You are on page 1of 4

Review

Reviewed Work(s): Text and Act: Essays on Music and Performance by Richard Taruskin
Review by: Stan Godlovitch
Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 56, No. 3 (Summer, 1998), pp.
307-309
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/432372
Accessed: 01-11-2016 00:29 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Tue, 01 Nov 2016 00:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Book Reviews 307

shipbuilding techniques that also involved a kind of tions, based primarily on subtle etymological analy-
weaving. It is easy to think of the proportional simi- ses, in order to make connections among a network of
larities between rows of oars moving in unison and seemingly disparate domains. Sometimes these con-
the lines of Doric columns. nections are quite loosely drawn; at others they are
The Greek temple, according to McEwen, symbol- bound together well.
ized the "householder/citizen" of the Greek polis, its One more thing: Even the paperback version of this
obvious order reflecting the order of the well-made MIT publication is beautifully designed and gener-
city. In a related point, McEwen also contrasts the ously illustrated with wonderful, and highly relevant,
well-ordered polis with the port, such as the drawings and photographs. And this would be as
Athens/Piraeus juxtaposition, the latter as disharmo- good an opportunity as any to say that MIT Press has
nious and ununified as the former aspires to being consistently published, what, in my opinion, have
well made. In Athens, McEwen claims, the mother been some of the most handsome books in aesthetics
city (metropolis)Iport relationship was reversed: the and art history, especially in architecture, that are
stable Athens having come to rely, through the prof- available anywhere. This book is one of them.
its of colonization, upon the moving ships of the Pi-
raeus for its survival and growth-its stability. DAVID GOLDBLATT
McEwen's reading of these architectural begin- Department of Philosophy
nings is an attempt to draw a connection between the
Denison University
remarkable lightness of the temple and its embodi-
ment of well-crafted kosmos. When explaining Vin-
cent Scully's observation that the Parthenon does in-
deed seem to take wing, McEwen says, "I strongly TARUSKIN, RICHARD. Text and Act: Essays on
suspect that the intention of their building was to de- Music and Performance. New York: Oxford Uni-
scribe the tension not so much of arrested movement versity Press, 1995, 382 pp., $14.95 paper.
as of movement that is not yet." However, this re-
mark, which I take to be a serious conclusion of her Who now is the voice on earth of Bach, of Mozart, of
thesis, goes entirely unexplained. Its neglect leaves Josquin? Certainly not the doctrinaire purveyors of
one to speculate further about a move toward a divine authenticity in Early Music. "Why not simply recog-
direction, a continuation of Greek colonization or a nize our modern Bach for what he is, and stop the
general progress of kosmos over the unmolded ape- nonsense about authenticity?" (p. 144)-and so a
iron. As a representation of the unity of craft and telling taste from this lively and pugnacious pamphle-
community, McEwen does say, the temple replaced teering collection which I recommend to anyone who
the caves and sacred groves as spaces of divine has thought about or developed a taste for historically
epiphanies, which I interpret as a "natural" to "artifi- authentic performance. The collection falls into two
cial" step and again an emphasis on the civilized polis. parts titled "In Theory" and "In Practice." Most items
One of McEwen's final claims, that Socrates had were published between 1986 and 1991. I will focus
neither "understood or appreciated the artifact played here upon "In Theory" although Taruskin wisely
as the sensible vehicle and anchor for political kos- never lets us conspire to isolate that from practice.
mos," would surely have to be balanced by a recogni- Because the pieces interweave and overlap, they are
tion of the dozens of analogies between form and treated below as the unit they constitute.
craft throughout the dialogues, and by the signifi- Although largely leveled against prominent fac-
cance of the role of the demiourgos, or craftsman of tions in the Early Music movement, Taruskin's invec-
the Timaeus. Also, her somewhat surprising conclu- tives trace the ailment of practice purism to a general
sion, contained in her final sentence, that "not only drift in twentieth-century music toward "dehuman-
metaphysics but all of Western thinking was first ized, geometricized art" (p. 136). The backroom bad
grounded in architecture," is entirely unsupported by guys turn out to be those modernists who have domi-
the strands of assumption in her book and would nated current taste in classical music performance
seem to contradict her earlier thesis about the com- for nearly a century. Among the evil demons are
mon "blood tie" with order. Even the somewhat Toscanini, Stravinsky, and Satie with their tireless
weaker thesis that Western thinking is grounded in campaigns respectively for text-centered literalism,
craft, even if craft were a necessary condition for impersonality, and lightness (p. 167), and their rejec-
more abstract speculation, is not defended. tion of any romantic and Teutonic musical aesthetic
Still, I would heartily recommend this book-it ex- which encourages high expressiveness, gravity, spon-
tends the imagination regarding an already somewhat taneity, and invention. Latterly muscling in on the au-
familiar domain and it stimulates new thinking about thority is the scholar, "Papa Doc, the musicologist"
early craft, architecture, and ordered thought. What (p. 187), epitomized in the "positivistic historicism"
McEwen does best is to draw broad-stroked connec- (p. 146) and "destructive authoritarianism" (p. 147)

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Tue, 01 Nov 2016 00:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
308 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

of Arthur Mendel, the Princeton musicologist. As one For Taruskin, ethical issues arise about musicians
amongst the "happy-go-lucky postmoderns" (p. 183), being true to themselves. By submitting slavishly
Taruskin identifies early-music "performance prac- (p. 129) to the Work and to the intentions of the dead
tice authoritarians" (p. 65) as ideologically heir to (both mummified by the musicologist), the performer
and typical of a pervasive twentieth-century posi- thereby abandons expressive responsibility. This cre-
tivistic and modernist persuasion, one which is hos- ates "a crisis of sincerity" which takes the form of not
tile to the "decentered musical polity" (p. 193) he de- "speaking truly and in one's own voice" (p. 135).
fends. So what is the fuss? The fuss is about the fact "The appeal to intentions is an evasion of the per-
that so-called historically authentic performance is former's obligation to understand what he is perform-
neither historical nor authentic (i.e., faithful recon- ing" (p. 98).
struction), but is just the expression of a contempo- If players are not always true to themselves, they
rary musical aesthetic, one reflecting purely twenti- may not be entirely to blame. There is a broader po-
eth-century tastes and (thus) liable to inhibiting litical side, reflecting not only the power of the schol-
musical inventiveness and individuality. "What Early ars to dictate the authoritative texts and techniques to
Music has been doing is busily remaking the music of be addressed, but also to bully performers, to give
the past in the image of the present, ... only calling the them "a 'bad conscience"' (p. 147) about what they
present by some other name" (p. 169). should properly be doing. This climate of authoritar-
Taruskin disputes not only the historical ambitions ian rule leads to the kind of revisionism that makes
of the reconstructionists, but their very program, one conductor trim all the richness (referred to by the
namely, to present early music properly, to recreate it, conductor as "fat" and "indulgence") in Brahms's Re-
as it was originally intended by the composer for its quiem in the name of authenticity. This gives us "not
time and place and as it must have sounded to its first a historically correct performance but a politically
audiences. "Historical reconstruction is just another correct performance" (p. 174).
variety of interpretive excess" (p. 59) because "there The ideology driving historical reconstruction con-
is no unmediated access to the past. All 'pasts' are cerns Taruskin greatly. Modernist scholasticism be-
constructed in the present" (p. 218). speaks "our impersonal, nay antipersonal, times"
Taruskin's sustained critique of what he terms "au- (p. 162). In their expurgation of romanticism, mod-
thenticism" operates along at least five fronts. Re- ernists favor precision, uniformity, and external
garding epistemological matters, Taruskin points out answers to performance questions. "Vitalist perfor-
the extreme fallibility in reconstructive efforts con- mance" is scorned (p. 130). "Elitism, purism, insis-
cerning what counts as the definitive musical texts. tence on scrupulous realization" (p. 132) triumph over
"Editing is interpretation. Period" (p. 85). Com- subjective choice and invention. "Verisimilitude" and
posers' intentions too are elusive and often change "depersonalization" displace "human content" and
regarding one and the same piece, e.g., Marais's expressiveness (p. 136). These are age-old themes re-
changes of heart (p. 71). We just do not and cannot bottled many times over. For what more (and no less)
know well enough exactly what went on to allow our have we here than the battles between Apollo and
speculative sketches to dominate performance choices. Dionysus, the classical and the romantic, reason and
Some composers, he notes, discover what their in- passion, objectivity and subjectivity, beauty and the
tentions were after hearing musicians perform their sublime, order and flux, enlightenment and mysti-
pieces. Further, "adherents to [authenticism] have cism, logic and intuition, mind and heart, authority
no unique claim in the matter of fidelity to the com- and freedom, law and will, mechanism and human-
poser's intentions. Everyone claims it" (p. 98). ism (to which Taruskin would add: text and act), ...
Worse, even where the composer's wishes-Pro- and so on? What the Apollonian forfeits is "tradition
kofiev, Debussy-have been captured for all to hear, as hermeneuts conceive it: cumulative, multiply au-
they may be completely ignored and even condemned thored, open, accommodating, above all messy, and
(pp. 188-189). therefore human" (p. 192).
The ontological dimension involves musical works. Following suit with those anthropologists who,
In aiming to get to some pristine entity, musicological ages ago, began to suspect that culture and tradition
attention turns to identifying the authoritative origi- are constructed and not found, Taruskin demands
nal, which, when distilled as a score, becomes reified that the authenticists face their own mere preferences
and then sanctified ("text-fetishism" [p. 187]), em- and acknowledge that "what we call historical perfor-
balmed in its barest essentials. In an ironic positivis- mance is the sound of now, not then," that its authen-
tic turn, by becoming thus isolated the text-based ticity derives not from historical verisimilitude "but
work becomes ahistorical, a museum piece fashioned from its being for better or worse a true mirror of late -
by its curators. Its only acknowledged properties twentieth-century taste" (p. 166). He insists that many
must be empirically verifiable, i.e., shorn of all un- of us like the "lean cuisine recipe" (p. 174) of mod-
documented and undocumentable vagaries. ern early music performance-its brightness, brisk-

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Tue, 01 Nov 2016 00:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Book Reviews 309

ness, "fleet coolness," clarity, energy, lightness, and First"-largely a tit-for-tat gripe session against de-
tractors-and dive directly into Taruskin's ever-
sparseness. All of this is just fine, so long as we ac-
cept it as our own way of wanting our music to sound. brisk, ever-energetic slug-fest against authenticist
In this more reflective regard, the early music move- bullies, first staged in 1981 at the American Musico-
ment "as a symptomatically modern phenomenon ... logical Society and reproduced here as "On Letting
is not historical but it is authentic" (p. 175). the Music Speak for Itself."
Well, what, besides honesty and self-awareness, One last quote (my favorite, not least because it
does Taruskin want? Appearances aside, he values seems the whole truth): "Some writers, myself among
greatly the work done in the name of historically au- them, have proposed that talk of authenticity might
thentic performance, but not for the reasons authenti- better be left to moral philosophers, textual critics,
cists offer. Such performances, at their sincere best, and luthiers" (p. 92). Questions about which woods to
give us ourselves, express our tastes, as do any per- use or how thinly to scrape down lute ribs always
formances that flow uninhibitedly from a living tra- seemed so much clearer than those about whether to
dition of music making. Taruskin awaits with some play the Renaissance lute near the bridge or the rose.
joy the ongoing evolution of early music practice, and Taruskin has sorted me out on this one.
is quite sure that, so long as it is not constrained from
without by the ideologues, pedants, and curators, it STAN GODLOVITCH
will grow into as richly heterogeneous a musical en- Human & Leisure Sciences
terprise as any we know. It will thus deepen our de- Lincoln University
veloping musical tradition, not least for its offering
New Zealand
yet more options for expressive invention, novelty,
and experiment. Scholarship is to be the servant of
performers ("Let us accept from the scholar in us
only that which genuinely excites the performer in DANTO, ARTHUR C. After the End of Art: Con-
us" [p. 62]), and the "positivistic purgatory, literalis- temporary Art and the Pale of History. Princeton
tic and dehumanizing, a thing of taboos and shalt- University Press, 1997, 239 pp., 18 b&w illus.,
nots" (p. 76) shall be cast from our midst. $24.95 cloth.
Of course, this all sounds rousingly-however un-
helpfully-romantic, and so it is. But who, really, Art has ended. There is still an enormous amount of
would want to pooh-pooh the virtues of musicianship art being produced. Anything at all can count as art.
Taruskin defends, all of which seem in their own right A definition of "art" in terms of necessary and suffi-
perfectly admirable personal virtues, e.g., conviction, cient conditions exists. In art everything is possible.
sincerity, responsiveness, imagination, communica- In art not everything is possible.
tion of delight, sharing of emotion, curiosity, open- Only someone with the combined skills and knowl-
mindedness, love of experiment, and more? And who, edge of a "star" in the history, criticism, and philoso-
really, can comfortably dismiss his generous liberal phy of art would attempt to make and reconcile the
pluralism, especially when you contemplate the al- above set of assertions. But Arthur C. Danto is such a
most invariably nastier alternatives? Dogmatic pushi- star, and in this volume of essays he tells a story that
ness just wrecks invention. Accept, as he invites, that makes all of them, singly and together, plausible.
"all times and places, past and present, are ideologi- Along the way he provides insight into the work of
cally heterogeneous" (p. 131), and, blessedly, one artists as diverse as Rembrandt van Rijn and Robert
may be spared the sheer craziness of educated adults Ryman.
savagely sniping at each other about-of all things- Most of the book is devoted to explaining how it is
how to play a piece of old music! The job of players, possible both for art to have ended and not ended, and
Taruskin reminds us, is not to play it the way it really what the consequences are for an artworld (ours) in
was. "Their job is to discover, if they are lucky, how which this is the case. The consistency of the appar-
we really like it" (p. 148). To what a pretty pass we ently contradictory statements 1) art has ended, and
must have come that not only does this need publish- 2) there is still a lot of art being made or done, relies,
ing, but that it is said in a climate of controversy. as one might expect, on a kind of trick. When Danto
I enjoyed these pieces. I enjoyed their passion, their discusses the "end of art," what he really discusses is
lightness, their humor, their conviction, and-as they the end of art history of a certain kind. Art, under-
grew on me-their author. There are some issues to stood in a particular way, he argues-using a phrase
which I take exception, but these papers were never of Hegel's-has fallen outside "the pale of history."
meant as solemn, cautious contributions to aesthetics. Hans Belting, Danto explains, has discussed art be-
They are diatribes, and nicely done for their purpose. fore the pale of history-art, that is, that falls outside
One small bit of advice: For maximum reading plea- the extension of the concept that developed in the
sure, skip the lengthy preamble, "Last Thoughts West around 1400 A.D. This was art made and done

This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Tue, 01 Nov 2016 00:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like