You are on page 1of 8

Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

The Philosophers' Cocoon


A safe and supportive forum for early-career philosophers. (Email Marcus Arvan at
'marvan@ut.edu' to become a contributor)

02/20/2019
Being good at being good at philosophy
A guest post by Ian James Kidd, University of Nottingham
Some years ago, a then-colleague would occasionally spot me sitting working in a coffee shop and join me to chat.
Sometimes, he would ask about whichever paper I was writing, and often offer to take a look. After reading the first
couple of paragraphs, my colleague would purse his lips, shake his head, and say, “No, you haven’t quite got it yet.”
What I hadn’t ‘got’ was the skill of crafting a good paper – a skill not only possessed but had fully mastered by my well-
published colleague. Almost every paper he wrote soon appeared in the ‘top’ journals, so similarly mastering that skill
would’ve supercharged my chances of securing a postdoc or a permanent job. Unfortunately, not once did my then-
colleague offer any advice on the skill of crafting a paper, leaving me without a crucial skill – that of translating one’s
philosophical ideas into the form of a publishable journal article.
I offer this recollection to illustrate what seems to be a crucial distinction between being good at philosophy and being
good at academic philosophy. Sitting in that coffee shop, what I lacked wasn’t the ability to come up with good and useful
philosophical ideas (one thing my then-colleague did, at the least, affirm). I lacked the specific performative academic
competence needed to successfully understand and exploit the norms and structures of academic philosophy. Without
that specific competence, my philosophical abilities were not able to do any professional work for me.
Clearly, there are many super philosophers out there, who can think widely, deeply, and clearly about aspects of existence
and our place within it. The problem is that many of them may be good at philosophy but are not always good at academic
philosophy – while they have a love of wisdom or craving to understand, what they lack are the practical and professional
abilities to enact their philosophising within the accepted forms and norms of academia. Crucially, I don’t say this as a
criticism of those philosophers - quite the opposite! My concern is that many good philosophers aren’t being helped
consistently to also become good academic philosophers. Before speculating on what one can do about this, let me fill out
the distinction a little.

Saying what makes a good philosopher is complex and always arouses disagreement, not least since the characteristics of
a good philosopher depend a lot on what one considers to be the aims of philosophising, and those are highly plural. The
ancient Indian philosophies regarded metaphysical theorising as crucial to the ‘liberation’ of humans from the ‘wheel of
suffering’, a conviction largely rejected by classical Chinese philosophers, for whom abstract theory was a distraction from
the spontaneity characteristic of a properly ‘harmonious’ life, something apt to be threatened by self-indulgent
‘cleverness’.
Within modern academic philosophy, one finds many different conceptions of the aims of philosophy, ranging from the
modest to the momentous. Common candidates may include advancing social justice, enhancing scientific enquiry,
informing public policy, or the solution of local intellectual problems or, at the other end, the development of ‘big picture’
accounts of life, the universe, and everything.
Across these aims, though, one can discern a stable set of attitudes, virtues, and dispositions constitutive of a good
philosopher, even if there is disagreement about their definition and relative priority – intellectual curiosity, fair-
mindedness, broad-mindedness, critical tenacity, insightfulness … to name just a few. Most of us would at least mention
these traits, not least when asked to list the ‘transferable skills’ afforded by a BA in Philosophy.
Being good at philosophy is, partly, a matter of having these sorts of traits, since they enable us to better perform the
activities constitutive of philosophising. They help us to see clearly, argue robustly, debate productively, explain lucidly,

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 1 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

and reason compellingly as both solitary thinkers and collaborative enquirers. But these traits don’t necessarily make one
good at academic philosophy – something that requires a different set of attitudes and competences.
A person can be good at this thing called philosophy without also being good at this thing called academic philosophy,
which is one historically recent, institutionalised form taken by philosophy. Think of how differently philosophy is
conceived and practiced in a medieval Christian monastery, a Zen Buddhist temple, or a 21st century British university.
Being good at academic philosophy means being confident and competent at being able to understand and productively
exploit the current professional and institutional norms and arrangements that currently structure most contemporary
philosophising. It requires a set of knowledge, skills, and virtues that are messily interwoven with complex systems of
social power and gendered, racialised, and class privilege.

Consider some of the things constitutive of being good at academic philosophy:


Being good at delivering ‘elevator pitches’, those crisp, concise statements of one’s project and its intellectual and
scholarly relevance.
Being good at crafting articles for the putatively ‘top’ journals.
Being good at writing successful funding and grant applications.
Being good at identifying and playing into ‘hot topics’, emerging trends, and other disciplinary tendencies that tend
to bring attention and money in their wake.
Being good at giving eloquent, engaging, charismatic talks.
Being good at presenting oneself as a highly professional, competent, effortlessly capable prospective hire.
Being good at playing the games of institutional and professional politics to secure for oneself various advantages
and resources.
Being good at dealing with academic presses, media offices, faculty research bosses, and others with power or
influence over the material and professional goods of academia.
Being good at social networking – at striking up conversations, forming contacts, and using who and what one knows
to leverage certain advantages (eg to acquire ‘insider knowledge’ about upcoming jobs, grants, and projects).
Three comments on these examples. First, the virtues that make one a good philosopher do not always apply
automatically (or at all) to these activities: an imaginative critic or theorist is not always similarly imaginative when it
comes to developing projects that play into newly emerging ‘research priorities’.

Second, success in being good at philosophy often requires a very different set of epistemic, practical, and interpersonal
competences, many of which are often classified as vices. ‘Playing the game’, in terms of institutional and disciplinary
politics, typically rewards traits such as aggressive ambition, insincerity, and self-interestedness. Not always, for sure, but
to play that game is to step into an arena with ever-finer lines between legitimate self-interest, pragmatic acquiescence,
and more Machiavellian traits.
A third comment on the traits needed to be good at academic philosophy is that they’re often correlated with social and
institutional systems of power and privilege. Think of the performative ability to give really excellent talks – at
conferences or before the hiring committee for your dream job – which requires virtues of articulation (lucidity,
eloquence, charismatic ‘presence’). Since all of these traits are highly gendered and strongly correlated with
socioeconomically privileged groups, our judgements about whether a speaker is manifesting them is well-established to
be highly corrupted by implicit biases, stereotypes, and by entrenched, tacit conceptions of what a philosopher looks like.
In an ideal world, all philosophers would be good at philosophy in its general and academic senses. Unfortunately, those
two sets of competences don’t always come as a pair. Some are good at philosophy, but unfortunately not so good at
academic philosophy – they can’t give talks well, can’t craft journal articles, and so on. Some are alright at philosophy, by
whatever standard, but extremely good at ‘academicking’ – able to effortlessly exploit the structures and norms of the
discipline to their advantage.

What is the usefulness of the distinction between being good at philosophy and at academic philosophy?
1/ It can offer consolation to those philosophers who infer from a lack of success in getting published, or called to

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 2 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

interview, or awarded research grants that they are no good at philosophy. They might be very good at philosophy, maybe
even really excellent. But they are not so good at academic philosophy, in the sense of having been afforded means of
acquiring that additional set of competences. Of course, what those philosophers want isn’t just the quiet assurance that
they’re good at philosophy, as they hoped, since what they’re also wanting is employment. But it’s worth emphasising that
many philosophers conceive of their subject in vocational terms, rather than as an incidental dimension of their life, just
as many musicians and artists conceive of their music and art as expressive of their deepest sensibilities and aspirations.
For these vocationally animated philosophers, their sense that they are actually no good at the activity that goes deep with
them, those animated by the ‘love of wisdom’, is a source of profound sadness and remorse. If that sense is a false one, it
ought to be repaired, since their distress is liable to be one of existential regret, as well as professional frustration (even if
the initial horribleness of being ‘post-academic’ can become the satisfaction of being a ‘free range philosopher’).
2/ A main reason some philosophers are not good academic philosophy is due to inadequate training, whether because
what they get is too little, too late, or insufficient in its breadth and sophistication. Naturally, the quality of training varies
enormously, depending on one’s supervisors, mentors, department, and institutional resources (many places wish they
could offer more training but find this impossible given their budgets and workloads).

Many young philosophers don’t get systematic training in the full range of skills required for professional life – for
instance, I was never taught how to plan a lecture, or how to deliver a lecture, or how to write lecture notes, or how to
design a reading list. Such professional skills can be acquired through the long process of trial and error, which some
insist is best, anyway. But trial and error require time, self-confidence, and a regular supply of funded opportunities (to
deliver lectures, for instance) that aren’t available to everyone.
All of this shows the contingency and variability of the sorts of formal and informal training that we all need to become
good at academic philosophy. Even though that training is essential for the professional advancement of ourselves and
our students, not everyone gets it reliably or regularly or to a sufficiently high standard.
3/ By thinking about the good at philosophy/being good at academic philosophy distinction, we’re better placed to think
critically about our profession’s values, norms, and priorities. Whether at the departmental or the disciplinary level,
academic philosophy is well-known to have serious problems – of prestige bias and implicit bias, to the invidious journal
ranking systems that systematically privilege certain topics, methods, and traditions over others, to entrenched and
enduring forms of intellectual xenophobia that marginalise so-called ‘non-Western’ traditions. Substantive inequalities in
who gets to enjoy the training and social capital to become good at academic philosophy exacerbate all of these problems.

This means that those who are good at philosophy and have the privilege of also being good at academic philosophy ought
to use their power for good. If you’ve been able to master the art of crafting journal articles, then pass it on to the early
career philosopher staring glumly at another rejection letter over their cold latte. If you’re able to play politics well, use
that to push for a fairer distribution of resources in your community. If you’re good at giving elevator pitches, take time to
try and impart that skill to shy graduate students.
This means that those good at being academic philosophy must exercise those difficult virtues which are more ‘other-
regarding’—those needed to resist the temptations to help entrench self-advantageous disciplinary norms and structures,
to resist the selfish imperative to play along with funding and ranking structures that accelerate one’s own career even as
they destroy the morale and working conditions of others … to name but a few.
If you’re good at philosophy and also good at academic philosophy, there’s a good chance you enjoy certain benefits, such
as tenure, a strong publication record, a degree of financial stability, and so on. If so, then try to help others to acquire
those goods, too. Pay it forward. Share the goods. Build the community. Pull up those below you, rather than look down
only with relief, quietly glad you’re no longer one of the struggling masses.

A lot of this work of academic collegiality is invisible and largely unrewarded, as it the case with most caregiving work.
The virtues of collegiality like generosity and patience aren’t the most prized within our increasingly competitive, self-
interested environment. If you have time to spend, the incentive structures push you to write your own articles, not to
devote the time to giving careful, thoughtful comments on other people’s. What’s done anonymously can’t be cashed in

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 3 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

for personal credit, hence the recent debate about possible reforms of the journal system.
Underlying these remarks is a deeper worry: that under the current disciplinary and professional conditions, being good
at academic philosophy is tending to outweigh being good at philosophy. We are wasting good philosophers by not
training them to take their roles as good academic philosophers, since they tend to drift out of our communities, their
intended professional homes. Worse still, we become increasingly at risk of overrewarding those who are trend-savvy,
self-promotionally forceful, and professionally cunning.
We need to be both good at philosophy and good at academic philosophy. We just need to value them both with a clear,
informed sense of their respective roles in the late modern forms of philosophising. It is a good thing if one can do the
elevator-pitch, grant-writing, ‘crafting a paper’ things, but only because they allow one to do the really important thing –
doing good philosophy. The balance sought is delicate, easily lost in environments crowded with targets, imperatives, and
pressures. But achieving such balance is itself a necessary competence that ought to be taught – systematically rather
than erratically – to emerging philosophers. We need to be good at what we do, but also good at being good at what we do
—and that means also being good to others, too.

My thanks to Craig French and Helen de Cruz for very helpful comments and discussion.

www.ianjameskidd.weebly.com

Posted by Helen De Cruz on 02/20/2019 at 08:17 AM in Graduate School, Guest post, Profession | Permalink
Reblog (0) | |

Comments
You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

A lot going on here. But, as is always my thought when I think about this distinction. Boy do I feel bad for those who are good at
academic philosophy but not good at philosophy. Simply learning the skill of how to churn out a publishable article by responding
to some tiny niche in the literature, or by solving or creating some mostly irrelevant puzzle, is not impressive. It's too bad more good
philosophers aren't rewarded for their goodness. In fact, when I think of the good philosophers as opposed to the good academic
philosophers that I know, it is the former who are almost always the better teachers, and the ones with whom I engage in genuine
philosophical conversation.

Posted by: SM | 02/20/2019 at 04:47 PM

Thanks, SM. I, too, want to emphasise that there are excellent philosophers who are outside the academic system. Publishing in
journals, working in a university, etc., is only one way to philosophise; it has many advantages, most obviously that of providing a
social and material infrastructure for enquiry. But there are other ways to philosophise, too!

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 02/20/2019 at 05:14 PM

SM refers to something that I think is indispensable to being a good philosopher in academia--being a good teacher. Because for the
overwhelming number of employed philosophers, that is the core of their professional lives.

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 4 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

Posted by: Alan White | 02/20/2019 at 08:52 PM

Hi Ian,

I wasn't really referring to good philosophers outside the academia. I was referring to good philosophers in the academia who can
play the publishing game, but can do a whole lot more. There are many good academic philosophers who I doubt can do much more
than write articles. Unfortunately, they seem to get the jobs. But I think that might be changing somewhat. I think good teaching is
being prized now.

As a later-stage graduate student, I am working on and thinking about my teaching as much as I can.

Posted by: SM | 02/20/2019 at 09:01 PM

I like Ian!

Posted by: Alan White | 02/20/2019 at 10:06 PM

If being a good academic philosopher is a distinct skillset from being a good philosopher, then doesn't that say something kind of
damning about academic philosophy and the position philosophy occupies within greater academia? If so, then why should one try
to be a good academic philosopher in the first place? Why not depend on something else for money (...I hear programming's more
in demand than lens grinding these days) and work on philosophy when one has the time?

I highly doubt that the independent philosophers who we now regard as "historical figures" would have benefitted from working
within the confines of the current academic system. Additionally, many of the specific ills of that system in America (i.e. tuition
creep for students, poor working conditions and criminally insufficient pay for non-tenure-track instructors, reliance on grant
funding institutions like Templeton, and so on) seem not terribly great to implicitly support by participating in that particular
system.

So yeah, I guess my question is: why bother learning the skills to prosper (relatively speaking) in a miserable, abusive professional
environment if one's goal is *really* just to do philosophy?
Posted by: Former Grad Student | 02/21/2019 at 11:09 AM

I have a print disability and this distinction is something I use to console myself, though a decent job would be an even better
consolation. In conversations, seminars, and talks, it often seems people find me to be pretty insightful, knowledgeable, and lucid.
But polishing written work for academic publication is so slow and exhausting for me that I fear I may never actually be able to do
it. One aspect of the academic game is that written arguments count for far more than any spoken arguments do. Overall, this may
be a good thing since it may make it easier to assess merit, but also entails that I will be less good at this particular game than
others.

Posted by: Smith&Jones | 02/21/2019 at 05:48 PM

Smith&Jones: thanks - yes, many of the academic skills are highly ableist, such as the reliance on written documents coupled to the
typical lack of easily accessible support for those with a range of disabilities. One could imagine alternative ways of sharing our
arguments: for instance, instead of writing up our articles, why not try a central repository of recorded talks - a sort of journal vlog
(jlog?) More universities have the necessary technology, and the Royal Institute of Philosophy blogs its talks for the London Lecture
series as well as publishes them in its journal: https://www.youtube.com/channel/UCEQRhXQwUe-1ZKIJmnBvHsw.

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 5 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 02/22/2019 at 07:25 PM

Former Grad Student: thanks - I think there *is* an important difference between the academic virtues and the philosophical
virtues - namely, that philosophy does not have to talk the familiar academic forms (degrees, journals, conferences, etc.). Academic
philosophy is the currently entrenched way of doing philosophy, and does have some advantages, even if many disadvantages (eg
the working culture of overactivity, systemic underfunding, etc.) But then I prefer to try and reform it from within, with the provisos
that those who stay inside the academic system recognise - and, where appropriate, engage and support - the philosophising that
goes on outside. We don't do that very well, it seems: the attitude very often seems to be, "once you're out, you're out!"

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 02/22/2019 at 07:32 PM

"It is a good thing if one can do the elevator-pitch, grant-writing, ‘crafting a paper’ things, but only because they allow one to do the
really important thing – doing good philosophy."

Why isn't this in conflict with the rest of the piece? Isn't the point that one can be a good philosopher without any competence in the
trappings of academia?

Posted by: C.W. | 02/22/2019 at 08:58 PM

Hi, C.W. I think one can philosophise outside of academia; this piece was more directed at those striving to pursue philosophising
within the academic system. In that system, one needs both sets of competences.

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 02/23/2019 at 04:55 PM

Hi Ian, this is super interesting and thought provoking. Two quick thoughts:
1. Is there a similar difference in other subjects? I mean, can one be a good biologist but not a good academic biologist or good
historian but not a good academic historian? I can imagine versions of both cases but they both seem quite different from your
philosophy examples - so, I can see that someone might be brilliant at historical research but so horribly shy that they never get a
job, but can’t quite think what it is to be brilliant at historical research but bad at writing history. Maybe that’s just my lack of
imagination or knowledge, though. But it does seem interesting to ask whether and how this distinction works elsewhere
2. I can see that some of the skills of being a good academic philosopher are very historically specific - writing good research grant
applications, say. But is there a huge amount of variation in the skills required to be an academic philosopher (at least in contexts
where such a job admits). I mean, I may be wrong but I kind of feel that being personable is probably important in lots of otherwise
very different academic settings. Is it possible that there’s less variation in the skills needed to be a good academic philosopher than
in the skills needed to be a good philosopher? Does that imply something interesting? Again, I’m not certain. But interesting stuff

Posted by: Stephen John | 03/01/2019 at 05:31 PM

What a great post! Now I'd just like to make two points: (1) Philosophers often act as competitors. But competition is not a feature
of what you call philosophy; rather it's a feature of what you call *academic* philosophy.
(2) It might be better to stop seeing "good quality" as a feature of individual philosophers. Rather good quality is a property of a
discussion, because whether or not something counts as good is determined by all the interlocutors involved.

Here's a brief post explaining these points in a bit more detail: https://handlingideas.blog/2019/03/02/the-competition-fallacy/
Posted by: Martin Lenz | 03/03/2019 at 07:46 AM

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 6 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

Hi Stephen! Thanks -

(1) I suspect similar forms of the distinction play out in different subjects, yes - eg the difference between subject skills/academic
skills will apply widely. There are excellent historians and botanists, even if they'd make poor academic historians and academic
botanists. They can trawl archives, collective specimens, classify, confirm details, make sense of puzzling findings, write up their
findings, etc., and do whatever botanists do ... they just don't do the academic things like writing journal articles or monographs etc.
Maybe one common difference IS writing up one's work in the formats of journals and monographs is a specific skill for academic
forms of history/botany, that aren't necessary for non-academic' history and botany?
(2) I agree a lot of the skills are contingent to the particular, evolving forms of late modern academic philosophy (eg managing
things like TEF and REF). Others will be generic to any institutionally organised enquiry, or to collectivised epistemic agency (eg
being able to initiate and sustain working relationships). Moreover, the borders between philosophy and other disciplines are often
fuzzy, hence people sometimes worrying about whether what they do is "really philosophy". We could distinguish between (a)
exclusively philosophical abilities and (b) abilities that are given a higher premium within philosophy than in other subjects,
perhaps? Close conceptual analysis, charting logical spaces, generating novel counterexamples ... people offer all sorts of
candidates.

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 03/03/2019 at 11:48 AM

Hi Martin! Thanks -

(1) I agree that competition is incentivised and facilitated by many of the structures and norms of academic philosophy, although I
think there can be competition outside of those structures (eg competition between rival schools for prestige, students, influence, of
the sort described in, eg, G.E.R. Lloyd's 'Adversaries and Authorities').

(2) I like your critique of the concept of 'quality'! It'd be very interesting, then, to see how the ideas in this post would play out if we
think of *our* being good philosophers. Some of the abilities for being a good philosopher are, as you say, even better when
exercised collectively - eg I can only be *so* creative when I'm working all by my lonesome.

Posted by: Ian James Kidd | 03/03/2019 at 11:57 AM

Many thanks for your reply, Ian!


(Ad 1) Right, I had not thought of schools, but such competitions seem to be in line with "academic" structures, rather than the
philosophies defended. In such cases, the claim to pursue the truth seems to be instrumental to gaining credibility over rivals. But
I'll check out Lloyd.
(Ad 2) Yes, I wonder whether the collective is tied only to certain forms of philosophy or necessary across the board. (I thought of
*public* reason as necessary as a source of normativity)

Posted by: Martin Lenz | 03/03/2019 at 05:50 PM

Verify your Comment


Previewing your Comment

Posted by: |
This is only a preview. Your comment has not yet been posted.
Post Edit
Your comment could not be posted. Error type:

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 7 of 8
Being good at being good at philosophy - The Philosophers' Cocoon 16/12/2020, 00(27

Your comment has been saved. Comments are moderated and will not appear until approved by the author. Post another
comment
The letters and numbers you entered did not match the image. Please try again.
As a final step before posting your comment, enter the letters and numbers you see in the image below. This prevents
automated programs from posting comments.
Having trouble reading this image? View an alternate.
Continue
The Philosophers' Cocoon
Powered by TypePad

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/02/being-good-at-being-good-at-philosophy.html Page 8 of 8

You might also like