You are on page 1of 7

Linos G.

BENAKIS

UDC 1/14:17
Linos G. BENAKIS

ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS IN BYZANTIUM*

Abstract

This paper argues that research in the primary sources must precede the investigation of Byzan-
tine philosophy. Two points are to be considered, on the one hand, the gathering of texts, and, on
the other hand, the study of texts in relation to their sources. Thus the external evidence as well as
the internal evidence of texts should be examined. In this double regard, the manuscripts containing
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics are considered. Their authors are Michael of Ephesos, Eustratios of
Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos, John Italos,
Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon.

Keywords: Byzantine philosophy, Aristotle’s Byzantine Commentators, Michael of Ephesos,


Eustratios of Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos,
John Italos, Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon.

This paper is primarily technical in nature. b. The study of texts in relation to their
It will argue that when one begins to examine a sources. Namely, the identification of
less investigated area of the field of Byzantine sources – distinguishing between instan-
Philosophy, research in the primary sources ces of mere borrowing and instances of a
must still precede every interpretative act and more critical incorporation of such sour-
critical approach. Here, research in the primary ces into Byzantine texts – the identifica-
sources means: tion of original elements, of direct or in-
a. The gathering of texts. This is not always direct influences, of tendencies in the use
an easy task, although the publication in of source materials, etc. Here, the ever-
recent decades of new critical editions of expanding secondary bibliography needs
texts by Byzantine philosophers has made to be consulted with caution, since some
it more feasible (Benakis, 1991). Older studies contain errors of interpretation
editions of Byzantine philosophers, some which may be more or less obvious.2
of which have been reprinted, also remain
the treatise On Virtue can be found.
useful, some unexpectedly so.1 2
There is, for example, the case of the article by
⃰ In a short form published as Benakis, 2009 and Giocarinis, 1964, where Eustratios seems to be
Benakis, 2013. a defender of the Platonic theory of ideas,
1
One such is the collection of texts by Nikeph- when in fact the opposite is true, as is evident
oros Blemmydes edited by Dorotheos Voulis- from the texts cited. It is also inexcusable for
mas and published in Leipzig in 1784, where A. Lloyd to speak of nominalism in Eustratios
67

67 WISDOM 2(9), 2017


Linos G. BENAKIS

This paper will, therefore, necessarily Of even greater importance is an exa-


consider both the external evidence and, as far mination of the ‘internal’ elements that consti-
as possible, the internal evidence regarding tute this interest, so that one might then under-
our texts. While its nature and methods remain stand the relation between our Byzantine au-
to be justified, this paper will have served its thors and the political thinking of the state phi-
purpose and satisfied its writer’s aims if it losophers of antiquity. The same point can ap-
stimulates an interest among new scholars in ply to the Ethics, where the identification of
conducting research and writing about this elements of Aristotle’s ‘moral’ teaching in the
highly productive area of Greek philosophy, works of Byzantine philosophers might be con-
one that has been somewhat neglected. I am sidered in relation to the presence of moral
certain that they will find such research richly problems and issues within both academic
rewarding, whether they engage in ‘technical’ teaching and within a Byzantine Lebensphilo-
research work or a more broadly conceived sophie that was firmly embedded in Christian
examination of the most significant problems dogma.
of Byzantine philosophy. There are numerous Byzantine commen-
As a starting point, one ‘external’ fact of taries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.
particular importance to our topic is the large Among the earliest of these was that of Mi-
number of manuscripts containing the Nicoma- chael of Ephesus (eleventh-twelfth century),
chean Ethics which have been preserved from who can be found in the circle of philosophers
the Byzantine period. There are approximately associated with Anna Komnene and who wrote
120 manuscripts, to which one might add 45 commentaries on book V and on books IX and
manuscripts of the Major Ethics and 25 of the X of the Nicomachean Ethics.4 A first edition
Eudemian Ethics. In order to put these numbers (by contemporary criteria) of these commen-
into perspective I cite the corresponding num- taries appeared in Venice in 1541.5 We must
bers of manuscripts of other key works by Aris- not overlook the fact that Michael of Ephesus
totle. There are 160 manuscripts of the Catego- was an experienced commentator, with exten-
ries from the Byzantine period, 140 of the De
Politics in 1821 as the first volume of the col-
interpretatione, 120 for the Prior Analytics, 120
lection. This was followed in 1822 by his pub-
for the Physics, 60 for the Metaphysics, 60 for
lication of the Nicomachean Ethics. He wrote
the De caelo, and 40 for the Poetics. I have dis- the following in his prologue, claiming that
cussed the Politics elsewhere (Benakis, 1982b). Ethics is a part of Politics: “both are one and
It is, therefore, essential to consider these num- the same science, of which Ethics can be con-
bers when considering the knowledge and inter- sidered the theoretical part, and Politics the
est of the Byzantines in the moral- political ide- practical.”
4
as of Aristotle.3 Michael Ephesius, in: Commentaria in
Aristotelem Graeca (=CAG) Vols. XX and
in the article cited in note 10, when he himself XXII, 3.
5
concludes that Eustratios’ method may be de- Aristotelis Stagiritae Moralia Nichomachia
fined as a form of conceptualism! cum Eustratii, Aspasii, Michaelis Ephesii
3
See the testimony of Adamantius Korais, who, nonullorum aliorurn Graecorum explana-
in his Hellenic Library published Aristotle’s tionibus, ed. B. B. Felicianus, Venetiis 1541.
68

WISDOM 2(9), 2017 68


Aristotelian Ethics in Byzantium

sive commentaries on Aristotle’s work: inclu- Eustratios’ Aristotelian commentaries were


ding books V–VIII of the Metaphysics, the the most interesting of any of those produced
Parva Naturalia, the Sophistici Elenchi, the De by a Byzantine philosopher, as the subject of
partibus and the De motu animalium, which, his discussion was not limited to the philoso-
fortunately, were included in the publishing pher’s style or definitions, but rather addres-
endeavor of the Prussian Academy.6 The com- sed the philosopher’s views and his teachings.
mentaries by Michael of Ephesus on Physics, Indeed, Eustratios appears to have been a
De caelo and the Rhetoric have not been pre- competent philosopher in the tradition of Mi-
served. For details of his knowledge and treat- chael Psellos and John Italos, whose student
ment of the Politics see my article mentioned he was. One finds within his work a combina-
above. In addition, the recent secondary litera- tion of Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism.
ture on Michael is reliable. This is evident in his resolution of the problem
In the same period, Eustratios of Nicaea of general concepts (the universalia), in which
(c. 1050 – c. 1120) composed commentaries on resolution Lloyd also finds that Eustratios has
books I and VI of the Nicomachean Ethics.7 resolved the problem of conceptual realism
Eustratios’s commentaries were also included (conceptualism) that can be found in the Al-
in the 1541 Venetian edition. Parts of them exandrian commentators, i.e. those of the
were also, surprisingly, included in E. Par- school of Ammonius and thence of all Byzan-
giter’s 1745 London edition entitled Aristotle tine scholars (see Benakis, 1978-1979).
of Morals to Nichomachus I. For the impor- In his study, Lloyd does not treat Eust-
tance and impact of Eustratios’ commentaries ratios’ work on the Ethics systematically.
on Aristotle’s work in the West one should There is undoubtedly fertile ground for future
consult a significant series of articles by Mer- research here. One strand that remains note-
cken, Sorabji, Lloyd, Trizio, and Benakis (see worthy is Eustratios’ influence on Western
Mercken, 1990b; Sorabji, 1990b; Loyd, 1987; Christian philosophy. Here, it should be noted
Trizio, 2006; Benakis, 1978-1979). According that the first Western commentary on the Ni-
to Sorabji, the esteemed scholar of the whole comachean Ethics, that by Albertus Magnus
tradition of Greek commentaries on Aristotle, (Cologne 1250-1252), appeared approximately
Eustratios of Nicaea introduced Platonic, 130 years later than that by Eustratios. Eustra-
Christian and anti- Arabic elements into his tios was already known in the West by that
texts, whereas Michael of Ephesus can be seen time, first through James of Venice (approx.
to have mainly followed the existing commen- 1130) and primarily through the translation
taries by Alexander of Aphrodisias and the and use of his commentaries, particularly on
Neoplatonic school of Alexandria. Also of Logic, by Robert Grosseteste in England. The
significance for any assessment of Eustratios latter called Eustratios ‘Commentator Graecus’
is the study by Lloyd, which argues that or simply ‘Commentator’ (compared to the
6
plain ‘Philosophus’ reserved for Aristotle). On
Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca (=CAG)
the subject of Eustratios’ influence in the
Vols. II,3; XIV; XXII,1; XXII,2; XIV,3.
7 West, we have the reliable studies by H.P.E
Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca (=CAG)
XX.
Mercken on Robert Grosseteste’s Latin trans-
69

69 WISDOM 2(9), 2017


Linos G. BENAKIS

lations of the Greek commentaries (see Mer- whole of the Nicomachean Ethics.10 This par-
cken, 1973). Mercken is also the author of a aphrase is attributed to Heliodoros of Proussa
paper, “Ethics as a Science in Albert the Great in this Berlin edition. It has also been at-
and Eustratios of Nicaea,” (Merken, 1990a) tributed to Andronikos Kallistos (1400-1486)
where the key issue, as to whether a scientia and to Andronikos Rhodios (!) in a first edi-
moralis rather than a practica moralis was tion that was published in Cambridge in 1679,
possible in the Middle Ages, is examined on and has also been attributed to John Filagrios
the basis of the first Latin commentary on the from Crete (s. Wartelle for cod. Napol. Gr.
Nicomachean Ethics, that of Albertus Magnus. 335). The most likely case is that this para-
Albertus only wrote on books I and VI. It is in phrase was the work of Constantine Paleokap-
these books that Aristotle deals with issues of pas, a 14th century monastic scholar.11 This
method in the Ethics and it is where he dis- work, which was a useful teaching tool for the
cusses the intellectual virtues, of which sci- Byzantines, was widely known.
ence or scientia is one. Eustratios, of course, George Pachymeres’ (1242-1310) para-
had commented on these same books and his phrase of the Nicomachean Ethics was writ-
authority is invoked by Albertus, who refers ten as part of his extensive work, the Philoso-
to him as Commentator Graecus. Clearly, an phia, which sought to provide “commen-
area of enquiry that then arises from this rela- taries” on the whole Aristotelian Corpus in 12
tionship and that deserves greater attention books and 238 chapters. These had only been
would be an investigation of the extent to published in a Latin translation: Venetiis
which Albertus Magnus’s views on the scien- 1545, Lugduni 1547, Parisiis 1547, 1555, and
tific understanding of ethics were influenced Basileae 1560. A first critical edition of book
by the writings of his Byzantine predecessor. ten has now been published within the series
Another Byzantine commentary on the “Corpus Philosophorum Medii Aevi - Com-
Nicomachean Ethics is the “Anonymous” mentaria in Aristotelem Byzantina” of the
commentary on books II to V.8 This text is a Academy of Athens (see Pachymeres, 2002).
compilation of mainly Alexandrian commen- This great Byzantine historian and philoso-
taries made by a Byzantine scholar, probably pher’s method was to select significant pas-
of the thirteenth century. There is a further sages from Aristotle’s work and then to pro-
anonymous Byzantine commentary on book vide them with explanations in simpler, more
VII of the Nicomachean Ethics.9 No reliable comprehensible terms, using language and
research has yet been carried out on either of ideas drawn from the ancient commentators.
these commentaries. Lastly, there is a commentary on the Ni-
There are also a number of paraphrases comachean Ethics that is attributed to the em-
that deserve our attention. In 1889 Heylbut peror John Kantakouzenos, or, under his mo-
published a Late Byzantine paraphrase of the nastic name, Ioasaph (after 1355), which re-
8
mains unpublished. This work, however, is
In Ethica Nicomachea 2-5. CAG XX pp. 122-
10
255. Heliodoros of Proussa, Paraphrasis. CAG
9
In Ethica Nicomachea 8. CAG XX pp. 407- XIX, 2, pp. 1-246.
11
460. This paraphrase is known from Hatch, 1879.
70

WISDOM 2(9), 2017 70


Aristotelian Ethics in Byzantium

identical to the commentary by Pseudo-Olym- also be detected throughout.


piodoros (a paraphrase of the commentary by The philosopher Nikephoros Blemmydes
the Alexandrian Olympiodoros). It is believed of Nicaea (1197-1272) also wrote a “Discourse
that Kantakouzenos had probably commis- on Virtue.”15 This, like his better-known works,
sioned a copy of this text and that this was later Epitome on Logic and Epitome on Physics, fol-
mistakenly attributed to him (see Nicol, 1968). lows closely upon the structure and language
It is not difficult to locate both brief and of Aristotle’s own works and thus cleaves to
lengthy references, explicit or otherwise, to the model provided by the Nicomachean Eth-
Aristotle, the Ethics, or commentators on the ics.
Ethics in other texts by Byzantine philoso- The Miscellanea philosophica et historica
phers. For example, we can readily find refer- by Theodore Metochites (1270-1337) is ac-
ences in the recent editions of Michael Psel- companied by a brief table of the names of an-
los’s writings: in chapter seven of the Philo- cient writers.16 This contains approximately
sophica Minora I and in chapters twelve and forty references to Aristotle, without, however,
thirty-two of the Philosophica Minora II.12 In always referencing the specific work by Aris-
paragraphs 66-81 of Psellos’s De omnifana totle cited in the text. The Nicomachean Eth-
doctrina there are numerous references to book ics, like the Metaphysics, Politics and Rheto-
2 of the Nicomachean Ethics, as well as to the ric, does not appear to have been mentioned by
Pseudo-Aristotelean On Virtue and Vice and Metochites. A fuller investigation of the Mis-
the Ethica Eudemia.13 These instances suggest cellanea and his other writings may show that
that Aspasius’s commentaries on Aristotle’s Metochites did, in fact, know and use these
writings on morality are a common source for works (see Hult, 2002).
Psellos as well as other Byzantines. Lastly, in this purely descriptive overview,
A further example is offered by the chap- I would like to mention the pre-eminently moral
ter “On moral virtue and other matters,” which dissertation by George Gemistos Plethon (1360-
is found in the collection Queries and Solu- 1452), his “On Virtue”. A new critical edition
tions written by the eleventh-century philoso- of this text contains an enlightening introduc-
pher John Italos.14 Here, Italos suggests that tion, from which it is clear that Plethon’s main
the ancient philosophers, primarily Aristotle, sources are Plato, Plutarch, Epictetus, Marcus
have given the most exact definition of what Aurelius, and the pseudo-Aristotelian On Virtue
might be termed ethical virtue. Italos includes and Vice.17 Plethon’s method itself shows the
seven passages from books I, II, V and VI of
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics in his chapter. 15
Νικηφόρου μοναστοῦ καὶ πρεσβυτέρου τοῦ
The presence of Aspasius’s commentary can Βλεμμύδου Ἐπιτομὴ Λογικῆς [Nikêphorou mo-
nastou kai presbyterou tou Blemmydou Epi-
12
Philosophica minora I 22-28 and Philosophica tomê Logikês, in Greek] (editio Lipsiae: 1784).
16
minora II 23-39, 109-111. See my critical re- Miscellanea, ed. Th. Kessling, Lipsiae, 1821,
view for these two valuable volumes from the 838.
17
Teubneriana: Benakis, 1995. Traite des vertus. Editio princeps by Br. Tam-
13
Omnifaria doctrina 43-49, chapters 66-81. brun-Krasker, Athens (Philosophi Byzantini 3)
14
Questiones quodlibetales 87-95, chapter 63. 1987.
71

71 WISDOM 2(9), 2017


Linos G. BENAKIS

influence of Aristotle, and the Mystran philoso- 248-249.


pher’s knowledge of the Aristotelian corpus is Benakis, L. G. (1982b). Was Aristotle's Politi-
in any case well-known from his entire body of cal Philosophy Ignored in Byzanti-
work (for Nicomachean Ethics, see, for exam- um? Proceedings of the 1st Panhel-
ple, De differentiis, V,1-2 and elsewhere.) Here, lenic Philosophy Conference: Philos-
however, we can draw a significant distinction: ophy and Politics (pp. 230-236). Ath-
while in Aristotle moral philosophy is “phe- ens: Kardamitsa.
nomenological”, and for that reason largely de- Benakis, L. G. (1991). Bibliographie Interna-
scriptive, morality in Plethon is the object of tionale sur la philosophie byzantine
science in the strict meaning of the term, and 1949-1990 Association Internationale
thus is wholly based on the first principles of des Études Byzantines. Comité Hel-
Metaphysics. Therefore, Plethon’s method can lénique des Études Byzantines. Bibli-
be seen to be Platonic, for it is to a great extent ographié byzantine publiée à
analytical. But in the case of the last great Byz- l’occasion du XVIIIe congre interna-
antine philosopher, too, research will need to tional d’études byzantines (pp. 319-
address other important aspects of his moral 384). Moscow.
teachings, such as his basic belief in the dual Benakis, L. G. (1995). Book review: Michael
nature of man, in absolute providence, and in Psellos, Philosophica Minora, Vol. I,
the moral-political character of free will, and J. M. Duffy (Ed.), Vol. II, D. J.
other such areas.18 O’Meara (Ed.). Hellenica 45, 191-
199.
REFERENCES Benakis, L. G. (2009). Aristotelian Ethics in
Byzantium. Medieval Greek Commen-
Barber, Ch., & Jenkins D. (Eds.) (2009). Me- taries on the Nicomachean Ethics Ch.
dieval Greek Commentaries on the Barber & D. Jenkins (eds.), 63-69,
Nicomachean Ethics. Leiden – Bos- 210-221.
ton: Brill. Benakis, L. G. (2013). Byzantine Philosophy,
Benakis, L. G. (1978-1979). To problêma tôn B. Athens: Parousia.
genikôn ennoiôn kai ho ennoiologikos Browning, R. (1963). The Patriarchal School at
realismos tôn Byzantinôn (The Prob- Constantinople in the Twelfth Centu-
lem of General Science and the Real- ry, Byzantion 32 (1962), 167-201 &
istic Realism of the Byzantines, in 33 (1963), 11-40.
Greek). Philosophy, 8/9, 311-340. Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca (CAG)
Benakis, L. G. (1982a). The Problem of General (1882-1904). Edita consilii et auctori-
Concepts in Neoplatonism and Byzan- tate academiae litterarum Regiae Bo-
tine Thought. (D. J. O’Meara, Ed.) russiacae. Vols. 1-23. Berlin: Georg
Neoplatonism and Christian Thought, Reimer Verlag.
Gémiste-Pléthon, G. (1987). De Traités de ver-
18 tus (Br. Tambrun-Krasker, Ed.) Philo-
This article is published with the editorial
elaboration of Georgia Apostolopoulou.
sophi Byzantini 3. Athens-Leiden:
72

WISDOM 2(9), 2017 72


Aristotelian Ethics in Byzantium

Academy of Athens. Merken, H. P. F. (1990a). Ethics as a Science


Giokarinis, K. (1964). Eustratius of Nicaea’s in Albert the Great’s First Commen-
Defense of the Doctrine of the Ideas. tary on the Nicomachean Ethics.
Franciscan Studies 24, 159–204. Proceedings of the Eighth Interna-
Hatch, W. M. (1879). The Moral Philosophy of tional Congress of Medieval Philos-
Aristotle. London: John Murray. ophy (S.I.E.P.M.). III, 251-260. Hel-
Hult, K. (2002). Theodor Metochites, On An- sinki: Yliopistopaino.
cient Authors and Philosophy. (K. Nicol, D. M. (1968). A Paraphrase on the Ni-
Hult, Ed.). Goteborg: Acta Universi- comachean Ethics Attributed to the
tatis Gothoburgensis. Emperor John VI Cantacuzene. Byz-
Lloyd, A. C. (1987). The Aristotelianism of antinoslavica 29, 1–16.
Eustratius of Nicaea. In J. Wiesner Pachymeres, G. (2002). Philosophia. Buch 10.
(Ed.) Aristoteles: Werk und Wirkung, Kommentar zur Metaphysik des Aris-
II, (pp. 341-351). Berlin, New York: toteles. In E. Pappa (Ed.): Commen-
De Gruyter. taria in Aristotelem Byzantina 2. Ath-
Mercken, H. P. F. (1973). The Greek Com- ens: Academy of Athens.
mentaries on the “Nicomachean Eth- Sorabji, R. (1990b). The ancient commentators
ics” of Aristotle in the Latin Transla- on Aristotle. In R. Sorabji (Ed.) Aris-
tion of Robert Grosseteste, Bishop of totle Transformed (pp. 1-30).
Lincoln (†1253), vol. 1: books I–IV Sorabji, R. (Ed.) (1990a). Aristotle transfor-
(= Corpus Latinum Commentariorum med. The Ancient Commentators and
in Aristotelem Graecorum VI/1). their Influence. London: Duckworth.
Critical edition with an introductory Trizio, M. (2006). Eustratius of Nicaea an Ab-
study by H. P. F. Mercken. Leiden: solute and Conditional Necessity. A
Brill. Survey of the Commentary on Book
Mercken, H. P. F. (1990b). The Greek Com- VI of the Nicomachean Ethics. Archiv
mentators on Aristotle’s Ethics. In R. für mittelalterliche Philosophie und
Sorabji (Ed.) Aristotle Transformed Kultur 12, 35-63.
(pp. 429-436). London.

73

73 WISDOM 2(9), 2017

You might also like