You are on page 1of 241

Mathematics, Poetry

and Beauty
This page intentionally left blank
Mathematics, Poetry
and Beauty

Ron Aharoni
Technion, Haifa, Israel

World Scientific
NEW JERSEY • LONDON • SINGAPORE • BEIJING • SHANGHAI • HONG KONG • TA I P E I • CHENNAI
Published by
World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd.
5 Toh Tuck Link, Singapore 596224
USA office: 27 Warren Street, Suite 401-402, Hackensack, NJ 07601
UK office: 57 Shelton Street, Covent Garden, London WC2H 9HE

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


Aharoni, Ron.
[Matematikah, shirah ve-yofi. English]
Mathematics, poetry, and beauty / Ron Aharoni, Technion, Israel Institute of Technology, Israel.
pages cm
ISBN 978-9814602938 (hardcover : alk. paper) -- ISBN 978-9814602945 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. Mathematical recreations. 2. Mathematics--Study and teaching. 3. Poetry in mathematics education.
I. Title.
QA95.A27413 2014
510--dc23
2014026663

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data


A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Hebrew edition: Matematika, shira veyofi (Hakibbutz Hameuchad Publishing, Tel Aviv, 2008)

Translators for the English edition: Merav Aharoni and Edward Levin

Copyright © 2015 by World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd.


All rights reserved. This book, or parts thereof, may not be reproduced in any form or by any means, electronic or
mechanical, including photocopying, recording or any information storage and retrieval system now known or to
be invented, without written permission from the publisher.

For photocopying of material in this volume, please pay a copying fee through the Copyright Clearance Center,
Inc., 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. In this case permission to photocopy is not required from
the publisher.

Typeset by Stallion Press


Email: enquiries@stallionpress.com

Printed in Singapore
Contents

Introduction: Magic 1

Mathematics and Poetry 3

Displacement 7

Part I: Order 13

The Curious Case of the Ants on the Pole 15

Hidden Order 19

To Discover or to Invent 25

Order and Beauty 29

Mathematical Harmonies 31

Why 2 is Not a Rational Number 39

The Real Numbers 41

The Miracle of Order 45

Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs 51

Independent Events 61

v
vi Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Part II: How Mathematicians and Poets Think 65

Poetic Image, Mathematical Image 67

The Power of the Oblique 77

Compression 85

Mathematical Ping-Pong 89

The Book in Heaven 95

Poetical Ping-Pong 99

Laws of Conservation 103

An Idea from Somewhere Else 111

Three Types of Mathematics 115

Topology 123

Matchmaking 129

Imagination 135

A Magic Number 143

Reality or Imagination 149

Unexpected Combinations 155

What is Mathematics? 159

Deep Tautologies 165

Symmetry 169
Contents vii

Impossibility 179

Infinitely Large 185

Cantor’s Story 189

The Most Beautiful Proof? 199

Paradoxes and Oxymorons 205

Self-Reference and Gödel’s Theorem 211

Halfway to Infinity: Large Numbers 219

Infinitely Small 223

Infinitely Many Numbers Having a Finite Sum 229

Twists 233

Part III: Two Levels of Perception 235

Knowing without Knowing 237

Content and Husk 239

Change 243

Estrangement 247

An Endless Encounter 251

Appendix A: Mathematical Fields 255

Appendix B: Sets of Numbers 257

Appendix C: Poetical Mechanisms Mentioned in the Book 259


Mathematics and Poetry

Poetry is the expression of the imagination. In it


diverse things are brought together in harmony
instead of being separated through analysis.

Percy Bysshe Shelley, English poet, 1792–1822, Defence of Poetry

Mathematics is concerned with understanding


the differences between similar things, and
what is shared by different things.

James Joseph Sylvester, English mathematician, 1814–1897

The moving power of mathematical invention


is not reasoning but imagination.

Augustus de Morgan, English mathematician, 1806–1871


The great German mathematician David Hilbert (1862–1943) noticed that
one of his students had started missing his lectures. When he asked for the
reason, he was told that the student had left mathematics in favor of poetry.
“Ah, yes,” said Hilbert, “I always thought he didn’t have enough imagination
for mathematics.”
Hilbert’s derision of poets should be taken with a grain of salt. After all,
his attitude toward physicists was not much better: he once declared that
“physics is too hard for physicists.” But he was not the only one who com-
pared mathematicians with poets, in favor of the first. Voltaire, for example,
said that “there was more imagination in the head of Archimedes than in
that of Homer.” Even poets agree. The American poet Edna St. Vincent
Millay entitled one of her sonnets “Euclid Alone Has Looked on Beauty
Bare.”

3
4 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

This poses a riddle. How can the austere and abstract world of mathe-
matics resemble art? What does geometry have in common with music, or
arithmetic with poetry? One answer is that both mathematics and poetry
search for hidden patterns.

This poem is a poem on people;


What they think and what they want
And what they think they want.
Besides this, there aren’t many things in the world
That we should care about.

Nathan Zach, “Intro to a Poem,” from Other Poems


A poem tells us what we really want. And what poetry does to human
emotions and cravings, mathematics does to order in the material world. It
tries to find the internal logic of things.
But this cannot be the full answer. Every science, exact or not, looks for
rules underlying external appearances. What is it about mathematics that
makes it more akin to poetry than any other science? There is another, more
prominent common feature that makes us feel that mathematics and poetry
are close: beauty. Nothing is as practical as mathematics. Our everyday life,
which is so dependent on scientific progress, is influenced by mathematics in
very tangible ways. This, however, is not the secret of its attraction, not for
professional mathematicians, and certainly not for amateurs. Most engage
in it for a completely different reason: its aesthetic value.
In this book, I will try to trace those features and mechanisms that are
common to poetry and mathematics, causing them to share the same type of
beauty. For this purpose, I will have to touch upon that most elusive of philo-
sophical questions — what is beauty? The unique perspective of comparing
two fields may offer a clue. The very fact that poetry and mathematics are
so far apart narrows the scope in which the answer should be sought. It is to
be found in the intersection of the two domains, which is much smaller than
each of them viewed separately. The smaller the overlap between the two
fields, the narrower the area for the common denominator to be searched.
As I said, the answer cannot be simple. But there is one word that
captures its essence: magic. The sense of beauty, in both poetry and
Mathematics and Poetry 5

mathematics, is the outcome of a sleight of hand aimed at concealing what


is really happening. Here, for example, is definite magic — one of the poems
entitled “Time and Eternity” by Emily Dickinson:

Adrift! A little boat adrift!


And night is coming down!
Will no one guide a little boat
Unto the nearest town?

So sailors say, on yesterday,


Just as the dusk was brown,
One little boat gave up its strife,
And gurgled down and down.

So angels say, on yesterday,


Just as the dawn was red,
One little boat, o’erspent with gales
Retrimmed its masts — redecked its sails —
And shot — exultant one!

What makes this poem so effective is its sincerity. Through it Dickinson


lays herself bare in a way she wouldn’t even dream of doing in real life.
“Adrift,” “gave up its strife,” “little,” “o’erspent with gales” — all these
describe her life as succinctly as possible, but she probably wouldn’t say
these words aloud even to herself. It is the metaphor that makes it possible
for her to express all these with such courage. The message is conveyed to
the reader only on a subliminal level. The effect is knowing, without really
knowing. The poem is telling us something deep without our being fully
aware of its meaning. A poem is a pickpocket who instead of stealing, puts
something in our pocket without us noticing.
No less powerful is the uncovering of a hidden truth. “Poetry is always
a search for the truth,” were Franz Kafka’s words to which we shall yet
return. The poem tells us that what is on the surface is only one aspect of
reality. The inner forces are of greater importance. Beneath the little boat
overwhelmed by the tempest there is a very brave vessel; and even if it looks
like it is about to sink, it spreads its sails and takes off. Could Dickinson’s
own life be depicted more beautifully than this?
6 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Emily Dickinson (1830–1886).

So, this book is about the magic of poetry and of mathematics, and how
close the two are. It is divided into three parts. Part I is about order. We
shall see in it how both fields uncover deep hidden patterns. In Part II we
shall study common techniques of the two fields. Finally, in Part III I will
try to draw conclusions on the concept of beauty.
But first, I want to give a glimpse of what’s to come. I would like to
describe one sleight of hand.
Displacement

The mechanism I want to discuss is common not only to poetry and to


mathematics. It appears in almost every area of human thought. Its name,
“displacement,” was coined by Sigmund Freud, who discovered it in dreams.
Displacement is the diversion of attention from a central figure to a side
one. The main character of the play is shunted to the murky edges of the
stage, while the spotlights focus on a less important figure. The main idea
is thereby presented incidentally, as if offhandedly. In dreams, so claimed
Freud, the aim is to conceal some forbidden content, letting the message slip
the attention of our inhibitions. This, according to Freud, is the aim of all
dream techniques. In mathematics and in poetry the effect is beauty. It is
a magician’s ruse, telling his audience “Look at what I am doing with my
right hand” while performing the trick with his left.
Here is an example in a poem, “About Myself” by the Israeli poetess
Lea Goldberg. It is an ars poetic poem (“ars” is the Latin word for “art”),
meaning that its topic is the poetry of its author. Goldberg examines the
connection between her poetry and her life, and reaches a painful conclusion:

[. . .]
My images are
Transparent like windows in a church:
Through them
One can see
How the light of the sky shifts
And how my loves
Fall
Like dying birds.

Lea Goldberg, “About Myself,” Lea Goldberg:


Selected Poetry and Drama, trans.
Rachel Tzvia Back

7
8 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The most transparent stratagem of this poem is the metaphor. In fact, it is a


second-order one, a metaphor within a metaphor. The poems are compared to
images, and the images, in turn, are likened to church windows. But the heart
of the poem is in its last three lines, in which the poetess tells with painful sin-
cerity of the fate of her loves. I live in my poems, she divulges, while in reality,
my loves fall dead — a complaint that accompanied Goldberg throughout her
life. Moreover, she hints that the two are connected, that the loves die because
of the poems. Isn’t it that the birds smash against the windows?
Sincerity by itself, however, does not produce beauty, and if the message
were presented directly, the poem would not be as moving. The last lines,
which deliver a blow to the stomach, penetrate our armor mainly because
we are unprepared. And the poem’s way of achieving this is the inciden-
tal, offhanded statement of the message. The birds-loves as if serve only to
exemplify the transparency of the windows. The dead loves are presented as
a mere illustration of something else. This is displacement.
Displacement, like all incidental communication of powerful emotions, has
great force. The reader feels as if he were being brushed by a feather, not
being sure if it touched him or not, which makes him shiver, as every good
poem should do.

Lea Goldberg (1911–1970); Born in Kovno, Lithuania; Immigrated to Israel in 1935.

When a straight line meets a polygon

In mathematics, and in science in general, a change of perspective is often the


key to the solution of a problem. The role of displacement here is different
from that in poetry. It is not meant to disguise the message, but to cast
Displacement 9

things in a new light. However, the sensation of beauty is generated the


same way. In both mathematics and poetry, the secret is that the message
is not completely understood. Things happen too fast. The idea is so new
that at first encounter it is not consciously absorbed.
Here is an example. Look at the hexagon in the picture. It is not convex,
that is, it has cavities. In the illustration, a straight line meets all six sides.

A six-sided polygon (a hexagon), with a straight line that intersects all its sides. Can you
also draw a seven-sided polygon (a heptagon), with a straight line intersecting all its
sides?

When a mathematician asks you to perform a task, chances are that he


is pulling your leg. It is likely that the mission is impossible. If you try (and
I suggest trying to actually feel this hands-on), you will quickly realize that
it cannot be done. Why? One way to see this is by change of perspective.
The question begins with a polygon, and asks you to construct a straight
line that will meet all its sides. Try the opposite: begin with the straight
line, and try to draw the polygon.
Before presenting the solution, let me formulate the principle on which
it is based. It is called the “river crossing principle.” An even number of
crossings of a river brings you back to the original bank, and an odd number
of crossings takes you to the other side.
By this rule I could know, for example, whether I went through the door of
my office an even or odd number of times (my office is located on the sixth floor,
and I can’t enter or leave it through the window). I don’t know what this num-
ber is, but I am certain that it is even: every time that I entered, I also went out
(these lines are being written outside the office). As simple as this principle may
appear, it is at the heart of many profound mathematical theorems.
So, let us draw the straight line, and then try to draw the heptagon. Let
us start at point Q and proceed along the sides of the broken line. How many
times will we cross the straight line on the way? Seven times, of course, since
each of the seven sides crosses the straight line. Since 7 is odd, by the river
crossing rule the heptagon must end on the other side of the straight line, not
10 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

on the side on which it began. That is, it ends on the side opposite Q. But
since the heptagon is closed, it should end at Q. This contradiction means
that the assumption that every side of the heptagon intersects the straight
line is impossible.

After seven crossings, we are on the other side of the river. The polygon is not closed.

How Many Games Are There in a Knockout


Tournament?

A knockout tournament is a competition in which the players are paired off.


Each pair competes and the winner advances to the next round.
Question: How many games will be played in a tournament with
16 players?
In the first round, the 16 players are arranged in 8 pairs, 8 games are
played, and the 8 winning players go on to the next round. These 8 players
are arranged in 4 pairs, and will play 4 games. In the third round, there
will be 2 games, and in the fourth, that will determine the champion, only
1 game. The total number of games is therefore 8 + 4 + 2 + 1 = 15.
The number 16 is a power of 2 — it is 24 , that is, 2× 2× 2× 2. As a result,
in each round all the players can be paired off. But a tournament can also
be held with a number of players that is not a power of 2. In such a case,
in some rounds there will be an odd number of players, and they cannot all
play. When this happens, the players are paired off except for a single player,
and the extra player advances to the next round without playing. How many
games will be held then?
A secret shared between mathematicians and poets is thinking in concrete
examples. Mathematicians also know that the simpler the example is, the
better. There is no such thing as a “too simple example.” The simplest
example here is that of a single player. In this case, the number of games
is 0. In the next simplest example, a competition with 2 players, there is a
single game. When there are 3 players, 2 games are held: a game between a
Displacement 11

pair, followed by game between the winner of the first round and the player
who was waiting on the sidelines. Let us now skip to a tournament with 10
players. The following diagram depicts a possible course of events. In the
first round 5 games were played; in the second, 2; in the third, 1; and in the
fourth, again 1.

Together: 5 + 2 + 1 + 1 = 9. This is not very hard, but in the case of


1000 players, the calculation will be tiring. Is there an easier way? Note that
in all cases we met, the number of games equaled the number of players,
minus 1. Is this coincidental? Almost certainly not. It is probably a rule:
the number of games is smaller by 1 than the number of players.
A good conjecture is essential, but it requires proof. And the proof here
is done by change of perspective. Instead of looking at the winners, look at
the losers. When there are 1000 players, each of the 999 players who did
not win the cup lost exactly once: there was exactly one game in which he
dropped out. Since each game has exactly one loser, for 999 players to lose,
there must be 999 games.
12 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The solution leaves us with a sense of beauty. It was economical — it


saved effort. It was concise, like a good poem. And there was magic. Things
happened fast, too fast for us to fully comprehend at first encounter. Like in
Lea Goldberg’s poem, the message was slipped under our noses, our attention
having been drawn to something else. Judging by the examples so far, a sense
of beauty is born in the unconscious grasp of a notion. We experience beauty
when we receive a strong message, whether emotional or intellectual, while
comprehending it only subliminally.
The Curious Case
of the Ants on the Pole

Only about myself did I know how to speak.


My world is as narrow as that of an ant.

Rachel Bluwstein, Israeli poetess, 1890–1931

There is an unknown number of ants on a one-meter long pole. The ants


move — some to the right, others to the left, but all at the same speed:
exactly one meter a minute. The pole is narrow, about as wide as a single
ant, and when two ants meet they cannot continue. They then behave like
colliding billiard balls, that is, each turns about and continues in the opposite
direction, at the same speed.

When two ants meet (left) they change direction (right).

Every so often, an ant reaches one of the pole ends, and then it falls off
and disappears forever.
Question: In the end, will all the ants fall off the pole? If so, how long will
this take?
At first glance, the answer seems to depend on the initial state, that is,
on the number of ants on the pole and their position. If there are many
ants, it seems that it might take a long time for all of them to fall off.
How can we test this? I have already told you the first secret of thinking
mathematically: studying examples. Mathematical thought is a play between
examples and abstractions. The difference between the two is that strokes in
the direction of the concrete can be done consciously, that is, examples can
be evoked deliberately. For this reason one ought to begin with examples.
An additional reason, of course, is that examples are the raw material of

15
16 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

abstraction. In the case of the ants, the simplest example is that of a single
ant. If the ant is at one end of the pole and goes toward the other end, it
will fall off in one minute. In any other case, it will fall in less than a minute.
But we still have not touched upon the core of the problem: the collisions. So
let us look at two ants, located at the opposite ends of the pole, advancing
toward each other.

After half a minute, they will meet in the middle of the pole, reverse
their directions, and fall off in another half a minute. So, both will fall after
exactly one minute.
The next example is a bit less obvious. Imagine one ant starting at the
right end, the other exactly in the middle, and they are advancing toward
each other.

The ants will meet after a quarter of a minute at a distance of a quarter of


a meter from the right end. They will reverse their directions, and then the
last ant to fall will be the ant on the left, that will fall after three quarters
of a minute. After exactly one minute, both ants will have fallen.
This is starting to look strange. In all three examples, all ants fell off the
pole within one minute. Let us go up one level of complexity higher, and
examine three ants. Consider the case where ant A starts from the left end,
and moves to the right; ant B starts from the middle and moves to the right;
and ant C starts at the right end and moves to the left.

After a quarter of a minute we shall see the following picture:


The Curious Case of the Ants on the Pole 17

After the collision, ants A and B will go towards each other, meet in the
middle after another quarter of a minute, reverse their directions and each
will fall after another half a minute. Ant C will had fallen from the right end
even before that. Again, it will take a total of one minute for all ants to fall.
Now this is really strange. In all our examples, all the ants fell within a
minute. Does this always hold true? The answer is “yes,” and the proof
is easy. That is, if you have the right insight. Strange as it may seem,
this insight does not add information but ignores information: it ignores
the identity of the ants. If we don’t care who the ants are, then what
happens at the moment two ants meet? Actually, nothing. Before their
meeting, one ant goes to the left, and the other to the right; after their
encounter, the exact same thing happens: then too, one ant proceeds to
the left, and the other to the right, at the same speed. But for our pur-
pose, which ant goes to the left and which goes to the right doesn’t
matter.
So in effect, there are no collisions. They were only there to confuse us.
The problem is completely identical to the problem: “ants are proceeding
along a one meter long pole, each at the speed of one meter per minute,
without colliding and without changing direction. How long will it take for
them to fall?” There is no mystery here. All will fall off in one minute
or less.
Mathematicians are a lucky breed. They get paid to play. When we take
into account the billions that are invested in mathematical research and edu-
cation, we would expect them to be busy with applied projects. In reality,
most mathematician allow themselves to indulge in problems like this one.
Why? Because the impractical appearance of this riddle is misleading. In
fact, it is a good example of the discipline’s primary strength: abstraction.
The ants in the problem are mathematical: real ants do not move at a uni-
form speed, and do not obey such simple rules. Mathematics is the study
of systems that follow well defined rules. And the abstraction is even more
evident in the solution, that strips the situation of its details, and exposes
its essence.
Ignoring the irrelevant, as in the ants problem, is a primary characteristic
of mathematical thought. Mathematics takes the abstraction process to its
extreme. It takes a complex looking tree, strips it of its leaves, and reveals
the trunk. Think, for example, of the concept of number. The person who
invented the number “4” understood that, as far as the rules of arithmetic
are concerned, it is immaterial if he had 4 stones or 4 pencils, what color
they are, and how they are arranged. 4 stones and 3 stones are 7 stones,
18 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

just as 4 pencils and 3 pencils are 7 pencils, and hence we can say abstractly
“4 + 3 = 7.” Abstraction is generalization, and generalization saves effort.
The rule we found for stones will be valid for any kind of objects, and at any
point in time. “Mathematics is being lazy,” said the mathematician George
Polya (1887–1985), “it is letting the principles do the work for you.” In
this respect, the ants question is very practical. Directly, it is not useful for
anything, because there are no ants like these in reality, but it educates the
person who solves it to think abstractly.
It may even be the case that problem was invented to model a real-world
phenomenon. Bundles of light waves (“solitons”) behave in collisions just
like the ants in the solution: they pass through one another.
Hidden Order

Nature does nothing in vain, and more is vain, when less will serve;
for Nature is pleased with simplicity.
Isaac Newton

Isaac Newton, English mathematician and physicist (1642–1727). In 1666, his


“miraculous year,” he fled from the plague to the village where he had been born, where
in one summer he developed the theory of gravity, several of the principles of modern
optics, and differential and integral calculus. He spent his later years in disputes over
priorities (especially with the German Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, on the discovery of
differential and integral calculus), in experiments in alchemy, and as master of the
British royal mint.

The power of concepts

A good concept is like a path that suddenly opens before you in a dark
forest. A minute ago the thicket seemed impenetrable; but from the moment

19
20 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the path was revealed, the way stands open. The English mathematician
Andrew Wiles, who solved the famous Fermat’s Conjecture, used another
metaphor. A good concept is like a light switch, that you find as you feel
your way in a dark castle. When you turn on the light, you know what is
in the room you are in. In the next room you will have to look for another
switch.
Here is a classic example, a problem composed in 1946 by Max Black, a
British philosopher and mathematician. Take an 8 × 8 board of 64 squares, and
cut out the lower left-hand corner and the top right-hand corner, like this:

Can all 62 squares be covered by 31 dominoes?

You also have 31 dominoes, each of which can cover two adjacent squares
of the board. All together, they can cover 62 squares, which is the number of
squares on the incised board. Can the board be covered with these dominoes?
You may have guessed the first step: look at small cases, even very small.
The smallest possible example is a 2 × 2 board. After the removal of two
opposing squares, we get:
Hidden Order 21

Of course, this shape cannot be covered with a single domino. Now try
a 4 × 4 board (We are skipping the case of a 3 × 3 board, since it contains
9 squares, and removing 2 leaves 7 squares, which is an odd number. An
odd number of squares cannot be covered without overlapping, since each
domino covers 2 squares). A bit of experimentation will convince you that
this is impossible.
In a 2 × 2 or 4 × 4 board it is easy to check all possibilities. In an 8 × 8
board this would be impractical, there are too many possibilities. We need
an idea. And the concept that hits the mark is coloring the squares black
and white.

Things now fall into place. Each of the 31 dominoes will cover one black
square and one white square. Since the squares we removed from the board
are both white, there are 32 black squares left, and only 30 white squares.
These cannot be covered by 31 dominoes that are supposed to cover 31
squares of each color.
The chessboard coloring revealed a concealed pattern. Emerging by
magic, as if from nowhere, it made things simple and clear.

The chocolate problem

Here is another example for the power of concepts. A chocolate bar mea-
sures 5 squares long and 4 wide. We want to divide the 20 squares among
22 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

20 children, so we must break the bar into its squares. The rule is that at
each step we may take one of the pieces we have at hand, and break it
along a single straight line. What strategy should we follow to apply as few
breakings as possible?
As usual, the first step is to consider simpler examples, which in this case
means having smaller dimensions. For example, a 3× 1 chocolate bar divided
among 3 children. Here we have no choice: 2 breakings are necessary. Let us
move on to a slightly bigger example: a bar of size 3 × 2, to be divided among
6 children. One way would be to first separate the two rows of 3 blocks apiece
by a single breaking. After this, we need another 2 breakings for each of the
2 rows, for a total of 5 breakings.

One lengthwise breaking, and 2 more in each row, for a total of 5 breakings.

Another way would be to separate the bar into 3 columns of 2 blocks


apiece, by 2 breakings. In each of these 3 columns we need an additional 1
breaking, for a total of 2 + 3 breakings. In this way, we need 5 breakings.

Two vertical breakings, and 3 horizontal ones, for a total of 5 breakings.

The different ways lead to the same result: a chocolate bar of n blocks
needs n−1 breakings. Namely, the strategy has no effect on the number
of breakings. We cannot separate the individual blocks with fewer than n − 1
breakings, nor with more than n − 1. Why is this so? Here, again, a correct
concept makes things simple. This is the number of pieces obtained
after each breaking. At the start the number of pieces is 1 — there is a
single bar. Each breaking turns one piece into two, thereby increasing the
number of pieces by 1. At the end of this process, there are n pieces. In order
Hidden Order 23

to go from 1 to n pieces, with each step adding a single piece, we need n − 1


steps.
As usual, once we have found the correct concept, we can generalize. It
transpires that the requirement of breaking along straight lines is irrelevant.
We can break any way we want, as long as each breaking turns a single piece
into two pieces.
To Discover or to Invent

Platonism

Don’t go around saying the world owes you a living; the world
owes you nothing; it was here first.

Mark Twain, American writer and humorist, 1835–1910

A standard physics department has both theoreticians and experimentalists.


Experiments are supposed to be the raw material for theories. In a mathe-
matics department it is rare to find experimentalists (surprisingly enough,
there are exceptions: in a leading Canadian university there was a Laboratory
for Experimental Mathematics for some period of time). Mathematicians
don’t need laboratories. They do their work in an office, on a blackboard or
on paper, and all they need is their minds. In this aspect they are superseded
only by philosophers.

The president of the university visited the mathematics


department.
“You know,” he told his hosts, “of all faculty members, I like math-
ematicians best. All they need is paper, a pen, and a wastebasket.”
Ruminating, he then added, “Philosophers are even better. They
don’t need the wastebasket.”

Scientists study the world. What do mathematicians investigate? Is it


something that exists in the world or the products of their feverish minds?
In short, do mathematicians discover or invent? Does mathematics discover
order that exists in the world or does it create the order? Do mathematicians
construct something new, like a house, or discover something that already
existed, the way Columbus discovered America? Is a concept like “even num-
ber” part of the external world, or is it only in the mind of the thinker?
This is supposed to be the subject of fervent dispute among mathemati-
cians. The approach that says that mathematical objects are as real as chairs
and tables is called “Platonism” (incidentally, the original Platonism is more

25
26 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

extreme. Plato argued that the concept of the table is more real than the
table itself). A bitter row is supposed to exist between Platonists and anti-
Platonists. In practice this is not the case. The twentieth-century American
mathematician Ralph Boas claimed that he had never met a mathematician
who was not a Platonist. Almost all mathematicians believe in the reality
of their objects. Numbers, geometric shapes, functions, evenness of num-
bers — these are all part of the actual world. Mathematics is discovery, not
invention. Mathematics reveals order that is out there in the world. A con-
cept is nothing more than mirror image in our brain of a pattern in reality.
A mathematician is more of a photographer than a sculptor.

The sum of an arithmetic sequence

Here is a discovery of order in the world — one made by a seven-year


old. This is one of the best known stories in the history of mathemat-
ics. Carl Friedrich Gauss (1777–1855) was the greatest mathematician of
the nineteenth century, some say of all times. At the age of three, he cor-
rected a mistake in calculations made by his father, a bricklayer. When he
was seven, the teacher of the class he attended wanted to have an hour’s
rest, so he told his students to calculate the sum of the numbers from 1
to 100. To his surprise, Gauss came to him after a few minutes with the
answer — 5050.
How did little Carl Friedrich do this? By finding order. In the sum
1 + 2 + 3 + · · · + 98 + 99 + 100, he matched 1 with 100, 2 with 99, 3 with 98,
and so on. The sum of each pair is 101. Since there are 50 pairs, the total
sum is 50 times 101, which is 5050.
The number 100 is even, so the terms between 1 and 100 could be matched
in pairs. How can we sum up the number between, say 1 and 1001? One trick
is adding 0 at the beginning. This, of course, doesn’t change the sum, and
now the number are paired off: 0 with 1001, 1 with 1000, and so on. After the
addition of 0 there are 501 pairs, each summing up to 1001, so the total sum
is 501 × 1001 = 501,501. Another way, perhaps the most direct, is this: the
average size of a number in the sequence 1,2, . . . ,1001 is the middle between
the first element and the last, namely between 1 and 1001, which is 501. The
sum of 1001 numbers is 1001 times their average, again 501 × 1001.
Was this Gauss’s invention, or discovery? Obviously, discovery. And in
fact he was not the first. This was discovered before him, and re-discovered
after him. Mathematical ideas are there to be discovered. If one mathe-
matician misses the idea, another will find it. That is why, in my opinion,
To Discover or to Invent 27

the tragically early (age 31) death of Franz Schubert was a greater loss to
humanity than the even earlier age death of Evariste Galois, the French
mathematical genius, at around the same time — early 19th century. The
discoveries that would have been made by Galois, had he lived to an old
age, have long since been made, while with the death of Schubert we lost
unimaginable treasures of beauty.

Carl Friedrich Gauss (Germany, 1777–1855), the greatest mathematician of the 19th
century. He contributed to the theory of complex numbers, number theory and modern
algebra. Together with the physicist Wilhelm Eduard Weber he built the first telegraph.
He spent his later years in seclusion in the observatory in Gottingen, and published very
little. The biographer Eric Bell estimated that if all of his discoveries had been published
in his lifetime, mathematics would have progressed by fifty years.

Is poetry invented or discovered?

And what about poetry? Is it in the world, or in the poet’s mind? We


would think that the answer is clear: obviously, poetry is invented. But
listen to what a mathematician (and a poet) has to say about this. Sofia
Kovalevskaya (1850–1891) was the favorite student of Karl Weierstrass, one
of the important mathematicians of the late nineteenth century. In one of
her letters she related to Weierstrass’s statement that a true mathematician
must be something of a poet:

In order to understand this, one must renounce the ancient prej-


udice that a poet must invent something that does not exist, that
28 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

imagination and invention are identical [ . . . ] The poet must see


what others do not see, must look deeper than others look.

Her words strike true. As we already mentioned, poets, like mathemati-


cians, are hunters of hidden patterns. An on-target metaphor reveals a simi-
larity that is out there. The target had existed before. When the poet Yehuda
Amichai writes,

Careful angels threaded fate within fate,


Their hands shook not, nothing dropped or fell.

Yehuda Amichai, “Twenty New Rubaiyat,” Poems


He expresses an existing truth: our fate is no more in our hands than the
thread is master of its fate; there are forces that direct it, as the seamstress
directs the thread. This is beautiful not because it is an invention but, mainly,
because it is true. As Franz Kafka claimed, poetry is always a search for the
truth.
Order and Beauty

Saving energy

When everything falls into its proper place, we say “Everything worked out
beautifully.” Why? Recognizing order is useful. It saves effort in coping with
the world. But why should it cause aesthetic pleasure?
To answer this, we must first realize that it is not mere order. Order
by itself is not necessarily beautiful. Nothing is more orderly than a blank
sheet of paper, and no combination of sounds is more orderly than absolute
silence. Nonetheless, a blank sheet of paper is not a work of art, and silence
does not possess the beauty of a Mozart symphony. A monotone series of
beats is orderly and predictable, but it does not constitute music. In order
to create a sensation of beauty, we need something beyond order.
The secret lies in a concept proposed in the second half of the 19th cen-
tury: saving mental energy. The industrial revolution in England led to the
idea that machines can replace not only muscle work, but also mental. This
led to the invention of the first computer, by Charles Babbage, and also
to a mechanical perception of the human mind. One proponent of this was
Herbert Spencer, who claimed that the mind, like other systems in the world,
seeks a state of minimal energy. Young Freud adopted this approach whole-
heartedly, and in the 1890s, when he was still taking first tentative steps
in psychoanalysis, he wrote a draft of a thick book entitled Physiology for
Psychologists, in which he tried to explain mental phenomena in terms bor-
rowed from the physical world of his time. Freud championed the Spencerian
idea that the psyche tries to reduce effort as much as possible, that is, to
save energy.
Like many before and after him, Freud quickly learned that psychological
terms that are effective as metaphors soon become useless when used con-
cretely. The concept of “saving energy” is too general to predict the behav-
ior of human beings. As a result, Physiology for Psychologists was shelved
around the year 1895, but echoes of it would reverberate throughout Freud’s
writings. The idea of saving energy was expressed most clearly in a book he

29
30 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

wrote in 1905 on humor, Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious. The
book’s thesis was that the pleasure we derive from a joke results from sav-
ing the energy of repression. The joke enables us to enjoy forbidden things
without having to repress them. Consequently, energy that was prepared to
repress the forbidden idea is unnecessary, and is transformed into pleasure.
Not much revelation came out of this book, as far as humor is concerned.
Freud himself was not happy with it, referring to it in later years as a needless
deviation from his main course. But the idea of saving energy caught on,
especially with respect to art. The idea is that a work of art disguises itself
as chaotic, demanding preparation of energy to tackle it, and then hidden
order is revealed, which means that the energy prepared can be saved. And
saved energy entails pleasure. Just like when we discover that we won a
battle we feel pleasure, because we no longer need the energy we prepared
for the struggle. The sensation of beauty, by this approach, arises when order
is suddenly revealed in disorder.
Music is one area in which this explanation works beautifully. In order
for music to be enjoyable, it has to be complex. It must seem to be disor-
ganized noise, and then to be realized as ordered. We constantly attempt
to decipher the stimuli that arrive from the outside world, and so we pre-
pare energy to organize noise. If we then discover order in the noise, this
energy is saved. Links between the sounds are revealed, which enable us
to predict what is coming. This happens in two dimensions: rhythm and
harmony. Rhythm is the organization in time, and harmony the connection
between the frequencies of the notes. In the next chapter, I will explain a bit
about both.
If the music is complex enough, these links are not straightforward, and
cannot be perceived consciously. This means that on the conscious level
we do not fully understand the order in the musical work. There is a gap
between the perceived lack of order and the hidden order that is uncon-
sciously revealed. And this gap, between what we consciously observe and
the unconscious perception, is the source of beauty.
Mathematical Harmonies

Rhythm and prediction

The pleasure we obtain from music comes


from counting, but counting unconsciously.
Music is nothing but unconscious arithmetic.
Gottfried Wilhelm Von Leibniz, German mathematician
and philosopher, 1646–1716
Like all animals, humans are future-oriented. They look where they are going
to be in a moment, not where they were. Even a historian, when he prepares
an omelet, is more interested in where the egg will be in a moment than in
where it was. There’s a simple reason for this: this is how living creatures
were formed by evolution. Evolution selected those life forms that are best
at leaving descendants after them.
Understanding the order in the world means being able to mould your
future surroundings to your advantage. This is why we derive pleasure from
musical rhythm. An expected rhythm saves the investment of energy in the
deciphering of the order hidden in the sounds. But it must not be too pre-
dictable, because in order to save energy, energy must first be rallied. If the
rhythm is sufficiently complex, and we are incapable of consciously decipher-
ing it, we prepare energy in order to guess the next note. When the order is
revealed, this energy is no longer necessary — we know what to expect. The
saved energy then turns into pleasure.

Pythagoras

And what about the second element of music, harmony? This is more of a
puzzle. We all know that some combinations of notes are pleasing to the
ear, while others are less so. For example, a C note sounds well with the
C one octave higher. Actually, when hearing them together we can hardly
distinguish between them. The C-G and C-E combinations, as well, sound

31
32 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

well together. The notes C, E, G are the basic chords of the C major scale,
the scale whose notes are played on the white piano keys. A composition
in C major frequently begins with the notes C, E, G in some order, strays
and wanders about, before finally returning to them. Music is built on the
tension between the digressions and the original harmony.
But why is one combination of notes pleasing, while another grates on
our ears? Surprisingly enough, the answer to this question is mathematical,
and it was discovered by one of the most fascinating figures in the history
of mathematics, Pythagoras. He was the founder and leader of a most rare
entity: a mathematical cult. The cult numbered about 600 men and women,
who lived in the Greek colony of Crotona in the south of the Apennine
peninsula, in the “heel” of the Italian boot. They donated all their posses-
sions to the community, and swore to keep their discoveries secret. Legend
has it that, one day Pythagoras was passing by a blacksmith’s workshop, and
realized that when the blacksmith struck rods with a simple ratio between
their lengths — for example, one was twice as long as the other or one
and a half times as long, the combination of the two sounds was pleasing
to the ear.
In modern terminology, two sounds sound well together if the ratio
between their frequencies is simple, that is, it is expressed by small num-
bers (for example 3:2 is simpler than 11:5). The frequency of a sound is the
number of times per second the air vibrates when the sound is produced,
or in more precise language: the number of peaks per second of the sound
waves. If the note is produced by a string, this is the number of vibrations per
second of the string. A difference of a single octave between notes (like that
between a C and the C above) means a ratio of 2 between their frequencies:
the frequency of a high C is twice that of the C below. The frequency of
the note G, the fifth in the octave (when beginning with C) is 3/2 times
that of the low C of that octave. In other words, for every 2 vibrations of
the C, there are 3 vibrations of the G. The ratio between the frequencies
of E and C is 5:4, again quite simple. This is why C, E, and G sound well
together.

Helmholtz

Why do simple ratios between frequencies cause pleasure? Pythagoras dis-


covered the phenomenon, but was unable to explain it. Another 2,400 years
Mathematical Harmonies 33

would have to pass before this question could be answered. The enigma was
solved by the German Hermann von Helmholtz (1821–1894), a true Renais-
sance man: a mathematician, physicist and physiologist, who also studied
aesthetics. His explanation was based on the phenomenon of “overtones.”
When a chord vibrates at a certain frequency, it also vibrates, at the same
time, at frequencies 2, 3, 4,. . . times higher. The overtones are weaker the
further they are from the original tone, namely the higher the ratio is to the
original frequency, but they are audible. In other words, when the note C is
played, most times we will also hear the C of an octave higher, with a fre-
quency exactly double, and also the G in the higher octave, whose frequency
is three times that of the original C. Simple ratio between two frequencies
means that they share overtones. For example: the C and the G in the same
34 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

octave share the G of one octave higher. Hearing these notes together, we
reveal hidden order. The notes are different, but, unconsciously we find a
factor common to both. Instead of chaos, order emerges.
Does this explain in full the pleasure people derive from music? Of course
not. It does not explain how come music can be so moving. It does not touch
upon the emotions aroused by music. It only relates to a pleasure that can
be classified as intellectual. But it is a good first start.

Mystical numbers

All this was beyond the knowledge of the ancient Greeks, who knew nothing
of frequencies. When people don’t know, they fantasize. In order to explain
harmony, Pythagoras and his school invented fanciful theories of the magical
powers of numbers and the ratios between them. “All is number” was their
strange slogan. That is, the world is ruled by simple numerical ratios. The
Pythagoreans believed that every important natural phenomenon has to
obey numerical laws. They maintained that there are simple ratios between
the diameters of the planetary orbits, and that the planets consequently
emanate “celestial music.” And they went far beyond that. They claimed
that every size in the world that is of any significance can be expressed as a
ratio between whole numbers.
A number that is the quotient of two whole numbers is called a “rational
number” (from the word “ratio”). Every whole number is rational: 4, for
example, is rational because it is the ratio between itself and 1, that is,
4:1 = 4. Every fraction with a whole-number numerator and denominator is
rational, because the fraction bar is actually a division sign: 17/3 is the ratio
between 17 and 3. So, the Pythagoreans believed that important quantities
in nature are rational.

Sobering up

The intellectual achievements of the ancient Greeks were nothing short of


miraculous. A very small people, numbering no more than a few hundred
thousand, developed conceptual systems whose fruits we continue to enjoy to
the present. They were motivated by their infinite respect for abstract ideas.
For the Greeks, abstractions held magical power, and were more important
than the real world. The Greeks were the first to study abstract concepts
for their own sake, without regard for applications. The Egyptians and the
Mathematical Harmonies 35

Babylonians studied numbers before, but they did so for practical ends. The
Greeks were the first to see numbers as a world worthy to be explored for
its beauty and inner harmony.
But even within the Greeks’ achievements, geometry enjoys a special
pride of place. It was in this field that the Greeks developed the concepts
of “axiom” and “proof,” and it was here that they reached the highest level
of abstraction. Pythagoras was one of the founders of Greek geometry. The
theorem that, to this day, is regarded (and rightly so) as the most important
and useful geometric theorem, is named after him, though in fact he was
not its discoverer. The theorem states that the sum of the areas of the
two squares based on the legs of a right triangle equals the area of the
square based on the hypotenuse. This is important because it enables us
to calculate distances. Given the lengths of the legs of a right triangle, we
can calculate the length of the hypotenuse. This means that knowing how to
calculate east-west and north-south distances, you can calculate the distance
between any two points.

The Pythagorean theorem: the sum of the areas of the two squares on the legs of a right
triangle equals the area of the square on the hypotenuse.

An interesting special case of this theorem is that in which the legs of a


right triangle are of the same length. Look at a square whose side is 1 unit
long. The diagonal of the square is the hypotenuse of a right triangle, with
equal legs, each 1 unit long.
According to the Pythagorean theorem, the diagonal, squared, is equal √
to 12 + 12 = 2. Therefore, the length of the diagonal, not squared, is 2.
There is a simple and especially beautiful proof for this individual case of
the theorem, that appears in a somewhat surprising place: one of Plato’s
36 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

According to the Pythagorean theorem, the √


length of the diagonal of a square 1 unit long
is 2.

dialogues (in which, as in all of Plato’s dialogues, the hero is Socrates),


entitled Menon. Look at the next drawing:

The area of the square based on the diagonal (with vertical lines) is twice the area of the
small square (with horizontal lines), because it contains 4 triangles, while the small

square contains only 2 triangles. The side of the larger square is therefore 2 the length
of the side of the small square.

Let’s assume that the length of the side of the small square (with
horizontal lines) is 1. The area of this square is therefore 1 × 1, that is, 1.
The large square, that is on a diagonal (and marked with vertical lines), is
composed of 4 triangles while the small square contains only 2 (all of the
triangles are congruent, that is, they are capable of perfectly fitting one over
the other). Therefore, the area of the large square is twice that of the small
square, which means that it is 2. The length of any square’s side√is the square
root of its area, and so the length of the large square’s side is 2. But look:
the side of the large
√ square is the diagonal of the small square! Therefore,
this diagonal is 2 long.
Geometry had a special place in the minds and hearts of the
Pythagoreans, and for them the diagonal of a square was an everyday object.
Therefore, they believed that the length of this diagonal should be rational.
For many years they tried to find what ratio it is. It is close to 75 , but it is not
quite that, because the square of 75 is 49
50 , which is almost 2, but not quite.
Mathematical Harmonies 37


Eventually they had to realize the bitter truth: that 2 is not rational. This
was such a severe blow that they vowed to keep it a secret. Due to the sect’s
secretiveness, not much is known about it for certain and the continuation
of the story might very well be spurious. But legend has it that Hippasus,
a sect member who revealed the secret to the world, was put to death for
doing so. This is almost certainly apocryphal. Hippassus drowned, and his
death might very well have been an accident. But the sect accredited it to
punishment by the gods.

Why 2 is Not a Rational Number

√ m
Actually, why isn’t 2 a rational number? Why can’t it be expressed
√ as n for
m
some whole numbers m and n? To see this, assume that n = 2. We shall
show that this assumption leads to a contradiction. First, we can assume
that mn is a reduced fraction, namely the numerator and the denominator
are not divisible by the same number, greater than 1. If not, we√just reduce
it, namely√divide by the common divisor. By the definition of 2, the fact
2
that mn = 2 means that m 2
n2 = 2. If we multiply both sides by n , we get:

(∗ ) 2n2 = m2
Now, we will divide our discussion into two cases: in one case, m is an
odd number, and in the other case, it is even. Each of these two cases will
lead to the desired contradiction. If m is an odd number, the right side of (∗ )
is the square of an odd number, so it is an odd number (the product of two
odd numbers is odd), while the left side is a multiple of 2, and is therefore
an even number. Since an odd number cannot be equal to an even √ one, the
right side cannot be equal to the left. (As an example of this case, if 2 = 75 ,
then 2 = 752 , meaning that 2 × 52 = 72 . Then the left side, 50, is even, while
2

the right side, 49, is odd.)


Assume next that m is even. Since, by assumption, m n is reduced, n must be
odd (if it were even, then the entire fraction could be reduced by 2). Since an
odd number squared is odd, on the left side of (∗ ) there is the product obtained
by multiplying 2 by an odd number. Such a product cannot be divisible by 4.
But on the right side we have an even number squared, which is divisible by 4.
So, the two sides must be different,
√ again a contradiction to the equality sign.
√ How do we then express 2? One way is√as an infinite decimal fraction:
2 = 1.4142135623 . . ., which means that 2 can be approximated by the
rational numbers 1, 1.4,√ 1.41, 1.414, and so on. Note that 1.4 = 75 and
1.4285714285 . . . = 107 . 2 is almost exactly in the middle between them! √
Almost, but of course not exactly: the middle is a rational number, and 2
is not rational.

39
The Real Numbers

It may take a long time to realize the full importance of a discovery. With
hindsight, the discovery of the existence√ of irrational numbers was a turning
point in the history of mathematics. If 2 is not the quotient of two integers,
then just how can we describe it? As we saw, the usual way is as an infinite
decimal fraction, which is the limit of an infinite sequence of numbers, whose
squares get closer and closer to 2. This was the gateway to the fundamental
concept of the limit, the cornerstone of the infinitesimal calculus.
The square root of 2 was not alone for long. It was soon joined by addi-
tional irrational numbers. The Greeks realized that if the root of a whole
number is not itself an integer
√ (another word√ for “whole number”), then it
is irrational. The roots√ 4,√which
√ is 2, or 9, which is 3, are √ integers, and
therefore rational. But 3, 5, √6 and so on, are√not. Nor is 2+1√rational:
if it were rational, then, since ( 2 + 1) − 1 = 2, the number 2 would
be the difference between two rational numbers, and hence rational itself,
which we know it isn’t.
The conclusion is that there are infinitely many irrational numbers. In
fact, they are so numerous that they are “dense,” in the sense that there
is an irrational number between any two distinct numbers. The rational
numbers look like a sieve, whose holes are the irrational numbers. An even
more startling discovery will be made at the end of the nineteenth century
by Georg Cantor: that the holes are the majority. There are more irra-
tional numbers than rational numbers. Among numbers, as among humans,
rationality is rare.
The rational and the irrational numbers together are called “real
numbers.” Of course, this is not a proper definition of the term. It is like
defining “living creatures” as “humans or nonhumans,” which does not tell
us what is a “nonhuman living being.” The real numbers were defined pre-
cisely only at the end of the nineteenth century, which was an era of tran-
sition from fuzziness to rigor, mathematical intuitions being supplemented
by precise definitions and proofs. In those years the principles of differential
and integral calculus were given explicit and accurate definitions, clear-cut

41
42 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

axioms were written for the natural numbers, and David Hilbert completed
the work that Euclid had left unfinished for 2,000 years: the writing of precise
axioms for plane geometry.
Two mathematicians, Richard Dedekind and Georg Cantor, were
responsible for the rigorous definition of the real numbers. Their definitions
provided the justification for the way in which these numbers had been
presented beginning in the sixteenth century, that is, as infinite decimals.
The number π, for example, which is the ratio of the circumference of circle
to its diameter, is written as 3.145912 . . . , going on ad infinitum. What this
means is that the numbers 3, 3.1, 3.14, 3145, . . . get nearer and nearer to π.
There is something special in the decimal expansion of rational numbers.
Everybody knows, for example, that 13 = 0.333 . . . , the 3s repeating forever.
This is true of every rational number. The decimal expansion of a rational
number keeps repeating from some point on, as in 2.4131313 . . . , in which
13 repeats indefinitely.
Indeed, what is this number, written as a fraction? There is a simple trick
that does the job. It uses the fact that surprises many people and exasperates
others, that 1 = 0.999 . . . . In order to understand why this equality is true,
we must first understand what 0.999 . . . is: it is the limit of the sequence 0.9,
0.99. 0.999, . . . . These numbers approach 1 because their distances from 1
1 1 1
are 10 , 100 , 1000 . . . — numbers that tend to zero.
Knowing that 0.999 . . . = 1, we can calculate 0.333 . . . . Since dividing a
number by 1 does not change it, we can write: 0.333 . . . = 0.333 ...
0.999 ... . In the last
quotient, every 3 in the numerator is matched by a 9 in the denominator.
Accordingly, the denominator is 3 times as large as the numerator (when I
explain this to children, I tell them about two brothers: for every amount of
money that one receives, the other receives three times as much. At the end
of the day, the second brother will have three times as much money as the
first). This means that the fraction is equal to 13 .
Let us now look at 2.4131313 . . . . The number 0.0131313 . . . is one-
tenth of 0.131313 . . . . We can write 0.131313 . . . = 0.1313... 13
0.9999... = 99 . (When
the numerator “receives” 13 one-hundredths, the denominator “receives” 99
one-hundredths; when the numerator “receives” 13 one-thousandths, then
the denominator receives 99 one-thousandths, and so on. Therefore, the
numerator is 13 99 as big as the denominator.) Summarizing, 2.4131313 =
2.4 + 10 × 99 = 2 409
1 13 2389
990 = 990 , a fraction.
The other direction is also true: every rational number can be written as
a recurring decimal fraction. This is proved, simply, by dividing the numer-
ator by the denominator. 73 , for example, is the result of dividing 7 by 3,
The Real Numbers 43

and performing the division we get 2.333. . . . It isn’t difficult to show that,
dividing one integer by another the numerals repeat themselves beginning
at a certain point.
This implies, for example, that the number 0.101001000100001. . . is not
rational, since it is not recurring. This is also a (somewhat vague) indication
that there are more irrational numbers than rational ones: recurrence is a
rare phenomenon, and “most” of the decimal fractions are nonrecurring.
The Miracle of Order

I see myself as a child on the beach gathering shells.

Isaac Newton

The most incomprehensible thing about the


world is that it is at all comprehensible.

Albert Einstein, 1879–1955

The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics

A physical theory must possess mathematical beauty.

Paul Dirac, British mathematician and physicist, 1902–1984

Einstein told us that even if we know something about the order that rules
the universe, we will never understand why it is there at all. It seems as
if nature built for us a castle, whose treasures we reveal bit by bit. And
we shall always be like children playing with shells on the shore of the sea,
the depths of which we will shall never fathom. But even more surprising
than the existence of order is the fact that it is expressed by mathematical
formulas. More than that — by the most advanced mathematical theories of
the day. The great number theorist Godfrey Harold Hardy (1877–1942) was
an avowed pacifist. His main research partner, John Edensor Littlewood,
spent World War I developing artillery. This may be why when, towards
the end of his life, Hardy summed up his experience as a mathematician in
his book A Mathematician’s Apology, he took comfort in the fact that none of
his discoveries had ever had any use, certainly not for military applications.
Not much later Hardy’s theories played a role in encryption theory, and now
they are indirectly applied in parts of computer science.
The annals of mathematics are replete with such examples. Today’s
esoteric fields are tomorrow’s basic scientific tools. A famous example: in

45
46 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the third century BCE Apollonius (262–190 BCE) developed a theory of


conic sections — the curves resulting from the intersection of a plane with
a conic envelope. These are the circle, the ellipse (of which the circle is a
special case), the parabola, and the hyperbola (it was Apollonius who coined
all these names).

The four sections of a cone cut by planes (from top to bottom): circle, ellipse, parabola,
and hyperbola.

Apollonius’ research was totally theoretical, without the slightest


practical intent. Almost two thousand years later, the German mathemati-
cian, astronomer, and astrologist Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) used con-
ical sections to describe the movement of the planets. The planets travel
around the Sun in elliptical orbits (and in a very special case — in a circle),
while the trajectory of an object that comes from infinity and is not caught in
the Sun’s gravitational field, but continues on its way, is usually hyperbolic;
parabolic in very singular instances.
Another famous example is the general theory of relativity. When Einstein
needed tools to discuss space-time geometry, he asked his mathematician
friends, and they told him that just what he needed already existed. The
tools had been developed some fifty years earlier by Bernhard Riemann
(1826–1866) and others, who never imagined that their discoveries would
be of practical use in the not so distant future.
Mathematics, which draws its problems from the real world, abandons
reality to advance on tracks originating from within itself — only to discover
that it preceded physics by a few decades or, sometimes, by centuries. Group
theory, for example, is a field of algebra that seems too abstract to have any
practical use. So much so, that in 1910 the Nobel laureate physicist James
The Miracle of Order 47

Jeans advocated removing it from the curriculum of Princeton University,


where he was visiting. Physics students, so he claimed, would never have
occasion to use it. Not long afterwards, group theory became one of the
most basic tools used by physicists, in particular in the field of elementary
particles. Today’s promising subatomic theory, string theory, would not have
been born without the tools that were developed in recent decades in alge-
bra and topology. Eugene Wigner, a Nobel Prize laureate in physics, wrote
an article that became famous, “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathe-
matics in the Natural Sciences.” He wrote about his amazement at the fact
that theorems proved for purely theoretical purposes quickly become rele-
vant for the real world. Why, of all disciplines, is higher mathematics the
proper tool? And how come it is deep and front line mathematics that is
needed?
One possible explanation is that “deep” and “elementary” are relative
concepts. The deep mathematical theories used by the ancient Greeks appear
elementary to a modern-day scientist. What looks deep to us might appear
elementary to creatures of higher intelligence. Physicists just use what they
have. If mathematicians provided them with better tools, they would have
used them.

Order in the world and order in mathematics

There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are
dreamt of in your philosophy.
Hamlet, in Hamlet by William Shakespeare, Act I

Yes, but there are also things in philosophy that have never
been dreamt of in heaven and earth.
Georg Christoph Lichtenberg, mathematician and satirist, 1742–1799

Mathematics describes the world, but there are also many things in math-
ematics that have never been dreamt of in the world. From the moment of
the invention of a mathematical concept, it has a life of its own. In fact,
most mathematical problems do not emerge from real life problems, but
from other mathematical problems. Questions gain their right to exist by
relating to earlier concepts. But then, the offshoots often return and join the
main river. Scientists suddenly realize that they need them, in spite of their
purely theoretical appearance.
48 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Beauty and truth

If the solution is not beautiful, I know it is wrong.


Buckminster Fuller, mathematician, architect, and inventor

The ideas chosen by my unconscious are those which reach


my consciousness, and I see that they are those which agree
with my aesthetic sense.
Jacques Hadamard, French mathematician,
1865–1963, from An Essay on the
Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field

My work always tried to unite the truth with beauty, but when
I had to choose one or the other, I usually chose beauty.
Hermann Weyl, German mathematician, 1885–1955
One of the characteristics most peculiar to mathematics is its conjectures.
These strange creatures are the forceful drive and the holy grails (there are
many of them) of mathematics. Conjectures may survive for hundreds of
years before being solved. And strangely enough, most of them are eventu-
ally proved, rather than refuted. How do mathematicians have the hunch
that a fact should be true? The surprising answer is that the best crite-
rion is aesthetics. Mathematicians believe a conjecture when they feel it is
beautiful.
Godfrey Hardy, the English mathematician already mentioned in this
book, received a letter in 1913 from a poor Indian clerk named Srinivasa
Ramanujan. The letter contained a collection of identities in number the-
ory. Hardy could prove some of them, but many he could not. He believed
they were true, because they looked so elegant. Ramanujan himself could
not explicitly prove some of them, but merely “dreamt” them. Hardy, who
realized that the young Indian was one of the great mathematical geniuses
of all time, invited him to England, where the two worked together for a few
years. Sadly, Ramanujan could not withstand the English climate and being
away from home. His health, which had not been good to start with, rapidly
deteriorated. He died in 1920, after having returned to India.
In the process of proving a mathematical conjecture, it frequently looks
as if the blanket is too short: if you pull to one side, the other will not be
covered. But if the hypothesis is beautiful, the mathematician believes that
the deep order behind it will act in his favor, and that he will uncover its
The Miracle of Order 49

Srinivasa Ramanujan (1887–1920), a mathematical genius who grew wild in India,


without formal university education. He was discovered by Hardy and Littlewood, came
to England, and worked with Hardy for about four years. He could not adjust to the
English climate, and returned to India, where he died at the age of 33.

underlying logic. And if not he himself, then those who come after him. It
seems that the goddess of mathematics is on the side of beauty — the more
beautiful the conjecture is, the better its chances of being correct. Beauty is
the guide to truth because it expresses an unconscious perception of order.
When everything falls into place, there must be an intrinsic reason.
Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs

Proofs really aren’t there to show you something is


true — they’re there to show you why it is true.
Andrew Gleason, American mathematician, born 1921
The strange usefulness of mathematics is a wonder. Another wonder, no
less curious, is that this order appears in concentrated pills. Deep order is
often revealed in concise formulations. Easily-formulated arguments, that
even a child can understand, float, as icebergs on the ocean, within complex
mathematical structures. Their proofs, in surprising contrast, sometimes fill
hundreds and even thousands of pages. How can simple facts have proofs
that are often tens of thousands of times more complicated than the facts
themselves, at least in terms of word count?
Let me describe four such cases. Four simply stated conjectures, whose
proofs are difficult or still elusive. Each of the four withstood determined
attacks, and two are still unproven. Such conjectures are alluring to both
professional and amateur mathematicians. Like a gambler who believes that
Lady Luck will favor him of all creatures on earth, every mathematician
harbors some hope that he will be the lucky one to be favored by the goddess
of mathematics. But innocent looking trees may have deep roots. Most of
the time, when the proof is finally found, it is not at all straightforward, and
requires new and surprising ideas.

Kepler’s sphere packing problem

The owner of an orchard wants to pack his oranges in a carton. As usual,


we will assume that these are mathematical oranges, that is, perfect spheres
all of the same size. We also assume that the carton is much bigger than the
oranges. (This condition is meant to ensure that what happens at the edges
of the carton will not be of decisive weight. In a more precise formulation of
the problem, we take larger and larger cartons, their size tending to infinity.)
How should the orchard owner pack the oranges, so that the largest possible

51
52 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

number will fit in the carton? This problem has two natural solutions. One is
to line the bottom of the carton with oranges, arranged in straight horizontal
and vertical rows, like this:

A seemingly economical packing. The next layer will sit in the spaces between the
oranges in the first layer.

Over the first layer we will now place the second layer, fitting the oranges
into the “holes” between every adjacent quadruple of oranges. The third
layer will fit into the holes between quadruples of oranges in the second
layer, and so on.
In the second natural solution, the oranges on the bottom of the carton
are arranged as a honeycomb, so that each orange is at the center of the six
oranges that surround it. Then, the holes between the oranges are filled, as
in the previous solution. The second layer, and succeeding layers, all have
this same honeycomb structure.

The honeycomb packing also seems economical.

Which of the two packing methods is more efficient? We are in store for
a surprise. The two methods, seemingly so different, are actually identical.
In the straight rows pattern, there are inclined planes arranged as a hon-
eycomb, and in the honeycomb pattern there are inclined planes arranged
in straight rows and columns. This is manifest when we build a pyramid
with a square base, with straight rows and columns packing. The illus-
tration below shows that there is a honeycomb packing at the side of the
pyramid.
Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs 53

The base of the pyramid is a square, in which the balls are arranged in straight rows in
both directions. If we look at the face of the pyramid, we see balls arranged as a hexagon
around a central ball — the honeycomb packing.

The fact that the two most natural packing methods coincide suggests
that this is indeed the most efficient packing. Johannes Kepler, whose name
was already mentioned in connection with the conic sections, surmised that
this is indeed the case. This very natural proposition waited 300 years to be
proved. Like many other famous conjectures, many incorrect solutions were
offered for it over the course of time. A proof that was accepted as correct
was found only in 1998 by the American Thomas Hales. Seven more years
would pass until the mathematical community agreed on the correctness of
the proof. The reason was the proof’s extensive use of computers, checking
details that are too complex to be done with pen and paper. The length of
the written part of the proof is also formidable: some 250 pages!

The four colors theorem

The basic requirement of a political map is that any two adjoining coun-
tries are colored differently, in order to be distinguishable from one another.
The more colors a mapmaker has at his disposal, the easier it is for him
to meet this requirement. For example, if the number of colors equals the
number of countries, no special effort is needed — each country has its
own color.
In 1852 the English mathematician Francis Guthrie noted that four colors
suffice for a proper coloring of the map of England’s counties. As a mathe-
matician (or as a poet) this prompted him to generalize. Is it not the case for
every map? Can’t every map be colored by just four colors? This problem
gained immediate publicity, and also an endless number of incorrect solu-
tions. The most famous of these was by Alfred Kempe in 1879. Unlike other
solutions, much time would pass before Kempe’s error was discovered; in the
meantime, partly thanks to his false solution, Kempe was elected a fellow of
the British Royal Society. After 11 years, it transpired that he had proved
54 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

less than he had claimed: that it was possible to color any map in five colors.
Election to the Royal Society is for life, and his membership remained in
force.
From then until 1976, when the theorem was finally proved, it was the
fate of every mathematician in the relevant field, combinatorics — which
happens to be my own field — to receive false proofs from amateurs who
tried their luck. When a proof was finally discovered, by the Americans
Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken, it became apparent to all that there
was a good reason for the elusiveness. Not only was the proof long and
complex; like Hales’ proof for the Kepler theorem, it made extensive use of
the computer to check more than a thousand special cases. The proof has
been somewhat simplified since then, but until this very day there is yet no
proof that does not rely on computers.
I cannot tell you much about the solution, but, as compensation, let
me tell you a more modest proposition, whose proof is easy. Assume that
the map is drawn in a special way, by adding one circle at a time, such as the
left-hand drawing on this page. The circles cut the world into “countries.”
In this case, you do not need four colors. Two suffice, as in the right-hand
drawing:

The map on the left is special: The borders are generated by circles. Such a map can be
colored with only two colors, as in the example on the right.

The simplest proof of this employs the concept of evenness and oddness
(once again, we see how useful this concept is!). Color each country lying
within an odd number of circles red, and color each country contained in
an even number of circles blue. In particular, the surrounding area (the
“sea”), that is contained in zero circles, is colored blue: zero is an even
number.
Let us show that this coloration fits the bill. That is, every two adjacent
countries are colored differently. Look at one country (call it A). Assume, as
an example, that A is contained in 5 circles. Since 5 is an odd number, by our
Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs 55

coloration rule, A is colored red. We have to prove that any country (call it
B) adjoining A is colored blue. On our map, crossing a border between two
countries means entering or leaving a circle. If to go from A to B we leave a
circle, then B is located within 4 circles (one fewer than A), and therefore is
colored blue (since 4 is even). If to go from A to B we enter a circle, B lies
within 6 circles. Since 6 is even, B has to be colored blue, which is just what
we had to show. You can easily convince yourselves that there is nothing
special about the number 5. The argument is valid for every number.

Ascending and descending sequences

In 1937 the German mathematician Lothar Collatz posed an innocuous look-


ing problem, a mathematical snakes and ladders game. In it, a sequence of
numbers is defined according to the following rule: when we get to an even
number, we divide it by 2; when we have at hand an odd number, we multiply
it by 3 and add 1.
Suppose, for example, that we begin with 10. Since 10 is even, we divide it
by 2. The result, 5, is odd, and so we multiply it by 3 and add 1. This yields
16, which is even, and is therefore divided by 2. The sequence we produce
is: 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1. If we begin with 100, we get:

100, 50, 25, 76, 38, 19, 58, 29, 88, 44, 22, 11, 34, 17, 52, 26, 13,
40, 20, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1

Both examples ended at 1. Is this always the case? Collatz’s conjecture


is that this is so. Wherever the sequence starts, it will always end up at 1.
Naturally, such a simple looking problem attracted a lot of attention, with no
real progress. The Hungarian mathematician Paul Erdős argued that today’s
mathematics does not have the tools needed to tackle it.
Why, then, do we nevertheless believe in the conjecture? There is a heuris-
tic, meaning to say informal, reason. It is that there are more “snakes”
(by which we go down) than “ladders” (by which we go up). The lad-
ders are longer, because when we go up we multiply by 3 and add 1,
while when we descend we divide only by 2. But the number of descents
is greater because every ascent is followed by a descent, while a descent is
not necessarily followed by an ascent. An ascent happens when we come to
an odd number, and after the multiplication by 3 (which keeps the num-
ber odd) and the addition of 1 we obtain an even number, after which
the rules demand that we go down. An assumption that has no proof,
56 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

but seems plausible, is that after every descent there still is a 50 percent
chance to descend further, and after that, there is an additional 50 per-
cent chance to descend, and so on. If this is so, it easily follows that for
every ascent (that rises by a factor of about 3), there are, on average,
2 descents. Since these two descents mean going down by a factor of 4,
every ascent times 3 is typically matched by a 4 times descent. There-
fore, on average, we drop further than we rise, so that, eventually, there
is a good probability of reaching 1. Of course this does not constitute
a proof, because even if the probability of an event is low, it can still
occur.
Another difficulty is that the numbers can go in a circle: there is no
a priori reason why, say, if we begin with the number 537, the sequence
will not eventually come around again to 537, just as when we begin with
1 we return to 1 (the sequence beginning with 1 is: 1, 4, 2, 1). To date no
such circle has been found, other than the one beginning with 1, and with
assumptions similar to those we mentioned, there is a good chance that no
other circle exists.
This is a famous conjecture. Is it also important? At first glance, the
answer is no. It isn’t connected to any other mathematical topic, nor does
it have any direct consequences. But, of course, this depends on the type of
its solution, if it will ever appear. If the solution will show that this series is
“random,” in the sense described above — that a snake has the same chance
to be followed by another snake as by a ladder, then we will understand
something of value about the structure of numbers.

The twin primes conjecture

A prime number is a number greater than 1 that is not divisible by any


number other than itself and 1. The first five prime numbers are: 2, 3, 5, 7,
and 11. Prime numbers are important because they are the building blocks
of numbers: every number can be written uniquely as the product of prime
numbers (ignoring the order of the multiplicands). The components of a
number can appear more than once, for example

1200 = 2 × 2 × 2 × 2 × 3 × 5 × 5 = 24 × 3 × 52

Ancient Greeks already knew that there are infinitely many primes. The
kingdom of natural numbers owes its complexity to the infinite number of
its fundamental building blocks.
Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs 57

Research in number theory was renewed in the seventeenth century, and


special attention was drawn to the behavior of prime numbers. One of the
most fascinating questions concerns their density: what portion of the num-
bers between 1 and a given number n do they constitute. For example, there
are 25 prime numbers between 1 and 100, that is, one quarter of the num-
bers are primes. Between 1 and 1000 there are 168 primes, about one sixth.
Between 1 and 1,000,000 there are 78,498 prime numbers, about 1 in 13.
These examples show that the higher the number, the smaller is the
relative part of the primes among numbers below it. The primes become
rarer and rarer. In the one thousand numbers between 1,000,001 and
1,001,000 there are fewer prime numbers than between 1 and 1,000. The
question is, at what pace do they diminish? The above data shows that
the rate of decline is not especially rapid. One million is a thousand times
greater than one thousand, but in the jump between one thousand and
a million, the portion of primes only dropped from 16 to 13 1
, about two
times.
We already mentioned Carl Friedrich Gauss in “To Discover or to Invent.”
In 1796, when he was nineteen years old, he proposed a conjecture regard-
ing the density of prime numbers. It is that between 1 and any number n
there are about lnnn prime numbers, with ln n being the logarithm in the
base e = 2.718 . . . of n. (we will learn about the number e towards the end
of the book. The concept “logarithm” is explained in the Glossary). This
conjecture, one of the holy grails of the mathematics of the 19th century,
was eventually solved independently in 1896 by two mathematicians, Jacques
Hadamard and Louis de la Vallée-Poussin. The theorem that they proved
became known as the “Prime Numbers Theorem.” It states that not only are
there infinitely many prime numbers in the world, but their portion among all
the numbers is also not negligible. There are many prime numbers between
1 and n, for a large n.
There are other manifestations of the proliferation of prime numbers.
Two famous conjectures point in this direction:

1. The Twin Prime Number Conjecture: There are infinitely many


“twin” pairs of prime numbers, that is, pairs with a difference of 2.
The first twin pairs of primes are:

(3, 5), (5, 7), (11, 13), (17, 19), (29, 31), (41, 43).

2. Goldbach’s Conjecture: Every even number larger than 2 is the sum


of two prime numbers.
58 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The Twin Primes Conjecture states that the set of prime numbers is suffi-
ciently rich to contain many prime numbers that are close together. Accord-
ing to Goldbach’s Conjecture, the set of prime numbers is rich enough to
express every even number as their sum. Both conjectures are very famous,
and are usually bound together. The Goldbach Conjecture is the better-
known of the two, possibly because it was named after a person. Christian
Goldbach, a minor German mathematician, got into the pantheon of math-
ematics due to a letter he sent to Leonhard Euler that contained the conjec-
ture. For a reason that will be explained in the next chapter, “Independent
Events,” no one doubts its veracity. Actually, typically the larger the even
number, the greater the number of ways it can be expressed as the sum of
two primes. The number 10 can be written in two ways as the sum of two
prime numbers: 3 + 7 and 5 + 5. The number 100 can already be written
as the sum of two primes in five ways: 3 + 97, 11 + 89, 17 + 83, 29 + 71,
and 41 + 59.
“Be wise, generalize,” goes a famous mathematical dictum. Here is a
generalization of the twin primes conjecture.
Conjecture: for every even number k there are infinitely many prime pairs
whose difference is k.
In other words, there are infinitely many pairs of prime numbers with a
difference of 4 between the pair; there are infinitely many pairs of prime
numbers with a difference of 6; and so on. The number k must be even,
because if the difference is odd, then one of the two numbers is even, and
therefore it is not a prime number (unless it is 2). This conjecture is also
similar in form to the Goldbach Conjecture, in which every even number is
the sum of two primes (in the new conjecture, it is the difference between
two primes). A major breakthrough was obtained in 2013, when the joint
effort of many mathematicians culminated in a proof of the conjecture for
all k > 244.

How can simple theorems have complicated proofs?

So, how can simple theorems demand complex proofs? This is a mystery,
to which I can only attempt an explanation. I think that this is an opti-
cal illusion: the simple statements are those that draw our attention. Like
adventurers who seek gold, and incidentally discover an entire continent,
mathematicians, too, try to solve simply stated problems, and in the midst
of doing so, discover complex theories. If they were to start from the end,
Simple Conjectures, Complex Proofs 59

from the theory, things would look differently. The simple statements in a
mathematical theory are only a small part of the body of knowledge, but they
are the most conspicuous because of their concise formulations. Our gaze is
riveted to them, and it seems to us that they are the main focus. Actually,
they only make up a small part of a big world, little pegs protruding out of
the big rock.
But I must admit: every time I encounter a short theorem with a long
proof, I am surprised anew.
Independent Events

Independence

There is good reason that mathematicians believe in the correctness of the


Twin Primes Conjecture and in Goldbach’s Conjecture. It is related to a
concept that is important not only in mathematics, but in life in general:
independence of events.
“Independence” means lack of causal link. Two events are independent
if information on one adds no knowledge regarding the probability of the
other. For example, many people believe that if they rolled a 6 in dice three
straight times, then there is little chance that the next toss will also be 6.
In reality, different tosses of the dice are independent: if the dice are fair,
then the events: “first roll 6” and “second roll 6” are not causally linked.
Of special importance is the realization that most events in the world do
not depend on your desires. There is no connection between the results of
a football game and your support of one of the teams. Blowing on the dice
before the toss doesn’t really help.
Here is another example: gender and eye color. Knowing that a person is
blond increases the probability that his or her eyes are blue. Knowing that
the person is a female provides no information regarding the color of her
eyes. The percentage of blue-eyed people is exactly the same among women
as in the entire population.

Independence and probability

Assume, for the sake of argument, that the proportion of people in the
1
population (whether men or women) whose first name begins with A is 20 .
That is, one out of every twenty people has a first name beginning with A.
Problem: among all married couples, what is the proportion of couples in
which the first names of both the husband and wife begin with A?

61
62 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

We can imagine two extreme cases. If all men whose first names begin
with A were to take an oath not to marry a woman whose first name begins
with A, there would be no couples like this. On the other extreme, if all men
whose names begin with A were to marry only women whose names begin
with A, then all the couples in which the husband’s name begins with A
1
would belong to this category, and they would constitute 20 of all couples.
A more realistic assumption, however, is that people do not choose their
spouses based on the first letter of their name. So there is no connection
between the two events: the first letter of the husband’s name and the first
letter of the wife’s name are independent events. What proportion of the
couples then have both names that begin with A? The husband’s name
1
begins with A in 20 of the couples, and assuming independence of events,
1
in 20 of these couples the wife’s name, too, begins with A. Therefore, the
1
couples in which the names of both spouses begin with A constitute 20 of
1 1
20 , which is 400 of all couples.
This exemplifies a principle: when two events are independent, the proba-
bility of their joint occurrence is the product of their individual probabilities.
Let us see this in the gender and eye color example. Assume that 13 of the
population has blue eyes, and that 12 of the population are women. Assuming
independence, the blue-eyed women are 13 of the women, namely a 13 of 12 of
the population, which is 13 × 12 = 16 . Likewise, the probability of rolling two
6’s in two dice is the product of the probabilities of rolling a 6 in each one,
that is: 16 × 16 = 36
1
.

Positive correlation, negative correlation

If two events are causally linked, then the occurrence of one changes the
probability of the other. We then say that the events are “dependent.” If the
occurrence of the first increases the chances of the other occurring, we say
that there is a positive correlation between them. For example, there is a
positive correlation between being blond and being blue-eyed. If the occur-
rence of one event decreases the probability of the other, we say that they
are negatively correlated. There is negative correlation between being blond
and being brown-eyed.
If the correlation between two events is positive, the probability that both
will occur is greater than the product of their individual probabilities. For
example, the positive correlation between being blue-eyed and being blond
means that if 13 of the population are blonds and 12 are blue-eyed, then more
than 16 of the population will be both blond and blue-eyed. As an extreme
Independent Events 63

example, assume that all blonds have blue eyes. In such a case, the set of
blue-eyed blonds is identical to the set of blonds, that is, it constitutes 13 of
the population, which is more than 16 .

Why is the Twin Primes Conjectures almost


certainly correct?

The Twin Primes Conjecture states that there are infinitely many numbers
n, such that both n and n + 2 are prime. Why do mathematicians believe in
it? To see this, let us explain why there are many twin primes between, say,
1 and 1,000,000.
The secret is that there is no obvious connection between the primality
of a number n and the primality of n + 2. These two events should be
independent. The fact that 101 is a prime number gives no reason to think
that 103, too, is a prime number, or the opposite. As already mentioned,
there are about 78,000 prime numbers between 1 and 1,000,000, which means
that about 1 out of every 13 numbers in this range is prime. In other words,
1
13 of the numbers up to a million are prime. If there is no dependence
1
between a number n being prime and n + 2 being prime, then for about 13
of these prime ns, n + 2 is also prime. Therefore, the portion of the numbers
1 1
n up to a million for which both n and n + 2 are primes is 13 of 13 , which is
1 1 1 1
13 × 13 = 169 . In other words, for about 169 of the numbers between 1 and
1,000,000 (about 6,000 numbers), both the number and the number n + 2
are prime. So, assuming independence, there should be approximately 6,000
pairs of twin prime numbers between 1 and 1,000,000.

The Twin Prime Number Conjecture, with some spare

Actually, there are more. There are 8,169 such pairs. This means that our
assumption of independence was not accurate. The dice are in fact stacked
in favor of twins. The reason is that these two events are actually dependent,
and positively correlated. A number n between 1 and 1,000,000 being prime
means that there is greater chance that n + 2 is prime. The reason is that
the prime numbers are not evenly distributed between 1 and 1,000,000. They
are more concentrated among the small numbers. About 16 of the numbers
between 1 and 1,000 are prime numbers, while between 1 and 1,000,000 only
1
about 13 are, remember? Accordingly, if we know that n is a prime number,
then there is a higher probability that it is small. Then n + 2, also, is small
64 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

(remember, we are talking about numbers from 1 to 1,000,000, an addition


of 2 is insignificant), and this increases the chances that n + 2 is prime.
1
It follows from this that more than 169 of the numbers n between 1 and
1,000,000 meet both conditions, that n and n + 2 are prime.

From million to infinity

Between 1 and 1,000,000 there are 8,169 twin prime pairs. A similar
calculation shows that the range between 1 and 10,000,000 is likely to con-
tain more than 50,000 twin prime pairs (the actual number is 58,980). This
means that when going from 1,000,000 to 10,000,000 new pairs are added,
namely, there are many twin primes located in the range between these
two numbers. Similarly, there are twin-prime pairs between 10,000,000 and
100,000,000. New pairs appear at each step, which means there are infinitely
many pairs.
Let me repeat: the assumption on which this argument is based, that there
is no negative correlation between the primality of n and that of n + 2, is
not rock solid. So, the argument does not constitute a proof. It only provides
good reason to believe in the conjecture.
Poetic Image, Mathematical Image

Words

If there is anxiety in a man’s mind, let him tell it.


Proverbs 12:25
Late in my professional life I made a partial career change, and began teach-
ing mathematics in elementary schools. I came full of enthusiasm and new
ideas. In particular, I believed in direct experience and addressing intuition.
I thought that if the children would have hands-on experience, the abstrac-
tions would come by themselves. I quickly learned how wrong I was, and
how essential is an interim stage that I missed: words. Human knowledge is
built one layer on top of another, and words are the cement that binds them
together. The first understanding of an idea is always intuitive, but in order
to build the next floor one needs to stabilize this understanding by precise
formulations. Man owes to words his ability to build skyscrapers of knowl-
edge. Here is a little related secret: telling your trouble to others is helpful not
only because of the release and the sympathy you may get. No less important
is the fact that you clothed your problem in words. This helps not to tread
in place. The next time you will start at the point you stopped last time.
But words are only the scaffolding for thought, not its engine. Purely
verbal thought is barren. This is why abstract words cannot touch the roots
of thought nor the profundities of emotions. To really reach people’s minds
and emotions, words must be used against themselves. This means, mainly,
constructing images instead of abstractions, pictures that are close to the
sources of thought. Mathematicians know this, as do poets. This is why
images occupy such a central place in both domains.

The poetical picture

One generalization is worth a thousand examples.


Anonymous

67
68 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

One example is worth a thousand generalizations.


Anonymous
In his book Twelve Conversations on Poetry the poet Yaoz-Kest explains
the difference between songs and poems: the song speaks of the general,
the poem about the individual. The song may use abstractions, the poem is
always concrete. Just like mathematics, it uses examples, that is, pictures, to
deliver its message. Here is a famous example, Goethe’s “Wanderer’s Night
Song II”:

Over mountains yonder,


A stillness;
Scarce any breath, you wonder,
Touches
The tops of all the trees.
No forest birds now sing;
A moment, waiting —
Then take, you too, your ease.

“Wanderer’s Night Song II,” Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, trans.


Christopher Middleton
Wandering in search of self discovery is not the invention of today’s back-
packers. In the romantic period, the wanderer who leaves civilization to seek
his inner truth was eulogized in many poems. Wilhelm Muller’s cycle of
poems Winterreise (A Winter Journey), put to music by Schubert, tells the
same story as in Goethe’s poem. There too, the wanderer, a frustrated lover,
longs to die — the meaning of the last two lines of “Wanderer’s Night Song
II.” Goethe’s poem, however, was the harbinger of the genre. Incidentally,
Schubert also set this poem to music, twice.
The first six lines of the poem paint a seemingly pastoral scene: mountain
peaks, treetops, birds. Actually, this is a sinister scene, everything being so
quiet and still. The uneven meter and the changing pattern of rhymes amplify
the sense of unease, reflecting the hero’s disquiet. And then, in the last line,
we understand: the threatening quiet is a reflection of the wanderer’s desire
to die, expressed as the wish to rest. The poem is thus conjured by four
means. Two that relate to external form (rhyme and meter), and two of
indirectness: the image, and the metaphor of death as rest.
Like the metaphor, the poetical picture is used for making an indi-
rect statement. It projects emotions and thoughts on the external world.
Poetic Image, Mathematical Image 69

David Fogel (1891–1944) was a master of images. Fogel was born in the
Ukraine and, except for a single year in Palestine, spent his entire life in
Europe. His poem “The Cities of My Youth,” one of his last two, was writ-
ten in 1941 in occupied France, in a state of sheer isolation and desperation,
with the Nazi manhunt nearing. The mood, however, is not particular to
this poem of his. All his poetry expresses a feeling of estrangement.

The cities of my youth,


Now I’ve forgotten them all,
And you in one of them.

In a rain puddle
Barefoot, you will yet dance for me
But you must have already died.

From my distant childhood


How I hastened to run,
Until I came to the white palace of old age —
And it is spacious and empty.

My fledgling steps
I shall never see,
Nor you, I shall not see,
Nor I of then.
The caravan of days,
From afar,
Moves on
From where to nowhere
Without me.

David Fogel, “The Cities of My Youth,” in Collected Poems

This is a poem of loss and surrender, of the abandoning of desires and lusts
that old age entails. But the detachment is not expressed abstractly. A prose
author would write “I forgot my youth.” Fogel writes tangibly, “I’ve forgotten
the cities of my youth.” Old age and death are both portrayed in a single
picture, the white palace. And most moving is the last picture, of the caravan
of days, that treads from one empty horizon to another, the poet being
alienated even from this bleak emptiness: “Without me.”
70 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

A mathematical picture: The number line


How do I think about my problems?
In a methodical and tangible way.

Karl Friedrich Gauss, mathematician

Mathematicians too, think in pictures. Words and formulas are used only
afterwards, for communication and stabilization. Here is a small example.
My daughter, who was seven at the time, was playing in the bathtub, and I
came in and told her she had to finish her bath in three minutes. She asked
for another five minutes. Okay, I negotiated, let’s make it another four. She
understood we were speaking about compromising in the middle and said,
“In that case, I’ll come out in 100 minutes.” If you can find the middle
between 3 and 100, I told her, you can stay for that amount of time. “51
and a half minutes” she said, without batting an eyelash (needless to say,
she didn’t stay that long.) To my question how she had calculated this, she
answered, “Half of 100 is 50, and half of 3 is one and a half, so the middle
between them is 50 and one and a half, which is 51 and a half.” But she
couldn’t explain why she calculated the middle this way — that’s how we
do it, and that’s that. Now, years later, I still don’t know how she did it.
But here is a picture that she may have had in her subconscious:

The middle between 3 and 100 is the middle between 0 and 103.

Our eye tells us that the middle between 3 and 100 is the middle between 0
(which is 3 units to the left of 3) and 103 (that is 3 units to the right of 100);
and the middle between 0 and 103 is half of 103, which is half of 100 plus
half of 3, just as my daughter had calculated.
The picture we used here is one of the most effective tools in mathemat-
ics, the “number line.” This is a line along which numbers are marked at
equal intervals. If we were to attribute it to a single person, it would be
Nicholas Oresme (1323–1382), a French prelate and mathematician. Actu-
ally, the number line is a very natural idea, because it is the reverse of
measurement. Measuring length quantifies geometry, while the number line
does the opposite: it brings geometry to the aid of numbers. It gives tangible,
geometric form to the concept of the number. Besides size, it also illustrates
direction, the negative numbers being to the left of zero.
Poetic Image, Mathematical Image 71

A well-known story about pictorial thought is told about the German


chemist Friedrich August Kekule. Kekule struggled for a long time to under-
stand the molecular structure of benzene (an oily, flammable hydrocarbon).
He knew this molecule contained six carbon atoms and six hydrogen atoms,
but he couldn’t understand how they were linked. Until one night, he dreamt
of a snake holding its tail, and when he awoke, he realized that the carbon
atoms are arranged in a circle.

Another famous mathematical picture, the “Venn diagram,” is used


to illustrate sets. It shows the distribution of elements among the sets.
The following Venn diagram shows three sets, A, B, and C. The shaded
area, for example, represents the set of elements in C that is not part
of A or B.

A coordinate system

The single picture that changed mathematical thought more than any other
is the Cartesian coordinate system. “Cartesius” was the Latin name of René
72 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Descartes (1596–1650), a French mathematician and philosopher, and the


system is named after him, even though it was also discovered at about the
same time by Pierre de Fermat (Curiously enough, simultaneous discoveries
are not rare, which attests to what extent ideas float in the air at the time of
their discovery). The Cartesian system is a two-dimensional extension of the
number line, with two axes in the plane instead of one. While the number
line represents numbers, the Cartesian system enables us to visualize pairs
of numbers. The horizontal axis is usually called the “x axis,” the vertical
axis the “y axis,” and each pair of numbers (x, y) corresponds to a point
reached by moving from the origin, which is the intersection of the axes,
x units to the right and y units up (if x is negative, the movement will be to
the left, and if y is negative, it is downwards). For example, the pair (3, 2)
corresponds to a point that is 3 units to the right of the origin of the axes,
and 2 units up:

At first glance, there is nothing new here. Sailors used this system long
before Descartes. To mark points on the globe they use two numbers, lati-
tude and longitude. So what is so brilliant about this discovery? Descartes’s
innovation was not the discovery of the coordinate system, but in realizing
its usefulness. Number pairs describe connections between numbers. As in
life, numerical relations often link pairs (of numbers, in this case) rather
than triplets or quadruplet. The coordinate system enables us to graphically
depict these relations.
Take for example, the relation between a number and its square. The set
of pairs that satisfies this relation is a collection of pairs of the form (x, x2 ).
For example, (0, 0) is such a pair, as is (3, 9), and also (−3, 9), because
(−3)2 = 9. This also includes pairs of numbers that are not integers, such as
(0.5, 0.25). If we draw all of these points on paper, the result is a “graph,”
Poetic Image, Mathematical Image 73

which is a picture that depicts the relation. In this instance, the graph we
obtain is a parabola. Each point on the parabola corresponds to one of the
pairs.

The relation between a number and its square is an example of a numeri-


cal function. A numerical function is a special type of relation between num-
ber pairs: a correspondence assigning a single number y to every number x.
A real-life example of a numerical function: drive along the highway between
Santa Fe, New Mexico and Denver, Colorado (the “Mile High City”). For
every mile you drive, mark your elevation above sea level. The graph that
describes this will show the elevation of the point as a function of the distance
from Santa Fe.
Like every function, the “square” is an input-output machine. Given an
input number, it outputs its square. The coordinate system helps us visualize
the action of this machine. But it can also visualize relationships that are
not functions. For example, “the distance of the point (x, y) from the origin,
(0, 0), is 1” is a relation between x and y. There are pairs that satisfy it,
and pairs that don’t, just as among people there are pairs who are married
and pairs that are not (and just as in the case of marriage, most pairs do
not satisfy the relation).
 By Pythagoras’ Theorem, the distance of the point
(x, y) from (0, 0) is x2 + y 2 . It follows that the
points (x, y) at distance 1
from the origin are those satisfying the equality x2 + y 2 = 1, which is true
if and only if x2 + y 2 = 1. Obviously, the points satisfying the condition lie
on a circle with radius 1 and center at the origin. So, the circle describes the
relationship given by the equation x2 + y 2 = 1. The algebraic equality was
transformed into a curve, and vice versa.
74 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The circle describes a relation between the value x of a point and the value y of the
point. The points on the circle are exactly the (x, y) points at a distance of 1 from the
origin of the axes; by the Pythagorean Theorem, this is true only if x2 + y 2 = 1.

Note that the equality x2 + y 2 = 1 does not express y as a function of x. A


function must assign precisely one value of y to each value of x, which is not
true of this equality. For example, for x = 0, two values of y are suitable, 1
and (−1).
Thanks to Descartes, relations of this type become visible, and therefore
easier to grasp. It is easier to visualize a circle than understand a formula.
But there is yet another advantage to the Cartesian system, which was in
fact Descartes’s original aim. It goes in the opposite direction: geometric
shapes are defined by formulas. For example, the collection of points (x, y)
for which x = y comprises a straight line, and the collection of points (x, y)
for which xy = 1 comprises the two branches of a hyperbola.

The graph describing the relationship xy = 1 between the variables x and y. It is called a
“hyperbola.”
Poetic Image, Mathematical Image 75

Both algebra and geometry benefit from this system. Algebra gains the
tangibility of geometric pictures, and geometry gains the use of algebraic
tools.

René Descartes, French mathematician and philosopher (1596–1650). He chose a military


career, but never took part in a battle. He spent his later years in Holland, until the
queen of Sweden summoned him to be her private tutor. He did not withstand the harsh
Swedish winter, and died of pneumonia shortly thereafter. His best-known contribution
to mathematics is the Cartesian coordinate system, that is named after him.
The Power of the Oblique

In science one tries to tell people, in such a way as to


be understood by everyone, something that no one
ever knew before. In poetry, it’s the exact opposite.

Paul Dirac, British mathematician and physicist

What did the poet mean?

To be a poem, a text should be oblique. Here, for example, is a poem by


Rachel Bluwstein, “When It Comes”:

And this is it? Only this?


Raising impatient eyes to this,
This, my lips, thirst to drink,
And with this, to warm the heart
in the chill of the night?
For this, to spurn God
and kick at His yoke?

This . . . and no more . . . no more

“When It Comes,” Rachel Bluwstein


Those who know Rachel’s life story (she is known to the Hebrew reader
by her first name) can guess what this poem is about: a forbidden and
unfulfilled love. But we don’t have to know the details in order to grasp the
mood the poem conveys, or in order to understand its message: “What is
life, in comparison to a single storm of passion?” and, “There are things
beyond the measure of everyday life.” The poem’s beauty lies in the sharp
turn in the last line. Until this line, the poem is a protest of the poet against
the world and against herself. And then, like in a punch line of a joke,
everything is overturned. She comes to grips with her choice and with the

77
78 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The poet Rachel Bluwstein (known simply as “Rachel”), was born in Russia in 1909 and
immigrated to Palestine in 1909. She died in Tel Aviv in 1931, of tuberculosis she had
contracted when she returned to Russia to treat the children of First World War refugees.

world, and accepts that the power of the heart is stronger than her. Due to
the suddenness of the insight, and its minimalist statement (“no more. . . no
more”), we perceive it like a feather’s brush, and can pretend as if we really
hadn’t heard it.

Indirect proofs

Indirectness is not just an artistic means of the poem; it is an essential. A


poem is never direct. We less expect to find indirectness in mathematics.
But when it does appear there, it is always a source of beauty.

A mathematician and his friend are walking in the


forest. The friend boasts: “In a flash, I can know
how many needles are on this pine tree.”
“How many?” the mathematician asks.
“143, 547,” says the friend, without batting an eyelash.
The mathematician takes a handful of needles,
and asks: “And how many now?”
The Power of the Oblique 79

This little story encapsulates several characteristics of mathematics. First


of all, economy: the mathematician saves himself the trouble of count-
ing the needles. He will subtract the new number his friend tells him
from the first, and the difference should equal the number of needles in
his hand, that can easily be counted. There is beauty in turning the
boasting against itself. Making your opponent do the work for you saves
energy, and hence is aesthetic. Economy of thought is a source of plea-
sure. Another source of beauty is the new element that comes out of the
blue — subtraction. But probably most beautiful is the mathematician’s
indirect approach. He doesn’t directly confront his friend’s boasting. He
doesn’t count the needles, and at the end of the story this number is
not known.
Some of the most beautiful arguments in mathematics are of this type.
There is nothing more elegant than showing that something exists, without
pointing at it concretely.

An irrational number to the power of a rational number



I already told you the story of the irrationality of 2. In the eighteenth
century more difficult proofs were discovered for the irrationality of certain
numbers. In 1737 Euler proved the irrationality of an important number
called e (approximately 2.718; we will return to it later). In 1768 Lambert
proved the irrationality of π, the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its
diameter.
Then came more complicated questions: for example, is πe, the product
of these two numbers, rational? There is no reason why it should be. As
already mentioned, in a certain sense there are many more irrational than
rational numbers (even though there is an infinite number of each), and
therefore we could reasonably assume that πe is irrational. At our present
state of knowledge, however, there no way of proving this. Is this important?
Not particularly. The only reason why we care is because “it is there,” or, as
Hilbert put it: “We can know, [therefore] we must know.” Questions of this
sort are important only because the methods developed to solve them may
turn out to be useful in other problems.
Hilbert was invited to the International Mathematics Congress held in
1900 to deliver one of the main speeches. In a daring move, especially con-
sidering his relatively young age (he was 38 at the time), he decided to give
a lecture on the challenges facing mathematics during the coming century.
80 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

He chose 23 problems that he saw as central. His intuition proved correct.


Most of these problems were solved during the twentieth century, and most
were gateways to important developments. The seventh problem √ was proving
the irrationality of certain numbers — for example eπ , or 2 2 . This problem
was solved in 1934 by the Russian mathematician Alexander Gelfond (1906–
1968),
√ and since then eπ is called the “Gelfond number.” He also proved that
2 2 is irrational, but he had to share the glory with another mathematician,
Theodor Schneider. It is called the “Gelfond-Schneider number.” And what
about π e , for example? Is it, too, irrational? It is a safe bet that it is, but
this is beyond our current state of knowledge.
These are deep problems, and I cannot tell you anything about the proofs.
But here is a simpler question: prove that there are two irrational numbers,
a and b, for which ab is rational. Indeed, there are such numbers. And we
shall show this without knowing the values a and b. Before beginning the
proof, let me mention a simple rule of powers: (xy )z = xyz . Here is a “proof”
by example:

(x2 )3 = x2 × x2 × x2 = (x × x) × (x × x) × (x × x) = x6 = x2×3

We want to prove the following:


Theorem: There are two irrational numbers, a and b, such that ab is
rational.
√ √2
√ possibilities. The first is that 2 is
We have to distinguish between two
rational. In this case, we are done: 2 is irrational, so we have an irrational
√ raised to an irrational power, producing a rational number. So, a =
number
b = 2 satisfy the theorem.
√ √2
The second possibility is that 2 is irrational. Look at the √number
√ √2 √2 √ 2 √
( 2√ )√ . According to the rule of powers mentioned above, ( 2 ) 2 =
√ 2× 2 √ 2
2 = 2 = 2 (the last equality is nothing but the √ definition of the
square root). √Therefore, once again the irrational power 2 of an irrational
√ 2 √
number, ( 2 ) 2 (remember, in the present case we assume that this is
an irrational number) is the rational number 2, which is precisely what we
wanted.
In fact, we know which of the two possibilities is true. By Gelfond’s
√ √2
Theorem, 2 is irrational. The merit of out proof is that it didn’t use this
deep theorem.
The Power of the Oblique 81

The pigeonhole principle

Here is another mathematical theorem whose proof is not explicit:


In Santa Barbara there are two people with exactly the same number of
hairs on their heads. (If you argue that this is too simple, because there are
probably two completely bald people, then we can state a stronger propo-
sition: there are two not completely bald people with the same number of
hairs.)
The proof is based on what is known as the “pigeonhole principle”: if 101
(or more) pigeons occupy 100 cells, then at least one cell will be taken by
more than one pigeon. In general, if the number of pigeons is greater than
the number of cells, two pigeons (at least) will have to crowd into a single
cell. The general formulation of this theorem is: When more than n objects
are divided into n types (“cells”), there will be at least two of the same type.
Can such a simple principle be of any value? The answer is “yes,” if the
cells are cleverly chosen. Returning to the hairs of the Santa Barbarians, it
is known that a person has at most 100,000 hairs on his head. At the time of
writing of this text, Santa Barbara has a population of around 104,000. So,
we may safely assume that there are at least 100,001 people in the city who
are not totally bald. Dividing the not-bald Santa Barbarians into types, by
the number of hairs on their head (that is, the first type has a single hair,
the second type has two hairs, and so on), we see that there are more people
than types. Therefore, there will be (at least) two people of the same “type,”
that is, who have the same number of hairs.

Independent sets

A set of numbers is “independent” (a term coined only for our purposes here)
if no number in it is divisible by another. For example, the set {3,5,6} is not
independent, because 3 divides 6. The set {3,4,5} is independent, because 5
is not divisible by 3 or 4, and 4 is not divisible by 3.
Question: How large can an independent set of numbers between
1 and 100 be?

As usual, a good advice is to begin with simple examples. In this case,


replace 100 by a smaller number. The smaller the better, so ask first what
the maximal size of an independent set of numbers between 1 and 1 is.
Obviously, {1} is an independent set, and so the maximal independent set
82 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

contains a single element. What about the numbers between 1 and 2? The
set {1, 2} is not independent (2 is divisible by 1), and so we can take only {1}
or {2} — in this case, as well, the maximal size of the independent set is 1.
Between 1 and 3? The set {2, 3} is independent, and contains two elements.
Between 1 and 4: the set {3, 4} is independent, as is {2, 3}, and there is no
independent set with 3 of these four numbers; so in this case, the answer is
2. Now let us skip to 10: the set {6, 7, 8, 9, 10} is independent, as are {5,
6, 7, 8, 9} and {4, 5, 6, 7, 9}, each of which has 5 elements. A simple check
shows that there is no independent set of size larger than 5.
By these examples, if n is even, then the maximal size of an independent
set of numbers between 1 and n is half of n. If n is odd, then the maximal
size is half of n + 1. For example, it is easy to find an independent set of 50
numbers between 1 and 100: {51, 52, 53, . . . , 99, 100} or {49, 50, 51, . . . , 98,
99}. And indeed, there is no independent set of size larger than 50. Here is
an elegant argument showing this. We shall prove that a set with 51 elements
is necessarily not independent. Formally:

A set of 51 numbers between 1 and 100 necessarily contains two


numbers, such that the smaller of them divides the larger.

The proof makes use of the pigeonhole principle. As always, the trick is
in defining the cells. Between 1 and 100 there are 50 odd numbers, and for
each of them we will define a “cell,” namely a set of numbers.
The first cell consists of 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64 — all powers of 2 below 100.
The second cell is 3, 6, 12, 24, 48, 96 — all multiples of 3 by powers of 2
(again, below 100).
The third cell is 5, 10, 20, 40, 80 — the multiples of 5 by powers of 2.
The fourth cell is 7, 14, 28, 56 — the multiples of 7 by powers of 2.
The cell corresponding to a given odd number will consist of the odd
number times all powers of 2 (namely, times 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, . . .). For example,
the cell for the number 3 will include the numbers 3×1 = 3, 3×2 = 6, 3×4 =
12, 3 × 8 = 24, 3 × 16 = 48, and 3 × 32 = 96. (We aren’t going beyond 100.)
The cell for 25 contains the numbers 25, 50, and 100; and the cell for 49
contains only two numbers: 49 itself, and 98 (multiplying by 4 already takes
us beyond 100.) So our cells look like this:
1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64 (the multiple of 1 by powers of 2)
3, 6, 12, 24, 48, 96 (the multiples of 3 by powers of 2)
5, 10, 20, 40, 80 (the multiples of 5 by powers of 2)
7, 14, 28, 56 (the multiples of 7 by powers of 2). . .
The Power of the Oblique 83

There are 50 odd numbers up to 100, so there are 50 cells. And every
number between 1 and 100 appears in one of them. As an example, which
cell contains 92? Divide 92 by 2, and we have 46, which is even, so we can
divide it again by 2 and get 23, which is odd. So, 92 = 23 × 22 , and therefore
92 appears in the cell of 23.
Recall what is our aim: we want to show that among any 51 numbers no
larger than 100 there is one that divides another. The 51 numbers go into
50 cells, and by the pigeonhole principle, two of them belong to the same
cell. But if two numbers belong to the same cell, the larger number will be
divisible by the smaller. For example, the numbers 12 and 96 belong to the
same cell, because 12 = 3 × 22 = 3 × 4 and 96 = 3 × 25 = 3 × 32. Since
4 divides 32, also 12 divides 96.

Co-prime numbers

The great Hungarian mathematician Paul Erdő s was told about a child
prodigy, Lajos Pósa, who already knew higher mathematics at the age of
twelve. Erdő s invited the young Pósa to a restaurant and asked him: “Prove
that, in any set of 51 numbers between 1 and 100, there are two co-prime
numbers.” (Two numbers are called “co-prime” if they do not have a common
divisor, apart from 1. For example, 5 and 9 are not divisible by any number
larger than 1, so they are co-prime, while 9 and 12 have 3 as a common
divisor, and therefore are not co-prime.) Pósa raised his head from his soup
bowl and said: “In a set of 51 numbers between 1 and 100 there are two
consecutive numbers.” Naturally, two consecutive numbers are co-prime. If,
for example, the smaller number is divisible by 3, the next one (the number
+1) is not.
Here, too, the pigeonhole principle is at work. The simplest way of proving
that there are two consecutive numbers among 51 numbers between 1 and
100 is to divide the numbers into 50 cells of consecutive pairs: {1, 2}, {3, 4},
{5, 6}, . . . , {99, 100}. Of the 51 numbers in this set, 2 will have to belong
to the same cell, meaning that they are consecutive.
Pósa left mathematical research at a young age. Erdő s used to refer to
mathematicians that abandoned research as “dead.” But Pósa is very much
alive: he devoted his life to the cultivation of gifted children, and produced
generations of bright mathematicians.
Compression

One merit of poetry few will deny:


it says more and in fewer words than prose.

Voltaire, French author and philosopher, 1694–1778

One merit of mathematics few will deny: it says


more in fewer words than any other science.

David Eugene Smith

I have no time for a short letter,


so I am writing you a long one.

Blaise Pascal, French mathematician and philosopher, 1623–1662


The German word for poetry is Dichtung, meaning “compression.” A short
poem can contain a whole world. The American poet Ezra Pound said that
“Great literature is simply language charged with meaning to the utmost
possible degree.” Compression is one of the poem’s magician tricks. When
many ideas are presented together, we do not follow all that is happening.
Things happen too fast to be consciously registered.
Any poem can serve as an example. The choice I made, “Smells,” is
tribute to a forgotten poet. Noah Stern was born in 1912 in Lithuania,
studied in the United States, and immigrated to Palestine in the 1940s. He
published very little — his only collection of poems appeared after his death.
He led a tormented life, served five years in jail for a murder attempt, and
eventually committed suicide in 1960.

The lilac that grows in secret


The lilac that grows silently blue somewhere
Reminded me of illusions on one continent.
And disappointments on another.

85
86 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

But the heavy smells of oranges


Already come to pleasure and to torture,
Already come to give and to choke, as witnesses
Of life in this homeland.

“Smells,” from Among the Clouds, Noah Stern

The Russian novelist Vladimir Nabokov said that smells are cloth hangers
for memories. The two smells evoke worlds of emotions. A lot is compressed
into the contrasts between the delicate, stealthy smell of the lilac and its
dim blue color, and the heavy smell of the oranges and the blinding light
of the southern country. The oranges give, like a mother’s breasts, but also
choke. Another expression of the poet’s ambivalence towards his homeland
is in the paradoxical wording “this homeland,” as if there may be more than
one homeland.
Compression is the secret of all art. It is compression that enables us
to return again and again to the same work of art, finding something new
at each visit. We are never tired of it, because so much is happening that
we never understand it in full. The haiku poet Matsuo Basho (1644–1694)
claimed that “a good haiku poem reveals only part of itself. We will never
grow tired of a poem that reveals only half of itself.” It should come as
no surprise that lengthy books have been written on poems of only a few
lines, or that thousands of words have been written on each note written by
Beethoven.
But isn’t this a case of “the eye of the beholder”? Does a poem or sonata
really contain so much, or are their interpreters simply being inventive? A
poem or sonata might be written very quickly. Even Beethoven, who was
known for his countless drafts, wrote his sonatas in much less time than
has been devoted to their analysis. Did so much really occur in his mind?
The answer is a resounding yes — not only because he was Beethoven, but
because our minds work much faster than we imagine. A short dream is
capable of containing an entire world; every thought is the result of a complex
process.

Why don’t people understand mathematics?

I have been giving this lecture to first-year classes for over


twenty-five years. You’d think they begin to understand it by now.

John Littlewood, English mathematician, 1885–1977


Compression 87

We still have not touched upon the best-known, and most deterring, quality
shared by mathematics and poetry: their difficulty. Both poetry and mathe-
matics are hard to understand. The reason for students’ difficulties is almost
always the same: the teacher doesn’t say all that he knows. He skips things.
Even if he is aware of everything that came before, he doesn’t have the time
to spell them all out.
Conveying a lot of information in a single statement is what compression
is all about. And it is this type of compression that is responsible for the dif-
ficulty in understanding poetry and mathematics. But there is a significant
difference between the two: the compression in mathematics is vertical, while
poetical compression is horizontal. In other words, in mathematics many
stages, built like floors one upon the other, are hidden within a single state-
ment. In poetry, many distinct ideas, not necessarily hierarchically ordered,
are compressed into one expression. This is why the vague understanding
of poetry causes no harm, while a hazy comprehension of mathematics gets
back at us in a later stage, when the next floor is built.
Mathematical Ping-Pong

“How to solve it”

Gauss is like a fox who effaces his


tracks in the sand with his tail.

Niels Abel, Norwegian mathematician, 1802–1829

Why is it so hard to understand mathematics?


Because mathematicians think in examples,
but tell you the abstractions.

Anonymous
How do mathematicians think? Unfortunately, or perhaps fortunately, there
is no recipe for this. A well-known book by George Polya, How to Solve It,
describes thought strategies for solving mathematical problems. Although
the book is replete with telling insights, reading it does not guarantee success
in problem solving. The way to learn problem solving is not to read how
others solved problems, but to solve them yourself.
Even though there is no magic formula, a basic trait of mathematical
thought can nevertheless be put in words: it is conducted like a ping-pong
game between examples and generalizations, between the tangible and the
abstract. From examples we build generalizations, that, in the next phase,
are confronted with other examples, which in turn lead to more accurate
generalizations. This ping-pong game is not symmetrical, since shots in one
direction — the abstract — involve magic, while the shots in the opposite
direction — the examples — are more down-to-earth. There is no recipe
for the generalization step. This is where we need illumination, the sudden
discovery of hidden order in the world. In other words, this is where the
beauty of mathematics is revealed.
Perhaps not surprisingly, the exact same can be said for poetry. There,
too, a continuous ping-pong game is conducted between the concrete and

89
90 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the abstract. But there is a basic difference: in poetry the game is held
within the poem itself. The abstract and the concrete coexist in the same
lines. In mathematics, in contrast, we see only the results: the game is
already over. It was there only at the stage of the struggle with the solu-
tion. The last shot in the solution is toward the abstract, and this is
all that we, the spectators, see. The reader is like someone who is late
for a play, arriving only for the last scene, after most of the charac-
ters have already made their exit. This is Abel’s complaint against Gauss
in the first quotation, and this is the anonymous student’s complaint in
the other.
So, in order to watch the ping-pong game of mathematical thought, we
have to seize the moment. As an example, let me tell you how a sixteen
year old discovered the formula for the sum of a geometric series. In the
next chapter, we will give it a short and elegant solution. The high school
student’s method was a bit less elegant, but it is a fine example of the phases
of mathematical inquiry, and provides a glimpse into the way mathemati-
cians think.

The sum of a geometrical series

There are two common types of sequences: arithmetic sequences, in which


each term is larger (or smaller) than its predecessor by a fixed number; and
geometric sequences, in which each term is larger/smaller than the preced-
ing number times a fixed number, called the “quotient” of the sequence.
The origin of this name is that each term is the geometric mean of its two
neighbors, meaning that its square is equal to the product of its neighbors.
For example, in the sequence 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64, that has quotient 2 the term,
4 is situated between 2 and 8, and 42 = 2 × 8. In the chapter “Invention or
Discovery” we learnt a formula for the sum of an arithmetic sequence (when
we sum the elements we actually call it a “series”). There is also a formula for
the sum of a geometric series, and I tried to lead the student to discover this
formula.
I showed him the sequence 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64, . . . , 1024, and asked him
what was its rule, which he quickly found: each term is twice as large as its
predecessor. I asked him if he could calculate the sum of the series, that is,
2+4+8+16+32+64+128+256+512+1024. The student was familiar with the
formula for the sum of an arithmetic series, and tried the idea that worked
there: finding the arithmetic mean of the terms (in an arithmetic sequence,
the trick is that the mean is in the middle between the first and last terms).
Mathematical Ping-Pong 91

He understood right away that this would not work here. In contrast with an
arithmetic sequence, the middle between the first and last terms (between 2
and 1024) is not the arithmetic average of the terms of the sequence, since,
for example, it is not equal to the middle between the second and the next
to last terms (between 4 and 512). Another idea is needed.

A conceptual leap

I expected the student to try small examples. I thought that he would calcu-
late the sums 2 + 4, 2 + 4 + 8, and so on, and find the regularity. But he sur-
prised me with a true insight, made of the material from which mathematical
discoveries are forged. “Let us look at the sum in the reverse order,” he sug-
gested. Like this: 1024+512+256+128+64+32+16+8+4+2. “This is about
2048,” he said (as usually happens at the beginning of a solution, things
were still hazy in his mind). That is, about twice the first term (1024). Why?
Because the addition of every term in the series halves the distance of the sum
from 2048. We start with a sum of 0 (that is, our shopping cart was empty),
and its distance from 2048 is, simply, 2048; the first term (1024) is half of
this, and so after its addition, the distance to 2048 will be 1024, which is
half the previous distance; 512 is half of the distance between 1024 and 2048,
and after its addition, the distance between it and 2048 is 512 — again, half
the previous distance. I think that the student had the following picture in
his mind:

The length of the entire “rod” is 2048. Starting at the left, each step takes us half of the
distance to the right end of the rod. In each phase, the distance from 2048 is the same as
the size of the last step that we took.

At each step, the distance from 2048 is the same as the term that we just
added. Now the student was already capable of calculating the exact sum.
The distance of 1024 + 512 + 256 + 128 + 64 + 32 + 16 + 8 + 4 + 2 from 2048
is the last term, that is, 2. Consequently, the sum equals 2048 – 2, namely
twice the first term in the series (1024), minus the last term (2).
The student found here the formula for the sum of a geometric series
with a quotient of 2: the sum is twice the last term, minus the first term.
In a formula, the sum is 2an − a1 , with the terms of the series labeled as
a1 , a2 , a3 , an . . . . This is the accepted notation for series: the first term is
labeled as a1 , the second as a2 ; and in general, the n-th term is denoted
92 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

as an . I asked the student to check the formula himself, by examining the


simplest example: what happens in a series with a single term? In this case,
n = 1, and the entire series consists of a1 , which is both the first and last
term. Using the formula that we found, the sum is 2a1 − a1 = a1 , which is
indeed the sum of the series consisting of a single element.

One more step

Next we moved on to a geometric series with a quotient of 3. For example,


what is the sum of the sequence 10 + 30 + 90 + 270 + 810, in which the
quotient is 3, that is, each term is 3 times as large as the preceding one? The
student tried his powers of generalization. If when the quotient is 2 the sum is
2an −a1 , then when the quotient is 3 the sum should be 3an −a1 , that is, three
times the last term minus the first term. This is a smart guess, that even an
experienced researcher would have made. I asked him to check an example.
He wanted to take the example I had given him (10 + 30 + 90 + 270 + 810),
but I encouraged him to use a simpler example. He looked at a sequence with
a single term — 10 (Remember the rule? There is no such thing as a too
simple example). Its sum is, obviously, 10, while, according to the formula
that he had guessed (3an − a1 ), the sum should have been (3 × 10) − 10 = 20
(in this case, the last term, 10, is also the first). So, the formula he guessed
does not work. The student wanted to abandon this line of thought, but I
came to his aid here. It was probably not by chance that 2 appeared in the
formula when 2 was the quotient. I encouraged him to try and compare the
results of his guesswork formula (3an − a1 ) with the actual sums, in several
examples. Take the sequence 10 + 30 + 90 + 270 + 810, and sum up its initial
terms:

The real sum The sum given by the false formula


10 + 30 = 40 3 × 30 − 10 = 80
10 + 30 + 90 = 130 3 × 90 − 10 = 260

These sufficed for the student to discover the law: the formula that he
had guessed gives twice as much as the truth. He must divide his formula
by 2. And indeed, the formula for the sum is 3an2−a1 . A quick check with
several examples showed the student that this indeed works.
Mathematical Ping-Pong 93

Generalization

Now it is a short way to the formula for the sum of a geometric series with
general quotient q. If, when the quotient is 3, the formula is 3an2−a1 , then
when the quotient is q, the formula has to be qaq−1 n −a1
(presumably the 2 in
3an −a1
the denominator of the formula 2 is q − 1, putting q = 3). For q = 2 we
get 2a2−1
n −a1
. But 2 − 1 = 1, and division by 1 doesn’t alter the number, so the
formula gives 2an − a1 , fitting the formula we found before. This explains
the student’s wrong guess: in the case q = 2 the denominator was hiding.
It was hard to guess that there is a 1 in the denominator, which is actually
2 − 1.
I then gave the student an additional example in which he could easily
check the formula: 1+10+100+1000+10,000. Here q = 10, and according to
the formula that we discovered, the sum is 10×10000−19 = 99,999 : 9 = 11,111.
Look at the sum and see why this is obvious.

Formal proof

A guess is not enough. We should prove it formally. At this point the student
exhibited surprising mathematical maturity. For the proof, he told me, we
need a formula for the terms of the sequence. This is not hard. If the first
term is a1 , and the second is q times bigger, then the second term is a1 q.
Similarly, the third term is the second term times q, namely, a1 q 2 ; and the
fourth is a1 q 3 . In general, the kth term is a1 q k−1 . If there are n terms in
the sequence, then the last term is a1 q n−1 , and the sum of the terms in the
sequence is a1 +a1 q +a1 q 2 +· · ·+a1 q n−1 . Our guess is that this sum is qaq−1
n −a1
.
qa1 q n−1 −a1 a1 q n −a1 n
Since an = a1 q n−1 this is in fact q−1 , which is q−1 = a1 qq−1
−1
. We
therefore have to prove:
qn − 1
a1 + a1 q + a1 q 2 + · · · + a1 q n−1 = a1
q−1
Division of both sides of the equation by a1 produces the equivalent formula:
qn − 1
(∗) 1 + q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 =
q−1
94 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Equality (*) can be proved by multiplying both sides by q − 1. The left side
will then be: (q − 1) × (1 + q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 ), which equals
q × (1 + q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 ) − (1 + q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 )
which, in turn, is q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 + q n − (1 + q + q 2 + · · · + q n−1 ). In
this sum, almost everything cancels out, leaving only q n − 1. Note now that
multiplying the right side of equation (*) by q − 1 produces q n − 1, so indeed
equality occurs in (*).
The Book in Heaven

Why are numbers beautiful? It is like asking


why is Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony beautiful.

Paul Erdő s, mathematician

We have already met the Hungarian mathematician Paul Erdő s (1913–


1996). He became a legend in his own time, not only because he was a
great mathematician, but also because of his unique lifestyle. He personi-
fied the image of the mathematician as detached from reality. He lived and
breathed mathematics, and his interest in real life was limited and abstract.
He traveled with only a light leather bag in his hand, relying on his hosts
for all things material. Watching a movie, he incessantly bothered his neigh-
bors: “What are they doing there [on the screen]?” He was very fond of
writing letters, that usually began with sentences like “Let n be a natural
number . . . .”
Erdő s’ style of working, too, was unique. He would usually collaborate
with his hosts on his many trips. Later in life, when he returned to Hungary
after many years of self-imposed exile, he would work with the pilgrims to his
mathematical shrine in the flat allotted to him in Budapest by the Hungarian
Academy. He had more research partners than any other mathematician in
history. Erdő s preferred to think about elementary problems, and his great-
ness was in his ability to understand the profundity concealed in apparently
simple problems. One of his earlier big achievements was an elementary proof
for the Prime Numbers Theorem. As mentioned in the chapter “Simple Con-
jectures, Complex Proofs,” this theorem had already been proved some 60
years earlier by Jacques Hadamard and Louis de la Vallée-Poussin, employ-
ing advanced means. An elementary proof was for many years a holy grail
for mathematicians. But instead of making him happy, the discovey caused
Erdő s much heartache. He proved the theorem in cooperation with a Nor-
wegian mathematician, Atle Selberg, and as was his custom, he immediately
told the entire world of it. This led Selberg to (erroneously) believe that

95
96 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Erdő s was trying to claim the credit for himself. Echoes of the quarrel that
erupted between the two reverberate to this very day.
Erdő s had his own private language, with a special vocabulary. He called
women “bosses,” and men “slaves”; children were “epsilons” (after the Greek
letter used in differential calculus to mark small numbers). Whenever he met
a small child, he would ask for his age, show him a coin trick, and then move
on to higher spheres. As someone who was born into the First World War and
witnessed the horrors of the Second World War, he called God the “Supreme
Fascist.”

A proof from the book for the sum of a geometric series

Erdő s used to talk about “the book in heaven,” which includes all the math-
ematical theorems, each with its most elegant proof. Being “from the Book”
is the greatest compliment a mathematical proof can receive. A friend of
mine, who discovered such a proof, made a wise remark following his dis-
covery: proofs from the Book aren’t always born as such. They rarely spring
from the forehead of their inventors in their full beauty. They often require
elaboration to become pearls.
In the last chapter I described the process experienced by a student who
discovered the formula for the sum of a geometric sequence. This was a
prolonged process, and the proof was not particularly elegant. Here is the
proof, after polishing.

Recall that we have to calculate the sum a1 + a1 q + a1 q 2 + · · · + a1 q n−1 .

Call this sum S. The secret is that multiplying the sum by q gives almost
the same sum. Multiplied by q, every term becomes the next term — except,
of course, for the last term, that does not have a next term. So, qS is
almost S. What is the difference? qS has an extra term a1 q n , the last term
after multiplication by q; and it lacks the first term, a1 .
The Book in Heaven 97

So, qS = S + a1 q n − a1 . This is an equation with S as unknown. To solve


it, shuffle terms: qS − S = a1 q n − a1 , or: S(q − 1) = a1 (q n − 1), and dividing
by q − 1 we get: S = a1 (a −1)
n

q−1 . This is the desired formula.

Paul Erdő s, Hungarian and citizen of the world (1913–1996).


Poetical Ping-Pong

In the pingpong of questions and answers


not a sound was heard
except:
ping ... pong ...

Yehuda Amichai, “The Visit of the Queen of Sheba,”


Two Hopes Distant, trans. by Chana Bloch and Stephen Mitchell

Poetry is the other domain in which the play between the abstract and
the concrete is essential. Like mathematics, poetry is an ongoing dialogue
between individual instances and generalizations, between the tangible and
the abstract, the low and the high. Metaphor, for example, is such a game:
from the individual to the general, and back. The poet thinks of something
specific, say, his lover’s eyes. In his excitement, he wishes to give this a more
general dimension, and he thinks about the general characteristics of eyes:
softness, or their shape. In the next step, he returns to something else that is
worldly, which has similar qualities: “Your eyes are doves.” Note that the last
shot in this game is in the direction of the tangible. This is a general feature
of the poetical ping-pong: the heart of the poem is given to the concrete,
and it is in this direction that the poem goes. This is the diametric opposite
of the ping-pong of mathematics, in which the last shot is always toward the
abstract.
As in mathematics, in poetry, too, the shots and their returns are so
fast that in order to follow them we must freeze the moment and look at
the game in slow motion. As an example, let us take Amichai’s poem from
which the quotation at the beginning of this section was taken. The poem
is based on the legend in which King Solomon and the Queen of Sheba pose
mental challenges to each other. For Amichai, these are the hide-and-seek
games of lovers, that substitute for the real thing. Towards the end of the
poem, however, the metaphor dissolves. The disintegration of the symbolism
mirrors the breakdown of the lovers when the time comes to depart.

99
100 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

All the word games


lay scattered out of their boxes.
Boxes were left gaping
after the game.

Sawdust of questions,
shells of cracked parables,
wooly packing materials from
crates of fragile riddles.

Heavy wrapping paper


of love and strategies.
Used solutions rustled
in the trash of thinking.

Long problems
were rolled up on spools,
magician’s tricks were locked in their cages.
Chess horses were led back to the stable.
Yehuda Amichai, “The Visit of the Queen of Sheba,”
trans. by Chana Bloch and Stephen Mitchell
The depiction of the games as shells transmits a sense of missed opportu-
nity — the two protagonists themselves wanted something beyond the shell,
but they did not reach it.

Concealed ping-pong

One of the most powerful poems on the Holocaust was written by Dan Pagis,
a survivor:
Here in this carload
I am Eve
with my son Abel
if you see my older boy
Cain son of Adam
Tell him that I . . .
Dan Pagis, “Written in Pencil in the Sealed
Railway-Car,” Transformation, trans. Stephen Mitchell
One source of the poem’s force is obvious — the nonstatement at its
end, that leaves the reader hanging in air, and compels him to return
Poetical Ping-Pong 101

to the poem’s beginning. But the real strength of the poem lies in
something else, less evident: the play between the abstract and the con-
crete. In these six short lines there are at least three transitions in each
direction.
The poem begins with the tangible. It tells of a particular woman, in a
railroad car that is not all cars, but a special one. Even the poem’s title
attempts to convey this, by insisting on the detail of the writing imple-
ment. We are so drawn to the woman in the car that we tend to forget the
metaphoric nature of her name. And yet, the poem is not only about the suf-
fering of this specific woman, and the poet gives her a name that represents
all women, with her son who represents all children.
From this generalization the poem returns to the concrete: “if you see
my older boy” — a simple, down-to-earth expression, the way a real mother
would talk about her son. These words allude to the unbelievable — Eve
still relates to Cain as a son, and even a beloved son. Poetry, as we know,
can bear unresolved contradictions.
At this juncture the concrete use of the word “son” is replaced by an
abstract meaning, as part of the wording “son of Adam” (the Hebrew, ben
adam, also means a human being, and especially, a decent human being).
This is obviously ironic — the last thing anyone could say about Cain is
that he was a decent human being. But alongside the abstract sense, the
words “son of Adam” also have a concrete meaning. Pagis reminds us that
the metaphoric “son of Adam” had a concrete source — there actually was
a person who was Adam’s son. In poetry research this maneuver is called
“metaphor reification” or “concretization.”
This, however, is not the end of the ping-pong game, since the words
“son of Adam” have an additional meaning: “You are your father’s son, not
mine.” Couples sometimes joke — “see what your son has been up to.” But
Eve says this in all seriousness, as an actual statement of fact — the last
move in the ping-pong game.
Laws of Conservation

You better cut the pizza in four pieces because


I’m not hungry enough to eat six.

Yogi Berra, baseball player

A law of conservation states that something — quantity, size, or ratio —


is preserved, even when other factors in the picture change. For example, if
you move the chair on which you are sitting, its position will change, but not
the relations between its parts, and it will remain a chair. Thanks to simple
laws of conservation like this, we can relate to the world in constant terms.
There are more abstract laws of conservation, such as the conservation of
number: if you take 4 stones and arrange them in a row, and then rearrange
them in a square, their number will not change. Even more abstract is the
conservation of matter. In a famous experiment the Swiss psychologist Jean
Piaget (1896–1980) transferred a liquid from a wide container to a narrow
one. Naturally, the liquid was higher in the narrow vessel, and when small
children were asked if the quantity of the liquid changed, they answered: yes,
there is more now, even though the liquid was poured from one vessel to the
other before their very eyes.
The best-known laws of conversation are those in physics: the conserva-
tion of mass, energy, momentum (the product mass × velocity), and angular
momentum. Elegant solutions can be found for many problems in physics
using these laws. A less-known fact is that laws of conservation are used in
mathematics as well. The difference is that the conserved elements are less
tangible, which makes the laws even more beautiful.
Conservation laws usually not regarded as such are the rules for expanding
or reducing fractions. Take a cake, and divide it into two halves. Unlike what
Yogi Berra thought, the total quantity of the cake does not change, and we
still have one cake. This means that 1 (one cake) is equal to 2 halves, or in
numerical formulation: 1 = 22 . Similarly, if we take 23 of a cake and divide
each of the two thirds into 5 pieces, the quantity of cake will remain the

103
104 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

1
same. But now each third has become 5 pieces, each of which is 15 th of the
cake. In other words, the two thirds together consist of 10 fifteenths, and so
we have 23 = 10
15 .

How to become rich by using a law of conservation

The American Sam Lloyd (1841–1911) was one of the most ingenious puzzle
creators of all times. He composed chess puzzles and mathematics puzzles,
was an amateur magician and a professional ventriloquist, and included ven-
triloquism in his magic acts. His son would “read” his thoughts, when it was
Lloyd himself speaking through his son’s mouth. In 1875 he composed (some
say, borrowed from another source) his most famous puzzle, the “15 puzzle,”
that is still popular today. It consists of a square with 16 smaller squares, on
15 of which are pieces bearing the numbers 1 through 15, with one square
remaining empty. A piece can be moved to the empty square if it adjoins the
empty square, that is, if it is alongside, above, or below the empty square.
The puzzle is usually played by sliding the squares around, and trying to
arrange them in order by a sequence of legal moves.
In order to boost sales, Lloyd offered a prize of $1000 (which was a con-
siderable sum in those days, but not enough to arouse suspicion) to anyone
who could exchange the places of the 14 and the 15.

The original configuration

Even Lloyd himself couldn’t imagine the consequences of his challenge.


The hysteria that it set off even exceeded that which was triggered by the
Hungarian cube a century later. People left their jobs and walked around
in the street with the game in their hands. In France, a law was enacted
forbidding playing the game at work. Lloyd became rich, without risking a
Laws of Conservation 105

The desired configuration

cent, because he knew that the task was impossible. In the nineteenth century
news didn’t spread as fast as they do in the internet age. For some reason, no
reporter thought to interview mathematicians, and much time passed before
people learned of the impossibility of meeting Lloyd’s challenge.
Before I prove this, I’ll announce a similar competition for the readers of
this book, a scaled-down version of Lloyd’s challenge. Start with the num-
ber 1, and at each move add or subtract the product of two consecutive
numbers. Anyone who manages to arrive at the number 10 will receive a
prize of $100.

Example:

As a first move, we could add to 1 the number 6, which is the


product of two consecutive numbers: 2×3. Now we have the number
1 + 6, that is 7. Now we can add, say, 20, which is 4 × 5 (another
product of two consecutive numbers), for a new sum of 27. We
can now, for example, subtract 12, which is the product of two
consecutive numbers (3 × 4), giving 15.

Could a better selection of moves reach 10? The answer is no, and my
$100 prize money is safe. Winning this game is impossible because of a law of
conservation: what is conserved here is the parity of the number. It always
remains odd. This is because the product of two consecutive numbers is
always even, since one of the two numbers is even. We started with 1, an
odd number, and we add or subtract even numbers. When an even number
is added to or subtracted from an odd number, the result is still odd. This
is why we will not reach 10, that is even.
106 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Something similar is at work in Lloyd’s game. There, too, a number is


associated with every state of the board that remains odd throughout the
game; while the number linked to the state in Lloyd’s challenge (the switch-
ing of the 14 and the 15) is even. Therefore, Lloyd’s money remained safe.
The difference between Lloyd’s challenge and the one I posed earlier on is
that Lloyd’s number is more hidden. His number was the number of order
changes of pairs of pieces (I’ll immediately explain the meaning of this term).
Let us move along the board in a certain order, as in the next drawing:

Even after the pieces have been moved, we will always go over them in
the order dictated by the arrow. As can be seen from the drawing, when we
go along the arrow we pass through the numbers in the following order: 1, 2,
3, 4, 8, 7, 6, 5, 9, 10, 11, 12, 15, 14, 13. An “order change” means a pair of
numbers that is not in the right order. 3 and 10, for example, are in the right
order in this sequence: 3 appears before 10, as in their regular order. But
between 5 and 8, for example, there is an order change. In this sequence, 8
appears before 5, while the normal order calls for 8 to follow 5. In the wiggly
sequence 15 appears before 14 — not the normal order between them, so
here is another order change. How many order changes are there in this
sequence in all? I’ll list the number pairs in this sequence that are not in the
right order — see if I’ve listed them all: (7, 8),(6, 8),(5, 8),(6, 7),(5, 7),(5, 6),
(14, 15),(13, 15),(13, 14). There are 9 pairs, and so, in the original situation,
there are 9 order changes of number pairs (as always, when following the
arrow). In the desired situation, in which the 14 and the 15 change places,
there is one less order change, since the (14, 15) pair is in the correct order
(look at the arrow, and you’ll understand why this is so). This leaves 8 order
changes in the desired situation. The secret here is that the number of order
changes remains odd, all the time, and therefore this situation — in which
there are 8 order changes (an even number) — can never be attained.
Laws of Conservation 107

Why does the number of order changes always remain odd? For the exact
same reason that the number in the competition I suggested above remains
odd: each move adds or subtracts an even number of order changes. Look
for example at the following move:

This move does not add any order change, and does not remove any order
change. For example, 12 appears before 13 in the wiggly order before this
move, as it does after this move. And this is true for all other pairs. Simply,
the order of the squares along the wiggly line hasn’t changed.
Here is another example:

The move in the drawing alters the order changes of 5 only with the
numbers 6, 7, 8, and 1. It adds 3 order changes (5 becomes out of order
with 6, 7, and 8) and subtracts 1 order change (after the move, 5 is in order
with 1, while before this move it was out of order with 1). So this move
adds 3 − 1 = 2 order changes. This is a typical example: in each move,
the number of squares with which the moving square changes order along
the wiggly line is 0, 2, 4 or 6. So, an even number of order changes will
be added or subtracted. This means that if, in the starting position, the
108 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

number of order changes was odd (to be precise, 9), then it will remain so
throughout the game. Consequently, not only is it impossible to attain the
state that Lloyd sought — any state with an even number of order changes
is an impossibility.

Conservation of inner truth

In many Greek tragedies the hero tries to escape his fate, only to realize that
it pursues him. The best-known tragedy in which this happens is Oedipus
Rex by Sophocles. Oedipus, the young prince of the city of Corinth, hears
a prophecy that he will kill his father and marry his mother. Horrified, he
decides to flee the city. On his journeys, he meets a man at a crossroads
and kills him in a fight. After this, he come to the city of Thebes, and at
the gate of the city he learns of a monster, the Sphinx, with the head of
a human and the body of a beast, who takes her toll on the city’s inhabi-
tants. The curse of the monster will not be lifted until the riddle she poses
will be solved. Oedipus solves the riddle, and the grateful people of the
city marry him to Jocasta, the widowed queen. Years later, when a plague
rages unchecked in Thebes, and the oracle claims that Oedipus himself is
responsible for this calamity, the truth is revealed to the king: he was a
foundling, and his mother Jocasta had given him to a shepherd to raise,
after she had heard the oracles utter the exact same prophecy that Oedipus
had heard; and the person he had killed at the crossroads was his biological
father.
Modern thought would view fate as symbolizing inner forces and wishes.
Constantine Cavafy, the avowed Hellenist, conveys this message in many of
his poems. The best known poem with this idea is probably “The City.” It
is a poem of “conservation of inner truth.” External circumstances, it says,
are not as important as who you really are.

You said, “I will go to another land,


I will go to another sea.
Another city will be found, better than this.
Every effort of mine is condemned by fate;
and my heart is — like a corpse — buried.
How long in this wasteland will my mind remain.
Wherever I turn my eyes, wherever I may like
Laws of Conservation 109

I see the black ruins of my life here,


where I spent so many years, and ruined and wasted.”

New lands you will not find,


you will not find other seas.
The city will follow you. You will roam the same
streets. And you will age in the same neighborhoods;
in these same houses you will grow gray.
Always you will arrive in this city.
To another land — do not hope —
there is no ship for you, there is no road.
As you scattered your days
you threw them away in the whole world, upon all seas.
Constantine Cavafy, “The City”
Cavafy lived from 1863 to 1933 in Alexandria, far from European culture
centers. He was gay, worked as a civil servant, wrote in Greek, and gained
his fame only after his death. But all these details tell us less than we can
learn from this poem.
What makes this poem so beautiful? It is not the content, that is not
new, but the way it is conveyed. Paradoxically, the message on the power
of inner forces is expressed externally. Not “you will remain you,” but “the
streets will remain the same streets”; not “you cannot flee from yourself,”
but “the city will follow you”; not “it doesn’t matter where you will be,”
but “in these same houses you will grow gray.”

Constantine Cavafy (1863–1933), a Greek poet who lived in Alexandria.


An Idea from Somewhere Else

It can’t be denied
Without symbols and simile there is no poem.

Nathan Alterman, “Footnote Poem,” Summer Festival

The metaphor

Sometimes, when a description of a missing person is broadcast, I wonder


why they bother. A description like “thin, short, athletic build, blue eyes,
gray hair, thin nose, about sixty years old,” is not really helpful. Except in
cases of a peculiar characteristic, it is very difficult to identity a person on
the basis of verbal description. If, however, the description were to state:
“the missing person resembles President Bush Jr.,” the chances of a positive
identification will soar. A single key opens a door that remained closed to a
pile of words.
What is the secret? In our minds we have a complete, ready-made picture
of George W. Bush’s appearance. Its reconstruction by breaking it into small
details resembles moving a building brick by brick. If, instead, we move it en
bloc, in all its detail, we can save much effort. Similarity to another person
enables us to transmit a person’s appearance without having to break it
down into details. And this is not the only advantage: most of a person’s
facial features are too subtle to be transmitted in words. In other words, it is
not always possible to even transfer the bricks. Some things can be conveyed
only by analogy.
This is one of the two components of the best-known poetical device,
metaphor. In Greek it means to transfer from another place. To describe a
certain situation, we borrow the pattern of another, usually more familiar,
situation. This is a powerful tool for transmitting information. So much so,
that it is constantly used in everyday language. Our daily speech is saturated
by metaphors, such as “it fell into my lap,” or “a heart of gold.” Even
“saturated with metaphors” is itself a metaphor. See how much information

111
112 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

is compressed into a single word: the feeling that, just as water saturates the
soil, metaphors are everywhere; that just as the water is inseparable from
the earth, so metaphors are so much absorbed in ordinary speech that we do
not even notice them. Just as resemblance between people is so effective for
description, a metaphor is capable of transmitting ideas that regular words
cannot. Thomas Ernest Hulme, a British poetry researcher and poet (and a
mathematician by education) who was killed in the First World War, claimed
that “plain speech is essentially inaccurate. It is only by new metaphors, that
is, by fancy, that it can be made precise.” The features of the mold that is
transmitted are sometimes too subtle to be transmitted in any other way.
This explains the prevalence of metaphor in poetry. Here, for example, is
a metaphor from “In the Twilight” by Hayyim Nahman Bialik, the Israeli
national poet:

We were left with no friend or fellow


like two flowers in the desert.
Hayyim Nahman Bialik, “In Twilight”
An entire world is conveyed by a single brushstroke (here is another
metaphor). The single line “like two flowers in the desert” communicates
the sense of loneliness: the thirst for love; the lovers seeing no one except
each other; their vulnerability; the contrast between their attitude to the
world and their feelings for each other — and I certainly missed many other
meanings. The desert is something familiar, and arouses in us a rich range
of emotions and associations, and so a small tableau succeeds in conveying
more than would many abstract adjectives. Here is poignant metaphor from
the same poet:

One by one, with none to see, like stars towards dawn,


My secret desires vanished.
Hayyim Nahman Bialik, “One by One, with None to See”
Is there a more effective way of portraying how a person’s childhood desires
disappear during the course of his life, without his being able to point to
the moment when this happened, than a comparison with the stars that
disappear in the morning? The special beauty of this metaphor is also due
to its revealing something about the image used. The unexpected awareness
of the difficulty in discerning just when the stars vanish at daybreak is in
itself beautiful. And the effect of the beauty of two truths revealed together
is greater than the sum of the two separate effects.
An Idea from Somewhere Else 113

But the metaphor would not have won its special standing if this was its
only power. The true secret of its force lies in its being on both sides of the
fence at the same time: it is an effective tool for transmitting information,
and also for its concealment. It enables us to grasp matters without having
to look them in the eye. It communicates the information innocently, as if
this was about something entirely different. Some metaphors of everyday life
have a similar role. We hear, for example, of “dropping out” of school, and
we are not attentive to the poetical quality of this expression, that replaces
blunt words like “leaving” or “expulsion.”
Indirect expression has great force, no less for the writer than for the
reader. Metaphor enables the writer to penetrate within himself and wrestle
with questions which he could not confront head on. For example, poetry
was Dan Pagis’s way of contending with his childhood Holocaust memories
that he did not otherwise dare to touch.
Once I read a story
about a grasshopper one day old,
a green adventurer who at dusk
was swallowed up by a bat.

Right after this the wise old owl


gave a short consolation speech:
Bats also have the right to make a living,
and there are many grasshoppers still left.

Right after this came


the end: an empty page.

Forty years now have gone by.


Still leaning above that empty page,
I do not have the strength
to close the book.
Dan Pagis, “The Story,” Synonyms, trans. Stephen Mitchell
No reader of the last lines can leave the child-adult who faces the blank page,
a metaphor for the adult confronting the emptiness of his lost childhood. The
poem as a whole is built around the motif of entering and leaving a book.
Look, for example, at the recurring line “Right after this came.” At one point
it refers to what occurs within the story (the owl delivers a speech), while in
its next appearance, it speaks of what happens outside the narrative (the last,
and blank, page follows). This is almost a play on words — identical words
114 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

that have different meanings, in this case even of different types. Another
play of being within and without the story is the green grasshopper (patently,
green in two senses) who is a child in the story, while the most touching
element of the poem is that the one who reads the story was a child at the
time, but is no longer one, because his childhood was stolen.
An effective metaphor is always condensed, that is, there are many points
of similarity between the tenor and the vehicle (the symbolized and the
symbol). This density has an effect on both of the metaphor’s roles: the trans-
mission of information, and its concealment. On the one hand, the simulta-
neous transmission of many ideas means efficiency in communication; while
on the other hand, when much information is delivered in a single effort, we
are incapable of consciously absorbing it all, and most of its assimilation is
subliminal.
In mathematics, just as in poetry, it often happens that ideas are brought
from one realm to another. And just as an apt metaphor is finer, the more
distant its tenor and vehicle are from each other, so too in mathematics:
the solution is more elegant if the idea is brought from a more distant field.
Number theory is known for the ideas that its draws from unexpected fields:
geometry, complex numbers, differential calculus, and actually, from almost
every other discipline of mathematics. In order, however, to present examples
of this type, we must first learn of the division of mathematics into its various
subdisciplines.
Three Types of Mathematics

Modern mathematics includes dozens of fields, and hundreds of subfields.


Gauss, in the beginning of the nineteenth century, actually knew all the
mathematics of his time. Hilbert, in the twentieth century, was familiar with
all the mathematical fields of his time, even if he did not master them all.
In the twenty-first century, a mathematician knows only a tiny fraction of
the mathematics of his time. But even if mathematics has been divided into
microscopic disciplines, its main branches have remained as they were. In
this chapter I want to describe its basis division into branches.
Modern mathematics can be divided into three main branches: contin-
uous mathematics, algebra, and discrete mathematics. The division is not
exhaustive. It is difficult to exactly fit some fields, such as geometry or math-
ematical logic, into any of these categories. But it is a useful division, and
basically a correct one.

Continuous mathematics

Continuous mathematics is concerned with things that change without leaps.


Here is an example of a continuous question:

A cat and a mouse are on a round field. These are a mathematical


cat and mouse, that is, they are points. They cannot choose their
speed — they both move at the same constant speed. On the other
hand, they are free to choose the direction in which they move.
Will the cat be able to catch the mouse?

The answer, that was proved by the Russian-English mathematician


Abram Besikovitch (1891–1970), is typical of continuous mathematics. No,
the cat cannot catch the mouse. But it can approach the mouse as closely as
it wishes. In other words, if it can stretch out a paw — no matter how short
the paw is — after enough time it will succeed in reaching the mouse. But if
it doesn’t have a paw to extend, it will only be able to approach the mouse,
but not to catch it. The reason why the cat can come as close as it wants is

115
116 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

that the mouse cannot run forever in the direction opposite to the cat, since
it will run into the fence. The reason why, despite the mouse’s inability to
escape, the cat cannot catch the mouse is that when both are close to each
other it is possible for the mouse to run almost directly away from the cat.

The cat and the mouse are on a round field. They can choose the direction in which to
move, but not their speed — both move at the same speed. Will the cat be able to catch
the mouse?

“As close as we want” is the essence of continuous mathematics. The


central concept in this field is the limit, that means getting as close as you
wish. For example, take the sequence of numbers 0, 0.9, 0.99, 0.999, . . . .
None of the terms in the sequence equals 1, but they approach 1; therefore,
1 is the limit of the sequence. This means that for any measure of proximity
(the length of the paw in the cat and mouse problem), beginning at a certain
place the terms of the sequence are nearer to 1 than this measure. Beginning,
1
for example, from the fourth term, the terms are closer than 100 to 1. The
1 1 1
limit of the sequence 1, 2 , 3 , 4 . . . is 0, because, for any measure of closeness
that we use, beginning from a certain term the numbers will be closer to 0
1
than that measure. For example, if the required measure of closeness is 1000 ,
the terms of the sequence are closer to 0 than this measure from the 1001th
term.
Here is another example from continuous mathematics:

A monk starts out from the bottom of a mountain at 8 a.m. He


is making his way to the monastery, at the top of the mountain.
He doesn’t necessarily walk at a uniform pace, sometimes he walks
faster and sometimes slower. He may stop every once in a while to
Three Types of Mathematics 117

enjoy the view. He reaches the monastery at nightfall, prays, and


goes to sleep. At 8 o’clock the next morning he sets out on his way
back, on the same path, and reaches the bottom at nightfall. Prove
that there is a point on this path where the monk was at exactly
the same time on both days.

Some people, when attempting to solve this problem, become bogged


down in details: did the monk first walk slowly, and afterwards quickly? Or
the opposite? They try to guess the location of this point. But all this is
irrelevant. In order to solve the problem, we must change our perspective.
Instead of thinking of a single monk on two days, we should think of two
monks on the same day. If both set out at the same time and walk on
the same path, one ascending and the other descending, they must meet;
and “meet” means to be in the same place at the same time. This solution is
based on a theorem that is very intuitive, but nevertheless needs proof. It is
called the “mean value theorem,” and may be formulated like this: someone
who is riding in an elevator from the second shopping level of a mall to the
−2 parking level must pass through a point that is on the ground floor. This
is so, because the ride is a continuous process. If jumps were possible, that
is, if our shopper could vanish at one point and reappear at another, then
he could start at the shopping level and arrive at the parking level without
ever actually being at the ground floor level. In a continuous world, this is
impossible.

Algebra

Ask high school students what is this algebra with which they are spending
so much time, and they will mumble something about “xs and ys.” What
are these, really? The answer is simple: they are names for numbers, and
high school algebra is nothing more than calling numbers by names (or,
more precisely, by letters). The need for letters arises in two contexts. One
is when we speak about general numbers, that is, about any number. In
order to relate to a general number, it must be given a name. Take, for
example, the following rule: “the product of a number plus 1 multiplied by
that same number minus 1 is the square of the number minus 1.” Rather
unwieldy, isn’t it? Written in a formula, it is shorter and more understand-
able: (x + 1) × (x − 1) = x2 − 1. When a letter denotes a general number,
it is called a “variable.” The second instance in which we need to assign
names to numbers is when the number is not known, and we attempt to
find it by some given information. For example, “the number plus 1 is 3.”
118 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Using names, this can be written: x + 1 = 3. In this role, x is called an


“unknown”.
Classic algebra was developed by the Greeks, and later by the Indians.
Based on their work, the Persian mathematician al-Khwarizmi wrote his
book al-Jabar, which gave the field its name, and through which algebra was
introduced to Europe. “Al Jabar” means balancing, and the book is called
so after the technique of solving equations by operating the same way on
both sides of the equation. For a lengthy period of time, algebraists devoted
themselves mainly to solving equations. The first nonobvious type of equa-
tion to be solved was the quadratic equation, such as x2 − 3x + 2 = 0. The
ancient Babylonians and Egyptians knew of ways to solve this, as did the
Chinese. The Greeks solved it geometrically (an example of this will appear
in the chapter “Impossibility”). The solution of third degree equations, such
as x3 +4x2 −6x+1 = 0, remained open, and was avidly sought by mathemati-
cians for more than two thousand years. The problem was finally solved by
several Italian mathematicians. The discovery of the solution was accompa-
nied by one of the most tempestuous dramas in the history of mathematics.
Two factors were responsible for this turmoil: the way in which the academic
world operated at the time, and the personality of two of the protagonists,
Niccolo Tartaglia (1500–1557) and Girolamo Cardano (1501–1576).
In the sixteenth century there were no academic journals, and communi-
cation of scientific ideas was done by letters. To the general public knowl-
edge was disseminated in a somewhat strange fashion: public debates, which
were a sort of academic wrestling matches. To win these competitions, many
mathematicians would not publish their discoveries. And so it happened
that the first mathematician to discover the solution of the third degree
equations, Scipione del Ferro (1465–1526), kept his method secret. He wrote
it for himself, and revealed it to his pupil Antonio Maria Fior only on his
deathbed. Fior was a mediocre mathematician. He understood only part of
the solution, namely, the solution for a certain type of equations, in which
the quadratic term was not present, that is, there is no squared term (for
example: x3 − 6x + 1 = 0). He did not understand that not much separated
this special case from the general solution. At that time Fior heard that
Tartaglia, a poor teacher living in Venice, also, had found the solution to
third degree equations. Certain of his superiority, Fior invited Tartaglia to a
competition. Each of the contestants posed thirty problems to his opponent.
Tartaglia found the method of solution of general third degree equations
Three Types of Mathematics 119

only during the competition, but once he did so, he solved all thirty of Fior’s
problems within two hours, and handily won the competition.
This is where Cardano entered the scene. Girolamo Cardano was a man
of many talents. Besides being a leading mathematician, he was also a physi-
cian, the author of encyclopedias, an inventor (the transmission system he
invented is in use to this day), and one of the first professional chess players
in history. On top of all this, he was also a compulsive gambler, which led
him to write the first book on mathematical probability — that also included
a chapter on how to cheat. According to his own testimony, he was cantan-
kerous. In 1570 he spent several months in prison on the charge of heresy:
he was accused of casting Jesus’ horoscope and attributing the events of his
life to the influence of the stars.
Cardano attempted to find the solution to third order equations by him-
self, and when he failed he implored Tartaglia to tell him the secret. Tartaglia
was himself a difficult man. At the age of twelve he almost died from a
sword blow from a French soldier that slashed his face and mouth. This
caused him to stutter (“tartaglia” in Italian means “stuttering”). He was
suspicious, and refused for quite some time to divulge his secret, but even-
tually gave in, after a promise by Cardano to find him a patron. To ensure
secrecy, Tartaglia sent the solution encoded in a poem. Cardano’s assurance
to attain support for Tartaglia was probably not sincere; at any rate, it never
materialized.
Tartaglia quickly came to regret his giving in to temptation, and began a
lengthy struggle, that was conducted in exchanges of letters. He was right: in
the end, Cardano did not honor his promise of secrecy. About a decade later,
Cardano heard that Tartaglia was not actually the first to discover the solu-
tion, having been preceded by del Ferro. Cardano no longer felt bound by his
promise, and he publicized the discovery. Tartaglia was furious. He invited
Cardano to a public debate, but the latter sent his talented pupil Lodovico
Ferrari (1522–1565). Tartaglia lost the contest, and was consequently dis-
missed from the academic position he had recently won, after many years of
poverty. In the end, he returned to his meager teaching position in Venice.
At about the same time Ferrari also discovered the solution to fourth degree
equations (such as x4 − x3 + 4x2 − 5x + 1 = 0).
Polynomial equations continued to provide inspiration to algebra also in
later years. But in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries algebra made a
sharp turn, and the meaning of the term changed. Modern algebra examines
120 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

operations. These are similar to arithmetic operations, but they can also
be much more general, and relate to more abstract mathematical objects.
An example is the movements in the plane. Among these movements there
is an operation called “composition.” Let us illustrate this. Draw a pic-
ture of something in the plane, say of a turtle, and select a fixed point of
reference.

Now the turtle can be moved in different ways. These movements are
called “transformations.” It can be rotated around the point of reference,
or moved in the plane — up, down, right, or left. Such a movement,
that does not involve change of angle, is called “translation.” Addition-
ally, movements can be combined: performing one movement and then
another. The composition of two transformations is dependent on their
order. If the turtle is first translated and then rotated, it will arrive at a
place different from the one it would reach if it were first rotated and then
translated.

The composition of two transformations: rotation 90◦ counterclockwise, followed by


translation to the right.

Motions in the plane are reversible. For example, if you move one meter
north, you can go back by moving one meter south. Likewise, a 90◦ clockwise
rotation can be reversed by a 90◦ counterclockwise rotation. The requirement
of reversibility is the generalization of a well known property of operations
with numbers: the addition of 7 can be reversed by subtracting 7; multipli-
cation by 3 can be reversed by division by 3. A set (a collection of elements),
together with reversible operations, is called a “group.” The group is the
Three Types of Mathematics 121

The composition of two transformations, in the opposite order: first translation to the
right, followed by a 90o counterclockwise rotation. The result is different.

most basic algebraic object. This does not mean that groups are simple
objects. They are surprisingly diverse and rich in structure.
Similarity of names usually indicates similarity in nature. What, then, is
the connection between modern algebra, that examines abstract operations,
and the study of equations? Why are they both called “algebra”? Not only
because equations involve arithmetic operations, but also for a deeper reason.
The French mathematician Joseph Louis Lagrange (1736–1813) discovered
a surprising connection between the possibility or impossibility of solving a
polynomial equation and operations on the set of solutions.
After the discovery of the solution to fourth order equations mathemati-
cians tried desperately to solve fifth order equations. In the beginning of
the nineteenth century a very surprising fact came to light: there is no gen-
eral formula for solving fifth order equations. This was discovered by the
Norwegian Niels Abel (1802–1829), who used Lagrange’s ideas. Abel died
of tuberculosis at an early age after a life of poverty and hardship, and
left a mathematical inheritance that would “provide mathematicians with
material for thought for two hundred years,” as one mathematician of the
period put it. Following him, the Frenchman Evariste Galois (1811–1832)
showed just which equations can be solved and which not (not every fifth or
higher degree equation is unsolvable; there are solutions for some equations
of higher than fourth order). Galois’s life, too, was tragic. He died in a duel
122 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

at the age of 20. Recognition of his discoveries came more than a decade
after his death. Galois used groups in his proof, and thereby further linked
group theory to algebra.

Discrete mathematics

The third main branch of modern mathematics is discrete mathematics.


This is the simplest of the three branches: its speaks only of sets and the ele-
ments belonging to them. There are no algebraic operations, and no concept
of a limit or of getting infinitely close, the heart of continuous mathematics.
Another name for discrete mathematics is “combinatorics,” and until the
beginning of the twentieth century, its common meaning was the counting of
possibilities. For example: how many 3-member committees can be selected
from among 10 people? In how many ways can 10 people be ordered in a row?
Until the middle of the twentieth century discrete mathematics was
the stepdaughter of mathematics. It owes its present respectability to a sin-
gle individual and to a technological revolution. The man who is accountable
for the change was Paul Erdő s, whom we have already met more than once.
Erdő s opened new directions in combinatorics, and showed the depths of
which the field was capable. The technological revolution that brought com-
binatorics to the fore was the invention of the computer. For combinatorics
proved to be the mathematics of the computer. A computer does not take
continuous steps. In its memory it stores 0s and 1s, with no numbers in
between. Going from one to the other is by jumps. As part of this field’s
growth, discrete mathematics came to include an increasing number of top-
ics, and its ties with other mathematical fields were strengthened.
Topology

Mathematics is the queen of the sciences,


and arithmetic is the queen of mathematics.

Carl Friedrich Gauss


If a mathematics beauty contest were to be conducted, my guess is that
arithmetic would take first place. This is the oldest mathematical field, and
it deals with the most basic mathematical object — the number. There is a
large gap between its depth and its seeming simplicity. It also has an espe-
cially large concentration of conjectures that even a child can understand
yet their proof has eluded mathematicians for centuries. One of the most
serious contenders for second place in the beauty contest is a more modern
discipline: topology. The Greek word topos means “location,” and topology
is the “science of a location.” A more precise definition is “the science of
rubber sheets,” since it examines the properties of sheets that are preserved
under distortion. Topologically, a person is identical to a pretzel with sev-
eral holes (the nostrils and the digestive system); and as far as topology is
concerned, a person can take off his shirt without first removing his sweater.
The difference between topology and geometry is that, in topology, it does
not matter whether a line is straight or not, and distances between points
are not measured. In other words, topology doesn’t care if its rubber sheets
are stretched and distances are enlarged. For it, the two sheets, the original
one and the stretched sheet, are identical.

The fixed point theorem

A topologist is a geometer with his hands tied behind his back. He forbids
himself to speak about distances. For him, the boundaries of a triangle and
that of a circle are the same, since a triangle can be distorted to become
a circle, or the other way around. But if distances aren’t measured, then
what remains to be said of shapes? One quality that topology examines is

123
124 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

whether or not a shape has holes, and if so, how many? It develops tools
to prove that two bodies are topologically equal, meaning that one can be
transformed into the other by stretching, rotation, or reflection.
One of the best known topological theorems is the Fixed Point Theorem of
the Dutchman Luitzen Brouwer (1881–1966). The theorem, dating to 1912,
speaks of a ball in some dimension. A “ball” of radius R is the set of all
points whose distance from a certain point (the center of the ball) is at
most R. In one dimension this is a 2R long segment; in two dimensions,
this is a disk (a “disk” is the inside of a circle, together with the boundary.
By “circle” we mean just the boundary). In three dimensions, this is a regular
ball, like the ones used in sports, and in four dimensions, it is a body that
cannot be visualized. Brouwer’s Theorem states that if we take such a body,
distort it, move it, and stretch it — without tearing! — and if we leave it
entirely within the same space that it previously occupied (that is, after the
transformation no point is outside the place in space occupied by the body
before the change), then there is a point that did not move. This is called a
“fixed point,” because it remains fixed in its place.

The gray shape on the right was obtained by the distortion and moving of the disk to the
left (note that all points remained within the disk). Point x did not move — the
distortion left it in place. Brouwer’s Fixed Point Theorem states that in every distortion
of a disk that leaves it within its original bounds, there is a point that stays put.

This theorem is no longer true if the body has a hole, for example if it is
a ring. If a disk is rotated, its center remains fixed, but if a ring is rotated,
there is no point that remains stationary — everything moves, since the
center of rotation is not in the ring.
The two-dimensional case of Brouwer’s Theorem can be demonstrated
with sheets of paper (although paper can only be crumpled and moved,
but not stretched, and therefore will not fully illustrate the theorem). For
Topology 125

a topologist, a rectangular sheet is the same as a disk, since a disk can be


distorted, without tearing, until it becomes a rectangle (just think about
what can be done with a sheet of Play-Doh). Take two sheets of paper, of
the same size and without holes, and place one exactly over the other. Now
take the upper sheet, fold it, crush it, and rotate it as you wish — but
without tearing it, and without any point on it going beyond the area of the
lower sheet. According to Brouwer’s Theorem, there is at least one point on
the upper sheet that remains above the exact same point that it was above
before. That is, it remained in place.
Its simple formulation, elegant proof (which I have not shown), and
many applications, make Brouwer’s Theorem beautiful. It is also a fascinat-
ing example of the application of one mathematical discipline to another.
Although the theorem’s formulation does not even hint at algebra, its
simplest and most common proof is algebraic. The proof uses tools from a
field called “algebraic topology,” that was founded by the Frenchman Henri
Poincarè (1854–1912). In the next chapter we will see a surprising use of the
Brouwer’s Theorem in discrete mathematics.

The Borsuk-Ulam Theorem

On the eve of the Second World War mathematics enjoyed a short-lived but
dramatic blossoming in Poland. Mathematicians whose names are known to
every present-day mathematician were active in the coffee houses of Lwow
and Warsaw, the two major centers of mathematics research: Stefan Banach,
Stefan Mazurkiewicz, Kazimierz Kuratowski, Alfred Tarski, Karol Borsuk,
and many others. Topology in particular benefited from this spurt of activity.
Stanislaw Ulam, later one of the fathers of the hydrogen bomb, was one of
the younger of the group. He was not a topologist by profession, but he
formulated a basic conjecture, which was quickly proved by Borsuk, and was
named after them the “Borsuk-Ulam Theorem.” First, an example of the
theorem:
At any given moment there are two antipodal points on the Equator
with exactly the same temperature.

The Equator is just an example: we could have used any circle instead; and
in place of temperature, we could have taken any other quantity, provided
that it is continuous, that is, without leaps. Temperature does not “jump” —
if at a certain point the temperature is, say, 10 degrees, then at neighboring
points the temperature will be close to 10 degrees. That was an example of
126 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

a one-dimensional case of the Borsuk-Ulam Theorem. Here is an example of


the two-dimensional case:

At any given moment, there are two antipodal points on the face
of the earth with exactly the same temperature and the same
humidity.

The face of the Earth is the boundary of a three dimensional ball. It is


two dimensional, since every point can be specified using two numbers —
the longitude and the latitude. In the two-dimensional case, the Borsuk-
Ulam Theorem states that for every two continuous quantities there exist
two antipodal points, such that both quantities are the same at the two
points. Topologists speak also of higher dimensional balls, and when the
number of dimensions rises, more quantities can be considered. For example:
on the three dimensional face of a four dimensional ball (don’t try to visu-
alize this — it is a pure abstraction), for every three continuous quantities,
there is a pair of antipodal points at which each of the quantities has the
same value.
The proof of the theorem for two or more dimensions is difficult. The one-
dimensional case, however, is quite simple. Remember, this case says that on
the Equator (which is just an example of a circle) there are two antipodal
points with the same temperature (which is an example of a continuous
parameter or, in mathematical terminology, a “continuous function”). To
prove this, we will draw a pointer with a head and tail, as in the following
illustration:

The Borsuk-Ulam Theorem states that if we rotate the pointer over the Equator, we will
come to a situation in which the same temperature is measured at the pointer’s head and
tail. This is proved by measuring the difference between the temperature at the head and
at the tail.

Place the pointer in any position, and calculate the difference between
the temperature at its head and the temperature at its tail. If, at the posi-
tion we chose, the difference is 0, that is, the temperature is the same at
the head and the tail — then these are the two antipodal points with the
same temperature, the existence of which we are after. We can therefore
Topology 127

assume that this difference is not 0. Let us say, for example, that the temper-
ature is 10 degrees at the head, and 3 at the tail, which gives us a difference
of 10 − 3 = 7 degrees. Now spin the pointer 180 degrees, to the position
where the head and tail switch positions, all the while measuring the dif-
ference in temperature between the head and the tail. When the pointer
arrives at its final position (that is, when the rotation of 180 degrees is com-
pleted), the temperature at the head (the former position of the tail) will be
3 degrees, and at the tail (where the head used to be), 10 degrees. The differ-
ence between the head and the tail is now 3 − 10 = −7 degrees. And so, the
difference changed from a positive value to a negative one. Since we assume
that temperature is a continuous parameter, that is, without leaps, then
according to the mean value theorem that we learned in the last chapter,
at some point the difference has to be 0. But 0 difference between the head
and the tail means exactly what we set out to prove — the existence of two
antipodal points with the same temperature!

An application in discrete mathematics

A person’s first response to the Borsuk-Ulam Theorem is liable to be — “So


what?” As evidence of the theorem’s importance, here is one of its many
applications, in this specific case, in discrete mathematics. The problem I
will describe makes no mention whatsoever of topology, but, surprisingly,
the proof is topological.
The problem is called the “necklace splitting problem.” Two thieves stole
a necklace. The necklace is open (that is, it is not circular), and it contains
beads of different types, with an even number of beads of each type. The
thieves want to divide their loot fairly, with each thief receiving the same
number of beads of each type. In order to do this they have to cut the neck-
lace. But cutting the necklace will lessen its value, and so they want to make
as few cuts as possible. How many cuts will they need? The Israeli mathe-
matician Noga Alon used the Borsuk-Ulam Theorem to prove the following
theorem:

The number of cuts needed does


not exceed the number of bead types.

As usual — we should examine first the simplest example possible. In


this case, a necklace with a single type of beads, in which case a single cut
suffices — in the middle. The case of two bead types, too, is easy to prove.
128 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Starting from 3 types, however, the only known proof uses the Borsuk-Ulam
Theorem.

In this particular example, when the necklace is cut in two places (marked by the scissors
in the drawing), the first thief receives the sections marked A, and the second thief
receives the section marked B.
Matchmaking

Matchmaker, matchmaker, make me a match.

Fiddler on the Roof

1912, the year in which Brouwer proved his fixed point theorem, also marked
a turning point in combinatorics. A cornerstone theorem of the field was
proved then. Its discoverer, Ferdinand Frobenius (1849–1917), was both the
blessing and the curse of the department of Mathematics at the Univer-
sity of Berlin. A blessing — because he was an outstanding mathematician;
a curse — because he was contentious. The reluctance of other mathemati-
cians to work with him was one of the reasons for the flourishing of Berlin’s
great rival, the University of Göttingen. Frobenius was an algebraist, not
a combinatorialist (combinatorics hardly existed as a separate field at that
time), and he worded his theorem in algebraic terms. When the Hungarian
Dénés König proved a stronger version of this theorem a few years later
and cast it in a combinatorial formulation, Frobenius ridiculed him for his
“inferior terminology.”
For many years König was the only one to recognize the importance of
Frobenius’ theorem. The theorem would become widely known only much
later, in 1935, when it was discovered independently by the Englishman
Philip Hall (1904–1982). The success of the new version (which was even-
tually named after Hall), might have been due to the intriguing name Hall
gave it: the “Marriage Theorem.” Sex sells, even in mathematics. Imagine,
Hall said, a set of acquainted men and women: each man is acquainted with
some of the women (possibly even with none). The men want to get married.
The rule is that a man may marry only a woman with whom he is acquainted
(these are mathematical men, and they don’t have tall demands — the sole
requirement is being acquainted). Naturally, the marriage must be monog-
amous, that is, a person (of either sex) may have only a single spouse. The

129
130 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

question that Hall asked is: under what conditions can all the men be mar-
ried? (Take note that we don’t insist that all the women will get married —
the problem was formulated before women’s lib.) In order to understand the
meaning of “under what conditions,” look at the following example:

When two men are acquainted with only a single woman, they cannot be matched.

Acquaintanceship is represented by lines. There can be no marriage for


all the men, since the two men are competing for a single woman, and so
one man will have to forego getting married. This example points to a nec-
essary condition for all the men to get married: the number of women must
be at least as large as the number of men. Otherwise, following the pigeon-
hole principle, two men would be matched with one woman. This condition,
however, is not sufficient for weddings for all to be held. For example, it
might happen that there are no fewer women than men, but there is a man
who is not acquainted with any woman — then this man cannot be matched
(the right-hand case in the following drawing). Or, in a large group of men
and women there may be two men who are acquainted with only a single
woman (like the two left-hand men in the middle drawing), and then they
cannot both marry. In each of the following drawings, A represents a set of
men who cannot get married because they are not acquainted with enough
women.

So, for a wedding of all the men to take place, it is necessary for every man
to be acquainted with at least one woman, for every 2 men to be acquainted
Matchmaking 131

with at least 2 women, for every 3 men to be acquainted with 3 women, and
so on. This is clearly a necessary condition. It is less clear that this is also
a sufficient condition. Namely, if every k men are acquainted with at least
k women, then all the men can get married. This is the content of Hall’s
Theorem:

Hall’s Theorem: There will be a wedding [i.e., all the men can be
married] if and only if every set A of men is acquainted with a
number of women at least the size of A.

Hall’s Theorem is important because of its many uses, and because it


served as the starting point for extensive and rich research in modern com-
binatorics. Theorems constructed in the pattern: “something (in this case,
a wedding) exists only if every. . . (in this case, every set is acquainted with
at least its size)” tend to be fruitful. They say “an object of a certain type
exists, unless a clear and present obstacle to this exists.” In our case: “The
possibility of a marriage for each of the men exists, unless there is a set of
men that is acquainted with too few women.”

Ménages à Trois

Hall’s theorem belongs to a rare species: theorems that are not hard to
prove, and yet they possess depth and many applications. Experience tells
that such theorems tend to have many different proofs. Pythagoras’ theorem,
for example, has hundreds of proofs, each with its own beauty. This is the
case also with Hall’s theorem. And surprisingly, the strongest proof, having
the furthest reaching conclusions, is topological. The topological proof has
applications beyond those of the combinatorial proofs.
One of these applications is to triple weddings. This is not what you
think. I am not talking about two men and a woman, but about a man, a
woman, and a third object, say their dog, or their lodging. Suppose, as an
example, that we add to the men and women a third element — hous-
ing type. Instead of being acquainted with women, now every man will
be acquainted with woman + housing (or woman + dog) pairs. A man’s
acquaintanceship with a woman + housing pair means that the man is
willing to marry this woman, on condition that they will live in this
housing.
132 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Example:

A man named Alan is acquainted with the pairs Alice + tent, and
Betty + house. This means that Alan is willing to marry Alice on
condition that they live in the tent, or with Betty on condition that
they live in the house. He is not willing to live with Alice in the
house, or with Betty in the tent. A second man, Bob, is acquainted
with Betty + tent.

Alan is acquainted with the pairs Alice + tent and Betty + house, while Bob is
acquainted with the pair Betty + tent. In this situation, there cannot be a marriage for
both men.

A marriage in this case is the assigning to each man of a woman + housing


pair that the man knows. Obviously, the marriage must be monogamous,
which means here that two men cannot get married to the same woman,
nor can two couples live together in the same housing. In our example,
there is no such marriage. Bob can only get married to the one pair with
which he is acquainted: Betty + tent. This means that if Bob gets married,
Alan will remain single. He cannot be married to Alice + tent, because
Bob took the tent for himself, nor to Betty + house, because Bob married
Betty.
Let us now return to the general case, and assume for a moment that
there is a marriage. In this case each man is acquainted with the woman +
housing pair that he has chosen for his marriage. If so, then (say) every 3
men are acquainted with 3 such pairs, the ones that they have chosen for
their marriages. These pairs are disjoint, meaning that all the women in
them are different, as are all the housing types. Consequently, if a marriage
of the men is possible, then every set of k men is acquainted with at least k
Matchmaking 133

disjoint pairs. In the case of Hall’s Theorem, in which the men married only
women, this condition suffices. Does it also suffice in this case? That is:

When, for every number k, every k men are acquainted with k


woman + housing disjoint pairs, is a marriage guaranteed?

The answer is “No.” In order to see this, all we have to do is look at


the above example. Each man is acquainted with at least one woman +
housing pair (Alan is actually acquainted with two disjoint pairs), and two
men together are acquainted with two such disjoint pairs: the two together
are acquainted with the two disjoint pairs Alice + tent and Betty + house
(Alan by himself was already acquainted with these 2 pairs, and so Alan and
Bob put together as a group certainly are acquainted with them). Nonethe-
less, there cannot be a marriage for both. Therefore, more is needed. And,
here, “more” means double: if we double our requirement (in fact, a bit less
than double), we will obtain a sufficient condition for the marriage.

Theorem: If every k men are acquainted with 2k − 1 disjoint


woman + housing pairs, then there is a marriage for all the men.

When 2 men are acquainted together with 3 disjoint pairs and each man is acquainted
with at least one pair, the marriage is assured.

For example, if we add to this example one more pair (Claire + apart-
ment), with which Alan is acquainted, then this requirement is met. For
k = 1, the requirement means that every man must be acquainted with
2k − 1 = (2 × 1) − 1 = 1, namely, every man must be acquainted with at least
one pair — this condition is met in the example. For k = 2, the condition
means that 2 men together must be acquainted with 2k − 1 = 2 × 2 − 1 = 3
disjoint pairs, and this condition is also met: the two men are acquainted
134 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

with the 3 disjoint pairs Alice + tent, Betty + house, and Claire + apart-
ment. And indeed, both men can be married: we match Alan with the pair
Claire + apartment, and Bob with the pair Betty + tent.
And here we are in for a surprise: the proof of this theorem is topolog-
ical. Topology is not mentioned in the theorem, and is totally unexpected.
Nonetheless, the only proof known uses topological tools — actually, a cer-
tain version of Brouwer’s fixed point theorem.
Imagination

Fantasy and imagination

The gift of fantasy has meant more to me than


my talent for absorbing positive knowledge.

Albert Einstein

The English poet and essayist Samuel Tayler Coleridge claimed that poetry
finds “similarity in difference.” The poet William Wordsworth (1770–1850)
used an almost identical definition in his philosophical poem “The Prelude”:
poetry discerns the similarities between things that look different to the
passive observer. Imagination is the ability to find features shared by two
seemingly distant objects. This ability is common to poets, mathematicians,
and scientists.
In the early seventeenth century a poetic movement that its opponents
called “Metaphysical poetry” emerged in England. It was characterized
by sophisticated metaphor and the discovery of unexpected similarities
between disparate objects. The leading figure in the movement was John
Donne (1572–1631). Here is a famous passage from one of his poems,
that bears the strange name “A Valediction Forbidding Mourning.” The
bond between the souls of the poet and his lover is compared to the rela-
tionship between the two arms of a compass. The analogy goes on and on,
and every time that we think it has been exhausted, yet another point of
similarity emerges.

If they be two, they are two so


As stiff twin compasses are two;
Thy soul, the fix’d foot, makes no show
To move, but doth, if th’ other do.

And though it in the centre sit,


Yet, when the other far doth roam,

135
136 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

It leans, and hearkens after it,


And grows erect, as that comes home.

Such wilt thou be to me, who must,


Like th’ other foot, obliquely run;
Thy firmness makes my circle just,
And makes me end where I begun.
John Donne, “A Valediction Forbidding Mourning”
The beauty of the last two lines lies in their multiple possible interpretations:
does “makes me end where I begun” mean that the lover aids the poet to
find his true inner voice? Or perhaps to return to his infancy?

Mathematical similarity

Poetry is the art of calling the


same thing by different names.
Anonymous

Yes, and mathematics is the art of calling


different things by the same name.
Jules-Henri Poincaré, French mathematician
One of the most famous reports by mathematicians of their creative process
was related by Poincaré. One day, he was walking in the street, not thinking
about anything in particular, at least not consciously, and he boarded a
trolley car. The moment he put his foot on the trolley’s steps, the light
flashed on. He realized that the problem that had occupied him for weeks
was identical to another problem, whose solution he knew.
Like in poetry, mathematical discoveries are often made by finding simi-
larities. Here is a threefold example: three problems that, superficially, seem
different, but have an identical underlying hidden structure. All three are
well-known: the calculation of the area of a triangle, the sum of the numbers
between 1 and a given number n, and how far an object accelerating at a
constant pace will travel.
First, for the simplest of the three, calculating the area of a triangle. The
area of a triangle is half the product of the side by its height. How can this
Imagination 137

Jules-Henri Poincaré, French mathematician (1854–1912), the father of modern topology.

be proved? One way is by first realizing that it is enough to prove this for
a right angle triangle. Every triangle can be divided into two right angle
triangles, like this:

If we prove the formula for each of the two right angle triangles that
were formed, then the area of the left-hand triangle is 12 ah, the area of the
right-hand triangle is 12 bh, and the area of the entire triangle is therefore
1 1 1
2 ah + 2 bh = 2 (a + b)h. Since the length of the bottom side is a + b, this
means that the area is half of the base multiplied by the height, as we wanted
to demonstrate. In an obtuse triangle, the height line is outside the triangle:
138 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

In this case, the area of the triangle is the difference of the areas of the
right angle triangles.
So, all we have left to prove is the formula for a right angle triangle, like
this:

Here is one way of proving this. Note that the distance of a point on the
upper side from the base increases at a constant rate as the point moves to
the right. The point furthest to the left is at a height (distance) 0 from the
base. If the entire upper side were at this height, it would fuse with the lower
one, and the area of the line formed would be 0. The point furthest to the
right is at a height of h above the base, and if the entire upper side were at
this height, it would assume the shape of a rectangle, the area of which is
the base times the height, that is, ah. The average height of the upper side
is the middle between 0 and h, namely, 12 h. The area of the triangle is the
product of the base times the average height, namely, a × 12 h, which is 12 ah,
which is what we wanted to prove.
In the chapter “To Discover or to Invent” we learned how Gauss calcu-
lated the sum 1 + 2 + 3 + · · · + n. In order to show its likeness to the calcula-
tion of the area of a triangle, I will present the solution somewhat differently.
Let us add 0 to the sequence, and write it as 0 + 1 + 2 + 3 + · · · + n. Adding
0 doesn’t change the sum. The first number is 0, and the last one is n. Since
the numbers grow at a fixed pace, their average is the middle between 0
and n, that is, 12 n. After we added 0, the number of terms in the sequence
is n + 1 (before we added 0, there were n terms). The sum of the terms of
the sequence is the number of terms multiplied by the average of the terms
Imagination 139

(this average is 12 n). That is, the sum is equal to 12 (n + 1)n — just like the
calculation of the area of a triangle: “half of the length of the base times the
height.”
Gauss’s method was a bit different. He matched 1 to n, 2 to n − 1, 3 to
n − 2, and so on. The next drawing shows the calculation of the sum of the
numbers from 1 to 6. 1 is joined to 6, 2 to 5, and so on.

The sum of the numbers from 1 to 6 is the number of circles in the lower
triangle. As we see from the drawing, this number is half the number of
circles in the rectangle, that is, half of 6 × 7, namely half of 42, which is 21.
This parallels the classic proof of the formula for the area of a triangle, as
illustrated in the next drawing:

The two triangles, the upper and the lower, complement each other to
form a shape of fixed height. This yields a rectangle, of height h with area
ah. The area of the triangle is half this, that is, 12 ah — which is exactly
Gauss’s proof!
140 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Finally, a physics problem: the calculation of the distance traveled by


an object accelerating at a constant pace. We will stipulate that the object
begins at a speed of 0, moves for t seconds, and during this entire time
its acceleration is a (that is, each second it increases its speed by a
meters/second). How far does the object travel? We said that it begins at
a speed of 0. If a meters/second are added to its speed each second, then
at the end, after t seconds, its speed will be at meters/second. The average
speed during its journey is the average between 0 and at, which is 12 at. The
distance is the product of the time multiplied by the average speed, that is,
t × 12 at = 12 at2 , which is a formula known to anyone who studied physics in
high school.
As we see, it is not only the formulas that are similar ( 12 appears in
all of them), the ways of arriving at them, too, are analogous — they all
use averages. I didn’t realize this connection when I was in high school,
and I understood it only when my son was in high school. Anyone who is
aware of the similarity between the problems understands all three better:
understanding is linking.

Isomorphism

Pushing the “Power” button on a radio changes its condition, from “off”
to “on,” or the opposite. It doesn’t take any child long to learn that the
same holds true for a computer, a television, or a game console. This is
an example of “isomorphism.” That is, structural likeness: two phenomena
sharing the same hidden structure. The radio, the computer, and the tele-
vision are “isomorphic” in terms of their on/off mechanism. We can add a
mathematical example. If we take the numbers 1 and (−1), the operation of
multiplication by (−1) reverses the on/off status, just like pressing an elec-
trical switch: when 1 is multiplied by (−1), it reverses and becomes (−1),
while (−1) multiplied by (−1) becomes 1.
In a party my daughter asked me what is the difference between the
buffets at the two sides of the hall. Being a mathematician, I answered
“they are isomorphic.” She asked me what does this mean, and by way of
an answer I suggested that we play the following game. Two players, each
in turn, picks a number between 1 and 9, which had not been selected so
far by either of the two players. Each player collects the numbers he chose,
and the winner is the player who has three numbers that total 15. Here is an
example of such a game. Call the players A and B. We record their moves,
as well as the numbers they have collected so far:
Imagination 141

A - 5 (the set of numbers collected so far is {5})


B - 7 (B has collected the set {7})
A - 6, his set of numbers chosen so far being {5, 6}. Now A threatens to
play 4, which together with 5 and 6 will total 15. So B has no choice:
B - 4. Now B has {4, 7}. B poses no threat, because in order to get to 15
from 4 + 7, 4 must be added, but 4 is already taken. So A is free to make
the following move:
A - 1 Now A has at his disposition {5, 6, 1}. At this point, A poses two
threats: to choose 8, which complements the 1 and the 6 he already has to
15; or 9, which, together with 5 and 1 (which he also possesses), total 15.
B can counter only one of these threats. If, for example, B takes 8, A will
choose 9 and win. If B chooses 9, A will select 8 and win. So A’s win is
guaranteed.
I played this game with my daughter. My son, who sat kibitzing, butted
in: “You’re playing tic-tac-toe!” He was right. Let us draw the familiar magic
square, in which each row, column, and diagonal totals 15:

Choosing a number between 1 and 9 is actually choosing a square in this


board. Instead of selecting a number, player A can draw an X in the corre-
sponding square, while player B marks an O. Somewhat surprisingly, every
threesome that totals 15 is a row, column, or diagonal in this square. There
are only eight threesomes of different numbers from 1 to 9 that total 15, and
all appear here. So a winning threesome in the game I proposed is just the
same as winning at tic-tac-toe. Let us see this by illustrating the rounds of
the above game between A and B on a tic-tac-toe board (on the boards in
the illustration, going from left to right; the “X” starts).
142 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The first three steps taken by players A and B, from left to right. In the first round A
chose 5, which is represented by the X in the left-hand drawing. B responded with 7,
which is represented by the O in this board. After the third round, the “X” player has
two possibilities of winning, only one of which can be blocked by the “O” player.

On the face of it, the number-choice game and tic-tac-toe seem differ-
ent, but a proper abstraction shows the identity between the two: they are
isomorphic. I asked my son how he discovered this, and he said that he iden-
tified two similar elements in both games: the threesomes, and the double
threat. In tic-tac-toe, too, the way to victory lies either in the opponent’s
oversight or in a double threat, that is, two threats only one of which can be
blocked.
“That reminds me” is one of the more common paths leading to mathe-
matical discoveries.
A Magic Number

Strangely, of all the real numbers the Goddess of Mathematics picked two
and assigned them a special role. One of them, π, which is about 3.141, was
already well known in antiquity. This is the ratio between the circumference
of a circle and its diameter, a ratio that already the ancients knew is the
same for all circles. The symbol π was first used in 1706 in a book by William
Jones, as the first letter of the word “perimeter.” The number π naturally
appears in geometric formulas, but, surprisingly enough, also in number
theory. The significance of the second special number, marked as e, with
a value close to 2.718, was discovered only in the seventeenth century. Its
meaning could be comprehended only with tools from differential calculus,
which developed then. Its importance quickly became apparent. The first
to name this number (as b, rather than e) was the German mathematician
and philosopher Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716). It was named e by the Swiss
Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the leading mathematician of the eighteenth
century. Contrary to the natural guess, Euler did not pick the first letter of
his own name. He wanted to use a vowel, and since he had already used the
letter a for some other value, he chose the second vowel in the alphabet.
It soon became clear that e is no less important than π. It appears in
varied contexts, and in many fields. In this chapter we shall meet it in four
roles.

Compound interest

The first meaning of e, discovered by the Swiss mathematician Jacob


Bernoulli (1654–1705) is about compound interest. Here is an example: cus-
tomer A invests $1000 in a savings plan that yields a 10 percent profit per
annum. How much money will A have after ten years? The first answer that
comes to mind is $2000, since the profit is 10 times 10 percent, which is
100 percent. In actuality, though, A will have more. A 10 percent profit each
1
year means that each year the principal is multiplied by 1 10 (or expressed as

143
144 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

a decimal — by 1.1). After one year, A’s account will contain 1.1 times $1000,
that is, $1100. At the end of the second year he will have 1.1 times $1100,
which is $1210. At the end of the third year he will have 1.1 times
$1210, and so forth. After k years, A will have $1000 × 1.1k . To answer
our question, after 10 years A will have $1000 × 1.110 , and since 1.110 is
approximately 2.59, he will have about $2590.
Customer B is more aggressive than A. He demands (and receives) inter-
1
est of 20 every half a year. How much will he have after 10 years? Before
answering, think: will B earn more or less than A? The answer is — more.
1
If it were not for this being compound interest, two half-years of 20 interest
1
would equal one year of 10 interest. Since, however, this interest is com-
1
pound, the interest for the two half-years comes to more than 10 , so each
year B will earn more than A. Using a calculation similar to that for A’s
1 20
profits, 20 half-years will end with B having 1000× (1+ 20 ) , which is about
2650 dollars.
Customer C is even more assertive. He demands that the 10 years be
1
divided into 50 parts (50 fifth-years), and that he receive 50 interest every
fifth-year. The same calculation reveals that after 10 years the initial $1000
1 50
investment will be multiplied by (1+ 50 ) , which is about 2.69. If a customer
demands that the 10-year period be divided into 100 parts, and that he
1
receive interest of 10 each tenth-year, his money will be multiplied by (1 +
1 100
100 ) , which is about 2.704, so that after 10 years he will have a sum of
approximately $2704 in his account.
The sequence we are looking at is (1 + n1 )n . As we saw from the examples,
the terms of the sequence increase as n increases. Yet, the rate of increase
decreases, and therefore the sequence does not tend to infinity, but rather
to a finite number, which is only a bit larger than 2.7. The limit of the
sequence is marked by e, which is approximately 2.718. This value is only
approximate, because e is not a rational number. Bernoulli’s definition is the
most commonly used of all the definitions of e.
It is not hard to see that if the numbers (1 + n1 )n converge to e, then the
numbers (1 − n1 )n converges to 1e . To see this, write 1 − n1 = 1/(1 + n−11
), so
 n
1 1 1 1
1− = 1 = 1 × 1
n (1 + n−1 )n (1 + n−1 ) n−1 1 + n−1

The last term tends to 1, and the one before it to 1e . There is a gruesome
story related to this calculation, told by the British writer and Nobel lau-
reate Graham Green. As a teenager he suffered from acute depression, and
he played Russian Roulette 6 times. In each attempt he had 1/6 chance
A Magic Number 145

of being killed. What was the probability of his survival? Since at each
attempt he had a 5/6 chance to stay alive, the answer is ( 56 )6 , which is 5/6
of 5/6. . . of 5/6 (6 times), namely (1 − 16 )6 . As we saw, this number is very
close to 1e , namely a bit more than a third. Not much. Green’s fans should
be relieved, but of course they wouldn’t know if he did succeed in killing
himself.

Secret friend

Another instance of the appearance of e in real life is related to the custom


of “Secret Friend” week in schools. Each child in the class is assigned a
classmate, his or her “secret friend,” who anonymously brings him gifts for
an entire week. The assignment of secret friends is done by lottery: slips with
all the children’s name are placed in a hat, and each child picks a slip with
a name of his or her secret friend. Obviously, there is a problem if a child
takes a slip with his own name.
What is the probability that no child will take a slip with his own name?
Surprisingly, the answer is almost independent of the number of children
in the class: the probability is almost exactly 1e . “Almost exactly” means that
the larger the number of children in the class, the closer this probability is to
1
e . The rate of convergence of this sequence is the fastest of all three examples
considered so far — the numbers approach 1e very quickly. If there are 30
children in the class, the probability differs from 1e only after the 30th digit!

Geometric mean

The average weight of 5 people is the sum of their weights divided by 5. If


we replace the weight of each one in the group with the average, the sum
will remain the same.

Example:

The average of 1, 2, 3, 4, and 5 is 3, because


1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 = 3 + 3 + 3 + 3 + 3.

This is also called “arithmetic mean.” There are also other kinds of averages,
the best known of which is the geometric mean. The geometric mean of a
146 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

set of numbers is the number that will leave the product unchanged if it is
exchanged for each of the numbers in the set.

Example:

The geometric mean of 3, 8, and 9 is 6, because if we replace each of the


three numbers with 6, the product will be 6 × 6 × 6 = 216, which is exactly
the product 3 × 8 × 9.

The arithmetic mean of 3, 8, and 9 is one-third of 3 + 8 + 9, which is


one-third of 20, namely 6 23 , a bit more than the geometric mean.
This is no coincidence. It is always the case: the arithmetic mean is greater
than or equal to the geometric mean. The two averages are the same only
if all numbers are equal: for example, the arithmetic mean of 3, 3, 3, 3 is
(of course) 3, and this is true also for the geometric mean. Look now at
the arithmetic mean of the numbers between 1 and 100. As was seen in the
chapter “To Discover or to Invent,” it is the middle between 1 and 100,
which is 50 12 . So, the geometric mean should be less. What is it? The answer
is about 100e . In general, the geometric mean of the numbers 1, 2, . . . , n is
approximately ne . This fact was proved by the Scottish mathematician James
Stirling (1692–1770).
What does the word “approximately” mean here? It means that the ratio
between the geometric mean and ne approaches 1 as n tends to infinity.
In our example, in which n is 100, the geometric mean is approximately
37.993, while 100 e is about 36.788. The ratio between these two numbers
(approximately 1.03) is quite close to 1. The higher the value of n, the closer
this ratio will be to 1.

A differential equation

A ladybug is standing in the Cartesian plane (see the “Poetic Image, Mathe-
matical Image” chapter), at the point (0, 1), that is, on the y axis, at a height
of 1. It begins to move to the right, along a line with a slope of 1, that is, at
an angle of 45 degrees with the axes, which means that for each unit that
it moves to the right it will go up one unit. As the ladybug advances, it
changes the angle of its movement — it always moves at an incline exactly
equal to its height above the x axis. For example, when it reaches the height
A Magic Number 147

of 2 above the x axis, the incline of its movement will be 2, meaning that it
goes up twice as fast as it moves to the right.

The ladybug is moving to the right and up. The ratio between its progress upwards and
its movement to the right is increasing: it is equal to the ladybug’s height above the x
axis. It can be shown that when the ladybug has advanced x units to the right, its height
is ex .

Obviously, the ladybug will climb very quickly: the further it rises, the
greater the rate of its ascent. The question is: what is the formula for the
curve that it follows? That is, after it has moved x units to the right, how
high will it be? The formula for this curve is y = ex . In other words, after
the ladybug has moved x units to the right, it will be at height ex . For
example, after a single time unit, it will be at height e; after two time units,
it will be at height e2 . In terms taken from differential calculus, the function
ex possesses a unique trait, that it equals its derivative (the derivative of a
function is its rate of change). This is the special property of the number
e, from which all its other characteristics are derived. The function ex does
indeed rise very rapidly: for example — after 10 units of movement to the
right, the beetle’s height, e10 , will be approximately 6000 units.
What I have just described is called a “differential equation.” Such an
equation prescribes the behavior of a curve. It tells what the slope of the
curve is, that is, the rate of increase of the value y as we advance along
the curve, at every point on it. The differential equation above says: If this
curve is described by the equation y = f (x), then the function f (x) is equal
to its derivative. As a formula, this becomes f  (x) = f (x). (The derivative
of a function f (x) is denoted by f  (x).) The simplest differential equation is
f  (x) = 0, which means: the derivative is 0, or, in other words, the rate of
change of the function is 0 (more simply put, the function does not change).
The solution of this equation is a constant function f (x) = c, where c is any
fixed number.
148 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Differential equations describe the geometry of curves, in terms of the


rate of their change. They are one of the most useful mathematical tools.

Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the greatest mathematician of the eighteenth century, and
one of the most prolific mathematicians of all time. The blindness from which he suffered
for the last seventeen years of his life did not curb his creativity.
Reality or Imagination

Don’t trust them too far

Some numbers look real, and others less so. Some appear as if they are part
of the real world, while others seem to be an arbitrary invention. The most
natural are the numbers that are indeed called — “natural”: 1, 2, 3, . . . .
They are visible and tangible. Four apples are concrete reality. Fractions, too,
never suffered from a lack of faith in their existence, since a half or a third of
something too can be seen and felt. This is not to say that they reached their
present form smoothly. The Egyptians knew only fractions with a numerator
of 1, such as 12 , 13 or 14 . The Romans had no special symbols for fractions,
only verbal descriptions. The fraction sign that we know was invented by
the Indians, and was brought to Europe only in the twelfth century by the
Arabs. But despite their difficult birth, the existence of fractions was never
doubted.
In contrast, there are some numbers that were, and are still suspected of
being fictitious. It seems that they are no more real than the unicorn, and
that the mathematicians who study them are playing make-believe. This was
the fate of the number 0, that, at least on the face of it, has no object, that
is, it doesn’t count anything. In Europe it gained respectability only in the
twelfth century.
Something similar happened to the negative numbers. When present day
elementary school children recite a descending numerical sequence, say, 9, 7,
5, 3, 1, there are usually two or three children in the class who would continue
-1, -3, -5. This just goes to show how natural the concept of negative numbers
is today. Children pick it up as if from the air. It is hard to believe that this
idea was still ferociously attacked in the nineteenth century. The famous
French mathematician Lazare Carnot (1753–1823) argued that “in order to
think about a negative quantity, something must be subtracted from 0, that
is, from something that does not exist — which is impossible.” The author
of a mathematic handbook, Busset, argued that the root of the problem in
mathematical education in France was teaching negative numbers. He wrote

149
150 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

that “thinking about quantities smaller than zero is the height of insanity.”
In 1831 Augustus De Morgan, an important English mathematician, wrote
that the appearance of negative numbers in real-life problems is just an
indication of incorrect formulation. If we ask how much a store owner earned,
and the answer comes out to be −10, it means only that we should have
asked: “How much did he lose?”, and then the answer would be the positive
number 10. If we were to ask, “In how many years will Robert be twice as
old as Sherman?”, and we get −3, we should have asked: “How many years
ago was Robert twice as old as Sherman?”, and then the answer would have
been a positive number: “3 years ago.” Today, the idea that “a profit of −10
dollars” means a loss of 10 dollars, or that “in −3 years” is simply 3 years
ago, is almost self-evident.
Other numbers were thought to be even more imaginary. They were even
called this: “imaginary numbers.” Today, these numbers have similar stand-
ing to the real numbers, but are still cloaked in an aura of mystery. Indeed,
there is something magical about them.

Imaginary and complex numbers

The need for new types of numbers usually arises in the solution of equa-
tions. Negative numbers are necessary to solve equations such as 5 + x = 2
(whose solution is x = −3); rational numbers were introduced to solve equa-
tions such as 3x = 2 (whose solution is x = 23 ). Irrational numbers first
2
√ to solve equations like x = 2, that is, in order to be
appeared in order
able to refer to 2. The next class of numbers, the imaginary numbers, also
can be understood in this manner: they are needed to solve equations of the
form x2 = −9. The square of a real number cannot be negative, so there
is no real number satisfying this equation. For, 32 = 3 × 3 = 9, and also
(−3)2 = (−3) × (−3) = 9. The discoverer of imaginary numbers (for, it was
a discovery — a notion was waiting there to be discovered) was the Italian
Rafael Bombelli (1526–1572).
√ He spoke of a number whose square is (−1),
that is, a number that is −1, but he did not assign it a name. Nor did
he call it an “imaginary number,” a name derisively given it by Descartes.

The accepted letter for −1, which is i (the first letter of “imaginary” or
the Latin “imaginarius”), was given it by Euler in 1777. Once we have this
number it is possible to solve equations such as x2 = −9: the two solutions
are 3i and −3i.
x2 + x +
In order to solve equations that are a bit more involved, such as √
9 = 0, we need combinations of i and real numbers like 5 + 3i or 2 + 23 i,
Reality or Imagination 151

and in general, a + bi, with a and b being real numbers. Such a number is
called “complex,” because it is composed of two parts, one real and the other
imaginary.

The fundamental theorem of algebra

New types of numbers were defined one after the other, and in each phase an
additional number type was needed for the solution of equations. Is there an
end to this process, or will it continue indefinitely? Fortunately, the complex
numbers are, indeed, the Promised Land. There is no need for further number
types to solve new equations. This fact, that is known as “the Fundamental
Theorem of Algebra,” was proved by the 22 years old Gauss in 1799. The
theorem states that the complex numbers are sufficient to solve any equation
of the type known as “polynomial,” such as x5 + 4ix4 − 3x3 + 10x + 1 + i = 0.
Gauss showed that every such equation has a complex solution, and that if
the equation is of the nth order, namely the highest exponent of the unknown
is n, then it has n solutions (the equation in the example is fifth-order, since
5 is the highest power of x in it).
Actually, this is true for more than polynomial equations. Almost every
equation has a solution. This is Pickard’s Theorem, which states that even if
one were to concoct some wild equation that uses regular operations (such as
multiplication, division, raising to a power, trigonometric functions), chances
are that it has a complex-number solution. “Chances are” means that the
equation has a solution for any value in its right-hand side, apart possi-
bly from one single value. For example, there is a solution for the equa-
tion 2x = 3 + i as there will be for any other number placed in the right
side in place of 3 + i, except for a single number: 0. There is no solution
for the equation 2x = 0. “Almost every equation has a solution” is quite
surprising. As far as the solution of equations is concerned, complex num-
bers are truly the last word. It is not that mathematicians stopped invent-
ing new classes of numbers. But the new classes are not there for solving
equations.

How complex numbers were born

Already the ancient Greeks spoke of the need to invent numbers with neg-
ative squares, but they did not devise any special letter for such numbers,
nor did they give them the official status of “numbers.” The story of the
152 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

birth of the complex numbers, in the sixteenth century, is intriguing. The


mathematicians of the sixteenth century simply brushed off quadratic equa-
tions such as x2 = −9 as unsolvable, which averted the need to invent
new numbers. But at that time mathematicians already were capable of
solving third- and forth-order equations, and an embarrassing phenomenon
emerged: at times an equation had real-number solutions, but complex
numbers were needed in an interim stage of the solution. Since, in this
case, they were not willing to forgo the solutions, the mathematicians
of the time were forced to acknowledge the existence of numbers with a
negative square.
As often happens, the seemingly purely theoretical entity proved
extremely useful. Complex numbers have applications in wave theory, elec-
trical engineering, quantum theory, and many other fields. Why is this so?
Mainly because of a magic formula, discovered by Euler.

The world’s most beautiful formula?

Mathematical beauty contests can be held by category: theorems, proofs,


formulas. In the formulas division, there are no contestants to Euler’s for-
mula:
eiπ = −1
Note that in this short formula four of mathematics most important num-
bers appear: 1, π, e, i, as well as the minus sign. Euler’s contemporaries were
so enchanted by this formula that they expected it to reveal the secrets of the
universe. This didn’t happen, but the formula is unquestionably important,
and is totally unexpected. Its real importance lies in it being a special case
of a more general formula, also by Euler. This formula states that for every
real number x (and, actually, for complex numbers, as well), the following
holds true:
eix = cos(x) + i sin(x)
On the right side, an angle x is measured in “radians”; a radian is approx-
imately 57◦ . The precise definition of a radian is: 2π radians (that is, approx-
imately 6.28 radians) are 360◦ , which means that π radians are 180◦ . The
formula eiπ = −1 is obtained by substituting π for x, since cos(π) = −1
Reality or Imagination 153

and sin(π) = 0. The trigonometric functions cos(x) and sin(x) are the basic
tools used to describe waves. This explains why the formula is so useful in
physics and in electrical engineering, where waves play a central role. Euler’s
formula states that when applied to the complex numbers, the trigonometric
functions and raising to a power are almost the same.
Unexpected Combinations

Eureka

Hiero, the king of Syracuse, assigned Archimedes (the greatest mathemati-


cian of the ancient world, 287–212 BCE) the task of checking the purity
of the gold in the crown that had been prepared for him. Archimedes was
soaking in his bath, when he suddenly made the connection between Hiero’s
problem and his sensation of weightlessness in the water. The words “Eureka!
Eureka!” (I discovered! I discovered!) that the legend has him shouting when
he ran into the street nude, have been used ever since for discoveries, whether
earth-shattering or not. This discovery gave birth to the famous Archimedes
principle, which states that the loss of weight of a body in water is the same as
the weight of the displaced water, that is, the same as the weight of the part of
the body immersed in a liquid, if this part were composed of the same liquid.
Arthur Koestler, the Jewish-Hungarian-English author of The Act of
Creation argued that this is the only way creative ideas are born. Every
creation comes into being by combining ideas. In other words, creativity is
not ex nihilo, out of the blue, but connects existing ideas. As Koestler put
this, it is the result of the meeting of two planes of thought. He called this
process “bissociation.” A classic example is the discovery of vaccine by Louis
Pasteur. In one of his experiments, Pasteur infected chickens with cholera
germs. One day, returning from his summer vacation and not wishing to
throw away the culture of germs that remained from before the summer, he
infected a batch of chickens with it. The chickens became only mildly ill, and
quickly recovered. This wasn’t surprising, since the germs were old and weak.
The surprise was that when Pasteur’s assistants tried to infect these chickens
with regular cholera germs, they did not develop the disease. When Pasteur
heard of this, he stared for a moment, and then said: “Don’t you see? They
were vaccinated!” This was not only one of the most useful flashes of insight
in human history, but also one of the brightest, since the term “vaccinated”
did not mean then what it means today. At the time the word “vaccine”
(from “vacca,” the Latin word for “cow”) referred to a process discovered by

155
156 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the English physician William Jenner about a century earlier. Jenner heard
from villagers that humans who had been infected by cowpox were immune
to human smallpox, and recommended that humans be intentionally infected
with cowpox. He knew nothing about the mechanism behind this process,
and didn’t dream about such creatures as germs. Pasteur understood this
mechanism in a flash, linking Jenner’s procedure with what had happened
to his chickens.
Many scientists attest of themselves that they made their discoveries in
this same way. Michael Atiyah, a great twentieth-century mathematician,
tells that he would talk with people about their work, hear ideas from all
different directions, and often things would connect with the problems that
occupied him at that particular time. Richard Feymann explained how easy
it is to become a genius. “It is easy,” he testified. “I just roll in my brain the
problem with which I am concerned at the time, until something comes and
connects to it.”
In a way, this is how the most famous conjecture in mathematics, named
after Fermat, was solved. The conjecture (now theorem) stated that for any
number n larger than 2, there are no integers x, y, z, all different from 0,
for which xn + y n = z n . This was also known as “Fermat’s Last Theorem,”
since Fermat claimed that he had proved it. He used to write down his
discoveries in the margins of his copy of Euclid’s geometry book. He wrote
this conjecture in the margin, and next to it: “I have a wonderful proof,
but there isn’t enough room to write it.” The conjecture remained open
for some 350 years, and tortured generations of mathematicians with the
mocking simplicity of its formulation. A decisive step in the direction of
its solution was the discovery of an unexpected connection with a conjecture
that was formulated in the 1950s, and that seemed completely unrelated, the
Taniyama-Shimura Conjecture. When the latter was solved in 1995 by the
Englishman Andrew Wiles (with a proof that was too long for the margins
of any book), Fermat’s Conjecture was proved together with it.
Koestler’s claim that every discovery is the result of joining together
previous ideas is probably an exaggeration. A completely new idea, unrelated
to known conceptions, has to appear every once in a while. But we cannot
deny that this is one of the richest sources of beauty.

Unexpected combinations in poetry

The melody you abandoned for naught yet returns


And the eye of the way opens wide.
Unexpected Combinations 157

The appearance of unexpected combinations is the most expected occurrence


in poetry. Take, for example, the above two lines, that open Nathan Alter-
man’s book of poetry Stars Outside. The wording “eye of the way” perplexes
the reader who must then search within himself: will going along the way
open worlds for the walker, like the opening of one’s eyes? Is the way to be
found more in his eyes than outside? Here is another Alterman combination,
the beginning of “Endless Encounter” (the second poem in Stars Outside):

For you stormed upon me, forever I will play thee


For nought a wall will stop you up, for nought I will erect barriers!

The storm joins the playing of music and the frothy river that nothing can
withstand, and we realize that even a beloved one can be played. The poem
then moves on to combinations such as “warring street, dripping raspberry
syrup,” “cities of trade, painful and deaf.”
Unexpected combinations means bringing together distant patterns, and
finding likeness between them. We saw that, in the eyes of many poets, this
is the main characteristic of poetry. The poetical combination can be odd,
but it is never arbitrary. It uncovers a true similarity between two patterns.
Indeed, there is a likeness between opening one’s eyes and the unfolding of
the way as one walks. “Warring street,” or “street dripping raspberry” are
apt combinations, not because a street can fight or drip blood, but because
the lover fights a lost battle, and he drips pain. In terms of the external world,
there isn’t much logic there, in terms of inner meanings there certainly is.

Harnessed together

You shall not plow with an ox and an ass together.

Deuteronomy 22:10
There is a term in Greek rhetoric known as “syllepsis,” meaning joining far
apart elements. Nathan Alterman was a master of such combinations.

From silence and glass panes


the nights of June are brittle

Nathan Alterman, “A Poem about Your Face,” Stars Outside


The reader is forced to seek the meaning of these words within himself.
Perhaps he will see in his mind’s eye walking on a quiet street in front of
windowpanes, or think how fragile is the quiet, and how precious. See, for
158 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

example what happens in another poem by Alterman from Stars Outside,


“The Marketplace in the Sunshine”:

With the dust gathering, despotic, and bubbling tumult,


With the fiery apples and in the storm of the oil,
With the cry of the iron bending to the smith,
With the thousand shields of the tin tubs,

The marketplace stands,


Foaming in the sun!

Nathan Alterman, “The Marketplace in the Sunshine,” Stars Outside


The richness of the marketplace demands a wealth of imagery. The poem
speaks of the noise and tumult in terms of light, and then ascribes to it the
human traits of a king. The fire is linked to apples (possibly referring to the
shape of the flame); the iron “bends” (like before a king); the tubs are the
shields of knights; the light joins a river’s foam — there are many more than
just two planes of thought here.

Nathan Alterman (1910–1970), born in Warsaw, Poland; immigrated to Palestine in 1925.


What is Mathematics?

The hard life of the definer

They say there is love in the world.


What is love?

Hayyim Nahman Bialik, “Take Me under Your Wing”

I shall not [. . . ] attempt further to define [pornography].


[. . . ] But I know it when I see it.

Potter Stewart, United States Supreme Court justice

We may not know quite what we mean by a beautiful poem, but


that does not prevent us from recognizing one when we read it.

Godfrey Harold Hardy, A Mathematician’s Apology

Ask a mathematician to define his profession, and chances are that he will
stutter. A physicist can say what it is that he studies, but a mathematician,
even after long years of research, will find it hard to define his occupation.
One of the common definitions of mathematics relates to its subject matter:
“the science of the number and shape.” In other words, numbers and geom-
etry. There is much truth to this. Almost every modern mathematical field
developed from one of these two fields, and almost every mathematical topic
has a geometric or numerical aspect. And strangely, the more mathematics
advances, the harder it becomes to separate the two: geometry contributes
to numbers, and numbers appear in geometry. But the reservation “almost”
is unavoidable: numbers or geometry appear in only almost every mathe-
matical field, not in all. For example, mathematical logic (which will be the
subject of a later chapter) touches upon neither numbers nor geometry. Or
take the ants puzzle in the first part: the concepts it used, — “collision,”
“change of direction” — were not numerical, and were hardly shape-related.

159
160 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Abstraction

If so, then what is special about mathematics? To answer, let me tell a story
from elementary school. When I go there I sometimes ask first-graders: how
many are 2 pencils and 3 pencils? The children learned that addition means
joining, so they join 2 pencils to 3 pencils, and find that they have 5 pencils.
Now I ask: how many are 2 erasers and 3 erasers? They immediately answer,
“5 erasers.”

“How do you know?”


“Because we saw that with the pencils.”
“So what?” I argue. “Maybe it is different for erasers?”

The children laugh. But my question is serious. Behind it lies the main
strength of mathematics: generality. Mathematics strips a situation of its
secondary details, and leaves the gist. In this case, the gist is that three
objects and two objects are five, regardless of their nature or arrangement
in space. Of course, we make abstractions all the time, and in every field of
thought. What is special about mathematics is that it takes abstraction to
an extreme, applying it to the most basic thought processes.
The classic example is the concept of number. Numbers were born by
the abstraction of the most fundamental thought process: the division of the
world into objects — separating the world into units and assigning them
names: “apple,” “family,” “state.” Counting means repeating the same unit
many times “2 apples,” “3 apples,” “4 apples”. . . .

Frege

The industrial revolution in nineteenth-century Europe had far-reaching con-


sequences, not only for man’s quality of life, but also for his self-perception.
Once it became clear that machines could replace human muscles and
skills, the path was short to the idea that man himself closely resembles a
machine. It is no surprise that Darwin’s theory of evolution, which changed
man’s view of his place in the world, came into being at that time, and
in England, the cradle of the industrial revolution. All this quickly led
to the idea that a machine could replace humans in thought, as well. In
the middle of the nineteenth century Charles Babbage attempted to build
an innovative calculating machine. Indeed, the mathematician-philosopher
What is Mathematics? 161

Blaise Pascal preceded him in building a calculating machine, but Bab-


bage’s machine had a wonderful feature: it could be programmed. Bab-
bage did not complete his project (a machine constructed by his blueprint
was made only a century and a half later), but the idea made waves in
England.
About twenty years later, in the 1870s, a mathematician-philosopher
named Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), from the University of Jena in Germany,
conceived of an even more ambitious idea. He proposed that not only could
a machine conduct mathematical operations, but also human thought itself
behaves like a machine. And if thought is mechanical, then it can be studied
mathematically, just like the movements of celestial bodies or the flow of
liquid in a pipe. Of all human thought, it is mathematics that obeys the
clearest and best-defined laws, and hence should be studied first. This was a
staggering idea: investigating mathematical thought in a mathematical way.
In other words, devising a mathematics of mathematics (or “metamathe-
matics,” as this is often called).
In the computer age, such an idea seems natural. Today we know that
machines can think, and that their thinking can be the subject of mathe-
matical study. At the end of the nineteenth century, when even Darwin’s
theory was fresh and controversial, this was a daring insight. It required
man to surrender his last claim to uniqueness: abstract thought. In hind-
sight, this was a turning point no less significant than Babbage’s calculating
machine.
Mathematical thought has many facets: constructing concepts that corre-
spond to phenomena in the world, forming conjectures, and building theories.
But there is a single part that mathematicians value most: proof. Frege lim-
ited himself to this aspect of mathematical thought, mainly because it is
amenable to formalization. He argued that a proof is a mechanical process,
a game with symbols on paper, that obeys clear, and even quite simple rules.
It is a “game” in the sense that it has rigid rules, that are not essentially
different from, say, those of chess. There are permitted moves, and there are
forbidden ones. Frege defined a proof as a series of sentences written (let us
say) on paper, each of which ensues from its predecessors, by one of a limited
number of deductive rules. It is easy for us, living in the twenty-first century,
to accept this idea, because this is the way that a computer works. A com-
puter thinks by taking a series of symbols encoded in electrical signals, and
acting on them in accordance with the rules programmed into it. It receives
as input a series of symbols, and produces as output another series of sym-
bols. Today, all this is self-understood; in Frege’s time, understanding that
162 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

a formal operation on symbols on paper could be considered as “thought”


was a breakthrough.
Frege’s ideas appeared first in a paper, and then in a book published in
1879 that was intended to be the first of three volumes on the foundations
of arithmetic. The book was almost totally ignored. The only reaction was a
devastating review by Georg Cantor (whom we already met in the chapter
“The Real Numbers”). As we will see, Cantor himself, in his turn, would
receive similar treatment by other mathematicians. The embittered Frege
published a second volume, in which he attacked the mathematicians of his
time. An intended third volume never appeared.
It might have taken humankind even longer to digest Frege’s discoveries,
but for the fact that Bertrand Russell had as a child a German nanny, and
therefore knew German. Russell traveled to Germany, read Frege’s articles,
and understood their importance. Once he returned to England he enlisted
the help of his teacher at Cambridge, Alfred North Whitehead, to a mega
task: writing parts of the mathematics of the time in the formal language
devised by Frege. The result of their work, Principia Mathematica, was a
heavy, almost unreadable, book, but changed the course of the subject called
“mathematical logic.”
For Frege, mathematics means playing with symbols. The mathematician
chooses a system of axioms, such as the axioms of number theory (for exam-
ple: “For every number n, n + 0 = n”). Then, he examines which theorems
can be proved from the axioms, in accordance with rigid and predetermined
rules of proof. As I already mentioned, this is a narrow perspective of math-
ematics. It ignores, for example, the step of selecting the axioms: why was a
particular system chosen, and not another? Systems of axioms do not just
spring out of the blue. They are meant to describe reality. The quality of the
system of axioms will determine whether they will lead to profound conclu-
sions, or will be barren. As experience witnesses, if the axioms come from
reality, they will prove to be fertile.
Frege tells us that the correctness of a proof can be checked mechanically.
And how about the much more important task, of finding proofs, namely the
act of proving itself? As we shall soon see, there is no mechanical way of doing
this. There are no recipes for proving theorems. And as of today, computers
lack the intuition that leads mathematicians to their proofs. I personally
believe that one day this aspect of mathematical thought, as well, will be
What is Mathematics? 163

understood, and computers will be capable of proving theorems, formulating


conjectures, and, in short — replacing mathematicians in all aspects of their
work. And when this happens, it will be thanks to Frege and his work.

Gottlob Frege (Germany, 1848–1925), mathematician and philosopher.


Deep Tautologies

It is like a déjà vu all over again.

Yogi Berra, baseball player

The vast majority of our imports come from outside the country.

George W. Bush

I always thought that record would stand until it was broken.

Yogi Berra

All mathematics is tautology

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Austrian philosopher, 1889–1951

What is the difference between mathematics and


philosophy? In mathematics, someone important is someone
who said something important. In philosophy, something
important is something that somebody important said.

Anonymous mathematician
In 1820 Gauss suggested that in order to communicate with intelligent inhab-
itants of the moon, if there are such, forests should be cleared in Siberia to
create a picture of the Pythagorean theorem (the same drawing that appears
in the chapter “Mathematical Harmonies”). This theorem is valid everywhere
in the universe, it was always there, and Pythagoras only had to discover it.
In other words, its information is hidden in its assumptions. Seemingly, it
does not really contain any new information, namely, it is a tautology. This
is what Wittgenstein claimed in the above quotation.
“Tautologia” in Greek means “an identical word.” It is an empty state-
ment that contains no new information. “Water is wet,” for example. A
“tautological argument” in logic means an argument that is always true,
such as: “If today is Tuesday, then today is Tuesday.” By what we saw

165
166 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

in the preceding chapter, a mathematical proof is a chain of tautologies.


Each line in it ensues, aided by tautologies, from the preceding lines. This,
however, is still distant from the conclusion reached by Wittgenstein in the
quotation above, that mathematics is a collection of tautologies, because the
challenge lies in connecting these tautologies in the right order. The correct
theorem must be guessed, and the right lines to be added must be found.
The Pythagorean theorem is indeed a combination of tautologies, but this
doesn’t mean that it is void of information, because it is an intelligent combi-
nation. “A proof is a nontrivial combination of trivial statements,” as one of
my teachers once said. As we all know, everything is easy after its discovery.
Once the proof is given in full, it is child’s play to check its correctness. The
work lies in discovering it — that is, knowing in which direction to go. To
say that “mathematics is tautological” is like saying that the Eiffel Tower is
nothing more than a collection of metal rods and screws.

Tautologies with a message

Something similar happens in poetry: there, too, apparent tautologies often


convey hard truths. Poetical tautologies are written with a wink: the empti-
ness is misleading. The next poem, by Nathan Zach, “I Hear Something
Fall,” is a chain of tautologies.

I hear something fall, said the wind.


Nothing, this is just the wind, the mother reassured.

You are guilty and you, too, are guilty, the judge
ruled for the accused. Man is only a man,
the doctor explained to the stunned relatives.

But why, why, the youth asked himself,


not believing his eyes.

Those who don’t live in the valley live on the hill


the geography teacher said
with no special zeal.

But only the wind that let the apple fall


remembered what the mother hid from her son:

That no consolation will ever, ever come.


Nathan Zach, “I Hear Something Fall,” from Other Poems
Deep Tautologies 167

Amusing? Perhaps. But it is also hard to miss the despair. The heroes of
the poem face the empty statements dumbfounded, and the message is that
man’s very existence is filled with despair; that nothing specific needs to be
known in order to realize the finality of life.

Haiku poems

Haiku is a strict Japanese poetic style, with exactly 17 syllables (in the
original). Haiku poems frequently depict a nature scene that relates to
a specific season. The Japanese poetry scholar R. H. Blyth said that
haiku poems are always tautological. They contain no new informa-
tion. Haiku poems are more about what does not happen than about
what does:

Darkening sea
voices of the wild ducks
faint whitely away.
Matsu Basho, 1644–1694
Externally, the ducks have gone. Internally, something has happened: their
voices left their mark upon the listener. The minimalism of the outside action
leaves a place for inner action.

Arriving alone
to visit someone alone
in the autumn dusk.
Yosa Buson, 1715–1783
The wording “Arriving alone to visit someone alone” is almost a tautology.
But who visits whom is not important — what is significant is what happens
within oneself, and the dusky autumn sensation that arises upon reading the
poem.

The old pond;


A frog jumps in —
The sound of the water
Matsu Basho, trans. R. H. Blyth
The frog, like the ducks, vanished. And yet another tautology: the sound of
the water, Blyth writes, is subsumed within the old pond — there is nothing
new here.
168 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Dawn rises
the storm is buried
in shrouds of snow.
Edo Watsujin, 1758–1836

Yet the day after the storm


the redness of the pepper.
Matsu Basho
These poems tell us: “the tempests beyond are unimportant,” and what
happens within is not dependent on the external events, as it would seem.

A camelia blossom fell.


A rooster crowed.
Another blossom fell.
Sakurai Baishitsu, 1768–1852
Symmetry

Tyger! Tyger burning bright


In the forests of the night
What immortal hand or eye
Could frame thy fearful symmetry.
William Blake, “Songs of Innocence and Experience”

Economy by symmetry

In a schoolbook that I had as a child there was a story about a king who
assigned to two artists the task of painting the royal chamber, one side of
the chamber to each. One artist labored for months, while the other just sat
idly. On the last day, after the first artist had completed his work, the other
artist placed mirrors on his side. The king came, and was greatly impressed
by the paintings on the first side. When he came to the other side, the second
artist showed him that his side had just as fine paintings. The king paid the
first artist his wages, and said to the other: “Here, you see the bills in the
mirror? You can take them on your side.”
Mathematicians are very fond of the second artist’s stratagem. Mathe-
matics never spares effort in order to spare effort, and it often, and very
successfully, uses symmetry for this purpose. There is no need to work twice
when a single time will do. Here is a famous example:
Two people are situated on the same side of stream L, one at point A and the
other at point B. This is a mathematical stream, namely, it is a straight line.
The person at B is dying of thirst, and the person at A wants to bring him
water from the stream, as quickly as possible. He has to go to L, and from there
to B. What route will he choose, so that he will have the shortest distance to
go? That is, what is the shortest (broken) line that touches L and connects A
with B?

In order to answer the question, we will reflect B with respect to L, which


gives us point B .

169
170 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The shortest broken line from A to B is obtained by reflecting the stream part of the line
from A to B , the reflection of B.

Every line that connects A with B and meets L corresponds to a line of


the same length that connects A with B . The shortest line connecting A
with B is of course the straight line. And so, in order to find the desired
line between A and B, connect A to B with a straight line, and reflect
with respect to L the part of the line on the side of B . Note that on the
line we obtain, the so called “angle of incidence” α equals the “angle of
reflection” β.
This is useful in physics. The principle of minimization of energy states
that a light beam passes between two points (even if reflected from a mirror)
along the shortest path — nature economizes.
The way to build an arch is another example of economy by reflection. As
is common knowledge, the Romans were no great innovators, and they bor-
rowed elements of their culture from the peoples that they conquered, espe-
cially from the Greeks. They took the use of arches in building from the Etr-
uscans, the inhabitants of Italy before them. This was an amazing invention:
self-supporting bricks, that do not need cement to bind them together. In
the ideal arch the pressure on each of the bricks is as small as possible, which
means that the pressure is distributed evenly among the bricks. In a circular
arch, which is probably the most natural and most common type, this condi-
tion is not fulfilled, because the stones on the sides of the arch are subjected
to greater pressure than those in the middle. So then, what is the correct
shape for an arch? This can be determined by calculations that are not espe-
cially complicated (the tool needed is differential equations). But there is a
simpler method, that avoids calculations: leaving this to nature. Instead of
building an arch, hang a string. Take a string of the length of the desired arch,
and hang it from two points as far apart as the distance between the arch
ends. The string will naturally assume a shape in which the tension is equally
distributed. Now all that remains is to turn the string over, so that its arch
points up. The Spanish architect Antonio Gaudi used this trick to plan his
buildings.
Symmetry 171

The round table game

Here is a game for two players. The players sit at a round table, and each
has an unlimited quantity of same size coins. Each in turn places a single
coin in an empty spot. The winner is the player who places the last coin,
that is, after his move there is no room left for the other player to place a
coin. Which player can assure a victory?
The answer is that the opening-move player has a strategy for winning.
He places a coin exactly in the center of the table. After this, he adopts
a mirror (or monkey) strategy: for every coin that the other player places
anywhere, he places a coin symmetrically, on the opposite side. This strategy
ensures that after each move the coin situation will be symmetrical, that is,
every coin has a matching coin opposite it. This guarantees the first player
a win, because he always can make a return move: since the coin placement
is symmetrical, if there is a spot open for the second player, there will also
be an (exactly opposite) opening for the first.

The first player places a coin in the center. Now, for every move by his opponent, he will
place a coin exactly opposite.
172 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The second player cannot use the mirror strategy, because of the unique
opening move of the first player, that cannot be mirrored: there is no sym-
metrical response to placing a coin in the center. By the way, the table
doesn’t have to be circular. This same strategy works for a rectangular or
elliptical table, because they, too, have a center.

Dido’s problem
A shepherd is given a rope, and is told that he can use it to fence off an area
as he wishes. Which shape should he choose, in order to fence off as large an
area as possible?

This is known as the “isoperimetric problem,” since it seeks a shape


of maximal area, given its perimeter (“isoperimetric” means “equal
perimeter”). Another common name is “Dido’s Problem,” after the first
queen of Carthage. Dido’s brother, the despotic ruler of the city-state of
Tyre, murdered her rich husband and expelled her as well. With compan-
ions, Dido landed on the shore of present-day Tunisia. For a sum of money,
the tightfisted locals promised to give her a patch of land that she could fence
off with the hide of one ox. Dido cut the hide into strips, which she joined
together into a single chord. She could use this chord to fence off an area, one
side of which was the sea shore. The question is: what shape should she have
chosen for this area? Dido made the right choice: a semicircle. This is half
of the shepherd’s problem with which we began this section. The solution
to the shepherd’s problem, as can easily be guessed, is the shape with the
greatest symmetry, namely, a circle.
Before explaining why this is so, we should first look at a simpler problem.
Let us assume that the shepherd doesn’t want to build his pen in just any
shape, but as a rectangle. Obviously, different types of rectangles can be
chosen, such as a very high and very narrow rectangle, or one that is very
wide and very low. Which one should the shepherd select? If we take “very
narrow” to an extreme, that is, a rectangle of width 0, its area will be 0; and
also if we take “very low” to an extreme, its area will be 0. We can imagine
that the optimal solution is in the middle between these two extremes, that is,
a square. This is indeed the case. The shepherd should mark off a square
with his rope.
Here is a simple proof. Let L stand for the average length of the sides of
the rectangle. That is, L is the perimeter of the rectangle (which is the length
of the rope) divided by 4. So, the perimeter is 4L. The sum of the lengths
Symmetry 173

of two adjoining sides is half the rectangle’s perimeter, which is 2L. Assume
that the length of one of the two adjoining sides is L + X. Since the sum of
the lengths of the adjoining sides is 2L, the length of the other side is L − X
(since L + X + L − X = 2L). The area of the rectangle is the product of the
lengths of the adjoining sides, which in this instance is (L + X) × (L − X).
When we open the parentheses, we obtain (L + X) × (L − X) = L2 − X 2 .
But X 2 cannot be negative. Accordingly, L2 − X 2 does not exceed L2 , which
is the area of the square with the same perimeter (each of whose sides is L
long). The smaller X is (that is, the closer the sides’ length to each other),
the larger the area of the rectangle.

The square and the rectangle in the picture have the same perimeter (4L). The area of
the square is greater.

Assume now that the shepherd still has to choose a rectangle, but he
can use the bank of a stream as one of the boundaries of his pen (just as
in Dido’s Problem). As usual, we will assume that this is a mathematical
stream, that is, a straight line. What shape should the shepherd choose for
his rectangle? Here, too, formulas could be used, but it is simplest to rely
on symmetry. The shepherd’s area is mirrored across the stream bank line.
The combination of the original rectangle with the reflected one is the
rectangular area that does not make use of the stream. Its entire perimeter
is a rope (albeit one that is partially imaginary) twice the length of the
shepherd’s rope. Consequently, the new (doubled) rectangle’s perimeter is
fixed; and as we already know, its area is maximal if it is a square. Since
the area of the shepherd’s original rectangle is half of the overall rectangular
area, the shepherd would do well to choose half a square.

Back to Dido and the isoperimetric problem

In the original (isoperimetric) problem, the shepherd is not limited in his


choice of shape for his pen, and he can choose any shape he wishes. As we
already mentioned, then he should choose a circular area. This argument is
called the “isoperimetric inequality”:
174 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The shepherd wants to use his rope to build a rectangle to the left of the stream, with
the stream itself being one side. The reflection of this rectangle (the dotted line) yields a
rectangle with a perimeter twice as long as the rope, and an area twice that of the
original rectangle. Of all the rectangles with a perimeter twice the length of the rope, a
square has the largest area. Therefore, the shepherd should choose a rectangle that is
half a square.

Of all the shapes with a given perimeter, the circle has the greatest area.

This theorem also has a three-dimensional version, which, too, is intuitive,


but harder to prove: of all the bodies with a given surface area, a sphere has
the largest volume. This is one of the reasons why mammals’ heads are quite
round. Why doesn’t man utilize this, and build more spherical structures?
Among other reasons, because spheres cannot be packed perfectly. It is much
easier to pack rectangles and boxes. This is why rooms in houses, for example,
have right angled corners.
But let us return to the two-dimensional case. It is not difficult to guess
that the circle is the optimal shape, it is harder to prove this. While the the-
orem was already guessed by the ancient Greeks, an (almost) rigorous proof
was given only in the middle of the nineteenth century, by the Swiss Jacob
Steiner (1796–1863), a contemporary of Gauss. Steiner was an autodidact,
and said that he hated formulas (he claimed that they hide the ideas) and
loved geometry. He used the concept of symmetry, but in the direction oppo-
site to the one used above in the rectangle case. In the case of the rectangle,
we concluded from the whole regarding its half; now, following Steiner, we
shall go from the part to the whole. Like the artist in the story, we will solve
half the problem, and derive our solution for the whole from it. As in Dido’s
story, the shepherd will be told that he may mark off a pen with his rope
(of fixed length), and that one side of the pen will be the bank of a river.
Symmetry 175

It is best for the shepherd (like Dido) to choose a semicircle. To show this,
assume that the shepherd used his rope and the line L to mark off a pen of
maximal area. A and B will be the points of contact between the rope and
L (see the drawing).

If the rope bounds a maximal area with the line L, then every point X on the rope “sees”
the segment AB at a right angle.

We have to prove that the shape chosen by the shepherd has to be a


semicircle with A and B as its ends. To show this, we will make use of a
well-known geometric fact: when a semicircle of diameter AB is constructed,
every point X on the semicircle “sees” the segment AB at a right angle. In
other words, for any point X on the semicircle, AXB is a right angle. What
is important for our purposes is that the opposite is true as well: any point
that sees the segment AB at a right angle and is located above this segment
is located on a semicircle the diameter of which is AB. Accordingly, all we
have to prove is that every point on the rope sees the segment AB at a right
angle, which will show that the rope is arranged in the shape of a semicircle.
All this, of course, based on the assumption that the shepherd marked off a
maximal area.
In order to understand the connection between the angle and the area,
let us conduct a simple experiment, Extend both arms straight out (without
bending them at the elbows), with some angle between them, and think
of a triangle whose points are your head and your two hands. What angle
should you form with your arms to form a triangle with the greatest possible
area? If you spread your arms completely to the sides, that is, at an angle of
180◦ , the triangle will be completely flat, and its area will be 0. If you raise
both arms straight up, and parallel (that is, at an angle of 0◦ ; if your body
didn’t get in the way, they would be the same line), the area of the triangle,
once again, will be 0. It is not hard to prove that the best case has your
hands perpendicular, that is, at a right angle. The proof of this fact uses the
formula for the area of a triangle as “the base times the height, divided by
2.” Formally stated, given the sides XA and XB (the “arms”) whose vertex
is X (the “head”), in order to create the triangle of maximal area whose
points are A, B, and X, the sides must meet at a right angle.
176 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Let us assume that there is a point X on the curve for which the angle
AXB is not a right angle (that is, not 90◦ ). Now modify the curve by changing
this angle to 90 degrees, without changing the two arcs over AX and over
BX (see the next drawing). According to the argument, the area is larger —
in contrast with the assumption that the curve bounds with L a maximal
area.

The right-hand picture is derived from the left-hand one by closing the span between the
sides XA and XB, so as to make them perpendicular. The domes C and D are preserved.
The length of the curve (the rope) is not thereby changed. The total area increased,
because the area of the triangle increased, while the area of the two domes remained as it
was.

Having worked hard to solve the riverbank case, we can use this to solve
our original problem, of the shepherd who does not have a stream that can
bound part of his area. In order to show that it is best for him to mark off
a circular area with his rope, we will assume that he chose an area of some
other shape. Take two points on the rope, A and B, that divide the rope
(that forms a closed shape) into two parts of equal length (see the left-hand
drawing):

The two shapes have the same perimeter. The circle on the right was obtained by
replacing the upper and lower parts (both of which are between A and B) in the
left-hand shape by semicircles. According to what we already proved, this increases the
area, and therefore the area of the circle is larger than that of the left-hand shape. This
is the isoperimetric inequality.

Replacing both the bottom and top parts of the shape with semicircles
will increase its area. To see this, draw a line between A and B, and note
that by the riverbank case, each part of the shape cut by this line increases
Symmetry 177

in area. But this is tantamount to replacing the entire shape by a circle —


and this is exactly what we wanted to prove.

Symmetry in poetry

An old man, what has he in his life?


He wakes in the morning, but morning doesn’t wake in him.

David Avidan, “A Sudden Evening,” Pressure Poems


These are the opening lines of a poignant poem on old age by a 28-year-
old. David Avidan, the enfant terrible of Hebrew poetry, was born in 1934.
When he died in 1996, alone and penniless, it was hard not to recall this
poem. I quoted it here because of the second line, that uses a poetic device
called “chiasmus”: the words “wake in the morning” are exchanged, to pro-
duce “a morning that (doesn’t) wake in him.” The term chiasmus has its
source in the Greek letter χ, called “chi” (with the German guttural kh).
In this example, the chiasmus proceeds from the outside in, from the morn-
ing outside to the morning (that is not) inside. The same happens in the
continuation of the poem:

He shuffles to the kitchen, and there


the lukewarm water reminds him
that at his age, that at his age, that at his age,
an old man — what has he in his mornings?
He arises on a summer morning, and already fall
mixes with evening in the light bulb above.

Once again, the outside is reflected within: the lukewarm water reminds the
old man of his lukewarm blood and his lukewarm life. In the last line there
is mirror reflection, but of opposites: the summer without is reflected as
autumn within.
In Nathan Alterman’s powerful poem “The Foundling,” inner reality is
the mirror reflection of the external one. Externally, the mother abandons
her baby; her inner truth is that he has abandoned her. The incongruity
between the picture and its reflection in the mirror only grows throughout
the poem. The symmetry of roles is joined by a temporal symmetry: the end,
the mother’s death, is a mirror image of its beginning, the son’s birth; and
her shrouds are a mirror image of his infant clothes. Nathan Zach, the other
great “Nathan” of Hebrew poetry, who knew Alterman well, testified that
178 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the poem painfully reflects Alterman’s relationship with his parents. I have
selected three stanzas from this long poem:

At the foot of the fence my mother placed me,


face creased and still, on my back.
And I looked at her from below, as from a well, —
Until she fled as one flees from a battle.
And I looked at her from below, as from a well,
And a moon was raised over us like a candle.

[. . . ]

She grew old in my prison and lean and small


And her face became creased as my face.
Then my little hands clothed her in white
Like a mother clothing her living child.
Then my little hands clothed her in white
And I carried her off without telling her where.

And at the foot of the fence I placed her


Watchful and still, on her back.
And she looked at me laughing, as from a well,
And we knew that we ended the battle.
And she looked at me laughing, as from a well.
And a moon was raised over us like a candle.

Nathan Alterman, “The Foundling,” based on a translation of


B. Harshav, The Modern Hebrew Poem Itself, eds. S. Burnshaw et al.
Impossibility

Ruler and compass constructions

One of the greatest contributions of the Greeks to geometry, along with the
ideas of “theorem,” “proof,” and “axiom,” was the concept of construction
of geometric objects using only a ruler and compass. The ruler used for
such constructions has no markers of length, and therefore cannot be used
to measure distance, but only to draw straight lines between given points.
A compass is used to draw circles, and to draw equal segments (a segment
is a finite part of a line). While lengths cannot be measured using only ruler
and compass, lengths of segments can be compared, and a segment equal in
length to a given segment can be marked off on a line.
These do not seem to form an impressive arsenal of tools, but this is
misleading. In actuality, much can be accomplished using these two simple
devices. A parallel to a given line can be drawn, through a given point; a
perpendicular to a line can be drawn from a given point on or outside it; an
angle can be bisected; and a segment can be divided into any finite number
of equal parts. It is possible to construct a perfect hexagon (with equal sides
and equal angles), an octagon, and — as Gauss proved at the age of 19 —
even a perfect 17-sided polygon. Gauss was so proud of his discovery, that
was almost certainly the first significant geometric construction since the
time of the Greeks, that it led him to prefer mathematics to philology, his
other academic interest. He asked that a 17-sided polygon be inscribed on his
tombstone. The tombstone mason refused, claiming that it was impossible
to tell the difference between this shape and a circle. This injustice was
corrected fifty years later, on a monument erected in memory of the great
man.
When we speak of geometric constructions, we mainly think of finding
points, or of forming shapes. But there is another type of construction, that
of lengths. We are given a certain segment, that serves as the “measuring
rod,” namely, it is arbitrarily defined as 1 unit long. We then want to build
a segment of length 2 (that is, double the length of the given segment), or of

179
180 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

1
2 (half of the given segment), and so on. It is easy to multiply the length
of the segment by a whole number (by simply adding more and more copies
of the segment, one next to the other), and it is not difficult to divide a
segment into a whole number of equal parts. So segments of any rational
length can be constructed (in order, for example, to construct a segment of
length 35 multiply the segment by 3, and then divide the result into 5 equal
parts). Euclid, in the fourth century BC, already knew how to geometrically
extract a root. That is, given a segment of length a, he could also construct a

segment of length a. This is done, as in the drawing below, by constructing
a right angle triangle with a hypotenuse of length a, and such that the
projection of one of its sides on the hypotenuse is of length 1. In the drawing,
the length of the projected side is labeled x, and the length of this side
√ √
is a, that is, x = a. Why? The triangles ACB and ADC have equal
corresponding angles. This implies that they are similar, meaning that the
ratios between their sides are equal. So, AD AC 1
AC = AB or, in other words, x = a .
x

By multiplying the sides of the equation by the denominators (x and a), we



obtain the equality x2 = a, meaning that x = a.

This construction can be used when a is larger than 1. The case of a


being smaller than 1 requires another drawing, in which the roles of 1 and
a in the triangle are interchanged, namely, the length AB is taken as 1, and
the length AD is a.

Three impregnable fortresses

The power of the ruler and compass is indeed surprising. But three construc-
tion problems remained unsolved, and frustrated the efforts of both pro-
fessional and amateur mathematicians for more than two thousand years.
They withstood vigorous assaults first by the Greeks, and then by the
Impossibility 181

mathematicians of Renaissance Europe. As is usual for famous problems,


many erroneous proofs were proposed for each.

(1) The most famous of the three was squaring the circle: given a circle
of a certain radius (say, one unit), construct, with the aid of a ruler and
compass, a square with the same area as that of the circle. In a second
formulation: find a segment whose length equals the circumference of the
circle. The first to tackle the problem was Anaxagoras (499–428 BCE).
Aristophanes derided the circle squarers in his play The Birds, and ever
since “squaring the circle” has been synonymous with attempting to
achieve the impossible.
(2) Doubling the volume of a cube: in the chapter “Mathematical Har-
monies” we saw how, for a given square, it is possible to construct a
square with double the area. This is plainly a square, the side of which
is the same length as the diagonal of the original square. Can something
similar be done for volume? Namely, for a given cube, can the side of
a cube of double the volume be constructed with the aid of a ruler and
compass?
(3) Dividing an angle into three equal parts: bisecting an angle using
ruler and compass is simple. Can an angle also be divided into three
equal parts?

Thousands of years of failure should have alerted mathematicians to the


existence of some inherent difficulty. But the notion of impossibility of math-
ematical tasks did not emerge until the beginning of the nineteenth century.
When it did appear, these three problems were its first victims: all were
proved impossible. Gauss was the first to suspect this, but could not prove it.
The impossibility of trisecting an angle and of doubling a cube was proved
in 1837 by the French mathematician Pierre Wantzel (1814–1848), and the
impossibility of squaring the circle was proved by the German mathematician
Ferdinand von Lindemann (1852–1939) in 1880.
The underlying reason for the impossibility of all three constructions is
expressed in the same theorem. This theorem says that a segment of length
a can be constructed only if the number a meets two conditions:

(1) a must be the solution of a polynomial equation with integer coefficients.


(2) Among all the polynomial equations for which a is the solution, the
equation of the lowest order is of an order that is a power of 2 (that is,
the order must be 1, or 2, or 4, or 8, etc.).
182 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Examples:

(1) Take the equation a2 − 2 = 0. This is a second order equation, √ and


its order, 2, is a power of 2. Its solution, which is a = 2, is there-
fore constructible. Indeed, we saw that the square root of any already-
constructed length can be obtained with a ruler and compass. In the
chapter “Mathematical √ Harmonies” we also saw a very simple way to
construct a segment 2 long: it is the diagonal of a square with a side
of length 1.
(2) The equation a4 − 2 = 0, too, fulfills the above conditions, since it is of
order 4, which is a power of 2. Sure enough, it is possible to construct

a segment of the length that is its solution, that is, of length 4 2. The
√ √
reason: 4 2 is the root of 2. The latter we can construct, and hence
we can construct its root.

How does this theorem lead to the conclusion that squaring a circle is
impossible? Let us take the version of the problem that speaks of circum-
ference: “Construct a segment the length of the circumference of a circle
with radius 1.” The circumference of a circle with radius 1 is 2π. If we knew
how to construct a segment of length 2π, by halving it we would obtain a
segment of length π. I already mentioned (in the chapter “The Power of
the Oblique,”) that in 1768 Lambert proved the irrationality of π. In 1880
Lindemann proved even more: that π is “very irrational,” or in technical
terms “transcendent” or “non algebraic.” This means that it is not a solu-
tion of any polynomial equation with integer coefficients not all of which
are 0, let alone the solution of a polynomial satisfying the conditions above.
So, by the theorem, π cannot be constructed.
What about the other version of squaring the circle, that of constructing
a square whose area is that of a circle of a given radius? Taking the radius to
be 1, the area of such a circle is π, and therefore the length of a side of the

square must be π. But with a compass and ruler we can construct from a
pair of segments a segment that is the length of their product, and so, from a
segment of length a we can also construct a segment of length a2 . If we were

capable of constructing a segment of length π, we would therefore be able
√ 2
to construct a segment of length π , which is π. But, as we already know,
this is impossible, and so a segment of length π cannot be constructed.
As for doubling the volume of a cube, assume that we can double the
volume of a cube with a side of length 1, whose volume is 1 × 1 × 1 = 1.
Twice 1 is 2, so presumably we would succeed in constructing a cube of
volume 2. Let x be the length of this cube’s side. The volume of a cube with
Impossibility 183

a side√x is x3 , so x would satisfy x3 = 2, or x3 − 2 = 0 (in other words,


x = 3 2). The equation
√ x3 − 2 is of order 3, and there is no equation of a
3
lower order that 2 solves. Since 3 is not a power of 2, condition (2) then
3

rules out the possibility of constructing a segment of length 2.
The last problem was the division of an angle into three equal parts. If this
could be done with a compass and ruler, it would be possible, among other
angles, to divide an angle of 60◦ into three equal parts, that is, to construct
an angle of 20◦ . It would then be easy to use these tools to construct a right
angled triangle with a hypotenuse of length 1, one of whose angles is 20◦ . It
can be proved that the side of such a triangle solves third order polynomial
equations; and 3 is the minimum order of equations that they solve. Since
3 is not a power of 2, according to part (2) of the theorem, such a segment
cannot be constructed.
Since the proofs of the impossibility of the three classical construction
problems, many other impossibility results have been obtained. These are
usually hard and deep theorems. There is a straightaway approach to show
that something can be done: just do it. It is more difficult to demonstrate
that something cannot be done.
Infinitely Large

The eternal silence of these infinite spaces frightens me.

Blaise Pascal, 1623–1662

The riddle of hyperbole

The artist breathes tranquility even in his anxiety.

Nikolai Gogol, 1809–1852, Russian author

Poetry is the spontaneous overflow of powerful


feelings from emotions recalled in tranquility.

William Wordsworth, English poet, 1770–1850


Poetry makes every effort to be indirect. Like any art, it distances itself from
its subject. Its language is generally understated, muted, indirect, symbolic,
metaphoric, and pictorial. All these means enable poetry to touch things that
direct approach cannot. But this is not always so. At least one poetic device
seems to do the exact opposite: it intensifies emotions and feelings. I am
speaking of hyperbole. The Greek word means “throwing too far” (“hyper”
means “too much,” and “vole” means “throw”). Mathematics, too, borrowed
this term, to describe a curve that is “thrown” to infinity — a hyperbola is
one of the conic sections mentioned in the chapter “The Miracle of Order.”
In poetic hyperbole, things are taken to an extreme and assume colossal
dimensions. Here it is in the poem “Stop All the Clocks” (also known as
“Funeral Blues”) by W. H. Auden, that became famous through its appear-
ance in the movie Four Weddings and a Funeral. Although it was originally
written as a parody of a eulogy for a politician, the poem was also meant to
be serious — which is the way it is perceived today.

Stop all the clocks, cut off the telephone,


Prevent the dog from barking with a juicy bone,

185
186 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Silence the pianos and with muffled drum


Bring out the coffin, let the mourners come.

Let aeroplanes circle moaning overhead


Scribbling on the sky the message He is Dead,
Put crepe down round the white necks of the public doves,
Let traffic policemen wear black cotton gloves.

He was my North, my South, my East and West,


My working week and my Sunday rest,
My noon, my midnight, my talk, my song;
I thought that love would last forever; I was wrong.

The stars are not wanted now; put out every one:
Pack up the moon and dismantle the sun;
Pour away the ocean and sweep up the woods:
For nothing now can ever come to any good.

W. H. Auden, “Stop All the Clocks”

Resolving the contradiction

It does seem confusing. What is right: understatement or exaggeration?


Distance, or intensified emotions? Can hyperbole be an exception among
the poetic devices, the only stratagem that puts the cards on the table, and
even more so, takes the message to an extreme? If this were so, we would
have to abandon the idea of indirectness as the common denominator of
poetic techniques. Fortunately, there is no need for this. Actually, hyperbole
is not different in this respect from all other poetic devices. Like the others,
it, too, is a tool for detachment. It does so by imparting a larger-than-life
dimension to the experience. The proportions that things receive are beyond
our usual receptive ability, and are therefore experienced in a detached way.
When the poet’s mourning is shared by the entire universe, it is no longer
his. When things are larger than life, a person doesn’t really feel them. The
suffering becomes the world’s, and not his own.
This is best seen in the everyday use of hyperboles, for they are endlessly
used (here is one example: “endlessly”) in spoken language, as well. “I’d die
for some chocolate,” “I could eat a horse,” “this headache is killing me,”
“I’m at my wit’s end” (“I’m at my wit’s end, the ants have even started
Infinitely Large 187

climbing up the refrigerator”), “a ton of money.” What purpose do these


hyperboles serve? There is some truth in an exaggerated metaphor such as
“this headache is killing me” — it means that it hurts more than I can bear
or, in other words, more than I can handle with my usual tools.
The same holds true for hyperbole in poetry. Take, for example, the
poem “See the Sun” by the medieval Hebrew poet Solomon Ibn Gabirol
(1021–1058). Ibn Gabirol did not have an easy life. He was orphaned at a
very young age, and suffered throughout his short life from a terrible skin
disease and torturous digestion problems. He had one consolation in life —
the support of a rich benefactor named Yekutiel. “See the Sun” is a lament
on the death of his beloved patron.

See the sun gone red toward evening


as though it were wearing a crimson dress,
stripping the edges of north and south
and, in violet, lining the wind from the west:

and the earth — left in its nakedness —


takes refuge in the shadow of night, and rests,
and then the skies go black, as though
covered in sackcloth, for Yequtiel’s death.

Solomon Ibn Gabirol, “See the Sun,” trans.


P. Cole, Selected Poems of Solomon Ibn Gabirol

This amazingly modern poem derives its force from three poetic devices.
The first is the twist at its end. The poem’s true meaning is revealed only
in the last line. One of the later chapters of the book will be devoted to this
device. Here let me just explain that the beauty of a twist lies in the fact
that everything that came before suddenly receives new meaning, and the
reader has to absorb and comprehend a great deal all at once. It is only in
the last line that the reader realizes that the portrayal of the sunset and
the earth’s departure by the sun is only a metaphor for the poet’s sense of
abandonment upon the death of his patron. We must then decipher anew
all the preceding lines. Since conscious thinking cannot absorb so much so
quickly, the understanding remains partially subconscious. The second device
of the poem is displacement, the offhanded statement of the crux of the
matter. Yequtiel’s death is mentioned as part of a metaphor: “as if it is
covered by sackcloth.” Very similar to the displacement in Lea Goldberg’s
“About Myself,” in the chapter on displacement at the beginning of this
188 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

book. Yet, the strongest device is probably the third one: hyperbole. The
pain at Yequtiel’s death is attributed to the entire world — to the earth, the
skies, the sun. Projecting his mourning to the skies, it is easier for the poet
to bear his pain.
The beauty of hyperbole resembles that of a majestic landscape. A soaring
cliff, or a tremendous mountain, are not fully comprehended by the viewer.
We are accustomed to perceiving the world around us in practical terms, of
action, and the cliff or the mountain are too great to even imagine climbing.
Similarly, poetic hyperbole transports matters beyond ordinary perception,
resulting in absorption without conscious understanding.
Cantor’s Story

O, infinity! the most fascinating of mathematical concepts.

David Hilbert

Infinity is the place where things happen that don’t.

An interpretation of the concept of infinity,


attributed to an anonymous student

Georg Cantor (1845–1918), German mathematician; the founder of set theory.

A mathematical feud

Mathematics, too, has its hyperboles, things that are bigger than the dimen-
sions of the world to which we are accustomed, and so the rules that prevail

189
190 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

in them appear strange and wondrous. This is the concept of infinity. The
Greeks already were charmed by this notion and the paradoxes that it cre-
ates. But the stormiest turning point occurred at the end of the nineteenth
century — stormy in the literal sense, and not only mathematically. The
concept of infinity became a battleground.
Except for quarrels regarding claims of priority of discovery, there are
hardly any disputes in mathematics. A prominent exception is the story
of set theory, a field that was developed in the late nineteenth century by
Georg Cantor (1845–1918). Cantor’s idea was so novel and surprising that
the mathematics community needed about twenty years to digest it. In those
two decades wars were waged, polemical articles written, and blood was shed,
almost literally. In these wars, several of the period’s leading mathematicians
took the wrong side.
Cantor was not a quarrelsome person, nor did he intend to overturn
the established order. He was engaged in a classic field known as “Fourier
analysis,” that was originally developed to analyze wave patterns. Cantor
made important contributions to this field, but not revolutionary ones. One
day, however, for one of his proofs he needed the following fact: that there is
more than one kind of infinity. There are large infinite sets, and there are
even larger. Before Cantor, mathematicians regarded all the infinite sets as
equal. All were thought to be very big, and that is all. No one tried to classify
infinite sets by size. Cantor showed that, not only was such a classification
possible, it was also productive and important. Just as one number can be
larger than another, one infinite set can be larger than another. This was
the starting point for a new theory — set theory.
The fundamental concepts of set theory are surprisingly simple. Every-
thing evolves from a single concept: an element’s belonging to a set. This
simplicity might have been responsible for the mathematical community’s
reluctance to accept the new theory. About fifty years later, John von
Neumann would demonstrate that all of mathematics can be formulated
within the framework of set theory, but when Cantor introduced his ideas it
was hard to believe that such a simple concept could be used to say anything
of importance.
Mainly, however, it was another idea that had Cantor’s contemporaries
up in arms: regarding infinity as a tangible entity. The mathematicians of the
nineteenth century were proud of their recent success in providing a rigor-
ous foundation for differential and integral calculus. Since its discovery in the
seventeenth century, calculus had proved to be extremely useful, second only
to the concept of the number. But for almost two centuries this field rested
Cantor’s Story 191

on shaky foundations, its terms being only vaguely defined. The central con-
cepts in calculus, “tending to a limit” was left fuzzy. Only in the nineteenth
century several mathematicians, notably Augustine-Louis Cauchy, Bernhard
Riemann, and Karl Weierstrass, provided precise definitions for these terms.
In these definitions infinity is something seen from afar but never reached.
Tending to infinity means that numbers become as large as we wish, but they
never reach infinity. Gauss reproached a friend with whom he corresponded:
“I must vigorously protest against the use you make of the term infinity, as
something that can be reached. Infinity is only a manner of speaking, mean-
ing numbers that are as large as we wish.” To this way of thinking, infinity is
“potential,” not “actual.” Having just exorcised the devil of actual infinity,
namely infinite quantities that exist on their own right, the mathematical
community was enraged to find Cantor bringing it back through the back
door.
Prominent mathematicians, led by the famous Leopold Kronecker, dispar-
aged Cantor’s theory, claiming it was worthless. Henri Poincaré, one of the
major mathematicians of the time, said that set theory was “a childhood
disease, from which mathematics would eventually recover,” and accused
Cantor of “corrupting the youth” — the same charge for which Socrates had
paid with his life some 2,300 years earlier. Unlike Socrates, Cantor was not
executed, but he did not receive a coveted university position. The attacks
against him further fueled the prolonged depression from which he suffered,
and he ended his days in a mental institution. Too late for him to enjoy, but
still in his lifetime, his theory was finally victorious, and its importance was
universally recognized. Nowadays, set theory is taught in first-year university
mathematics courses.

Why numbers are unnecessary to compare sets

The first hurdle that Cantor had to overcome was definition. In order to
speak of larger and smaller infinite sets, a precise definition is needed for
these terms. But first, an even more basic question must be answered: when
are two sets of equal size? For finite sets, the answer is clear: two sets are
of equal size if they contain the same number of elements. A set of 5 books
is equal in size to one of 5 pencils. But in the infinite case, we don’t have
numbers at our disposal. Here, Cantor had an extraordinary insight: numbers
aren’t really needed. Equality of set size can be defined without them, even
in the finite case. For example, in order to prove that each of your two hands
has the same number of fingers, you don’t have to count the fingers on each
192 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

hand. Just match them, by putting your hands against each other. This is
called “correspondence”:

Two sets A and B are of equal size if there exists a correspondence, assign-
ing to each element of A an element of B, in such a way that each element
from B corresponds to exactly one element from A.

There is a one to one correspondence between the set of flowerpots and the set of flowers,
that is, exactly one flower corresponds to each flowerpot, and vice versa. This shows that
the two sets are of the same size. This definition skips the concept of number, and can be
used for infinite sets, as well.

Another name for correspondence is “function.” If the function is named,


say, f , then for the element x of set A the corresponding element in B is writ-
ten as f (x). The correspondence showing equality of sizes of sets is required
to fulfill the following: for every element y in the set B there is exactly one
element x in the set A for which f (x) = y. Just as in the fingers example.
Cantor might have been the first, after thousands of years of mathemat-
ics, to realize that numbers are merely intermediaries. The fact that a person
has 5 fingers on his right hand means that there is a one to one correspon-
dence between the fingers of his right hand and the set {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}. This
correspondence is effected by counting, that is, passing over the fingers and
saying the numbers: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5. A similar correspondence exists between
the fingers of the left hand and the same set of numbers {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}.
The two sets of fingers are the same size as that of the numbers from 1 to
5, and therefore are of equal size. Cantor understood that there is no need
for mediation: the fingers on the two hands can be matched directly. In the
infinite case, when we have no numbers at our disposal, this is the only way
Cantor’s Story 193

to define equality of size between sets. Two infinite sets are defined as being
of equal size if there is a one to one correspondence that matches all elements
of the first to all elements of the second.

The magic of infinity

A small space has as many parts as a big one.

Blaise Pascal, French mathematician and philosopher, 1623–1662


Cantor’s definition of equality of size leads to conclusions that at first
encounter seem absurd. Two sets can be of equal size even if one seems
patently larger than the other. In the finite case the whole cannot be of
equal size to its part. In the infinite case, this is definitely possible, that is, a
set may be of equal size to its proper subset. For example, it seems clear that
there are more natural numbers than even numbers. Isn’t it the case that
only half of the natural numbers are even? But this intuition is misleading.
In order to show this, have 0 correspond to 0, 1 correspond to 2, 2 to 4,
3 to 6, and so on. Each natural number corresponds to the even number
that is its product by 2. Expressed as a function, for every natural number
n the corresponding number is f (n) = 2n. Note that here we are including
0 among the natural numbers. This is customary, but when convenient we
shall omit 0 from the set of natural numbers.

0 1 2 3 4 5 6…

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12…

There is a one to one correspondence between the set of natural numbers and its subset,
the set of even numbers.

Hilbert put this in the form of a story about a hotel in heaven having
infinitely many rooms, numbered as 1, 2, 3, . . . . One day all the rooms were
filled. And then, in the evening, another guest arrived. If the hotel were finite,
the guest would have been stranded. But having infinitely many rooms in
his hotel, the manager could easily solve the problem. Using a public address
system, he asked each guest to move to the next room. The guest in room
no. 1 moved to room no. 2, the guest in room no. 2 to room no. 3, and so
on. Each guest now has his own room, and room no. 1 is vacant and ready
to receive the new arrival.
194 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The hotel is full, but if each guest moves to the next room, a vacancy appears.

The next day, too, the hotel was full. That evening, something even more
distressing happened: an infinite number of new guests arrived! But again,
the hotel manager did not lose his cool. He asked the guest in room no. 1
to move to room no. 2, the guest in room no. 2 to move to room no. 4,
the guest in no. 3, to room no. 6, and on and on. Note that an infinite
number of rooms are thereby vacated — all those with odd numbers (1,
3, 5, . . . ). These rooms can house the infinite number of new guests. For
anyone who encounters Hilbert’s hotel for the first time, this probably seems
mystifying, even entertaining, and possibly even beautiful. I must admit that,
even as a professional mathematician, who uses this idea on an everyday
basis, Hilbert’s hotel still has not lost its charm for me.
And here is another surprise: the set of points on the short segment in the
following drawing is equal in size to the set of points on the long segment. One
correspondence between them is shown in the drawing. Point Q sends “light
beams,” and each point on the upper segment corresponds to its shadow on
the lower segment.

The upper segment has the same number of points as the lower one, despite their being
of different lengths. The beams that emanate from a single point establish a one to one
correspondence.
Cantor’s Story 195

Even more surprisingly, the set of points on a finite segment is equal in


size to the set of points on the entire infinite line! In order to show this, we
will take a segment without its two ends, and bend it into a semicircle. The
same idea of light beams creates a correspondence between the points of the
bent segment and those of the straight line, as in the following drawing:

A finite segment with its two endpoints being removed is bent into the shape of a
semicircle. The beams issuing from the light source then show that the segment is equal
in size to the entire infinite straight line.

Inequality between sets

These examples may create the impression that all infinite sets are of the
same size. Cantor’s great discovery was that this is not so: there are large
sets, and larger ones.

For each flowerpot there is a corresponding flower. This means that the set of flowers is
at least as large as the set of flowerpots.

To show this, we have to define inequality between set sizes. Let us begin
with the concept “at least as large as . . . ”: when is set A at least as large as
set B? Once again, let us begin with the finite case. In the figure above there
196 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

are 5 flowers and 3 flowerpots. Since 5 is bigger than 3, there are more flowers
than flowerpots. This definition, however, is not applicable to the infinite
case, because there we cannot count. Accordingly, we will define it, once
again, by means of correspondence. The drawing illustrates a correspondence
of the set of flowers to that of the flowerpots, that satisfies the following
condition: for each flowerpot there is a corresponding flower.
This definition is applicable also for infinite sets: a set A is at least as
large as a set B if there is a correspondence assigning to every element of A
an element of B, such that all of B is covered. That is, for each element in
B there is at least one element in A corresponding to it.
The next drawing, for example, illustrates why the set of points of the
segment [0,1) (that is, all the points between 0 and 1, including 0 but not 1)
is larger than or equal to the set of natural numbers. For each natural num-
ber there is a corresponding point from the segment (actually, many points
correspond to each number).

Countable and uncountable sets

A set is called “infinite” if it contains a sequence of distinct elements, say


a1 , a2 , a3 , . . . . In other words, a set is infinite if to each natural number we
can assign a different element in the set. If there is such a sequence in set A,
then A can use the sequence to cover the natural numbers; that is, A is at
least as large as the set of natural numbers. Simply assign 1 to a1 , assign 2
to a2 , assign 3 to a3 , and so on. This covers all the natural numbers, using
elements of A, which, by the definition of inequality between set sizes, means
that A is larger than or equal to the set of natural numbers.
Cantor’s Story 197

The conclusion is that every infinite set is greater than or equal (in size)
to the set of natural numbers. In other words, the set of natural numbers is
the smallest infinite set. An infinite set of exactly the same size as that of
the natural numbers is called “countable.” Cantor’s first great discovery was
that there are infinite sets that are not countable. That is, they are actually
greater than the set of natural numbers. This discovery is so basic that it
deserves a chapter of its own.
The Most Beautiful Proof ?

No one shall expel us from the paradise


that Cantor has created for us.

David Hilbert

There are several parameters to the beauty of a mathematical proof. To be


beautiful it should be short, surprising, relating to an important and deep
fact, and applicable to other problems, from different mathematical fields.
Besides the element of surprise, none of these is a necessary condition by
itself. Brevity is not essential — a lengthy proof may have the beauty of an
edifice. Nor is centrality a cardinal condition — there are beautiful solutions
for peripheral problems, too. And finally, beauty is not dependent on utility.
But a proof that fulfills all four of these conditions is definitely beautiful.
Only a few proofs meet all these conditions. Cantor’s proof is one of them.
I suppose that there is not a single mathematician who would not put this
proof in one of the first places in his list of the most beautiful proofs. It is
short and important, it is used in many fields, and the method on which it
is based was the starting point for a whole mathematical field. Despite its
simplicity, it can cause shivers in mathematicians who see it for even the
hundredth time. Cantor proved the following general theorem:

For every infinite set, there is a larger set.

The diagonal method

Say it all, but say it slant.

Emily Dickinson

Cantor arrived at his theorem in two stages. In the first stage, he proved only
that not all infinite sets are of equal size. As already mentioned, the smallest
infinite set is the set of natural numbers, and Cantor proved that there is

199
200 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

a larger set. In other words, there are sets that cannot be counted.
“Uncountable,” they are called.
Cantor’s proof is explicit. Not only does it show that there is an uncount-
able set, it also expressly presents such a set. This is the set of sequences
composed of 0’s and 1’s. There are many such sequences. For example: 0, 0,
0, 0, . . . ; 1, 1, 1, 1, . . . ; 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, . . . ; or 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 0,
0, 1, . . . . Cantor showed that there are not just many sequences like these,
there are very many, more than the natural numbers.
The proof is by negation. That is, upon assuming that the theorem is false,
a contradiction is reached. Let us assume, Cantor said, that it is possible to
count all the sequences whose terms are 0 and 1. The enumeration below is
just an attempt, whose purpose is to make things concrete:
S1 = 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, . . .
S2 = 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, . . .
S3 = 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, . . .
S4 = 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 0, 1, . . .
S5 = 1, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, . . .
S6 = 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, . . .
S7 = 0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0, . . .
..........................................................................
The assumption is that all 0, 1 sequences should appear in this list.
Namely — that we succeeded in counting all of them. But now, Cantor
said, I will show you that in actuality you must have failed to count them
all. I will show you a sequence that definitely does not appear in this list.
To this end, look at the diagonal of the table:
S1 = 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, . . .
S2 = 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, . . .
S3 = 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, . . .
S4 = 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 0, 1, . . .
S5 = 1, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, . . .
S6 = 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, . . .
S7 = 0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0, . . .
..........................................................................
Now, write the sequence that appears on the diagonal: S = 0, 1, 0, 1, 0,
0, 0, . . . and change every 0 in it to 1, and every 1 to 0. This gives us the
sequence T = 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, 1, . . . . What is special about T? It differs from
S in each of its terms. Since the first term in S is the first term in S1 , we
know that T differs from S1 in its first term: S1 has 0 in the first place, while
The Most Beautiful Proof ? 201

T is defined as 1. Consequently, T is not equal to the sequence S1 . Similarly,


T is different from S2 in its second place: S2 has 1 in its second place, and
T reversed it. It has 0 in the second place. And if T is different from S2
in the second place, the two cannot be the same sequence (if two sequences
are equal, they are equal in all places). T differs from S3 in its third place,
and therefore is not identical to S3 . And on and on: for each number i, the
sequence T is different from the sequence Si in the ith place. Accordingly, T
differs from all the sequences Si , that is, T does not appear in the list. So,
this list does not include all the 0,1 sequences in the world! And this is true
for every attempt to count the 0,1 sequences. Every such attempt must fail.

Conclusion: The set of real numbers is not countable

One of the conclusions of this theorem is that there are more real num-
bers than natural numbers. Every sequence of 0’s and 1’s can be matched
with a real number, by adding a 0 and a decimal point to the left of the
sequence. For example, the sequence 0, 1, 0, 1, . . . corresponds to the num-
ber 0.0101. . . ; the sequence 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, . . . corresponds to the real
number 0.00110011. . . . Since the sequences whose terms are 0 and 1 cannot
be counted, it is also impossible to count all the real numbers of this type,
that is, the numbers in whose decimal representation a 0 appears before the
decimal point, and only 0 and 1 after it. These, of course, are only a small
portion of all the real numbers, and if even these cannot be counted, then
all the real numbers most certainly are uncountable.
For obvious reasons, the idea used by Cantor in his proof is called the
“diagonal method.” Since its discovery, it has repeatedly proved its effec-
tiveness, and has become a standard mathematical tool. We will return to
its later exploits, but first, let us see how it developed into a proof that for
every set there is a larger one.

The power set

Two years later, Cantor proved the more general result already mentioned:
there is no largest set. Every set has a set larger than itself.
Like the proof for the existence of an uncountable set, the proof is explicit.
For every set A, Cantor exhibited a specific set larger than A. This is the
set of subsets of A. Set S is called a “subset” of A if it contains part of the
elements of A. “Part” means any part — S might contain no element at all
202 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

(that is, it will be empty), or it might contain all the elements of A (that is,
it will be equal to A). For a reason that will immediately become clear, the
set of the subsets of A is called the “power set” of A. For example, if A is
the set of the two terms {1, 2}, its power set contains 4 sets: {1}, {2}, {1, 2},
and the empty set, that contains no element, and that is labeled Ø.
Cantor proved the following:

The power set of A is larger than A itself.

In the example above, the size of A is 2, while the size of its power set
is 4, and so the power set is indeed larger. In a simpler example, if A is the
empty set Ø, then it has a single subset, which is it itself. Its power set is
therefore of size 1, while the set itself has only 0 terms. The set A = {1, 2, 3}
has 3 elements, as compared with its 8 subsets:

Ø, {1}, {2}, {3}, {1, 2}, {1, 3}, {2, 3}, {1, 2, 3}.

The source of the name “power set” is evident from these examples. A set
of n elements has 2n subsets, that is, the size of its power set is 2 to the power
n. (In these examples: a set of size 2 has 22 = 4 subsets; a set of size 3 has
23 = 8 subsets; and a set of size 0 has 20 = 1 subsets.)

Cantor plays with Mr. Potato Head

How did Cantor prove his theorem? Let me demonstrate, using the familiar
toy Mr. Potato Head. This is a toy model to which you can add ears, a
mustache, eyebrows. . . . In our version, each feature has precisely two possi-
bilities — being there or not. So for example, our Mr. Potato Head either
has a moustache or not, either has eyebrows or not, and so on. Each choice
of features creates a different character: one has a moustache and eyebrows
but no ears, and another has ears and eyebrows, but no moustache. So a
character is determined by a subset, any subset, of the set of features. Can-
tor’s theorem (“there are more subsets than elements”) reads in this case:
There are more characters than features.
How do we prove this? To show that a set A is larger than a set B we
should show that it is impossible to cover A by B. In our case, in which
we want to show that there are more characters than features, we should
The Most Beautiful Proof ? 203

show that there is no assignment of characters to features that covers all


characters.
So, suppose that we are given some correspondence, that assigns to every
feature a character. I (or rather, Cantor) will show you a character that is
not covered, namely it is not assigned to any feature. In fact, I will construct
such a character in front of your eyes. Let us call this character Out of
Spite — you will soon understand why.
Remember? To each feature there is assigned a character. So, there is a
character assigned to the nose. Now, this character may have a nose, and it
may not. Out of Spite will do precisely the opposite: if this character has a
nose, Out of Spite chooses not to have one. If it doesn’t, Out of Spite chooses
to have a nose. In any case, Out of Spite is different from the character
assigned to the nose. They differ with respect to whether they have a nose
or not.
Let us go next to the moustache. There is a character assigned to it.
This character may have a moustache, and it may not. If it has, Out of
Spite will choose not to have a moustache. If it does not have a moustache,
then Out of Spite will choose to have a moustache. Then Out of Spite is
different from the character assigned to the moustache — they differ on the
moustache.
I think it is clear how Out of Spite is defined, and how he gained his
name: for every feature, he chooses oppositely to the choice of the character
assigned to that feature. It differs on the hair from the character assigned to
the hair, and on the left ear from the character assigned to the left ear. The
result? Out of Spite is different from all characters assigned to the features.
It is not equal to any of them. So, we found a character (Out of Spite)
that is not assigned to any feature. Since this argument worked for every
assignment, it implies that there is no assignment covering the characters by
features. There are too many characters to be covered.
In order to prove Cantor’s general theorem, that the power set of every
set A is larger than A, just give A as a set of features to Mr. Potato Head.
If he is mathematically inclined, he will agree to use any set — say the set
of even numbers. We have seen that there are more characters formed by
choices of subsets of A than the size of A. That is, the subsets of A are
more numerous than A itself. This means that the power set of A is larger
than A.
204 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Cantor proved that the number of possible characters of Mr. Potato Head you can form
with given features is larger than the number of features, even if the number of features
is infinite.

Even after many years of acquaintance with this proof, I am still charmed.
The definition of Out of Spite is a rabbit popping out of a hat. The proof is so
short and surprising, that it takes some time to digest. It has few competitors
for the ratio between importance and length.
Returning to more abstract terms, what Cantor argument says is this.
Let A be any set. If f is an assignment of subsets of A to elements, so that
to every element a of A we assign the subset f (a), there is a subset C (after
“Cantor” — this is the “Out of Spite” set) that is not assigned any element.
What is C? An element a belongs to C if it is not included in f (a). This is
the “spite.” So, C is the set of elements that do not belong to the set assigned
to them by f . This is a rather confusing definition. It smells of circularity,
which is another name for “self-reference.” A bit like defining a man as “the
father of the person hereby defined,” or a number as “the number hereby
defined, plus 1.” Such definitions tend to generate paradoxes, like a man who
is own father or a number that is greater than itself by 1. And indeed, this is
what happened next in set theory. Paradoxes appeared as if from nowhere,
threatening to topple the entire beautiful edifice erected by Cantor.
Paradoxes and Oxymorons

A parody of a proof

Cantor’s proof fell victim to something rare among mathematical proofs: a


parody. And not just any parody, but one that an entire generation of math-
ematicians treated with all seriousness. In 1903 Gottlob Frege completed
the second part of his treatise on the foundations of arithmetic. I already
mentioned the sorry fate of the first volume that received scant attention.
An even more unpleasant surprise awaited Frege now. He sent the almost
finished text to Bertrand Russell in England. Russell sent him a shocking
reply: he showed that Frege’s assumptions lead to a contradiction, a paradox.
Frege attempted over the course of several weeks to resolve the contradic-
tion, and finally gave up. He added a pessimistic appendix to his book, in
which he changed the system of proof that he had used, in such a way that
it lost much of its power. Frege never wrote the third volume. Russell, who
had discovered his paradox some time before receiving Frege’s book, contin-
ued writing his own book, Principles of Mathematics, but he, too, added a
similar appendix, with an attempted solution to the problem.
Actually, Russell’s paradox was not new. Cantor found it, in a somewhat
different formulation, some twenty years earlier. Cantor’s formulation went
like this: according to the theorem (that we presented in the last chapter),
for every set there is a set larger than it. But what happens if we take the
set of everything in the world? By the theorem, for this set, too, there is one
that is larger than it. But this is absurd. This is the largest possible set —
every other set is contained in it!
In this formulation, the contradiction is called “Cantor’s Paradox.” Can-
tor himself wasn’t very upset by it. He probably understood that it does
not pose a significant threat to his theory (as indeed became clear later on).
Other mathematicians, as well, did not take it seriously. Russell’s paradox,
in contrast, did make waves. In those years mathematicians tried to write
precise axioms for set theory, and they realized that naı̈ve axiomatization
will not do. It leads to contradictions.

205
206 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Russell’s contradiction had greater impact because of its simpler formu-


lation. Cantor relied on a theorem, his theorem that for every set there
is a larger one. Russell’s paradox is a one line contradiction, constructed
from scratch. But as mentioned, the two paradoxes are really the same.
Unlike Cantor, Russell was not a creative mathematician, but he had
good mathematical education, and he knew what has to be done upon
encountering a contradiction: analyze the proof leading to the contradic-
tion. His analysis led to the argument that, actually, is at the heart of
Cantor’s paradox. Here it is: most of the sets that we can think of do
not belong to themselves. For example, the set of chairs does not belong
to itself, because it itself is not a chair. The set of natural numbers does
not belong to itself, because it itself is not a natural number. But there
also are sets that do belong to themselves, for example, the set of all the
things in the world, since it is something in the world; or the set of all
sets (since it itself is a set); or the set of everything whose name begins
with “s.”

Call the set of all the sets that do not belong to themselves R (after
Russell). Does R belong to itself? By the definition of R, a set belongs
to it if and only if it does not belong to itself. If we apply this rule to R
itself, we obtain: R belongs to itself only if it does not belong to itself. This
is a contradiction: a proposition and its negation cannot both be true at
the same time.

Russell formulated a parable to illustrate the paradox. A barber who lives


in a small village vows to give a haircut to precisely those villagers who do
not cut their own hair. But now he is in a quandary: must he cut his own
hair, or not? If he gives himself a haircut, then, according to the vow he
took, he cannot cut his own hair. But, if he will not give himself a haircut,
then he must do so!

To cut, or not to cut?


Paradoxes and Oxymorons 207

The story of the barber is not a paradox. His vow simply cannot be
realized. Russell’s set, however, seems to lead to a real contradiction. Is
this so? Certainly not. If the mathematical axioms are chosen well, they
will not result in a contradiction, because they will describe reality, and in
reality there are no contradictions. Like every paradox, this one was born
out of a shaky definition. Behind Russell’s paradox, as behind the original
paradox of Cantor, is an assumption called the “Axiom of comprehension.”
This states that every property defines a set: the property of “being a chair”
defines the set of all chairs; the property “being an even natural number”
defines the set of even natural numbers. This assumption, however, enables
circular definitions. As Russell’s paradox shows, with the help of the axiom
of comprehension, we can define a set for which the relationship “belonging
to itself” is self-defined.
For a brief moment, the foundations of mathematics shook. It seemed
as if the paradox would expel us from Cantor’s paradise. But things were
soon set right. Ernst Zermelo wrote in 1908 a system of axioms, that was
improved in 1922 by Abraham Fraenkel. The Zermelo-Fraenkel system of
axioms does not contain the axiom of comprehension. Sets are constructed
with greater care, from axioms that (apparently) do not lead to circular
definitions. And so, Cantor’s paradise remained unscathed, enabling Hilbert
to say that the danger of expulsion had passed (his declaration cited above:
“No one shall expel us from the paradise that Cantor has created for us,” was
made in 1926). This is still one of the most beautiful mathematical fields,
and the paradoxes no longer trouble it. In fact, the upheaval had a positive
side, as well: the paradoxes of set theory led to some of the most fascinating
developments in modern mathematics.

Paradoxes in probability

There are lies, damned lies, and statistics.

Mark Twain

A paradox is not a real contradiction. Its trick is concealing a flawed assump-


tion, and drawing from it an absurdity. It is a hidden error, leading to an
apparent one. Solving a paradox means exposing the error. Probability is
an area in which intuitions are often misleading, and hence it is easy to
cheat there and create ostensible contradictions. Of the many paradoxes in
probability I chose one, called “the envelopes paradox.”
208 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Suppose that your rich uncle presents you with two sealed envelops, and
tells you that he put in one of them — you do not know which — a dou-
ble amount of money as he put in the other. You are free to choose an
envelope, which you do. You open it and find a $100 bill. Now your uncle
evinces double generosity: “If you want, you can change your choice,” he
offers. Of course, without first opening the second envelope. The question
now is whether it is worthwhile to switch, or not? You randomly chose
one of the envelopes, and so there is a 12 probability that you chose the
envelope with the smaller sum. In that case, the second envelope contains
$200, and switching will give you a profit of $100. There is a probabil-
ity of 12 that the envelope you chose contains the larger sum, in which
case the other envelope will contain a $50 bill, and you will lose $50. So
switching the envelopes is a gamble in which there is a 50 percent chance
to win a larger sum, and a 50 percent chance to lose a smaller sum — a
gamble that is definitely worth taking. And if so, then it is worthwhile to
switch.
But this is patently absurd. The argument is not dependent on you having
found $100 in the envelope. Had you found $1000, the conclusion should have
been the same. But if so, then it would be worthwhile to switch in any case,
meaning that you should switch even before you open the envelope. But this,
of course, is silly, if only for the reason that it would be worthwhile then to
switch again.
The deceit is quite subtle. It is based on an unstated assumption: that
each sum has the same probability of being in the envelopes. In our case, in
which you opened the envelope and found $100 in it, it is assumed that the
likelihood that the uncle put $50 in one envelope and $100 in the other is
the same as the second possibility, of $100 and $200. If we were to assume
that the probability of the first possibility is much greater than that of the
second, you could reasonably expect the envelope you didn’t open to contain
$50, and so it would not be worthwhile to switch.
The assumption that each sum has the same chance is necessarily erro-
neous. This is because there are an infinite number of possible sums. When
there are (say) 10 possibilities, each with the same probability, the proba-
1
bility of each is 10 . When there are infinitely many possibilities, if each had
the same degree of probability, then the probability of each of them would
have to be 0. But this means that none of them could happen! This means
that the probability is not uniform. There are combinations of sums that are
more likely than others.
Paradoxes and Oxymorons 209

Here is an example clarifying this point. Assume that your uncle does
not have more than $2,000,000. In this case, if you find $1,000,000 in the
envelope that you opened, you know for a certainty that the second envelope
contains half a million dollars, and not two million. In this case, obviously,
it is not worthwhile to switch.

Poetical paradoxes

I open the collection of poems True Love by the Israeli poet Dalia
Ravikovitch (1936–2005), and this is what I find:

Until a little head bursts forth


Red like the orb of the setting sun.
Dalia Ravikovitch, “He Will Surely Come,” from True Love
The bursting forth is represented by the imagery of its opposite, sun-
set. Or:

Silence screams within me


And I scream within it.
from “The Beginning of Quiet”

Dalia Ravikovitch, 1936–2005.

Saying something and its opposite in the same breath is called an


“oxymoron,” that in Greek means “stupid wise man.” Samuel Taylor
Coleridge wrote in his Biographia Literaria:
210 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

[The power of the imagination] reveals itself in the balance or reconcili-


ation of opposite or discordant qualities: of sameness, with difference; of
the general with the concrete; the idea with the image; the individual
with the representative; the sense of novelty and freshness with old and
familiar objects; a more than usual state of emotion with more than usual
order [. . . ].

We learn from this that poetry, too, uses paradox. But there is a basic
difference: while a mathematical paradox conceals error, there is always truth
behind a poetical oxymoron. Beneath the apparent contradiction there is
internal logic. By the death bed of the poetess Rachel there were found the
lines “Only what I lost/is my possession eternal” (My Dead). This contains
a truth, because external possessions can be lost. Only what is internalized
remains.
Paradox is one of the means poetry uses to maintain tension between sur-
face and interior — the tension that, as I have strived to show, is responsible
for the sensation of beauty. Pulling the carpet of logic from under our feet
forces us to seek the truth within, and understand that beneath abstract
thought there are things no less significant.
Self-Reference and Gödel’s Theorem

Hilbert’s program

Twenty-four is a good age for making scientific revolutions. Isaac Newton


was that age in his miraculous year, 1666, in which he developed the theory
of gravity, discovered differential and integral calculus, and formulated the
basic laws of modern optics. Einstein was that age when he discovered the
special theory of relativity. And so was Kurt Gödel (Austria, 1906–1978)
when he proved a theorem that changed our view of mathematics.
The chapter “What Is Mathematics?” described the revolution brought
about by Frege, who understood that human thought — and especially math-
ematical thought — can be studied mathematically. The field that thereby
came into existence was called “mathematical logic.” Frege’s ideas were con-
tinued in the early twentieth century by Bertrand Russell, Alfred North
Whitehead, and David Hilbert. Hopes soared. Frege taught that it was pos-
sible to describe the process of mathematical proof in mechanical terms. He
showed that a mathematical proof is just a series of marks on paper that
obey well-defined rules. The simplicity of these rules enables us to mechan-
ically examine whether a series of marks is a proof or not. In modern day
terminology, a computer could do that. But if this is so, then we can be even
more daring: perhaps a computer can also find proofs? Can a computer pro-
gram be written that, upon being given a statement (in itself a collection of
marks on paper), will be capable of proving it, or of telling us that it cannot
be proved? Just imagine what a wonderful world this would be! Mathemati-
cians could retire, and leave the proofs to computer programs. And even if
such a program would not be practical, its mere possibility would be of vast
theoretical value.
Questions such as these were asked in the first three decades of the twen-
tieth century. At that time, of course, computers did not yet exist, and in
place of “computer programs” people used the term “algorithm,” which is
a recipe that dictates a precise order of operations, like a recipe for baking
a cake. The logicians of that period searched for an algorithm that would

211
212 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

check whether a formula is provable or not, and if it decided that there is


a proof, it would find one. The main person pushing towards this goal was
Hilbert. In fact, he presented his generation with a complete program, con-
sisting of a few challenges. At that time, logicians were mainly interested in
number theory. A system of axioms for number theory that was formulated
in 1889 by the Italian Giuseppe Peano (1858–1932) was thought at the time
to be the last word, and assumed to imply all true statements about num-
bers. Hilbert’s program related to this system. The tasks he set for his fellow
mathematicians were:
1. Prove that Peano’s system is complete, in the sense that for each formula
the system can prove the formula, or its negation.
2. Find an algorithm deciding for every formula in number theory whether
it is true in the natural numbers or not.
3. Find an algorithm deciding whether a formula is provable from Peano’s
axioms.
4. Prove that Peano’s axioms are consistent, namely that they do not lead
to a contradiction. In fact, the existence of the natural numbers, that
obey these axioms, proves this consistency. But Hilbert wanted a proof
that relies only on the form of the axioms, not the fact that there is a
body obeying them. Such a proof is called “syntactical.”

A methodical, but not very efficient, detective

Look again at item 3 above — the search for an algorithm that tests prov-
ability. There is a natural candidate for such an algorithm: simply, trying all
possibilities. Given a formula you want to check for provability, go system-
atically, from shorter to longer, over all possible series of symbols. For each
such sequence check to see whether it proves the formula, or perhaps proves
its negation. Most of the sequences are not proofs at all, but just jumbles
of symbols. But perhaps, by chance, like the monkey hitting a typewriter
at random, you will hit a proof of the formula or its negation. If there is
such a proof, you will get to it at some point. And since checking whether a
sequence of symbols is a proof of a given formula is doable, the algorithm is
well defined.
Obviously, this is not very efficient. It is like a police detective trying to
solve a murder case by examining all the people in the world, one by one.
Just as police investigations aren’t conducted in this manner, so, too, no
Self-Reference and Gödel’s Theorem 213

one would try to find proofs for mathematical theorems by writing random
marks on paper. However, at this stage we are not looking for an efficient
algorithm, but for any algorithm at all.
But there is a worse and deeper problem. It is that we don’t know when to
stop. The algorithm of the murder detective is not efficient, but it is feasible,
since there are only a finite number of people in the world, and at some point
the algorithm will end. The situation is different for mathematical proofs.
If a proof is found at some point during our search, well and good. But
if we have examined a million series of signs, and none of them yields the
desired proof? Obviously, we could continue on to the one-million-and-first
series, but we would never be able to stop and declare: “We exhausted all
possibilities, and have not found a proof, so there is none.” There is always
the possibility that in our next step we would stumble upon the proof. Oil
prospectors face this dilemma, but in their case, there is at least a theoretical
limit: if they drilled and reached the other side of the earth, this is a clear
sign of failure. As far as proofs are concerned, there is no phase in which we
should give up.
But note: if we know for sure that one of the possibilities indeed occurs,
the formula is provable, or its negation is, then we are in good shape. We
can check at each step whether the sequence of symbols at hand is a proof
for the formula, or of its negation. Knowing that there exists a proof of one
of these, it is guaranteed that at some point our sequence of symbols will
be such a proof. So, the algorithm will terminate. So, if item 1 of Hilbert’s
program is true, namely every formula is provable or its negation is, then we
also have an algorithm for deciding which of the two cases it is.

Gödel’s theorem and the demise of Hilbert’s program

In September 1930 a conference on the foundations of mathematics was held


in Königsberg, and was attended by some of the best mathematicians of
Europe. An announcement given at the end by a young, shy and slightly-
built mathematician went hardly noticed. Luckily, one mathematician did
understand the significance of what would be later described as “the most
important theorem of the 20th century,” and spread the word. It was John
Von Neumann, who realized the revolutionary implications of the discovery
made by the young mathematician, Kurt Gödel.
Gödel shattered Hilbert’s program, in all its details. He proved that the
Peano axiom system is not complete; that there is no algorithm for deciding
whether a formula on number is true or not; that there is no algorithm for
214 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

finding proofs in the Peano system; and that there is no syntactical proof of
the consistency of the Peano axioms.
The first of these negative results got most of the fame. It is called
“Gödel’s incompleteness theorem.” It is that there are true statements about
numbers, which Peano’s axioms cannot prove. Of course, since they are true,
their negation also cannot be proved. So, there are statements that both they
and their negation cannot be proved.
OK, you may say, so Peano was stupid, and didn’t devise a good axiom
system. Let somebody cleverer come, and propose a better axiom sys-
tem, that will be complete. Namely, it will decide everything — for each
formula, it will prove the formula or its negation. But Gödel’s argument
has a much wider scope: it is valid not only for Peano’s axioms, but also
for every reasonable axiom system, where “reasonable” means that it is
possible to decide, for every sequence of symbols, if it is an axiom in the
system or not.
Gödel’s theory drew the attention of a young Englishman named Alan
Turing (1912–1954). In addition to his being an exceptionally strong math-
ematician, Turing also had mechanical skills, and he wanted to give more
tangible form to Gödel’s arguments. To this end, he invented the first the-
oretical model of a computer. The actual construction of a computer did
not lag far behind. During World War II, Turing participated in building
a primitive computer, as part of the effort to break the German code for
communications with submarines. Gödel’s theory was therefore a significant
step toward the creation of the computer.

Kurt Gödel (1906–1978) proved what some consider to be the most important theorem of
the twentieth century — that any reasonable set of axioms for number theory is
incapable of proving all true facts about the natural numbers.
Self-Reference and Gödel’s Theorem 215

Circularity

Prayers created God,


God created man,
And man creates prayers
That create God that created man.

Yehuda Amichai, “Gods Come and Go, Prayers


Remain Forever,” Open Closed Open

Gödel was inspired in his proof by a paradox named after the French math-
ematician Jules Richard (1862–1956). This paradox, like Russell’s (in the
preceding chapter), is a parody of Cantor’s diagonal method. Like Russell’s
paradox, its deception lies in self-reference. In fact, this is the case in all
long-lasting paradoxes. It seems that the human mind is not built to eas-
ily detect circularity. The best known paradox based on self-reference is the
so-called “Liar’s Paradox,” invented by Greek philosophers back in the 5th
century BC.

This sentence is false.

Think about the truth value of this sentence: if the sentence is true, then,
according to its content, it is false. But if it is false, then, again, according
to its content, it is true. As in Russell’s paradox, we found a statement that
is correct only if it is incorrect, which is plainly impossible. Rivers of ink
have been poured over this paradox, and philosophers spent many sleepless
nights wrestling with it. Actually, the deception behind it is quite simple,
and is not very different from the definition of a number as “itself plus
1.” The circularly-defined concept in the paradox is the truth value of the
sentence. A sentence does not come into the world with a truth value pinned
to its collar. In order to calculate the truth value of a sentence, we must
do something: compare it with reality. This sentence, however, speaks of
its own truth value, and therefore the part of reality to which it must be
compared is none other than the truth value itself, that is, the result of the
current examination. Thus, the truth value of the liar’s sentence is defined
by reference to itself. Actually, it is defined simply as its own negation. This
is a circular definition, and is therefore invalid. The liar’s sentence just has
no truth value — it is neither true nor false.
216 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Gödel constructed a paradox of his own, a much more refined one. He


considered a statement similar to that of the liar, the difference being that it
does not relate to its truth value, but to the possibility of its being proved.

This statement cannot be proved.

Let us name this sentence “G.” The following sequence of arguments


about G leads to a contradiction:

1. Assume first that G can be proved. Anything that can be proved is


patently correct, so in this case G is also correct.
2. But if G is correct, then, according to its content, G cannot be proved,
since it states its own unprovability.
3. The previous two arguments show that the assumption that G is provable
implies a contradiction. G is then both provable and unprovable.
4. By 3, G cannot be proved, for if it is, a contradiction is obtained.
5. The four first arguments, taken together, show that G cannot be proved.
6. We have shown that G cannot be proved. But by the content of G (that
states its own unprovability) we have precisely proved G by this!
7. In 5 we showed that G cannot be proved. In 6 we actually gave a proof for G.
These two, together, constitute a contradiction — that is, a paradox.

This paradox is subtler than the Liar’s Paradox, and the circularity it
conceals is not as simple (a hint: the problem lies in the assumption that
“what can be proved is correct,” which, if used in proofs, becomes circu-
larly defined). We arrived at a contradiction here, because we looked at the
statement formulated in words. Gödel, in contrast, did not arrive at a con-
tradiction. He did not write his statement in words, but as a formula that
speaks of numbers — an outstanding achievement by itself. Dressed as a for-
mula, Gödel’s sentence does not result in a contradiction, but in a formula
that is true in the natural numbers, yet it cannot be proved.

Ars poetic poems

Light didn’t just come my way


Nor did I inherit it from my father,
But from my bedrock I bore it,
And hewed it from my heart.
Self-Reference and Gödel’s Theorem 217

[. . . ]

And under the hammer of my agony


My heart, my rock of strength, shattered
A spark flew to my eye
And from my eye to my verse.

And from my verse it slips forth to your heart,


To fade away in your ignited fire.

And I, with my pith and heart’s blood


Pay the price of the flames.
Hayyim Nahman Bialik
Self-reflection appears in poetry, as well. This happens, more than anywhere,
in ars poetic poems, in which the poet speaks of his or her poetry. We already
encountered a poem of this type, in the passage from “About Myself” by
Lea Goldberg. “Light Didn’t Just Come My Way” contains two ideas that
appear in many ars poetica poems. One is that poetry is not the result of
conscious decision, and the poet is merely a passive conduit in the hands of
inner forces (“A spark flew to my eye/And from my eye to my verse”). The
other is the poet’s complaint: while he suffers fiercely, others are entertained
by his poetry (“To fade away in your ignited fire”).
Here is another poem about the poet’s passivity, also by Lea Goldberg,
and again, from “About Myself”:

Simply:
There was snow in one land
And desert in another
And a star in an airplane window
At night
Above many lands.

They came to me
And commanded me: Sing.
They said: We are words
And I surrendered, and sang them.
Lea Goldberg, “About Myself”
Ars poetica poems occupy a surprisingly large place in poetry as a whole.
Should this be attributed to the excessive narcissism of poets? Probably not.
218 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

I believe that the answer is not to be found in the personality of poets, but in
the beauty inherent in circularity, in having something hang in air because
it is hanging on itself.
To end this chapter, here is an amusing example of circularity in poetry.
In the poem “A Tale of Two ‘Garoos” by the Israeli poet Abraham Shlonsky,
the negativist no-‘garoo responds to everything with a “No.” After learning
his lesson, he is asked whether he will remain in his obstinacy.

Will you go on saying “No”?


“No,” he answered. “No, no, no!”
Abraham Shlonsky, “A Tale of Two ‘Garoos”
Halfway to Infinity: Large Numbers

I will make your descendants as numerous as the


stars of heaven and the sands on the seashore.

Genesis 22:17
One of the heroes of the English author David Lodge tries to explain to his
friend the meaning of eternity. “Think,” he says, “of a ball of steel as large
as Earth, and a fly alighting on it once every million years. When the steel
ball is rubbed away by the friction, eternity will not even have begun.”
Mathematicians wouldn’t be impressed by this image. For them, the num-
ber of years that will pass until the ball is rubbed away is not especially big.
Assume, as an extreme example, that the number of atoms in the ball is that
of the number of atoms in the universe, which is estimated at 1080 . Assume
also that with every alighting, only a single atom adheres to the foot of the
fly. After a million times 1080 , that is, 1086 years, the ball will be rubbed
away. Much larger numbers appear in some mathematicians’ work every day,
especially in my own field, combinatorics. For example, the number of ways
in which 100 people can be ordered in a line is much greater than this.
We can deal with such numbers, but they are difficult to comprehend.
Even “a million” is a number that people cannot grasp. In the O. J. Simpson
murder trial, in which the defendant was charged with murdering his ex-wife
and her friend, an expert witness testified for the prosecution that there was
one chance in a billion that the blood samples found at the murder scene
did not belong to the accused. An expert for the defense claimed that the
chance is one in several million, and this statement was enough to acquit
Simpson — the jurors didn’t have a clue as to the meaning of “one chance
in a million.”
Mathematicians, too, don’t really understand the meaning of large num-
bers, but they live with them quite well, and they know how to write them
concisely. The trick consists of operations that repeat other operations. Mul-
tiplication, for example, is a repetition of addition, and raising to a power is
a repetition of multiplication. 1010 means “10 to the tenth power,” that is,

219
220 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

10 times 10 time 10 . . . — multiplying 10 by itself 10 times. This is 10 billion,


which is written as a 1 followed by 10 zeros. 1010 means ten to the (10 to the
10

tenth power), and is written as a 1 followed by 1010 zeros. If we were to write


this on a strip of paper, the strip would circle the world about 1,000 times.
Is there any meaning to numbers like these? In some conference, a well-
known mathematician claimed that there is not. “There is no practical sig-
10
nificance to numbers like 1010 . They are larger than any physical size that
will ever be defined. They are also too big to be treated with the regular
mathematical tools. We will never be able, for example, to check whether
10
1010 + 1 is a prime number.”
One member of the audience stood up and asked: “Suppose that two
mathematician come to you, one with a proof of Fermat’s Conjecture for
10
all the numbers smaller than 1010 , and the other with a proof of Fermat’s
Conjecture for all the numbers larger than 1010 . Which of the results will
10

be more interesting for you?” The lecturer was forced to admit, as would any
mathematician, that the second result would be more important. (Fermat’s
Conjecture was explained above, in the “Unexpected Combinations” chapter.
At the time of this story it was not yet solved.)
At this point someone else got up and said: “1010 + 1 is not a prime
10

number, because 1010 can be written as a fifth power, that is a5 .” (For this
10

purpose it suffices for the power 1010 to be divisible by 5, which is clearly


the case.) The number is therefore of the form a5 + 1, and a number of this
form is not a prime. It is the multiple of two smaller numbers, since a5 + 1 =
(a + 1) × (a4 − a3 + a2 − a + 1) (the reader is invited to check this identity,
by opening the brackets). The moral of this story is that, even though we
are incapable of grasping the meaning of large numbers, mathematics may
still be able to deal with them.
Perhaps because of its name, children are fascinated by the number
“googol,” which is 10100 , written as 1 followed by 100 zeros. Many chil-
dren think that this is the largest number in the world. A googol is small
change compared to the number 1010 , but still it cannot be comprehended.
10

Once I asked my daughter, “Is there something in the world of which there
are a googol?” Without stopping to think, she answered, “Yes. In a second
there are a googol googolths of a second” (just as there are ten tenths of a
second in a second). Of course, this is cheating — “googolths of a second”
exist only in our imagination, we cannot clock them.
There is an additional way in which gigantic numbers appear, presum-
ably in the real world: combinations. For example, a number we already
mentioned: the number of ways in which 100 people can be ordered in a line.
Halfway to Infinity: Large Numbers 221

How is this number calculated? Each of the 100 people can be put in the
first place in the line, and there are then 99 possibilities of putting someone
in the second position (only 99, because the first person was already cho-
sen). Accordingly, there are 100 × 99 possibilities for placing people in the
first two positions. For each of these possibilities, there are 98 ways to select
the third person, and so, we have 100 × 99 × 98 ways to fill the first three
places. Continuing, we find that the number of ways to arrange 100 people
is 100 × 99 × 98 × 97 × · · · × 3 × 2 × 1, a number denoted by 100! and is
called “100 factorial.” Using the formula of James Stirling (in the chapter “A
Magic Number”), 100! can be estimated to be about 10150 , which is much
larger than the number of atoms in the universe. The number of ways in
10
which Earth’s inhabitants can be arranged in a line is greater than 1010 —
so here is this number, in a real-life situation. But, these, too, are not indeed
from real life. No one intends to arrange people in all possible ways, nor even
to order their names on paper.
Infinitely Small

Everything changes

Everything flows.

Heraclitus, Greek philosopher, ca. 540–480 BCE


Everything flows. The world changes unceasingly — and examining the world
means examining its change, like the motion of bodies. Bodies move contin-
uously, and not in jumps — or so it was believed until the appearance of
quantum theory about a century ago. And for bodies that are not micro-
scopic, modern physics, as well, assumes continuous change. The mathemat-
ical field that examines continuous changes in the world is called “differential
calculus.”
It is sometimes jokingly said that differential calculus was discovered by
someone who believed that the world is flat — and was right. An ant that
stands on a large and smooth ball thinks that it is standing on a plane,
since from close up the surface appears flat. It was for this reason that
people believed that the earth was flat until they possessed the means to
distance themselves from it, both in thought and in practice. In a certain
sense, differential calculus restores this belief. The assumption on which it
is based is that when a smooth line is observed through a microscope, it
appears straight. Actually, this is the definition of a “smooth line.” When
curved lines in the world are examined, they are generally assumed to be
smooth. Incidentally, since the discovery of fractals, this assumption is no
longer deemed necessary. No matter from what proximity fractal lines are
observed, they still appear rough.
Like many fundamental ideas, differential calculus, too, was discovered
by the Greeks. They knew how to look at things “through a microscope.”
The way in which they calculated the area of a circle, for example, looks
as if it was taken directly from seventeenth-century differential and integral
calculus. They took the circle and divided it into small sectors, as in this
drawing:

223
224 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

If the sectors are very narrow, to a good approximation they look like
triangles. Their base looks like a straight line, just as the earth appears flat
to someone observing it from a low height. And we know how to calculate
the area of a triangle: this is the base, times the height, divided by 2. If we
think of every sector as being almost a triangle, then its height is the radius
of the circle. The area of each sector, therefore, is more or less its base times
the radius of the circle, divided by 2; and the narrower the sectors, the better
this approximation. In consequence, the area of the circle, which is the sum
of the sector areas, is — to a good approximation — the radius, times the
sum of the base lengths, divided by 2. But the sum of the base lengths is the
circumference of the circle. So, the area of the circle is its radius, multiplied
by the circumference, and divided by 2. Since the circumference of a circle
of radius R is 2πR, its area is 2πR × R2 = πR2 , which is the formula you
probably remember from high school. Incidentally, why is the circumference
of a circle 2πR? This is a question of definition. The number π is defined as
the ratio between the circumference of the circle and its diameter, that is,
between the circumference and 2R.
In antiquity, the use of arguments of this type to calculate areas and
volumes was known as the “method of exhaustion.” It was developed by
Eudoxus, and already appeared in Euclid’s Elements, that was written
in the fourth century BC. The master of this method was Archimedes.
He could calculate the area of a circle, the volume of a sphere, and the
inscribed area between a parabola and a straight line. Among all his accom-
plishments, Archimedes most appreciated these calculations. He asked that
a cylinder and a ball inscribed within it be engraved on his tombstone,
as a testament to the result of which he was most proud, that the vol-
ume of the cylinder that inscribes a sphere is 32 times as large as that of
the ball.
The idea of “looking through a microscope,” that is, using sizes that tend
to zero, enjoyed renewed currency in the seventeenth century. This began,
actually, by looking through a telescope. Tycho Brahe, the great Danish
Infinitely Small 225

Archimedes asked that this drawing be engraved on his tombstone. He proved that the
volume of the ball inscribed in the cylinder is 23 of the volume of the cylinder. He thereby
discovered the formula for the volume of a ball.

astronomer (1546–1601), conducted more precise observations than any of


his predecessors, and Johannes Kepler, who worked with Brahe in Prague,
derived from them three rules that govern the behavior of the planets. The
young Newton attempted to explain these rules, and needed a mathematical
tool suitable for the study of motion. Modern differential calculus was born
out of this need. At the same time, Gottfried Leibniz developed in Germany
similar ideas, and also invented the notation that is used in the field to
the present day. Newton, who was suspicious by nature, feared that Leibniz
was trying to steal his results. He had sent letters to Leibniz in which he
presented his ideas, but mail was very slow at that time. Newton believed
that Leibniz’s slow response was meant to enable him to elaborate Newton’s
ideas and take credit for them. Newton initiated an inquiry by the British
Royal Society, the results of which he himself wrote — judge and jury rolled
into one. Notwithstanding this, Newton undoubtedly was the more original
of the two. Leibniz himself was exceedingly generous toward his rival, and
said that: “Newton is responsible for the better half of mathematics up to
his time.”
Differential calculus’ counterpart is integral calculus. Differential calculus
derives information about infinitely small changes from the global behavior of
a system. For example, calculating the momentary speed of a body, by know-
ing its position at any moment. Integral calculus does the opposite: it derives
global behavior from the momentary behavior. For example, calculating the
position of a body at any given moment, based on knowledge of its speed at
any moment.
226 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Archimedes, a Greek who lived in Sicily (287–212 BCE). The greatest mathematician of
the ancient world, he was a man of many talents — mathematician, engineer and
inventor. He developed a type of pump named after him, invented the planetarium, and
built sophisticated weaponry for the defense of his city, Syracuse, against the Romans.
When the city was finally conquered, a Roman soldier found him drawing geometric
shapes in the sand. As the legend goes, when the soldier asked him what he was doing,
he replied, “Don’t bother my circles” — an answer that cost him his life.

Representation by a small thing

A poet must have his childhood close at hand.

Theodore Roethke, American poet, 1908–1963

The study of infinitely small sizes has a parallel in poetry, a mechanism


called “representation by a small thing.” This term was coined by Freud,
who discovered it in dreams. In a dream it is used, like all other dreamwork
devices, to camouflage forbidden contents. A loaded message is represented
by a small and seemingly insignificant detail. This mechanism plays a sim-
ilar role in poetry: the indirect transmission of the message. The result is
poetry’s well-known economy of language. Here, for example, is a poem by
the Russian poetess Anna Akhmatova (1889–1963). The poetess’s confusion
is represented by a seemingly inconsequential detail, wearing a glove on the
wrong hand:

My breast grew helplessly cold,


But my steps were light,
Infinitely Small 227

I pulled the glove from my left hand


Mistakenly onto my right

Anna Akhmatova, “Song of the Last Meeting,” trans. in From


the Ends to the Beginning: A Bilingual Anthology of Russian Verse

Emily Dickinson was a poetess of small things:

To make a prairie it takes a clover and one bee,


one clover, and a bee,
And revery.
The revery alone will do
if bees are few.

Emily Dickinson, “To Make a Prairie” [no. 1755]

Small things, the poem teaches us, leave space for imagination. Since they
don’t take much space, the rest will be filled by our thoughts. The next poem,
by the American poet William Carlos Williams, speaks of the importance of
details:

so much depends
upon

a red wheel
barrow

glazed with rain


water

beside the white


chickens

William Carlos Williams, “The Red Wheelbarrow”

This is most likely a childhood picture. Nowhere as in childhood memories


is there such a gap between seeming lack of importance and intensity of
emotions. A childhood picture, experience, or small object can mean worlds
for the grownup. The proportions of a child’s experience are different from
those perceived by an adult. And, as Theodore Roethke attests, a poet’s soul
is needed to perceive this in adulthood.
228 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The Japanese, who raised miniaturization to an art form in many fields,


did this in poetry, as well. A haiku is a bonsai poem, fashioned of small
details loaded with emotion and thoughts:

The dead body


Of a trodden-on crab,
This autumn morning.

Masaoka Shiki, 1867–1902


A small detail can teach of what occurrences outside, and also of what is
happening within:

The shadow of the washing-post


Teaches
That winter is in full force.

Masaoka Shiki
Infinitely Many Numbers
Having a Finite Sum

The Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea (490–425 BC) was preoccupied with the
relation between the freeze frame and the whole picture. Two millennia later,
mathematicians would be occupied with the same issues, which would lead
them to invent differential calculus. Zeno, who lacked the necessary tools,
thought that he had reached contradictions, the most famous of which is
“the paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise.” The original paradox speaks of a
race between Achilles and a tortoise, but I prefer to write a slightly different
version, on a competition between the two hands of a clock. The question is
this:
The hands of the clock meet at 12 o’clock. At what hour will they meet
again?
Zeno’s paradox states that this will never happen. This is absurd, but
Zeno had a “proof.” At exactly 1 o’clock the hour hand will be ahead
of the minute one, because it will point to 1, while the minute hand will
point to 12. By the time the minute hand reaches 1, the hour hand will
1
advance a bit. Actually, we know exactly how much: 12 of an hour, since
1
its speed is 12 that of the minute hand, and the minute hand advanced
1
from 12 to 1. Now the hour hand points to the hour 1 12 (1:05), and the
minute hand has to reach this place. But until it does so, the hour hand
1
will advance a bit more. And, once again, we know exactly how much: 12
1 1 1
of the minute hand, that is, 12 × 12 = 144 of an hour. The minute hand
has to reach this place, and in the meantime the hour hand will advance
1 1 1
a bit more, 12 × 144 = 1728 of an hour. This will continue in the same
way: every time that the minute hand reaches the previous position of the
hour hand, the hour hand will advance a bit more in the meantime. It
therefore seems that the minute hand will never be able to catch up to
the hour hand! There will always be some gap between them, even if it
becomes increasingly small. In the original paradox, in which Achilles ran
against a tortoise, Achilles gives the tortoise a head start. According to
the exact same argument, Achilles will never be able to catch up to the

229
230 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

tortoise, because every time that he reaches the tortoise’s former position,
the tortoise will have advanced in the meantime, even if only a little bit.
But we know, of course, that the minute hand will pass the hour hand,
and that Achilles will quickly overtake the tortoise. So where does Zeno
cheat?
Before we answer that, let us ask ourselves: at what hour exactly do the
two hands meet? We could write an equation, and then solve it. But there
is a more elegant, and much simpler, way to do this. Over the course of 12
hours the two hands meet 11 times: every whole hour and something; except
for the hour 11 and something, since then the meeting will be at 12, and not
at “11 and something.” Now, note that the time that passes between each
two meetings of the hands is the same. A simple way to see this is to remove
the numerals from the clock, and to rotate it so that at the time of a meeting
it will look as if both hands are pointing to 12 o’clock. Now it is clear that
the exact same time will pass until the next meeting as passed between 12
o’clock and the first succeeding meeting. Therefore, the 12 hours of the day
divide into 11 equal parts. And so, 12 11 of an hour passes between each two
meetings. The first meeting after 12 o’clock will be at the hour 12 11 , which is
a little before 1:06.
Where did Zeno go wrong? His argument was correct up to a certain point,
but he erred in his conclusion. He divided the time to the next meeting of
the hands into infinitely many parts. The sum of these periods of time (in
1 1 1
hours) is 1 + 12 + 144 + 1728 + · · · . This is an infinite series, that is, the
sum of infinitely many numbers. Zeno argued that since there are infinitely
many terms, the sum is infinite, namely, the time that will pass until the
next meeting is infinite. This, however, is wrong. The sum of an infinite
number of numbers can be finite, on condition that the numbers decrease
at a sufficiently rapid pace. And this is what happens here: each number
is smaller than its predecessor by a factor of 12. This means that it is a
1
geometric series, with a quotient of 12 (we first encountered this notion
in the chapter “Mathematical Ping-Pong”). And every geometric sequence
with a quotient smaller than 1 has a finite sum. The classic example is the
geometric series with the quotient of 12 , a series in which each element is
smaller than its predecessor by a factor of 2. The sum is 1 + 12 + 14 + 18 + · · · ,
which is 2. In order to see this, observe that the distance of 1 from 2 is
1; the distance of 1 + 12 from 2 is 12 ; the distance of 1 + 12 + 14 from 2 is
1
4 . The addition of each element in the series halves the distance from 2.
Accordingly, the partial sums of the series tend to 2. The “partial sums” are
Infinitely Many Numbers Having a Finite Sum 231

the sums of the first elements — in this case, the first partial sum is 1, the
second partial sum is 1 + 12 , the third partial sum is 1 + 12 + 14 , and so on.
It is also not difficult to prove that if q is a positive number smaller
than 1, the infinite geometric series 1 + q + q 2 + q 3 + · · · converges to a
finite number. What number? We can calculate this with the method we
used in the chapter “The Book in Heaven.” Use the letter S for the sum
1 + q + q 2 + q 3 + · · · . Multiply each element in the series by q. This gives
us qS = q + q 2 + q 3 + q 4 + · · · . Note how close is the expression for qS
to S itself: it just misses the first term, 1. So, qS = S − 1. This can be
viewed as an equation in the unknown S, that can be easily solved. Moving
S to one side we get S(1 − q) = 1, and then by dividing both sides by
1
(1 − q), we obtain S = 1−q . For example, if q = 12 , for which the series is
1 + 12 + 14 + 18 + · · · , we obtain S = 1−1 1 = 2, which is what we discovered
2
1
earlier. In the case of the clock, q = 12 , so by this formula the hands will meet
after 1 + 12 + 144 + 1728 + · · · = 1− 1 which is 12
1 1 1 1
11 hours, as we already know.
12

Sequences that tend to 0, with sums that nevertheless


are infinite

Is it always the case that when the elements of the series tend to 0, the
series sum is finite? The answer is no. The simplest example of this is the
following:
1 + 12 + 12 + 13 + 13 + 13 + 14 + 14 + 14 + 14 · · · (next comes 5 times 15 ). The elements
tend to 0, but two halves are 1, three thirds are 1, and four fourths are 1 —
we have a sum of 1 an infinite number of times. This means that the partial
sums of the series tend to infinity, that is, the sum is infinite.
The next example is more sophisticated, and also more important,
because it appears in numerous contexts. This is the series 1+ 12 + 13 + 14 +· · · ,
which is called the “harmonic series.” Its elements tend to 0, but its sum is
infinite, which means that its partial sums tend to infinity. In order to see
this, partition the sum as follows:
     
1 + 12 + 13 + 14 + 15 + 16 + 17 + 18 + 19 + 10 1 1
+ · · · + 16 · · · . Each pair of
1
parentheses contains a sum that is at least 2 . Why? The first pair has two
numbers, each of which is at least 14 , so the sum is at least 12 ; the second
parenthesis contains 4 numbers, each of which is at least 18 , so the sum is at
least 12 , and so on. So, we have a sum of infinitely many numbers each being
at least 12 , which gives infinity.
Twists

In jokes, unexpected twists make for a humorous effect. In mathematics and


in poetry they generate a sense of beauty. In this chapter I want to return to
poems, in which the twist plays a special role: those having a total change
of meaning in their last line. We already met such a poem, “See the Sun,”
in the chapter “Infinitely Large,” and discussed the subtlety of the trick.
When the meaning of a whole poem changes in the last line, a lot of
information has to be digested in a split second. Suddenly, all previous lines
have to be re-interpreted. Since our conscious mind is not quick enough
to grasp all these changes so fast, most of the message remains not fully
understood.
Let me exemplify this in a poem by the Israeli poet Jacob Steinberg
(1887–1947), “The Book of Life.”

It may happen that a child, not having a playmate


Would hug a thick book, and though not being able to read
Would leaf through it, page after page.

And then suddenly, as if burdened by some mystery,


his hands would rest
His tiny fingers clutching to some code, and in his
eyes there freezes an unanswered hope.
For just a fleeting moment a victorious smile brushes his lips,
And then slowly the tired head falls,
and with a last whining his mouth goes quiet.
Then, just before the child falls asleep, unheeded,
a hand takes the book away.
An lo, the play is over, like the play of the life of a man.

On its face, this is an uninspired poem. The metaphors are corny, and the
story slow and heavy. But then everything changes in the last line. Suddenly
we realize that all details of the poem are metaphors for the course of human

233
234 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

life. Each line has to be read anew. Life is like a book too hard to understand;
man is like a child desperately trying to decipher the code of a book, an
attempt that is doomed to fail; fate treats a man towards the end of his life
like a forgiving father, that puts his child to sleep at night; the child’s sleep
turns out to be, in fact, death; the opening words of the poem — “It may
happen” acquire an ironical meaning — it is not that “it may happen,” it is
always the case.
So, the twist is a trick of condensation. A lot of information is compressed
into one line. But it is a special type of condensation: it does not require
conciseness. On the contrary, the longer the poem is, the more information
is compressed into the last line. The details are not understood correctly
at first reading, so they may as well be said at length. The moment of
illumination will be too brief for a conscious scanning of all these details and
reinterpreting them.
Let me just point out one other stratagem that Steinberg’s poem uses that
makes it a gem: the reversal of roles between tenor and vehicle. Throughout
the poem, and in particular in the last line, it seems that life is a metaphor
for reading the book. “The play is over, like the life of a man.” The meaning
is of course the opposite, “life is for us like a book to an ignorant child.”
“Knowing without knowing,” all the way.
Knowing without Knowing

Men use words only to disguise their thoughts.

Voltaire, 1694–1778, French philosopher

What makes a person beautiful? One factor is essential: that we should not
know why he or she is beautiful. Beauty is said to be “blinding,” “stunning,”
“breathtaking” — all expressions attesting to its being beyond our conscious
understanding. We may feel stunned by scenery that is too majestic for us to
grasp with our ordinary tools of perception. Beautiful musical compositions
are too complex for us to know just what happens in them. Beauty is hidden
in what we don’t completely understand, at least not consciously.
This explains many of the so familiar characteristics of poetry. They are
all related to the aim of the poem, of sneaking messages without our notice.
The poetic devices are meant to distract our attention, so that the message
slips under the radar of consciousness. Brevity, for example, is nothing but
the magician’s dexterity, meant to deceive our critical faculties. The use
of external devices, like rhyme and meter, is meant to draw our attention
away from the content. This is the handkerchief under which the magician
performs his tricks. Outside appearance hides internal messages: an apparent
paradox hides deep truth, while verbally similar phrases may conceal deep
underlying contrast.

Poetical repetition

In nonfiction there are few sins more serious than repetition. A piece of
information that appears twice in the same text is like a stitch in a garment
that is wrongly exposed. “I already know that,” the reader thinks, and the
magic disappears. In poetry, by contrast, repetition is a powerful device.
A famous example is the poem by the Spanish poet Federico Garcia Lorca
(1898–1936), “Lament for Ignacio Sanchez Mejias.” Mejias, a close friend of
the poet, was a bullfighter that was killed in the arena. In every second line

237
238 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

the poem repeats the time of the corrida, and the effect is strong — the
poem’s fame is well-deserved. The following is one stanza from the poem:
At five in the afternoon,
It was exactly five in the afternoon.
A boy brought the white sheet
at five in the afternoon.
A frail of lime ready prepared
at five in the afternoon.
The rest was death, and death alone.

“Lament for Ignacio Sanchez Mejias,” The Selected


Poems of Federico Garcia Lorca, trans. Stephen Spender and J. L. Gili
“Anaphora” is the name given by the Greeks, in the theory of rhetoric, to the
repetition of the same combination of words at the beginning of sentences.
Epiphora is repetition at the end of sentences, as in this poem. The secret
is in the tension between exterior and interior. While on the surface things
repeat, underneath there is change. In “Lament for Ignacio Sanchez Mejias,”
for example, while the words jog in place, the content develops towards a
climax, with the tension increasing in each line. The repeated words also
convey another meaning: they are like a hammer banging at the mourner’s
head, forcing him to face the fact he so wishes to deny.
Poetical repetition has an anesthetic aim. When we hear an expression
for the second time, we are misled to believe that there is no need to deci-
pher it again. When it comes around a third time, it already all but evades
conscious attention. By this the poem attains the magician’s goal: diversion
of attention. Something very similar occurs in the two well-known poeti-
cal repetitions of form, those of sounds (rhyme) and of tempo (meter). The
repetitive sounds lull us, and the external similarity between the words leads
us to expect like meaning, as well. Thus the poem can sneak in messages
below the threshold of consciousness, touching the reader while avoiding
drawing his conscious attention to the touch.
Content and Husk

Why poetry?

This poem is a poem of people;


What they think and what they want
And what they think they want.

Nathan Zach, “Intro to a Poem,” from Different Poems


Poetry is a necessity, not a luxury. It has existed in every society for which
there is historical documentation, and it plays a role in everyone’s life,
whether he or she is aware of this or not. Even the most trite pop song
contains a poetical nucleus; our everyday communication is replete with
metaphors and symbols; poetry can even be found in road rage curses. But
why is this so? What need is there for this strange form of communica-
tion, that, on the face of it, does not seem to transmit any information, and
frequently is not understood? What place does it fill in our lives?
This chapter will speak of one, well known, answer to this question: poetry
opens a window to our inner selves. It enables us to touch deep places within
us. This answer is based on a picture of the psyche as consisting of inside
and husk. The psyche has a thin shell of logic, that mediates between the
inner mental forces and the external reality. This shell is vital for dealing
with the world, but it has its price: like every mediator, it creates a partition.
It constitutes a barrier that hinders direct access to the inside of the psyche.
And denying inner truth naturally creates longings. As a result, man always
searches for ways to fool logic, in order to reconnect with his inside. Poetry,
and art in general, are one of the means to achieve this. They can dupe the
husk, if only for a fleeting moment. Poetry teaches a person that his inner
world is no less important than the outer one. It helps him to skip beyond
what he thinks he wants to what he wants.

239
240 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Poetical detachment

As you set out for Ithaka


hope the voyage is a long one

Athika, Constantine Cavafy, trans. Edmund Keeley and Philip Sherrard


In order to penetrate our armor, poetry deludes us. It directs the reader’s
attention to external elements, in order to facilitate access to inner strata. All
poetical devices described in this book are harnessed to this goal. All create
a gap between what is on the surface and what is underneath. Seemingly
irreconcilable contrasts hide inner logic; combinations that seem impossible,
contain truth; metaphors distract attention from the real meaning — all
these provide the reader with a life preserver floating on the water for him
to grasp when another part of him dives deep down.
The human psyche attaches to the world in many ways, each of which
can be detached. When the external hold is severed, room is made for deeper
connections. I want to tell here about one type of detachment, with which
poetry is especially enamored: detachment of intent or of will. Will is prob-
ably man’s strongest point of attachment to the world, and therefore its
detachment has an especially potent effect. The poem is skeptical of exter-
nal desires — it attempts to show the heart what are its true longings. The
poem by Nathan Zach quoted above (for the second time, but for a different
purpose than in the first chapter) is indicative of precisely this detachment.
Go slow, these lines say. Stop for a moment — is what you imagine that you
want what you really desire, deep down?
A classic example is to be found in ars poetica poems. As I already men-
tioned, these poems often declare that the poet does not control what he writes.
This claim assumes an especially strange form in the poem After My Death by
Hayyim Nahman Bialik. Not only as regards why he writes poetry, but also as
to why he does not, the poet’s conscious “I” is not in charge.

After my death mourn me this way:


“There was a man — and see: he is no more;
before his time this man died
and his life’s song in mid-bar stopped;
and oh, it is sad! One more song he had
and now the song is gone for good,
gone for good!”

After My Death, Hayyim Nahman Bialik; trans. oldpoetry.com


Content and Husk 241

Bialik, still alive, prophesies that he will never sing his true song, as if this
were not at all dependent on his will. His true song, he explains in the
continuation of the poem, was destroyed within him, without intent and
without his being able to control this.

Poetic justice

History describes what has happened,


poetry says what should have happened.

Aristotle, philosopher, 384–322 BCE


There is wisdom in language. It absorbs and expresses covert processes and
hidden thought structures. An expression attesting to the role of detachment
of intent in poetry has taken root in all languages: “poetic justice.” It was
coined by the English critic Thomas Rymer, a contemporary of Shakespeare.
Poetic justice is justice appearing from nowhere, recompense that is detached
from the sin, but nevertheless suits it. As in poetry, it seems, on the surface,
that there is a break between the act and its punishment. Underneath, the
truth is revealed: at its best, poetic justice comes from within the person’s
character.
A recent example that comes to mind is from the Falklands War. In the
1970s a junta of generals seized power in Argentina, and for about a decade
they committed atrocious crimes. Thousands disappeared in torture cham-
bers, hundreds were thrown, bound, from airplanes into the sea. No force
could withstand the ruling military faction. And then, in 1982, the generals
took a foolish step: they took control of the Falkland Islands, windy and
insignificant isles in the southern Atlantic Ocean, that were under British
sovereignty. Great Britain, headed by Margaret Thatcher, went to war and
defeated Argentina. The war was limited to the islands, and did not reach
the mainland, thousands of kilometers away. Nonetheless, within a short
time after the war the rule of the generals disintegrated in some inexplica-
ble way, to be replaced by a democracy. It might have been the generals’
failure in what was supposed to be their strongest side, war, that led to
their internal collapse. At any rate, what the popular opposition failed to
achieve was done by a senseless war. Justice did not come here from some
external authority, nor was it directly connected to the act, but there was
truth in it.
242 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Whence the name “poetic justice?” It is called so because something sim-


ilar to what occurs in a poem takes place within it: the covert, subterranean
links are more significant than what is visible. As the poet Percy Bysshe
Shelley said, in a passage cited in an earlier chapter, poetry finds the inner
similarity between things that, on the face of it, appear different.
Change

Each wave owes the beauty of its line only to


the withdrawal of the preceding one.

Andre Gide, author


Connecting with inner forces and deep desires is a well-known aspect of
poetry. What is less well-known, and more subversive, is another goal:
change. One of art’s roles is to attain the so desired, and so difficult, aim
of changing.
To illustrate how art does this, I will begin with a somewhat prosaic
example: putting on shoes. A person trying to put his foot into a stubborn
shoe will randomly shake his foot this way and that, without any specific
direction. Surprisingly enough, this usually works, and the foot enters the
shoe. This is surprising because it isn’t clear how chance shaking can be
effective. No one mixes random ingredients in a bowl with the hope that the
resulting dish will be a success, or just let his legs lead him aimlessly when
he wants to get from point A to point B. Why does this work in the case
of the shoe? The answer is that shaking up releases from being stuck, that
is, from an undesired equilibrium. On the foot’s way into the shoe stable
situations are liable to be created, that is, situations that are difficult to
exit, but nonetheless are not the goal (the foot in the shoe). This is like a
person searching for the deepest valley who reaches a shallow one. He might
not even know whether he has reached his destination.
If our explorer wants to reach the desired valley, he must be carried away
from this temporary point of equilibrium (this is the mathematical term for
our local valleys). This is the benefit of random shaking. This idea is used
in applied mathematics in a method for finding the minimum of functions.
Every once in a while random movements are introduced to escape local
valleys.
In life, as in mathematics, sometimes a good shaking is needed to solve
a problem. Anyone who has gone through a crisis knows how it can be
an impetus for change. Old modes of behavior suddenly turn out to be

243
244 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The danger facing someone who is searching for the lowest point: when he reaches a
valley, he is liable to be stuck, instead of climbing out of the present valley, to look for
the deeper one. In life, too, the conduct that solves a local problem might not be effective
in an overall perspective.

ineffective, and a person must retreat within himself to mobilize new forces.
Upon returning to the external world, he is likely to use new, often better,
behavioral strategies.
But crises exact a stiff price, one that cannot be paid too often. This
is why man invented ways to bring about minor shakeups, in which only
one attachment to the world becomes undone, gently and not explicitly. The
effect is not sweeping, but even a small change is of value. Art is one of
the ways to induce such a shaking. The mind sends many minute tentacles
to the world, to hold onto ideas, objects, or people. Art removes, if even
for a fleeting moment, the grasp of one tentacle. For a moment the energy
that was invested in the external world is detached, and retreats inward.
When reattached, it can be rebuilt in a new form. A painting that represents
its object from a new angle, the reorganization of sounds in music, or the
unconventional arrangement of ideas in poetry — all these undo existing
attitudes, making us aware of other possible ways of relating to the world.

Detachment and creativity

When asked how he arrived at his discoveries, Einstein replied: “I ignored


an axiom.” It is not entirely clear to what axiom he referred, because he
disregarded many, but most likely he meant the belief that the result of a
measurement is independent of the relationship between the measurer and
the measured. In the theory of relativity the measured mass of a body, like its
length, depend on its speed relative to the measurer. Einstein says that to dis-
cover something new, the old has to be relinquished. Sometimes a discovery
is not a new idea, but the waiving of an old one. Geniuses like Einstein are
Change 245

capable of giving up old conventions without any external stimulus. Most of


us need a shaking that comes from the outside.
Creativity means, before everything, willingness to abandon habitual
thought patterns. This is why creativity is so close to humor. Humor is
simply the ability to distance ourselves from things. Like humor, creativity
demands not taking conventions too seriously.

Know yourself

For childhood
does not grow, no, never.
It is covered with layers, like a thickening shell.

“Noah in the Districts of the Sea,” from


Separate Places, Shulamit Hareven
In our psychology-savvy times, it’s almost a cliché that change needs self-
understanding. In order to change a behavioral pattern, a person must first
recognize it. Less well-known is the fact that the opposite is true, as well, and
perhaps even more so: in order to know himself, a person must first change.
It is hard to be aware of a behavioral pattern if you are immersed in it up to
your neck. You first have to give it up, to some degree. The reason for this is
that deep personality traits come to the world bound up with their denial.
We don’t want to know that it is possible to act otherwise. The personality
builds barriers against changing.
This means that a shakeup is a tool not only for change, but also for
attaining insights. A shock causes a retreat inward, which in turn leads to
self-examination. “Unexamined life is not worth living” was Socrates’ —
perhaps a bit exaggerated — slogan. Since the time of the Greeks, art has
been thought to be one of the superhighways for self-observation. Tragedies,
for example, give the viewer opportunity to exert his emotions, and thereby
come into contact with them, through identification, while not having to
experience tragedy in his own life.
Estrangement

Not mine

None of that is mine. I look at it


with surprise. Of whom, from where, all that?

I do not know. An inheritance? No relative or


acquaintance has left me a thing. What now?

Shall I leave this place? If none of that is


mine, perhaps I’ll leave this place. And soon?

I don’t believe in the question’s good faith


and I look at myself with surprise.

“Surprise,” from Other Poems, Nathan Zach; trans. Yoseph Milman


Science advances by leaps. A scientific revolution takes place every decade or
two in almost every field. Anyone who has ever seen the progress of a flock
of swallows knows what I’m talking about: the leader of the flock makes a
sudden turn, and the entire swarm of birds follows his lead and changes direc-
tion. “Quantum leaps” of this sort are made in the natural sciences: a new
method or a new concept are invented, and the efforts of the entire scientific
community are diverted to the new direction. It seems that progress in the
humanities is of a completely different nature. Leaps are rare, and progress
is more like the flow of a long and wide river. But there are exceptions, and
major discoveries occur also in the humanities. An example in question is a
notion discovered in the 1920s by the Russian art scholar Viktor Shklovsky,
and named by him “estrangement.”
Shklovsky was a theater critic, and a close friend of the poets Anna
Akhmatova and Osip Mandelshtam. In some respects he was a lucky person,
because, unlike most of those around him, he was not directly affected by
the Stalinist terror, and he and his family miraculously escaped the frequent

247
248 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

purges. The term “estrangement” that he coined comes from “strange,” and
means placing things in a strange and new light, for the purpose of restoring
pristine freshness to their perception. Shklovsky argued that as the years
pass our senses becomes dulled, and they need to be shaken to revital-
ize them. The role of art, he said, is to cause someone who lives next to
the sea to hear anew the murmur of the waves to which he has long been
accustomed.
Estrangement is a type of shaking. What is special about it, among other
artistic shakeups, is our awareness of it. In most artistic experiences a person
forgets himself. Someone watching a movie is usually absorbed in the plot and
a person listening to a symphony forgets the world outside. Estrangement
does the opposite — it places a mirror before the viewer, and causes him
“to look at himself in surprise.” The result is the shock of alienation, and
the awakening of consciousness to automatic responses. Like the surprise
of Monsieur Jordan, the hero of Molière’s The Bourgeois Gentleman, who
suddenly realizes that he has been speaking prose his entire life.
The experience of estrangement is often accompanied by pleasure. For a
moment we cease to be slaves to habit, and become its masters. A famous
example is the pleasure we derive from discovering the origin of words. Some-
one who discovers that the three words “radio,” “radiator,” and “radius” all
are derived from the Greek word radia, meaning “beam,” suddenly becomes
master of the words instead of their slave, and entertains the pleasure of
freedom. Indeed, one of the terms Shklovsky uses for estrangement is “de-
automatization.”
Estrangement is particularly characteristic of modern art. Picaso, with his
deformed faces, causes us to re-think the way we perceive our surroundings.
Stravinsky shocked the ears of the audience of the beginning of the twentieth
century, and caused people to stop for a moment and think about what is
music and what is the role of sounds in their life. Brecht declared it as
an aim, to cause people to step back from the show and realize they are
watching theater, and not real life. These are manifest cases, but even when
the estrangement is not so obvious it is always there, in all art, if only for
the reason that it is taken out of the context of everyday life, and happens
in a museum or a concert hall.
Estrangement 249

Leaving habit behind

Leaving habit behind is essential to the solution of many mathematical prob-


lems. Here are some examples, in addition to those we have already met.

1. Is it possible to cut a round cake into 8 pieces with 3 straight-line cuts?


2. Can 4 triangles be formed with 6 matches?
3. The following drawing shows how it is possible to pass through 9 points
arranged in a square with a broken line (a line composed of straight
sections, that is drawn without lifting the pencil from the page) with 5
sections. Can this also be done with a line of only 4 sections?

4. A patient has to take daily one pill of type A, and one pill of type B.
One day, each of the two bottles had exactly two pills left. And then
disaster struck — both bottles fell and broke, and the pills were mixed
up. Unfortunately, the two types of pills look the same, and the patient
cannot distinguish between them. What will he do?

Habit is the obstacle to solving each of these problems. The first problem
is difficult, because we are accustomed to cutting pizzas, and a pizza is
divided into 6 sections with 3 cuts, and not 8. But there is a difference: a
pizza is thin, while a cake has another dimension in which it can be cut —
its height. If we only think in terms of this third dimension, the solution is
easy: divide it into 4 pieces by two vertical cuts, as with a pizza; and then
cut the cake across its width, perpendicular to the vertical axis.
For the second problem, as well, we have to overcome habit: we are used
to two-dimensional matches puzzles, in which the matches lie in the plane.
As soon as we forgo this assumption and allow the matches to be in three
dimensions, the solution is simple — try it for yourselves.
250 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The difficulty with problem no. 3 is that we assume that the broken line
has to be drawn within the square. If we allow it to go beyond the square,
then the solution is quite easy. Here it is:

As to the fourth problem, here is a hint: it is not necessary to take whole


pills, they can be divided into pieces!
An Endless Encounter

Don’t worry about people stealing your ideas. If your ideas


are good, you’ll have to ram them down people’s throats.

Howard Aiken, IBM engineer and inventor

The bridge that is never entirely crossed

Few sensations can be compared to that of making a scientific discovery. All


of a sudden, everything falls into place — the examples, the partial results,
the hypotheses that were raised on the way. For at least a single moment it
seems that the world is going your way. We can only imagine the exultation
of Francis Crick and James Watson at the moment of illumination in 1953
when they uncovered the double helix structure of DNA. How, all at once,
all facts gathered up to that point coalesced into a coherent whole.
The moment of illumination is supposed to be brief. It is a transition from
a state of non comprehension to comprehension, and this can be done only
once. But this is not quite the case. As far as beauty goes, this moment lasts
forever, as an endless encounter. The joy of discovery remains as time passes,
both for the discoverer and for the learner. This is because the transition
is never fully consummated. Things are never fully understood. Perception
always remains on two levels, along with the wonder at the beauty of the idea.
It will be interesting to compare this with another product of human
thought in which surprising shifts play a major role — the joke. There the
situation is just the opposite: a joke is like a burnt match. Instead of ongoing
wonder and a sense of beauty, it leaves behind a sensation of release, and
after being heard the first time, it is no longer funny. This is because in a
joke, the bridge is crossed in its entirety. Moreover, after the bridge has been
crossed, it is demolished. After hearing the joke, you are on the other side
of the river, with no way back. The perspective irrevocably shifts with the
punch line, when we realize that the former perspective was merely bait, and
is abandoned now.

251
252 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The turning point in mathematics and in poetry is not a complete change


of perspective. We always have one foot on each bank of the river. The reason
for this is that a new idea requires its discoverer, and its learner, to establish
a complex structure in his brain, and structures are not erected all at once.
Usually, they continue for a long time in embryonic form. And so things
continue to be a source of amazement even after they seemingly are known.
The order in the world is too complex to be understood fully, and the receiver
knows that a still deeper order exists beyond the horizon. It is as if what he
discovered is only a gold trace on the rock face, that indicates the existence
of a richer lode deep in the earth.

Are mathematicians and poets really alike?

On our journey we encountered many points of similarity between mathe-


matics and poetry. But any comparison between the mathematician and the
poet fails in one place: their mode of work. Open a window to the mathe-
matician’s office and the poet’s attic, and look at how they work. For the
mathematician, we can see more than one mode of working. Some mathe-
maticians work alone, while others need to talk to someone in order to think
better. It also happens that a mathematician’s work style changes during his
career, usually in the direction of teamwork. As the years pass researchers
forge scientific ties, and work more with colleagues or students. Some dis-
cover in the course of time that the pleasure derived from working together
is comparable to that of a scientific discovery. A common course of events is
that at a young age a person engages in research by him (or her)self, making
at this stage the most significant discoveries, and as he or she grows older he
prefers to work with others. In any case, most of the articles written today
in mathematics (and even more so in the natural sciences) have more than a
single author, that is, they are the result of joint work. The writing of a poem
in company, in contrast, sounds so absurd that if it exists, it is undoubtedly
done as a lark.
There is an additional difference between mathematicians and poets. I’ll
reveal a secret to you, one that is probably hidden from the public, but is well
known to families of mathematicians: whether he works by himself or with
fellow researchers, most of the time the mathematician stares into space. He
tries to draw pictures for himself in his mind, to examine individual cases,
formulate hypotheses. He also reads other mathematicians’ papers. The poet
doesn’t engage in any of these. He doesn’t read the work of others in order to
find inspiration (if he were to do so, this would be transparent). He doesn’t
An Endless Encounter 253

invest effort in examining special cases. His staring, so it seems to me, is less
intensive, and he works as if in a dream.
All this stems from one basic difference: while the mathematician tries
to discover something in the world, the poet’s aim is to dive within him (or
her)self. The discovery of order in the world can be done in a conversation
with someone else, and be aided by ideas of others, but only the individual
himself can delve into his soul.

The role of split perception in poetry and in mathematics

There is another difference regarding the two-level perception. In poetry,


split perception is absolutely essential. It enables the poet to dive into
himself, and bypass the barriers of critical thought. The indirect state-
ment mechanisms are weapons used to penetrate the logical armor that
surrounds the psyche like a shell. In other words, in poetry split per-
ception is the aim, and the poetic devices are all means intended to
produce it.
It is a different story in mathematics. Split perception is not an aim, but
a byproduct. It has no independent role of its own, and is an effect of the
discovery process. The sense of magic is only the outcome of the difficulty
in consciously digesting the new ideas. As already noted, beauty serves as a
motivation for mathematicians. But it isn’t the primary goal.

Depth

Maybe its nice, after all, to write poems.


You sit in your room and the walls grow taller.
Color deepens.
A blue kerchief becomes a deep well.

Dalia Ravikovitch, “Surely You Remember,” The Window,


trans. Chana Bloch and Ariel Bloch
But this isn’t the whole story. If this were all, the mathematician would
not need to have something of the poet in him. There is a more essential
similarity between the poet and the mathematician: both look for depth, one
in life, and the other in the material world. Both seek subterranean patterns,
and to this end both use nonstandard methods of thinking. A new discovery
requires momentary disregard of pure logic, plunging into the depths of the
254 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

unconscious, from where new ideas, both strange and beautiful, are meant
to be drawn. In poetry, too, split perception is not just a means, but the
result of thought modes of this type. Mathematical magic, like poetic magic,
is produced by unexpected leaps of thought, and from amorphous thought in
which “a blue kerchief becomes a deep well.” This is the matter from which
beautiful mathematical discoveries and beautiful poems are cut out. And
whoever is capable of such thought could become a perfect mathematician
or a perfect poet.
Appendix A: Mathematical Fields

Algebra: Algebra was invented by the Indians, who later handed it down
to the Arabs. It reached the West through Al-Khwarizmi’s book Al-Jabar,
literally meaning “restoration.” This refers to a common way of solving equa-
tions, by identical operations on the two sides of the equation. The main idea
in algebra is calling numbers by names of letters. This is useful in two cases:
when we want to speak about general numbers (in this case the letter is
called “variable”) and when we want to find an unknown number by some
indirect information on it (in this role the letter is called “unknown”). The
meaning of the word “algebra” changed in the nineteenth century, and came
to denote the study of operations, like the four operations in numbers, but
more general and abstract. The most basic example of a structure with an
operation is the “group”, a set with one operation that has similar properties
to those of addition in the integers.
Combinatorics, or Discrete Mathematics: A field dealing with (usually)
finite sets, and relations defined on them. Classical combinatorial problems
are about counting: in how many ways can you choose a committee of 4 out of
100 people? “Discrete” is the opposite of continuous, so discrete mathematics
usually deals with integer quantities, as opposed to quantities that can be
as small as we please. Computers act discretely — a cell can be active or
non active, with no intermediate possibilities, and a digit is either 0 or 1,
with no third possibility. Hence the study of computer actions needs discrete
mathematics. For this reason discrete mathematics has flourished in the last
half century.
Differential and Integral calculus: A branch of mathematics that deals
with limits, in particular with tending to zero or to infinity. So, in particular
it deals with quantities that are “infinitely small” (meaning really — as
small as we please), and hence it is also named “infinitesimal calculus.” The
seeds of this field were sawn already by the ancient Greeks, who used it
to calculate areas and volumes. In the seventeenth century the field had a
revival, because it is so useful in physics, in particular in the study of motion.

255
256 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

The most prominent among its developers were Fermat, Barrow, Newton and
Leibniz. Differential calculus studies continuous change. It goes from the
global behavior to the local, for example calculating the velocity of a body
at a given moment from knowledge of its overall motion. Integral calculus
goes the other way — from local to global. For example, from knowing the
velocity of a body at every given moment to the overall distance that it
covers in its motion.
For about two hundred years mathematicians studied the notions of tend-
ing to zero and to infinity in an intuitive manner. In the nineteenth century
it transpired that precise definitions were needed. French and German math-
ematicians — Cauchy, Riemann, Cantor and Weirstrass, took on this job.
They got rid of notions like “infinitesimally small quantities”, and replaced
them by “quantities as small as we please”.
Mathematical logic: This is the “mathematics of mathematics”, namely
mathematical study of what mathematicians do. The field began with
Aristotle, who pointed out some basic rules, and defined what is logical
implication. It revived towards the end of the nineteenth century, with the
realization of Frege that a mathematical proof is a game that could be played
mechanically (in modern day terminology — by a computer). A far reaching
revolution in the field was made by Gödel, who proved in 1931 some impos-
sibility results. For example, that no “reasonable” set of axioms for number
theory can prove all true statements about numbers, and that though a
computer can recognize a proof, no single computer program will be able to
prove all provable statements in Number Theory.
Number Theory: The oldest and one of the deepest mathematical field.
Its objects, the natural numbers (1, 2, 3, . . . ), are seemingly simple, but
their study gave rise to the development of entire mathematical fields — for
example, algebra.
Set theory: The basic notion of this theory is a very simple one — elements
belonging to sets. While the study of finite sets is given to combinatorialists
(see above), set theory concerns itself with infinite sets. One of its main
topics is the study of sizes of sets. Cantor, the founder of the field, proved
that even in the infinite realm there are different possible sizes — there are
big infinite sets, and there are bigger.
Topology: Topology is geometry without measuring distances. If you take a
rubber sheet, and stretch or compress parts of it in some directions, without
making any cuts in it, for the topologist the sheet will remain the same. What
matters is only the number of holes in the sheet, which does not change with
stretching and compressing.
Appendix B: Sets of Numbers

Natural numbers: The numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, . . . . These numbers indeed live


up to their name. Mathematics takes thought processes and abstracts them,
and in this case it is the most basic process that is abstracted: partitioning
the world into types of objects. When objects of the same type repeat, we
count them “1 apple, 2 apples, 3 apples, . . .”. The number 0 had a slow start.
It reached Europe only in the 12th century.
Integers: These include the natural numbers, plus the negative numbers,
−1, −2, −3, . . . . Negative numbers had an even harder time being accepted
than 0. They got legitimacy in Europe only in the 16th century.
Rational numbers: Another name for these is simply “fractions”. A ratio-
nal number is a number that can be written as the quotient of two integers,
the divisor being non zero. For example, 73 , or −2
5 . The rational numbers
arrived much before the negative numbers, because they arise very natu-
rally: even ancient man had to divide apples to 3 equal parts. Pythagoras
believed that rational numbers rule the world — every important quantity
should be rational.
The reals: Pythagoras was disillusioned.
√ He discovered that not every natu-
ral quantity is rational. For example, 2 is not. Namely, there is no rational
number whose square is 2. So, we have to invent such a number. This num-
ber can be approximated by rational numbers as well as we please, meaning
that there are rational numbers whose square is as near as we please to 2.
In the nineteenth century it was realized also that π, the ratio of the cir-
cumference of the circle to its diameter, is also irrational. Of course, this
ratio, too, can be approximated by rational numbers. Using approximation,
we can construct many irrational numbers. Cantor, towards the end of the
nineteenth century, proved that the irrationals are many indeed: they are
more numerous than the rational numbers.

257
258 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

Algebraic numbers: These are real numbers that are the √ solution to a
polynomial equation with integer coefficients. For example, 2 is algebraic,
because it is the solution of the equation x2 = 2.
Complex numbers: The square of a real number is always non-negative.
This means that in the real numbers you will not find a number x satisfying
the equation x2 + 1 = 0 (in other words x2 = −1). So, such a number must
be invented, just like negative numbers were invented to solve equations
like x + 1 = 0. Such a number, later denoted by i (for “imaginary”) was
introduced in the sixteenth century. Once i is around, it can be combined
with real numbers, namely multiplied by them and added to them. The
result of such operations is called a “complex number”, for example 3 + 2i
(complex, because it is composed of two parts, the real part — the 3 in the
example above, and the imaginary part — the 2i in the example. Actually,
we say that the imaginary part is 2, the i being indicated by the word
“imaginary”). Gauss showed that using complex numbers, any polynomial
equation can be solved. So, there is no need in further extension of the
kingdom of numbers, at least not from the direction of seeking solutions for
equations.
Appendix C: Poetical Mechanisms
Mentioned in the Book

The following definitions of the poetic devices mentioned in the book are
titled in the direction of the topic of this book, namely, their effect on the
reader and the way they generate beauty.
Anaphora: the repetition of the same combination of words at the begin-
ning of sentences; a special case of the poetical repetition, in which an
expression recurs throughout the poem. As in many poetical mechanisms,
this creates a gap between the external expression and the underlying con-
tent: the repetition conceals change. Every time that the poem returns to
this expression it has a slightly different meaning, if only for the cumulative
effect. Repetition at the end of sentences is called epiphora.
Chiasmus: crossing. The word has its source in the Greek letter χ, called
“chi” (the parallel of X). Chiasmus exchanges places or roles, such as “He
wakes in the morning, but morning doesn’t wake in him.”
Compression: expressing many ideas with a single symbol. Compression
is not a mechanism by itself, and may be effected in many ways, including
metaphor, multiple meanings of words, or a picture that contains many mes-
sages. This is such an outstanding poetical trait that it is sometimes used
as part of the definition of poetry. Poems, like jokes, transmit their mes-
sages concisely. The German word for poetry is “Dichtung,” which means
“compression.”
Conceit: a sophisticated metaphor, in which the distance between the tenor
and the vehicle (see “Metaphor,” below) is large. The word has its source in
the originally Latin word “concept.” This term was invented to describe the
type of metaphors used by the members of a seventeenth-century poetical
movement in England, who were called the “Metaphysical poets” by their
opponents.
Displacement: turning the spotlight on one element of the poem, while the
true message is in an idea that appears at its fringes. That is, displacement
emphasizes a less important element in order to incidentally transmit the

259
260 Mathematics, Poetry and Beauty

significant message. Freud discovered this mechanism in dreams, and it also


appears in everyday use. For example, magnification words, like “very”, are
often used for displacement, diverting the stress of the sentence from the
main message to the magnifying word.
Hyperbole: exaggeration. The word means in Greek “throwing too far.” For
example: “I’d die for some chocolate.” Like other poetical devices, hyper-
bole generates detachment. Unlike the other mechanisms, however, that
diminish or use indirect statement, hyperbole reaches detachment by dis-
tancing the idea. When things are exaggerated and assume superhuman
dimensions, we do not sense them directly; it’s as if they’re from another
world.
Metaphor: from the Greek word meaning “to transfer from another place.”
It uses a usually familiar pattern, called the “vehicle,” to describe a (usually)
less familiar pattern, called the “tenor.” A distinction is sometimes drawn
between simile, that uses the words “like” or “as,” such as “my beloved is
like a young stag” in the Song of Songs, and metaphor, which does not use
such words, thereby equating the two terms (the tenor and the vehicle), such
as “your eyes are doves” or “all the world is a stage.” Actually, the difference
between simile and metaphor is minor.
Metaphor is the most widespread poetical device, and is the device most
closely identified with poetry. Its power lies in its double role: the transmis-
sion of information, and its concealment. It is at the same time an efficient
way of conveying ideas, and an indirect way of doing so.
Oxymoron: “stupid wise man” in Greek. The combination of opposites in
the same expression, such as “darkness as clear as day,” or “silence screams
within me.” The exterior contradiction generally conceals an inner truth.
Rhyme and meter: like many poetical mechanisms, rhyme and meter turn
to the external aspects of words, in order to distract the reader’s attention
from the inner meaning, thereby enabling it to be delivered subliminally.
In this respect, rhyme and meter are close to the mechanism of poetical
repetition (see “Anaphora”).
Syllepsis: joining together two unrelated ideas, that often belong to differ-
ent realms. This is a special case of zeugma, that combines two things
that might or might not be related, such as “I ate the salad and the
omelet.”
Turnaround: a twist that sheds new light on everything that came before
it. The twist usually comes at the end of the poem. It enables compression
Appendix C: Poetical Mechanisms Mentioned in the Book 261

(see above) without conciseness: at the moment of the turnaround, the reader
must absorb, all at once, the meanings of many things that appeared before-
hand, and that must suddenly be reinterpreted. Since it is impossible to
absorb so much all at once, a large part of the absorption is necessarily
subconscious.

You might also like