussed in the previous
grants, but she herself is an immigrant. The con- section, he is differentiating the out-group. While he
tradiction is that while she is trying to sustain a is very positively disposed toward immigrants who
difference between herself and immigrants, she still “get a job and do everything right,” he is hostile to
remains an immigrant herself. The distinction she is those who try to gain profit without contributing any-
trying to sustain dissolves—indeed the immigrant thing. He then gives voice to an imagined immigrant
category expands to include “everybody.” Yet, the saying, “Oh, my brother went over [to Ireland] and
dissolution of the difference is only a temporary col- got this, and the other thing, so I’m going to go over.”
lapse (Gillespie, 2007a). Despite reversing self/other This utterance comes close enough to the common
positions, she continues regardless. The difference is collective Irish experience of emigrating to America
reconstructed on the basis of her neighbors being so that the distinction between the Irish and the
“Albanians” and “Romanians” and the fact that she “scamming” immigrants collapses. As if responding to
wanted “something different” for her son. a voice pointing out that this is what the Irish have
Unplanned semantic movements are also evi- done, Eoin accepts, “Now, fair enough, the Irish do it
dent amongst the Irish locals receiving immigrants. all the time,” and recounts the experience of a friend
Ireland has a long history of emigration and thus who went to America and worked there illegally. To
there is a point of historical commonality between maintain some distinction from the other, however,
immigrants and the local Irish. In the following Eoin proceeds to qualify his complaint, restricting
excerpt we see how Eoin, an Irish local, in the pro- his identification to working immigrants and block-
cess of criticizing a subgroup of immigrants comes ing the identification with immigrants who abuse the
to see the Irish as the same. The collapse of the self/ system and take what they can.
other boundary occurs because of the collective Geographic movement leads to semantic move-
Irish history of economic migration to America and ment, both for those who move and for those who

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 705


receive, and often for many years later. The geo- have had uncomfortable future implications for the
graphic movement of immigration creates huge self. For example, if Aidan considered the idea that
semantic reverberations, as all the people affected refugees might have legitimate reasons for seeking
by the movement reposition themselves in relation refuge, it would imply both that his previous claims
to that movement. were wrong and that he would need to change his
behavior toward asylum seekers in the future.
From Geographical Movement to Semiotic mediation is focused upon resolving
Semiotic Regulation practical and semiotic problems within a here-and-
Encountering alterity cannot be reduced to now context (Abbey & Valsiner, 2005) and the
contact in the sense of co-presence in the same process is fundamentally open-ended. Thinkers and
geographical space. For a genuine encounter with speakers can never be fully aware of where the trajec-
alterity to occur, the perspective of the other has to tory of their semiotic regulation will lead (Valsiner,
permeate the self and to some extent, transform the 2001). Equally, in the use of semantic barriers we
self. In the empirical examples above, we explored have seen how both immigrants and locals tackle
how semantic barriers within the self are built and situated questions within an interview context,
used to regulate this encounter, sometimes resisting how they guard themselves from the implications
and sometimes opening up to alterity. In the same of alternative points of view, and how the trajectory
way that living tissue expunges alien objects, seman- of their discourse can lead to unplanned outcomes.
tic barriers operate within the semantic realm to For example, Carla began by differentiating herself
expunge discomforting ideas; just as the body regu- from immigrants, only to acknowledge that she too
lates what enters it, the self regulates what enters the was an immigrant. And Eoin moved from differ-
semiotic realm. entiating immigrants in Ireland from the Irish, but
Semiotic regulation refers to the way in which ended up pointing out similarities.
meanings and actions regulate the thoughts and Research on semiotic regulation has tended to
actions of self and other (Vygotsky & Luria, 1994). focus upon the way in which thoughts and feelings
To regulate these meanings, as we have illustrated, are regulated, promoted, inhibited, or transformed.
the self can construct semantic barriers so that the For example, Josephs and Valsiner (1998) analyzed
content of ideas (the semantics) can block other the way in which people circumvented generalized
ideas, specifically the perspectives of other people beliefs that could not be easily ignored in such a way
or groups. The focus of semantic barriers is not on as to be able to act contrary to those beliefs without
strategies per se, but on the idea complexes, or social challenging the beliefs directly. In the present chap-
representations (Marková, this volume), which have ter we have been analyzing the way in which people
a semantic logic that undermines the perspective of can circumvent the perspective of the other. The
the other—such as beliefs about essential difference appearance of alternatives that need to be dealt with
grounded in blood, genes, or culture. Ideas that by the individuals demonstrates that the perspec-
the other is essentially different or fundamentally tive of the other can be difficult to ignore, especially
untrustworthy provide a basis for expunging their in an interview context. However, using semantic
perspective from the semiotic system of the self. barriers enables tarnishing the other as essentially
Equally, believing that all humans are essentially different or untrustworthy and thus makes the act
the same can potentially give the perspective of the of dismissing their point of view much easier. As
other credibility within the semiotic system of the such, semantic barriers are a form of semiotic cir-
self. cumvention, where the object being circumvented
Semiotic regulation, and its specific form in is an alternative and somewhat discomforting idea
the work of semantic barriers, is forward oriented. or perspective.
Whether the use of signs is internal or external, there A key question is: how do the different perspec-
are always implications for the past, present, and tives of the various stakeholder groups get within
future (Valsiner, 2001). Equally, semantic barriers the self? In each of the excerpts analyzed above,
exist in a temporal realm, and also have implications there is more than one perspective interacting.
for the past and point toward the future. Why do How do these different perspectives get within the
Aidan, Alike, Sinéad, and Celia all work to circum- discourse of one individual? Specifically, how is it
vent the perspective of others? If the perspective of that immigrants are able to see themselves from the
the other were entertained, it is likely that it would perspective of the people they left behind in their

706 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


home country in one moment and in the next from throughout history, and Eoin additionally had the
the perspective of the host community? This is a imagined experience of his friend, to draw upon.
variant of the long-standing problem of internaliza- Using this experience allowed them to semiotically
tion. Namely, it is empirically evident that people’s regulate the alternative representations of migrants
thoughts and discourse navigate alternative points of as essentially different or only migrating to “rip peo-
view, but it remains less clear how these alternative ple off.” Thus we see that people are able to regulate
points of view become internalized by individuals. meanings about the self and self-reflect, not only
Geographic movement may provide one aspect of from social positions actually occupied, but also
an answer to this. from social positions inculcated and imagined, pos-
Geographic movement provides a mechanism sibly with the aid of elaborate symbolic resources—
through which diverse perspectives can infiltrate such as Irish national narratives of migration.
the self. Simply put, before any individual leaves
their country of origin, they are locals. As locals Future Directions
they encounter immigrants as “other” (i.e., the The overall aim of this chapter has been to fol-
immigrants who come to their home country). low the consequences of the geographic movement
Accordingly, immigrants-to-be already have the of immigration into the semantic movements that
perspectives of locals toward both the people who result. We have also shown the ways in which geo-
leave and the people who arrive. Once the immi- graphic movement leads to encounters with alterity,
grants-to-be leave and become immigrants, these which can be threatening because of the alternative
previous perspectives toward others can be reversed representations of self and other that are encoun-
and turned upon the self. Thus, previous experience tered. We have focused on the boundary between
of others as immigrants becomes mapped onto self self and alterity, and tried to analyze the way in
and the immigrants are, to some extent, able to see which the self either tries to expunge alterity or
themselves from the perspective of nonimmigrants. remain open to it. In this final section, we outline
One of the core problems of the development of self, potentially fruitful lines for future research.
according to Mead (1932), is how people can get At a general level, we encourage research to focus
outside of themselves and thus become self-aware. upon movement: geographic movement, semantic
In geographical movement, people are, in a sense, movement, and above all, the relation between the
stepping out of themselves and becoming other geographic and semantic movement. By studying
(Gillespie, 2006), and thus the previous exteriority this relationship, we suggest, researchers can develop
they had in relation to others becomes exteriority a genuinely social and material analysis of semantic
they have in relation to themselves. and psychological processes. Within this orientation
The excerpts analyzed in the present chapter illus- to future research we want to raise four specific lines
trate the role of geographic movement in semiotic of research.
regulation. Helén, for example, first had the expe- First, which representations, or semantic content,
rience of other people leaving her home country enable people to dismiss or silence alterity? We iden-
of Spain, then when she moved to Ireland, she was, tified ideas about nationality and belonging as being
through the words of her mother, able to turn these a basis for postulating a taken-for-granted essential
previous experiences of others toward herself and, difference (Billig, 1995). Are there additional repre-
with some discomfort, see her self as other. Equally, sentational complexes that can be used in this way?
Lysette takes her own experience of misunderstand- Do representations about genetics, mental illness,
ing the Greeks, inhabiting a mythical realm, to terrorism, specific religious or national groups, and
forgive the Greeks who misunderstand her and her so on, reveal similar properties? Can we understand
African heritage. In both of these cases we see how the representations that colonialists used to have in
geographic movement enables a stepping out of the relation to their colonies as serving similar functions
self, and thus self-reflection and self-regulation. (Said, 1978)? In any case, what are the key aspects
But what of the Irish who have not moved geo- of a representation that enable it to be dismissive of
graphically? It is possible, although they have not alterity?
migrated, that geographic movement does still have Second, would the identified semantic barriers
an important role to play, this time at the level of and essentializing representations be evident in face-
collective history. Aidan and Eoin, for example, to-face or mediated contact with alterity? Our anal-
had the imagined migration experience of the Irish ysis has not pertained to any actual contact zones,

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 707


but from intragroup discussions and interviews, elaboration of alternative representations; does it
and we have analyzed how participants engage then follow that blocking the elaboration of alterna-
with the voice of the other, which they them- tives closes down the potential for dialogical trans-
selves have given voice to. We have shown how formation? Or, might the converse be true—that
the voice of the other is silenced, and equally, how the existence of semantic barriers and the resistance
stigmatizing views are blocked, but would either that motivates them is in fact evidence of a tension
of these happen when the self is in actual contact and thus the presence of change?
with the other? There has been a lot of research
on whether contact can overcome intergroup
References
conflict and it would, we suggest, be profitable Abbey, E., & Valsiner, J. (2005). Emergence of meanings
to analyze the interactional processes within such through ambivalence. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung/
contact. Specifically, we ask, are semantic barriers Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 6(1), Art. 23.
and essentializing representations evident in actual Abu-Laban, Y., & Garber, J. A. (2005). The construction of the
geography of immigration as a policy problem: The United
interactions? And perhaps most interestingly, how
States and Canada compared. Urban Affairs Review, 40,
would the other respond to encountering essen- 520–561.
tializing and silencing representations? Bhatia, S., & Ram, A. (2001). Locating the dialogical self in the
Third, why do some people at some points in age of transnational migrations, border crossings and diaspo-
time feel threatened by alterity and feel the need ras. Culture & Psychology, 7, 297–309.
Bhatia, S. (2002). Acculturation, dialogical voices and the construc-
to dismiss it? How does the content of the alter-
tion of the diasporic self. Theory & Psychology, 12, 55–77.
ity interact with their own semantic being to pro- Billig, M. (1995). Banal nationalism. London: Sage Publications.
duce a threat to be resisted? Semantic barriers do Deaux, K. (2006). To be an immigrant. New York: Russel Sage
not cause the silencing of a representation. Rather, Foundation.
they are the tools that are used to do so. In many Dixon, J., & Durrheim, K. (2000). Displacing place-identity: A
discursive approach to locating self and other. British Journal
cases, alternative tools could have been used. Why,
of Social Psychology, 39, 27–44.
for example, does Sinéad draw upon the idea that Ellis, M. (2005). Unsettling immigrant geographies: U.S. immi-
people naturally belong to different countries, while gration and the politics of scale. Tijdschrift voor Economische
Aidan draws upon the idea that belonging is irrel- en Sociale Geografie, 97, 49–58.
evant? And perhaps, even more interestingly, what Espiova, N., & Ray, J. (2009). 700 million worldwide
desire to migrate permanently. http://www.gallup.com/
is that makes the same person shift between his/her
poll/124028/700-Million-Worldwide-Desire-Migrate-Per-
use of semantic barriers blocking or enabling the manently.aspx (accessed February 23, 2010)
same alternative? We saw how Aidan contradicted Figgou, L., & Condor, S. (2007). Categorising category labels in
himself, once arguing about the ulterior motivation interview accounts about the “Muslim minority” in Greece.
of immigrants and then enabling sameness between Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 33, 439–459.
Gillespie, A. (2 003). Supplementarity and surplus: Moving
self and other. Future research can focus on the
between the dimensions of otherness. Culture & Psychology,
social conditions that make alterity threatening and 9, 209–220.
on the ways that individuals psychologically negoti- Gillespie, A. (2005). Malcolm X and his autobiography: Identity
ate and semantically move between these. This takes development and self-narration. Culture & Psychology, 11,
us to questions of motivation, and the overall, often 77–88.
Gillespie, A. (2006). Becoming other: From social interaction to
overgeneralized, feelings that guide people (Valsiner,
self-reflection. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
1998). Gillespie, A. (2006). Games and the development of perspective
Fourth, what are the conditions for more or less taking. Human Development, 49, 87–92.
transformative dialogical engagement? Numerous Gillespie, A. (2007a). Collapsing self/other positions: Identi-
theorists and researchers whose work originates with fication through differentiation. British Journal of Social
Psychology, 46, 579–595.
Mead, Vygotsky, and Piaget have shown how devel-
Gillespie, A. (2007b). Time, self and the other: The striving tour-
opment hinges upon encounters with alterity, and ist in Ladakh, north India. In L. Simao & J. Valsiner (Eds.),
sometimes even conflictual encounters (Psaltis & Otherness in question: Development of the self. Greenwich, CT:
Duveen, 2007). Why then is it that people often resist Information Age Publishing.
alterity? And specifically, what are the conditions Gillespie, A. (2008). Social representations, alternative represen-
tations and semantic barriers. Journal for the Theory of Social
that lead at an individual level to a developmental
Behaviour, 38, 375–391.
encounter and, at a social level, to the production Hall, S. (1987). Minimal selves. In L. Appignanesi (Ed.) Identity:
of more perspective-transcending knowledge? We The real me: Post-modernism and the question of cultural iden-
have shown how semantic barriers can block the tity (pp. 43–149). London: ICA.

708 encounteri ng a lt e r i t y: g e o g r aphi c a n d sem a n tic m ovem en ts


Hermans, H. J. M., & Dimaggio, G. (2007). Self, identity, and O’Sullivan-Lago, R. (2009). The dialogical self in a cultural con-
globalisation in times of uncertainty: A dialogical analysis. tact zone: The impact of cultural continuity. Unpublished
Review of General Psychology, 11, 31–61. doctoral dissertation. Oxford Brookes University, UK.
Hermans, H. J. M. (2001). The dialogical self: Towards a theory O’Sullivan-Lago, R., Abreu, G. d., & Burgess, M. (2008).
of personal and cultural positioning. Culture & Psychology, “I am a human being like you”: An identification strategy
7, 243–281. to maintain continuity in a cultural contact zone. Human
Hobson, P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan. Development, 51, 349–367.
Howarth, C. (2002). Identity in whose eyes? The role of repre- O’Sullivan-Lago, R., & Abreu, G. d. (2009) The dialogical self
sentations in identity construction. Journal for the Theory of in a cultural contact zone: Exploring the perceived “cultural
Social Behaviour, 32, 145–162. correction” function of schooling. Journal of Community &
Hubbard, P. (2005) Accommodating otherness: Anti-asylum Applied Social Psychology (published online).
centre protest and the maintenance of White privilege. O’Sullivan-Lago, R., & Abreu, G. d. (2010). Maintaining con-
Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, 30, tinuity in a cultural contact zone: Identification strategies in
52–65. the dialogical self. Culture & Psychology, 16, 1–20.
Jovchelovitch, S. (2007). Knowledge in context: Representations, Perret-Clermont, A. N. (1980). Social interaction and cognitive
community, and culture. London: Routledge. development in children. London: Academic Press.
Kadianaki, I. (2009). Dramatic life courses: Migrants in the Pomerantz, A. (1986) Extreme case formulations: A way of legiti-
making. In J. Valsiner, P. C. M. Molenaar, M. C. D. P. Lyra, mizing claims. Human Studies, 9, 219–229.
& N. Chaudhary (Eds.), Dynamic process methodology in the Psaltis, C., & Duveen, G. (2007). Conservation and conversa-
social and developmental sciences. New York: Springer. tion types: Forms of recognition and cognitive development.
Kadianaki, I. (2010a). Negotiating immigration through symbolic British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 25, 79–102.
resources: the case of immigrants living in Greece. Unpublished Raudsepp, M., & Wagner, W. (in press). The essentially other:
doctoral dissertation. University of Cambridge, UK. Representational processes that divide groups. In I. Marková
Kadianaki, I. (2010b). Commentary: Making Sense of Immigrant and A. Gillespie (Eds.), Trust and conflict: Representation, cul-
Identity Dialogues. Culture & Psychology, 16, 437–448. ture and dialogue. London: Routledge.
Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. London: Said, E. W. (1978). Orientalism: Western conceptions of the Orient.
Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd. London: Penguin. UNDP (2009). Human Development
Koser, K. & Salt, J. (1998). The geography of highly skilled report 2009. Overcoming barriers: Human mobility and
international migration. International Journal of Population development. New York: United Nations Development
Geography, 3, 285–303. Programme.
Levinas, E. (1991). On thinking-of-the-other: Entre nous. London: UNWTO (2009). UNWTO world tourism barometer (World
The Athlone Press Ltd. Tourism Organization), 7, 1–17.
Luke, J. L. (2004). The foreign-born population in the United Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
States: 2003. Current Population Reports (pp. 20–551). University Press.
Washington: U.S. Census Bureau. Valsiner, J. (2001). Process structure of semiotic mediation in
Mac Éinrí, P. (2006). “Ireland: what models for integration?” In human development. Human Development, 44, 84–97.
B. Fanning Immigration and social change in the Republic of Valsiner, J. (2002). Forms of dialogical relations and semiotic auto-
Ireland. Manchester: Manchester University Press. regulation within the self. Theory & Psychology, 12, 251–265.
Marková, I., & Gillespie, A. (2007). Trust and distrust: Josephs, I., & Valsiner, J. (1998). How does autodialogue work?
Sociocultural perspectives. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Miracles of meaning maintenance and circumvention strate-
Publishing. gies. Social Psychology Quarterly, 61, 68–83.
Martin, J. (2006). Reinterpreting internalization and agency Verkuyten, M. & de Wolf, A. (2002). Being, feeling and doing:
through G. H. Mead’s perspectival realism. Human Discourses and ethnic self-definitions among minority group
Development, 49, 65–86. members. Culture & Psychology, 8, 371–399.
Märtsin, M. (2009). Rupturing otherness: Becoming Estonian in Verkuyten, M. & Steenhuis, A. (2005). Preadolescents’ under-
the context of contemporary Britain. Integrative Psychological standing and reasoning about asylum seeker peers and
and Behavioral Science, 44, 65–81. friendships. Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 26,
Mead, G. H. (1932). The philosophy of the present (Edited by 660–679.
Arthur E. Murphy). La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing Vygotsky, L. S., & Luria, A. (1994). Tool and symbol in child
Company. development. In R. Van der Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The
Moghaddam, F. M. (2002). The individual and society: A cultural Vygotsky reader (pp. 99–174). Oxford: Blackwell.
integration. New York: Worth Publishers. Wagner, W., Duveen, G., Themel, M., & Verma, J. (1999).
Moscovici, S. (1974/2008). Psychoanalysis: Its image and its pub- The modernization of tradition: thinking about madness in
lic. Cambridge, UK: Polity. Patna, India. Culture & Psychology, 5, 413–445.
Mountz, A. (2004). Embodying the nation-state: Canada’s Wertsch, J. V. (1991). Voices of the mind: A sociocultural approach to
response to human smuggling. Political Geography, 23, mediated action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
323–345. Yarbrough, R. (2009). “Becoming Hispanic” in the “New
Onishi, A., & Murphy-Shigematsu, S. (2003). Identity narratives South”: Central American immigrants’ racialization experi-
of Muslim foreign workers in Japan. Journal of Community & ences in Atlanta, GA, USA. GeoJournal (early view published
Applied Social Psychology, 13, 224–239. online).

g i lle spie, ka dia n a ki, o’su lliva n - l ago 709


CHAPTER

Crossing Thresholds: Movement as a


33 Means of Transformation

Zachary Beckstead

Abstract
Any cultural practice in human life is accomplished by some kind of movement within the culturally
organized environment. This includes movement in our everyday environments (e.g., home to school
and work) and travel that extends beyond our home community. While going from our home to the
grocery store entails some form of border crossing (e.g., private < >1 public), long-distance travel brings
us into contact with unfamiliar lands, sights, smells, and people, and involves taking up a social role and
position (e.g., soldier, tourist, immigrant, pilgrim). In an age when human mobility is increasing with an
emphasis on speed and efficiency, pilgrimage remains a popular form of movement where many varieties
of transformation is the goal. Thus, pilgrimage provides a concrete historical and cultural framework for
human travel. Pilgrimages can be viewed socially and structurally (e.g.,Victor Turner’s ideas of communitas
and the debates surrounding this), personally and culturally (through looking at material culture relevant
for the persons on the move), and in terms of tourism as a version of secularized and commercialized
pilgrimage. This paper builds an understanding of pilgrimage from a developmental, cultural, and
psychological framework. Elaborating Turner’s notion of normative communitas, I examine how pilgrims
are guided and constrained toward episodic moments of deep affective value and how these experiences
overgeneralize and feed-forward to the pilgrims’ future encounters with the world.
Keywords: pilgrimage, social guidance, semiotic mediation, externalization and internalization process,
sacred

Our modern world is filled with rapid move- Boundary crossings are commonplace, and
ment and expanding mobility. Distances that successful travel is largely measured by how fast
people travel are increasing, while the time it takes people and information can be transported from
to reach these far-away locations is decreasing. Flow place to place. However, travel has not always
of goods, ideas, and people circulate around the been commonplace and marked by efficiency.
globe in large quantities and at dizzying speeds. It is Indeed, the English word travel is derived from the
little wonder that “travel” seems to have become the French word travail, and so historically travel has
“image of the age” and that: been connected to hardship, effort, and suffering.
Traveling to distant (and even not-so-distant) lands
. . . porous borders, portable allegiances, virtual entailed large time commitments, physical exer-
networks, and elastic identities now more than tion, crossing rigidly protected borders, entangle-
ever evoke the language of mobility, contingency, ments between countries, collectivities and nations,
fluidity, provisionality, and process rather than that of the uncertainty of finding lodging and food, and
stability, permanence and fixity. a host of other dangers that existed in unknown
(Euben, 2006, p. 1) lands and on the paths to these places. Travelers

710
across Europe for centuries encountered rutted soldier performs different actions, wears a different
roads that violently jostled carriages and the seas of uniform, engages socially with others differently
course were a precarious place for anyone. Indeed, than a pilgrim would. However, these social roles
traveling was etymologically related to childbirth as and identities are fluid and can blur together, as the
it suggested labor, toil, and trouble (Oxford English case of the Crusades highlights (see below for the
Dictionary, 2011). tourist becoming a pilgrim). Indeed, these roles sug-
gest but do not determine how a person relates with
Different Forms of Movement the world (or how the world relates to the person).
Since humans emerged on the scene of Earth’s his- Human exploration of unfamiliar lands is
tory, we have been moving, migrating, and spread- ancient and can be found in many varieties and for
ing out over the Earth, leaving behind our genetic various purposes: trade, quests for knowledge, and
and material traces. Like all organisms, human conquest. On the one hand, travel has functioned to
beings have frequently moved to follow food, find open groups and individuals to novelty in the form
shelter, and temporarily escape harsh environmental of goods and ideas (Euben, 2006; Turner & Turner,
conditions. As nomadic or semi-nomadic forms of 1978). Through the work of merchants and traders,
movement gave way to a more sedentary lifestyle, bridges were made between diverse countries and
human beings established more-or-less enduring markets, as each was enriched materially and educa-
centers or locations for their clans, villages, cities, tionally from the other. Trade between countries and
and homes. Large-scale movement of human popu- communities also led to the construction of roads
lations slowed without completely ceasing, as many and technological advancements in how people trav-
diasporas illustrate. Yet large scale movements eled. Extensive Roman roads and Great Silk Roads
of migrations have always coexisted with more are but two examples of how early trade between
small-scale movements of people in their everyday, countries and groups expanded travel for not just
ordinary settings. In addition to the survival func- merchants and traders, but also for common people
tions of movement, human beings move for social in search of the unknown, knowledge, pleasure, or
purposes. That is, we not only leave our homes to their particular deity (Löschburg, 1979). Travel for
fetch water, but to also fetch a spouse. Social and the pursuit of knowledge can be found in The Epic
cultural activities provide the impetus for much of of Gilgamesh (transcribed 1900 BCE) where “the
our movement as we make small journeys to work attainment of wisdom was linked to direct experi-
or school, to visit family and friends and to return ence of the radically unfamiliar” (Euben, 2006, p.
back home. Movement is thus interwoven in all of 20–21). Interestingly, Plato argued for the impor-
our experiences and flavors the texture of our lives as tance of travel and firsthand experience for the
we travel between places in our local settings. benefit of political life and the development of
We can also move far from our local communi- theôros (Euben, 2006, p. 22).
ties through various forms of border-crossing travel. Yet, travel has also been utilized as an act of con-
While going from our home to the grocery store quest or subordination of the other. War has been a
entails some form of border crossing (e.g., private ubiquitous form of movement in which otherness
< > public), long-distance travel brings us into con- is confronted and subjugated. Although conquests
tact with unfamiliar lands, sights, smells and people, and the quest for knowledge and riches can be sepa-
and involves taking up a social role and position (e.g., rated in function, they have often been intertwined.
soldier, tourist, immigrant, pilgrim). With each par- For instance, Alexander the Great’s famous expe-
ticular form of travel, ordinary people take up social ditions included philosophers and early natural-
roles and positions. That is, movement outside of ists such as Aristotle along with soldiers. Scientific
our everyday settings entails that individuals become knowledge expanded along with the reach of the
a soldier, explorer, tourist, pilgrim, business person, Roman Empire. As noted above, the Crusades of
traveler, or anthropologist. From the perspective of the Middle Ages provide a stark example of when
those who encounter travelers, knowing if a person two different forms of travel (war and pilgrimage)
is a tourist or soldier has implications on whether have been blended. The Crusades were principally
or not the person offers money-making opportu- a military expedition, blessed by the Pope, and sec-
nities or potential death. For the person traveling, ondarily a pilgrimage to the Holy Land in which
these social roles call forth different paths of action soldiers were granted indulgences. In spite of the
and ways of relating with the world. Obviously the obvious horrors of war, conflicts offer individuals

beckstea d 711
of poor economic standing the opportunity to visit may elect to move toward the goal as slowly as pos-
new and unfamiliar lands. sible. Pilgrimages provide opportunities for people
In historical terms, traders have been called the then to go “offline” and explore the world at a decel-
first known travelers who “realized that outside erated speed (Slavin, 2003). Moreover, and in con-
their narrow circle there were other people, other trast to a business trip, pilgrimages are self-initiated
goods and even treasures” (Löschburg, 1979, p. 9). journeys to places and objects of exceptional per-
Although certain forms of travel have become more sonal and social value where the form of movement
salient throughout human history (e.g., pilgrimage in is an essential. Hardships and difficulties of travel
the Middle Ages and tourism in this era), the various are not trivial annoyances to be avoided, but rather
forms of travel have been interlinked making a chro- prepare the travelers for some form of personal or
nology of travel difficult, if not impossible. What is social transformation.
important to note is that the experience of traveling is
influenced not only by the reasons for traveling (and The Pilgrimage: Cultural Psychology of
the corresponding social roles), but also the means Spirituality in Movement
(e.g., cultural tools) people use to travel. Natural Pilgrimage is an ancient form of travel and there-
elements, animals, and human beings have each been fore has common-sense as well as academic conno-
used for transporting goods and people, and have tations. That is, we speak colloquially of going on
also constrained and shaped where human beings a pilgrimage to see and stand where John Lennon
can travel and how fast—or in other words, their was killed (Kruse, 2003) as readily as we describe
experience as travelers. Except for certain periods in our visits to Mecca or Jerusalem. Pilgrimages have
history—specifically during the Roman era and the also extended beyond typical religious traditions
construction of their road system (Löschburg, 1979), as people have made pilgrimages to battlefields
travel had been a slow, difficult, and arduous activity. (Gatewood & Cameron, 2004). Nevertheless,
Traveling and crossing boundaries posed many risks, Islam, Hinduism, Buddhism, and Christianity
and travelers encountered discomfort at almost every have long-standing traditions of pilgrimage as part
step. One unknown traveler lamented: of their faith practices. For instance, Hindus travel
to sacred places such as Varanasi where they bathe
Oh, hard is travel and severe,
in the waters of the Ganges River and visit temples
It makes my belly ache.
and shrines. Gesler and Peirce (2000, p. 225) note
Lice bite on my bed of straw.
that the city of Varanasi derives its sacred character
I miss my soft white sheets,
because it is considered by many to be the center
A fool I am to travel,
of the universe and is associated with mythical
Then, and why?, I ask.
events, is linked with the abodes of the gods, and
(cited in Löschburg, 1979, p. 31)
is a microcosm of all other sacred places in India
It is perhaps easy to forget the challenges, uncer- and therefore transcends (for many) all other places.
tainty, and threats facing travelers of the not-too- The deceased (human) are transformed into ances-
distant past. Indeed, this lament generally diverges tral spirits (nonhman) along side the banks of the
from our modern experiences of travel that are Ganges at Varanasi. Additionally, India also is the
marked by comfort, leisure, and speed. birthplace of Buddhism and thus the sites related
In the midst of this period where speed and effi- to the major events of the Buddha’s life are central
ciency of movement are highly valued, travel for the to Buddhist pilgrimage. However, as Buddhism
sake of the experience created by the travel itself— spread and the possibility of adherents visiting
historically known as pilgrimage—remain a popular India decreased, Buddhist practice supported the
and even increasing form of travel. This fact poses a construction of proxy pilgrimage sites. That is, in
paradox. On the one hand, pilgrimage is animated order to offer adherents access to holy sites that
and supported by our modern mobility paradigm were out of their reach, “copies” of many original
and technical advances, and on the other hand, it pilgrimage sites were re-created in the new land. For
offers an alternative to the frenetic pace of life and instance, in Japan, pilgrimages to the Thirty Holy
overarching technological frameworks in which Places of Kannon in the Western Provinces, the
human beings are enmeshed. Although the business Saikoku Pilgrimage at Seigantoji at Nachi on the
traveler tries to arrive at the destination as quickly coast south of Kyoto, and the Eighty-Eight shrines
as possible, the same person going on a pilgrimage on the Island of Shikoku continue to draw many

712 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


pilgrims follow a circular course and circumambu- that are experienced by the person as spiritual or
late a series of temples and shrines and encounter somehow transcendent as they encounter religious
sacred relics along the way (see MacWilliams, 2004; and/or in some way sacred artifacts.
Foard, 1982). What is also of note is that pilgrimages entail
movement directed at sites that are considered by
What is a pilgrimage or what does it communities and individuals to be sacred sites
entail? (Turner and Turner, 1978) that are supported and sanctified by tradition.
Finding a widely accepted definition of pilgrim- These places have been transformed by human and
age can be difficult as scholars and social institu- (asserted) supernatural intervention, and contain a
tions grapple with issues of religion/tourism, length form of charisma and power to the perspective of
of distance and time required to be considered a pil- the pilgrim because of their association with divinity
grimage, and mode of transportation (e.g., whether (i.e., theophany), sacrifice (i.e., battlefields), beauty,
a pilgrimage can be made by vehicle or needs to and/or with some other social virtue (e.g., creativity,
be on foot). Victor Turner described pilgrimage as honor, celebrity). As Victor Turner noted,
mysticism externalized (and mysticism is pilgrimage
self-initiated journeys by individuals and groups to far-
internalized). Foard (1982, p. 232) describes pil-
away places brings people into contact with places and
grimage as a “religious journey, both temporary and
objects that are “intimately associated with the deepest,
long, to a particular site or sites, which are invested
most cherished, axiomatic values of the traveler . . .
with sanctity by tradition.” Similarily, Chélini and
(Turner & Turner, 1978, p. 241)
Branthomme (1982) conceptualize pilgrimages as
marked by three interwoven components: the exis- One characteristic unifying the manifold types of
tence of a sacred place; spatial distance to be covered; travel to distant places is the desire for transforma-
and special ritual acts to be done by the individual tion. People travel and make pilgrimages in order
or group prior to, during, and after the trip, and to effect change and to be moved in profound
while at the sacred site. We can observe that Foard ways. The target of transformation is often the
and Chélini and Branthomme offer a broad defini- self. People make pilgrimages in hopes of forgive-
tion of pilgrimage that situates it as a spiritual or ness (modifying God-individual relationship), for
religious activity with long- and short-term travel. physical healing, to gain merit for the next life,
Both definitions seem to restrict pilgrimage to reli- or for hoped-for-futures (e.g., success in business,
gious travel; however, Foard (1982) observes that health in childbearing). Humility, faith, and char-
historically pilgrimages and what we would now call ity become a key virtues for many pilgrimages as
tourism have been intertwined. individuals travel far from home to powerful places
In order to go beyond emphasizing the struc- and must rely on the kindness of others and as they
tural elements of pilgrimage (i.e., the distance to encounter sacred objects of their faith. Pilgrimages
travel, required ritual attitudes and prescriptions, thus become the catalyst for reorganization of a
etc.), I suggest that the complex phenomenon of person’s value system (Beckstead, 2010; Beckstead,
pilgrimage should be understood along structural in press). The expectation and hope is that the
(form), functional (purpose), and experiential (e.g., return traveler is not the same as when he or she
as a spiritual experience) dimensions. Each type left and that there has been significant change in
of pilgrimage has its own dynamic structure (e.g., the personal realm because of the journey to a
rules, prescriptions, built-up environment, types of sacred or extraordinary and far-away location. The
encouraged movement) and therefore exists only pilgrim should bring back not only stories, photos,
within social and historical contexts. Moreover, souvenirs, and mementos, but also a less tangible
pilgrimage serves institutional and personal goals; yet significant insight or feeling that modifies their
it has been prescribed by religious and social insti- relationship with the world. As I expand below, this
tutions for their own goal orientations (e.g., to pro- transformation of the self and the person–world
mote faith, or to encourage war as in the case of relationship is related to the social suggestions in
the Crusades), and people make pilgrimages out of the immediate material environment. Pilgrims tak-
devotion, curiosity, desire for healing, to increase ing the Camino de Santiago encounter numerous
their status or understanding and for other mutu- signs such as sea shells, smaller shrines, and relics
ally overlapping reasons. Furthermore, pilgrimages that point the way and prepare the pilgrim for their
are marked by episodic moments of deep relevance arrival and transformative experience.

beckstea d 713
Targets of transformation can also at times There also exist “mini-pilgrimages” in the social
include social others and the environment. The secular worlds. Children are sent on field trips to
Crusades had the intention to take back the Holy city halls, temples, shrines, and a host of other
Land and rid it of Muslims. Sax notes how transfor- locations of great social value with the desire and
mation through pilgrimage in Hinduism includes expectation that they will return home affected in
and extends beyond the individual: some way. Self-initiated journeys are likewise made
so that systemic changes occur in intrapersonal
By journeying to these powerful places and
and interpersonal realms, and between the person
performing certain actions there, pilgrims achieve
and their environment. Foard notes the similarity
some kind of transformation, either in themselves
between pilgrimages and shūgaku ryokō, the school
or in their circumstances. Pilgrims may be bodily
trips senior high-school students make in Japan to
transformed or cured of disease, or the deity
the temples, shrines, and national historic sights
itself may be transformed . . . . A pilgrim’s relatives
(Foard, 1982, p. 248):
may be transformed . . . , or his prospects—of
prosperity, fertility, liberation. Pilgrimage places The initiatory overtones of these trips are obvious,
can themselves be created or transformed by the down to their antistructural rambunctiousness. These
actions of pilgrims. students are not, of course, being brought to revere
(Morinis 1984, p. 279) Buddhas, bodhisattvas, and kami, but to make the
Japanese tradition their own.
In all religious faiths, the actions of pilgrims modify
the places visited in terms of the built landscape These ubiquitous “field trips” serve to promote
and for those living at or near the pilgrimage place institutional goals and provide opportunities for
(Eade & Sallnow, 1991). Pilgrims leave behind their children to internalize the social suggestions, or to
“footprints” as they join together in ritual activity, “make the Japanese [or any other] tradition their
inscribe their name at critical places, make cairns own” (Ibid). Through these mini-pilgrimages young
on the side of the road (see Fig. 33.1), and spend people are socialized and affectively guided toward
money contributing to the economic development reconstructing the values and traditions suggested
of the pilgrimage site and surrounding areas. Thus, by the goals-oriented social institutions that orga-
places that pilgrims visit are transformed in both nize and frame these journeys. Of course these
mundane and sacred ways. mini-pilgrimages are not only for children; every age

Figure 33.1 Cairns (indexical signs) constructed at the side of a pilgrimage path to the Peace Pagoda in western Massachusetts.

714 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


group visits museums, battlefields, and other more thinking (Valsiner, 2000, 2007). Subjective culture,
culturally organized secular sites. As with religious Simmel describes, is the process of drawing on
pilgrimages, secular pilgrimages draw on “guides” objective cultural objects and “its measure is the
to assist the individuals on their journeys (Bharati, extent to which the psychic life-processes makes
1963; Foard, 1982). use of those objective goods and accomplishments”
What are the conditions that lead to these (p. 234). Subjective culture and objective culture do
changes? How does the pilgrimage experience not exist independently since subjective culture can
facilitate social and personal development? only be accomplished through the use of objective
culture. Simmel’s insights point to the mutuality
Pilgrimage as Cultivation: The between person and culture, and as Fuhrer (2004,
Lens of Georg Simmel p. 73) argues,
Travel to distant places is intertwined with
. . . the general insight underlining the concept of
change and is a process that fits what Georg Simmel
cultivation as a reciprocal feedback process refers
described as cultivation, an analogy used for the
to Simmel’s conviction of the human being’s
development of natural organisms applied to
unique capacity to complete his/her personality by
human beings. This notion provided the basis for
internalizing influences external to his/her personal
his conceptualization of culture. Cultivation implies
sphere. That is, Simmelian cultivation means the
that something changes from one state to another,
elaborative change of inherent opportunities that the
and more specifically for Simmel, it entails the
developing individual cannot reach out to on his/
unfolding development of a thing beyond its “pre-
her own without socio-cultural ‘structures’—i.e., in
vious developmental possibilities” (Simmel, 1971,
my terms the external mind—external to him or her.
p. 228). Simmel uses the example of a pear tree to
What this also means is that establishing, expressing
illustrate how a gardener only takes the latent “natu-
and transforming a person’s subjective culture—i.e.,
ral” potential of the wild pear tree and “brings it
in my terms internal mind—through external,
to the most complete unfolding of its own nature”
material things is a process that continues throughout
and transforms it into an tree that bears edible fruit
the life-span.
(p. 228). Cultivation then is not only development
of an organism, but development in accordance Person and culture are intertwined and mutually
with inner core or deepest dispositions. Cultivation related, each transforming the other. Pilgrimage is
entails some form of intervention that guides the one exemplar of a cultural practice that is supposed
organism toward its potential, and this applies to lead people toward a “heightened existence” as
to things found in nature and to human beings. people journey to the places imbued with social and
However, in discussing cultivation in the realm of religious relevance.
human beings he makes the critical point that,
Cultural Psychology of Pilgrimage: Build-
. . . culture exists for only if man draws into his
ing a Theoretical Account
development something that is external to him.
Before exploring how pilgrimage experiences
Cultivation is certainly a state of the soul, but
become a source for transformation, let me briefly
one that is reached only by means of the use of
clarify the theoretical framework I am adopting in
purposefully created objects.
this chapter. Contemporary socio-cultural psychol-
(p. 229, emphasis in original)
ogy is filled with theoretical claims—usually based
For Simmel, then, cultivation occurs when on empirical work—that lack clear grounding in the
human beings and institutions draw upon “pur- wider methodology cycle (Branco & Valsiner, 1997).
posefully created objects” for their development or The axioms I take as the basis of this theoretical expo-
to arrive at a “heightened existence” (Simmel, 1971, sition come from basic developmental science and
p. 233). Objective culture refers to things in a state of social psychology of the constructionist kind.
embellishment and growth that guides or points the
psyche to its fulfillment or path to be taken in order The Axiomatic Bases
to achieve an elevated existence. Semiotic devices— Firstly, I take as axiomatic that human develop-
language, rituals, cultural images and artifacts, and ment and meaning-making processes unfold in irre-
practices—can be considered elements of objective versible time (Bergson, 1913, 1944). This notion
culture that are set up to guide human feeling and posits that time flows from an infinite past to an

beckstea d 715
infinite future and no event ever repeats itself; hence, to our neighbor about the weather, play with our
the future is inherently uncertain and unpredictable. children, or visit a museum, and these interactions
This is an inevitable given in all biological systems, lead to reconstruction of new signs intraperson-
or open systems. As defined by von Bertalanffy ally and feed forward into our future encounters
(1968), an open system is characterized by the inter- with the world. Our experience and action can also
actions of its components with the environment leave behind traces and signs in the environment.
and the nonlinearity of those interactions. Open These signs can be apprehended and experienced by
systems—in contrast to closed systems—engage others and can take the form of utterances or per-
in exchange relations with their environment. haps embodied in the built-up environment or
Novelty is only possible in open systems. made available in some other material form. In vari-
Secondly, because of the openness and general ous ways the signs of the world become “translated
unpredictability of the future, human beings and into internal signs (or internalization), and inner
institutions develop signs to overcome this uncer- signs find an expression in shared signs (externali-
tainty and ambivalence to make what is fluid more zation)” (Zitttoun, 2010, p. 174). This translation
stable (Shweder, 1995, pp. 41–42; Josephs, Valsiner, and sign-exchange process can be conceived as a
& Surgan, 1999). Cultural tools like roads and semiotic process and builds on Simmel’s notion of
paths as wells as meanings or signs (e.g., the notion culture-as-cultivation (Fuhrer, 2004).
that “travel is exciting”) promotes movement and Fifthly, human development and semiotic pro-
increases human exploration of unfamiliar realms cesses occur in specific settings, which are orga-
that is necessary in any form of travel. Of course nized to guide and enrich the semiotic processes
paths and roads are also evocative of feelings and (Innis, 2011; Murakami, 2011). These settings
ideas of uncertainty. Thus, signs or meanings mediate can be schools, the workplace, home, church, or
between the past and future and provide stability in a myriad of other places in our everyday world or
an inherently ambiguous world. they can be memorials, temples, shrines, and other
Thirdly, there exist perceptual and cognitive lim- sacred or quasi-sacred settings. Human beings are
its upon relating with environment. We can only wholes (e.g., open systems) and embedded in the
follow the length of the road or path with their environment, and actions only make sense against
visual system up to the horizon, but there is knowl- the wider social milieu. Thus I draw on the socio-
edge that something exists beyond. Like all other genetic viewpoint that considers personalized
organisms, humans can use roads and paths as a way meaning-making activities as unfolding and always
to go from A to B because of the perceptual cues guided by others (Lawrence & Valsiner, 2003).
the path affords and our particular bodily configu- Social institutions guide and constrain human
ration. However, given our species-specific ways of development in socially desired directions by set-
relating to the environment (our umwelt), a path or ting up affective boundaries (i.e., “how one should
road may have a meaning that goes beyond what it feel here”) through the activities and material cul-
affords (i.e., the meaning of movement or transpor- tural objects that make up these settings (González-
tation; see Chang, 2009 for a discussion of umwelt). Ruibal, 2011; Beckstead et al., 2011). Pilgrimage
Paths connect and bridge known and unknown far- sites and the pilgrimage route offer rich settings
away places. Victor Turner (1969/2009) has noted that are organized through discursive and non-
that Ndembu hunters would “blaze a trail” by leav- discursive strategies and elements to immerse and
ing a series of marks on trees in order to find their guide people toward encounters with sacred places
way back home from unknown territory (p. 15). and objects. However, people actively interpret
Indeed, ritual practice bore the meaning of con- (constructively internalize) these social messages
necting the unknown and known realms for the and suggestions and can resist (or ignore), modify,
Ndembu and of bridging the sensorily perceptible and offer alternative interpretations and under-
realm of the living with the invisible realm of the standings. This builds on the notion of inclusive
dead (p. 15). Similarly, pilgrimages offer sensorily separation of human beings and the environment
perceptible markers and ritual practices that not where both are parts of a larger whole (Valsiner,
only connect living and dead/deity, but also orient 2000). Both the external environment and person
people toward their uncertain futures. co-develop in relation to each other.
Fourthly, I draw on the notion that our experi- This chapter, then, offers a cultural psychological
ences within the world leave traces in us. We speak perspective of pilgrimage rooted in semiotics. People

716 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


move through the environment encountering peo- that societies and individual people draw upon to
ple, buildings, and other artifacts that -material and guide them in their development and can be consid-
symbolic traces of human living—of which they ered liminal structures that are between and betwixt
make sense and internalize. Culture is thus the pro- past and future, familiar and unfamiliar, and ordi-
cess that relates people to the world through signs nary and extraordinary. Not surprisingly then, the
or semiotic mediation and guides individuals’ expe- metaphor of paths and concrete paths, roads, and
rience and sense making (Valsiner, 2007). Through routes have been conceived as important in foster-
the construction and use of signs (both intrapsy- ing social and personal development.
chological and in the environment), here-and-now
settings are transformed for human beings. Human Liminality and Communitas: Freedom
relating to the world through culture thus “entails and Constraint
simultaneous closeness to, and distance from, the Understanding how pilgrimages may lead social
actual situation the person is in” (Valsiner, 2007, communities and individuals to a “heightened exis-
p. 72). tence” has largely been predicated on the notions of
liminality and communitas. Victor Turner expanded
Finding the Way along the Arnold Van Gennep’s (1960/2004) work on rites of
Pilgrimage Path passages and his provocative notion of liminality.
The notion of the path provides a rich metaphor Van Gennep posited that any rite of passage (or
of the journey of life—as we move from birth to rite of transition) was marked by three separate
death. The path or road was seen in Japanese society but interrelated phases—separation, liminality, and
as an important element of the development and aggregation. With the first phase, the individual
realization of the self (Tobin, 1992, p. 24). Traveling physically and symbolically is separated from the
away from home and one’s family allowed the per- social community. The liminal or marginal phase
son to gain important experience by meeting social finds the individual or community in an ambiguous
and concrete “others.” The path in many diverse realm or state where previous social conditions
religions indicates the way—providing people with (e.g., status) no longer exist (or are temporarily sus-
potential answers to fundamental questions and pended) and the new social state is not known or
longings. The routes, paths, and trails taken by the is at least uncertain. In the third and final phase,
traveler can be viewed as an exceedingly important the individual or group returns with a new social
aspect of the pilgrimage. Pilgrimage is a form of path status to the stable and mundane life conditions
taking and path making, as pilgrims leave behind where they are expected to reintegrate into the
their traces in the roads they take, objects they leave society and follow the norms of the community
behind, and narratives they share afterward. Path that accompany their new status. In other words,
making then is a semiotic device of culture, and as the individual moves from a stable state to a highly
Christopher Tilley (1994) notes, fluctuating transitional period before physically and
symbolically returning to the social order in a new
. . . a journey along a path can be claimed to be a
social state. Van Gennep developed his framework
paradigmatic cultural act, since it is following in the
while working in “primitive” societies and argued
steps inscribed by others whose steps have worn a
that rites of passage were obligatory.
conduit for movement which becomes the correct or
Victor Turner (1978) took van Gennep’s notion
‘best way to go.’
of liminality and developed its meaning to entail
(p. 31)
more than a transitional period but also a trans-
The path is a cultural transformation of the formative phase. He argued that “liminality is not
natural environment that, in the case of pilgrims, only a transition but also a potentiality, both what is
tourists, and other sojourners, enables them to ‘going to be’ and more importantly also ‘what may
seek answers to fundamental questions (e.g., why be” ’ (Turner & Turner, 1978, p. 3). Separation from
live?) and makes sense out of religious and spiritual one’s society has a liberating effect as one moves
values. In this sense, paths and symbolic movement from the center to the social and spatial periphery.
of pilgrimages provide social guidance through What differentiates the rituals Turner explored from
the traces of others and orient pilgrims toward the that of Van Gennep was that they were marked
future (this point is developed below). Paths are by a high degree of voluntariness. Hence he made
therefore a quintessential aspect of objective culture the distinction between liminal (obligatory) and

beckstea d 717
liminoid (voluntary) phenomena. As religious life interaction, thus allowing individuals to relate to
had become increasingly intertwined with the sec- each other out of a sense of love and fellowship. As
ular and mundane aspects of daily living (even in the pilgrim travels away from their particular com-
monastic life), Turner argued that pilgrimages were munities, they encounter symbolic markers and
prime examples of a liminoid and transformative engage in ritual activities that convey more universal
phenomena since the pilgrim set out voluntarily meaning (e.g., “we are all one”). Status differen-
from their place of residence and the structured tiation is symbolically erased as pilgrims put on
social orders, crossing into new lands and ambig- the similar clothing and unity is amplified because
uous states and statuses. The physical separation of the temporal and spatial distance from everyday
from one’s home community and journey to a new life. These symbolic markers, joint travel, and social
place provided a rich metaphor for transformation distance are then seen as leading to a “community
from one social status to another, and the possible of feeling” that is not bound to blood or particular
becoming realized. Alex Gillespie (2006) notes that locations, but rather toward more abstract notions of
the pilgrim and tourist become “nobody” since they humankind (Turner & Turner, 1978, p. 201).
lose their familiar social positions, roles, history, The pilgrimage path as marginal space played a
and expectations. They are free to play with their significant role in breaking down structure, combin-
identity and how they present themselves since they ing the sacred and profane, and revealing dangers and
move beyond their home community and the social freedom of travel. Pilgrims of all segments of society
expectations (Gillespie, 2006, pp. 62–63). On the shared the same route and interacted together out-
social level, liminality has been associated with anti- side under unusual circumstances. Patterns of typical
structure and seen as an important condition for social interaction could be reconfigured in this con-
fostering group cohesion and communitas. text. Much like birth and death, travel in the form
of pilgrimage could be considered a great equalizer
Examining Social Transformations (Foard, 1982, p. 239). Thus liminality opens up pos-
in Pilgrimage sibilities for challenging and questioning dominant
Pilgrimage as a cultural activity that intervenes structures in one’s social environment.
and guides people toward a “higher existence” Turner’s conceptualization of communitas,
is expressed in Turner’s concept of communitas. marked by freedom, unity, and community, however,
Indebted to Durkheim, Turner (1969) saw pilgrim- has been widely challenged as utopic and essentialist
ages as a process ideally overcoming group division (Eade & Sallnow, 1991). Critiques have pointed out
and leading to social unification. For him, pilgrim- that non-Christian pilgrimages do not fit the model
age leads to a “relatively unindifferentiated com- of communitas and so it has little generalized value
munitas, community or even communion of equal outside of the Christian context. Other pilgrimages
individuals” and echoes Martin Buber’s I–Thou rela- are marked by status distinctions instead of social
tionship when he describes it as a “direct, imme- homogenization and unity (Eade, 1991). Graham
diate and total confrontation of human identities” St. John (2001) articulates a common criticism that
(pp. 96, 132). Pilgrimage is a socially regenerative is leveled at Turner’s notion of communitas when he
ritual because it operates partially outside of social states that within events such as pilgrimages, “perfor-
structure and everyday settings of interaction marked mative homogeneity is delineated at the expense of
by social stratification and obligation. That is, out- open-ended political maneuvering and contestation”
side of everyday social structures and social roles (p. 49). That is, critics argue that instead of faith-
that often shape our human interactions, pilgrim- fully promoting unity or similarity of experience,
age’s liminal phase space allows for fellow pilgrims pilgrimages often contain contested viewpoints and
to (often temporarily) spontaneously and generously meanings, and exist in a highly political zone of
relate to each other as they approach and interact at conflicting interests. Instead of seeing pilgrimage as
the pilgrimage center. Pilgrimage in this light can be a vehicle that transforms difference into similarity,
seen as a ritual activity oriented toward overcoming these scholars emphasize the competing voices,
divisions and cleavages in the social fabric of a group interests, and groups that engage each other.
that inevitably occur in the day-to-day interaction of However, communitas is predominately treated
group members. Leaving behind one’s home com- as an either/or prospect, as if unity and difference
munity, according to Turner, engenders freedom could not coexist synchronously or diachronic-
from social obligations and entrenched patterns of ally. There are examples in the literature for both

718 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


pilgrimages that lead the (temporary) abandonment is a personal and social process and draw on and
of social hierarchies and social cohesion as well as elaborate Turner’s notions of normative communitas
the maintenance and instantiation of social hierar- and the approach of the pilgrim to the holy site.
chies and division between social groups (Coleman,
2002). Moreover, as Coleman (2002) argues, Pilgrimage as an Unfolding Social and
both communitas and contestation should not be Individual Process
seen as antagonistic, but rather as in many ways Pilgrimage is a communal activity in which peo-
complementary and sharing common ground. ple move about and eat together, engage in conversa-
Although scholarship on pilgrimages has gene- tions, and participate in ritual acts of devotion with
rated a plethora of research and writing on Turners’ their fellow believers. Even if pilgrims begin their
model of communitas, focusing on the validity of journey alone, they soon encounter fellow travelers
this model has certain drawbacks. First, communitas and strangers along the path, especially as they draw
is either assumed or negated a priori and thus the near to the pilgrimage center. Pilgrimages are dra-
very mechanisms that are employed to foster cohe- matic rituals that occur in public settings, and pil-
sion and socially sanctioned messages, as well as grims encounter living social others and the traces
the strategies used to challenge and resist them, of those who have passed before (and perhaps passed
are neglected. Second, the emphasis on treatment away). However, these journeys are “individualistic”
of communitas often fails to distinguish between in the sense that they are voluntary and “each is
existential communitas and normative communitas. a personal act, following a personal decision, and
Many accounts of communitas read Turner as resulting in a wide range of personal experience” (B.
eschewing structure and social guidance and there- Lewis, cited in Turner, 1974, p. 175). Pilgrims on
fore fail to keep his distinctions between different the same path and going toward the same destina-
forms of communitas in mind. The latter notion can tion may have similar though not the same goals,
highlight the ways that social control and guidance experiences, and hopes and expectations. Pilgrimage
is part of the pilgrimage process and a constitutive is a general process and undertaking people make
aspect of the pilgrimage experience. As I examine for particular reasons and aims (even if these aims
below, social guidance plays a significant role in are similar and shared with others), and therefore
orienting pilgrims’ sense making and fostering each pilgrim’s journey has a unique developmental
moments of deep affective value. Third, and in a trajectory.
related vein, emphasizing the model of communitas We can also understand the unique and personal
has perhaps obscured Turner’s phenomenological aspects of pilgrimages if we reexamine the notion
analysis of the unfolding process of pilgrimage from that human development and meaning making take
the standpoint of the pilgrim, particularly as they place in irreversible time (Bergson, 1913, 1944;
approach their destination. Nevertheless, critiques Abbey, 2007). Recall that this axiom states that
of the communitas model are indeed valuable in time flows from an infinite past to an infinite future
arguing that pilgrimage experience is interwoven with and no event ever repeats itself; hence, the future is
an intricate and dynamic socio-cultural setting. inherently uncertain and unpredictable. This sug-
gests that the conditions of environments are con-
Cultural Psychological Perspective on stantly changing, requiring organisms to preadapt to
Pilgrimage possible and never given situations (Josephs et al.,
How do abstract social values and messages that 1999). Existential uncertainty requires that human
pilgrims glean become “internalized” and powerfully beings create signs and strategies to anticipate the
felt meanings? In other words, how do pilgrimages tentative futures and regulate their relationship with
lead to a “heightened existence” for the individual the environment (Valsiner, 1998; Shweder, 1995).
pilgrim? I do not mean to assert that pilgrimages Pilgrimages thus allow people to adapt and orient
have only been investigated as a social phenomenon themselves to uncertain futures. Because of this pre-
as opposed to a personal or individual phenomenon. adaptation function and the distancing function
Neither do I wish to explore the personal instead of of leaving one’s everyday environment, pilgrimages
social aspects of pilgrimage. Rather, my intent is to provide individuals (and groups) the critical distance
examine how social and personal worlds constrain from their ordinary life settings and encounters with
each other in the context of pilgrimage. In order socially and personally important artifacts that guide
to accomplish this task, I consider how pilgrimage and suggest how individuals should relate to their

beckstea d 719
environment (e.g., concrete others, deceased loved inevitable or anticipated by Malcom X (and indeed
one’s, institutions, and themselves) and to the devel- it was “shocking” at least for others).
opment of their personal ways of being and value In spite of the different circumstances under
systems (Beckstead, in press). which pilgrims make their journey, there are always
personal reasons and hopes that motivate and frame
How Personal Transformation Works their experience. Of course Malcom X’s experi-
Reorganization and modification of one’s ence demonstrates only one path (trajectory) of
value system through pilgrimage is exemplified in transformation. That is, pilgrimages allow indi-
Malcolm X’s Autobiography (Malcom X, 1966). viduals to come to terms with their illnesses and
The pilgrimage to Mecca is a religious obligation inevitable death, gain strength to deal with and flee
for every orthodox believer and must be made at from abusive relationships (Jansen & Kühl, 2008),
least once, if health and circumstances permit. seek redemption (Murakami, 2011), and decide
Thus, Malcom X undertook this journey, hesitantly, about possible future job opportunities (Hoshino,
and after his sister financed his trip (Malcom X, 2007) among other things. Indeed, as with the
1964/1999, pp. 325–326). After reaching Mecca case of Malcom X, even those with major illnesses
and worshipping with a diverse group of believers, often return with a new perspective on their illness
he writes that: instead of a cure. Asking what the causal agent is
for these transformations would be misleading from
You may be shocked by these words coming from
the theoretical perspective I outlined above. Since
me. But on this pilgrimage, what I have seen and
human beings are open-system and actively con-
experienced has forced me to re-arrange much of my
struct meaning, actions and meanings therefore are
thought-patterns previously held and to toss aside
not caused in a mechanical fashion. In other words,
some of my previous conclusions. . . . During the
pilgrimage experiences orient people toward uncer-
past eleven days here in the Muslim world, I have
tain futures, allow them to anticipate possible fates,
eaten from the same plate, drunk from the same
and reconfigure their relationship with their world.
glass, and slept in the same bed (or on the same
Pilgrimage is rooted personal desires, questions,
rug)—while praying to the same God—with fellow
longings, and needs. However, pilgrimages do not
Muslims, whose eyes were the bluest of blue, whose
occur in a context-free zone, free of constraints
hair was the blondest of blond, and whose skin was
where people can explore, evaluate, and reorga-
the whitest of white. And in the words and actions
nize value and meaning systems, and anticipate the
and in the deeds of the ‘white’ Muslims, I felt the
future. Pilgrimages transpire and unfold in parti-
same sincerity that I had felt among the black African
cular organized settings. The next section examines
Muslims of Nigeria, Sudan, and Ghana.
how pilgrimages—especially paths pilgrims take—
(p. 347)
constrain and enrich the semiotic processes of pil-
Malcolm X’s experience “re-arranged” his value sys- grims and contribute to the transformation and
tem and re-framed how he saw and related with oth- development of the person–world relationship.
ers in the interpersonal domain. The “white” person
no longer meant to him “power” and “corruption” Social Organization and Guidance
after worshipping together and praying to the same of Pilgrims
God, and as those familiar with the life of Malcolm Although freedom from social obligations,
X, his worldview and relating with others shifted roles, and mundane concerns is often a desired and
in dramatic fashion. Malcom X’s transformation realized aspect of pilgrimages, Turner refutes the
of worldviews was based on a communal experi- notion that pilgrimage is a completely open and
ence rooted in rituals (both ordinary and sacred) uninhibited zone for social and personal develop-
and shared by a variety of people of different races. ment. Turner posited that pilgrimages typically
Of course race and racial issues played a major begin as unorganized and relatively unstructured
role in Malcom X’s life prior to his Hajj to Mecca. movement toward a holy site and then “under the
However, for the purpose of this chapter, the point influence of time, the need to mobilize and orga-
I wish to convey is that what often is transformed in nize resources to keep the members of a group
a person’s value system may be a by-product of their alive and thriving, and the necessity of social con-
journey and not what was initially intended: the trol among the members in pursuance of these
“outcome” of Malcom X’s Hajj to Mecca was not and other collective goals, the original existential

720 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


communitas is organized into a perduring social feeling, so that the final ingress to the holiest shrine
system . . . ” (Turner & Turner, 1978, p. 169). of all will be for each pilgrim a momentous mat-
Rules, codes, and norms and material structures ter” (pp. 22–23). What is particularly noteworthy
(e.g., way-stations, hospices, vendors, churches, in this account is: (a) that Turner treats the pil-
etc.) become established for pilgrims at the pilgrim- grimage as an unfolding process across time and
age center. Turner calls this form of pilgrimage nor- space, and (b) he treats “sacredness” (here discussed
mative communitas since it is an attempt by social as “reverent feeling”) as a dynamic phenomenon
institutions to guide pilgrims toward collective that emerges in the subjective realm through the
goals (and to offer safety), and subsequently order pilgrim’s movement and encounters with objects
and organization is introduced to reach this end. in the environment. In some sense, we can observe
For Turner, then, social guidance and control plays constraint systems becoming more operative—
a significant role in the pilgrimages. Social guid- since they are never entirely absent—as the pilgrim
ance comes from collective systems and institutions draws nearer after encountering traces or external
that run pilgrimages, and from other groups—for signs of previous pilgrims (cairns and other inscrip-
instance local parishes and churches (Eade, 1991) tions) and from collective meaning systems (e.g.,
and tourist companies that develop over the course religious artifacts). Pilgrims are thus immersed in
of time to support and assist pilgrims. the pilgrimage field, canalized toward understand-
We can observe how social guidance begins ing and relating with the objects as sacred objects
prior to pilgrims’ physical journeys as they become (instead of ordinary objects). Key to this guidance
oriented to both the everyday and symbolic dimen- is the complex spatiality and material cultural
sions of their journey and surroundings through the objects that constitute the pilgrimage environment
use of symbolic resources. Pilgrims hear and read (Gonzálex-Ruibal, 2011; Beckstead et al., 2011;
accounts of previous pilgrims, look at photographs, Beckstead, in press).
and become more familiar with the settings, local From the perspective of the pilgrim, then, there
customs, and history of where they will be visiting. is movement (physical and in the subjective experi-
Guidebooks, maps, pilgrimage accounts, pilgrimage ence) from the ordinary/everyday environment, to
accounts, and other symbolic resources function in the unfamiliar, and to the sacred realm (see Fig. 33.2).
similar ways: to prepare pilgrims for the everyday This is not to say that the sacred is not to be found
and mundane necessities of life (e.g., where to eat in everyday environments, but rather to argue that
and sleep); orientation toward interacting with the sacred (or extraordinary) is differentiated from
foreign people; history and meanings of the holy the ordinary or mundane in the process of pilgrimage
site; and normative ways of acting at the pilgrimage as the pilgrim moves toward his or her destination
center. On the journey pilgrims encounter a plethora (or destinations as in the case of many forms of pil-
of signs that can offer literal direction (e.g., shells grimage) and as they approach the sacred site. What
found along the Camino to Santiago de Compestela, is cultivated in the pilgrim is a sense of “sacred”—as
letting pilgrims know they are going in the right a more- or less-developed and articulated sign—that
direction), in both the literal and metaphorical sense. modifies how pilgrims relate to the holistic field. As
I noted above, Turner argues this movement toward
Approaching the Goal the sacred site is intended to increase the “load of
Turner focused on the socially regenerative nature reverent feeling” in order to make the final ingress
of pilgrimages, but also examined pilgrimage from a “momentous matter” (Turner & Turner, 1978,
the perspective of the individual pilgrim within the pp. 22–23). Moving from the ordinary to the sacred,
social context. Nowhere is the perspective of the the pilgrim crosses a threshold—a boundary—which
pilgrim more apparent for Turner than in his brief is itself an evocative experience.
discussion of the pilgrim’s approach to the pilgrim- Christopher Tilley makes a similar point regard-
age center or holy site. He noted that as the pilgrim ing how monuments are approached. Referring
draws nearer, he or she is increasingly hemmed in to Günther Schlee’s (1992) research on Kenyan-
by sacred relics and through the vividness and trials Ethiopian camel herders’ journeys to their lineage
of the long journey becomes more vulnerable to the origin sites, Tilley states that “the shortest route to
religious and social messages (Turner & Turner, p. a ritual mountain from any point on the plain is
10). The purpose of the approach, Turner argued, not taken but rather a prescribed walk in which it
was to build up a “considerable load of reverent can be approached and seen from the propitious

beckstea d 721
Figure 33.2 Ascending the hill toward the Peace Pagoda.

direction” (Tilley, 1997, p. 28). Tilley emphasizes one or two minutes I got the feeling of completely
the importance of the way that humans encounter sinking into a different world. The chirping of the
monuments in movement and states, “there is an art cicadas in the trees around me is more intense. I
of moving in the landscape, a right way (socially con- feel as though I was the only one existing in the
strained) to move around in it and approach places world. I feel as though I am at the centre of the
and monuments. Part of the sense of place is the universe.
action of approaching it from the right (socially pre- I have gained the knowledge that ‘I am not liv-
scribed) direction” (Tilley, 1994, p. 28). ing, but rather that I am being allowed to live.’. . . As
Turner might add that social guidance mecha- soon as I was certain that the eighty-eighth temple,
nisms used to draw in and immerse pilgrims in the Okuboji, was getting closer, my eyes overflowed with
field function to constrain the flow of feeling for the tears, and there was nothing I could do to stop them.
pilgrim and prepare them to internalize the more I walked along without thinking, repeating ‘thank
abstract messages that a collective system wants to you, thank you’ over and over, waving clenched fists
emphasize (e.g., sacrifice, love, peace) (Turner & with huge tears running down my cheeks.
Turner, 1978). (Hoshino, 2007, p. 70; emphasis included in original)
The approach of a pilgrim is captured in
Hoshino notes that this pilgrim did not consider
Hoshino’s (2007) account of a pilgrim on the
himself religious or even very spiritual, though
Shikoku pilgrimage route in southern Japan. This
he did feel reverence for Buddha. He had taken
pilgrimage is comprised of 88 temples that are
this journey to cleanse his mind and body from
traditionally associated with Kobo Daishi. Wherever
the impurities of the world (Ibid, p. 68). Yet his
the pilgrims started from, they made a circuit route
experience led to feeling communion and a deep
visiting each temple. Pilgrims pass through the four
intimacy with his immediate surroundings and
provinces of Shikoku (Awa, Tosa, Iyo, and Sanuki)
humanity. There is an almost willful passivity ori-
and travel nearly 1,400 kilometers. The following
entation that evoked or was evoked as the pilgrim
comments were made by a pilgrim as he approached
approached. Indeed, it was even prior to reaching
the final temple:
the final temple that this pilgrim began to expe-
[Early morning arrival at temple] . . . Today I was rience overwhelming (positive) emotions. This
alone, so I could chant slowly and loudly. Within deeply emotional experience had a corresponding

722 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


relation on the meaning system through the insight souvenirs, photos, journals, or some other material
that he was “not living, but rather . . . being allowed artifact that functions as a mnemonic device and is
to live” and so his relationship (at least temporar- suffused with meaning by the person. These objects
ily) with the world (and himself ) had been reor- afford discussion about the pilgrim’s experience
ganized. What is important to emphasize is that with others and with the pilgrim him or herself.
the very abstract notion of “I am not living, but In addition to the relics a pilgrim brings home, his
rather I am being allowed to live” is more than an or her status may be transformed, as is well-known
abstract utterance, but rather is deeply felt. Perhaps in the case of the pilgrimage to Mecca or Hajj. In
this pilgrim has heard the idea of “being allowed to very concrete and symbolic ways, the pilgrimage
live” before, but here it becomes internalized and experience has longevity.
linked with deep affective value. We could inter- Furthermore, pilgrims often are socially guided
pret his approach—his chanting, movement, and to share their experiences, go to church, and par-
prior experiences along the route and at other tem- ticipate more fully in the activities of their religious
ples—as preparing him to be open to and to inter- organization. For instance, pilgrims visiting Lourdes
nalize this message. are encouraged to return to their churches and share
Pilgrims are situated in this spatially and tem- their experiences with each other after making their
porally bounded field with sensuous and symbolic journey. Likewise, I have observed religious services
dimensions that function in the intrapersonal dedicated to the experiences of Mormon pilgrims
realm. Although the pilgrim’s development is inter- returning from their youth-oriented pilgrimage
twined with the here-and-now setting, they also (what is colloquially called trek). Often these include
have the uniquely human capacity to go beyond young people and adults who attended the pilgrim-
the setting to imagine other worlds of “what has age standing before the congregation and talking
been” and “what could be” (Abbey, 2007; Josephs, about the trails, blessings, and lessons learned from
Valsiner, & Surgan, 1999). Pilgrims then can be their experience. I have never heard a “testimony”
closely connected to the environment and at other that has been negative, and many follow a pattern in
times enter into abstract reflection that distances which young people talk about their initial appre-
them from the here-and-now context. These offer hension about being away from family, friends,
two different modes of engagement—one intimate and technology and finding happiness, fellowship,
and connected and the other distanced. In the con- and the “spirit of God.” Many people seem deeply
text of pilgrimage, it is not too difficult to imagine moved in retelling their experiences and insights.
how these processes might be recursively related; We could posit that the intended audience of these
the pilgrim upon entering the grotto where Christ testimonies are twofold; the other members of the
was reportedly interred might reflect on what it congregation and the self (i.e., person sharing their
was like thousands of years ago (distance) and feel testimony). These instances of talking to others are
more connected to the place because of this reflec- also form of an auto-dialogue in which individuals
tion. Abstraction and reflection can either distance can reconstruct and reframe their understandings
one from the field or bring one into more intimate and experiences in the social arena while talking to
connection with it. themselves. Social others encourage—though do
not enforce—this activity, promoting talk as a way
The Continuities of the Path: How of continued internalization/externalization (see
Pilgrimage has Longevity Valsiner, 2007, pp. 112–116) after the pilgrim has
Although social guidance is operative prior to and returned home.
during pilgrimages, it often continues after a pilgrim If we consider pilgrimage as a fluid phenomena
returns home. Pilgrimages encompass more than transpiring in irreversible time, then orientation
the period that the pilgrim is on the path and at the and guidance can be found at two levels: first, pil-
holy site. Each pilgrimage includes prior preparation grims are oriented toward addressing mundane
and individuals share their experiences and insights concerns and relating to the immediate and partic-
with their family and friends. Occasionally pilgrims ular environment; and second, pilgrims search for
are invited to speak to larger groups about their and are guided toward more general meanings and
journey, which then may then resonate with others futures that extend beyond the pilgrimage setting.
listening, even in the distant future (Watson, 2006). Extending and modifying Turner’s notion of nor-
Almost always pilgrims return with mementos, mative communitas, which focuses on the legalistic

beckstea d 723
aspects of pilgrimages, we could postulate that social pilgrim, on the other hand, has struggled and trav-
guidance functions to: eled (and travailed) much to reach their symbolic
destination and have acted out of a deep belief of
1. facilitate the everyday basic needs and the healing or saving powers of the place imbued
concerns of pilgrims, with a sacred presence. Thus the reasons for pilgrim-
2. constrain and orient pilgrims toward noticing ages and tourist travels are often seen as opposed;
the “holy” or otherwise salient features of the the pilgrim is motivated by faith, hope, redemption,
landscape, or any other religious sentiment and a tourist is
3. prepare pilgrims for moments of heightened propelled by hopes of pleasure, self-education, and a
emotional responses and internalizing abstract desire for encounters with exotic cultures.
social values, However, this distinction and dichotomiza-
4. integrate pilgrims’ generalized insights and tion—while offering an economic typology—has
changes upon returning home. been criticized as entirely too reductionistic (Foard,
1982). For instance, pilgrimages also include activi-
Social guidance, therefore, has immediate and ties that would traditionally be labeled tourist acts
more long-term consequences for pilgrims and (e.g., sightseeing, consumerism, pleasure seeking).
guides the semiotic process of pilgrims in the here- Pilgrimages have historically involved actions ori-
and-now environment of the pilgrimage field and ented toward devotion and pleasure. Almost since
orients them toward then-and-there contexts after its inception, the Ise pilgrimage included enter-
their journey is complete. Pilgrimage experiences tainment, the enjoyment of special foods, and
that become internalized then are extended to even trips to pleasure quarters (Foard, 1982, p.
new situations. Yet we still can examine how pil- 238). Discussing Christian pilgrims in the Middle
grims are guided toward “momentous moments” Ages visiting Italy before continuing their journey,
or episodic moments of deep affective value. This Löschburg (1979) notes that:
occurs through the movement of pilgrims from
extraordinary to sacred settings and is related to Agents and ship chandlers kept office in the
the discursive and nondiscursive signs and devices open, offering among other things, excursions
that differentiate the sacred from the ordinary and sightseeing trips of several weeks into the
(Beckstead, 2010). The sacred < > nonsacred (or surrounding countryside. They also contracted longer
ordinary < > extraordinary ordinary) sign complex passages. Contracts were made for the return journey,
(see Josephs et al., 1999 for a discussion of sign com- including berth, two daily meals, fresh drinking
plexes) is a powerful social regulator and facilitator water and the cost of sightseeing, safe-conduct
of personal transformation. and rent of a donkey. Everybody profited from the
pilgrims’ travel, Venice, other ports of call on the
way, the Turks who had to be paid for safe-conduct,
The Secular Transformation:
the authorities in Jerusalem who charged entrance
Pilgrimage and Tourism
fees everywhere . . . It was a well thought-out business
Pilgrimage has typically been conceived as a
not unlike modern tourism. Pilgrimages were
“religious journey” and linked with spiritual goals,
organized just like the packaged tours of our day.
attitudes, and activities. However, different forms
(p. 36)
of travel such as tourism have proliferated and beg
the question of how openly should pilgrimage be Commercial and religious activities have long been
defined and understood. Are pilgrimages only reli- intertwined as economic structures emerge in rela-
gious journeys? How are pilgrimage and tourism tion to spiritual centers (Dahlberg, 1991; Turner
related or distinguished? Often there is a line drawn & Turner, 1978). Elements of pleasure have been
between the tourist and pilgrim that distinguish the associated with pilgrimages, but the reverse is
tourist as a pleasure seeker on a leisure quest and the also true: spiritual experiences also accompany
pilgrim as devotee on a spiritual quest. At first blush, tourism (see Fig. 33.3) (Gatewood & Cameron,
there are certainly differences between the pilgrim 2004; Foard, 1982). Taking time and the con-
and tourist. Many modern representations portray structive nature of meaning making into account,
the tourist as searching for exotic and novel loca- we might recognize that people at various points
tions and sites and constantly with camera ready to may participate in activities and feel like a pil-
pounce on the best photographic opportunity. The grim or tourist. This is not to say that there is no

724 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


(by themselves) as falling within the domain of pil-
grimage. Yet their experiences and meanings con-
structed from these experiences reconfigure their
intentions and create moments of elevated feel-
ing that feed into their relating to the immediate
environment and overgeneralize to texture their
lifeworld. This tourist to pilgrim transformation
can be illustrated in the following account. My
friend and colleague from Turkey recounted her
visit to the House of the Virgin Mary in Ephesus,
Turkey, which I later asked her to write down.
Long having been considered the last residence of
the Virgin Mary in the Christian tradition, this
site is today venerated by Christians and Muslims
alike. Pilgrims have traveled to the Ephesus since
an invalid German nun reported having detailed
visions of a house where the Virgin lived. Years
later a French clergyman searched for the House
of the Virgin Mary and found a house matching
the nun’s description. Pilgrims visit in large part
for the healing waters that are associated with the
spring that runs under the house. Tangible markers
of healing are left behind (e.g., crutches, walkers)
Figure 33.3 Trail leading to Ginkakuji Temple (Kyoto) where
by those who have reportedly been healed by the
people pass by stores before arriving at the Temple.
sacred waters.
My colleague, Cedya, had visited the house
meaningful difference between tourism and pil- when she was younger and wishes she had made
grimage. Certainly the destination and meanings had come true after visiting and taking some of
ascribed to the symbolic settings will necessarily vary the water. She connected her fulfilled wishes to the
for the pilgrim and tourist, but both are searching water and Mary, and had promised to return to pay
to reach a “heightened existence” (Simmel, 1971, p. respect and offer her gratitude. Cedya was raised
233) via spatially distant encounters with meaning- as a Muslim though she did not “wholeheartedly
ful locations. The tourist and pilgrim are both on practice it.” At this point in her life course, she
a quest and the symbolic settings become “divine considered herself to be agnostic. Yet she looked
go-betweens” in the pilgrim’s attempt for salva- forward to returning to fulfill her promise. On the
tion (Mullins, 1974, p. 1) or self-reconstruction. day she visited the House of the Virgin she visited
Pilgrims and tourists travel to effect change and giv- touristic places around Izmir (near Ephesus) with a
ing a fixed boundary between to the two could lead group of friends:
us to overlook the experiences of pilgrims becoming
tourists and tourists becoming pilgrims. Having seen the antique city of Ephesus a few
minutes ago, I was in a mode of a happy and a little
Tourists Becoming Pilgrims bit tired tourist. I was not quite in my religious mode
My preceding argument is that the lines between but I was also excited having come to accomplish
tourism and pilgrimage are not sharply defined, in a promise that I failed to keep for years. Having
part, since historically sightseeing, pleasure seek- come to the House of Virgin Mary was more like
ing, and purchasing of local goods have been inter- accomplishing a dry task for me. (emphasis added)
twined with pilgrimages. Moreover, the trajectory Cedya had considered the House of the Virgin to
can be reversed in that “tourists” have spiritual be similar to other touristic places she had visited
experiences that are more associated with pilgrim- and it is evident that she considered herself a (tired)
ages (Hoshino, 2007). That is to say that tourists tourist and not a pilgrim. At this point her visit had
can become pilgrims even when their initial activ- little spiritual significance for her and instead was
ities and reasons for travel are not understood more of checking something off of a to-do list. This

beckstea d 725
experience of being a tired tourist shifted dramatically even people with me did not notice that I was
as she entered the House of the Virgin: experiencing something special, neither did I tell
them anything about it.
However, as we walked into the garden of the
House, my mind was filled with a sudden peace of Cedya came to the House of the Virgin with similar
mind which was far different than a relaxation that belief and value system (nonreligious, Muslim back-
would come up from an accomplishment of a task. ground) to her friends and, yet with a unique history
Also, I felt like I was surrounded by a very serene and relationship to the place. Her friends attributed
atmosphere. All of my anxieties and psychological her experience to the Jerusalem Syndrome, which
burdens which usually make up my very default Cedya refuted since, as she told them, she kept her
existence were away from me. I remember that experience private. This statement is interesting
I accepted this mode quite naturally, enjoyed the because it demonstrates how the trajectory an indi-
serenity and thought that I could stay there forever. vidual is experiencing can branch off from the joint
I do not quite remember people around me or activity and supposed consensual experience and
anything that impressed me to step into such a state activity of the group. Cedya’s lived experience and
of mind. I rather found myself in such a tranquil meaning construction diverged from her friends’
mode. I felt like I really appreciated the Holiness of and was to a large extent hidden from them.
the place.
(emphasis added) Human Beings: Caught between the
Mundane and the Spiritual
Moving through the entrance triggered a sudden
People make “sacred journeys” thereby crossing
and surprising shift in the feeling-tone of Cedya. As
boundaries from the ordinary to the extraordinary.
I argued above, approaching symbolic places is espe-
Yet utilizing a simple dichotomy of sacred/profane
cially evocative and thresholds are usually marked
would suggest that sacred is what is out there, unfa-
by ornaments that function to guide the person’s
miliar, and wholly other. In this sense, the sacred
affective relating to the field. Not surprisingly Cedya
is something one would not encounter in a local
could not remember what evocated this elevated
environment since our local life settings are familiar.
“state of mind” though for her there was an unmis-
Does this imply that one would have to leave our
takable modification in her affective feeling field.
normal settings to have elevated spiritual feelings?
What was a touristic experience and place became
Of course the sacred/profane structure is unten-
to her marked by the hypergeneralized feeling field
able for many reasons. One weakness is that sacred
(Valsiner, 2007) that was later described in terms of
objects are constantly circulating, especially as pil-
holiness, peace, and serenity. This elevated affective
grims return with holy water and dirt (or sand)
response and meaning then fed-forward and regulated
and other artifacts of devotion. Sacred objects do
how she related with her immediate environment
not simply remain in a single place; rather they
and impacted her future expectations.
circulate and cross boundaries from far away to
I prayed in the church there. I drank the holy water near. Shrines and relics become part of ordinary
and made new wishes. And I said ‘I will come back life settings inside or near the home (Mazumdar &
here and I will visit here as much as I can.’ Of course Mazumdar, 2003). Museums are one secular place
I made wishes that I really would like them to come that operates between the boundary of mundane < >
true; and if they come true I was supposed to visit spiritual that does not always require long-distance
the House. travel and yet affords settings for moments of deep
affective value.
Cedya recalled that her experience at the House of
Pilgrimage and similar travel is purposeful move-
the Virgin was so unexpected because her experi-
ment toward something that is highly valued. Yet
ence there was so incongruent with her earlier
sacred ornaments saturate our settings that people
experiences visiting sites around Izmir. She had not
pass by and typically only catch in their peripheral
gone there expecting to have a moving and spiritual
vision (Valsiner, 2008). Churches, small roadside
experience.
shrines, and other architectural structures can be
Later, I remembered it and told about it to my the focus of movement (e.g., church attendance),
friends a few times. Some friends told me about the but in our everyday routines they are bypassed.
Jerusalem syndrome. I do not feel like my experience What functions do they serve in the intrapersonal
fits into something like Jerusalem syndrome, because domain? What communicative messages do they

726 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


convey? For instance, roadside shrines marking the encounter artifacts of great significance. Grounded in
death of someone are commonplace in the United everyday realities while reaching toward the numi-
States. Why does someone construct this object? nous, pilgrimages join together the elevated and ordi-
What does it communicate? For whom? Under nary, sacred and profane, structure and antistructure.
certain conditions it seems that they can provoke This is apparent as the pilgrim is faced with the mun-
episodic escalation of feeling in spiritual directions. dane aspects of securing lodging, finding places to eat
In other words, material objects in our everyday and relieve themselves, boredom, and fatigue. These
settings can episodically trigger shifts in a person’s everyday concerns and objects occur and exist in
affective field (see Fig. 33.4). This brings to focus close spatial and temporal proximity to the encoun-
that, as González-Ruibal (2011) posits, ters with holy and sacred objects. Additionally, the
telos of any pilgrim is rooted in addressing basic life
There lies the power of things: they keep us
circumstances such as physical pain, spiritual or psy-
remembering us other things, people, places and events
chological suffering, boredom, loss of job and more,
to which they are associated, whether we want it or not.
as well as with a desire to take part in a world set
(p. 154)
apart from the ordinary and initiate some form of
Many of the material artifacts that we encounter in transformation—personal, social, and/or physical.
our everyday life settings can become the catalyst The efficacy of self-transformation, insight, and
for “hyper-abstract and overgeneralized higher-level increased faith for the pilgrim is bound up with
total feelings” (Valsiner, 2007, p. 312). their encounters with material and symbolic objects,
other people, and far-away places, which could be
Conclusion: Guided Exploration called the pilgrimage field. Material cultural artifacts
of Liminal Worlds are crucial components in the pilgrimage experience
Pilgrimage is a transitory phenomenon consti- and sacred viewings of these objects are emotionally
tuted by movements of people from various points of charged. However, for pilgrims these objects do not
departure to sacred centers. Geographic movement stand alone since they are embedded in rich, liminal
has consequences for the movement of meaning and environments. Although the final holy site might be
reverberations in the psyche of the traveler (Gillespie the goal, pilgrims arrive after hardship, encountering
et al., 2011). Any travel in which borders are crossed other significant objects and places, ritual acts, and
has the potential to become a destabilizing experience. conversations with fellow travelers. The holistic
Victor Turner’s notion of liminality emphasized the organization of these settings and the semiotic guid-
possibility of “what might be.” Pilgrims leave their ance of pilgrims crossing the boundary from ordinary
ordinary environments and gain a critical distance to sacred places are crucial conditions to fostering
from their everyday world as they move toward and emotionally salient and transformative experiences.

FIGURE 33.4 Jizo statues found on the


roadside and at large temples and shrines.
They are ubiquitous in Japan, especially
Kyoto.

beckstea d 727
Future Directions to symbolically evocative places. What other
theoretical approaches can be constructed to
1. Understanding pilgrimage as a process that
overcome the main paradigms of communitas and
extends beyond the path and pilgrimage center
contestation, and the tension between universality
opens up possibilities for future study. What are
and particularity reflected in this dichotomy
the developmental implications of pilgrimages
(Coleman, 2002)?
as people face futures that are always under
4. What are the implications of increasing
construction? How do their pilgrimage experiences
commercialization of pilgrimage places? How do
and signs derived from their pilgrimage encounters
sign complexes such as authentic < > unauthentic
feed-forward and continue to reverberate and
inhibit or block the spiritual qualities of
shape their value systems, identities, and self–other
pilgrimage? Are shopping malls a place of modern
understandings? In other words, how do changes
pilgrimage? Should travel for cosmetic surgery
that take place during and in the field of pilgrimage
be considered a form of pilgrimage? How does
generalize and texture the lifeworld of pilgrims
the secular social world borrow from pilgrimage
long after their journey? How do their experiences
traditions?
act in their self and other dialogues, if at all?
This issue tackles the complex interrelationship
of microgenesis and ontogenesis and brings us Note
1. This symbol indicates a boundary that relates at least
back into contact with Karl Buhler’s notion of two concepts that have often been conceptualized as oppo-
abstractive generalization (1990). How could this sites. In this sense, the symbol implies the notion of unified
phenomenon be studied in research on pilgrimage? opposites.
2. As the case of Cedya above suggests, we can
examine travels to pilgrimage places at varying References
levels of organization. That is, we can look at the Abbey, E. (2007). Perpetual uncertainty of cultural life: Becoming
individual or the group (i.e., the immediate group reality. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), Cambridge handbook
of socio-cultural psychology. New York, New York: Cambridge
that the person is journeying with or the more University Press.
abstract community of fellow pilgrims). Eade and Beckstead, Z., Twose, G., Levesque-Gottlieb, E., & Rizzo, J.
Sallnow (1991) and others have argued that the (2011). Collective remembering through the materiality
experience is multivocal in apparent contradiction to and organization of war memorials. Journal of Material
Turner’s notion of communitas. One possible way of Culture, 16(1).
Beckstead, Z. (in press). Value internalization on the move: The
going beyond this false dichotomy would be to the revivification of faith along the pilgrims’ path. In A. Branco
collective or joint experience and meaning making & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Cultural psychology of human values.
and the trajectories of individual meaning making as Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publications.
they converge and diverge in real time. Studying this Beckstead, Z. (2010). Liminality in acculturation and pilgrim-
process suggests that group activities and individual age: When movement becomes meaningful. Culture &
Psychology, 16 (3), 383–393.
meaning making would need to be captured and Beckstead, Z., Cabell, K., & Valsiner, J. (2009). Generalizing
examined in relation to each other. How could through conditional analysis: Systemic causality in the world
Sato’s Trajectory Equifinality Model (Sato et al., of eternal becoming. Humana Mente: Journal of Philosophical
2011) be utilized to accomplish this understanding? Studies, 11, 65–80.
3. Pilgrimages and similar visits to places of Bergson, H. (1913). Time and free will. London: George Allen.
Bergson, H. (1944). Creative evolution. New York: Random
symbolic and social value are quite complex. House, The Modern Library.
Explanatory approaches that grapple with Bertalanffy, L. V. (1968). General system theory: Foundations,
personal and social transformation must move development, applications. New York: Braziller.
beyond reductionistic frameworks that offer Bharati, A. (1963). Pilgrimage in the Indian tradition. History of
deterministic and linear accounts of change. Religious Traditions, 3, 135–167.
Bühler, K. (1990). Theory of language: The representational func-
The notion of catalysts broadly defined as the tion of language. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
study of conditions under which something Cabell, K. R. (2010). Catalysis: Cultural constructions and the
happens—offers a systematic causal framework conditions for change. Journal of Integrated Social Sciences, 2.
that unites the richness of empirical phenomena Retrieved from www.jiss.org/ on October 24, 2010.
with the generalizing value of science (Beckstead, Chang, R. S. (2009). Relating to environments: A new look at
umwelt. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publication, Inc.
Cabell, & Valsiner, 2009; Cabell, 2010; Chélini, J., & Branthomme, H. (1982). Les chemins de Dieu—
Beckstead, 2010). This could help flesh out Historie des pererinages chrétiens des origines a nos jours. Paris:
the possible trajectories of visitors’ experiences Hachette.

728 c rossi ng thre sholds: m ove m e nt as a m ea n s of tra n sform ation


Coleman, S. (2002). Do you believe in pilgrimage: Communities, Moreno-Arcas, M., & Marriot, M. (1981, November). The physics
contestation, and beyond. Anthropological Theory, 2, 355–368. of a South Indian pilgrimage. Paper presented at the 10th
Dahlberg, A. (1991). The body as a principle of holism: Three Annual Conference on South Asia, University of Wisconsin,
pilgrimages to Lourdes. In J. Eade & M. Sallnow (Eds.), Madison.
Contesting the sacred: The anthropology of Christian pilgrimage, Morinis, A. E. (1984). Pilgrimage in the Hindu tradition: A
(pp. 51–76). New York: Routledge. case study of West Bengal. New York, NY: Oxford University
Eade, J. (1991). Order and power at Lourdes: Lay helpers and the Press.
organization of a pilgrimage shrine. In J. Eade & M. Sallnow Mullins, E. (1974). The pilgrimage to Santiago. New York:
(Eds.), Contesting the sacred: The anthropology of Christian Taplinger.
pilgrimage, (pp. 51–76). New York: Routledge. Murakamy, K. (2011). Culture in action: A discursive approach.
Eade J., & Sallnow, M. (1991). Contesting the sacred: The anthro- In J. Valsiner (Ed.) Oxford handbook of culture and psychology.
pology of Christian pilgrimage. New York: Routledge. New York: Oxford University Press.
Euben, R. (2006). Journeys to the other shore: Muslim and western Oxford English dictionary online. Definition of “travel.” Retrieved
travelers in search of knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton from http://www.oed.com/travel.
University Press. Sato, T., Fukuda, M., Hidaka, T., Kido, A., Nishida, M., &
Foard, J. (1982). The boundaries of compassion: Buddhism and Akasaka, M. (2011). The authentic culture of living well:
the national tradition in Japanese pilgrimage. The Journal of Pathways to psychological well-being. In J. Valsiner (Ed.),
Asian Studies, 41(2), 231–251. Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Fuhrer, U. (2004). Cultivating minds: Identity as meaning-making University Press.
practice. London and New York: Routledge. Sax, W. (1990). Village daughter, village goddess: Residence,
Gatewood, J. B. & Cameron, C. M. (2004). Battlefield pilgrims at gender, and politics in a Himalayan pilgrimage. American
Gettysburg Military National Park. Ethnology, 43, 193–216. Ethnologist, 17(3), 491–512.
Gesler, W. M., & Pierce, M., (2000). Hindu Varanasi. Schlee, G., (1992). Ritual topography and ecological use: The
Geographical Review, 90(2), 222–237. Gabbra of the Kenyan/Ethopian borderlands. In D. Parkin
Gillespie, A., Kadianaki, I., & O’Sullivan-Lago, R. (2011). & E. Croll (Eds.), Bush base: Forest farm (pp. 110–128).
Encountering alterity: Geographic and semantic movements. London and New York: Routledge.
In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. Shweder, R. (1995). Cultural psychology: What is it? In
New York: Oxford University Press. N. Goldberger & J. Veroff (Eds.), The culture and psychol-
Gillespie, A. (2006). Becoming other: From social action to self- ogy reader (pp. 41–86). New York and London: New York
reflection. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publication, Inc. University Press.
Gold, A. G. (1988). Fruitful journeys: The ways of Rajasthani Simmel, G. (1971). On individuality and social forms: Selected
pilgrims. Berkeley, CA: University California Press. writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gonzálex-Ruibal, A. (2011). Archeology and the study of mate- Slavin, S. (2003). Walking as spiritual practice: The pilgrimage to
rial culture: Synergies with cultural psychology. In J. Valsiner Santiago de Compostela. Body Society, 9, 1–18.
(Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: St. John, G. (2001). Alternative cultural heterotopia and the
Oxford University Press. liminal body: Beyond Turner and confest. The Australian
Hoshino, E. (2007). Current increase in walking pilgrimages. Journal of Anthropology, 12, 47–66.
In M. Rodriuez del Alisal, P. Ackerman, & D. P. Martinez Tilley, C. Y. (1994). A phenomenology of landscape. Oxford: Berg
(Eds.), Pilgrimages and spiritual quests in Japan (pp. 63–70). Publishers.
New York & Oxford: Routledge. Tobin, J. (1992). Japanese preschools and the pedagogy of
Innis, R. (2011). Meaningful connections: Semiotics, cultural selfhood. In N. R. Rosenberger (Ed.), Japanese sense of self
psychology, and the forms of sense. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), (pp. 21–39). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford Turner, V. (1969/2009). The ritual process: Structure and
University Press. anti-structure. New Brunswick, NJ: Aldine Transaction.
Jansen, W., & Kühl, M. (2008). Shared symbols: Muslims, Turner, V., & Turner, E. (1978). Image and pilgrimage in Christian
Marian pilgrimages and gender. European Journal of Women’s culture. New York: Columbia University Press.
Studies, 15, 295–311. Valsiner, J. (2008). Ornamented worlds and textures of feeling:
Josephs, I., Valsiner, J., & Surgan, S. (1999). The process of The power of abundance. Outlines: Critical Social Studies,
meaning construction. In J. Brandtstatder & R. M. Lerner 10(1), 67–78.
(Eds.), Action and self-development (pp. 257–282). Thousand Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies. New Delhi,
Oaks, CA: Sage. India: Sage.
Kruse, R. (2003). Imagining strawberry fields as a place of Valsiner, J. (2000). Culture and human development. London,
pilgrimage. Area, 35, 154–162. Thousand Oaks, CA, and New Delhi, India: Sage
Lawrence, J. A., & Valsiner, J. (2003). Making personal sense: Publications.
An account of basic internalization and externalization Van Gennep, A. (1960/2004). The rites of passage. London:
processes. Theory & Psychology, 13(6), 723–752. Routledge.
Löschburg, W. (1979). History of travel. German Democratic Watson, J. (2006). Walking pilgrimage as caritas action in the
Republic: Edition Leipzig. world. Journal of Holistic Nursing, 24, 289–296.
MacWilliams, M. (2004). Living icons: “Reizō” myths of the Zitttoun, T. (2010). How does an object become symbolic?
Saikoku Kannon pilgrimage. Monumenta Nipponica, 59(1), Rooting semiotic artifacts in dynamic shared experiences.
35–82. In B. Wagoner (Ed.), Symbolic transformation: The mind in
Malcom, X. (1964/1999). The autobiography of Malcom X: As movement through culture and society (pp. 173–192). London
told to Alex Haley. New York, NY: Ballantine Books. and New York: Routledge.

beckstea d 729
CHAPTER

Never “at-Home”?: Migrants between


34 Societies

Mariann Märtsin and Hala W. Mahmoud

Abstract
This chapter explores the dialectic meaning of “home,” and movement away from home. Movement away
from home—or migration—is characterized as a dynamic, dialectic, and developmental experience. We
emphasize the sense of being at-home and the intertwined sense of identity as interlinked and mutually defining
anchors of our existence that become inevitably shaken and ruptured in the experience of migration. But
when looking at how this rupture is experienced and managed, we highlight the inherently complex and
dialectic nature of migration, instead of seeing it as a unidirectional sequence from rupture to shock, to
coping and finally to new stable being. We discuss the complexities of migration experiences as entailing
dialectics of home and non-home, rupture and continuity, novelty and everydayness, changing and remaining.
The sense of being at-home is simultaneously enabling and constraining, helping us to build self-continuity in a
new environment, yet also holding us back and distancing us from novelty. Similarly, migration is a threat, yet
also a promise; it is a painful, yet possibly exhilarating experience that makes us lose our center of security
and familiarity, yet also opens up opportunities for transformation and reinvention.
Keywords: home, migration, identity, rupture, dialectics, development, ambivalence, repatriation

The phenomenon of home is one of the most Or is it “where the heart is”? And how does migra-
fundamental aspects of being human. Its signifi- tion affect the value and meaning of home in our
cance pervades our everyday language in the form existence?
of metaphors and proverbs we use to communicate Indeed, the difficulty in answering such ques-
feelings of comfort, security, belonging, ease, famil- tions stems from the existential pervasiveness of
iarity, and roots. For example, the proverb “there is the meaning and value of home in our everyday
no place like home” captures the essential value of lives, society, culture, and history (Moore, 2000).
home in our lives. Phrases like “I feel at-home” or Home cannot be defined; it can only be experienced
“make yourself at-home” reflect feelings of famil- and characterized. As such, our objective here is to
iarity, easiness, and comfort. Similarly, we refer to address the above questions by investigating the
home as a place that offers security and protection characteristics of home and how migration affects
(Charleston, 2009), as the well-known English pro- the personal, identity-related, experiential meaning
verb “an Englishman’s home is his castle” and its of home in our lives.
Estonian counterpart “minu kodu on minu kindlus” In this chapter, we adopt a dialectic view of
indicate. But what is home? Is it the house, neigh- home and migration. Migration is seen as a com-
borhood or country where we were born or raised? plex phenomenon that entails dialectics of home
Is it the place where our loved ones live or have and non-home, rupture and continuity, novelty and
lived? Is it a single place or a multitude of localities? everydayness, changing and remaining. We see the

730
sense of being at-home as simultaneously enabling According to Sixsmith (1986), our modes of
and constraining, helping us to build self-continuity experience in relation to and within home yield
in a new environment, yet also holding us back a tripartite division. Firstly, home is a physical
and distancing us from novelty. Similarly, we look location, a dwelling surrounded by physical bounda-
at migration as a painful, yet possibly exhilarating ries, divided into territories and supplied by different
experience that makes us lose our center of secu- services. As a physical structure, home separates the
rity and familiarity, yet also opens up opportunities private space of individuals and their families from
for transformation and reinvention. Although the the public space, functioning therefore as a means
new country of residence is a place full of novelty of regulating privacy (Altman, 1976; Märtsin &
and foreignness, it is also filled with possibilities for Niit, 2005).
re-establishing familiar patterns of everyday life. Secondly, home has a social meaning. It is a
Therefore, the processes of being at home, being milieu of a person’s everyday interactions with
away from home, and being “never at home” are others (Hayward, 1975), a meaningful and emo-
complex, dialectical and ever-changing. This reflects tionally based relationship between people and
the dynamic, relational, mutually defining relation- their environment that becomes embodied and
ship between individuals and their environments, anchored through ordered structures of space, time,
echoed in the majority of chapters in this volume and socio-cultural worlds (Dovey, 1985). As a “node
(see for example Boesch, 2011; Marková, 2011; in networks of social relations” (Easthope, 2004, p.
Rasmussen, 2011; Zittoun, 2011). 137), home is defined by relationships with others
Throughout this chapter, we address issues from this and previous generations (Parkin, 1999),
of being at home, away from home, and never functioning as a bridge between past, present and
at home, in relation to migrants in general. Our future, thus giving the person continuity in time
aim is to unpack some of these complexities and and space (Twigger-Ross & Uzzell, 1996; Manzo,
show that both home and migration are not stable 2005).
or unidirectional phenomena. The movement Finally, home is a personally relevant and sig-
away from home is not necessarily characterized nificant place. It is an extension of the self, which
first by disruption, loss, pain, and later by coping, starts to represent the self through the person’s
reconstruction, and new stability. Instead, we aim investment into the place. It functions as a nucleus
to explore it as being a fundamentally ambiguous through which one defines oneself (Hayward, 1975;
experience of loss in relation to finding, change Proshansky et al., 1983; Sarbin, 1983; Dovey, 1985;
against the backdrop of everydayness, and disrup- Twigger-Ross & Uzzell, 1996; Fried, 2000). In his
tion within continuity. This dialectic approach is description of his home office, Boesch (2007a), for
followed throughout the chapter, where we start example, illustrates how the objects that surround
by characterizing the complex meaning of home in him are laden with personal meaning, evoke per-
our lives, then move on to the rupturing experience sonally significant memories and reflect his identity.
of migration and what it does to our sense of iden- Home has thus something to do with our identity.
tity and sense of being at-home. Next, we explore To be “home” involves knowing where and who you
how migrants attempt to re-establish the sense of are, being oriented in space and inhabiting a secure
being at-home when away from home, and finally, center (Dovey, 1985). This identity-giving quality
we discuss the possibility and impossibility of of home, then, is our focus in this chapter.
feeling at-home again. From this perspective, home is a subjective,
experiential, identity-related phenomenon. Along
Meanings of Home those lines, Manzo (2005) reminds us that places
From the vast research into the meaning and gain their meaning through our lived experiences.
experience of home, several common categories Home, then, may not refer to one physical location
emerge. Home is seen as a “nucleus of culture” (a dwelling, neighborhood, city, or homeland), but
(Boesch, 1991), a field that organizes and provides rather to a bricolage of various experiences within
a reference point for our actions; it is a point of and in relation to a variety of home-places involving
departure and return, a haven where one returns several significant others. This experiential sense of
after a journey or at the end of one’s life (Moore, being at home involves bodily, spatial, kinesthetic,
2000). Through home we perceive and experience sensual, emotional, rational, and interpersonal
the world (Hayward, 1975; Case, 1996). qualities that combine speakable and unspeakable,

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 731
explicit and tacit, reflective and prereflective ways discussion. That is, we are interested in exploring
of experiencing. It is this broad experiential sense of the absence of home—migration—as simultane-
being at-home (Case, 1996) that concerns us in this ously painful and exhilarating, as promising yet
chapter. threatening, as a need and also a possibility for
self-exploration, transformation, and reinvention.
Antinomies of Home
But what does this sense of being at-home entail? Home and Identity
And how do we experience home? As Dovey (1985) The sense of being at-home is intertwined with
correctly argues, the sense of being at-home is only a sense of identity. In conceptualizing identity, we
experienced through dialectics that entail interde- draw on the work of Holland and her colleagues
pendent, mutually defining antinomies in tension (Holland, Lachicotte, Skinner, & Cain, 2001;
(Billig, 1996; Marková, 2003). Home is animated Holland & Lachicotte, 2007), who suggest that:
by the tension between home and journeying, secu-
Identities are social and cultural products through
rity in an insecure world, inside and outside, the
which a person identifies the self-in-activity and
feeling of being at-home as opposed to yearning
learns, through the mediation of cultural resources,
for home, self in relation to other, and private in
to manage and organize himself or herself to act in
relation to public (Dovey, 1985; Manzo, 2005). It
the name of an identity. Identities are personally
involves a powerful combination of the tangible with
significant, actively internalized, self meanings, but
the intangible, concrete and ethereal, physical and
first and foremost [ . . . ] they are formed in relation to
imaginary, inflexible and flexible (Papadopoulos,
collectively produced social identities.
2002). Although home is often represented by com-
(Holland & Lachicotte, 2007, p. 114)
fort, it can also be a place full of obligations (Moore,
2000). It can be a private place free from the gaze Identity is therefore a meaningful way of being
of the other, while being also a place of isolation in the world that has emerged through our con-
for those who cannot leave it (Fried, 2000; Rowles, tinuous and repeated engagement with others in
1983). Home is the primary locus where those dia- various activity contexts (Märtsin, 2010). Our
lectics are experienced, negotiated, and rendered identities are shaped by our interactions with
meaningful (Papadopoulos, 2002). According to others, while our sense of who we are shapes the
Dovey (1985), to experience the meaning of home way we act and interact in the world. Yet, identity
is to experience such dialectics: “There is no sense of is more than just a self-understanding constructed
home unless there is also journeying. [ . . . ] Without through internalization and accommodation of
a public realm there is no privacy. And in a sense, others’ perceptions of us. Instead, as a way of being, it
without homelessness, we would not be concerned also goes beyond those internalized meta-perspectives
with what home means” (p. 48). to include bodily, sensual, reflective/rational and
The experiential, emotional, and dialectic quali- prereflective/affective ways of experiencing who one
ties of home make it at once very flexible yet con- is. Thus, to signify this generalized sense of what
servative (Dovey, 1985), enabling yet constraining it means to be me, we herein use the notion sense
(Boesch, 1991). It is flexible because it is embodied of identity. Importantly, self-continuity and sense
in the patterning of experience, behavior, and emo- of sameness are central to our conceptualization of
tions. However, home is also conservative because identity. Falmagne’s (2004) words capture this idea
the qualities of familiarity, comfort, identity, secu- eloquently: “In some content-related sense I am
rity in their all-pervasiveness become easily taken constructed differently at [ . . . ] different moments.
for granted (Dovey, 1985). As such, the meaning However, I remain myself, not you” (p. 835). Sense
and value of home are awakened in their absence of identity, then, gives us a meaningful sense of
(Dovey, 1985; Case, 1996; Papadopoulos, 2002; who we are, where we come from and where we are
Diriwächter, 2009). As a secure center through heading; it bridges the past through the present
which we become oriented in time and space, to the unknown yet anticipated future. It refers to
absence of home makes us lose this sense of rooted- a sense of seeing oneself as continuous and more
ness (Tuan, 1980; Easthope, 2004; Chow & Healey, or less the same across various, even contradictory
2009) and thus creates a basis for self-exploration. experiences in the world.
Here is where the simultaneous enabling and con- Our sense of identity is partly constructed
straining nature of home becomes crucial for our through our engagement with others in places and

732 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


spaces that we consider to be our home. Through experience “that hurts our expectances, prodding the
our engagement with home-places we feel rooted subject cognitively as well as affectively to feel, think,
in a certain space and time context and we feel we and act” (Simão, 2003, p. 450). Because of the rup-
belong to the groups we engage with in those con- ture, the patterns that sustained life before are no
texts. Sense of identity and sense of being at-home longer functional, and the taken-for-granted is ques-
are mutually defining; we derive our sense of iden- tioned (Stein, 1986; Zittoun, Duveen, Gillespie,
tity, our sense of sameness, continuity, and rooted- Ivinson, & Psaltis, 2003; Zittoun, 2004, 2006). In
ness from the experiences of being at-home, while the words of Josephs (2002): “The formerly taken-
home becomes a significant place precisely because for-granted (and thus backgrounded) life-world
of these meaningful experiences. Put differently, suddenly becomes foregrounded and ‘visible’ ”
we are who we are because we come from a certain (p. 171). In discussing first experiences in a new
locale in space and time, and we call this locale our context, we thus move away from the concept of
home because we derive our sense of identity from culture shock that has been widely employed to
the experiences within and in relation to it. describe the disorienting and disturbing nature of
As already indicated, this sense of identity is not meeting a new context (Ward, Bochner, & Furnham,
necessarily a reflective and conscious self-definition, 2001), and toward the dialectic and multifaceted
but rather a tacit sense of knowing how things experience of breaking up the taken-for-granted,
are and what to expect. Familiarity and taken-for- living in between cultures, and renegotiating
grantedness are the primary features of this way of identities (Bhatia & Ram, 2001b).
being (Heller, 1995), which involves sensual ele- By bringing to awareness the taken-for-granted,
ments such as familiar smells, sounds, colors, shapes the rupture of migration concurrently provokes
and language, as well as everyday routines, such as questions about one’s sense of identity as it was
eating certain foods at certain times or sleeping in intertwined with the sense of being at-home.
our own bed with our own pillow and duvet (Case, Experiencing a rupture in one’s sense of identity
1996). It also involves our embeddedness in social resulting from migration is an all-encompassing
relations and our belonging to certain groups. As feeling that one’s normal way of being no longer
Shotter and Lannamann (2002) suggest: “Our being “flows” in the new context. That is, although migra-
and belonging arise from the condition of being tion introduces a disruption in physical environ-
embedded in an ongoing flow of spontaneous, ment, self-understandings, values, practices, social
reciprocally responsive, living activity, occurring relations, etc., all these elements as an intertwined
between us and the other in the group” (p. 597). whole become broken as we encounter the strange-
Through our belonging to different groups and ness of the new physical and social environment.
engagement with different activities we also inter- Meintel (1973) correctly argues that feelings of
nalize values, cultural practices, and roles related alienation and isolation resulting from cultural
to these. All these elements come together to form strangeness, unfamiliarity, and unpredictability may
an intertwined and not easily disentangled whole well start to diminish once the migrant becomes
of being in space and time, rooted in a subjective familiar with the new environment. In this sense,
conception of “home,” and including idiosyncratic such culture shock represents the less significant and
ethnic, national, religious, and other self-defini- less enduring aspects of being a stranger, while the
tions. Therefore, our sense of identity in relation to more significant and serious shocks resulting from
home forms a part of the holistic, taken-for-granted being a stranger are indeed those of self-discovery,
existence, guiding our functioning in the world in a where the migrant’s previously established values
powerful, yet often unreflective manner. and beliefs about the world and oneself are chal-
lenged, and by implication, the social world that
Migration as Rupture endorsed them. Those sudden, unforeseen revela-
Migration is a rupturing experience that intro- tions about the world they had taken for granted
duces a break into a person’s normal and taken- are much more significant and of a longer lasting
for-granted flow of being (Becker, 1997; Zittoun, effect than the shocks of the new environment per
2007a, 2007b), and produces a diversity of ever- se (Meintel, 1973). Zittoun (2007a) similarly states:
changing outcomes ranging from pain and trauma “The first criteria to consider an event as a signifi-
to feelings of exhilaration, excitement, relief and cant rupture, is that it is subjectively, consciously or
self-discovery. Migration could be a disquieting unconsciously, perceived by a person as questioning

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 733
her sense of self and sense of continuity” (p. 190). and more recently Boesch (1991) suggest, humans
Importantly however, a rupture in one’s sense are guided by their goals and imagined futures and
of identity in relation to home may take various therefore questions about anticipations and motiva-
forms. tions largely shape the way in which migration as a
To begin with, rupture to one’s sense of iden- rupture is experienced.
tity in relation to home may have taken place even Boesch’s (1991, 2007b) work is important to the
prior to migration. As Graham & Khosravi (1997) current discussion also in another way. He suggests
note, most of the research on home has been written that all human functioning and meaning making
by those who left it, but it should not be assumed is characterized by the tension between Heimweh
that those who have not moved are in a secure state, and Fernweh, between known home (or more gen-
feeling “at-home.” Research on political refugees, for erally “I”) and unknown faraway (more generally
example, shows that they leave their countries pre- “non-I”). That is, while being within the familiarity
cisely because they do not “feel at-home.” Zarzosa of home, humans long for the strange, foreign,
(1998), a Chilean refugee describing her experi- and unknown. They are attracted by the promise
ences of the 1973 coup, explains that: “One can of the other that is undiscovered. Yet moving away
become an exile while remaining on one’s soil [ . . . ] from home makes them Unheimlich—unhomely or
Chile was my country of origin, but ceased to be my homesick; it makes them long for their intimate,
home” (pp. 189–190). This experience of “internal hidden, secure, and safe haven in the world. Home
exile” (Abu-Lughod, 1988) while remaining in one’s is intimate and safe, but also known and unexciting.
soil can be caused by different reasons, such as a Faraway can be a promise, but also a threat.
radical political change, which ideologically divides Understanding this double-bind, this tension
people of the same country, or belonging to an between “home” and away and the dialectics within
ethnic population that is not officially recognized by both realms is, in our view, crucial for understanding
the country, or feeling and acting differently from the experience of migration. These contradictory
what is socially accepted. Lawrence, Benedikt, and feelings are discussed next.
Valsiner (1992), for example, discuss this latter kind
of “homeless in the mind” in the case of a young Encountering the New Physical
woman living in and eventually breaking free from Environment
an ultra-orthodox Jewish community. Encountering the foreign environment may not
Similarly, people may feel uncomfortably initially result in alienation or nostalgia but may
restricted in their home community because of their indeed involve a great deal of exhilaration (Meintel,
inability to fulfill their life plans and aspirations. 1973). This is because humans are not only oriented
For example, Märtsin’s (2009a) semi-longitudinal toward what is familiar, but are also attracted to what
multiple-case study, which explored how young escapes immediate understanding (Van Leeuwen,
Estonians studying in the United Kingdom made 2008; Boesch, 1991). The experience of Elina1, a
sense of themselves in relation to their experiences young Estonian woman arriving to London, illus-
in a new environment, touched on this issue. Many trates this excitement about the new and unknown
of the participants indicated that they left Estonia (Märtsin, 2009a, pp. 140):
because it was too small and offered too few oppor-
Elina2: For example, when the metro train pulled
tunities for them and for their anticipated future
into the station, my stomach was turning. It was
ways of being. For these “internal exiles,” then,
something new for me. Wow! Everything is so
leaving home may be in agreement with their life
interesting! Yes. Like a child. Double-decker buses . . .
projects (Giddens, 1994). In fact, and especially in
the case of temporary migrants such as international The initial excitement and fascination may be
students, leaving home may actually be perceived as replaced or complemented by other feelings, such
an attempt at actualizing one’s life project by seeking as nostalgia and homesickness, caused by the loss of
educational, career, or financial opportunities subtle elements of one’s past life—familiar smells,
believed to enrich one’s life. In this sense, there is sounds, tastes, and bodily experiences of being in
a degree of choice in leaving home, which is based certain spaces and places. In many cases, the migrant
on feelings of discomfort or restriction, whether or experiences both ends of the continuum, or can go
not the person in question intends on returning through various stages throughout their time in the
home in the future. As Bühler and Massarik (1968) new environment. Van Leeuwen (2008) argues that

734 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


cultural strangeness or contact with a new culture rupture may arise from an experience of personal
can give rise to “affective ambivalence”, i.e., coexis- isolation, where the person feels that the environ-
tence of positive and negative feelings toward home ment is unfamiliar and instead of recognizing the
and non-home. On the one hand, cultural strange- person, it rejects and excludes them (Van Leeuwen,
ness can cause “existential unease” simply because it 2008). This seems to be the case with Säde, a young
puts our taken-for-granted common sense into ques- Estonian woman studying in England (Märtsin,
tion. On the other hand, contact with a new culture 2009a, pp. 197):
may give rise to positive feelings of wonderment
Säde: It truly bothers me how they ignore these
and fascination (Van Leeuwen, 2008).
dots [in my name] [ . . . ] I can’t stand it. I’ve been
The example of Elina above illustrates a positive
polite and everything, calmly reminded them, but I
rupture in encountering the new physical environ-
constantly get smacked in the face, up to the point
ment. But in contrast, the new physical environ-
that I’m already worried that they will not use them
ment may introduce an uneasy rupture. Consider
on my diploma [ . . . ] They know how things should
the experience of Zein, a Sudanese refugee in Cairo,
be. It’s like some sort of disturbing privilege that you
who was interviewed as part of a qualitative study
are demanding your stupid dots [ . . . ] Perhaps I’m so
investigating the culture, identity, and coping path-
touchy about this because my name has always been
ways of Sudanese refugees in Cairo (Mahmoud,
so central for me.
2010)3:
Säde’s feeling of “getting smacked in the face”
Hala: What do you miss from life [in Sudan]?
emerges out of her perception of others’ perception
Zein: By God, a lot [ . . . ] the nature, the rain, the
of her. She thinks that her university considers her
fields, the houses [ . . . ] I mean, we had big houses
needs to be trivial, unimportant, sees them as “dis-
[in Sudan], all on the ground floor [ . . . ] here [in
turbing privilege.” This feeling of not getting recog-
Cairo], sometimes the weather is very cold for us
nition and acknowledgement about something that
[ . . . ]. Sudanese meals are also different from what’s
is important for her, and instead being considered as
available here [in Cairo].
an alien because of her strange needs, thus heightens
Many other Sudanese refugees in Cairo men- Säde’s sense of being disconnected with her old way
tion that they miss the “earth” or “soil” of Sudan. of being. In contrast, there are many examples of
This represents a subtle type of loss that neverthe- migrants who were never recognized in their home-
less highlights the pervasive and general loss of the lands, but become appreciated and acknowledged
sense of being at-home and its associated sense of in the new environment. This is the case for poets
identity. and artists who realize their potential away from
their homeland.
Encountering New and Old Social Others Encounters with new social others, identify-
Moving away from home entails both coming ing and being identified by them is central in the
into contact with new social others, as well as a process of renegotiating one’s sense of identity, and
qualitatively renewed kind of contact with old re-establishing familiarity after migration. Migrants
social others in the homeland. As the work of Mead strive to understand who these new social others
(1934) and its recent development (Gillespie, are (e.g., What are their values, their customs?)
2007), as well as growing research into migrant and they also get a sense of who they are through
identity suggests (inter alia Aveling & Gillespie, these encounters (e.g., How do these people see
2008; Bhatia & Ram, 2001a; Hermans, 2001; me? Who do they think I am?). At the same time,
Kadianaki, 2009; O’Sullivan-Lago & de Abreu, their sense of identity is still very much tied to the
2010), our identities are constructed and constantly social environment of their homeland. Visits to the
renegotiated through encounters with others. Thus, homeland or visitors from the homeland and even
encountering new and old social others may intro- indirect ways of learning about their home commu-
duce additional threats and ruptures to a migrant’s nities (e.g., media, correspondence) can contribute
sense of identity. Coming into contact with new to a changed way that migrants both perceive and
social others may shake our preestablished sense of are perceived by their home community. Consider
identity because we no longer get the recognition for example the experience of Andres, a young man
and acknowledgement we used to get from others studying in England. When talking about his visits
in the homeland (Van Leeuwen, 2008). Therefore, to Estonia, Andres says (Märtsin, 2009a, pp. 131):

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 735
Andres: Some sort of freedom that you have here in are experiencing the flow of others’ callings, which
London. You are over 30, but you don’t feel this total are unfamiliar and to which we do not yet have
social pressure that we have in Estonia. In that age spontaneous responses (Shotter & Lannamann,
you have to have achieved something and if you are 2002). That is, we are engaged with others in
just [ . . . ] doing your research or something, you are activity contexts that do not seem familiar and
just a nonsense bloke. You are just wasting your time, mundane and in which we do not necessarily know
prolonging your childhood. This is precisely what yet how to respond and interact. The otherness is
I’ve been told in Estonia. That [pause] in Estonia, if thus very actively present, demanding a response
you are away for a bit longer, you immediately feel from us. Nonetheless, it is not part of our being
[pause]. Others who have returned from abroad have and as unknown and unfamiliar, remains absent.
said this too. Someone I know who lives in Paris, Thus the sense of being in between, in transition,
says that he comes to Estonia, is there for a week and not anymore there, but also not yet here emerges
already feels that he should get a mortgage and buy a (Bhatia & Ram, 2001b), and is characterized by
flat. This is the way you do things. feelings of liminality, ambiguity, and ambivalence
(Turner, 1967; Harrell-Bond & Voutira, 1992;
Unlike Säde’s example above, Andres thinks that Becker, 1997; Coker, 2004).
others at home do not acknowledge his chosen Turner (1967), in his classic work on liminal-
way of being. Instead, he is considered as a “non- ity, considers society to be a “structure of positions.”
sense bloke,” who is “prolonging his childhood.” Interstructural human beings are those “transitional
Not being recognized by his old home commu- beings” or “liminal personae” who are at once “no
nity makes him turn his gaze toward other groups, longer classified and not yet classified” (p. 96). They
toward other “in-betweeners” who seem more simi- are neither one nor another; they are betwixt and
lar and therefore more attractive to Andres. between all the recognized positions in space and
Thus, both home and resident communities, as time. In other words, they are “at a threshold outside
well as other groups beyond these, are crucial in the the boundaries of society” (Becker, 1997, p. 119).
redefinition of one’s sense of identity in relation From this perspective, migrants can be considered
to home. Because of the rupture of migration, the transitional, interstructural, or liminal beings who are
migrant’s position in relation to both home commu- at once no longer at-home, neither in relation to their
nity and resident community becomes questioned homelands nor in relation to their new habitat.
and needs to be reconstructed from a position of The inherent ambiguity in any liminal posi-
being in between. tion is associated with feelings of ambivalence. As
Valsiner (2006) contends, ambiguity of existence
Liminal Space between Home and leads to ambivalence in human feeling, acting, and
Non-Home thinking. Although ambiguity and ambivalence
Thus far, the discussion has focused on the mul- are present in every human psychological act (see
tifaceted, complex repercussions of moving away Abbey & Valsiner, 2005; Valsiner, 2006; Valsiner &
from the homeland. A central thread of argument Abbey, 2006), they become exaggerated in the case
that appears both implicitly and explicitly is that of migrants. Therefore, besides the intrinsic ambi-
the experience of moving away from home acti- guity in any liminal position, there is also a marked
vates the dialectic of home and non-home, as these degree of ambivalence—i.e., stressful uncertainty,
become simultaneously present and absent in our being simultaneously drawn in opposite directions,
way of being in the new context. On the one hand, and having mixed feelings toward people, objects,
we are physically away from home, cut out from values, meanings, and so forth. Being a stranger in
those routine and familiar callings from others a foreign culture, where common sense no longer
that we respond to spontaneously (Shotter, 2003, serves its function (Leeuwen, 2008) increases ambi-
2008). Yet through that absence, by realizing what guity and ambivalence. Not having a clear social
it meant to be at-home, the sense of home becomes position can make different possibilities equally
very much present in the new context. Hence, it desirable, repulsive, or confusing for the person
becomes a powerful reference point, a lens through (Mahmoud, 2010).
which we evaluate the new encounters with This state of being in between is vivid in the
others and otherness. On the other hand, in the new case of Ruth, a young Estonian woman studying in
and physically present socio-cultural context we England (Märtsin, 2009a, 2009b). Talking about

736 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


the possibilities of living in England after having Home away from Home
stayed several months in Estonia, she says (Märtsin, Thus far we have been concerned with migra-
2009b, pp. 207): tion as change. Our focus has been on the novelty
of the physical and social environment that dis-
Ruth: I don’t know, my mood changes all the time.
rupts the taken-for-granted flow of everydayness.
[ . . . ] I started to think with horror that what if I’ll
However, everyday life continues also beyond the
come to the point when I actually don’t need to
rupture of migration. That is, migrants’ lives are not
return to England anymore [ . . . ] To be honest I
lived only in the registers of catastrophe, drama,
don’t want to think about it now. At the same time I
and change, but also in mundane and ordinary
really liked it in Estonia in the summer. I don’t know,
registers. Furthermore, novelty changes too; with
probably I’ll have to stay being amphibious.
time and through repeated encounters, the unor-
Importantly, the ambivalence between home and dinary becomes ordinary. Thus migration is not
non-home can extend beyond comparisons of the only about changing, but also about remaining and
new environment with the old one. Instead, ambiv- maintaining. In other words, because our sense of
alence can well exist within one’s relation to home being at-home and its associated sense of identity
itself, where home becomes the source of extreme are dependent upon the qualities of familiarity,
ambivalence. For example, for many Sudanese refu- comfort, and continuity, one way of dealing with
gees in Cairo, Sudan at once symbolizes both their the rupture of migration is by re-establishing those
home and the unwanted (Mahmoud, 2005). Sudan qualities. Yet underlying our discussion about estab-
represents their home, their sense of identity, their lishing continuity is the idea that maintenance, just
loved ones, their productive roles, their memories. as alteration, is an active and transformative process
On the other hand, it represents war, rejection, (Valsiner, 2007). In what follows we thus talk about
genocide, torture, abuse, fear, and death. As a result, “progressive, new adaptations between the person
those refugees tend to have a sharply ambivalent rela- and her environment” (Zittoun, 2011) that are
tionship toward their homeland. Heimweh/Fernweh characteristic to transition periods triggered by the
tension (Boesch, 1991) thus becomes awakened and rupture of migration.
renegotiated, as both home and the faraway appear
simultaneously strange and hostile, while also being Pathways of Re-Establishing Continuity
known and safe. Rupture of migration exists in relation to con-
Yet the refugees’ experience thus described sur- tinuity, and change happens only against the back-
faces another aspect of liminality. The space of drop of sameness. In the words of Hall, Coffey, and
in-betweenness, opened up by migration is, meta- Lashua (2009), “change is experienced and accom-
phorically speaking, a space where everything is pos- modated through mundane, everyday registers”
sible and where one can experiment with different (p. 551). Migrants attempt to keep certain every-
ways of being. However, although the transforma- day activities untouched in the new context, even
tion and development is intrinsic in the rupture if the ways of conducting these activities become
→ repair cycle, the possibility of perceiving limi- altered. The Sudanese refugees may miss the smells
nality as promise and not as threat is linked to the and tastes of their traditional cooking in their new
safety net around the liminal space. In other words, life in Cairo, but the pattern of eating at certain
migrants who have others’ advice or their own aspi- times of the day together with certain social oth-
rations and life goals that allow them to transition ers may remain, and is brought forward to the new
to the other side through the ambiguity are more context, where it continues to build up migrants’
likely to see it as possibility for change and growth, personal history. The everyday practices that we
while it remains a threatening and hostile territory need to attend to thus function as kind of safety
for those who do not have such social or symbolic nets in the space of in-betweenness. This dialectic
support at their hand. of change and continuity, novelty and sameness in
It is also clear that safety nets are not always understanding oneself and the world, is thus central
offered to migrants. Instead they need to be discov- to our understanding of migration.
ered and created. The (re)establishment of a sense In order to move beyond the break in one’s way
of home away from home—that is, creation of sup- of being and re-establish sense of continuity and
port systems that allow coping with liminality—is sameness, in order to turn threat into promise, and
the topic we turn to now. respond to new challenges, individuals’ experience

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 737
and knowledge stores that build upon available cul- since many of them project their own unfulfilled
tural resources can be mobilized (Zittoun, 2006, ambitions and dreams onto their children. Although
2007a). Sense of sameness and continuity can procreation is an important protector of their iden-
entail different things for different people (Becker, tities, it imposes increased difficulties for them and
1997). For some, it involves linking with loved their entire family. How to protect and safeguard their
ones, for others it involves sustaining daily rou- children? How to give them the needed education?
tines or activities that were part of the familiar and How to maintain their connection with the (parents’)
taken-for-granted flow of being. For others still, it homeland? Despite these dilemmas, some refugees
means using resources (Zittoun, 2007b; Zittoun continue to want to have more children, because pro-
et al., 2003; Zittoun, 2011), such as institutions, creation is a core value that sustains their personhood
music, literature, or dance to make sense of their in the midst of inevitable change (Mahmoud, 2008,
current situation and do the psychological work 2010). Consider the case of Michael, an unemployed
that is needed for reaching new stabilities. These Sudanese refugee in Cairo who has seven children
and other elements of the sense of being at-home and struggles to provide the food of the day for them
constitute familiar spaces in which the migrants’ (Mahmoud, 2010):
past ways of being were appreciated and rendered
Hala: Tell me more about your life here. You said
meaningful. Retaining those activities, bringing
that you came here temporarily in order to travel?
them to the present as an old basis for new creations,
Michael: One always seeks improvement. And
therefore means retaining one’s sense of continuity,
I was thinking that from Sudan to Egypt, there
and in a way, creating an experiential “home” in
will be improvement, and then we could move
the new environment (Mahmoud, 2010). In what
somewhere better from Egypt so that my children
follows we elaborate some common pathways for
could get educated. This was my ambition. I want
re-establishing continuity through strengthening
my children to have a good education. If they do
the ties with the past home.
not have an education, they will be lost. They could
Maintaining routines of everyday life can be a
become criminals. I wish my children could get a
powerful pathway for re-establishing continuity and
good education. I want my children to say, ‘Baba,
recreating home in the new environment (Becker,
you worked hard for us.’ This is all I want from this
1997; Desjarlais et al., 1995). Many migrants care
world.
to cook their own food, burn incense, and perform
their ordinary activities, habits, and hobbies from Michael, like many other refugees and migrants,
home. When possible, traditional dress is worn is confronted with a catch-22 situation. By having
(Mahmoud, 2010): many children he is challenged in his identity as a
father providing for them and securing their future.
Hala: So when you feel that you miss your family in
At the same time, having many children is essential
Sudan, or anything else from Sudan, what do you do?
for preserving his identity as a man and husband
Zein: I try to [pause] for example, if it’s family,
and for carrying his legacy.
I bring out the photos, if it’s food, I try to cook
Linking with family and friends back home is
it, if it’s something social, I try to gather with the
another way of recreating continuity and coming
Sudanese here [. . .] everything I miss from Sudan,
closer to home, since “home” involves connected-
I try to do here.
ness through meaningful relationships with friends
Sense of continuity also involves complying with tradi- and family (Dovey, 1995). For example, many
tional familiar cultural values that ensured self worth young Estonians studying in England reported that
at home. For example, the Sudanese refugees in Cairo their relations with their parents had improved sig-
consider the domain of fertility and procreation an nificantly after their departure to England (Märtsin,
important protector of their previously established 2009a). They claimed to have long and deep dis-
sense of identity. In many parts of Sudan, one of the cussions about their experiences in the new envi-
primary roles for a man or woman is to have chil- ronment and about their families’ lives back home
dren. In Cairo, married Sudanese refugees continue over phone and internet—an experience they
to embrace the value of childbearing very highly. This hardly had when living at home. Again we can see
is a value that reinforces their manhood and woman- the Boeschian Heimweh/Fernweh dialectic at work
hood, as they were defined in their past. It is also their here—that which is out of reach and absent is dear
only opportunity to continue their lost life projects, and longed for.

738 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


Lastly, cultural retention is a powerful means for then, the absence of familiar and homely, while
ensuring continuity and activating the sense of being depriving them of support, can enable transforma-
at-home. Some refugees or migrants, especially those tion and innovation, while the relatedness of this
who belong to a social network of people from their novelty to what is absent also allows preserving a
own tribe or background, will try to recreate their sense of continuity.
social gatherings and celebrate national holidays or
special occasions in the new environment, in order Migration as Process of Becoming
to revive their culture (Mahmoud, 2010): (An)Other
As already indicated, migration is ultimately a
Hala: Are there people from your tribe here?
transformative and developmental experience. It is
Taheyya: Yes, there are many. Many of my relatives
a process of becoming (an)other. The rupture may
are here. Also, we go every fortnight [to] the Nuba
become repaired through the maintenance of old
Mountains nursery to revive our culture. We speak
ways of being. Yet through this repair the main-
Rotana [tribal language] all day, and we perform our
tained old way of being becomes transformed.
dances. [This is] something that brings us together,
The old everyday practices become recreated and
because life and work increase the gap between us.
renewed. Although they may look the same on the
Although fostering bonds with home may help to surface, the process of rendering them the same has
sustain and recreate everydayness, it also serves in brought along change and transformation.
intensifying feelings of nostalgia and homelessness Thus, it is not only the re-establishment of the
(Mahmoud, 2010), as well as increasing the gap familiarity of the old home that can function as a
between the migrant and the local communities. bridge to the new way of being in a new environ-
Likewise, linking with family can remind the person ment. The event of migration itself can be seen as a
of what they are missing. This makes the migrants’ necessary link in one’s life project that meaningfully
attempts of re-establishing continuity through the connects the past with the present and anticipated
strengthening of home ties an inherently ambiva- future. Continuation of one’s life project, a mean-
lent endeavour, since it reinforces the mode of limi- ingful way of changing and developing as a person
nality. For example, Sadek, a 27-year-old Sudanese that emerges from the experience of migration, can
refugee man in Cairo mentions that he is comforted thus also provide the needed sense of sameness and
when talking about his family, yet at the same time continuity. Moreover, the redefinition of the self
the thoughts are painful and add to his suffering through actualizing new empowering identities in
(Mahmoud, 2010): the new context may also foster feelings of comfort,
recognition, and self-worth which are necessary
Hala: Is there anything that you like to talk about
for establishing the sense of being at-home, and its
and which makes you feel better?
associated sense of identity (Mahmoud, 2010).
Sadek: Well, when I talk about my family, it gives
For example, some Sudanese refugees in Cairo
me ra’ha nafseyya [psychological peace] but at the
have coped with their ruptured preestablished ways
same time suffering. You feel that you have not done
of being by gaining empowerment through acting as
anything for them. You feel that you haven’t fulfilled
representatives of the refugee community; they have
your duties. All of this is poured on you. It is both
proudly redefined themselves as activists and helpers
happiness and sadness. You are happy that you are
of fellow refugees (Mahmoud, 2010). Likewise,
remembering them, but at the same time [sad].
consider the case of Andres, who reinvents himself
Boesch (1991) too emphasizes this ambivalence. He as a European person in order to make sense of the
recognizes that the absence of home can deprive a liminality of being between Britain and Estonia
person of its supportive elements, putting at stake a (Märtsin, 2009a, pp. 130):
sense of familiarity and stability. At the same time,
these supportive elements can also be constrain- Andres: I have probably developed, I don’t know if
ing, exactly because of their taken-for-grantedness it is European identity. [ . . . ] Being European means
and stability. Using Robinson Crusoe’s cave explo- differentiating oneself from the rest of the world. It
sion as an example, he argues that the explosion is not in the sense of differentiating, but in the sense
functioned as a trigger and basis for Crusoe’s self- of thinking and acting freely. I feel natural in this
transformation, which was regulated by his memo- environment [in Britain/Europe]; it doesn’t feel like
ries of his self prior to the explosion. For migrants going abroad. Or like, I go abroad from Estonia,

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 739
I go to Europe. It’s not that, it’s my environment. become adults.” There is a deep and pervasive
And I definitely want it to stay this way. And I am meaning to Thomas Wolff’s title: “You Can’t Go Home
afraid that if I go there [to Estonia], perhaps I’ll Again. Home is, indeed, never again!” (p. 198).
get stuck there, and all this will somehow remain The difficulties related to repatriation thus stem
closed. from the inevitable change in the home environ-
ment as well as in the migrant’s own way of being
For Andres then, seeing himself as European allows
and sense of identity that have changed through
going beyond the distinction between Estonia and
the migration experience. This process of self-
Britain. This higher-level self-definition brings the
discovery and knowledge accumulation, including
two environments together in a meaningful man-
the renegotiated sense of being at-home and the
ner and allows Andres to rebuild his sense of con-
reconstruction of the taken-for-granted everyday-
tinuity while simultaneously responding to his new
ness may not be fully realized until an actual return
experiences.
home (Meintel, 1973). Homecoming is not only
Migration is thus an inherently ambiguous
about the arrival in the physical environment, but
experience, ripe with discontinuity in the midst of
more importantly about the re-establishment of
incredible sameness, filled with excitement and pain
all the meaningful connections with the environ-
of finding and losing. The experience of migration
ment, people, and with one’s own way of being
not only makes us reconstruct our patterns of every-
(Constable, 1999; Papadopoulos, 2002). Although
day life, but it also changes our perceptions of our
the (maybe idealized) image of home sustains
original home, and our self-understandings, acting
migrants during exile, it can collapse abruptly
sometimes as a powerful trigger for redefining
upon return (Maletta et Al., 1989; Zarzosa, 1998;
ourselves and becoming (an)other. Through con-
Habib, 1996; Ghanem, 2003). Repatriation is thus
tact with unfamiliar worlds, we gain knowledge
another migration, another uprooting entailing
and experience, and we change. This change takes
a separation from the physical location of the
place as we make the initially unfamiliar world
country of residence and its social networks.
our own, and push the foregrounded experiences
The experience of Helena, a young woman from
of strangeness to the background as ordinary and
Estonia, who returned home after having lived half
known. Although this re-established normal flow of
a year in England as an exchange student, illustrates
being becomes functional in a new context, it may
the difficulties that homecomers may experience
become dysfunctional for other contexts, including
(Märtsin, 2009a, pp. 153):
the previously known and familiar home. This raises
the question: how do migrants fit in when they go
Helena: During the last month I’ve been trying to
back home?
[. . .] cope with being in Estonia. Somehow I still feel
that this isn’t my life or that I’m not able to live it
Never At-Home?
anymore the way I used to (before leaving). I still feel
And when they return to the place they were born,
that I moved on with my life while living in England.
they will be, more than likely, in a different space and
And coming back and staying here is like a step back
therefore remain, in a sense, in exile.
in my life. A very difficult step. [ . . . ] I feel that I’ve
(Constable, 1999, p. 225)
changed so much and I don’t want to go back where
Perhaps the best-known repatriation story in the I started. [ . . . ] Sometimes I even feel as if I have
Western world is that of Odyssey, who upon return- returned to hell. I don’t feel as if I’m at home. I miss
ing home, not only fails to recognize his land, the people and the things we used to do, and the
but nobody recognizes him either (Papadopoulos, life we used to live. [ . . . ] I’ve understood that there
2002). As we have indicated, migration inevitably is nothing keeping me here. And after graduation
brings with it change and reinvention, even if it I’d like to go and live somewhere else. [ . . . ] When
entails recreating the familiar patterns of everyday you go to live in a new place, then you are kind of a
life and retaining continuity and sameness beyond blank page [ . . . ] You can create a picture of yourself
disruption. Furthermore, people and places change and you like that new picture. And then you go back
with or without migration. As Fried (2000) has and you have to be who you were before. And it’s so
argued: “If we grow and age in place, the environ- difficult to stay who you have become, because all
ments in which we are born and reach adolescence the people are different and they see you the way you
are no longer the same as the places in which we used to be. [ . . . ] It’s difficult to explain, but this is

740 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


the way I felt. I moved on and then I had to move home communities, for they “have made it.” Yet,
back to be able to be here [in Estonia]. while evoking pride, the changed socio-economic
status may also evoke feelings of being an outsider
Helena’s description indicates how one’s sense of in the general atmosphere of poverty and depriva-
identity is intertwined and emerges out of her joint tion. Similarly, those migrants who have become
activities with others in specific time and space con- acquainted with different gender roles in the new
texts. When this background of taken-for-granted environment, for instance, return home to face the
connections is not there anymore to support her traditional gender roles that have now become alien
way of being, she feels lost. The reinvented way of to them (Striffler, 2007; Zarzosa, 1998). Migrants
being seems thus not to be functional in the old/new who have received years of education abroad may
environment and she needs to go through another return to their home villages feeling disenchanted
cycle of reinvention to re-establish the meaningful with the traditional worldviews they may find there
sense of identity and sense of being at-home. (Salih, 1969/2002).
The connections with old and new social Constable’s (1999) interesting study of Filipina
others and the views we think they hold about domestic workers in Hong Kong shows how returning
us—the meta-perspectives—can be simultaneously home has become an increasingly ambivalent
upsetting and pleasant, because of the feelings of thought for the women. On the one hand, home
nonbelonging that they evoke, as well as the admi- is where their families and personal histories are.
ration they may carry. The work of Graham and On the other hand, the experience of working and
Khosravi (1997) for example indicates that political living in Hong Kong, despite their low social status,
refugees, who return to their homeland after the has brought them a sense of independence, empow-
end of a period of political turbulence or war, feel erment, and liberation. When they go home briefly,
or are made to feel by their home communities they often experience a honeymoon period after
that they abandoned the country at times of diffi- which their homecoming goes downhill. They start
culty and therefore have no place in it upon their the confrontation with problems at home, with tra-
return, as in the case of Iranian political refugees ditional gender roles and constraints. This makes
in Sweden. And although the home communities their feelings about possibly returning for good
see them as reminders of a painful past, returnees largely ambivalent.
are hurt by the collective silence that they think Repatriation then is another cycle of migration,
characterizes the home communities regarding the accompanied by mixed feelings of alienation, disil-
events that made them flee (Maletta et al., 1989; lusionment, estrangement, unfamiliarity, and some-
Habib, 1996; Zarzosa, 1998). The situation for ref- times guilt. As Hall (1987) put it, “Migration is
ugees can be even more devastating. Besides the fact a one-way trip. There is no ‘home’ to go back to”
that millions of refugees in the world never return (p. 44). However, like migration, homecoming is
home, the ones who repatriate find themselves in an ambivalent experience full of feelings of pride
a war-devastated homeland that may not resemble and guilt, joy and shame, of wanting to belong, but
the home they had in mind. This can certainly also wanting to remain distinct. And again, there
cause them tremendous confusion, ambiguity, and is the everydayness that unfolds under and beyond
ambivalence. On the other hand, the refugees who that ambivalence, which shakes one’s security and
spend years seeking asylum start painting a pleasant comfort, functioning as an anchor in the process of
image of their future homes in the resettlement recreating one’s ordinary ways of being and turning
countries (Mahmoud, 2010). Many refugees come change into the mundane.
to the new host country with high expectations
(Stein, 1981), only to arrive (if ever) in countries Conclusion: Migration as a Dynamic,
so foreign to them that they start experiencing the Dialectic, and Developmental Experience
difficulties of being away from home all over again In this chapter, we attempted to explore the mean-
(see Holtzman, 2000). ings of home and how these are affected by the expe-
Furthermore, some returnees come home having rience of migration. Home has been characterized as
achieved a somewhat higher position in the social a complex, dynamic, dialectic, and experiential phe-
and economical ladder, of which they are proud. nomenon. We emphasized the sense of being at-home
Bhatia (2007), for example, discusses how Indians and the intertwined sense of identity as interlinked
living in the United States, are admired by their and mutually defining anchors of our existence

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 741
that become inevitably shaken and ruptured in the The research into cultural change and migration has
experience of migration. But when looking at how in recent years moved away from seeing cultures
this rupture is experienced and managed, we have as mutually exclusive entities and toward a more
emphasized the inherently dynamic, dialectic, and process-oriented approach, which seeks to under-
developmental nature of migration, instead of see- stand how multiple cultural ways of being are held
ing it as a unidirectional sequence from rupture to simultaneously in a constant dialogue by individuals
shock to coping and achieving a new stable being. who move between cultures. Thus our conceptual-
Migration is accompanied by complex, contradic- ization of migration as a dynamic and dialectic pro-
tory, ambivalent feelings and attempts to cope with cess that entails simultaneous renegotiation of bonds
novelty against the backdrop of sameness, change in with and meanings of home and new environment
relation to continuity, and reinvention against the is becoming increasingly present in contemporary
backdrop of the mundane. Similarly, we have tried migration research. However, the third aspect we
to move away from the representation of home and have emphasized in this chapter—the inherently
resident societies as “hermetically sealed or mutu- developmental nature of migration—has been less
ally exclusive spaces” (Bhatia & Ram, 2001b, p. central in this area of research. Therefore, we would
3), but rather have seen them emerging as mutu- welcome studies that take a fundamentally develop-
ally defining aspects of our being through our lived mental approach to migration, seeing it as leading
experiences in and between them. to change and growth alongside the maintenance of
Another implication of the discussion in this homeliness, and explicitly explore the double-binding
chapter is the irreversible effect of movement on experience of promise and threat of migration.
one’s sense of identity, giving rise to a mix of feel- In our discussion we have already hinted at
ings in relation to one’s homeland and one’s sense another possible alley of research—that of exploring
of identity. The return home turns out to be sig- the experiences of internal exiles. Migration research
nificantly complex and dynamic, to the extent that has traditionally been concerned with those groups
it sometimes is experienced as yet another cycle of of individuals who move between cultures or whose
migration. Emphasizing this intertwined and mutu- family has in the past moved between cultures. Yet
ally defining character of societies and dialectics of in our multicultural, achievement-oriented class
moving between them has thus taken us away from societies, the experience of social exclusion is not
either/or, entity-like definitions, lists, and termino- common only for migrants, but for many locals too.
logies. And this is an important contribution that Exploring how people come to be foreigners in their
socio-culturally informed studies, including these own country, how they carve out spaces for them-
reported in this chapter, have made to migration selves on the margins of the popular subcultures in
research. their home society, and how they come to consider
Before closing, we should, once more, stress the migration as a way of dealing with this feeling of
idiosyncratic and highly personal nature of home, being an internal outsider, are thus questions which
moving away from home, and returning home. Such are worth exploring further. Our conceptualization
experiences are not shaped by the circumstances of of migration as a dynamic, dialectic, and develop-
migration per se, but more so by the individual per- mental experience that may begin far before the
son in question. The diversity of circumstances sur- actual event of migration may be especially suitable
rounding the experience of home and movement, for these kinds of studies.
and all the complexities and tensions involved, Finally, in this chapter we have been concerned
may seem threatening to our comfortable way of with the individuals’ experiences of migration. Yet
seeing the world. Nevertheless, it is also liberating to the individuals carve out spaces for themselves in
know that migration can be an exhilarating experi- the context of societal and institutional structures,
ence, opening up new horizons for the person, and such as education, employment or health care,
animating communications between and within which is simultaneously enabling and constraining.
cultures. Although this intertwinement of migrants and
institutions has not been our focus here, we would
Future Directions welcome studies that turn away from looking
But where does this conceptualization of migra- at migrants as humans whose being is rendered
tion as inherently dynamic, dialectic, and develop- problematic by their belonging to a liminal space
mental experience leave us with our research efforts? between cultures and societies, and toward exploring

742 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


institutional structures that constrain migrants selected readings of Ernest E. Boesch (pp. 219–237). Charlotte,
in their efforts to cope with liminality. We would NC: Information Age Publishing.
Boesch, E. E. (2011). Culture: Result and condition of action. In
thus hope to see future studies that examine how J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology.
societal structures and institutions enable and con- Oxford: Oxford University Press.
strain migrants in imagining themselves forward in Bühler, C., & Massarik, F. (1968). The course of human life. A study
the new context. This type of analysis seems to be of goals in the humanistic perspective. New York: Springer.
especially important in the case of refugees, yet can Case, D. (1996). Contributions of journeys away to the defi-
nition of home: An empirical study of a dialectic process.
be equally useful for understanding the experiences Journal of Environmental Psychology, 16, 1–15.
of other migrants too. Charleston, S. (2009). The English football ground as a repre-
sentation of home. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 29,
144–150.
Acknowledgments
Chow, K., & Healey, M. (2009). Place attachment and place
We are sincerely grateful to Irini Kadianaki for her valuable
identity: First-year undergraduates making the transition
feedback on the ideas presented in this chapter, many of which,
from home to university. Journal of Environmental Psychology,
we believe, have become clearer and more grounded thanks to
28, 362–372.
her contribution.
Coker, E. M. (2004). “Travelling pains”: Embodied metaphors
of suffering among southern Sudanese refugees in Cairo.
Notes Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry, 28, 15–39.
1. All personal names have been changed to preserve the con- Constable, N. (1999). At home but not at home: Filipina nar-
fidentiality of participants. ratives of ambivalent returns. Cultural Anthropology, 14(2),
2. The interviews in Märtsin’s (2009a) study were conducted 203–228.
in Estonian, transcribed verbatim and later translated to English Cornish, F., Peltzer, K., & MacLachlan, M. (1999). Returning
by her. strangers: The children of Malawian refugees come “home”?
3. All the interviews in Mahmoud’s (2010) study were con- Journal of Refugee Studies, 12(3): 264–283.
ducted in Arabic, then translated and transcribed verbatim in Desjarlais, R., Eisenberg, L., Good, B., & Kleiman, A. (1995).
English. World mental health: Problems and priorities in low-income
countries. New York: Oxford University Press.
Diriwächter, R. (2009). Heimweh or homesickness: A nostalgic
References look at the Umwelt that no longer is. In R. S. Chang (Ed.),
Abbey, E., & Valsiner, J. (2005). Emergence of meanings through Relating to environments: A new look at Umwelts (pp. 163–185).
ambivalence. Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 6(1). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
Retrieved from http://www.qualitative-research.net/fqs/ Dovey, K. (1985). Home and homelessness. In I. Altman and
Abu-Lughod, J. L. (1988). Palestinians: Exiles at home and C. M. Werner (Eds.), Home environments (pp. 33–64). New
abroad. Current Sociology, 36(2), 61–69. York: Plenum Press.
Altman, I. (1976). Privacy: A conceptual analysis. Environment Easthope, H. (2004). A place called home. Housing, Theory and
and Behavior, 8(1), 7–29. Society, 21(3), 128–138.
Aveling, E.-L., & Gillespie, A. (2008). Negotiating multiplicity: Falmagne, R. J. (2004). On the constitution of “self ” and
adaptive asymmetries within second generation Turks’ “soci- “mind.” The dialectic of the system and the person. Theory &
ety of mind.” Journal of Constructivist Psychology, 21, 1–23. Psychology, 14(6), 822–845.
Becker, G. (1997). Disrupted lives: How people create meaning in a Fried, M. (2000). Continuities and discontinuities of place.
chaotic world. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 20, 193–205.
Bhatia, S. (2007). American karma. Race, culture, and identity in Ghanem, T. (2003). When forced migrants return “home”: The
the Indian diaspora. New York: New York University Press. psychosocial difficulties returnees encounter in the reintegra-
Bhatia, S., & Ram, A. (2001a). Locating the dialogical self in the tion process. RSC Working Paper No. 16. Refugee Studies
age of transnational migrations, border crossings and diaspo- Center. University of Oxford.
ras. Culture & Psychology, 7(3), 297–309. Giddens, A. (1994). Modernity and self-identity. Cambridge,
Bhatia, S., & Ram, A. (2001b). Rethinking “acculturation” in UK: Polity Press.
relation to diasporic cultures and postcolonial identities. Gillespie, A. (2007). Becoming other. From social interaction to
Human Development, 44(1), 1–18. self-reflection. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
Billig, M. (1996). Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach Graham, M., & Khosravi, S. (1997). Home is where you make
to social psychology (New ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge it: Repatriation and diaspora culture among Iranians in
University Press. Sweden. Journal of Refugee Studies, 10(2), 115–133.
Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic action theory and cultural psychology. Habib, N. (1996) The search for home. Journal of Refugee Studies,
Berlin: Springer-Verlag. 9(1), 96–102.
Boesch, E. E. (2007a). A mediation on message and mean- Hall, T., Coffey, A., & Lashua, B. (2009). Steps and stages:
ing. In W. J. Lonner & S. A. Hayes (Eds.), Discovering Rethinking transitions in youth and place. Journal of Youth
cultural psychology: A profile and selected readings of Ernest Studies, 12(5), 547–561.
E. Boesch (pp. 309–330). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Harrell-Bond, B., & Voutira, E. (1992). Anthropology and the
Publishing. study of refugees. Anthropology Today, 8(4), 6–10.
Boesch, E. E. (2007b). Reality as metaphor. In W. J. Lonner & S. Hayward, G. (1975). Home as an environmental and psycho-
A. Hayes (Eds.), Discovering cultural psychology: A profile and logical concept. Landscape, 20, 2–9.

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 743
Heller, A. (1995). Where are we at home? Thesis Eleven, 41(1), Märtsin, M. (2010). Identity in dialogue: Identity as hyper-
1–18. generalized personal sense. Theory & Psychology, 20(3),
Hermans, H. J. M. (2001). The dialogical self: Toward a theory 436–450.
of personal and cultural positioning. Culture & Psychology, Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society from the standpoint of
7(3), 243–281. a social behaviourist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Holland, D., & Lachicotte, W. (2007). Vygotsky, Mead, and the Meintel, D. A. (1973). Strangers, homecomers, and ordinary
new sociocultural studies of identity. In H. Daniels, M. Cole, men. Anthropological Quarterly, 46(1), 47–58.
& J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Vygotsky Moore, J. (2000). Placing home in context. Journal of
(pp. 101–135). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Environmental Psychology, 20, 207–217.
Press. Moos, R. H., & Schaefer, J. A. (1986). Life transitions and crises:
Holland. D., Lachicotte, W., Skinner, D., & Cain, C. (2001). A conceptual overview. In R. H. Moos (Ed.), Coping with life
Identity and agency in cultural worlds. Cambridge, MA: crises: An integrated approach. New York: Plenum Press.
Harvard University Press. O’Sullivan-Lago, R., & de Abreu, G. (2010). Maintaining con-
Holtzman, J. D. (2000). Nuer journeys, nuer lives: Sudanese tinuity in a cultural contact zone: Identification strategies in
refugees in Minnesota. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. the dialogical self. Culture & Psychology, 16(1), 73–92.
Josephs, I. E. (2002). “The Hopi in me.” The construction of Papadopoulos, R. K. (2002). Refugees, home, and trauma. In
a voice in the dialogical self from a cultural psychological R. K. Papadopoulos (Ed.), Therapeutic care for refugees: No
perspective. Theory & Psychology, 12(2), 161–173. place like home (pp. 9–41). London: Karnac Books.
Kadianaki, I. (2009). Dramatic life courses: Migrants in the mak- Parkin, D. (1999). Mementoes as transitional objects in human
ing. In J. Valsiner, P. C. M. Molenaar, M. C. D. P. Lyra, & displacement. Journal of Material Culture, 4(3), 303–320.
N. Chaudary (Eds.), Dynamic process methodology in the social Proshansky, H., Fabian, A., & Kaminoff, R. (1983). Place
and developmental sciences (pp. 477–492). London: Springer. identity: Physical world socialisation of the self. Journal of
Lawrence, J. A., Benedikt, R., & Valsiner, J. (1992). Homeless Environmental Psychology, 3, 57–83.
in the mind: A case-history of personal life in and out of a Rasmussen, S. (2011). Cultural anthropology. In J. Valsiner
close orthodox community. Journal of Social Distress and the (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. Oxford:
Homeless, 1(2), 157–176. Oxford University Press.
Mahmoud, H. W. (2005). Coping with transition: The use of Rowles, G. D. (1983). Place and personal identity in old age:
symbolic resources by Sudanese refugees in Cairo (Unpublished Observations from Appalachia. Journal of Environmental
MPhil Dissertation). University of Cambridge. Psychology, 3, 299–313.
Mahmoud, H. W. (2008). Exploring identity changes of Salih, T. (1969/2002). Season of migration to the north
Sudanese refugees in Cairo: Liminality and the frustrating (D. Johnson-Davies, trans.). London: Penguin Classics.
struggle between stability and change. Al-Raida, 120–121, Sarbin, T. R. (1983). Place identity as a component of self: An
11–19. addendum. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 3, 337–344.
Mahmoud, H. W. (2010). Disrupted lives and shattered dreams: Shotter, J. (2003). “Real presences.” Meaning as living move-
Culture, identity, and coping pathways among Sudanese ref- ment in participatory world. Theory & Psychology, 13(4),
ugees in Cairo (Unpublished PhD Dissertation). University 435–468.
of Cambridge. Available at: http://repository.forcedmigra- Shotter, J. (2008). Conversational realities revisited: Life, lan-
tion.org/show_metadata.jsp?pid=fmo:5471. guage, body and world. Chagrin Falls, OH: Taos Institute
Maletta, H., Shwarcberg, F., & Schneider, R. (1989). Back home: Publications.
Psychosocial aspects of the exiles’ return to Argentina. In Shotter. J., & Lannamann, J. W. (2002). The situation of social
P. R. Pressar (Ed.), When borders don’t divide: Labour migra- constructionism. Its “imprisonment” within the ritual of
tion and refugee involvements in the Americas. New York: theory-criticism-and-debate. Theory & Psychology, 12(5),
Centre for Migration Studies. 577–609.
Manzo, L. C. (2005). For better or worse: Exploring multiple Simão, L. M. (2003). Beside rupture—disquiet; beyond the oth-
dimensions of place meaning. Journal of Environmental er—alterity. Culture & Psychology, 9(4), 449–459.
Psychology, 25(1), 67–86. Sixsmith, J. (1986). The meaning of home: An exploratory
Marková, I. (2003). Dialogicality and social representations: The study of environmental experience. Journal of Environmental
dynamics of the mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Psychology, 6, 281–298.
Press. Stein, B. N. (1981). The refugee experience: Defining the
Marková, I. (2011). Social representations as anthropology of parameters of a field of study. International Migration Review,
culture. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and 15(1/2), 320–330.
psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stein, B. N. (1986). The experience of being a refugee:
Märtsin, M., & Niit, T. (2005). The home as a territorial system Insights from the research literature. In C. L. Williams,
(II). In R. García-Mira, D. L. Uzzell, J. E. Real, & J. Romay & J. Westermeyer (Eds.), Refugee mental health in resettle-
(Eds.), Housing, space and quality of life (pp. 151–170). ment countries (pp. 5–23). Washington, D.C.: Hemisphere
Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Publishing Corporation.
Märtsin, M. (2009a). Identity construction as a personal sense- Striffler, S. (2007). Neither here nor there: Mexican immigrant
making process: A case study of Estonian students in the workers and the search for home. American Ethnologist,
United Kingdom (Unpublished PhD Dissertation). University 34(4), 674–688.
of Bath. Available at: http://opus.bath.ac.uk/17149/. Tuan, Y. F. (1980). Rootedness versus sense of place. Landscape,
Märtsin, M. (2009b). Rupturing otherness: Becoming 24, 3–8.
Estonian in the context of contemporary Britain. Integrative Turner, V. (1967). The forest of symbols: Aspects of Ndembu ritual.
Psychological and Behavioral Science, 44(1), 65–81. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

744 never at h om e ?: m i g r ants b e t we e n s ocieties


Twigger-Ross, C. L., & Uzzell, D. L. (1996). Place and identity Zittoun, T. (2006). Transitions: Development through symbolic
processes. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 16, 205–220. resources. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
Valsiner, J. (2006). Ambivalence under scrutiny: Returning to Zittoun, T. (2007a). Dynamics of interiority. Ruptures and
the future. Estudios de Psicologia, 27(1), 117–130. transitions in the self development. In L. M. Simão &
Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies: Foundations of J. Valsiner (Eds.), Otherness in question. Labyrinths of the
cultural psychology. New Delhi, India: Sage Publications. self (pp. 187–214). Charlotte, NC: Information Age
Valsiner, J., & Abbey, E. (2006). Ambivalence in focus: Publishing.
Remembering the life and work of Else Frenkel-Brunswik. Zittoun, T. (2007b). The role of symbolic resources in human
Estudios de Psicologia, 27(1), 9–17. lives. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge hand-
Van Leeuwen, B. (2008). On the affective ambivalence of living book of sociocultural psychology (pp. 343–361). Cambridge,
with cultural diversity. Ethnicities, 8, 147–176. UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ward, C., Bochner, S., & Furnham, A. (2001). The psychology of Zittoun, T. (2011). Life course: A sociocultural perspective. In
culture shock. London: Routledge. J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology.
Zarzosa, H. L. (1998) Internal exile, exile and return: A gendered Oxford: Oxford University Press.
view. Journal of Refugee Studies, 11(2), 189–198. Zittoun, T., Duveen, G., Gillespie, A., Ivinson, G., & Psaltis,
Zittoun, T. (2003). The hidden work of symbolic resources in C. (2003). The use of symbolic resources in developmental
emotions. Culture & Psychology, 9(3), 313–329. transitions. Culture & Psychology, 9(4), 415–448.
Zittoun, T. (2004). Symbolic competencies for developmental
transitions: The case of the choice of first names. Culture &
Psychology, 10(2), 131–161.

m ä rtsin , m a h m ou d 745
This page intentionally left blank
PA RT
9
Culture of Higher
Social Regulators:
Values, Magic, and
Duties
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Values and Socio-Cultural Practices:


35 Pathways to Moral Development

Angela Uchoa Branco

Abstract
The major claim I make in this chapter is that psychology must overcome the traditional tendency
of considering the topic of moral development as an almost exclusive domain of cognitive-oriented
constructivists. When we consult the literature about subjects concerning moral development, we easily
find a vast amount of references that draw on constructivist assumptions, where Piaget’s and Kohlberg’s
ideas still prevail. However, some authors are already pursuing explanations for moral development
elsewhere, namely, taking a different, less reductionist, epistemological scientific approach. This alternative
approach relies on a cultural and systemic paradigm that makes it possible to take into account the
complexities of human development. As I analyze the issue from a cultural psychological perspective,
I first refer to the conceptual origins of the constructs pertaining to the area, their roots spreading from
philosophy and sociology. Then I highlight some of the main contributions of a few key philosophers,
social scientists, and psychologists to the theme, however far from presenting an actual review of their
interesting ideas. Last, but not least, I present to the reader my own contemporary elaborations on
the topic, drawing on the resourceful contributions of theorists such as Shweder, Rogoff, Tappan, and
Valsiner to come up with a perspective that I like to designate as a socio-cultural constructivist approach
to moral development. From such perspective, culture, affect, cognition, and motivation (values) all
come to the forefront of the analytic picture in order to investigate the ontogenesis and the cultural
co-construction of moral development. The cognitive bias is therefore overcome, and the intertwined
quality of affect plus cognition now plays a fundamental role in the emergence of specific moral
motivations found in social practices and individuals’ actions.
Keywords: moral development, values, moral motivation, cultural psychology, morality, ethics

One of the most important consequences of separating the


individual from the social world, and cognitive processes from
affect, in moral psychology theories, has been a deep impov-
erishment in the treatment of morality as a fundamental,
pervasive aspect of human functioning. Morality refers not
to the abstract world of reasoning but to the world of actions
and choices, having, at least potentially, deep social and
interpersonal implications and involving both intrapsychic
cognitive and affective mechanisms.
—P. Paolichi, 2007

749
L’egoisme est la racine de tous les vices; l’orgueil en est une
branche. Lorsque l’orgueil grandit, il arrive un moment où
l’individu deviant stupide.
—A. N. Philippe, 1902

Why did it take so long for psychology to actually psychology tried to maintain the issue outside its
address morality development issues at both moti- boundaries, at a distance, for a long time. In general,
vational and interaction domains? Except for cogni- psychologists’ incursions on the topic were timid
tive psychologists such as Piaget, Kohlberg, Blasi, and outstandingly primitive or simplistic. When we
and similarly oriented theorists, very few scientists think about Freud’s limited ideas about guilt and
in developmental psychology carried out scientific identification processes during Oedipus uncon-
studies to make sense of how moral and ethical scious experiences, and behaviorist reductionism
values develop along human ontogenesis. This has sweeping away any idea of human intentionality
always surprised me as a researcher of human social and reflexivity—as it claimed for simplistic, mecha-
interactions and relationships, since I started to nistic behavior conditionings—we wonder why
investigate the roots of aggression and the promo- the topic remained for so long as a matter seriously
tion of prosocial development (Branco, 1989, 2003, taken into account almost exclusively by philosophy
2009; Branco & Mettel, 1995). After all, ethics and and sociology.
morality are a major concern to human life and Piaget’s reaction to this unforgivable lack of
experience. Together and embraced with economy interest, which prevailed in the twentieth century,
and politics, ethics and morality provide the rules offered a significant contribution to the study of
and principles for social organization and human moral judgment development in children. When he
interactions that may, or may not, create possibili- published his 1932 book on children’s moral devel-
ties for mutual respect and therefore the construc- opment, the prevalent idea held by most psycholo-
tion of democratic societies. gists and by some important sociologists was that
Consisting of omnipresent concepts applied human beings were not responsible for the moral
to both personal, subjective, and collective social consequences of their actions. For psychoanalysts,
realms, morality and ethics are the two sides of a irrationality triumphed over intentional reflexivity,
same coin, which consists of human daily life inter- and for behaviorists, as well as for Marx-aligned soci-
actions and relationships, constructed and recon- ologists, one should mostly blame, respectively, the
structed at multiple different levels, from family to mother (Freud), the family (person’s conditioning
international domains. From a systemic perspec- history), and poverty (Marx), which resulted from
tive (Bronfrenbrenner, 1989; Ford & Lerner, 1992; capitalist oppression. Miserable life conditions and
Thelen & Smith, 1998), moral concepts, beliefs, experiences of criminals, and other moral offenders,
and socio-cultural practices mutually and continu- left no room for intentional thought, reflexivity, or
ously construct each other at all levels (from micro any sort of personal choice or decision whatsoever.
to macro to global), and they have fundamental This, however, sounded overwhelmingly absurd even
effects on our everyday lives. The way moral values for laypeople, and later on, new approaches to the
(or their absence) guide our actions and judgments issue—from constructivism to cultural psychology—
in powerful ways can never be overestimated. This proved that even though what happens to us has
chapter is a contribution to the topic, and refers to strong impact over our development, we are as well
some of the main thinkers that can help psychology responsible, although in different degrees, for our
to take a more proactive role in the investigation— own actions.
and better understanding—of the development of Although sociology, behaviorism, and psycho-
ethics, moral values, and social practices that lie at analysis downplayed individual responsibility,
the core of a just and democratic society. Piaget and Kohlberg, inspired by Kant’s philosophy,
put a special emphasis on individual activity, auton-
Psychology and the Development of Moral omy, and responsibility. That opened a new era for
Values and Interactions approaching the issue of moral responsibility, but, as
Although morality and ethics have always been of we will see, their contributions were constrained to
central relevance to philosophers and sociologists, a person’s discourse and judgment regarding moral

750 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
dilemmas about what is right or wrong in complex unfairness, and injustice, the antinomy relating to
social situations. Hence, this chapter aims at bring- one’s own and others’ behavior concerning mat-
ing the topic of moral development to discussion ters of justice, loyalty, and human welfare. Morality
from a critical approach of mainstream psychology (going forward I will use the term “morality” to
while assuming a socio-cultural constructivist psy- encompass its sociological complement, “ethics”) is
chological perspective that highlights the role of directed linked to the historically constructed notion
culture and constructive individuals. Some selected of human dignity and the value of human existence.
interdisciplinary contributions to the topic are dis- The value and dignity assigned to human existence
cussed, aiming at a better understanding of human have their Western roots in Greek philosophy,
beliefs, values, and interaction patterns development flourished during Enlightenment and more recently
along ontogenesis. I will particularly emphasize how became the core of humanistic philosophy. The
values and interactions develop within complex sit- major accomplishment of such values was the inter-
uations where dilemmas concerning right or wrong nationally approved Declaration of Human Rights
become of particular relevance within contexts of in 1948 by the United Nations. At an abstract level,
everyday life experiences with peers, family, strang- few nations and people disapprove the Declaration’s
ers, all the way to national and international affairs. terms. However, as cultural psychologists would
insist, problems arise when those general assertions
need to be translated into real life judgments, deci-
Ethics and Morality: Conceptual Issues
sions, and actual behaviors. In everyday life, state
Despite the confusion resulting from the etimol-
laws may conflict with cultural norms that may also
ogy of the words derived from their Latin and Greek
conflict with subjective moral principles, giving rise
origins—both ethos (Greek) and moris (Latin) refer
to endless battles and controversies that very often
to “customs”—according to Hegel (1999) morality
are extremely difficult to negotiate or solve. This is
refers to the personal principles that guide an indi-
the foremost reason why the topic demands a trans-
vidual’s conduct, while ethics refers to the collective
and multidisciplinary approach. For example, social
norms within society domains. In fact, this differen-
norms and rules mostly pertain to sociology; axi-
tiation was also acknowledged by ancient Greek phi-
ology and transcendence, universalism versus con-
losophers and thinkers, and Sofocles’ play Antigona
textualism are matters of philosophical reasoning;
reveals the major dilemma faced by the protagonist
and subjectivity, the development of social motiva-
when she has to decide between abiding by per-
tion and personal actions are certainly topics that
sonal, family cultural principles versus by collective
demand efforts by psychology in order to shed some
(urbes), public, social norms. As she disobeys the last,
light onto the complexity of moral phenomena.
she suffers a death sentence that was no easy task to
the king, Cleonte, to pronounce. Ghosts whisper-
ing the faults of both choices haunted the characters Philosophical Roots and Contributions
all along the play. The masterpiece illustrates how Evil or good, right or wrong? Humanity has
people often need to make a choice between ter- long struggled with these issues. Plato and Aristotle,
ribly conflicting moral rules concerning right versus among Greek philosophers, while dedicating their
wrong, and makes us wonder how such incompat- insightful thoughts searching for the truth, also
ible moral principles develop. Moreover, we need to suggested, respectively, that truthful reason and
understand how individuals abide by one or other happiness were the major goals in life. Virtues con-
principle, and actually choose among them depend- sisted of, particularly to Aristotle, a very important
ing on multiple and complex conditions and sub- characteristic to be cultivated and promoted by
jective interpretations. In fact, both personal and humans.
collective cultures (Valsiner, 1987, 2007) are too The French philosopher Rousseau considered
plural, contradictory and complex, and we should kindness as a human natural propensity, only cor-
not be surprised to realize how complicated it is to rupted by society with its norms, unfair relations,
be able to predict people’s choices and to determine and the distortion of natural values of goodness
underlying motives and moral principles. and virtue. Rousseau emphasized the importance
What makes a value or an action moral or ethi- of a pedagogy oriented to promote good and pre-
cal (its social counterpart)? The answer lies in evalu- vent society’s negative influence over the developing
ations and actual behaviors regarding rightness, child. Émile, his most famous book, does an eulogy
fairness, and justice in opposition to wrongness, to human inbuilt kindness, and promotes his ideas

bra n co 751
about how the morality of goodness should impreg- (Valsiner & Cairns, 1992). In lay words, the two
nate everyday life, and bring about justice and fair sides of a same coin, except for these sides are pro-
politics. In his own words, “deep in our souls, there foundly interconnected although distinct from each
is an innate principle of justice and virtue with other. Taking into account that Hegel’s tendency
which, despite our own beliefs, we judge our and was toward the social side, for him morality issues
other’s actions as good or evil, and it is this principle are sort of absorbed by sittlichkeit, or ethics.
that I name as conscience” (Rousseau, 1966). Marx does not particularly address the subject of
Although Rousseau underlined innate, biologi- morality or ethics. His powerful emphasis on his-
cal predispositions toward goodness, Kant relied torical materialism highlights history and economy
almost exclusively on reason to establish the parame- to make sense of politics and sociology. In sharp
ters for moral judgment and actions. His most well- contrast to Kant, Marx justifies the means when the
known contribution to the discussion of morality goals are considered as good, just, or socially desir-
was a maxim that he designated as the “categori- able. Weber criticizes this positioning, and reconsid-
cal imperative.” Along his numerous philosophical ers the importance of also taking into account the
writings this principle was stated in different ways, means, for human dignity must be preserved, even
but could be shortly summarized as “you should when radical changes are socially necessary to pro-
act as though the principle governing your will and vide for justice within society. On the other hand,
action may simultaneously serve as a principle ori- Durkheim (1973) takes an extremely positive and, I
enting a general law” (Kant, 1994). Kant emphati- would say, even naïve perspective. As he sees society
cally claimed for the supremacy of reason over any like the only legitimate parameter for morality, he
other argument. For the German philosopher, no reduces this fundamental dimension of subjective
ends justify immoral means, and human dignity and social experience to a simple function of the
prevails over any utilitarian goal. The utmost final- social system. Everyone should then submit to the
ity of human values and actions is the promotion of system and learn the desirable moral behaviors that
human worth and goodness, no matter how social society expects them to learn. Later on, they have
utilitarianism defends the notion that social benefits to act toward each other according to the mecha-
overrule human individuals’ rights and transcendent nisms of what he designated as “organic solidarity”
condition. (Durkheim, 1973).
Hegel (1999), however, did not agree with such Last but not least, I would like to refer to
ideas on what he considered to be a too abstract Habermas’ bright ideas concerning discursive ethics
conceptualization of reason as the only guide for (Habermas, 1990, 1991). The concept of a discur-
morality. Hegel considered that a dialectical bal- sive ethics is significantly meaningful, particularly
ance was needed to contemplate both individuals from contemporary scientific and philosophical
and society. His proposal of a dialectical materialism perspectives. This concept, intrinsically linked to his
creates a tension between the individual and soci- Theory of Communicative Action, allows Habermas
ety, and this overcomes the excessive idealism of his to substitute Kant’s epistemic and moral subject by
mentor. Morality—in his word moralitat— is now a heuristically productive category of discursive
related to the subject, while the concept of ethics— intersubjectivity. Now, the intellectual effort to make
sittlichkeit—refers to collectivities such as institu- sense of what truth is—or may be—is not taken by
tions, society, and the state itself. The dialectical a singular rational individual but, instead, it is taken
tension created by the individual-society polarity, by the participants of a fairly negotiated discourse,
though, needs to be comprehended assuming that constructed through intensive and democratic com-
individual morality is always socially mediated, and munication. He argues for the restoration of spon-
social ethics is permanently enriched by people who taneity, sociability, solidarity, and cooperation as
live within the social group or community. There the necessary ground for communicative action,
is no person without society and no society with- which he thinks is more important than instru-
out persons. His dialectical ideas, hence, will further mental action (Freitag, 1997). Although Habermas’
contribute to the dialogical and inclusive approach arguments sound much more in tune with the new,
of contemporary cultural psychology, which cannot semiotics- and complexity-oriented paradigm, they
conceive morality and ethics as different, exclusive suffer from a significant weakness resulting from
categories but, au contraire, they are conceptual- the naiveté of their own assumptions. Society, and
ized as distinct but subject to “inclusive separation” consequently social practices, are characterized by

752 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
cultural historical power games that are a funda- judgments. The amount of counter-evidence against
mental, central aspect of negotiations. The actual positive correlations between superior cognition
possibilities for anything like spontaneity or fair and/or language skills, and moral actions, though,
negotiations are not substantial. In other words, is definitely undeniable (Kurtines & Gewirtz,
discursive ethics resulting from intersubjective com- 1991). Nuremberg court reports very well show the
munication must always take into account those independence between cognition and morality in
power games, and the co-construction of morality astounding ways (Arendt, 2000).
needs to be considered as a permanent process of Ratner (2002), a ferocious critic of idealism and
negotiation and change that weighs up the role of cognitivism, argues that:
unequal communication conditions.
Kohlberg’s abstract stages disregard and obscure
concrete moral values and reasoning. They collapse
The Appropriation of Moral Development
vastly different values in common categories that
by Cognitive Reductionism
promote the false appearance of similarity. They are
Piaget’s and Kohlberg’s interest on the psycho-
impoverished, incomplete descriptions of people’s
logical study of moral development allowed for
real moral values and reasoning [ . . . ]. Subsuming
knowledge construction on a specific dimension
[ . . . ] responses in any of Kolhberg’s stages or
of moral development, namely, moral judgment or
categories [ . . . ] expunges them of interesting,
moral reasoning. Even though their ideas and work
important, concrete views of life and fosters the
advanced our knowledge when they used the cat-
erroneous impression that they are ‘basically’
egories of heteronomy and autonomy to describe
similar. In fact, the specific values and views that
the general mindset of developing children—with
constitute the subjects’ moral reasoning are far more
heteronomy preceding autonomy in ontogenesis—
interesting, important, and real than notions such as
the notion of universal stages, so well-appropriated
postconventional reasoning.
by Kohlberg, is hard to sustain, even if we con-
(pp. 191–192)
strain our analysis just to cognition. The role of
language, so brilliantly emphasized by Vygotsky Notwithstanding, the amount of influence and
(1978), is however excessive in the establishment of research generated by Piaget and Kohlberg cannot
Kohlberg’s six stages of moral development— pro- be overestimated. Even today the great majority
gressively arranged along ontogeny in two levels cat- of research and theoretical literature in psychology
egorized as preconventional, two as conventional, about moral development is based on or directly
and two as postconventional levels of moral devel- related to their work. Books and research reports
opment. Kohlberg, though, was not bothered about related to their cognitive-constructivist perspective
how language games could determine some of the continue to proliferate and do represent the vast
nuances between stages, and he did not take that majority of literature in psychology concerning the
into account. It turned out that more advanced theme (Daniel, Lapsey, & Narvaez, 2004; Kurtines
stages à la Kohlberg are usually inferred from & Gewirtz, 1991). As this chapter does not intend
mostly linguistic, discursive degrees of sophistica- to do a review on the subject (easily found else-
tion. In fact, we can say that Kohlberg reassured the where, see Damon & Lerner, 2006; Killen & Hart,
Platonic faith in the power of the rational good later 1995), I will particularly speak to a couple of recent
assumed by Kant (Kohlberg, 1970, 1984), namely, theorists that still address the complex issue of
when a person knows what is right, s/he will neces- moral development from a cognitive-constructivist
sarily struggle to act accordingly, for reason prevails theoretical framework.
over any other human characteristics. Kohlberg goes
even further in his strong beliefs linking rationality The Persistence of Cognitive Reductionism:
and morality. For him, only actions resulting from Contemporary Psychologists on the
rational choice—cognition plus intention—could “Moral Self ”
deserve the label of a moral action. Bergman (2004) One of the most well-known theorists related
reminds us that “in Kohlberg’s view only a judg- to a constructive, cognitivist framework is Augusto
ment that an action is right or obligatory makes that Blasi (1983, 1990, 1999), although he does advance
action moral” (p. 25). In short, Kohlberg’s extreme the study of moral development beyond the usually
rationalism led him to conclude that moral actions narrowed investigations of narrative judgments typ-
are almost an inevitable expression of high moral ical of Kohlberg’s tradition. However, Blasi is still

bra n co 753
too faithful to Kant’s legacy. The innovation intro- perspective, that a moral self may emerge later
duced by him and other similarly oriented psychol- through meaningful experiences (Branco, Branco,
ogists (as we will see below) is the role of personality & Madureira, 2008).
and self in relation to morality. They also refer to Damon (1984; Damon & Lerner, 2006) asserts
the notion of identity, not with a social psychology that morality and self are separate conceptual sys-
connotation, but as a concept that sounds closer to tems, which are only later integrated in ontogeny.
the clinical psychology vocabulary. He argues that stages of moral development, as pro-
For Blasi (1999, 2004), we agentically structure posed and studied by Kohlberg and followers, are
our motives and desires, namely, we structure our not related to moral action. Damon suggests that
will, and then begin to establish our identity. The true personological dynamics need to be taken into
action is therefore chosen by the subject according account, and again refers to morality as being a cen-
to his/her freedom of will. Hence, each person has a tral aspect in a person’s identity that can provide for
free choice that determines, in significant ways, the consistent moral actions.
shaping of his/her own identity. The bet on ratio- Colby and Damon (1993) studied 84 individ-
nal choices, however, are too unrealistic, as con- uals—called as exemplars—whose self was deeply
temporary psychology progressively demonstrates, impregnated with morality principles. The authors
for instance, by acknowledging the role of affect, were able to demonstrate that self and morality can
emotions, nonverbal and unintentional motives as lead to “spontaneous actions,” and therefore they
legitimate and important factors contributing to the concluded for their unity, namely, moral selves will
constitution of the individual’s motivational system. behave morally. It seems to me that claiming for
But Blasi does not go that far. He states that moral- “unity” is perhaps too much, because we all know
ity results from a successful integration of personal- that such a perfect consistency—moral selves will
ity, and it is granted by the need for self-consistency always behave morally—cannot be true. In case
underlying moral choices. According to him, if I am they mean moral selves tend to behave morally, then
a moral person, a rational logic syllogism will oblige it is too simplistic and obvious. Subsequently, the
me to act morally in order to reduce dissonances. authors leave out of the equation the major role of
Therefore, even if there are different motives at work contexts (with their numerous variables and con-
on a certain situation, the moral self, consisting of ditions) and competence (i.e., the ability to act in
a deep motivational structure, will prevail and lead effective ways). Bergman (2004), for instance, refers
the person toward moral actions. After all, betraying to the complexity of human motivation, affirm-
oneself is something unthinkable, according to the ing that even activists who work hard for common
author. good are also motivated by ambition, pride, anger,
For Blasi, moral understanding needs to precede need to please others, or even fear. Moreover, Colby
moral identity, and the logic sequence requires that and Damon (1993) do not examine their exem-
moral understanding leads to moral identity that plars’ specific motivations, and by attributing their
leads to moral action, because of the necessity of actions just to blind obedience to abstract moral
identity integration of one’s personality (1990). In principles, the authors provide us with a perfect
addition, “self-consistency [is] as a central tendency example of reductionism. Another shortcoming of
in personality organization” (Blasi, 1983, p. 201). their position resides in the fact that their model
Nucci (2004) criticizes Blasi, arguing that his only describes the existence of significant integra-
model pretty much suggests the existence of a kind tions between self and morality, but it does not shed
of “homunculus” who freely decides to be consis- any light on how such integration does develop
tent. Affect, Nucci says, is as important for moral- along ontogeny.
ity as reason and identity are, but this issue is not Although researchers as Wren (1991) propose
quite elaborated by the author. Even though he simplistic linear schemes such as moral thinking
attacks Blasi’s reductionism, evoking the complexity generating moral motive, which in turn generates
of human personality, he still believes and overem- moral action, Lapsley and Narvaez (2004) present
phasizes self-consistency and the idea that a moral a much more sophisticated model. Although cogni-
self needs to be nurtured since childhood. Without tively biased, their model suggests the inclusion of
disagreeing that a moral self cultivated from early the aretaic dimension, that is, the dimension where
childhood has a substantial chance to deeply inter- virtues and values are taken into account. They
nalize moral values, I insist, from a developmental affirm, among other ideas, that more recently we can

754 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
observe a growing interest in the relations between appraisal and response, it does play a major role in
moral rationality and selfhood, moral cognition and human psychological functioning, not just regard-
personological processes. They criticize Piaget’s bio- ing the development of morality. Affect and cogni-
logical and structuralist bias (as in morphological tion are in fact interwoven into a single process of
maturation plus the concept of stages), and under- unification, and their distinction for analytical pur-
line the fact that both Piaget and Kohlberg showed poses contemplates the principle of inclusive sepa-
no interest in the self, moral motivation, or identity. ration earlier mentioned in this chapter. In general,
As Piaget and Kohlberg said nothing about virtues, though, to most theorists studying moral develop-
they put aside a whole important dimension of ment the reference to affect comes easily, but it is
moral development. Lapsley and Narvaez (2004) better spoken out than actually meant.
then go a step ahead, but still have difficulties to To conclude, cognitive-constructivist perspec-
explain the evidence against consistency in moral tives end up bringing forth a network of ill-defined
behavior presented by the so-called moral individu- constructs such as moral motives, moral understand-
als. Data allow us to confirm the existence of some ing, moral identity, moral self, moral action, self-re-
coherence when self characteristics are kept in mind; flection, etc., as though all were different things, but
nevertheless, cross-situational variability concerning quite often one translating into others, all claiming
moral actions is certainly undeniable. for intentionality, reflexivity, integration, and unity.
Lapsley and Narvaez (2004) refer to the two Such unity and integration, though, is impossible from
major variances of morality: justice and care. But a systemic perspective, for it demands a dialogical
again the voice of justice prevails, since they, too, framework from which development and change
claim for a social-cognitive theory that demands the can actually occur, and innovations can substan-
examination of the “moral personality in order to tially emerge as a result of multi-causality, plurality,
understand moral functioning”. Most of the con- and interdependence.
structs they use in their arguments are cognitive Turiel (2002) has also elaborated on the topic
constructs like scripts, schemes, strategies, compe- of morality, including dimensions such as care and
tencies and so on. They agree with their colleagues welfare in addition to justice and human rights.
that personality is “organized into coherent, inte- Hoffman (2000), on his turn, has emphasized the
grated systems that impose constraints on the range role of empathy together with cognition, but his
of possible configurations” (p. 196). They go on stages for empathy development typically follow a
stressing self-coherence while claiming that goal cognitivist tendency. But neither takes into account
systems “structure the organization of the cogni- the existence of culture as a powerful canalizing
tive-affective system and influence the perception, force driving moral thinking and actions in specific
selection, and interpretation of various contextual contexts.
settings” (p. 196). However, contradictions can be In short, why does the study of moral develop-
found when they say that “schemes filters percep- ment need to free itself from cognitivism? First,
tion” and that “there is now mounting evidence that there is no universal developmental pathway for
much of our lives is governed by cognitive processes moral development as cognitivists want (Cole,
that are tacit, implicit, and automatic . . .” (p. 197). 1998). And second, Staub (1992, 1993, 2003), with
Now I ask: Where did the previously mentioned his bright work on the roots of anti- and prosocial
construct of “affect” by the authors go? Again, we behavior, provides us with plenty of evidence that
observe that the affective dimension disappears demonstrates that extreme violence is often perpe-
when they assert that a “social-cognitive approach trated by individuals with very sophisticated cognition
emphasizes the central importance of self-processes, (I recommend his book on the origins of genocide,
personal goals, and life tasks that give meaning Staub, 1989).
to one’s motivated behavior and purposive striving”
(p. 197). The Turning Point: Integrating
Unlike cognitivists, contemporary psychology is Historical-Cultural and Constructivist
increasingly pointing out at the blending of affect Assumptions from a Systemic Framework
and cognition (Ford & Lerner, 1992; Rosa, 2007; . . . to develop is not to become more rational. Instead,
Valsiner, 2007). If affect guides selective memory [the individual] enters a new frame of mind about
retrieval, filters perceptions and sensations, as well self-other relationships.
as channels the person’s attention for reflective (Paolichi, 2007, p. 570)

bra n co 755
As many theorists dedicated to the scien- and sociopolitical histories within particular
tific study of human psychological phenomena environments.
have pointed out, human development cannot Meaning-making processes are absolutely central
be addressed by linear, reductionist, or simplistic in determining the quality of our interactions and
approaches anymore. Au contraire, the adoption of relationships, and in studying the moral dimen-
a systemic perspective is a must to make sense of the sion of our collective and individual experiences.
complex, dynamic, and processual nature of human However, meaning-making processes are not just
development. Psychological phenomena can only be constrained to language and cognition as most
understood from an inclusive framework that con- semiotics experts end up suggesting in one way
siders multi-causality and interdependence as the or another (Leeds-Hurwizt, 1995; Pearce, 1967;
epistemological ground for theoretical elaborations, Saussure, 1966). The roles of emotions, body, and
the phenomena being characterized by permanent affect are increasingly acknowledged and taken
dialectical tensions between process-and-structure into account by contemporary theorists (Lewis, &
and individual-and-culture tensions, among other Haviland-Jones, 2004; Rosa, 2007; Valsiner, 2007).
“inclusive” dualities (Ford & Lerner, 1992; Morin Hence, the scientific investigation of moral expe-
& Prigogine, 2000; Schnitman, 1996; Thelen & riences and development requires multi-causality
Smith, 1998; Valsiner, 2007). Contemporary all- approaches that certainly challenge those who find
encompassing systemic approaches have definitely it easier to emphasize this or that aspect, such as
overcome functionalist interpretations of reality, cognition, intention or behavior, in order to explain
and cleverly take a process perspective to study the moral dimension of human beings.
human phenomena according to its multifaceted, Processes involved in meaning construction,
complex nature. Systemic perspectives also empha- viewed from a socio-cultural and a constructiv-
size the interwoven flow of time dimensions along ist perspective, are numerous and relate to each
change and stability processes, which consist of other in extremely complex ways. Such processes
the main characteristics of open, multiple, interac- take place within and throughout different levels
tive, developing living systems. Living systems are of open-ended systems—i.e., individual and social
dynamic but also hierarchically organized in web- organizations (e.g., Branco, 2001, 2003; Valsiner,
like networks, which overlap and intermingle with 2005, 2007). Aspects such as cultural-historical
each other along irreversible time. Hence, systems frameworks, specific culturally structured contexts
exist at different though interrelated levels, and one and social interactions, situational characteristics,
level—the person—cannot be fully understood communication and metacommunication dynam-
without the analysis of other levels as well—orga- ics, individuals’ subjectivities and goal orientations,
nized contexts for human and societal development all play a fundamental role in the co-construction
constructed over a history of interdependent cul- of meanings emerging within particular social activi-
tural contexts. ties; consequently, all play a central role in the emer-
When psychology finally realized that its object gence of particular experiences.
of study was complex, but still analyzable in terms The encompassing view of semiotics (Rosa, 2007;
of general laws and regularities, it started to inves- Valsiner, 2007) brings together language, affect, and
tigate human experiences in order to identify and body as essential parts of meaning-making processes.
analyze meaning-construction processes (Bruner, Consequently, this perspective prevents the naïveté
1997), for those lie at the core of psychological of one-dimensional, biased approaches to issues of
phenomena occurring along social interactions morality, ethics, and their development, for now the
within culturally oriented contexts (Valsiner & subject can be addressed from a broader and system-
Rosa, 2007). The same applies to moral experiences like perspective compatible to its complex nature.
concerning right and wrong regarding our relations One important controversy on moral issues is
with others, ourselves, and the world. From such the pseudo-dichotomy: universalism versus contex-
a viewpoint, it is not difficult to understand why tualism (Lourenço, 1998). Why is it a false dichot-
morality and ethics are phenomena simultaneously omy? To start with, our status among biological
characterized by both convergences—related to our species constrains our options and demands a cou-
singular ecological status in the animal kingdom— ple of general principles to grant our own survival
and divergences, resulting from our unique cultural as a social species. Even though general principles

756 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
are still object of endless negotiations, some wide- Cultural Approaches to the Study of
ranging laws—such as reciprocity, mutual respect, Moral Development
and certain degrees of tolerance toward diversity— Building on Vygotsky’s legacy concerning the
are a definitive “must” for global survival; otherwise cultural-historical roots of human development and
we may end up blowing ourselves up in the near the role of language and contexts to explain complex
future. On the other hand, because of diverse real- psychological phenomena, many theorists have elab-
ity conditions, we developed within very distinc- orated models to understand human development in
tive geographical and cultural-historical contexts, relation to meaning-construction process. As Bruner
characterized by different sets of norms and rules (1997) brilliantly puts the subject, meaning-construc-
that emerged and developed to grant each group’s tion processes are indeed the major topic to be inves-
survival. The result is diversity, namely, multiple tigated by psychology. Among those who have studied
ethnic, social, and individual singularities. the moral dimension of development, I should men-
Globalization has acted upon cultural histories tion some authors whose contributions are of partic-
and human diversity according to an agenda toward ular interest. Shweder deserves a special place for his
hegemony. But such agenda is a dangerous one, insightful ideas concerning the cultural construction
because it presupposes the existence of an actual of morality along everyday life experiences (Shweder,
balance between democratic nations, and this is a 2001; Shweder & Much, 1987). His most interesting
huge pitfall from a capitalist perspective. It is very work (Shweder & Much, 1987) nicely demonstrates
difficult to envision societies and people sharing the the inaccuracy of Kohlberg’s research on moral devel-
same degree of power and quality of life—a tricky opment based on his six stages theory.
culture-dependent category! Even though desir-
able, people need to be alert concerning the pos- A Case against Ethnocentrism
sibilities for just and fair international sociopolitical Analyzing their interview with a Hindu man
contracts. New trends are always possible but great called Babaji, Shweder and Much (1987) show
efforts will be needed to promote changes toward a the impossibility to follow Kohlberg’s orientation
progressively better planetary balance among differ- regarding the interviewee’s classification. Where a
ent cultures and societies. cognitive-constructivist approach would suggest
The important aspect we have to consider from classifying Babaji into a lower moral judgment
a scientific viewpoint (Wilson, 2007) is that diver- category—conventional stage—Shweder and Much
sity is an essential source of innovation and develop- disagree, and denounce Kohlberg’s ethnocentric
ment, and therefore needs to be preserved. Thus we classificatory system as consisting of a pitfall. Why?
conclude that contextualism indeed makes sense. The answer is that in Hindu culture, acts such as
This is certainly true, but human survival with robbery are condemned not only from a social-
dignity also demands the existence of some basic contractual perspective (conventional reasoning),
general principles of mutual respect, and respect but from a much broader, universal, spiritual, and
for the intensively negotiated conditions for pre- existential framework related to the meaning of life
serving human rights and worthiness. The univer- (postconventional reasoning). Their analyses bring
sal declaration of human rights here plays a vital forth the major role played by culture on topics
role. The acceptance of a broad ethic/moral spec- like morality and ethics, and such deconstruction
trum can allow individuals and societies to abide of the cognitivist teleology expands our knowledge
by negotiated laws of justice and efforts for mutual beyond the ethnocentric boundaries that previ-
understanding. Therefore, it is possible, although ously claimed for universal patterns and standards
not easy, to rely on constant negotiations over the for moral development and evaluation.
dialectical tensions resulting from universalism Shweder and Much (1987) consider everyday
and contextualism, in order to establish ethical life interactions as the relevant site to study moral
principles and norms for social regulations among development. They also claim for the “objective”
humans. In other words, biology and culture do possibility to assess and analyze meanings when the
not necessarily oppose each other, and may jointly researcher can conjecture and distinguish between
operate toward continuous negotiations allowing valid and invalid inferences based on prior knowl-
for both convergence and divergence—i.e., both edge of culture, context, relationships, and prac-
shared basic moral values and multiple expressions tices. The acknowledgment of divinity dimensions
of moral diversity. led Shweder, Much, Mahapatra, and Park (1997)

bra n co 757
to identify three different types of ethics, which are children. Also the case of slavery is worth analyzing:
not mutually exclusive but have different priorities today it is condemned, but for centuries it was seen
depending on culture and history: autonomy, com- as perfectly moral and acceptable by most civilized
munity, and divinity. The distinction of different nations! Ratner thus has a very good point when he
types of morality is also stressed by Gilligan (1982; convincingly shows how history and culture in fact
Brown, Debold, Tappan, & Gilligan, 1991). She determine what is, or is not, classified as moral or
criticizes most authors, particularly Kant’s affiliates, immoral along sociohistorical time.
for the exclusive consideration of reason and justice In addition to denounce the biased, too abstract,
in detriment of care and loyalty. Even though her and noncontextualized cognitive-constructivist theo-
first evidence that women and men were different— ries of moral development, Ratner also criticizes
caused by general dispositions to prioritize justice Gilligan (1982) for not analyzing actual cultural
over care (men) or care over justice (women)— aspects of morality, even though she investigates
was later questioned (Lourenço, 1998), her work gender, situations, and feelings. Other narrativists, as
reveals the complexity of morality, and the existence Tappan (1992), also do not escape from Ratner’s sharp
of principles other than justice, which participate critiques. According to Ratner (2002), just referring
in the dilemmas over right and wrong regarding to and investigating people’s narratives for “recurrent
human experience. words,” “shifts in narrative,” and “emotional reso-
nances, inconsistencies in styles, the use of first, sec-
Radical Culturalism ond or third person voice, turn taking etc [all end up
A typical representative of a radical cultural posi- to] obfuscate the cultural content of moral belief” (p.
tioning is Carl Ratner. Ratner’s cultural perspective 192). He goes on criticizing the “reiteration compul-
(2002) is strongly based on Activity Theory, there- sion” of discursive psychologists like Edwards (1999),
fore being consistent with the views of Leontiev’s and also Gee (1999), when he states that “most work
ideas, also shared by some contemporary fundamen- in discourse analysis, for example, focuses on linguis-
talists. Ratner compares the American and Chinese tic (semiotic) properties of statements and ignores
senses of love and value, and finds that the way each cultural concepts and activities that are embodied in
culture promote one’s responsibility for each other the statement’s content” (Ratner, 2002, p. 128). He
is always based on the quality of cultural activities alleges that most discursive psychologists do not add
mostly observed in specific cultures. He invites anything to the mere words pronounced by research
researchers on the topic of morality to investigate participants, consequently their studies well illustrate
the cultural activities and concepts that mediate an individualistic approach, instead of an actual cul-
and organize morality in specific contexts. Ratner tural approach to complex psychological phenom-
(2002) provides and analyzes various examples such ena. To further emphasize this aspect, Ratner quotes
as abortion (i.e., whether the embryo has a status of Sobel’s appraisal of society’s excessive individualism
person), premarital sex, gender roles, etc. According when he states that:
to him, “cultural concepts stipulate which social
. . . at the outset of the 18th century most people
relationships between individuals deserve to receive
seemed to regard themselves as having porous
help as well as the kind of help that is morally
boundaries and as part of wider or ‘we-self.’ [ . . . ]
appropriate” (p. 187). He argues that prostitution
By the close of this period, the ideal white male was
can be considered as moral in some cultures because
individuated, self-concerned, and determined to
it is a voluntary contract between individuals, with
succeed in a rapacious market economy.”
mutual agreement, and does not involve dishonesty.
(2000, p. 4, in Ratner, 2002)
Therefore, it is a commodity exchange from a capi-
talist perspective, based on the buy-and-sell logic of In a few words, Ratner is a very convincing advo-
free markets. This may sound preposterous or weird cate for a cultural approach for the study of moral-
for some people, but the same dilemma emerges ity. The major problem with Ratner, as I see it, is
when students buy the authorship of manuscripts that based on such extreme denial of individualism
or dissertations from someone willing to sell them. he also denies individuality as well as the stance of
Would consensual contracts and free-market rules self and personal agency, showing an explicit con-
still apply? tempt toward individuals.
Other problematic or dilemmatic issues arise: Even targeted by Ratner, Tappan (1992, 1997,
some people think pornography is innocuous for 1998) can be pointed out as an author who

758 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
represents, under the umbrella of cultural psychol- cultures, and her definition of human development
ogy, a narrative approach to the study of moral emphasizes progressive degrees of individuals’ par-
development. In his investigations, he stresses the ticipation in cultural practices. She draws on results
significance of language for meaning-creation and of many anthropological studies and she herself
attribution processes that pave the ground for moral develops interesting investigations on socializa-
judgment and action. No wonder he also presents tion, among other issues. Rogoff presents and thor-
and actually finds a broad range of variability and oughly discusses the concept of social participation
diversity while studying persons belonging to differ- (Rogoff, 1990, 2003) to explain human develop-
ent cultures, particularly members of different social ment in specific cultural contexts. In her examples,
classes. she informs how some cultures, for instance, mor-
According to Ratner (2002), many qualitative ally value discreetness and humbleness while others
researches are too abstract and do not objectively value bragging and arrogance; also, how some trea-
(concretely) refer to specific values or beliefs, namely, sure autonomy while others stress interdependence.
they just count frequencies of certain words, there- In a similar vein with the work of Margaret Mead
fore the results are too general to add any innova- (1937), Rogoff draws attention to huge contrasts
tion to scientific knowledge about psychological existing between cultures that morally value shar-
phenomena. In defense for a cultural approach that ing and cooperation, in opposition to others that
makes qualitative studies of psychological phenom- proudly promote individualism and competition. In
ena meaningful, Ratner (2002) states: short, she provides substantial evidence for cultural-
ism and contextualism regarding the construction
A cultural psychological analysis transcends the
of dependence versus autonomy, individualism and
subject’s knowledge. The subject is aware of details
collectivism, and many other apparently antagonist
of her psychological functions: however, she is not
practices and values, some of them qualifying to
aware of how these details reflect cultural activities
participate of the domains of morality and ethics.
and concepts. [ . . . ] We may say that a cultural
Paolichi’s (2007) socio-cultural viewpoint calls
psychological analysis goes beyond describing
our attention to the other side of the dialogical rela-
manifest psychological themes that individuals are
tion between culture and individual. He underlines
aware of and delves into latent cultural themes that
the agenciality of the self (i.e., human beings need to
pervade individuals’ psychological phenomena but
be seen as reflexive agents). He stresses the action of
remains outside the individuals’ awareness.
intentional selves in intentional worlds. Narratives
(pp. 178–179)
should, then, be analyzed to find meaningful, plau-
Therefore, the task of cultural psychology is “to sible, and convincing evidences (as Bruner suggests,
remain faithful to what the subjects say, yet tran- 1997) for moral motivation. Paolichi (2007) con-
scend the literal words to apprehend the cultural cludes for the inexistence of hierarchically fixed
meanings embedded in the words [ . . . ]” (Ratner, system of principles, and argues for the possibilities
2002, p. 179). Shweder, very likely, would not of different interpretive frameworks. He elaborates
disagree, since that is also his approach to moral on affect and motivation but he neither expands his
investigations. However, Ratner’s good ideas do not analysis on these topics, nor highlights the role of
necessarily imply that he utilizes a flawless research power relations and the existence of different val-
design. The project he proposes to investigate chil- ues systems within a same society (Bronfenbrenner,
dren’s moral beliefs (Ratner, 2002) presents many 1989).
methodological problems because of excessively
inductive instruments for obtaining children’s nar- Moral Development from a Cultural
ratives, for example. Constructivist Perspective
From a cultural constructivist framework, the
Social Practices and Meaning foundation stone for the ontogenesis of moral val-
Constructions ues, practices, and actions consists of a true amalgam
Another theorist who provides an insightful con- of culture, motivation, and affect. This means that
tribution to the topic, although she does not use the actual ground for the development of ethics and
the concept of morality, is Barbara Rogoff (2003). morality lies in the historically contextualized blend
She analyzes phenomena related to the diversity of culture, affect, cognition, and motivation, which
of social norms, practices and beliefs in different gives rise to a permanent and mutual co-construction

bra n co 759
of values and human actions within social practices. framework populated with semiotic processes to
This perspective does not privilege either the domain understand morality, and alerts about the existence
of semiotics—or meaning-construction processes, of conflicting, ambiguous messages and values that
or the domain of social activities and practices. It call for a detailed and profound analysis.
conceives culture as the result of a historical mutual According to Barth (1993), contemporary
constitution between human social practices and authors have little to offer about values, in contrast
values, and also overcomes the dichotomy between with those of the 1950s and 1960s, and this is why
culture and individual. Social practices canalize we need to bring a constructive and dynamic con-
values that promote social practices and so on and ceptualization of values to the forefront of theoreti-
on. Culture canalizes individuals’ trajectories; and cal psychology (Branco, 2006; Valsiner, Branco, &
active, constructive individuals promote cultural Dantas, 1997). The inference of values and their
changes. This happens even though not according role in moral development, though, can only occur
to a deterministic approach, for indeterminacy also after complex analysis and interpretations of observ-
plays a fundamental role in the development of able actions, cues, and strategies mostly found in
open systems, hence, personal and social develop- communication and metacommunication phenom-
ments (Lyra, Fogel, & Valsiner, 1997). ena (Branco, Pessina, Flores, & Salomão, 2004;
Because of the centrality of meaning co- Fatigante, Fasulo, & Pontecorvo, 2004; Fogel &
constructive processes, and the conceptualization Branco, 1997; Lavelli, Pantoja, Hsu, Messinger, &
of hierarchically organized—though dynamic— Fogel, 2005).
networks of meanings, the study of everyday com- Last but not least, it is worthwhile to discuss the
munication and metacommunication processes is issue of moral intentionality as a “must-be” char-
necessary to make sense of how ethics and moral- acteristic of moral action. The stress put on moral
ity evolve in determined contexts. Values, beliefs, intentionality may be fallacious, and it derives from
and goals consist of the core of human motiva- the excessive emphasis on morality as cognition. No
tional system, which develop according to experi- doubt intentionality is a fundamental ingredient for
ences along microgenesis and ontogenesis. Values moral action; however, such intentionality does not
are conceptualized as those particularly affect-laden need to be explained in terms of morality. The point
beliefs (Valsiner, Branco, & Dantas, 1997), which here is that many people can behave in “moral” ways
offer more resistance to change because of their without being capable of presenting a nice discourse
major function in providing a sense of continuity on the “moral” quality of their own behavior. As
to human self-development (Branco & Madureira, moral values and actions are differently internalized
2008; Branco, Branco, & Madureira, 2008; Branco by different people, such awareness is definitely not
& Valsiner, in press). However difficult, though, necessary to qualify the person’s action as moral. To
even values can eventually change, since the whole keep this in mind helps us to free morality for good
system is open and therefore deeply meaningful from cognitive and linguistic abilities found in dis-
experiences may radically transform developmental courses about sophisticated reasons for one’s own
trajectories (Soares da Silva, 2003). actions. In short, less-educated people can indeed
Scientific knowledge construction has mostly be exceptionally moral.
relied on episteme (related to Plato’s notion of truth),
but a growing number of theorists claim that phro- Virtues as Values
nesis (related to Aristotle’s ideas on wisdom) should In relation to moral values, there is a topic
occupy an equal status concerning knowledge con- rarely mentioned by psychology but very promis-
struction. Human experience transcends and goes ing to be investigated: virtues as values, namely, the
beyond cognitive theories. For too long, develop- arataic dimension of moral development (Camps,
mental psychology constrained itself, as mentioned 2005; Galán, Águila, Blanco, Camps, et al., 2005;
before, to the study of language and cognition. Lourenço, 1998).
When contemporary studies show how affect and Virtue is a psychological category that refers to
motivation are central for meaning-construction the notion of excellence in respect to moral stan-
processes then a new venue is open for actual con- dards (Rosa, 2007). According to Camps (2005), it
sideration of all of human dimensions as parts of a is not right to affirm that in order to bring virtue to
wholesome development (Branco, 2009). Paolichi the forefront we need to go back to small commu-
(2007) argues for the centrality of an interpretation nities where a belonging feeling is easier to develop,

760 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
and where easier identification among individu- and both need to be congruent with the reasons
als makes possible their mutual recognition. The that determine the precious quality of community’s
author criticizes the myths related to the notion of norms, which will allow for the achievement of a
virtue, and proclaims that it is not necessary that level of excellence in the community’s practices.
people share a same language, religion, nor ethnic (Vargas-Machuca, 2005, p. 322)
background to be able to understand that solidar-
ity, mutual respect, tolerance, and responsibility are Consequently, solidary motivation and action
virtues that all individuals, no matter their social are fundamental to provide for moral development
position, must strive to accomplish and develop. at all levels, from institutional to personal inter-
She goes on, saying that: actions. As Vargas-Machuca (2005) well puts it,
“ . . . as a general hypothesis, I sustain that structures
. . . the ethics of principles or pure duty is not of solidarity and solidary motivation/attitudes are
enough, [ . . . ] the procedural ethics is insufficient: engaged in feedforward processes: the first stimu-
it is necessary to complement it with an ethics lates the appearance of the second, and the second
of virtues. Otherwise, we forget or ignore that [improves] the quality of the first”(p. 328).
democracy literally means ‘people’s government,’
demos’ government. The construction of demos must Research Perspectives: The Mutual
be one of the objectives of the ethics of our time. Constitution of Moral Discourse and
(Camps, 2005, p. 28)
Moral Practices
Camps wonders what sort of virtues our demo- Many are the possibilities to investigate moral
cratic societies actually need, and concludes that development from a socio-cultural constructivist
human dignity, independently of time or place, perspective. The work of most cultural psycholo-
will always require individuals and society to pay gists (some already mentioned in the previous sec-
allegiance to virtues (or values) related to univer- tion) do correspond to a theoretical-methodological
sal duties and rights. Without acknowledging the approach in tune with the premises presented here.
existence of basic human duties and rights, directly Our research team has also investigated the issue
linked to corresponding virtues, no freedom, jus- using adapted ethnographic approaches, interviews,
tice, mutual tolerance, and diversity acceptance will as well as microgenetic analysis of both naturalis-
prevail over oppression, prejudice, and injustice. tic observations and filmed interactions during
Moreover, as citizens, we shall actively engage in the structured sessions (e.g., Barrios & Branco, 2010;
promotion of such virtues or values with the aim of Freitas, 1999; Martins, 2000; Palmieri, 2003). As a
constructing democracy. brief illustration, Barrios and Branco (2009) made
Vargas-Machuca (2005) asserts that the virtue use of all of the above mentioned methods. Our aim
of solidarity must be the imperative for democratic was to investigate, within the context of an early
justice. He claims that: child educational institution, the kind of every-
day activities and the dynamics of teacher-students
. . . moral solidarity is not conditioned to mutual interactions in relation to a possible incentive—or
identification, nor to a sense of belonging, nor inhibition—of moral development among children.
even to reciprocity, for its foundation resides in the After direct observations of some groups, and two
recognition, respect and consideration due to other filmed sessions of an activity selected by the teacher
people, and this constitutes the primordial moral herself to “promote” moral development, we pro-
argument, which demands the person to imagine ceeded to interview the teachers, the coordinator,
him/herself in a similar situation as that of other and the principal in order to investigate how they
people. conceptualized moral development and its promo-
(p. 319) tion among children.
The author highlights the role of motivation, The groups of children studied included kids
therefore goals, beliefs and values, when he further between 5 and 6 years old. Results showed a gen-
elaborates: eral absence of conceptual knowledge about moral
development, which was defined by all interviewees
In fact, in order to grant the blooming of virtues as behavioral control, discipline, and obedience;
within political domains, motivation and powerful social skills and good manners were also occasion-
incentives for individuals’ actions are necessary, ally mentioned (Barrios, 2009). The activity selected

bra n co 761
by the teacher to encourage moral development was development can be highly influenced by the quality
particularly expressive concerning such conceptual- of relationships and educative techniques employed
izations. First, she selected a book meant to be used by caregivers—i.e., empathy development depends
with 3- to 4-year-old children. Second, the content on cultural values, rules and practices. Another
of the book consisted of a few assertions, illustrated important branch of biological sciences, ecology,
with pictures, about what a young child could or today poses a dramatic challenge to human societ-
could not do, especially concerning its abilities and ies, meaning the need to share a planetary environ-
difficulties (“I can draw,” “I can play with my friends,” ment characterized by an interconnected world. So
etc. versus “I cannot take medicines by myself,” “I biology as well joins human and social sciences in
cannot hurt the cat,” etc). During the activity, the demanding for a world with basic ethical and moral
teacher read the sentences and showed the pictures negotiated principles, to allow for the successful
to the kids, asked nonsense questions—like “What survival of diverse cultures and societies.
does ‘to draw’ mean?”—to one child at the time, The major challenge for psychologists, in par-
and did not allow them to talk whatsoever. Next, ticular, comprises knowledge construction about
she asked them to draw and do some mimics about how internalization of values occurs. Realizing
the “story.” In sum, no talking, no discussion, only that certain cultural practices canalize certain val-
obedience was required. The microgenetic analysis ues is not enough, so the key for moral develop-
of everyday social interactions plus the interactions ment will demand investigative actions at all levels
that happened during the session clearly revealed a of individual and social lives. Besides the necessary
pattern where discipline, inhibition and elimination construction of a more just society, characterized by
of child-child interactions prevailed. ever-improving economic and political institutions,
Data found in other studies with similar goals everyday life interactions need to be impregnated
carried out by our team within school contexts have with a sense of justice, care, and empathy that tran-
consistently shown teachers’ ignorance concerning spires in most human interactions. Microsystems
not only moral development, but related concepts such as family, school, and other relevant commu-
such as cooperation and prosocial behavior (e.g., nity sites have to be continuously co-constructed in
Branco, 1989, 2003, 2009; Palmieri & Branco, order to entail positive social interactions among
2008; Oliveira, 1999; Salomão, 2001). The conclu- participating individuals.
sions we draw from such results are quite worrisome Imitation and affectivity, together with induc-
and suggest that little—if any—attention is paid tive techniques, which facilitate the development
to the social objectives of school education. Even of empathy, and the utilization of consistent rules
worse, with the exception of Kohlberg’s traditional constructed on the grounds of genuine dialogues
projects, most schools allow hidden curricula to even when people hold divergent positions, have
take care of the development of ethics and morality, shown to be substantially effective (Damon &
often stating explicitly that such issues are solely a Lerner, 2006; Fleer, Hedegaard & Tudge, 2009;
matter of families’ responsibility (Branco, 2009). Valsiner & Connolly, 2003;). Cultural psychology,
though, will particularly remind us to provide for
Practical Perspectives: The Promotion the actual engagement of individuals in cooperative
of Ethics and Moral Development social practices, where moral values are concretely
The socio-cultural constructive theoretical translated into autonomous, respectful, and car-
approach—constantly elaborated within a systemic ing interactions among participants. The power of
framework—opens a vast field of practical perspec- cultural canalization, then, cannot ever be overesti-
tives concerning the promotion of ethics and moral mated (Branco, 2009; Rogoff, 2003; Valsiner, 1989,
development. From genetics, we learn about the 2007).
existence of predispositions for both aggression and
competition, on one hand, and for prosocial behav- Conclusions and Future Directions
iors and cooperation, on the other. The obvious The question of morality [then] would not be the
conclusion is that culture therefore makes the differ- problem of one person, one party or one society, and
ence, and the encouragement of ethics and morality nor would it be an exclusive matter of philosophy or a
does not go against any innate predisposition for particular science. The question of morality concerns
sheer selfishness. In addition, studies about empa- all of us, everyone. It is the central issue of social life,
thy show that its emergence is indeed innate, and its and cannot be dissociated from a democratic, just and

762 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
rational project for humanity along its historical time, the absence of respect, justice, and solidarity. In
both at present as well as in future times. other words, today’s world is plagued by competi-
(Freitag, 1997) tion and individualism that leave little to no room
for moral and prosocial actions among people.
Psychology needs to approach social sciences in gen- Therefore, we have to face the necessity to inves-
eral, particularly anthropology, sociology, history, tigate the complex development of subjective and
and political sciences as already suggested. Here collective goals, values, actions, and interactions
I claim for the need that science further dare to to actively construct a better future for mankind,
examine and carry out the difficult task of unrav- rooted in mutual respect, diversity acceptance, and
eling the complexities of human experience. Of the commitment to promote equality, freedom and
similar importance is to highlight the need for solidarity in everyday life.
the encouragement of reflexivity, autonomy, and Globalization certainly turned all societies,
responsibility at the levels of social institutions and nations, and cultures, no matter their specificities,
individuals. I also stress the relevance of the topic into members of a planetary interdependent net-
of moral development in contemporary globalized work. Like a huge visible and invisible system, tech-
world, for moral neutrality simply does not exist. nology, economy, and cultural practices lead people
What may exist is an attempt to divert our attention from all over the world to surrender to the power of
from the topic or to comply, intentionally or not, the irresistible hegemony created by the media, the
with the prevalent unawareness regarding the issue. Internet, and capitalism. As globalization culturally
Along phylogeny and historical time, human canalizes whole generations of people everywhere,
groups have found different ways to live together, human beings need to confront a historical turn-
intermingling competition, cooperation, and indi- ing point, namely, how to collaboratively develop
vidualism in many distinct versions. Periods of shared ethics and moral guidelines to make social
war and peace characterized our history ever since. relations viable, from everyday interactions to inter-
Political and religious leaders as well as intellectual national negotiations. Thus, there is an unavoidable
personalities contributed in multiple ways to guide need to engage in meaningful interpersonal and
people and civilizations along history. Although international dialogues. As ethics and moral issues
many paved the road for the construction of proso- are a fundamental aspect of our coexistence, the
cial values and practices, some stood out claiming topic will necessarily become a must-investigate-
for intolerance, inequality, and prejudice (e.g., discuss-and-negotiate agenda, which will perma-
Hitler), and many created a kind of moral void— nently develop—hopefully—into promising peaceful
among them Freud, Nietzche, and Marx—as they and productive social relations at all possible levels.
overemphasized the supremacy of either individuals Within the realms of psychology, a lot can
or collectivities. This sort of trap—radical individ- be done in order to contribute to the achieve-
ualism or collectivism—we can no longer endorse. ment of an increasingly peaceful and better world.
As Lash (1987) puts it, we cannot give our sup- Developmental contexts such as family, school,
port to societies that actively encourage extreme entertaining, and leisure sites should be carefully
individualism, narcissism, and the nurturance of studied to unveil the actual everyday processes that
a minimal self. Competition and individualism, continuously create and promote practices and val-
which facilitate aggressivity, are counter-productive ues too often incompatible with ethics and morality.
for teamwork, and teamwork requires cooperative Awareness of activities’ structures and communica-
efforts that have proved much more effective than tion and metacommunication mechanisms and
tough rivalry among individuals. Competition and strategies—which create subtle beliefs related to
individualism, or the annihilation of individuality, prejudice and injustice—will certainly consist of a
all create a lot of ambiguity and personal frustra- first step. The role of the media, the internet, vid-
tion, for even within the context of global capital- eogames—i.e., the industry of cultural standards
ism, collaborative efforts are exceptionally needed and individualistic values demands serious inves-
at most levels, including socio-affective support tigation. Scientific psychological knowledge will
and friendly actions. As a result of this lack of then help parents, teachers, and policy makers to
moral reflexivity and action, most people complain find more efficient ways to foster moral develop-
today about the excesses of violence, hostility, social ment. New institutional proposals, the implemen-
indifference, very low levels of empathy, as well as tation of novel practices, and eventual interventions

bra n co 763
will also be necessary to encourage moral develop- psychology. In T. Wren (Ed.), The moral domain: Essays in the
ment according to the principles of democracy and ongoing discussion between philosophy and social sciences (pp.
38–79). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
freedom with responsibility. Kohlberg’s welcome Blasi, A. (1999). Emotions and moral motivation. Journal for the
contributions concerning dialogue and group com- Theory of Social Behavior, 29, 1–19.
munication should be extended, and new perspec- Branco, A. U. (2009). Cultural practices, social values, and child-
tives for educational and cultural change can emerge hood education. In M. Fleer, M. Hedegaard, & J. Tudge
and be put into practice. (Eds.), World Yearbook of Education 2009–Childhood studies
and the impact of globalization: Policies and practices at global
Evidently, scientific transdisciplinary investiga- and local levels (pp. 44–66). London: Routledge.
tion will be needed, as well as permanent discus- Branco, A. U. (2006). Crenças e práticas culturais: Co-construção
sions about alternative approaches to make sense e ontogênese de valores sociais. [Cultural practices and
of, and to promote ethics, morality, and moral beliefs: Co-construction and ontogenesis of social values].
development within society. Consequently psychol- Revista Pro-Posições–UNICAMP, 17, 139 – 155.
Branco, A. U. (2003). Social development in cultural context:
ogy, together with other social sciences, will face Cooperative and competitive interaction patterns in peer
the challenge to develop theoretical perspectives relations. In J. Valsiner & K. Connolly (Eds.), Handbook of
that take into account the systemic, complex, and developmental psychology (pp. 238–256). London: Sage.
dynamic nature of the topic. These efforts will help Branco, A. U. (2001). Contextual, interactional, and subjective
explain the mutual constitution of cultural prac- dimensions of cooperation and competition: A co-construc-
tivist analysis. In S. Chaiklin (Ed.), The theory and practice
tices (activities) and cultural meanings (semiotic of cultural-historical psychology (pp. 107–123). Aarhus,
domain), as well as the development of moral indi- Denmark: Aarhus University Press.
viduals (subjectivities) and societies (collectivities). Branco, A. U. (1998). Cooperation, competition and related
This challenge, though, has to be taken not just by issues: A co-constructive approach. In M. C. Lyra &
psychological and social sciences, but also by all J. Valsiner (Orgs.), Child development within culturally struc-
tured environments (Vol. 4). Construction of psychological
diverse fields of knowledge and human activities so processes in interpersonal communication. Norwood, NJ:
we can jointly find out and encourage developmen- Ablex Publishing Corporation.
tal changes toward justice and happiness. Branco, A. U. (1989). Socialização na pré-escola: O papel da pro-
fessora e da organização das atividades no desenvolvimento de
interações sociais entre crianças [Socialization in preschool:
References The role of teacher and activities in the development of child-
Arendt, H. (2000). Eichmann em Jerusalem. São Paulo: Schwarcz child interactions]. Doctoral dissertation, University of São
Ltd. Paulo, Brazil.
Barrios, A. (2009). Desenvolvimento sociomoral em criancas da Branco, A. U., Branco, A. L., & Madureira, A. F. (2008). Self
educacao infantil: Uma perspectiva sociocultural construtivista development and the emergence of new i-positions: Emotions
[Sociomoral development in preschool children: A socio- and self-dynamics. Studia Psychologica (Bratislava), 6, 23–40.
cultural constructivist perspective]. Master dissertation, Branco, A. U., & Madureira, A. F. (2008). Dialogical self in
University of Brasilia, Brazil. action: The emergence of self-positions among complex
Barrios, A., & Branco, A. U. (2010, October). Desenvolvimento emotional and cultural dimensions. Estudios de Psicología,
moral: Estudo das concepções de professores da educação infantil 29, 319–332.
na perspectiva sociocultural construtivista. [Moral development: Branco, A. U., & Mettel, T. P. L. (1995). O processo de canali-
A study of early education teachers’ conceptualizations from zação cultural das interações criança-criança na pré-escola.
a sociocultural constructivist perspective]. Paper presented at [Cultural canalization processes of child-child interactions in
the 40th Meeting of SBP (Brazilian Society of Psychology), preschool]. Psicologia: Teoria e Pesquisa, 11, 13–22.
Curitiba, PR, Brazil. Branco, A. U., Pessina, L., Flores, A., & Salomão, S. (2004).
Barth, F. (1993). Are values real? The enigma of naturalism in A sociocultural constructivist approach to metacommunica-
the anthropological interpretaion of values. In M. Hechter, tion in child development. In A. U. Branco & J. Valsiner
L. Nadel, & R. Michod (Eds.), The origin of values. (Eds.), Communication and metacommunication in human
Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter. development (pp. 3–32). Greenwich, CT: Information Age
Bergman, R. (2004). Identity as motivation: Toward a theory of Publishing Inc.
moral self. In K. Daniel, D. K. Lapsey, & D. Narvaez (Eds.), Branco, A. U., & Valsiner, J. (in press). Cultural psychology of
Moral development, self, and identity (pp. 21–46). Mahwah, human values. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Bronfenbrenner, U. (1989). Ecological Systems Theory. In
Blasi, A. (2004). Moral functioning: Moral understanding and R. Vasta (Org.), Annals of child development (Vol. 6)
personality. In K. Daniel, D. K. Lapsey, & D. Narvaez (pp. 187–249). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
(Eds.), Moral development, self, and identity (pp. 335–347). Brown, L., Debold, E., Tappan, M., & Gilligan, C. (1991).
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Reading narratives of conflict and choice for self and moral
Blasi, A. (1983). Moral cognition and moral action: A theoretical voices: A relational method. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L.
perspective. Developmental Review, 3, 178–210. Gewirtz (Eds.), Handbook of moral behavior and develop-
Blasi, A. (1990). How should psychologists define morality? ment (Vol. 2: Research) (pp. 25–62). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Or, the negative side-effects of philosophy’s influence on Erlbaum Associates.

764 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
Bruner, J. (1997). Atos de significação. Porto Alegre, Brazil: Killen, M., & Hart, D. (1995). Morality in everyday life:
ArtMed Editora. Developmental perspectives. New York: Cambridge University
Camps, V. (2005). El concepto de virtud pública. In P. C. Galán, Press.
R. Águila, D. Blanco, V. Camps et al. (Eds.), Democracia y Kohlberg, L. (1970). Education for justice: A modern statement
virtudes cívicas (pp. 19–40). Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva. of the Platonic view. In N. Sizer & T. Sizer (Eds.), Moral
Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1993). The uniting of self and moral- education: Five lectures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
ity in the development of extraordinary moral commit- Press.
ment. In G. G. Noam & T. E. Wren (Eds.), The moral self Kohlberg, L. (1984). The psychology of moral development. San
(pp. 149–174). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Francisco: Harper & Row.
Cole, M. (1998). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline. Kurtines, W. M., & Gewirtz, J. L. (1991). Handbook of moral
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. behavior and development. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Daniel, K., Lapsey, D. K. & Narvaez, D. (2004). Moral devel- Associates.
opment, self, and identity. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Lapsley, D. K., & Narvaez, D. (2004). A social-cognitive approach
Associates. to the moral personality. In K. Daniel, D. K. Lapsey, &
Damon, W. (1984). Self-understanding and moral develop- D. Narvaez (Eds.), Moral development, self, and identity
ment from childhood to adolescence. In W. M. Kurtines & (pp. 189–212). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behaviour, and moral Lash, C. (1987). O mínimo eu: A sobrevivência psíquica em tempos
development (pp. 109–127). New York: Wiley. difíceis. [The minimal self: Psychic survival in difficult times].
Damon, W., and Lerner, R. (2006) Handbook of child psychology. São Paulo, SP: Editora Brasiliense.
New York: John Wiley and Sons. Lavelli, M., Pantoja, A. P. F., Hsu, H., Messinger, D., & Fogel,
Durkheim, E. (1973). Les régles de la method sociologique. Paris: A. (2005). Using microgenetic designs to study change pro-
PUF. cesses. In D. M. Teti (Org.), Handbook of research methods in
Edwards, D. (1999). Emotion discourse. Culture & Psychology, developmental science (pp. 40–65). Baltimore, MD: Blackwell
5(3), 271–291. Publishers.
Fatigante, M., Fasulo, A., & Pontecorvo, C. (2004). This is not a Leeds-Hurwitz, W. (1995). Social approaches to communication.
dinner: Metacommunication in family dinnertime conversa- New York: The Guilford Press.
tions. In A. U. Branco & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Communication Lewis, M., & Haviland-Jones, J. (2004). Handbook of emotions.
and metacommunication in human development. Greenwood, New York: The Guilford Press.
CT: Information Age Publishers. Lourenço, O. (1998). Psicologia de desenvolvimento moral:
Fleer, M., Hedegaard, M., & Tudge, J. (2009). Childhood studies Teoria, dados e implicações.[Psychology of moral develop-
and impact of globalization: Policies and practices at global and ment: Theory, data and implications]. Coimbra, Portugal:
local levels. London: Routledge. Livraria Almedina.
Fogel, A., Branco, A. U. (1997). Metacommunication as a Lyra, M. C., Fogel, A., & Valsiner, J. (1997). Dynamics and inde-
source of indeterminism in relationship development. In terminism in developmental and social processes. Mahwah, NJ:
M. C. Lyra, A. Fogel, & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Dynamics and inde- Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
terminism in developmental and social processes (pp. 65–92). Martins, L. C. (2000). Crenças e valores morais em pré-adoles-
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. centes: Uma análise sócio-cultural construtivista em con-
Ford, D. H., & Lerner, R. M. (1992). Developmental systems textos comunicativos semi-estruturados [Moral values and
theory: An integrative approach. London: Sage. beliefs in adolescents: A sociocultural constructivist analysis
Freitag, B. (1997). Itinerários de Antígona: A questão da mor- within semi-structured communicative contexts]. Doctoral
alidade. [Antigona’s itinerary: The question of morality]. dissertation, University of Brasilia, Brazil.
Campinas, Brazil: Papirus Editora. Mead, M. (1937). Cooperation and competition among primitive
Freitas, J. (1999). Orientações para crenças acerca do desenvol- peoples. New York: McGraw-Hill.
vimento moral das crianças na perspectiva dos pais [Parent’s Morin, E., & Prigogine, I. (2000). A sociedade em busca de valores
beliefs orientations concerning children’s moral develop- [Society in search for values]. Lisboa, Portugal: Instituto
ment]. Master dissertation, University of Brasilia, Brazil. Piaget.
Galán, P. C., Águila, R., Blanco, D., Camps, V. et al. (2005). Nucci, L. (2004). Reflections on the moral self construct. In
Democracia y virtudes cívicas. Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva. K. Daniel, D. K. Lapsey, & D. Narvaez (Eds.), Moral devel-
Gee, J. P. (1999). An introduction to discourse analysis: Theory and opment, self, and identity (pp. 111–132). Mahwah, NJ:
method. New York: Routledge. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Oliveira, S. M. (1999). Crencas e valores sobre educacao e desen-
University Press. volvimento de criancas de dois a tres anos de idade [Values
Habermas, F. (1990). Justice and solidarity. In T. Wren (Ed.), The and beliefs about education and development of two-
moral domain (pp. 224–251). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. tothree-year-old children]. Master’s dissertation, University
Habermas, J. (1991). Escritos sobre la moralidad y la eticidad. of Brasilia, Brazil.
Buenos Aires: Paidós. Palmieri, M. W. (2003). Cooperação, competição e indi-
Hegel, G. F. (1999). Coleção Os Pensadores. São Paulo: Nova vidualismo na pré-escola: Análise de contextos de
Cultura. desenvolvimento[Cooperation, competition and individ-
Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and moral development: ualism in preschool: Developmental contexts’ analysis].
Implications for caring and justice. New York: Cambridge Doctoral dissertation, University of Brasília, Brazil.
University Press. Palmieri, M., & Branco, A. U. (2008). Educação infantil,
Kant, I. (1994). Crítica da razão prática. Artur Morão, Trad. cooperação e competição: Analise microgenética sob uma
Lisboa: Edições 70. perspectiva sociocultural. [Early education, cooperation

bra n co 765
and competition: A sociocultural microgenetic analysis]. cultural influence. In P. Oliner, S. Oliner, L. Baron, L. Blum,
Psicologia Escolar e Educacional, 11, 365–378. D. Krebs, & M. Smolenska (Eds.), Embracing the other:
Paolichi, P. (2007). The institutions inside: Self, morality, and Philosophical psychological, and historical perspectives on altru-
culture. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge hand- ism (pp. 390–412). New York: New York University Press.
book of sociocultural psychology (pp. 560–575). New York: Staub, E. (1989). The roots of evil: The origins of genocide and
Cambridge University Press. other group violence. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
Peirce, C. S. (1967). Annotated catalog of the papers of Charles Press.
S. Peirce. R. S. Robin (Ed.). Amherst, MA: University of Tappan, M. B. (1992). Texts and contexts: Language, culture, and
Massachusetts Press. the development of moral functioning. In L. T. Winegar &
Ratner, C. (2002). Cultural psychology: Theory and method. J. Valsiner (Eds.), Children’s development within social context
New York: Plenum. (pp. 93–117). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. Tappan, M. (1997). Language, culture, and moral develop-
New York: Oxford University Press. ment: A Vygotskian perspective. Developmental Review, 17,
Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking: Cognitive develop- 78–100.
ment in social context. New York: Oxford University Press. Tappan, M. (1998). Moral education in the zone of proximal
Rosa, A. (2007). Dramaturgical actuations and symbolic com- development. Journal of Moral Education, 27(2), 141–161.
munication: Or how beliefs make up reality. In J. Valsiner & Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1998). Dynamic systems theory. In
A. Rosa (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psycho- W. Damon & R. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of child psychol-
logy (pp. 293–317). New York: Cambridge University Press. ogy, 5th ed., Vol. 1: Theoretical models of human development
Rousseau, J. (1966). Émile ou de l’education. Paris: Garnier- (pp. 563–634). New York: Wiley.
Flammarion. Turiel, E. (2002). The culture of morality: Social development, con-
Salomão, S. (2001). Motivação social: Comunicação e meta- text, and conflict. New York: Cambridge University Press.
comunicação na co-construção de crenças e valores no Valsiner, J. (2007). Culture in minds and societies. New Delhi,
contexto de interações professora-alunos [Social motiva- India: Sage.
tion: Communication and metacommunication in the Valsiner, J. (2005). Soziale und emotionale Entwicklungsaufgaben
co-construction of values and beliefs in teacher-students im kulturellen Kontext. In J. Asendorpf & H. Rauh (Eds.).
interactions]. Master’s dissertation, University of Brasilia, Enzyklpadie der psychologie, Vol. 3: Soziale, emotionale und
Brazil. Personlichkeitsentwicklung. Gottingen, Germany: Hogrefe.
Saussure (1966). Course in general linguistics. New York: Valsiner, J. (1987). Culture and the development of children’s
McGraw-Hill. action. Chichester, USA: Wiley.
Schnitman, D. F. (1996). Novos paradigmas, cultura e subjetivi- Valsiner, J., Branco, A. U., & Dantas, C. (1997). Socialization
dade. Porto Alegre, Brazil: ArtMed Editora. as co-construction: Parental belief orientations and hetero-
Shweder, R., Much, N. Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (1997). The geneity of reflection. In J. E. Grusec & L. Kuczynsky (Eds.),
“big three” of morality (autonomy, community, and divinity) Parenting and children’s internalization of values (pp. 283–306).
and the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A. Brandt, & New York: Wiley.
P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health (pp. 119–169). London: Valsiner, J., & Cairns, R. (1992). Theoretical perspectives on
Routledge. conflict and
Shweder, R. A., & Much, N. C. (1987). Determinations of mean- development. In C. V. Shantz & W. W. Hartup (Eds.), Conflict
ing: Discourse and moral socialization. In W. M. Kurtines & in child and
J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Moral development through social interac- adolescent development (pp. 15–35). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
tion (pp. 197–244). New York: Wiley & Sons. University Press.
Shweder, R. (1991). Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cul- Valsiner, J., & Connolly, K. J. (2003). Handbook of developmental
tural psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. psychology. London: Sage.
Soares da Silva, A. P. S. (2003). Continuidades e descontinui- Valsiner, J., & Rosa, A. (2007). The Cambridge handbook of socio-
dades na narrativa de história de vida de homens que tiveram cultural psychology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
envolvimento com o crime [Continuities and discontinuities Vargas-Machuca, R. (2005). Solidaridad. In P. C. Galán,
in biographical narratives of men previously involved with R. Águila, D. Blanco, V. Camps et al. (Eds.), Democracia
crime]. Doctoral dissertation, University of São Paulo, Brazil. y virtudes cívicas (pp. 311–338). Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva.
Staub, E. (2003). The psychology of good and evil: Why children, Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
adults, and other groups help and harm others. New York: University Press.
Cambridge University Press. Wilson, E. O. (2007). Biophilia and the conservation ethic. In
Staub, E. (1993). Individual and group selves: Motivation, D. J. Penn & I. Mysterud (Eds.), Evolutionary perspectives
morality, and evolution. In G. Noam & T. Wren (Eds.), The on environmental problems (pp. 249–257). Piscataway, NJ:
moral self (pp. 337–358). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Transaction Publishers.
Staub, E. (1992). The origins of caring, helping and non-aggres- Wren, T. (1991). Caring about morality: Philosophical perspectives
sion: Parental socialization, the family system, schools, and in moral psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

766 values and so ci o -cult ur a l pr act i ces: path ways to m ora l developm en t
CHAPTER

The Intergenerational Continuity


36 of Values

A. Bame Nsamenang

Abstract
Intergenerational values generate from cultural scripts and family exchange systems, which induce family
solidarity that sustains intergenerational transmission and continuity of values. Intergenerational values
vary by culture, family form, and individuation into individualistic or interdependent norms, among
other values. Across history, family values have changed and are changing in response to micro-familial
and macro-societal factors, technological transformations, and globalizing forces. In consequence, family
profiles are changing, exemplified by an accentuating visibility of multiple generations of grandchildren
and grandparents in households in variable degrees across Minority- and Majority-World countries.
Regrettably, intergenerational research hitherto has privileged the Euro-American nuclear family form in
a world of diverse family forms. Equity and objectivity in science oblige attention to the intergenerativity
of family forms in its global diversity. A learning research position could lead to the discovery of the
changing intergenerational phenomena of the Majority World’s extended families in context to enrich
and extend theory and the knowledge base of intergenerativity. This disposition can prime theoretic
innovation and methodological creativity to respect the diversity that exists to be discovered. Since
intergenerational phenomena traverse several disciplinary boundaries, it seems plausible to adopt a
multidisciplinary research framework.
Keywords: family forms, multigenerational families, social-exchange norms, family solidarity, intergenera-
tional values transmission, intergenerational continuity of values, intergenerational discontinuity of values,
multidisciplinary research approach

Whether human origins are viewed as crea- species by transmitting their genes and traits to
tionism or evolutionism, the human being can- their offspring.
not be disjoined from nature. Biologists position This chapter is a discursive triangulation of my
evolution as the process by which populations work, selective archival research, and my ongoing
of species, including humans, acquire and trans- participant observation since 1993 as an instruc-
mit their traits across generations (Baig, 2002). tor in a yearly hands-on, faith-based course on
Evolutionary theory explains the survival and HIV/AIDS lay-counselor training (Nsamenang &
transmission of human genes and other traits by Loomis, 2003) in which trainees have been mul-
way of natural selection (Wood, 2011; All About tigenerational, mixed-sex cohorts. The discourse
Science.org, 2011). Biological evolution entails sidelines the obscure debate over evolution as “fact
the changes in the genetic material of a popula- and theory,” “fact not theory,” and “only a theory,
tion of species over time. The modern theory of not a fact” (Moran, 1993; Muller, 1959; Religious
evolution posits that individuals best suited to Tolerance.org., 2011) to refer tacitly to evolution
their environment of adaptability perpetuate the simply as changes in any trait or gene frequency in

767
a population of organisms from one generation to Social evolution speaks to “a past that is cul-
the next. In this sense, evolution (e.g., Smocovitis, turally present as tradition” and that has been
1996) includes: (1) differences in trait composition “encoded in customs rather than in genes and trans-
between isolated populations over many generations mitted socially rather than biologically” (LeVine,
that may result in the origin of new species in both 1974, p. 227). Culture, as social heritage and cul-
biological and social senses, and (2) all living organ- tural tools, nudges human values in the direction
isms alive today are theorized to have descended of a given community’s cultural meaning systems.
from a common ancestor (or ancestral gene pool), As Maquet (1972) asserts, the universal humanity
therein precluding the idea of creationism. in the human genome shapes into diverse specific
Ambitiously, the chapter is framed to incite a individualities in different contexts, hence the vari-
shift of discourse and research focus on intergenera- ety of intergenerational continuity of values across
tional transmission of values from privileging Euro- the globe.
American nuclear family orientations to researching Visualization of human nature and social evo-
family values in the context of the world’s cultures. lution occur within the meaning systems of the
My primary mission is to point to how different diverse cultural communities worldwide, albeit not
enculturation regimes and social exchange systems with the same lenses and epistemology of scientists.
shape intergenerational learning and how different Thus, cultural worldviews or frames of reference to
family forms endeavor to sustain continuity of atti- the universe exude mindsets, human motives, and
tudes and values through varied cultural tools and intergenerational values as well as mediate their
processes. I believe different family forms and inter- transmission channels. Soyinka (1990, p. 37) pos-
dependent versus individualistic exchange norms ited “an ethnocultural reality, a humane quality
are responsible, at least in part, for the global diver- which uniquely informs human artifacts, music,
sity of intergenerational values. Although Western poetry, and philosophy”, and obviously family soli-
cultures privilege adults with child care, African darity and support networks, as a “crucial factor of
cultures separate child-care skills from the life human existence.” Intergenerational continuity
period of parenthood and situate child-care train- of values connotes evolution in the sense of both
ing as a familial commitment for children to learn biological and social transmission across genera-
(Nsamenang, 2008) as part of their shared manage- tions. This fact highlights the evolutionary basis of
ment, caregiving, and socially distributed support grandparents to family security (Silverstein, 2009).
of the family (Weisner, 1997). Accordingly, African Worldwide, parents and grandparents seek to pass
family values socialize children into social exchange on their values and the exchange norms of their
norms that commit them to sibling and elder care families to their next generations, hoping to ensure
(Nsamenang, 2010a). not merely the survival of their offspring, but that of
During development, boys and girls build up their culture as well (Reagan, 1996). In fact, long-
a “parental identity” (Goodnow, 1988, p. 289) lived and supportive grandparents who served as
within the cultural contexts in which they are surrogate parents (in cases of parental death, envi-
parented; sibling caregiving primes them gradu- ronmental threats, or parental absence resulting
ally into the parental role. The “. . . process and the from migration, imprisonment, or other causes)
experience of childhood does not end with childhood enhanced the survival chances of their grandchil-
itself. It remains within all of us as a live and informa- dren (e.g., Dudley-Grant, 2001).
tive experience that influences our current and future The impetus for this essay is the fact that the con-
relationships and activities” (Neven, 1996, p. 13). In tinuity of intergenerational interconnectedness in
some cultures, children are cared for by their par- family systems is increasingly being threatened and
ents or grandparents with the understanding that shattered by a flux of unrestrained social schisms
children will take care of parents and grandparents and innovations in information and communica-
in their old age. In the Caribbean, child care may tion technologies. Of course, there are obvious
not be provided only by the extended family, but policy implications for intergenerativity research
may also involve dependable adults in the com- to understand how to sustain cultural identity as
munity (Dudley-Grant, 2001). Understanding the enshrined in the United Nations’ (UN) Convention
structure and function of different family forms can of the Rights of the Child (1989).
therefore enrich and extend intergenerativity dis- Indeed, intergenerational research ought to
course and research. figure out how to promote cultural identity and

768 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


simultaneously equip the next generations, particu- include a wide circle of kin and servants. In Senegal
larly in Africa, with the right techno-cognitive val- and much of Africa, the concept of family is fluid
ues and contextually suitable skills to cope with and (Vandewiele, 1981); it sometimes includes a polyg-
make progress in a competitive, knowledge-driven amous man and his wives and children, spousal
global community. This is important in the face of kin, and friends. In blended families —the result of
the aversive attitudes to immigrants reported around divorce or the death of a spouse followed by remar-
the globe. So, how would research contribute to riage and a new generation of children—mothers
“cultivating” mindsets and value systems inclusive of and fathers can be both biological parents and step-
and tolerant of the growing presence of immigrants parents simultaneously, along with stepsiblings.
and refugees in both Minority and Majority World Communal families also exist in many parts of the
countries? If ethnocultural reality is a universal but world. These families are usually extended families
varying feature of cultures, then, we must problem- living in one household, including father, children,
atize scientific narratives and programmatic research brothers, sisters, aunts, uncles, cousins, elders or
that have regarded or interpreted the expression or grandparents. Sometimes such societies are matriar-
assertion of some ethnocultural realities as positive chal, with everyone living under roof being related
and useful but considered others as negative and through a grandmother, mother, or aunt; some
detrimental from instinctual inclinations and not societies are patriarchal, with everyone being related
from research evidence. through a grandfather, father, or uncle. Everyone
The intergenerational stake hypothesis (Bengtson within this community has his or her own share of
& Kuypers, 1971) holds that children and parents responsibilities and often every home within the
diverge on family solidarity measures because they community helps with child care, elder care, and
manifest different expectations and understandings the destitute.
of filial relationship status. Intergenerational differ- The growing number of immigrant families in
ences in value perceptions result from changes in different countries and their acculturative values
the timing of life-course events for parents and chil- increases and complicates family values. It is critical
dren (Hareven, 1994). Instead of timing events in to remark that throughout the world, family patterns
concert with the family’s collective needs and soli- vary greatly between urban and rural settings and
darity, children display a more individualized tim- reflect such differences as ethnicity, class structure,
ing wedged on peer norms, for example. Although and religion, among others. Differences in family
parents are concerned with the continuity and inter- forms and demographic behaviors are more striking
generational transmission of values they have found for migrants to Europe and North America from
useful and important in life, children focus mainly developing countries. The immigrants bring into
on the differences in the two generations’ value sys- their recipient communities the demographic pro-
tems in an attempt to establish independence from files and more traditional exchange values of their
their parents. When children notice confusions and natal cultures and agrarian economies. However,
ambiguities in their interactions with adults, they intergenerational values research continues to be
endeavor to transform them into familiar routines draped in conventional theories and methods of the
of their peer culture (Carsaro, 1990). But children dominant culture, therein losing sight of the rich
are not mere accommodators of adult norms and diversity of intergenerational values that coexist. In
values; they are also creative social producers of their this sense, North American counseling perspectives
own worlds (Nsamenang & Lamb, 1995). tend to gloss over the intergenerational values of
The next section presents forms of family around most African refugee and immigrant families.
the globe but without a judgmental eye. Across times, family structure took a variety
of forms throughout the world and increasingly
Family Forms around the World adjusted to continuously changing family circum-
A variety of family forms rather than a universal, stances. Such diverse data sources as history, eth-
single family form is found around the world. In a nography, sociology, demography, and law, among
nutshell, the principal family structures and house- others, reveal the human family as an institution
hold patterns are nuclear, extended, and blended, and not a biological fact founded on the natural
albeit with several other variants. The nuclear house- bond of consanguinity. That is, intergenerational
hold contains two generations, parents and chil- exchange values need not be family-based or
dren. Extended families are multigenerational and biological.

n sa m en a n g 769
Early scholars of family history applied Darwin’s consanguineous triangle of husband-wife-children,
biological theory of evolution in their theory of relatively isolated from other social connections.
family systems, therein reinforcing the idea of social This has been called the oedipal model of the family,
and cultural evolution. This theory was quite popu- and it is a form of patriarchal family.
lar until it was challenged in the 1980s by sociologi- Such systems generally assume that the mother’s
cal theories, most notably structural functionalism. husband also serves as the biological father but in
Research was framed by and reported mainly within many societies around the world, social fathers take
the kinship terminologies of the Western family. care of children without regard to whose paternity is
The family types of pre-industrial Europe belonged involved. For example, “African grandfathers, uncles,
into two basic groups, the simple household system, stepfathers, foster-fathers, older brothers, cousins,
i.e., the nuclear family, and the joint family house- family friends, and other men who take responsibil-
hold, i.e., the extended family (Kertzer & Barbagli, ity to care for non-biological children do play and
2002). In the joint family household system, early have played” the paternal role (Nsamenang, 2010b,
marriages allowed for multigenerational families to p. 388). Emphasis on the nuclear family has lured
form. The organization of the pre-industrial fam- some researchers and interveners into thinking about
ily is now believed to be similar to modern types and working on the nuclear family as the “right” kind
of family (Geller, 1994). Many sociologists used to of family. This belief is an incredibly misinformed
believe that the nuclear family was the product of one as across the globe at any point in human social
industrialization, but Colón and Colón (2001) cite history there have been all sorts of views on what
evidence proposed by Peter Laslett suggesting that families are and how they are composed.
the causality is reversed, and that industrialization In some families, a woman may have children
was so effective in Northwestern Europe specifically with more than one man or a man may have chil-
because the preexistence of the nuclear family fos- dren with more than one woman. For collateral
tered its development. The extended kinship is very relatives, more classificatory terms come into play,
strong in non-Western cultures and any event in the terms that do not reflect nor build on the terms
individual’s life is, in principle, a group concern. used within the nuclear family. The nuclear family,
Family relations and dynamics were characterized at least in the research literature, appears to be the
by patriarchal relations and gendered roles, early most researched family form and the one form that
marriage, low divorce rate, and low age at first birth international advocacy and the donor community,
(Cliquet, 2003). In Nigeria, for instance, the eldest including UN agencies, promote as best-suited for
male is the patriarch and is the head of not just the family welfare policies and child-rights programs.
immediate, but the entire extended family. In that This policy positioning is deeply regrettable, as it
role, he is the adjudicator of family disputes—from pays attention mainly to a minority of family real-
the personal to those about division of the family’s ities and the English-language literature, largely
wealth. He’s also the spiritual leader of the family bypassing other family forms and literature in non-
(Nossier, 2003). There was also childbearing into English languages. This bias may be attributed to
higher ages, as well as high fertility and larger house- the capturing impact of Western-Christian civiliz-
hold size. ing crusades and the Euro-American hegemonic
control of the world. In large measure the para-
Cultural Blinders: The Oedipal Model graphs that follow draw content from the website:
of Family Theophanes(2010).AroundtheWorldinSearchofDi
Although some families stress the importance fferentFormsof“Family”. Retrieved on October 9,
and authority of the father (patriarchy), others give 2010.
primacy to that of the mother (matriarchy). Other
families are endogamous in character, which per- Other Family Forms
mits marriage within a specific group or they may Polyamory translates quite literally as “multiple
have an extreme exogamous emphasis, which taboos loves” (Weitzman, 1999). It is the practice that con-
marriage within closely related kin. Most Western senting adults decide to create marriage-like bonds
societies employ kinship terminology based on with more than one individual at a time (Barker,
conjugal or nuclear families, which they regard as 2005). It is distinct from polygamy and polyandry in
having a degree of relative mobility. They seem to the fact that it is usually composed of multiple per-
hold the idea that there is only one type of family, a sons of either sex and if it ends up in a harem-type

770 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


system this is generally coincidental, not intentional. in favor of Western societies. Programmatic research
Everyone within the group does not necessarily have in non-Western societies such as Africa is noticeable
to share sexual bonds but in these networks emo- by its scarcity and what little research has been done
tional bonds are always of overriding importance. has largely been in comparison with European and
Pockets of polyamorous groupings around the American datasets. As such, it has been reported
world are not open about their choice because of within the conceptual and family systems of
the strong prejudice cultures have regarding it (see Eurocentric epistemes and normative systems.
Allan & Harrison, 2002). Polyandry is probably the Compared to Western societies, non-Western com-
rarest form of family ever practiced by humanity at munities have been little-researched in their own
any point in history. It is speculated that with the terms; hence we know little about the contextual
combined statistics of modern and ancient cultures, situativity of their intergenerational solidarity and
polyandry only makes up less than 2% of the world values transmission, except for few studies captured
population (Levine, 1988). It is a practice in which in socio-cultural surveys (e.g., Colón & Colón,
one wife will marry several husbands who are usually 2001). Scientific discourse and research reports tend
brothers. This is matriarchal society at its extreme. to place fateful values on the so-called “researched”
The wife will bear children and the husbands will societies, implying non-Caucasian peoples, with
share duties within and outside the home. This prac- concepts whose meanings are variable and incon-
tice is sometimes used when one husband is rarely sistent in the literature. For example, the African-
home (e.g., a sailor, hunter, migrant worker, mer- Caribbean family has been presented as exhibiting
chant, etc.) so another may stay to care for the wife unique mating and childrearing patterns and the
and children. It can be used as a form of popula- emotional availability and social ties of their men to
tion control, as one woman can only have so many children are unclear (Sharpe 1996). With this state
children in her lifetime but men can potentially sire of the field, it seems plausible, in this section, to
dozens, if not more. present only a synopsis and broad overview of the
Polygyny or polygamy is a relationship in which sparse intergenerativity literature available to the
one husband has at least two wives. Unlike polyan- author and to devote more space to examining what
dry the wives are usually unrelated (Ridley, 1995). the pluralism of intergenerational values that exist
Polygyny is practiced in some Middle Eastern in the world’s varied family forms portend. It also
regions as well as in various places in Africa and endeavors to prompt inclusive discourse about and
Latin America, but it is not a universal practice. research into intergenerational solidarity and con-
Sororal polygyny is a type of marriage in which two flict of values in their global diversity. The desire is
or more sisters share a husband, but this is specifi- to extend the field by priming innovative research
cally prohibited in Islam (see al-Lahaydan, 2011). methodologies into hitherto unexplored intergen-
Polygyny is illegal in the United States and Canada, erational phenomena with the objective of rousing
but it is an aspect of fundamental Mormonism that the discovery of the intergenerational transmission-
is practiced in parts of the United States. The prin- of-values stories that exist in all cultures.
ciple most often associated with Mormon funda- Intergenerational continuity of solidarity values,
mentalism is plural marriage, a form of polygyny as documented in a number of studies, suggests that
(Bradley, 2002). In Christian Filipinas the fam- the family plays a key role in the socialization and
ily is monogamous but multiple wives are allowed transmission of values. The family has a universal
in Muslim Filipino families (Herrington, 2010). and basic role (Hareven, 1991). For the majority of
Nsamenang (1992) recorded polygyny among the people the most influential aspect of the immedi-
Nso Muslim of Cameroon as 17.5% but it is not ate social context is the family, which is increas-
universal among Nso Muslim. In the Kisumu, ingly becoming a multigenerational unit across
Siaya, and South Nyanza districts of Kenya, women the world. Indian-Caribbean families, like those in
in polygynous unions represented 38%, 47%, and Africa, tend to share their limited resources and have
41%, respectively (Kenya, 1986). mutual obligations to each other. It is not unusual
to see several generations of African and Caribbean
Intergenerational Values Transmission: family members living in the same house or in
What Do We Know? houses built close to each other, even after marriage
Literature on intergenerational values transmis- (Seegobin, 1999). African “kinship is the nucleus
sion is vast but lopsided in geographical reference from which social networks ramify, moral behavior

n sa m en a n g 771
is initiated and prosocial values, productive skills contingent nature (Becker, 1997). This explains why
and the mother tongue are learned” (Nsamenang some views of continuity have deconstructed the
et al., 2008, pp. 55–56). notion of continuity; in doing so, they have empha-
The notion of continuity is central to intergen- sized disruption (Becker, 1993, 1997) and life reor-
erational values transmission research. How family ganization (Becker & Kaufman, 1995). The family
members perceive continuity is directly related to is shaped by continuities and discontinuities in cul-
their particular cultural ethos and family exchange tural history, and by disruptions to the ongoing fab-
norms. Family members interact in two ways, out- ric of everyday life, such as those caused by slavery,
ward and inward. The outward interaction reflects colonialism, war, civil unrest, chronic poverty, and
how members respond and openly interact with migration (Becker, 1997; Becker & Beyene, 1999;
one another. The inner interaction has more to do Elder, Rudkin, & Conger, 1995). These and other
with each member’s perception of or inner feelings events have directly threatened family cohesion and
about interacting. Perceptions can carry more influ- generational continuity in the present and future.
ence than the reality of the act or interaction. Both The “United States is far from unique in rep-
sides of family interaction affect the dynamics of the resenting a confluence of voluntary immigrants,
family and the self-image of individual members. involuntary immigrants, and conquered indigenous
The two sides to family interaction make family peoples” (Greenfield, 1994, p. x). In Africa (e.g.,
dynamics and values transmission much more com- Nsamenang, 2002), the continuities and discon-
plex and account for family members harboring tinuities in family structures and functions partly
different feelings, perceptions, and action tenden- reflect the extent to which multigenerational fam-
cies related to the same event. Furthermore, family ily members are coping with the coexistence of
forms provide the primary setting through which traditionalism, the “modernism” of Islamic-Arabic
culture is defined and interpreted (Luborsky & heritage, Western-Christian colonialism, and glo-
Rubinstein, 1987). As a conduit of culture, the fam- balizing acculturation in the face of Africanity
ily represents continuity. The family is key to most (indigenous African realities). The contemporary
phenomena that represent cultural continuity, such African family is thus best seen “as an intergenera-
as family solidarity, social organization, religion, and tional, multilocal, psychosocial community linked
ritual; it is the repository of specific cultural beliefs to local, national and global economies and polities”
and practices and a primary site for cultural mean- (Bradley & Weisner, 1997, p. xxvi). For most com-
ing for grandchildren and grandparents (Hareven, munities and families these forces are useful but at
1978). In fact, the notion of continuity of solidarity several points they crash, causing a deepening loss of
should be central to gerontological theories of aging personal and collective identity and an intensifying
and elder care. Throughout much of gerontology’s sense of alienation.
history, theories of continuity have been grounded Early intergenerational values transmission
in a model of life-course development that empha- research on acculturation reported significant inter-
sizes “normative” behavior in individuals rather generational differences in three generations of
than in the family unit. Jingxiong (2009) recently Japanese Canadians in their retention of traditional
studied the single-child policy in three-generation values of familism (Maykovich, 1980). Maykovich’s
families in urban China and pleaded for genuine conclusions supported the theoretical proposi-
knowledge on factors that influence children’s life- tion that acculturation is a multiphase process,
styles in multigenerational families. Family disloca- whether it is measured by the retention of tradi-
tions regardless of cause exert dire consequences on tional familism or the adoption of “New World”
intergenerativity. (i.e., American) values (Akiyama, Antonucci, &
Continuity theory (Atchley, 1989) has largely Campbell, 1997). Similarly, Sugiman and Nishio’s
focused on the individual rather than the family (1983) study of socialization and cultural duality
and has been informed by a normative perspective. among aging Japanese Canadians concluded that,
Increasingly, families in many parts of the world share in contrast to the traditional age-related norms of
a household with both their parents and grandpar- the first generation, middle-aged second-genera-
ents, especially in three-generation families. There tion parents demonstrated a decreased dependence
has been a shift away from constructs that model on their children for support in later life. Ujimoto
normativity to concepts that problematize phe- (1987) attributed this change in support expecta-
nomena and examine them in their fragmented and tions to generational differences in the retention

772 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


of traditional first-generation values. Among the maintain intergenerational connectivity. Although
Nso of Cameroon, Nsamenang and Lamb (1995) some research has reported that African American
reported substantial similarity in generations of men have fewer supports than African American
parents living in quite diverse circumstances as women and are less integrated into social networks
well as significant variation of parenting values by (Barker, Morrow, & Mitteness, 1998), other studies
sex, parental generation, rural-urban residence, found that although African American men’s net-
religion, and level of education. This study, along works were sometimes less extensive; they were nev-
with Africa’s historical traumas and social schisms, ertheless complex.
inform us that African family adaptation, like those An apparently ignored area of intergenerational
of African Americans, has been an ongoing struggle research is the impact on autobiographical memory
to create a meaningful, sustainable, and coherent when shifting the elderly into elderly homes. That is,
pattern of everyday life. Regrettably, African and how is an elderly person’s intergenerativity affected
African American generational transmission pat- by placement in an old-people’s home? This invokes
terns have been studied primarily in comparison the sense of place attachment. In Abraham Maslow’s
to norms derived from data obtained from urban hierarchy of needs, belongingness is about human
Caucasian families (Cantor, 1979; Shimkin, bonding; most accounts of identity formation dis-
Shimkin, & Frate, 1978). cuss self-definition vis-à-vis others, not in vacuums
Intergenerational transmission research has but in physical and social settings with some signifi-
focused largely on family generations but with little cant others. Place attachment, then, is as central to
evidence of attention on such value spaces as the so- adult attachment and identity as it is to intergenera-
called demographic transitions and the transmission tional connectedness and values transmission. Most
of values, skills, and proficiencies in family forma- adults, having consolidated their identity forma-
tion, the workplace, and peer generation, particu- tion that involved systematic differentiation of the
larly in cultures in which age grading is normative. self from the nonself, break down these processes
This author (Nsamenang, 1992) has explained the and barriers in adult life, particularly in old age,
bonds and deference in African peer groups and the such that places and their social networks become
caring responsibilities of older siblings as a prod- invested with personal memories and connotations.
uct of family socialization and parental education Places and neighborhoods become extensions of the
with emphasis on the notions of locus of authority, self, so to speak, culminating in autobiographical
seniority, and filial service; core elements of African insideness that is held with sensitive reminiscences,
social solidarity systems. In this regard, we can as when almost everyone resists hospitalization and
extend continuity theory by exploring disruptions some elderly resist abandoning their residences
(Becker, 1993, 1997) in the life courses of peer gen- to enter elderly homes. Another neglected area of
erations in societies where age grading is common. intergenerational research is the accentuating wave
Exploring the ways in which people seek to amelio- of interethnic and interracial marriages and the mul-
rate disruptions to cohesion and solidarity in their ticultural intergenerativity such families engender.
families and life journeys, striving to regain a sense In addition, research on intergenerational trans-
of continuity and personal integrity have direct mission is only beginning to study grandparent–
relevance for the study of aging. Even when con- grandchild relationships, which may have a greater
tinuity appears to be present in daily life and peo- potential for the transfer of intergeneration-distinct
ple take their sense of continuity for granted, they information. The role of grandparents and grand-
strive to maintain it, especially in old age (Becker, children in caregiving in both developed and devel-
1997). Older parents may enhance family solidarity oping societies has received increased albeit lopsided
and continuity for all generations (Bengtson et al., research attention over the last decades. In part, this
1996). As custodians of family history and autobio- trend reflects the aging of societies, the greater avail-
graphical memories, elders have the greatest stakes ability of grandparents in families across the globe,
in their group’s roots and repairing historic disrup- the emergence of alternative family forms, and dif-
tions, as well as with the maintenance of tradition fering government policies on Social welfare services
and the continuity of the generations (Keesing, (Silverstein, 2009). Family caregiving demographics
1992). As such, elders would be expected to resist presuppose that providing care to one’s aging parents,
social change, combating change through tra- even in elderly people’s homes, is a normative Euro-
ditional roles and statuses and working overtime to Western task and family responsibility. However,

n sa m en a n g 773
providing care to a grandparent by children, ado- Changing Dynamics in Intergenerational
lescents, and young adults tends to be considered Values
a non-normative life task; even cursory observation Micro- and macro-social, political, and eco-
would reveal this as a normative task in the Majority nomic factors provide the parameters for under-
World, particularly in Africa. Whereas the reigning standing changes in family structure and values.
Western developmental theories position the care of The African family, for instance, persists as a unit
children as a specialized task of adulthood, African of production, consumption, reproduction, and
life-span theories separate the learning of childhood accumulation that has been intensely battered by
skills from the life stage of parenthood (Nsamenang, the economic downturns that have transformed the
2008) and situate sibling caregiving into children’s settings in which families make their decisions and
“shared management, caretaking, and socially dis- socialize children. Worldwide, opportunities have
tributed support” of the family (Weisner, 1997). arisen from considerable socio-economic changes
Thus, different cultural orientations fan out differ- that continue to alter the structure of the family
ing generational transmission values and profiles. away from traditional patterns toward new ones
The International Society for Behavioural generated by the expansion of education, health
Development (ISSBD) Bulletin has reported a set care, technologies, employment, and migration.
of research on grandparenting from a range of For example, in the Oriental Gulf states, contem-
cultural backgrounds and theoretical and method- porary means of communication have increased the
ological traditions (Weichold, 2009). Nishiyama knowledge of young people and given them spe-
and Yamada (2009) focused on female three- cific alternatives that put them in touch with peers
generational relationships over time in Japan all over the world, and especially in the West. That
and highlighted the issue of mutual support and contact influences the values, traditions and prac-
role reversal between generations. Oburu (2009) tices of Gulf youth and complicates socialization
explored support and caregiving, sometimes to a by their families (El-Haddad, 2003). Similar forces
burdensome degree, provided by grandparents open new opportunities as well as produce multiple
of sub-Saharan African orphaned children. The constraints. A telling case is that of African families
“burden” is perhaps being imputed from the inter- affected by intrafamilial schisms and engrossed in
pretative visions of scholars but may not be an expe- longstanding fragile economies, chronic poverty,
rienced reality of Africa’s grandparents, given their poor governance, and civil conflicts (Bigombe &
cultural exchange values. Bullock (2009) departs Khadiagala, 2003).
from the tradition of focusing grandparenting African parents are always exasperated about
research on grandmothers to understand parent- their children’s unwed parenthood, which is now
ing among grandfathers who raised children along alarming in many countries. Traditionally, there
with grandmothers. This approach is necessary usually is little aversion toward such children, even
in the sense that “to consider the status of either the so-called illegitimate ones. Illegitimacy does
sex without reference to the other is to distort the not exist in the Western sense in that every child
reality we are trying to understand” (Fortes, 1950, is always the “child” of someone, of an individual
p. 363). Two more papers within the special issue or of the family of origin (Nsamenang, 1992). This
dealt, first, with grandchildren as caregivers who is because in most African communities, children
provide support and help to their grandparents of unwed mothers belong to their families of ori-
(Fruhauf & Orel, 2009), and second, the behav- gin. In Western societies single-parent families are
iors of grandparents in three-generation Chinese often seen as nuclear families that for one reason or
families that may induce a more negative devel- another have been divided. This can be the case, but
opmental pathway for grandchildren (Jingxiong, is not always. It is true that single parents can result
2009). The special section also includes field from divorce or widowhood but it is also becom-
reports of sociological research on grandparenting ing more common for individuals to purposefully
by research teams in Brazil (Kosminsky, 2009), the opt to be a single parent, although in some cases
UK (Smith, 2009), and the Philippines (Antonio, hedonistic attitudes and career or economic consid-
2009). Taken together, these studies reveal consis- erations underpin options for childlessness. With
tency of support and help to generations in the artificial insemination, tolerant attitudes to single
different contexts and family traditions in which parenthood, and the option of adoption, these fam-
the research was done. ilies are growing in number.

774 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


Single-parent homes are not really accepted more of its unidirectional nature has been studied
in African family traditions. They do have some than its reciprocal complexity.
benefits, however, but are not without dire conse- Social and emotional interdependence are the
quences on next generations. A single parent has the norm through which family members view each
sole responsibility and rights to care for the child other and the family unit. Social norms of the
or children, meaning they will not have to struggle Filipino family, for instance, dictate close family
with differences in maternal and paternal values relationships, emotional ties, loyalties, and eco-
and parenting methods (Richter & Morrell, 2006). nomic exchanges (Williams & Domingo, 1993).
However, in Western societies the single-parent fam- Therefore, family continuity is best studied in the
ily has been growing more accepted and has begun nature and direction of responsibilities and obli-
to truly make an impact on political culture and the gations within families as well as solidarity and
social welfare system. The majority of single-parent mutual support across the life spans of several gen-
families are more commonly single-mother families erations. In Africa, such mutuality exists in child
than single-father. These families face many difficult care and elder care. The unexpected projection
issues besides the fact that they have to raise their that 22 to 28% of unpaid caregivers to family and
children on their own, but also have to deal with friends in the United States are young people age
issues related to low income, “hostile” social welfare 18 to 40 years (Center on Elderly People Living
systems in some countries, and generational issues if Alone, 1995) points to the direction in which
procreative partners are not revealed to the children. uncritical intergenerativity research may lead the
Many single parents struggle with low incomes and field.
find it hard to cope with other issues that they face, Social exchange can be viewed not only as a
including connectedness to extended-kin networks, means by which those who are old maintain power
especially if there are societal snares to the single- but as a major vehicle for perpetuating continuity
parent status. across the generations. When family exchange breaks
down, elders suffer from loss of power as expressed
Forces Supporting Intergenerational through role loss. To retain power, elders must have
Continuity of Values a negotiable commodity to exchange as well as the
Continuity is a human need and a universal flexibility to adjust to changes in the extended fam-
expectation (Harris, 1989) although in family val- ily. For many elderly persons around the world,
ues, the concept has a culture-specific character caregiving and guiding grandchildren is their “nego-
(Becker, 1997). One way to interpret the variety tiable commodity.” But in African intergenerational
of the continuity of values is to shift away from relations, the parent, especially the father, is increas-
ongoing universalization of Western family forms ingly becoming the net loser, as his once undisputed
to design and interpret research on the shape that authority is declining as children and their mothers
the different socio-cultural tools and artifacts are becoming economically viable and finding their
that mediate family values take in different cul- way in the world without necessarily relying on
tural contexts. A second framework is the cultural men’s protection and guidance (Nsamenang, 2000).
structuring of family forms and the organization Mutual reciprocity or intergenerational transfer
of life courses within family systems, given fami- research over the life course, especially in Majority-
lism as a primary value in most cultures (Cuellar, World families, should not only focus on ongoing
1990). In Cambodia, for example, families are exchanges but should explore anticipation of elder
the social platform from which cultural moral- care in the growing generation of the elderly. In
ities generate to individuals, reinforcing family Cameroon, where publicly organized social security
connectedness to reveal evidence of good-face/ schemes are remarkable for their dearth or ineffi-
bad-face in behavioral intentions (Smith-Hefner, ciency, both the young and old rely on intrafamilial
1999). Similarly, in Cameroon, the conjugal unit schemes that comprise parental lifelong investment
is the hub of family formation from which social in childrearing in anticipation of filial service as an
networks ramify, moral behavior is initiated, and old-age social security net (Nsamenang, 2002). In
prosocial values, productive skills, and other cul- this light, Kenyans perceive old age as “a reaping for
tural learnings occur (Nsamenang et al, 2008). the elderly whose rewards for successful childrear-
Universally, the parent–child generational rela- ing were expected to be unconditional support from
tionship is an important and complex one, but adult children” (Oburu, 2009, p. 7).

n sa m en a n g 775
Having a big extended family is highly valued United States. Despite lower birth rates and women
in Africa and other Majority-World societies as a delaying childbirth, increased longevity has resulted
source of emotional sustenance and mutual support. in people from four or five generations being alive
Accordingly, mutual assistance is one reflection of a at the same time and at times in the same house-
broader cultural ethos about family relationships to hold (see Jingxiong, 2009). We need to more keenly
which people in a given group subscribe and learn address issues that result from multiple generations
values and skills. Portraits of social interdependence and multiracial families coexisting not only in soci-
and preparation of future generations should map ety but also in the workplace, and the same house-
out how family continuity is perpetuated in cultur- hold in all societies.
ally specific ways as well as what nuclear and extended As social mobility and migration has become
families are doing to fit children and grandchildren more racially and ethnically diverse, dating, cohabit-
into a changing world. Mutual assistance and con- ing, and marrying a person of another race or ethnic
cerns about the goodness-of-fit of children in future origin has become more tolerable, at least among
years are deeply embedded in the cultural context liberal men and women and their sometimes frus-
of family life of most societies. This is, and related trated but helpless kin. Worldwide, the number of
issues, a critical element in intergenerational conti- interracial or interethnic families is increasing, but
nuity in terms of familism and its change from vari- we know little yet about the intergenerational phe-
ous causes that should be tracked in their contextual nomena they engender and create. In recent times,
situativity and variation. same-sex couples have also cracked the family door
The cross-transfer of currencies is evidence of to gain recognition, but this is an acutely contested
continuity and discontinuity of mutual support family form in most countries.
and ongoing involvement with families, even when It is now obvious that the family is both a custo-
dislodged from family units. Of course, differences dian of tradition and an agent of change. However, a
between families and groups in overall approaches widespread assumption hints that family continuity
to social connectedness and induction of skills, the through the generations will override individual dis-
factors to which families assign the greatest salience, continuities (Becker, 2000), yet the contemporary
and the degree of “loss-of-face” or disaffection family is beset by internal and external disruptions
expressed over family relations are expected to dif- that threaten family continuity. Among persons
fer across families and cultures. We suspect that the who have migrated from other societies, threats to
varied approaches to mutual assistance and com- continuity lie in food items and feeding habits, cul-
petency preparations have been shaped by cultural tural and language differences between generations,
traditions, family norms, and role expectations, as long-standing separations from loved ones, and
well as by threats of their disruption. Competing changes in younger generations’ views of the family.
demands on everyone’s time, energy, and resources Furthermore, job loss, divorce, illness, and death are
are important, but are changing the shape of inter- among the many disruptions that force families to
generational expectations and actual values that are regroup or detach. The late twentieth century also
expressed. ushered in new household structures, particularly
with Euro-Americans, with unwed parents, gay par-
Sources of Changing Family Patterns and ents, and remarried parents who brought with them
the Toll of Family Discontinuities a series of step-kin. Divorce, premarital childbear-
Intergenerational research has been shaped ing, and single parenthood are losing some social
by the “spirit” of the early European settlers and stigma almost everywhere, albeit at different rates.
pioneers in the New World who claimed mobil- Children in divorced families generally experi-
ity as their birthright. The original colonies were ence independence at an earlier age; some develop
not long-established before expansion began on close relationships with more than one adult, and
the East Coast for more farming land inland. The they develop new relationships with each parent.
frontier was the next piece of unexplored land to However, children’s sense of stability cannot help
the west, and successive generations of Caucasian but be disrupted by the breakup of their family
Americans worked their way from the Atlantic coast units, as parents date other people, and in some
across the continent to the Pacific coast. After the cases new families come into existence as a result of
American Civil War, many freed slaves migrated to these new relationships. These not-so-blended fami-
spread African American family patterns across the lies require tremendous emotional, if not, social and

776 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


financial adjustment and are expected to be con- (Tangwa, 1996)—but for the Western audience, as
fused about which values to perpetuate. Children most editors of most of my manuscripts have sought
with same-sex parents also face complex social and clarifications for the American audience? That is,
emotional issues, including building perspective on African scholars tend to research and report in a
gender roles as well as dealing with social aversion of manner to satisfy Western markets rather than to
this nontraditional family structure. promote understanding of their intergenerational
values or other realities. As such, intergenerational
Policy Considerations research in Africa has largely lost sight of the soil out
Although the UN Convention on the Rights of the of which the contemporary family structures have
Child (1989) has been critiqued as an overly Euro- grown and the exchange values they have produced
Western document (Reid, 2006), it nevertheless sup- (Kishani, 2001).
ports everyone’s right to a cultural identity. In order An important issue is the extent to which various
to uphold cultural identity, an intergenerational forces that should be tracked have modified “tradi-
research agenda should take the Convention into tional” family forms and values to create generation
explicit consideration. Research is largely matricen- gaps and what state parties have in place to sustain
tric, reflecting lack of focus on parenting as a shared family solidarity and tackle intergenerational cri-
duty between father and mother. Researchers and ses. The mixture of cultures within nation-states
policy planners need to do more to understand and is a fact that is gaining increasing recognition and
take into account what states and families should importance in both national and international
do to give every child that right. The tendency in affairs (Greenfield, 1994). What does it portend for
research to observe and measure people in lieu of lis- theory, research methods, and policy, for example,
tening to and working with them somehow breaches if “new immigrants from Asia and Latin America
this right. The image of African family systems and have added a large measure of cultural and phe-
intergenerational values in print used to guide pol- notypic diversity to the American population in
icy development and programming by otherwise recent decades” (Perez, 2009)? Intergenerativity
well-intentioned donors and international advo- in the Majority World is driven more by socially
cates has been offered mainly by itinerant foreign distributed norms and less by economic fortunes,
researchers and does not only “embody the different per se. In the majority of families, worldwide eco-
perspectives which such expatriates bring to Africa” nomic considerations are not as salient or central to
(Wober, 1975 p. ix) but also largely excludes what exchange values for child care and elder care as are
the recipients know and the apprehension they have emotional investment and the spirituality of child-
about the services. bearing (Sam, 2007).
In the light of Wober’s (1975, pp. ix–x) wisdom,
intergenerational research might “turn a corner” Recapulative Reflections
if it increasingly comes into the hands of Africans The family is a universal institution, the hub of
“with their own outlooks, needs, and directions of intergenerational values. It has varied and will con-
enquiry.” Smith (2004, p. 222) made a related point tinue to differ in form, function, and generation of
by noting how Nigerians who were bearing children continuity values across time and lived family cir-
did “not conceptualize what they are doing in the cumstances. Social exchange is central to the con-
language or formulas of demography.” Although tinuity of family values; reciprocity and equity are
development cooperation agents experience dif- core values in all social exchange systems. However,
ficulty understanding African ways of thinking intergenerational inequitable thinking is perceptible
and acting, many African-born policy makers and in political motives when individuals and interest
scholars often make many of the same mistakes as groups that would have been expected to support
expatriates (Creekmore, 1986). Whose interest and early-childhood services and elder care oppose Social
perspective should be the focus of research? Security benefits to these cohorts of citizens.
A related concern is whether rights consider- We live in a world that deserves intergenerational
ations come to the fore when research reports cre- research inclusive of family values in the context
ate or conjure stigmatizing allusions of research and diversity of the world’s cultures. Regrettably,
participants. What does it mean if researchers, even the extant corpus of intergenerativity knowledge
African scholars, must figure what to see or hear and is Euro-American in main thrust and value con-
how to report it not for their own people—Africans tent. It has mainly been strewn from middle-class

n sa m en a n g 777
European and American families and largely reflects scientific disciplines and interactions among scien-
the conceptual lenses and practical issues that shape tists, intergenerational phenomena, and the scope
their visions of the world and individualistic social and cultural inclusivity of intergenerational research
exchange norms. As such, intergenerational trans- agendas.
mission research has been cast in the epistemes and In Africa’s agrarian societies, production is fam-
kinship realities of the Euro-American nuclear fam- ily-based, mostly unspecialized, and accredits chil-
ily for projection onto the intergenerativity and dren as significant contributors. Until the recent
policy prescriptions for the rest of humanity. Any past, successive generations of Africa’s children were
intergenerational research that obtained data from socialized into similar livelihoods, typically farm-
non-Western samples was designed within compar- ing and local crafts. With rapid globalizing shifts of
ative paradigms with little, if any, explicit goal of production and career prospects to workplace pro-
understanding the intergenerativity within societies cesses and the knowledge economy, career fortunes
in their own right. Furthermore, the methodologies are more dependent on an inherent division of
and norms developed from research on Western labor and competitive specialization than on inter-
nuclear families have been and continue to be used generational transmission of family work ethic and
as referential grids for research worldwide. vocational aptitudes. Increasingly, individualism in
So, intergenerational research has largely under- global labor markets is diffusing into other spheres
mined or bypassed the family values inherent in the of life, including individual identity, solidarity val-
family systems and socially distributive norms of ues, mutual exchange systems, and the legal system,
the vast majority of the world’s families, particularly among several others. Intergenerativity research
those in Africa. If the knowledge base from research will happen within changing social and economic
on intergenerational values or any other behavioral opportunities accentuated by the necessity for youth
phenomenon is overwhelmed by one culture, and to move away from home in search of employment
it does not matter which culture (Ardila, 1982), and better life prospects. This trend has already
it plainly ignores or excludes the situativity of the resulted in declines in the availability of multigen-
researched phenomenon in other cultures. Such erational family members in African households
research transgresses global era values and only at and neighborhoods. With growing urbanization,
best depicts a partial and obviously misguided pic- rural African parents and communities are losing
ture of the reality or the full spectrum of the phe- children and youth increasingly to sprawling city
nomenon it objectively claims to understand. slums and, through illegal migration, into precari-
Scientific objectivity thus obliges and justifies ous conditions abroad (Nsamenang, 2011). These
any and all efforts to shift the paradigm to broaden phenomena are disrupting African family structure
the scope and subject content of intergenerational and complicating values transmission. When social
research. In the next and final section of this chap- exchange breaks down, elders suffer from loss of
ter, I endeavor to articulate my preliminary views power and the disaffection of being forgotten by
on how to move forward with intergenerational their families; they are disappointed in their chil-
research within African cultural settings. dren who failed, in the light of psychosocial theory
(Erikson, 1968) to ensure their old-age welfare.
Future Directions In spite of the Euro-American parochialism of
In a globalized world of plural cultures, the future research databases, we cannot afford to dismiss the
of intergenerational research that speaks to intergen- extant knowledge base on intergenerational values.
erativity in its entire diversity will depend on stead- We must be keen and ready, nevertheless, not to
fast commitment to the belief that “all cultures can acquiesce to a state of a scientific field that lopsid-
contribute scientific knowledge of universal value” edly reports research on Anglo-American intergen-
(UNESCO, 1999). The production and sharing of erativity as if it represented largely uncharted African
knowledge and perspectives from intergenerational intergenerational profiles. We must plan and design
research will occur under changing conditions inci- research from a resourceful apprehension that the
dental to the micro-familial, macro-societal, and “most creative theories are often imaginative visions
globalizing forces that will continue to profoundly imposed upon facts; the source of imagination is also
impact family values and their transmission chan- strongly cultural” (Gould, 1981, p. 22). In accept-
nels. Various key factors have indeed transformed, ing science as part of culture, we must acknowledge
and will continue to alter the relationships between that by its nature science “influences what scientists

778 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


see and how they see it and, more critically, what and knowledge systems build up from local cul-
scientists report, ignore, or fail to notice, as when ture and the people’s worldviews. Mazrui and Ajayi
serendipitous research findings are not reported (1998) claimed that science and technology in Africa
(Nsamenang, 2010b, p. 389). Therefore, we must were once quite advanced, comparable to European
go beyond questioning the current state of the sci- levels of the time, in the fields of human and veter-
ence in order to ingeniously correct an inadvertent inary medicine, agriculture, food conservation, fer-
bias in intergenerational research. mentation, metallurgy, and the preparation of soap
Accordingly, the central mission of Africa- and cosmetics. Slowly, the importance and influence
centric research should be to discover the situativity of indigenous knowledge diminished because of the
of intergenerational phenomena and their changing success of Western science and technology and the
trends in Africa. In so doing, we must work from economic and political power that accompanies that
an understanding of Africa’s triple heritage (Mazrui, success, but also because of deliberate denigration
1986) of historically earlier Islamic-Arabic fam- and treatment of Africa’s knowledge and techniques
ily patterns and later Western-Christian nuclear as antiprogressive.
family ethos superimposing a toll on deep-seated For these and other reasons, the knowledge sys-
African family values. African family values are said tems of other cultures are reported and understood
to be deep-seated in the sense that, thus far, scien- in reference to Western systems, a disrespect of
tific evidence reveals Africa as the origin of modern diversity and great harm to humanity. By its design,
humans (Johanson, 2008). As such, Africa should Western science is reductionistic, mechanistic, and
be researched as home of the earliest and longest- attached to quantitative measurement. On the other
standing versions of family forms and intergener- hand, traditional science relies on naturalistic obser-
ational transmission of values. Research within vation from an inclusive point of view. Scientists
this hybrid context will require plausible theoreti- limit or “reduce” their explanations of phenomena
cal as well as methodological innovations because to unique observations; this reductionistic approach
no existing theory suitably explains Africa’s triple- tends to ignore some facts that may be key factors in
strand braid of family values. some situations (Laccarino, 2003). The traditional
Faith in science and the work of intergenerativity knowledge of non-Western cultures puts empirical
researchers permits proposal of alternative theories observations into a larger context. Thus, in all cul-
and methods. I invoke Bertold-Brecht’s wisdom tures, we can notice efforts to harmonize empirical
as a guide: “The aim of science is not to open the observations in order to represent phenomena and
door to infinite wisdom, but to put a limit to infi- to be able to interpret and predict them. Such holis-
nite error” (Cited in Laccarino, 2003). The handiest tic knowledge provides much of Africa with frames
strategy is the scientific method, an established set of reference to individuate a sense of belonging to
of rules that should be applied to all phenomena networks of social others that support satisfaction
regardless of context. In the search, we must recog- of basic needs.
nize that Africa possesses its own conceptual grids Laccarino (2003) refers to Szent-Gyorgyi as hav-
and knowledge bases, which may explain, at least in ing identified the problems of modern science as the
part, why scholars who have applied Western mod- inability to integrate results and concepts that come
els and epistemes to African phenomena discovered from different approaches and levels of analysis.
that they did not exactly fit (MacGaffey, 1981; African scholars tend to experience difficulty con-
Ojiaku, 1974). necting or translating their academic or professional
Scientific understanding is one knowledge system knowledge and research skills to the appalling state
among many others (Nakashima, 2000). Cultures of their continent and ethnic communities. The
from all regions of the world have developed com- extent to which African scholars are knowledgeable
plex views of nature, rooted in their philosophy, of the social capital of their communities is at best
which has led to their understanding and explana- tenuous. The tacit juxtaposition of primitive versus
tion of the natural world. The indigenous knowl- civilized values in scientific literature exacerbates
edge of non-European cultures is the expression their difficulty.
of specific ways of living in the world, of a specific Africa’s exchange values open up opportunities
relationship between society and culture, and of a to learn about elder care within the family and to
specific approach to the acquisition and construc- approach analysis of phenomena with holistic,
tion of knowledge (Laccarino, 2003). These insights integrative lenses. Such opportunities prime an

n sa m en a n g 779
innovative disposition to theory and method in on August 13, 2011 from http://www.youtube.com/watch?
order to address a phenomenon not as a defined v=GbSbaRb6cGU.
Antonio, A. Z. (2009). Grandparenting in the Philippines: A
concept but as it is implanted in context. Ingenious micro-study on strengths and needs. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56),
application of integrative thinking can thus insti- 30–33.
gate contextually sensitive research into the com- Antonucci, T. C., & Cantor, M. H. (1994). Strengthening
plex intersubjectivity inherent in the transmission the family support system for older minority persons. In
of family values across diverse family forms and cul- J. Jackson & Task Force on Minority Issues (Eds.), Minority
elders: Five goals toward building a public policy base (2nd ed.,
tural contexts. The scientific community should be pp. 40–45). Washington, DC: Gerontological Society of
ready to re-evaluate what the out-of-Africa-origins of America.
modern-humans theory (Johanson, 2008) portends Atchley, R. (1989). A continuity theory of normal aging
and Africa’s potential contributions to intergenera- (Abstract). The Gerontologist, 29, 183–190.
tional values research, as the Renaissance scientists Baig, M. (2002). The evolution theory. Retrieved online from
www.albalagh.net/kids/science/evolution.shtml on August
did with the ancient knowledge of the Greek and 13, 2011.
Arab scholars (Laccarino, 2003). Barker, J. C., Morrow, J., & Mitteness, L. S. (1998). Gender,
Intergenerational relationships and exchanges informal social support networks, and elderly urban African
are sites of reaction to wider social change or key Americans. Journal of Aging Studies, 12, 199–222.
sources of change (Jamieson, 2006). That is, inter- Becker, G. (1980). Growing old in silence. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
generational exchange values need not be traditional Becker, G. (1993). Continuity after a stroke: Implications for life-
or biological. Older adults and younger peers can course disruption in old age. The Gerontologist, 33, 148–158.
validate and help each other. Intergenerational Becker, G. (1997). Disrupted lives: How people create meaning in a
mentoring, for instance, can make a significant chaotic world. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
difference in a child’s or elder’s life. Some of the Becker, G., & Beyene, Y. (1999). Narratives of age and uproot-
edness among older Cambodian refugees. Journal of Aging
modes in which intergenerational values are gener- Studies, 13, 295–314.
ated and spread are culture-specific; but they have Becker, G., Beyene, Y., & Canalita, L. C. (2000). Immigrating
been changing in all cultures and will continue to for status in late life: Effects of globalization on Filipino
adjust to prevailing conditions. If research reveals American veterans. Journal of Aging Studies, 14, 273–292.
that the benefits of intergenerational interactions Becker, G., & Kaufman, S. R. (1995). Managing an uncertain
illness trajectory in old age: Patients’ and physicians’ views of
accrue to both the younger and the older genera- stroke. Medical Anthropology Quarterly, 9, 165–187.
tions, are they universal and inert or do they vary Bengtson, V. L., & Oyama, P. S. (2007). Intergenerational solidar-
by family forms and social exchange systems? What ity: Strengthening economic and social ties. Background paper
policy insights could be lost if research continues to for the expert group of the UN Department of Economic
privilege economic exchange if some culture-spe- and Social Affairs, Division of Social Policy Development.
New York: United Nations.
cific factors are more salient in Africa? Population Bengtson, V., Biblarz, T., & Roberts, R. (2002). How families still
profiles are changing, as the number of elderly matter. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
and multigenerational families of all countries is Bengtson, V., Rosenthal, C., & Burton, L. (1996). Paradoxes
increasing, more rapidly in some countries than of families and aging. In R. H. Binstock & L. K. George
others, posing an unprecedented challenge to cur- (Eds.), Handbook of aging and the social sciences (4th ed.,
pp. 254–282). New York: Academic Press.
rent and future generations. Most of these factors, Beyene, Y., Becker, G., & Mayen, N. (2002). Perceptions of
and the fact that intergenerativity values cross dis- aging and sense of well-being among Latino elderly. Journal
ciplinary boundaries, necessitate interdisciplinarity of Cross-Cultural Gerontology, 17, 155–172.
and triangulation. Brannen, J. (2006). Cultures of intergenerational transmission in
four-generation families. Sociological Review, 54, 133–154.
Bullock, K. (2009). Expanding the intergenerational relation-
References ship: Grandfathers raising grandchildren. ISSBD Bulletin,
Akiyama, H., Antonucci, T. C., & Campbell, R. (1997). 2(56), 7–9.
Exchange and reciprocity among two generations of Japanese Cantor, M. H. (1979). The informal support system of
and American women. In J. Sokolovsky (Ed.), The cul- New York’s inner city elderly: Is ethnicity a factor? In
tural context of aging: Worldwide perspectives (pp. 163–178). D. E. Gelfand & A. J. Kutzik (Eds.), Ethnicity and aging:
Westport, CT: Bergin & Garvey. Theory, research and policy. New York: Springer.
All About Science.org (2010). Darwin’s theory of evolution: Carsaro, W. A. (1990). The underlife of nursery school: Young
Atheory in crisis. Retrieved online from www.darwins-theory- children’s social representations of adult rules. In G. Duven
of-evolution.com/ on January 17, 2010. & B. Lloyd (Eds.), Social representations and the development
Al-Lahaydan, M. (2011). The Quran Chapter 4 verse 23. of knowledge. (pp. 11–26). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
English translation: Sahih International. Retrieved online University Press.

780 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


Center on Elderly People Living Alone (1995). Medicaid and Kaufman, S. R. (1988). Illness, biography, and the interpreta-
long-term care for old people (Public Policy Fact Sheet tion of self following a stroke. Journal of Aging Studies, 2,
No. FS18R). Washington, DC: American Association for 217–227.
Retired People. Keesing, R. (1992). Custom and confrontation: The Kwaio strug-
Colón A. R., & Colón, P. A. (2001). A history of children: A socio- gle for cultural autonomy. Chicago: University of Chicago
cultural survey across millennia. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Press. Kenya (1986). Kenya contraceptive prevalence survey (Provincial
Creekmore, C. (1986). Misunderstanding Africa. Psychology report, Central Bureau of Statistics). Nairobi: Nairobi Govern-
Today, 12, 40–45. ment Printer.
Cuellar, J. (1990). Aging and health: Hispanic American elders. Kishani, B. T. (2001). On the interface of philosophy and lan-
Stanford, CA: Stanford Geriatric Education Center. guage: Some practical and theoretical considerations. African
Elder, G. H., Jr., Rudkin, L., & Conger, R. D. (1995). Studies Review, 44(3), 27–45.
Intergenerational continuity and change in rural America. Kosminsky, E. (2009). Reports from the Lab: Grandmothers and
In V. L. Bengtson, K. W. Schaie, & L. M. Burton (Eds.), grandchildren in transitional families. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56),
Intergenerational issues in aging: Effects of societal change 22–27.
(pp. 30–60). New York: Springer. LeVine, R. (1974). Child rearing as cultural adaptation. Teachers
El-Haddad, Y. (2003). Major Trends Affecting Families in the College Record, 76(2), 226–239.
Gulf Countries. In Major trends affecting families: A back- Luborsky, M., & Rubinstein, R. L. (1987). Ethnicity and life-
ground document. Report for United Nations, Department times: Self-concepts and situational contexts of ethnic iden-
of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy tity in late life. In D. Gelfand & C. Barresi (Eds.), Ethnic
and Development, Program on the Family (2003). Archived dimensions of aging (pp. 35–50). New York: Springer.
at: http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/family/Publications/mtel- Luborsky, M., & Rubinstein, R. L. (1997). The dynamics of
haddad.pdf. ethnic identity and bereavement among older widowers. In
Fruhauf, C. A., & Orel, N. A. (2009). Grandchildren caregivers: J. Sokolovsky (Ed.), The cultural context of aging: Worldwide
Individual and family development. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), perspectives (2nd ed., pp. 304–315). Westport, CT: Bergin
12–16. & Garvey.
Goodnow, J. J. (1988). Parents, ideas, actions, and feelings: Maquet, J. (1972). Africanity. New York: Oxford University
Models and methods from developmental and social psy- Press.
chology. Child Development, 59(2), 286–320. Moran, L. (1993). Evolution is a fact and a theory. The TalkOrigins
Greenfield, P. M. (1994). Preface. In P. M. Greenfield & Archieve: Exploring the Creation/Evolution Controversy.
R. R. Cocking (Eds.), Cross-cultural minority child develop- Retrieved online on October 18, 2007 from www.talkori-
ment. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. gins.org/faqs/evolution-fact.htm
Groger, L., & Kunkel, S. (1995). Aging and exchange: Differences Muller, H. J. (1959). One hundred years without Darwin are
between black and white elders. Journal of Cross-Cultural enough. School Science and Mathematics, 59, 304–305.
Gerontology, 10, 269–287. Retrieved on October 18, 2007 from http://www.skeptic-
Hareven, T. K. (1978). Transitions: The family and the life course files.org/evolut/100pcnts.htm
in historical perspective. New York: Academic Press. Mutran, E. (1985). Intergenerational family support among
Hareven, T. K. (1982). Family time and industrial time. blacks and whites: Response to culture or to socioeconomic
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. differences. Journal of Gerontology, 40, 382–389.
Hareven, T. K. (2001). Historical perspectives on aging and family Neven, R. S. (1996), Emotional milestones. Melbourne, Australia:
relations. In R. H. Binstock & L. K. George (Eds.), Handbook Australian Council for Educational Research Ltd.
of aging and the social sciences (5th ed., pp. 141–159). San Nishiyama, N., & Yamanda, Y. (2009). Visual narratives of
Diego: Academic Press. grandparents-parent-child relationships from the perspec-
Harris, G. G. (1989). Concepts of individual, self, and person tive of young adult grandparents. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56),
in description and analysis. American Anthropologist, 91, 2–6.
599–612. Nossier, N. (2003). Family in the new millennium: Major trends
Herrington, D. A. (2010). Living in the Philippines: Family pat- affecting families in North Africa. Article in Major Trends
terns. Retrieved from http://www.livinginthephilippines. Affecting Families: A Background Document. Report for
com/style9.html on 9 October, 2010. United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs,
Herrington, D. A., & Fortes, M. (1950). Kinship and marriage Division for Social Policy and Development, Program on the
among the Ashanti. In A. R. Radcliffe-Brown & B. Frank Family (2003). Archived at: http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/
(Eds.), African systems of kinship and marriage. Oxford: family/Publications/mtnosseir.pdf.
Oxford University Press. Nsamenang, A. B. (1992). Human development in cultural con-
Jamieson, L. (2006). Intergenerational relationships: Theory and text: A third world perspective. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
method. UK: Centre for Research on Families and Relation- Nsamenang, A. B. (2002). Adolescence in sub-Saharan Africa:
ships, Department of Sociology, University of Edingburgh. An image constructed from Africa’s triple inheritance (pp.
Jingxiong, J. (2009). The role of grandparents in three-generation 61–104). In B. B. Brown, R. W. Larson, & T. S. Saraswathi
families in urban China. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), 16–17. (Eds.), The world’s youth: Adolescence in eight regions of the
Johanson, D. (2008). Origins of Modern Humans: Multi- globe. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
regional or Out of Africa? Retrieved online from http:// Nsamenang, A. B. (2008). Agency in early childhood learning
www.actionbioscience.org/evolution/johanson.html on March, and development in Cameroon. Contemporary Issues in Early
13, 2008. Childhood, 9(3), 211–223.

n sa m en a n g 781
Nsamenang, A. B. (2010a). The culturalization of developmen- Smith, D. J. (2004). Contradictions in Nigeria’s fertility transi-
tal trajectories: A perspective on African childhoods and tions: The burdens and benefits of having people. Population
adolescences. In L. A. Jensen (Ed.), Bridging cultural and and Development Review, 30(2), 221–238.
developmental approaches to psychology: New synthesis in the- Smith, P. K. (2009). Grandparenting and intergenerational rela-
ory, research and policy (pp. 388–425). New York: Oxford tionships: Work from Goldsmiths, University of London,
University Press. UK. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), 27–30.
Nsamenang, A. B. (2010b). Fathers, families, and children’s Smith-Hefner, N. J. (1999). Khmer American: Identity and moral
well-becoming in Africa. In M. E. Lamb (Ed.), The role of education in a diasporic community. Berkeley, CA: University
the father in child development (pp. 388–412). Hoboken, NJ: of California Press.
John Wiley & Sons. Smocovitis, V. B. (1996). Unifying biology: The evolutionary
Nsamenang, A. B. (2011). L’émigration clandestine des jeunes synthesis and evolutionary biology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
camerounais en Europe. In C. Bolzman, T-O. Gakuba & University Press.
I. Guissé (Eds.), Migrations des jeunes d’Afrique subsaharienne: Soyinka, W. (1990). The African world and the ethnocultural
Quels defis pour l’avenir? (pp. 139–161). Yaounde, Cameroon: debate. In M. K. Asante & K. W. Asante (Eds.), African cul-
PUA. ture: The rhythms of unity (pp. 13–38). Trenton, NJ: Africa
Nsamenang, A. B., Fai, P. J., Ngoran, G. N., Ngeh, World Press, Inc.
M. M. Y. Forsuh, F. W., Adzemye, E. W., & Lum, G. N. Tangwa, G. F. (1996). Bioethics: An African perspective.
(2008). Ethnotheories of developmental learning in the west- Bioethics, 10(3), 183–200.
ern grassfields of Cameroon. In P. R. Dasen & A. Akkari Taylor, R. J., & Chatters, L. M. (1986). Patterns of informal
(Eds.), Educational theories and practices from the “majority support to elderly black adults: Family, friends, and church
world.” New Delhi, India: Sage. members. Social Work, 31, 432–438.
Nsamenang, A. B., & M. E. Lamb (1995). The force of beliefs: Theophanes (2010). Around the world in search of different
How the parental values of the Nso of northwest Cameroon forms of “family”. Retrieved online from http://hubpages.
shape children’s progress towards adult models. Journal of com/hub/Around-the-World-in-Search-of.Different -Forms-
Applied Developmental Psychology, 16(4), 613–627. of-Family on August 13, 2011.
Oburu, P. (2009). HIV/AIDS generated caregiving burdens and United Nations (1989). Convention of the Rights of the Child.
the emergent two generation family structure in sub-Saharan Retrieved January 8, 2009 from http://www.un.org/docu-
Africa. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), pp. 7–9. ments/ga/res/44/a44r025.htm Vandewiele, M. (1981).
Perez, A. D. & Hirschman, C. (2009). The changing racial Influence of family, peers, and school on Senegalese adoles-
and ethnic composition of the US population: Emerging cents. Psychological Reports, 71, 434–436.
American identities. Population & Development Review, Vygotsky, L. (1978) Mind in society: The development of higher psy-
35(91), 1–51.Reagan, T. (1996). Non-Western educational chological processes. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
traditions: Alternative approaches to educational thought and Press.
practice. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Weichold, K. (2009). Introduction to intergenerational relation-
Religious Tolerance.org. (2011). Origins of species, etc.: Is evolu- ships: Grandparenting. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), 1.
tion merely a “theory”? Retrieved online from http://www. Weisner, T. S. (1997). Support for children and the African fam-
religioustolerance.org/ev_stat.htm ily crisis. In T. S. Weisner, C. Bradley, & C. P. Kilbride (Eds.),
Richter, L., Foster, G., & Sherr, L. (2006). Where the heart is: African families and the crisis of social change (pp. 20–44).
Meeting the psychosocial needs of young children in the context of Westport, CT: Bergin & Garvey.
HIV/AIDS. The Hague, The Netherlands: Bernard van Leer Williams, L., & Domingo, L. J. (1993). The social status of
Foundation. elderly women and men within the Filipino family. Journal
Rubinstein, R. L. (1987). In-depth interviewing and the struc- of Marriage and the Family, 55, 415–426.
ture of its insights. In S. Reinharz & G. D. Rowles (Eds.), Wober, M. (1975). Psychology in Africa. London: International
Qualitative Gerontology. New York: Springer. African Institute.
Shimkin, D., Shimkin, E., & Frate, D. (1978). The extended fam- Wood, T. C. (2009). There is no Darwin Conspiracy. Answers
ily in black societies. Chicago: Aldine. Research Journal 2, 11–20. Retrieved online on August 13,
Silverstein, M. (2009). Commentary: Intergenerational relation- 2011 from www.answersingenesis.org/contents/379/arj/v2/
ships: Grandparenting. ISSBD Bulletin, 2(56), 17–19. No_Darwin_Conspiracy.pdf

782 intergener at i onal co nt i nui t y o f valu es


CHAPTER

The Making of Magic: Cultural


37 Constructions of the Mundane
Supernatural
Meike Watzlawik and Jaan Valsiner

Abstract
Construction of magical thinking has been central for human cognitive adaptation to uncertainty of
living. In this chapter, we present a rare comparison of how such thinking is culturally constructed across
two different countries (Germany and the United States) and historical periods (1920s and 2000s).
We demonstrate how reanalysis of empirical data from other historical periods can be a productive
epistemological step in comparison with current historical phenomena. Heinz Werner’s and Martha
Muchow’s work on magical thought in the 1920s continues to be of importance in the twenty-first
century.
Keywords: cultural tools, magical beliefs, Heinz Werner, Martha Muchow

Kultur entsteht aus dem Bestreben des Menschen,


Chaos zu vermeiden und Glück zu gestalten.
[Cultures emerges from the human ambition
to avoid chaos and to create luck.]
—Boesch, 2000, p. 12

Magical thinking is all around us. In Germany, a Relieved, he continues to walk his way. In South
black cat—coming from the right disappearing to Korea, a white butterfly flutters past a boy in the
the left—crosses the path of a man on his way to park. It is the first one he sees that year. He is devas-
work. The man is startled for a moment and then tated, because the butterfly is a bad omen: A family
cites the following lines internally: member will die soon. He calls a friend to tell her
about it. In Mexico, an older woman almost set her
Schwarze Katze von links nach rechts, purse on the ground next to her while sitting in a
[Black cat from left to right], café ready to order tea. In the last second, she stops
bringt Schlecht’s, herself and puts the purse on the chair next to her.
[brings bad things,] She decides not to challenge luck and be safe since
schwarze Katze von rechts nach links, putting down the purse on the ground would have
[black cat from right to left,] meant to lose all the money that is in it. The Dieri,
Glück bringt’s. an indigenous Australian group from the South
[brings luck.]. Australian desert, would call upon the spirits of

783
their ancestors to grant them power to make a heavy (see Boesch, 2000, for his definition of valence). If
rainfall during dry seasons (Leuba, 1912). the individual is indifferent to this matter, being
The themes of the incidents described above are unable to predict it will not have an impact.
luck, bad luck, unforeseen personal tragedies, and Ways to (re)gain control over the situation are
natural forces (e.g., rain, wind). What do these thus necessary (see for example, Lefcourt, 1973)—yet
themes have in common? All of them cannot will- not possible—since the situation constantly changes
ingly be controlled or unerringly predicted by the ahead of the control efforts. It is that uncertainty
involved or affected individuals. Of course, here it is that makes the need for the emergence of culture—
assumed that one believes in (bad) luck. Of course, semiotic mediation—both possible and necessary
there are individuals who do not, who base their (Boesch, 2011; Valsiner, 2007). Of course the lay-
interpretations of the world on different belief sys- person needs to survive, and there are some options
tems and, thus, would use other concepts to pre- for that. One option is to still admit that one can-
dict/anticipate what will happen in the future. not do anything, but to believe in a (higher) power
Interesting here is the differentiation between that can (e.g., a deity), or to invent an action that
Spiel (game) and Glücksspiel (gamble/game of luck will, by definition, have a positive impact on the
or chance). In the case of the game (e.g., chess), the outcome (see Belzen, 2011). The emerging routines
players learn or agree on certain rules. The question (e.g., luck making, fate determining) that are based
of why a game took a certain turn or led to a certain on magical beliefs can either be created by individu-
outcome can be explained by the players (B was a als, groups, or even societies. The invention of dei-
result of A, which allows for conclusions like: next ties takes the form of circularity of control—a person
time, I do A to arrive at B). In the case of the gamble, invents a supernatural figure for the purposes of
the players have less control. Of course, gambling controlling him- or herself (Valsiner, 1999). In case
also follows certain rules, but the outcome is uncer- of human willful efforts to control the situation, the
tain/unpredictable. Luck is assumed to determine agent of such control becomes indeterminate.
whether, for example, the roulette ball falls into a
black or red slot. For the notion that all games are The Foundational Role of Magic
“games of chance,” see Neveux (1966). Leuba describes one characteristic feature of
The examples above show that—no matter which magic as follows:
cultural setting (culture as condition for action; see
The term magic I would restrict to those practices
Boesch, 2011; Eckensberger, 2011)—an individual
intended to secure some definite gain by coercive
may still try to predict or influence the unpredict-
action in essential disregard [ . . . ] of the quantitative
able/uncontrollable by interpreting objects (signs)
relations implied in the ordinary and in the scientific
in a specific manner or by engaging in specific
dealings with the physical world [ . . . ].
actions (culture as a result of action). While doing
(1912, p. 350)
so, differences in culture are reflected by differences
in the meaning-making processes involved. Leuba bases this definition on observations made
in “primitive” cultures and children—a comparison
Trying to Control the Uncontrollable not uncommon at the time (cp. Frazer, 1920; Tylor,
World 1871; see Lévy-Bruhl, 1921, for critique). Also,
Uncontrollability and unpredictability imply that Werner (1927) assumed that only the people close to
the causes for a certain and favored outcome are nature in traditional societies—at that time labeled
unknown. Depending on the perspective, this leaves “primitive man”—and children/adolescents (are able
the individual with none (I do not know what to do, to) believe in magic. For Werner, the counterpart
so I do nothing) or endless ways (I do not know what of the magical adolescent was a nonmagical, adult,
to do, so anything might help) to act so that the prob- civilized man. The former would be convinced that
ability of an outcome, which the individual regards objects are ultimately not moved by natural causes,
as positive, increases. These two conclusions can but that individuals and the surrounding objects are
be interpreted as the opposite ends of the possibil- secretly interrelated, that they influence each other
ity spectrum—both can leave the individual either in a magical and nonnatural way. Piaget —following
helpless or overwhelmed, but not in control. The the lead of Levy-Bruhl—explained this causality of
feeling of helplessness only emerges if the individual the child’s thinking with the “Law of Participation.”
actually has an interest in predicting future events He considered participation to be “the result of simple

784 th e maki ng o f mag i c


transduction, of the syncretistic fusion of particular to Leuba, Piaget stresses that magic has something to
observations” (Piaget, 2001, p. 33). Participation is, do with wanting to influence the external world in
thus, the favor of one’s own wishes/desires (in different ways, see
Box 37.1 for classifications). In other words: For the
. . . relation which primitive thought believes to child, it is one way of controlling or, at least, wishing to
exist between two beings or two phenomena which control the outside world because convincing alterna-
it regards either as partially identical or as having a tive explanations (arguments) are not available. This
direct influence on one another, although there is becomes possible because the boundaries between
no spatial contact or intelligible causal connection the self (thought) and the external world (things) are
between them. less rigid than they are in adults (Piaget, 1969).
(Piaget, 1969, p. 132)

Piaget explained this way of thinking by an egocen- Who Believes in Magic?


tric logic (“constant assimilation of external processes The question is, whether it is true that only
to schemas arising from internal experience,” 1969, children, adolescents, and the “primitive” believe in
p. 132) that is overcome when the child discovers that magic and perform magical practices. The examples
others do not think like it does, when it is disillusioned, given at the beginning of this chapter would suggest
so that it has to “bow to the exigencies of control and otherwise.
verification which are implied by discussion and argu- If magical practices/rituals like the ones described
ment” (Piaget, 2001, p. 302). Eventually, according to above are observed in adults, some sort of “distur-
Piaget, the child will thus replace the egocentric logic bance” is often assumed. Piaget (1969) points out
with “true” logic (see Piaget, 2001). that Freud would take narcissism as an explanation
Where does magic play a role in this? Piaget for the magical practices some of his adult patients
assumes that the egocentric logic corresponds with a performed. The assumption here is that adults, who
primitive psychological causality, “probably in a form are in love with themselves, consider their desires
that implies magic proper” (2001, p. 303), since chil- and wishes of special value and thus believe in their
dren believe that their desires can influence objects. efficacy—which Piaget distinguishes strictly from the
They believe in the obedience of external things. child’s developmental phase of narcissism (absolute
It is important to note that “magic,” as described egocentricity). Piaget himself assumes that magical
here, is summarizing cognitive processes based on practices and beliefs in adults can be explained by
the Law of Participation. Other authors have used a temporary weakening of the boundaries between
it in the same, but others also in different ways. the self and the external world. The examples he
Sully (1897), for example, uses the term “magic” to gives are involuntary imitation (e.g., someone has a
describe imaginativeness of children, thus, referring stuffed nose, the observer feels like blowing his nose
to fantasy. Following these observations, Piaget uses to improve the situation of the other), anxiety, and
the term magic “for the use the individual believes monoϊdeic desire. Piaget says that when adults experi-
he can make of the [above defined] participation to ence anxiety, processes that usually only occur in chil-
modify reality” (1969, p.132). In correspondence dren (feelings of participation) can be observed. The

Box 37.1 Classifying Magical Practices by Structure (Piaget, 1969)


• Magic by participation between actions and things: The child performs an action (including mental
operations like, e.g., counting) to influence an event that he or she either desires or fears.
• Magic by participation between thought (only internally or articulated aloud) and things: The child
thinks of something to modify reality (e.g., wishing for somebody to visit in order to increase the
likelihood of this event).
• Magic by participation between objects: The child uses (or particularly does not use) an object to
influence another object (e.g., wearing a certain pair of socks when competing in sports because they
make you a better athlete).
• Magic by participation of purpose: The child regards objects as living and purposive (animism).
The object thus has a will, which can be influenced by the child’s will, displaying participation between
the object’s and the child’s will (e.g., telling the clouds to go away).

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 785


example he gives is the desire to “observe even the factors (e.g., temperature, evaporation). This obser-
most insignificant details of the ordinary routine so vation leads Meehl to define magic as a
that the balance of things shall not be upset” (Piaget,
. . . belief, quasi-belief, or semi-serious entertainment
1969, p.164). Rituals thus help adults to maintain a
of the possibility that events which, according to
feeling of control, which can only be explained by the
the causal concepts of this [or other] culture[s],
above-mentioned feeling of participation (=magic).
cannot have a causal relation with each other, might
In the case of the desire, participation goes hand in
somehow nevertheless do so.
hand with animist ideas.
(1964, as cited in Berenbaum, Boden, & Baker, 2009, p.54)
The study of these shows that it is generally sufficient
Meehl’s definition of magic, as presented here, is a
ardently to desire something outside of our control
rather broad one. Others prefer a narrower approach
[ . . . ] in order to have the impression of a sort of
to, for example, be able to differentiate between
hostile power seeking to mock us. The desire thus
magical thinking and peculiar beliefs. Here, both are
becomes hypostatised in the things and by projection
considered to be one and the same (see Berenbaum,
personifies fate and events. This realist tendency is
Boden, & Baker, 2009, for further readings on this
sufficient to cause any number of magical tendencies.
topic). Even though being taken from the Manual
(Piaget, 1969, p.164)
for Use with Checklist of Schizotypic Signs, the defi-
Piaget illustrated this description with the story nition seems to describe a possible behavior among
of a man who is reluctant to take off his raincoat adults that are not in need of any treatment (see
after it stopped raining to prevent rain from starting Belzen, 2011). Berenbaum et al. (2009) actually
again—an example for which Risen and Gilovich draw a picture of a continuum: On one end would
(2008) later show that many adult individuals actu- be those individuals who do not believe in magic or
ally believe that the likelihood of the event “no rain” apply magical practices, on the other end, patients
actually decreased because of “them not taking off with psychopathological symptoms—suffering from
the raincoat” even though they recognize ratio- delusions (=extreme versions of magical thinking)—
nally that the events are not correlated. This can be would be found. In the middle, nonpathological
observed in different cultures—“primitive” or not: cases that (partially) believe in magic and maybe
even apply magical practices would complete the
People in different cultures, regardless of their explicit
continuum.
beliefs, do not much differ in the tendency for
This assumption is supported by studies that
negative outcomes to jump to mind and in the use of
focus on ritualized behavior in clinical obsessive-
accessibility as a cue for judging likelihood. Instead,
compulsive disorder (OCD) and nonclinical cases.
cultures are more likely to differ in their access to and
Here, rituals are believed to be necessary to ensure
reliance on abstract rules that override such automatic
a positive outcome of some, often apparently
associations and assessments [. . .]. Thus, members of
unrelated event. Consistent with Piaget (1969),
some cultures fully believe that it is bad luck to tempt
Franzblau (1997) showed—for the nonclinical
fate. Members of other cultures intuitively believe it
cases—that engaging in rituals is perceived as reduc-
(and often behave accordingly) but simultaneously
ing feelings of anxiety, fear, and discomfort, while
know that the belief is not rational.
at the same time increasing feelings of control and
(Risen & Gilovich, 2008, p. 305)
security. Reuven-Magril, Dar, and Liberman (2008)
The difference between adults and children seems to show similar mechanisms in OCD patients: They
be that, for the child, magic (=participation) is a way describe rituals as means for achieving an illusory
of thinking to which there is, for at least some time, sense of control to cope with stressful life events—
no alternative. Phelps and Woolley state that chil- just with a different intensity. By drawing a pic-
dren rely on magic when “they encounter events that ture of a continuum between the pathological and
both violate their expectations and elude adequate the nonpathological, we address a topic that oth-
physical explanation” (1994, p. 385). Adults, how- ers have already discussed in the past. Kretschmer
ever, know—if the environment has provided them (1921), for example, thought that thin individuals
with this knowledge—about the scientific, fact-based tended to be introverted and timid, which was seen
background of different phenomena. They know, for as a milder form of the negative symptoms exhib-
example, that rain cannot be influenced by not tak- ited by withdrawn schizophrenics. Even though
ing off a raincoat since the rain is influenced by other Kretschmer’s constitutional approach, linking body

786 th e maki ng o f mag i c


shape to personality, does not influence today’s per- • I believe in them anyway. I know this sounds
sonality theory anymore, the description of a con- crazy, but it is as it is. (3)
tinuum between the normal and pathological is still
up to date. The person in this example is rational and believes
in miracles at the same time. This contradiction
does neither confuse him, nor does it mean he is
What is Real Logic? crazy. Circumvention allows him to balance incom-
Berenbaum et al. connect magical thinking with
patible domains of belief: Everyday knowledge and
“errors” in thinking. According to them, these errors
religious reasoning, showing that it sometimes is
lead to “judgments, decisions, and beliefs that are
not an either/or question when it comes to being
not entirely rational and logical” (2009, p.198).
rational or not.
“Real” logic or nonmagical thinking would thus
What is missing from Josephs’ and Valsiner’s
be based on rationality and would be “error-free.”
example is the reason for why the man decides to-
Nevertheless, not only children, but also adults often
despite his accentuated rationality—believe in mir-
are irrational—one reason being emotional processes
acles. Is it because he would question his parents’
that interfere with rationality (cp. Pham, 2007).
upbringing and their beliefs if he questioned bibli-
Many examples for this irrationality can be found
cal miracles, which he does not dare doing? Or is
in Dan Ariely’s book (2008) Predictably Irrational:
the argumentation closer to the one used in Pascal’s
The Hidden Forces that Shape Our Decisions.
Wager (cp. Hacking, 1972) that makes the man
Josephs and Valsiner (1999) prefer the term
believe in miracles? Or is the reasoning a completely
inconsistencies over errors in thinking, and map the
different one? Cathcart and Klein (2008) describe
associated meaning-making processes with which
Pascal’s Wager very informally, but to the point as
humans try to make sense of themselves and the
follows:
world. Using microgenetic developmental analysis,
they show that, in fact, the belief in miracles (magi- [Pascal] argued that deciding whether or not to
cal thinking) utilizes the same meaning-making believe in God is essentially engaging in a wager.
processes that are used in everyday life, which leads If we choose to behave as if there is a God and we
them to the argument that these processes are essen- get to the end and it turns out there isn’t, it’s not
tial and mature rather than primitive—in contrast such a big deal. Well, maybe we’ve lost the ability to
to what Leuba, Werner, Piaget, and others have sug- thoroughly enjoy the Seven Deadly Sins, but that’s
gested. Josephs’ and Valsiner’s interviewees most of small potatoes compared to the alternative. If we bet
the time argued not in the extremes of “miracles there isn’t a God, and get to the end only to find out
happen or do not happen,” but rather allowed for there is a God, we’ve lost the Big Enchilada, eternal
the possibility that they “might or might not” hap- bliss. Therefore, according to Pascal, it is a better
pen. This reminds us of Meehl’s definition of magic strategy to live as if there is a God.
in which—despite knowing better—individuals (p. 100)
would still consider causal relations between appar-
A deeper microgenetic analysis would be necessary
ently unrelated events as possible explanations; even
to answer this question—if answering it is pos-
though they might start off with a preference for
sible at all, since some of the underlying reasons
either “might” or “might not.” Using Josephs’ and
might not be directly accessible for the individual.
Valsiner’s (1999) terminology, this apparent con-
If they are, for example, part of the sub- or uncon-
tradiction can be solved by applying circumvention
scious, they might only lead to a vague feeling of
strategies. Circumvention is a meaning-making pro-
anxiety (see for example, Mayer & Merckelbach,
cess that temporarily neutralizes generalized semi-
1999).
otic macro-organizers that represent convictions,
worldviews, rules, etc. An example for circumven-
tion of meaning by focusing on harmonious coexistence Voices from the Past
of meaning complexes is the following (Josephs & A step toward answering the questions above is
Valsiner, 1999, p. 111): the analysis of already existing data. In 1928, Heinz
Werner and Martha Muchow—working at Hamburg
• Rationally, the biblical miracles cannot University in close collaboration with William Stern
happen. (1) and Ernst Cassirer—developed a questionnaire to
• I am a rational man. (2) examine (magical) personal customs, which was

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 787


published in the Journal for Educational Psychology destiny when you had to make important decisions
in Germany (Muchow, 1928). Precedent inter- or perform in a certain way or when you thought
views with adolescents and adults at Hamburg’s that the outcome was mainly a question of chance?
Psychological Laboratory had shown the relevance
of these magical customs with which adolescents as This question also included an explanation of what
well as adults tried, for example, to secure the positive oracles—as one example of magical practices—are,
outcome of future actions or to influence decisions which was taken from Muchow’s (1928) question-
that depended on chance in favor of their wishes. naire. The explanation was the following:
It is assumed that about 600 completed question- By oracle we mean the following:
naires must have existed at the time, but that most a. Oracles for which you had to do something
of them were lost at the beginning of World War that had (almost) nothing to do with the expected or
II (Faulstich-Wieland, 2007). Fortunately, a few of feared (e.g.; balancing on a low balustrade, foot
these questionnaires still made their way to Clark racing a car or bus to a certain point, gathering a
University in Worcester, Massachusetts, together certain number of hats, coins, etc.).
with other academic belongings of Heinz Werner, b. Oracles for which you remain rather passive
which allowed us to reexamine the then-collected (e.g.; two bus lines drive past your house, seeing
data. In addition, we translated Muchow’s question- one of the two on your way home brings “good
naire and had it filled out by current undergradu- luck,” seeing the other brings “bad luck;” counting
ate students of the Psychology Department at Clark the trees that grow alongside a certain street, if the
University, so that we can compare the answers final number is even, it is considered “good,” if it is
given 80 years ago with the answers provided today. uneven “bad,” etc.).
A brief description of both samples can be found in
Table 37.1. Of Werner’s and Muchow’s interviewees, 18.6%
(N=8, with 2 missing) said that they did not use ora-
Comparing the Use of Magic cles at all when they were younger, and 25% (N=10)
Then and Now of ours said they did not. All others had consulted
Although Werner (1927) argued that only chil- oracles of some sort with varying frequency, show-
dren and the primitive believe in magic, his and ing that it was and is a quite common phenomenon
Muchow’s data provides evidence that also adults among adolescents.
believe in magic and engage in magical rituals—as Question 2: Do you still use the oracles described
already discussed above. In the following sections, above [or other magical practices]?
we will introduce an excerpt of the questions asked
in both studies and the results for both samples. This Of the ones that consulted oracles as adolescents,
will allow us to see if magical rituals have changed 84.9% (N=28) of Werner’s and Muchow’s intervie-
in content and use, or whether the underlying func- wees and 83.3% (N=25) of ours still use(d) oracles
tions of rituals have stayed the same over time. (occasionally) today. In both cases, it is striking that
many claim to know that oracles or other magical
Question 1: Did you [as an adolescent] sometimes practices are irrational (e.g., with statements like
need so-called oracles or interrogations of your “They are interesting but of course not reliable”

Table 37.1 Sample description


Brief description of the two samples
Muchow & Werner, 1928 (MW) Watzlawik & Valsiner, 2009 (WV)

Study conducted in Hamburg, Germany Study conducted in Worcester, MA, USA

N = 43 N = 40

9 females, 24 males, for 10 sex is unknown 26 females, 14 males

Average age: 23.4 (SD = 5.3) (14 missing) Average age: 20.4 (SD = 4.8)

788 th e maki ng o f mag i c


[WV-ID 9]), but that they would still perform adults, but emerging adults (Arnett, 2004) that are
them, if: still in an exploratory state and are, thus, prone to
using practices that allow them to feel in control of
(a) a very important decision has to be made
their lives. Nevertheless are they aware of the magi-
(e.g., “Yes, rarely, only for important decisions”
cal practices’ irrationality, so that applying magic
[WV-ID 24]);
does (a) not equal participation beliefs as found
(b) the decision to make is very insignificant
in children, and (b) is also not pathological since
(e.g., “I still perform them often today, but never
it helps the individual to cope with current inse-
before big decisions, it appears to be playful and
curities. At this developmental stage, magical ritu-
wrong” [“Ich übe sie heute noch des öfteren, aber
als can therefore be a possible coping strategy (cp.
nie vor großen Entscheidungen, es erscheint mir
Keinan, 1994). It is thus questionable, if it is only
spielerisch und unrecht”] [MW-ID 3]); or
a developmental stage or even disturbance. It seems
(c) the situation is extremely stressful (e.g., “In
more likely that these practices fulfill certain func-
times of strong mental efforts, when overstimulation
tions: facilitating decisions, providing a feeling of
of the nerves occurs, rituals of this kind re-emerge”
control, or regulating emotions. The answers to the
[“In Zeiten von starker geistiger Anstrengung, bei
following questions will provide further insight in
Überreizung der Nerven treten solche Bräuche
this matter.
wieder auf”] [MW-ID 456], or “unless I have
absolutely no idea about what to do” [WV-ID 12]). Question 3: Can you remember how you came
The argumentations found in both samples are up with these rituals; specifically, can you tell
very similar and can be phrased in terms of Josephs’ us something about the inner and outer causes
and Valsiner’s (1999) concept of circumvention of that would help us understand how these rituals
meaning. As in the example introduced above, we developed?
would start off with the statement:
Of Werner’s and Muchow’s interviewees, 28 pro-
• Believing in magical rituals is irrational. (1) vided an explanation for why they came up with
these magical rituals, as did 29 of our interviewees.
Then the self-evaluation follows:
We categorized the answers to give an overview of
• I am a rational person. (2) the different explanations. In Table 37.2 the differ-
ent categories, sample answers, and frequencies can
To still be able to apply magical rituals, circum-
be found.
vention is necessary, which can be achieved by dif-
The most frequent answer in both samples is
ferent paths of meaning making:
that magical rituals were or are used, because they
• But in this situation, it still might help me find the
were introduced by others or were observed in oth-
right solution. (3a)
ers. The answer that magical rituals are a cultural
• But I do not use them for important things
thing goes in the same direction. These rituals are
anyway. (3b)
thus suggested or shown by different sources that,
• But it makes me feel better at the moment. (3c)
for example, Bronfenbrenner (1979) divided into
In each case, the contradiction between being a different, but cross-linked systems. Attitudes and
rational person and applying or believing in magical ideologies that characterize cultural groups would
practices is solved and allows for a balanced evalu- be subsumed under the macrosystems, whereas the
ation of the situation. Of course, this is only neces- family, peers, and others form different microsystems.
sary if a contradiction exists. In both samples, few From both, as well as in-between systems, magical
interviewees seemed to simply accept their beliefs rituals can be suggested (see Figure 37.1).
in magical practices and did not evaluate this as Whether an individual adopts the rituals depends,
“irrational.” Some even stated the following: “It on the one hand, on the intensity with which they are
[consulting oracles] seems logical” [WV-ID 18]. reinforced, on the other, individual characteristics—
Circumvention is then not necessary. such as anxiety, emotional salience/awareness, etc.—
The answers to Question 2 showed, that no also play an important role (cp. Berenbaum et al.,
matter if we look at the data collected in 1928 or 2009). Another individual mechanism is described by
in 2009, many adults still apply magical rituals the participants from 1928. They mention the par-
(oracles) in different situations. Of course, it can allel occurrence of events as one possible cause for
be argued that the 2009 sample does not consist of the emergence of magical rituals. In fact, Pronin,

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 789


Table 37.2 Categories, sample answers, and frequencies of the different explanations for why magical practices
emerged (multiple answers possible)
Category Sample answers 1928 2009

Learned rituals • Mostly through the influences of friends. I saw them doing 13 15
through or from it and would try for myself.
others • My mother came from Lusatia, which is full of superstitions.
The whole upbringing was interspersed with it.
Rituals are consid- • I guess using a coin was something that was part of the – 2
ered to be part of culture I was growing up with.
the culture

Rituals were just • Made them up, they dealt with chance. For example, ‘If I make 6 4
“made up” (on the this shot in basketball I’ll get an A on my test.’
spot), emerged • Quickly, I said to myself: ‘If you reach the door at the same time
from sudden as the man (to make me go faster), you will find something nice,
ideas/impulses
a letter, a lunch.’ I promised myself a reward, but I knew that it
might become true even without the promise to me; I did not
want to promise anything completely absurd. But I knew that
it could also not occur, but I admitted that to myself only after
I performed what I had promised something for. I used those
rituals thus to incite myself.
Rituals were • They started when I started driving and I often would count 5 2
triggered by cars passing, and one day after the eighth car, there was an
unpleasant/ accident. I do not know why it affected me.
traumatic • In my opinion, they emerged after unpleasant experiences that
experiences
needed an explanation. One is rarely inclined to see oneself as
the determining causal factor of the unfavorable events.
Rituals emerged • The cause of this ritual is, in my opinion, that I walked that 6 –
by the coincidental way maybe coincidentally and then, especially that day, the
parallel occurrence lessons would—contrary to expectations—be good.
of events

Others • A certain anxiousness [ . . . ] was over-compensated by a strong 5 4


religiosity, that caused a fast faith in wonders. The rituals might
have been an outlet of this faith; they were their field of activity.
When the thought of causality slowly interfered, religiosity served
to outcompete it (God can do anything, even act against laws).

Wegner, McCarthy, and Rodriguez (2006) showed in rituals. The chronosystem (see Figure 37.1) stresses the
several studies—with which they examined whether importance of the situation when we examine the
having thoughts related to an event before it occurs emergence of magical rituals. An individual might be
leads people to infer that they caused the event (mag- more receivable for the adoption of magical rituals in
ical causation)—that this quite often is the case, even stressful than nonstressful situations (e.g., after trau-
when the thought-about outcome was unwanted matic or stressful events, Keinan, 1994; also De Rios,
by the research participants (also cp. Rothbart & 1997, presented how cultural superheroes [magical
Snyder, 1970). In 2009, this parallel occurrence is realism] can be used as an intervention for trauma-
only referred to by the interviewees with the examples tized children). Another important factor of “time”
given for the traumatic events that proceeded magical or the chronosystem is the Zeitgeist being reflected

790 th e maki ng o f mag i c


Macrosystem

Exosystem
extended family

Mesosystem

Microsystem

laws family The ideolo-


individual gies
peers
religious
group

Chronosystem
environmental events and transitions over the life course Figure 37.1 Different environments with
potential influence on magical rituals
(cp. Bronfenbrenner, 1979).

in the content of different rituals. Even though the “powerful”— meaning the effect on the person, not
function of rituals seems to be fairly stable over time the effect they had for the person—as other rituals
(based on the observations presented above), the con- that almost seem to dictate the actions of an indi-
tent is not. Werner’s and Muchow’s participants state, vidual and are perceived as not willingly controllable
for example, that they would count a specific type of (“I suffered from such mental compulsion and they
horse (“Schimmel”=gray horse) which was, at their bothered me” MW-ID 480). The latter would lead
time, still an important matter of transportation. us to rituals described in connection with OCD and
With horses being replaced by cars, they are not men- would therefore serve a different function: reducing
tioned anymore by today’s participants. Overall, we feelings of anxiety, fear, and discomfort, and increasing
can say that magical rituals are not caused by a single feelings of control and security. For the first, additional
factor, but emerge out of the interplay of personal, evidence is provided by the answers to Question 4
social, and cultural factors (cp. Risen & Gilovich, (see below).
2008). Closely related to the question about what Again, we observe a continuum of ritual con-
causes magical rituals is the question of what they trollability: from willingly and purposely inventing
are good for: Why do individuals engage in magical and applying rituals that are based on the Law of
practices? Some answers to this question are already Participation to being dictated by such rituals that
implied in the categories described in Table 37.2. The cannot be willingly controlled. The cases in which
rituals that were made up on the spot, for example, individuals state that rituals help, but that they do
serve the function of self-motivation. This is explic- not have to perform them necessarily, would lie in
itly mentioned by the interviewees: “Because I tend between the above-described extremes. It is very
to procrastinate often these help me stay on task” likely that the relief (emotional component) an indi-
(WV-ID 11), or “to make me go faster” (MW-ID vidual feels after applying a certain ritual determines
472). They are applied to serve a specific purpose at the frequency with which it is used, but we can-
a certain moment (only). They are very much con- not prove this assumption with the data collected.
trolled by the individual to challenge oneself, escape Further research is needed in this case.
boredom, or—as one of Muchow’s and Werner’s We stated above that children rely on magic when
interviewees phrased it—“to counterbalance the they encounter events that both violate their expec-
too much reinforced intellectualism in school” tations and elude adequate physical explanation.
(MW-ID 485). Rituals of this kind seem to be not as Is this also true for adults? Two of our participants

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 791


actually describe events that would fall into this cat- Overall, the samples do not differ much in
egory, one being: “I thought if I was skating par- their answers confirming that anxiety was and is an
ticularly good one day—and not the others, and I important trigger for magical rituals.
was doing everything the same, there must be some
Question 5: What happened if you were meant to
mysterious force that was improving my ability or
do something to influence an outcome and then you
that I was just getting lucky that day” (MW-ID 5).
didn’t succeed? [American sample only]
Experimental studies with adults also confirm that
adults also tend to assume relations between events, For the American interviewees, we added the above
where—rationally speaking—there cannot be any question to find out how fragile/stable the belief in
(cp. Risen & Gilovich, 2008; Pronin et al., 2006). these rituals was. The answers were again catego-
Thus, magic is indeed considered when we are lack- rized and are displayed in Table 37.4.
ing alternative, rational explanations—but not only The different reactions to the failure of a ritual
then. may be influenced by the importance the particular
ritual has for that person. Some of our interviewees
Question 4: Do you think that these rituals that you
were just able to “shrug it off” (low importance),
performed during adolescence developed because you
other simply denied the failure and looked for alter-
were afraid of important decisions or maybe even
native explanations (high importance)—the most
afraid of life in general?
popular one being blaming oneself instead of the
Of our interviewees, 29 answered this question, ritual.
as did 30 of Muchow’s and Werner’s intervie- Although Werner and Muchow did not ask
wees. The interviewees in both groups differenti- specifically what we asked, some participants still
ated between the different things they were afraid described situations in which rituals lost their
of—if they were afraid—so that we decided to do importance or were abandoned altogether. The fol-
the same when summarizing their answers (see lowing case shows that the importance of what one
Table 37.3). wishes for also is an important factor:

Table 37.3 Summary of the answers to Question 4 (multiple answers possible)


Category Sample answers 1928 2009

No 11 9

Yes (without further explanations) 5 6

Maybe (without further explanations) – 5

Afraid of life in general • Probably more because of being afraid of life 5 –


in general.
Afraid of important decisions • They did not that much emerge because of 5 –
being afraid of life, but because of being
afraid of important decisions.
Afraid that something bad will • Probably, I’ve always been afraid of losing a 5 7
happen (failure) family member.
• Maybe because I was scared that if I didn’t
have these rituals it would be hard for me to
get motivated any other way.
• I think I was afraid of not being perfect.
Afraid of solely being responsible for • Because I don’t want to be solely in charge/ 2 2
one’s actions responsible for my actions.
Afraid of authorities • Being afraid of the mother and school. 2 –

792 th e maki ng o f mag i c


Table 37.4 Categories, sample answers, and frequencies for the answers to what would happen if a ritual was not
successful (American sample only) (N = 23)
Category Sample answers 2009

Blame myself, instead • I would blame myself most likely (for poor preparation, etc.) 6
of ritual rather than blame the rituals, although I may consider what
the outcome would have been if I had followed them.
Shrug it off/ignore it • I’d just ignore the oracle and do what I wanted anyway. 4
• Shrug it off.
Feel bad/awful • I would feel awful. 3

Try again (later) • I would make sure to do it next time; it was almost like a 3
superstition.
• Then I would try again and hope it worked better.
Re-interpreted situation • Talk myself into believing that it actually worked, just in a 2
modified version.
Change ritual (was flawed) • Perhaps the ritual was flawed; I would need to modify it. 1

Deny it, but keep • I start denying it, but still believing in it next time it occurs. 1
believing in it

Would be disappointed, but • Disappointed but didn’t diminish my belief in them. 1


kept believing in them

Lost some faith in them • I lost some faith in the rituals. 1

Think about it • I would walk away and think about what happened. 1

When my parents were in hospital, badly injured (N=26; 78.8%). Only one person said that he did
because of a car accident, I desperately tried different speak to others about these things. Unfortunately,
things to influence their fate. Being very religious he did not comment any further on this statement.
from early on, I prayed to God. I also jumped over Six people (18.2%) replied that they selected the
a fence in the yard that was 1.3 m high and believed people they talked to very carefully: They did talk
that things would turn out well because of my to some and did not talk to others. What were the
success. When my mother died shortly after, things reasons for not talking to anyone or to carefully
changed: I now hated religion and with that all select the appropriate confidants? Most of the par-
rituals that I once cherished and that now seemed ticipants that gave reasons said that they were afraid
useless to me. I swore to myself never to believe in others would laugh at them, they were embarrassed
any rituals like that again, or to suppress them should or feared embarrassment (N=18). Other reasons
they occur nevertheless, were that discussing a ritual might have affected
(MW-ID 476) its success (N=1), the ritual was not a conscious
thing (N=1), one did not want to bother others
Question 6: Did you keep those rituals a secret or
with subjects they were not interested in (N=1), the
did you talk to others about them? Who did you
ritual was too important (N=1), or too insignificant
tell? If you didn’t tell anyone, what were the reasons?
(N=1), or—last but not least—the ritual was not
[German sample only]
the business of anyone else (N=1).
A question that only the German sample answered These answers show that magical rituals usu-
was the one above asking whether rituals were kept ally are a very private matter. Applying magic often
secret or not. The vast majority says that they did means to act against one’s better knowledge (“I
not speak to anyone about their magical practices know this is not rational, but . . .”), which cannot

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 793


easily be justified when being confronted with it. complex—practical, occasional, concrete [relations
The functions discussed above show, nevertheless, are reflected].
that magical rituals make “personal” sense and can (Vygotsky, 1931, p. 250)
fulfill different, important purposes (see Question
The process of differentiation and hierarchical inte-
3)—even though knowledge would suggest other-
gration in the process of moving from complexes to
wise. Furthermore, the magical rituals created by
concepts was viewed by Vygotsky to entail an impor-
the person oneself are parts of personal culture—
tant transitional form—that of pseudo-concept. This
hence not necessarily shareable with others.
is a form of reasoning that at the outside looks like
concept (i.e., seems organized by an abstract, unitary
Conclusion: The Unbearable Pleasures relation between objects), but in reality remains a
of Magic complex (i.e., entails multitude of relations between
If we think that a society has left magical think-
objects). Among those relationships, the beliefs in
ing behind, because of the technological and eco-
rationality of the necessarily irrational world are
nomic orientations, think twice. The phenomena of
widespread.
fascination with Harry Potter and the lures of get-
The invention of the supernatural is particularly
ting rich by luck on a stock market bring us to new
rampant in critical life situations. In the civil war in
magics of the video screens and consumer cults.
Uganda in the late 1980s, it was the war activities
Contemporary societies abound in ever-new magi-
that were cast in the power of supernatural forces
cal rituals in public life and on TV screens. Hence,
(Behrend, 1999). Such inventions are possible
magical rituals:
thanks to the capacity of the mind to create semi-
. . . are not merely the product of people who have otic hierarchies that can include high-level field-like
failed to reach formal operational thought; rather, signs (Valsiner, 2007). The crucial nature of the
they reflect the felt limits of science and technology supernatural forces a person could believe in is their
for answering questions about meaning, value, and nebulosity—they are considered to be responsible
being. These issues are significant, not only in their for very concrete acts, yet they are not in any place.
own right, but also for the insight they provide into They are believed to be everywhere.
the wider importance of existential concerns in
human development. Future Directions
(Vandenberg, 1991, p.1284) Contemporary cultural psychology needs to take
a fresh look at newly emerging examples of magi-
Instead, magical thinking is part of any forward-
cal thinking. Looking at these phenomena at the
oriented productive thinking. Human minds weave
intersection of society and individuals can reveal
their semiotic webs of organization of the meaning
the connections of intrinsic motivational forces and
so as to face the future. This is mostly accomplished
social guidance of human minds. More specifically,
by thinking in complexes—rather than in concepts.
it would be important to study:
Lev Vygotsky emphasized that:
• What kinds of social representations (“luck,”
. . . the complex, like the concept, is a generalization “devil,” “success,” etc.) support the emergence and
and unifier of concrete varied objects. However, use of new personal magical rituals;
the tie with which this generalization is built, • How a person creates one’s new “lucky
can be of most different type. Any kind of link charm” in one’s personal life? How would magical
can lead to the inclusion of a given object in a moments enter into any mundane area of living?
complex, if it only practically exists—and the The invention of a ritual of luck in competitive
characteristic feature of the complex is exactly settings, or of a new belief in the power of a new
that. When linkages of unified type—logically electronic gadget in bringing happiness into
equivalent to one another—are at the foundation of private lives;
the concept, very varied factual linkages that often • How social institutions promote the use of
have nothing in common with one another, are magic thinking in social situations—in peace and
the bases of a complex. In the concept, objects are war settings.
generalized by one characteristic, in a complex—by
most varied practical bases. That is why in the Acknowledgments
concept the relevant, unifying link and relationship The work on this chapter was supported by the Feodor
between objects finds its reflection, while in a Lynen Scholarship to the first author, awarded by Alexander von

794 th e maki ng o f mag i c


Humboldt-Stiftung. The careful maintenance of Heinz Werner F. K. Oser, & W. G. Scarlett (Eds.), Psychological studies on
papers in Heinz Werner Library at Clark University by Seymour spiritual and religious development. Being human: The case of
Wapner is to be specially acknowledged. religion (Vol. 2) (pp. 101–114). Lengerich, Germany: Pabst
Science.
Keinan, G. (1994). Effects of stress and tolerance of ambigu-
References
ity on magical thinking. Journal of Personality and Social
Ariely, D. (2008). Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that
Psychology, 67(1), 48–55.
shape our decisions. New York, NY: Harper Collins.
Kretschmer, E. (1921). Körperbau und charakter [Physique and
Arnett, J. (2004). Emerging adulthood: The winding road from late
character]. Berlin: Springer.
teens through the twenties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lefcourt, H. M. (1973). The function of the illusions of control
Behrend, H. (1999). Alice Lakwena & the Holy Spirits. Oxford:
and freedom. American Psychologist, 28(5), 417–425.
James Currey.
Leuba, J. H. (1912). The varieties, classification, and origin of
Berenbaum, H., Boden, M. T., & Baker, J. P. (2009). Emotional
magic. American Anthropologist, 14(2), 350–367.
salience, emotional awareness, peculiar beliefs, and magical
Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1926). Das denken der naturvölker [How natives
thinking. Emotion, 9(2), 197–205.
think] (2nd ed.). Wien, Austria: Braumüller.
Boesch, E. E. (2000). Das lauernde chaos [The lurking chaos].
Bern, Switzerland: Hans Huber. Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1985). How natives think. Princeton, NJ:
Boesch, E. E.(2011). Culture: Result and condition of action. In Princeton University Press. [Original: 1911]
J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of psychology and culture. Mayer, B., & Merckelbach, H. (1999). Unconscious processes,
New York: Oxford University Press. subliminal stimulation, and anxiety. Clinical Psychology
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The ecology of human development: Review, 19(5), 571–590.
Experiments by nature and design. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Muchow, M. (1928). Fragebogen des Hamburger Psychologischen
University Press. Laboratoriums über persönliche bräuche [Questionnaire of
Cathcart, T., & Klein, D. (2008). Plato and a platypus walk into the Hamburg Psychological Laboratory about personal cus-
a bar . . . Understanding philosophy through jokes. New York: toms]. Zeitschrift für Pädagogische Psychologie, 29, 494–496.
Penguin Books. Neveux, M. (1966). The oracle, the ordeal and the bet. Diogenes,
De Rios, M. D. (1997). Magical realism: A cultural interven- 14(56), 92–114.
tion for traumatize Hispanic children. Cultural Diversity and Pham, M. T. (2007). Emotion and rationality: A critical review
Mental Health, 3(3), 159–170. and interpretation of empirical evidence. Review of General
Del Río, P., & Alvarez, A. (2007). Prayer as the kingdom of Psychology, 11,155–178.
heaven: Psychological tools for directivity. In J. Valsiner & Phelps, K. E. & Woolley, J. D. (1994). The form and function
A. Rosa (Eds.), Handbook of sociocultural psychology of young children’s magical beliefs. Developmental Psychology,
(pp. 373–394). New York: Cambridge University Press. 30(3), 385–394.
Eckensberger, L. H. (2011). Culture inclusive action theory: Piaget. J. (1969). The child’s conception of the world. Totowa, NJ:
Action theory in dialectics and dialectics in action theory. In Littlefield, Adams & Co.
J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of psychology and culture. Piaget, J. (2001). The child’s conception of physical causality. New
New York: Oxford University Press. Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Faulstich-Wieland, H. (2007). Martha Muchow—Leben und Pronin, E., Wegner, D. M., McCarthy, K., & Rodriguez, S.
Werk [Martha Muchow—Life and works] [online docu- (2006). Everyday magical powers: The role of apparent
ment]. Recallable via: http://www.uni-hamburg.de/fachbere- mental causation in the overestimation of personal influ-
iche-einrichtungen/fak_4/bibliothek/laudatio.pdf [Accessed ence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91(2),
November 2009]. 218–231.
Franzblau, S. H. (1997). The penomenology of ritualized and Reuven-Magril, O., Dar, R., & Liberman, N. (2008). Illusion
repeated behaviors in nonclinical populations in the United of control and behavioral control attempts in obsessive–
States. Cultural Diversity and Mental Health, 3(4), 259–272. compulsive disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 117(2),
Frazer, J. G. (1920). The golden bough (3rd ed.). London: 334–341.
MacMillan. Risen, J. L., & Gilovich, T. (2008). Why people are reluctant to
Gess, N. (2009). Magisches Denken im Kinderspiel. Literatur tempt fate. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95(2),
und Entwicklungspsychologie im frühen 20. Jahrhundert 293–307.
[Magical thinking in children’s games. Literature and devel- Rothbart, M., & Snyder, M. (1970). Confidence in the predic-
opmental psychology in the early 20th century]. In T. Anz tion and postdiction of an uncertain outcome. Canadian
& H. Kaulen (Eds.), Literatur als spiel. Evolutionsbiologische, Journal of Behavioural Science, 2(1), 38–43.
ästhetische und pädagogische konzepte [Literature as game. Sully, J. (1897). Untersuchungen über die kindheit [Studies of
Evolutionary-biological, aesthetic, and educational concepts] childhood]. Leipzig, Germany: Wunderlich.
(pp. 295–314). Berlin: de Gruyter. Tylor, E. B. (1871). Primitive cultures: Researches into the devel-
Hacking, I. (1972). The logic of Pascal’s Wager. American opment of mythology, philosophy, religion, art, and custom.
Philosophical Quarterly, 9(2), 186–192. London: Murray.
Josephs, I., & Valsiner, J. (1999). Meaning-making and miracles: Werner, H. (1927). Die magie im leben des kindes [Magic in the
The creative inconsistencies of the mind. In K. H. Reich, life of the child]. Berliner Illustrierte Zeitung, 45, 1815.

watz l aw ik, va lsin er 795


CHAPTER

Duties and Rights


38
Fathali M. Moghaddam, Cristina Novoa and Zachary Warren

Abstract
Evidence for relativistic theories of rights and duties is overturned by an analysis of supererogatory acts
in Afghan, Asian, and Spanish-speaking cultures. The authors present a cultural evolutionary account of
the development of rights and duties to explain the appearance of certain universals in the domain of
justice. An order of evolution is proposed: from functional origin in primitive social relations, to informal
labeling as “rights” and “duties,” to formalization in black-letter law. The authors recommend two future
directions of research: an investigation of the cycle of rights and duties as understood in different political
and cultural contexts, and a closer analysis of universal duties, beyond human rights alone.
Keywords: rights and duties, supererogation, cultural evolution, primitive social relations, universals,
family rights and duties, religious systems, normative justice, cycle of rights and duties, Afghan culture,
Latino and Spanish cultures, Asian cultures

Do you refuse me, Antigonê? I want to die with you: against the king, even though she knows she will be
I too have a duty that I must discharge killed for this act. Her sister Ismene also requests to
die with Antigonê, in order to discharge her duty.
These words are spoken by Ismene, sister to
This duty, says Antigonê, is for laws that:
Antigonê, in a play by the same name, written by
Sophocles (442 B.C./1977, p. 207) at a time when . . . are not merely now: they were, and shall be,
Athenian democracy was at its height. The democ- Operative for ever, beyond man utterly
racy of Athens was centered on duties, demands (Sophocles, 442 B.C./1977, p. 203)
placed by others on the persons who owe them.
Every Athenian male citizen not only served in the The centrality of duties in ancient Athens seems
military, but also had judicial, legislative, and execu- far removed from the culture of twenty-first-century
tive duties: Western societies. Indeed, the march of technologi-
cal, scientific, economic, and political progress in
Even many of the highest offices in the land were Western societies has been accompanied by a trum-
filled by allotment and so could fall on any citizen; peting of rights, what we are owed by others, from the
almost all offices could be held only for a single year. struggles of the suffragettes to win voting rights for
In this way maximum participation was achieved, women, to desegregation and the civil rights move-
and every man was a public servant. ment that eventually allowed an African-American
(Lang, 2004, p. 7) to be elected as America’s president in 2008, to gay
This sense of duty was shared by women: rights, disabled person’s rights, senior rights, chil-
Antigonê buries her brother Polyneicês, a rebel dren’s rights, patients’ rights, animal rights, and

796
so on. But this has not been a universal trend; the later, selected duties and rights became transformed
“progress of rights” has not moved forward much and formalized in black-letter law. A psychological
in practice, if at all, in some countries. For exam- understanding of duties and rights thus considers
ple, though rights such as freedom of expression the development of these informal rights and duties,
and freedom of assembly are taken for granted in which evolved prior to formal, black-letter law.
Western societies, these remain severely restricted This overall process will be explored using exam-
in many parts of the world, such as China, Iran, ples of supererogatory duties, behaviors that a person
and Russia. Indeed, despite the 30 articles set out in is not obligated to perform, but is applauded for car-
the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human rying out, and supererogatory rights, or what a person
Rights, and “agreed to” by nearly all nations as signa- is owed by others, but is willing to forgo for the sake
tories, there are obvious violations of rights in many of the greater good (Moghaddam, 2008, p. 56).
countries. These sometimes include Western coun- We use cross-cultural examples from case studies
tries as well; critics point to the U.S.-led invasion of in Afghani, East Asian, and Spanish-origin cultures
Iraq in 2003, torture of Iraqis at Abu Ghraib prison to showcase the power of social norms in shaping
by U.S. military personnel, and other such “inci- formal and informal rights and duties. Evidence for
dents” to support the claim that Western societies relativistic theories of rights and duties, we argue,
also violate human rights. is overturned by a cultural evolutionary account of
It seems, indeed, that there is “. . . no universally social behavior in the domain of justice. We propose
honored conception of rights and duties” (Louis & that although there are large variations in duties and
Taylor, 2005, p. 105), and that rights and duties are rights across cultures and across time, this variation
normative and can be socially constructed and justi- has masked certain universals, small in number but
fied in many different ways, particularly by those of great importance.
who enjoy greater power. For example, in some Our argument in support of universals is “top-
societies powerful groups serve their own interests down” and is rooted in our “cultural evolutionary”
by highlighting duties (e.g., in Iran the duty to obey conceptual framework. On the other hand, we work
the “Supreme Leader” is highlighted), whereas in “bottom-up” to show variations across cultures in
other societies, power groups prioritize certain rights rights and duties. Given the foundational influ-
(e.g., the right of the super-rich to spend hundreds ence of religious systems on conceptions of rights
of millions of dollars to influence election results and duties in the contemporary world, we begin by
in the United States, justified under the “right to exploring rights and duties in religious systems.
freedom of expression”). This relativistic viewpoint
runs against the idea, as suggested by Antigonê, that Religious Systems and the Hierarchy of
there are duties (and rights) that are “not merely Contemporary Rights and Duties
now,” but “forever” and “beyond man” in the sense The next day he took out two denarii, gave them to
that they are found in all human cultures. the innkeeper, and said, ‘Take care of him; and when
The question of whether there are universal I come back, I will repay you whatever more you
rights and duties is one of a number that psycho- spend.’
logical science has explored, as reflected in the (Luke 10:35 (NRSV))
volume The Psychology of Rights and Duties that
brought together an international group of leading Today the concept of supererogatory action is
scholars in this field (Finkel & Moghaddam, 2004). generally used in a secular context, though its ori-
We begin this discussion by describing a hierarchy gins lie in religious ethics. The term appears in the
of rights and duties and clarifying our position on Christian ethical debates in the late Middle Ages in
five questions that are central and must be addressed reference to voluntary works that are besides, over
in any psychological account of duties and rights, and above God’s commandments. In the biblical
including the question of possible universals. Next, parable of the Good Samaritan, a man from the
we describe a cultural evolutionary account of the southern region of Samaria in Israel finds a stranger
development of duties and rights. This evolution- on the roadside who had been beaten by robbers.
ary perspective suggests that certain functional The Samaritan takes the stranger to an inn, bandages
behaviors evolved early in our history, and at a later his wounds, pays for his lodging, then promises to
stage in human evolution these were labeled “duties go above and beyond: “I will repay you whatever
and rights” as part of informal everyday life. Still more you spend.”

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 797


In Latin, “super-erogare” means to over-expend, (1978), and Robin Attfield (1979), is that an act
or pay in addition. In the Roman Catholic tradi- becomes supererogatory when it meets three crite-
tion, supererogatory acts constitute not simply the ria: (1) it is beyond the call of duty, (2) it is meri-
performance of good works, but good works beyond torious or praiseworthy, and (3) omission of the
sacramental requirement. Roman Catholic officials act is not blameworthy. Secular acts of supereroga-
held that such acts, often performed by saints, could tion have been argued to include legal pardon and
create a “store of merit which the Church can dis- clemency by kings and presidents, volunteering and
pense to others to make up for deficiencies” (OED, community service, acts of qualified self-sacrifice
1989). This framework has been applied to other such as election to be an organ or blood donor, and
acts such as sexual abstinence in place of marriage acts of forgiveness, conscientious tolerance, and
and procreation (Mellema, 1991). In the early six- forbearance (Heyd, 1982; Benbaji & Heyd, 2001;
teenth century, controversy erupted around the Portmore, 2003).
Catholic Church’s interpretation of supereroga- To be clear, little has been written about super-
tory acts in exchange for indulgences paid to the erogatory rights and duties, but some debate around
church. These were cited perhaps most famously the criteria for supererogatory acts continues in the
in the Ninety-Five Theses against the church by disciplines of philosophy and ethics. One group
Martin Luther. Today, the Church of England still argues that supererogatory actions must be self-
requires all clergy to declare allegiance to thirty-five sacrificial and other-regarding: the act should be
articles of faith including one (Article 14) stating “completely gratuitous” (e.g., Heyd, 1982), it should
that “the performance of supererogatory acts cannot bring “much good for the other person,” and should
be taught without arrogance and impiety” (“Opera be performed “at considerable cost or risk to the
quae Supererogationis appellant non pussunt sine agent” (Rawls, 1971, p. 11), and should be “more
arrogantia et impietate preaedicari”) (Book of onerous for ourselves” than for others (Hale, 1991).
Common Prayer, 1662/1999). Others disagree, arguing that supererogatory acts can
Importantly, the concept of supererogation is not be self-regarding (Kawall, 2009) and without benefit
unique to Christianity. In Jewish law the Talmudic or even intended benefit for others (Mellema, 1991).
concept of “beyond the letter of the law” (lifnim Susan Hale (1991) argues that there are no truly
mishurat ha din) applies to self-sacrificial acts of fair- supererogatory actions, only apparently supereroga-
ness and charity that go above the bare minimum tory actions motivated by duty or principle. This is
prescribed by law (Shilo, 1978). In Islam, the con- reminiscent of debates in social psychology about
cept of Isaal-e-Sawaab refers to performing a good whether or not there really is altruism, behavior
deed and granting the heavenly reward for that act intended to help another, without regard for benefit
to another person, a practice not entirely unlike the to oneself. Among the major theories of altruism,
Roman Catholic conception of stored merit, as well the empathy-altruism model of Batson (1995) is
as the Church of Latter Day Saints’ doctrine sur- closest to assuming there is true altruism—all of the
rounding the afterlife and “saving ordinances” for others dismiss this assumption (Moghaddam, 1998,
deceased relatives. To perform nafl prayers in Islam, Chapter 9). In this discussion we are not interested
prayers beyond the general minimum of five times in the question of whether or not either supereroga-
each day, is supererogatory. So too are extra fast- tory acts or altruism actually exist according to some
ing, the giving of voluntary charity (sadaqa) beyond objective criteria, but in the question of how, by
obligatory alms (zakat). labeling a behavior as “supererogatory,” society influ-
In secular ethics, divine command is substituted ences behavior. In the next section, we further clarify
for formalized laws and rights. British philosopher our conceptual orientation.
J. O. Urmson (1958) argued that saintly and heroic
acts should constitute a fourth category in secular Five Basic Questions
ethics, beyond categories of mandatory, permitted, At the outset it is useful to clarify our position on
and forbidden. A soldier who throws himself on a five foundational questions concerning duties and
grenade to save the life of his comrades, according rights: source, function, relationship to supereroga-
to Urmson, is committing a supererogatory act. It tory rights, free will, and replaceability. First, what
is neither required, nor morally neutral, nor forbid- is the source of duties and rights, particularly as set
den by law. The standard view, generally held by out in formal or black-letter law? Second, what is
philosophers Urmson (1958), Sheldon Peterfreund the functional nature of black-letter law? Third,

798 duti es and r i g hts


what is the relationship between black-letter law and child into the river, since doing so would be a crimi-
supererogatory duties and rights? Fourth, should we nal offense. On the other hand, if the child acci-
assume that humans have some measure of free will dentally falls into the river, black-letter law does not
(in the domain of rights and duties, at least)? Fifth, stipulate that Sam must dive into the river to save
are rights and duties replaceable? the child. If the child falls into the river and drowns,
With respect to the source, there are two major Sam will not be sent to jail for failing to be coura-
positions: natural law, whereby duties and rights are geous enough to dive into the river to save the child.
assumed to have derived from natural and divine However, if Sam does dive into the river and saves
sources, and to have been discovered by humans; the child, she will be enthusiastically applauded and
and positive law, where duties and rights are human she might even receive a medal: a supererogatory
constructions and can vary over time and across duty fulfilled (see Figure 38.1)
societies. The account we develop strongly supports Although informal social and cultural norms
a positive law interpretation, based on cultural evi- influence parenting practices, and in turn, the for-
dence. We argue that duties and rights arise out mation of rights and duties, formal black-letter
of cultural evolution that is to some degree shared law also influences family contexts and informal
between humans and other animals, but we do not norms. The relationship is reflexive. For example,
see it as necessary to assume an inherent universal black-letter law formally defines certain parental
“moral grammar” (Hauser, 2006). Rather, we adopt duties according to definitions of abuse and neglect.
a functional interpretation whereby certain behav- However, numerous instances illustrate the mis-
iors, later interpreted as duties and rights, prove to match that can occur between parenting practices
be adaptive and continue to manifest themselves in and the law, particularly among immigrant groups;
the behavior of animals and humans. parenting practices that are common in one culture
Second, we adopt a minimalist interpretation may be legally construed as neglect and a failure to
with respect to the functional nature of black-letter fulfill parenting duties in another. The practice of
law. That is, black-letter law answers the question: cupping, a traditional medical technique performed
what is the minimal or lowest standard of accept- in some cultures, is interpreted as child abuse in
able behavior? This “minimal” takes shape, we some contexts. In regions of Africa, a mother who
believe, with respect to the functional needs of soci- fails to circumcise her female child is chastised by
ety. Black-letter law reflects the baseline conditions other women in the community, whereas female
for the survival of a particular form of society, given circumcision in the United States is punishable by
its various characteristics, and especially its group- prison and the child may even be removed to gov-
based inequalities and power relationships. From ernment child custody. Similarly, Hmong parents
this perspective, then, law is a set of rules, enforced who view epilepsy as a form of spiritual rapture
by institutions, that sets the minimal acceptable have often been charged with neglect for not seek-
standard of behavior, to sustain a particular type of ing treatment for their children (Coleman, 2007).
sociopolitical order. Also, black-letter law reifies the informal rights
Third, black-letter law and supererogatory duties and duties in the family. Imagine a woman named
and rights together define the boundaries of obli- Helen, a retired English banker living in Paris, who
gations, since we argue that supererogatory duties decides to make a will that leaves almost all of her
and rights establish the “upper level” for standards considerable fortune to charity. This is accepted by
of behavior in a given society, just as black-letter her first husband and their two children, who are
law establishes a minimal or “lower level” standard English and live in England. Indeed, after the ini-
of behavior. For example, imagine if Sam is stand- tial shock of learning about the contents of the will,
ing on a bridge, looking down at the boats passing most of Helen’s English family applauds her action
in the river below. A father and child are standing as an example of a supererogatory duty. However,
near Sam. Black-letter law sets the minimal “lowest” the situation is very different with Helen’s second
standard for Sam’s behavior: Sam must not push the husband, a Frenchman, and their three French

Black letter law Supererogatory Figure 38.1 The continuum of “minimal


rights and duties standard” (black-letter law) to exemplary
(supererogatory rights and duties) behavior.

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 799


children, who all live in Paris and adhere to French causally determined rather than normatively regu-
law. From the perspective of Helen’s French fam- lated. For example, when her optician asks Susan,
ily, her will is not only illegal, but immoral. Indeed, “Can you read the last line?” This has to do with
in 26 out of 27 member countries of the European Susan’s visual performance being causally deter-
Union (EU), Helen’s will would be regarded as ille- mined by factors such as aging (what Moghaddam,
gal, because in most of these countries about half 2002, has termed performance capacity). Susan could
of the estate is automatically inherited by surviving read the last line when she was 20 years old, but can
children (unless they have committed parent killing no longer read it now that she is 50 years old. But
or the like). In most of the European Union, Helen if Susan’s optician asks, “What do you think that
would not be legally allowed to leave her estate to symbol means?” This question has to do with the
charity. meaning we ascribe to things, or what Moghaddam
The situation in England and Wales is very dif- (2002) has termed performance style (for example,
ferent because the individual enjoys almost complete “Oh yes, that symbol represents a mysterious love
freedom to decide who will inherit the estate, and potion on this tropical island!” versus, “That symbol
thus there is room for Helen to carry out a super- is just a gimmick used by the local tourist board to
erogatory duty by allocating her estate to charity. attract more visitors to this island!”).
This Anglo-Saxon tradition of individual choice is The fifth question concerns the replaceability
also present in the United States. Now consider the and interchangeability of duties and rights: can a
influence of black-letter inheritance law for a recent duty always be reinterpreted as a right, and a right
immigrant family to the United States. If the fam- as a duty? We can identify two main conceptual
ily immigrated from one of those 26 EU nations in positions on this issue (see Dembour, 2006 for an
which Helen’s action was illegal, informal family per- example of a more detailed classification). First is the
ceptions of inheritance rights and duties will likely natural law position, which holds that at least some
give way to formal law, over successive generations. duties and rights are fixed. For example, the duty to
In essence, black-letter law sets the boundaries of abide by certain moral imperatives, such as “thou
supererogatory duties and rights. shalt not steal,” “thou shalt not kill,” and so on are
Fourth, in religious systems as well as in secular purely duties; a duty to abide by the command “not
ethics, a supererogatory act assumes at least a mini- to steal,” “not to kill,” and so on, cannot be changed
mal level of free will and conscious choice, so that to a “right not to steal,” a “right not to kill,” and so
merit can be rewarded on the basis of the assump- on. Similarly, a “right to freely choose a God” can-
tion that the meritorious person freely chose to do not be replaced by a “duty to freely choose a God.”
good rather than evil. It is assumed, for example, The other view, which we find more compelling,
that saints and heroes are not forced to do good takes positive law as a point of departure, where
works; they act as individual agents. But in tradi- duties and rights can be interpreted as replaceable in
tional experimental psychology, it is assumed that almost all cases. This is suggested by various exam-
independent variables (such as environmental fac- ples across societies in areas such as inheritance of
tors external to the person, or cognitive mechanisms estates and voting in elections.
within the person) serve as causes, and bring about
changes in dependent variables. In this cause–effect The Power of Context and Replaceability
relationship, there is no room for free will. An argu- of Rights and Duties
ment has been made that while some behaviors are Our final two suppositions—the power of social
causally determined, other behaviors, including context to influence choices and free will, and the
behavior in the realm of duties and rights, are better replaceability of rights and duties—merit special
explained through a normative account, which does attention as keystones in our argument. For the
allow for free will (Moghaddam, 2002). first, consider Gregory Mellema’s (1991) prisoner
A normative account of behavior assumes that example. A man is held prisoner by political ter-
much of human thought and action is regulated rorists, and he is commanded to swear allegiance
by norms, rules, and other features of the norma- to the leader of the terrorists—and to renounce
tive system. Most of the time, most people behave allegiance to his own government. The prisoner
according to the rules for correct behavior in a given knows that a refusal to cooperate will result only
context. However, people can choose to behave in in bad consequences. He will be beaten, and the
non-normative ways; second, certain behaviors are angered terrorists will only stiffen their resolve to

800 duti es and r i g hts


eradicate all opposition to their cause. Moreover, no Importantly, as we will observe through animal
one but the terrorists will ever know if he refuses. and cross-cultural human examples in the next sec-
Nevertheless, the man is willing to endure these bad tion, the fact that supererogatory duties and rights
consequences. As a man of high principle, he is sim- are manufactured by culture does not make them
ply unwilling to renounce allegiance to his own gov- arbitrary. In practice, duties and rights embody
ernment. Mellema considers the prisoner’s decision internal logic and serve adaptive purposes for sur-
supererogatory because he acts out of a concern for vival. Our argument assumes a social intuitionist
morality or principle. It would appear that the pris- model, where morality, like language, is an evolu-
oner chooses this freely, without force or coercion— tionary adaptation for intensely social life; moral
indeed, against coercion. intuitions are both innate and enculturated and
Now suppose the prisoner had been a mem- can best be understood in an evolutionary context
ber of the Taliban government in 2001, and his (Bekoff, 2005; Haidt, 2001).
capturer had been an American military officer. To some extent, attention to cultural context
Would it make a difference on whether the act can makes it obvious that rights and duties are replace-
be called supererogatory? Then, would it make a able. Replaceability can simply be a matter of group
difference if the prisoner were John Walker Lindh, perspective. Suppose there is an English woman of
an American citizen who fought on the side of some wealth named Lady Slattery, and Lady Slattery
the Taliban? In the first case, we must ask: whose writes a will leaving the bulk of her estate to her
morality and whose consequences make the act gardener. One group of villagers claim that Lady
supererogatory? In the second example, group Slattery “Did not have a right to do this!” while
affiliation and expectations of citizenship matter: another group claims, “She did her duty, because the
John Walker Lindh is an American citizen, but gardener was completely devoted to her.” Because
affiliated with the Taliban. For Lindh, a decision Lady Slattery lives in England, black-letter law
not to renounce allegiance to the Taliban would allows her to fulfill this right/duty. But as seen in an
be supererogatory within the norms of Taliban earlier example, had she lived in France she would
group identity, and forbidden within the norms be obligated (by French law as it stands in 2010) to
of American group identity. In fact, Lindh did leave at least half of her estate to her children—and
not report his American citizenship to his cap- her choice would have been limited at the outset.
tors, despite the fact that it might have provided Similarly, in the domain of elections, the act
him better treatment. What becomes apparent is of voting can be interpreted as a right or a duty,
that assumptions of praise are relative to perspec- depending on context. According to black-letter law,
tive: Who blames? Who praises? In both cases, the voting is treated as a right in some countries (such as
moral logic is rooted in group identity. the United States) but a duty in some others (such
Free will, for an individual, therefore presumes as Australia, Belgium, and Switzerland). Even in
certain group constraints. However, a social psy- countries where voting is treated as a right, the atti-
chological perspective also considers collective and tude of (at least some) citizens is that citizens have
communal acts, beyond individual choices. Duties a duty to vote. For example, among some groups of
and rights are fundamentally normative expressions, “patriots” it would be unpatriotic for a citizen not
and norms are shaped by groups and cultures more to vote in national elections. On the other hand,
than individuals. Consider a collective agreement among other groups, who might also see themselves
by a military group not to pillage an enemy village as patriotic, it is a duty not to vote, because voting
captured in war, or to show clemency when it is nei- in national elections would strengthen the central
ther required nor forbidden. If supererogatory acts government and thus work against their libertar-
may be collective expressions, it follows that super- ian vision of what the nation should be in the ideal
erogatory rights and duties can be expressed through (i.e., a country of free individuals unencumbered by
groups and networks: family networks, tribal net- a strong central government).
works, nation-states, and networks of nation-states A clearer variation across countries concerns the
such as the United Nations. Indeed, international participation of prison inmates in elections. In the
declarations of human rights and duties may be United States, inmates are banned from voting in
argued as supererogatory acts themselves, as merito- most states, and even former inmates are banned in
rious expressions by diverse communities respond- some states. In the European Union, seven of the
ing to global forces. 27 European Union member states (including the

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 801


United Kingdom) do not permit inmates to vote in constraints—result in certain universal styles of
elections. In these countries, inmates do not have behavior adopted by humans, the roots of which lie
the opportunity to carry out voting as a supereroga- in our evolutionary past.
tory duty, because they do not have it as a legal right.
In other countries where inmates have the right to Primitive Social Behaviors among
vote in elections, voting can become a supereroga- Animals
tory duty. The evolutionary account we provide suggests
The proposition that duties and rights are that the roots of “fairness” should be found in ani-
replaceable is also supported by a number of empiri- mal behavior and, indeed, there is some evidence
cal studies (Moghaddam & Riley, 2005), particu- to support this idea. Rudimentary behaviors that
larly in the family context. For example, in studies later developed to be labeled as duties and rights are
of families with young children, researchers found reflected in cooperation and empathy among ani-
that parents tried solving sibling conflicts through mals (Bekoff, 2005). Elephants help injured or ill
“care” orientations emphasizing duties (“You should members of their group, as do whales and dolphins.
share your toys with your sister because she loves During play, high-ranking wolves are known to
you”) while young children prioritized “justice” ori- “handicap” themselves by engaging in role reversal
entations emphasizing rights (“It’s not fair—these with lower-ranking wolves, even allowing the low-
are my toys!”) (Lollis, Ross, & Leroux, 1996; Lollis, ranking wolves to bite. If the low-ranking wolves
Van Engen, Burns, Nowak, & Ross, 1999). The bite too hard, it will initiate a “play bow” of sub-
same transaction, sharing a toy with a sibling, led mission before the play resumes. Coyotes who bite
different actors to invoke either rights or duties in too hard during play can be ostracized by the rest
accordance with their perspective. As the author- of the group (Bekoff & Allen, 1997). Ant colonies
ity figures in the family system, parents appealed are highly cooperative; often individual ants will
to duties; in contrast, children challenged parental sacrifice themselves to increase survival chances of
authority by invoking their rights (Moghaddam & the group (Wilson, 1975). Monkeys react nega-
Riley, 2005). tively when they witness other monkeys receiving
more favorable rewards for the same effort, or for
Primitive Social Relations and the less effort (Brosnan & de Waal, 2003). Mice reacted
Evolution of Duties and Rights in ways that could be interpreted as empathic when
Having explored a few ways that duties and they observed cagemates, but not strangers, suffer-
rights are bound by group context and social posi- ing pain (Langford et al., 2006). Although insects
tioning, we now turn to illustrations that help and animals do not make sacrifices, act empathic, or
describe duties and rights as functional adaptations feel unfairly treated out of political ideology or prin-
that evolve over time. A cultural evolution explana- ciple, their behavior has been interpreted as reflect-
tion assumes two major stages in the development ing “wild justice” (Bekoff, 2005) and demonstrating
of duties and rights: first, the emergence of certain a level of behavioral continuity between animals and
styles of behavior, termed primitive social relations humans. Humans were able to move to increasingly
(Moghaddam, 2002, p. 40), that are adaptive and complex interpretations of justice through the evo-
enable some people to compete better for scarce lution of their sophisticated social lives.
resources and to improve survival chances; second,
at a later stage the labeling of such adaptive behaviors Human Settlements, Duties, and Rights
as a duty or a right, depending on cultural condi- The evolution of duties and rights in human
tions. The timing and sequence of the second stage, societies took a dramatic turn after the transition,
labeling and interpreting primitive social relations in around 12,000 years ago, from hunter-gatherer to
terms of duties and rights, is unclear. It might evolve settlement societies. Development of agriculture and
tens of thousands of years after the emergence of a the domestication of animals allowed for the growth
particular primitive social relation, or shortly after. of a reliable surplus, which was used by power elites
In this theory, primitive social relations arise out to develop institutions for governance and control.
of the common challenges confronted by humans. Through the monopoly and control of the surplus,
These challenges are partly based on human physi- power elites supported security and military forces,
cal characteristics and the physical environment. as well as administrations for collecting taxes and
Commonalities here—bodily and environmental redistributing wealth to benefit their supporters.

802 duti es and r i g hts


These developments led to the growth of larger and without “calling in the law” (Ellickson, 1991). Here
more complex urban centers, with an established duties and rights appear as functional adaptations,
elite enjoying “high culture.” For example, the with cultural variations reflecting local conditions, a
Minoan civilization that flourished on the island topic we turn to next.
of Crete lasted about 1,500 years, from 2,600 to
1,100 B.C., and centered around luxurious palaces Culture and Supererogatory Acts
with over 1,000 rooms each. The Minoans were one Whereas our argument for universals in rights
of a number of civilizations that flourished in the and duties was top-down and began with discus-
Mediterranean region from around 5,000 years ago sions of primitive social relations and evolutionary
and laid the foundation for the Greek city-states, processes at a high level of abstraction, we now turn
culminating in the golden age of Athenian democ- to a bottom-up analysis to highlight variations in
racy. The foundation for these developments was rights and duties across cultures. Our specific focus
trade between stable and secure urban centers. is on supererogatory rights and duties in Afghan,
The development of large urban centers and the Asian (especially Korean), and Latino- and Spanish-
flourishing of interstate and intrastate trade and culture family contexts. Family units are primary
commerce had foundational implications for social sites for the development and transmission of super-
relations, because now a normative system was erogatory rights and duties. Certainly, the family
needed to regulate frequent and necessary interac- is only one of many social systems into which a
tions between strangers, rather than just kin. Until developing child is socialized, but all societies have
this time, and for almost all of our evolutionary his- developed one or another form of family structure
tory, we lived in small, nomadic groups. Evidence (Segall, Dasen, Berry, & Poortinga, 1999). In fam-
suggests that during the many thousands of years of ily contexts we can observe how culture defines
our existence as hunter-gatherers, we lived in groups certain behaviors as either duties or rights, obliga-
numbering a few hundred in size (e.g., Dunbar, tory or supererogatory. However, in highlighting
1993). This long evolutionary past has led some variations across cultures, we do not lose sight of
researchers to argue that the optimal size for human possible universals and in the concluding discussion
groups continues to be 150 to 200 members (see we argue that the highlighting of cultural variations
Moghaddam, 2008, p. 34). Certainly, this “optimal ultimately serves the purpose of pointing to a small
group size” seems to exert influence on the way even number of commonalities across cultures.
high-income twenty-first-century societies are orga-
nized, particularly in terms of the organization of Socialization of Rights and Duties in
local or “everyday-level” small groups. For example, Families
although many people now work in organizations Human beings do not develop in isolation, but
with hundreds of thousands of employees and live rather in a unique physical and social context influ-
in cities with millions of inhabitants, they actually enced by culture. Culture and child-rearing is there-
function in small work units (e.g., the office or uni- fore intimately linked: children must learn to survive
versity department) and neighborhoods that allow and grow in their given context, and parents must
some level of intimacy and face-to-face interaction prepare the next generation for integration into the
with other group members (Moghaddam, 2008, pp. existing culture (Bornstein, 2010). Cultural values
77–79). However, whereas during our hunter-gath- therefore influence not only the form of families,
erer era our small groups consisted mainly of others but schools, neighborhoods, and other social struc-
who were our kin, in twenty-first-century Western tures. The shape that these social structures take has
societies our work, neighborhood, and even social great implications for rights and duties, as we will
groups tend to consist of nonkin. see later.
Out of interactions between nonkin individu- Within families, duties can be delegated to par-
als and groups has evolved practices such as turn- ents, children, or members of the extended family.
taking, which appears across multiple cultures In most cultures, however, actors with the greatest
(Moghaddam, 2000), as well as other practices face-to-face interactions with children—for exam-
that help mitigate competition over resources and ple, parents, teachers, and babysitters in Western
encourage collective fairness. These normative prac- contexts—are most directly responsible for provid-
tices continue to influence behavior in modern soci- ing the bare necessities of development. In many
eties, so that for the most part order is maintained contexts now, failure to fulfill these duties can be

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 803


formally prosecuted as child abuse or neglect. work, and so on), whereas European-American kin
Nevertheless, it is important to remember the ori- support is characterized by the extended family pro-
gins of these behaviors as informal duties establish- viding economic resources or emotional support to
ing a minimum requirement for behavior. parents (Sarkisian & Gerstel, 2004). In both cases,
In countries such as the United States, for exam- members of the extended family are not expected
ple, parents are almost solely responsible for feed- to provide resources to the same degree as parents.
ing, protecting, and nurturing their child. In other Nevertheless, they are commended for their actions
more collectivistic cultural environments, the child’s on behalf of children for which they are not directly
regular face-to-face interactions include members of responsible.
the extended family, neighbors, and family friends.
By extension, the minimal duties assigned to par- Rights and Duties in Asian Families
ents in the United States are now assigned to aunts, Culture dictates more than who is responsible for
uncles, grandparents, and the like. Among the Nso what within the family; the family is also “nested”
in Cameroon, for example, a child “belongs” to the in a context of larger social and religious values. For
community as a whole. Educating the child accord- example, among the Javanese, Indonesia’s largest
ing to social norms and enforcing discipline is an ethnic group, a patriarchical social structure and the
obligation shared by all adults, not merely parents heavy influence of Hinduism means that individuals’
(see Nsamenang in this volume for a discussion of opportunities, duties and rights are determined by
social exchanges in non-Western family contexts.) The their gender as well as their caste. Boys—particularly
exercise of such duties is not seen as encroaching on eldest sons—have greater responsibilities than their
a parent’s responsibilities because the parents are not siblings, but they also enjoy more attention from
solely accountable for the child—and perhaps not their families and have greater rights than their sis-
even principally responsible for the child’s develop- ters. Similarly, individuals from the Brahmana (spir-
ment (Rabain, 1979). itual leaders) caste enjoy greater rights than those in
Beyond these minimalist obligations, character- the Ksatrya (warriers), Waisya (traders), and Syudra
izing behaviors as supererogatory duties becomes dif- (low class society) (Shwalb et al., 2010).
ficult because what is laudable (though not required) Perhaps one of the best-known examples can be
in one context may be expected in another. There found in East Asians’ parenting practices; a review
are informal pressures at play, which complicate of this literature shows that socialization goals of
assumptions about what is “required.” For exam- Asian and Asian-American mothers emphasize
ple, payment by an uncle for his nephew’s school children’s duties to bring honor to the family in a
tuition may be supererogatory in Western contexts way that is consistent with the interdependent and
though required in others. In the United States, an collectivistic Asian culture (Kim & Wong, 2002).
uncle would not be the boy’s legal guardian, so he Many attribute this phenomenon to East Asia’s
has no minimum legal responsibility. In the absence cultural roots in Chinese Confucianism, a compre-
of social norms that pressure him into supporting hensive philosophical system encompassing eth-
a child that is not his, the uncle’s contribution is ics, interpersonal relations, and governance. This
supererogatory by virtue of meeting all conditions philosophy is the basis for filial piety (Xiao), one
established by theorists: the act is beyond the call of the most important and distinctive concepts of
of duty, meritorious, and its omission is not blame- Asian families. In Korea, for example, the devotion
worthy (Peterfreund, 1978). However, if the uncle of children to parents involves a number of duties
lives in a context where there are informal social that can be classified into five broad categories:
pressures to support his nephew—e.g., an assump- obeying (e.g., Myong-Shin-Bo-Kam, children must
tion that males must be caretakers of extended kin, immediately answer when called), attending (e.g.,
as often the case in tribal societies—paying for the Kuk-mong-yo-keul, when parents are ill, children
nephew’s education fails the first condition of a must give priority to attending to their illness), sup-
supererogatory act and becomes an ordinary duty. porting (e.g., Don-Mon-Seun-Sup, children must
Then there may be substantive varieties, a divi- ensure parents are comfortably housed and fed),
sion of labor in supererogatory duties, as it were. comforting (e.g., Yi-ki, children must be careful not
For example, kin support among African-American to expose themselves to danger and cause their par-
families usually takes the form of practical support ents distress), and honoring (e.g., So-hak, children
(child care, help with transportation, household must restrain themselves from dietary and sexual

804 duti es and r i g hts


pleasure for 3 years after their parents’ death) (Kim contexts. Much like Koreans, Latino- or Spanish-
& Choi, 1994). Filial piety rooted in Confucian origin families are also characterized by an inter-
ideals is widespread throughout other countries as dependent orientation (Oyserman, Coon, &
well, including Vietnam and Japan. Surveys reveal Kemmelmeir, 2002). A review of literature indi-
that the importance of children’s duties in Vietnam cates that three cultural values rooted in this orien-
is on par with Korea: more than 90% of adolescents tation— familism (familismo), respect (respeto), and
agreed with the statement that no matter what the moral education (educación)—are held by Latinos
circumstances, they would support their parents in of all national origins and underlie many parenting
their old age (Le, 2000). However, some research decisions, including the assignment of rights and
suggests that filial piety has weakened in postmod- duties (Halgunseth, Ispa, & Rudy, 2006). Of these,
ern societies (Shwalb et al., 2010). respeto and educación are most relevant for our dis-
In addition to these filial duties, parents in Asian cussion of rights and duties, since they bear on the
families also have duties to their children. In order duties of children and parents, respectively.
for children to reach maturity and exercise these In an ethnographic study of Mexican-American
obligations, parents must first raise, care for, and immigrant families, researchers described that by
educate their children. Indeed, in Korea, Vietnam the age of 4 years, children are taught verbal and
and other Asian societies, the concept of “womb nonverbal rules of demonstrating respect, such as
education” (thai giao in Vietnamese) stipulates politely greeting elders, not challenging elders’ views,
particular duties for a woman to her unborn child and not interrupting adults’ conversations (Valdes,
(Shwalb et al., 2010; Kim & Choi, 1994). Although 1996). Thus, behaviors parallel some of the filial
basic parental duties of raising children may be duties apparent in East Asian cultures. However, the
fairly uniform—feeding, protecting, socializing to meaning of respeto is more comprehensive in that
cultural norms—the nuances and meanings of these it includes respecting the role of each member of
duties vary by cultural context. For example, one the family, not just parents. For example, sisters did
ethnographic study revealed cultural differences in not act affectionately toward their husbands or boy-
attitude toward motherhood among Korean and friends in front of their brothers because to do so
Canadian women (Kim & Choi, 1994). Whereas would be interpreted as a falta de respeto, an affront
Canadian mothers emphasize personal (career) to the brothers’ sense of dignity and their roles as
development and maternal caregiving equally, brothers (Valdes, 1996).
Korean mothers place greater weight on their role as Respeto is also an important motivator in the
caregivers, and see little conflict in sacrificing their grief responses of children and other survivors when
careers for their children. This reflects the Korean a loved one dies. In an account of the funeral cer-
culture’s deep-rooted consciousness of parent and emonies of Mexican-Americans in Texas during
child unified in “body and soul” (ilshim dongche; the 1930s through 1950s, Williams recounts fam-
Choi, 2000; Shwalb et al., 2010). Parents’ contin- ily obligations surrounding the funeral rites. Wakes
ual support for their children is also seen in their were held in the home over the course of an entire
greater willingness to support their adult children night, and talking and laughing were strictly prohib-
financially. In a cross-national survey of European, ited during the viewing. At no point was the body
North American, and Asian countries, Korean par- left unattended, since doing so would be a sign of
ents were most willing to pay off their children’s disrespect. At that time, widows were also expected
debt, contribute to college education, and pay for to wear black for the remainder of their lives, a con-
wedding celebrations (Gallup, 1983 as cited in crete symbol of their enduring duty and loyalty to
Kim & Choi, 1994). This intense child-centeredness the deceased (Williams, 1990).
reflects many parents’ beliefs about their role in the If respeto is the value most central to children’s
lives of their children: it is the parents’ duty—and a duties in this culture, educación is the most impor-
critical part of their existence—to continually sacri- tant value for understanding adults’ duties to their
fice for their children (Shwalb et al., 2010). children. Educación extends beyond the English
word “education” in that it also refers to the train-
Rights and Duties in Spanish-Origin ing in responsibility, morality, and interpersonal
Families relations. A close comparison is the concept of bil-
Respect for parents and hierarchical family dung (education) active in German taxonomy since
structures, however, are not unique to East Asian the sixteenth century: broadly, bildung refers to not

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 805


only a transfer of literacy or a body of knowledge, adolescents in one study were increasingly likely to
but also to a process of personal and cultural matu- believe that disagreeing with parents was acceptable
ration (Schmidt, 1996). Ethnographic accounts of and that autonomy was desirable (Fuligni, 1998).
Mexican immigrant mothers indicate that mothers This seemed to indicate a shift from duties (obedi-
often mention la educación de los niños (the moral ence to parents) to rights (freedom to make personal
education of their children) as an important paren- decisions). Another example concerns changing
tal responsibility. Further studies also indicate the expectations around the marriage decisions of sons
importance of this duty: in a study on child-rearing and daughters. Spanish-heritage families often expe-
practices of U.S.-born and foreign-born parents of rience conflict in these areas, since parents empha-
European, Mexican, Cambodian, and Vietnamese size children’s duty to accept a “good match” while
descent, Mexican parents reported that social sons and daughters stress their right to choose a
skills and motivation were as or more important mate (Baptiste, 1987).
for children’s school readiness than cognitive skills
(Okagaki & Sternberg, 1993). Similarly, a second Between Laws and Norms: The Case of
study found that Latinos gave higher importance Afghan Rights and Duties
ratings to children’s socio-emotional characteristics We have seen how black-letter law and infor-
than Euro-American or Asian-American parents mal perspectives influence each other, but what if
(Okagaki & Frensch, 1998). enforcement of black-letter law appears weak or
Just as respeto motivates the duties surrounding absent? Such is the case in Afghanistan. In Western
funeral ceremonies, educación plays an important literature, Afghanistan is often depicted as a “law-
role in the birth and baptism ceremony, another less” and tribal society where drug lords gather
important traditional life-cycle ritual. Most impor- private armies and build mansions with illegally
tant here is the compadrazgo (literally co-parent- acquired gains. Despite a new constitution and
hood), the practice of expectant parents selecting a strengthened national police force for enforcement,
married couple from among their friends to be the Afghan laws regarding safety, prohibition of alcohol
child’s sponsors at a baptismal ceremony. On the and gambling, or compliance with intellectual prop-
day of the ceremony, the compadres, which the child erty rights are rarely enforced. The Afghan-Pakistan
will eventually refer to as madrina and padrino, are border has remained highly porous; credentials of
responsible for purchasing the white christening Pashtun tribal identity are often a more impor-
outfit. This functions as a symbol of the padrinos’ tant “passport” than actual citizenship for travel
duty: to take care of the child’s physical and spiritual across the Durrand Line envisioned by the British
needs in the event of the parents’ absence (Williams, (Barfield, 2010). At the same time, Afghanistan is
1990) remarkably rule-bound. Daily life is regulated by
a mix of “renegade” freedoms and strict cultural,
Rights and Duties in Flux moral, and religious codes—most orally, informally,
Although the previous case studies have focused and locally transmitted through family and village
primarily on duties—whether of parents, children, networks. During Taliban rule and still today, an
friends, or extended family—it is nevertheless Afghan man could own and operate a gun, drive a
important to address the issue of rights as well. motorcycle, and set up his own dentist’s office with-
Earlier we argued that rights and duties are in the out a government-issued license. However, during
vast majority of cases replaceable, and that children Taliban rule the same man would be expected to
will give preference to autonomy while adults will grow a beard to a fist’s length, and perform namaz
emphasize obligations. We also illustrated the influ- (Arabic, salah) prayers five times a day—or face
ence of culture and group context on the formation imprisonment and beating. Even today, Afghans still
of rights and duties. But what happens when fami- accept harsh legal interpretations that most Western
lies move from one cultural context to another? How cultures would not tolerate. Under conservative
are diverse perspectives and identities negotiated, interpretations of Sharia (Islamic) law, specifically
and what does this mean for rights and duties? for the hudud, adultery is punishable by death from
In immigrant families, conflict over diverse per- public stoning. Religious conversion from Islam
spectives and identities is marked by generational to any other faith tradition explicitly warrants the
differences. For successive generations of Mexican death sentence, though can be appealed under con-
and Central American families in the United States, ditions of “insanity.” In January 2008, an Afghan

806 duti es and r i g hts


court sentenced a 23-year-old journalism student predominantly Shi’a region of the central high-
to death for asking questions about women’s rights lands, Bamiyan province.
under Islam (Sengupta, 2008). As these examples illustrate, what constitutes a
Where these apparent paradoxes of lawless- duty or right—and therefore also what goes beyond
ness and strict rules intersect, a picture of cultural the “minimum” behavior required—is negoti-
rights and duties emerges. Like any complex society, ated on multiple levels. In tribal societies, lineage
Afghans divide and order themselves along a mul- members generally have mutual obligations to
titude of different social categories, each with for- assist each other—as well as mutual liabilities, in
mal and informal rule structures. These categories terms of honor and often finances. Anthropologist
may contradict each other, or apply simultaneously, Bernt Glatzer (1996) observed that among Durrani
depending upon the circumstances. Certain rights Pashtun nomads in the western part of the coun-
afforded by local interpretations of Sharia law may try, patrilineally related kin provide social security
be encouraged or discouraged by local custom, and and political support. But relations between them
further negotiated at kinship levels. For example, can become strained when competing for author-
an urban man who takes a second wife by choice, ity in the kin group and for inheritance. Property
as allowed formally by law, will be ostracized and is passed patrilineally, as are feuds about previous
scorned by the first wife’s family network, if con- inheritance. Within maternal kin, however, which
ducted without their permission. Although the let- lack this resource competition, relations tend to be
ter of the law, for moderate Islamic interpretations, marked by “cordiality and helpfulness” (Dupree &
requires women’s hair to be covered in public, most Gouttierre, 1997, p. 116).
late-teenage and adult Afghan women still dress in A people, an ethnic group, and a tribe are called
full-body burqas. qawm in Pashto and Dari, and most other lan-
Not only is law bound, adapted, and some- guages of Afghanistan. The term reveals that ethnic
times extended by cultural customs, but also the groups and tribes are structured by genealogical ties.
enforcement of law and customs are negotiated Subtribe or clan is khel in Pashto often extending to
at the level of kinship networks. Consider that in the level of a neighborhood or village. Kin groups
2004, the Afghan Loyal Jirga, or Grand Assembly, are normally expansive, stretching from the nuclear
agreed upon a constitution that provides that both family unit and the khel, to the tribe, to the larger
genders “have equal rights and duties before the ethnic group. Last in line is the nation-state, which
law” (Constitution of Afghanistan, Article 22:2). can be fluid where nation-state boundaries and khel
Culturally, women are generally not allowed to or qawm boundaries contradict—such as along the
pedal bikes, drive cars, travel alone, or serve as border between Afghanistan and Pakistan. Local seg-
primary household head in the presence of a male mentations between tribes are sometimes described
alternate. Women who run for political office, by the Arab proverb, “I against my brother. My
attend co-educational schools, or travel alone often brother and I against my cousin. My cousin, my
face serious threats; many women have been killed brother, and I against the world.” The potential for
or mutilated for taking these actions, even after the tension with kin is expressed in a common Afghan
fall of the Taliban in 2001. Yet many Afghan fami- saying, “Do you have an enemy? I have a cousin.”
lies still urge their daughters to attend local schools, Beneath and between the formal law and vernacular
and restrictions on women’s mobility and dress practices governing social behavior are unwritten
varies considerably across kinship networks and supererogatory rights and duties. An individual can
nuclear families. This heterogeneity is not arbitrary. be applauded for giving up an “unwritten” right,
In many cases, conditions of poverty at the village or expected to give up a particular right to pre-
level trump conservative religious customs; women serve social harmony. When facing a shared enemy
will work in fields without burqas and assume oth- or threat, the importance of preserving harmony
erwise traditional patrilineal roles for survival. In within these kinship bonds increases. An heir to an
the 2005 parliamentary elections, the world wit- inheritance may volunteer to share portions of the
nessed Afghan women running for parliamentary inheritance with other kin, or demonstrate forbear-
office, often campaigning through extended family ance or tolerance over a past grievance, where that
networks of support. In 2005, Afghanistan nomi- preserves kinship collaboration.
nated its first and only female governor, Habiba Another example of supererogatory duties
Sarobi, to assume control of the more liberal and and rights appears in the Pashtunwali code of

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 807


hospitality toward guests and travelers. A guest in Common Goals, Different Expressions
someone’s home has the supererogatory right to As part of cultural evolution, rights and duties
ask the host for tea and food. These are custom- across cultures can best be understood as evolved
arily offered by the host, with varying degrees of ways of resolving dilemmas; solutions instead of
expectation that the guest should accept the offer. black-letter law (Ellickson, 1991). As we have seen,
The guest has the unwritten right to accept these these are best understood using an evolutionary-
offers, but sometimes preserves social harmony by ecological approach. Dilemmas may arise from spe-
not doing so. Taken to an extreme, a guest may cific physical, environmental, cultural, and historical
demand from the host extraordinary items beyond facts and are resolved by structured tribal and group
what is offered, including bedding, clothes, and affiliations where adaptive duties and rights can be
even money. If the guest demands to be served enforced (Ferguson & Whitehead, 1992). For exam-
meat, a luxury food for most Afghan families, the ple, in Sherry Ortner’s (1989) study of the Sherpan
host family would be expected by custom to do Buddhist community of Darjeeling, Nepal, super-
so. A failure to serve the guest would be consid- erogatory acts were found to resolve contradictions
ered shameful. However, exercising these rights in the social hegemony and strengthen low-class
may provoke resentment from the host. Similarly, social identity. In particular, voluntary construction
in the Christian parable of the Good Samaritan, of Buddhist temples by low-class Sherpan work-
the Samaritan offers the innkeeper money for the ers in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
guest, and then promises to pay for anything more served an adaptive function: on the one hand, these
that the guest might need. Offering the option to were acts of charity or religious devotion, but on
the guest is supererogatory; it is granting a right, the other, they were an expression of working-class
perhaps gratuitously, that simultaneously goes empowerment. Constructing a temple was a “denial
beyond the law and preserves honor within a kin- that having fewer material resources defined them as
ship and cultural context. ‘small,’ and of no social consequence” (p. 151). The
Supererogatory duties and rights for guests apply act carried indirect benefits, such as self-expression
even during wartime. Jason Eliot (1999) recalls and expression of group identity, and resistance of
a story of Ahmad Shah Massoud, leader of the culturally defined hegemony. Ortner explains that
Northern Alliance, who, while inspecting the front “many small [low-status] people who participated
lines against the Taliban in the late 1990s, acciden- in the monastery foundings were like the returning
tally took a wrong turn, lost the route, and drove heroes of the schema, newly empowered and express-
unarmed into the heart of a Taliban stronghold. ing or claiming ‘bigness’ ” (p. 153). Supererogatory
Massoud, who was instantly recognized and facing acts maintained group harmony and collaboration.
almost certain death, demanded confidently to see An informal system of meritorious acts made the
their leader. So baffled were his hosts at the sudden working class powerful, and in turn, kept the pow-
appearance of their arch-enemy, they obliged, and erful class in check: priests and power figures were
a cordial exchange was reported between the rival praised for “making statements of smallness, of
leaders. Their meeting was just long enough not (political) concern for the people and of (religious)
to offend custom, but short enough to prevent the egolessness.” Arguably, this expression is no differ-
Taliban from realizing that Massoud’s appearance ent from the submissive “play-bow” among wolves
in their midst was nothing more than a one-in-a- or other cooperative, evolved animal behaviors.
million mistake (p. 76). Within family units, child–parent dilemmas of
Whether this legend is exactly true or not, it status, inheritance, and identity were resolved by
conveys the reality of the Afghan duty of hospital- sending the children to a monastery. Low-income
ity toward guests. In this case, it saved Massoud’s parents unable to provide inheritance for children
life, but his protection was only afforded when he through property and arranged marriages, could
presented himself as a guest, rather than a fighter. otherwise elevate their family’s status through reli-
The shift in positioning meant a shift in social codes gious participation. Many children pressured their
for what constitutes fair behavior. Certainly, the parents to send them to be monks or nuns, where
very same shift in positioning would not work in monasticism conveyed high status and exit from
a Western culture: a member of the Taliban wan- low-class obligation (p. 180). Sending a child to
dering into an American military camp would be join was considered a super-meritorious act, and
served something quite different than tea! both parents and children were praised.

808 duti es and r i g hts


Not entirely dissimilar is the American tradition are best understood with reference to principles that
among teenagers from primarily low- and middle- function within cultural and functional contexts,
income families to join the military, gaining access rather than separate from them.
to higher status and income. The act of voluntarily
joining the military is generally considered merito- Minority-Majority Cycle of Rights and
rious, an opportunity to sacrifice for the benefit of Duties: An Example of Universals?
one’s country. When the risk of bodily self-sacrifice The identification of cultural variation in rights
increases, such as during active combat, the degree of and duties can be useful, in part to demonstrate the
merit increases. In theory, veterans of war are given enormous plasticity and range of possibilities in
special respect and valor by their government and human social life. But we must also return to the
countrymen. Super-meritorious and supererogatory question of universals: are there universals in rights
acts in combat are rewarded with purple hearts, sil- and duties in the family context? If so, do they have
ver stars, and other medallions. Failure to exemplify wider implications outside the family context? Based
special bravery in combat is not punished or blame- on the functional analysis we have been using, one
worthy, but in the case of mandatory military ser- possible universal in this context is the minority-ma-
vice, failure to serve in combat can be punished. jority cycle of rights and duties (Moghaddam, 2004),
elaborated below.
The Soldier’s Sacrifice In all human societies, infants come into this
Can there be a “universal ethic” of service in a world completely helpless and dependent on others.
soldier’s sacrifice? Possibly so, but from a functional This means that the young have less power than their
perspective, supererogatory acts are informal meth- caretakers; it is the caretakers who (initially at least)
ods of resolving dilemmas. They promote social set the rules for behavior and assign rights and duties
harmony and survival, rather than a set of universal to the young. Irrespective of whether the child is in
values per se. Supererogatory acts are best under- a Spanish, Korean, Afghan, or any other culture, it
stood therefore not in categories but rather in func- is adults who assign duties in particular. In the care-
tional shades and degrees. These degrees vary based taker–child relationship, caretakers tend to focus on
on the pressures exerted by the social conditions and the duties of children, whereas children assert their
relevant spheres of cultural influence. Age, gender, rights. This tendency is most extreme in Western
and status, for example, may change the expectations societies, where youth rebellion has become a “tra-
beyond formal duty, as well as calculations of the dition.” Our contention is that the same tendency
sacrifice and intentions involved in a supererogatory for caretakers to emphasize duties (“You have to do
act. Consider, for example, the case of the American your homework;” “You must tend to the sheep.”)
Pat Tillman. Among the thousands of American and for the growing child to emphasize rights
soldiers who sacrificed their lives in Afghanistan (“I want to go play with my friends.”) is found
and Iraq, the American press and the United States across cultures (Moghaddam & Riley, 2004).
government gave special attention and praise to Although the child, a power minority, empha-
Tillman, stating the significance of his sacrifice. sizes rights, and the caretaker, a power majority,
Tillman was an American football player who, after emphasizes duties, the child shifts position when
the events of September 11, 2001, turned down a she or he becomes an adult. The child who 20 years
multi-million dollar professional sports contract in ago was rebelling against her parents (“I don’t want
May 2002, to enlist in the United States Rangers to do that!”) shifts position and emphasizes duties
(Krakauer, 2009). Tillman’s decision to join the when she has her own child (“I am telling you, you
military was considered supererogatory in large part have to do that!”). This “cycle” of rights and duties
because of the apparent sacrifice involved. A sol- has wider implications outside the family context.
dier from a low-status background with less access The study of minority-group behavior reveals
to resources than Tillman would not normally be that in their relationships with majority groups,
given the same public praise for the deontological minorities tend to give priority to rights—this is
considerations of his supererogatory choice. Given reflected in minority-rights movements around the
so many financial and personal reasons not to join world, along with movements for indigenous peo-
the military, Tillman is assumed to have acted out ples’ rights, Black rights, women’s rights, gay rights,
of principle rather than social or cultural pressures. and so on. On the other hand, majority groups
It is our position, however, that supererogatory acts emphasize duties, broadly the duty to obey laws that

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 809


support the status quo. However, when a minority that is manifested very soon after birth (Collis,
gains power and manages to become the majority, 1985) and is essential for key aspects of social life,
then there tends to be a shift of emphasis by that such as communications (Duncan, 1972). Without
newly empowered group from rights to duties. This turn-taking, communication quickly breaks down.
in part explains the so-called paradox of revolution After the emergence of primitive social relations,
(Middlebrook, 1995): prior to revolutions, minor- there evolve cultural practices for labeling the behav-
ity groups emphasize rights (e.g., “The people must ior. For example, depending on cultural conditions,
be free to speak and say what they want;” “The “having a turn to speak” can be interpreted as a right
people have a right to a higher standard of living.”), or a duty. In democratic societies, “the right to free
but if a revolution succeeds and a former minor- speech” is given considerable importance, whereas
ity group takes over the government, then the “new in dictatorships this right is limited to certain power
majority” shifts focus to duties (e.g., “That is not groups and leaders.
free speech, that is anarchy—we must have limits;” Irrespective of the political and family systems
“The people have a duty to work hard.”). The first of societies, certain rights and duties are necessar-
author witnessed this firsthand during the 1978– ily assigned and adopted as a requirement for using
1979 revolution in Iran: when in opposition to the certain modern technologies. In these cases, the
Shah, Ayatollah Khomeini and his group demanded requirements of technology override local cultural
all kinds of freedoms and rights for the people, but variations. For example, Iran is a dictatorship in
when they became the government themselves, they which women are treated as second-class citizens,
clamped down on rights and used an iron fist to whereas women enjoy equal rights in Western
demand that people “do their Islamic duties.” democracies. However, a woman driving a car in
Although the minority-majority cycle of rights Iran participates in turn-taking in traffic with equal
and duties seems to be pervasive in actual politi- rights to other drivers, just as is the case in Western
cal processes, there have also been attempts, on societies. This is because modern roads and cars
paper at least, to reinterpret and use duties to serve require standardized rights and duties for all driv-
the interests of all humankind, including minori- ers. Of course, it is possible to deprive a group of
ties, and to argue that duties are a precondition the right to drive in the first place (for example, it
for rights. Two examples of this are the Universal is illegal for women to drive automobiles in Saudi
Declaration of Human Responsibilities, proposed by Arabia).
the InterAction Council of Former Heads of State Working bottom-up, we can identify almost
and Government (preamble, Universal Declaration countless cross-cultural variations in duties and
of Human Responsibilities, 1996), and the American rights, including supererogatory acts, reflecting the
Declaration of the Rights and Duties of Man, pro- enormous plasticity of human behavior. However,
posed by the International Council of American our conceptual orientation allows us to also work
States in Bogotá, Colombia in 1948. top-down and to identify a small but important
number of possible universals in the domain of
Summary and Future Directions: duties and rights, an example being the minority-
In Search of Universals majority cycle of rights and duties. Of course, even
We see the exploration of duties and rights to be in the case of this possible “universal,” there are cul-
part of a response to the urgent need for cultural tural variations in how it is manifested. For exam-
psychology to address “The question of relation- ple, although parents in both the United States and
ship between societies . . .” (Valsiner, 2009, p. xi). Afghanistan emphasize the duties rather than the
Rights and duties are foundational to worldviews, rights of their children in the home as they attempt
and shared understandings of rights and duties can to socialize them to behave “correctly,” there will be
serve as a basis for organizing relationships between differences in the nature of the duties emphasized,
and within societies. the communications used, rewards and punish-
The functional argument we have proposed ments practiced, and so on. Consequently, we need
begins with certain behaviors, termed primitive to tread carefully in how we interpret “universals” in
social relations (Moghaddam & Riley, 2004), that rights and duties. This is an area for further research:
prove to be advantageous for the survival of groups to test the universality of the rights-duties cycle, and
and become pervasive across groups in the course to explore the different duties and rights emphasized
of evolution. An example is turn-taking, a behavior in this cycle in different cultures.

810 duti es and r i g hts


Similarly, care is necessary when searching for more recent minority movements. Whereas individ-
and interpreting other universals in duties and ual rights are a relatively recent focus, individual and
rights. Although some attention has been given collective duties have been a historical focus. Research
to the psychology of rights and possible univer- is needed to explore the implications of these differ-
sals there, little has been done by way of exploring ent paths of development for the behavior of citizens
universal human duties. For a right to be justified, responding to government programs.
theorists contend that it has to represent a justi-
fied claim-to (a person’s justified claim to, say, clean
drinking water) and a justified claim-against (a jus- References
The Anglican Church (1662/1999). The book of common prayer.
tified claim against some addressee to make water London: Everyman’s Library [1662 translation].
unavailable by polluting a water source) (Feinberg, Attfield, R. (1979). Supererogation and double standards. Mind,
1973). Thus, any justified right—such as universal 88, 481–499.
human rights—must be accompanied by a duty Baptiste, D. A. (1987). Family therapy with Spanish-heritage
immigrant families in cultural transition. Contemporary
(claim-against), as the InterAction Council and oth-
Family Therapy, 9, 221–251.
ers have argued. However, little empirical work has Barfield, T. (2010) Afghanistan: A cultural and political history.
been done to investigate these underlying duties, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
and whether there is cross-cultural agreement on Batson, C. D. (1995). Prosocial motivation: Why do we
them. For example, we can imagine different societ- help others? In A. Tesser (Ed.), Advanced social psychology
(pp. 333–381). Boston: McGraw–Hill.
ies agreeing that something is a justified claim-to,
Bekoff, M. (2005). Wild justice and fair play: Cooperativeness, for-
but disagreeing about the justification of claim- giveness, and morality in animals. Boston: Bacon & Allyn.
against. Or perhaps arrive at the same conclusion Beckoff, M., & Allen (1997). Cognitive ethology: Slayers, skep-
about a justified right, but disagree on what claim- tics, and proponents. In R. Mitchell, N. S. Thompson, &
against was necessary to get there. H. L. Miles (Eds.), Anthropomorphism, anecdote, and animals.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Duties underpin and complement rights, as has
Benbaji, H., & Heyd, D. (2001). The charitable perspective:
been previously suggested, and as our examples Forgiveness and toleration as supererogatory. Canadian
affirm. Thus, duties are a part of even the most indi- Journal of Philosophy, 31, 567–585.
vidualistic cultures. It is important to note also that Bornsetin, M. H. (2010). Preface. In M. H. Bornstein (Ed.), The
these prevailing cultural norms can be suspended handbook of cultural developmental science. New York: Taylor &
Francis.
temporarily, as is often the case during emergencies
Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2003). Monkeys reject
such as natural disasters or terrorist attacks. During unequal pay. Nature, 425, 297–299.
this time, triage, the prioritization of patients based Choi, S. J. (2000). HanGukIn SimRihak [Korean psychology].
on severity of injuries and chances of survival, Seoul, South Korea: Chung-Ang University Press.
becomes the principle motivation for most medi- Coleman, D. (2007). The role of law in relationships within
immigrant families: Traditional parenting practices in conflict
cal actors and public managers. By necessity then,
with American concepts of maltreatment. In J. E. Lansford,
everyday notions of individual rights are often tem- K. D. Deater-Deckard & M. H. Bornstein (Eds.), Immigrant
porarily put on hold. Future research should focus families in contemporary society. New York: Guilford Press.
on how these rights and duties are understood, Collis, G. M. (1985). On the origins of turn-taking: Alternation
maintaining an eye out for whether government and meaning. In M. D. Barrett (Ed.), Children’s single-words
speech (pp. 217–230). Chichester, England: Wiley, John &
recommendations to citizens should be couched as
Sons, Inc.
either rights or duties. The Constitution of Afghanistan (2004). Article 22, Clause 2.
Future research should also attend to the impli- Dembour, M. D. (2006). Who believes in human rights? Reflections
cations of the different evolutionary paths through on the European Convention. New York: Cambridge University
which duties and rights have come to take their con- Press.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (1993). Coevolution of newocortex size, group
temporary shapes. For most of human history, societ-
size and language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16, 681–735.
ies have been organized as dictatorships, with people Duncan, S. (1972). Some signs and rules for taking speak-
being trained to give highest priority to their duties to ing turns in conversation. Journal of Personality and Social
obey authority figures, such as emperors and popes. Psychology, 23, 283–292.
Rights, particularly individual rights, evolved out of Dupree, N. H., & Gouttierre, T. E. (1997). The society and its
environment. In
revolutionary struggles of the relatively powerless
R. Nyrop, and D. Seekins (Eds.), Afghanistan country study.
against the powerful, as reflected in various conflicts, Washington, DC: Library of Congress.
from the French Revolution to clashes involving Ellickson, R. C. (1991). Order without law: How neighbors settle
Black Power, women’s liberation, and various other disputes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 811


Elliot, J. (1999). An unexpected light: Travels in Afghanistan. Luther, M. (1957). Explanation of the Ninety-Five Theses (Thesis
New York: Picador. 58), in H. Grimm (Ed.), Works (Vol. 31), Philadelphia:
Feinberg, J. (1973). Social philosophy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Muhlenberg Press.
Prentice Hall. Louis, W. R., & Taylor, D. M. (2005). Rights and duties as
Ferguson, R., & Whitehead, N. (1992). The violent edge of group norms. In N. Finkel & F. M. Moghaddam (Eds.), The
empire. In R. Ferguson & N. Whitehead (Eds.), War in the psychology of rights and duties: Empirical contributions and
tribal zone: Expanding states and indigenous warfare. Santa Fe, normative commentaries (pp. 105–134). Washington, D.C.:
NM: School of American Research Press. American Psychological Association Press.
Finkel, N., & Moghaddam, F. M. (Eds.) (2004). The psychol- Mellema, G. (1991). Beyond the call of duty: Supererogation, obli-
ogy of rights and duties: Empirical contributions and normative gation, and offense. Albany, NY: State University of New York
commentaries. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Press.
Association Press. Middlebrook, K. J. (1995). The paradox of revolution: Labor,
Fuligni, A. (1998). Adolescents from immigrant families. In state, and authoritarianism in Mexico. Baltimore, MD: Johns
V. McLoyd & L. Steinberg (Eds.), Research on minority Hopkins University Press.
adolescents: Conceptual, theoretical and methodological issues Moghaddam, F. M. (1998). Social psychology: Exploring universals
(pp. 127–1 43). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. across cultures. New York: Freeman.
Glatzer, B. (1996). Dynamics of camp formation among Pashtun Moghaddam, F. M. (2000). Toward a cultural theory of human
nomads in west Afghanistan. Nomatic Peoples, 39, 29–52. rights. Theory and Psychology, 10, 291–312.
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: Moghaddam, F. M. (2002). The individual and society: A cultural
A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological integration. New York: Worth.
Review, 108, 814–834. Moghaddam, F. M. (2008). How globalization spurs terrorism.
Hale, S. C. (1991). Against supererogation. American Philo- Westport, CT: Praeger Security International.
sophical Quarterly, 28, 273–83. Moghaddam, F. M., & Riley, C. J. (2005). Toward a cultural
Halgunseth, L. C., Ispa, J. M., & Rudy, D. (2006). Parental con- theory of human rights and duties in human development.
trol in Latino families: An integrated review of the literature. In N. J. Finkel & F. M. Moghaddam (Eds.), The psychology of
Child Development, 77, 1282–1297. rights and duties (pp. 75–104). Washington, DC: American
Hauser, M. D. (2006). Moral minds: The nature of right and Psychological Association.
wrong. New York: Harper Perennial. Moghaddam, F. M. (2004). The cycle of rights and duties in
Heyd, D. (1982) Supererogation: Its status in ethical theory. intergroup relations. New Review of Social Psychology, 3,
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 125–130.
InterAction Council (1996). Universal declaration of human New Revised Standard Version Bible (1989). New York: Division
responsibilities. of Christian Education of the National Council of Churches
Kawall, J. (2009). Virtue theory, ideal observers, and the super- of Christ in the United States of America.
erogatory. Philosophical Studies, 146, 179–196. Nsamengang, A. B. (2011). Intergenerational continuity of val-
Kim, U., & Choi, S. H. (1994). Individualism, collectivism and ues. In J. Valsiner & C. Zimmerman (Eds.) The Oxford hand-
child development: Korean perspective. In P. Greenfield & book of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford University
R. Cocking (Eds.), Cross-cultural roots in minority child devel- Press
opment (pp. 227–257). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates. Okagaki, L., & Frensch, P. (1998). Parenting and children’s
Kim, S. Y., & Wong, V. Y. (2002) Assessing Asian and Asia- school achievement: A multiethnic perspective. American
American parenting: A review of the literature. In K. Kurasaki, Educational Research Journal, 35, 123–144.
S. Okasaki, & S. Sue (Eds.), Asian American mental health: Okagaki, L., & Sternberg, R. (1993) Parental beliefs and chil-
Assessment methods and theories (pp 185–219). New York: dren’s school performance. Child Development, 64, 36–56.
Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers. Oxford English Dictionary (1989). “Supererogation.” Oxford
Krakauer, J. (2009). Where men win glory: The odyssey of Pat English Dictionary (2nd ed). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Tillman. New York: Doubleday. Ortner, S. B. (1989). High religion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Lang, M. (2004). The Athenian citizen. Athens, Greece: The University Press.
American School of Classical Studies at Athens. Oyserman, D., Coon, H., & Kemmelmeier, M. (2002).
Langford, D. J., Crager, S. E., Shehzad, Z., Smith, S. B., Sotocinal, Rethinking individualism and collectivism: Evaluation of
S. G., & Levenstadt, J. S. et al. (2006). Social modulation theoretical assumptions and meta-analyses. Psychological
of pain as evidence for empathy in mice. Science, 312, Bulletin, 128, 3–27.
1967–1970. Peterfreund, S. (1978). On the relation between supererogation
Le, H. V. (2000). Vietnamese youth value beyond Doi Moi: and basic duty. Personalist, 59, 54.
Tradition, continuity and change in culturally shared outlooks Portmore, D. W. (2003). Position-relative consequentialism, agent-
on the family, education, leisure and community. Master’s the- centered options, and supererogation. Ethics, 113, 303–332.
sis, RMIT University, Melbourne, Australia. Rabain, J. (1979). L’enfant du lignage. Paris: Payot.
Lollis, S., Ross, H., & Leroux, L. (1996). An observational study Rawls, J. (1971). Theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
of parents’ socialization of moral orientation during sibling University Press.
conflicts. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 42, 475–494. Sarkasian, N., & Gerstel, N. (2004). Kin support among
Lollis, S., Van Engen, G., Burns, L., Nowak, K., & Ross, H. Blacks and Whites: Race and family organization. American
(1999). Sibling socialization of moral orientation: “Share Sociological Review, 6, 812–837.
with me!” “No, it’s mine!” Journal of Moral Education, 28, Schmidt, J. (1996). The fool’s truth: Diderot, Goethe & Hegel.
339–357. Journal of the History of Ideas, 57, 625–644.

812 duti es and r i g hts


Segall, M. H., Dasen, P. R., Berry, J. W., & Poortinga, Y. H. UNHCR. United Nations universal declaration of human rights.
(1999). Human behavior in global perspective: An introduction Accessed November 15, 2009 from http://www.un.org/en/
to cross-cultural psychology. Needham Heights, MA: Pearson documents/udhr/
Education Company. Urmson, J. (1958). Saints and heroes. In A. Melden (Ed.), Essays
Sengupta, K. (2008, January 31). Sentenced to death: Afghan in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
who dared to read about women’s rights. The Independent Valdes, G. (1996). Con respeto: Bridging the distances between cul-
Online. Accessed February 17, 2010 from www.independent. turally diverse families and schools. An ethnographic portrait.
co.uk/news/world/asia/sentenced-to-death-afghan-who- New York: Teachers College Press.
dared-to-read-about-womens-rights-775972.html Valsiner, J. (2009). The importance of being in-between. In
Shilo, S. (1978). On one aspect of law and morals in Jewish law: A. C. de Sousa Bastos & E. P. Rabinovich (Eds.), Living in
Lifnim Mishurat Hadin. Israel Law Review, 13, 359–390. poverty: Developmental poetics of cultural realities (pp. ix–xii).
Shwalb, D. W., Shwalb, B. J., Nakazawa, J., Hyun, J. H., Van Charlotte, NC.: Information Age Publishing.
Le, H. & Satiadarma, M. P. (2010). East and Southeast Asia: Williams, N. (1990). The Mexican American family. New York:
Japan, South Korea, and Indonesia. In M. H. Bornstein (Ed), General Hall.
The handbook of cultural developmental science (pp. 445–464). Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge,
New York: Taylor & Francis. MA: Belknap.
Sophocles. (442 B.C./1977). The Oedipus cycle: Oedipus Rex, Zimbardo, P. (2007). The Lucifer effect: Understanding how good
Oedipus at Colonus, Antigone (D. Fitts & R. Fitzgerald, Trans.). people turn evil. New York: Random House.
New York: Harvest/HBJ. (Original work written 442 B.C.)

m ogh a dda m , n ovoa , wa rren 813


This page intentionally left blank
PA RT
10
Cultural Interfaces:
Persons and Institutions
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

The Interface between the Sociology


39 of Practice and the Analysis of Talk in
the Study of Change in Educational
Settings
Harry Daniels

Abstract
The point of departure for this chapter is the long-running methodological debate concerning the
separability or inseparability of person and context in the analysis of human functioning. The intention is
to discuss one means of bringing together the psychology that has developed in the wake of Vygotsky’s
early twentieth-century writing with the sociology of pedagogy developed by Basil Bernstein. The
chapter also draws on methodological developments emanating from a 4-year study of professional
learning in multi-agency services. The analysis provides a way of examining the sequential and contingent
emergence of new forms of understanding in specific institutional settings. This provides one approach to
research engagement with the processes of mutual shaping that occur between persons acting and the
institutional settings in which they act.
Keywords: methodology, separability, Bernstein,Vygotsky, institutional modality

There is a long-running tension, within the and enables (Daniels, 2008, p. 1). Sawyer (2002)
so-called macro-micro debate (e.g., Huber, 1991), argues that even the socioculturalists who do make
between those, such as Giddens, who hold that a theoretical claim for inseparability witness certain
individual and group cannot be analytically sepa- forms of dualism in their empirical work. His reso-
rated because “the notions of action and structure lution of the central tension is to reject the “strong”
presuppose one another” (Giddens, 1979, p. 53) and forms of both inseparability and dualism and calls
those, such as Archer (1995, p. 88), who propose for an approach to analytic dualism that:
various forms of analytical dualism as a coun-
. . . must include postulates about the two-way causal
ter to the notion of inseparability. This same ten-
relationship between individual and social properties,
sion is witnessed in recent developments of post-
including the internalization processes associated
Vygotskian theory where writers such as Rogoff
with development and the externalization processes
(1998, pp. 2, 7) espouse a thesis of inseparability
whereby individuals affect social structure.
and others such as Valsiner (1998, p. 1) advance
(Sawyer, 2002, p. 300)
the case for analytic dualisms (Sawyer, 2002). As I
have noted elsewhere, much of the sociocultural or In this way he rejects the individualism that is
Activity Theory research that claims a Vygotskian the hallmark of much cognitive psychology and the
root fails to fully articulate an appropriate theory of deterministic internalization that Bernstein sug-
social structure and an account of how it directs and gests is to be found in some approaches to macro-
deflects the attention of the individuals it constrains sociology.

817
A crucial problem of theoretical Marxism is the 2004). However texts and/or utterances need not
inability of the theory to provide descriptions of be accorded primacy, as Archer (2000) argues that
micro level processes, except by projecting macro it is our practice in the world that gives rise to our
level concepts on to the micro level unmediated by self-consciousness,
intervening concepts though which the micro can be
both uniquely described and related to the macro level. This is not simply of matter of [practice] coming
(Bernstein, 1993, p. xv) before anything else, though temporally it does just
that; it is also a question of viewing language itself as
In this chapter, I will develop an account of insti- a practical activity, which means taking seriously that
tutional structures as cultural/historical products our words are quite literally deeds, and ones which
(artifacts) that play a part in implicit (Wertsch, do not enjoy hegemony over our other doings in the
2007) or invisible (Bernstein, 2000) mediation of emergence of our sense of self.
human functioning and that are in turn transformed (p. 121)
through human action. In so doing, I will draw on
recent developments in post-Vygotskian theory and Practices and the institutions in which they arise are
Bernstein’s sociology of education. That is, I will also transformed over time. Zandee and Bilimoria
seek to avoid the trap of projecting unmediated (2007) focus on the historical making and unmak-
macro-level concepts onto the micro-level. The aim ing of institutions. That is, they move from a focus
is to provide a means by which the mutual shaping on the “process by which institutions are produced
of the macro and micro can be seen through and and reproduced” (Phillips et al., 2004, p. 638) to
explorations in the development of understanding. the processes through which existing institutions
“weaken and disappear” (Scott, 2001, p. 182).
Approaches to the Macro-Micro Problem
Mäkitalo and Säljo (2002) outline the recent Mediation: From Vygotsky to Bernstein
history of the engagement of social science in the The mediational process is one that neither
development of understandings of the ways in denies individual or collective agency nor social,
which institutions exert a formative effect on the cultural, or historical influence. At the very heart
production and maintenance of social order. Their of Vygotsky’s (1987) thesis is the argument that the
particular interest is on the relationship between introduction of new tools into human activity does
the structural and enduring features of institutions more than improve a specific form of functioning, it
and interactional dynamics (p. 58). The attempt to transforms it. Tools, such as language, are cultural,
unravel what is institutional about talk, and the ways historical products that mediate thinking and feel-
in which talk shapes institutions, brings together ing and are in turn shaped and transformed through
macro-micro debates with concerns about the rela- their use in human activity. It is through tool use
tions of the present to the past. Makitalo and Säljo that individual/psychological and cultural/histori-
contrast aspects of structuralist, ethnomethodological, cal processes become interwoven and co-create each
and sociocultural approaches. That is, between the other. Vygotsky links the development of conscious-
determination of individual social action by social ness to semiosis, and specifically to linguistic semio-
structures, as in structuralist accounts, the genera- sis, and thus links the specifically human aspects of
tion of social structures and institutions through our practical and mental life to socio-historical con-
communicative action, as in some ethnomethod- texts (Hasan, 2005, pp. 135, 136).
ological positions (e.g., Garfinkel, 1967), and It is important to note that Vygotsky’s thoughts on
sociocultural accounts in which the primary cultur- the nature of mediation changed during the course of
ally and historically generated meditational means, his writing. Wertsch (2007) distinguishes between the
speech itself shapes and is shaped by the situation accounts of, what he terms explicit and implicit media-
in which it takes place. In this chapter, I wish to tion. The former is explicit in that an individual or
pursue the notion that the construction of social another person who is directing this individual overtly
and organizational reality involves the production and intentionally introduces a “stimulus means” into
of oral, written, and even gestural texts, which par- an ongoing stream of activity and the materiality of
ticipate in the constitution of organizations (Searle, the stimulus means, or signs, involved tends to be
1969). In other words, the texts we produce and obvious and nontransitory (p. 180). He contrasts this
exchange not only represent a world, but also have with implicit mediation, which he sees as a feature of
the property of constituting it (Putnam & Cooren, the later cultural/historical phase of Vygotsky’s work.

818 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


. . . implicit mediation typically does not need to be framework in order to open up the possibility of
artificially and intentionally introduced into ongoing studying the ways in which such action transforms
action (as in explicit mediation). Instead, it is part of an institutional structures while also being shaped by
already ongoing communicative stream that is brought them. In this way, I will seek to outline an approach
into contact with other forms of action. Indeed, one to the mutual shaping and transformation of indi-
of the properties that characterizes implicit mediation viduals and institutions.
is that it involves signs, especially natural language,
whose primary function is communication. In contrast
Mediated Action in Institutional
to the case for explicit mediation, these signs are not
Settings
purposefully introduced into human action and they
Wertsch (1998) has advanced the case for the use
do not initially emerge for the purpose of organizing
of mediated action as a unit of analysis in socialcul-
it. Instead, they are part of a pre-existing, independent
tural research because, in his view, it provides a kind
stream of communicative action that becomes
of natural link between action, including mental
integrated with other forms of goal-directed behavior.
action, and the cultural, institutional, and histori-
(Wertsch, 2007, p. 183)
cal context in which such action occurs. This is so
Similarly for Hasan (2002) and Bernstein (2000), because the mediational means, or cultural tools, are
visible semiotic mediation mediates a specific cat- inherently situated culturally, institutionally, and
egory of reasoning, a certain range of technical con- historically. However, as he had recognized earlier,
cepts, and a particular relation to the physical phe- the relationship between cultural tools and power
nomena of the world whereby the world is classified and authority is still under-theorized and in need
and categorized in a certain way (Hasan, 2002, p. of empirical study (Wertsch & Rupert, 1993). This
152). Whereas invisible semiotic mediation is con- recognition is an important step forward from the
cerned with the ways in which unself-conscious original Vygotskian thesis, which as Ratner (1997)
everyday discourse mediates mental dispositions, notes, did not consider the ways in which concrete
tendencies to respond to situations in certain ways social systems bear on psychological functions. He
and how it puts in place beliefs about the world one discussed the general importance of language and
lives in, including both about phenomena that are schooling for psychological functioning; however
supposedly in nature and those that are said to be in he failed to examine the real social systems in which
our culture (Hasan, 2002). these activities occur. The social analysis is thus
reduced to a semiotic analysis that overlooks the real
Invisible Mediation world of social praxis (Ratner, 1997).
Invisible semiotic mediation occurs in discourse Wertsch’s statement that cultural tools are in
embedded in everyday ordinary activities of a social themselves powerless and only have impact when
subject’s life. Bernstein (1990) argues that while the agents use them (Wertsch 1998, p. 30), when pre-
context for mediation is always the social practices of sented starkly in this way could appear platitudi-
discourse, an important qualification is that in such nous. Nevertheless, the statement carries an impor-
practices individuals take up specific social positions tant reminder about the focus and methods for
and are positioned. The same context offers differ- research on learning resources. With his concern
ent possibilities for socially positioned actors. for the materiality of means (including speech), he
underlines the way in which the material properties
Participation in social practices, including
of tools can illuminate “how internal processes can
participation in discourse, is the biggest boot-
come into existence and operate” (Wertsch, 1998, p.
strapping enterprise that human beings engage in:
31). He suggests that goals arise as part of the “back-
speaking is necessary for learning to speak; engaging
ground framework” or context within which action
with contexts is necessary for recognising and dealing
is carried out and that there may be conflict between
with contexts. This means, of course, that the contexts
the goals of the agent and the embedded goals of the
that one learns about are the contexts that one lives,
tools. He is interested also in how new forms of medi-
which in turn means that the contexts one lives are
ated action result from emergence of new means and
those which are specialised to one’s social position.
“unanticipated spin-offs.” Here he notes that tools
(Hasan, 2005, p. 153)
can emerge in unpredictable ways through misuse or
I will bring the analysis of the sequential and contin- borrowing from different contexts or through use for
gent development of innovation into a Bernsteinian different purposes than designers intended.

da n iels 819
Wertsch also considers issues of power and they in turn shape the thoughts and feelings, the
authority with respect to cultural tools and their identities and aspirations for action of those engaged
use. He describes mediational means as “differen- in interpersonal exchange in those contexts. Hence
tially imbued with power and authority,” “privileg- the relations of power and control, which regulate
ing” and citing Goodnow, imbued with “cognitive social interchange, give rise to specialized principles
values” (Wertsch, 1998). The notion of cognitive of communication. These mediate social relations.
values includes “why it is that certain knowledge In order to understand social mediation it is nec-
is publicly available and openly taught while other essary to take into account ways in which the prac-
forms or knowledge are not” and why certain types tices of a community, such as school and the family,
of solutions are more highly regarded than others are structured by their institutional context (Abreu
(Wertsch, 1998, p. 66). He suggests that the “emer- & Elbers, 2005). There is a need to connect the the-
gence of new cultural tools transforms power and ory of social formation of mind with the descrip-
authority” (Wertsch, 1998, p. 65) and that “forces tions that are used in research. This should provide
that go into the production of a cultural tool often a means of relating the social/cultural/historical
play a major role in determining how it will be context to the form of the artifact—in the present
used” (Wertsch, 1998, p. 142). He raises questions case the patterns of talk understood and analyzed
about how tools are manipulated by users and what as communicative action. We need to understand
tactics are used for employing others’ tools. This is the principles of communication in terms derived
an important departure from approaches to socio- from a study of principles of social regulation at the
cultural studies of the formation of mind, which institutional or organizational level.
neglect the wider situation in which people act. The
analysis of relations of power and control as they The Regulation of Action in Institutions
impact on the production of cultural tools and their It is not just a matter of the structuring of inter-
use is a vital feature of research that seeks to under- actions between the participants and other cultural
stand an enriched, embedded view of human func- tools, rather it is that the institutional structures
tioning in the situation in which it develops. themselves are cultural products that serve as media-
tors. When we talk, as Makitalo and Säljo (2002)
Bernstein and the Need for a Language argue, we enter the flow of communication in a
of Description stream of both history and the future (p. 63). When
Bernstein (1993) argued that the enrichment of we talk in institutions, history enters the flow of
Vygotskian theory calls for the development of lan- communication through the invisible or implicit
guages of description, which will facilitate a multi- mediation of the institutional structures.
level understanding of discourse, the varieties of My suggestion is that there is need to analyze
its practice, and the contexts of its realization and and codify the mediational structures, as they
production. There is a need to connect the theory deflect and direct attention of participants. In this
of social formation of mind with the descriptions sense I am advocating the development of cultural/
that constitute part of the methodological apparatus historical analysis of the invisible or implicit media-
of empirical research. This should provide a means tional properties of institutional structures, which
of relating the social/cultural/historical context to themselves are transformed through the actions of
the form of the artifact. If processes of social forma- those whose interactions are influenced by them.
tion are posited, then research requires a theoretical This move would serve to both expand the gaze
description of the possibilities for social products of Vygotskian theory and at the same time bring
in terms of the principles that regulate the social sociologies of cultural transmission, such as that
relations in which they are produced. We need to developed by Bernstein (2000), into a framework
understand the principles of communication in in which institutional structures are analyzed as
terms derived from a study of principles of social historical products, which themselves are subject to
regulation. dynamic transformation and change.
Different social structures give rise to differ- Bernstein’s (2000) model is one that is designed
ent modalities of language, which have specialized to relate macro-institutional forms to micro-inter-
mediational properties. They have arisen, have been actional levels and the underlying rules of commu-
shaped by, the social, cultural, and historical circum- nicative competence. He focuses upon two levels:
stances in which interpersonal exchanges arise and a structural level and an interactional level. The

820 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


structural level is analyzed in terms of the social pupils will be more asymmetrical, that is, more
division of labor it creates (e.g., the degree of spe- clearly hierarchical. In this example the regulative
cialization, and thus strength of boundary between discourse and its practice is more explicit and distin-
professional groupings). The interactional level is guishable from the instructional discourse. Where
analyzed in terms of the form of social relation it the theory of instruction gives rise to a weak clas-
creates (e.g., the degree of control that a manager sification and weak framing of the practice, then
may exert over a team member’s work plan). Thus children will be encouraged to be active in the
the key concept at the structural level is the con- classroom, to undertake inquiries and perhaps to
cept of boundary, and structures are distinguished work in groups at their own pace. Here the relations
in terms of their relations between categories. The between teacher and pupils will have the appearance
interactional level emerges as the regulation of the of being more symmetrical. In these circumstances
transmission/acquisition relation between teacher it is difficult to separate instructional discourse from
and taught (or the manager and the managed), that regulative discourse, as these are mutually embed-
is, the interactional level comes to refer to the peda- ded. The formulation of pedagogic discourse as
gogic context and the social relations of the work- an embedded discourse comprised of instructional
place, classroom, or its equivalent. and regulative components allows for the analysis
Power is spoken of in terms of classification, of the production of such embedded discourses in
which is manifested in category relations which activities structured through specifiable relations of
themselves generate recognition rules. Possession power and control within institutions.
of these category relations allows the acquirer to be The language that Bernstein has developed,
recognized by a difference that is marked by a cat- uniquely, allows researchers to take measures of
egory as would be the case of the rules that allow a institutional modality. That is, to describe and posi-
professional to be recognized as belonging to par- tion the discursive, organizational, and interactional
ticular professional group. This is not simply a mat- practice of the institution. Bernstein’s work has not
ter of finding out which service someone belongs placed particular emphasis on the study of change
to, it also refers to the ways forms of talk and other (see Bernstein, 2000) and thus, as it stands, has not
actions may be seen as belonging to a particular pro- been applied to the study of the cultural/historical
fessional category or grouping. When there is strong formation of specific forms of activity. In the next
insulation between categories (i.e., subject, teach- section I will discuss some of the methods of data
ers), each category is sharply distinguished, explic- collection and analysis that were developed in a
itly bounded, and has its own distinctive specializa- study of professional learning in rapidly changing
tion; then classification is said to be strong. When contexts.
there is weak insulation, then the categories are less
specialized and their distinctiveness is reduced; then The Learning in and for Interagency
classification is said to be weak. Work Project
Different institutional modalities may be The Learning in and for Interagency Working
described in terms of the relationship between power project (LIW) was a UK research council (TLRP-
and control, which gives rise to distinctive discur- ESRC) study that was co-directed by Harry Daniels
sive artifacts. For example with respect to schooling, and Anne Edwards. It was concerned with the learn-
where the theory of instruction gives rise to a strong ing of professionals in the creation of new forms of
classification and strong framing of the pedagogic practice that require “joined-up” solutions to meet
practice, it is expected that there will be a separation complex and diverse client needs. We studied profes-
of discourses (school subjects), an emphasis upon sional learning in children’s services that aim to pro-
acquisition of specialized skills, the teacher will be mote social inclusion through interagency working.
dominant in the formulation of intended learn- Working with other professionals involves engaging
ing and the pupils are constrained by the teacher’s with many configurations of diverse social practices.
practice. The relatively strong control on the pupils’ It also requires the development of new forms of
learning, itself, acts as a means of maintaining order hybrid practice. This called for joined-up responses
in the context in which the learning takes place. from professionals and stressed the need for new,
This form of the instructional discourse contains qualitatively different forms of multi-agency prac-
regulative functions. With strong classification and tice, in which providers operate across traditional
framing, the social relations between teachers and service and team boundaries.

da n iels 821
Vygotsky was concerned to study human func- of change. He announced that “behaviour can be
tioning as it developed rather than considering func- understood only as the history of behaviour” (p. 65).
tions that had developed. The essence of his “dual He was pursuing a method that allowed for a devel-
stimulation” approach is that subjects are placed opmental analysis of process that explained human
in a situation in which a problem is identified and functioning in terms of dynamic causal relations.
they are also provided with tools with which to solve The dual stimulation method is important in that “it
the problem or means by which they can construct creates the conditions under which a subject’s course
tools to solve the problem. When applied to the of action toward an experimentally given goal makes
study of professional learning, it directs attention to explicit the psychological processes involved in that
the ways in which professionals solve problems with action” (Valsiner, 1990, p. 66). His central concern
the aid of tools that may be provided by researchers. was to study human functioning as it developed
We studied professional learning in workshops that rather than considering functions that had devel-
were broadly derived from the “Change Laboratory” oped. The essence of this approach is that subjects
intervention sessions, developed by Yrjö Engeström are placed in a situation in which a problem is identi-
and his colleagues in Helsinki (Engeström, 2007, see fied and they are also provided with tools with which
Chapter X this volume), which incorporates a dual to solve the problem or a means by which they can
stimulation method. construct tools to solve the problem.
In laboratory sessions the participants were helped
The task facing the child in the experimental context
to envision and draft proposals for concrete changes
is, as a rule, beyond his present capabilities and
to be embarked upon. They discussed and designed
cannot be solved by existing skills. In such cases a
interventions, which were intended to bring about
neutral object is placed near the child, and frequently
changes in day-to-day practices and, at times, in
we are able to observe how the neutral stimulus is
the social structures of the workplace. These actions
drawn into the situation and takes on the function
were prompted by reflections on the tensions and
of a sign. Thus, the child actively incorporates these
dilemmas raised by data. Prior to the workshops,
neutral objects into the task of problem solving. We
interview and observational data were used as a base
might say that when difficulties arise, neutral stimuli
from which to select data that mirror embodied
take on the function of a sign and from that point
tensions, dilemmas, and structural contradictions
on the operation’s structure assumes an essentially
in the practices of each site. In this way, critical inci-
different character.
dents and examples from the ethnographic mate-
(Vygotsky, 1978, p. 74, italics added)
rial are brought into Change Laboratory sessions to
stimulate analysis and negotiation between the par- The essence of this approach, when it is applied to
ticipants. The crucial element in a Vygotskian dual examining professional learning, is that it directs
stimulation event is the co-occurrence of both the attention to the ways in which professionals solve
problem and the tools with which to engage that problems with the aid of tools that are provided
problem. by researchers and become modified in the course
Vygotsky’s cultural/historical psychology cre- of expansive learning. In the Learning in and for
ated demands for methods that could not be met by Interagency Work Project, the focus of our research
the existing resources that early twentieth-century was on the operational work of education, social-
psychology offered him. He instigated the develop- care and health professionals working within chil-
ment of methods that were commensurate to the dren’s services.
challenges that his theoretical program required. In each local authority our research methodol-
ogy was organized around series of “developmental
The search for [the] method becomes one of the work research” workshops involving operational
most important problems of the entire enterprise staff. Prior to (and in between) the workshops the
of understanding the uniquely human forms of research team collected interview and observational
psychological activity. In this case, the method is data that was then scrutinized in workshop settings
simultaneously prerequisite and product, the tool and by researchers and children’s services profession-
result of study. (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 65) als from each local authority. We worked in three
multi-agency settings:
Vygotsky (1978) consistently argued the case for
a historically based psychology. By this he meant (a) Nortonville, a school whose remit has been
a psychology that is concerned with the process extended to act as base for other agencies,

822 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


(b) Wildside, a children-in-public-care team, From a Bernsteinian standpoint, the relations
and of power and control, which regulate social inter-
(c) Seaside, a multi-professional team that change, give rise to specialized principles of com-
originally was comprised of education professionals munication. These mediate social relations and
but expanded to incorporate social-care and health shape both thinking and feeling: the “what” and
practitioners. “how” as well the “why” and “where to” of practice.
We were concerned with the ways in which wider
We organized six Developmental Work Research
social structures impact on the interactions between
(DWR) workshops at each site. The aim was to
the participants and their patterns of communica-
build upon professionals’ “everyday” understand-
tive action.
ings of multi-agency working, juxtaposing these
with reflective, systemic analyses of the ways in
A Model of Description
which current working practices either enable or
A model of the setting in which the develop-
constrain the development of innovative multi-
ment of such multi-agency functioning develops
agency working. The stated aim of the workshops
must refer to the group of professionals who were
was to address the challenges of multi-agency pro-
involved in the workshops, the wider local authority
fessional learning by:
and the clients who were to be served by emergent
• encouraging the recognition of areas in multi-agency practices.
which there is a need for change in working
practices, and
Classification and Framing
• suggesting possibilities for change through
Bernstein’s (2000) concepts of boundary strength
reconceptualizing the “objects” that professionals are
(classification) and control (framing) can be applied
working on, the “tools” that professionals use in
to many aspects of such a model. Here we use the
their multi-agency work and the “rules” in which
terms instrumental or instructional practice to refer
professional practices are embedded.
to the pragmatic actions within practice. Within the
workshop group, the strength of classification (hori-
Analyzing and Describing the Sites zontal division of labor) in the practices of profes-
There was a need to refine a language of descrip- sional agencies and control (framing) over the mem-
tion, which would allow the research to “see” insti- bership of these groups was examined. The strength
tutions as they did their tacit psychological work of distinctions in the vertical division of labor, the
through the discursive practices that they shape. A strength of the marking of hierarchy, and the associ-
way of describing what were essentially the peda- ated relations of control within this hierarchy were
gogic modalities of the settings in which we were also seen to be central facets of the structuring of
intervening was required. That is, the most likely the workshop groups. The strength of control over
forms of institutional practice that would be sus- the regulative practice (matters of order, identity,
tained in those settings needed to be described. and relation) was also noted. In many respects this
A crucial element in the description was to be an shows similarities with Engeström’s (1992) discus-
attempt to try to identify points at which commu- sion of the “why and where to” aspects of activity
nicative action will engage with the transformation in that the reference is to the values and beliefs that
of the institution. We recognised the importance underpin practice. The features of the practices
of developing an approach to the analysis and within the DWR group were modeled as follows in
description of our research sites that could be used Table 39.1.
to monitor changes that took place over the course
of our intervention. All the more so because we Table 39.1 The DWR group: Model features
were minded by the understanding that differ-
ent social structures give rise to different modali- Instrumental or
ties of language that have specialized mediational instructional practice Classification Framing
properties, This was part of the development of Horizontal yes yes
an account of institutional structures as cultural/
historical products (artifacts) that play a part in Vertical yes yes
implicit (Wertsch, 2007) or invisible (Bernstein, Regulative Practice yes
2000) mediation.

da n iels 823
Table 39.2 The local authority: Model features The codings were agreed upon for the full model
Classification Framing for each site, as shown in Figure 39.2.
We also noted the means by which attempts
Horizontal yes were made to coordinate services in the wider local
authority, as well as the form of any recent disrup-
Vertical yes yes
tion in the order of the local authority. These fea-
Boundary with DWR yes tures are given in Figure 39.3.
group A crude typification of these sites in terms of
a general application of Bernstein’s model of the
embedded features of pedagogic practice in which
In the local authority the vertical division of instructional Practice (I) and regulative practice (R)
labor between members of the workshop and are mutually embedded, but in which one may pre-
their colleagues in the wider authority was also dominate (see Fig. 39.4).
taken as a key feature of the research sites as was In this way we arrived at condensed codings of
the extent to which boundaries were maintained what may be seen as the historical legacy presented
between the professions in the local authority. at the moment when we sought to engage with
The control over the boundary relations between groups of professionals at each site.
the workshop groups and the local authority was
analysed and described, somewhat awkwardly,
as the framing of those relations where strong Analyzing Communicative Action at Each Site
framing was taken as a boundary maintained by David Middleton proposed an approach to anal-
the authority, weak framing as a boundary rela- ysis that focused on the forms of social action that
tion in which the workshop group maintained are accomplished in talk and text and the sorts of
control and an intermediary position in which communicative devices that are used (Middleton
a relatively fluid two-way flow of communica- et al., 2008)1. This was designed to focus the ana-
tion was maintained. The features of the prac- lytic attention of the research team on emergent
tices within the local authority were modeled as distinctions that were argued by participants. This
follows in Table 39.2. involved the examination of the shift from the
The extent to which clients were classified as “given” to the “to-be-established.” “What it is to do”
belonging to a particular category of need (strong or “to learn” was not to be assumed as an analytic
classification) or as the “whole child” (weak clas- a priori (Middleton, 2004). Rather, such issues are
sification) was also noted. This was taken as the approached as participants’ concerns or “members
division of labor within the client community. categories” (Sacks, 1992; Edwards & Stokoe, 2004;
Each aspect of this model was described for each Stokoe, 2006). This analytic shift aimed to move
site through data gathered through extensive obser- from framing communication as descriptions cor-
vations and interviews. A coding grid was developed responding to states in and of the world, to the per-
for each aspect. The codings were independently formative organization of communicative action. In
validated by two researchers. An example is given other words, what we do with talk and text can be
in Figure 39.1. analyzed in terms of what it accomplishes (Potter &

Model Feature -- Division of Labour (Vertical)


Exemplar interview question - How hierarchical is the management in your work ?
Coding
1. C-- = All members of a ‘flat’team
2. C++ = Strong hierarchy (director, dep director, principal, senior, junior)

- 1 2 3 4 5
C-- C- C+/- C+ C++
Seaside X

Wildside X

Nortonville X Figure 39.1 Example of coding grids applied


to model of description.

824 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


Wildside Seaside Nortonville

DWR group

Horizontal C- F- C+/- F+/- C++ F++

Vertical C- -F- C- - F+/- C+ F++

Regulative Practice F+/- F++ F- -

Local Authority

Horizontal C + F+ C+ F+ C+ F+

Vertical C- F - C++ F+/- C++F++

Control over DWR F+/- F++ F- -

group boundary Free flow Control with LA Control with DWR

Clients

Horizontal C- C- - C+ +
Figure 39.2 Agreed codings for the
full model

Wetherell, 1987; Edwards & Potter, 1992; Edwards, of the year in which the six DWR workshops were
1992). We emphasized that addressing such issues organized at each site. In drawing analytical atten-
required a focus on the sequential and contingent tion to the significance of claims to experience, we
organization of session-communicative action. That were also able to highlight the temporal organiza-
is, how people’s contributions to the sessions are tion of communicative action. We also used forms
contingently related to each other in terms of the of discursive analysis to trace the emergence of what
sequential organization of their talk (Middleton can be taken as the collective and distributed knowl-
et al., 2008). edge of people who are charged with the task of
Its cyclical application enabled: reading, review- working together. We aimed to track the emergent
ing, interrogating, collating, and comparing all the practical epistemologies (cf. Wickman & Ostman,
audio-visual evidence from the intervention sessions 2002; Wickman, 2004) that come and need to be
in order to identify the emergent strands of learning taken as given in order to take account of hitherto
and proposals for change. The approach was devel- unaddressed gaps in the realization of multi-agency
oped as a means of identifying strands of commu- practice. Such gaps were identified and worked on
nicative action, which witnessed the sequential and through participation in the DWR sessions at each
contingent development of concepts over the course research site.

Seaside Wildside Nortonville

Coordination of Perceived lack of Strong strategy No strategy which


agencies and agents response to impacted on case
operational staff study site.
views (at several Strategy developing
levels) within rest of LA

Disruptions Several major re- Recent leadership


organisations changes and
Radical localisation reconfigured
of services systems
Figure 39.3 Features of the local
authority (LA)

da n iels 825
• Seaside I/R The regulative aspect of predominant

• Nortonville I/R The instructional / instrumental aspect is predominant

• Wildside I/R An intermediary / balanced position


Figure 39.4 Representation of the
structure of pedagogic practices at each
study site

Initially we approached the data with what attend to in order to learn to do multi-agency work-
could be termed a minimal operationalisation of ing? In other words, did they lead to some form of
“what it is to learn” from a participant’s perspec- departure or development in claims concerning the
tive. We examined the data for ways participants practice of the participants? This step enabled us to
signaled some forms of awareness that theirs’ or complete the definition of the protocol with:
others’ knowledge state is at issue. Such “noticings”
Departure: identify shifts toward qualititatively
provide the resource that engages the participants in
different positions in practices in terms of the
their definition/delineation and deliberation of the
formulation of emergent distinctions.
nature of the practices that make up their multi-dis-
Development: identify when participants specify
ciplinary work. In the data we could identify many
new ways of working that provide the basis for
such strands of noting and noticing such distinc-
becoming part of, or having become part of,
tions that make the difference. Indeed this sort of
what they take to be and warrant as a significant
analysis provided us with a basis for defining a pro-
reformulation of their practices.
tocol for guiding interrogation and analysis of the
data in terms of the sequential organization of such Sequences of communicative action were analyzed
strands. The analysis was therefore initially guided in the transcripts of the workshops. Some sequences
in terms of the following protocol: progressed to departures, others remained at other
stages within the model. Related sequences were
Deixis: identify when there is some nomination or
identified and these were grouped into strands of
“pointing” to a particular issue in terms of drawing
talk that wove their way through the progress of the
attention to a distinction that is then worked up to
each series of workshops. These strands (comprised
make a difference in subsequent turns.
of different types of sequences) witnessed the pro-
Definition and delineation: look for how that is-
gression of learning through and with talk in the
sue is elaborated in the uptake of others in terms of
workshops. The themes that these strands addressed
how the following are warranted and made relevant
and the contradictions that gave rise to their emer-
through: (i) qualifications identifying further distinc-
gence were analyzed in activity theoretic terms. At
tions; (ii) orderabilities in the organization and
the end of the project, participants were interviewed
delivery of past, present, and future practice; (iii) ex-
about what they gained from the experience and
pansive elaborations of the problematics of practice.
subsequent analysis revealed the traces of each site’s
Deliberation: identify how some working consensus
strands in the interviews at each site. In this way we
on what is the case emerges in terms of evoking both
developed an approach to the analysis of commu-
particularities and generalities of marking distinctive
nicative action in the workshops themselves, along
features of past, present, or future practice.
with a rudimentary approach to validation. The
The analysis then turned to examining in what ways next move was to consider the relation between the
such sequences mattered. If we identified strands communicative action that took place and the his-
of deixis, definition/delineation, and deliberation, torically given structures that shaped the practices
what were their contingent consequences for par- of participants.
ticipants? Did they make visible distinctions that The overall challenge of the project was to show
made the difference in ways that participants could how institutionally established categories and ways
be identified as attending to what was necessary to of arguing could be reformulated and transformed

826 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


into new strategies and activities as part of learning ing of boundaries was most likely to be achieved
what it is to become engaged with and in multi- through external influence on the values and beliefs
agency work. However, without the comprehensive within the DWR group (the regulative practice).
analysis of the communicative action within the ses- This was confirmed through the analysis of com-
sions across all the research sites we would not have municative action within the workshops. An educa-
been able to progress to the final analysis of those tional psychologist acted in this way.
transformations (Daniels, 2006). In Seaside the focus of communicative action was
on the rules and practices of communication within
Communicative Action and the instructional practice. Participants became frus-
Structural Change trated by the contradiction between legacy rules
The notion that guided the further development (maintained by the local authority) and the new
of the analysis was that the institutional arrange- emergent objects of multi-agency work. They had
ments at a particular site would direct and deflect already established a strong regulative practice before
the possibilities for action by participants. This sug- the DWR intervention was initiated. On the basis
gestion was witnessed in the findings. of this legacy they sought to examine the contradic-
The data suggest that at a very general level there tions in the instrumental aspects of their practice
were stronger values of classification and framing of and began to bend (or even break) the legacy rules.
the instructional practice in Nortonville and pro- The strong boundary between the workshop group
gressively weaker values in Seaside and Wildside. and the local authority was maintained through
In addition, a consideration of the nature of the practices of communication in which instructions
regulative practice in each site suggests strong fram- (rules) were formulated and transmitted by local
ing in Seaside, weak framing in Nortonville, with authority strategists who were unresponsive to
Wildside occupying an intermediary position. replies or ideas formulated by operational profes-
Thus, in Nortonville the instructional practice sionals within the workshop group. This approach
(which was strongly classified and highly framed) which we termed ‘d-analysis’ confirmed that the
predominates over the weak regulative discourse. boundary between the workshop group and the
Whereas in Seaside the relatively weak boundar- local authority was the focus of the communicative
ies witnessed in the weaker values of classification action in the workshops.
of the instructional practice were embedded in the In Wildside the relation with clients became the
regulative practice through which common values predominant concern. There were no strong barriers
and meanings have been the object of much of the between the group and the authority, and although
early work of the team. In Wildside an intermedi- the categories of professional agencies within the
ary position was witnessed in the embedding of the authority remained strong, the learning focused on
instruction and regulation. ways in which multi-agency work could be coordi-
Over the period of interventions in the work- nated through strategic tools. These tools were the
shops, many structural transformations were focus of much of the communicative action in the
witnessed. The Bernsteinian analysis revealed Wildside workshops.
the boundaries where communicative action in The strong boundaries around the professional
each site was most engaged and how that action categories and the strong control over professional
was regulated. Analysis revealed how a focus on behavior in Nortonville maintained the practices of
institutional boundaries and relations of control individual specialists. In what was, in essence, a con-
provided important tools for understanding the tract culture in which specialist labor was purchased
shaping of transformative learning in specific in order to meet needs that were stipulated by one
settings. agency, there was no debate or development of the
For example, by the end of the intervention it regulative discourse, the “why and where-to” features
was the weaker regulative practice of Nortonville of the practice. Here the formation of a collection of
that was the object of intervention from an external specialists was mediated by explicit means. Whereas
agent. The historical legacy of the strongly bound- at Wildside there were weak boundaries around the
aried extended school site within which professional professional categories in which professionals were
practices were highly controlled. These remained situated in the workshop and they were more in con-
distinct from each other provided a setting in which trol than their peers in Nortonville. However their
a move to multi-agency working and thus weaken- operational professional practice witnessed strong

da n iels 827
boundaries between services and their professional At the same time it carries with it the possibility of
peers. In Seaside the weakened professional bound- rethinking notions of agency and reconceptualizing
aries and relations of control that had been weak- subject position in terms of the relations between
ened through rule breaking and bending gave rise possibilities afforded within the division of labor
to a collection of workers who drew on the primary and the rules that constrain possibility and direct
strengths of their colleagues when they recognized and deflect the attention of participants.
the need for their expertise. Values coordinated by
strategy resulted in a coordinated collection of spe- Future Directions
cialists in the field. The implicit meditational effect There are many challenges ahead for the devel-
of the boundary between the operational and strate- opment of this approach. Given that the delicacy
gic aspects of the work resulted in transformations, of the model of description may be adjusted to the
in the form of rule bending, that were not open to demands of the research question:
articulation by practitioners. It was only when their 1. How do we ensure that we are asking the
changes in practice were represented to them that right questions about the potential institutional
they realized the nature of the changes they had contributing factors, which exert a formative effect
made in their work. on inter- and intrapersonal functioning, and
2. How do we ensure that we are observing
Conclusion the relevant forms of inter- and intrapersonal
This approach gives some insight into the shap- functioning when we come to consider the shaping
ing effect of institutions as well as the ways in which of institutional change?
they are transformed through the agency of partici-
pants. We modeled the structural relations of power These are questions about what might be called lens
and control in institutional settings, theorized as cul- adjustment in research.
tural/historical artifacts, which invisibly or implic- There is a related question concerning the con-
itly mediate the relations of participants in practices siderable challenge inherent in the search for meth-
in which communicative action takes place. This odologies that allow us to uncover the range and
communicative action was then analyzed in terms extent of invisible or implicit meditational means in
of the strands of evidence of learning in and for new different situations.
ways of working. This provided empirical evidence
of the mutual shaping of communicative action by Notes
organizational structures and relations and the for- 1. I am grateful to David Middleton for permission to draw
on project notes for this section.
mation of new professional identities.
This approach extends the application of
Bernstein’s work to the study of the transformation References
Abreu, G., & Elbers, E. (2005). The social mediation of learn-
of institutional modalities over time. The analysis ing in multiethnic schools: Introduction. European Journal of
of communicative action provides an approach to Psychology of Education, 20(1), 3–11.
the consideration of the sequential and contingent Archer, M. (2000). Being human: The problem of agency.
development of concepts over time in specific insti- Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Archer, M. S. (1988). Culture and agency: The place of culture in
tutional settings.
social theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.
This approach to modeling the structural rela- Archer, M. S. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic
tions of power and control in institutional set- approach. New York: Cambridge University Press.
tings were theorized as cultural/historical artifacts, Bernstein, B. (1990). The structuring of pedagogic discourse (Vol.
which invisibly or implicitly mediate the relations IV): Class, codes and control. London: Routledge.
Bernstein, B. (1993). Foreword. In H. Daniels (Ed.), Charting
of participants in practices. Their communicative
the agenda: Educational activity after Vygotsky. London:
action may be analyzed in terms of the strands of Routledge.
evidence of learning in and for new ways of work- Bernstein, B. (2000). Pedagogy, symbolic control and identity:
ing, giving some insight into the shaping effect Theory, research, critique (Revised edition). Lanham, MD:
of institutions, as well the ways in which they are Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc.
Daniels, H. (2001). Vygotsky and pedagogy. London: Routledge.
transformed through the agency of participants. It
Daniels, H. (2006). Analysing institutional effects in Activity
opens up the possibility of developing increasingly Theory: First steps in the development of a language of
delicate descriptions of the rules and division of description. Outlines: Critical Social Studies, 2, 43–58.
labor that are obtained within and between settings. Daniels, H. (2008). Vygotsky and research. London: Routledge.

828 th e inter face b e t we e n t he so ci o logy of practice


Edwards, D., & Potter, J. (1992). Discursive psychology. London: Potter, J. & Wetherell, M. (1987). Discourse and social psychology
Sage. beyond attitudes and behaviour. London: Sage Publications.
Edwards, D., & Stokoe, E. H. (2004). Discursive psychology, Putnam, L. L., & Cooren, F. (2004). Alternative perspectives
focus group interviews, and participants’ categories. British on the role of text and agency in constituting organizations.
Journal of Developmental Psychology, 22, 499–507. Organization, 11, 323 – 333.
Engeström, Y. (1992). Interactive expertise: Studies in distributed Ratner, C. (1997). Cultural psychology and qualitative methodol-
working intelligence. University of Helsinki, Department of ogy: Theoretical and empirical considerations. London: Plenum
Education. Research Bulletin 83. Press.
Engeström, Y. (2007). Putting Vygotsky to work. The change Rogoff, B. (1998). Cognition as a collaborative process. In
laboratory as an application of double stimulation. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychol-
H. Daniels, M. Cole, & J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge ogy (Vol. 2): Cognition, perception, and language (5th ed.)
companion to Vygotsky (pp. 363–382). Cambridge, UK: (pp. 679–744). New York: Wiley.
Cambridge University Press. Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation (Vol. I and II). Oxford:
Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood Blackwell.
Cliffs, Prentice-Hall. Sawyer, K. (2002). Unresolved tensions in sociocultural theory:
Giddens, A. (1979). Central problems in social theory: Action, Analogies with contemporary sociological debates. Culture &
structure, and contradiction in social analysis. Berkeley, CA: Psychology, 8(3), 283–305.
University of California Press. Scott, W. R. (2001). Institutions and organizations (2nd ed.).
Hasan, R. (2002). Semiotic mediation and mental development Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
in pluralistic societies: Some implications for tomorrow’s Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of lan-
schooling. In G. Wells & G. Claxton (Eds.), Learning for life guage. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
in the 21st century: Socio-cultural perspectives on the future of Stokoe, E. (2006). On ethnomethodology, feminism, and the
education. Oxford: Blackwell. analysis of categorical reference to gender in talk-in-inter-
Hasan, R. (2005). Semiotic mediation, language and society: action. Sociological Review, 54(3), 467–494. (Special issue
Three exotripic theories—Vygotsky, Halliday and Bernstein. ‘New Horizons in Ethnomethodology’).
In J. J. Webster (Ed.), Language, society and consciousness: Valsiner, J. (1998). Dualisms displaced: From crusades to ana-
Ruqaiya Hasan. London: Equinox. lytic distinctions. Human Development, 41, 350–354.
Huber, J. (1991). Macro–micro linkages in sociology. Newbury Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky
Park, CA: Sage. (Vol. 1): Problems of general psychology. In R. W. Rieber &
Makitalo, A., & Säljo, R. (2002). Talk in institutional context A. S. Carton (Eds.), Thinking and speech, N. Minick (trans.).
and institutional context in talk: Categories as situated prac- New York: Plenum Press.
tices. Text, 22(1), 57–82. Wertsch, J. (1998). Mind as action. New York: Oxford University
Middleton, D. (2004). Concepts, learning and the constitution Press.
of objects and events in discursive practice. In A. N. Perret- Wertsch, J. V., & Rupert, L. J. (1993). The authority of cul-
Clermont, C. Pontecorvo, L. Resnick, T. Zittoun, & B. Burge tural tools in a sociocultural approach to mediated agency.
(Eds.), Joining society: Social interaction in adolescence and Cognition and Instruction, 11(3–4), 227–239.
youth (pp. 204–215). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Wertsch, J. V. (2007). Mediation. In H. Daniels, M. Cole, &
Press. J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Vygotsky.
Middleton, D., Brown, S., Daniels, H., Edwards, A., Leadbetter, New York: Cambridge University Press.
J., & Warmington, P. (2008). Making the difference in Wickman, P. (2004). The practical epistemologies of the class-
interagency working: Analytic challenges in studying pro- room: A study of laboratory work. Science Education, 88,
fessional learning in communicating what matters. In 325–344.
C. Candlin & S. Sarangi (Eds.), Handbook of applied linguis- Wickman, P., & Ostman, L. (2002). Learning as discourse
tics communication in professions and organisations. Berlin: change: A sociocultural mechanism. Science Education, 86,
Mouton de Gruyter. 601–623.
Phillips, N., Lawrence, T. B., & Hardy, C. (2004). Discourse Zandee, D. P., & Bilimoria, D. (2007) Institutional transforma-
and institutions. Academy of Management Review, 29(4), tion through positive textual deviance. International Journal
635–652. of Sociology and Social Policy,27(11/12), 469–482.

da n iels 829
CHAPTER

The Work of Schooling


40
Giuseppina Marsico and Antonio Iannaccone1

Abstract
The communication process between the school and home is a universal relation that is crucial for
cultural organization of human development. Through the balcony metaphor, the chapter outlines how
the school is a place in between, a border constantly interfaced with both internal aspects (practices,
discourses and different actors) and the wider sociocultural climate. The school balcony, as a border zone,
is an area of contact with other relevant educational settings. By standing on the balcony and by adopting
a binocular-type vision focused inside and outside school, this contribution explores the many processes
implied in the work of schooling, moving from the role played by the socio-economic and cultural
dimensions, passing through the analysis of intersectional points with other educational contexts (such
as family-school meetings), arriving at the definition of identity in the school (the suggested Educational
Self notion). The choice to “be” on the school balcony, even if it’s an uncomfortable position, allows one to
assume a perspective where one is able to grasp the inherent dynamism of the boundary phenomena.
Keywords: balcony, boundary process, inside and outside the school, school-family intersection,
Educational Self notion

When you think about the school, the most com- This image, that you probably draw from bio-
mon image that comes to your mind is likely a large, graphic memory and experience as a student,
multi-storied building with a spacious entrance and comes in clearly and seems ordinary to your eyes.
several rooms, more or less of the same size. Besides negligible details, the school seems a place
connoted by some features—including architec-
tural features—concurring to build a prototypical
and shareable image. When we think about the
work of schooling, something similar happens.
Suddenly the image comes to mind of a classroom
furnished in a standard way, with students and
teachers carrying out some activities. The visual
and virtual tour of the school, slowly winding
before your eyes, seems to follow a specific path-
way: you enter the building through the nearly
empty entrance hall,

All conversational sequences we present in the following pages were fully transcribed according to the Jeffersonian conventions
(Jefferson, 1985). See the appendix for symbol definitions that are used in the excerpts.

830
Why a balcony? Why would a school need a
balcony? Can you visualize a balcony? Obviously,
a school does not need a balcony—but the school
can be considered to be a metaphoric balcony of the
society itself.

The School as a Balcony


Schools all over the world hardly ever have balco-
nies2. In this imaginary topology, we want to look at
the work of schooling from the viewpoint of a met-
aphoric balcony. In our view, the school is just com-
parable to a balcony because it is exactly a place in
between. It is part of the whole—an establishment
of learning—but also a frontier, bordering on the
walk through the corridors, outside. In fact, the balcony is a place that is a non-
place. It is an extension of the house where various
events of daily life and many relevant social interac-
tions take place. But the balcony is also a space out-
stretched toward the outside, suspended in space.
It brings the intimacies of the inside to the public
visibility on the border with the outside—without
abandoning the inside.
School as balcony must constantly face the
internal and external world in terms of culture—
sociopolitical climate, social change, systems of
beliefs and values, conceptions of education or,
in other words, the Weltanschauung and Bildung
shared at given time. It also faces challenges in
terms of social norms (for example, how the rela-
tions between adults and children in different social
enter a classroom where something is going on settings are regulated) and of relations with others
between teacher and students, following a format institutions (such as families, religious organizations,
(front lesson, discussion, assessment). local authorities, etc.).
The metaphor evoked—like every metaphor—is
not a strategic and simple way to summarize con-
cepts. It is an evocative modality to talk about the
work of schooling because it contains the way to
immediately grasp the multifaceted and concrete
state of this specific topic (Lakoff & Johnson, 1980;
Dooremalen & Borsboom, 2010). Looking at the
work of school from the balcony is certainly an
uncommon and maybe uncomfortable position.
On the balcony you are actually exposed to unex-
pected events such as the change of weather condi-
tions. However, from the balcony you can observe
both inside and outside the building. From this
position you can grasp both internal elements com-
But is that really all there is? Do not you think that ing out—like the good smell of coffee or an Italian
something is missing? What’s missing? Something kitchen, people laughing or quarrelling—and exter-
does not actually appear in this journey—something nal elements coming in—for example, fresh air,
that the schools do not have—a balcony. light, smog, and noise. Many other things happen

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 831


in the narrow and hanging space of a balcony. The seems to be heuristically relevant, from the point
balcony actually exposes you to world outside. It is of view of psycho-social processes, to explore some
a physical space distinct from the house’s interior, psychological dynamics and exchanges between
which is instead made of well-known objects with life contexts where development events take place.
their usual place. It is a distinct social space where The use of boundary notion is,obviously, not new
some forms of interaction with neighbors take place. in psychology. Sufficient is to refer to Kurt Lewin’s
From the balcony, you can observe life going on and perspective focused on boundaries (Lewin, 1936).
be observed in return, you can look at the changing
landscape, the world in movement, the succession Boundary Processes and Psychological
of the seasons. On the balcony, you can grow plants Membranes
or keep the dustbin. It is the boundary conditions—structured and
dynamic as a “membranes” in biological systems
Inside and Outside: The Balcony as a (Beloussov, 1998)—that we need to explore. The
Border Zone inherent open-ended nature of sociocultural phe-
Applying this metaphor to the work of schooling, nomena requires a new theoretical framework
we may say that choosing to be on the balcony tran- that enables us to grasp the fluidity of the rela-
scends the idea of school as a closed territory, char- tions between different parts of the dynamic sys-
acterized by its own culture of education (Bruner, tem (Tavory, Jablonka, & Ginsburg, 2012). Recent
1996), estranged and far away from the real world. advances in modern biology seem to provide a set of
This choice rather assumes a perspective able to heuristic concepts useful to investigate the complex-
grasp the dynamism and movement between dif- ity and fluidity of the relationship between differ-
ferent social settings, connections and implications ent contexts. One of these is the notion of plasticity
between school and broader culture characterized derived from Waddington’s epigentetic approach
by some ideas about education, some specific form (1940, 1957). Plasticity is related to the different
of social organization, beliefs, and shared models possible responses (more or less adaptive, active,
of behavior, as well as sociopolitical and economic predictable, or reversible) of one organism to the
change. In the metaphor, the balcony is the point of various environmental conditions. Such fluid and
contact between the school—with its own practices opened-ended plasticity is a relevant feature of the
and discourses (laughing and quarrelling), its old boundary conditions. The interest for the bound-
and new cultural artifacts (coffee, Italian kitchen, ary process is strictly connected with the “crossing
material and symbolic objects that are available boundaries” phenomena. It calls for focusing on
and familiar)—and the outside world, where dif- what happened on the border or, following our met-
ferent social changes take place (succession of the aphor, what happens on the balcony. We will adopt
seasons and change of landscape), and in which dif- binocular-typevision, enabling us to constantly
ferent educational models and belief systems coex- focus on both aspects—what happens to actors
ist, sometimes opposing and disorienting (fresh air, inside and outside school in the broader cultural
light, smog, and noise). Like every boundary zone context—because we are aware that school walls, as
(Lewin, 1936; Tüomi-Gröhn, 2007; Tüomi-Gröhn argued, are much more permeable than previously
& Engeström, 2003; Konkola, 2001), the school theorized by psychological research.
balcony is a place of social interaction with other Even though constantly paying attention to the
actors (neighbors) and of intersection with other whole of field forces (Lewin, 1951) inside and out-
educational contexts, relevant for a child’s develop- side school, we will attempt to “zoom in,” from the
ment. In order to manage the encounter with the analysis of some elements of sociocultural context
“Other” (for example, families, other education significantly affecting education, to the way school
agencies, community), a school has at its disposal gets in contact with other education agencies, to
more or less adequate tools (plants or dustbin) that explore how the history of one’s educational experi-
can make it fruitful or difficult meeting the world ence affects the definition of Self.
outside.
In this contribution we will attempt to better A View through the Balcony
direct the look, focusing not only on what hap- Our privileged position on the balcony enables us
pens inside and outside school, but especially what to clearly observe the twofold function of school,
happens on the border. The construct of “border” referring to both individual and interpersonal

832 th e work o f scho o li ng


processes and contextual and cultural aspects with assumes that development can be understood only
their interconnection. This position enables us to considering it as a process integrated with social and
see the unity of differences operating within the environmental conditions.
same whole (Valsiner, 2009). School holds a promi- Since its first comparison in the 1970s,
nent position in most societies—as well as in psy- Bronfenbrenner’s model has had a great impact
chological research—because of its crucial role in on the psychological field. Unlike other models,
both individual and social life. In the school con- although sophisticated, it offers conceptual tools
text, the individual reaches a series of cognitive, essential to understand the relationship between cer-
social, and affective achievements that are funda- tain specific elements of development and the role
mental in development to become able to appropri- played by the characteristic of the environment. As
ate of the culture he/she belongs to (Rogoff, 2003; stressed by the ecological systems perspective, family
Lopez, Najafi, Rogoff, & Arauz, 2012) and it hap- and school are the fundamental contexts in which
pens through more and more active participation social development takes place. This assumption,
in shared social practices. Within the sociocultural widely shared, is the basis of many researches that, at
context of a given society, school is also the cata- different levels, have examined how things work in
lyst element—sometimes propulsive, sometimes these two micro-systems. Few studies, instead, have
inhibitory—of specific social processes (Toomela investigated their intersection. How and where do
& Valsiner, 2010; Cabell, 2010; Steininger, 2008). family and school contexts intersect? Which is the
On the other hand, school plays more frequently representations’ systems produced by the actors in
a homeostatic function, devoted to preserving the one context toward the other micro-system? Which
status-quo of society. are the regulatory dynamics taking place during the
encounters of the two micro-systems? These ques-
Context as a Ground of a Figure tions require defining the nature of this intersection
The key element allowing the creation of the and the way in which the person becomes person-
relationship inside and outside the school is the idea in-the-context. Valsiner’s notion of context (1987)
of a link between context and culture with the figure is closer to the concept of the functional relation-
itself (Kindermann & Valsiner,1995). In this sense, ship between person and environment, in which the
context is the background of a figure, and cannot exist organism creates the context and the context creates
separately, according to Herbst’s co-genetic logic the organism in return, even if they are not melted
(1995). When a phenomenon comes into being, into one entity. This differs from Rogoff’s perspec-
context is necessarily there. This idea is in contrast tive (2003), in which the two aspects are consid-
with the cross-cultural and “traditional” psychologi- ered similar and connected, rather than unified but
cal concept of context, understood as something separated. The idea of inclusive separation (Valsiner,
into which a person is placed. Following this per- 1987) is a more heuristic look at the relationships
spective, school should be a context into which a than the idea of exclusive separation, in which person
child is placed. Instead, we argue that when a child and context are just separated—or fusion, in which
enters the school, this context becomes part of the they cannot be distinguished at all. A phenomenon
child just because he is in the school. A relationship cannot be theoretically analyzed “in relation” with-
between the child and the school is thus established, out having parts that relate. In order to understand
rather than a unilateral effect of school, family, or the dynamic nature of the relationship between per-
society on the child. This could be an example of son, context, and culture, it is worthwhile to theo-
the view we would not follow—context, and its retically keep person and environment together, like
cultural features, as separated from individual pro- separate entities always related as a whole.
cesses taking place in school. In some sense, even
Bronfenbrenner’s model (1979) de facto accepts that The Mutual Feed-Forward Loop
view. He would probably oppose this claim, but the The theoretical perspective—sensitive to the con-
way he presents the context at multi-level essences of nections and mutual definition between different
different systems actually separates the context from elements within the same whole and to the mutual
actors. Undoubtedly, the ecological theory of human feed-forward loop between person and context—
development is one of the most interesting scientific seems to support the methodological choice of “posi-
perspectives to have emerged during the twentieth tioning on the balcony,” constantly directing the
century to study the development processes. It look inside and outside school. In this way, is thus

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 833


possible to examine how, during everyday activities scientific production is based on a series of studies
inside school—on a intrapsychic and interpsychic in sociology and economics leading to the scathing
level of analysis (Doise, 1982)—the extraordinary and common conclusion that—despite an almost
endeavour of the formation of higher mental pro- universal diffusion of alphabetization and basic
cesses (such as formal language, reasoning, problem education—it is quite impossible, as a matter of
solving, etc.) takes place. In addition, is it also pos- fact, to significantly “democratize” the effects of
sible to explore how the personality construction is education. It is not possible to provide every stu-
consolidated through the relationship with others dent, independently from his own socio-economic
and significant adults. Within this dimension the origins, actual opportunities of redemption from
construct of Educational Self is grafted. As we will the original status through education. This is an
argue more fully below, it is a specific part of Self evidence-based conclusion stressing the critical state
emerging from the individual’s experiences in the of democratic foundations with respect to school.
educational contexts. It takes place during the school As a matter of fact, despite evident differences in
age, but goes on throughout life, playing a role every accessing educational resources and cultural capital
time people are involved in educational activities or (Bourdieu & Passeron, 1970), many people would
have to deal with educational contexts. claim that these differences are not actually relevant
On a more general level of analysis, school is at school. Every student, provided with good will
instead the institution “formally” charged with and enough perseverance, will be able to achieve
human development. It is a social organization that, every aspiration. Democratic systems are based on
in theory, takes care of—or should take care of (con- the reassuring claim that, at least in principle, it is
ditional mood is required especially in relation to actually possible to remove the obstacles causing
depressed or developing areas)—an entire genera- “socio-economic diversity” in a large number of the
tion of children and youths in a given historic and population. Education is charged with the funda-
cultural moment. The fundamental construction mental responsibility to put citizens in a position
of human beings as members of society is thus at of equal rights and opportunities, by actually sup-
stake in school and, as a consequence, the construc- porting those who move from disadvantaged social
tion of collective future directions, the opportuni- and economic positions. Unfortunately, although
ties for positive or negative change, is also at stake. more people can access education, school seems
Also in jeopardy is the fundamental play for pres- still unable to narrow the socio-economic gap, even
ent and future models of collective life, as well as in rich countries. Employment statistics still show
social rights—for example, the opposition between a clear and direct relationship between type of job
democratization and privatization affecting the and a family’s socio-economic resources. In other
right to access school, a debate taking place in dif- words, social class of origin, choice of the course of
ferent rich and developing countries. These remarks study, and school achievements are so tightly linked
impose to examine what surrounds the metaphori- that school seems to be an instrument to maintain
cal balcony from which we are analyzing the work social stratification (Dei, 2000).
of schooling. Through the balcony, these elements Besides a student’s actual starting condition,
reach school, becoming a fundamental element in related to his or her family’s social and cultural
constructing school’s everyday life and its systems capital, there is a second level of influence play-
of activity (Engeström, 1987). The first element to ing a relevant part in enhancing or balancing the
be taken into account is the socio-economic dimen- effects of social differences in the classroom. The
sion of cultural context in which school acts. In forms of organization established in the classroom
this perspective, a historical review of the processes, lead to different arrangements in teachers’ formal
leading to specific concepts of school and to some power conduct and in students’ group informal
outcomes of teaching and learning processes, can be power relationships (Fele & Paoletti, 2003). These
very useful. complex processes originate from socio-economic
differences—as well as any other difference of
Homeostatic Functions of the School age, gender, disability, etc.—anchoring to group
Since the 1960s, extensive scientific literature dynamics. These dynamics can minimize or, more
in development and education psychology stressed frequently, radicalize the perception of differences,
the dramatic effects of families’ socio-economic affecting group inclusion and exclusion processes.
conditions on children’s school experience. This Many studies in social psychology (see Speltini &

834 th e work o f scho o li ng


Palmonari, 2007 for an overview) stress how this activating (according to some social psychologists of
dichotomy—being inside or outside the group— development) a sort of “defensive” representation,
clearly affects the perception of specific individual realized in the “individualistic” gift theory. The
characteristics. The group tends to “assimilate” attribution of failure to a student’s specific charac-
members emphasizing common traits and underes- teristics becomes a teacher’s vindication.
timating differences. On the other hand, differences Fortunately, a large part of modern education
with nonmembers or conflicting out-group mem- psychology provides alternative explications to fail-
bers are overestimated (Tajfel, 1981). ure, by contextualizing it and restoring the complex
Through psycho-social studies, we can more of human experience as a whole (Carugati & Selleri,
systematically stress common sense extension and 2005). Some just point out the relationship between
depth of socio-economic differences affecting people failure and socio-economic variables, while others
life, also in so-called welfare societies. Several sharp stress how learning is an interpersonal process by
studies incontestably show the basic privileges pro- nature. In the latter category of studies, failure is
vided by some socio-economic conditions, dramati- identified with specific social skills, especially argu-
cally highlighting inequalities between students in mentative ones (Muller Mirza, Perret-Clermont,
choosing courses of study, achieving educational Tartas, & Iannaccone, 2009). Thus, the problem
goals, and accessing jobs. Although for different rea- shifts from the student’s cognitive and motivational
sons, teachers also often underestimate the effects fund to the ability of establishing relationships with
of socio-economic conditions on students. For others—in situations in which confronting ideas
example, the belief that students’ success or failure is and points of view leads him or her to become aware
mainly related to endogenous and motivational fac- of the necessary operations to solve problems—en-
tors is still commonly held (Iannaccone & Marsico, hancing a cognitive progress (Iannaccone, 2010).
2007). It is not unusual to say: “He is a child with In the same socio-constructivist direction, there are
scarce motivation to learn,” or “He is not inclined other interesting perspectives referring to the so-
for school,” as if learning processes would totally rely called “Brunerian culturalist.” view Bruner (1990,
on a sort of magical energy someone has and some- 1996) outlines an idea of cognitive and learning
one else does not have. In this case, researchers argue processes as a construction of meaning with respect
that people use this gift theory (Mugny & Carugati, to their social and cultural frameworks. Common
1985) to account for the extraordinary variability sense, on one hand, and “contextualist” researchers,
of individuals in achieving educational goals. The on the other hand, are a good example—even if not
impossibility to unequivocally attribute success—or exhaustive—of the numerous ideas of school circu-
failure—to clear and identifiable causes, would lead lating within society. These ideas can significantly
people to identify elements of individual conduct affect educational policy and practices, on a national
(e.g., will, specific flairs), or, at worst, of familiar and local level. These different visions lead to con-
behaviour (“with that family, he can’t get far!”). flicting and incompatible conclusions also concern-
Teachers instead seem to turn to the gift theory for ing the problem of the actual democratization of
different reasons, as far as they have a specific experi- educational action. As already mentioned, among
ence of learning processes. They use this argument in the more diffused representations, a naïve vision of
defense of their own professional identity. school certainly exists, which overestimates positive
The teacher’s profession is actually directed effects making unclear the latent socio-economic
toward mass alphabetization and education of variables. This perspective considers school a path-
future citizens, despite challenges related to socio- way to individual and social redemption without
economic and cultural origin. In everyday life, he manifest rifts. A sort of relationship between stu-
must instead cope with an obvious sequence of dents’ “will” and success in study is thus established.
failures. It does not frequently happen, as it can be This idea has been fully shared in both the scientific
argued, that students with low socio-economic ori- community and everyday discourses. It is however
gins totally recover the initial gap. Thus, teachers undeniable that education has actually improved
must cope with the rigidity and immobility of social life conditions of large populations.
reality much more than they would expect with
respect to their job. This dramatically questions Maintaining Status-Quo of Society
professional principles (especially for novice teach- Sociology and psychology have shown the less
ers and those worn out by difficult experiences), simplistic and reassuring side of the functioning

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 835


of educational institutions. Even before psychol- and informal relationships (Daniels, 1995, 2004;
ogy of education stressed the social and contextual Fele & Paoletti, 2003). In this context, different
dimension of learning and failure (Daniels, 2012; types of communicative interactions are regulatory
Perret-Clermont, 1979; Carugati & Selleri, 2005), elements par excellence. They define and maintain
sociology already described a school slightly differ- order—not necessarily that expected by the institu-
ing from common sense’s idealized and stereotyped tion—but also to foster potential change in social
image. Pierre Bourdieu and Jean-Claude Passeron organization. Communicative interactions—as
(1970) shook school’s traditional image. School is argued by contemporary communication theories—
not just a place in which knowledge is transmit- just marginally correspond to the typical metaphor
ted, but also a context in which social inequalities of information transmission. Communicating is,
are reproduced. According to these French schol- first of all, to share meaning and to establish a com-
ars, the fundamental element of social distinction mon ground in order to cooperate or to conflict, to
concerns a sort of circularity of socio-economic establish social borders between two or more indi-
characteristics. Inequalities in parents’ economic viduals. From this point of view, language can be
and cultural resources and the different place they actually considered an activity that is not limited to
occupy in social division of labor originate nurs- information transmission. Power relationships, per-
ing practices and interaction modalities that will sonal and professional identities, etc. are equally at
provide children a sort of educational legacy with stake. Language plays a crucial role in classroom life.
which they participate to the educational experi- Because of its malleability and sensitivity to the con-
ences. These instruments will vary according to the texts of use—especially social and professional—it
social and economic context of origin. Without is often indicated as the key factor to account for
generalizing, these differences will “tend” to fos- disadvantage and socio-economic differences. From
ter students’ behaviors and learning styles that do this starting point, pioneering sociolinguistics study
not always fit with the aims and activities of school. the relationship between social belonging and lin-
This will inevitably leads students to different forms guistic competence. Basil Bernstein’s approach
of integration and assessment outcomes related to (1971) to socio-linguistic disadvantage is one of the
their “suitability” with respect to the educational best-known and most-criticized ones. He attempts
context’s features. The following step can be easily to analyze the mechanisms of reproduction, mainte-
argued: a not very brilliant student will probably be nance, and change of social order through language
directed toward vocational training and will have and symbolic systems used in families and schools.
more limited access to job markets. It is understood Bernstein’s fundamental point is that language and
that these forms of social distinction do not deal symbolic systems in the family can dramatically
very much with the actual potentialities of students. diverge from those in the school. He believes that
The educational context, in this type of analysis, is every social context establishes which meaning
considered as a filter definitely based upon psycho- must be linguistically actualized, also determining
social characteristics of students that are, more or which syntactic and lexical choice can be made.
less implicitly, directed to predetermined careers. Individuals trained in specific contexts find them-
Through these clear remarks, sociological analysis selves in a brand new situation at school—from the
provides valuable elements to fully clarify the educa- sociolinguistic point of view—probably facing dif-
tional institutions’ role—beyond proclamations and ficulties of adaptation affecting performance. This
theoretical goals—in “validating” socio-economic can trigger a process of marginalization or even
differences. However, on this level of analysis, socio- exclusion by the institution. Although Bernstein’s
logical perspective runs the risk of providing a fatal- ideas remarkably contributed to the debate about
istic and unmodifiable picture, if not supplemented the role played by so-called socio-linguistic codes in
by further analysis of real social dynamics taking integrating students into classroom social life and
place in educational contexts. discourses, they present several critical aspects. The
Actually, there is a potential margin of action also socio-linguistic code’s idea itself has been widely
on the level of classroom activities. Preliminarily, it is criticized because it is difficult to be defined and
worthwhile to observe that every form of social dis- operationalized. Actually, research demonstrated
tinction has correspondence in students’ communi- inadequacy of some aspects of Bernstein’s theory.
cative interactions. As a matter of fact, the classroom For instance, the relationship between socio-lin-
actually is a social system supported by both formal guistic codes and abstract references has been widely

836 th e work o f scho o li ng


falsified. Dialects—widely used by lower classes— For this reason they can seem like “proof ” against
against Bernstein’s expectations, are very elaborate change. Rather, in presence of a threat to profes-
at the linguistic level and fully usable in describing sional situations—like those challenging teachers
and manipulating abstract meanings. After obser- on the level of social reputation and salary—these
vation studies in the classroom (Edwards, 1990), elements can get even more radical.
findings demonstrate that the problem of commu- If teachers’ system of representations is the
nicative disadvantage—and probably other forms first element to be taken into account when plan-
of marginalization—is not related to the availability ning effective educational strategies, the second
of socio-linguistic codes, rather to the acceptance of element should necessarily concern teachers’ and
a new system of rules—also linguistic ones—char- students’ “perception” of classroom social life. It is
acterizing classroom context and diverging, some- quite clear, on this point, that the different socio-
times dramatically, from everyday life. economic origins are easily perceivable in the class-
Focus thus shifts from the idea of inadequate room. Despite schools’ attempts to minimize the
socio-linguistic competence to the idea—much display of socio-economic differences, all the actors
more complex and probably able to account for of the learning community are in some way aware
many forms of disadvantage—of specificity in of the distribution of economic and social resources
processes of meaning attribution to activity. As among peers. Beyond external cues, linguistic marks
Iannaccone (2010) reports, if cognitive activity can- and interaction styles in the classroom constantly
not be separated by the meaning that individuals recall students’ social and cultural origins. Besides,
attribute to situations in which they act, it is con- in the case of immigrant children, these indicators
vincing that some students’ marginalization and are further emphasized by the cultural framework
exclusion processes are rather triggered by how they they refer to in everyday rituals and relating to the
interpret learning situations and the social system educational system. Social psychology has clearly
below. demonstrated that perceptive availability of such
similarities and differences generates social categori-
Some “Practical” Implications zation. Groups of students will then be formed with
Planning every educational activity in this respect to these social indicators. Even the groups’
specific area of interest starts from a preliminary “entry rituals” will be based on the ability of the sin-
remark: evaluating the impact of students’ socio- gle student to show behaviors and lifestyles fulfilling
economic origin on class life and analyzing how it a group’s expectations. Thus, it is useful for teachers
is perceived by the different actors of the learning to monitor spontaneous social groups’ architecture
community. in the classroom. It can be useful to recall Sherif and
A first important element is the so-called teach- Sherif ’s experiment (1953, 1961)—veritable mile-
ers’ folk psychology (Bruner, 1996). Bruner’s state- stones of social psychology—clearly showing how it
ment makes clear, beyond any doubt, how much is possible to act upon group dynamics, establishing
educational and professional activity is directed by conditions for competitive and cooperative climates
adults’ representations, namely by teachers. If some to emerge. Although this experiment is just one of
of these systems of believes can hide the effects of numerous possibilities to tune group climate, at the
socio-economic differences or tend to transfer the same time it represents a clear example of group
problem through individualistic and de-contextual- management in education. It also makes clear how
ized explanations, it is quite evident that educational negatively emphasizing class differences is always a
acting will be ineffective, despite the best intentions. problem that must not be underestimated. Conflict
In order to actually cope with potentially negative is a “natural” modality human beings use also to
effects of socio-economic differences in the class- assert their identity. The “negative” radicalization of
room, it is required to start by fostering teachers to social fabric can make this process extremely dan-
become aware of the real problem, causes, and con- gerous and able to interfere with every educational
sequences. Teachers’ systems of representations play initiative, if not bearing in mind its nature.
a fundamental role in constructing and reinforcing It is quite evident that an in-depth knowledge of
teachers’ professional identities (Iannaccone, Tateo, the wider social phenomena such as in-group/out-
Mollo, & Marsico, 2008). They are “constituent” group processes or socio-economic characteristics of
elements of what can be defined as the teacher’s individuals is absolutely essential. These dimensions
Educational Self (Iannaccone & Marsico, 2007). regulate everyday life in different social contexts in

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 837


which the actors are involved. They are reflected temporary shared space (functional, not structural,
in the work of schooling, showing a clear overlap balcony) that is a prominent extension of the insti-
between inside and outside the school. tutional wall. It can be assumed that school, in this
way, intends to promote a satisfactory home-school
What Happens on the Balcony: Looking at interaction, that is, surely, an essential component
Crossing Boundaries of effective education (Huntsinger & Jose, 2009;
As we have argued in the previous pages, a number Henderson & Berla, 1994). The reason for this
of elements belonging to the wider social and cultural occurring in a specific space and time, decided by
contexts are not alien to the way the school works the school, is a different question. What would
in practice; on the contrary they act as catalyzers, happen if the school communicated the child’s
providing contextual support, which leads to certain evaluation by formal letter, e-mail, press release on
form of schooling rather than others. These sociocul- local TV, or via the Internet (allowing, in such a
tural dimensions (socio-economic levels, ingenuous way, the comparison of student’s performances all
or expert theories on education, the school’s repre- over the world)?
sentations, etc.) pass metaphorically through the bal- If school intends to support parents’ involvement
cony and enter the territory of the school. in children’s education and fruitful family-school
Studying what happens on the border between relationships, why not organising meetings with
inside and outside the school means first paying parents at home? What would parent-teacher meet-
attention to the intersections it has with other life ings be like at home? After all, this is not uncom-
contexts relevant to the development and educa- mon for other professionals like doctors or social
tion, first and foremost the family. The relevance workers. Why not for teachers? How would teachers
of “crossing boundaries” and of intercontextual be received at home? Which forms of social interac-
dynamics between family and school are presented tion would take place and with what effect on the
in this section. relationship between the teacher, parents, and child?
The crossing boundaries phenomenon (Marsico, Would teachers keep the same institutional function
Komatsu, & Iannaccone, in press) became evident even in a different social structure?
when we consider the contact’s points with school School instead decides to invite parents, emu-
and family. In fact, it is possible to consider bound- lating a certain kind of informality. This informal-
ary encounters, such as meetings and conversa- ity, however, is only partial (a formal informality).
tions, and events that provide connections between Encounters are placed into an official context,
systems. That was precisely the focus of a research organized according to specific institutional rules.
project carried out by the present authors that tried Even though it is a balcony, a border zone, it is
to describe what happens when the family goes to still the school’s balcony, that parents can enter
the school to receive the evaluation of their child tip-toeing, feeling uneasy, or on the contrary with
during the school-family meetings3 (Iannaccone & confidence, arrogance, and self-assurance. What
Marsico, 2007). social rules, instead, would modulate the school-
The aim of this research was to explore the social family encounters if they happened in an infor-
space emerging from the interaction between fam- mal place such as the bar on the corner where
ily and school. In the situations under examination, parents and teacher, drinking a coffee and discuss-
we try to understand how school culture comes into ing the child’s school performance (an informal
contact with family culture via a dynamic of delimi- formality)? The articulation between “formality/
tation of competences over the key issue of chil- informality” and “openness/closedness” is also evi-
dren’s education. At this level of analysis, we were dent in another school event that occurs at the end
particularly interested in the interactional activities of the school year, when students’ assessments are
and in the conversational strategies that schools put up on the wall of the school’s entrance-hall.
and families adopt during the “school report cards It is an open space, but institutionally character-
delivery” event. This kind of encounter, as in any ized, yet another of the school’s border zones. Why
social space, causes an adjustment between the par- are some ways of communicating adopted, while
ticipants, who will eventually converge or diverge in others are avoided or judged not admissible? What
their evaluation of the child. Metaphorically speak- are the effects on school-family communication
ing, meetings take place just on the balcony. School and on social regulation of meetings? Although
invites family into its own “territory,” creating a we are aware of the several possible alternatives to

838 th e work o f scho o li ng


communicate, in the study hereafter presented, we First of all, during the meeting two or more
focus on a particular point of intersection between adults, both of whom are responsible in different
family and school. ways for a child’s education, are compared, together
with their different perspectives on education that
The Family Goes to School somehow compete for the privilege of “having their
The school and family cultures, in the meeting sit- say” about a human being at a critical stage of his/
uation constituted by the presentation of the school her life. In this one-to-one match, the school should
report, will necessarily have to come into contact in represent a public institution and as such it is a sort
a micro-systemic space. If in daily life family and of an “official voice.” The family, in the least prob-
school communicate almost exclusively via the child/ lematic cases, will spontaneously agree with this rep-
pupil, in this case the meeting is face-to-face, and the resentation; in the most difficult cases (for instance,
respective representations of the child/pupil enter when the child does not embody the good student
into direct contact in a conversational space. From an prototype and his/her parents accuse the teachers of
ecological and cultural viewpoint, we could say that being the main reason for this), it will defend its
the “report delivery” event represents an occasion in own conflicting positions.
which the family micro-system and the school micro- The idea of the school’s “official voice” is certainly
system meet/clash, highlighting the meso-systemic an unsuitable generalization of concrete observed
connections (both the successful and fruitful ones conversational dynamics. Indeed, teachers follow
and the unsuccessful or fruitless ones) between two an enormous variety of educational models, which
life contexts of key importance in one’s upbringing are only partially in line with syllabus indications
(Bronfenbrenner, 1979). During this appointment, and social, cultural, and scientific expectations. As
two cultural worlds come into contact, each one with studies on professional identities and sociocultural
its specific sets of beliefs and organization, specific dimensions in working organizations have clearly
social climates and viewpoints (which can sometimes highlighted, what the teacher does is the result of
differ greatly, such as on the educational processes, a process of adaptation with unforeseeable out-
the child/pupil’s growth and the management of the comes (Iannaccone et al., 2008). What makes this
adult-child relationship). The school-family meeting process difficult to foresee is the co-participation of
is thus a critical event, not only for the reasons men- elements of the teachers’ human and professional
tioned above, but also for the meanings it acquires biographies with the sociocultural conditions of the
in the experience of the actors involved. Suffice it to working contexts. From a more strictly scientific
consider how the school’s evaluation of their child viewpoint, this plurality of “voices” is identified as
may be perceived by the parents as an evaluation of the expression of the various social representations
their own educational skills, or how the process of the co-existing in professional contexts as in any other
definition of a pupil’s identity is strictly connected social context. This obviously increases the com-
with his/her school experience, and the value that plexity of defining the “success/failure at school”
school success or failure acquires in relation to a posi- (Monteil, 1989) category when the issue at stake is
tive or negative definition of the Self (as discussed in the outcome of a school-family meeting.
the next pages). In the school context, with its institutionally
In the school-family meeting, the main con- “ratified” rules, the definitions of “good pupil” and
versational topic should be, at least in theory, the “bad pupil” will in any case be placed within specific
student. Again in theory, teachers meet parents to traditions (in this school, children have always stud-
present them the results of their child’s learning in ied hard and obtained good results when they went
school. The meeting may end (as it sometimes does) on to high school), specific conducts, and adjust-
with a few laconic exchanges from which the parents ments. Although “modulated” by their belonging to
are supposed to grasp all the necessary information the institutions, the categories of people involved in
to understand whether their children are “good” or the issue of success at school represent the result of
“bad” students. The few laconic exchanges should a complex social process, influenced by a number of
also allow parents to “justify,” when required, their key elements (Ligorio & Pontecorvo, 2010).
children’s inadequacies at school. What really hap- On a broader level of analysis, when looking at
pens, albeit within a relatively short time span, a school’s organizational features and cultural tradi-
is much more complicated than it may seem tions, some elements contributing to the students’
(Iannaccone & Marsico, 2007). success/failure can be identified. Every school, as a

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 839


social and cultural context, is a space where repre- the family’s perceptions of the school’s success/fail-
sentations are elaborated. It could be considered as ure and the family’s socio-economic origins.
a social place in which different actors, with differ-
ent roles and different life experiences, live together, Types of Interactions, Family’s
albeit often unwillingly. As in any other community, Socio-Economic Status, and
also at school these actors produce shared narratives, School Results
use gossip to maintain the social order, give credit to Using an ethnographic approach, several meet-
various “legends” about what apparently happened ings between family and school were observed and
at that school in the past, about its pupils’ (posi- audio/video-recorded. More precisely, 22 fami-
tively or negatively) sealed fate, about this or that lies were involved (and 26 pupils, since some of
teacher being good or bad. In other words, a school the families observed had more than one child at
is also a set of narratives (Bruner, 1996) that in turn the school). To conduct this study, the parents,
generate expectations and modulate the behavior of with their child, went to school by appointment
the actors who carry out their daily activities there. to meet the teacher who presented them with the
Teachers themselves have specific representations of child’s school report. The meeting was also attended
their work in the different school contexts. Families (though at this time on a basically “nonparticipat-
also often choose the school for their child accord- ing” role) by a researcher, who audio-taped and took
ing to its potential to fulfill their expectations about note of any potentially significant events occurring
what the child is capable of and what, in their opin- during the specific meeting. Besides the record-
ion, he/she should do when he/she “grows up.” This ing of meetings between family members and the
crossfire of teachers’ professional identities and par- teacher in charge of presenting the report card,
ents’ representations of success heavily contributes the research comprised a second phase, featuring a
to creating very different expectations concerning semi-structured interview. The interview’s general
schools. This will influence, and not negligibly, the aim is to analyze the voice of the family immediately
students’ success/failure parameters and the nature after the report card delivery ritual. What is the par-
of their education. In this way, school as a social, ents’ evaluation of their child’s school report? Was it
complex context will represent a significant frame- what they expected? And what do they hold respon-
work for a punctual definition of the notion of aca- sible for success in school? And for failure? And, in
demic success/failure. For instance, when a teacher turn, what explanations can the child/pupil provide
defines his/her students as a “bad” or a “good” class, for the marks received? The interview, which was
he/she is probably using a Lewinian-type category. entirely filmed, was conducted by a researcher who
Besides, how could he/she otherwise say that, on had a conversation with the family.
a given day or moment of the school year, his/her The analysis of the transcripts and the field notes
class seems particularly “bright” or extraordinarily show three main modalities of interactional activi-
“dull”? By adopting Lewin’s notion of group, every ties. We will see that these activities are related to
student in his/her daily class life, beyond his/her family’s socio-economic level and to the student’s
individual distinctive features (which no psychol- school results. In fact, during the first analysis of
ogy would completely deny), is also an element the school-family meetings, in 42.3% of cases the
of some more complex interdependence. To use management of the meeting involved parents and
a metaphor frequently employed by cultural psy- teachers converging toward consensual modalities
chologists, we could consider him/her “a thread in (alliances). However, in 34.6% of cases, the family
a complex weft.” Being “interwoven” with the other seems to comply with the image of the pupil pro-
actors in the educational context, he/she necessar- posed by the teacher (acquiescences). Finally, conflicts,
ily lives inside a sort of social polyphony, where the in a more or less latent way, affected 23.1% of the
sense of his/her acting will depend on the interac- meetings (oppositions). By comparing the frequency
tions between his/her individuality and the social of these modalities with the socio-economic level of
contexts in which he/she experiences his/her daily the family, we obtain an interesting result. Alliances,
interactions. The research focuses on the articula- for instance, were never observed during meetings
tion between the participants’ representations and with families of low socio-economic level. They
interactional activities. This methodological choice did, however appear in 50% of all meetings with
allowed us to explain several consistencies between medium-level families and in the 60% of families
school/family meeting management (by parents), with a high socio-economic level. In a similar way,

840 th e work o f scho o li ng


opposition was more frequent for the higher socio- percentage of the students with good results at school
economic levels (from the 17% of low-level fami- comes from medium and high socio-economic lev-
lies to the 30% of high-level families). Conversely, els (60%,). Conversely, the percentage of failures is
the interaction modalities of acquiescence are very higher among students of a low socio-economic level
frequent on a low socio-economic level (83%) and (about 83%). Taking into account the broader cate-
are almost negligible at high levels. It would seem gory of “troubled experiences at school” (that include
reasonable to explain these differences with at least every type of socio-relational and cognitive deficit),
two types of factors. The first factor could be related this relationship is even more pronounced. All the
to a type of “cultural capital” (Bourdieu & Passeron, students from families with a low socio-economic
1970). Considering that high socio-economic lev- level have some kind of trouble at school, compared
els generally correspond to a thicker and better- with half of the students from medium-level families
constructed educational experience, it is possible and the 60% of students from high-level families.
that the medium- and high-level families feel more
“akin” to the school discourse and are better able
Opposition, Alliance, and Acquiescence in
to cope with the teachers. These families are more
the Family-School Interactions
familiar with the typical communication tools of the
The following are some examples of meetings
school context, and they have a greater proximity to
between families and the teacher, who was appointed
the sociocultural origin of the teachers. The second
by the class board to deliver the school report; the
factor that could explain the different modalities of
examples concern three kinds of interaction events:
meeting management is related to a sort of self-per-
opposition, alliance, and acquiescence.
ception of the social asymmetry in that relationship.
Acquiescence, a passive relationship modality, indi- In particular, the meetings developed in the
cates a clear acceptance of the teachers’ comments form of oppositions, alliances, and acquiescences
by the families of a lower socio-economic level. depending on the goals’ orientation. In other
Predictably, the dynamics of school-family words, this kind of encounter assumes different
meetings is also related to the student’s success/ social configurations depending on the conver-
failure. In particular, the alliance is more typical of gent or divergent participants’ evaluation of the
the discussions about successful situations (75%). student’s result’s. When school and family agreed
Acquiescence, on the other hand, is more frequent on the child’s evaluation, they easily shared view-
during the discussion of students’ failures (57%). points. On the contrary, when the academic assess-
Typically, a “good” student facilitates the agreement ment represented, for instance, a threat to the
of the evaluation between the family and the school. educational choices that a specific family considered
Instead, a problematic student could be the “stake” of necessary, more dynamic and conflictual commu-
conflictual dynamics (29%), or alternatively (and this nications emerged. Therefore, the divergent goals’
is the more frequent case) of forms of passive accepta- orientation, mainly observed in the opposition in
tion of the evaluation (57%) by the parents. In fact, family-school interaction, stressed the communi-
opposition and acquiescence, taking into account cation breakdown between teachers and parents
the data mentioned above, seem to be the modali- and allowed us to understand the details of such
ties used to cope with the student’s failure related to events and the arguments evoked by participants
the socio-economic origin of the family. In this sense, with respect to, for example, how the problem is
since failure goes along with oppositional and acqui- presented, who is responsible for it, what has to be
escent forms of interaction, it is probable that the done in order to solve it and by whom.
different frequency of these modalities can be traced
back to the social level of the families. In particular, Opposition
we saw that opposition and acquiescence tend to be Meeting #1
respectively associated with medium-high and low Participants: Teacher, Father, (boy) Pupil
socio-economic levels. To better contextualize the The school-family meeting involved the teacher,
discourse, it is appropriate to clarify the relationship, the 13-year-old student (attending the third year of
which is also reported in literature (Schizzerotto, Italian middle school4) and his 46-year-old father,
1988; Ballarino & Cecchi, 2006), between the aca- an employee in a private company.
demic performance of students and the socio-eco- The student’s family is made up of his father,
nomic level of their families. Actually, the highest mother, and an elder (18-year-old) sister.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 841


The student’s school performance, according to does not exactly fit “our orientation” (the teach-
his teachers, is just around the pass mark, and he is ers’ ideas). The teacher’s opening approach and his
weak in technical subjects. The teacher thinks that choice of points to highlight primarily result from
the student needs to concentrate better and that his general opinion that the student is distracted
his parents should monitor him more closely. His by his after-school sports activities. In this open-
father seems to take this statement as a criticism and ing part, the father seems to accept the teacher’s
answers back, stating that, in order to grow up well, explanations.
a person needs to have the time “to do everything” In a subsequent phase, which constitutes a turn-
(e.g., school, fun, sports, etc.) and that school must ing point in the conversation, the teacher, while
guarantee students the chance to express their trying to identify the reasons for the student’s
potential in many different fields. bad performance in certain subjects, specifically
In the opening part of the conversation, the addresses his family (I think there is also a problem
teacher highlights the boy’s weakness in techni- with being regularly followed at home). The con-
cal subjects, which he considers a “serious thing,” versation’s main topic then becomes that of time
with a generally positive attitude. At the same management: from the time management of class
time, he underlines (confirming his implicit activities, the conversation, partly because of the
“opinion” of the student) how his physical edu- parent’s reply, will gradually move on to time man-
cation performance is “good,” while his behavior agement in the boy’s overall education.

Excerpt 1: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
11. TEACHER: so this is it, quite correct (.) in 11. DOCENTE: per cui rimane questo abbastanza
his interpersonal relationships (.) he is sociable and corretto (.) nei rapporti interpersonali (.) è socievole
cooperates with his classmates, takes an active part in e collabora con i compagni partecipa alla vita
school life (.) but he is not very constructive (2.0) I scolastica in modo attivo (.) ma poco costruttivo (2.0)
think here there is a problem=with=being=regularly credo che qui ci sia il problema=di=una =verifica
followed also at home and (1.0) I mean here continua anche a casa e (1.0) cioè qui vogliamo dire
we basically mean that he (.) when he organizes praticamente che lui (.) quando organizza deve meglio
himself he must use his time better (.) and he spendere i tempi (.) e deve=vedere=come=deve=fare
must=learn=how=he must=do it because> [...]
[...] 12. PADRE: alla conclusione ci vogliono dei
12. FATHER: to the end there are time limits::: tempi:::
13. TEACHER: that is not all (.) there are 13. DOCENTE: non solo questo (.) tantissime
many other things (.) for example it is important to altre cose (.) per esempio non affidarsi alla memoria
not merely count on one’s memory but to try and cercare di capire e cercare di:::
understand and try and ::: 14. PADRE: >attivare un processo logico di
14. FATHER: >activate a logical reasoning ragionamento<
process< 15. DOCENTE: cercare sempre di elargire la
15. TEACHER: always try to provide an spiegazione (.) mettere da parte i dubbi (.) e chiedere
explanation (.) dispel all doubts (.) and ask the teacher all’insegnante affinché (.) vengano eliminate certe (.)
in order to (.) eliminate some (.) situations=to=be situazioni=per=poter=poi=non=accumulare
able=then=to avoid=continually=slowing down=the =ritardi=nel processo di apprendimento (.) che qua
learning process (.) that here we can say is on diciamo che è regolare (1.5) gli obiettivi didattici
track (1.5) the teaching objectives set have been programmati sono stati raggiunti in modo parziale
partially reached (1.0) he attended the extra maths (1.0) ha partecipato al corso di recupero di matematica
course (.) and passed it and=this=is certainly (.) con sufficiente risultato e=questo=qua sicuramente
a=positive=fact=because (.) before this extra course è un=fatto=positivo=perché (.) prima di questo corso
he::: didn’t have this current passion for studying di recupero lui::: non aveva ancora questa affezione a
maths too (.) now he seems to be::: studiare pure la matematica (.) pare che adesso stia:::

842 th e work o f scho o li ng


Starting from turn #16, the father adopts a true intergenerational differences (“and this is let’s say a
defensive strategy, using a defensive argument first, problem with I think 99% of young people today”).
and then a second, more generic one, showing a spe- The father, by using specific and detailed arguments,
cific concept of education that differs from that of contrasts his way of educating his son (based on trust
the school. This is the moment in which the clash and respect for his autonomy) with the aims of the
between school and family culture first becomes school. This is a good example of what we intend as
evident. At turn #18, the father also refers to opposition.

Excerpt 2: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
16. FATHER: >I if I must< (.) express a global 16. PADRE: >io se devo< (.) esprimere un giudizio
opinion=we=at=home=do follow him we have (1.0) globale=noi=in=casa=lo seguiamo abbiamo (1.0) le
the difficulties I think all parents have (.) these days (.) difficoltà che secondo me hanno tutti i genitori (.) nel
because this is nor[mal] tempo moderno (.) perché è un fatto nor[male]
17. TEACHER: [yes] 17. DOCENTE: [sì]
18. FATHER: >the thing that< (3.0) as a parent I 18. PADRE: >quello che< (3.0) io come genitore
must say the truth not that I justify my son’s attitude devo dire la verità non è che giustifico l’atteggiamento
on the contrary I am very critical when he doesn’t di mio figlio anzi sono estremamente critico nel
apply himself< and this is let’s say a problem with I momento in cui lui non si applica< e questo diciamo
think 99% of young people today (.) with whom we che è un difetto penso del 99% dei ragazzi di oggi
have contact (.) I told him that in my opinion to be (.) con i quali noi abbiamo contatti (.) io a lui gli
complete one must find the time to do everything ho detto che secondo me una persona per essere
(.) he must find the time to study (.) time to have completa deve trovare tempo per fare tutto (.)
fun (.) because if not if a boy were focused only on deve trovare tempo per studiare (.) tempo per il
one thing (.) I mean studying (.) he would also have divertimento (.) perché altrimenti se un ragazzo
limits (.) I think he has also [some potential] fosse solo monotematico (.) cioè verso lo studio (.)
19. TEACHER: [potential yes] avrebbe anche dei limiti (.) io credo che lui abbia
20. FATHER: speaking as a parent I’ll tell you anche [delle potenz]
this (.) in my opinion if I notice (1.0) well (.) >maybe 19. DOCENTE: [potenzialità sì]
sometimes today as school doesn’t exist anymore< 20. PADRE: detto da genitore vi dico questo (.)
(.) that is when we used to go to school school was secondo me se io noto (1.0) ecco (.) >forse delle volte
something positive (.) back then either you did it or oggi siccome non esiste più la scuola< (.) cioè quando
you did it and that was it (.) today I think everybody noi andavamo a scuola c’era una scuola in positivo
has great potential (.) but >we must have the ability (.) allora tu o lo facevi o lo facevi basta (.) oggi
to let them express it< secondo me hanno tutti delle grosse potenzialità (.)
21. TEACHER: this is another reason why there però >noi dobbiamo avere la capacità di fargliele
have to be time limits too (.) the time he has (.) that esprimere<
he spends at home (.) if he [only spends it playing 21. DOCENTE: per ciò ci vorranno anche dei
football] tempi (.) lui il tempo che ha (.) che spende a casa
22. FATHER: [I’ll tell you something] (.) se lo [spende solamente per il calcio]
23. TEACHER: there is a time for football (.) 22. PADRE: [io vi dico una cosa]
but it can’t be football all day so that the thing also 23. DOCENTE: si dà uno spazio per il calcio (.)
continues::: into the next day the match they’ve played ma non deve essere calcio tutta la giornata che poi
they talk about it again the following day and then it’s la cosa continua anche::: il giorno dopo la partita
basically all about the match (.) that once it’s started it che hanno fatto la raccontano anche il giorno dopo
goes on and on::: e praticamente diventa tutta una partita (.) che
comincia e si va avanti così:::

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 843


At turn #29, the teacher once again tries to where “you must always be active and operative.”
return to his theory that the boy is “too busy” with At turn #30, he identifies a possible solution in
his after-school activities. Once again, the father the democratization of the teacher-pupil relation-
opposes his specific view of the problem, referring ship, on which the “pleasure of studying” should
to his condition as a worker in the private sector, depend.

Excerpt 3: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
29. TEACHER: also because they are busy with 29. DOCENTE:anche perché sono presi da
so many other activities in the afternoon tante altre attività pomeridiane
30. FATHER: no Sir=not on this (.) I can assure 30. PADRE:professore no=no su questo (.) vi
you that I also said something else to him (.) you posso assicurare che io a lui ho detto anche un’altra
were talking about time management (.) I’m 46 now cosa (.) lei diceva la gestione del tempo (.) io oggi
and when I am out working (1.0) for my company ho 46 anni e quando vado a fare lavori (1.0) per la
(.) they teach time management I mean they tell me mia azienda a me (.) insegnano la gestione del tempo
there is time to do everything because I work in the cioè a me dicono c’è tempo per fare tutto perché io
private sector =they=make us=work=twenty=hours=a lavoro nel privato=ci=fanno=lavorare=venti=ore=
day (1.0) and they want us to be always (1.0) al giorno (1.0) e vogliono che noi siamo sempre
active and operative (.) the basic problem here in (1.0) attivi e operativi (.) il problema di base che c’è
my opinion is exchange (1.0) I mean you must have secondo me il confronto (1.0) cioè voi dovete avere
a more democratic exchange with the students un confronto un po’ più democratico coi ragazzi
meaning that basically the students must learn the nel senso che praticamente i ragazzi devono capire
pleasure of studying (.) this is the crucial thing il piacere di studiare (.) questa è la cosa fondamentale

From turn #37, the teacher’s words betray his the school in all this, I wonder”). This educational
personal view of the aims of the school. In his opin- vision, reminiscing about a sort of “withdrawal into
ion, parents’ requests for sports and music activi- tradition,” highlights another element of variability
ties would represent a real problem (“and where is in the school-family relationship.

Excerpt 4: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
37. TEACHER: it may not be your case but some 37. DOCENTE: non sarà il caso vostro però
parents::: come to tell us that afterwards they have to alcuni genitori::: vengono a dire che poi deve andare
go to the gym because they have scoliosis in palestra perché ha la scoliosi
38. FATHER: no=no, absolutely no way::: 38. PADRE: no=no, assolutamente non esiste:::
39. TEACHER: they must study music because 39. DOCENTE: deve fare musica perché piace la
they like music and where is the school in all this I musica e la scuola dico io quando viene e lasciano il
wonder and they leave it to the school to deal with the problema esclusivamente alla scuola
problem

Alliance school, her father, a 40-year-old bus driver, and her


Meeting #9 mother, a 37-year-old hairdresser. The student’s
Participants: Teacher (female), student (female), family is composed of the father, the mother, the
Father, Mother. student, a younger sister (age 9 years) and a younger
The participants are the teacher, the 11-year-old brother (age 8 years). During the meeting, the
female student attending the first year of middle teacher starts the discussion by presenting the new

844 th e work o f scho o li ng


report card, introduced by a recent school reform, below) seems to focus on the “transition” from
to the parents. In a second phase, the teacher deals primary school to the first year of middle school
with the positive assessment of the student’s per- and its effects on the pupil’s school experience. The
formance and her participation in class. The core school-family alliance appears to be another core
of the conversation (reported in the transcript element of the conversation.

Excerpt 4: Meeting #9
English translation: Italian original:
47. TEACHER: then:: let’s say she attended (.) 47. DOCENTE: quindi:: diciamo che lei ha
she applied herself (.) she understood that (.) the seguito (.) si è impegnata (.) ha capito che (.) le
situations (were) (.) well she realized quite quickly situazioni (erano) (.) ecco quello che ha capito
that things were different (.) that:: the approach was abbastanza rapidamente che le situazioni erano
different (.) that behavior was different (.) maybe diverse (.) che:: l’approccio era diverso (.) che il
because she has a family behind her (.) quite simply. comportamento era diverso (.) forse perché ha la
(.) that is I assume that are kids aged ten=eleven famiglia alle spalle (.) detto molto francamente.
years and (.) if they have a choice between (.) (.) cioè io parto dal presupposto che questi sono
playing and working (.) they prefer to play so ragazzi comunque di dieci=undici anni (.) e che
when>they don’t have (.) some constraints< that is fra (.) il gioco e il lavoro (.) preferiscono il gioco
the family on one side and the school on the other per cui nel momento in cui >non hanno (.) dei
side to guide them (.) it’s clear that they can easily paletti< cioè la famiglia da una parte e la scuola
[lose::] dall’altra che l’indirizzi (.) è chiaro che possono
tranquillamente [perdere::]
48. FATHER:[it’s she had this passage] 48. PADRE: º[ci sta’ che ha avuto questo passaggio]º
49. TEACHER: if we could (.) but how (.) 49. DOCENTE: se potessimo (.) ma come (.) se
if we could (.) have a walk (.) there’s the sense of potessimo (.) andare a fare una passeggiata (.) là c’è il
responsibility ok senso di responsabilità e va beh
50. MOTHER: but at this [age] 50. MADRE: ma a questa [età]
51. TEACHER: [there is not] 51. DOCENTE: [là non esiste]
52. MOTHER: [unfortunately there’s not] 52. MADRE: [purtroppo non esiste]
53. TEACHER:[there’s not] that’s why you need 53. DOCENTE:[non esiste] ecco perché ci
family and school (.) that is two entities leading vuole la famiglia e la scuola (.) cioè due entità che li
them and guiding them guidano e li indirizzano
54. MOTHER: definitely 54. MADRE: sicuramente
55. TEACHER: then they realize they can’t move 55. DOCENTE: per cui loro si rendono conto
just within such [constraints] che loro non possono muoversi se non all’interno
di quei [paletti]
56. MOTHER: [definitely] 56. MADRE: [sicuramente]
57. TEACHER: so when there’s a cooperation 57. DOCENTE: e quindi allora quando c’è
between school and family things (.) generally go questa sinergia tra scuola e famiglia le cose (.) in
58. MOTHER: go better genere vanno
59. TEACHER: go better (.) maybe let’s say go 58. MADRE: vanno meglio
better in the sense that to some extent: some problems 59. DOCENTE: vanno bene (.) forse diciamo
are overcome: and it is also clear that when they che vanno meglio nel senso che a un certo punto:
improve they can improve even more ((laughs)) well certi problemi si superano: e poi è chiaro che quando
I mean ((laughs)) and in this case she has done just vanno meglio poi possono andare anche meglio
that: demonstrated this situation (.) she applied herself ((ride)) cioè voglio dire ((ride)) e in questo caso lei ha:
(.) at the beginning she was quite uncertain (.) now dimostrato questa situazione (.) si è impegnata (.) i
she starts to chime in a bit too much raising her little primi tempi era abbastanza incerta (.) adesso comincia
finger (.) but anyway a intervenire un poco po’ troppo con quel ditino
alzato (.) ma comunque tutto sommato

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 845


Acquiescence The student’s family also includes a 45-year-old
Meeting #16 father, a blue-collar worker, and an older brother
Participants: Teacher (female), Student (female), (age 16 years). The teacher presents the assessment
Mother of the student whose marks are poor in a number of
The participants are the teacher, the 12-year-old subjects. The mother never replies to the presenta-
student attending the second year of middle school tion of the report card and the meeting ends in just
and her 40-year-old mother, who is unemployed. a few turns.

Excerpt 5: Meeting #16


English translation: Italian original:
1. TEACHER: well well >we already talked with 1. DOCENTE: va bene va ben >con la signora
you madam< so you already know the situation abbiamo già parlato< quindi già sa la situazione (.)
(.) eh::: (.) let’s give the marks in detail::: (.) let’s eh::: (.) diamo nel dettaglio i voti::: (.) diciamo::
say:: in short (.) in Italian she got a pass (.) the sintetici (.) in italiano ha avuto sufficiente (.) storia
same for history and geography however in the (.) e geografia lo stesso mentre invece nelle (.) altre::
other:: subjects foreign language that is English she discipline lingua straniera cioè inglese non °sufficiente°
has a °fail° (.) eh:: maths and science >science and (.) eh:: matematica e scienze >scienze e matematica<
maths< >chemistry=physics=natural sciences< fail (.) >scienze chimiche=fisiche=naturali< non sufficiente
technology fail (.) art pass (.) music good (.) physical (.) educazione tecnica non sufficiente (.) educazione
education good (.) religion pass >well these are the artistica sufficiente (.) educazione musicale buono (.)
marks or rather< she started to improve a little bit educazione fisica buono (.) religione sufficiente >va
well I::: let’s say I gave her (.) a pass in humanities but beh questi sono i risultati anzi< lei ha cominciato pure
she did the same as with the others <she didn’t study un poco a migliorare cioè io::: diciamo gli ho messo
enough> she did with me (.) that is she must pay (.) la sufficienza nelle materie letterarie ma lei come ha
more attention (.) and she must study more (.) so fatto con gli altri <che non ha studiato abbastanza>
eh:: let’s take a look at her behavior (.), she’s behaves lo ha fatto con me (.) lei cioè deve stare più attenta
well but she chats °too much° eh=eh (.) e deve stare deve studiare di più (.) quindi
eh:: vediamo il comportamento (.) è corretto però
chiacchiera °molto° eh=eh
2. MOTHER : [()] 2. MADRE: [()]
3. TEACHER : [she’s °too° distracted] 3. DOCENTE:[si distrae molto °si distrae
<with respect to interpersonal relationships she molto°] <nei rapporti interpersonali spesso collabora (.)
often collaborates (.) even though she’s not very anche se riservata> cioè partecipa (.) anche se diciamo
communicative> I mean she participates (.) although non=non=non si esprime diciamo così (.) chiacchiera
let’s say she doesn’t=doesn’t= doesn’t express herself però non (.) <però non è una ragazza che dice le sue
(.) she chats but not (.) <but she’s not a girl who talks cose:> non:: è un po’ chiusa (.) partecipa alla vita
about herself:> no:: she’s a bit introverted (.) she takes scolastica in modo attivo (.) a volte poco costruttivo (.)
an active part in school life (.) sometimes not very eh::: nell’organizzazione del lavoro ha bisogno molto
constructive (.) eh::: to organize the work she needs >a >molto bisogno di essere aiutata< (.) lei::(.) la vedo
lot of help< (.) she::(.) I often see she’s °very distracted° spesso °molto distratta° (.) adesso è il momento (.) che
(.) the time is now (.) she must apply herself (.) si deve impegnare (.) il processo di apprendimento
the learning process is not regular in all the subjects non è regolare in tutte le aree logicamente (.) >perché
of course (.) >because she has some fails< and the ha delle insufficienze< e gli obiettivi didattici (.) sono
learning objectives (.) have been only partially achieved stati raggiunti in modo parziale si:: giacché solo in parte
yes:: because only partially (.) she achieved (.) the (.) ha raggiunto (.) gli obiettivi sufficiente di sufficienza
objectives and got a pass she attended the additional ha frequentato i laboratori di (.) recupero di matematica
workshops (.) for maths (.) IT and pottery with good (.) di informatica e ceramica con buoni risultati >ai
results >you got good marks in the workshops<! laboratori hai avuto buoni risultati<! invece:::(.) chi lo
instead:::(.) who knows!(.) that’s the:: situation of::: sa!(.) questa è la:: situazione del::: >è si=si certo!< (.)
>is yes=yes of course!< (.) now she must apply (.) please adesso lei si deve impegnare (.) la faccio firmare (.) (.)
sign here(.) (.) yes:::now I’ve got to leave:: si:::io ora vi lascio::
4. MOTHER: yes! 4. MADRE: si!
5. TEACHER :so that:: 5. DOCENTE:cosi::

846 th e work o f scho o li ng


What is Actually at Stake in School-Family orientation (instrumental versus holistic-orienting
Meetings? vision of school).
At wider level of analysis, the delivery of the With respect to the first opposition, the clash
report cards represents a real “ritual,” as it has all between school and family cultures becomes evi-
the main features of this type of social interaction. dent when the parents refer to a multi-dimensional
The school-family meeting takes place, as we have educational vision in accordance with the idea that
seen, in an institutional place (the school) and at to be well-balanced, a person must do several expe-
a specific time (for example every 4 months), and riences (see the Excerpt 1: Meeting #1, turn #18).
the participants are individuals having specific roles This wide concept of education differs from the
(the teacher, the parents, the pupil/child), each mono-dimensional educational vision presented in
assigning, though within the same framework, a several teachers’ talks (as in the Excerpt 4: Meeting
particular symbolic meaning to the event. In such #1, turn #39) and circumscribed almost exclusively
encounters the actors stage all the complexity of to the school engagements.
interpersonal dynamics in an institutional context. The second type of opposition is between instru-
These are also meetings of different voices that tell mental versus holistic-orienting vision of school held
different points of view, modulated by specific sets by parents.
of beliefs, stemming from the experiences lived
by the actors. In many cases the child’s success or The Functional Dimension of
failure ends up representing the “stakes” in a con- the School
frontation between the family’s and the school’s One of the key points around which parents
differing educational views. Taking a particular organize their representations of school is what
perspective, inspired by economic dimensions, it is could be called the functional dimension, relating
possible to depict an intriguing economically ori- to the different purposes that families think the
ented picture of school-family meetings as a real educational experience should have. In this dimen-
space of negotiation between parents and teachers. sion, it is possible to identify a first basic type of
At this point the main research question could be: argumentation among those (and these are primar-
What is actually at stake in school-family meet- ily families with a lower socio-economic status) who
ings? First, the stake is the different representation consider school a relevant factor for social mobility
of “education” and “school” held by parents and (see Excerpt 6, below).
teachers. This difference can lead to a two types Participants: Father, Mother, Daughter,
of opposition. One is between school culture Researcher
and family culture, even if not necessarily in the The participants are the researcher, the 12 years
form of conflict (multi-dimensional versus mono- old female student attending the II year of middle
dimensional vision of the educational process). school, the father, 41 years old hydaulic, and the
The second one is within the families’ educational mother, 37 years old housewife.

Excerpt 6: Interview #16


English translation: Italian original:
54. FATHER: well:: (.) but:: (.) I think:: (.) 54. PADRE: va bè:: (.) ma:: (.) io penso che:: (.)
((laughs)) school is definitely everything (.) ((ride)) la scuola è tutto in effetti (.) oggi: (.) essere
nowadays: (.) to be educated in something (.) I think:: istruiti in qualche cosa (.) secondo me:: (.) è di obbligo
(.) it’s must (.) so:: better one (.) has more quality:: (.) (.) quindi::anzi uno (.) più ha qualità:: (.) su (.) un
on (.) a field (.) the more it goes:: (.) and the future (.) settore (.) più va avanti:: (.) e il futuro (.) in effetti:: (.)
really:: (.) it’s absolutely positive really [ . . . ] è del tutto positivo in effetti
[...]
57. MOTHER: in fact without school (.) 57. MADRE: in effetti senza scuola (.) senza
without anything (.) ((laughs)) we can’t do:: niente (.) ((ride)) non possiamo fa:: niente proprio
anything ((laughs)) ((ride))

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 847


These parents adopt an instrumental vision of comprehensive and progressive discovery of their
school; they believe that obtaining a degree will Self and adapting to the sociocultural context, by
make it easier to find a suitable job. They also means of an empathetic element that is distinctive
believe that education differentiates people and of the teacher-student relationship.
helps to position a person socially. The voice of Participants: Father, Mother, Daughter,
those parents who see school as essential to support- Researcher
ing their children’s growth is completely different. The participants are the researcher, the 11 years
They seem to refer to a holistic-orienting repre- old female student attending the I year of middle
sentation of school (see Excerpt 7, below), where school, the father, 52 years old doctor, and the
educating means accompanying pupils through a mother, 49 years old housewife.

Excerpt 7: Interview #2
English translation: Italian original:
43. MOTHER: surely it’s different from the school 43. MADRE: sicuramente è diversa dalle scuole
we went to (.) before they were (.) so strict (.) that we che abbiamo frequentato noi (.) prima c’era (.) una
were afraid of teachers (.) of the head teacher (.) when rigidità (.) tale per cui c’era il timore del professore
we went to school (.) if we studied it was because (.) del preside (.) quando si andava a scuola (.) se si
(1.5) there was this (.) now they’re more::: open (.) studiava era perché (1.5) c’era questo (.) adesso c’è
available (.) towards the children (.) to understand una maggiore::: apertura (.) disponibilità (.) nei
them and also their problems if there are any (1.5) riguardi dei ragazzi (.) a comprenderli anche verso
different from the school of the past (.) I can’t tell you i loro problemi se ci sono (1.5). diversa dalla scuola
if the old school (1.5) was better we should see it in precedente (.) non le so dire se era migliore (1.5)
time to see the results (.) now they seem to want to do quella precedente dovremmo vedere nel tempo ai
MANY things (1.5) too many things forgetting (1.5) fini dei risultati (.) adesso sembra che si vogliano fare
one’s point of view ((smiles)) tante TANTE cose (1.5) troppe cose perdendo (1.5) il
punto di vista ((sorride))

This holistic-orienting model of school may be by attributing school results to the child’s disposi-
easily related to the notion of the “parental func- tional aspects rather than contextual ones.
tion” as “taking charge” of one’s child as a whole Participants: Teacher, Father, (boy) Pupil
and following every aspect of his/her growth. This In Excerpt 8 (turn #7), the adult shows a clear
perception of school is similar in many ways to a attributional bias. In fact, parents and teachers seem
family group, and its functions are comparable with to overestimate the “internal” origin of school results
the educational functions of a family. (referring to personal characteristics and his effort
Those opposite views of the school’s function are in his studying), underestimating situational factors
part of the same perception shared by the common (like for example the school system’s organization,
sense. According to this, the school is a relevant fac- the curricula, the teaching methodology adopted, the
tor in promoting the development of each individ- family’s supporting role). Even in case of opposition
ual even when moving from a low socio-economic between family and school, adults converge anyway,
and sociocultural level. and form a strategic peace treaty by stressing the dis-
But the stake in school-family meetings is also positional and internal dimensions of the pupil.
the adults’ perception of the child. In this case it is In Excerpt 9 (turns #48 and #49) and Excerpt 10
possible to talk of an attributional bias (Ross, 1977; (turns #5 and #6), it is possible to see such conver-
Nisbett & Ross, 1980; Ross & Nisbett, 1991) (see gence between teachers and parents.
Excerpt 8) and an opposition between the adult’s Participants: Teacher, Father, (boy) Pupil
culture and the youth’s culture (as in Excerpt 9). Participants: Teacher, Pupil (female), Father
During the report card delivery event, the adult’s The meetings between families and school are an
culture keeps its distance from the youth’s culture, adjustment of the social positions at stake. In the

848 th e work o f scho o li ng


Excerpt 8: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
5. FATHER:((reading the report)) so (.) 5. PADRE: ((legge la scheda)) allora (.) Italiano
Italian pass (.) History and Civic Education pass (.) sufficiente (.) Storia e Educazione Civica sufficiente (.)
Geography pass (.) Foreign Language pass (.) Sciences Geografia sufficiente (.) Lingua Straniera sufficiente (.)
and Mathematics pass (.) Chemistry, Physics and Scienze e Matematica sufficiente (.) Scienze Chimiche
Natural Science pass (.) Design and Technology fail Fisiche Naturali sufficiente (.) Educazione Tecnica
(.) so (.) >this is a really serious<thing::: (.) >Art pass< non sufficiente (.) quindi (.) >qua ci sta proprio un
(.) Music pass (.) Physical education good (.) this I dato< grave::: (.) >Educazione Artistica sufficiente<
didn’t::: doubt (.) English pass (.) Religion pass, even (.) Educazione Musicale sufficiente (.) Educazione
Religion just a [pass] Fisica buono (.) questo non::: avevo dubbi (.) Inglese
sufficiente (.) Religione sufficiente, pure Religione
suffici[ente]
6. SON: [eh]! 6. FIGLIO:[eh]!
7. TEACHER: >let’s say it all defines < his 7. DOCENTE: >diciamo che denota un po’
character::: (.) (1.0) and these (these) (.) technical tutto< il carattere di::: (.) (1.0) e queste (queste)
things for example fail (2.0) we must try and::: (.) cose tecniche per esempio non sufficiente (2.0)
improve them because I also think it’s due (.) to a::: dobbiamo cercare di::: migliorarci perché credo che
behavioral thing I think sia anche dovuto (.) a un fatto di::: comportamento
penso

Excerpt 9: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
47. FATHER: I also want to say that from the 47. PADRE:voglio poi dire che dall’inizio
beginning of the course (.) to the end of the course del corso (.) alla fine del corso si sono (.) creati
some prejudices (.) basically developed (.) and when fondamentalmente dei preconcetti (.) e quando si
prejudices have developed teachers find it difficult to creano dei preconcetti gli insegnanti hanno difficoltà
overcome them (.) these things these are things I’m a scioglierli (.) queste cose sono cose che io vi dico da
telling you as a parent (as a parent) you know why? genitore (da genitore) sapete perché? perché conosco
because I know (.) the guy I know that teachers (.) (.) il pollo allora io so che gli insegnanti (.) alcune
sometimes (.9) because my son if you tell him off (.) volte (.9 perché mio figlio se lo sgridate (.) potete
even if you don’t touch him (.) he’ll be mortified for anche non toccarlo (.) lui rimane mortificato per un
some time he looks for affection::: periodo di tempo e lui va alla ricerca dell’affetto:::
48. TEACHER: [he’s sensitive] 48. DOCENTE:[è sensibile]
49. FATHER: [he’s sensitive] I’ve never seen him 49. PADRE: [è sensibile] io non lo mai visto (.)
(.) that superficially the thing=didn’t=affect=him when che con superficialità gli è passata=la=cosa=addosso lui
they criticized (.) him it’s always been with with::: quando gli hanno mosso (.) una critica è sempre stato
deeply struck con con::: sensibilmente colpito

opening part of each meeting there can be a more or processes of attribution of meaning operated by the
less explicit conflict between the two “educational cul- participants. The constant articulation between indi-
tures” or, conversely, an alliance. If the family accepts vidual points of view (sets of beliefs expressed by sin-
the school’s evaluation (which is very frequent, obvi- gle individuals) and representations emerging during
ously, in the case of positive evaluations), this does the conversational interactions is particularly inter-
not produce dynamic conversations: a conflict, of esting. The need to defend one’s position encourages
any form, contributes to clarifying the sophisticated the participants to seek “shared” arguments.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 849


Excerpt 10: Meeting #8
English translation: Italian original:
1. TEACHER: so then (.) ((reads the school report 1. DOCENTE: allora quindi (.) ((legge la scheda
card)) in Italian (.) pass mark (.) in history and civics di valutazione)) in italiano (.) sufficiente (.) in storia
pass mark (.) in geography good (.) foreign language e educazione civica sufficiente (.) in geografia buona
good (.) science maths pass mark (.) chemistry (.) la lingua straniera buono (.) scienze matematiche
physics pass mark (.) technics pass mark (.) arts è sufficiente (.) scienze chimiche fisiche e naturali
good (.) physical education good (.) music good (.) sufficiente (.) educazione tecnica sufficiente (.)
religion very good (.) >we talked about the girl at the educazione artistica buono (.) educazione fisica buono
beginning had a phase (.) educazione musicale buono (.) religione distinto (.)
>abbiamo già detto che la ragazza all’inizio ha avuto
una fase
2. FATHER: [she got some] 2. PADRE: [ha avuto un po’]
3. TEACHER:[now she’s recovering instead] (.) we 3. DOCENTE: [adesso invece si sta riprendendo]
hope that (.) that’s the evaluation global (.) noi questo ci auguriamo (.) questo è il giudizio
globale
4. FATHER: global 4. PADRE: globale
5. TEACHER: first the evaluation of behavior (.) 5. DOCENTE: prima il giudizio sul
she behaves correctly (.) collaborates with mates (.) comportamento (.) un comportamento corretto (.)
even if she’s a little bit reserved collabora con i compagni (.) anche se lei è riservata
6. FATHER: yes=yes closed 6. PADRE: sì=sì chiusa

School-Family Meetings as a or less complying with the model proposed by the


Negotiation Space family or by the school.
It’s worth underlying that adults’ culture (par- But the object rising or decreasing in value is
ents and teachers) opposes youths’ culture funda- also the school itself. For some parents, the school
mentally, with: rises in value if it trains the child for a job, and it
decreases in value if it does not provide the child
a) the denial of child’s role as partner in the
with technical competencies. Therefore, it is evi-
social interaction. In fact the meetings made the
dently an instrumental vision of the school. For
presence of the participating pupils insignificant.
some other parents, the school rises in value when
When “the family goes to school” to learn about
it forms the human being. It instead decreases in
its children’s evaluation, the situation becomes, in
value when it becomes instrumental, and provides
almost all cases, an “adult affair.” To the children,
superficial factual knowledge, without a general
who should actually be at the center of what is
framework of meaning.
happening, a minimum conversational space
In the opposition between adults’ and youths’
is given. During the meeting with families, the
cultures we noted that adults manipulate the dis-
predominant need is the comparison between two
positional element and de-value the context. They
educational cultures; and
emphasize the attributional bias to defend their iden-
b) the shirking of adults’ responsibilities
tity of adults interacting with children. Magnifying
through the overvaluation of pupil’s dispositional
the attribution bias could be, from the psycho-social
elements, and the undervaluation of the elements
point of view, a sort of defense, probably to protect
of the educational context, both within school and
their self-representation and the image of the fam-
outside school (family).
ily’s and school’s good functioning as constructed by
It is quite evident that the stake in school-family the parents and teachers. School evaluation ends up
meetings is the pupil’s value. How much is it worth? coinciding more with what child is rather than with
In the case of the opposition between the multi- what child knows.
dimensional and the mono-dimensional vision of The analysis of the school-family meetings shows
education, the child’s value depends on his more that the individual psychological dimension is of

850 th e work o f scho o li ng


value in explaining school success and failure. The of specific knowledge and skills, but we are more
knowledge of folk-psychological aspects, that is interested in how the work of schooling contributes
the child’s individual dimension, is manipulated, to the definition of the Self. Adopting a binocular
becoming a commodity, a stake. This causes a de- vision from the balcony on which we are, it is easy
valuation of contextual aspects, such as the school to observe that the Self is formed through a vari-
organization, the curricula, the teaching methodol- ety of experiences both inside and outside school.
ogy, the family’s supporting role, the students’ socio- Suffice it to consider the interrelationships and the
economic level and standard of living, the presence constant transitions among different social settings
of risk factors within the context, or, in Lewin’s in which each person is engaged (for example, fam-
(1951) words, the “force field” operating when a ily, peers, school, etc.). At same time, it is thus not
given behavior takes place. The dimensions taken exaggeration to say that the history of educational
into account outlined an intriguing economically experiences, as a part of life’s wider trajectory, plays
oriented picture of “school-family” meetings as a a crucial role in the construction of the Self (Bruner,
real negotiation space, underlining that what really 1996). Every educational institution is the expres-
happens on the border of these two educational sion of a given culture and will tend to transmit,
micro-systems, even if only on a relatively small bal- reproduce, and cultivate knowledge, beliefs, norms
cony, is much more complicated than it seems. of behavior, and even emotions on the basis of which
Of the many encounters between parents and students interpret the natural and social world. Even
teachers that take place in a short space of time, the the idea of Self, with its limits and characteristics, is
school report event, as we have seen, constitutes a typical of a given culture. School therefore contrib-
true boundary zone (Tuomi-Gröhn & Engeström, utes to the formation of the student’s Self in such
2003) between the territory of the school and that a way as to fit with the cultural requirements: for
of the family. In this contact situation, that could, example, the emphasis on the values of individuality
in some ways be defined “cultural” (Iannaccone & rather than affiliation, the role of agency and indi-
Marsico, 2007), a number of fundamental elements vidual effort rather than cooperation, etc. (Bruner,
of the symbolic-representative dimension gener- 1996). This is the starting point of the reflection
ated by the encounter between parents and teachers that led to the idea of Educational Self considered as
emerged. Along this boundary, a series of psycho- a specific dimension of the Self, a regulatory process
social processes take place that are the product of emerging from the experiencing of the I-Other rela-
the encounter and discursive exchange between par- tionship (Bakhtin, 1979/1986) in the educational
ents and teachers. These processes would seem to context (Iannaccone & Marsico, 2007).
be unpredictable a priori as they are connected to
the attribution of sense of the players involved in Defining Educational Self: Two Sides
the encounter. They appear to be interwoven with of the Same Coin
contextual factors (the type of school, the condition The idea of Educational Self involves two related
of success/failure, the disciplinary areas on which aspects: the construction of the Self during the
“critical” evaluations insist, etc.). In our research, as school age in the adults’ discourse and the emer-
in other works (Valsiner, 2007b), the boundaries, gence of the Self when an adult interacts within an
by acting as “membranes,” modulate and determine educational context (see Fig. 40.1).
the relationship between the parts of the system. The construction of the Educational Self (see Fig.
They make certain elements dynamic, inhibiting 40.1a) is basically a dialogical process, taking place
others. From this standpoint, school-family meet- during the school age and involving multiple voices
ings take on different configurations that led to the expressing different points of view, modulated
emergence of many of the psycho-social and contex- by specific sets of beliefs and actors’ experiences
tual dimensions involved. (Markova, 2006). Young people interact with adults,
experiencing a dialogical and contractual space
Behind the Balcony: What Happens in where the adults’ and peers’ voices provide different
the School? “as-if ” possibilities, contributing to define what a
The next step in our attempt to look at inside person could be in present and in future time. The
and outside school from the special location chosen student’s Self, somehow unclear, comes into contact
calls for a glance behind the balcony. Many things with adult “voices” and is asked to negotiate, reject,
take place in the school with respect to the learning or accept the different possible definition provided

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 851


a) construction of the Self during the school age
in the adults' discourse
Educational Self

b) emergence of the Self when


an adult experiences the educational context Figure 40.1 The two aspects of the
Educational Self

(Simao & Valsiner, 2007). Through the processes or of childhood) held by the actors (parents and
of active internalization and symbolic mediation teachers) and on the Educational Self as formed
described above, the child will construct his own through one’s own educational history. Teachers,
Educational Self and will activate it every time he for instance, reinterpret the educational models,
subsequently acts in an educational context. teaching styles, representations, and formal and
This is the second characteristic of the Educational informal norms, that they internalized in a contin-
Self, that is to become salient every time that the uous dialogue between the voices populating their
person is involved in an educational activity (see educational and professional Self (Iannaccone et al.,
Fig. 40.1b), for example during significant turning 2008; Ligorio & Tateo, 2008). In other words, past
points and life transitions such as higher educa- experiences as a student become a lens suitable for
tion or professional training activities. The school reading and interpreting all the present complexity
experiences then emerge, providing values, models of dynamics in the institutional context and also
of behavior, norms, symbolic repertoires, emotional for modulating the discourse, identity positioning,
experiences, knowledge and practices that are inter- and social behavior. Suffice it, for instance, to con-
nalized in the form of “voices” that will constitute sider how parents feel during the school report card
a capital of symbolic resources on which the indi- delivery event.
vidual will draw (Zittoun, 2006). The first dimension of the Educational Self per-
This theoretical idea could help to understand tains to the adults’ discourse about the child’s Self
how individuals learn to manage the cognitive, (see Fig. 40.2a). In the excerpts presented below, it is
emotional, and social dimensions with respect to possible to observe the role played by the definitions
the identity and the different Self positions when of the pupil’s Self provided by the parents and teach-
involved in educational activities (Hermans, 1996). ers, the discourses about the scholastic assessment
Even an elderly person would experience an impli- and the explications of the academic success/failure
cation of the Educational Self when enrolling for a stressed by adults and pupils and, finally, the process
university of the third-age course (Leibing, 2005). of “active internalization” of the adults’ feedback in
In other words, the Educational Self can be con- the definition of the Educational Self.
ceived as a process of sense making on the move, Afterward, we’ll discuss the second aspect of the
referring to the past but, at the same time, shed- Educational Self, pertaining to the reactivation of
ding light on the future development of Self (Linell, this dimension of the Self when the adult enters
2009). The voices of the educational context define the educational context. Some arguments evoked
the individual’s identity: what he/she is, is not, by participants during home-school encounters
should be and should not be, would be and would and interviews with parents realized after the report
not be (Valsiner, 2007a). card’s delivery, explain how the Educational Self is
A good example of the significant role played reactivated and used to make sense of what happens
by the Educational Self is provided just by the to the pupil at school through the polyphony of the
school-family meeting. In this encounter, as we voices of the Self related to the educational experi-
argued above, parents and teachers have to attri- ences in the adults’ discourse.
bute meaning to their child’s success or failure at
school, provide explanations, negotiate their view- Polyphonic Configurations: From
point with the other, adjust their vision of the child Opposition to Juxtaposition of Voices
with that provided by the school report card. This School-family meetings are highly meaning-
social sense-making process, that takes place in a ful events that involve perceptions, sense making
conversational space, is based on the educational and personal evaluations affecting the construc-
perspective (i.e., the representation of schooling tion of Self (Berger, 1995; Dazzani & Faria, 2009;

852 th e work o f scho o li ng


Polyphony of the adults’ discourse
From the evaluation of the school performance to the child personality
The child active internalization of the adult’s feedback

a) construction of the Self during the school age


in the adults’ discourse
Educational Self

b) emergence of the Self when


an adult experiences the educational context Figure 40.2 The construction of the child’s
Educational Self in the adult’s discourse

Huntsinger & Jose, 2009). The meetings are the The Voice of Youth
place where the teacher and parents’ representations The Excerpt 12 refers to the same family as
of the student are defined, made explicit, and mod- Excerpt 11. The discursive interaction between
ulated at a micro-genetic level (Marsico, Komatsu, father and son during the interview focuses on the
& Iannaccone, in press). During the meetings, the dimension of evaluation embedded in the process of
student’s Self—somewhat unclear and ill-defined— identity definition.
must come into contact with adults’ voices negotiat- The boy positively evaluates his less-than-excellent
ing, rejecting, or accepting the different positions. school results, showing that his self-esteem is not
This results in a very dynamic situation stressing the attached to the academic assessment (turn #10). The
fluid and dialogical nature of the Self-definition’s father’s statement (turn #15) produces a conversational
process. shift that determines a discursive overlap between the
The following excerpts of the family-school assessment of his son’s academic performance and that
meetings concern three types of dialogical events in of the person (“you’re worth so much?”).
which the voices of parents and teachers produce In this case, the Self is directly involved with
different polyphonic configurations: Opposition of the value that the boy attaches to himself. The pro-
voices (Excerpt 11), Different intonation of the voice cess of identity definition is ongoing, this clearly
(Excerpt 13), and Juxtaposition of voices (Excerpt makes it difficult for the boy to answer (turn #16:
14). Moreover, Excerpt 12 (The voice of youth) is, on “I don’t know how much I’m worth”). During the
the other hand, an example of an interview with a meeting, he must face the institutional voice of the
family that shows some relevant dimensions affect- school that defines his competence and his psycho-
ing the definition of the Self. social characteristics through the artifact, the school
report card. He must also face two other voices as
Opposition of Voices equally meaningful on a psychological level (parent
In Excerpt 11 we can observe an “opposition and teacher). They straightway express in the pres-
of voices” emerging during a meeting between ence of the child the opposite perceptions of his Self
teacher, student (a 13-year-old) and his father (mature versus immature) as shown in Excerpt 11.
(a 46-year-old). In this polyphony, the boy must mediate between
The school and the family voice different percep- what he thinks about himself and what the signifi-
tions of the child. For the school, the boy is shallow cant others think about him. In this case, it is pos-
and not very constructive. He should be kept an eye sible to talk about a polyphony of voices that define
on because he is not yet independent and respon- a dynamic and dialogical system of the Self under
sible. He is still immature and needs the control and construction.
guidance of adults (turn #11). For the family, the
boy is fairly independent. He can accomplish his Different Intonation of the Voice
assignments and can evaluate both himself and the Excerpt 13 shows the “different intonation of the
teachers. He is certainly mature and able to estab- voice” by the school and the family, attaching differ-
lish relationships based on trust rather than control ent connotations to some behaviors and psychologi-
(turns #24 and #42). cal characteristics of the child’s Self. The meeting

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 853


Excerpt 11: Meeting #1
English translation: Italian original:
11. TEACHER: in class=little constructive this 11. in classe=questo poco costruttivo è::: dovuto
is::: probably due to his (1.5) following lessons not probabilmente a (1.5) un attenzione in classe non
always (.) correctly (1.5) in organizing his work he sempre (.) corretta (1.5) nell’organizzazione del
is still a little uncertain lavoro manifesta ancora qualche incertezza
[...] [...]
24. FATHER: then I’ll (1.5) repeat it to you since 24. PADRE: io allora (1.5) vi ripeto siccome
we basically (.) established (.) both with my daughter praticamente noi abbiamo (.) impostato (.) sia con
and with him (.) a trust-based relationship (1.5) in mia figlia che con lui (.) un rapporto di fiducia
which I basically say I trust you (.) you’ve got to do (1.5) in cui praticamente dico io mi fido di te (.) tu
your things (.) I don’t even want to have to check devi fare le cose(.) io non voglio nenache venire a
on that every day (.) because I obviously check on it verificarle tutti i giorni (.) perché io chiaramente le
periodically verifico a step
[...] [...]
42. FATHER: . . . what I notice (what I notice) and 42. PADRE: . . . io quello che noto (quello
obviously I’m telling you this in a very (.) relaxed way che noto) e chiaramente dico a voi in modo (.)
is that they can judge themselves (.) they can judge molto rilassato che loro da soli si sanno giudicare
their teachers (.) they have their own evaluation (.) sanno giudicare i professori (.) hanno una
scale [inside] scala di valutazione dei professori loro la hanno
[internamente]
43. TEACHER: [but] they could have a higher 43. DOCENTE: [però] potrebbero avere
self-esteem than [that which] un’autostima superiore rispetto a [quella che]
44. FATHER:[nooo] this is a mistake that I don’t 44. PADRE:[nooo] questo no su questo è un
make because I tell him be critical about yourself (.) errore che io non commetto perché io gli dico tu
because you can be critical about yourself everyday criticati (.) tanto perché tutti i giorni ti potrai criticare

Excerpt 12: Interview #1


English translation: Italian original:
9. RESEARCHER: and what do you think of 9. RICERCATRICE: tu invece che pensi di
these school results? questi risultati scolastici?
10. SON: they’re ok ((smiles)) 10. FIGLIO: vanno bene ((sorride))
11. RESEARCHER: was it what [you expected]? 11. RICERCATRICE: era quello che [ti aspettavi]?
12. SON: [yes=yes] 12. FIGLIO: [sì=sì]
13. FATHER: >that is you in your opinion you 13. PADRE: >cioè tu secondo te devi avere tutti
should have a pass in all subjects?< sufficiente?<
14. SON: °yes° ((smiling)) 14. FIGLIO: °sì° ((sorridendo))
15. FATHER: >you’re worth so much?< 15. PADRE: >tanto vali?<
16. SON: °I don’t know how much I’m worth° 16. FIGLIO: °non lo so quanto valgo° ((abbassa
((looks down)) gli occhi))
17. FATHER: >you don’t know how much you’re 17. PADRE: >non lo sai quanto vali?<
worth?< ((smiling)) ((sorridendo))
18. SON: °no° 18. FIGLIO: °no°

854 th e work o f scho o li ng


Excerpt 13: Meeting #11
English translation: Italian original:
1. TEACHER: before re:ading (.) the evaluations 1. DOCENTE: prima di le:ggere (.) le valutazioni
reported for each:: discipline (.) I would say that the riportate per le varie:: discipline (.) volevo dire che
pupil is: a little taciturn (.) ((laughs)) I would say (.) l’allievo è: un po’ taciturno (.) ((ride)) volevo dire (.)
eh! (.) is a little taciturn (.) eh:: (.) he loves his own eh! (.) è un po’ taciturno (.) eh:: (.) ama pure stare
company::: (.) he’s often stimulated to [be] da solo::: (.) molte volte viene sollecitato a [essere]
2. MOTHER: [become part of ] 2. MADRE: [a inserirsi]
3. TEACHER: become part of (.) >no become part 3. DOCENTE: a inserirsi (.) >no a inserirsi!<
of!< (.) because he can do it (.) I mean being close to (.) perché si inserisce bene (.) cioè a stare vicino a
someone (.) but if he must sit alone he do:esn’t have qualcuno (.) però se deve stare seduto da solo no:n
difficulties (.) that’s maybe trova alcuna difficoltà (.) cosa che magari
4. MOTHER: just to not be near 4. MADRE:pur di non stare vicino a
5. TEACHER: eh=eh he would prefer to be alone 5. DOCENTE: eh=eh preferirebbe stare da solo (.)
(.) rather than::: (.) but he’s not aso[cial] più che::: (.) ma non è che è aso[ciale]
6. MOTHER: [no=no] 6. MADRE:[no=no]
7. TEACHER: for heaven’s sake (.) on the contrary 7. DOCENTE: per carità (.) anzi è un ragazzino::.
he’s a boy::.
8. MOTHER: but: he’s a little:: (.) a:n (.) not in 8. MADRE: però: e un po’:: (.) u:n (.) non in
bad sense (.) but:: he’s got his own:: [ideas] senso cattivo (.) però:: diciamo che ha le sue:: [idee]
9. TEACHER: [ideas] (.) so: (.) as they say:: (.) 9. DOCENTE: [idee] (.) per cui: (.) si dice::
better alone than in bad company (.) but (.) I think:: (.) meglio solo che mal accompagnato (.) però (.)
(.) he should start to get used to spend time with secondo me:: (.) dovrebbe cominciare ad abituarsi
((laughs)) the types of (.) is not like ((laughs)) (.) a stare anche un po’ con ((ride)) i vari tipi (.)
in the sense (.) taciturn=silent (.) also to manage chi non è come lui ((ride)) (.) magari nel senso (.)
himself for taciturno=silenzioso (.) anche per gestirsi per
10. MOTHER: no (.) I don’t believe it’s (.) being 10. MADRE: no (.) io non credo sia (.) di essere
taciturn or not (.) because actually he gets on well taciturno o meno (.) perché in realtà lui si trova bene
with G. ((mentions a school mate)) who (.) when he con G. ((cita un compagno)) che (.) ºquando attacca a
buttonholes he never stops (.) they know each other parlare non la finisce piùº (.) si conoscono tantissimo
very well
11. TEACHER: () 11. DOCENTE: ()
12. MOTHER: but:: he doesn’t like:: (.) nosy 12. MADRE: però:: gli danno fastidio:: (.) gli
people invadenti
13. TEACHER: eh! (.) but we have some in class 13. DOCENTE: eh! (.) purtroppo ci sono in classe
(.) eh:: and he has to learn to cope with them (.) eh:: ed è anche giusto che lui li sappia affrontare

involved the teacher, the 11-year-old student, and [ideas]”). In the opinion of the family, the boy has
his 42-year-old mother, a housewife. clear ideas about the type of interactions and persons
According to the teacher, the boy is introverted he looks for (turn #12). In short, the family reinter-
and tends to avoid social relationships (turns #1 and prets the boy’s taciturn and loner aspects in positive
#3). This closure could be a potential sign of an aso- terms, emphasizing his need for autonomy.
cial personality. He should instead open up to social
interaction in order to learn how to tune his behavior Juxtaposition of Voices
and how to manage social relationships (turn #9). In Excerpt 14 presents a “juxtaposition of voices”
accordance with the school’s voice, the boy has dif- between family and school during the meet-
ficulties in social integration. From the family’s point ing involving the teacher, 13-year-old student, his
of view, the boy chooses to spend time alone because 50-year-old father, a doctor, and his 40-year-old
of specific preferences (turn #8: “he’s got his own mother, a teacher.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 855


Excerpt 14: Meeting #13
English translation: Italian original:
11. TEACHER: although are only in the first 11. DOCENTE: siamo anche al primo
4-months term (.) let’s say that the important thing quadrimestre (.) diciamo che l’importante che::: il più
is::: that overall he seems a mature boy (.) I must tell delle volte appare come un ragazzo maturo (.) vi
you the truth devo dire la verità
[...] [...]
23. TEACHER: for the deepness of thinking 23. DOCENTE: per la profondità proprio di
pensiero
24. MOTHER: yes 24. MADRE: si
25. TEACHER: yes but at other times, on the 25. DOCENTE: si poi in altri momenti invece
other hand
26. MOTHER: yes that’s true 26. MADRE: si è vero
27. TEACHER: he seems a child to me 27. DOCENTE: mi sembra un bambino
28. MOTHER: yes that’s true=that’s true 28. MADRE: si è vero =è vero
[...] [...]
36. MOTHER: ok he’s always like that! ok well 36. MADRE: va beh è sempre così! va beh che
he’s only 10! c’ha dieci anni!
37. TEACHER: let’s say >he’s in this phase of 37. DOCENTE: si diciamo >che è in questa fase
growth < so he shows alternate phases di crescita< per cui mostra queste fasi alterne
38. MOTHER: [()] 38. MADRE: [()]
39. TEACHER: [yes=yes yes=yes] 39.DOCENTE: [si=si si=si]
40. FATHER: he needs to leave childhood behind 40. PADRE: si dovrebbe lasciare alle spalle un
poco di infanzia
41. TEACHER: eh! eh! he made a poster in 41. DOCENTE: eh! eh! ha fatto un cartellone in
classroom on adolescence and I asked him I said classe sull’adolescenza e io gli ho chiesto dico ma
why have you drawn a shrimp? perché rappresenta un gambero?
[...] [...]
50. TEACHER: that is what he said later on (.) 50. DOCENTE: poi me l’ha raccontato così (.)
actually effettivamente
51. MOTHER: () 51. MADRE: ()
52. TEACHER: let’s say when he wants and::: 52. DOCENTE: diciamo quando vuole e::: è
he’s one hundred percent mature and at other times maturo al cento per cento altre volte poi
53. FATHER: he is like that at home too 53. PADRE: lo fa anche a casa
54. MOTHER: at home he’s like that 54. MADRE: pure a casa è così

The voices of the family and the school seem himself therefore seems to be aware of the instability
to converge toward a common perception of the typical of the pre-adolescent phase. This uncertainty
child’s Self (turns #11, #25, #26, #27, #28). For echoes the mother’s discourse (turn #36) account-
both teacher and parents the boy shows a sort of ing for the son’s apparent immaturity by attributing
inconsistency, switching from mature behaviors to him a “lower” age (“ok well he’s only 10!”), when he
childish ones (turns #52, #53, #54). The voice of is actually 13 years old.
the child is evoked by the teacher through a semiotic
mediation device. In fact, the teachers reports (turn Poliphony, Symbolic Resources
#41) that during a classroom activity, the pupil, and Temporality
when asked to create a poster, decided to portray The main purpose, formally estabilished, of the
adolescence as a “shrimp,” showing the presence of school-family meeting is to communicate to the
a self-reflexive process with respect to the fluctua- parents the results of the child’s scholastic devel-
tions in the definition of his own identity. The boy opment. What actually emerges is more complex

856 th e work o f scho o li ng


and interesting from a dialogical viewpoint. First, defining what the child is, what he is not, what he
the communication of the academic results is situ- should and should not be, what he could and could
ated within a ritualistic and structured context of not be.
activity in which many other elements are at stake.
The excerpts presented show that during the school- An Easy Shift
family meetings, the child is provided with a set of In the previous pages we have underlined how
symbolic resources in the form of the voices that the process of definition of a child’s identity is closely
the adults use to talk about his Self. The pupil then connected with his/her scholastic experience. In
draws on these resources and on the different defini- this perspective, academic success or failure acquires
tions of the Self given by the significant adults (par- value in relation to a positive or negative definition
ents and teachers). A space of negotiation is thus of the Self (as seen in the Excerpt 2). Besides, school
opened in which the pupil can decide to accept, assessments are also frequently used not only to
reject, or remodulate the possible definitions of the define the features of a “good” or “bad” student, but
Self. The outcomes cannot be predicted, but what also to connote the child/pupil’s identity.
matters here is the interactive and dialogical nature Scholastic assessment ends up coinciding with
of this process. It is a fluid and problematic process what the child is rather than with what the child
for the child because these voices can be either con- knows (as in Excerpt 8, turn #7: the teachers says,
sonant, dissonant, or opposite to one another. At the “let’s say it all defines his character”).
same time, they can partially agree with the child’s Excerpt 15, on the other hand, concerns an inter-
self-perception or else they can totally disagree with view with a family made up of an 11-year-old pupil,
it. This process takes place within the constraints her 52-year-old father, a doctor, and her 49-year-old
of power relationships and the framework of the mother, a housewife. The pupil’s academic perfor-
specific culturally situated activity. The power rela- mance, according to her teachers, is very good.
tionships limit the range of possible Selves that the The excerpt shows that for both the teachers and
child can construct because the polyphony of voices parents the school results tell what kind of person
is however a “selection” emerging within given cul- the child is. In this excerpt, the adults account for
tural parameters (Bruner, 1996). They define the school success or failure by attributing academic
different identity “possibilities,” for instance what a performance to the child’s dispositional and inter-
“good” or “bad” pupil is, or what a growing child nal aspects (Excerpt #15 turn #21: the father says,
should or should not become. Besides, the school- “she’s responsible”). Thus, results define the pupil
family meetings and their voices are contextualized but they are the outcome of her personal charac-
within a time perspective (see Fig. 40.3). teristics in return, like a sort of identity definition
Thus, there is a time “before” the meeting, con- feedback loop. It is evident how scholastic assess-
cerning the whole experience of the pupil in the ment can take on meanings that are more closely
educational context. This experience contributes to related to the definition of identity and “self-value,”
defining his Self and can be partially documented showing how assessing performance can easily
through the academic assessment. There is a “pres- become assessing the person. This has a particularly
ent” time of the meeting and, finally, there is a time meaningful connotation on a psycho-social level,
“after,” concerning the development of the Self in especially considering the very delicate transitional
the future. This development can be only imagined phase pre-adolescents and adolescent students are
within the range of some culturally defined iden- going through, in which they face the fundamental
tity options. The adults’ voices then contribute to task of constructing their Selves.

Past/Present Future

Poliphony
School-family meetings: the adults’ voices about the child

As is As could be
As should be Figure 40.3 Polyphony and time perspective.
As may not be Adapted from Valsiner (2007) with permission.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 857


Excerpt 15: Interview #2
English translation: Italian original:
18. RESEARCHER: why (.) do you think your 18. RICERCATRICE: perché (.), secondo voi,
daughter got these very good results? What do vostra figlia ha ricevuto questi risultati che sono
you put it down to? sicuramente ottimi? a cosa lo attribuite?
19. FATHER: because she is certainly (1.5) in 19. PADRE: perché sicuramente lei (1.5) nelle
the humanities (.) we know she’s more talented materie umanistiche (.) sappiamo è più portata (.) le
(.) she likes reading writing she writes quite well piace leggere scrive abbastanza bene proprio perché
because indeed at home she’s been encouraged to a casa è stata abituata alla lettura
read
20. MOTHER: >apart from the fact< that she’s a 20. MADRE:>a parte il fatto< che è una
very conscientious girl (.) she has a conscience (.) she bambina molto coscienziosa (.) lei ha una coscienza
does everything what has to be done (.) fa tutto quello che deve essere fatto
21. FATHER: [she’s responsible] 21. PADRE: [è responsabile]
22. MOTHER: [she’s very responsible] she 22. MADRE: [è molto responsabile] non è
isn’t a superficial girl (.) that leaves things she’s una bambina superficiale (.) che lascia le cose è
responsible and conscientious responsabile e coscienziosa

In short, on a broader conceptual level, scholastic and the son (a 13-year-old student) are discussing
assessment seems to acquire symbolic meanings and the child’s school results.
to become: (1) a modulator of the identity-building During the first phase of the interaction
process; (2) an element that can confirm or desta- (turns #19 to #26), the father and the son start
bilize the emerging idea of Self; (3) a negotiational an exchange in which the parent asks the son to
space with respect to the way pupil is perceived by answer for his level of diligence in his studies
both parents and teachers. (turn #19: the father says, “but you believe that
you study the subjects thoroughly in the right
The Child’s Active Internalization way all the subjects?”), reproposing at turns #21
of the Adults’ Voices and #23 his personal viewpoint on the method
The legacy of “evaluations about the person” is of study. In a first phase of the dialogue, the son
the object of the active internalization process that seems to assume an acquiescent position (turns
is, the raw material for the definition of the Self. The #20, #24 and #28). When the researcher asks him
following excerpt shows how the child reformulates straight out to express his own opinion on why
and elaborates the judgements on the Self, emerging his academic performance is not brilliant, the child
during the dialogical interaction with the adults, and appears to be uncertain and confused (turn #28:
uses them to talk about himself. Actually, it is not a “don’t know!”). The uncertainty seems to disappear
passive echoing of adult voices, but a personal and at turn #30 when the child chooses to account for
active redefinition of the identity options provided his performance by evoking his “superficial” atti-
by the adults’ discourse. These options dialogically tude to his studies. Actually, in this turn it would
define what the child is but at the same time imply appear that the child chooses to talk about him-
the exclusion of what he is not. In other words, the self with the same connotations as his father’s
child appropriates of the “adult voices” that talk discourse. Nevertheless, he mediates—this could
about the Self, performing that process that goes be understood as a son’s active internalization—
from the externalization of the semiotic forms to between the adult’s voice—that defines him as
their internalization as tools for defining and regu- “superficial”—and the self-perception he is con-
lating the Self. structing of a person that, despite the recognition
The dialogical definition of the child’s Self is of this lack of diligence, does not judge himself in
shown in Excerpt 16, also taken from Interview #1, totally negative terms (turn #30 “even in things I
in which the researcher, the father (a 46-year-old) like a pass is okay”). This represents a clear example

858 th e work o f scho o li ng


Excerpt 16: Interview #1
English translation: Italian original:
19. FATHER: >but you believe that you study 19. PADRE: >ma credi che tu approfondisci
the subjects thoroughly< (.) >in the right way all giusto nelle materie< (.), >in un modo corretto a
the subjects<? tutte le materie<?
20. SON: °no° ((lowers his eyes)) 20. FIGLIO: °no° ((abbassa gli occhi))
21. FATHER: >and what did your father always 21. PADRE: >e che ti ha detto sempre tuo
tell you< (.) >Italian language, history e geography padre< (.), >italiano, storia e geografia non si può
you can’t get pass mark< prendere sufficiente<
22. SON: °not pass mark° 22. FIGLIO: °non sufficiente°
23. FATHER: no (.) I said pass mark >is scant 23. PADRE: no (.) ho detto che sufficiente
because pass mark:::< means that you actually gave >è poco perché sufficiente:::< vuol dire che
a quick look at the pages (.), am I wrong? praticamente hai fatto una girata dei fogli (.), o mi
sbaglio?
24. SON: °yes° 24. FIGLIO: °sì°
25. FATHER: >that’s what I always say to you?< 25. PADRE: >te lo dico sempre?<
26. SON: eh! ((nod)) 26. FIGLIO: eh! ((fa cenno con la testa))
27. RESEARCHER: why do you think you got 27. RICERCATRICE: perché secondo te, hai
these results? avuto questi risultati?
28. SON: °don’t know!° 28. FIGLIO: °bo!°
29. RESEARCHER: according to dad it’s clear, 29. RICERCATRICE: secondo papà è abbastanza
what about you? chiaro, secondo te?
30. SON: maybe because I am superficial (1.0) 30. FIGLIO: perché sono superficiale forse
well I don’t go into enough::: even in things I like a (1.0), cioè non approfondisco::: pure quello che mi
pass is okay ((smiles and lower his eyes)) piace lo stesso sulla sufficienza va bene ((sorride e
abbassa lo sguardo))

of the modulation and negotiation between the Son #1, when asked by the researcher, seems to
adult’s voice and the child’s vision of his own Self. accept this viewpoint (turn #43), but he immedi-
In Excerpt 17 the researcher is interviewing a ately proposes a complementary explanation (I did
family composed of two sons, 12 and 13 years old, what I had to do) in terms of compliance to the
attending two different classes at the same school, school’s requirements. Son #2 seems to agree with
the father, a 45-year-old nurse, and the mother, a his brother’s explanation (turn #45). In this case,
41-year-old housewife. Again in this case, the par- the children’s definition of Self seems to agree with
ticipants are discussing the school results. the adults’, and it doesn’t require a significant nego-
In this excerpt, the parents introduce a wider tiation between different or opposite viewpoints as
time perspective in the evaluation of their sons’ in Excerpt 16. The children seem to comply with
scholastic results (turns #39 to #41). The par- the expectations of both the family—commitment
ents suggest that the results at school are related to grow up—and the school—a “good” pupil ful-
to life expectations and the commitment required fills his assignments. Nevertheless, the two pupils in
to study is the same quality that should serve to Excerpt 17 do not disagree with the adult position
face the forthcoming challenges of life. The topic but play a different type of active appropriation
at stake is commitment, which goes beyond the and negotiation between voices. In this case they
boundaries of the school results (turn #41). It is “attune” their definition of the Self by appropriat-
something “acquired” through education but nec- ing and internalizing the categories of the adults’
essary for life. In this case, the two sons had good discourse. Then they use these categories as self-reg-
marks, so their capability is not questioned and ulatory instances in order to orient their semiotic
commitment is “already” part of the definition of behavior, their self-presentation, and sense-making
Self provided by the adults (teacher and parents). of school experiences.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 859


Excerpt 17: Interview #3
English translation: Italian original:
39. MOTHER: because there’s a question 39. MADRE: perché poi comunque dietro
underlying all this there’s a question of (.)preparing c’è tutto un discorso (.), per la preparazione del
the future (.) the society (.) as we know (.) is (.) so futuro (.) La società, sappiamo, è ormai (.), quindi
it’s important (.) the=crafts=doesn’t=exist=anymore è importante (.) non=esiste=più=il=mestiere, il
(.) the=manual=labor (.) so with three sons we try to lavoro=manuale=artigianale. Quindi con tre maschi
make them understand the importance cerchiamo di fargli capire l’importanza
40. FATHER: we talk with them above all about 40. PADRE: ci si parla con loro soprattutto di
these problems questi problemi
41. MOTHER: commit yourself for your future 41. MADRE: impegnatevi per il vostro futuro
(.) now we’ve done our job ((gesticulates)) (.) do (.), ormai il nostro lo abbiamo fatto ((gesticola)),
your best for your future (1.5) and that’s the only per il vostro futuro impegnatevi (1.5) ed è l’unico
way by nowadays (.) and so it’s good to commit modo al momento (.) e quindi è bene impegnarsi
oneself (1.5) to have a better future (1.5) per avere il futuro più facile
42. RESEARCHER: why do you think you got 42. RICERCATRICE: secondo voi perché avuto
these marks? (names SON #1) why? questi voti? Corrado perché?
43. SON #1: ((smiles)) during the school year (.) 43. FIGLIO 1: ((sorride)) nel corso dell’anno
I applied myself (.) I did what I had to do scolastico (.) mi sono impegnato, ho fatto quello
che dovevo fare
44. RESEARCHER: so perseverance rewarded you 44. RICERCATRICE: quindi la costanza ti ha
(.) and what about you (names SON #2)? premiato (.) E tu Adriano, perchè?
45. SON #2: eh::: (2.0) let’s say the same thing 45. FIGLIO 2: eh::: (2.0) diciamo per la stessa
cosa
46. RESEARCHER: you applied yourself? 46. RICERCATRICE: ti sei impegnato?
47. SON #2: yes 47. FIGLIO 2: sì

In more general terms, Excerpts 16 and 17 are The Other Side of the Coin: The
examples of the symbolic process of active appro- Educational Self in the Adult’s Life
priation that leads to the construction of the Self. The second characteristic of the Educational
What happens is that the children are provided with Self (see Fig. 40.4b) is the fact that it emerges and
images of the Self, norms, values, and explanations becomes salient every time the person participates
of their behavior. They elaborate the signs adults use in an activity within an educational context5. The
to talk about them but at the same time they elabo- legacy of symbolic resources (systems of activity,
rate these signs to produce their own view, which is emotional experience, etc.) attached to the school
partially coinciding and partially not. experience, is used by the adults to regulate and

a) construction of the Self during the school


age in the adults’ discourse
Educational Self

b) em ergence of the Self when


an adult experiences the educational context

the experienced Self is imm ediately reactivated with its related emotional mood
the educational experience is used to make sense of what happens to the pupil at school
Figure 40.4 The emergence of the adult’s
the voices of the Self related to the educational experiences emerge in adults’ discourse
Educational Self

860 th e work o f scho o li ng


modulate the interaction and to make sense of #26). Then the researcher asks for the father’s opin-
what happens in this type of situation. This pro- ion (turns #27, #30).
cess emerges in our data under three different Both the mother and the father left school after
forms: obtaining their middle school diploma and went
out to work. In turn #24, the mother immediately
1) the experienced Self is immediately
refers to the important turning point in her life
reactivated with its related emotional mood;
(“instead I decided to get a job”). She juxtaposes a
2) the traces of the educational experience are
present and a past situation linked by the person of
used to make sense of what happens to the pupil at
her teacher. She was a good student, she loved the
school; and
school, but she decided to leave despite her teacher’s
3) points 1 and 2 emerge in the adult’s
advise. When she comes back to school as a mother,
discourse through the voices of the Self related to
she meets again the same person, who has become
the educational experiences.
in the meantime the headmaster, and she reports
The first form is presented in Excerpt 18, where his discourse in the third person (“when he saw me
we can see how the experienced Self of the parents is he told me ‘don’t do to your son what you did to
immediately reactivated by the school-family meet- yourself ’ ”) to argue in favor of her present belief as
ing. The researcher interviews a family just after a parent of a school-age son (“going to school is bet-
the school-family meeting. The family is composed ter than going to work”). The narrative of the moth-
by the father, a 41-year-old craftsman, the mother, er’s biography (turns #24, #29 and #31) seems to
a 40-year-old waitress, and the son, age 12 years. be attached to an immediate activation of an emo-
First, the researcher asks the parents to evaluate tional and “nostalgic” mood (“If I could go back
their son’s school. The mother starts to talk about yes”). On the other hand, when the father is asked
the headmaster, who was incidentally her teacher to evaluate the school (turn #30) he immediately
when she left the school before finishing (turns #24, presents not only the same “nostalgic” mood (“we

Excerpt 18: Interview #8


English translation: Italian original:
24. MOTHER: yes he’s a smart person (.) when 24. MADRE: sì una persona in gamba (.)
he saw me I took my son to middle school for the quando mi vide la prima volta che portai mio figlio
first time (.) because I didn’t finish the school (.) I in prima media (.) perché io non ho continuato (.)
just finished the middle school and didn’t want to ho fatto la terza media e non ho voluto continuare
go on (.) even if I got good notes (.) when he saw (.) anche se andavo moto bene a scuola (.) come mi
me he told me don’t do to your son what you did to vide disse non far fare a tuo figlio quello che hai
yourself (.) he came home to tell me I must go on (.) fatto tu venne fino a casa che io dovevo continuare
instead I decided to get a job mi misi in testa che dovevo andare a lavorare
25. RESEARCHER: in general (.) what is your 25. RICERCATRICE: e in generale (.) rispetto alla
idea about the school? scuola che idea avete?
26. MOTHER: it’s a good thing (.) beyond 26. MADRE: è una cosa buona (.) a parte una
literacy (.) going to school is better than going to cultura generale (.) è meglio andare a scuola che
work lavorare!
27. RESEARCHER: does daddy think so too? 27. RICERCATRICE: anche il papà pensa così?
28. FATHER: yes=yes 28. PADRE: sì=sì
29. MOTHER: If we could go back yes 29. MADRE: se tornavamo indietro sì
30. FATHER: that’s what I said earlier to the 30. PADRE: l’ho detto prima alla professoressa
teacher (.) I sat down at the little school desk (.) I (.) mi sono seduto nel banchetto (.) io ritornerei
would go back to school again un’altra volta a scuola
31. MOTHER: it’s very nice (.) I loved going to 31. MADRE: è molto bello (.) a me piaceva
school (.) a lot andare a scuola (.) tanto

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 861


would go back to school again”), but he accounts her daughter’s school with her own experience as
for the activation of a specific “educational” behav- a student. It should be noted that she evokes the
ior (I sat down at the little school desk). Excerpt emotional condition (“we were afraid”) and the
18 shows how the adults, while getting in contact relationship with the adults (“the teacher, the prin-
with the educational context, immediately activate cipal”) rather than other dimensions such as learn-
a repertoire of voices, norms, emotions, and behav- ing. In the same way, the difference between “her”
iors that are part of the Educational Self, and use it school and that of her daughter is described in terms
to make sense of their life trajectory as individuals, of “open-mindedness” and attention to the student’s
students, and parents. The parents “know” how to “problems” rather than subjects or methods.
behave and self-regulate at school, even if they are Excerpt 19, on the other hand, is taken from
actually there as parents, because they immediately Interview #3 involving two sons, (12 and 13 years
grasp their previous experience. At the same time, old), the father, and the mother.
the internalized teacher’s voice, once addressed to In this excerpt, the focus of both parents (turns
them as students, is now used to account for their #40, #41 and #48) is on the change that has taken
choices as parents. place in terms of methods, subjects, and programs.
The second characteristic of the adult’s As in Excerpt 7, the parents immediately refer to
Educational Self is that the educational experience their own school experience to make comparisons.
is used to make sense of what’s happening at school. These are two examples of the different way adults
The parents provide some evaluations of the school refer to their school experience to make sense of
with respect to their past experience and account for their children’s situation. Although, the parents’
a change, which is not easy to elaborate. evaluations focus on different dimensions, the emo-
As shown in Excerpt 7 (turn #43) the mother tional experience and the relationship versus the
immediately compares the present situation of learning and the method, both the excerpts show a

Excerpt 19: Interview #3


English translation: Italian original:
39. RESEARCHER: and in general (.) what do 39. RICERCATRICE: e in generale (.) voi
you parents think about the school? genitori che pensate della scuola?
40. MOTHER: it has made great strides from 40. MADRE: si sono fatti passi da gigante da un
time to time (1.5) maybe too many [many:::] momento all’altro (1.5) troppi forse [troppi:::]
41. FATHER: [many] (.) we remember our 41. PADRE: [troppi] (.) noi ci ricordiamo la
school once upon a time (.) a school with (.)a scuola di un tempo (.) di una scuola con (.) un
teacher (.) schematic (.) mechanical (.)school isn’t insegnante (.) schematica (.) meccanica (.) invece
like that any more (.) the programs (.) the subjects la scuola di adesso no (.) sui programmi (.) sulle
(.) are different (.) they do (1.5) not have to study materie (.) è diverso (.) devono (1.5) più studiare
like (.) we used to but like::: (3.0) how can I say non in modo (.) come facevamo noi una volta ma
come::: (3.0) come posso dire
42. RESEARCHER: maybe not the [content] 42. RICERCATRICE: forse non tanto
i[contenuti]
43. FATHER: [the content] 43. PADRE:[i contenuti]
44. RESEARCHER: [a method?] 44. RICERCATRICE: [un metodo?]
45. FATHER: [yes a method] 45. PADRE: [sì un metodo]
46. RESEARCHER: school in general has changed 46. RICERCATRICE: la scuola in generale ha
like::: fatto tanti cambiamenti un po’:::
47. FATHER: hasty 47. PADRE: affrettati
48. MOTHER: we don’t have the time to (.) get 48. MADRE: non abbiamo avuto il tempo di
to grips with one phase and (.) they’ve suddenly (.) regolarci in una fase che subito (.) sono subito
moved on to the next one (.) I don’t know (.) maybe passati alla successiva (.) non so (.) può darsi che
that’s good (.) I can’t really say sia buono (.) non so analizzare la cosa

862 th e work o f scho o li ng


certain difficulty in making sense of the change with willing-to-be a successful or unsuccessful student
respect to their own school experience (Excerpt 7, (Excerpts 7, 18, and 19), parent (Excerpts 7 and 18),
turn #43; Excerpt 19, turns #47 and #48), which is teacher or worker (Excerpt 20) with the related emo-
attached to an emotional vividness. Once the school tional and relational implications. The Educational
was rigid but reassuring, schematic but stable, it is Self is also used to make sense and to regulate some
not only the student’s Self that must adapt to the types of power relationships (Bruner, 1996), provid-
“hasty” change but also the Selves of the parents as ing a framework to account for the teacher-student
former students. relationship (Excerpts 7, 18, and 19) and for the social
The last aspect of the adult Educational Self is value of the education (Excerpt 18). The Educational
the polyphony related to the educational experi- Self is a legacy of symbolic resources made of the set
ences emerging from the adults’ discourse. An of knowledge, beliefs, narratives, and affective states
example of such polyphony is presented in Excerpt established during the personal educational life. We
20, which is taken from an interview with a fam- can draw on it when participating as adults in an
ily composed of a 12-year-old son, the father and educational activity, playing different roles and func-
the mother, both 45-year-old teachers. The sense tions, such as in school-family meetings.
of the school experience is expressed in the dia- The adult would thus activate the Educational
logue between the different voices of the Self, in Self—that is what has been defined here as the self-
this case the I-teacher and the I-father (Ligorio & regulatory instance of the Self formed during the
Tateo, 2008). dialogical interaction in educational contexts—to
When the father is asked to evaluate his son’s make sense of the school experience of the child as
school, the answer is expressed through an alliance of a pupil but also of their own experience as parents
the I-positions of “father” and “teacher” (turn #31). or teachers.
Nevertheless, this evaluation calls into the picture The idea of Educational Self results from a dynamic,
the father’s self-evaluation as a good teacher (“doing situated and dialogical process as underlined by the
it with passion”) and the whole set of knowledge excerpts discussed. The definition of Educational Self
derived from the personal school experiences in dif- has to do with the formation of Self during a critical
ferent moments of his lifetime (“pupils are different stage in life. More in general, this is not a static entity
than in the past”). but follows the same complex and fluid process of
In short, the function of the Educational Self elaboration of the identity throughout the personal
emerging from the excerpts is that of regulating and trajectory, in which “what is” is connected with “what
making sense of the adult’s encounter with the school, was,” “what is not yet, but is about to come” (Valsiner,
through the activation of the specific symbolic rep- 2009, p. 18). The analysis of school-family meetings
ertoires related to the experience of having-been or provided some initial hints about how the polyphony

Excerpt 20: Interview #4


English translation: Italian original:
30. RESEARCHER: what do you think about 30. RICERCATRICE: cosa pensate della scuola
your children’s school? che stanno frequentando i vostri figli?
31. FATHER: the school (1.5) for me as 31. PADRE: la scuola (1.5) per me che sono un
a teacher and I have seen many schools (.) this insegnante e che ho visto parecchie scuole (.) questa
school really works (.) I don’t know all the teaching è una scuola che realmente funziona (.) non conosco
staff because the school works (.) if the teachers (.) tutti gli insegnanti perché la scuola funziona (.) se
understand the pupils(.) >believing in their own job< ci sono gli insegnanti (.) che capiscono i ragazzi (.)
(.) doing it with passion (.) which is not always the >che credono nel loro lavoro< (.) che lo fanno con
case (.) in the school=world=like (.) elsewhere in our passione (.) il ché non è sempre riscontrabile (.) nel
life and so (.) it depends on the teacher (.) today the mondo=scolastico=come (.) in tutti i settori della
relationships with the pupils are different than in nostra vita e quindi (.) dipende dall’insegnante (.)
the past oggi i rapporti con i ragazzi sono diversi rispetto al
passato

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 863


position neither comfortable nor usual, but now we
Others: School can start again from here. Having a quick glance
The teachers’ definition
of the child
and using a renewed attention, we would probably
realize that the walls of the school, first rigid, now
seem more porous, plastic, and permeable. As the
Others: Family
The parents’ Negotiation
contours of cell membranes they let through some
definition Space Child’s Self elements from sociocultural world. We would, then,
of the child recognize that the limited space of the balcony is a
very dynamic open-ended system. It’s a boundary,
which, just as every liminal threshold, is a meeting
place. From the balcony we can, finally assume a
different angle to see what occurs inside the school.
Dialogical tension
In this way, we would become aware that the work
of schooling is constantly interwoven with several
elements related to what there is on the outside of
Myself-Others (parents-teachers)
the balcony (in society), what happens beyond the
balcony (in the school) and what happened or is
As if As will be happening on the balcony itself.
It’s always refreshing to summarize, at the end of
Past/Present Future a long discussion, the main issues stressed.
Using the metaphor of a balcony we pointed out
Figure 40.5 Negotiation space and dialogical tension. how the school is a place in between, a border always
interfaced with both internal aspects (practices, dis-
of Educational Self would emerge from the process of courses, and different actors) and a wider sociocul-
active internalization and semiotic mediation of the tural climate. The school balcony, as a border zone,
significant adult voices that enter into contact with is an area of contact with other relevant educational
the child’s idea of Self, in course of elaboration or as settings. In order to grasp the dynamic and fluidity
elaborated so far (see Figure 40.5). of this interconnection we need to look at boundary
The school-family meetings open a dialogi- phenomena. A binocular vision focused on inside
cal space where the different voices determine a and outside school allows us to take in consideration
dynamic system open to different “as-if ” possibili- the many processes implied in the work of schooling,
ties, contributing to defining what a person could moving from the role played by the socio-economic
be in future time. It is a space of dialogical ten- and cultural dimensions, passing through the analy-
sion characterized by ambivalence and uncertainty sis of intersectional points with others educational
whose borders are permeable rather than rigid. It contexts (such as family-school meetings), arriving
is a polyphonic space where the confrontation at the definition of identity in the school (the sug-
with significant others (myself-others) such as, for gested notion of the Educational Self ).
instance, parents and teachers activates a process of Looking across the balcony, for example, we
definition-redefinition-remodulation of the child’s highlighted which elements reach school, becoming
Self (Simao & Valsiner, 2007). It stimulates a dia- fundamental factors in constructing school’s every-
logue and a process of definition and specification, day life. We outlined that the first element to be
stressed by both “what I think about Me” and by taken into account is the socio-economic dimension
“what others think about Me.” of cultural context in which school acts. We also
stressed the relevant effects of families’ social and
Conclusion: Still Standing on the Balcony cultural capital on children’s school experience.
Why not to do a little exercise now? You just try Paying attention to what happens on the balcony
to rewind the tape of the visual and virtual tour of means, primarily, takes into account the intercon-
the school. What do you see at this moment? The textual connection between school and other life
building, the entrance-hall, then the corridors and contexts as in the case of home-school interactions.
classrooms. Can you visualize the balcony? The Such boundary encounters make evident the intri-
metaphorical balcony on which we have been and cacy of the interpersonal dynamics in an institu-
where we explored the work of schooling was a tional setting.

864 th e work o f scho o li ng


The school-family meetings take place in a par- static vision of schooling, stressing concepts such
ticular time and space (just on the metaphorical as “boundary process,” “psychological membranes,”
school balcony) within specific “formal/informal” “intercontextual dynamics,” and “intersection
and “open/closed” parameters established by the points.” In a way, we have pointed out the move-
school. Along these lines, three main modalities ment and the openness rather than the static nature
of interactional activities (Opposition, Alliance, and the closure. It’s precisely this “being in between”
and Acquiescence) emerge during the parents- that should be further explored. By standing on the
teacher meetings that are strictly connected to the border and by facing constantly the tension among
family’s socio-economic status and child’s school different parts of the system, new intriguing research
results. questions come forward:
We have also suggested an economically ori-
ented view of the school-family meeting to stress 1) How to develop theoretically the balcony
what is actually at stake in this crossing boundary metaphor and its implication in studying boundary
phenomenon. The different representations of edu- conditions? In order to expand the Border Zone
cation (multi-dimensionality versus mono-dimen- concept with respect to the home-school interaction,
sionality) and school (instrumental versus holistic which other crossing boundary phenomena should
vision) evoked by parents and teachers and the one consider? There are many other different
child’s value (in terms of how much he is worth as a intersection points between school and family that
person and not only as a student) are the objects of could be empirically explored. One of these occurs
negotiation or, more roughly, the indexes of stock when the parents accompany their child to the
exchange quotations becoming, to a certain extent, school. What happens during this daily entrance in
commodities. the school’s territory? What kind of social processes
As we have underlined, the meetings look really take place on the liminal threshold constituted
heuristically interesting also because it is possible to by the entrance-hall? Which are the institutional
observe the twofold articulation of the Educational rules ordering this scholastic daily routine and
Self. On one hand, the teachers’ and parents’ dis- under which conditions are they violated? What is
courses on school evaluation make explicit several admitted, what is rejected, or just tolerated on this
definitions of the pupils’ Self. Such definitions pro- border? In other words, what passes through the
vide a range of identity options that the child should balcony and what does not?
negotiate and cope with during the critical process of 2) Which types of experiences make the
constructing his/her Self. On the other hand, during emergence of the Educational Self possible? The
school-family meetings, adults are asked to manage reciprocity of the relationships in motion (Past-
different activities, which is very meaningful from a Present-Future) and the dialogical nature of each
psycho-social point of view. They have to make sense “I” position in motion (the ambivalence between
of the child’s school experience, account for his per- to-be and to-become) must be explored with
formance, negotiate between the family and school respect to the formation of student’s Educational
culture, etc. These activities require the recourse to Self. Besides, how can we grasp the “polyphony of
the symbolic system of autobiographical and social voices” affecting the definition of Self in others’
knowledge related to their personal educational educational activities and experiences inside and
experience. Through the balcony metaphor we can outside the school?
look with a new lens at current work of schooling, 3) How can one explore the regulatory function
at its complexity and at its unavoidable interconnec- of the Educational Self at the level of social roles
tions with the broader cultural paradigms of a given and power relationships? It represents, indeed, the
society. Studying these extremely complex systems of framework both for the selection of the possible
relationships between inside and outside the school Selves to be constructed by the child within certain
require the researchers to stand exactly on the bal- cultural parameters and for the regulation of social
cony in spite of the rain or the heat. relationships and social valorization of the education
within a given society.
Future Directions 4) Which is the role played by the Educational
It seems to us that a common trace can be iden- Self in the adulthood? How does it “work”? To
tified throughout our discussion. In this chapter, understand the idea of adult Educational Self could
in fact, we have made an attempt to go beyond a be useful to study its reactivation when the person

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 865


is involved in an educational activity, for example,
(( )) short annotations about extra-verbal or
during significant turning points and transitions contextual elements are reported in double-
in life, such as higher education or professional round brackets
training activities.
5) How to reveal the ambiguity of the [ beginning of juxtaposition of speakers; the
measurement system used by the school in the square brackets are vertically aligned
evaluation report card? Are those measures (such ] end of juxtaposition of speakers
as the marks) an instrument to commoditize the
education? How does this translation of the complex .h heavy inspiration
educational process occur? What could be lost or
h. heavy expiration
added? Is the translation system clear or is it only
outwardly evident? And to whom? (0.2) length of pause in seconds
6) Which communicative strategies the school
could be improved to make the meeting with the (.) pause shorter than 0.2 seconds
family more effective? Could they be constituted
by “interaction protocols,” helpful in reformulating
both conflict and acquiescence interactions?
Acknowledgments
We wish to thank Jaan Valsiner for his constant support, for
his generosity, for our insightful meetings that were essential for
the development of the ideas presented in this chapter. We also
Appendix: Transcription Conventions want to thank Luca Tateo for his helpful feedback on an earlier
The transcription of school-family meetings version of the manuscript and the K-seminar’s participants for
and interviews is in line with the conventions of their numerous interesting suggestions.
Jefferson’s (1985) Conversational Analysis.
Notes
1. The chapter is the result of a shared reflection of the
authors. However, Antonio Iannaccone wrote the paragraphs
. descending tone entitled “Homeostatic functions of the school,” “Maintaining
status-quo of society,” “Some practical implications,” “Types of
, ascending tone interactions, family’s socio-economic status, and school results.”
Giuseppina Marsico wrote the introduction, the other para-
? interrogative tone graphs, conclusion, and future research’s directions.
2. In architectural terms the balcony is a part of the building
::: extension of preceding sound (proportional that protrudes outward. It’s an element added to the body of
to the number of colons) the building, a sort of platform beyond the outer wall bound-
ary. Therefore, the balcony enables the relations with adjacent
- sound or word interruption surroundings. For this reason we can define the balcony as a real
social space, a place to meet and exchange where many social
= no articulation between words events occur. As an example, one of the authors (Marsico) reports
some “snapshots” of life during her childhood. Many times she
__ (underlined) emphasis on the words under-
has seen her mother calling their neighbor across the balcony to
lined borrow, for example, eggs for a cake and then give her a piece
once the cake was prepared by passing the tray from one balcony
M (capital letters) increase of volume
to another. Many other times she has seen her mother on the bal-
°° the words between these signs are whispered cony chatting with a neighbor of micro-events that had occurred
in the little world of the neighborhood. In a sense, the balcony
>< the words between these signs are pro- was a venue for exchanging gossip that performs the function
nounced in an accelerating tone of maintenance of the social order. She herself repeatedly has
observed from the balcony the neighbor across, accessing daily to
<> the words between these signs are pro- a series of actions and to life that flowed in the opposite house.
nounced in a decelerating tone 3. The research was realized in a middle school in the South
of Italy.
() the words between these signs are not 4. Year 8 in the Italian educational system, which requires
perfectly comprehensible. The brackets are assessment in years 5, 8, and 13.
empty when the talk is absolutely unintel- 5. The authors are grateful to Luca Tateo for his participation
in defining the emergence of adult’s Educational Self and in com-
ligible
menting on the related excerpts discussed in the chapters.

866 th e work o f scho o li ng


References Hermans, H. (1996). Voicing the Self: From information pro-
Bakhtin, M. M. (1979/1986). Speech genres and other late essays. cessing to dialogical interchange. Psychological Bulletin,
Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. 119(1), 31–50.
Ballarino, G., & Checchi, D. (2006). Sistema scolastico e disugua- Huntsinger, C. S., & Jose, P. E. (2009). Parental involvement in
glianza sociale. Bologna: Il Mulino. children’s schooling: Different meanings in different cultures.
Berger, E. H. (1995). Parents as partners in education: Families Early Childhood Research Quarterly, 24(4), 398–410.
and schools working together (4th ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Iannaccone, A. (2010). Le condizioni sociali del pensiero. Milan:
Merrill Prentice-Hall. Unicopli.
Bernstein, B. (1971). Class, Codes and Control. Volume 1. Iannaccone, A., & Marsico, G. (2007). La famiglia va a scuola.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Discorsi e rituali di un incontro. Rome: Carocci.
Bourdieu, P., & Passeron, J.-C. (1970). La reproduction: Eléments Iannaccone, A., Tateo, L., Mollo, M., & Marsico, G. (2008,
pour une théorie du système d’enseignement, Paris: Editions de February). L’identité professionnelle des enseignants face au
Minuit. changement: Analyses empiriques dans le contexte italien.
Bronfenbrenner, U. (1979). The ecology of human development. Travail et formation en éducation,. [Online], retrieved from:
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. http://tfe.revues.org/index754.html
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Jefferson, G. (1985). An exercise in the transcription and analysis of
University Press. laughter. In T. van Dijk (Eds.), Handbook of discourse analysis
Bruner, J. (1996). The Culture of education. Cambridge, MA: (Vol. III). London: Academic Press.
Harvard University Press. Kindermann, T., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.) (1995). Development of
Cabell, K. R. (2010). Mediators, regulators, and catalyzers: A person context relations. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
context-inclusive model of trajectory development. Psychology Associates.
& Society, 3. Konkola, R. (2001). Developmental processes of internship poly-
Carugati, F., & Selleri, P. (2005). Psicologia dell’educazione. technic and boundary-zone activity as a new model for activity.
Bologna: Il Mulino. In T. Tüomi-Gröhn & Y. Engeström (Eds.), At the boundary-
Daniels, H. (1995). Pedagogic practices, tacit knowledge and zone between school and work. New possibilities of work-based
discursive discrimination: Bernstein and post-Vygotskian learning (pp. 148–186). Helsinki: University Press.
research. British Journal of Sociology of Education,16(4), Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago:
517–532. University of Chicago Press.
Daniels, H. (2004). Activity theory, discourse and Bernstein. Leibing, A. (2005). The old lady from Ipanema: Changing
Educational Review, 56(2), 121–132. notions of old age in Brazil. Journal of Aging Studies, 19(1),
Daniels, H. (2012). The interface between the sociology of practice 15–31.
and the analysis of talk in the study of change in educational Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psychology. New York:
setting. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Oxford handbook of culture and McGraw-Hill.
psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. Lewin, K. (1951). Field theory in social science. New York: Harper
Dazzani, M. V., & Faria, M. (2009). Família, escola e desem- &Row.
penho acadêmico. In M. V. Dazzani & J. A. Lordello (Eds.), Ligorio, M. B., & Tateo, L. (2008). Just for passion: Dialogical
Avaliação educacional: Atando e desatando nós. Salvador De and narrative construction of teachers’ professional iden-
Bahia, Brazil: EDUFBA. tity and educational practices. European Journal of School
Dei, M. (2000). La scuola in Italia. Bologna: Il Mulino. Psychology, 5(2), 115–142.
Doise, W. (1982). L’explication en psychologie sociale. Paris: Ligorio, M. L., & Pontecorvo, C. (2010). La scuola come contesto.
PUF. Prospettive psicologico-culturali. Rome: Carocci.
Dooremalen, H., & Borsboom, D. (2010). Metaphors in psy- Linell, P. (2009). Rethinking language, mind, and world dialogi-
chological conceptualization and explanation. In A. Toomela cally. Interactional and contextual theories of human sense-mak-
& J. Valsiner (Eds.), Methodological thinking in psychol- ing. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
ogy: 60 years gone astray?. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Lopez, A., Najafi, B., Rogoff, B., & Arauz, R. B. (2012).
Publishing. Collaborating and helping as cultural practices. In J. Valsiner
Edward, J. (1990). Language in education. In H. Giles & W. P. (Eds), Oxford handbook of culture and psychology. New York:
Robinson (Eds.), Handbook of language and social psychology. Oxford University Press.
Chichester, West Sussex, UK and New York: John Wiley and Markova, I. (2006). On “the inner alter” in dialogue. International
Sons. Journal for Dialogical Science, 1(1), 125–147.
Engeström, Y. (1987). Learning by expanding: An activity-theo- Marsico, G., Komatsu, K., & Iannaccone, A. (Eds.) (in
retical approach to developmental research. Helsinki: Orienta- press). Crossing Boundaries. Intercontextual dynamics
Konsultit. between family and school. Charlotte, NC: Information
Fele, G., & Paoletti, I. (2003). L’interazione in classe. Bologna: Age Publishing.
Il Mulino. Monteil, J-M. (1989). Eduquer et former. Grenoble, France,:
Henderson, A., & Berla, N. (1994). The family is critical to stu- Press Universitaires de Grenoble.
dent achievement. Washington, D.C.: National Committee Mugny, G., & Carugati, F. (1985). L’intelligence au pluriel.
for Citizens in Education. Cousset, Fribourg: Delval.
Herbst, D. (1995). What happens when we make a distinction: An Muller Mirza, N., Perret-Clermont, A.-N., Tartas, V., & Iannaccone,
elementary introduction to co-genetic logic. In T. Kindermann A. (2009). Psychosocial processes in argumentation. In N. Muller
& J. Valsiner (Eds.), Development of person context relations. Mirza & A.N. Perret-Clermont (Eds), Argumentation and edu-
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. cation. London and New York: Springer.

m a rsico, ia n n accon e 867


Nisbett, R. E., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies Tavory, I., Jablonka, E., & Ginsburg, S., (2012). Culture and
and shortcomings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: epigenesis: A Waddingtonian view. In J. Valsiner (Eds), Oxford
Prentice Hall. handbook of culture and psychology. New York: Oxford
Perret-Clermont, A. N. (1979). La construction de l’intelligence University Press.
dans l’interaction sociale. Berne: Peret Lang. Toomela, A., & Valsiner, J. (Eds) (2010). Methodological thinking
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. in psychology: 60 years gone astray? Charlotte, NC: Information
New York: Oxford University Press. Age Publishing.
Ross, L. (1977). The intuitive psychologist and his shortcom- Tüomi-Gröhn, T. (2007). Developmental transfer as a goal of
ings: Distortions in the attribution process. In L. Berkowitz collaboration between school and work. Action. International
(Eds.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 10). Journal of Human Activity Theory, 1, 41–62.
New York: Academic Press. Tuomi-Gröhn, T., & Engeström, Y. (Eds.) (2003). Between school
Ross, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The person and the situation: and work: New perspectives on transfer and boundary crossing.
Perspectives of social psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill. Amsterdam: Pergamon.
Schizzerotto, A. (1988). Vite ineguali. Disuguaglianze e corsi di Valsiner, J. (1987). Culture and the development of children’s
vita nell’Italia contemporanea. Bologna: Il Mulino. action. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Wiley.
Sherif, M., & Sherif, C.W. (1953). Groups in harmony and ten- Valsiner, J. (2007a). Culture in minds and societies. New Delhi,
sion: An integration of studies on intergroup relations. New India: Sage.
York: Octagon Books. Valsiner, J. (2007b). Looking across cultural gender boundar-
Sherif. M., Harvey, O. J., White, B. J., Hood, W. R., & Sherif, ies. Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 41(3–4),
C. W. (1954/1961). Intergroup conflict and cooperation: The 219–224.
Robbers Cave experiment. Valsiner, J. (2009). Integrating Psychology within the globaliz-
Simão, L. M., & Valsiner, J. (2007). Otherness in question. ing world:A requiem to the post-modernist experiment with
Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Wissenschaft. Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science,
Speltini, G., & Palmonari, A. (2007). I gruppi sociali, Bologna: 43,1–21.
Il Mulino. Waddington, C. H. (1940). Organisers and genes. Cambridge,
Steininger, B. (2008). Katalüsator—Annäherung an einen UK: Cambridge University Press.
Schlüsselbegriff das 20. Jahrhunderts. In E. Müller & F. Waddinghton, C. H. (1957). The strategies of the genes, London,
Schmieder (Eds.), Begriffsgeschichte der Naturwissenschaften UK: Allen &Unwin.
(pp. 53–71). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Zittoun, T. (2006). Transitions: Development through symbolic
Tajfel, H. (1981). Human groups and social categories. Cambridge, resources. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
UK: Cambridge University Press).

868 th e work o f scho o li ng


CHAPTER

Collaboration and Helping as


41 Cultural Practices

Angélica López, Behnosh Najafi, Barbara Rogoff, and Rebeca Mejía-Arauz

Abstract
This chapter examines children’s collaboration and helping from the perspective that understanding
prosocial development requires attention to the cultural practices and values in which children and
adults participate. Children’s ways of engaging with each other and with adults are based on practices of
their families and the current and historical practices of their communities. We examine cultural values
related to the helpfulness and propensity to collaborate that are common among Mexican, Latino/a,
and Indigenous-heritage U.S. and Canadian children, as compared with European-American middle-class
children. Central to this cultural difference are community values and practices regarding the relation of
individuals with their communities—values that can be seen in the organization of children’s families and
communities.
Keywords: Helping, collaboration, prosocial development, initiative, observation, cultural practices, his-
tory, schooling, Indigenous, Mexico

This chapter focuses on cultural and historical helping. Children show more prosocial behavior
bases of collaboration and helping. We draw atten- in contexts where such behavior is encouraged and
tion to children’s development of helpfulness and col- required or expected (Kartner, Keller, & Chaudhary,
laboration in the context of the value placed on these 2010; Nsamenang, 1992). In communities where
ways of interaction in families and communities, collaboration and helping with initiative are
for adults as well as for children. the norm, children may be encouraged to develop
Child development research often treats chil- these aspects of prosocial skill.
dren’s prosocial development as individual matura- Our cultural/historical analysis brings together
tional stages of accomplishment, as children learn community values and practices that help to make
to help others and collaborate. Helping or altruistic sense of population differences in Mexico and the
behavior is characterized as developing through nine United States in children’s collaboration and help-
stages through adolescence, originating in simple ing. A number of studies indicate that children
prosocial behavior such as responding positively to from Indigenous and Indigenous-heritage com-
others and reacting to others’ distress in infancy; munities of Mexico are especially helpful and col-
as children grow older they become more able to laborative in research settings as well as in school
detect subtle cues if someone needs help (Eisenberg and in work with their families and communities.
& Fabes, 1998). We suggest that their helpfulness and orientation
However, in communities that emphasize com- to collaborate are related to community prac-
munity-mindedness, helpfulness, and collabora- tices, values, and organization that appear to be
tion, children may be more prepared to detect such widespread in Indigenous communities of the
cues indicating that others need help and to initiate Americas.

869
Indigenous and Indigenous-Heritage Hence many Mexican families, in Mexico and
Practices of the Americas, and Schooling immigrating to the United States, have involvement
Our cultural/historical focus is on experience in communities that were historically Indigenous.
with cultural practices and values, which are distinct However, most Mexican immigrants in the United
from people’s ancestry and place of residence. We States do not live in communities that recognize
examine historical roots of cultural practices sur- themselves or are recognized as Indigenous-heritage
rounding collaboration and helping, in examining (Urrieta, 2003), and participation in Indigenous
the traces of Indigenous practices among two practices among U.S. Mexican-heritage families is
related populations: (1) Mexican children who live often not recognized.
in families or communities that identify themselves Limited maternal schooling may often serve as
as Indigenous, and (2) children whose families are an index of familiarity with Indigenous practices
likely to have ancestral ties to Mexican Indigenous among recent Mexican immigrants to the United
communities but who do not live in Indigenous States and among many Mestizo people (of mixed
communities nor even necessarily recognize Indigenous and European heritage) from rural
Indigenous roots. We suggest that both are likely Mexico (Correa-Chávez & Rogoff, 2009; López
to have experience with Indigenous communities’ et al., 2010; Silva, Correa-Chávez, & Rogoff, 2010).
practices, and examine research investigating the Because of power dynamics and unequal distribu-
extent to which this is the case. tion of resources, rural and Indigenous towns in
About 12% of the current population of Mexico is Mexico have historically had little access to Western
identified as Indigenous (CONAPO, 2005; Corona, schooling—a European and U.S.-origin institution
2001), and a large proportion of immigrants to the (Meyer, Ramirez, & Soysal, 1992; Najafi, Mejía-
United States are from Indigenous communities. Arauz, & Rogoff, 2008; Reese, 2002). Although
For example, in 2003–2004, 16–20% of California Mexican communities with limited schooling are
farmworkers were of Indigenous origins (Aguirre, not always ethnically Indigenous, Mexican com-
Intl., 2005; CONAPO, 2005.) In addition, the munities where schooling is limited are often mar-
majority of families emigrating from Mexico to the ginalized rural communities that have connections
United States come from campesino (rural) areas with Indigenous practices stemming from com-
in states such as Michoacán, Guanajuato, Oaxaca, munity history and/or from contact among neigh-
Jalisco, and Zacatecas (National Population Council boring communities, with exchange of ideas and
of Mexico, 2000) where many populations have practices.
Indigenous histories (López, Correa-Chávez, Rogoff, Families coming from pueblos that once consid-
& Gutiérrez, 2010; Lorente Fernández, 2006). ered themselves Indigenous are more likely to main-
However, because of national attempts to erase tain some Indigenous practices and have limited
such an identity in Mexico, many campesinos in schooling than families that have migrated to cit-
Mexico prefer not to identify as Indigenous-heritage ies and have more access to formal schooling (Frye,
as it is an identity that is often subordinate politi- 1996; López et al., 2010; Vigil, 1998). In a town
cally, economically, and socially (Fox, 2006; Lorente that was considered Indigenous a generation ago,
Fernández, 2010). In the early 1900s in Mexico, families have little involvement in Western schooling
there was a strong nationwide agenda to “modernize” and engage in several longstanding Indigenous prac-
the nation by cutting ties with Indigenous tradi- tices, whereas in nearby Guadalajara, people with
tions and language (Bonfil Batalla, 1987, 1988; extensive schooling in the last generation engage
Stavenhagen, 1988). In some rural pueblos (towns), in these Indigenous practices in an attenuated
people still consider themselves to be Indigenous, form, and professional families with generations of
but in others they make reference to previously schooling do not report engaging in these practices
being Indians, with a dynamic view of Indianness (Najafi, Mejía-Arauz, & Rogoff, 2008).
that focuses on changing social status and cultural We speculate that the notable helpfulness and
practices (Lorente Fernández, 2010; Urrieta, 2003). collaboration among Mexican and Mexican-heritage
In the early 1900s, many Indigenous towns were children fits with a valued cultural practice that may
transformed into campesino towns, but they often stem in part from the organization of family and group
retained recognizably Indigenous practices (Frye, work in Indigenous communities of the Americas.
1996; Lorente Fernández, 2010; Urrieta, 2003; This practice—being acomedido/a—basically involves
Vigil, 1998). being alert to surrounding events and ready to

870 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


spontaneously contribute to the direction of the range of community activities and therefore have
group. Being acomedido/a fits with a cultural tradi- less opportunities to learn through intent commu-
tion in support of learning that appears to be wide- nity participation (de León, 2000; Gaskins, 2000;
spread in Indigenous communities of the Americas— Morelli, Rogoff, & Angelillo, 2003; Rogoff, 2003).
intent community participation. In communities where young children are regularly
included in the wide range of social and produc-
tive activities, they are often in a position to observe
A Valued Learning Tradition of Indigenous
and listen to ongoing events, and they are expected
America: Intent Community Participation
to pay attention and contribute to them. In turn,
The distinctive approach to helping and working
such inclusion seems also to encourage children’s
with others demonstrated by children from fami-
active interest in knowing what is going on and in
lies with Indigenous Mexican histories is in keeping
contributing to it with initiative.
with a cultural tradition in support of learning that
The defining features of learning through intent
Rogoff and colleagues have dubbed learning through
community participation are articulated in a prism
intent community participation (Rogoff, Paradise,
with seven integrated facets, which together describe
Mejía-Arauz, Correa-Chávez, & Angelillo, 2003;
this cultural tradition for organizing learning. Here
Rogoff, Moore, Najafi, Dexter, Correa-Chávez, &
we present an updated version of the prism (Rogoff,
Solís, 2007). In this approach, children are included
2011), which continues to be under revision as we
in the wide range of activities of the community,
learn more about how to characterize this cultural
and they are encouraged and expected to learn by
tradition for organizing learning. Reading from
observing and pitching in to ongoing collaborative
the upper left-hand facet on Figure 41.1, learning
activities (Chamoux, 1992; Corona & Pérez, 2005;
through intent community participation has these
de Haan, 1999; de León, 2000; Rogoff, 2003).
seven interrelated characteristics:
Collaboration and helping (along with learning
through observation) are key aspects of learning 1. Learners are incorporated in the range
through intent community participation. of ongoing endeavors of their families and
Learning through intent community partici- communities, with expectations and opportunities
pation is a part of all children’s lives but is limited to contribute.
in communities that restrict children’s access to 2. Learners are eager to contribute, belong,
observing and participating in the range of every- and fulfill roles that are valued in their families
day activities of their community. In middle-class and communities. Other people present are
communities where high levels of schooling are involved in accomplishing the activity at hand,
prevalent, children are seldom included in a wide and may provide guidance.

3. L earning by means of:


Keen attention, during or
anticipating contributing to 4.
2. ongoing endeavor with agency. Social
Motive: Guidance from organization
Learner is community expectations of endeavors:
eager to contribute, and sometimes Collaborative.
belong, & fulfill role. other people. Learner trusted to
Others’ motive is contribute with initiative.
to accomplish endeavor Flexible leadership;
(and maybe to guide). all may guide.
1. Learner is Calm mutual pace .
incorporated
7. Assessment: of
and contributing to 5. Communication:
arrangements & progress,
family/community Coordination of
to aid contributions. shared endeavors with
endeavors.
During the endeavor. nonverbal +verbal
Thru direct feedback
conversation.
from outcome & Dramatization,
6. Goal of education:
acceptance
Transform participation narratives.
of efforts. Figure 41.1 The multifaceted prism articu-
learn demeanor, responsibility,
© Barbara Rogoff,
information, skills June 2011
lating the features of learning through intent
to contribute, belong in community. community participation.

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 871


3. Learning involves keen attention, during Collaboration among Mexican and
or in anticipation of contributing, guided by Indigenous-Heritage Children of the
community-wide expectations of responsible Americas
contribution and sometimes by other people. Cultural Differences in Children’s Extent
4. Social organization involves collaborative and Means of Collaboration
engagement in family and community endeavors, To our knowledge, all of the available investiga-
with flexible leadership and trust in learners tions comparing cultural backgrounds find more, or
to take initiative, along with others who also at least as much, collaboration among Indigenous
participate at a calm mutual pace. and Indigenous-heritage and Mexican children
5. Communication occurs through as compared with those with less experience with
coordination of shared endeavors through Indigenous practices, including European-American
articulate nonverbal conversation and children. Several of the studies have uncovered dif-
parsimonious verbal means, as well as through ferent ways of coordinating among children from
narratives and dramatization that contextualize different backgrounds.
information and ideas. Mexican-heritage children have shown a more
6. The goal of education is transformation cooperative orientation than European-heritage
of participation, which involves learning to children in game situations (Kagan & Madsen,
collaborate, with appropriate consideration and 1971, 1972; Knight & Kagan, 1977; Nelson,
responsibility, as well as learning information and Kagan, & Gumbiner, 1982). Also, Mexican-
skills to be responsible contributors belonging in heritage children from regions of Mexico with
the community. Indigenous history more often attempted to
7. Assessment includes evaluation of the become collaboratively involved in their sibling’s
success of the arrangements as well as the learner’s toy-building instruction than did Mexican-heritage
progress, in support of learners’ contributions, children whose parents had extensive experience
during the endeavor. Feedback is direct, from with Western schooling (Silva et al., 2010).
the outcome of learners’ efforts and the acceptance A study of sibling collaboration found wide-
(or not) by others of the efforts as productive spread collaboration but with different ways of
contributions. (Rogoff, 2011) coordinating among the three siblings (Angelillo
& Rogoff, 2005). Sibling triads, aged 5 years to 15
This chapter focuses on the first three facets in years, spent almost all their time collaborating as a
examining research on children’s collaboration and threesome or at least touching base with each other
helping with initiative and keen attention to ongo- in exploring a miniature museum exhibit, in both
ing events. In addition, our suggestion that the cul- European-heritage and Mexican-heritage children
tural value of being acomedido/a helps understand from the United States (with mothers averaging
Mexican-heritage children’s collaboration and helping 17 grades and 8 grades of schooling, respectively).
with initiative highlights an aspect of the fifth facet. In an average of only 7% of the time segments for
After reviewing research on cultural differences both backgrounds were any of the three siblings not
in helping and collaboration, we argue that the coordinating with or monitoring the others.
cultural value of being acomedido/a contributes However, the ways that the children coordinated
to the explanation of cultural differences in stud- with each other varied in the two backgrounds
ies of helpfulness and collaboration, and we draw (Angelillo & Rogoff, 2005). The European-heritage
attention to cultural differences in keen observa- U.S. siblings usually coordinated with each other
tion and listening, which are an important part of by dividing up access to the exhibit by explicitly
knowing when to pitch in and help. We also relate negotiating whose turn it would be (in 62% of the
cultural differences in collaboration and helping 30-second time intervals). They often interrupted
to historical changes in the circumstances of and each other’s exploration agendas and discussed how
assumptions about childhood in the United States to manage turn-taking, whose turn it was, and how
and Mexico. We argue that children’s prosocial long turns would be; their turn-taking negotiations
development is based not only on the growth of sometimes included friction: “But you’ve had a
individual children but also deeply reflects the lot of turns. We haven’t even gotten to touch that
social organization and valued practices of their thing.” Among the Mexican-heritage U.S. sibling
communities. groups, turn-taking occurred half as often (in 31%

872 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


of the time intervals in which the siblings were coor- smoothly done and, apparently at least, with no
dinating with each other), and when turn-taking disagreements or negotiating.
occurred, it generally was smooth and undisputed, (Paradise & de Haan, 2009, pp. 192–193)
with few interruptions of each other’s turns. The
Mexican-heritage U.S. siblings’ intervals of coor-
Cultural Differences in Staying Engaged
dination without dividing up turns often seemed
When Not Directly Interacting
to involve coordination by fluidly blending their
There also appear to be cultural differences in
agendas together, combining their interests.
remaining engaged when another child has a more
Turn-taking may be a strategy, like division
active role. When their partner took a more leading
of labor, for subdividing an activity or access to
role in instructing a younger child how to play a game,
resources, contrasting with engagement together
pairs of Navajo children remained more engaged than
with a common agenda. European-American chil-
European-heritage children. The European-heritage
dren relied on turn-taking more than Navajo chil-
children more often became sidetracked and inatten-
dren when pairs of 9-year-olds were asked to teach a
tive or made statements that repeated or were unre-
7-year-old to play a game (Ellis & Gauvain, 1992).
lated to their peer’s previous statements, whereas the
When asked to work on group projects, Warm
Navajo children were more likely to extend or support
Springs Indian students in Oregon worked together
information given by their peer to instruct the youn-
effectively without intervention from the teacher,
ger child (Ellis & Gauvain, 1992).
whereas Anglo students often disputed over turns,
In a study of collaboration among U.S. Mexican-
who would lead, and how to carry out the tasks,
or European-heritage 7- to 9-year-old children con-
requiring teacher intervention (Philips, 1983).
structing a three-dimensional wooden honeybee
Similarly, European-American middle-class
puzzle according to a model, Najafi and Rogoff
mothers commonly regulated their toddlers’ and
(2007) also found differences in the children’s col-
young children’s access to desired objects through
laboration and their staying on track when another
turn-taking, and they reported enforcing turn-taking
child took the lead (see Fig. 41.2). The children’s
to manage disputes between their young children;
communities differed in Indigenous histories and
these strategies were almost never used or reported
experience in Western schooling across generations.
by Guatemalan Mayan mothers (Mosier & Rogoff,
The 13 European-American triads were from fam-
2003). The Mayan 3- to 5-year-olds often got access
ilies with extensive schooling—their mothers aver-
to a desired object by blending agendas with the tod-
aged 14 grades of schooling and most of their grand-
dler, such as by helping the toddler with the object
parents had completed at least 12 grades of school,
or enhancing the toddler’s efforts with the object,
as is common among European-American popula-
rather than trying to get it away from the toddler,
tions (Bronfenbrenner, 1992). The 16 triads of chil-
unlike the European-American middle-class 3- to
dren whose families had immigrated to the United
5-year-olds. The Mayan siblings’ collaboration with
States from Indigenous-heritage regions of Mexico
the toddler involved little intervention from their
had mothers with an average of 7 grades of school-
mothers.
ing; their grandparents had usually completed less
Fifth- and sixth-graders in a Mazahua Indigenous
than 6 grades. (Most of the children were born in
community (in central Mexico) worked in small
the United States; most of their parents were born
groups with smooth and flexible roles, in figuring
in Mexico.) The children of both backgrounds had
out how to install panes of glass into window frames
similar amounts of experience making 3D puzzles
in a school construction project:
and model toys.
Each decided what to do and when to do it by The Mexican-heritage children from a community
coordinating his or her activities with the others of with Indigenous history usually worked with at least
the group . . . At no time was there any sign of tension one other child either in dyads or as a coordinated
or of one member of the group disputing when ensemble with all three children pitching in together
another took over the more active role. Neither were and staying in touch, in 72% of the 30-second
there signs of children in any way asking or signaling time segments, compared with 57% of the seg-
when they were about to ‘take over,’ or that it was ments for European-heritage U.S. children whose
their ‘turn.’ On the contrary, there was no way to families had generations of extensive experience
foretell when the role switching between performer with Western schooling (and related traditions). In
and observer-supporter would take place. It was turn, the triads of European-heritage U.S. children

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 873


Figure 41.2 Three Mexican-heritage chil-
dren work together to assemble a honeybee
puzzle according to a completed model, in
the foreground.

from families with extensive Western schooling had & John, 1971; Deyhle, 1991; Lipka, 1991; Romney
a higher proportion of segments in which they did & Romney, 1963). Children often take on helpful
not work with others in their triad (Najafi & Rogoff, roles where they are responsible for family work and
2007; see also Correa-Chávez, 2010), and they more caring for young siblings and for animals, contrib-
often went off task. Occasions when one or two of uting to celebrations and festivals, and serving as
the children were off-task for more than half of the language brokers for their parents (Alcalá, Rogoff,
30-second segment were twice as frequent among Mejía-Arauz, Coppens, & Roberts, 2011; Delgado-
the European-heritage U.S. triads than among the Gaitán, 1987; Gaskins, 2000; González, Moll, &
triads of Mexican-heritage U.S. children from a Amantí, 2005; Lorente Fernández, 2010; Maynard,
community with Indigenous history (23% of the 2002; Nájera-Ramírez, 1997; Orellana, 2001;
segments versus 11%). Orellana, Dorner, & Pulido, 2003; Tharp, Estrada,
Thus, the comparative findings indicate that Dalton, & Yamauchi, 2000; Urrieta, 2010; Weisner
children from communities with Indigenous- & Gallimore, 1977). Children’s involvement in such
American histories are more, or at least as, likely to activities is often more common in Mexican and
collaborate than children from families with exten- Indigenous-heritage communities than in European-
sive Western schooling (and related) experience. American middle-class communities (Farver, 1993;
The collaboration among children from communi- Telzer & Fuligni, 2009; Whiting & Edwards, 1988;
ties with Indigenous American histories seems to be Whiting & Whiting, 1975; Zukow, 1989).
more fluid and less likely to involve turn-taking to The children’s contributions often fit with the
divide the activity, and the children appear to be organization of family and community endeavors,
more engaged when not directly involved. which ethnographic work in various Indigenous-
Children’s collaborative strategies are likely to be history communities characterizes as involving
related to familiarity with distinct formats for inter- wide-ranging multi-way horizontal collaborations
action, as they develop repertoires of cultural prac- with respect for individual autonomy (Lamphere,
tice based on their experiences in the surrounding 1977; Paradise, 1987, 1996; Paradise & de Haan,
social and societal organization (Gutiérrez & Rogoff, 2009; Sindell, 1997). For example, Pelletier (1970)
2003). This calls attention to the organization of the described a form of horizontal collaboration in an
institutions and communities in which children and Indigenous community in Canada where everyone
their families participate. contributed as they were needed, “observing and
feeling” the process of life and work (p. 21). The
The Organization of Collaboration within collaboration was community-wide, exemplified by
Families and Communities of the Americas the smooth, horizontal organization of community
Collaboration in family and community work events such as banquets and funerals. When outsiders
from early ages is common in Indigenous and tried to impose a hierarchical organization on such
Indigenous-heritage communities of the Americas, events, the organization of community events
including many Mexican rural communities (Cazden became much less effective.

874 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


The horizontal organization noted in a variety of become parents, their interactions with their children
Indigenous communities of the Americas resembles may reflect the practices related to schooling that
the teamwork described by Senge (1990) in very suc- they have experienced (Chavajay, 2006; LeVine
cessful teams. Such teams show alignment, which is et al., 1991; Mejía-Arauz, Rogoff, & Paradise, 2005;
when a group of people function as a whole, comple- Richman, Miller, & LeVine, 1992; Rogoff, Mistry,
menting each other’s efforts with common direction Göncü, & Mosier, 1993).
and harmonizing individual energies. “Individuals For example, when Guatemalan Mayan mothers
do not sacrifice their personal interests to the larger with extensive Western schooling constructed a puz-
team vision; rather, the shared vision becomes an zle with three related children, they took on a role
extension of their personal visions” (pp. 234–235). resembling the managerial, hierarchical approach
Senge illustrated these points with the alignment common among school teachers, often dividing
within leading sports teams and jazz ensembles that the group into solo or dyadic teams (Chavajay &
are “in the groove.” The process includes sponta- Rogoff, 2002; parallel results were found among
neity, innovations, and coordinated action, “where other Mayan families interacting with fathers, see
each team member remains conscious of other team Chavajay, 2008). Mayan mothers from the same
members and can be counted on to act in ways that town whose families engaged in relatively traditional
complement each others’ actions” (p. 236). Mayan practices were more likely to interact with the
three children in multi-way collaboration, with all of
Solo Work Related to Western Schooling, in the participants working together in a coordinated
Contrast with Collaboration manner where everyone contributed to the task.
Solo involvement is common in Western school- Similarly, European-American and Mexican-
ing (Au & Mason, 1981; McCollum, 1989; Mehan, heritage U.S. children whose mothers had exten-
1979; Philips, 1983). In classroom settings, biases sive experience with Western schooling more often
sometimes occur against groups with cooperative social worked as dyads or alone in the presence of two
orientations, and competitive or solo-performance other children, during an origami paper-folding
orientations are often favored (Widaman & Kagan, demonstration (Mejía-Arauz, Rogoff, Dexter, &
1987). Common practices of Western schooling— Najafi, 2007). U.S. Mexican-heritage children from
such as enforcement of turn-taking, individual work communities with Indigenous histories more often
assignments, individual rewards, and punishment of collaborated as an ensemble with the two other
students who aid each other—may often discourage members of the triad.
students from helping each other (Graves & Graves, In a follow-up study, U.S. children of both
1983; Kagan, 1984; McClintock, 1974; Ramírez & European and Mexican heritage showed less collab-
Castañeda, 1974; Whiting & Whiting, 1975). oration as a whole group than children from three
A contrast between cooperative adult-child and Mexican backgrounds. However, no differences
teacher-directed approaches is clear in a study ask- appeared in extent of collaboration among children
ing Mexican Mazahua parents and non-Mazahua residing in communities in Mexico that varied in
teachers to put together a market stall with a Indigenous histories and in experience with Western
Mazahua child. The parents treated the children schooling (Mejía-Arauz, Roberts, & Rogoff, 2008).
as part of the endeavor throughout, welcoming The authors suggested that the social organization of
their contributions and suggestions as responsible the children’s schooling might have canceled out the
and active collaborators (de Haan, 1999, 2001). In expected differences in the social organization that
contrast, local teachers took charge, assigning and might occur in their families. The Mexican children
dividing parts and evaluating how well the task had whose mothers had extensive Western schooling
been carried out. In general, the teachers did not attended a school that encouraged collaboration,
engage with the children in the task and did not whereas the Mexican children from a historically
welcome their suggestions. Indigenous town (and whose mothers had only
Family involvement in Western schooling (and basic schooling) attended a school that emphasized
related practices) may compete with experience with solo work. It makes sense that children’s modes of
Indigenous community practices. Among families working together are related not only to their fami-
with extensive Western schooling, children’s indi- lies’ practices but also to their experience in school
vidual solo efforts may be encouraged in division of (Matusov, Bell, & Rogoff, 2002). Children’s col-
family labor and individual rewards. When students laboration and helping develop with experience

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 875


with their communities’ practices and institutions, We speculate that the value system of being
which may vary in values regarding collaboration acomedido/a may stem in part from an Indigenous
and helping. emphasis on collaboration, collective action, and
In addition to their experience with the prac- horizontal social relations where everybody helps
tices of schooling, families with extensive school- out. The concept of tequio (derived from the
ing are likely to have experience with a whole Náhuatl word cuatequitl meaning communal work)
constellation of related practices that are often is a way that work is organized to benefit the col-
characteristic of middle-class cultural traditions. lective. This is a practice that has been prevalent
Beyond providing experience with a distinctive in Indigenous communities of Mexico, apparently
form of social organization where helping others since pre-Hispanic times. It involves service or
is often discouraged and children’s work is often work for a community project such as constructing
solo, extensive Western schooling connects with roads, other public service projects or the intro-
a set of related practices. These include bureau- duction of new services such as formal schooling,
cratic occupations, cosmopolitan living arrange- potable water, and clinics. Tequio has been essen-
ments, small nuclear families, age segregation, tial for marginal communities as one of the most
and limited contributions by children to child vigorous institutions for perseverance and solidarity
care and family work, as well as less likelihood of the community; it is sustained with egalitarian
of being involved with traditional Indigenous discourse (Warman, 2003). The practice of commu-
practices (Rogoff & Angelillo, 2002; Rogoff, nity contributions has also been adapted to reflect
Correa-Chávez, & Navichoc Cotuc, 2005). modern day realities. Many Mexican immigrants
In the next section, we offer the idea that the col- in the United States routinely send money to build
laborative orientation of children and their families infrastructure and prepare fiestas for towns in which
in Indigenous and Indigenous-history communities they no longer physically live.
may be understood in the context of a cultural value The concept of being acomedido/a fits with
system that emphasizes helping with initiative, that ethnographic research that indicates that collabora-
is, being acomedido/a. tion and helping is expected and often voluntarily
offered among Indigenous-heritage and Mexican-
A Cultural Value Promoting Helping with heritage children (de Haan, 2001; Delgado-Gaitán,
Initiative: Being Acomedido/a 1987; Lamphere, 1977; Paradise, 1996; Tharp,
The cultural value of being acomedido/a may Estrada, Dalton, & Yamauchi, 2000; Valenzuela,
relate to the extent of collaboration and helping 1999; Weisner, Gallimore, & Jordan, 1988). In
among Mexican-heritage children. According many Indigenous Mexican-heritage and Mexican-
to interviews by López (in preparation), many American communities, children readily contribute
Mexicans define being acomedido/a as helping not to ongoing activities in responsible helping rela-
because one has been asked to but because one acts tions, especially in caring for younger children and
on an opportunity to pitch in. Such coordinated in multi-age teams responsible for family work
and collaborative interactions are characterized by (Delgado-Gaitán, 1994; Maynard, 2002; Orellana,
ready helping. 2001; Ramírez & Castañeda, 1974).
The cultural value of being acomedido/a has For example, all 3- to 17-year-old children in a
rarely been the topic of academic discourse. We formerly Nahua town near Mexico City helped in
have only found the work of González (2001, their families’ household, farm, and forestry activi-
2006), who described being acomedido/a as being ties from 3 to 7 hours daily and reported that their
able to accommodate to the surroundings and activities were satisfying (Ramírez Sánchez, 2007).
make oneself useful. González described this as In another Indigenous-heritage town in central
a common teaching among Mexican parents, to México, children spontaneously join their elders
teach children to be acomedido/a(s) to fit in wher- in a complex organization of collective voluntary
ever they may find themselves by being able to work (cuatequitl). “In the absence of any coercive
empathize with others’ needs in order to work col- attitude or pressure in order for them to do their
lectively. She described the mothers’ narratives in work, children are enabled to find the jobs they like
her study as teaching their children to be aware of best, always in coordination with others” (Corona
their surroundings and interpret sometimes hidden & Pérez, 2005, p. 8). Older children in Mexican
meanings to what is said. heritage families in the United States and in Mexico

876 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


often help and guide younger children in how to observe and directly interact with their peers; this
do things like braid hair, tie shoes, carry out chores, was described by Inuit teachers as “students helping
and do homework (Azmitia, Cooper, García, & each other” (Eriks-Brophy & Crago, 2003). Though
Dunbar, 1996; Valdés, 1996). such behavior is often penalized, this method may
In cultural contexts where prosocial behavior and be a primary form of classroom interaction for
social responsiveness are important values, a recip- some students (Delgado-Gaitán & Trueba, 1985;
rocal orientation is expected. Childhood is a system Mercado, 2001; Paradise & de Haan, 2009; Trueba
of reciprocity and exchange among the Nahuas of & Delgado-Gaitán, 1985). It may reflect the value
Tlaxcala, Mexico, where everyone helps members of placed on helping with initiative, in the concept of
their family, especially those in the same household being acomedido/a.
(Ramírez Sánchez, 2007). The Nahua children in
Tlaxcala claim not to be working even when heavily A Study of Children Helping with Initiative
involved in family work. They describe their involve- During an origami paper-folding demonstra-
ment as just “helping” as a matter of being part tion, cultural differences appeared in the extent
of the family, and regard “working” as paid work to which children helped each other with initia-
outside the family. tive or in response to other children’s requests
for help (such as when another child asked “Can
The Centrality of Initiative in Helping you show me how to do that?” or “How did you
In helping others without being asked, children do that?” or slid the paper figure toward the child
act with initiative and also with a sense of interde- with an imploring expression; Najafi, Mejía-Arauz,
pendence with others (Kartner et al., 2010; Paradise & Rogoff, 2005). Triads of 6- to 10-year-old chil-
& de Haan, 2009). Among the Mazahua of Mexico, dren were from one of three cultural backgrounds
“children learn to behave in ways that produce a in a California town that has a high proportion of
high degree of apparently unplanned coordination, immigrants from rural regions of Michoacán and
cooperation, and integration, yet [with] each indi- Jalisco, Mexico: 10 triads of U.S. Mexican-heritage
vidual child [following] his or her own path without children from backgrounds likely to include experi-
being ‘organized’ by anybody else” (Paradise, 1987, ence with Indigenous practices (with mothers who
p. 206). had completed an average of 7 grades), 10 triads of
Comparative studies indicate that Indigenous- U.S. European heritage middle-class children whose
heritage Mexican children more often pitch in to mothers had completed an average of 15 grades, and
help with family activities with initiative, simply as 11 triads of U.S. Mexican heritage children whose
members of the household, compared to Mexican- mothers had completed an average of 13 grades.
heritage children whose families have less connec- A research assistant showed the children how to
tion with Indigenous practices and more experience fold their origami figures, following a script that
in Western schooling (Alcalá et al., 2011). Mexican encouraged them to help each other as each child
Indigenous-heritage children often underplayed folded a paper figure. Most of the help given by
their extensive contributions to household work the children was in the form of a demonstration,
and spoke of their work in collective terms, whereas across all three backgrounds; there were also small
Mexican children whose families had extensive amounts of fixing another child’s figure, monitoring
schooling played up their more limited contribu- and verifying another’s folding, and explanation (see
tions in individual terms (Coppens, Alcalá, Mejía- Fig. 41.3).
Arauz, & Rogoff, 2011). However, Mexican chil- The U.S. Mexican-heritage triads composed of
dren of both backgrounds claimed that children children whose families are likely to be familiar
should help their families by pitching in to help with Indigenous practices (whose mothers had
with household work, simply to be responsible, like only basic schooling) often spontaneously offered
anyone else in the family. to help other children, without being requested
Such helping with initiative has also been to help. They did so more often than triads of
found in classroom settings with Indigenous and European-American and U.S. Mexican-heritage
Mexican-heritage children. Inuit (Canadian) chil- children whose mothers had extensive Western
dren have been found to share information in order schooling (averaging 2.0 times versus 1.2 and 0.7
to help their peers (Eriks-Brophy & Crago, 2003). times, respectively). There were not significant dif-
Inuit children often walked around the room to ferences between the backgrounds in the extent of

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 877


Figure 41.3 A triad folds their origami figures;
the Origami Lady is seated to the right, facing
the children, just off camera.

help in response to another child’s request for help. Mi madre me enseñó a saber ayudar. Eso fue el primer
(However, children from the Mexican-heritage conocimiento que yo tuve. Me dió responsabilidad desde
backgrounds with basic or extensive maternal temprana edad.
schooling helped in response to 70% and 85% of [My mother taught me to know when to pitch in.
other children’s requests for help, respectively, com- That was one of the first things I learned. She gave
pared with European-heritage children responding me responsibilities at a young age.]
to 51% of other children’s requests for help; Najafi, (54-year-old male taxi driver)
Mejia-Arauz, & Rogoff, 2005.)
Helping with initiative may support smooth Participants were also asked if they felt there was
coordination among members of a group. Thus a a difference in the prevalence of the cultural value of
child who notices another child’s error in folding being acomedido/a in different regions of Mexico,
could quickly reach over and offer help that is read- for example, in a small town or in a metropolitan
ily accepted. The pace of the activity would not be city like Guadalajara or Mexico City. Of the 15
interrupted as it would if the child had to ask for respondents who responded to the question, 14
help and then wait for it. (93%) said that people in small towns were more
acomedidos/as. For example,

Mexican Adults Explain “Being Definitivamente sí, hay diferencias increíbles porque
Acomedido/a” en el rancho se nota la diferencia y gente es como, y no
To examine the concept of “being acomedido/a,” quiero decir que es gente pobre porque también hay
López informally interviewed 17 adults in gente con lana pero sí, gente más sencilla, entonces hay
Guadalajara, México regarding how they define and gente con más de esa actitud.
use the term. All 17 adults were familiar with the [Definitely, there’s incredible differences because in
term and did not have trouble describing it. They the hamlets, you can see the difference and
reported that being acomedido/a connotes having people are like, and I don’t want to say poor people
human quality, humility, and educación in which because there’s also people with money but yes the
one helps spontaneously, without being asked and people are simpler, there’s people with more of that
without thinking of getting anything in return. attitude.]
It differs from simply helping in that helping can (29-year-old female research assistant)
imply doing something from a feeling of obligation
Another respondent explained,
or having been asked, but in being acomedido/a the
desire to help comes from within. Pienso que en la cuidad se da menos, como la gente anda
Many of the adults stressed that being acomedido/a tan a la carrera y tiene miles de actividades y como que
has to do with the values that are inculcated early in ya no se da tan espontáneamente eso. A diferencia de las
childhood. One participant explained, poblaciones más pequeñas, yo creo que sí se da más.

878 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


[I think there’s less of it in the city, because people are with children with less connection with Indigenous
in such a hurry and have thousands of activities and practices and more family experience in Western
it’s like that isn’t done as spontaneously. In contrast schooling (Correa-Chávez & Rogoff, 2009; López,
with smaller towns, I think it’s seen more.] Correa-Chávez, Rogoff, & Gutiérrez, 2010; Silva,
(52-year-old female professor) Correa-Chávez, & Rogoff, 2010; Silva, Shimpi, &
Rogoff, 2009).
A 29-year-old research assistant explained that
Traditionally, in Indigenous communities of the
to be acomedido/a, one has to be aware of the sur-
Americas, observation has been a prevalent method
roundings, be attentive, and be ready to pitch in
of learning that includes children’s active engage-
when necessary, knowing when and how to con-
ment in the range of their community’s work and
tribute. When asked about what it means to be
social activities, as they learn through intent com-
acomedido/a, she responded:
munity participation (Chamoux, 1992; Corona &
Yo creo que ser acomedido es tener sobre todo la Pérez, 2005; de Haan, 1999; de Leon, 2000; Rogoff,
iniciativa, o sea, como no esperar a que te lo pidan, sino 2003; Rogoff et al., 2003, 2007). For example,
tener esa iniciativa para hacerlo, pero también tener la adults in a Mazahua community in Mexico describe
visión y la sensibilidad de saber cuando es el momento observation as a more crucial and direct way of
para hacer las cosas. Y además, sí, tienes que a veces conveying knowledge and learning than actually
tener conocimiento de la situación porque si yo quiero giving directions during work situations, especially
ser acomedida en algo pero no sé de que se trata, pues a when dealing with more complex skills and knowl-
veces estorbas más de lo que ayudas. edge (de Haan, 1999). Because young children are
[I think that being acomedido is to have above regularly included in a wide range of social and
all initiative, that is to say, not waiting to be asked, productive activities of their community, they are
but having the initiative to do it, but also having often in a position to observe and listen to ongoing
the vision and the sensitivity to know when is the events, and they are expected to pay attention to be
moment to do things. And also, yes, you do have to able to contribute to them. In turn, such inclusion
sometimes have knowledge of the situation because seems also to encourage children’s active interest in
if I want to be acomedida in something but I don’t knowing what is going on and in contributing to it
even know what it’s about, well sometimes you (Paradise & Rogoff, 2009).
would disturb more than you help.]

A common proverb echoes this respondent’s Distinct Conceptions of Childhood


explanation that one does not want to be a nui- Historically, several distinct conceptions of
sance when helping because of not knowing what childhood met up and are interwoven in the lives
is going on, but rather useful by being alert and of families with roots in Indigenous communities
ready to help: “El acomedido siempre queda mal [the of Mexico: those stemming from Indigenous prac-
acomedido person always winds up looking bad].” tices and values and those that came with Spanish,
This proverb highlights the importance of keenly British, French, and U.S. formal schooling and col-
observing ongoing activities and knowing when and onization. In communities where learning through
how to pitch in. People are sometimes criticized for intent community participation is prevalent, chil-
being too acomedido/a(s) if their actions are inter- dren are often included as participants in the com-
preted as being in others’ business. Thus, the con- munity along with everyone else and are encour-
cept of being acomedido/a involves being attentive, aged to pitch in helpfully (with or without use of
keenly observing surrounding events, to be able to the term acomedido/a). They are treated as people
appropriately pitch in with initiative. whose contribution and initiative are valuable to
the group.
Keen Attention as a Basis for Taking In contrast, in modern Western societies child-
Initiative in Being Acomedido/a hood is often treated as a period of continuous
Keen attention to surrounding events is essen- dependency in which children are considered not
tial to being acomedido/a, to know when and in to be able to act independently (Strathern, 1988).
what way to pitch in. Comparative studies indicate In this sense, children are consumers of care and
that children from communities with Indigenous are seen as inadequate to meet their needs of being
American histories more often attended keenly to clothed and fed through production activities
an interaction not directed toward them, compared (Hecht, 1998; Ramírez Sánchez, 2007).

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 879


In Mexico, current childrearing practices of the Sánchez, 2007, p. 90). The definition of a good
middle class, such as child-focused activities and child in this community includes “being a child that
age segregation, were highly influenced by discourse helps out,” which is similar to ideas related to being
regarding childhood at los Congresos Panamericanos acomedido/a. As one participant in this research
del Niño [Panamerican Congress on Children], explained, people do not want to be labeled or want
which began in 1916 (Corona Caraveo, 2003). their children to be labeled as desacomedida/o (un-
During 1916 to 1935, discussions on childhood acomedida/o). Ramírez Sánchez (2007) describes
revolved around “improving the race,” focusing on work and icnoliz (the Nahuatl word for respect) as
the majority of children who were impoverished going hand in hand, where the reward of work is to
children of Indigenous communities, mestizos, give respect as well, and mutual respect is instilled
negros (of African descent) and criollos (of European to maintain good relationships. In this Nahua com-
descent) whom the state tried to “purify” racially. munity, the child is seen as a complete social actor
The goal was to make them more like children of from the moment of birth, contrasting with ideas
the upper and middle classes, whose childhood in Western societies where childhood is conceptual-
was populated with toys, children’s literature, and ized as dependence on adults and a child must go
child-focused educational methods. The middle- through several stages to learn to be a contributing
class household was considered a private domain member of their community.
and children’s education was considered a tool to
open doors for individuality in life, without col- The Importance of Individual and
lective goals. This concept differed radically from Cultural Processes in Research on Human
childhood in rural and farmworking communities Development
where members defined themselves in terms of col- Throughout the twentieth century, psychologi-
lective work and solidarity. According to authors cal research on childhood was oriented around con-
of this time (1916–1935), there was no clear dif- trolled research situations that produced a tendency
ferentiation between adult and child work, in con- to examine developmental processes and mental
trast with the upper and middle classes (Corona functions of childhood without consideration
Caraveo, 2003). of cultural or historical processes (Cole, 1996).
Social welfare programs have had heavy influ- During the second half of that century and since
ence on how childhood has been viewed in Mexico. then, the role of culture and social arrangements in
Compulsory schooling took effect in Mexico in 1917 children’s development has become clear, thanks to
for grades 1–6 and in 1993 for grades 7–9, although the work of many scholars, especially the Whitings,
many children continued to drop out before com- Bronfenbrenner, Bruner, Cole, and Scribner, and
pleting 9th grade (Ley General de Educación, art. the influence of Vygotsky.
4). The Oportunidades program (which began in In order to understand helpfulness and collabo-
2002, but formerly operated as Progresa since 1997) ration in Mexican-heritage children, the family and
provides cash payments to low-income families in community practices in which children participate
exchange for regular school attendance as well as need to be examined, moving away from focusing
family participation in talks aimed at changes in solely on individuals as they mature or assuming
parenting, producing social and cultural transfor- that their environments match those in which the
mations (Escobar Latapí, 2009). These programs researchers grew up. Childhood and family func-
have segregated children from the range of activi- tions are tied to the histories of communities and
ties of their communities and discouraged children’s nations, including their education policy, national-
contributions to the ongoing work of their families ism, and colonization.
and communities. In particular, the cultural value of being
However, views on childhood in Indigenous and acomedido/a appears to be related to Mexican
Indigenous-heritage communities can still be con- national and Indigenous communities’ interrela-
trasted with those of Western societies. For example, tions. The Indigenous practices of inclusion of chil-
children in a Tlaxcala Nahua community are still dren in nearly full community functioning may be a
considered contributors to the family’s economy, source for the cultural value of being acomedido/a,
although now they attend school. “Work plays a key even in the face of industrial and colonial pressures
role in that period of life rather than being a prob- to individualize. Indigenous practices may even
lem that undermines and harms children” (Ramírez have spread to the colonizing populations, yielding

880 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


cultural values that persist for many Mexican and work in Indigenous-heritage and cosmopolitan communities
Mexican-immigrant populations beyond particular in México. Unpublished manuscript.
Angelillo, C., & Rogoff, B. (2005, September). Coordination
Indigenous communities. This may help to explain among siblings of European American middle-class and
the widespread findings of collaboration and keen Mexican-descent engaging with a science exhibit. Presented at
attention among these populations. the meetings of the International Society for Cultural and
We have tried to move beyond the view of Activity Research, Seville, Spain.
helpfulness and extent of collaboration as solely Au, K., & Mason, J. (1981). Social organizational factors in
learning to read: The balance of rights hypothesis. Reading
individual characteristics and have suggested Research Quarterly, 17, 115–152.
that a view of community dynamics is necessary Azmitia, M., Cooper, C. R., García, E. E., & Dunbar, N. D.
to understand such practices. The cultural value (1996). The ecology of family guidance in low-income
of being acomedido/a sheds light on research on Mexican-American and European-American families. Social
helpfulness and collaboration among Mexican- Development, 5, 1–23.
Bonfil Batalla, G. (1987). El México profundo, una civilización
heritage and Indigenous-heritage communities of negada. México City, Mexico: Grijalbo.
the Americas. Bonfil Batalla, G. (1988). Panorama étnico y cultural de México
Likewise, analyses of cultural values and prac- [Ethnic and cultural panorama of Mexico]. In R. Stavenhagen
tices can illuminate the extent and means of col- (Ed.), Política cultural para un país multiétnico [Cultural policy
laboration and helping among children who have for a multiethnic country] (pp. 61–68). Mexico City, Mexico:
Secretaría de Educación Pública.
experience with other cultural practices, including Bronfenbrenner, U. (1992). Child care in the Anglo-Saxon
those of Western schooling. Historical analyses are mode. In M. E. Lamb, K. J. Sternberg, C. P. Hwang, &
indispensable to understanding the origin of such A. G. Broberg (Eds.), Child care in context (pp. 281–291).
values and practices in the context of the roles of Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
children in a community. Historical analyses are Cazden, C. B., & John, V. P. (1971). Learning in American
Indian children. In M. L. Wax, S. Diamond, & F. O.
key to understanding the dispersal and transfor- Gearing (Eds.), Anthropological perspectives on education
mations of cultural practices with changes across (pp. 252–272). New York: Basic Books.
generations and with contact and mobility of com- Chamoux, M.-N. (1992). Aprendiendo de otro modo [Learning
munities. The study of childhood needs to take in other ways]. In M.-N. Chamoux (Ed.), Trabajo, técnicas
into account worldwide changes and conditions y aprendizaje en el México indígena [Work, skills and learning
in Indigenous Mexico] (pp. 73–93). México City: Centro de
in which children are developing, contexts that Investigaciones y Estudios Superiores en Antropología Social,
may be distant from the conditions that inspired Ediciones de la Casa Chata.
psychological theories based on recent Western Chavajay, P. (2006). How Mayan mothers with different amounts
cultural traditions. of schooling organize a problem-solving discussion with chil-
dren. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 30,
371–382.
Acknowledgments Chavajay, P. (2008). Organizational patterns in problem solv-
We are grateful for the participation of the children and the
ing among Mayan fathers and children. Developmental
assistance of the teachers and principals of Starlight, Valencia,
Psychology, 44, 882–888.
Loyola Village, El Dorado, and Sierra Vista Elementary Schools
Chavajay, P., & Rogoff, B. (2002). Schooling and traditional col-
in the research reported here. We especially thank Eileen
laborative social organization of problem solving by Mayan
Fuller, Noni Reis, Maureen Callanan, Catherine Cooper, and
mothers and children. Developmental Psychology, 38, 55–66.
Nameera Akhtar. The research was carried out with support from
Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology. A once and future discipline.
CONACYT (Mexico), a traineeship from the National Institute
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
of Health (1 T32-MH20025), a grant from the National Science
CONAPO (2005). Carpeta Informativa 2005. Retrieved July 9,
Foundation (Grant No. 0837898), a UC Santa Cruz Presidential
2007 from http://www.conapo.gob.mx/prensa/carpeta2005
Dissertation Award, and the University of California Santa Cruz
Consejo Nacional de Población [National Population Council
Foundation endowed chair held by Barbara Rogoff. Author
of Mexico] (2000). Geografía de la migración México–Estados
Mejía-Arauz is now affiliated with the ITESO University in
Unidos [Geography of Mexico–U.S. migration]. Retrieved on
Guadalajara, Mexico.
July 1, 2009 from http://www.conapo.gob.mx/ publica-
ciones/intensidadmig/cap04.pdf
References Coppens, A., Alcalá, L., Mejía-Arauz, R., & Rogoff, B. (2011).
Aguirre, International (2005, June). The California farm labor Children’s initiative in family household work in Mexico.
force overview and trends from the national agricultural work- Unpublished manuscript.
ers survey. Retrieved June 16, 2007 from the University of Corona, R. (2001), Tamaño de la población indígena
California Agricultural Personnel Management Program web- mexicana. La población de México en el nuevo siglo, CONAPO.
site: http://apmp.berkeley.edu/images/stories/LaborMarket- Retrieved July 9, 2007 from http://www.conapo.gob.mx/
Info/calnaws.2003–04.pdf publicaciones/Lapoblacion/0.pdf
Alcalá, L., Rogoff, B., Mejía-Arauz, R., Coppens, A., & Roberts, Corona, Y., & Pérez, C. (2005, June). The enrichment of com-
A. D. (2011). Children’s initiative in contributions to family munity relations through children’s participation in ceremonial

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 881


life. Presented at Childhoods 2005: Children and youth in González, N. (2001). I am my language: Discourses of women and
emerging and transforming societies. Oslo, Norway. children in the borderlands. Tucson: The University of Arizona
Corona Caraveo, Y. (2003). Diversidad de infancias: Retos y Press.
compromisos [Diversity of childhoods: Challenges and González, N. (2006). Testimonios of border identities: Una mujer
commitments]. Tramas, 20, 13–31. acomedida cabe done quiera [An acomedida woman fits in
Correa-Chávez, M. (2010). The organization of interaction anywhere]. In D. Delgado Bernal, A. C. Elenes, F. Godinez,
and communication in US Mexican heritage siblings’ joint & S. Villenas (Eds.), Chicana/Latina education in every-
activity. Unpublished manuscript, Clark University. day life: Feminista perspectives on pedagogy and epistemology
Correa-Chávez, M., & Rogoff, B. (2009). Children’s attention (pp. 197–213). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
to interactions directed to others: Guatemalan Mayan and González, N., Moll, L., & Amantí, C. (2005). Funds of knowl-
European American patterns. Developmental Psychology, 45, edge: Theorizing practices in households, communities, and class-
630–641. rooms. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
de Haan M., (1999). Learning as cultural practice: How children Graves, N. B., & Graves, T. D. (1983). The cultural context
learn in a Mexican Mazahua community. Amsterdam: Thela of prosocial development. In D. L. Bridgeman (Ed.), The
Thesis. nature of prosocial development (pp. 243–264). New York:
de Haan, M. (2001). Intersubjectivity in models of learning and Academic.
teaching: Reflections from a study of teaching and learning in a Gutiérrez, K., & Rogoff, B. (2003). Cultural ways of learn-
Mexican Mazahua community. In S. Chaiklin (Ed.), The theory ing: Individual traits or repertoires of practice. Educational
and practice of cultural – historical psychology (pp. 174 – 199). Researcher, 32, 19–25.
Aarhus, Denmark: Aarhus University Press. Hecht, T. (1998). At home in the street: Street children of northeast
de León, L. (2000). The emergent participant: Interactive pat- Brazil. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
terns in the socialization of Tzotzil (Mayan) infants. Journal Kagan, S. (1984). Interpreting Chicano cooperativeness. In J.
of Linguistic Anthropology, 8, 131–161. L. Martinez & R. H. Mendoza (Eds.), Chicano psychology
Delgado-Gaitán, C. (1987). Traditions and transition the (2nd ed., pp. 289– 333). Orlando, FL: Academic.
learning process of Mexican children: An ethnographic view. Kagan, S., & Madsen, M. C. (1971). Cooperation and com-
In G. Spindler & L. Spindler (Eds.), Interpretive ethnography petition of Mexican, Mexican-American, and Anglo-
of education: At home and abroad (pp. 333–362). Hillsdale, American children of two ages under four instructional sets.
NJ: Erlbaum. Developmental Psychology, 5, 32–39.
Delgado-Gaitán, C., & Trueba, H. T. (1985). Ethnographic study Kagan, S., & Madsen, M. C. (1972). Rivalry in Anglo-American
of participant structures in task completion: Reinterpretation and Mexican children of two ages. Journal of Personality and
of “handicaps” in Mexican children. Learning Disability Social Psychology, 24, 214–220.
Quarterly, 8, 67–75. Kartner, J., Keller, K., & Chaudhary, N. (2010). Cognitive and
Deyhle, D. (1991). Empowerment and cultural conflict: Navajo social influences on early prosocial behavior in two sociocul-
parents and the schooling of their children. Qualitative tural contexts. Developmental Psychology, 46, 904–914.
Studies in Education, 4, 277–297. Knight, G. P., & Kagan, S. (1977). Development of prosocial
Ellis, S., & Gauvain, M. (1992). Social and cultural influences and competitive behaviors in Anglo-American and Mexican-
on children’s collaborative interactions. In L. T. Wineger & American children. Child Development, 48, 1385–1394.
J. Valsiner (Eds.), Children’s development within social context Lamphere, L. (1977). To run after them: Cultural and social bases
(Vol. 2) (pp. 155–180). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. of cooperation in a Navajo community. Tucson: University of
Eriks-Brophy, A., & Crago, M. (2003). Cultural or linguis- Arizona Press.
tic? Evidence from Inuit & non-Inuit teachers of Nunavik. LeVine, R. A., LeVine, S. E., Richman, A., Tapia Uribe, F. M.,
Anthropology & Education Quarterly, 34, 396–419. Correa, C. S., & Miller, P. M. (1991). Women’s schooling
Eisenberg N., & Fabes, R. A. (1998). Prosocial development. and child care in the demographic transition: A Mexican case
In N. Eisenberg & W. Damon (Eds.), Handbook of child study. Population and Development Review, 17, 459–496.
psychology social, emotional, and personality development Lipka, J. (1991). Toward a culturally based pedagogy:
(pp. 701–778). New York: Wiley & Sons. A case study of one Yup’ik Eskimo teacher. Anthropology &
Escobar Latapí, A. (2009). Mexico’s progreso-oportunidades Education Quarterly, 22, 203–223.
programs: Where do we go from here? In M. J. Bane & R. López, A., Correa-Chávez, M., Rogoff, B., & Gutiérrez, K.
Zentero (Eds.), Poverty and poverty alleviation strategies in (2010). Attention to instruction directed to another by U.S.
North America (pp. 203–232). Cambridge, MA: Harvard Mexican-heritage children of varying cultural backgrounds.
University Press. Developmental Psychology, 46, 593–601.
Farver, J. (1993). Cultural differences in scaffolding play: A Lorente Fernández, D. (2010). Ser respetuoso es ser “persona”:
comparison of American and Mexican mother-child and El niño y la pedagogía moral de los Nahuas del Centro de
sibling-child pairs. In K. MacDonald (Ed.), Parent-child México. [Being respectful is being a “person”: The child
play: Descriptions and implications. Albany, NY: SUNY and moral pedagogy of the Nahuas of Central Mexico].
Press. Unpublished manuscript.
Fox, J. (2006). Reframing Mexican migration as a multi-ethnic Lorente Fernández, D. (2006). Infancia nahua y transmisión
process. Latino Studies, 4, 39–61. de la cosmovisión: Los ahuaques o espíritus pluviales en la
Frye, D. (1996). Indians into Mexicans: History and identity in a Sierra de Texcoco, México [Nahua childhood and transmis-
Mexican town. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. sion of world view: The ahuaques or rain spirits in the Sierra
Gaskins, S. (2000). Children’s daily activities in a Mayan village. of Texcoco, México]. Boletín de Antropología Universidad de
Cross-Cultural Research, 34, 375–389. Antioquia, 20, 152–168.

882 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


Maynard, A.E. (2002). Cultural teaching: The develop- context of the market. Ph.D. Dissertation, Department of
ment of teaching skills in Maya sibling interactions. Child Anthropology, University of Pennsylvania.
Development, 73, 969–982. Paradise, R. (1996). Passivity or tacit collaboration: Mazahua
McClintock, C. G. (1974). Development of social motives in interaction in cultural context. Learning and Instruction, 6,
Anglo-American and Mexican-American children. Journal of 379–389.
Personality & Social Psychology, 29, 348–354. Paradise, R., & de Haan, M. (2009). Responsibility and reci-
McCollum, P. (1989). Turn-allocation in lessons with North procity: Social organization of Mazahua learning practices.
American and Puerto Rican students: A comparative study. Anthropology & Education Quarterly, 40, 187–204.
Anthropology & Education Quarterly, 20, 133–156. Paradise, R., & Rogoff, B. (2009). Side by side: Learning through
Mehan, H. (1979). Learning lessons: Social organization in the observing and pitching in. Ethos, 37, 102–138.
classroom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Pelletier, W. (1970). Childhood in an Indian village. In S. Repo
Mehan, H. (1985). The structure of classroom discourse. In T. A. (Ed.), This book is about schools (pp. 18–31). New York:
van Dijk (Ed.), Handbook of discourse analysis (pp. 120–131). Pantheon Books.
London: Academic. Philips, S. U. (1983). The invisible culture: Communication
Mejía-Arauz, R., Rogoff, B., Dexter, A., & Najafi, B. (2007). in classroom and community on the Warm Springs Indian
Cultural variation in children’s social organization. Child Reservation. New York: Longman.
Development, 78, 1001–1014. Ramírez III, M., & Castañeda, A. (1974). Cultural democracy,
Mejía-Arauz, R., Rogoff, B., & Paradise, R. (2005). Cultural bicognitive development, and education. New York: Academic
variation in children’s observation during a demonstra- Press.
tion. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 29, Ramírez Sánchez, M. A. (2007). Helping at home: The con-
282–291. cept of childhood and work among the Nahuas of Tlaxcala,
Mercado R. (2001). Los saberes docentes como construcción Mexcio. In B. Hungerland, M. Liebel, B. Milne, & A.
social [Teachers’ knowledge as social construction]. Doctoral Wihstutz (Eds.), Working to be someone: Child focused research
thesis. Mexico City: Dep. Invest. Educ. Centro Invest. Estud. and practice with working children (pp. 87–95). London and
Av. IPN. Philadelphia: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Meyer, J., Ramirez, F. J., & Soysal, Y. (1992). World expansion Reese, L. (2002). Parental strategies in contrasting cultural set-
of mass education, 1870–1980. Sociology of Education, 65, tings: Families in México and “El Norte.” Anthropology &
128–149. Education Quarterly, 33, 30–59.
Morelli, G. A., Rogoff, B., & Angelillo, C. (2003). Cultural Richman, A. L., Miller, P. M., & LeVine, R. A. (1992). Cultural
variation in young children’s access to work or involvement and educational variations in maternal responsiveness.
in specialized child-focused activities. International Journal of Developmental Psychology, 28, 614–621.
Behavorial Development, 27, 264–274. Rogoff, B. (2011). Introduction to learning through intent com-
Mosier, C. E., & Rogoff, B. (2003). Privileged treatment of tod- munity participation. In Rogoff et al. (Eds.), Pitching in and
dlers: Cultural aspects of individual choice and responsibility. catching on: Learning through intent community participation.
Developmental Psychology, 39, 1047–1060. Rogoff, B., & Angelillo, C. (2002). Investigating the coordinated
Najafi, B., Mejía-Arauz, R., & Rogoff, B. (2005, September). functioning of multifaceted cultural practices in human
Cultural variation in helping among US European- and Mexican- development. Human Development, 45, 211–225.
heritage children. Presented at the meetings of the International Rogoff, B., Correa-Chávez, M., & Navichoc Cotuc, M. (2005).
Society for Cultural and Activity Research, Seville, Spain. A cultural-historical view of schooling in human develop-
Najafi, B., Mejía-Arauz, R., & Rogoff, B. (2008, September). ment. In D. Pillemer & S. H. White (Eds.), Developmental
Culture as constellations of practices: Patterns across generations psychology and social change (pp. 225–263). New York:
of three communities in Guadalajara. Presented at the meet- Cambridge University Press.
ings of the International Society for Culture and Activity Rogoff, B., Mistry, J., Göncü, A., & Mosier, C. (1993). Guided
Research, San Diego, CA. participation in cultural activity by toddlers and caregivers.
Najafi, B. D., & Rogoff, B. (2007, March). The social orga- Monographs for the Society for Research in Child Development,
nization of collaboration among children of Mexican- and 58, (Serial No. 236).
European- heritage. Presented at the meetings of the Society Rogoff, B., Moore, L., Najafi, B., Dexter, A., Correa-Chavez,
for Research in Child Development, Boston, MA. M., & Solis, J. (2007). Cultural routines and practices. In
Najéra-Ramírez, O. (1997). La fiesta de los Tastonanes [The festi- J. Grusec & P. Hastings (Eds.), Handbook of socialization
val of the Tastonanes]: Critical encounters in Mexican festival (pp. 225–263). New York: Guilford Press.
performance. Albuquerque, NM: University of New Mexico Rogoff, B., Paradise, R., Mejía-Arauz, R., Correa-Chávez, M., &
Press. Angelillo, C. (2003). Firsthand learning through intent par-
Nsamenang, A. B. (1992). Human development in cultural ticipation. Annual Review of Psychology, 54, 175–203.
context. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Romney, K., & Romney, R. (1963). The Mixtecans of Juxtlahuaca,
Orellana, M. F. (2001). The work kids do: Mexican and Central Mexico. In B. B. Whiting (Ed.), Six cultures: Studies of child
American immigrant children’s contributions to households rearing (pp. 541–691). New York: Wiley & Sons.
and schools in California. Harvard Educational Review, 71, Senge, P. M. (1990). The fifth discipline: The art and practice of the
366–389. learning organization. New York: Doubleday.
Orellana, M. F., Dorner, L., & Pulido, L. (2003). Accessing Silva, K., Correa-Chávez, M., & Rogoff, B. (2010). Mexican-
assets: Immigrant youth’s work as family translators or “para- heritage children’s attention and learning from interactions
phrasers.” Social Problems, 50, 505–524. directed to others. Child Development, 81, 898–912.
Paradise, R. (1987). Learning through social interaction: The Silva, K. G., Shimpi, P., & Rogoff, B. (2009, March). Children’s
experience and development of the Mazahua self in the attention and learning in an interaction not directed to

lópe z , n a ja fi, rogoff, m ejía - a rau z 883


them: A Guatemalan Mayan and European American compar- at the workshop on Intent Community Participation, Ajijic,
ison. Presented at the meetings of the Society for Research in Mexico.
Child Development, Denver. Valdés, G. (1996). Con respeto: Bridging the distance between
Sindell, P. S. (1997). Some discontinuities in the encultura- culturally diverse families and schools: An ethnographic
tion of Mistassini Cree children. In G. D. Spindler (Ed.), portrait. New York: Teachers College Press.
Education and cultural process: Anthropological approaches (pp. Valenzuela, A. (1999) Subtractive schooling: U.S.–Mexican youth
383–392). Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press. and the politics of caring. Albany, NY: State University of New
Stavenhagen, R. (1988). Introducción [Introduction]. In York Press.
R. Stavenhagen (Ed.), Polıtica cultural para un país multié- Warman, A. (2003). Los indios mexicanos en el umbral del milenio
tnico [Cultural policy for a multiethnic country] (pp. 7–21). [The Mexican Indians in the threshold of the millennium].
Mexico City, Mexico: Secretaría de Educación Pública. México City, Mexico: FCE.
Strathern, M. (1988). The gender of the gift. Berkeley, CA: Weisner, T. S., & Gallimore, R. (1977). My brother’s keeper: Child
University of California Press. and sibling care-taking. Current Anthropology, 18, 169–190.
Telzer, E. H., & Fuligni, A. J. (2009). Daily family assistance Weisner, T. S., Gallimore, R., & Jordan, C. (1988). Unpackaging
and the psychological well-being of adolescents from Latin cultural effects on classroom learning: Native Hawaiian peer
American, Asian, and European backgrounds. Developmental assistance and child-generated activity. Anthropology &
Psychology, 45, 1177–1189. Education Quarterly, 19, 327–351.
Tharp, R. G., Estrada, P., Dalton, S. S., & Yamauchi, L. A. Widaman, K. F., & Kagan, S. (1987). Cooperativeness and
(2000). Teaching transformed. Achieving excellence, fairness, achievement: Interaction of student cooperativeness with
inclusion, and harmony. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. cooperative versus competitive classroom organization.
Trueba, H. T., & Delgado-Gaitan, C. (1985). Socialization of Journal of School Psychology, 25, 355–365.
Mexican children for cooperation and competition: Sharing Whiting, B. B., & Edwards, C. P. (1988). Children of different
and copying. Journal of Educational Equity and Leadership, worlds: The formation of social behavior. Cambridge, MA:
5, 189–204. Harvard University Press.
Urrieta, L., Jr. (2003). Las identidades también lloran: [Identities Whiting, B., & Whiting, J. (1975). Children of six cultures: A
also cry:] Exploring the human side of Indigenous Latina/o psycho-cultural analysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
identities. Educational Studies, 34, 147–168. Press.
Urrieta, L., Jr. (2010, July). Learning comunidad through intent Zukow, P. G. (1989). Sibling interaction across cultures: Theoretical
community participation in San Miguel Nocutzepo. Presented and methodological issues. New York: Springer-Verlag.

884 coll abor at i on and he lpi ng as cult u ra l practices


CHAPTER

A Cultural-Historical Approach to
42 University/Community Collaborative
Interventions
Deborah Downing-Wilson, Robert Lecusay, Ivan Rosero, and Michael Cole

Abstract
In this paper we explore approaches to intervention research viewed from a broadly conceived
cultural-psychological perspective. Although scholars who adopt this perspective share a belief in the
centrality of culture in human development, they may differ in how they conceive of culture and how
it enters into and participates in human thought and action. We examine two cultural-psychological
strategies for developing and sustaining innovative educational environments: design experimentation
and mutual appropriation. Design experimentation is an approach in which researchers and practitioners
collaborate to simultaneously engineer innovative learning environments and understand salient aspects
of human cognition and learning. They do so by developing and implementing, in a specific educational
setting, a version of a learning design and iteratively revising this design in light of results from each
implementation. Mutual appropriation refers to interventions in which the nature of the intervention
is not prespecified, but negotiated among participants over time. We examine these approaches by
introducing two examples of university-community research and educational collaborations. The first
collaboration, The Beach Boys & Girls Club, is an example of an intervention based on the principles of
design experimentation, while the second, the Town and Country Learning Center, illustrates the mutual
appropriation approach. Through this comparative examination of the two intervention perspectives, we
endeavor to show that a mutual appropriation approach can help the field create interventions that are
themselves developmental in their fundamental methodology.
Keywords: Cultural Historical Activity Theory, Design Experiment, Intervention Research,
Learning Ecology, Mutual Appropriation.

In this chapter we posit two strategies for designing, and his followers working in the tradition of
implementing, and seeking to sustain collaborative Cultural-Historical Activity Theory (CHAT).
intervention programs located in community settings Our discussion centers on the ways in which the
during the after-school hours. Both systems involve two strategies differ with respect to how the relation-
cooperation between university groups (undergraduate ships are established, how they are structured, and
and graduate students as well as professors) and how the activities are organized in response to the
community organizations (children and their adult needs of the respective communities, the participants
caretakers). Both are intended to create new forms involved, and the resources available. The first strat-
of activity, the motive of which is to promote the egy adheres most closely to what has come to be called
development and well-being of the participants and “design experimentation.” The second strategy follows
the organizations from which they come. Both instan- a logic that we refer to as “mutual appropriation.” We
tiate a variety of principles of learning, development, argue that both approaches have their merits and
and instruction derived from the work of Vygotsky their challenges. Through the creation of functional

885
systems of interactions appropriate to their histori- colleagues (2004, p. 18) summarized this aspect of
cal/sociocultural/ecological circumstances (local and the approach as follows:
global) they require us to focus on culturally orga-
“Design experiments were developed as away to carry
nized activities in their institutional settings as units
out formative research to test and refine educational
of analysis. Both provide useful ways to bridge the
designs based on theoretical principles derived
gap between standard, laboratory-style experimenta-
from prior research. This approach of progressive
tion and situations-of-use, which include the broader
refinement in design involves putting a first version
sociocultural environment beyond the immediate
of a design into the world to see how it works. Then,
circumstances under investigation.
the design is constantly revised based on experience,
until all the bugs are worked out.”
Design Experimentation 3. Those who adopt design experimentation as
In the early 1980s, Ann Brown and her col- a method also argue that it is important to study
leagues embarked on a series of classroom-based a wide variety of “authentic” (DBRC, 2003) or
studies focused on guided instruction and assess- “natural” settings or “contexts” (Barab & Squire,
ment in social contexts. These studies challenged 2004; Cobb et al., 2003).
mainstream psychology and education research, cre-
ating what Brown and Campione called “. . . a sea The first line of research we discuss was carried
of change in theories of learning . . . an awakening to out very much in the spirit of design experimenta-
the fact that real-life learning is intrinsically entan- tion as characterized above, although, with a some-
gled with situations” (Brown & Campione, 1998, p. what different orientation both toward the rela-
154). Brown (1992) and her colleague, Allan Collins tionship between tasks and their settings and with
(1992), referred to this new methodology as “design respect to the expectation that all the “bugs” would
experimentation.” They viewed design experiments be, could be, or should be worked out.
as a serious alternative to, or supplement to, ran-
domized, tightly controlled research paradigms. Intervention through Mutual Appropriation
In recent years the idea of design experimenta- In a follow-up paper on design interventions,
tion has been taken up by a number of research- Brown and Campione (1998), having by this time
ers interested in advancing theories of learning and had several more years of experience implementing
development (see the special issues on this topic their idea of “communities of learners,” introduce
in the Educational Researcher, 2003; and Journal of the idea that not only do design experiments seed the
Learning Sciences, 2004). Despite differences among environment with ideas and concepts that take root
them, proponents of design-based research are likely in the community, migrating and persisting over time,
to agree with three principles that will be central to but participants appropriate these ideas and con-
our discussion: cepts, reshaping and deploying them in unpredict-
able ways through personal interpretation and expe-
1. “The metaphor of ecology is used to emphasize rience. They used the term, “mutual appropriation”
that designed contexts are conceptualized as inter- (a term they attribute to Newman, Griffin, & Cole,
acting systems rather than a collection of activities or 1989) to describe this transformation of the original
a list of separate factors that influence learning. Ideally design experimentation concept. In using the term
design experiments offer a greater understanding “mutual appropriation” as an explicit alternative to
of a learning ecology by designing its elements and the idea of design experimentation, we should note
observing how these elements work together to that we are applying the idea at a different level of
support learning. Components of a learning ecology analysis than that deployed by Newman et al., who
typically include the learning activities or achievement were seeking to describe the bidirectional quality
goals that are set for the students, the types of discourse of participant learning in a zone of proximal devel-
and ways of participating that are encouraged, the opment (Newman, Griffin, & Cole, 1989). In the
material artifacts provided, and the practical means present context, “mutual appropriation” is used to
through which relations among these elements can characterize the interactions between organizations
be orchestrated.” (Cobb et al., 2003, p. 9) representing those who are doing the intervening
2. For design experiments to achieve its goals, and the partner organization in which, in the spirit
it is necessary to conduct iterative embodiments of of Long’s (2001) work on “developmental socio-
the designed pedagogical activity. Collins and his logy,” both university and community participants

886 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


attend to each others’ attempts to “appropriate, institution furnishes local experience, children,
manipulate, subvert or dismember” (p. 233) partic- space, equipment, and supervision of the activi-
ular new initiatives introduced by their partners in ties to provide the undergraduates with a valuable
the process of their ongoing joint activity. However, research experience.
contrary to the usual negative implications of such 2. The programs are mixtures of “leading activ-
terms as “subvert” and “dismember,” our experience, ities” (as proposed by cultural-historical activity
following our own version of a mutual appropria- theorists, e.g., Elkonin, 1999) including affilia-
tion approach, sees these features of the interven- tion, play, learning, peer interaction, and work.
tion process as perfectly normal and healthy. They The physical location can be crucial to shaping
are required for reciprocity, in which the both sides how play, learning, and other leading activities
of the interaction (organizationally speaking) are are combined. For example, rules of decorum in
doing their best to achieve the common goals that a school or library encourage quiet attentiveness
anchor their continued interactions, while staying but discourage play. Rules of decorum at a Boys
focused on their individual activities, which may and Girls Club or a HUD Learning Center may
or may not mesh perfectly with those of the other afford a great range of possibilities for engagement,
participants. play being one prominent possibility, but also offer
constant invitations to become distracted from the
Resisting Dichotomizing: Some Common task at hand.
Principles of Our Two Interventions 3. Whenever possible, participant structures are
Up to this point we have been focused on designed to minimize power differentials between
drawing a distinction between the two strategies the participants, particularly between the under-
of intervention research for purposes of setting up graduates and the children with whom they work.
a useful comparison. But it would be foolish, in The issue of participation structures and power
our view, to draw too clear a distinction between differentials is also greatly affected by the combi-
the two approaches as we have experienced them. nation of sponsoring institutions and the concrete
The distinctions matter, but the two interventions, activities that are the focus of the collaboration. In
despite important differences (perhaps unsurpris- both of the cases we examine, formal education in
ingly because they were carried out by the same the form of homework was considered mandatory
research group) share certain theoretical assump- by the local community participants, and the rules
tions concerning the nature of desirable environ- for “homework time” were different than those
ments for promoting development of children for “enrichment time.” Parents from different eth-
and undergraduates as a result of collaborations, nic backgrounds may demand from their children
under either of the two contrasting interventionist higher levels of deference to adults and educators
banners. Consequently, before digging more deeply than we are accustomed to. In addition, the age of
into the differences between the two intervention the children involved interacts with both the nature
strategies as we have practiced them, we stop to of the institution and the parental cultural expecta-
consider the assumptions common to both lines of tions to shape authority relations.
research. These assumptions played out differently 4. Heavy emphasis is placed upon the value of
in the two research projects, but as ideals to be communication in a variety of media including
sought for, they are shared presuppositions on our computers, conversation, and writing, in the ser-
parts, even though they were differentially shared vice of solving goals that are provided within the
with our community partners, who have their own activity setting. Not only is “the thought completed
ideas on the subject. in the word” but in other forms of externalization
that enable the transformation of sense into mean-
1. The intervention strategies reported on here ing (Vygotsky, 1987). Consequently, the principle
are both joint undertakings between a univer- of forefronting the use of a variety of communica-
sity and a community institution. In both strat- tion means is one of the central principles govern-
egies the university brings theoretically guided ing our pedagogical intervention research. The ways
experience and expertise at building activities in which this principle is embodied in the activities
and artifacts that promote learning and develop- varies enormously, depending on the institutional
ment, as well as supervised undergraduates to the venue, the availability of computers and other digital
community institution as labor. The community technology resources, the age of children involved,

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 887


and the expertise of the participants, both local and investigator, the social ecology of the activity, and
from the university. the resources available to them. Evaluations have
5. Participation by the children is voluntary. included videotaped records of 5th D participant
Children are free to leave at any time. Consequently, interactions, data mining of student fieldnotes,
the games and other activities that participants questionnaires, on-site observations by third-party
engage in must adhere to goals that the children spectators, and indices of the monetary support
find compelling. In practice, the principle that chil- provided by both the university and community
dren should not be forced to engage in the activi- institutions.
ties is routinely breached at times when homework Looking first to the 5th D activity systems as
is mandated by the local adults representing the an ensemble, perhaps the most striking result is
community organization. Nonetheless, this norm that both the particular combination of activities
is maintained in as many activities as possible and and the form of the individual activities that evolve
routinely produces strong affective bonds among from the initial design are highly sensitive to local
the participants after as few as 9 weeks. constraints and resources. No two 5th Ds, even
when implemented by the same researcher with the
The Design Experiment Intervention: same group of undergraduates in two community
The Fifth Dimension organizations of the same kind in highly similar
The Fifth Dimension (5th D) is an after-school communities, behave like replicas of each other.
activity system designed for elementary-school-aged Within a period of months, if not weeks, each sys-
children. University students enrolled in a course tem takes on its own characteristics, a blend of val-
that focuses on fieldwork in a community setting ues, norms, and practices characteristic of the local
visit these after-school sites to play, work, and learn institution (its staffing, architectural structure, its
as the children’s partners. A detailed account of the location in the community, etc.) and its univer-
history, design, and implementation of the 5th D sity partners (who may be from backgrounds in
model can be found in Cole and the Distributed a variety of social science disciplines, sophomores
Literacy Consortium (2006). or seniors, predominantly of one ethnic group or
The activities at these sites are designed to instan- several, etc.).
tiate the principles summarized above. This is done Tracing implementations in widely disparate
using a variety of artifacts including educational conditions quickly reveals that some 5th Ds have
computer games, written instructions for playing failed to survive initial meetings between univer-
these games in a goal-oriented, collaborative man- sities and potential community sponsors. Others
ner, artifacts for distributing the children’s and the have been implemented and run successfully, only
university students’ use of the games, and imaginary to cease operation after less than a year as a result of
figures (instantiated via letters, email, or electronic inability to satisfy institutional imperatives that went
chat) that interact with the participants to encour- undetected in the startup phase. Some 5th Ds have
age them to externalize their thinking and critically continued to a point where the two collaborating
reflect upon their joint activities. institutions discover that they do not really share a
common vision of a good developmental environ-
Evaluating the Fifth Dimension ment for children. Some have been forced to close
Interventions when the level of continuity in staffing (on either
A variety of analytical methods have been spe- the university or community side) is inadequate,
cially designed to evaluate the usefulness and short- degrading the quality of the ensuing activity. Still
comings of the 5th D principles and the resulting others have continued for several years, but coin-
activities and programs (Blanton et al., 1997; Cole cidence of several “risk factors” (decreased funding,
& the Distributed Literacy Consortium, 2006; loss of key personnel in two or more parts of the sys-
Mayer, Schustack, & Blanton, 1999). The specific tem) have led to their demise despite their recognized
data sources used by different implementers of a value. Finally, many implementations prosper and
5th D (approximately 40 different research groups increase in scope, sometimes “giving birth” to new
from different parts of the world) depend heavily generations of 5th Ds. At the time of this writing,
upon the expectations of their local communi- 30 years after the experiment began, dozens of
ties, the professional criteria of the academic dis- 5th Ds and their associated university-community
ciplines they answer to, the specific interests of the superstructures are in operation.

888 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


Evaluated in terms of a study of sustainablility, sizable working-class Mexican-American minor-
the form of design experiment represented by the ity. Among the school-age children, the Mexican-
5th D can be summarized as follows: (1) Provide a American population was considerably higher than
“starter tool kit” consisting of artifacts, rules, and it was among the adults, and many of these children
standard roles as resources for creating the joint attended the after-school program at the club. The
activity system; (2) begin with a central structure BGC charged a nominal fee for participation, but
and core activities and watch them change over children from families who could not afford the fee
time in relation to the local setting; (3) seek to sus- were given scholarships.
tain the activity system as long as possible, focus- Figure 42.1 presents a schematic overview of the
ing on the factors that threaten sustainability and local ecology provided by the building in which the
the measures that are successful in extending the 5th D was housed. The 5th D was separated from
life of the ever-changing experimental design; (4) the entrance-hall “control center” of the club by
identify the factors precipitating the death of the a large window wall, making the 5th D activities
program. visible from most everywhere in the building. The
From this summary, it is clear that the 5th D opposite wall of the 5th D room had big windows
is a kind of “upside-down” form of design experi- that looked out on a large swimming pool, which
mentation. Instead of seeking to fine-tune a single was in constant use. The doors of the 5th D were
design until the experimenter has “gotten it right,” always kept open, so children could come and go at
the interest is in how a system of activities that has will, as was true in the rest of the club. At any given
been shown to “get it right” when faithfully imple- time most of the areas of the club were populated
mented, is pulled apart, rearranged, and melded by children engaged in a wide range of activities.
with its social ecology (or expelled) in the course of Club policies changed slightly in keeping with the
joint activity between the partner institutions over a priorities of the current directors. At times the large
long period of time. central area would be blaring with rock music and
children playing hopscotch, while at other times the
The Beach Boys and Girls Club: current director would see that the children were
A Concrete Example engaged in one of the specialized activity rooms and
In the spring of 2006, the partnership between the central area was quieter.
the Laboratory for Comparative Human Cognition The 5th D program operated Monday through
(LCHC) at the University of California, San Diego Thursday afternoons, competing on a “come as you
UCSD and the Beach Boys and Girls Club (BGC) choose” basis with other BGC activities. On any
was the oldest in the UCLinks program and served given day, five to eight undergraduates1 and one
as the prototype upon which a number of subse- or two graduate students, plus a “5th D coordi-
quent 5th D programs were modeled (see Cole & nator” were present to interact with the children.
the Distributed Literacy Consortium, 2006 for Daily attendance at the BGC fluctuated between
details). At the time this project began (mid-1980s), 30 and 40 elementary- and middle-school children.
the research team was determining to what extent Typically 10 to 20 of these children participated in
new communication technologies could provide the 5th D program at some point in their afternoon
effective tools and legitimate motives for children stay.
to engage in reading, writing, and problem solving, In the early 1990s the partnership was struc-
and whether such technologies could also unite tured so that the BGC provided the space and the
researchers with each other, universities to their administrative support associated with the running
communities, and different communities with each of the club, while the LCHC paid for most of the
other. The team was also concerned with working 5th D activities by employing a site coordinator,
out a means of in situ evaluation that would justify sharing in the cost of computers and software, and
the amount of resources necessary to maintain such generally providing and maintaining the supplies
a program. necessary for the day-to-day running of the 5th
The BGC was located in a relatively affluent San D program. Unfortunately, the BGC experienced
Diego suburb. It sat next to a public middle school chronic staffing problems and the high turnover
and across the street from a public elementary school. of BGC employees became an ongoing challenge
However, while the neighborhood’s population was for the 5th D program. In the fall of 1996, by
mostly middle-class Anglo-American, there was a prior agreement, the BGC hired and paid a site

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 889


(A)

STORAGE

PARKING
PARKING
AREA POOL

5THDD
5TH Basketball Court
PORCH

(hand ball, tag,


PARKING

dodge-ball, football)

GYMNASIUM
DESK
Game
OFFICES HW

Room Arts & Teen


(football, Crafts Room
ping pong) (science & PARKING
ROOM

tech)

(B)
STORAGE

PARKING
AREA POOL

5TH D Basketball Court


PORCH

(hand ball, tag,


PARKING

dodge-ball, football)

GYMNASIUM
DESK
Game Room
OFFICES HW

(football, Arts &


ARTS Teen
ping pong) Crafts Room Figure 42.1 (A) Schematic overview of the
AND (science & PARKING
TEEN Beach Boys and Girls Club. (B) Overview
ROOM

CRAFT tech)
ROOM showing direction of influence in the instiga-
(SCIENCE AND
TECH) tion of change.

coordinator to run the 5th D, but the funding was as the computer room staff member when the 5th
insufficient to support a permanent employee. At D was not in session. On the university side of the
times, former university students who had partici- partnership, the changing organizational arrange-
pated in the practicum served as coordinators for a ments for the practicum course provided opportu-
school term, or a school year after graduating, but nities to study issues of sustainability that few had
more often the club hired someone new, who was anticipated in the beginning.
then trained on the job by 5th D staff. During the years of its operation, the 5th D
morphed well beyond its initial design, although
Tracking Changes in the 5th D as a the “core of the activities” remained relatively
Learning Ecology unchanged: undergraduates and children played an
BGC events showcased the friendly and rela- ever-changing variety of computer games together,
tively stable relationship between UCSD and the children advanced through the individual games on
BGC. For example, children from the 5th D were their way to the role of “Young Wizard’s Assistant,”
recognized publicly on awards nights at the club, and various unobtrusive ways of assessing children’s
and at the end of each quarter a sort of going- academic progress were studied. After many years of
away party was held as a ritual way of thanking the instability, the university had built hiring of tempo-
undergraduates and easing the pain of separation rary teaching staff into its budgetary and curricular
for both the undergraduates and the children, who regime, while the BGC had hired an extremely effec-
often had formed strong bonds of affection. In addi- tive 5th D site coordinator, and the undergraduate
tion, the BGC regularly advertised the presence of students flocked to participate.
the 5th D in its publications. The relationship was The inclusion of a variety of BGC activities,
also reflected in the BGC budget, which showed an including arts and crafts, board games, and outdoor
increase over the years in the number of hours and sports achievements within the 5th D’s regime of
the salary for the site coordinator, who also served interaction, served to infuse the 5th D program into

890 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


virtually all of the BGC activities (see Fig. 42.1B). approached members of LCHC about establishing
As a result, the 5th D program became the best-at- a Fifth-Dimension-style, university-community part-
tended part of the programming offered by the BGC. nership in a local after-school community center. The
However, in the summer of 2006, the BGC closed site chosen, Town and Country Learning Center
for renovation for a period of 2 years and the 5th D (T&CLC), is housed in a federally subsidized,
program ceased operation. An attempt was made to 144-unit apartment complex called Town and
open a 5th D in a nearby BGC, but at that institu- Country Village. The complex is located in a neigh-
tion the program was not welcomed by staff who had borhood of South-Central San Diego, where the
worked out their own regime of activities. Unlike the majority of the residents are African-American. Two
Beach BGC, the children at the new club did not adjacent apartments inside the complex have been
qualify as an underserved population, making efforts converted to serve as a community/learning center
to sustain the partnership difficult to justify from the for the exclusive use of the residents.
perspective of the university. When the Beach BGC From the beginning it was clear that applying the
did reopen 2 years later, the 5th D program was not 5th D model at T&CLC would be difficult, if not
reinstituted. So, while 5th Ds continue to exist and impossible. Neither the geography of the local center
prosper in many locations, this particular design, (see Fig. 42.2) nor the federally mandated expecta-
effective by many criteria, could not be sustained. tion that adults as well as children could use the lim-
ited computer facilities, afforded a child-centered,
Using the Mutual Appropriation Strategy: relatively closed space that could serve as the hub of
Town and Country Learning Center 5th D activities.
In early 2007 the Director of Education of An added consideration was the program of struc-
the San Diego Supercomputer Center (SDSC) tured educational and enrichment activities already

(A)

Kitchen Teen
Ms. V’s Room
office

Homework
Area
Teen council Homework
Teen council, Ladybugs
Ladybugs Store

Patio
Garden

Parking Lot

(B)
Science Cooking World of Warcraft
Sims
Facebook
Kitchen
Teen Room
Ms. V’s Office MySpace
Raffle

Homework S. A. M.
Area
Teen Rec. Rooom Media Room W. I. T. S.
Council Arts & Garageband
Roe Room Store
Crafts iMovie Figure 42.2 (A) Schematic overview of the
Town and Country Village Learning Center.
Educational Homework Patio Health (B) Schematic overview of the Town and
computer activities Education Garden Country Village Learning Center showing
Gardening concentrations of influence. Key: Circle =
Olympiad Block
Parking Lot T&CLC original activity, Rectangle =
Party
Bod Squad Dance LCHC activity, Circle & Rectangle = hybrid
activity.

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 891


in place for the resident youth. These activities were sides of the partnership, that motivates our use of
primarily organized by the site coordinator, Ms. V., the term “mutual appropriation.” We have some
and were geared toward helping the youth nego- history with the phrase, as discussed earlier in the
tiate their personal as well as academic lives (e.g., paper, but here we’ve begun to think about mutual
book clubs, teen service projects (Teen Council), appropriation in new and specific ways. Not only do
elementary-school-girl etiquette club (The the partners in this project mutually appropriate the
Ladybugs), food sales). Responding to health con- activities and the activity system in ways that fur-
cerns of some of the resident women, Ms. V. would ther their own goals and the overarching goals of the
also on occasion organize nutrition and exercise program (in this case, to promote the development
activities at the center. In the process of familiariz- and well-being of all those involved) but the par-
ing ourselves with the circumstances on the ground, ticipants also strive to act in ways that are mutually
we simply joined in and tried to help Ms. V. with appropriate, support, or at very least do not subvert,
whatever it was she was already doing. When help the efforts of the other players. Through mutual
was needed with homework, we helped with home- appropriation, so conceived, a yours-mine-ours
work. When the computer network was unstable, activity system is able to spawn hybrid activities that
one of our team members with a computer-science neither of the original players could have conceived
background helped stabilize the network. nor implemented on their own.
During this time we kept in mind the possibility
that individual activities that had proven successful Tracking Changes in the T&CLC Mutual
in the 5th D system might be adapted for use in the Appropriation Model
T&CLC program. Of equal importance, we hoped Before we began our collaboration with the
that lessons from our past university-community T&CLC community, Ms. V., as the sole site coor-
partnerships could be applied in developing our rela- dinator, had the difficult task of organizing activi-
tionship with Ms. V. and the youth at T&CLC, as ties for a group of 20 to 40 participants who varied
well as with the broader community of residents in widely in age, interests, and consistency of atten-
the apartment complex. It was out of these circum- dance. She had to be strategic about the kinds of
stances that the approach we are referring to here as activities she developed because it was impossible
“mutual appropriation” was born and is evolving. for her to supervise all of these activities at the same
What is emerging is a reflexive way of collaborating time. In order to monitor the flow of youth in and
on the design of activities at the T&CLC that privi- out of the center, she locked all entrances except the
leges and builds upon the already-established prac- one door that was in her line of sight as she sat at
tices at the site. For purposes of exposition (since her desk. She distributed activities throughout the
all of the resulting changes were linked in various center according to age and proximity to her office,
ways to each other, not only in our activities at the placing the younger children engaging in school-
site but in the way we organized the corresponding work in the areas closest to her, while the presumably
course at UCSD), we can crudely distinguish three more mature, self-reliant teenagers were allowed to
parts to the mutual appropriation strategy that have work independently at the far side of the center.
so far emerged (see also Fig. 42.2): That was our starting point. Over time, the struc-
ture and content of the activities changed depending
1. Pre-existing activities that underwent changes
upon who initiated the new, joint activities and the
because of the addition of 10 to 12 UCSD under-
source of ideas for the innovation.
graduate students to the daily program.
2. Hybrid activities that arose from discussions
Pre-Existing Activities
among LCHC participants, Ms. V., and the chil-
As noted earlier, we began our partnership by
dren/youth at the site.
helping out with the programs that were in place
3. New activities introduced by LCHC that
when we arrived. We started with homework—
could fit into the ongoing structure of T&CLC but
something we knew a lot about, but soon found
which depend critically on the presence of LCHC
that we would need to make some fairly substantial
and the special resources it brings to the site in the
adjustments in our approach.
form of technology and expertise.
Ms. V. could not, as a practical matter, offer a
It is this more or less horizontal mixing of great deal of individualized homework assistance,
approaches, where leadership is exercised by both so her routine was to insist that the children com-

892 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


pleted assignments to the best of their ability before example concerns after-school snacks. A number of
asking for help. Once undergraduates were present, issues compromise the ability of T&CLC families
the routines at homework time changed. Our desire to provide nutritious foods for their children. Not
to get the kids through their homework and leave only are funds extremely limited for virtually all
time for enrichment activities that were the heart of the resident families at T&C, but local options
of our interests meant that we had to relax some of for buying fresh food are virtually nonexistent and
our power-leveling preferences and ask the under- fast-food chains are ubiquitous.
graduates to take on more of a tutoring role than As mentioned earlier, when we first started to
we normally like. Ms. V.’s request to do the tutoring work with Ms. V. and the residents at T&CLC,
quietly put further constraints on what in our view food sales were a regular practice designed for raising
could have been time productively spent by the chil- funds for basic materials at the center. Items for sale
dren and undergraduates delving deeply into the consisted primarily of prepackaged sugary or salty
content of the homework. Asking the kids to finish snacks, or easy-to-prepare items, such as nachos.
their homework first and then get quiet help from The children were purchasers as well as purveyors
the undergraduates created an atmosphere where of these snacks. The unhealthy quality of all these
“checking” homework was preferable to discussing foods raised concerns for us. Ms. V. was well-aware
it. Over time, however, we found compromises. of the health issues, but she was balancing the need
Ms. V. eased her requirement that the children do to raise money and the kids’ enthusiasm for con-
their homework within eyesight of her office, and suming these familiar snacks against her concerns
allowed some children to work with undergraduates about health.
in other areas of the learning center. When the Early in our work at T&CLC we began to work
weather was pleasant, tables would be moved out- out an arrangement in which we supplemented her
side and tutoring could take place without concern monies for providing snacks. Of equal importance,
for making too much noise. These adaptations not we began to introduce new ways of engaging in the
only addressed the problem of a distracting home- preparation of snacks, including the development
work environment, but allowed the undergraduates of the Science Cooking Club. The club was initi-
to tutor the children in deeper and more focused ated by a number of undergraduates who organized
ways. collaborative cooking sessions for the kids, com-
Another change that occurred, owing to our plete with nutrition lessons that entailed Internet
presence and the resulting increase in manpower, research to find nutritional information and recipes
was that a concerted effort could be made to for food that were both healthy and agreeable to the
collect report cards and progress reports for each kids. For example, fruit and vegetable smoothies
of the children. LCHC needed such information were a big hit. These cooking activities sparked a
to document the effectiveness of its program and number of new projects that included making a
Ms. V. needed it for her own accounting purposes, video documentary about preparing healthy and
but it was a time-consuming task that had routinely tasty smoothies and producing a smoothie recipe
been pushed aside by more pressing demands. An book. The video and recipe book were in turn digi-
unintended consequence of actually tracking chil- tized and posted to the T&CLC website, not only
dren’s progress in school was to bring to the fore to showcase the collaborative work between the kids
severe deficiencies in the academic achievement of and the undergraduates, but to allow succeeding
many of the children. This information led to dis- generations of undergraduates and local youth to
cussions about how best to support the children in build upon these achievements.
their current school assignments while simultane- In order to ensure that the kids could reason-
ously providing enrichment experiences that would ably apply their new knowledge of nutrition at
fill in sometimes gaping holes in their knowledge home, Ms. V. asked that whenever possible, the
that made independent completion of homework cooking activities used only ingredients that could
assignments impossible for many. be obtained locally. The sad fact that the only place
within walking distance to buy fresh produce (in
Hybrid Activities a very limited selection) was a local “99¢ Store”
Over time, activities began to emerge that are complicated the food project and exponentially
best described as hybrids of ideas from the two sides increased the educational value of the enterprise for
of the partnership (see Fig. 42.2B). One illustrative the university students.

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 893


The center had a struggling vegetable garden. because they have relatively defined goals, can be
Taking advantage of this situation, we organized for carried out in separate areas of the center to ward
a routine where, as some of the kids and undergrad- off intrusions from other activities, and thereby
uate buddies worked in the kitchen, others labored make professionally acceptable levels of documen-
in the garden, breaking soil, building raised garden tation and orderly data collection possible (see Fig.
plots, and doing online research about vegetables 42.2B).
and their optimal growing conditions. The results One such activity involved building a virtual
included salads and sautéed greens, which in turn world, called “Worlds of Internet Technology
led to new recipes, salad dressing taste tests, new and Science” (WITS). Similar in look and feel to
documentary films about gardening, and a garden “Second Life,” WITS uses a kid-friendly computer
recipe book. programming language for easily incorporating
The kitchen-garden connection turned out to be flash animations and digital photos and videos.
a cross-cultural connection as well. Collard greens, These arrangements make it possible to build a
beloved in the African-American community, were variety of environments, fill them with objects col-
unfamiliar to the undergraduates. In their research, lected from various media, and display them in an
the kids and buddies found that the traditional attractive fashion to others. The builders of WITS
ways of cooking the greens were not all that healthy. were interested in learning if this kind of facility
With the assistance of a local parent (who for the would be useful in after-school science education.
first time began to participate in the activities at the When it was first introduced, WITS attracted a
center), a compromise recipe was worked out that number of the elementary- and middle-school chil-
made everyone happy. dren who built rooms, filled them with pictures,
As these examples show, the new, hybrid activ- and explored the potentials of this world-building
ities were beneficial not just in terms of providing program. But after a few sessions, they lost interest.
material, educational, and social resources, but also Obligated to “push the envelope” of WITS’s poten-
in terms of motivating the creation of additional tial, Ivan Rosero, a graduate researcher in our lab,
new activities. The new recipes, the new garden, sought to redesign the way in which WITS was
the multiple video and textual documents of these implemented to determine how it could be made
activities, and their representation on the T&CLC useful in our after-school setting in a manner that
website helped create a network of interrelated would be motivating for the youth. With the sup-
artifacts and practices that the undergraduates and port of a local oceanographic institute interested in
youth could draw upon as they redesigned existing extending its public education program, Ivan deve-
activities and developed new ones. These documen- loped a project he called the Ocean World Activity
tary and representational practices also fit perfectly, (OWA) in which a group of elementary-school girls
both with UCSD’s ethos of encouraging reflection explored topics in marine science. He used a partially
and communication about site activities and with designed WITS undersea world as one component
Ms. V.’s custom of staging quarterly block parties of a multi-modal activity that included a visit to
for the youth and local residents. We grasped the the local aquarium, use of plush toys representing
opportunity provided by these parties to present various ocean creatures, and artwork to be placed in
the products of the children’s work to their com- the WITS virtual ocean.
munity. As others have shown (i.e., McLaughlin & This new form of activity generated excite-
Brice-Heath, 1993) such public presentations can ment not only among the children, but among the
be a source of motivation for new joint projects. oceanographers who were struggling to figure out
new ways to engage the general public, and espe-
New Activities Introduced by the cially under-represented groups, in oceanographic
University Partners concerns. Because the multi-modal WITS activity
With Ms. V. ‘s approval, LCHC has also intro- involved many new forms of mediation and repre-
duced a number of activities geared toward devel- sentational practices, communication technologies,
oping the T&CLC kids’ interests in, access to, and and challenges for social organization, it served as
knowledge of science, technology, engineering, perfect site for Ivan’s thesis work.
the arts, and math (what we have learned to call Over time, several such UCSD-initiated projects
a “STEAM curriculum”). Typically, these activi- have been implemented at T&CLC. Some have
ties also serve as research foci for graduate students involved encouraging physical exercise including

894 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


one activity called the “Bod Squad.” Developed by First, LCHC did not initiate the project. It was
a UCSD triathlete and graduate student researcher originated in discussions that came to us “second-
Tamara Powell, the Bod Squad introduced pedom- hand.” As a consequence of this mediated initia-
eters into races around the apartment complex’s tion, each side of the institutional partnership
circular drive and expanded existing activities such could feel as if the other were initiating the sugges-
as jump rope and freeze tag to include academic tion to interact. The equal power sharing embod-
elements. New UCSD initiatives are a continual ied in that beginning was quickly fused into a
source of new activities that are seen as valuable by variety of ritual joint, communicative gatherings,
the community, fun by the children, and objects of most prominently, Ms. V.’s participation via con-
research for the UCSD partners. ference call in weekly class discussions with the
UCSD students. This gave voice to both Ms. V.
Contrasting the Two Strategies and the students’ interests and concerns, while
Our goal, as stated at the outset, was to contrast the researcher/teachers could step back and allow
two strategies for university-community collabora- everyone to speak and be heard. During the after-
tive interventions in local after-school programs. It noons at T&CLC, Ms. V. ruled. There was never
is to that topic that we now return. a question of UCSD overpowering her. She has
Both of the research/intervention strategies done her utmost to make sure that the students’
discussed above are versions of an iterative, action experience is academically valuable to them, but
research program. Both allow us test and improve at the same time that she wants them to adhere
upon our theoretical understanding of how to use to the organization she suggests; lots of discussion
CHAT to chart the development of joint activi- goes on informally in the midst of the activity
ties within the collaborating organizations. Both itself.
are longitudinal studies anchored by our desire to Second, the two projects differ in the relation-
understand the process of sustaining the activities ship of the joint activity center to the ecology of the
as long as possible; our data allow us, albeit imper- children’s lives, their “contexts.” The BGC exists as
fectly, to trace development at three different time a safe and healthy place for kids to go after school
scales: microgenetic interactions in structured separate from their homes. Although they vary in
activities, ontogenetic changes in the children over size, every BGC we know of has a building of its
months and years, and cultural-historical time, own, often a large, multi-purpose public space. It
represented by the interactions among the partici- is a place where kids go until their parents come to
pants as representatives of their institution that do get them, or until a specified hour when they are to
or do not result in sustainability. Both approaches go home. They are often escorted in groups. It is a
provide insight into the changing relationships group activity in a place set apart. T&CLC, on the
between the designed activity and its ecology over other hand, is located near the geographic center of
time. an apartment-house complex. Parents sometimes
However, they also differ in important respects. send their children to the center to get help with
A 5th D had already been shown incapable of exist- their homework or simply to get them out of their
ing in a HUD housing center in prior years, and it hair. The children come and go freely, but the cen-
failed, despite a great deal of effort and mutual good- ter is virtually never empty from the time it opens
will. Neither partner could adjust sufficiently to meet at 3:00 p.m. until it closes at 7:00 p.m. It came to
the legitimate, local requirements of the other. But be called “The Learning Lounge” when UCSD stu-
a system employing the principles that were a part dents were there. But it was, and remains, a cross-
of the theory that is still growing out of the 5th D roads and source of varied support for many of the
intervention could be implemented in such an envi- families in the community.
ronment. This could be done if the basic system of This combination of a genuine sharing of power
joint activity at the institutional level could provide and responsibility and the particular location of
the coordinated resources to ensure that the activity T&CLC within its community where a large num-
occurs at the face-to-face level of kids, undergradu- ber of the community’s concerns become a part of
ates, and researchers (who we refer to as “observant the joint activity, gave rise to an entirely new set of
participants”). challenges. Over time, swamped by special needs,
Two leading design principles are at the heart the activity system, T&CLC “learning lounge”
of the implementation of the T&CLC project. expanded. It became a runaway object.

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 895


T&CLC as a runaway object At first it seemed that the addition of new
Runaway object is a term coined by Yrjo activities, and bringing in different constituencies
Engeström, who explains the meaning of the term of local residents would fit well within our mutual
as follows: appropriation approach, but we soon discovered
that there can be too much of a good thing. At
Objects are concerns, they are generators and foci
total capacity, we found it an effort just to main-
of attention, motivation, effort and meaning.
tain the Learning Lounge and a few activities that
Through their activities people constantly change
could be made attractive to the kids. Before long
and create new objects. [Runaway] objects are often
we were spending so much of our time coordi-
not intentional products of a single activity but
nating with all of the new organizations whose
unintended consequences of multiple activities.
expertise we were calling on that we no longer
[Runaway objects] have the potential to escalate and
had any time for analysis of what we were doing,
expand up to a global scale of influence. They are
and we could no longer even specify our object of
objects that are poorly under anybody’s control and
analysis!
have far-reaching, unexpected effects.
(Engeström, 2009, p. 304)
The Center for Community Well-being
The 5th D remained a familiar object of analysis As might be expected, the strains that we were
because of its socio-ecological position between the experiencing were also being experienced, in their
school and the home and the relative affluence of the own way, by all of the parties we had involved at
community. The social circumstances of the children T&CLC. As a consequence, while we have con-
and their families were rarely a focus of concern in tinued to develop the Learning Center Learning
organizing the 5th D activities. The routines were Lounge activities, we have banded together with
sufficiently flexible to permit the inclusion of chil- colleagues from the university as well as the larger
dren dubbed “special needs,” which included in our community that is home to the T&C Apartment
case a child with Asperger’s syndrome and mentally complex to create the Center for Community Well-
challenged children, as well as myriad children who Being (CCW; www.ccw.org; See Figure 42.3).
were deemed difficult in some way. To the CCW has fallen the task of engaging the
As time progressed, we discovered that at runaway object that emerged at T&CLC. It coordi-
T&CLC the special needs of the children extended nates the activities of an interdisciplinary group of
well beyond anything we had been confronted UC San Diego faculty and staff with partner organi-
with before. We were not dealing with a few zations in the Southeastern San Diego community
special-needs children. At T&CLC we were dealing to develop integrated projects aimed at improv-
with a special-needs community. Health problems ing education, health, economic development,
appeared in the form of widespread obesity and neighborhood safety, and community services.
diabetes, among the children’s caretakers as well as
the children. Unemployment was so bad that fami- Final Comments
lies were constantly moving out because they could Both of the strategies we describe here were
no longer afford subsidized housing. Healthy food developed under the constraints of the specific local
was not locally available, and affordable healthy ecologies in which they were embedded. The encap-
food amounted to an oxymoron. sulated nature of the BGC partnership is typical
Initially we tried to incorporate the required new of Fifth Dimension projects, but not universal.
activities into the center. We contacted colleagues Members of the LCHC research group, for example,
in the medical school for help in organizing edu- have maintained an in-school and after-school
cational activities for parents. We began to collabo- program for more than a decade at a local elemen-
rate with our colleagues in CALIT2, the local UC tary school where numerous 5th D activities have
technology center that takes an interest in new uses become part of the daily practices of the classroom
of technology for health and education. We con- teachers. This can be seen as evidence that some 5th
tacted people in the Urban Community Gardens D programs can and do morph into arrangements
movement. We searched for, and found help from, that come to resemble the mutual appropriation
a UCSD extension in identifying ways to increase model. The vast majority of its specific routines and
the availability of local and affordable workforce local cultural features evolve into hybrids of those of
training programs. the contributing institutions.

896 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


University Community

Laboratory of
Town & Country
Compareative
Learning
Human Cognition
Center
San Diego
Supercomputer Local High
Center School

Local Middle
California Institue
School
of Telecommu-
nications and Local
Information Elementary
Technology school
UCSD School of
YMCA
Medicine
Non-profit
Center for
Organizations
Research on
Educational Local Free
Equity, Clinic
Assessment, and
Teaching

Figure 42.3 Schematic showing the relationships between the university and community participants in the Center for Community
Well-Being.

The project at T&CLC is also specific to its to change its methods as its environment may
historical/social/cultural time and space. Whether demand.” (p. 126) She described the Hull House
initiated by the university or the local community, as a place where information was interpreted, rather
the specific activities that, as an ensemble, came to than as an agent for social leveling. In her eyes, Hull
occupy T&CLC evolved into a hybrid new form House was first and foremost a meeting place where
of after-school educational activity. The explosive a cross-section of Chicago residents united around
expansion of the institutional arrangements that common social problems (Addams, 1893/2002b).
were required to implement and sustain the various Addams’ sentiments are echoed in more recent
new objectives—health, employment, nutrition, works of Lave and Wenger (1991) and Matusov, St.
etc.—seemed naturally to evolve into the CCW Julien, Lacasa, and Candela (2007). For Lave and
with its broader mandate and greater institutional Wenger (1991) the business of a community is the
and geographic reach. As a result we are witnessing ongoing activity that shapes and sustains the com-
at present the objectives of our original program munity itself. Learning is a byproduct of the pro-
extended into areas and in ways we could not have cesses of negotiation and renegotiation of one’s par-
imagined. ticipation in community life. Matusov et al. (2007),
The two research strategies, involving two kinds who, like us, make undergraduate education a key
of cooperative social arrangements, clearly have element in their approach, note that learning and
important precedents in their general impulse. The development are integral parts of the process of
connections to the work of Dewey’s laboratory transcending one’s life circumstances, and as such
school and general philosophy are obvious in each. require a certain amount of directionality. They ask,
They also have some well-established precedents in “Who defines that directionality? How is it defined?
Jane Addams’ work at Hull House, where she put Who talks on behalf of the “transcending” (p. 36)?
“enrichment” programs like poetry reading on hold It is precisely these complicated issues of agency,
until some very practical services like temporary both personal and institutional, that continue to
housing, daycare, education, medical and legal ser- vex and inspire the development of the design
vices could take root. Addams insisted that the value experiment and mutual appropriation strate-
of the neighborhood program rests in its “. . . flex- gies. As we continue to explore these programs we
ibility, its power of quick adaptation, its readiness hope to bring them into conversation with others

downi ng- w ilson , lecu say, rosero, cole 897


sharing common theoretical grounding, such as Yrjö on far transfer. Journal of Educational Computing Research,
Engström’s Developmental Work Research approach 16, 371–396.
Brown, A. L. (1992). Design experiments: Theoretical and
(Engestrom, 2010) and allied approaches in the par- methodological challenges in creating complex interventions
ticipatory action research tradition (Schensul, 2010). in classroom settings. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 2(2),
Although it seems clear to us that these alternative 141–178.
strategies have much in common, they are developing Brown, A. L., & Campione, J. C. (1998). Designing a com-
in very different social, economic, and cultural ecol- munity of young learners: Theoretical and practical lessons.
In N. M. Lambert, B. L. McCombs (Eds.), How students
ogies, and so are certain to diverge in unpredictable learn: Reforming schools through learner-centered education
and interesting ways. We look forward to fruitful (pp. 153–186). Washington, D.C.,: American Psychological
discussions among the various approaches. Association.
Cobb, P., Confrey, J., diSessa, A., Lehrer, R., & Schauble, L.
Acknowledgments (2003). Design experiments in educational research. Edu-
cational Researcher, 32(1), 9–13.
The authors acknowledge the support of our col-
Cole, M., & The Distributed Literacy Consortium (2006). The
laborators at the University of Colorado, Boulder’s Fifth Dimension: An after-school program built on diversity.
Physics Education Research group and Tufts’ Center New York: Russell Sage Foundation Publications.
for Engineering Education and Outreach as well as Collins, A. (1992). Towards a design science of education. In
the research group at Cornell University who sup- E. Scanlon & T. O’Shea (Eds.), New directions in educational
technology (pp. 15–22). Berlin: Springer.
ported our learning of, and use of Worlds for Internet
Collins, A., Joseph, D., & Bielaczyc, K. (2004). Design research:
Technology and Science (WITS). Robert Lecusay Theoretical and methodological issues. Journal of the Learning
acknowledges support from the National Science Sciences, 13(1), 15–42.
Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship and Elkonin, D. B. (1999). Toward the problem of stages in the
the American Educational Research Association’s mental development of children. Journal of Russian and East
European Psychology, 37, 11–29.
Minority Dissertation Fellowship Program in
Engeström, Y. (2009). The future of activity theory: A rough
Education Research. Support from a grant to the draft. In A. Sannino, H. Daniels, & K. D. Gutiérrez (Eds.),
Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition Learning and expanding with Activity Theory (pp. 303–328).
from the UCLinks Program from the Office of Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
the President of the University of California is also Engström, Y. E. (2010). From individual action to collec-
tive activity and back: Developmental work research as an
gratefully acknowledged.
interventionist methodology. In P. Luff (Ed.), Workplace
Portions of this chapter draw upon the previ- studies recovering work practice and informing system design
ously published Downing Wilson, D., Lecusay, R. (pp. 150–166). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
& Cole, M. (2011). Design experimentation and Newman, D., Griffin, P., & Cole, M. (1989). The construction
mutual appropriation: Two strategies for university/ zone: Working for cognitive change in school. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
community collaborative after-school interventions.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate
Theory & Psychology, 1–25. peripheral participation. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Notes Long, N. (2001). Developmental sociology: Actor perspectives.
1. Undergraduates attended twice a week in addition to London: Routledge.
attendance at class on campus twice a week, where they read aca- Matusov, E., St. Julien, J., Lacasa, P., & Candella, M. (2007).
demic texts deemed relevant to their site participation. Learning as a communal process and as a byproduct of social
activism. Critical Social Studies, 1, 21–35.
References Mayer, R. E., Schustack, M. W., & Blanton, W. E. (1999). What
Addams, J. (1893/2002a). The objective value of the social settle- do children learn from using computers in an informal,
ment. Reprinted in J. Bethke Elshtain (Ed.), Jane Addams and collaborative setting? Educational Technology, 39, 27–31.
the dream of American democracy. New York: Basic Books. Schensul, J. J. (2010). Engaged universities, community based
Addams, J. (1893/2002b). The subjective necessity for social settle- research organizations and third sector science in a global sys-
ments. Reprinted in J. Bethke Elshtain (Ed.), Jane Addams and tem. Human Organization, 69(4), 307–329.
the dream of American democracy. New York: Basic Books. Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky, Vol. 1:
Blanton, W. E., Moorman, G. B., Hayes, B. A., & Warner, M. Problems of general psychology. New York: Plenum.
L. (1997). Effects of participation in the Fifth Dimension

898 a c ultural -hi sto r i ca l approach to u n iversit y


PA RT
11
Social Networks and
Cultural Affectivity
This page intentionally left blank
CHAPTER

Affective Networks: The Social Terrain


43 of a Complex Culture1

Nandita Chaudhary

Abstract
Affective networks of relationships frame every social encounter that a person has in life. Mainstream
psychological research has, however, failed to take adequate consideration of these dynamics in the
writing about and exploration of human conduct across cultures. In every step of research, we espouse
elements of our habitual cultural dynamics. When we consider a context unfamiliar for us, we tend
to superimpose our familiar ways of living onto the other culture, the other person. Also, there is a
preference for quantifiable, observable elements of human conduct, which has contributed to much
knowledge about human phenomena in specific settings but everyday lives of ordinary people all over the
world remain largely ignored by psychological research. This occurs on account of the tedium involved in
searching the streets for processes that defy simple labeling and categorization. The greater the distance
between the socio-economic, cultural, and geographic conditions of a researcher and the researched, the
more arduous the journey of intersubjectivity, the agreement between partners in research. This makes
our judgments more prone to incorrect exploration. Indian community life is characterized by complex,
confounding and contradictory manifestations of ways of living owing to internal and external factors.
This makes it all the more critical to inform ourselves about ambient social reality and personal proclivity
in order to understand people and their conduct. This chapter discusses some of these features of social
life in India that impinge upon interpersonal encounters, and thereby need to be attended to in research.
Keywords: culture, person, environment, ecology, social cognition, cultural differences, Indian family life

As a term, culture has continued to defy simple intersubjectivity of any encounter and the interob-
elucidation. Scholars persist in searching for ways of jectivity of the social group determine the ways in
defining culture with reference to nature, commu- which a people are going to be constructed, whether
nication, meaning, material, or activity. It is essen- as objects to be guided into making sense of their
tial to reflect on academic discourse related to the own lives, or as participants, capable of defining
term precisely because there has been an inadvertent their own reality. Whereas intersubjectivity refers to
marginalization of non-Western, minority, subaltern the agreement in perspectives between individuals;
societies based on the definition of culture in schol- interobjectivity is relevant because there are cultur-
arly discourse, especially in the field of psychology. ally shared variations regarding the world around us
Thus the definition of culture and its application (Moghaddam, 2003). Moghaddam contends (2011)
has become recognized as a political issue over the this is an essential consideration in academic dis-
years. In theories, methods, and interpretation—in course; otherwise we will continue to have increas-
fact, in every step of our research—we espouse ele- ingly isolated dialogues within the social reality of
ments of the explicit and implicit relations among our own cultural or academic affiliations. Human
people and between people and their worlds. The relations “rely on the non-conscious engagement

901
in practices that occur within a social field” outside between two separate elements of reality, in inde-
of the subjects, and not primarily on intersubjec- pendent existence. Reality is constructed with logi-
tive relations (Sammut, Daanen & Sartawi, 2010, cally separate processes of individuals on the one
p. 452). Priming intersubjectivity over and above hand, and their environments on the other. This for-
interobjectivity creates a bias toward individualism mulation is neat, but somewhat inadequate when it
and reductionism emerging out of Western individu- comes to explaining the human condition. Another
alistic traditions and suffers from what Moghaddam way of considering the person-environment inter-
(2010) labels as the “embryonic fallacy” (p. 465). face is inclusive separation, where a person is viewed
This tendency to assume that psychological experi- as distinct, but without being independent of,
ences are initiated at birth has resulted in intersub- but in constant interaction with the environment
jectivity becoming a “problem” to understand since (Valsiner, 1998). This approach has several impor-
it becomes difficult (if not impossible) to explain tant consequences on the way in which theory and
HOW we comprehend others’ perspectives IF we research is advanced.
are the source of our own understanding? The solu-
tion to this is contained in the cultural resources Conversational Structures
that surround us. In cultural psychology, attempts are made to
This chapter focuses on the study of social rela- understand culture at the individual level as it is
tionships among Indians from within, primarily to guided by collective culture, while simultaneously
inform the academic audience about the unique creating it (Valsiner, 2001). The study of culture as
ways of understanding the world that characterize social interactions between individuals and small
Indian communities. If an “outsider” position on groups was identified as critical by Simmel (1971)
Indian culture and tradition is adopted, interpreta- when he distinguished between “subjective” and
tions are not likely to fit the phenomena very well, “objective” culture. By analyzing individual action,
precisely because of the different emphases that are Simmel studied how social institutions are influ-
placed on cultural activity. And yet, in this world enced. He advanced and idea that structure of a
of created contrasts, compare we must. In order to social setting (whether it is dyadic and triadic) is
advance reasonable comparisons and constructions fundamental; interactions between two people,
about people, we need to better understand their and those between three or more, would be very
realities by adopting favorable approaches. In this different in nature, to the extent that the increase
manner, culture is not seen simply as a disturbance in size of group would result in greater “individual
for the elegance of a research design. Cultural activ- freedom.” The “inner unity of a group loosens as a
ity and ascribed meanings are so “dense” that if group becomes larger” (Farganis, 1993, p. 40) on
these are not considered from an indigenous per- account of multiple mutual relationships. Rather
spective, the basic agenda of the (re)search could be than going into size of group and beyond, I am going
obfuscated. to select the distinction between the dyad and triad
that Simmel makes in order that we can understand
Inclusive Separation and the the fact that the structure of social interaction can
Person-Environment Interface have deep impact upon the dynamics of discourse
A meta-conceptual paradigm for dualisms con- through the examples provided in this chapter. This
structs the person and environment as distinct from demonstrates that cultural reality operates not only
each other. Duality is a favored format precisely at an individual level, but also at the group level—in
because it facilitates simple heuristic advancement this instance implying that the size of a group can
in the study of any phenomenon. However, when impact social dynamics. I will pick up this point for
we are dealing with human social phenomena, met- discussion a bit later.
allurgical precision is not a precondition, and the To return to inclusive separation and the interface
ways of presenting social processes has to fit. For between a person and the environment, we can visu-
instance, the person in any given social setting is at alize the intersection of person and the surrounding
the same time influenced by, and influencing the context (read culture here) in Figure 43.1.
context. The complete separation of the two pro- If we visualize a person as object A in the below
cesses will have to be an artificial one. The inter- Figure 43.1, and the environment as not-A, or B;
action between person and environment in such using Valsiner’s notion of inclusive separation (2004,
a system is visualized as a transfer of information p. 18), we can assume a point X on the surface

902 af fec ti ve ne t wo rk s: t he so ci al t e r ra in of a com plex cu ltu re


B (not-A), a culture, whether as a child or an outsider, we are
the context confronted by a context that is “overexplained, over-
determined by meaning” (Valsiner, 2001, p. 117,
emphasis original). How do these meanings become
manifested? Valsiner continues with a statement
that human minds have the proclivity for jumping
to conclusions in any encounter. When symbolic
forms are created in collective culture, where multi-
Person-Context
A Interface
ple motives contribute toward polysemy, or multiple
meanings, the mind rushes to make sense of these
Figure 43.1 Person-environment interface experiences (Obeyesekere, 1990, p. 56). We are it
seems, primed for telling stories (Turner, 1996):
The constant yet unnoticed ‘power of story’ as a
where a person and the context meet. There are
mental activity like vision, for instance, is really the
two ways of understanding this interface. One that
quality of the mind that makes everyday life possible
argues for what Valsiner calls exclusive separation, the
in the human sense. Here we mean story not in the
point where non-A starts and A ends; and the other
sense of entertainment, but as a thread that we are
where this is seen as the meeting point between
capable of weaving. Much as these networks bind us,
A and non-A, and thus the interface of BOTH A
they also create complex webs of activity, identity,
(the person) and non-A (the context), resulting in
reality and family.
a dialogical interface between these two features
(p. 13)
that is at the same time, both A and B. This dialog-
ically (as distinct from a dialectically) constructed The teleological function of the capacity of humans
view of the person-in-context allows for us to argue for storytelling was really to save our worlds from
for a space where we can include both processes. collapsing into chaos, dealing with the overwhelm-
Dialogicality between phenomena (Bakhtin, 1981), ing uncertainty that confronts us at every moment
whether these are perspectives or persons, permits of our lives. Toward this end, we take everyday
us to consider different processes not in opposi- experiences and color them with our own (socially
tion (A versus not-A) but as relational (A or not-A); guided) meanings and connections, and manufac-
focusing on the interface between the two positions. ture our stories about experiences, people, ourselves.
After all the formation of not-A in itself originates We are able to see patterns in phenomena, come to
the moment that one considers A, and is thus foun- conclusions, or adduce reasoning. However, there is
dational for this. If we apply the dialogical princi- another process in operation that we use with amaz-
ple to the relationship between a person and her ing alacrity: abduction. Abduction is the tendency
environment, there is an inevitable dynamic re-de- of the human mind to pick out a possible solution
scription of the world. We can therefore construct (Peirce, 1955). Somewhat like a hunch where we
such a relationship with the following elements that have an intuition that there is some connection,
are not distinct from each other, but in constant even sufficient similarity can be the criterion for
dynamic exchange with each other. Culture can be problem solving when we use abduction. In scien-
visualized as the activity that belongs in between the tific research, for instance, the initial idea of a study
person and the environment rather than the person is obtained through the process of abduction. It is
belonging to culture, or the culture belonging to a after that initial identification that we move toward
person (Valsiner, 2007). This interface, the semiper- inductive and deductive processes for logical analy-
meable membrane allows messages to travel both sis. In social encounters, this abduction of meaning
ways; from the person to the environment, and is formative for the ways in which collective sense is
from the environment to the person. constructed and applied, as we will see later in the
chapter.
Supplement, Surplus and Excess: There are some other processes in cultural
The Process of Abducting Meaning encounters that have relevance for this discussion.
In the dialogue between nature and culture, the Here I would like to introduce the notion of supple-
person and her context, there emerge several pro- ment (Derrida, 1974/1997) that is described as that
cesses that require explication. When a person enters activity exterior to original, natural element, that

ch au dh a ry 903
attempts to replace it in any given situation, like with, fought against or discussed; but it cannot be
child-rearing practices that realize the completion ignored. In the co-construction of meaning, indi-
of the deficient natural system (Gillespie, 2003). vidual minds contribute actively to collective mean-
Interestingly, it is both the accretion as well as sub- ing by tugging at these in specific ways, constantly
stitution functions of any supplement that charac- renewing the organic reality of cultural meaning
terize the idea of a supplement according to Derrida systems.
(1974/1997). When human beings interact, the Let me take an example from Indian cultural
emergence of one idea leads to the simultaneous dynamics and attempt to apply some of the theo-
production of its alternative, and we have to under- retical ideas presented in the preceding paragraphs.
stand the open, dialogical relations between social Among Indians, we find that there is an impressive
phenomena. In dialogical relations, for instance, and almost exaggerated centrality that is placed on
it is the relational rather than the logical, dichoto- others. One such other is the mother who finds place
mous categorization of phenomena that are con- in the dramatic as well as the everyday (Chaudhary
sidered. Perhaps cultural activity can be assumed & Bhargava, 2006; Desai, 2010; Kakar & Kakar,
to be accumulated “supplementarity,” both add- 2007; Thomas, 1995). In a more detailed exami-
ing to and substituting for natural processes and nation of gender relations, we find that the status
perhaps in many domains, even overtaking these. of the mother is not simply a question of gender
Of course taking a dialogical approach to the inter- relations that places men at a superior place as is
action between nature and culture (and not dialec- often misconstrued on account of the predominant
tics) make it quite impossible (and rather futile) to patriarchy of Indian society. The status of women
disentangle the points of departure from nature and is believed to be lower than men on account of
the entry of culture in most instances. Linked with demographic, traditional, and social findings. This
the notion of the supplement in human activity is the makes it quite difficult to understand paradoxical
process of communication that becomes essential manifestations of attitudes toward women in con-
for any cultural process to sustain. Meaning already temporary Indian society from an outside perspec-
exists when a person enters social interchanges and tive (Bumiller, 1990).
is not something that each individual person manu-
The woman may be discriminated from birth, seen
factures afresh on his or her own. In the communi-
as a burdensome liability in her youth, be treated
cation, social groups set up individuals for certain
unfairly and badly by the husband, actively harassed
confrontations over and above others through con-
by her in-laws, but somehow when came to her
versations, rituals, myths, and several other cultural
role as a mother, particularly of a male child, her
processes. This predetermination of individual real-
power and influence knew no bounds. To the Indian
ity is clearly intended by the social group, and then
imagination, the mother represents the source of all
actively reconstructed through everyday interactions
things.
during which a person both “gives” and “gives off”
(Desai, 2010, p. 25)
certain messages (Goffman, 1959) what Bakhtin
(1990) terms as “excess,” thus making the “other” a There is a clear worshiping of the idea of mother-
very larger than life element in the reality of humans hood by people; despite the fact that the same person
(Mead, 1934). This perhaps reflects almost an oppo- may not be respected within another relationship.
site orientation from that of the bias of individual- As Desai suggests further, that in the sociopolitical
ism where intrapsychic phenomena are privileged. context, it is not the person but the position that is
The “surplus,” the enlightened information that our marked. It is not surprising therefore, that India has
minds are capable of engaging with regarding Self in been home to some of the most powerful women
the world of others (Gillespie, 2003) are central to in the political arena. Social positioning is another
the dynamic construction of culture. activity that needs mention in order to understand
this fully. One of the first features of a person that an
Cultural Dynamics in a Specific Instance: Indian will attempt to assess (perhaps as important
The Indian Mother as gender) is the social status, which would include
Cultural processes precede and succeed every economic status, ethnic membership, place of ori-
individual’s life, and impact these in long-lasting gin, caste group, etc. This is not simply to get a pic-
ways by preparing the setting with prior attention. ture of a person’s circumstances, but to assess what
Thus the culture that we live within can be argued the position is with respect to himself or herself; as

904 af fec ti ve ne t wo rk s: t he so ci al t e r ra in of a com plex cu ltu re


a guide to appropriate conduct after considering this weave in with other relationships that the child
whether the person is above or below in social status has to live among?
with reference to the self (Varma, 2005). In inter- I have argued, in fact that when a mother is so
personal interactions, similarly, it is the role and important, then perhaps there would be wisdom
relationship rather than demographic descriptors in preparing for unfortunate eventualities, espe-
that define conventions for close social encounters. cially where survival rates may be compromised on
The Indian sense of self is believed to be constantly account of health status. Several scholars (Kurtz,
changing, partly because context is considered to be 1992; Trawick, 1990; Tuli & Chaudhary, 2010)
formative in determining conduct (Menon, 2003). have found a corresponding importance that is
An imposition of an assumption of “ontological placed on other people in addition to the impor-
individualism” (Bellah et al., 1985) while analyzing tance of the mother that could be characterized by
social interactions in India would be misplaced. The the dialogicality, the inclusive separation of mothers
variability in the ways people can approach a situ- and others (Chaudhary, 2006). The child is believed
ation will be limited to predetermined categories to be naturally attached to the mother, but very
guided by the ideology of individualism, and would intense and intimate exchanges between mother
thus fail to be understood appropriately. and child are often private, even within the socially
To advance the point about “mothers” in India, dense context. In the presence of others, the mother
we find that in the care of children, although the is actively encouraged to distance herself and cor-
mother is considered pivotal, this emphasis does not respondingly promote closeness of the child with
preclude the importance of other members within others. The dynamic arrangement for correspond-
the child’s network. But before going any further ing supplementary resources enhances her activity
I would like to add a cautionary note here. When I along with creating a substitute for her role in a per-
speak of Indianness, I do not imply a homogenous, son’s life. Here we find possible instances for both
monolithic structure of a consolidated, coherent enhancement of as well as the potential substitution
way of living. If anything, Indian culture provides us for the mother. Women in the larger family network
with the exact opposite of each of these adjectives. often compete between each other playfully for the
The number of people, the diversity in languages, child’s care and attention. Perhaps why this happens
ethnic practices, stories, and spirituality makes such is precisely on account of the putative centrality of
statements rather impossible to make. Even the past a mother’s role in a child’s life. This is perhaps an
is textured with variety and multiplicity. India “does instance of supplementarity in the Derridean sense.
not have one past, but many pasts” (Ramanujan, This emphasis is also communicated in the kin term
1999, p. 187). To add to the texture of variability Ma-si in Hindi that refers to the mother’s sister as
is the fact the past always has a constant presence in “like-mother,” as this term translates. It is also note-
our present (Anandalakshmy, 2010). worthy that the mother’s sister is also potentially
substitutive in several ethnic groups in India; in the
At certain levels there are aspects of cultural
event of a woman’s death, the marriage between her
traditions in India that can be traced to roots as far
husband and her sister is not only permitted, it is
back as a few thousand years, but such a continuity
also seen as the best possible option (for the chil-
must not be confused with stagnation.
dren). This theme resonates widely in Indian litera-
(Thapar, 2000, p. xxv)
ture and popular media.
Thus we find that there is an intricate interweav- Regarding maternal love, Hindi has a spe-
ing of “pasts,” which, along with geographical dis- cial expression “Mamta,” also a popular name for
tance and ecological variation, make it possible that women, which finds an important place in every-
people of one area may not have stepped over into day discourse. An investigation of people’s under-
another, and thus “every description of tradition standing of the term demonstrated that mother’s
can be as a negation or contradiction of another” love had a sort of magnetic quality with regard to
(Anandalakshmy, 2010, p. 19). So when we write meaning. In the interviews, people were eager to
about any phenomenon, this reality must be kept as discuss meaning, sometimes extending the feel-
an essential clause. Returning to the issue of moth- ings of (this form of ) love to other relationships,
erhood in India that I am using as an example of a debated about the specificity or flexibility of moth-
dramatic domain of activity in India, what are some er’s love, and even chose to say in some instances,
of the manifestations of this centrality and how does that Mamta was responsible for making mothers

ch au dh a ry 905
more vulnerable to manipulation and exploitation • Any declaration about a particular phenomenon
by uncaring children! There seemed to be no doubt by a person is based on the ‘dialogically established
about the “natural” quality of Mamta, although it shared social reality at this stage’
could transcend the specific mother and her bio- • Transcending of specific perspectives is inevitable
logical child and manifest itself in other affiliations through assimilation of terminologies into everyday
as well (Chaudhary & Bhargava, 2006). I will deal language
with this in greater detail in a later section.
Advancing this proposal, we can visualize any con-
struction of potential activity with the self and oth-
Social Setting and Situated Discourse ers as arranged in the following manner. Consider a
Everyday conversation has a fluid and flexible
person who is approaching an event. I propose these
quality that makes it rather elusive to consider for
four domains of activity as dialogically related (rather
academic study. However, in order to approach
than separated from each other). The first category
people in context, it is essential to explore ordi-
is the self and itself, we carry an elaborate range of
nary experiences of unexceptional members of
predispositions that we have inherited and created
any given society. Rommetveit (1992) discusses
for ourselves as people, a strong internal proclivity
the essential components of a dialogically based
that constitutes our subjectivity. Another domain is
sociocognitive approach to the study of human
a person’s information and approach toward the out-
beings. Proposing basic distinguishing features of
side world that constitutes our objectivity. I define
this approach, he places importance on context-
this not simply as the “unbiased, impartial” attitude
situated discourse:
as defined, but the belief in an impartial, unbiased
What distinguishes a socio-cognitive and dialogical element of our collective reality! Then there is the
paradigm from orthodox ecological psychology is real or imagined “other person(s)” in any encoun-
an acknowledgement and superordinate concern ter. The individual under discussion here will have
with cultural invariance and variance, with social an element of intersubjectivity, the belief about the
construction of shared realities, and with issues of beliefs of the other. This is taken as a stance which
‘intersubjectivity’ encountered in our encounters the person operates from, an assumed objectivity
with ‘Lebenswelt’ (lifeworld) from within. about the world. Once the intersubjective capacity
(p. 21) is developed ontogenetically, we conduct ourselves
with this basic element of our reality. Then the last
If this approach is accepted as a basic tenet of
element is the putative knowledge of collective and
human activity, then we have to accept some of the
social reality, tradition and convention. This presen-
corollaries about the human mind as well. These are
tation can be a seen as one possible way of under-
extracted from Rommetveit (1992, p. 21–23):
standing the constituents of a person’s perspectives
• The human mind is basically social and informs us in any given encounter.
not only about a person, but also that which is being
interacted with Methods of Approaching the Study of
• Ordinary language mediates this activity for known Human Beings, Intersubjectivity and
as well as novel experiences the “Psychologist’s Fallacy”
• Shared social reality guides a person’s approach Every cultural community creates over the years
towards any encounter with the ecological-cultural a range of shared understandings of social reality.
reality These “collaboratively constructed objectifications of
• These predispositions place limits on potential the world” that are shared within and between cul-
conduct, although not entirely tures is what Moghaddam (2003, p. 222) refers to as
• On account of these predispositions, activity is interobjectivity. If we search ancient Hindu texts for
always from a ‘particular’ perspective defining human activity, the delineation of sravana
• ‘Attunement to the attunement of the other’ char- (hearing about or experiencing), manana (thinking
acterises human activity about, cognition) and nidhidhyasana (meditation),
• In any situation, the respective meanings are make the three important methods for study of
guided by subjective perspectives, and can never be reality, what can be argued as first-person, second-
absolute person and third-person methodology (Rao, 2008).
• Joint attention and dialogue facilitates the The focus is placed on transactional AND transcen-
‘attunement to the attunement of the other’ dental reality, and consciousness receives a central

906 af fec ti ve ne t wo rk s: t he so ci al t e r ra in of a com plex cu ltu re


place in such a construction. The complex and con- is possible to see this phenomenon as confusion
founding construct of consciousness has driven its between subjectivity and intersubjectivity, a capa-
study outside of mainstream psychology, focusing bility for social cognition that children are believed
largely on measureable domains of activity. In the to develop around the age of 4 years of age! Several
study of the self, the primary search has been for other overlaps can also be visualized: that between
the consolidation of literature about a notion of self interobjectivity and objectivity, where social reality
that is based in the ideology of individualism. More is assumed as being a universal principle; or between
recently, we have encountered several approaches subjectivity and objectivity, a common mistake that
to research and theory that have attempted to con- our version of the truth is the final word.
trast the development of self in other cultures where Moscovici (1976) stated that societies are con-
there is a departure from the ontology of individual- structed largely around their own survival. As far as
ism that characterizes most theorizing about the self human conduct and social processes is concerned,
(Menon, 2003, Misra, 2010). ambiguity and ambivalence prevail over exactness
and clarity. Depending upon the situation, soci-
Ambiguity in Cultural Dynamics ety “inhibits what it stimulates” (p. 149) with the
It has been my experience that most industri- simultaneous excitement and inhibition of particu-
ous projects in our discipline have tended to suffer lar tendencies like aggression, sex, or hunger. The
from a syndrome that could be characterized as an chances for satisfaction of these is either inhibited
“avoidance of ambiguity.” We search for means and or enhanced depending upon the situation, and
standard deviations in the troubling conditions of within cultural dynamics lie the prohibitions as well
the central tendency that is (often unquestioningly) as strategies for transgression. Thus when we speak
assumed. To speak of “a culture, this culture, as a about meaning and culture, it is possible to see how
consensus on fundamentals—shared conceptions, meanings are complex, multiple, and even contra-
shared feelings, shared values—seems hardly viable dictory. Everyday talk is authored by human beings
in the face of so much dispersion and disassembly; but it is constantly attributed to society (Valsiner,
it is the faults and fissures that seem to mark out 2007) since the distinctive quality of social processes
the landscape of collective selfhood” (Geertz, 2000, is that they seamlessly enter personal positions and
p. 250). vice versa.
Psychology’s stories could be argued as being The study of linguistic terms has been a very
told largely from the stance of an informed aca- important introduction in unraveling cultural
demic discussing a naive subject both within any reality (Wierzbicka, 1997) and providing a local
culture and cross-culturally. James (1884) remarked framework within which culture is manifested in
that psychologists become confused about what is the minds of its members. There are other sym-
in their minds and what exists in the minds of their bolic modes like ritual, icons, art, and music, which
subjects, what he calls the “psychologist’s fallacy.” provide valuable insights into the meaning systems
Consequently, psychologists tend to attribute and of any culture. Through decades of the dance of
impose ideas that they have in their minds onto oth- meaning and symbolism, collective culture becomes
ers, initiating the debate about assumed positions, focused on some elements of created ideas more
privileged perspectives and putative objectivity in than on others. Through this sifting of symbols, the
research and other academic activity. The mutual unique collection of ideas that emerge at any given
recognition of consciousness is an essential ingre- time is the substance of culture. To return to the
dient in the methodology for investigating human domain of motherhood in India, we find it is greatly
experience. If we use Table 43.1 as a template, it “overdetermined” by meaning (Obeyesekere, 1990)
such that it is believed to be at the center of existence
of every woman within herself and for every man
Table 43.1 An orthogonal arrangement of self-other in his association with his mother, as was discussed
understanding in the earlier section. If we look at the vocabulary
Person Level Individual Group for a mother’s love, there is an interesting dynamic
arrangement of ideas that emerges. Like any cultur-
Self Subjective Objective ally valued symbol, motherhood in Hindi is labeled
by a special term that is at the surface simple and
Other Intersubjective Interobjective
straightforward to understand.

ch au dh a ry 907
With this objective we (Chaudhary & Bhargava, gradually transforms the meaning of words that
2006) proposed a study to investigate people’s beliefs become over-laden with a singular meaning. But the
about the meaning of the Hindi word Mamta, story does not end there. Actually the story never
which is commonly believed to be the “natural” ends. In our conversations with individual people,
love of a mother for her child. Although there were we found that although the starting point becomes
several dictionary meanings available in addition to the well-known meaning, people’s arguments take
“mother’s love,” through the interviews it emerged the meaning in other directions, like the possibility
that both collectively and individually, the meaning that the meaning could also include father’s love,
seemed to have first become quite reduced at a col- love for a pet, feelings toward a friend in need, quite
lective level, and then was found to again expand in easily. However, none of these meanings return even
the individual meaning. At the collective level, the remotely to selfishness, pride, and greed. The mean-
several dictionary meanings had actually become ing is unequivocally positive, despite the fact that it
simply reconfigured into a single meaning, “mother’s could have harmful outcomes (like the spoiling of
love” characterized as deeply selfless and devotional. a child with unconditional love could make him or
A mother’s life is constructed as revolving around her dismissive toward the parent).
her children and vice versa. This dictionary mean- In Figure 43.2, there are two points in time at
ings of Mamta which originally carried meanings which meaning is being transformed, or at least
like Yeh mera hai, is prakar ka bhav (this is mine, this changing in emphasis. Firstly, we have the collec-
kind of feeling), mamatva, apnapan (self-feeling), tive shift over the centuries of a term originally cre-
lobh (greed), moh (love), abhimaan (pride), garv ated with a certain range of meanings (Point A in
(pride), sneh and prem (both meaning love); and Fig. 43.2). Guided by cultural priorities, one mean-
lastly we find mata ka apni santan ke prati sneh (a ing takes precedence over all others and remains
mother’s love for her child) (Pathak 1995, p. 612). dominant in the initial reaction of all respondents
The Sanskrit root word from which Mamta derives without exception. Soon after this declaration is
is mamatva, meaning “love for the self ” and pride. made, and people actually say they may not know
So the idea starts with love for the self, or selfish love, about this since they are not “experts” or experienced
expands to reach pride, love, ownership, and greed. in the matter (some men and unmarried women
Additionally, Mamta is also a popular name for a said this), the participants in the study went com-
woman in India. Over the centuries, the diction- fortably into a detailed description of their views
ary meanings have become rather obscured as “soci- on the matter. This is characterized by point B in
ety” has adopted (or abducted) the last meaning, the diagram (see Fig. 43.2). This is the moment in
that of mother’s love toward her child, as the single the interview where people were actually construct-
accessible meaning for ordinary users of Hindi. ing their views on the matter. It is proposed that in
We find that social history made up of contribu- every social encounter, this is precisely what hap-
tions by individual people and collective movement pens. People’s views on matters are not something

Sense of belonging

Love for a vulnerable person


Love for self Father’s love

Love
A
A mother’s love for her child

Mamta Selfless love

Natural devotion to offspring


Figure 43.2 Schematic diagram of instances
COLLECTIVE MEANING INDIVIDUAL MEANING of “abduction” in the meaning of “Mamta”

908 af fec ti ve ne t wo rk s: t he so ci al t e r ra in of a com plex cu ltu re


they always carry around in their heads a priori; Let us take another example of cultural beliefs
these meanings are actually constructed and and practices from a recent study. A total of 46
re-constructed in the actual encounters of everyday female university students in New Delhi, India were
life. The interview is simply a social opportunity, asked about the sleeping arrangements at home
albeit with its own particular formalities and this is (Chaudhary & Gilsdorf, 2010). It was reported
precisely why the active, flexible interview method that at the age of 5 years, all of them were sleep-
becomes critical as a technique for data collec- ing in the same bed with another person: parents,
tion (for an excellent illustration, see Bernheimer & grandparents, siblings, or another family member;
Weisner, 2007). and currently, 23 of them still continued to sleep in
If we return to Table 43.1, we can conjecture that the same bed/room as their parents. Although these
there is an obscuring of the distinction between two patterns may have persisted on account of several
sets of processes, one between interobjectivity and factors, especially the space available and number
objectivity: that people believe the cultural meaning of members in a home, the electricity costs of using
to be a natural endowment. Menon (2003) supports extra power and therefore extra expense; these sleep-
this interpretation in her declaration that Indians ing arrangements were argued mostly on the basis of
do not distinguish between convention and natu- emotion, security, love, and care. It was found that
ral law. The other mixing is between the collective the young women justified co-sleeping with reasons
meaning as being personal. The latter connection is like: the young child needs physical contact for love
typical of cultural activity where collective beliefs are and security (at age 5 years) and predominantly
articulated AS IF they are personal. This is a process “fun” and affection at their current age. Those who
at the individual level that strengthens and sustains had moved into an independent room reported that
society and culture. What we experienced during they often returned to their parents’ room whenever
the interviews was an enthusiastic defense of a cul- the mother was alone at home, as in the afternoon
turally valued notion. People defended the presence or when the father was away; something that they
and need for this love in order for society to sur- found very pleasurable. It is important to note that
vive and prosper through the careful nurturing of these were all young women, and responses of men
individual children. This unequivocal acceptance of would have been different. Inspired by Shweder’s
an idea is a demonstration of the power of cultural work (Shweder, Mahapatra, & Miller, 1988), a sec-
activity and its active recreation through individual ond phase was added to the study related to gather-
voices. Also, the confusions that we have between ing opinions about a specific hypothetical situation:
what we believe as individual agents and collectively A young mother who shifts her 5-month-old baby
shared ideas, prepares us for supplication. out of her bed to a cot in another room. This ques-
tion was asked of 51 college-going female students
Justifying Cultural Practices: Sleeping and 103 parents and other family members in the
Arrangements in the Home students’ homes (51 men and 52 women). The
Advancing the reason/randomness debate related findings showed that with the exception of one
to cultural practice, another important feature of respondent (a student’s mother) who argued that
any cultural practice is that although it may be arbi- the mother must have had her reasons, there was
trary and/or adaptive, in its justifications provided an unequivocal objection to the action of separating
by members of culture, it is argued as strategic and the child. “How could she do something so ‘cruel’?”
meaningful. We find that people actively justify “When the child grows up she will also not care
actions and invest much emotion in the choices that about her parents since she was rejected by them
they putatively “make” in ways of living. At the risk at this tender age?” “It is very inconvenient for the
of sounding dismissive, there is some evidence for a mother to run up and down to another room at
sort of exaggerated ownership that is communicated night?” “How will there be love and attachment?”
while discussing personal choices that may simply “A ‘real’ mother would never do such a cruel thing!”
have been a matter of adopting prevailing practices. (Emphasis original).
The commitments that we are primed toward from In another study of mothers and their young
a very early age become the glue that binds people infants and choices for sleep arrangements through
to their culture. Gradually, these ties may become observations and interviews of mothers and other
loosened as we travel through our lives and encoun- caregivers (Kaur, 2010), there was a similar finding
ter other ways of living. related to opinions about proximity during sleep.

ch au dh a ry 909
70
60
Number of respondents

50
40
30
20
10
0
Physical Needs Mother Physical Child is Child will Other
Needs love and careless safety too young be lonely Figure 43.3 Opinions of respondents about
affection independent sleeping of a 5-month-old
Reasons baby (N=154)

Although it was considered essential for the mother indicating the enormity of what he had done and
and child to be close together, it was also possible pleaded him to return her boy to life as he was
to substitute the mother for any other person, like a innocent. She threatened to leave Shiva if he was
grandmother. This was done as much to release the unable to do this. Shiva then asked his guards to
mother for household work and other children as search the world to find a mother who was sleeping
for the baby; and also sometimes to make the older with her back towards the baby and bring the head
person feel involved in the home. This resonates of the baby to him so he could replace the son that
well with the earlier discussion about the coexist- he had killed. The guards searched everywhere until
ing importance of the mother and others presented they discovered an elephant mother and her baby
earlier in the chapter. In response to the query where she was turned away from the baby. They took
about proximity during a baby’s sleep, 11 (out of away the head of the baby elephant and Ganesha was
27) participants shared a legend as a justification recreated. This legend carries a strong and resounding
not only for sleeping close to the baby, but actually message: Mothers who turn away from their babies
always remaining “facing the baby” during sleep, in sleep run the risk of losing their child to the forces
preferably with your hand on the child in order to of danger.
protect the child and facilitate a sleep “free of fear.” (Kaur, 2010, p. 34–35)
Regarding facing the child during sleep, however,
Here we find the instance of a phantasm (Boesch,
all of them asserted its importance, to the extent
1991; Valsiner, 2001), a personal reconstruction
that if the mother got tired of sleeping on one side,
of a myth in order to make it available and appli-
she would flip over lengthwise rather than face
cable to an individual person. Whereas myths are
away from the child. Consolidating the responses
collective stories that guide cultural reality, the
of the different people who had different versions
phantasm makes these myths adaptively available
and lengths of the story, a close approximation of
for individual consumption. In most instances, we
the legend would be:
are unable as individual minds, to grasp the reasons
This story is about the Hindu god Shiva and his wife for the bind that these collective realities place on
goddess Parvati. As the legend goes, one day Parvati us, whether it is attachments to the homeland, the
was taking her bath and wanted to have a person people in our lives, or the things that we cherish
guarding her bathing area. For this purpose, she (Boesch, 2002, p. 134). We find again that simi-
created a ‘son’ from the dirt of her body. Shiva was lar to the instance of the meaning of Mamta that
not aware of who this person was when he returned derived from older meanings, one of these meanings
home. This was his own son, Ganesha whom Parvati seemed to be abducted for personal use. Similarly,
had created for her own safety. Ganesha also did in the retelling of this story, the women of different
not know who this man was at the entrance to the ages were using the myth in a very personal manner
home, and thus prevented Shiva from entering his since the question was not about myths they know
own home. Deeply angered by being prevented from about divine mothers and children; but when they
entering his own home, Shiva severed Ganesha’s were asked how they sleep and why! As indicated in
head. Upon seeing this, Parvati turned upon Shiva the review of research on morality referenced above,

910 af fec ti ve ne t wo rk s: t he so ci al t e r ra in of a com plex cu ltu re


Hindus do not make a systematic differentiation and is characterized by dense, plural communities
between convention and morality in everyday con- from all over India, with an estimated population
duct. I argue here, that a similar confounding exists of 13,662,885. For the families that participated in
between mythical reality as constructed in daily dis- this study, most young couples were living as nuclear
course and everyday conduct, what Pattanaik (2009) units (average family size was 3), all with only one
calls the tendency to understand the world accord- child at the time of the study. Although the moth-
ing to principles of “Mythos” rather than “Logos,” ers were not working outside the home, they were
which he describes as a propensity for the subjective, all educated and fathers of the young children were
discursive and descriptive rather than being bound employed in salaried jobs in the private sector. There
by logical argumentation. But this does not also was a characteristic enthusiasm for education among
imply an absence of logical thought among Indians, the urban residents and a great deal of effort is placed
it simply indicates preferences and propensity in the on children’s preschool education and future school
ways in which the world is understood. selection at this age. The homes were equipped
There seems therefore, no confusion in combin- with toys, books, and other materials that children
ing scientific reasoning with spiritual discourse, played with regularly, and mothers typically were
no difficulty in blending traditional and modern engaged very closely with the actions of the chil-
beliefs, using adaptive strategies that Tuli labels as dren, deeply curious about the study and what the
“elective interdependence” (Tuli, & Chaudhary, researcher was doing with the children and how this
2010). Ambiguity, according to Trawick (1990) is would be interpreted. The participants in the study
an overarching principle of social life among the were eager about the study, primarily on account of
Indian community. It is true that it remains hard the fact that they considered such a participation
if not impossible to characterize a billion people to be “good for the child.” In contrast, the rural
with one overarching feature, but this term is one families were usually large, with several couples and
that certainly has appeared as a descriptive label for children living in co-residence with their relatives.
Indians often enough. Apart from this, the movement between families
within the community was characterized by fluidity
Culture, Context, Relationships and and flexibility. Children were relatively free to roam
Social Cognition: Another Example the streets at this age, usually in the company of
In the preceding arguments, I have tried to refer- other children who were older. Very few of the chil-
ence examples that display the critical importance dren attended the one government-run preschool
of context in understanding findings, although program, and although education was valued, the
much of psychological research persists in adopting educational future of the children did not emerge as
the opposite view: that context-free, “pure experi- an important concern at this age. It is important to
mentation” is the best method of studying people. note that the economic and religious profile of the
Certainly, the engagement in relationships that groups was quite similar, although very difficult to
occurs in a particular setting gives us critical infor- compare on the basis of the different ecological and
mation about intersubjectivity and interobjectivity economic characteristics of the urban (read corpo-
that are needed to understand conduct. Unless we rate) and rural (agricultural) economy. The rural and
notice and explore affective networks in a cultural urban families had a similar relative socio-economic
setting, we are unable to advance toward a compre- position within their community. They were neither
hensive analysis of events, whether these are within from among the very rich nor the very poor in their
or outside of scientific research. respective regions; and in that sense were assumed
In another study that was conducted in two to be comparable. That is the differences between
distinct subcultural conditions to explore precisely the two groups could be attributed mostly to the
how the social setting will influence children’s con- ecological differences, that is rural urban differences
duct and adult interactions with and about children, in family life. The study was focused on children’s
Bhargava (2010) examined 3-year-old children’s sociocognitive abilities, to map the ways in which
social cognition in urban Mumbai (a large metrop- the ecological setting, epistemological orientations,
olis) and rural Rajasthan. The village selected for and social interactions framed children’s expressions
the study was small (population of 2,904, primarily of self and other persons. While using multiple
agricultural, and typically rural). Mumbai has been methods, the study focused on using standardized
the commercial capital of the country for centuries methods (false-belief task), language assessment

ch au dh a ry 911
(receptive and expressive language based on picture These two groups belong within one national-
descriptions), a play task (using similar materials) ity and certainly also one cultural group if we take
developed especially for the study, and a storytell- the popular meaning of culture. However, we can
ing task where an ancient Indian story was used for see that in many ways the social context forms an
gathering adult input to the child. The presentation essential part, not only of the child’s social cogni-
of play materials required the family to put away all tion, but also of the shared understanding of the
toys belonging to the child so that there was some world, the objectivity and interobjectivity. To act as
similarity in the conditions for the activity. There if the experience of playing with a kitchen set with
was a tremendous contrast observed here, since only a mother doll and a baby doll is “free” of context,
one rural home had some toys for the children that and can be expected to manifest in all children at
were within the child’s reach. around the same maturational stage is another addi-
The findings indicated that although 3-year-old tion that we can safely add to the list of common
children fail the false-belief task as is expected of fallacies with which psychologists can be afflicted.
their age, the reasons for their responses within the As a consequence, if a dyadic, “context-free” experi-
task could be attributed to their handling of dolls/ mentation with objects is considered in a multi-
puppets, and the discourse features of their com- party social context, then the child will certainly be
munity. Both these findings also demonstrated reacting more to the transformation in the social
marginal advantages for urban children over the setting rather than the task at hand. There were
rural children. Let me elaborate this point. In the other very engaging differences that emerged in dis-
play with objects, there was a distinct “fear” of the course strategies. This time, it was the number of
dolls as could be seen from the videos of several interacting adults rather than rural and urban dif-
rural children. Additionally, even those who were ferences that emerged. For example, when dyadic
not fearful found them to be unfamiliar, despite the homes (with mother and child) were separated from
fact that these dolls were custom-made to “look” multi-party homes (the child with several adults,
familiar in terms of hair, clothing, and appearance. including the mother, grandparents, others), irre-
Urban children on the other hand went speedily to spective of location, the differences in discourse
play with dolls, often making sounds while simu- strategies (amount of talk by adults to child, for
lating quarrels or other actions. It is not that this example) were significant, rather than by the rural-
sort of play was not found among rural children, urban division. It is thus immediate context and the
but its frequency and arrangements were apprecia- larger ecological setting both that need to be consid-
bly different. During the play task, the researcher ered along with several other factors. This certainly
ask

You might also like