You are on page 1of 29

Behavioralism

Oxford Research Encyclopedia of International


Studies
Behavioralism  
Inanna Hamati-Ataya
Print Publication Date: Jan 2012 Subject: International Relations Theory
Online Publication Date: Jan 2018 DOI: 10.1093/acrefore/9780190846626.013.376

Updated references, expanded discussion of "Behavioralism in a Post-Behavioralist


Era."

Updated on 26 March 2019. The previous version of this content can be found here.

Summary and Keywords

Behavioralism is a paradigm that became predominant in American social sciences from


the 1950s until well into the 1970s. Although its reign did not last beyond the 1980s, it
has transformed the fields of (American) political science and international relations (IR)
so profoundly that it remains to this day an essential, albeit implicit, component of their
identity. The article starts with the context in which behavioralism emerged, then
engages the “Behavioral Revolution” in American political science and presents its main
epistemic, ontological, and axiological tenets. It then moves more specifically to
Behavioralism in IR, and to the terms of its “second debate.” The article concludes with
an assessment of Behavioralism’s legacy.

Keywords: Chicago School, Cybernetics, Easton, Epistemology, international system, Kaplan, Methodology,
Models, (neo)positivism, Quantitativism, Realism, Reflexivity, second debate, science, systems theory, theory,
values

Introduction
Behavioralism is a paradigm that became predominant in American social sciences from
the 1950s until well into the 1970s. Grounded in a belief in the unity of science and the
unity of human behavior, Behavioralist scholars developed scientific, quantitative
methodologies for the study of political processes and opened up the discipline to a wide
range of theories and methods imported from the social and mathematical sciences.
Because they believed that political phenomena could be subjected to the methods of
science, Behavioralists turned their back on the normative legacy of the discipline and
replaced political philosophy with the philosophy of science, thereby setting new
Page 1 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

standards for the formulation of concepts, hypotheses, theories, and protocols for
empirical testing and explanation building. Although Behavioralism’s paradigmatic reign
did not last beyond the 1980s, it has transformed the discipline so profoundly that it
remains to this day an essential, albeit implicit, component of its identity.

Because of Behavioralism’s inscription in different socio-intellectual contexts that are all


relevant for understanding its emergence, development, content, and impact on political
science and international relations (IR), and for the understanding of which it is also
relevant, a reference essay on Behavioralism necessarily takes multiple risks and has to
avoid several pitfalls. The first is to present the tenets of this school of thought
independently of the specific socio-intellectual context of both the American society and
the American Academy, thereby offering an unreflexive, de-contextualized, and ahistorical
account that fails to convey the relationship between cognitive consensus and socio-
historical constraints, and that simultaneously fails to reconstruct the meaning this
particular research program had for its main actors and opponents. Alternatively, the
danger is to give context too great a weight in the assessment of the content, value, and
contributions of Behavioral(ist) research, thereby imprisoning it in its own historicity, and
failing to appreciate the intellectual importance of its scholars’ input, of the profound
dilemmas they raised, and of the equally legitimate objections they faced.

At a second, related level, one has to avoid succumbing to the existent disciplinary
narrative of IR, a social science that views and tells its story as a succession of great
debates, with all the dichotomies, oppositions, and narratives of exclusion and conflict
such written history entails. Insofar as Behavioralism was a contending party in IR’s so-
called second debate, it is particularly difficult to extract it from the textbook histories of
the field and from its scholars’ institutionalized memory of it. While this can be said of all
the theories, paradigms, and cognitive doctrines that populate IR textbooks, it is
especially problematic for Behavioralism, which is often viewed as having
professionalized the discipline (Waever, 1997). Any reference to Behavioralism will
therefore be inevitably inscribed in intellectual and discursive strategies that aim to
assess the development of IR as a cognitive field of production, as well as its identity as
an autonomous academic discipline.

With these problems and constraints in mind, this article presents Behavioralism as a
historical contribution to, and reflection on, recurrent and fundamental epistemic
problems in the field. The article starts with the context in which Behavioralism emerged,
then engages the “Behavioral Revolution” in American political science and presents its
main epistemic, ontological, and axiological tenets. It then moves more specifically to
Behavioralism in IR, and to the terms of its second debate. The article concludes with an
assessment of Behavioralism’s legacy.

Page 2 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Behavioralism in Context: An American School


of Thought
Behavioralism finds its disciplinary and intellectual roots in Behaviorism, a school of
psychology founded by James B. Watson and influenced by the work of physiologist
Jacques Loeb (Lasswell, 1950, p. 553). Behaviorist psychology attempted to resolve the
dispute about the content, structure, and processes of human consciousness by evading
all questions about the content of the “little black box,” [focusing instead] on the
relationship between the stimulus as it acts on the black box and the black box as it
reacts to the stimulus (Merkl, 1969, p. 142).

It followed the lead of animal psychology, which operated on the basis that introspective
inquiry being impossible, one could only study animals’ behavior (Mead, 1934). The logic
of extracting the study of human beings from introspection and from the limited and
problematic understanding of the inner workings of the human mind and volition became
particularly attractive for social psychologists, who considered that, unlike intentions,
motivations, ideas, or beliefs, behavior could be understood with a great measure of rigor
and objectivity if the right scientific methods were applied. As Behaviorism, and then
Behavioralism, developed, these limitations were progressively waived, and
Behavioralists started concerning themselves “with the processes of cognition, feelings,
and with evaluations of human consciousness” (Merkl, 1969, p. 143). (On the differences
between Behaviorism and Behavioralism, see Easton, 1962).

In the United States, Behavioralism spread from psychology to the rest of the social
sciences, gaining a stronghold at the University of Chicago, which became, from the
1950s onward, a place where some of the leading Behavioralists coexisted with some of
their most renown and strongest opponents. In political science, the Chicago School, led
by Charles E. Merriam, had since the 1920s explicitly criticised the established tradition
of institutionalism for its limitations and its inability to produce a rigorous understanding
of political processes (Truman, 1969, p. 50). “Anxious to secure federal financing for
social science research, but apprehensive that some unenlightened ‘persons confound
social science and socialism’,” its scholars coined the term behavioral science and shifted
the ontological focus of political science research to the concept of political behavior
(Somit & Tanenhaus, 1967, p. 183) (For early Chicago School research, see Gosnell, 1937;
Lasswell, 1936, 1948; Merriam, 1939, 1945; Merriam & Gosnell, 1949; Schuman, 1935).

For some Behavioralists, “the existence of some key attitudes and predispositions
generated in the American culture,” such as “pragmatism, factmindedness” and
“confidence in science” (Dahl, 1969, p. 69) explain the success of Behavioralism in the
United States. In the United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization’s
(UNESCO) 1950 report on the state of “Contemporary Political Science” in the world,
Harold Lasswell thus writes:

Page 3 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

[i]n America, one does not appreciate political theories that do not lead to any
empirical study and have no influence on the conduct of public affairs… .
Americans respect science and technology, and our specialists in political science
dream of a field where authority is founded on experimental results and not on
dialectic alone. (Lasswell, 1950, p. 552, my translation; see also Cook, 1950, p. 83
and Merriam, 1950, p. 255, in the same volume)

These statements are meaningful at least because of their performative nature and as
illustrations of the new spirit that had taken hold of American political science, which, in
its Behavioral branch, was pursuing the project of a “science of politics” as it was
conceived at the turn of the 20th century, thereby breaking away from the philosophical
roots of the discipline.

Whether or not the American culture can be credited for the “rapid flowering of the
behavioral approach in the U.S.” (Dahl, 1969, p. 69), the impression that Behavioralism is
a specifically American phenomenon is shared by both American and non-American
scholars, as manifested in Hedley Bull’s (1966) critique of Behavioralist IR. Similar
scientific research had undoubtedly been attempted elsewhere—for example, in British
mathematician Lewis Fry Richardson’s theory of war (see Rapoport, 1957)—but the
United States provided a more favorable milieu for the propagation of such an intellectual
movement.

Behavioralism’s success can be better explained by the convergence of the interests and
concerns of American social scientists, on the one hand, and those of the American
government and public agencies on the other. In post-1945 America, government officials
needed reliable input from scientific disciplines that would help them understand the
roots and causes of different social, national, and international problems, assess their
possibilities for action, and predict or anticipate future outcomes and changes. At the
time, economics was the only social science to have gained such credibility in the eyes of
academics and politicians alike.

American social scientists were also keen to demonstrate the relevance of their fields of
study for practical social problems. In this specific socio-intellectual setting, political
science suffered from a composite complex of inferiority and an acute existential crisis
over the state of the discipline, which were due to a combination of several factors:

the discovery that the talents and skills of political scientists were not highly
valued by governmental personnel officers; the disconcerting realisation, by those
who did spend some time in the public service, of the profound difference between
the “accepted wisdom” of the profession and the reality of the governmental
process; the inability of traditional political science to account for the rise of
fascism, national socialism, and communism, or to explain the continuation of
these regimes in power; a growing sensitivity to, and unhappiness with, the
basically descriptive nature of the discipline; and a knowledge of apparent

Page 4 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

advances in other social sciences and a mounting fear that political science was
lagging behind its sister professions.

(Somit & Tanenhaus, 1967, p. 184)

Electoral processes and voting behavior, in particular, had been subjected to


sophisticated and impressive analyses by sociologists and social psychologists, who, with
the use of survey methods, were turning their craft into an appealing empirical science.

Quantitative studies were themselves facilitated by the development and wider


application of computers, which made it possible to use complex mathematical and
statistical computations. Behavioralist political scientists imported from other disciplines
the successful methods they thought would ground their analyses in scientific and
rigorous methodologies. This explains the emergence of a new generation of scholars who
were trained in areas that had never before been relevant to political science itself, such
as mathematics, physics, biology, economics, sociology, and psychology.

The specific impact on American political science of sociology and psychology was also
triggered by the arrival in the 1930s of a significant number of European—mainly
German—immigrants, who brought with them a new intellectual culture that exposed
their American colleagues to the works of Weber, Marx, Durkheim, Freud, Pareto, and
others, to a new philosophy of knowledge (logical positivism), and to a wide range of
analytical concepts and social theories that would be crucial to the development of
Behavioral science (Dahl, 1969, p. 69; Somit & Tanenhaus, 1967, p. 184).

Most of these European scholars were in fact radically opposed to Behavioralism


(Gunnell, 1993, 2006), with the notable exceptions of Heinz Eulau and Karl Deutsch. The
intellectual tradition that traveled with them to the United States took on a different
meaning and served very different research agendas. At the University of Chicago, where
Leo Strauss and Hans Morgenthau battled for the preservation of the philosophical
legacy of the discipline, the Department of Political Science was producing a new
generation of influential Behavioralist scholars who would bring prestige to the Chicago
School and to the entire discipline—most notoriously, Harold Lasswell (1936, 1948), V. O.
Key, Jr. (1956, 1968, 1969), David B. Truman (1951), Herbert Simon (1947), Gabriel
Almond (1950), David Easton (1953, 1965), Quincy Wright (1942, 1955), and Morton A.
Kaplan (1957). Behavioralism became prominent at Harvard with Karl Deutsch (1963)
and Sidney Verba (1961), Almond’s collaborator (Almond & Verba, 1963), at Yale with
Robert A. Dahl (1961) and at Stanford with Eulau (1966, 1977, 1986; see also Eulau,
Eldersveld, & Janowitz, 1956; Eulau & Prewitt, 1973; Eulau & Wahlke, 1978; Eulau,
Wahlke, & Buchanan, 1962).

Behavioralism also benefited from the support of the major American funding agencies.
The Social Science Research Council (SSRC) established in 1945 a Committee on Political
Behavior, chaired by a Behavioralist and naturally “behaviorally inclined.” The Carnegie,
Rockefeller, and Ford Foundations played an important role in promoting Behavioral
research, the latter having its own Behavioral Science Program. Behavioralist scholars

Page 5 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

soon monopolized the allocation of private and public grants, to the point that “access to
public funds was largely limited to the social sciences deemed worthy of the appellation
‘behavioral sciences’” (Somit & Tanenhaus, 1967, p. 185).

The 1950s proved to be a turning point for Behavioralism in both American political
science and American IR. It was not unusual after that point for Behavioralists to hold the
most prestigious and influential positions in the profession, including the Presidency of
the American Political Science Association (APSA) and membership in the SSRC. While
political theory and its normative, ethical tradition of inquiry had constituted the core of
the discipline since its establishment in the United States (Gunnell, 1993), Behavioralism
succeeded in marginalizing and even stigmatizing philosophically oriented scholars,
thereby monopolizing much of the American scholarly production of the field. It also
profoundly reshaped its cognitive tenets, terminology, methodologies, and scholarly
ethos, while redefining its relationship to the other social (and the non-social) sciences.
(For further readings on Behavioralism in the development of Political Science, see Baer,
Jewell, & Sigelman, 1991; Crick, 1959; Easton, 1997; Gunnell, 1993; Somit & Tanenhaus,
1967).

The Terms of the Behavioral Revolution


For the Behavioralists, as well as their critics, the debate around Behavioralism was
grounded in the opposition and tension between innovation and tradition (Eulau, 1969).
The Behavioral Revolution started as a declared protest (Dahl, 1969) against traditional
political science, which it viewed as being both too descriptive and too speculative,
lacking rigor and ambition, and incapable of analytical theorization and therefore of
cognitive growth. David Easton (1953) famously diagnosed the discipline as undergoing a
deep malaise that made its practitioners incapable of justifying their institutional
existence and intellectual relevance to the problems of the age. For the Behavioralists,
the problem originated in the discipline’s attachment and grounding in the disciplines of
philosophy and history, which prevented it from developing rigorous explanations of
specific political processes and grounded its discourse in general and obscure
assumptions wherein concepts such as human nature and power remained hermetic to
scientific explanation.

The answer to the discipline’s crisis was delineated in Easton’s (1962, pp. 7–8) definition
of the Behavioralist creed, which is subtended by a belief in both the unity of science and
the unity of human behavior:

1. Regularities: There are discoverable uniformities in political behavior [that] … can


be expressed in generalizations or theories with explanatory and predictive value.
2. Verification: The validity of such generalizations must be testable, in principle, by
reference to relevant behavior.
3. Techniques: Means for acquiring and interpreting data … need to be examined
self-consciously, refined, and validated.

Page 6 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

4. Quantification: Precision in the recording of data and the statement of findings


require measurement and quantification.
5. Values: Ethical evaluation and empirical explanation involve two different kinds of
propositions that, for the sake of clarity, should be kept analytically distinct.
6. Systematization: [T]heory and research are to be seen as closely intertwined parts
of a coherent and orderly body of knowledge.
7. Pure science: [T]he understanding and explanation of political behavior logically
precede and provide the basis for efforts to utilize political knowledge in the solution
of urgent practical problems of society.
8. Integration: Because the social sciences deal with the whole human situation,
political research can ignore the findings of other disciplines only at the peril of
weakening the validity and undermining the generality of its own results.

The Science of Political Behavior and Processes

The first important tenet of Behavioralism is that the social sciences can be as scientific
in their methods, modes of explanation, and conclusions as the pure sciences, the same
understanding of science prevailing in both. The objective, then, was to discover
regularities and patterns of behavior similar to the laws observed in nature. Given that
social organization and human behavior are governed by dynamic processes rather than
static patterns of repetition, the scientific models that were emulated were those of
biology, wherein systems are conceptualized on the basis of their functions and
interactions with their environment, rather than those of physics, wherein explanation
derives from the effect of covering laws of behavior on the properties of individual or
aggregate bodies. This explains why systems theory (Easton, 1953, 1965; Kaplan, 1957)
and cybernetics (Deutsch, 1963, 1978) became predominant in Behavioralist literature, as
they provided Behavioralists with the conceptual framework for the study of political
processes in terms of social adaptation, equilibrium, information processing, and
homeostatic regulation. (On the influence of scientific paradigms on Political Science, see
Schubert, Alker, & Zinnes, 1983).

The realm of political science per se was therefore epistemically conceived in


(neo)positivist terms, insofar as science concerns itself with givens, that is, observable
facts or, at most, observable manifestations of non-factual phenomena. Behavior therefore
took ontological precedence over such notions as human nature, freedom, reason, or
power. This (neo)positivist epistemology, however, should be understood as defining the
realm of science, not of knowledge in general. Although many Behavioralists adopted
(neo)positivism and even scientism as comprehensive attitudes toward the social world,
most of them did acknowledge that Behavioral science cannot encompass the realm of
understanding, and that many dimensions of human behavior and politics can only be
grasped by relying on historical, philosophical, and even ethical inquiry. This point was
misunderstood by most of their opponents, and by most commentators in both political
science and IR, who indiscriminately conflated Behavioralism and (neo)positivism,
thereby including the former in any critique of the latter. The Behavioralists’ aim, in fact,

Page 7 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

was to delimit the realm of scientific explanation and extract those phenomena that could
be explained scientifically from the over-arching paradigms of philosophical or historical
understanding that precluded the development of a rigorous empirical knowledge of
social reality.

Insofar as social processes can be objectified scientifically, the observer has to operate a
separation between what can and cannot be observed and agreed upon through the
methods of science. The datum of Behavioral science should therefore be amenable to
measurement, quantification, testing, and replication, which explains the introduction of
mathematics for the purpose of formulating rigorous relationships among clearly defined
variables. To the extent that regularities can be discovered, Behavioralism aspired not
only to explain past or present behavior and processes, but also to predict or anticipate
future ones, based on a precise assessment of the weight different variables take in
different settings. The development of analytical theories, wherein variables are
operationalized and related to one another within specific boundary conditions, should
therefore be validated by empirical testing. Those variables that cannot be tested—either
directly or indirectly—cannot be retained by Behavioral science.

This epistemic attitude was explicitly opposed to two modes of inquiry. The first is the
descriptive model of historical investigation, which is conceived as being concerned with
singular, rather than recurrent, phenomena. This is related to the difference between
synchronic and diachronic analysis (Eulau, 1969, p. 6). While history constitutes the
Behavioralist’s laboratory, it cannot spontaneously generate any explanation unless the
comparative method is used to assess the effect of changed historical conditions on the
behavior of individuals or social groups. Comparison, in turn, requires the methodical
construction of constants (parameters) and variables, so that it becomes possible to
measure variations and say something meaningful about what makes different social
systems evolve and how change operates.

The second mode of inquiry Behavioralism rejected is that which aims for transcendental
truths and characterizes philosophical, normative, and ethical discourse. More
specifically, it intended to extract political science from the speculative, ahistorical, and
universalizing narratives of philosophy, which is disqualified because it does not allow for
an “intersubjective validation” of knowledge of the social world (Eulau, 1969, p. 11). It is
this specific aspect of Behavioralism that most radically alienated traditional scholars
such as Leo Strauss, who considered that Behavioralism (identified with (neo)positivism)
implied a depreciation of prescientific, common sense knowledge. The aim was no longer
to attain an “absolute knowledge of the Why, but only” a “relative knowledge of the
How” (Strauss, 1969, pp. 97, 104).

Heinz Eulau (1969) provided a good conceptualization of this duality, thereby also
highlighting Behavioralism’s self-awareness of its own limitations:

Perhaps it is best to think of the study of politics as an ever-expanding set of


concentric circles, with a core that undergoes change very slowly, if at all, and
with a periphery that is ill-defined and forever changing. At the core we find the
Page 8 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

most traditional of approaches… . Here the search is for Truth, with a capital “T,”
and for eternal knowledge. At the periphery we encounter the agenda of
behavioral science which, unlike any other agenda, knows no limits … because the
method of science does not know final knowledge. Here inquiry is undertaken as
much to reduce ignorance as to discover truth. What knowledge emerges is
assumed to be partial, possibly temporary, contingent on the state of science, and
always probabilistic. As science reduces ignorance, it may know what is not the
case; it does not arrogate to itself knowledge of the truth. In this sense, behavioral
science is without firm boundaries and its agenda is never exhausted.

(Eulau, 1969, pp. 18–19)

Within this cognitive framework, Behavioralism developed a specific language, and a


novel terminology largely imported from other sciences. Behavioralist works
characteristically start with very detailed definitions of concepts and variables used, and
a clear statement of the research questions investigated, with clearly defined hypotheses
and protocols for testing them. The shift from traditional to scientific research is
exemplified in Harold Lasswell and Abraham Kaplan’s (1950) Power and Society, which
became the first Behavioral work to broadly impact the discipline and was famously
criticized by Morgenthau (1958, pp. 19–20) as a “monstrosity” that reflected a “thorough
misunderstanding of the nature of political theory and its relationship to empirical
research.” A comparison with Morgenthau’s Scientific Man Versus Power Politics (1946)
reveals the shift operated by the Behavioralists in terms of terminology, background
literature, and methodology.

As they developed new bridges connecting them to the rest of the social (and non-social)
sciences, the Behavioralists further alienated those scholars who considered that political
science was a discipline whose central object of study—power—distinguished it from all
other fields of inquiry. From a Behavioralist perspective, the ontological focus on political
behavior, which is merely one type of social behavior, precluded any such intellectual and
institutional autonomy. Interdisciplinarity was both an epistemic and an ontological
necessity, and many Behavioralists in fact denied political science the status of academic
discipline.

Values, Judgment, and the Ethos of Behavioral Science

In retrospect, the Behavioralists’ extensive discussions of methodological questions were


due to the absence of such discussions in traditional political science. Methodology was
by no means pursued as an end in itself. Although the Behavioralists widely contributed
to the introduction of the philosophy of knowledge and science in the disciplinary
literature, their aim was to improve the concepts and methods of research for the
purpose of empirical and practical relevance. For their critics, however, the stress on
methodology, methods, and the technicalities of science was shifting attention away from
the most important and meaningful questions, most of which appealed to the judgment of
the scholar rather than to technical standards of inquiry. In the process of achieving

Page 9 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

science, Behavioralists thus remained “open to the charge of strenuously avoiding that
dangerous subject, politics” (Bay, 1969, p. 140) and were even accused of turning “the
students of political science into political eunuchs” (McCoy & Playford, 1967, p. 9).

This general impression was more specifically related to the central question of the
relation of values to knowledge, which was one of the most central points of contention
between the Behavioralists and their critics. Here again, criticism was addressed to the
(neo)positivist underpinnings of Behavioralism, that is, to the delineation of the epistemic
and ontological realm of inquiry within whose boundaries Behavioralism consciously
limited itself. Eulau summarized Behavioralism’s axiological stance with respect to three
important questions pertaining to values:

First, on the question of whether values can and should be studied by the methods
of science, the answer is an unequivocal “yes,” just as the answer is “yes” to the
question of whether behavioral science can assess the consequences of alternate
policy choices. Second, on the question of whether a “value-free” social science is
possible, the answer is “no,” though the exclusion of value considerations in the
form of biases that distort scientific inquiry is desirable. And third, on the question
of whether behavioral science can arrive at judgments of what is “good” and what
is “bad,” the answer is that it cannot—that such judgments are, indeed, the task of
ethics as a separate enterprise.

(Eulau, 1969, pp. 11–12)

The Behavioralists had thereby adopted Max Weber’s position (see in particular Easton,
1953, p. 221), which is based on the “logical heterogeneity” between “statements of
facts” and “value-judgments” (Weber, 1949A, 1949B). Their central concern was to
extract value judgments from scientific explanation proper and guarantee that,
regardless of the context of discovery, the logic of explanation would remain unaffected
by personal or collective value preferences (Kaplan, 1964). The stress on methodology,
wherein value-control became an important standard, was meant to separate science
from ideology, and to critically raise the awareness of scholars to their own preferences,
assumptions, and biases, and of how these polluted the scientific process (Greene, 1970).
Some Behavioralists (such as Dahl) even adopted the strategy of clearly stating their
political and ideological preferences to their readers at the beginning of their analyses.
Much of these positions entailed a validation of the American democratic system. The
criteria for making such judgments were, however, rarely articulated (Bay, 1969, p. 122).

The real disagreement among Behavioralists was over the “behavioral scientist’s own
involvement in the issues of the day,” a classical dilemma for all social scientists,
including Weber himself (Weber, 2004). Since “there is nothing in the logic of science that
compels the scientist to commit himself to one of several conflicting public purposes—or
to withhold his commitment,” “commitment is as defensible as its opposite… . In this
respect, then, the scientist must come to terms with his own moral conscience. Neither
science nor philosophy can legislate his course of action” (Eulau, 1969, p. 12).

Page 10 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

The nuanced discussions and disagreements over the scholar’s ethos as a social agent
became entwined with a general tendency to confuse value neutrality (cognitive
objectivity/impartiality) with ethical neutrality (moral disengagement/indifference), two
notions that became subsumed under the generic expression value-freedom (Hamati-
Ataya, 2011). Much of the debate between the Behavioralists and their opponents
revolved around this confusing notion. With the rise of the culture of (neo)positivism in
American academia, the ethos of social and moral disengagement prevailed (Gunnell,
1993, p. 223), and the more nuanced understanding of the relation of values to
knowledge that Behavioralists had earlier offered was not only blurred but swept away by
the pressing concerns of empirical research. (For a later defense of Behavioralism’s
concern with values, see Rogers, 1977 and Searing, 1970).

A typical example of the confusion between value neutrality and ethical neutrality is
found in Strauss’ critique of Behavioralism, which also reflects the general impression
that Behavioralists have by and large taken the discipline toward a disengagement from
its most central ethical concerns: “Positivistic social science is ‘value-free’ or ‘ethically
neutral’: it is neutral in the conflict between good and evil, however good and evil may be
understood … moral obtuseness is the necessary condition for scientific
analysis” (Strauss, 1969, p. 98). For Strauss, this resulted directly from Behavioralism’s
rejection of common-sense and dialectical knowledge: by adopting the “perspective of the
scientific observer,” Behavioralists had forgotten the equally legitimate and equally
necessary “perspective of the citizen” (Strauss, 1969, p. 106).

These attacks on the Behavioralist ethos were not restricted to the debates among
political scientists. Behavioralists from all disciplines were accused of hiding their
implicit collusion with power behind the veil of value-freedom. In the 1960s, a general
dissident movement developed in American social sciences, leading to the establishment
of such associations as the Radical Caucus in Sociology, the Sociology Liberation
Movement, the Union for Radical Political Economists, and the Caucus for a New Political
Science, which considered the sciencizing of the discipline as a pursuance of “politics by
other means” (Surkin & Wolfe, 1970, p. 4). The general impression was that “the rigorous
adherence to social science methodology adopted from the natural sciences and its claim
to objectivity and value neutrality function as a guise for what is in fact becoming an
increasingly ideological, non-objective role for social science knowledge in the service of
the dominant institutions in American society” (Surkin, 1970, p. 14).

After having succeeded in significantly altering the epistemic attitude of political


scientists by stressing the importance of conceptual and methodological rigor,
Behavioralism was now faced with the dilemmas arising from its flirtation with
(neo)positivism. In a reflexive awakening that is rare among scholars enjoying the
authority and prestige of their dominant paradigm, Easton (1969) himself, then the
President of the APSA, offered such a critical assessment, acknowledging the need for
moral evaluation and philosophical inquiry, and for a new, “post-behavioralist revolution.”

Page 11 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Behavioralism and IR’s “Second Debate”


The Behavioral Revolution is considered to have launched IR’s so-called second great
debate. After the founding debate between Realism and Idealism over the what-question
concerning the discipline’s subject matter (Spegele, 1996, pp. xv–xvi), the second debate
is unanimously viewed as being about methodology and the how-question (Jackson &
Sørensen, 2003, p. 45; Vasquez, 1983, p. 19). This narrative is based on the generally
accepted—but not wholly correct—view that most Behavioralists were Realists (Brown &
Ainley, 2005, p. 33) who “challenged not the picture of the world that the realists had
provided but the realist conception of what constitutes an adequate scientific theory and
the procedures to ‘verify’ that theory” (Vasquez, 1983, p. 23).

The Modelling of International Processes

With the establishment of IR’s first paradigm, Realism, the idea that world politics
followed some objective laws and trends that the discipline was expected to discover and
explain was a familiar and widespread assumption. This made IR “an obvious candidate
for the application of the scientific method” (Crawford, 2000, p. 30). In their seminal 1950
reader, Principles and Problems of International Politics, Realists Hans J. Morgenthau and
Kenneth Thompson thus included a text by Nicholas Spykman (1950) that delineated the
difference between science and history: “what is true of one apple only is an historical
truth; what is true of apples in general is a scientific truth. The historical interest lies in
the unique quality of the individual apple, the scientific interest, in the qualities which it
has in common with all apples.” For Spykman, the “problem of science is to find out how
things work” (p. 23), and this is precisely what the Behavioralists intended to do.
Behavioralism was therefore to a large extent a natural development for IR—the
pursuance of Realism’s scientific aspirations with the emerging methods and techniques
of the age. The disagreement between Behavioralists and some Realists concerned the
belief in the unity of science, that is, that the same methodologies and standards applied
to both the physical and social sciences. Particularly controversial were the introduction
of quantitative analysis and the use of statistics.

Quincy Wright’s (1942) A Study of War may be considered the earliest Behavioralist work
in American IR, and an important achievement for the Chicago School itself (see also
Wright, 1955). In the following decade, Behavioralism imposed its marks on the field, with
such as works as Snyder, Bruck, and Sapin (1954) Decision Making as an Approach to the
Study of International Politics, which became, with James Rosenau’s (1966) article “Pre-
Theories and Theories of Foreign Policy” and Margaret and Harold Sprout’s (1956) Man-
Milieu Relationship Hypotheses in the Context of International Politics, a paradigmatic
reference for Foreign Policy Analysis (See also Rosenau, 1971). In 1957 were published
the two most influential texts, Morton A. Kaplan’s System and Process in International
Politics and Deutsch, Burrell, and Kann’s Political Community and the North Atlantic
Area. These two studies announced the general trend of Behavioralist IR scholarship: a
primordial concern for the philosophy of science (and knowledge), the use of concepts,
theories, and methodologies developed in the non-social sciences, and a reliance on
Page 12 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

quantitative data and analyses. (Important Behavioralist contributions are found in Knorr
& Verba, 1961, and Rosenau, 1961).

While not a self-styled Behavioralist work, Kaplan’s (1957) System and Process was
typical of the shift operated by Behavioralism in IR. Often viewed as a Realist for his
contribution to the conceptualization of the balance of power, Kaplan significantly
rejected the use of power as a meaningful concept for theoretical and empirical analysis
and hence turned his back on all the classical literature of Realist IR that borrowed so
heavily from political philosophy. Kaplan instead adopted systems theory as developed by
W. Ross Ashby in his Design for a Brain (1952) and treated the international system as a
type of homeostatic multistable system that could regulate itself by changing its internal
variables to search for better stability. Kaplan envisaged six different types of
international system in a state of equilibrium, characterized by a different organization of
their unit-actors (national and supranational) and a different distribution of capabilities
across the system. Two of these had existed (the balance of power and loose bipolar
systems), and the remaining four were properly modeled for the purpose of explanatory
and predictive analysis. Richard Rosecrance (1963) would later follow Kaplan’s example
and identify eight historical models of the international system between 1740 and 1960.
Anarchy was thus no longer conceived as a monolithic ideal-type for conceptualizing
either the international system or international state-behavior.

Deutsch also turned his back on Realism’s legacy and adopted communications theory
and cybernetics to analyze security communities. Unlike Kaplan, he relied heavily on
statistical analyses, which became his central methodology for testing hypotheses. Both
Kaplan’s and Deutsch’s approaches to equilibrium and stability were grounded in the
holistic, homeostatic analogy, whereby equilibrium results from dynamic regulatory
processes that operate within the system’s functional units. This differed significantly
from the individualist, market analogy that was later used by Kenneth Waltz (1979),
wherein equilibrium was the “unintended consequence of rational individual
action” (Guzzini, 2002, p. 37).

Behavioralism’s openness to the other sciences was not restricted to its borrowing of
their techniques and cognitive frameworks of inquiry. IR itself became open to, and
shaped by, specialists from other disciplines, such as economist Kenneth Boulding (1962,
1975), physicist Herman Kahn (1960, 1962, 1965), or mathematician Anatol Rapoport
(1963, 1989). John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern’s (1944) Theory of Games and
Economic Behavior became a reference for Behavioralist IR scholars, and Nobel Prize
winner Thomas Schelling developed Game Theory for the study of strategy and arms
control (Schelling, 1960, 1966; Schelling & Halperin, 1961). By and large, quantitative
analysis became a primordial methodology for Behavioralist IR, leading to such research
projects as the workshop on comparative international systems analysis Kaplan set up at
the University of Chicago (Kaplan, 1968), J. David Singer and Melvin Small’s The
Correlates of War Project (1963), which led to a series of handbooks, such as The Wages

Page 13 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

of War, 1816–1965 (1972), or the Dimensionality of Nations Project (see LINKS TO


DIGITAL MATERIALS).

The focus on quantitativism should not preclude, however, an appreciation of the


important intellectual developments Behavioralism brought to IR. The Behavioralists
opened up the discipline to a wide range of theories and paradigms that proved to be very
useful, and even necessary, for producing a more sociological discourse on world affairs,
drawing on communications theory, the sociology of organizations and administrations,
and the like. This introduced the important distinction between “action theories” of
foreign policy and “interaction theories” of international systems (Holsti, 1971, p. 168).
Behavioralism also operated a significant transformation in the way IR scholars perceived
the international system and its alleged rational and unitary actors—the states. Graham T.
Allison’s (1971) The Essence of Decision revealed the weight of conflicting
administrations in foreign policy decision-making processes; Deutsch’s and Kaplan’s own
works stressed the importance of information as a determining variable for evaluating
and explaining states’ behavior—and therefore states’ “rationality” itself; Kaplan’s System
and Process and Rosenau’s (1969) Linkage Politics contributed to reversing the Realists’
distinction between the domestic and the international, by showing their mutual influence
in the realm of policy making.

By the 1970s, Behavioralism had become the leading paradigm in IR. While Morgenthau
still ranked first among IR scholars, he was followed closely by Deutsch and Kaplan,
whose System and Process became the second classic of American IR after Morgenthau’s
Politics Among Nations (Finnegan, 1972). Like their colleagues in the other social
sciences, however, the Behavioralists were under attack on all fronts. As they pushed the
scientific agenda farther than their Realist predecessors had done, they found themselves
in the middle of a debate that aggregated against them not only the more classical
Realists, but the latter’s critics as well. This coincided with the general feeling that IR
had become specifically American in nature, and there was nothing more American than
Behavioral IR itself.

The “Bull-Kaplan Debate”

IR’s second debate is the first one to involve a real, albeit difficult, discussion among its
protagonists. It also addressed the most fundamental and recurrent questions for the
discipline, insofar as it touched upon such issues as the nature of knowledge, science,
theory, and explanation; the level-of-analysis and unit-of-analysis problems; the relation to
history; the social role and responsibility of science, as well as the ethical dilemmas its
practitioners face. Most, if not all, of the issues that would feed IR’s following debates
and controversies had already been discussed by the Behavioralists and/or their critics.
The debate itself, however, often turned into a dialogue of the deaf. The intellectual
origins, background knowledge, and perspectives of its protagonists were too different to
permit the adoption of a common language that would sustain the discussion. As a result,
there was a great deal of genuine misunderstanding on both sides.

Page 14 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

The Behavioralists’ critics were particularly annoyed by the extensive use of quantitative
analyses, which they viewed as reflecting a dangerously (neo)positivist approach to
international reality. Stanley Hoffmann (1960, pp. 46–47), who had been a disciple of
Raymond Aron and shared Aron’s Weberian, interpretative perspective, saw it as a return
of the “old and mistaken [Durkheimian] habit of treating social facts like things,” leading
to a “mechanistic” social science wherein “men and societies are reduced to
communication systems, without much concern for the substance of the ‘messages’ these
networks carry.” Equally problematic for him was the focus on stability and equilibrium:
“since purposes and values other than preservation of the system are left out … the status
quo becomes an empirical and normative pivot.” For Hoffmann, Kaplan’s systems theory
was merely “a huge misstep in the right direction—the direction of systematic empirical
analysis” (Hoffmann, 1960, p. 40).

It is, however, Hedley Bull’s defence of the classical approach that disciplinary history
remembers the most. The so-called second debate is often referred to as the “Bull-Kaplan
debate,” following an exchange between the two authors in World Politics (Bull, 1966;
Kaplan, 1966) that occupies a central place in Knorr and Rosenau’s (1972) second debate
reference volume Contending Approaches to International Politics. This is a symbolic but
nonetheless misleading reduction of the overall picture. It is symbolic because it reflects
the view that Behavioralism was an American intellectual project whose assumptions and
objectives remained incomprehensible beyond the circle of its American practitioners, as
Bull himself candidly noted. It is nonetheless misleading because, of all the scholars
associated with Behavioralism in IR, Kaplan is the one who least fits the profile. Not only
did he never use the term Behavioralism or any of its variations, he also shared with its
critics their rejection of (neo)positivism as a philosophy of knowledge and science,
pursuing his critique of (neo)positivism further than any of its “classical” opponents (See
Kaplan, 1969, 1971, 2000; Kaplan & Hamati-Ataya, 2014). This important epistemic
stance, however, has been widely ignored in the discipline (with the exception of Hamati-
Ataya, 2010, 2012; and Spegele, 1982).

Bull’s critique (1966) was addressed to a wide variety of works representing the scientific
approach —including those of Kaplan; von Neumann and Morgenstern; Schelling;
Deutsch; and Richardson—which all “aspir[e] to a theory of international relations whose
propositions are based either upon logical or mathematical proof, or upon strict,
empirical procedures of verification” (p. 362). Against their assumptions and
methodologies, Bull defended the classical approach to theorizing that “derives from
philosophy, history and law, and that is characterised above all by explicit reliance upon
the exercise of judgment” and by the assumption “that if we confine ourselves to strict
standards of validation and proof there is very little of significance that can be said about
international relations” (p. 361). Bull also made explicit some unspoken reasons that
explained British scholars’ radical rejection of Behavioralism, which many of their
American counterparts probably shared but never expressed so bluntly or so honestly.
These included:

Page 15 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

feelings of aesthetic revulsion against [Behavioralism’s] language and methods,


irritation at its sometimes arrogant and preposterous claims, frustration at our
inability to grasp its meaning or employ its tools, a priori confidence that as an
intellectual enterprise it is bound to fail, and professional insecurity induced by
the awful gnawing thought that it might perhaps succeed.

(Bull, 1966, p. 363)

Some of Bull’s main propositions against Behavioralist IR were common among the
latter’s critics. Their main objection concerned its (neo)positivist leanings, which
promoted scientific methodologies and a “fetish for measurement” at the expense of “the
only instruments that are at present available for coming to grips with the substance of
the subject,” namely, “intuition” and “wisdom” (Bull, 1966, pp. 366, 372). For Bull, the
scientific approach had added nothing meaningful to the understanding of international
relations that could not be, or was not already, revealed by the classical approach. More
importantly, by turning their back on history and philosophy, the scientists had “deprived
themselves of the means of self-criticism” (Bull, 1966, p. 375). This particular point would
become central two decades later in IR’s so-called third debate (Lapid, 1989) between the
next generation of “scientific” IR scholars—the Neorealists—and their Critical critics (see
in particular the exchange between Richard Ashley, 1986 and Kenneth Waltz, 1986; and
an exposition of the general problem in Hollis & Smith, 1991).

Morton Kaplan took on the task of responding to Bull’s and others’ criticisms against the
“scientific approach” (Kaplan, 1966). His reply is the most incisive counter-attack found
in the literature. Kaplan pointed out Bull’s tendency to subsume under a general, ill-
defined, and misunderstood category a wide range of approaches that differed greatly in
terms of logical reasoning, mode of inference, theoretical framework, and level of
analysis (Kaplan, 1966, pp. 12–13). As one of the proponents of the scientific approach,
Kaplan was better equipped to identify and assess these differences, and his criticism
only amplified Bull’s acknowledgment of the traditionalists’ ignorance and
incomprehension of what the scientists were doing and, more importantly, of what
science was and entailed. These comments extended even to the content of these
approaches, as Kaplan easily demonstrated that authors like Bull and Hoffmann had
either not read, or not understood, the new theoretical imports such as Game Theory
(Kaplan, 1966, p. 14).

Kaplan’s second line of argumentation addressed the very modes and methods of inquiry
that the traditionalists claimed as their own, superior tools, namely, historical and
philosophical inquiry, and intuition. Whether conscious or not, the implicit result of
Kaplan’s critique is an appropriation of the central traditionalist scholarly values, in the
form of a tu quoque argument that turned these very values against them. Responding to
the attack on the scientists’ disregard for history, he thus noted:

[t]he vaunted sensitivity to history that the traditionalists claim … is difficult to


find. Those traditionalists who have done a significant amount of historical
research … confine themselves largely to problems of diplomatic history that are
Page 16 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

unrelated to their generalizations about international politics … or to more


specialized problems that are idiosyncratic. This is not an accident but is a direct
product of the lack of articulated theoretical structure in the traditionalist
approach. It is ironic that the traditionalists are so sure that they alone are
concerned with subject matter that they are unaware of the extent to which those
applying the newer approaches are using history as a laboratory for their
researches. This development is unprecedented in the discipline and is a direct
product of the concern of those using scientific approaches for developing
disciplined and articulated theories and propositions that can be investigated
empirically.

(Kaplan, 1966, pp. 15–16)

Kaplan also argued that philosophy was given greater attention by those who pursued
scientific rather than traditional approaches. Although he did not spell it out clearly, he
was mainly referring to the philosophy of knowledge and science, rather than to the
political philosophy that traditionalists such as Bull were keen on preserving. His
criticism, which focused on the speculative dimension of the traditionalists’ philosophical
assumptions and statements, nonetheless encompassed all philosophical inquiry:

The traditionalists talk as if the newer methods have excluded philosophy as a tool
for the analysis of international politics. Unfortunately, few of them … have
demonstrated any disciplined knowledge of philosophy; and many of them use the
word as if it were a synonym for undisciplined speculation. There are many
profound questions that in some senses are genuinely philosophical; the systems
approach, among others, is related to a number of philosophical assumptions....
There are, moreover, some important mistakes that ought to be avoided. Political
theory ought not to be called philosophy merely because it is formulated by a man
who is otherwise a philosopher unless the ideas have a genuine philosophical
grounding. If the ideas are merely empirical propositions, as in the case of most
philosophical statements used by traditionalists, they stand on the same footing as
other empirical propositions…. Even if some matters of concern to international
politics are profoundly philosophical, not all are. It is essential … to address the
proper methods to the proper questions and not to make global statements about
international politics, as do the traditionalists, which assume the relevance of the
same melange of methods regardless of the type of question.

(Kaplan, 1966, pp. 18–19; for Kaplan’s philosophical writings, see Kaplan, 1969,
1971, 1976A, 1976B, 1989, 1992, 2000, 2006)

Most ironic perhaps was Kaplan’s scientific treatment of the notion of human intuition,
which he extracted from the romanticized narrative of the traditionalists by reminding
them that intuition itself was an object of science, that its intervention in the cognitive
process could only be understood by applying the methods of science, and that it was

Page 17 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

actually being studied by precisely those scientific approaches that the traditionalists
neither understood nor wanted to explore (Kaplan, 1966, pp. 3–5).

Kaplan’s third line of argumentation addressed the rationale and methodology of the
scientific approach, whose objective is to produce statements that can be subjected to
empirical validation, rather than speculative generalizations. Science is a process of trial
and error wherein theories and models are used to test hypothetical propositions. The
content of these theories should therefore not be confused with reality itself. If the
attempt to construct models is not made, knowledge remains based on speculations that,
however attractive, inherently logical, or intuitively correct, cannot permit the
advancement of knowledge and therefore of appropriate social action. That the
traditionalists should be appalled by the mere attempt to test some propositions about
the social world could, according to Kaplan, only be explained by their misunderstanding
of the scientific endeavour itself: “The traditionalists mistake explicitly heuristic models
for dogmatic assertions. They mistake assertions about deductions within the framework
of a model for statements about the open world of history” (Kaplan, 1966, p. 20). This
disjunction between the respective views of the proponents of science and of tradition
provides a good analytical grid for assessing much of the discussion, confusion, and
controversy that surround IR’s second debate.

Behavioralism in a Post-Behavioralist Era


Some scholars have recently called for a revival of Behavioral IR as a sub-field concerned
with the explanation of the behavior of leaders, rather than states, thereby refocusing
Behavioralism on the individual as a unit of analysis, and on the underlying processes
that account for political judgment and decisions (James, 2007; McDermott, 2004A;
Mintz, 2005, 2006, 2007; Walker, 2007). As opposed to first-generation Behavioralism and
its aspirations for grand, “systemic” theorizing, Behavioral research today embodies “the
rise of micro-level approaches in IR and political science more generally” and reflects a
demand for a more nuanced and sophisticated understanding of “the relationship
between psychology and rationality” (Kertzer & Tingley, 2018, p. 3; McDermott, 2004A).
Through a sustained cross-disciplinary engagement with analytical and empirical
frameworks developed in the increasingly appealing field of political psychology (Hafner-
Burton, Haggard, Lake, & Victor 2017; McDermott, 2004B), contemporary Behavioralists
now offer alternative insights into foreign policy making and diplomatic interactions,
moving beyond constructivist, group-level social theorizing perspectives to focus on the
interactions of individual leaders operating at face-to-face level, and drawing on
theoretical models and advances in social neuroscience and neurobiology (e.g., Holmes &
Yarhi-Milo, 2017; McDermott, 2004; McDermott & Hatemi, 2014; Yarhi-Milo, 2014).

It is unclear whether such a research program can reclaim Behavioralism’s place among
the leading paradigms of IR, or whether, especially outside of North American political
science, IR scholars are ready to welcome such a revival. The historiography of IR shows,
indeed, that Behavioralism’s history, identity, and purpose have been significantly warped

Page 18 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

in the institutional memory of the field, and contemporary IR scholars may be skeptical as
to the value of a renewed engagement with a school of thought that textbooks often
depict as a defeated empire. It might be too early to assess the prospects of the current
Behavioral research agenda, but as the temptation to turn the page on Behavioralism’s
past remains powerful, at least in post-positivist circles, some concluding reminders and
remarks on the legacy of first-generation Behavioralists are in order.

Behavioralism has undoubtedly contributed to the development of political and


international theory by promoting—or restoring—the unity of the social sciences, and
more generally by opening them up to the ontic, philosophical, and practical problems
they share with the physical and natural sciences. The range of positive and negative
intellectual and socio-academic reactions this unitary spirit triggered back then can easily
be understood if we consider the implications of contemporary calls for inter-
disciplinarity and all the challenges they pose to scholars’ authority, visibility, capacity for
adaptation, or mere academic survival. As the boundaries between and among the
different sciences and academic fields become increasingly eroded, forcing us all to
stretch our knowledge and epistemic skills in new directions and out of our academic
comfort zones, an engagement with the intellectual ethos of the Behavioralists is
especially enlightening—one might even be admiring of their capacity to stubbornly think
their object across well-established and highly constraining disciplinary boundaries.

In political science and IR, the Behavioralists’ concern for conceptual and methodological
rigor has raised scholars’ awareness of the inherent ambiguities, biases, and value-
preferences that subtend their intellectual production, as well as their standards for
analytical rigor and practical usefulness to the world they attempt to explain, and
sometimes reform. Behavioralism, in short, “has made the discipline more self-conscious
and self-critical” (Somit & Tanenhaus, 1967, p. 190). This view was more obvious to
Behavioralism’s closer critical observers half a century ago than it is now to the new
generation of IR scholars socialized into anti-positivist disciplinary narratives. Nowadays,
Behavioralism is usually viewed as belonging to the discipline’s least reflexive past. This
mainly results from the systematic confusion of Behavioralism with (neo)positivism, the
latter being critiqued for combining the two greatest sins post-positivists could envisage:
an epistemic instrumentalist “bias towards objective explanation” and a consequent
“moral non-cognitivism” that leads to an inevitable “moral scepticism” (Frost, 1996, pp.
12–13; Spegele, 1996, p. 7).

At a time when reflexivity has become a buzzword in IR (Tickner, 2013) and elsewhere in
the social sciences, IR scholars and students would greatly benefit from a serious
engagement with its actual history and its different manifestations across IR’s intellectual
paradigms—including those, such as positivism, that are claimed to be naturally non-
reflexive despite their pioneering contributions to reflexivity (Hamati-Ataya, 2018). Such
a novel reading of our collective past should also be grounded in a truly historical
understanding of the conditions in which knowledge is constituted—especially how socio-
political constraints, such as those of the Cold War (Reisch, 2005) have explicitly or tacitly

Page 19 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

impacted the epistemological, theoretical, and axiological positions and formulations of


American IR scholarship.

Early Behavioralists were neither oblivious nor indifferent to either the problem of truth
or the problem of values. In the current state of the field, where the discussion between
(neo)positivists and post-positivists has reached a dead-end, while both postmodernism
and the politics of “untruth/post-truth” threaten to make the whole debate about truth,
objectivity, and values meaningless, it is worth reconnecting with this generation of
pioneers who pondered the difficulties of conceptualizing the political without losing
sight of the dilemmas of science and social action. Putting aside Behavioralism itself, and
taking into account the socio-historical context and stakes that were specific to the
moment that saw its emergence, the work of scholars such as Easton, Eulau, or Kaplan is
worth re-reading today. One might find in their oeuvre a rigorous, responsible, and
courageous attempt to improve our understanding of political reality without
surrendering to the easier options of either asserting transcendental truths with no
concern for their empirical accuracy or impact on human life, or of offering a loosely
descriptive account of the world from an uncritical, common-sense, or introspective
perspective. If IR students are willing to free themselves from the “isms” imposed by the
culture of disciplinary history and the textbook narratives of “great debates,” a critical
and contextual engagement with these great scholars and the ambitious movement they
proposed might help them develop a deeper understanding of the recurrent theoretical
and philosophical problems they are bound to face as social scientists.

Links to Digital Materials


Center for Systemic Peace. Quantitative studies and databases on societal and systemic
conflicts.

The Centre for the Study of Civil War at the Peace Research Institute Oslo.
Research and data on national, international, and transnational dimensions of civil wars.

Correlates of War Project. Includes archives of J. David Singer and Melvin Small’s
original project, with an updated data collection covering different aspects of war and
conflict.

Dimensionality of Nations Project. Rudolph J. Rummel’s project on Dyadic Foreign


Conflict Variables 1950–1965, containing data on conflict behavior.

EUGene. D. Scott Bennett and Allan C. Stam’s Expected Utility Generation and Data
Management Program. Generates and manages data for quantitative analysis of war and
international relations.

The Heidelberg Institute for International Conflict Research. Research and


analysis of national and international political conflicts based on the COSIMO (Conflict
Simulation Model).

Page 20 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Paul Hensel’s International Relations Data Site. Provides links to on-line data
resources for IR research.

Political Database of the Americas. Comprehensive data collection on the politics and
institutions of the Americas.

References
Allison, G. T. (1971). Essence of decision: Explaining the Cuban missile crisis. Boston, MA:
Little, Brown.

Almond, G. (1950). The American people and foreign policy. New York, NY: Harcourt,
Brace.

Almond, G., & Verba, S. (1963). The civic culture: Political attitudes and democracy in five
nations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Ashley, R. K. (1986). The poverty of neorealism. In R. O. Keohane (Ed.), Neorealism and


its critics (pp. 255–300). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

Baer, M. A., Jewell, M. E., & Sigelman, L. (eds.). (1991). Political science in America: Oral
histories of a discipline. Lexington, KY: University Press of Kentucky.

Bay, C. (1969). Politics and pseudopolitics: A critical evaluation of some behavioral


literature. In H. Eulau (Ed.), Behavioralism in political science (pp. 109–140). New York,
NY: Atherton Press.

Boulding, K. (1962). Conflict and defense: A general theory. New York, NY: Harper &
Brothers.

Boulding, K., & Glahe, F. R. (1975). Collected papers: International systems: Peace,
conflict resolution and politics. L. D. Singell (Ed.), Boulder, CO: Colorado Associated
University Press.

Brown, C., & Ainley, K. (2005). Understanding international relations (3rd ed.). London,
UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

Bull, H. (1966). International theory: The case for a classical approach. World Politics,
18(3), 361–377.

Cook, Thomas I. (1950). Les méthodes de la science politique notamment aux Etats-Unis.
In La science politique contemporaine: Contribution à la recherche, la méthode et
l’enseignement (pp. 75–95). Paris, France: UNESCO No 427.

Crawford, R. M. A. (2000). Idealism and realism in international relations: Beyond the


discipline. London, U.K.: Routledge.

Crick, B. (1959). The American science of politics: Its origins and conditions. London,
U.K.: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Page 21 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Dahl, R. A. (1961). Who governs? Democracy and power in an American city. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.

Dahl, R. A. (1969).The behavioral approach in political science: Epitaph for a monument


to a successful protest. In H. Eulau (Ed.), Behavioralism in political science (pp. 68–92).
New York, NY: Atherton Press.

Deutsch, K. W. (1963). The Nerves of Government: Models of Political Communication and


Control. New York, NY: Free Press.

Deutsch, K. W. (1978). The analysis of international relations (2nd ed.). Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Deutsch, K. W., Burrell, S. A., & Kann, R. A. (1957). Political community and the North
Atlantic area: International organisation in the light of historical experience. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.

Easton, D. (1953). The political system: An inquiry into the state of political science. New
York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

Easton, D. (1962). Introduction: The current meaning of “behavioralism” in political


science. In J. S. Charlesworth (Ed.), The limits of behaviouralism in political science (pp.
1–25). Philadelphia, PA: American Academy of Political and Social Science.

Easton, D. (1965). A systems analysis of political life. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.

Easton, D. (1969). The new revolution in political science (presidential address to the
American Political Science Association). American Political Science Review, 63(4), 1051–
1061.

Easton, D. (1997). The future of the postbehavioral phase in political science. In K. R.


Monroe (Ed.), Contemporary empirical political theory (pp. 13–46). Berkeley: University
of California Press.

Eulau, H. (1961). Recent developments in the behavioral study of politics. Standford, CA:
Stanford University Press.

Eulau, H. (1963). The behavioral persuasion in political science. New York, NY: Random
House.

Eulau, H. (ed.). (1966). Political behavior in America: New directions. New York, NY:
Random House.

Eulau, H. (1969). Tradition and innovation: On the tension between ancient and modern
ways in the study of politics. In H. Eulau (Ed.), Behavioralism in political science, (pp. 1–
21). New York, NY: Atherton Press.

Eulau, H. (1977). Technology and civility: The skill revolution in politics. Standford, CA:
Hoover Institute.
Page 22 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Eulau, H. (1986). Politics, self, and society: A theme and variations. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.

Eulau, H., Eldersveld, S. J., & Janowitz, M. (eds.). (1956). Political behavior: A reader in
theory and research. New York, NY: Free Press.

Eulau, H., & Prewitt, K. (1973). Labyrinths of democracy: Adaptations, linkages,


representation, and policies in urban politics. New York, NY: Bobbs-Merrill.

Eulau, H., & Wahlke, J. C. (eds.). (1978). Politics of representation: Continuities in theory
and research. London, U.K.: SAGE.

Eulau, H., Wahlke, J. C., & Buchanan, W. Eds. (1962). The legislative system: Explorations
in legislative behavior. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.

Finnegan, R. (1972). The field of international relations: The view from within. Towson
Journal of International Affairs, 7, 1–24.

Frost, M. (1996). Ethics in international relations: A constitutive theory. Cambridge, U.K.:


Cambridge University Press.

Gosnell, H. (1937). Machine politics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Greene, T. H. (1970). Values and the Methodology of Political Science. Canadian Journal
of Political Science, 3(2), 275–298.

Gunnell, J. G. (1993). The descent of political theory: The genealogy of an American


vocation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Gunnell, J. G. (2006). Dislocated rhetoric: The anomaly of political theory. The Journal of
Politics, 68(4), 771–782.

Guzzini, S. (2002). Realism in international relations and international political economy:


The continuing story of a death foretold. London, U.K.: Routledge.

Hafner-Burton, E. M., Haggard, S., Lake, D. A., & Victor, D. G. (2017). The behavioral
revolution and international relations. International Organization, 71(S1), S1–S31.

Hamati-Ataya, I. (2010). Knowing and judging in international relations theory: Realism


and the reflexive challenge. Review of International Studies, 36(4), 1079–1101.

Hamati-Ataya, I. (2011). The “problem of values” and international relations scholarship:


From applied reflexivity to reflexivism. International Studies Review, 13(2), 260–288.

Hamati-Ataya, Inanna (2012). Beyond (Post)Positivism: The Missed Promises of Systemic


Pragmatism. International Studies Quarterly, 56(2), 291–305.

Hamati-Ataya, I. (2018). Crafting the reflexive gaze: Knowledge of knowledge in the


social worlds of international relations. In A. Gofas, I. Hamati-Ataya, & N. Onuf (Eds.),

Page 23 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

The SAGE handbook of the history, philosophy and sociology of international relations
(pp. 13–30). London, U.K.: SAGE.

Hoffmann, S. (1960). Contemporary theory in international relations. Englewood Cliffs,


NJ: Prentice Hall.

Hollis, M., & Smith, S. (1991). Explaining and understanding international relations.
Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.

Holmes, M., & Yarhi-Milo, K. (2017). The psychological logic of peace summits: How
empathy shapes outcomes of diplomatic negotiations. International Studies Quarterly,
61(1), 107–122.

Holsti, K. J. (1971). Retreat from utopia: International relations theory, 1945–70. Canadian
Journal of Political Science, 4(2), 165–177.

Jackson, R., & Sørensen, G. (2003). Introduction to international relations: Theories and
approaches (3rd ed.). Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.

James, P. (2007). Behavioral IR: Practical suggestions. International Studies Review, 9(1),
162–165.

Kahn, H. (1960). On thermonuclear war. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Kahn, H. (1962). Thinking about the unthinkable. New York, NY: Horizon Press.

Kahn, H. (1965). On escalation. New York, NY: Praeger.

Kaplan, A. (1964). The conduct of inquiry. San Francisco: Chandler.

Kaplan, M. A. (1957). System and process in international politics. New York, NY: John
Wiley & Sons.

Kaplan, M. A. (1966). The new great debate: Traditionalism vs. science in international
relations. World Politics, 19(1), 1–20.

Kaplan, M. A. (1968). New approaches to international relations. New York, NY: St.
Martin’s Press.

Kaplan, M. A. (1969). Glimpses into a philosophy of politics. In Macropolitics: Essays on


the philosophy and science of politics (pp. 3–48). Chicago, IL: Aldine.

Kaplan, M. A. (1971). On historical and political knowing: An inquiry into some problems
of universal law and human freedom. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

Kaplan, M. A. (1976a). Justice, human nature, and political obligation. New York, NY: Free
Press.

Kaplan, M. A. (1976b). Alienation and identification. New York, NY: Free Press.

Page 24 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Kaplan, M. A. (1989). Science, language, and the human condition (rev. ed.). New York,
NY: Paragon House.

Kaplan, M. A. (1992). The nature of reality as illuminated by quantum physics and


mathematical logic. World and I (August), 595–609.

Kaplan, M. A. (2000). My post-postmodern objective account of theory and moral


Analysis. The Review of Politics, 62(4), 675–706.

Kaplan, M. A. (2006). Human reason and a common world: Why Wittgenstein and Rawls
are both wrong. The Review of Metaphysics, 60(2), 359–384.

Kaplan, M. A., & Hamati-Ataya, I. (2014). Transcending postmodernism. London, U.K.:


Palgrave.

Kertzer, J. D., & Tingley, D. (2018). Political psychology in international relations: Beyond
the paradigms. Annual Review of Political Sciences, 21, 1–23.

Key, V. O., Jr. (1956). American state politics: An introduction. New York, NY: Alfred A.
Knopf.

Key, V. O., Jr. (1968). The responsible electorate: Rationality in presidential voting, 1936–
1960. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press/Belknap.

Key, V. O., Jr. (1969). Politics, parties and pressure groups. New York, NY: Thomas Y.
Crowell.

Knorr, K., & Rosenau, J. (eds.). (1972). Contending approaches to international politics
(2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Knorr, K., & Verba, S. (1961). The international system: Theoretical essays. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.

Lapid, Y. (1989). The third debate: On the prospects of international theory in a post-
positivist era. International Studies Quarterly, 33(3), 235–254.

Lasswell, H. (1936). Politics: Who gets what, when, how. New York, NY: Wittlesey House,
McGraw-Hill.

Lasswell, H. (1948). Power and personality. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.

Lasswell, H. (1950).Psychologie et science politique aux Etats-Unis.” In La Science


politique contemporaine: Contribution à la Recherche, la Méthode et l’Enseignement, (pp.
542–553). Paris: UNESCO No 427.

Lasswell, H., & Kaplan, A. (1950). Power and society: A framework for political inquiry.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Page 25 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

McCoy, C. A., & Playford, J. (1967). Introduction. In C. A. McCoy & J. Playford (Eds.),
Apolitical politics: A critique of behavioralism (pp 1–10). New York, NY: Thomas Y.
Crowell.

McDermott, R. (2004a). The feeling of rationality: The meaning of neuroscientific


advances for political science. Perspectives on Politics, 2(4), 691–706.

McDermott, R. (2004b). Political psychology in international relations. University of


Michigan Press.

McDermott, R., & Hatemi, P. K. (2014). The study of international politics in the
neurobiological revolution: A review of leadership and political violence. Millennium, 43,
92–123.

Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self and society from the standpoint of a social behaviorist. C.
W. Morris, (Ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Merkl, P. H. (1969). “Behaviouristic” tendencies in American political science. In H. Eulau


(Ed.), Behavioralism in political science (pp. 141–152). New York, NY: Atherton Press.

Merriam, C. E. (1939). Prologue to politics. New York, NY: Johnson Reprint.

Merriam, C. E. (1945). Systematic politics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Merriam, C. E. (1950). La science politique aux Etats-Unis. In La Science Politique


Contemporaine: Contribution à la Recherche, la Méthode et l’Enseignement (pp. 242–
257). Paris: UNESCO No 427.

Merriam, C. E., & Gosnell, H. (1949). The American party system: An introduction to the
study of political parties in the United States. New York, NY: Macmillan.

Mintz, A. (2005). Behavioral IR. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the
International Studies Association, Honolulu, HI, March.

Mintz, A. (2006). Behavioral IR as a subfield of international relations. Paper presented at


the annual meeting of the International Studies Association, San Diego, CA, March.

Mintz, A. (2007). Why behavioural IR? International Studies Review, 9(1), 157–162.

Morgenthau, H. J. (1946). Scientific man versus power politics. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.

Morgenthau, H. J. (1958). The state of political science. In H. J. Mrgenthau (Ed.),


Dilemmas of Politics (pp. 7–26). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Rapoport, A. (1957). Lewis F. Richardson’s mathematical theory of war. Journal of Conflict


Resolution, 1(3), 249–299.

Page 26 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Rapoport, A. (1963). Mathematical models of social interaction. In R. D. Luce, R. R. Bush,


& E. Galanter (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology (vol. 2; pp. 493–579). New
York, NY: John Wiley and Sons.

Rapoport, A. (1989). The origins of violence: Approaches to the study of conflict. New
York, NY: Paragon House.

Reisch, G. A. (2005). How the cold war transformed philosophy of science. To the icy
slopes of logic. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

Rogers, C. B. (1977). Behaviorism, ethics, and the political arena. In J. E. Krapfl & E. A.
Vargas (Eds.), Behaviorism and ethics (pp. 355–371). Kalamazoo, MI: Behaviordelia.

Rosecrance, R. (1963). Action and reaction in world politics: International systems in


perspective. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.

Rosenau, J. (ed.). (1961). International politics and foreign policy. New York, NY: Free
Press.

Rosenau, J. (1966). Pre-theories and theories of foreign policy. In R. B. Farrell (Ed.),


Approaches to comparative and international politics (pp. 27–92). Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press.

Rosenau, J. (ed.). (1969). Linkage politics: Essays on the convergence of national and
international Systems. New York, NY: Free Press.

Rosenau, J. (1971). The scientific study of foreign policy. New York, NY: Free Press.

Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University


Press.

Schelling, T. C. (1966). Arms and Influence. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Schelling, T. C., & Halperin, M. H. (1961). Strategy and arms control. New York, NY: The
Twentieth Century Fund.

Schubert, G., Alker, H. R., Jr., & Zinnes, D. (1983). The evolution of political science:
Paradigms of physics, biology, and politics. Politics and the Life Sciences, 1(2), 97–124.

Schuman, F. L. (1935). The Nazi dictatorship: A study in social pathology and the politics
of fascism. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

Searing, D. D. (1970). Values in empirical research: A behavioralist response. Midwest


Journal of Political Science, 14(1), 71–104.

Simon, H. (1947). Administrative behavior: A study of decision-making processes in


administrative organizations. New York, NY: Free Press.

Page 27 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Singer, J. D., & Small, M. (1972). The wages of war, 1816–1965: A statistical handbook.
New York, NY: John Wiley.

Snyder, R. C., Bruck, H.W., & Sapin, B. (1954). Decision making as an approach to the
study of international politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Somit, A., & Tanenhaus, J. (1967). The development of American political science from
Burgess to behavioralism. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.

Spegele, R. (1982). Rediscovering debates in the international studies: Morton Kaplan’s


system epistemology revisited. Theory and Decision, 14, 293–328.

Spegele, R. (1996). Political realism in international theory. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge


University Press.

Sprout, M., & Sprout, H. (1956). Man-milieu relationship hypotheses in the context of
international politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Spykman, N. J. (1950).Methods of approach to the study of international relations. In H. J.


Morgenthau & K. W. Thompson (Eds.), Principles and problems of international politics.
Selected readings (pp. 60–69). New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

Strauss, L. (1969). What is political philosophy? In H. Eulau (Ed.), Behavioralism in


political science (pp. 93–108). New York, NY: Atherton Press.

Surkin, M. (1970). Sense and non-sense in politics. In M. Surkin & A. Wolfe (Eds.), An end
to political science: The caucus papers (pp. 13–33). New York, NY: Basic Books.

Surkin, M., & Wolfe, A. (1970). Introduction: An end to political science. In M. Surkin &
A. Wolfe (Eds.), An end to political science: The caucus papers (pp. 3–8). New York, NY:
Basic Books.

Tickner, A. B. (2013). Core, periphery and (neo)imperialist international relations,


European Journal of International Relations, 19(3), 627–646.

Truman, D. B. (1951). The governmental process: Political interests and public opinion.
New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

Truman, D. B. (1969). The impact on political science of the revolution in the behavioral
sciences. In H. Eulau (Ed.), Behavioralism in political science (pp. 38–67). New York, NY:
Atherton Press.

Vasquez, J. A. (1983). The power of power politics. A critique. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press.

Verba, S. (1961). Small groups and political behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.

Page 28 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019


Behavioralism

Von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Waever, O. (1997). Figures of international thought: Introducing persons instead of


paradigms. In I. B. Neumann & O. Waever (Eds.), The future of international relations (pp.
1–37). New York, NY: Routledge.

Walker, S. G. (2007). Back to the future? Behavioral IR as a case of arrested development.


International Studies Review, 9(1), 165–170.

Waltz, K. N. (1979). Theory of international politics. Reading, PA: Addison-Wesley.

Waltz, K. N. (1986). Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A response to my


critics. In R. O. Keohane (Ed.), Neorealism and its critics (pp. 322–345). New York, NY:
Columbia University Press.

Weber, M. (1949a).The meaning of “ethical neutrality” in sociology and economics. In E.


A. Shils & H. A. Finch (Eds.), Max Weber on the methodology of the social sciences (pp. 1–
47). Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Originally published in 1917.

Weber, M. (1949b). “Objectivity” in social science and social policy. In E. A. Shils & H. A.
Finch (Eds.), Max Weber on the methodology of the social sciences (pp. 49–112). Glencoe,
IL: Free Press. Originally published in 1904.

Weber, M. (2004). The vocation lectures.D. Owen & T. Strong (Eds.). London, U.K.:
Hackett. Originally published in 1918.

Wright, Q. (1942). A study of war. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Wright, Q. (1955). The study of international relations. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-
Crofts.

Yarhi-Milo, K. (2014). Knowing the adversary: Leaders, intelligence, and assessment of


intentions in international Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Inanna Hamati-Ataya

Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences and Humanities (CRASSH),
University of Cambridge

Page 29 of 29

PRINTED FROM the OXFORD RESEARCH ENCYCLOPEDIA, INTERNATIONAL STUDIES (oxfordre.com/internationalstudies).


(c) Oxford University Press USA, 2019. All Rights Reserved. Personal use only; commercial use is strictly prohibited (for
details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 14 May 2019

You might also like