You are on page 1of 44

Chapter 30

Social Justice
History, Theory, and Research

JOHN T. JOST AND AARON C. KAY

Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be
rejected or revised if it is untrue; likewise laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished
if they are unjust.
—John Rawls (1971)

The best safeguard against fascism is to establish social justice to the maximum possible extent.
—Arnold Toynbee (1976)

Social justice is a concept that originates in philosophical only by authorities but also by other relevant social actors,
discourse but is widely used in both ordinary language and including fellow citizens. The three aspects of our defini-
social science, often without being clearly defined. By syn- tion correspond, roughly, to distributive, procedural, and
thesizing the common elements of various philosophical interactional justice, as we use the terms in this chapter.
treatments (e.g., Elster, 1992; Feinberg, 1973; Frankena, A theory of social justice need not address all three aspects,
1962; Miller, 1999; Walzer, 1983), it is possible to offer but it should address at least one of them. Conceived of in
a general definition of social justice as a state of affairs this way, social justice is a property of social systems—or
(either actual or ideal) in which (a) benefits and burdens perhaps a “predicate of societies” (Frankena, 1962)—as
in society are dispersed in accordance with some alloca- suggested also by Rawls (1971) and Toynbee (1976).
tion principle (or set of principles); (b) procedures, norms, A just social system is to be contrasted with those systems
and rules that govern political and other forms of decision that foster arbitrary or unnecessary suffering, exploitation,
making preserve the basic rights, liberties, and entitlements abuse, tyranny, oppression, prejudice, and discrimination.
of individuals and groups; and (c) human beings (and per- The foremost problem for scholars (or would-be practition-
haps other species) are treated with dignity and respect not ers) of social justice is that considerable disagreement persists,

This chapter is dedicated to the memory of George L. Jost (1916–2002), who worked for social justice in several different contexts: first as a
communications specialist who received a Bronze Star in the U.S. military stationed in Italy during World War II; later as part of the Catholic
Workers’ anti-poverty movement led by Dorothy Day and Peter Maurin in New York City; and in the mid-1960s as a co-founder of the Friends
of FIGHT civil rights organization in Rochester, NY, which worked with Saul Alinsky to challenge racial discrimination (see Horwitt, 1989,
p. 486). The writing of this chapter was supported in part by research grants made available to John T. Jost by the New York University Center
for Catastrophe Preparedness and Response and the National Science Foundation (BCS-0617558) and to Aaron C. Kay by the Canadian
Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council. The authors wish to thank Mahzarin R. Banaji, Ramona Bobocel, Mitchell Callan,
Irina Feygina, Susan T. Fiske, Danielle Gaucher, Daniel Gilbert, Erin Godfrey, Curtis D. Hardin, Erin Hennes, György Hunyady, Orsolya
Hunyady, Lawrence J. Jost, Margarita Krochik, Ido Liviatan, Anesu Mandisodza, Gabe Mendlow, Jaime L. Napier, Tom R. Tyler, Kees
Van den Bos, and Jojanneke Van der Toorn for extremely helpful advice and commentary on the material contained herein. We also
acknowledge Tina Schweizer for her diligence in compiling the extensive bibliography. Finally, the authors would like to express their
appreciation for all of the members of the International Society for Justice Research (ISJR) and wish that they could do “justice” to all of
the many scientific and practical contributions made by the members of that society.
1122
Handbook of Social Psychology, edited by Susan T. Fiske, Daniel T. Gilbert, and Gardner Lindzey.
Copyright © 2010 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Lewinian Tradition in Social Psychology 1123

even after centuries of debate, concerning each of the part in the development of social psychology” (1962, p. 2).
elements incorporated in our definition (see Boucher & Specifically, he wrote that:
Kelly, 1998; Campbell, 2001; Miller, 1999; Solomon &
Murphy, 2000). What is to be considered a truly fair prin- Social psychology began to flourish soon after the First World
ciple for distributing benefits and burdens and why? Is it War. This event, followed by the spread of communism, by the
equity, equality, need, or some other principle of allocation? great depression of the ’30s, by the rise of Hitler, the genocide of
Similarly, what is a reasonable or appropriate set of rights, the Jews, race riots, the Second World War and its consequent
liberties, and entitlements? And what does it mean to treat anomie, stimulated all branches of social science. A special chal-
others with dignity and respect? These are difficult ques- lenge fell to social psychology. The question was asked: how
is it possible to preserve the values of freedom and individual
tions, to be sure, but they are not in principle unanswerable.
rights under conditions of mounting social strain and regimenta-
They have been addressed by some of the greatest minds
tion? Can science help provide an answer? (p. 4)
in Western civilization, including Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes,
Locke, Hume, Rousseau, Kant, Hegel, Marx, Mill, and Allport’s own work on The Nature of Prejudice (1954)
Rawls. In this chapter, we summarize the major scientific as well as a predecessor, The Authoritarian Personality by
contributions of social psychology to the understanding and Adorno, Frenkel-Brunswik, Levinson, and Sanford (1950),
practice of social justice. sought to employ theories and methods in social psychology
to diagnose and ultimately defeat prejudice, intolerance, and
other apparent obstacles to social justice. It has been sug-
gested darkly on more than one occasion that the individual
LEWINIAN TRADITION IN
who exerted the strongest influence over the development of
SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY
social psychology in the 20th century was Adolf Hitler (e.g.,
Cartwright, 1979; Jones, 1985/1998).
Social Justice as a Central Theoretical and
World War II illustrated far too vividly both the dev-
Practical Concern of Social Psychology
astating effects of social injustice and the human capac-
It was not long ago that questions of social justice were ity to overcome it. In its aftermath, issues of social justice
at the forefront of theoretical and empirical inquiry in were central to social psychological theory and research.
social psychology. The father of modern social psychol- Textbooks routinely covered themes such as morality, con-
ogy, Kurt Lewin, promoted the discipline as, among other science, crime and punishment, prejudice, authoritarianism,
things, a scientific means of fostering democratic, egali- propaganda, war and peace, and the determinants of revo-
tarian norms and preventing tyranny and oppression from lution (e.g., Brown, 1965; Doob, 1952; Klineberg, 1940;
gaining the upper hand in society. Although he seldom (if Krech & Crutchfield, 1948). However, as was the case with
ever) couched these goals in the explicit language of social Lewin’s writings, such themes were often approached in the
justice, it is clear that his “applied” research programs on absence of an explicit social justice framework, and terms
overcoming certain forms of prejudice, outgroup hostility, such as “justice” and “fairness” were not necessarily used
and self-hatred among Jews—to mention some of the most to illuminate them. As we shall see, it was not until decades
salient examples—reflected a commitment to social justice later that social justice research became a subfield or area of
as well as a scathing critique of authoritarianism and the specialization within social psychology. Before then, con-
fascist ideology that had seized the hearts and minds of siderations of social justice seemed to permeate the field as
so many of his fellow citizens in 1930s Germany. Lewin a whole, albeit tacitly. None of the first three editions of The
self-consciously strove to integrate theoretical and applied Handbook of Social Psychology contained a chapter devoted
goals, which he believed could be “accomplished in psy- to studies of social justice per se (Miller, 2001, p. 528), but
chology, as it has been accomplished in physics, if the several chapters covered pertinent subjects, such as preju-
theorist does not look toward applied problems with high- dice and ethnic relations, leadership, social structure, politi-
brow aversion or with a fear of social problems” (Lewin, cal behavior, international relations, collective action, and
1944/1951, p. 169). It is not surprising that one of Lewin’s social movements.
doctoral students, Morton Deutsch, went on to become one Social psychological research on theories of justice
of the most illustrious contributors to the field of social (especially equity theory) began to flourish in the 1960s,
justice research (see Deutsch, 1999). but the demarcation of social justice research as a spe-
Another prominent social psychologist of the post- cific subfield came years later. For instance, Social Justice
war era, Gordon Allport, observed that, “Practical and Research (a specialized interdisciplinary journal) was first
humanitarian motives have always played an important published in 1987 under the editorship of Melvin Lerner,
1124 Social Justice

and the International Society for Justice Research (ISJR), so-called “justice motive,” that is, the extent to which people
whose members constitute the journal’s core readership, are motivated to promote fair treatment of others and not
was not officially created until a decade later. These pro- merely by considerations of self-interest (Lerner, 1977,
fessional developments have allowed researchers to delve 1980, 2003; Miller, 1977; Montada, 2002; Tyler, 1994; see
more deeply into questions that are unique to justice- also Tyler & Smith, 1998). The point is not that justice and
related theories and findings, but they also reflected (and self-interest are always opposed—plainly, they are not. In
may have even contributed to) some degree of separation fact, the sense of justice may originate in humans and other
(and, therefore, marginalization) of social justice research primates in the self-protective desire to insure that they
within the larger discipline of social psychology. By the receive what they “deserve” (Brosnan, 2006; Brosnan &
mid-1960s, some social psychologists had already begun DeWaal, 2003). When members of disadvantaged groups
to have sober second thoughts about Lewin’s vision of band together to push for civil rights or other improvements
humanistic, action-oriented research aimed at human bet- in their quality of life, they are fighting on behalf of social
terment and social justice (Ring, 1967). McGuire (1965), justice as well as personal and collective self-interest (e.g.,
for instance, admonished his more “applied” colleagues for Piven & Cloward, 1978). Nevertheless, the purest evidence
being “too preoccupied with the Berlin wall, the urban of a “justice motive” in human beings comes from cases
blight, the population bomb, and the plight of the Negro in in which people are willing to risk or sacrifice their own
the South” and quipped that students who wished to solve welfare to insure that others are treated fairly (e.g., Lerner,
social problems should consider joining “the law or the 2003; Monroe, 2004).
ministry” (pp. 138–139).
In retrospect, social psychologists’ commitment to Rational Choice Theory and Its Discontents
social justice research in the middle of the 20th cen- Truly selfless behavior appears to violate both the norma-
tury may be attributable, at least in part, to the societal tive and descriptive assumptions of rational choice the-
urgency that accompanied the need to defeat fascism in ory, according to which individuals should (and at least
Europe and elsewhere (e.g., see Lewin, 1939/1948a). But, sometimes do) act on the basis of self-interested pref-
one might ask, do we not face urgent problems related to erences to maximize benefits and minimize costs (e.g.,
social justice even today? What, if anything, should be Becker, 1976; Kreps, 1990). It is generally assumed that
done about yawning economic inequality under capital- in economic markets and other forms of social exchange,
ism; racial disparities in criminal sentencing, including those preferences and behaviors that maximize individ-
the imposition of the death penalty; gender disparities in ual welfare will predominate (e.g., Axelrod, 2006). As a
hiring, salary, and promotion at work; the persistence of result, rationally self-interested behavior should be more
prejudice; religious, ethnic, and other forms of violent readily observable than other forms of behavior that do
conflict, including war, terrorism, and torture; and the not, on average, offer equivalent benefits. Some ratio-
problems posed by global climate change, environmental nal choice theorists acknowledge that certain constraints
degradation, and species extinction? One need not be a (such as limits on the availability of information or mate-
doomsday prophet to suspect that the continued survival rial resources) can lead to nonrational behavior, but as
of the human race depends ultimately on its capacity to a general rule this per-spective leaves relatively little
see past purely selfish, parochial sources of motivation room for any significant drivers of behavior other than
and to embrace what social psychologists refer to as “the self-interest. For this reason, rational choice theory has
justice motive.” been widely criticized by psychologists and other social
and behavioral scientists for being unrealistic—that
is, descriptively inaccurate (e.g., see Green & Shapiro,
The Justice Motive in Human Behavior
1994; Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982; Nisbett &
Solomon Asch (1959) insisted that social psychologists Ross, 1980).
study not only the perpetration of injustice but also “the vec- One major line of attack emerged from work on
tors that make it possible for persons to think and care and “bounded rationality” (Simon, 1957) and shortcomings in
work for others” (p. 372). More specifically, he wrote that: human judgment and decision making (Kahneman et al.,
“It is of considerable consequence for any social psychology 1982). Both contributions suggested that the limited cog-
to establish the grounds of concern for the welfare of other nitive capacities of human beings insure major departures
persons or groups, and how these are related to the concern from normative standards of rationality. It has been less
individuals feel for their own welfare” (p. 368). Such com- common to critique rational choice theory from a motiva-
ments presage research programs on “altruism” (Krebs & tional perspective, but decades of research in social psy-
Miller, 1985), prosocial behavior (Batson, 1998), and the chology have demonstrated that the motivational systems
Lewinian Tradition in Social Psychology 1125

underlying human behavior are considerably more complex research suggests that evolutionary processes did produce
than is suggested by the rational choice model (see Fiske, justice-oriented behavior in marmosets, Capuchin mon-
2004; Higgins & Kruglanski, 2000; Shah & Gardner, keys, and other nonhuman primates (see Brosnan, 2006;
2008). If Lerner (2003) is correct that humans—and perhaps Brosnan & DeWaal, 2003; Burkart, Fehr, Efferson, & van
other species as well (Brosnan, 2006; Brosnan & DeWaal, Schaik, 2007).
2003)—possess a “justice motive,” then it is sure to con-
flict with the unadulterated pursuit of rational self-interest The Altruism Debate
on at least some occasions (e.g., Güth, Schmittberger, & Quite apart from considerations of gene replication, social
Schwarze, 1982; Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1986; psychologists have debated the role of self-interest in sup-
Rabin, 1993). Or, to put the same point differently, the attain- porting versus undermining prosocial behavior. The ques-
ment of social justice is constrained by the extent to which tion, kicked around in many a dorm room over the years,
individuals behave exclusively according to the principles of is whether bona fide altruism really exists or whether help-
rational choice theory, insofar as social justice requires ing behavior is always motivated by some form of egoism.
individuals to act on the basis of principles that sometimes Batson and Shaw (1991) characterize the dispute as follows:
conflict with the maximization of self-interest.
Similar questions concerning the relative importance Advocates of universal egoism claim that everything we do,
of selfish versus prosocial motivations (including motiva- no matter how noble and beneficial to others, is really directed
tions for justice) have cropped up in evolutionary biology toward the ultimate goal of self-benefit. Advocates of altru-
from time to time. Some, including Darwin (1871), suggest ism do not deny that the motivation for much of what we do,
that evolutionary mechanisms are unlikely to privilege any including much that we do for others, is egoistic. But they
traits that are not fundamentally selfish: claim that there is more. They claim that at least some of us,
to some degree, under some circumstances, are capable of a
qualitatively different form of motivation, motivation with an
It is extremely doubtful whether the offspring of the more sym-
ultimate goal of benefiting someone else. (p. 107)
pathetic and benevolent parents, or those who were most faith-
ful to their comrades, would be reared in greater number than In support of the latter conclusion, Batson and colleagues
the children of selfish and treacherous parents belonging to the have offered into evidence a large number of studies
same tribe. He who was ready to sacrifice his life . . . rather
addressing the “empathy–altruism hypothesis” (e.g.,
than betray his comrades, would often leave no offspring to
Batson, 1990; Batson et al., 1991; Batson & Shaw, 1991).
inherit his noble nature. (Darwin, 1871, p. 475)
They suggest that witnessing the distress of others insti-
Several prominent evolutionary theorists have echoed gates empathic emotions (such as compassion and tender-
the notion that evolution favors selfish over prosocial (or ness) that facilitate perspective-taking and the setting of
“altruistic”) behaviors (e.g., Dawkins, 1989). The basic helping goals. Although helping behavior brings certain
logic underlying such approaches is that any genes that fail rewards—including the reduction of guilt and other negative
to promote their own replication (at a significantly greater emotions—one cannot conclude that the helper was moti-
rate than they promote the replication of others’ genes) will vated by those rewards. Thus, Batson (1990) sought to
not survive for long. determine whether “the empathically aroused helper (a)
Crucially, however, the alleged “selfishness” of genes benefits the other as an instrumental goal on the way to
does not necessarily translate into selfishness at the level reaching some self-benefit as an ultimate goal (egoism) or
of individual (or collective) behavior (e.g., Crespi, 2000; (b) benefits the other as an ultimate goal, with any result-
Krebs, 2008). It is possible that prosocial behaviors that ing self-benefits being unintended consequences (altru-
evolved primarily to ensure the survival of genetic rela- ism)” (p. 340). Although it is not possible to review the
tives facilitate the helping of other, nonkin individuals specific details of individual studies here, Batson and col-
(Park, Schaller, & Van Vugt, 2008). Models of cultural leagues (1991) have made a reasonably strong case for the
evolution, according to which specific behavioral char- existence of altruistic motivation.
acteristics can be transmitted by social learning, can also This is not to say that their position is bereft of detrac-
explain the propagation of traits that are other- (rather than tors. Most notably, Cialdini and his coauthors have argued
self-) regarding (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003). For these rea- that altruistic behavior, even when triggered by empathic
sons and others, there is no reason to assume that prosocial emotions, is never truly selfless. Rather, they propose that
behavior is inconsistent with fitness or survival (especially the circumstances giving rise to empathic concern also
in the span of a single lifetime), regardless of whether it is elicit other feelings, such as sadness (Cialdini et al., 1987;
at odds with economic perspectives on human rationality. Maner, Luce, Neuberg, Cialdini, Brown, & Sagarin, 2002;
Although it is beyond the scope of this chapter, empirical Schaller & Cialdini, 1988) and perceptions of “oneness”
1126 Social Justice

or “self-other overlap” (Cialdini, Brown, Lewis, Luce, & (2002, p. 159) and inquires about different types of justice
Neuberg, 1997; Maner et al., 2002; Neuberg et al., 1997), and ways of being just (or unjust). According to one promi-
and that these are capable of generating seemingly selfless nent interpretation, for Aristotle:
behaviors. From the standpoint of social justice, it may
not matter greatly whether the motivation to help others The hallmark of a just apportionment is equality. In distribu-
(and to sustain sacrifices in doing so) stems from purely tion, this consists in maintaining the same ratio of quantified
altruistic desires or from the so-called “moral emotions” goods or burdens to quantified merit for all recipients. In
rectification, it consists in restoring the parties to the relative
or processes of social identification. The important point is
position (schematized as “equality”) they were in before one
that human beings do appear to be capable of setting aside
harmed the other. (Broadie, 2002, p. 36)
narrow self-interest to make the world a “better” (i.e.,
putatively more just) place. The specific nature of these Interpretational ambiguity arises from the fact that in Attic
justice-related concerns is the subject of the next section. Greek the same word (isotes) is typically used to mean both
justice and equality; the word is best translated as “geomet-
rical equality” or “proportionality” (Vlastos, 1962/1997).
A TYPOLOGY OF SOCIAL Thus, Aristotle says that a just distribution is one that is
JUSTICE CONCERNS impartial in the sense of “treating equals as equals” (see
also Feinberg, 1973; Frankena, 1962; Mansbridge, 2005),
The earliest theory-driven research in sociology and psy- but his conception of distributive justice emphasizes what
chology on the topic of social justice tackled questions of social scientists today would call principles of equity, pro-
distributive fairness, especially considerations of “equity” portionality, or merit (Deutsch, 1975; Lerner, 1974; Walster,
and relative deprivation in the allocation of resources (e.g., Walster, & Berscheid, 1978).
Adams, 1965; Crosby, 1976; Lerner, 1974; Walster, Walster, Aristotle appreciated one of the chief difficulties of jus-
& Berscheid, 1978). Next came work on procedural jus- tice theories based exclusively on equity or proportionality
tice, which addressed not only outcomes but the decision- principles—namely, that decision makers disagree about
making rules used to determine those outcomes (Folger, which “inputs” (or merits) should be utilized in determin-
1977; Leventhal, 1980; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Thibaut & ing proportional outcomes (or rewards):
Walker, 1975). Soon thereafter, a third type of justice was
investigated—namely, interpersonal (or interactional) jus- The matter of distribution “according to merit” also makes this
tice—to incorporate concerns about informal as well as clear, since everybody agrees that what is just in distributions
formal treatment by others in everyday life (Bies & Moag, must accord with some kind of merit, but everybody is not
1986; Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993). Finally, although talking about the same kind of merit: for democrats merit lies
Aristotle anticipated not only distributive but also retribu- in being born a free person, for oligarchs in wealth or, for some
of them, in noble descent, for aristocrats in excellence. (2002,
tive and restorative justice concerns nearly 24 centuries
p. 162, lines 1131a24–29)
ago, empirical studies addressing these latter concerns
have only recently become a cottage industry in social psy- Indeed, the notion that political or ideological factors influ-
chology and neighboring disciplines (Braithwaite, 1989; ence one’s conception of social justice is a central theme of
Carlsmith, Darley, & Robinson, 2002; Vidmar, 2002). We this chapter, and we will return to it in our review of the
do our best to summarize theoretical and empirical prog- research literature.
ress on the social psychological understanding of each of A few other aspects of Aristotle’s theory of justice
these five types of social justice concerns, with an advance deserve mention, insofar as they, too, anticipate important
apology to our readers for the necessarily selective nature social scientific contributions and controversies. For one
of our review. thing, Aristotle addresses the relationship between what is
legal and what is just, and he clearly sees a close relation-
Distributive Justice ship between them. He writes, for instance, that

Aristotle and the History of the Concept People regard as “unjust” both the person who breaks the law
One of the earliest influential accounts of distributive and the grasping (i.e., unequal-minded) one; hence, clearly,
both the law-abiding person and the equal-minded one are just.
justice—that is, the issue of how to allocate scarce
In that case, the just is what is lawful and what is equal, while
resources fairly and appropriately—was Aristotle’s. In
the unjust is what is unlawful and what is unequal. (p. 159)
Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle (ca. 322 BCE)
observes that “we call just the things that create and pre- Aristotle’s discussion of the individual who is “grasping”
serve happiness and its parts for the citizen community” or “unequal-minded” (pleonexia: the tendency to “get more
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1127

for oneself ”; Broadie, 2002, p. 36) presages research on the meaning and use of the term “justice,” which (having
dispositional or individual differences in selfishness (i.e., studied law) he equated with the concept of jurisprudence.
a “proself ” orientation in the language of De Cremer & Marx saw justice as an inherently bourgeois concern akin
Van Vugt, 1999) and its consequences for justice-related to noblesse oblige, and he expressed disdain for the “vulgar
outcomes. Aristotle also observes that, “The worst sort of socialists” of his era who, in his view, championed empty
person . . . is the one whose badness extends even to his slogans such as “a fair day’s wages for a fair day’s work.” He
treatment of himself and of those close to him, but the best was also skeptical about philosophical attempts to develop
sort is not the one whose excellence extends to his treat- abstract or universal conceptions of justice that would
ment of himself, but to his treatment of another; for it is transcend specific social and historical circumstances,
this that is a difficult task” (2002, p. 160). This discussion such as those proffered by Kant or Hegel (see L. J. Jost &
foreshadows the social psychological distinction between J. T. Jost, 2007). Thus, most scholars agree that Marx gen-
“justice for oneself” and “justice for the other” (e.g., erally eschewed justice-based arguments in making the
Gollwitzer, Schmitt, Schalke, Maes, & Baer, 2005; Sutton case for revolution and the overthrow of the capitalist sys-
et al., 2008), as well as Lerner’s (2003) more general tem (see Tucker, 1969; Wood, 1972/1980). Instead, Marx
thesis that, in its purest form, justice motivation opposes appealed to collective self-interest, as in the famous line
self-interest. from The Communist Manifesto: “Workers of the world
Although Aristotle equated justice with acting in an unite; you have nothing to lose but your chains!” That is, he
egalitarian (non-selfish), law-abiding manner, he recog- saw it as obviously in the objective interests of the working
nized that the degree of impartiality (or perhaps universality) class to overthrow the capitalist system, and he assumed
required by the law can lead to perverse outcomes if one that their material life circumstances would (eventually)
ignores the particulars of a given case or situation. He lead them to this realization.
argues that a reasonable person may (on occasion) depart Even if Marx himself saw little revolutionary potential
from adhering to what is legal (and therefore what is just) in appeals to social justice, many of his followers have dis-
to arrive at a superior outcome (or decree): cerned in his writings the seeds of a powerful justice-based
critique of capitalism (e.g., Campbell, 2001; Husami,
It is clear, then, what the reasonable is; and that it is just, and 1978/1980). For instance, Marx argued that capitalism
better than just in one sense. From this it is also evident who depends for its very existence on “surplus value” being
the reasonable person is: the sort who decides on and does created through the labor process. The basic idea is that no
things of this kind, and who is not a stickler for justice in the worker is ever paid what his or her work is actually worth
bad sense but rather tends to take a less strict view of things, (to the employer; that is, the value of what is produced);
even though he has the law to back him up—this is the reason-
otherwise, there would be no profit (or profit motive). But
able person. (2002, p. 175, lines 1137b33–1138a3)
the worker who wants to survive and provide for his or her
Thus, justice may be the “mightiest of the excellences” family has no real choice in a capitalist society but to pro-
(p. 160, lines 1129b27-8), but it is not the only excellence duce wealth for those capitalists who happen to control the
(see also Rawls, 1971). Courage, wisdom, and self-control means of production. Marx clearly denounced this situation
were also cardinal virtues, along with justice (Adelson, as a form of “exploitation,” and it is one of the reasons that
1995). John Stuart Mill (1869) likewise distinguished he predicted (and longed for) the transition from capitalism
between justice and other moral principles, such as generos- to socialism and communism, which he believed would
ity and beneficence (see Frankena, 1962). Finally, it should finally put an end to class-based oppression. Thus, Marx
be noted that Aristotle recognized the need for retributive (or objected to the stark economic inequality between social
rectificatory) justice, but by aligning his conception of jus- classes that characterizes the capitalist mode of produc-
tice with what is “law-abiding,” he ruled out the possibility tion on grounds that are basically indistinguishable from
that certain acts of vengeance (or “vigilante justice”) could considerations of social justice (see also Campbell, 2001;
be considered just, even if they are seemingly motivated by Husami, 1978/1980; Konow, 2003). At the same time, he
a desire for justice. worried that certain conceptions of justice would be used
to provide ideological cover for the status quo.
Marxian Tradition
There is also Marx’s normative claim, in his Critique of
The writings of Karl Marx have probably inspired more the Gotha Program, that under socialism, the appropriate
social justice movements than any other piece of litera- principle of distribution should be “from each according to
ture, with the possible exceptions of religious texts (see their ability, to each according to their needs” (see Miller,
Adelson, 1995; Solomon & Murphy, 2000). It is ironic, 1999). As Lerner (1974) and Deutsch (1975) point out,
then, that Marx himself was notoriously suspicious about taking into account the needs of individuals is a principle
1128 Social Justice

of distributive justice that is not necessarily incorporated support for the welfare state, which redistributes wealth
in other theories of social justice, including Aristotle’s. But and other valued resources in such a way as to reduce the
“need considerations are more than a reaction to actual misery of those who are worst off without extracting an
deficiencies of resources” (Schwinger, 1986, p. 223), and equivalent amount of suffering from those who are better
they function much like other distributive justice principles, off, is justified or—in the language of Frankena (1962) and
especially in relationships built on trust. Similarly, value Feinberg (1973)—“justicized”, that is, shown to be just, on
is often attached to the principle of equality of outcomes (as largely utilitarian grounds (e.g., Campbell, 2001; Konow,
well as opportunities) across individuals and social classes, 2003; Sen, 1979).
and many interpret Marx’s demand for a “classless society” Although philosophical utilitarianism is quite clearly
as a call for thoroughgoing egalitarianism with respect to a normative theory about how people ought to behave,
distributive outcomes (e.g., see Campbell, 2001). descriptive research in psychology suggests that in many
It is possible that as a practical matter Marx’s condem- situations people are indeed highly sensitive to the per-
nation of “utopian socialists” led him to underestimate ceived consequences of an action (e.g., the degree of harm
the extent to which perceptions of social injustice based that results from it) when evaluating its moral soundness
on principles of equality or need (and the accompanying (e.g., Cushman, Young, & Hauser, 2006; Haidt & Graham,
sense of moral outrage that accompanies them) contain 2007; Kohlberg, 1978). In a series of experiments involving
revolutionary potential. Research throughout the social and the well-known “trolley problem,” which requires decision-
behavioral sciences reveals that anger in response to felt makers to make hypothetical but morally troubling life-and-
injustice—that is, moral outrage—is one of the most robust death decisions about appropriate and inappropriate ways
predictors of participation in collective action and motiva- of minimizing harm to innocent bystanders, research par-
tion for social change (e.g., Gurr, 1970; Martin, Scully, & ticipants do make cost–benefit calculations and favor utili-
Levitt, 1990; Montada & Schneider, 1989; Moore, 1978; tarian solutions (e.g., taking action so that one bystander
Tyler & Smith, 1998; Van Zomeren, Postmes, & Spears, is killed while five others are spared)—as long as the
2008; Wakslak, Jost, Tyler, & Chen, 2007). Although Marx emotional salience of the costs is relatively low for either
himself was deeply angered by the exploitation of work- situational or dispositional reasons (Greene, Sommerville,
ers in capitalist society, he sought to develop a dispassion- Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001; Koenigs, et al., 2007).
ate historical analysis and therefore said much less about Interestingly, cognitive load manipulations interfere with
social justice than he might otherwise have done. the type of moral reasoning that gives rise to utilitarian
solutions (Greene, Morelli, Lowenberg, Nystrom, & Cohen,
Liberal-Progressive Tradition 2008). When emotional processing predominates, people
Due in part to Marx’s skepticism, the concept of “‘social look much more like “deontological” theorists adhering to
justice’ was more readily embraced by liberals and pro- moral absolutes than utilitarians making complex calcula-
gressives than by socialists proper,” (Miller, 1999, p. 3). tions (see also Baron, 1993).
There are two major Western liberal traditions that are
most responsible for scholarly and practical interest in Deontological Approaches Deontologists hold that
questions of social justice. Sandel (1998) sums up these determinations of right and wrong depend not only on the
traditions succinctly in posing the following question: consequences of human action but also on other consid-
“Should justice be founded on utility, as Jeremy Bentham erations, including transcendent justice principles, such
and John Stuart Mill argue, or does respect for individual as the assumption that it is wrong to kill an innocent,
rights require a basis for justice independent of utilitarian healthy person under any circumstances. One of the most
considerations, as Kant and Rawls maintain?” (p. 184). famous proponents of a deontological approach to justice,
These two possibilities are generally referred to as the util- Immanuel Kant (1785/1993), proposed that a “categorical
itarian and deontological perspectives, respectively, and imperative” exists to “[a]ct only according to that maxim
each is considered in turn. whereby you can at the same time will that it should
become a universal law” (p. 30). In other words, justice
Utilitarianism Utilitarianism is a consequentialist theory requires us to do only those things that it would make
of justice, insofar as it assumes that the most just outcome or rational sense to universalize. Lying to gain personal
procedure is whatever results in the “greatest happiness of advantage, for instance, would violate the categorical imper-
the greatest number.” Of course, utilitarian philosophers ative, because if everyone lied for personal gain it would
disagree about how to gauge “happiness” and related con- be impossible to maintain trust and cooperation in society.
structs, such as “well-being,” “public interest,” and “gen- Although some reject the notion that universal principles
eral good” (see Bowie & Simon, 2007). Nevertheless, of justice could work in highly dissimilar cultures and
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1129

societies, others find promise in the Kantian aspiration to Michelbach, Scott, Matland, & Bornstein, 2003; Schulz &
develop an objective conception of justice—as embodied, May, 1989). For instance, Mitchell, Tetlock, Mellers, and
for instance, in the work of John Rawls. Ordóñez (1993) found that most people sought to maxi-
Rawls (1971) famously proposed that the most just mize the minimum standard of living in their society.
social system is the one that would be chosen by rational However, there are studies showing clear departures from
decision makers under a “veil of ignorance,” that is, in the what Rawls would have expected (e.g., Curtis, 1979). Most
absence of any specific knowledge of their own status or damningly, a research program summarized by Frohlich
position within the adopted system. Drawing in part on and Oppenheimer (1992) revealed that most of the partici-
psychological theory and research, including the work pants in their experiments, which were conducted in the
of Piaget (1932/1965) and Kohlberg (1969), Rawls con- United States, Canada, and Poland, opted for a “floor con-
cluded that under these circumstances rational individuals straint” (some safety net) but without any “ceiling” (i.e.,
ought to (and in fact would) select a system that would, limitation on maximum income). Their preferences, in
ceteris paribus: (a) minimize the degree of inequality other words, included social systems that contained more
in social and economic outcomes, and (b) maximize the inequality than Rawls’ theory would allow. Although this
outcomes of those who would occupy the worst position evidence does not disconfirm Rawls’ (1971) theory of
in the system. Taken together, these principles imply that what is objectively just, it does suggest that actual decision
some degree of inequality in society is tolerable, but only to makers find it challenging to leave behind their own personal
the extent that it benefits even those who are relatively dis- experiences and cultural baggage in placing themselves behind
advantaged, for example, by creating enough wealth that a “veil of ignorance.” The fact that social group and ideo-
everyone truly benefits. Rawls’ work constitutes, among logical differences are frequently observed in experiments
other things, a normative theory of justice that is meant to involving “hypothetical societies” suggests that people are
be “consistent with the laws of psychology,” and, ultimately, anchored to a considerable extent by the economic realities
a complex philosophical defense of political liberalism in and justice beliefs that operate in their own societies, even
the Kantian tradition of developing and enforcing a rational when they are explicitly instructed to ignore them (Bond &
“social contract,” that is, the consent of the individual to Park, 1991; Mitchell, Tetlock, Mellers, & Ordóňez, 1993;
participate in society (see also Rawls, 1993). Mitchell, Tetlock, Newman, & Lerner, 2003; Scott,
Empirical studies cannot determine what Rawls’ hypo- Matland, Michelbach, & Bornstein, 2001).
thetical decision makers would or should choose under the
Conservative Critique of the Liberal–Socialist
constraints he envisioned. This is because, as a practical
Tradition
matter, it is impossible to divorce actual decision mak-
ers from their own personal characteristics, experiences, It should be clear from the foregoing that most philo-
beliefs, and opinions. Some philosophers have suggested sophical conceptions of social justice, especially those
that this impossibility represents a fatal flaw in Rawls’ the- that emphasize egalitarian and welfare (i.e., need-based)
ory (rendering it, if not incoherent, useless for determining principles, were developed by liberals or socialists who
what justice principles real people would or should pre- were critical of traditional social, economic, or political
fer). Nonetheless, the purpose of the “veil of ignorance” arrangements (e.g., see Barry, 2005). Miller (1999) notes,
was to imagine the possibility of developing an objective for example, that “social justice has always been, and must
conception of social justice by insuring decision-making always be, a critical idea, one that challenges us to reform
impartiality and eliminating all potential sources of bias. our institutions and practices in the name of greater fair-
Empirical studies can address the question of what distribu- ness” (p. x). This explains why the concept of social jus-
tive justice principles people generally prefer when per- tice is sometimes denounced by political conservatives and
sonal sources of bias are at least muted (though not entirely others on the political right who seek to vindicate existing
removed). institutions that they regard as—if not always perfectly
The research literature provides mixed evidence just—at least necessary, efficient, or otherwise defensible
for the notion that actual decision makers would favor (e.g., Hayek, 1976).
Rawls’ justice principles over attractive alternatives, such Historians often trace the origins of modern political
as sheer wealth maximization. In some studies, research conservatism to Edmund Burke, an Irish-born member of
participants who lack information that would enable them Parliament in England who famously opposed the French
to act on the basis of self-interested motives do indeed eval- Revolution and encouraged his fellow citizens to “look
uate the fairness of various distributional schemes in ways backward to [the authority of] their ancestors” rather than
that are at least somewhat similar to how Rawls theorized turning to revolution (Burke, 1790/1987, p. 30; see also
they should behave (Bond & Park, 1991; Brickman, 1977; Viereck, 1956; White, 1950). Burke and his followers thus
1130 Social Justice

rejected liberal and socialist ideas as well as the broader Berscheid (1978). The theory holds that in rendering
intellectual context of the Scientific Enlightenment in judgments about distributive justice, people seek to deter-
which those ideas were developed (Jost, 2009), express- mine whether there is a proportional relationship between
ing “contempt for all forms of egalitarianism, which struck their inputs (e.g., degree of effort, ability, time, training,
[Burke] as a doctrine that is profoundly at odds with all the etc.) and the outcomes they receive (e.g., payments and
evidence of nature and history” (Shapiro, 2003, p. 152). other rewards as well as costs or punishments). To make
Burke also emphasized the importance of tradition and this determination in practice, people typically draw inter-
favored gradual, incremental reforms over more radical personal comparisons involving similar or relevant oth-
social change, because he believed that “conserving an ers (e.g., Festinger, 1954) or intrapersonal comparisons
imperfect inherited world from the worse imperfections based on their own prior experiences and expectations
that human beings are capable of contriving is the busi- (Adams, 1965).
ness of political leadership” (p. 152). To this day, political If an individual concludes that the ratio of inputs to out-
conservatism can be characterized in terms of two major puts in a given case is disproportionate, psychological dis-
principles, namely traditionalism (or resistance to change) tress is theorized to ensue; such distress, in turn, is expected
and, relatedly, the justification of inequality or hierarchy to motivate the individual to restore equity (Walster,
(Jost, Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway, 2003). Berscheid, & Walster, 1973; but see Greenberg, 1984). An
To the extent that conservatives (and libertarians) have important aspect of equity theory—an aspect that arguably
offered new theories of social justice, they have tended is what makes it a theory of justice rather than simply a
not to dismiss principles of need and equality outright but theory of attribution, social judgment, or preference—is
rather to subordinate them (at least on occasion) to other that people are hypothesized to dislike being overbene-
principles, such as merit, prosperity, and personal freedom fited (i.e., rewarded in a disproportionately favorable man-
(e.g., Nozick, 1974; Smith, 1776; Solomon & Murphy, ner) as well as being underbenefited. However, the latter
2000). It has been suggested that conservatives possess is especially aversive because it violates both justice and
unique “moral intuitions” and that they place a higher pre- self-interest (Walster, Walster, & Berscheid, 1978; see also
mium on loyalty to the ingroup, obedience to authority, Boll, Ferring, & Filipp, 2005; Loewenstein, Thompson, &
and attaining purity (Haidt & Graham, 2007). However, Bazerman, 1989; Peters, Van den Bos, & Bobocel, 2004).
the glorification of ingroup, authority, and purity concerns In terms of emotional responses, those who are underbene-
have (in a number of historical cases) been associated fited are assumed to feel angry and resentful, whereas those
with authoritarianism and even genocide (e.g., Altemeyer, who are overbenefited are assumed to feel guilty (e.g.,
1996; Kelman & Hamilton, 1989; Rummel, 1997; Staub, Hegtvedt, 1990; Homans, 1961/1974; Jost, Wakslak, &
1992). This makes them unlikely candidates (on norma- Tyler, 2008; Schmitt, Behner, Montada, Müller, & Müller-
tive grounds) to be considered general moral or justice Fohrbrodt, 2000). Anger, which is an approach-oriented,
principles. A stronger case can be made for moderate outward-directed emotion, is generally associated with
conservative principles such as desert, merit, prosperity, protest, whereas guilt is not (e.g., Wakslak, Jost, Tyler, &
and personal freedom (e.g., Mitchell et al., 2003; Nozick, Chen, 2007). According to equity theory, it is distressing
1974; Smith, 1776; Solomon & Murphy, 2000). Some to observe inequity in the relationships of others as well as
interpret the fact that political orientation is correlated with in one’s own relationships. There are two ways in which
justice beliefs to mean that disagreements over what is just people can cope with aversive reactions engendered by the
are ultimately ideological and therefore intractable; others presence of inequity: (a) they can restore equity in actuality
aspire to elevate the terms of debate by bringing scientific (i.e., objectively), by increasing or decreasing inputs (e.g.,
evidence to bear on the selection and application of vari- by working harder or withholding effort) or outputs (e.g., by
ous justice principles in resource allocation. giving or taking more or less in terms of benefits or bur-
dens); or (b) they can restore equity psychologically (i.e.,
Social Psychological Theories and Evidence subjectively), by rationalizing or otherwise reconstruing
Equity Theory No theory has been more broadly influen- the nature or relative evaluation of inputs and outputs so
tial to the empirical study of social justice than the one that as to make the situation or relationship seem equitable
arguably came first: equity theory. Aristotle (384–322 BCE) (Hatfield & Sprecher, 1984).
argued that justice requires proportionality, that is, “equal- The evidence has supported the basic tenets of equity
ity of ratios” (2002, p. 163; line 1131a31). This insight theory to an impressive degree (Ambrose & Kulik,
provides the starting point for equity theory, as developed 1999; Greenberg, 1993; Mowday, 1991). Consequently,
by Homans (1961); Adams (1965); Blau (1968); Walster, it has influenced several areas of social science, rang-
Berscheid, & Walster (1973); and Walster, Walster, & ing from the study of close relationships (Utne, Hatfield,
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1131

Traupmann, & Greenberger, 1984; Van Yperen & Buunk, that characterizes their own dealings with others but also
1990) to organizational behavior (Ambrose & Kulik, 1999; the degree of equity in society at large.
Bolino & Turney, 2008). Inequity produces physiological
arousal (Markowski, 1988), and the desire to establish (or Criticisms and Limitations Despite the consider-
restore) equity appears to be an important factor in children’s able evidence marshaled in support of equity theory,
resource allocations (Leventhal & Anderson, 1970; but see several limitations—both theoretical and empirical—
Lerner, 1974). Participants are especially likely to follow have been noted. For one thing, cultural differences
the equity norm when distributing rewards between them- exist in the extent to which people prefer equity over
selves and a competitor in the presence of a mirror, presum- other allocation principles, such as equality (Bolino &
ably because the mirror increases adherence to salient social Turnley, 2008; Chen, 1995; Fischer & Smith, 2003).
norms (Greenberg, 1980). Perceptions of equity are related Furthermore, the original formulation of the theory does
to perceptions of stability and contentment in new marriages not specify whether people will respond to inequity by
and other close relationships (Utne, Hatfield, Traupmann, & actively changing the circumstances to restore equity in
Greenberger, 1984; Van Yperen & Buunk, 1990; but see objective terms or by engaging in subjective processes
Montada, 2003; Sprecher & Schwartz, 1994), and percep- of reconstrual. Feelings of power or efficacy may play a
tions of inequity (i.e., feeling overbenefited) can also help large (and, on the basis of equity theory, unanticipated)
to explain negative reactions that are (ironically) caused role in determining which route will be pursued (Cook &
by high levels of social support (Gleason, Iida, Bolger, & Hegtvedt, 1986; Mowday, 1991; Weick, Bougan, &
Shrout, 2003). Perceptions of inequity also explain seem- Maruyama, 1976). Those who are especially interested in
ingly anomalous behavior in workplace settings, including preserving social harmony tend to restore equity through
employee theft of property belonging to an organization subjective, rather than objective, means (Bierhoff, Buck, &
that is seen as underrewarding its employees (Greenberg, Klein, 1986).
1993). A key contributor to “social loafing” (i.e., the ten- Equity theory is noticeably silent about the specific
dency for people to exert less effort in the presence of social comparison standards (e.g., friends, siblings, cowork-
others) is the assumption by some group members that ers, or bosses) that people invoke in determining whether
their co-workers will do less than their share (Jackson & their ratio of inputs to outputs is equitable. Although the
Harking, 1985); this assumption apparently causes people referent may be obvious in the context of a dyadic rela-
to diminish their own involvement to maintain the balance tionship, it may not be so clear in many other real-world
of equity. In one study, participants who were led to commit situations. It is assumed that people generally determine
a transgression and then forgiven for it were more likely whether their rewards are equitable based on comparisons
than others to comply with a subsequent request, presum- involving their own prior experiences, those of similar oth-
ably because “forgiveness . . . represent[s] a type of aid, ers (e.g., coworkers), and those based on system-specific
or gift, that upsets the balance of a relationship” (Kelln & expectations, such as organizational policies or promises
Ellard, 1999, p. 864) and creates a psychological need to (Goodman, 1977). The availability and relevance of specific
reestablish balance (or equity). referents likely dictate which ones are selected (Kulik &
Austin and Walster (1974) proposed that, when comput- Ambrose, 1992; Levine & Moreland, 1987). Choices of
ing their equity ratios, people do not simply compare them- referent type should also depend on individual differences
selves with specific referents but also form perceptions of in levels of “equity sensitivity” (e.g., Miles, Hatfield, &
“transrelational” equity or equity with the world (EwW), Huseman, 1994); people are expected to seek out those
which refers to the overall degree of equity (or inequity) referents that best allow them to minimize psychological
that is present in the totality of a person’s relationships. If a distress (O’Neill & Mone, 1998).
person is frequently manipulated or taken advantage of by Another oft-cited limitation of equity theory is its
others (e.g., the proverbial “sucker”), he or she falls well apparent insensitivity to procedural justice concerns (e.g.,
short of maintaining EwW. Similarly, if a person routinely Folger, 1986; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Thibaut & Walker,
exploits others (e.g., a racketeer, an unethical business 1975). For instance, fairness judgments are not driven
person), he or she is generally aware of holding an ineq- solely by input–output ratios but are also affected by pro-
uitable position relative to “others in general.” People also cedural factors that interact with those ratios. Specifically,
use stereotypes and social judgments to subjectively estab- people react unfavorably to a state of inequity only if (a)
lish equity, balance, complementarity, and the “illusion of it results from a decision that was made by another person
equality” with respect to the social system as a whole (Kay, (as opposed to oneself), and (b) they believe that a different
Jost, & Young, 2005). Taken in conjunction, this work decision could have reasonably been made (Cropanzano &
suggests that people not only monitor the degree of equity Folger, 1989). If a situation of inequity is perceived as
1132 Social Justice

occurring because of one’s own choices or because of people are worse off than others” (p. 3; see also Williams,
unimpeachable decisions made by others (i.e., decisions 1976/2000). Egalitarians assume, in other words, that the
made as a result of fair procedures), negative reactions do “demand for equality is built into the very concept of jus-
not generally ensue. tice” (Frankena, 1962, p. 20), but they do not necessarily
assume that justice always requires perfect equality or that
Principles of Equality and Need A number of authors equality is the only relevant principle of social justice.
have pointed out that equity is by no means the only Arbitrary inequality, in which goods or access to goods are
appropriate principle of distributive justice (e.g., Clark & meted out capriciously, haphazardly, or in direct violation
Mills, 1979; Deutsch, 1975; Elster, 1992; Feinberg, 1973; of notions of deservingness, is particularly objectionable
Konow, 2003; Jost & Azzi, 1996; Leventhal, 1980; Miller, to most people, including philosophers (Feinberg, 1973).
1999; Walzer, 1983). They take what is sometimes referred In other cases, what really bothers egalitarians is not that
to as a pluralistic or “multidimensional” approach to jus- some have less than others but that some simply do not
tice norms (Cohen & Greenberg, 1982; Mikula, 1984; have enough to meet their basic needs (Frankfurt, 1987).
Reis, 1984). Along these lines, Lerner (1974) observed This may explain why principles of equality and need are
that people’s conceptions of justice can take various forms, frequently bundled together in liberal–socialist conceptions
and that different situations call for different justice prin- of social justice.
ciples (see also Lerner & Whitehead, 1980; Törnblom & When individuals hold conflicting or competing goals,
Foa, 1983). When recipients share a common “identity,” people tend to rely on formal rules—such as those codi-
as in the case of families, the Marxian principle of allo- fied by the legal system—to arrive at the fairest allocation
cation based on need is much more likely to be adopted of resources (Lerner, 1974). Equity is deemed most fair
than when no such identity or affiliation exists (see also in situations in which people feel both dependent on and
Deutsch, 1975; Lamm & Schwinger, 1980; Lerner, 1974). nonequivalent to other social actors, as in marketplace envi-
The idea of dishing out relative dinner portions to one’s ronments (Deutsch, 1975; Lerner, 1974). Thus, the impor-
children on the basis of their report cards (e.g., merit)— tance of equity considerations (relative to other justice
regardless of their ages, sizes, or appetites—strikes one as norms) depends upon perceptions of social relations; that
inherently unjust if not downright absurd. Rather, a need- is, the ways in which people see themselves as connected to
based allocation seems far more appropriate. Similarly, others (or not) when it comes to sharing resources (Clayton &
members of close-knit groups may prefer norms of equal- Opotow, 2003; Huo, 2002; Wenzel, 2001, 2002). Often
ity (or parity) in dispersing benefits and burdens, presum- what looks like the application of (or preference for) an
ably because of the value placed upon the maintenance of equality principle is really the application of an equity
harmonious social relations (Deutsch, 1975; Konow, 2003; principle under circumstances in which “the scrutineer per-
Wenzel, 2000). ceived the relevant inputs to be equal” (Reis, 1984, p. 39).
Of all of the putative justice principles, equality has This returns us to the Aristotelian injunction to “treat
received far and away the most philosophical attention equals as equals” (and to treat unequally those who are
(e.g., Frankena, 1962; Miller, 1999; Nagel, 1991; Pojman & unalike in a relevant, that is, nonarbitrary way; Feinberg,
Westmoreland, 1997; Rawls, 1971; Solomon & Murphy, 1973, pp. 100–101).
2000; Vlastos, 1962/1997; Walzer, 1983). Demands for The most popular equity principle in common circu-
equal rights and equal treatment under the law have been lation is the principle of merit; that is, the rewarding of
fundamental causes of political revolution and constitution- individuals on the basis of contributions or entitlements,
building in Europe and the Americas since the time of the such as ability, effort, motivation, and achievement
Enlightenment. Equality is central to the liberal–socialist (e.g., Frankena, 1962; Hayek, 1976; Nozick, 1974).
tradition, and leftists today are distinguished largely by Justifications for this principle are frequently utilitarian in
their advocacy for greater social, economic, and political nature, insofar as they suggest that a meritocratic system
equality (e.g., Nielsen, 1985). Although previous gen- creates incentives for productivity that are beneficial to
erations of conservatives, including Burke (1790/1987), society as a whole. Miller (1999) has suggested that prin-
objected to egalitarianism in various guises, most con- ciples of equality and merit are compatible in certain ways
servatives today endorse political equality (e.g., one and that social justice may require an integration of the
person, one vote) and equality of opportunity in educa- two. For one thing, both equality and merit “stand opposed
tion and economic domains. But, as Parfit (1998) notes, to a distribution of advantages on the basis of luck”
to subscribe to egalitarianism as a justice principle also (p. 201); this suggests that the extent to which the capitalist
requires being “concerned with people’s being equally system may be considered just by egalitarians and meri-
well off;” that is, to believe that, “It is in itself bad if some tarians alike depends upon the extent to which outcomes
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1133

are not attributable to chance (or nepotism or simply being in According to Deutsch, distributing resources purely based
the right place at the right time). Furthermore, Miller argues, on equity would disrupt the mutual respect required for
on normative grounds, that the principle of merit should fostering “enjoyable” social relationships. Deutsch (1985)
never be used to allocate “those goods and services that reviewed several studies contradicting the commonly held
people regard as necessities, such as health care” (p. 200). notion that distributing rewards (and punishments) on the
On this point, there is general agreement between subjec- basis of the equality principle necessarily results in a loss
tive and objective conceptions (see also Lupfer, Weeks, of efficiency or productivity. He found that egalitarianism
Doan, & Houston, 2000). Research participants do feel enhanced cooperation and, therefore, group performance.
that different types of resources should be allocated on the Research has generally supported Deutsch’s conten-
basis of different justice principles (Fiske & Tetlock, 1997; tion that the three principles of equity, equality, and need
Törnblom & Foa, 1983), and that burdens and necessities tend to vary in their applicability, and so are differentially
should be distributed with regard to considerations of need valued as a function of situational and dispositional factors
and equality rather than merit (e.g., Gamliel & Peer, 2006; (e.g., Barrett-Howard & Tyler, 1986; Bolino & Turnley,
Matania & Yaniv, 2007; but see Törnblom, Mühlhausen, & 2008; Clark & Mills, 1979; Deutsch, 1985; Reis, 1984).
Jonsson, 1991). However, it is not always clear whether this variability in
allocation preferences is due to justice-related or instru-
Cooperative Versus Competitive Social Systems mental concerns; that is, people might prefer one principle
Deutsch (1975) offered an analysis that was highly com- over another for reasons that have little to do with justice
patible with that of Lerner (1974) but differed in two sig- (Montada, 2003). People’s allocations of resources appear
nificant ways. First, whereas Lerner focused on the forms to reflect a blend or combination of different justice prin-
of distribution that would be seen as most just in various ciples along with considerations of self-interest (e.g., Jost &
social contexts, Deutsch (building on his earlier work in Azzi, 1996; Konow, 2003; Mikula, 1984), and they may
Lewin’s Group Dynamics laboratory) addressed the related engage in post hoc rationalizations of certain distributive prin-
but distinct issue of which forms of distribution would be ciples and outcomes that they would not necessarily choose
most effective at helping a group to reach a given goal. ex ante (Diekmann, Samuels, Ross, & Bazerman, 1997).
Second, Deutsch outlined three, rather than four, primary
types of distributive justice, dropping the conception of jus- Do Liberals and Conservatives Prefer Different Justice
tice as law-abidingness, possibly in recognition of the fact Principles? Given that one of the core ideological differ-
that the “laws of the state . . . may be themselves unjust” ences between political liberals and conservatives concerns
(Frankena, 1962, p. 3). Hence, Deutsch’s taxonomy is a the value that is placed on equality of outcomes (e.g., Jost,
little less Aristotelian and a little more Marxian. The sig- Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway, 2003), it is not too sur-
nificance of overarching social systems is emphasized in prising that justice preferences and judgments covary with
Deutsch’s (1985) “crude law of social relations,” by which political orientation (e.g., Bartels, 2008; Christiansen &
“the characteristic processes and effects elicited by a given Lavine, 1997; Emler, 2002; Furgeson, Babcock, & Shane,
type of social relationship also tend to elicit that type of 2008; Rossi & Berk, 1997; Skitka & Tetlock, 1993). In
social relationship” (p. 69); that is, competitively structured so-called “hypothetical society” paradigms, for instance,
social systems beget competitive behavior, and coopera- liberals generally prefer more egalitarian distributions of
tively structured systems beget cooperation. wealth that also offer protections for those who are in great-
According to Deutsch (1975), the equity principle should est need, whereas conservatives are more likely to prioritize
be emphasized only in those situations in which “economic equity, efficiency, and individual merit (Mitchell, Tetlock,
productivity is a primary goal” (p. 143), insofar as it breeds Mellers, Ordóñez, 1993; Mitchell, Tetlock, Newman, &
competition and even conflict as social by-products. By Lerner, 2003). These differences in justice preferences are
contrast, in the context of social systems that prioritize clearly consistent with philosophical differences among
personal development, communal welfare, and cooperation, socialists, liberals, and conservatives that go back several
the most constructive method of distributing resources is centuries (Jost, 2009).
on the basis of need and equality, consistent with Marxian Mitchell and colleagues (1993) observed that ideologi-
social theory. Failing to consider the needs of its mem- cal polarization was greatest for judgments of hypothetical
bers, Deutsch argued, would “obviously be disruptive of societies containing moderate degrees of meritocracy.
any group that has a primary concern for the development Presumably, this is because liberals see the justice glass
and welfare of its members” (p. 147). Furthermore, if the as half-empty under such circumstances (emphasizing the
goal is to maximize the harmoniousness of social relations, role of chance), whereas conservatives see it as half-full
equality should be the distributive principle of choice. (emphasizing ability and effort). Napier and Jost (2008a)
1134 Social Justice

found that economic inequality is differentially related to (e.g., Crosby, 1976; Davis, 1959; Gurr, 1970; Pettigrew,
self-reported happiness levels for liberals and conserva- 1967; Runciman, 1966). The central insight for theories
tives. Specifically, increasing economic inequality in U.S. of social justice is that judgments of fairness and satisfac-
society from 1974 to 2004 (measured in terms of various tion (or, conversely, unfairness and dissatisfaction) are
macro-economic indices) was associated with decreased often derived not on the basis of some abstract or absolute
subjective well-being in general, but liberals were more standard. Rather, they are the result of an inherently com-
strongly affected than were conservatives, apparently parative process in which one’s own situation is contrasted
because the conservative belief that inequality is often with that of others—or, as with regard to equity compari-
legitimate and meritorious provides a kind of “ideological sons, on the basis of intrapersonal comparisons involving
buffer” against the negative hedonic effects of inequality. one’s own prior states and expectations (e.g., Albert, 1977;
Davies, 1962; Guimond & Dambrun, 2002; Zagefka &
Relative Deprivation and Social Comparison Unlike Brown, 2005).
the preceding accounts, relative deprivation theory does not Davies (1962) proposed an influential theory of revolu-
specify which principles of distributive justice people will tion in which he argued that social and political unrest is
prefer under specific circumstances. Rather, it addresses a most likely to occur when a prolonged period of improve-
more general question about the social and psychological ment in living conditions is followed by a brief but pain-
processes leading to the appraisal of a given situation as ful period of decline, such that the gap between people’s
either just or unjust (Davies, 1962; Gurr, 1970). In essence, subjectively rising expectations and their objectively wors-
the theory holds that people will experience moral out- ening circumstances becomes intolerable. This argument
rage and engage in collective action aimed at changing an sought to reconcile (a) Marx’s claim that abject depriva-
unjust status quo if and only if they perceive themselves to tion would lead members of underprivileged groups (such
be relatively deprived (Tyler & Smith, 1998). Theories that as the working class) to realize that they have “nothing to
pivot on the concept of relative deprivation are not theories lose but their chains” and therefore rebel against the status
about how to recognize or implement social justice per se; quo, and (b) Tocqueville’s historical observation that “the
rather they seek to understand when people will and will most overwhelming oppression often burst[s] into rebel-
not perceive social injustice, and the question of whether lion against the yoke the moment it begins to grow lighter.”
such perceptions are accurate or inaccurate is largely unad- Several historical cases—including Dorr’s Rebellion of
dressed (e.g., see Walker & Smith, 2002). In other words, it 1842 and the Russian Revolution of 1917—seem to fit
is not specified and does not matter—from the perspective Davies’ account, which is sometimes referred to as “pro-
of relative deprivation approaches—whether people appeal gressive” relative deprivation theory. Building on this
to equity, equality, or need principles (or no justice prin- work, Gurr (1970) proposed that a significant gap between
ciples at all) in formulating and acting upon perceptions of people’s expectations and their capabilities creates “the
relative deprivation. What matters is simply whether or not necessary precondition for civil strife in any kind.” In a
they are aggrieved. series of cross-national studies, he found that both short-
term economic deprivation and long-term strains (i.e., dis-
Origins of Relative Deprivation Theory Relative depriva- crimination) tend to magnify frustration and the eventual
tion theory began with a relatively simple empirical obser- likelihood of political rebellion.
vation: when asked about their degree of satisfaction with
the promotion system in the U.S. army, soldiers’ judgments The Distinction Between Individual and Group
had little to do with current rank, promotion rates, or their Deprivation Runciman’s (1966) well-known distinction
actual likelihood of promotion. Instead, judgments were based between egoistic (individual) and fraternal (group) forms of
largely on where the soldiers felt they stood in comparison relative deprivation has proven especially useful in social
with fellow soldiers of similar rank. If they were worse psychological research (e.g., Crosby, 1976; Walker &
off than the other soldiers around them, they felt deprived Smith, 2002). Studies show, for example, that relative depri-
(Stouffer, Suchman, DeVinney, Star, & Williams, 1949). vation at the group (but not individual) level of analysis is
Thus, soldiers’ feelings of satisfaction (or dissatisfaction) a powerful determinant of prejudice and outgroup hostil-
were not due to a careful analysis of the characteristics of the ity (e.g., Dubé & Guimond, 1986; Guimond & Dambrun,
system itself, but rather depended upon social comparison 2002; Fiske, 1998; Hafer & Olson, 1993; Pettigrew et al.,
processes (Festinger, 1954; see also Brickman, Coates, & 2008; Tyler & Smith, 1998; Walker & Pettigrew, 1984).
Janoff-Bulman, 1978; Olson & Hazlewood, 1986). Given the consistency of this result, it seems worthwhile
This initial observation inspired a slew of kindred theo- to ask whether the converse—feeling that one’s group
ries addressing the phenomenon of relative deprivation is relatively gratified in comparison with another group—is
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1135

associated with decreased hostility. Unfortunately, the Meen, & Robertson, 1995). Nevertheless, feelings of personal
answer is no; rather, group-based feelings of relative grati- deprivation have been linked to a number of consequential
fication (or perhaps superiority) are also associated with outcomes, including women’s dissatisfaction with house-
outgroup hostility (Dambrun, Taylor, McDonald, Crush, & hold divisions of labor (Freudenthaler & Mikula, 1998;
Meot, 2006; Guimond & Dambrun, 2002). Perceptions of but see Biernat & Wortman, 1991); career disengagement
relative deprivation (and the anger elicited by such per- (Tougas, Rinfret, Beaton, & de la Sablonnière, 2005); and
ceptions) may explain action taken by advantaged groups symptoms of stress among the unemployed (Walker &
to stop government programs designed to help members Mann, 1987).
of disadvantaged groups (Leach, Iyer, & Pederson, 2007;
Pettigrew & Meertens, 1995). When those at the top claim Criticisms and Limitations Relative deprivation theo-
injustice and discrimination from below (e.g., Major et al., rists tend to assume, often tacitly, that members of disad-
2002), it is difficult to know whether such claims are based vantaged groups are “revolutionaries-in-waiting,” and that
sincerely on fairness concerns or are simply strategic ploys they will fight against the status quo as soon as the full
to maintain their own advantage, but the difference seems and frustrating extent of their deprivation is made obvious
important. through direct social comparison with others (or with what
Several studies have investigated the extent to which per- might have been). Members of advantaged groups, too, are
ceptions of relative deprivation motivate the disadvantaged hypothesized to feel relatively deprived when actual out-
to improve their own or their group’s position—or to par- comes fall short of (even lofty, unrealistic) expectations.
ticipate in collective action more generally (see Walker & Thus, Gurr (1970) concluded that, “men are quick to aspire
Smith, 2002). Group deprivation contributes more strongly beyond their social means and quick to anger when those
than individual deprivation to collective action, possibly means prove inadequate, but slow to accept their limita-
because perceptions of group deprivation are more likely to tions” (p. 58). The problem is that too many data sets fail
elicit negative, outward-directed emotions, such as anger to corroborate these strong claims (e.g., Gurney & Tierney,
(Leach, Iyer, & Pedersen, 2007; Walker & Smith, 2002), 1982; McPhail, 1971; Thompson, 1989; see also Kinder &
whereas perceptions of individual deprivation may be asso- Sears, 1985, pp. 701–702). The perception of relative
ciated with more inward-directed emotions, such as depres- deprivation in and of itself does not seem to be a sufficient
sion and anxiety (Hafer & Olson, 2003; Walker & Mann, cause of anger, protest behavior, or participation in collec-
1987). Although most studies link group (rather than individ- tive action, as Crosby’s (1976) original list of precondi-
ual) relative deprivation to participation in collective action tions suggested (see also Klandermans, Van der Toorn, &
(Dion, 1986; Dubé & Guimond, 1986; Guimond & Dubé- Van Stekelenburg, 2008; Van Zomeren, Postmes, & Spears,
Simard, 1983; Kessler & Mummendey, 2001; Walker & 2008).
Mann, 1987), some evidence suggests that collective action At the least, people must perceive the status quo as ille-
is most likely to result when both forms of deprivation are gitimate to challenge it, but perceptions of illegitimacy are
experienced (Foster & Matheson, 1995). highly contingent on ideological and other factors (e.g.,
Crosby (1976) originally proposed that five conditions see Jost & Major, 2001; Tyler, 2006). As a result, rebellion
must be met for feelings of individual (or egoistic) relative is much rarer than relative deprivation and related theo-
deprivation to ensue: (1) a person must notice that another retical perspectives would imply (Jost, Banaji, & Nosek,
possesses more than s/he does, (2) s/he must desire what 2004). Contrary to Gurr’s (1970) supposition that “men are
the other person has, (3) s/he must feel entitled to it for quick to aspire” beyond their means, social psychologi-
some reason, (4) s/he must think that it can be realistically cal research reveals that “social comparison biases tend to
attained, and (5) s/he must not feel personally responsi- prevent awareness of disadvantage, and attribution biases
ble for the state of deprivation. Reflecting on the results tend to legitimize disadvantage” (Major, 1994, p. 294; see
of survey research, Crosby, Muehrer, and Loewenstein also Crocker & Major, 1989; Jost, 1997). Thus, despite the
(1986) trimmed the list of preconditions to two—wanting fact that women are dramatically underpaid compared with
something and feeling that one deserves it. The other three men and suffer various other forms of discrimination,
factors, they concluded, were more distal causes of rela- women generally show little discontent or resentment con-
tive deprivation, and their effects were hypothesized to be cerning their payment and employment status (Crosby,
mediated by the two more proximal states of wanting and 1982) and no overall deficit in terms of satisfaction when
deserving. The extent to which various preconditions are compared with men (Diener, 1984; but see Fujita, Diener, &
necessary and/or sufficient to engender feelings of relative Sandvik, 1991).
deprivation is still largely unknown (but see Bernstein & It is telling that Pettigrew (2002) ultimately regarded the
Crosby, 1980; Olson & Hazlewood, 1986; Olson, Roese, relative deprivation perspective “not [as] a fully developed
1136 Social Justice

theory itself,” but rather “a key construct that can link linked to the human need to commit to long-term goal pur-
different levels of analysis” (p. 353). Neither Stouffer and col- suit (Hafer, Bègue, Choma, & Dempsey, 2005; Lerner, 1977,
leagues (1949) nor their many accomplished successors— 1980; Lerner, Miller, & Holmes, 1976).
including Davis (1959), Davies (1962), Runciman (1966), More than 40 years of empirical research has supported
Pettigrew (1967), Gurr (1970), and Crosby (1976)—were specific hypotheses derived from just world theorizing
able to specify the precise circumstances under which draw- (Furnham, 2003; Hafer & Bègue, 2005; Lerner, 1980;
ing upward social comparisons would consistently lead Lerner & Miller, 1978). Much of this work has addressed
the disadvantaged to participate in collective action aimed psychological processes associated with victim derogation
at social change. As Kinder and Sears (1985) noted: “the (see also Napier, Mandisodza, Andersen, & Jost, 2006;
deepest puzzle here is not occasional protest but pervasive Ryan, 1971). For instance, research participants who learn
tranquility—why, in Moore’s (1978) words ‘people so often about a woman’s suffering and are denied the opportunity
put up with being the victims of their societies’ ” (p. 702). to help her directly are more likely to defame her char-
Collective action does not result simply from the perception acter than are participants who are able to compensate
that one’s aspirations have been violated; rather, collective her in some way (Lerner & Simmons, 1966). Studies of
action most likely requires the dynamic interplay of a com- this type suggest that people are generally threatened by
plicated set of social, psychological, and political variables. the presence of injustice and are therefore motivated to
restore justice (i.e., through reparations); however, if they
Belief in a Just World In seeking to establish a theoreti- are prevented from doing so, they will engage in mental
cal foundation in developmental psychology for his theory gymnastics (such as rationalization) to deny or minimize
of the justice motive and belief in a just world, Lerner the unjust event (e.g., Reichle & Schmitt, 2002). Research
(1975) proposed that: reveals that (when opportunities to help are blocked) many
people derogate those who are impoverished, unlucky, and
“[T]he child (in order to gain better, more secure outcomes) unemployed; those who are sick with cancer, pneumonia,
develops a personal contract with the self. The terms of this and HIV; and victims of sexual assault, spousal abuse,
contract are simply that he/she is willing to do certain things, and electric shock (Hafer & Bègue, 2005). The desire to
give up certain things, on the assumption that a particular maintain the belief in a just world apparently even leads
desired outcome will ensue. The child designs the child’s people to derogate themselves for their own misfortune
goal-seeking, the adult patterns his/her life around this per- (Olson & Hafer, 2001). It also encourages them to lionize
sonal contract, mainly because it is to the person’s benefit those who are the beneficiaries of luck and good fortune,
to develop the psychology of entitlement. People want to including those who are powerful and/or physically attrac-
deserve their outcomes, get what they are entitled to receive. tive (Callan, Powell, & Ellard, 2007; Dion & Dion, 1987;
The concern with one’s own deserving, or personal contract,
Ellard & Bates, 1990; Kay, Jost, & Young, 2005).
gets linked to the commitment to justice—to an insistence
Experimental research on the belief in a just world has
that others get what they deserve—in various ways. . . . This
psychology of entitlement provides the inevitable basis of the
focused on victim-blaming as the most common behavioral
concern with justice for others.” (p. 13) outcome (Hafer & Bègue, 2005), possibly because it seems
so paradoxical that the desire for justice would lead people
On this view, human beings want adamantly to believe to treat others so unjustly. Relatively little has been done to
that their efforts and investments will be reciprocated; that experimentally test other theoretical assumptions of the
is, that they will be rewarded for delaying personal gratifi- original theory, to pinpoint the psychological mechanisms
cation and participating in civilized society (Lerner, 1975, involved, or to explore other possible means of satisfying
1980). A natural extension of this “personal contract” is the the justice motive. But, there are exceptions to this general-
motivated belief that people’s outcomes (i.e., rewards or pun- ization, including the demonstration that denial, avoidance,
ishments) are caused by “who they are or what they have and distancing are effective means of coping with the threat
done” (Lerner, 1987, p. 108). According to Lerner (1980), posed by innocent victims (Drout & Gaertner, 1994; Hafer,
people cling so strongly to this “fundamental delusion” that 2000a, 2000b; Pancer, 1988). Exposure to complementary
any information contradicting it—such as children suffering stereotypes in which an “illusion of equality” is created by
from terminal illness or innocent persons being victimized— ascribing positive, redeeming characteristics to members
causes psychological distress. To cope with distress, people of disadvantaged groups and negative, offsetting char-
convince themselves that the social world operates according acteristics to members of advantaged groups also helps to
to rules of deservingness, namely that people “get what they sustain the belief that societal arrangements are just (Jost &
deserve and deserve what they get.” The desire (or motive) Kay, 2005; Kay & Jost, 2003; Kay, Jost, et al., 2007; see
to attain justice—both for oneself and for others—is thus also Gaucher, Hafer, Kay, & Davidenko, in press).
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1137

To maintain the belief in a just world, people may recon- as with many other variables in social and personality
struct (or selectively recall) details of the past, such as mis- psychology, there are both dispositional and situational
remembering that a smaller lottery prize was awarded to sources of variability in the justice motive and the need to
a “bad” person than was actually the case (Callan, Kay, believe in a just world.
Davidenko, & Ellard, in press; Haines & Jost, 2000).
Reaction-time paradigms reveal that exposure to information Deservingness and Entitlement There may be no single
that threatens (vs. satisfies) the belief in a just world (e.g., theme more commonly enshrined in Western ideology than
a criminal “getting away with it” vs. being apprehended) that of individual deservingness (Kluegel & Smith, 1986;
produces an automatic preoccupation with justice-related Wegener & Liebig, 2000). It figures prominently in charac-
constructs (Hafer, 2000a; Kay & Jost, 2003). Knowledge of terizations of the Protestant work ethic (Jones, 1997; Katz &
a victim’s innocence (Correia, Vala, & Aguiar, 2007), pro- Hass, 1988; Weber, 1958), culturally prevalent conceptions
longed suffering (Callan, Ellard, & Nicol, 2006), or status of personal control and causation (Nisbett & Ross, 1980),
as an ingroup member (Aguiar, Vala, Correia, & Pereira, the belief in a just world (Lerner, 1980), and various system-
2008) exacerbates justice concerns at an implicit as well as justifying belief systems, including meritocratic ideology
explicit level of awareness. Dalbert’s (1998, 2001, 2002) and faith in the American dream (Jost & Hunyady, 2005;
work suggests that the belief in a just world serves an addi- McCoy & Major, 2007). The take-home message from
tional function that was not outlined in Lerner’s original for- empirical inquiry is that people are far more likely to feel
mulation of just world theory; specifically, it operates as a that the existing social, economic, or political system is fair
personal resource that helps people cope with unjust events and just to the extent that they see recipients of various dis-
that occur in their daily lives (see also Lipkus & Bissonnete, tributive outcomes (e.g., wealth and poverty) as personally
1996; Lipkus, Dalbert, & Siegler, 1996; Schmitt & Dörfel, deserving of those outcomes (e.g., Jost, Blount, Pfeffer, &
1999; Tomaka & Blascovich, 1994; Vermunt, 2007). This Hunyady, 2003). People seem to feel more justified in dis-
may help to explain its prevalence and even its high degree criminating against those who are stigmatized on the basis
of social desirability (Alves & Correia, 2008). of characteristics that are seen as personally controllable,
Research on dispositional measures of the belief in the such as obesity (e.g., Crandall, & Martinez, 1996; Puhl &
just world, which was initiated by Rubin and Peplau (1975) Brownell, 2003; Quinn & Crocker, 1999).
and summarized first by Lerner and Miller (1978), has Social psychologists have devoted considerable research
continued more or less unabated (Furnham, 2003). Some attention to understanding how notions of deservingness (and
authors have questioned whether measuring the belief entitlement)2 are related to processes of attribution, stereo-
in a just world as a relatively stable personality variable typing and prejudice, perceptions of discrimination, political
(using explicit, self-report techniques) really captures the ideology, and appraisals of the legitimacy of social systems
motivational construct as originally described in just world (e.g., Jost & Banaji, 1994; Jost & Major, 2001; Major, 1994).
theorizing (Hafer & Bègue, 2005; Lerner, 1977, 1980), but Studies show that perceptions of personal causation and
there is little doubt that the individual differences approach
has significantly shaped research agendas.1 Studies show
that those who score highly on the belief in a just world 2
Feather (1994) has distinguished crisply between concepts of
are more likely to engage in victim derogation (inter deservingness and entitlement, noting that “whereas deserving-
alia, Anderson, 1992; Braman & Lambert, 2001; Carr & ness pertains more to the evaluative structure of actions and their
MacLachlan, 1998; Crandall & Martinez, 1996; Dalbert, outcomes . . . entitlement pertains more to an external, consensu-
2002; De Judicibus & McCabe, 2001; Furnham, 1995; ally based framework of laws, rights, and social norms that may
Jost & Burgess, 2000; Kristiansen & Giuletti, 1990). Thus, be tacitly acknowledged or more formally prescribed” (p. 368;
see also Feather, 1999). Major’s (1994) account of entitlement,
however, blurs the distinction: “If an individual fulfills certain
preconditions, he or she will feel entitled to certain outcomes.
1
There may be more than one type of belief in a just world These preconditions may be either ascribed (e.g., she is of a par-
(Furnham, 2003). Distinctions have been proposed, for example, ticular race or sex) or earned (e.g., he has made particular contri-
between beliefs in a just vs. unjust world (Furnham, 1985), beliefs butions)” (p. 299). Lerner’s (1987) definition of entitlement-“a
in a just world for the self vs. others (Bègue & Bastounis, 2003; sense of requiredness between the actor’s perceived outcomes
Lipkus, Dalbert, & Siegler, 1996; Sutton et al., 2008), and beliefs and attributes or acts”-similarly amalgamates the two constructs.
in immanent vs. ultimate justice (Maes, 1998). Factor analyses The important point is that symbolic and material resources are
confirm that a multidimensional factor structure exists, but the frequently allocated on the basis of who the recipient is and what
theoretical significance of such findings is not always entirely he or she has done and that both of these are generally accepted
clear (Hafer & Bègue, 2005). as fair and legitimate (see Feather, 2008).
1138 Social Justice

deservingness lead people to hold more and less favorable of meritocracy and deservingness—have been associated
attitudes toward high and low status targets, respectively with the tendency for members of low status groups to
(e.g., Weiner, Perry, & Magnuson, 1988). Endorsement view their own state of disadvantage as relatively legiti-
of just world beliefs and system-justifying ideologies that mate (Crandall, 1994; Jost, 1995; Jost, Banaji, & Nosek,
emphasize deservingness are associated with increased prej- 2004; Olson & Hafer, 2001; Quinn & Crocker, 1999). For
udice toward African Americans and obese people, among example, women who score higher on the belief in a just
other stigmatized groups (Crandall & Martinez, 1996; Rim, world are less likely to report career-related discontentment
1988). Attributions of deservingness act not only as causes (Hafer & Olson, 1993), and ethnic minorities who espouse
but also as releasers of prejudice (Crandall & Eshleman, the belief that it is possible to climb the status hierarchy are
2003), insofar as they seem to justify the expression of less likely to view negative outcomes as due to discrimina-
preexisting negative attitudes toward certain social groups tion or unfairness (Major et al., 2002).
(Allport, 1954; Jost & Banaji, 1994). Espousing political There is also experimental work showing that “depressed
conservatism, which often leans heavily on the assumption entitlement” (and tolerance of injustice more generally) can
of personal deservingness (or individual responsibility), also be produced or exacerbated under specific situational condi-
predicts both implicit and explicit devaluation of those who tions. For instance, priming members of a low status group
are disadvantaged in society, including African Americans with meritocratic ideals makes them less likely to regard
(e.g., Crandall, 1994; Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004; Jost, unfair treatment (by a higher status group member) as caused
Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway, 2003; Nosek, Banaji, & by sexism or discrimination (McCoy & Major, 2007; see also
Jost, 2009; Pratto, Sidanius, Stallworth, & Malle, 1994; Biernat, Vescio, & Theno, 1996; Jost & Kay, 2005; Quinn &
Sears, van Laar, Carrillo, & Kosterman, 1997; Sidanius, Crocker, 1999). Research on system justification theory
Pratto, & Bobo, 1996). similarly suggests that people may be motivated (for epis-
The concept of deservingness is useful for understanding temic, existential, and relational reasons) to view inequalities
resentment directed at people who are extremely successful among individuals and groups as fair, legitimate, and defen-
(i.e., “tall poppies”). According to Feather (1994), people sible rather than due to discrimination, unfairness, or his-
first try to determine whether an individual is personally torical accident (e.g., Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004). As with
responsible for their outcome; that is, the extent to which regard to the belief in a just world and many other areas of
“the outcome is assumed to be produced by the person and social justice research, system justification tendencies vary
related to the person’s intentions” (p. 13). Next, they con- as a function of both dispositional and situational vari-
sider the values of the behavior and the outcome. When a ables (Jost, Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway, 2003; Jost &
positively valued behavior is seen as leading to a positively Hunyady, 2005; Kay & Zanna, 2009; Kay, Gaucher, Peach,
valued outcome (e.g., training hard to win a competitive Laurin, Friesen, Zanna, & Spencer, 2009).
race) or a negatively valued behavior is seen as leading to
a negatively valued outcome (e.g., cheating and losing the Social Dilemmas Social dilemmas are situations that pit
race), the perceiver will experience the outcome as deserved. self-interest against collective interest. Although scholarly
By contrast, valence mismatches between the behavior and interest in these situations typically derives from an interest in
outcome (e.g., cheating and winning the race or training how people with “mixed motives” make difficult decisions,
hard and losing it) lead to perceptions that the outcomes are there are clear implications for social justice—principally
undeserved. Thus, people tend to react negatively to success for the distribution of resources across individuals and
that is seen as undeserved and are eager to see “tall poppies” even across generations of individuals. Experimentally cre-
fall under such circumstances (Feather, 1994, 1999). ated social dilemmas involve two essential characteristics:
Much research, including studies of relative depriva- “(a) at any given decision point, individuals receive higher
tion and social comparison processes mentioned previ- payoffs for making selfish choices than they do for making
ously, has explored the ways in which people’s perceptions cooperative choices . . . and (b) everyone involved receives
of entitlement relate to issues of social justice. One use- lower payoffs if everyone makes selfish choices than if
ful focus has been on the conditions that lead members everyone makes cooperative choices” (Weber, Kopelman, &
of disadvantaged or low status groups (such as women) Messick, 2004, p. 281). Defined in these terms, there are
to develop a “depressed sense of entitlement” that leads three major classes of social dilemmas (i.e., miniature social
them to be satisfied with less than others receive (Blanton, systems) studied by experimentalists (Komorita & Parks,
George, & Crocker, 2001; Callahan-Levy & Messé, 1979; 1995). These are the prisoner ’s dilemma, in which two indi-
Hogue & Yoder, 2003; Jost, 1997; Major, 1994; Pelham & viduals must choose between “cooperating” and “defect-
Hetts, 2001). The endorsement of various ideological ing,” with the knowledge that, although defecting will offer
belief systems—especially those that reinforce notions an individual the highest possible payoff when his or her
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1139

partner cooperates, if both defect, the outcome will be sig- outcomes for others than for themselves, and “reciprocal
nificantly worse than if both cooperate; the public goods cooperators,” who engage in prosocial behavior only to the
game, in which people must decide how much to contribute extent that they expect others to reciprocate (Kurzban &
to a common resource pool that others will benefit from, Houser, 2001; Perugini & Galluci, 2001).
regardless of how much they actually contributed; and the But why, exactly, do prosocials cooperate more than
resource dilemma, in which all group members are able to proselfs? Two major explanations have been offered. First,
draw from a given resource pool, but with the awareness it has been suggested that prosocials are more likely to
that overharvesting will deplete it entirely (because the construe the goal of social dilemma situations in terms of
resource is replenished only occasionally). maximizing collective (as opposed to individual) rationality
Although cooperative, prosocial behavior is by no means (Liebrand, Jansen, Rijken, & Suhre, 1986; Simpson, 2004;
unheard of in these types of situations, it is less common Utz, Ouwerkerk, & Van Lange, 2004). Second, it is possible
overall than is competitive, self-interested behavior. People that prosocials are more likely than proselfs to expect that
cooperate roughly 30%–40% of the time in laboratory stud- others will cooperate rather than defect (e.g., Smeesters,
ies, aggregating across different types of social dilemmas Warlop, Van Avermaet, Corneille, & Yzerbyt, 2003).
(Komorita & Parks, 1995). Because competitive strategies Interested readers are directed to more detailed reviews of
violate principles of equality and (assuming equivalent how social value orientation (Bogaert, Boone, & Declerck,
inputs) equity, understanding the factors that inhibit compe- 2008) and other individual difference variables (Van Lange,
tition and promote cooperation is an important goal of social De Cremer, Van Dijk, & Van Vugt, 2007) predict behav-
justice research (Schroeder, Steel, Woodell, & Bembenek, ior in experimentally created social dilemmas. The general
2003). A comprehensive research literature (produced by assumption is that justice-related behavior in these situa-
social psychologists, economists, sociologists, political sci- tions has fairly deep roots both in personality and social-
entists, and others) highlights numerous factors associated ization experiences (Au & Kwong, 2004; De Cremer & Van
with cooperative behavior in social dilemma situations, Lange, 2001; J. T. Jost & L. J. Jost, 2009; Kuhlman, Camac,
including shared social identification (Kramer & Brewer, & Cunha, 1986; Van Lange, 2000).
1984). Many excellent reviews of this literature exist, and
theoretical integration has been achieved to a considerable Structural Factors Several studies have investigated
extent (see Kollock, 1998; Komorita & Parks, 1995, 1996; the influence of dilemma structure on cooperative versus
Weber, Kopelman, & Messick, 2004). Thus, our summary competitive behavior. For instance, cooperation increases
will be confined to those empirical insights that speak most whenever structural changes (such as direct social con-
readily to the theme of social justice. tact) foster the development of a common group iden-
tity (Gächter & Fehr, 1999; Kramer & Brewer, 1984;
Individual Differences A fruitful focus of research has Orbell, Van de Kragt, & Dawes, 1988; Wit & Kerr, 2002).
addressed individual differences in social value orientation— Although systems for monitoring and sanctioning the indi-
that is, the extent to which people are concerned with self ver- vidual’s behavior may be effective when they are firmly
sus other regarding preferences and/or outcomes (Messick in place, they tend to undermine subsequent cooperation
& McClintock, 1968; Van Lange, 2000). Individuals who once they are removed because they reduce perceptions
hold prosocial orientations are more likely to cooperate in of others’ cooperative intent (Yamagishi, 1988; see also
social dilemmas than are individuals with “proself”—or, Mulder, van Dijk, De Cremer, & Wilke, 2006; Tyler &
as Aristotle would say, “grasping”—orientations (Bogaert, Jost, 2007). When people are highly uncertain about the
Boone, & Declerck, 2008; De Cremer & Van Lange, 2001; availability of a collective resource, they expect that others
De Cremer & Van Vugt, 1999; Kollock, 1998; Kramer, will engage in greater harvesting behavior and also har-
McClintock, & Messick, 1986; Smeesters, Warlop, Van vest more resources themselves (Budescu, Rapoport, &
Avermaet, Corneille, & Yzerbyt, 2003; Weber, Kopelman, & Suleiman, 1990; Gustafsson, Biel, & Gärling, 1999; but see
Messick, 2004). Prosocial individuals are more likely than de Kwaadsteniet, van Dijk, Wit, De Cremer, & de Rooij,
others to restrict their take of scarce resources (Roch & 2007; Van Dijk, Wilke, Wilke, & Metman, 1999; Wit &
Samuelson, 1997), conserve environmental resources for Wilke, 1998).
the greater good (Van Vugt, Meertens, & Van Lange, 1995), One common response to social dilemma situations is to
and volunteer their time to help others (McClintock & appoint a leader who is expected to oversee the distribution
Allison, 1989). They are also more likely to value equal- of resources (Hardin, 1968). Studies show that group mem-
ity of outcomes than are proselfs (Eek & Gärling, 2006). bers are, indeed, more likely to appoint a leader when they
A similar distinction has been proposed between “altruistic are aware that a valued resource is being rapidly depleted
cooperators,” who seem to be more interested in positive (Messick et al., 1983) and when the use of resources is
1140 Social Justice

otherwise difficult to oversee (Samuelson, 1991). Group appraisals are determined at least as much, if not more, by
identification, as usual, plays an important role in determin- the perceived fairness of procedural versus distributive fac-
ing the behavior of leaders and followers (Tajfel & Turner, tors (e.g., Tyler & Smith, 1998). The pioneers of this research
1986). Those who identify strongly (vs. weakly) with their tradition, Thibaut and Walker (1975), were primarily inter-
group are more likely to support the democratic election of ested in third-party decision making, such as legal decisions
a leader (Van Vugt & De Cremer, 1999) and to be inspired made by judges or juries (see also Leventhal, 1980). This
by committed, fair leaders to increase their level of coopera- work demonstrated that the perceived fairness of the specific
tion (De Cremer & Van Vugt, 2002). However, leaders may procedures used to render a verdict or decision influences
develop a sense of elevated entitlement, abandon norms of people’s evaluations of both the final outcome and the deci-
equality, and reserve an overabundance of resources for sion maker. Researchers have not looked back since; there
themselves—especially when they have been appointed has been far more research on aspects of procedural justice
rather than elected (De Cremer & Van Dijk, 2005). On the than on aspects of other types (including distributive jus-
other hand, charismatic leaders can be effective at inducing tice) over the past quarter of a century.
even “proselfs” to cooperate (De Cremer, 2002), whereas
“Voice” and Other Procedural Justice Criteria
autocratic leaders increase the likelihood that members will
abandon the group when faced with a conflict between per- According to Walker, Lind, and Thibaut (1979), “the belief
sonal and group interests (Van Vugt, Jepson, Hart, & De that the techniques used to resolve a dispute are fair and
Cremer, 2004). These and other findings attest to the endur- satisfying in themselves” (p. 1402) follows from two major
ing significance of Lewin’s distinction between democratic procedural features: “(a) process control, referring to how
versus autocratic leadership—and Deutsch’s extrapolation much people are allowed to present evidence on their behalf
to cooperative versus competitive social systems—for ana- before the decision is made, and (b) decision control; that
lyzing justice-related procedures and outcomes. is, whether individuals have any say in the actual rendering
The choice of whether to cooperate or not when con- of the decision” (Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996, p. 189; see
fronted with a social dilemma depends to a great extent on also Ambrose & Arnaud, 2005). That is, people want to
how the situation is “framed” (or construed). Does it call for know that they will have input into (and are therefore able
cooperation and the privileging of collective (or communal) to exert at least some influence over) the decision-making
interests? Or does it offer a chance to maximize one’s own process as well as the decision itself. Thibaut and Walker
outcomes? Subtle manipulations can influence the extent to (1975) proposed that when people possess these two types
which the same social dilemma situation is seen through one of perceived control they are able to trust that procedures
or the other of these frames. Specifically, the use of differ- will be fair and that their short-term and especially long-
ent labels (Batson & Moran, 1999; Liberman, Samuels, & term outcomes will be favorable in general (but see Azzi &
Ross, 2004) or metaphors (Allison, Beggan, & Midgley, Jost, 1997 for an application to majority–minority inter-
1999) within the context of the same dilemma affects coop- group relations).
eration rates. Furthermore, the priming of specific mindsets Research has been supportive of the notion that process
(Elliott, Hayward, & Canon, 1998) and even incidental control (i.e., the chance to present one’s own “side” to a
exposure to objects that symbolize competitiveness ver- third-party decision maker) is a fundamental determinant
sus cooperativeness (Kay, Wheeler, Bargh, & Ross, 2004) of justice appraisals (e.g., Houlden, LaTour, Walker, &
can lead people to construe the same dilemma situation in Thibaut, 1978; Thibaut & Walker, 1975; cf. Shapiro & Brett,
drastically different terms and, therefore, to behave in more 2005). Thibaut and Walker’s pioneering work has influenced
or less prosocial ways (Kay & Ross, 2003; Tenbrunsel & myriad research programs, including research on the so-
Messick, 1999; Weber, Kopelman, & Messick, 2004). called “voice effect;” that is, the demonstration that the
opportunity to express one’s views or feelings during
the course of the decision-making process significantly
Procedural Justice
increases perceptions of procedural fairness (Folger, 1977;
Although the terms “social justice” and “distributive justice” Lind & Tyler, 1988; Van den Bos, 2005). Studies show
are often used interchangeably by philosophers and layper- that the presence of voice affects not only justice judg-
sons (e.g., Miller, 1999), social scientists in recent decades ments but is also associated with increased positive affect,
have come to recognize that justice considerations pertain not decreased negative affect, and greater trust in authorities
merely to the allocation of resources but also to the methods (e.g., Brockner et al., 1998; Folger, Rosenfeld, Grove, &
or procedures by which decisions are made at work, in politi- Corkran, 1979; Lind, Kanfer, & Earley, 1990; Lind & Tyler,
cal life, in the family, etc. A major thrust of contemporary 1988; Shapiro & Brett, 2005; Tyler & Blader, 2003; Tyler,
social psychological research has demonstrated that justice Rasinki, & Spodick, 1985; Van den Bos, Wilke, & Lind,
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1141

1998; Van Prooijen, Karremans, & van Beest, 2006; Van 274–277; see also Greenberg, 1993; Sweeney & McFarlin,
Prooijen, Van den Bos, & Wilke, 2004). 1993). At the same time, different theoretical models of
At the same time, voice is by no means the only vari- procedural justice emphasize distinctive (and sometimes
able that influences perceptions of procedural justice. competing) underlying causes of procedural justice effects
Leventhal, Karuza, and Fry (1980) identified six factors (e.g., Cropanzano & Folger, 1989; Lind & Tyler, 1988;
that can contribute to justice appraisals. To be considered Thibaut & Walker, 1975; Tyler & Lind, 1992; Van den Bos &
fair, they argued, decisions must be made (a) consistently Lind, 2002). The question is why people care as much as
across instances and time periods; (b) neutrally, that is, they do about the procedures that are used to determine
without bias, preconceptions, or self-interest; (c) on the their outcomes and not just about the favorability of the
basis of accurate information; (d) with an opportunity to outcomes themselves.
make corrections if necessary; (e) in consideration of the
interests of all relevant parties; and (f) ethically. Leventhal Instrumental Models Thibaut and Walker (1975) initially
(1980) pointed out that, depending upon the specific cir- proposed that people seek control (or voice) over both the
cumstances, some of these “rules” may be weighted more process and decision because they want to ensure that
heavily than others. Consistent with this view, situational the ultimate outcome will be fair and favorable (see also
differences (e.g., variability in the formality of a given Walker, Lind, & Thibaut, 1979).3 The benefits of procedural
decision-making setting) affect the criteria that people fairness, in other words, were assumed to be tangible and
use in making judgments of procedural fairness (Barrett- instrumental. Given the fact that people often exhibit naïve
Howard & Tyler, 1986). Nevertheless, aggregating across realism by seeing their own “side” in a dispute as more cor-
a wide range of situations, people tend to prioritize three of rect and reasonable in comparison with that of their adver-
these criteria—consistency, accuracy, and ethicality—in saries (Ross & Ward, 1996), it is possible to view the desire
determining whether procedural justice requirements have for fair procedures as a subtle expression of self-interest
been satisfied (Barrett-Howard & Tyler, 1986; Lind & motivation (Folger et al., 1979; Shapiro & Brett, 2005;
Tyler, 1988). Tyler, 1994; Van Proojien et al., 2008). However, this inter-
Skitka (2002; Skitka & Houston, 2001; Skitka & Mullen, pretation was not the one favored by Thibaut and Walker.
2002) has argued that procedural justice concerns are sus- As Van den Bos (2005) noted, “An important aspect of the
pended when people perceive “moral mandates”; that is, Thibaut and Walker (1975) model was the focus on whether
when they feel especially strongly about a specific issue people received fair outcomes and not so much on how
or outcome, such as whether or not abortion is legally pro- favorable outcomes were to people . . . It is therefore more
tected. Moral mandates, as defined by Skitka and her col- appropriate to label these authors’ theory as the ‘instrumen-
leagues, are to be distinguished from strongly held attitudes tal model,’ and . . . it is wrong to call this the ‘self-interest
(Skitka, Bauman, & Sargis, 2005) and are associated with model’ ” (p. 284).
anger directed at those who are seen as violating them
(Mullen & Skitka, 2006). On the basis of her research, Skitka Relational Models A clear alternative to instrumen-
(2002) concluded that “when people have a moral mandate tal explanations for why people care about procedural
about an outcome, any means justifies the mandated end” justice emerges from relational models of procedural
and “fair procedures do not ameliorate the sense of injus- justice (Tyler & Lind, 1992), such as the group-value
tice people experience when a morally mandated outcome model (Lind & Tyler, 1988). The basic idea is that peo-
is threatened or rejected” (p. 594). Napier and Tyler (2008) ple are concerned about the fairness of procedures largely
reviewed this evidence and arrived at a different conclusion, because of the implications that these procedures hold for
namely that even when people experience intense moral their feelings of self-worth, which are often derived from
conviction about a given issue (e.g., immigration, abortion, processes of social identification (Tajfel & Turner, 1986).
or civil rights), they are still more likely to accept a decision
made by authorities when they believe that procedural fair-
3
Referent cognitions theory provides yet another account of
ness norms have been observed than when they have not
procedural justice effects (Cropanzano & Folger, 1989; Folger,
(see also Gibson, 2008; Tyler & Mitchell, 1994).
1986). From this perspective, when a procedure is experienced
Why Do People Care About Procedures? as unfair, people begin to compare what actually happened to
what “could” have happened. To the extent that other referents
There is little question that procedural characteristics affect are available, that is, if people can easily imagine an alternative
overall perceptions of fairness and satisfaction and also procedure, negative reactions (including perceptions of injustice)
exert downstream effects on an extremely wide range of are more likely to ensue (see also Van den Bos, Lind, Vermunt, &
social and organizational variables (Van den Bos, 2005, pp. Wilke, 1997).
1142 Social Justice

As Tyler (1994) explains, “The basic assumption of the information (Skitka, 2002; Van den Bos, Wilke, Lind, &
relational model is that people are predisposed to belong Vermunt, 1998).4 Even abstract experimental manipulations
to social groups and that they are attentive to signs and of general self-uncertainty (having nothing to do with ques-
symbols that communicate information about their posi- tions of fairness) are capable of increasing participants’ atten-
tion within groups” (p. 851). The quality of procedures, it tion to the procedural aspects of a given situation (see Van
is argued, reflects the extent to which people are valued, den Bos, 2001; Van den Bos, Wilke, & Lind, 1998; see also
respected, and understood by decision-making authorities. Diekmann, Barsness & Sondak, 2004, for an organizational
The notion that individuals would be strongly motivated to field study).
obtain information about social standing is consistent not
only with social identity theory but also with models of
Interactional (or Informal) Justice
social belongingness, reputation, and shared reality (e.g.,
Baumeister & Leary, 1995; Hardin & Higgins, 1996). The philosopher Frankena (1962) observed that “society
Relational models of procedural justice can help to explain does not consist merely of the law or the state: it has also a
“voice” effects, insofar as the opportunity to express one’s more informal aspect, comprised of its cultural institutions,
own point of view allows individuals to express their values conventions, moral rules, and moral sanctions.” Thus, he
to fellow group members and authorities (Lind, Kanfer, & argued, “In order for society to be fully just, it must be just
Earley, 1990; Tyler, 1987). Such models also bring to the in its informal as well as in its formal aspect” (p. 2). If this
fore other benefits of procedural arrangements, including is correct, then it is possible to speak of social injustice
the communication and building up of trust, standing, and as arising not merely as a consequence of unfair treatment
social status (Tyler, 1989; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, & proffered by institutionally sanctioned authority figures,
Wilke, 2002). People do infer from procedural treatment the such as politicians, judges, police officers, bosses, teach-
extent to which authorities accord them with trust, standing, ers, and so on, but also on the basis of how citizens tend to
respect, and value, and consider them to be worthy group treat one another. It is in this sense that prejudice, discrimi-
members (e.g., Heuer, Blumenthal, Douglas, & Weinblatt, nation, and authoritarianism on the part of ordinary citizens
1999; Huo, 2002; Smith, Tyler, Huo, Ortiz, & Lind, 1998; can contribute to a social climate that is undemocratic and
Tyler, 1994; Tyler, Degoey, & Smith, 1996). To put the fundamentally unjust, as Lewin (1939/1948a) noted with
same point more negatively and, consequently, more dra- regard to fascist society. Several models of interpersonal
matically, to treat someone unjustly is to deny them the ben- justice have been put forth by social and organizational
efits and trappings of social belongingness (see Baumeister psychologists over the years; few of them deal explicitly
& Leary, 1995). with behavior or circumstances that are as extreme as those
associated with fascism, but the models clearly do involve
Epistemic Models Social comparison processes are a broader conception of social justice than is suggested by
fundamental to prominent models of distributive justice, more formal models of distributive or procedural justice.
including theories of relative deprivation (Crosby, 1976),
equity (Walster, Walster, & Berscheid, 1978), equality and Fairness of Interpersonal Treatment
need (Deutsch, 1975), and perceived entitlement (Major, Tyler and Lind (1992; Tyler, 1989) deserve credit for high-
1994). That is, people often decide whether they have been lighting a number of ways in which aspects of social inter-
treated fairly by comparing their own situation to that of action affect perceptions of procedural justice (see also
relevant others (or, in the case of equity theory, comparing Leventhal, 1980; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). This idea was
their own ratio of inputs to outputs to the ratios of oth- taken further by Bies and colleagues (Bies & Moag, 1986;
ers). In the real world, however, many people are largely
ignorant about the sizes of their colleagues’ salaries, their
neighbors’ inheritances, and their friends’ tax breaks; thus,
4
it is often difficult to make direct social comparisons, Brockner & Wiesenfeld (1996) have also noted that perceptions
of procedural and distributive justice frequently interact with one
and many justice appraisals are made under conditions of
another, such that “when outcomes are unfair or have a negative
uncertainty.
valence, procedural justice is more likely to have a direct effect
It has been suggested that people often rely on procedures
on individuals’ reactions”; “when procedural justice is relatively
as heuristic substitutes for social comparison information low, outcome favorability is more apt to be positively correlated
(Van den Bos & Lind, 2002; Van den Bos, Lind, Vermunt, & with individuals’ reactions”; and “the combination of low pro-
Wilke, 1997). In the absence of unambiguous information cedural fairness and low outcome favorability engenders par-
with which to draw conclusions about distributive justice, ticularly negative reactions” (p. 191; regarding implications for
for example, people are compelled to rely on procedural self-evaluation, see also Brockner, Heuer, & Magner, 2003).
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1143

Folger & Bies, 1989; Tyler & Bies, 1990), who distinguished point of view the study of social justice is too important to
between “structural” and “interactional” components of be mired in semantic or taxonomic disputes for long. There
decision-making procedures. In stressing the importance may well be circumstances in which it is useful to distin-
of the latter, Bies and Moag (1986) noted that people are guish between cases involving procedural (or formal) and
sensitive not merely to the structure or content of a given interactional (or informal) justice, but little is gained by
procedure, but also to the “quality of interpersonal treat- exaggerating or reifying such divisions. It seems reason-
ment they receive during the enactment of organizational able enough to assume that procedural justice and interac-
procedures” (p. 44; see also Colquitt, Greenberg, & Zapata- tional justice constitute two important aspects of “fairness
Phelan, 2005). In other words, people do not just want fair of treatment” (Van den Bos, 2005).
procedures at work and elsewhere; they also want fair treat- Probably the most compelling empirical case for sepa-
ment in a much broader sense. rating the constructs comes from a series of studies sug-
What constitutes fair interpersonal treatment? Bies gesting that people spontaneously distinguish between
and Moag (1986) initially focused on four aspects of structural and interactional aspects of procedures (see
social interaction: respect, truthfulness, justification (i.e., Bies, 2001). However, mapping this difference onto the con-
the provision of timely, adequate explanations for deci- cepts of procedural and interactional justice requires one to
sions), and propriety (i.e., sensitivity, appropriateness, and define procedural justice solely in terms of formal, struc-
the avoidance of prejudicial treatment). The data speak tural aspects of procedures (Bobocel & Holmvall, 2001). In
favorably with respect to the predictive validity of each point of fact, the most influential research and theorizing on
of these four facets of interactional justice (e.g., Colquitt, procedural justice does not treat procedural justice in such
2001; Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & Ng, 2001). This limited terms; rather, it views interpersonal treatment as a key
has only encouraged researchers to continue nominating determinant of perceptions of procedural justice (Folger &
additional candidates, such as dignity, the provision of Bies, 1989; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Tyler & Bies, 1990;
feedback, and consideration of employees’ (and other con- Tyler & Blader, 2000; Tyler & Lind, 1992). For example,
stituents’) views (Folger & Bies, 1989; Greenberg, Bies, & relational models of procedural justice (e.g., group-value
Eskew, 1991; Tyler & Bies, 1990). Some authors have and group engagement models) stress that both formal
suggested that interactional justice is comprised of two structures and mechanisms and the manner in which these
separate constructs, namely informational justice, which are implemented (i.e., fairness of treatment) are important
emphasizes communicative aspects, such as truthfulness for the same social psychological reasons: they signal one’s
and justification, and interpersonal justice, which guar- degree of social acceptance, group inclusion, status, and
antees sensitive, respectful, and appropriate treatment. worth (Tyler & Blader, 2003).
(See Bies, 2005; Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993). The notion that procedural and interactional justice are
partially overlapping constructs also emerges from the
Relationship Between Procedural and research literature on themes of insult and disrespect, inso-
Interactional Justice far as these refer to both qualities of treatment and social
More than 20 years of research (most of which comes from outcomes in themselves (see Miller, 2001, for a review).
the field of organizational behavior) confirms that percep- People tend to experience a wide range of violations,
tions of interactional justice help to explain how employ- including structural forms of injustice, poor interpersonal
ees and others respond to decisions made by authority treatment, and receipt of inequitable outcomes, as upset-
figures (Bies, 2005; Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & ting at least in part because they convey some measure of
Ng., 2001; Colquitt, Greenberg, & Zapata-Phelan, 2005). disrespect. Additional facts—such as the observation that
Everyone agrees that—in addition to or in conjunction people respond more harshly to perceived injustices when
with formal mechanisms, such as rules and policies— they are committed publicly rather than privately and that
informal aspects of social interaction matter a great deal apologies can be quite effective at alleviating the sense
when people are asked to evaluate the fairness of proce- of injustice—are supportive of the notion that feelings of
dures and outcomes. Nevertheless, scholars disagree con- injustice and disrespect are intertwined (Miller, 2001).
siderably about whether interactional justice concerns At the same time, there is some evidence indicating that
should fall under the rubric of procedural justice or be people sometimes react differently to procedural versus
considered an entirely independent type of justice con- interactional violations. Perceptions of procedural justice
cern (see Bies, 2001, 2005; Bobocel & Holmvall, 2001; predict reactions to and evaluations of the system (e.g.,
Colquitt, Greenberg, & Zapata-Phelan, 2005; Greenberg, one’s organization), whereas perceptions of interactional
1993; Tyler & Blader, 2003). A fair amount of ink has been justice predict reactions to and evaluations of representa-
spilled in an effort to resolve this question, but from our tives of the system (e.g., supervisors) who communicate the
1144 Social Justice

decisions (Ambrose, Seabright, & Schminke, 2002; Aryee, schemes are typically seen as reasonable and legitimate by
Budhwar, & Chen, 2002; Colquitt, 2001; Fuller & Hester, the public at large—indeed, they are seen as cornerstones
2001). These results are easily interpretable from the of the “justice system.” But how, specifically, are these
standpoint of social exchange theories (e.g., Cropanzano, systems of punishment justified or, more precisely, “jus-
Prehar, & Chen, 2002; Masterson, Lewis, Goldman, & ticized?” Questions such as these have been investigated
Taylor, 2000). To the extent that people view rules and pro- most directly by scholars focused on the study of retributive
cedures as under the control of the system, the perceived justice concerns, namely the question of “how people who
fairness of formal procedures should affect the “relation- have intentionally committed known, morally wrong actions
ship” that people develop with the system. Likewise, to the that either directly or indirectly harm others, should be pun-
extent that people view the quality of interpersonal treat- ished for their misdeeds” (Carlsmith & Darley, 2008).
ment they receive as under the control of the person (or
persons) with whom they are interacting, the perceived Is Vengeance Ours?
fairness of treatment should affect the relationships that
Two broad kinds of justifications for punishment have
people develop with those specific actors.
been offered, both of which originate in the seminal work
Finally, meta-analytic evidence reveals that procedural
of moral philosophers. Bentham (1962/1843) argued that
and interactional justice concerns are indeed correlated and
punishment, to be justified, must serve some utilitarian pur-
partially overlapping, but they do predict somewhat differ-
pose; that is, it must benefit society overall—making social
ent behavioral responses (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001;
life better or happier in some important way (cf. Greene &
Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & Ng, 2001). Informational
Cohen, 2004). How might punishment benefit society? It is
and interpersonal justice concerns also predict somewhat
certainly possible that the threat and/or execution of pun-
different behavioral outcomes (Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg,
ishment serves to prevent or reduce the number of poten-
1993; Kernan & Hanges, 2001). However, to justify con-
tial acts of injustice. Whether through specific deterrence
ceptualizing procedural and interactional justice perceptions
(which aims to punish an offender sufficiently to deter him
as fundamentally different phenomena, one would want to
or her from committing similar offenses in the future), inca-
show that structural and interpersonal aspects of procedures
pacitation (in which an offender is temporarily or even per-
exert their influence on justice-related judgments and behav-
manently prevented from committing additional offenses
iors through different psychological mechanisms (Bobocel &
through incarceration or some other method), or general
Holmvall, 2001; Miller, 2001). Apparently, this has yet to be
deterrence (in which certain individuals are punished so as
demonstrated. But, rather than seeking to neatly compart-
to deter others from committing similar offenses), a utilitar-
mentalize different areas of social justice research, a better
ian approach emphasizes the potential benefits punishment
strategy for conveying the theoretical and practical signifi-
can have for society as a whole.
cance of interactional justice might be to broaden the range
Kant (1790/1952) offered a different justification for
of phenomena to be understood and explained. For example,
punishment. He argued that punishment was fair insofar
experimental and other studies of hostility, aggression, stig-
as people deserve to be punished for immoral behavior;
matization, harassment, social exclusion, and inappropriate
punishment “balances the scales,” so to speak. From a just-
humor are not necessarily considered part of the social jus-
deserts perspective such as this, the worse the perpetrator’s
tice canon, but this work should be incorporated, insofar as it
actions, the harsher the punishment that is required to
speaks directly to the ways in which individuals are or are not
restore justice. As Kant said, punishment “should be pro-
treated with dignity and respect in their daily lives and why
nounced over all criminals in proportion to their wicked-
(e.g., Bargh, Raymond, Pryor, & Strack, 1995; Ford, Boxer,
ness” (as cited in Carlsmith, Darley, & Robinson, 2002,
Armstrong, & Edel, 2008; Gelfand, Fitzgerald, & Drasgow,
p. 397). Although there are clear parallels here to equity
1995; Kurzban & Leary, 2001; Link & Phelan, 2001;
theory and other work on distributive justice, Carlsmith and
Maass, Cadinu, Guarnieri, & Grasselli, 2003; Rudman &
Darley (2008) distinguish between concepts of distributive
Ashmore, 2007; Struch & Schwartz, 1989; Watson,
and retributive justice as follows:
Ottati, & Corrigan, 2003).
[D]istributive justice theories tend to assume positive outcomes
Retributive Justice and are concerned with whether those positive outcomes should
be shared out equally, equitably . . . or on the basis of needs.
Following acts of clear injustice, individuals, groups, and In keeping with the standard conventions in this area, we will
societies often enact some form of punishment. When appre- reserve the term “distributive justice” to discuss reward alloca-
hended and found guilty, perpetrators are jailed, fined, or in tions, and use “retributive justice” to refer to punishments that
some way reprimanded for their actions. Such punishment people deserve for their wrongdoing. (p. 195)
A Typology of Social Justice Concerns 1145

Increasingly, researchers have sought to flesh out the social that the nation’s military has been practicing torture for 40
psychological underpinnings of support for policies that years (Crandall, Eidelman, Skitka, & Morgan, 2009).
involve punishment. Generally, the aim is not to understand Studies such as these raise the important possibility that
the best or most rational reasons to support policies of pun- people may be actually motivated (consciously or uncon-
ishment (the normative question), but to discover why peo- sciously) to support highly aggressive forms of retribu-
ple support such policies, regardless of the objective quality tion (such as torture and capital punishment) by one set of
of the reasons for their support (the descriptive question). justice-related reasons (e.g., intuitions about fairness and
For instance, researchers have pitted utilitarian, deterrence- deservingness) or even nonjustice-related reasons, such as
related concerns against Kantian notions of just-deserts to authoritarianism, social dominance, or racial prejudice (e.g.,
determine which is the stronger motivation of support for Dambrun, 2007; Ho, ForsterLee, ForsterLee, & Crofts, 2002;
strict punishment (Carlsmith, 2006; Carlsmith, Darley, & Johnson, Whitestone, Jackson, & Gatto, 1995; McKee &
Robinson, 2002; Darley, Carlsmith, & Robinson, 2000). Feather, 2008; Rossi & Berk, 1997; Sidanius, Mitchell,
One firm conclusion emerges from these studies: People Haley, & Navarrete, 2006) and yet offer a different set of
are far more attuned to the severity of a crime and its moral justice-related reasons (e.g., utilitarianism, deterrence) as
significance when assigning punishment than they are to post hoc justifications or rationalizations for taking or sup-
information pertaining to the likelihood of either general porting punitive action. Such a possibility is broadly consis-
or specific deterrence (Carlsmith & Darley, 2008; Darley tent with the notion that moral judgment is often the result
& Pittman, 2003; Kahneman, Schkade, & Sunstein, 1998; of automatic, intuitive judgments, rather than deliberative
McFatter, 1982). reasoning (Darley & Pittman, 2003; Haidt, 2001).
More specifically, the desire for retribution is motivated A far more optimistic image of retributive justice motives
by the perceived immorality of unjust behavior and the comes from theoretical models that emphasize the desire to
moral outrage that accompanies such perceptions. Studies affirm group or community values or standards (Tyler &
show that people actively search for information related to Boeckman, 1997; Vidmar, 2002). The guiding idea is that
morality when assigning punishment, that moral culpability unjust actions threaten the assumption that social consensus
and seriousness influence the harshness of recommended exists with regard to justice and morality and that meting
punishment, and that moral outrage mediates the relation- out punishment can be an effective way of affirming shared
ship between the severity of an offense and recommended values (Wenzel & Thielman, 2006). From this perspective,
punishments (Carlsmith, 2006; Carlsmith, Darley, & punishment serves to communicate the group’s values and
Robinson, 2002; Darley, Carlsmith, & Robinson, 2000). may therefore repair feelings of social identification—
Cultural and religious norms affect specific attitudes about feelings that can be damaged when group members are
retributive and other forms of justice (Cohen & Rozin, confronted with an explicit challenge to their values
2001; Henrich et al., 2001), but the desire to punish those (Vidmar, 2000). However, if one’s primary goal in assign-
who commit serious transgressions seems fairly universal. ing punishment is to reaffirm social values and the consen-
A fascinating contrast exists between the objective deter- sus of group norms, restorative justice—which involves
minants of punishment attitudes, which are largely Kantian, coming up with prosocial alternatives to traditional forms
and the subjective reasons that people give in explaining of punishment—is probably a better option.
their support for punishment, which lean toward utilitari-
anism (e.g., Ellsworth & Ross, 1983). Such a divergence Restorative Justice
has been observed, for example, in the dramatic context
of debates over the use of torture in U.S. military prisons The concept of restorative justice represents an alternative
abroad. Although people who endorse torture generally to traditional ways of thinking about crime and punishment
say that their opinion is driven by their conviction that it (Bazemore, 1998; Braithwaite, 1989; Roberts & Stalans,
successfully prevents future harm, experimental evidence 2004). More than any other approach discussed in this
reveals that support for harsh interrogation tactics is pre- chapter (and perhaps even the entire Handbook), notions
dicted by the perceived moral status of the target, and not about restorative justice have developed out of professional
by information concerning the likely effectiveness of the practice rather than academic circles. As a result, restor-
interrogation process (Carlsmith, 2008; Carlsmith & Sood, ative justice procedures have unfolded in realistic settings
2009; Janoff-Bulman, 2007). The motivation to justify the in fascinating ways, but there has been tremendous vari-
social system also plays a role in popular support for tor- ety and, therefore, imprecision concerning the definition
ture, insofar as citizens deem torture to be more accept- of restorative justice practices. Although the goals of most
able and justifiable to the extent that it is seen as part of restorative justice programs appear to be similar, the meth-
the societal status quo; that is, when they are told (falsely) ods for achieving them differ considerably. Roche (2006)
1146 Social Justice

offered the following description: “One way to think of was not devoted to the issue until roughly a decade later.
restorative justice is simply as a particular method for deal- Braithwaite (1989) was instrumental in drawing attention
ing with crime that brings together an offender, his or her to the phenomenon of “reintegrative shaming”—a form of
victims, and their respective families and friends to discuss shaming behavior in which the community condemns the
the aftermath of an incident, and the steps that can be taken transgression but not the transgressor, seeks to treat all of
to repair the harm an offender has done” (p. 217). Thus, the parties with dignity and respect, and attempts to bro-
rather than relying on a third party to impose a unilateral ker a situation of forgiveness. Although it is not synony-
punishment upon a particular offender, restorative justice mous with restorative justice, reintegrative shaming theory
programs give the justice process “back to their rightful (RST) was the first academic attempt to explain how and
owners: offenders, victims, and their respective communi- why restorative justice programs can succeed. Harris
ties” (Wenzel, Okimoto, Feather, & Platow, 2008, p. 376). (2006) observed that “one of the most distinctive fea-
In restorative justice sentencing, the various parties are tures of RST is its focus on the social process of shaming
encouraged to express their feelings, come to an agreement as the crucial mechanism in crime control” (p. 330). The
about the harm that has occurred, and decide together what generation of shame-related emotions is thought to dis-
actions should be taken to reestablish a sense of justice. courage future offenses by introducing a powerful signal
The aim of such programs is to promote healing and jus- as to what is considered wrong and motivating the offender
tice through open discussion, consensus, and forgiveness. to preserve his or her (presumably valued) relation-
Rather than simply meting out punishment—punishment ships with the “shamer” (Braithwaite, 1989; Braithwaite
can be part of restorative justice outcomes, but it is not & Braithwaite, 2001). By focusing on the shameful act
usually considered to be necessary—the agreed upon rather than the individual who committed it, reintegra-
actions often involve the offender participating in events or tive shaming is thought to foster reintegration rather than
activities that are directly related to the restoration of jus- stigmatization, which frequently results from traditional
tice (e.g., participation in community service, etc.). When legal proceedings. Research on specific social psychological
applied appropriately, this procedure is thought to help mechanisms triggered by restorative justice sanctions is
the victim and the broader community feel that justice has scarce, and the available data indicate considerable nuance
been restored and to reintegrate the perpetrator into com- and complexity concerning the emotion of shame and
munity life so that he or she will be more likely to respect the important task of shame management. Nevertheless, there
its norms in the future. A well-known example concerns is empirical support for the notion that shame-based emo-
the “truth and reconciliation” commission established in tions are evoked by restorative justice procedures (Ahmed &
South Africa, following the abolition of the apartheid sys- Braithwaite, 2006; Harris, 2006; Murphy & Harris, 2007;
tem (Gibson, 2004). for conflicting views on shame and guilt, see Leith &
Research provides modest support for the general effec- Baumeister, 1998; Tangney, 1995).
tiveness of restorative justice programs. It has been associ- Other research programs emphasize different social
ated, for example, with decreased recidivism in groups of psychological mechanisms. Wenzel and colleagues (2008),
juveniles, bullies, and white-collar criminals (Ahmed & for example, stressed the role of social identification needs
Braithwaite, 2006; Harris, 2006; Latimer, Dowden, & Muise, in driving the restorative justice process. When victims (and
2005; Murphy & Harris, 2007; Rodriguez, 2007). These other observers) view themselves as sharing a common
data should be interpreted with caution, however, because group identity with the offender, restorative justice is often
self-selection biases and measurement problems limit the preferred, presumably because it seeks to reestablish values
kinds of causal inferences that can be drawn. Furthermore, and preserve a sense of community. When the offender is
the effectiveness of restorative justice programs is likely to viewed as an outgroup member, however, more traditional
depend upon a number of contextual variables, including forms of punishment are seen as appropriate, insofar as they
offense type (Braithwaite & Mugford, 1994). But, evidence restore the balance between the status of the offender and
from quasi-experimental paradigms in which a range of the victim or community (Wenzel & Thielmann, 2006).
beneficial effects of restorative justice programs has been Drawing on the work of Kurt Lewin, Tyler (2007) observed
demonstrated across a range of contexts and offenses is espe- that restorative justice, like procedural justice, has the poten-
cially impressive (Strang et al., 2006; Wallace, Exline, & tial to encourage individuals to rely upon intrinsic motivation
Baumeister, 2008). rather than external pressures in regulating their behavior.
From a social psychological perspective, the crucial Following a transgression, both victims and perpetrators
question is not simply whether such programs are effective develop social psychological needs (pertaining to status
but why. Although the earliest restorative justice programs and belongingness, respectively) that need to be addressed
originated in the late 1970s, serious intellectual attention (Shnabel & Nadler, 2008). The opportunity for social
Obstacles to Attaining Social Justice 1147

exchange, in which victim and perpetrator can satisfy each threat not merely to social justice but to democracy itself (see
other’s needs, may be a particularly effective way to help also Reich, 1946/1970). Specifically, they proposed that eco-
both parties. Despite the potential benefits of restorative nomic frustration and harsh childrearing tactics, among other
sentencing procedures, public opinion polls reveal that atti- dynamics, lead certain individuals (including a majority of
tudinal support for restorative justice programs decreases individuals in some circumstances, such as Nazi Germany)
significantly as the severity of the crime increases (Roberts & to develop fascist (or proto-fascist) tendencies. The result
Stalans, 2004). For crimes that are particularly severe, was a population containing a disproportionate share of citi-
experimental research suggests that combining retribu- zens gravitating toward rigid, stereotypical ways of thinking
tive and restorative justice procedures may best satisfy the and extreme forms of prejudice and intolerance toward oth-
desire for justice (Gromet & Darley, 2006). ers, especially those who are considered deviants or conve-
One final question can be raised about the overarch- nient scapegoats. Subsequent research has shown that highly
ing goals of restorative measures and whether they always threatening circumstances elicit increased authoritarianism,
serve the broader cause of social justice. Capehart and especially in individuals who are prone to such responses
Milovanovic (2007) put it this way: (e.g., Bonanno & Jost, 2006; Brown, 1965; Davis & Silver,
2004; Doty, Peterson, & Winter, 1991; Feldman, 2003; Jost,
The glaring question is “Restore to what?” If, for example, Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway, 2003; Lavine, Lodge, &
structures and a particular form of community organizations Freitas, 2005; Napier & Jost, 2008b; Stenner, 2005).
reduce or repress the search for self-development and actu- Altemeyer (1981) updated the “classic” theory of authori-
alization, then, the transformative theorists argue, simply to tarianism to emphasize three major characteristics of the
restore relations to this previous state is by itself contributing disposition: (1) “a high degree of submission to the authori-
to the sustaining of reductive or repressive practices (p. 61;
ties who are perceived to be established and legitimate”; (2)
emphasis added).
“a general aggressiveness, directed against various persons,
The problem highlighted here is by no means limited to the which is perceived to be sanctioned by established authori-
study of restorative justice; it should serve as a reminder ties”; and (3) “a high degree of adherence to the social con-
always to consider the “forest” as well as the “trees,” ventions which are perceived to be endorsed by society”
that is, the overall extent to which the social system that (1981, p. 148). Scores on the Right-Wing Authoritarianism
is being created or reinforced by the implementation of (RWA) scale predict a wide range of attitudes and behaviors,
specific principles or mechanisms (allegedly in the name including racial prejudice; sexism; homophobia; victim-
of distributive, procedural, interactional, retributive, or blaming; punishment of deviants; severity of jury sentenc-
restorative justice concerns) actually is worth reinforcing ing decisions; lack of support for civil liberties and freedoms;
(see also Tyler & Jost, 2007). and approval of illegal governmental activities, such as wire-
tapping, unconstitutional drug raids, and political harassment
and intimidation (e.g., see Altemeyer, 1981, 1996, 1998).
OBSTACLES TO ATTAINING Social Dominance Orientation (SDO) gauges individual
SOCIAL JUSTICE differences in “general support for the domination of certain
socially constructed groups over other socially constructed
There are numerous potential obstacles to the attainment groups,” whether on the basis of “race, sex, religion, social
of social justice, including both selfishness and laziness. class, region, skin color, clan, caste, lineage, tribe, mini-
There is also the tendency to dehumanize one’s enemies mal groups, or any other group distinction that the human
or to otherwise exclude them from the “scope of justice,” mind is capable of creating” (Sidanius & Pratto, 1999).
so that common standards of decency, fairness, and moral- Support for social dominance is comprised of two sub-
ity simply are not applied to certain groups or individuals factors: the desire for ingroup superiority and generalized
(e.g., Clayton & Opotow, 2003; Deutsch, 1985; Hafer & opposition to equality (e.g., Eagly, Diekman, Johannesen-
Olson, 2003; Opotow, 1995). In this section we focus on Schmidt, & Koenig, 2004; Foels & Pappas, 2004; Freeman,
the ways in which authoritarianism, social dominance, and Aquino, & McFerran, 2009; Jost & Thompson, 2000).
system justification tendencies can threaten to undermine Altemeyer (1998) estimated that, when combined in a
the cause of social justice. statistical model, respondents’ scores on RWA and SDO
scales account for more than half of the observable varia-
Authoritarianism and Social Dominance tion in prejudice and ethnocentrism. Guimond, Dambrun,
Michinov, and Duarte (2003) found that SDO mediates the
Adorno, Frenkel-Brunswik, Levinson, and Sanford (1950) effect of social position (i.e., belonging to a high status and/
identified a personality syndrome that they regarded as a or powerful group) on prejudice.
1148 Social Justice

Perhaps the most succinct and compelling explanation Greece had ever raised moral objections about slavery;
for why social dominance poses an inherent threat to the several philosophers of Aristotle’s era had criticized the
attainment of social justice comes from Walzer (1983), practice, but Aristotle apparently rejected those criticisms
who observed that: (Kraut, 2002, pp. 277–8). How could such a brilliant ethi-
cal mind possibly find itself arguing that such a brutal,
The critique of dominance and domination points toward an exploitative institution as slavery was not only necessary
open-ended distributive principle. No social good x should be but also just? The answer, it seems, has to do with sys-
distributed to men and women who possess some other good y tem justification, defined as the conscious or unconscious
merely because they possess y and without regard to the mean- motivation to defend, bolster, and justify existing social,
ing of x. This is a principle that has probably been reiterated, at economic, and political institutions and arrangements
one time or another, for every y that has ever been dominant.
(Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004). Kraut (2002) writes:
But it has not often been stated in general terms. (p. 20)

In other words, it is unjust for individuals to disproportion- No doubt, Aristotle believed that slavery was justified in part
ately receive benefits or burdens simply because of some because that was a convenient tenet for him to hold. Had he
other (arbitrary, irrelevant) characteristic that they possess, come to the opposite conclusion, he would have been forced
such as belonging to a dominant or subordinated group. This to announce to the Greek world that its political institutions,
which he greatly valued (however much he also criticized
is because, among other things, it violates basic notions of
them), rested on resources that could not be justly acquired or
deservingness, including the merit (or contribution) prin-
used. The all too human tendency to avoid upheavals of thought
ciple, as well as what Mansbridge (2005) referred to the and revolutions in social practice certainly played a role here.
“logic of formal justice”—the prescription to “Treat every- But . . . in order for Aristotle to have arrived at the sincere con-
one equally unless you can give relevant reasons for unequal viction that slavery was just, his social world had to present
treatment” (p. 337; emphasis added). As Sidanius and Pratto itself to him in a way that supported that thesis. (p. 279)
(1999) point out, it is a regrettable if not reprehensible fact
about many social systems that—at least in part because of Thus, a combination of social, cognitive, and motivational
their social group memberships—some individuals possess factors apparently led Aristotle to the conclusion that some
a “disproportionately large share of positive social value,” individuals are “natural slaves” (by virtue of their “child-
including “such things as political authority and power, good like helplessness”) and others are “natural masters” (by
and plentiful food, splendid homes, the best available health virtue of their “rational faculties”). Thus, he argued that both
care, wealth, and high social status,” whereas others “pos- slaves and masters benefit from the institution of slavery. As
sess a disproportionately large share of negative social value, a result of these beliefs, Aristotle and his fellow Athenians
including such things as low power and social status, high- were able to feel better about their own society and to
risk and low-status occupations, relatively poor health care, rationalize away any guilt, dissonance, or negative affect
poor food, modest or miserable homes, and severe negative that they might have otherwise felt. To make matters worse,
sanctions (e.g., prison and death sentences)” (pp. 31–32). because of Aristotle’s philosophical stature, his argu-
ments were resurrected in 16th-century Spain to justify the
enslavement of indigenous people in the New World (Kraut,
System Justification: The Palliative Function 2002, p. 277).
of Ideology
Motivation to Justify the Societal Status Quo
It would be difficult to find a more astute justice theorist or
a bigger authority on ethical behavior in the entire history If Aristotle himself was tempted to excuse the injustices
of Western civilization than Aristotle. And yet, there are inherent in the social system he knew and loved, what hope
aspects of his belief system that strike contemporary audi- is there for the rest of us to avoid a similar fate, at least with
ences as anomalous and obviously wrong-headed, possibly respect to some subset of social issues? According to sys-
even immoral. Probably the most obvious example is his tem justification theory, all of us are motivated—to varying
spirited defense of the institution of slavery as practiced by degrees, as a function of both dispositional and situational
so many of his fellow Athenian citizens (see Kraut, 2002; factors (e.g., Jost & Hunyady, 2002, 2005; Kay & Zanna,
Miller, 1995).5 It is not the case that no one in ancient 2009)—to rationalize away the moral and other failures
of our social, economic, and political institutions and to
derogate alternatives to the status quo (Jost, Liviatan, van
5
Aristotle’s views on women (and sex differences in general) are der Toorn, Ledgerwood, Mandisodza, & Nosek, 2009;
also easily subject to criticism on normative as well as descrip- Kay, Gaucher, Peach, Laurin, Friesen, Zanna, & Spencer,
tive grounds (e.g., Miller, 1995, pp. 239–246). 2009). Thus, despite the fact that most Americans espouse
Obstacles to Attaining Social Justice 1149

egalitarian ideals and acknowledge substantial income explain why: (a) they strongly favor advantaged over dis-
inequality in society, surveys show that a majority of U.S. advantaged groups on implicit as well as explicit measures
respondents judge the economic system to be highly fair and (Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004); (b) their Black–White racial
legitimate (Bartels, 2008; Jost, Blount, Pfeffer, & Hunyady, attitudes lagged behind those of liberals by over thirty
2003). In the context of a chapter on social justice, it is years in the United States (Nosek, Banaji, & Jost, 2009);
worth pointing out that in the United States today the com- (c) they are more likely to deny problems associated with
bined net worth of the 400 wealthiest citizens exceeds $1 global climate change and to resist efforts to change cur-
trillion (Mishel, Bernstein, & Allegretta, 2005) and that rent environmental practices (Feygina, Goldsmith, & Jost,
corporate chief executives earn more than 500 times the sal- in press); and (d) they are relatively insulated against the
ary of their average employee (Stiglitz, 2004). It would be negative hedonic effects of increasing inequality (Napier &
difficult to find any justice principle (i.e., equity, equality, Jost, 2008a). Thus, at least some of the attitudinal differ-
need, etc.) that would “justicize” this degree of economic ences observed between liberals and conservatives can be
inequality, and in fact the inequality has arisen not because understood in terms of variability in system justification
it was judged in advance to be fair but because of imper- tendencies.
sonal “market forces” that most citizens accept (consciously
Costs and Benefits of System Justification
or unconsciously) as legitimate (see also Benabou &
Tirole, 2006; Kluegel & Smith, 1986). System justification appears to satisfy a constellation of
epistemic needs to attain certainty and create a stable, pre-
Stereotyping as System Justification One way in dictable worldview (Jost, Glaser, Kruglanski, & Sulloway,
which people engage in system justification is through 2003); existential needs to manage threat and perceive
the use of stereotypes (such as Aristotle’s stereotypes of a safe, reassuring environment (Kay, Gaucher, Napier,
slaves and masters) that ascribe to individuals and groups Callan, & Laurin, 2008); and relational needs to achieve
characteristics that render them especially well-suited to shared reality with important others, including friends and
occupy the status or positions that they do in the current family members who are also motivated by system justifica-
social order (e.g., Allport, 1954; Eagly & Steffen, 1984; tion concerns (Jost, Ledgerwood, & Hardin, 2008). Perhaps
Hoffman & Hurst, 1990; Jost & Banaji, 1994; Jost & Kay, because it addresses these various needs, system justifica-
2005; Kay, Jost, et al., 2007; Kay et al., 2009; Sidanius & tion conveys palliative psychological benefits, including
Pratto, 1999). It is important to point out that members of increased positive affect and (especially) decreased negative
disadvantaged groups sometimes internalize system-justi- affect (Janoff-Bulman, 1992; Jost & Hunyady, 2002; Kay,
fying stereotypes and evaluations of themselves, and this Gaucher, Napier, Callan, & Laurin, 2008; Kluegel & Smith,
almost surely has the consequence of decreasing their like- 1986; Lerner, 1980; Napier & Jost, 2008a; Wakslak, Jost,
lihood of rebelling against the status quo or participating in Tyler, & Chen, 2007). At the same time, however, system
collective action aimed to change it (e.g., Ashburn-Nardo, justification is associated with low self-esteem, depression,
Knowles, & Monteith, 2003; Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004; ambivalence, and outgroup favoritism among members
Jost, Pelham, & Carvallo, 2002; Lewin, 1941/1948b; of disadvantaged groups, who may be “caught” between
Rudman, Feinberg & Fairchild, 2002; Uhlmann, Dasgupta, competing desires to feel good about themselves and to
Elgueta, Greenwald, & Swanson, 2002). feel good about the social system to which they belong
(e.g., Ashburn-Nardo, Knowles, & Monteith, 2003; Jost &
System-Justifying Aspects of Conservative Ideology Burgess, 2000; Jost, Pelham, & Carvallo, 2002; Jost &
Certain ideologies—such as political conservatism, which Thompson, 2000; O’Brien & Major, 2005).
developed in part out of Edmund Burke’s (1790/1987) It has been suggested that system-justifying attitudes
critical resistance to the French Revolution and his efforts reflect a “moral motivation” to protect society and that
to “vindicate” the social order—satisfy the “goal” of sys- “the benefits of justifying the system are not just palliative,
tem justification as well (see Jost, Glaser, Kruglanski, & they are meaning-providing and can often be important
Sulloway, 2003; Jost, 2009). More than two centuries after for human flourishing” (Haidt & Graham, 2009, p. 391).
the French Revolution, political conservatives continue to Without disputing that system justification contributes
show stronger implicit as well as explicit preferences for to social stability and carries with it a number of social
order, stability, conformity, and tradition (over chaos, flex- and psychological advantages for the individual, group, and
ibility, rebelliousness, and progress), in comparison with society, it seems important to point out that it is probably
liberals and others (Jost, Nosek, & Gosling, 2008). The fact neither moral nor immoral in and of itself. System justifi-
that political conservatives are motivated more strongly cation can indeed inspire people to celebrate and vindicate
than liberals by system justification motivation helps to truly just institutions and practices. Nevertheless, the same
1150 Social Justice

motivation can lead us—as it may have led Aristotle—to tolerate circumstances, such as slavery, apartheid, or caste
venerate those features of the social system (e.g., customs, systems, that seem obviously unjust to outsiders, or in ret-
traditions, and practices) that should, on normative rospect, or from the point of view of clearly established
grounds, be changed. As Frankena (1962) pointed out, “All standards of just treatment (Crosby, 1982; Deutsch, 1985;
sorts of injustices may be enshrined in the rules of society, Lerner, 1980; Martin, 1986; Moore, 1978). Some such cases
as those who settled this country knew and as many of those are said to reflect “false consciousness,” defined as false
whose ancestors did not come willingly know even now” beliefs that serve to sustain injustice or oppression (Fox,
(pp. 8–9). 1999; Jost, 1995; Lind & Tyler, 1988). They may also sug-
gest the presence of system justification motivation, that is,
the desire to exonerate the existing social system and, in so
FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE: WHAT CAN doing, to minimize or overlook its injustices, whether petty
SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY CONTRIBUTE TO or grand (see Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, 2004; Jost et al., 2009;
SOCIAL JUSTICE? Kay et al., 2009).
For all of these reasons, the scholar of social justice must
The topic of social justice brings into stark relief both the at least bear in mind the possibility that there are objective
promise and challenges of social psychology in a way that per- standards of justice, even if specific candidates are bound
haps no other subject matter covered in this Handbook does. to be controversial (e.g., see Feinberg, 1973; Hare, 1981;
Among other things, social justice is a theme that requires Miller, 1999; Rawls, 1971). Much as researchers use sci-
one to consider and integrate insights arising from individual, entific means to identify the objective causes of subjective
group, and system levels of analysis (Doise, 1986; Stangor & well-being (or happiness) of individuals (e.g., Kahneman,
Jost, 1997). Students of social justice—like those who dare to Diener, & Schwarz, 1999), it should be possible for social
confront questions of rationality or truth—must grapple with scientists to discover which characteristics of social systems
the uneasy relationship between the subjective and the objec- are more and less likely to maximize equity, equality, need,
tive or, what is nearly the same in this context, descriptive facts liberty, respect, and other putative principles of social justice,
about how people actually think, feel, and act with respect to and which characteristics lead disproportionately to unjust
justice considerations and normative standards about how outcomes, such as suffering, exploitation, abuse, prejudice,
they ought to behave if their actions and institutions are to be and oppression. It seems like a daunting task to develop
considered just (see also Baron, 1993; Elster, 1992; Feinberg, objective (as well as subjective) measures of well-being at
1973; Frankena, 1962; Konow, 2003; Lerner, 2003; Miller, the system or societal level, but there is no way of know-
1999; Payne & Cameron, in press; Sandel, 1998; Tyler & ing whether scientific methods can gain traction on age-old
Jost, 2007; Walzer, 1983). problems of social justice unless and until it is attempted.
Of course, reasonable (as well as unreasonable) par- Work by Jasso (1999) suggests that it may be possible
ties can disagree about what justice entails, and many to draw meaningful comparisons among different societies
longstanding, seemingly intractable conflicts, such as the with respect to their abilities to satisfy certain standards of
Arab-Israeli conflict, involve interpersonal or intergroup distributive justice. By extending this general approach to
disputes over what is considered fair and legitimate (e.g., incorporate objective, quantifiable indicators of well-being
Deutsch, 2006; Gibson, 2008; Jost & Ross, 1999; Kelman, (e.g., health, wealth, education, work satisfaction, and qual-
2001; Leung & Stephan, 2000; Mikula & Wenzel, 2000). ity of life) in drawing comparisons among nations that pri-
At the same time, it is not entirely satisfying to conclude oritize different justice principles, empirical research could
simply that justice (like truth or beauty) is in the “eye of leverage utilitarian and other insights concerning social
the beholder.” As Miller (1999) observed, “Popular beliefs justice. Likewise, it may be feasible to compare societies
about social justice may turn out to be defective in vari- in terms of how well they adhere to specific deontological
ous ways; for instance, they may prove to conceal deep principles; indeed, some human rights organizations col-
contradictions, or involve serious factual errors” (p. x). If lect international data to draw precisely such comparisons.
we accept this possibility, then we cannot merely assume The most compelling normative theory (or metatheory) of
that justice consists solely of what people think is just (see social justice will probably combine elements of utilitarian
also Sampson, 1983), even though it may be a difficult task and deontological approaches and reconcile multiple, poten-
to determine what actually is just (or unjust) in any given tially conflicting justice principles—such as equity, equality,
situation. need, merit, liberty, consistency, accuracy, and ethicality—
Another reason why one cannot simply interpret the sub- in some hierarchical structure that weights such principles
jective acceptance of a given state of affairs as conclusive differentially as a function of contextual variables, local
evidence of its objective fairness is that people sometimes contingencies, and domains of application. As John Stuart
From Theory to Practice: What Can Social Psychology Contribute to Social Justice? 1151

Mill (1910) observed, “Not only have different nations and drawn from the scientific study of human nature. It has
individuals different notions of justice, but, in the mind of been suggested, for instance, that current legal protections
one and the same individual, justice is not some one rule, against racial discrimination (e.g., the Davis doctrine) are
principle, or maxim, but many, which do not always coin- inadequate because they focus exclusively on conscious
cide in their dictates” (p. 51). intention as an explanation for human behavior and the
Empirical research has a crucial role to play in clear- basis for assigning legal responsibility, whereas contempo-
ing away common misconceptions—including erroneous rary social and cognitive psychology has demonstrated that
assumptions, stereotypes, and misunderstandings about automatic, implicit (i.e., unintentional) processes are capa-
the causes of human behavior—and thereby updating and ble of producing discriminatory outcomes (Greenwald &
elevating public discourse about matters of social justice Krieger, 2006; Kang & Banaji, 2006; Krieger, 1995; Lane,
and morality (Greene, 2003; Payne & Cameron, in press). Kang, & Banaji, 2007; Lawrence, 2008; but see Mitchell &
Over time, we have seen that scientific findings can change Tetlock, 2006 for a dissenting view).
culturally prevalent representations of free will, conscious- All of this returns us to the grand Lewinian ambitions
ness, responsibility, and so on, and these changes slowly with which we began this chapter. The notion of solving
manifest themselves in legal and judicial transformations social problems through rational, scientific means rather
(e.g., Blasi & Jost, 2006; Greene & Cohen, 2004; Wegner, than ideological (or even coercive) means is particularly
2002).6 Cognitive scientists have contributed mightily to attractive (e.g., Allport, 1954, 1962; Deutsch, 1999; Lerner,
refining normative theories of rationality (e.g., Kahneman 1980, 2003; Lewin, 1939/1948a; Mansbridge, 2005;
et al., 1982; March & Simon, 1958; Thaler, 1991) as well McGuire, 1985; Walton & Dweck, 2009). Along these lines,
as formerly philosophical (and even metaphysical) treat- Kurt Lewin (1939/1948a) argued that the objectives of sci-
ments of epistemological questions in general (Goldman, ence and social justice were in fact highly compatible:
1992; Kornblith, 1999; Quine, 1969; Stich, 1990). In recent
years, philosophers have incorporated evidence from social To believe in reason means to believe in democracy, because
and personality psychology in evaluating Aristotelian and it grants to the reasoning partners a status of equality. It is
other normative (as well as descriptive) theories of ethics, therefore not an accident that not until the rise of democracy
virtue, and moral character (Appiah, 2008; Doris, 2002; at the time of the American and French Revolutions was the
Flanagan, 1991; Harman, 1999; J. T. Jost & L. J. Jost, goddess of “reason” enthroned in modern society. And again,
it is not an accident that the first act of modern Fascism in
2009). There is no a priori reason to assume that social
every country has been officially and vigorously to dethrone
psychological research will be less useful in forging the
this goddess and instead to make emotions and obedience the
kinds of normative conceptions of justice and injustice all-ruling principles in education and life from kindergarten
that have traditionally been the bread and butter of moral to death.
philosophy and legal scholarship (see also Tyler & Jost,
2007). I am persuaded that scientific sociology and social psychology
Another basis for optimism concerning attempts to based on an intimate combination of experiments and empiri-
cal theory can do as much, or more, for human betterment as
“naturalize” the study of social justice comes from explicit
the natural sciences have done. However, the development of
efforts to integrate legal studies with research in the social
such a realistic, nonmystical social science and the possibility
and behavioral sciences (e.g., Sunstein, 2000), including of its fruitful application presuppose the existence of a society
calls for “psychological jurisprudence” (Darley, Fulero, which believes in reason. (p. 83; emphasis added)
Haney, & Tyler, 2002; Haney, 1993; Tyler & Jost, 2007)
and “behavioral realism” (Blasi & Jost, 2006; Hanson & Thus, Lewin was enthusiastic—even “heroic,” according
Yosifon, 2004; Kang, 2005; Krieger & Fiske, 2006). Each to some (e.g., Ring, 1967)—about the use of social science to
of these represents a concerted attempt to bring the law serve the ends of social justice and, in so doing, to improve
and public policy into better alignment with conclusions society. The evidence we have reviewed in this chapter sug-
gests that considerable progress toward this most ambitious
goal has been achieved (e.g., see Benabou & Tirole, 2006;
6
Deutsch, 1985, 2006; Frohlich & Oppenheimer, 1992;
Philosophers, including Rawls (1971), often strive to develop
Jasso, 1999; Konow, 2003; Lerner, 1987; Lind & Tyler,
normative theories of justice that satisfy the principle of “mini-
mal psychological realism,” that is, theories that are at least con- 1988; Major, 1994; Mikula & Wenzel, 2000; Miller, 2001;
sistent with what is known about the laws of human psychology. Payne & Cameron, in press; Pettigrew et al., 2008; Rossi &
Legal authorities, too, have a vested interest in prescribing laws Berk, 1997; Skitka & Tetlock, 1993; Thibaut & Walker,
that are psychologically realistic in the sense that most citizens 1986; Tyler, 2006, 2007; Tyler & Jost, 2007; Van den Bos,
will be able to follow them. 2005; Van Lange, 2000; Wakslak et al., 2007). At the same
1152 Social Justice

time, the jury is still out on whether the theories and methods Anderson, V. N. (1992). For whom is this world just? Sexual orientation
and AIDS. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 22, 248–259.
of social psychology can offer unique, indispensable
Appiah, K.A. (2008). Experiments in ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
insights that—when combined with those gathered from University Press.
philosophy, law, history, anthropology, sociology, econom- Aristotle (2002). Nicomachean ethics (S. Broadie & C. Rowe [Eds.],
ics, political science, and other disciplines—will enable the Trans.). New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work published
human race to attain the highest degree of social justice in 384-322 BCE).
practice and to permanently overcome its most stubborn, Aryee, S., Budhwar, P. S., & Chen, Z. X. (2002). Trust as a mediator of
the relationship between organizational justice and work outcomes: Test
pernicious obstacles. We follow Kurt Lewin in supposing, of a social exchange model. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 23,
however optimistically, that they can. 267–286.
Asch, S. E. (1959). A perspective on social psychology. In S. Koch (Ed.),
Psychology: A study of a science (Vol. 3, pp. 363–383). New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Ashburn-Nardo, L., Knowles, M. L., & Monteith, M. J. (2003). Black
REFERENCES Americans’ implicit racial associations and their implications for inter-
group judgment. Social Cognition, 21, 61–87.
Au, W. T., & Kwong, J. Y. Y. (2004). Measurements and effects of social-
Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequality in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
value orientation in social dilemmas: A review. In R. Suleiman,
Advances in experimental social psychology, (Vol. 2, pp. 267–299).
D. V. Budescu, I. Fischer, & D. M. Messick (Eds.), Contemporary
New York: Academic Press.
psychological research on social dilemmas. (pp. 71–98). New York:
Adelson, H. L. (1995). The origins of a concept of social justice. Cambridge University Press.
In K. D. Irani & M. Silver (Eds.), Social justice in the ancient world
Austin, W., & Walster, E. (1974). Participants’ reactions to “equity with the
(pp. 25–38). Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. world.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 10, 528–548.
Adorno, T. W., Frenkel-Brunswik, E., Levinson, D. J., & Sanford, R. N. Axelrod, R. (2006). The evolution of cooperation (Rev. ed.). New York:
(1950). The authoritarian personality. New York: Harper. Perseus.
Aguiar, P., Vala, J., Correia, I., & Pereira, C. (2008). Justice in our world Azzi, A. E., & Jost, J. T. (1997). Votes without power: Procedural justice
and in that of others: Belief in a just world and reactions to victims. as mutual control in majority–minority relations. Journal of Applied
Social Justice Research, 21, 50–68. Social Psychology, 27, 124–155.
Ahmed, E., & Braithwaite, V. (2006). Forgiveness, reconciliation, and Bargh, J. A., Raymond, P., Pryor, J. B., & Strack, F. (1995). Attractiveness
shame: Three key variables in reducing school bullying. Journal of of the underling: An automatic power-sex association and its conse-
Social Issues, 62, 347–370. quences for sexual harassment and aggression. Journal of Personality
Albert, S. (1977). Temporal comparison theory. Psychological Review, 84, and Social Psychology, 68, 768–781.
485–503. Baron, J. (1993). Heuristics and biases in equity judgments: A utilitarian
Allison, S. T., Beggan, J. K., & Midgley, E. H. (1996). The quest for “simi- approach. In B. A. Mellers & J. Baron (Eds.), Psychological perspec-
lar instances” and “simultaneous possibilities”: Metaphors in social tives on justice (pp. 109–137). New York: Cambridge University Press.
dilemma research. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, Barrett-Howard, E., & Tyler, T. R. (1986). Procedural justice as a criterion
479–497. in allocation decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice. Cambridge, MA: 50, 296–304.
Addison-Wesley. Barry, B. M. (2005). A treatise on social justice. Berkeley, CA: University
Allport, G. W. (1962). The historical background of modern social psy- of California Press.
chology. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.), The handbook of social Bartels, L. M. (2008). Unequal democracy: The political economy of the
psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 1, pp. 1–80). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. new gilded age. Princeton, NJ : Princeton University Press.
(Original work published in 1954) Batson, C. D. (1990). How social is an animal? The human capacity for
Altemeyer, R. (1981). Right wing authoritarianism. Winnipeg, Manitoba, caring. American Psychologist, 45, 336–346.
Canada: University of Manitoba Press. Batson, C. D. (1998). Altruism and prosocial behavior. In D. Gilbert,
Altemeyer, B. (1996). The authoritarian specter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard S. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology
University Press. (pp. 282–316). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Altemeyer, B. (1998). The other “authoritarian personality.” In M. P. Zanna Batson, C. D., Batson, J. G., Singlsby, J. K., Harrell, K. L., Peekna, H. M., &
(Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 30, pp. 47–92). Todd, R. M. (1991). Empathic joy and the empathy–altruism hypoth-
New York: Academic Press. esis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61, 413–426.
Alves, H., & Correia, I. (2008). On the normativity of expressing the Batson, C. D., & Moran, T. (1999). Empathy-induced altruism in a prisoner’s
belief in a just world: Empirical evidence. Social Justice Research, 21, dilemma. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29, 909924.
106–118. Batson, C. D., & Shaw, L. L. (1991). Evidence for altruism: Toward a plu-
Ambrose, M. L., & Arnaud, A. (2005). Are procedural justice and distrib- ralism of prosocial motives. Psychological Inquiry, 2, 107–122.
utive justice conceptually distinct? In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire
(Eds.), Handbook of organizational justice (pp. 59–84). Mahwah, NJ: for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation.
Erlbaum. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 497–529.
Ambrose, M. L., & Kulik, C. T. (1999). Old friends, new faces: Motivation Bazemore, G. (1998). Restorative justice and earned redemption:
research in the 1990s. Journal of Management, 25, 231–292. Communities, victims, and offender reintegration. American Behavioral
Ambrose, M. L., Seabright, M. A., & Schminke, M. (2002). Sabotage in Scientist, 41, 768–813.
the workplace: The role of organizational injustice. Organizational Becker, G. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago:
Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 89, 947–965. University of Chicago Press.
References 1153

Bègue, L., & Bastounis, M. (2003). Two spheres of belief in justice: Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame, and reintegration. New York:
Extensive support for the bidimensional model of belief in a just world. Cambridge University Press.
Journal of Personality, 71, 435–463. Braithwaite, J., & Braithwaite, V. (2001). Shame and shame manage-
Benabou, R. & Tirole, J. (2006). Belief in a just world and redistributive ment. In E. Ahmed, N. Harris, J. Braithwaite, & V. Braithwaite (Eds.),
politics. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121, 1652–1678. Shame management and regulation (pp. 3–69). Cambridge, England:
Bentham, J. (1962). Principles of penal law. In J. Bowring (Ed.), The works Cambridge University Press.
of Jeremy Bentham (pp. 396). Edinburgh: W. Tait. (Original work pub- Braithwaite, J., & Mugford, S. (1994). Conditions of successful reintegra-
lished 1843). tion ceremonies: Dealing with juvenile offenders. British Journal of
Bernstein, M., & Crosby, F. (1980). An empirical examination of relative Criminology, 34, 139–171.
deprivation theory. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 16, Braman, A. C., & Lambert, A. J. (2001). Punishing individuals for their
442–456. infirmities: Effects of personal responsibility, just-world beliefs, and
Bierhoff, H. W., Buck, E., & Klein, R. (1986). Social context and perceived in-group/out-group status. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 31,
injustice. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice 1096–1109.
in social relations (pp. 165–185). New York: Plenum. Brickman, P. (1977). Preference for inequality. Social Psychology
Biernat, M., Vescio, T. K., & Theno, S. A. (1996). Violating American values: Quarterly, 40, 303–310.
A “value congruence” approach to understanding outgroup attitudes. Brickman, P., Coates, D., & Janoff-Bulman, R. (1978). Lottery winners
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 32, 387–410. and accident victims: Is happiness relative? Journal of Personality and
Biernat, M., & Wortman, C. B. (1991). Sharing of home responsibilities Social Psychology, 36, 917–927.
between professionally employed women and their husbands. Journal Broadie, S. (2002). Philosophical introduction. In S. Broadie & C. Rowe
of Personality and Social Psychology, 60, 844–860. (Eds.), Aristotle, Nicomachean ethics: Translation, introduction, and
Bies, R. J. (2001). Interactional (in)justice: The sacred and the profane. commentary (pp. 9–91). New York: Oxford University Press.
In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational Brockner, J., Heuer, L., & Magner, N. (2003). High procedural fairness
justice (pp. 89–118). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. heightens the effect of outcome favorability on self-evaluations: An
Bies, R. J. (2005). Are procedural justice and interactional justice con- attributional analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
ceptually distinct? In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook Processes, 91, 51–68.
of organizational justice (pp. 85–112). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Brockner, J., Heuer, L., Siegel, P. A., Wiesenfeld, B., Martin, C., Grover, S.,
Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. S. (1986). Interactional justice: Communication et al. (1998). The moderating effect of self-esteem in reaction to voice:
criteria of fairness. In B. Sheppard (Ed.), Research on negotiation in Converging evidence from five studies. Journal of Personality and
organizations (pp. 43–55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Social Psychology, 75, 394–407.
Blanton, H., George, G., & Crocker, J. (2001). Contexts of system justifi- Brockner, J., & Wiesenfeld, B. (1996). An integrative framework for
cation and system evaluation: Exploring the social comparison strat- explaining reactions to decisions: Interactive effects of outcomes and
egies of the (not yet) contented female worker. Group Processes & procedures. Psychological Bulletin, 120, 189–208.
Intergroup Relations, 4, 126–137. Brosnan, S. F. (2006). Nonhuman species’ reactions to inequity and their
Blau, P. M. (1968). Social exchange. In D. L. Sills (Ed.), International implications for fairness. Social Justice Research, 19, 153–185.
encyclopedia of the social sciences (Vol. 7). New York: Macmillan. Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F.B.M. (2003). Monkeys reject unequal pay.
Blasi, G., & Jost, J. T. (2006). System justification theory and research: Nature, 425, 297–299.
Implications for law, legal advocacy, and social justice. California Law
Brown, R. (1965). Social psychology. New York: Free Press.
Review, 94, 1119–1168.
Budescu, D. V., Rapoport, A., & Suleiman, R. (1990). Resource dilemmas
Bobocel, D. R., & Holmvall, C. M. (2001). Are interactional justice and
with environmental uncertainty and asymmetric players. European
procedural justice different? Framing the debate. In S. Gilliland,
Journal of Social Psychology, 20, 475–487.
D. Steiner, & D. Skarlicki (Eds.), Research in social research in social
issues in management: Theoretical and cultural perspectives on orga- Burkart, J. M., Fehr, E., Efferson, C., & van Schaik, C. P. (2007). Other-
nizational justice (pp. 85–108). Greenwich, CT: Information Age. regarding preferences in a non-human primate: Common marmosets
provision food altruistically. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Bogaert, S., Boone, C., & Declerck, C. (2008). Social value orientation
Sciences, 104, 19762–19766.
and cooperation in social dilemmas: A review and conceptual model.
British Journal of Social Psychology, 47, 453–480. Burke, E. (1987). Reflections on the revolution in France. In
J.G.A. Pocock (Ed.), Reflections on the revolution in France
Bolino, M. C., & Turnley, W. H. (2008). Old faces, new places: Equity
(pp. 1–218). Indianapolis: Hackett. (Original work published 1790).
theory in cross-cultural contexts. Journal of Organizational Behavior,
29, 29–50. Callahan-Levy, C. M., & Messé, L. A. (1979). Sex differences in the
allocation of pay. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37,
Boll, T., Ferring, D., & Filipp, S. (2005). Effects of parental differential
433–446.
treatment on relationship quality with siblings and parents: Justice
evaluations as mediators. Social Justice Research, 18, 155–182. Callan, M. J., Ellard, J. H., & Nicol, J. E. (2006). The belief in a just world
and immanent justice reasoning in adults. Personality and Social
Bonanno, G. A., & Jost, J. T. (2006). Conservative shift among high-
Psychology Bulletin, 32, 1646–1658.
exposure survivors of the September 11 terrorist attacks. Basic and
Applied Social Psychology, 28, 311–323. Callan, M. J., Kay, A. C., Davidenko, N., & Ellard, J. H. (in press). The
Bond, D., & Park, J. (1991). An empirical test of Rawls’s theory of jus- effects of justice motivation for memory for self- and other-relevant
tice: A second approach, in Korea and the United States. Simulation & events. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology.
Gaming, 22, 443–462. Callan, M. J., Powell, N. G., & Ellard, J. H. (2007). The consequences
Boucher, D., & Kelly, P. (Eds.). (1998). Social justice from Hume to Walzer. of victim physical attractiveness on reactions to injustice: The role of
New York: Routledge. observers’ belief in a just world. Social Justice Research, 20, 433–456.
Bowie, N. E., & Simon, R. L. (2007). The individual and the political Campbell, T. (2001). Justice (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin’s Press.
order: An introduction to social and political philosophy (4th ed.). Capehart, L., & Milovanovic, D. (2007). Social justice: Theories, issues,
New York: Rowman & Littlefield. and movements. New York: Rutgers University Press.
1154 Social Justice

Carlsmith, K. M. (2006). The roles of retribution and utility in determining Crandall, C. S., Eidelman, S., Skitka, L. J., & Morgan, G. S. (2009). Status
punishment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 437–451. quo framing increases support for torture. Social Influence, 4, 1–10.
Carlsmith, K. M. (2008). On justifying punishment: The discrepancy Crandall, C. S., & Eshleman, A. (2003). A justification–suppression of the
between words and actions. Social Justice Research, 21, 119–137. expression and experience of prejudice. Psychological Bulletin, 129,
Carlsmith, K. M., & Darley, J. M. (2008). Psychological aspects of retribu- 414–446.
tive justice. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psy- Crandall, C. S., & Martinez, R. (1996). Culture, ideology, and antifat atti-
chology (pp. 193–236). San Diego, CA: Elsevier. tudes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 1165–1176.
Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2002). Why do we pun- Crespi, B. J. (2000). The evolution of maladaptation. Heredity, 84, 623–629.
ish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. Journal of Crocker, J., & Major, B. (1989). Social stigma and self-esteem: The self-
Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 284–299. protective properties of stigma. Psychological Review, 96, 608–630.
Carlsmith, K. M., & Sood, A. M. (2009). The fine line between interroga- Cropanzano, R., & Folger, R. (1989). Referent cognitions and task decision
tion and retribution. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, autonomy: Beyond equity theory. Journal of Applied Psychology, 74,
191–196. 293–299.
Carr, S. C., & MacLachlan, M. (1998). Actors, observers, and attributions Cropanzano, R., Prehar, C. A., & Chen, P. Y. (2002). Using social exchange
for third world poverty: Contrasting perspectives from Malawi and theory to distinguish procedural from interactional justice. Group &
Australia. Journal of Social Psychology, 138, 189–202. Organization Management, 27, 324–351.
Cartwright, D. (1979). Contemporary social psychology in historical per- Crosby, F. (1976). A model of egoistical relative deprivation. Psychological
spective. Social Psychology Quarterly, 42, 82–93. Review, 83, 85–113.
Chen, C. C. (1995). New trends in rewards allocation preferences: A Sino–
Crosby, F. (1982). Relative deprivation and the working woman.
U.S. comparison. Academy of Management Journal, 38, 408–428.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Christiansen, N. D., & Lavine, H. (1997). Need-efficiency trade-offs in
Crosby, F., Muehrer, P., & Loewenstein, G. (1986). Relative deprivation
the allocation of resources: Ideological and attributional differences
and explanation: Models and concepts. In J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman, &
in public aid decision making. Social Justice Research, 10, 289–310.
M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative deprivation and social comparison: The
Cialdini, R. B., Brown, S. L., Lewis, B. P., Luce, C., & Neuberg, S. L. Ontario symposium (Vol. 4, pp. 17–32). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
(1997). Reinterpreting the empathy–altruism relationship: When one
Curtis, R. C. (1979). Effects of knowledge of self-interest and social rela-
into one equals oneness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
tionship upon the use of equity, utilitarian, and Rawlsian principles of
73, 481–494.
allocation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 9, 165–175.
Cialdini, R. B., Schaller, M., Houlihan, D., Arps, K., Fultz, J., &
Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006). The role of conscious rea-
Beaman, A. L. (1987). Empathy-based helping: Is it selflessly or selfishly
soning and intuition in moral judgment: Testing three principles of
motivated? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 749–758.
harm. Psychological Science, 17, 1082–1089.
Clark, M. S., & Mills, J. (1979). Interpersonal attraction in exchange and
Dalbert, C. (1998). Belief in a just world, well-being, and coping with an
communal relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
unjust fate. In L. Montada & M. J. Lerner (Eds.), Responses to victim-
37, 12–24.
izations and belief in a just world (pp. 87–105). New York: Plenum.
Clayton, S., & Opotow, S. (2003). Justice and identity: Changing perspec-
Dalbert, C. (2001). The justice motive as a personal resource: Dealing with
tives on what is fair. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7,
challenges and critical life events. New York: Plenum.
298–310.
Dalbert, C. (2002). Beliefs in a just world as a buffer against anger. Social
Cohen, A. B., & Rozin, P. (2001). Religion and the morality of mentality.
Justice Research, 15, 123–145.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 697–710.
Dambrun, M. (2007). Understanding the relationship between racial preju-
Cohen, R. L., & Greenberg, J. (1982). The justice concept in social psychol-
dice and support for the death penalty: The racist punitive bias hypoth-
ogy. In J. Greenberg & R. L. Cohen (Eds.), Equity and justice in social
esis. Social Justice Research, 20, 228–249.
behavior (pp. 1–41). New York: Academic Press.
Dambrun, M., Taylor, D. M., McDonald, D. A., Crush, J., & Méot, A.
Cohen-Charash, Y., & Spector, P. E. (2001). The role of justice in organiza-
(2006). The relative deprivation–gratification continuum and the atti-
tions: A meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
tudes of South Africans toward immigrants: A test of the V-curve hypoth-
Processes, 86, 278–321.
esis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 1032–1044.
Colquitt, J. A. (2001). On the dimensionality of organizational justice:
A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, Darley, J. M., Carlsmith, K. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2000). Incapacitation
86, 386–400. and just deserts as motives for punishment. Law and Human Behavior,
24, 659–683.
Colquitt, J. A., Conlon, D. E., Wesson, M. J., Porter, C. O. L. H., & Ng, K. Y.
(2001). Justice at the millenium: A meta-analytic review of 25 years Darley, J.M., Fulero, S., Haney, C., & Tyler, T. (2002). Psychological juris-
of organizational justice research. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, prudence: Taking psychology and law into the twenty-first century. In
425–445. J.R.P. Ogloff (Ed.), Taking psychology and law into the twenty-first
century (pp. 35–59). New York: Plenum.
Colquitt, J. A., Greenberg, J., & Zapata-Phelan, C. P. (2005). What is
organizational justice? A historical overview. In J. Greenberg & Darley, J. M., & Pittman, T. S. (2003). The psychology of compensatory
J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook of organizational justice (pp. 3–56). and retributive justice. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7,
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. 324–336.
Cook, K. S., & Hegtvedt, K. A. (1986). Justice and power: An exchange Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man and selection in relation to sex.
analysis. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice London: John Murray.
in social relations (pp. 19–41). New York: Plenum. Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University
Correia, I., Vala, J., & Aguiar, P. (2007). Victim’s innocence, social cat- Press.
egorization, and the threat to the belief in a just world. Journal of Davies, J. C. (1962). Towards a theory of revolution. American Sociological
Experimental Social Psychology, 43, 31–38. Review, 27, 5–19.
Crandall, C. S. (1994). Prejudice against fat people: Ideology and self- Davis, J. A. (1959). A formal interpretation of the theory of relative depri-
interest. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 882–894. vation. Sociometry, 22, 280–296.
References 1155

Davis, D.W., & Silver, B. D. (2004). Civil liberties vs. security: Public Doty, R. M., Peterson, B. E., & Winter, D. G. (1991). Threat and authori-
opinion in the context of the terrorist attacks on America. American tarianism in the United States, 1978–1987. Journal of Personality and
Journal of Political Science, 48, 28–46. Social Psychology, 61, 629–640.
De Cremer, D. (2002). Charismatic leadership and cooperation in social Drout, C. E., & Gaertner, S. L. (1994). Gender differences in reactions to
dilemmas: A matter of transforming motives? Journal of Applied Social female victims. Social Behavior and Personality, 22, 267–277.
Psychology, 32, 997–1016. Dubé, L., & Guimond, S. (1986). Relative deprivation and social protest.
De Cremer, D., & Van Dijk, E. (2005). When and why leaders put them- In J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative depri-
selves first: Leader behaviour in resource allocations as a function of vation and social comparison: The Ontario symposium (Vol. 4,
feeling entitled. European Journal of Social Psychology, 35, 553–563. pp. 201–216). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
De Cremer, D., & Van Lange, P.A.M. (2001). Why prosocials exhibit Eagly, A. H., Diekman, A. B., Johannesen-Schmidt, M. C., & Koenig,
greater cooperation than proselfs: The roles of social responsibility and A. M. (2004). Gender gaps in sociopolitical attitudes: A social
reciprocity. European Journal of Personality, 15, 5–18. psychological analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
De Cremer, D., & Van Vugt, M. (1999). Social identification effects in 87, 796–816.
social dilemmas: A transformation of motives. European Journal of Eagly, A. H., & Steffen, V. J. (1984). Gender stereotypes stem from the
Social Psychology, 29, 871–893. distribution of women and men into social roles. Journal of Personality
De Cremer, D., & Van Vugt, M. (2002). Intergroup and intragroup aspects and Social Psychology, 46, 735–754.
of leadership in social dilemmas: A relational model of cooperation. Eek, D., & Gärling, T. (2006). Prosocials prefer equal outcomes to maxi-
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 126–136. mizing joint outcomes. British Journal of Social Psychology, 45,
De Judicibus, M., & McCabe, M. P. (2001). Blaming the target of sexual 321–337.
harassment: Impact of gender role, sexist attitudes, and work role. Ellard, J. H., & Bates, D. D. (1990). Evidence for the role of the justice motive
Sex Roles, 44, 401–417. in status generalization processes. Social Justice Research, 4, 115–134.
De Kwaadsteniet, E. W., van Dijk, E., Wit, A., De Cremer, D., & Elliott, C. S., Hayward, D. M., & Canon, S. (1998). Institutional fram-
de Rooij, M. (2007). Justifying decisions in social dilemmas: ing: Some experimental evidence. Journal of Economic Behavior and
Justification pressures and tacit coordination under environmental Organization, 35, 455–464.
uncertainty. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33, 1648–1660. Ellsworth, P. C., & Ross, L. (1983). Public opinion and capital punishment:
Deutsch, M. (1973). The resolution of conflict. New Haven: Yale University A close examination of the views of abolitionists and retentionists.
Press. Crime & Delinquency, 29, 116–169.
Deutsch, M. (1975). Equity, equality, and need: What determines which Elster, J. (1992). Local justice: How institutions allocate scarce goods and
value will be used as the basis of distributive justice? Journal of Social necessary burdens. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Issues, 31, 137–149. Emler, N. (2002). Morality and political orientations: An analysis of their
Deutsch, M. (1985). Distributive justice: A social–psychological perspec- relationship. European Review of Social Psychology, 13, 259–291.
tive. New Haven: Yale University Press. Feather, N. T. (1994). Attitudes toward high achievers and reactions to
Deutsch, M. (1999). A personal perspective on the development of social their fall: Theory and research concerning tall poppies. In M. P. Zanna
psychology in the twentieth century. In A. Rodrigues & R. Levine (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 26, pp. 1–73).
(Eds.), Reflections on 100 years of experimental social psychology (pp. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
1–34). New York: Basic Books. Feather, N. T. (1999). Judgments of deservingness: Studies in the psychol-
Deutsch, M. (2006). Justice and conflict. In M. Deutsch, P. T. Coleman, & ogy of justice and achievement. Personality and Social Psychology
E. C. Marcus (Eds.), The handbook of conflict resolution: Theory and Review, 3, 86–107.
practice (2nd ed., pp. 43–68). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Feather, N. T. (2008). Perceived legitimacy of a promotion decision in
Diekmann, K.A., Barsness, Z. I., & Sondak, H. (2004). Uncertainty, fair- relation to deservingness, entitlement, and resentment in the context
ness perceptions, and job satisfaction: A field study. Social Justice of affirmative action and performance. Journal of Applied Social
Research, 17, 237–255. Psychology, 38, 1230–1254.
Diekmann, K. A., Samuels, S. M., Ross, L., & Bazerman, M. H. (1997). Fehr, E. & Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of human altruism. Nature,
Self-interest and fairness in problems of resource allocation: Allocators 425, 785–791.
versus recipients. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, Feinberg, J. (1973). Social philosophy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
1061–1074.
Feldman, S. (2003). Enforcing social conformity: A theory of authoritari-
Diener, E. (1984). Subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, anism. Political Psychology, 24, 41–74.
542–575. Festinger, L. (1954). A theory of social comparison processes. Human
Dion, K. L., (1986). Responses to perceived discrimination and relative Relations, 7, 117–140.
deprivation. In J. M. Olson, H. C. Peter, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Feygina, I., Goldsmith, R., & Jost, J. T. (in press). System justification and
Relative deprivation and social comparison: The Ontario symposium the disruption of environmental goal-setting: A self-regulatory per-
(Vol. 4, pp. 159–179). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. spective. In R. Hassin, K. Ochsner, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Social cogni-
Dion, K. L., & Dion, K. K. (1987). Belief in a just world and physi- tive and neuroscientific approaches to self-control. New York: Oxford
cal attractiveness stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social University Press.
Psychology, 52, 775–780. Fischer, R., & Smith, P. B. (2003). Reward allocation and culture: A meta-
Doise, W. (1986). Levels of explanation in social psychology. Cambridge, analysis. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 34, 251–268.
England: Cambridge University Press. Fiske, A. P., & Tetlock, P. E. (1997). Taboo trade-offs: Reactions to transactions
Doob, L. W. (1952). Social psychology: An analysis of human behavior. that transgress the spheres of justice. Political Psychology, 18, 255–297.
New York: Holt. Fiske, S. T. (1998). Stereotypes, prejudice, and discrimination. In
Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. D. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social
New York: Cambridge University Press. psychology (4th ed., pp. 357–414). Boston: McGraw-Hill.
1156 Social Justice

Fiske, S. T. (2004). Social beings: A core motives approach to social psy- Gelfand, M. J., Fitzgerald, L. F., & Drasgow, F. (1995). The structure of
chology. New York: Wiley. sexual harassment: A confirmatory analysis across cultures and set-
Flanagan, O. (1991). Varieties of moral personality: Ethics and psycho- tings. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 47, 164–177.
logical realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gibson, J. L. (2004). Overcoming apartheid: Can truth reconcile a divided
Foels, R., & Pappas, C. J. (2004). Learning and unlearning the myths we nation? New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
are taught: Gender and social dominance orientation. Sex Roles, 50, Gibson, J. L. (2008). Group identities and theories of justice: An experi-
743–757. mental investigation into the justice and injustice of land squatting in
Folger, R. (1977). Distributive and procedural justice: Combined impact South Africa. The Journal of Politics, 70, 700–716.
of “voice” and improvement on experienced inequity. Journal of Gleason, M. E. J., Iida, M., Bolger, N., & Shrout, P. E. (2003). Daily sup-
Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 108–119. portive equity in close relationships. Personality and Social Psychology
Folger, R. (1986). A referent cognitions theory of relative deprivation. In Bulletin, 29, 1036–1045.
J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Social comparison Goldman, A. (1992). Liaisons: Philosophy meets the cognitive and social
and relative deprivation: The Ontario Symposium (Vol. 4, pp. 33–55). sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Gollwitzer, M., Schmitt, M., Schalke, R., Maes, J., & Baer, A. (2005).
Folger, R., & Bies, R. J. (1989). Managerial responsibilities and procedural Asymmetrical effects of justice sensitivity perspectives on prosocial
justice. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, 2, 79–90. and antisocial behavior. Social Justice Research, 18, 183–201.
Folger, R., Rosenfield, D., Grove, J., & Corkran, L. (1979). Effects Goodman, P. S. (1977). Social comparison processes in organizations. In
of “voice” and peer opinions on responses to inequity. Journal of B. Staw & G. Salancik (Eds.), New directions in organizational behav-
Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 2253–2261. ior (pp. 97–132). Chicago: St. Clair.
Ford, T. E., Boxer, C. F., Armstrong, J., & Edel, J. R. (2008). More than Green, D. P., & Shapiro, I. (1994). Pathologies of rational choice theory:
“just a joke”: The prejudice-releasing function of sexist humor. A critique of applications in political science. New Haven, CT: Yale
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 159–170. University Press.
Foster, M. D., & Matheson, K. (1995). Double relative depriva- Greenberg, J. (1980). Attentional focus and locus of performance causality
tion: Combining the personal and political. Personality and Social as determinants of equity behavior. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 21, 1167–1177. Psychology, 38, 579–585.
Fox, D. R. (1999). Psycholegal scholarship’s contribution to false con- Greenberg, J. (1984). On the apocryphal nature of inequity distress.
sciousness about injustice. Law and Human Behavior, 23, 9–30. In R. Folger (Ed.), The sense of injustice (pp. 167–188). New York:
Frankena, W. K. (1962). The concept of social justice. In R. B. Brandt Plenum.
(Ed.), Social justice (pp. 1–29). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Greenberg, J. (1993). Stealing in the name of justice: Informational and
Frankfurt, H. (1987). Equality as a moral ideal. Ethics, 98, 21–42. interpersonal moderators of theft reactions to underpayment inequity.
Freeman, D., Aquino, K., & McFerran, B. (2009). Overcoming benefi- Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54, 81–103.
ciary race as an impediment to charitable donations: Social dominance Greenberg, J., Bies, R. J., & Eskew, D. E. (1991). Establishing fairness
orientation, the experience of moral elevation, and donation behavior. in the eye of the beholder: Managing impressions of organizational
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 35, 72–84. justice. In R. A. Giacalone & P. Rosenfeld (Eds.), Applied impression
Freudenthaler, H. H., & Mikula, G. (1998). From unfulfilled wants to the management: How image-making affects managerial decisions (pp.
experience of injustice: Women’s sense of injustice regarding the lop- 111–132). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
sided division of household labor. Social Justice Research, 11, 289–312. Greenberger, E. (1984). Defining psychosocial maturity in adolescence.
Frohlich, N., & Oppenheimer, J. A. (1992). Choosing justice: An experi- Advances in Child Behavioral Analysis & Therapy, 3, 1–37.
mental approach to ethical theory. Berkeley: University of California Greene, J. D. (2003). From neural “is” to moral “ought”: What are the
Press. moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature
Fujita, F., Diener, E., & Sandvik, E. (1991). Gender differences in nega- Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 846–849.
tive affect and well-being: The case for emotional intensity. Journal of Greene, J. D., & Cohen, J. (2004). For the law, neuroscience changes noth-
Personality and Social Psychology, 61, 427–434. ing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of
Fuller, J. B., Jr., & Hester, K. (2001). A closer look at the relationship London B (Special Issue on Law and the Brain), 359, 1775–17785.
between justice perceptions and union participation. Journal of Applied Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D.
Psychology, 86, 1096–1105. (2008). Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral
Furgeson, J., Babcock, L., & Shane, P. (2008). Behind the mask of judgment. Cognition, 107, 1144–1154.
method: Political orientation and constitutional interpretive prefer- Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., &
ences. Law & Human Behavior, 32, 502–510. Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement
Furnham, A. (1985). Just world beliefs in an unjust society: a cross-cultural in moral Judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108.
comparison. European Journal of Social Psychology, 15, 363–366. Greenwald, A. G., & Krieger, L. H. (2006). Implicit bias: Scientific foun-
Furnham, A. (1995). The just world, charitable giving and attitudes to dis- dations. California Law Review, 94, 945–967.
ability. Personality and Individual Differences, 19, 577–583. Gromet, D. M., & Darley, J. M. (2006). Restoration and retribution: How
Furnham, A. (2003). Belief in a just world: Research progress over the past including retributive components affects the acceptability of restorative
decade. Personality and Individual Differences, 34, 795–817. justice procedures. Social Justice Research, 19, 395–432.
Gachter, S., & Fehr, E. (1999). Collective action as a social exchange. Guimond, S., & Dambrun, M. (2002). When prosperity breeds intergroup
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 39, 341–369. hostility: The effects of relative deprivation and relative gratification on
Gamliel, E., & Peer, E. (2006). Positive versus negative framing affects prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 900–912.
justice judgments. Social Justice Research, 19, 307–322. Guimond, S., Dambrun, M., Michinov, N., & Duarte, S. (2003). Does
Gaucher, D., Hafer, C., Kay, A. C., & Davidenko, N. (in press). social dominance generate prejudice? Integrating individual and con-
Compensatory rationalizations and the resolution of everyday under- textual determinants of intergroup cognitions. Journal of Personality
served outcomes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. and Social Psychology, 84, 697–721.
References 1157

Guimond, S., & Dubé-Simard, L. (1983). Relative deprivation theory and Hatfield, E., & Sprecher, S. (1984). Equity theory and behavior in organi-
the Quebec nationalist movement: The cognition–emotion distinction zations. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, 3, 95–124.
and the personal–group deprivation issue. Journal of Personality and Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation, and liberty: Volume 2—The mirage
Social Psychology, 44, 526–535. of social justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gurney, P., & Tierney, K. (1982). Relative deprivation and social move- Hegtvedt, K. A. (1990). The effects of relationship structure on emotional
ments: A critical look at twenty years of theory and research. responses to inequity. Social Psychology Quarterly, 53, 214–228.
Sociological Quarterly, 23, 33–47.
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Gintis, H., &
Gurr, T. (1970). Why men rebel. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. McElreath, R. (2001). In search of homo economicus: Behavioral
Gustafsson, M., Biel, A., & Gärling, T. (1999). Outcome-desirability bias in experiments in 15 small-scale societies. The American Economic
resource management problems. Thinking & Reasoning, 5, 327–337. Review, 91, 73–78.
Güth, W., Schmittberger, R., & Schwarze, B. (1982). An experimental Heuer, L., Blumenthal, E., Douglas, A., & Weinblatt, T. (1999). A deserv-
analysis of ultimatum bargaining. Journal of Economic Behavior and ingness approach to respect as a relationally based fairness judgment.
Organization, 3, 367–388. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 1279–1292.
Hafer, C. L. (2000a). Do innocent victims threaten the belief in a just Higgins, E. T., & Kruglanski, A. W. (Eds.) (2000). Motivational science:
world? Evidence from a modified Stroop task. Journal of Personality Social and personality perspectives. New York: Psychology Press.
and Social Psychology, 79, 165–173. Ho, R., ForsterLee, L., ForsterLee, R., & Crofts, N. (2002). Justice versus
Hafer, C. L. (2000b). Investment in long-term goals and commitment to vengeance: Motives underlying punitive judgements. Personality and
just means drive the need to believe in a just world. Personality and Individual Differences, 33, 365–378.
Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 1059–1073. Hoffman, C., & Hurst, N. (1990). Gender stereotypes: Perception or
Hafer, C. L., & Bègue, L. (2005). Experimental research on just-world rationalization? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58,
theory: Problems, developments, and future challenges. Psychological 197–208.
Bulletin, 131, 128–167. Hogue, M., & Yoder, J. D. (2003). The role of status in producing depressed
Hafer, C. L., Bègue, L., Choma, B. L., & Dempsey, J. L. (2005). Belief in entitlement in women’s and men’s pay allocations. Psychology of
a just world and commitment to long-term deserved outcomes. Social Women Quarterly, 27, 330–337.
Justice Research, 18, 429–444. Homans, G. C. (1974). Social behavior: Its elementary forms. Oxford:
Hafer, C. L., & Olson, J. M. (1993). Beliefs in a just world, discontent, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. (Original work published 1961).
and assertive actions by working women. Personality and Social Horwitt, S. D. (1989). Let them call me rebel: Saul Alinsky, his life and
Psychology Bulletin, 19, 30–38. legacy. New York: Knopf.
Hafer, C. L., & Olson, J. M. (2003). An analysis of empirical research on Houlden, P., LaTour, S., Walker, L., & Thibaut, J. (1978). Preference for
the scope of justice. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7, modes of dispute resolution as a function of process and decision con-
311–323. trol. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 14, 13–30.
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuition- Huo, Y. J. (2002). Justice and the regulation of social relations: When and
ist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834. why do group members deny claims to social goods? British Journal of
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality opposes justice: Social Psychology, 41, 535–562.
Conservatives have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize. Husami, Z. (1980). Marx on distributive justice. In M. Cohen, T. Nagel, &
Social Justice Research, 20, 98–116. T. Scanlon (Eds.), Marx, justice, and history (pp. 42–79). Princeton,
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2009). Planet of the Durkheimians, where commu- NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1978).
nity, authority, and sacredness are foundations of morality. In J. T. Jost, Jackson, J. M., & Harkins, S. G. (1985). Equity in effort: An explanation of
A. C. Kay, & H. Thorisdottir (Eds.), Social and psychological bases the social loafing effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
of ideology and system justification (pp. 371–401). New York: Oxford 49, 1199–1206.
University Press. Janoff-Bulman, R. (1992). Shattered assumptions: Towards a new psychol-
Haines, E. L., & Jost, J. T. (2000). Placating the powerless: Effects of legit- ogy of trauma. New York: Free Press.
imate and illegitimate explanation on affect, memory, and stereotyping. Janoff-Bulman, R. (2007). Erroneous assumptions: Popular belief in the
Social Justice Research, 13, 219–236. effectiveness of torture interrogation. Peace and Conflict: Journal of
Haney, C. (1993). Psychology and legal change: The impact of a decade. Peace Psychology, 13, 429–435.
Law and Human Behavior, 17, 371–398. Jasso, G. (1999). How much injustice is there in the world? Two new jus-
Hanson, J., & Yosifon, D. (2004). The situational character: A critical real- tice indexes. American Sociological Review, 64, 133–168.
ist perspective on the human animal. The Georgetown Law Journal, Johnson, J. D., Whitestone, E., Jackson, L. A., & Gatto, L. (1995). Justice
93, 1–179. is still not colorblind: Differential racial effects of exposure to inad-
Hardin, C. D., & Higgins, E. T. (1996). Shared reality: How social veri- missible evidence. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 21,
fication makes the subjective objective. In R. M. Sorrentino & E. T. 893–898.
Higgins (Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cognition, (Vol. 3, pp. Jones, E. E. (1998). Major developments in five decades of social psychol-
28–84). New York: Guilford. ogy. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of
Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 3–57). Boston: McGraw Hill.
1243–1248. (Original work published 1985).
Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, method, and point. Jones, H. B., Jr. (1997). The Protestant ethic: Weber’s model and the
New York: Clarendon Press. empirical literature. Human Relations, 50, 757–778.
Harman, G. (1999). Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue Jost, J. T. (1995). Negative illusions: Conceptual clarification and psycho-
ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the logical evidence concerning false consciousness. Political Psychology,
Aristotelian Society, 99, 315–331. 16, 397–424.
Harris, N. (2006). Reintegrative shaming, shame, and criminal justice. Jost, J. T. (1997). An experimental replication of the depressed–entitlement
Journal of Social Issues, 62, 327–346. effect among women. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 21, 387–393.
1158 Social Justice

Jost, J. T. (2009). “Elective affinities”: On the psychological bases of left– Jost, L. J., & Jost, J. T. (2007). Why Marx left philosophy for social
right differences. Psychological Inquiry, 20, 129–141. science. Theory & Psychology, 17, 297–322.
Jost, J. T., & Azzi, A. E. (1996). Microjustice and macrojustice in the allo- Kahneman, D., Diener, E., & Schwarz, N. (Eds.). (1999). Well-being:
cation of resources between experimental groups. Journal of Social The foundations of a hedonic psychology. New York: Russell Sage
Psychology, 136, 349–365. Foundation.
Jost, J. T., & Banaji, M. R. (1994). The role of stereotyping in system- Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J.L., & Thaler, R.H. (1986). Fairness as a con-
justification and the production of false consciousness. British Journal straint on profit seeking: Entitlement in the market. American Economic
of Social Psychology, 33, 1–27. Review, 76, 728–741.
Jost, J. T., Banaji, M. R., & Nosek, B. A. (2004). A decade of system jus- Kahneman, D., Schkade, D., & Sunstein, C. R. (1998). Shared outrage and
tification theory: Accumulated evidence of conscious and unconscious erratic awards: The psychology of punitive damages. Journal of Risk
bolstering of the status quo. Political Psychology, 25, 881–920. and Uncertainty, 16, 49–86.
Jost, J. T., Blount, S., Pfeffer, J., & Hunyady, Gy. (2003). Fair market Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.) (1982). Judgment under
ideology: Its cognitive-motivational underpinnings. In R. M. Kramer & uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. New York: Cambridge University
B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 25, pp. Press.
53–91). Oxford: Elsevier. Kang, J. (2005). Trojan horses of race. Harvard Law Review, 118,
Jost, J. T., & Burgess, D. (2000). Attitudinal ambivalence and the conflict 1489–1593.
between group and system justification motives in low status groups. Kang, J., & Banaji, M. R. (2006). Fair measures: A behavioral realist revi-
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 293–305. sion of “affirmative action.” California Law Review, 94, 1063–1118.
Jost, J. T., Glaser, J., Kruglanski, A. W., & Sulloway, F. J. (2003). Political Kant, I. (1952). The science of right. (W. Hastie, Trans.). In R. Hutchins
conservatism as motivated social cognition. Psychological Bulletin, (Ed.), Great books of the Western world (pp. 397–446). Edinburgh:
129, 339–375. T. & T. Clark. (Original work published 1790).
Jost, J. T., & Hunyady, O. (2002). The psychology of system justification Kant, I. (1993). Grounding for the metaphysics of morals (3rd edition,
and the palliative function of ideology. European Review of Social J. W. Ellington, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Original work pub-
Psychology, 13, 111–153. lished 1785).
Jost, J. T., & Hunyady, O. (2005). Antecedents and consequences of Katz, I., & Hass, R. G. (1988). Racial ambivalence and American value
system-justifying ideologies. Current Directions in Psychological conflict: Correlational and priming studies of dual cognitive structures.
Science, 14, 260–265. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, 893–905.
Jost, J. T., & Jost, L. J. (2009). Virtue ethics and the social psychology Kay, A. C., Gaucher, D., Napier, J. L., Callan, M. J., & Laurin, K. (2008).
of character: Philosophical lessons from the person-situation debate. God and the Government: Testing a compensatory control mechanism
Journal of Research in Personality, 43, 253–254. for the support of external systems. Journal of Personality and Social
Jost, J. T., & Kay, A. C. (2005). Exposure to benevolent sexism and com- Psychology, 95, 18–35.
plementary gender stereotypes: Consequences for specific and dif- Kay, A. C., Gaucher, D., Peach, J. M., Laurin, K., Friesen, J., Zanna, M. P., &
fuse forms of system justification. Journal of Personality and Social Spencer, S. J. (2009). Inequality, discrimination, and the power
Psychology, 88, 498–509. of the status quo: Direct evidence for a motivation to see is
Jost, J. T., Ledgerwood, A., & Hardin, C. D. (2008). Shared reality, system the way things are as the way they should be. Journal of Personality
justification, and the relational basis of ideological beliefs. Social and and Social Psychology, 97, 421–434.
Personality Psychology Compass, 2, 171–186. Kay, A.C., & Jost, J.T. (2003). Complementary justice: Effects of “poor
Jost, J. T., Liviatan, I., van der Toorn, J., Ledgerwood, A., Mandisodza, A., & but happy” and “poor but honest” stereotype exemplars on system
Nosek, B.A. (2009). System justification: How do we know it’s moti- justification and implicit activation of the justice motive. Journal of
vated? In A.C. Kay et al. (Eds.), The psychology of justice and legiti- Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 823–837.
macy: The Ontario symposium (Vol. 11). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Kay, A. C., Jost, J. T., Mandisodza, A. N., Sherman, S. J., Petrocelli, J. V., &
Jost, J. T., & Major, B. (Eds.) (2001). The psychology of legitimacy: Johnson, A. L. (2007). Panglossian ideology in the service of system
Emerging perspectives on ideology, justice, and intergroup relations. justification: How complementary stereotypes help us to rational-
New York: Cambridge University Press. ize inequality. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social
Jost, J. T., Nosek, B. A., & Gosling, S. D. (2008). Ideology: Its resur- Psychology (pp. 305–358). San Diego, CA: Academic Press/Elsevier.
gence in social, personality, and political psychology. Perspectives on Kay, A. C., Jost, J. T., & Young, S. (2005). Victim derogation and victim
Psychological Science, 3, 126–136. enhancement as alternate routes to system justification. Psychological
Jost, J. T., Pelham, B. W., & Carvallo, M. R. (2002). Non-conscious forms of Science, 16, 240–246.
system justification: Implicit and behavioral preferences for higher sta- Kay, A. C., & Ross, L. (2003). The perceptual push: The interplay of
tus groups. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 586–602. implicit cues and explicit situational construals on behavioral intentions
Jost, J. T., & Ross, L. (1999). Fairness norms and the potential for mutual in the prisoner’s dilemma. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
agreements involving majority and minority groups. In E. Mannix, 39, 634–643.
M. Neale, & R. Wageman (Eds.), Research on managing groups and Kay, A. C., Wheeler, S. C., Bargh, J. A., & Ross, L. (2004). Material prim-
teams/Volume 2: Context (pp. 93–114). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. ing: The influence of mundane physical objects on situational con-
Jost, J. T., & Thompson, E. P. (2000). Group-based dominance and opposi- strual and competitive behavioral choice. Organizational Behavior and
tion to equality as independent predictors of self-esteem, ethnocentrism, Human Decision Processes, 95, 83–96.
and social policy attitudes among African Americans and European Kay, A. C., & Zanna, M. P. (2009). A contextual analysis of the social and
Americans. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 36, 209–232. psychological consequences of system justification. In J. T. Jost, A. C.
Jost, J. T., Wakslak, C., & Tyler, T.R. (2008). System justification theory Kay, & H. Thoristtodor (Eds.), Social and psychological bases of ideol-
and the alleviation of emotional distress: Palliative effects of ideol- ogy and system justification. New York: Oxford University Press.
ogy in an arbitrary social hierarchy and in society. In K. Hegtvedt & Kelln, B. R. C., & Ellard, J. H. (1999). An equity theory analysis of the
J. Clay-Warner (Eds.), Justice: Advances in group processes (Vol. 25, impact of forgiveness and retribution on transgressor compliance.
pp. 181–211). Bingley, England: JAI/Emerald. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 864–872.
References 1159

Kelman, H. C. (2001). Reflections on the social and psychological pro- Krieger, L. H., & Fiske, S. T. (2006). Behavioral realism in employment
cesses of legitimization and delegitimization. In J. T. Jost & B. Major discrimination law: Implicit bias and disparate treatment. California
(Eds.), The psychology of legitimacy: Emerging perspectives on ideol- Law Review, 94, 997–1062.
ogy, justice, and intergroup relations (pp. 54–73). Cambridge, England: Krech, D., & Crutchfield, R. S. (1948). Theory and problems of social psy-
Cambridge University Press. chology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Kelman, H. C., & Hamilton, V. L. (1989). Crimes of obedience: Toward Kristiansen, C. M., & Giulietti, R. (1990). Perceptions of wife abuse: Effects
a social psychology of authority and responsibility. New Haven, CT: of gender, attitudes toward women, and just-world beliefs among col-
Yale University Press. lege students. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 14, 177–189.
Kernan, M. C., & Hanges, P. J. (2001). Survivor reactions to reorganiza- Kuhlman, D. M., Camac, C., & Cunha, D. A. (1986). Individual differ-
tion: Antecedents and consequences of procedural, interpersonal, and ences in social orientation. In H. Wilke, D. Messick, & C. Rutte (Eds.),
informational justice. Journal of Applied Psychology, 87, 916–928. Experimental social dilemmas (pp. 151–176). New York: Verlag Peter
Kessler, T., & Mummendey, A. (2001). Is there any scapegoat around? Lang.
Determinants of intergroup conflicts at different categorization levels. Kulik, C. T., & Ambrose, M. L. (1992). Personal and situational deter-
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 1090–1102. minants of referent choice. Academy of Management Review, 17,
Kinder, D. R., & Sears, D. O. (1985). Public opinion and political action. 212–237.
In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology Kurzban, R., & Houser, D. (2001). Individual differences in cooperation
(3rd ed., pp. 659–741). New York: Random House. in a circular public goods game. European Journal of Personality, 15,
Klandermans, B., Van der Toorn, J., & Van Stekelenburg, J. (2008). 37–52.
Embeddedness and identity: How immigrants turn grievances into Kurzban, R., & Leary, M. R. (2001). Evolutionary origins of stigmatiza-
action. American Sociological Review, 73, 992–1012. tion: The functions of social exclusion. Psychological Bulletin, 127,
Klineberg, O. (1940). Social psychology. New York: Holt. 187–208.
Kluegel, J. R., & Smith, E. R. (1986). Beliefs about inequality: Americans’ Lamm, H., & Schwinger, T. (1980). Norms concerning distributive jus-
views of what is and what ought to be. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de tice: Are needs taken into consideration in allocation decisions? Social
Gruyter. Psychology Quarterly, 4, 425–429.
Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Cushman, F., & Hauser, M. Lane, K. A., Kang, J. & Banaji, M. R. (2007). Implicit social cognition and
et al. (2007). Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral the law. Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 3, 427–451.
judgements, Nature, 446, 908–911. Latimer, J., Dowden, C., & Muise, D. (2005). The effectiveness of restor-
Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The cognitive-developmental ative justice practices: A meta-analysis. The Prison Journal, 85,
approach to socialization. In D. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of socializa- 127–144.
tion theory and research (pp. 347–480). Chicago: Rand-McNally. Lavine, H., Lodge, M., & Freitas, K. (2005). Threat, authoritarianism, and
Kohlberg, L. (1978). Revisions in the theory and practice of moral develop- selective exposure to information. Political Psychology, 26, 219–244.
ment. In W. Damon (Ed.), New directions for child development: Moral Lawrence, C.R. (2008). Unconscious racism revisited: Reflections on
development (Vol. 2, pp. 83–87). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. the impact and origins of “the id, the ego, and equal protection.”
Kollock, P. (1998). Social dilemmas: The anatomy of cooperation. Annual Connecticut Law Review, 40, 931–978.
Review of Sociology, 24, 183–214. Leach, C. W., Iyer, A., & Pedersen, A. (2007). Angry opposition to gov-
Komorita, S. S., & Parks, C. D. (1995). Interpersonal relations: Mixed- ernment redress: When the structurally advantaged perceive them-
motive interaction. Annual Review of Psychology, 46, 183–207. selves as relatively deprived. British Journal of Social Psychology, 46,
Komorita, S. S., & Parks, C. D. (1996). Social dilemmas. Boulder, CO: 191–204.
Westview. Leith, K. P., & Baumeister, R. F. (1998). Empathy, shame, guilt, and nar-
Konow, J. (2003). Which is the fairest one of all? A positive analysis of ratives of interpersonal conflicts: Guilt-prone people are better at per-
justice theories. Journal of Economic Literature, 41, 1188–1239. spective taking. Journal of Personality, 66, 1–37.
Kornblith, H. (Ed.) (1999). Naturalizing epistemology. Cambridge, MA: Lerner, M. J. (1974). The justice motive: “Equity” and “parity” among
MIT Press. children. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 539–550.
Kramer, R. M., & Brewer, M. B. (1984). Effects of group identity on Lerner, M. J. (1975). The justice motive of social behavior: Introduction.
resource use in a simulated commons dilemma. Journal of Personality Journal of Social Issues 31, 1–19.
and Social Psychology, 46, 1044–1057. Lerner, M. J. (1977). The justice motive: Some hypotheses as to its origins
Kramer, R. M., McClintock, C. G., & Messick, D. M. (1986). Social values and forms. Journal of Personality, 45, 1–52.
and cooperative response to a simulated resource conservation crisis. Lerner, M. J. (1980). The belief in a just world: A fundamental delusion.
Journal of Personality, 54, 576–592. New York: Plenum Press.
Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle: Political philosophy. New York: Oxford Lerner, M. J. (1987). Integrating societal and psychological rules of entitle-
University Press. ment: The basic task of each social actor and the fundamental problem
Krebs, D. L. (2008). How selfish by nature? In C. Crawford & D. L. Krebs for the social sciences. Social Justice Research, 1, 107–121.
(Eds), Foundations of evolutionary psychology (pp. 293–312). New Lerner, M. J. (2003). The justice motive: Where social psychologists found
York: Taylor & Francis. it, how they lost it, and why they may not find it again. Personality and
Krebs, D., & Miller, D. T. (1985). Altruism and aggression. In G. Lindzey & Social Psychology Review, 7, 388–399.
E. Aronson (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (3rd ed., pp. 1–71). Lerner, M. J., & Miller, D. T. (1978). Just world research and the attri-
New York: Random House. bution process: Looking back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85,
Kreps, D. M. (1990). A course in microeconomic theory. Princeton, NJ: 1030–1051.
Princeton University Press. Lerner, M. J., Miller, D. T., & Holmes, J. G. (1976). Deserving and the
Krieger, L. H. (1995). The content of our categories: A cognitive bias emergence of forms of justice. In L. Berkowitz & E. Walster (Eds.),
approach to discrimination and equal employment opportunity. Advances in experimental social psychology (pp. 133–162). New York:
Stanford Law Review, 47, 1161–1248. Academic Press.
1160 Social Justice

Lerner, M. J., & Simmons, C. H. (1966). Observer’s reaction to the “innocent Lupfer, M. B., Weeks, K. P., Doan, K. A. & Houston, D. A. (2000). Folk
victim”: Compassion or rejection? Journal of Personality and Social conceptions of fairness and unfairness. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 4, 203–210. Psychology, 30, 405–428.
Lerner, M. J., & Whitehead, L. A. (1980). Procedural justice viewed in the Maass, A., Cadinu, M., Guarnieri, G., & Grasselli, A. (2003). Sexual
context of justice motive theory. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social harassment under social identity threat: The computer harassment para-
interaction: Experimental and theoretical contributions from psycho- digm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 853–870.
logical research (pp. 219–256). Bern, Austria: Huber. Maes, J. (1998). Immanent justice and ultimate justice: Two ways of
Leung, K., & Stephan, W. G. (2000). Conflict and injustice in intercul- believing in justice. In L. Montada & M. J. Lerner (Eds.), Responses to
tural relations: Insights from the Arab-Israeli and Sino-British disputes. victimizations and belief in a just world (pp. 9–40). New York: Plenum
In S. Renshon & J. Duckitt (Eds.), Political psychology: Cultural and Press.
cross-cultural perspectives (pp. 128–145). New York: McMillan. Major, B. (1994). From social inequality to personal entitlement: The role
Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New of social comparisons, legitimacy appraisals, and group membership.
approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. Gergen, In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol.
M. Greenberg, & R. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange (pp. 27–55). New 26, pp. 293–355). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
York: Plenum Press. Major, B., Gramzow, R. H., McCoy, S. K., Levin, S., Schmader, T., &
Leventhal, G. S., & Anderson, D. (1970). Self-interest and the maintenance Sidanius, J. (2002). Perceiving personal discrimination: The role of
of equity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 15, 57–62. group status and legitimizing ideology. Journal of Personality and
Leventhal, G. S., Karuza, J., & Fry, W. R. (1980). Beyond fairness: A the- Social Psychology, 82, 269–282.
ory of allocation preferences. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social Major, B., Quinton, W. J., & McCoy, S. K. (2002). Antecedents and con-
interaction (pp. 167–218). New York: Springer-Verlag. sequences of attributions to discrimination: Theoretical and empirical
Levine, J. M., & Moreland, R. L. (1987). Social comparison and outcome advances. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psy-
evaluation in group contexts. In J. C. Masters & W. P. Smith (Eds.), chology (Vol. 34, pp. 251–330). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Social comparison, social justice, and relative deprivation: Theoretical, Maner, J. K., Luce, C. L., Neuberg, S. L., Cialdini, R. B., Brown, S.,
empirical, and policy perspectives (pp. 105–127). Hillsdale, NJ: Sagarin, B. J. (2002). The effects of perspective taking on helping: Still
Erlbaum. no evidence for altruism. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Lewin, K. (1948a). Experiments in social space. In K. Lewin (Ed.), 28, 1601–1610.
Resolving social conflicts (pp. 71–83). New York: Harper. (Original Mansbridge, J. (2005). Cracking through hegemonic ideology: The logic of
work published 1939). formal justice. Social Justice Research, 18, 335–347.
Lewin, K. (1948b). Self-hatred among Jews. In K. Lewin (Ed.), Resolving March, J. G., & Simon, H. A. (1958). Organizations. Oxford: Wiley.
social conflicts (pp. 186–200). New York: Harper. (Original work pub-
Markowski, B. (1988). Injustice and arousal. Social Justice Research, 2,
lished 1941).
223–233.
Lewin, K. (1951). Problems of research in social psychology. In K. Lewin
Martin, J. (1986). The tolerance of injustice. In J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman, &
(ed.), Field theory in social science: Selected theoretical papers (pp.
M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative deprivation and social comparison: The
155–169). New York: Harper & Row. (Original work published 1944).
Ontario Symposium (pp. 217–242). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Liberman, V., Samuels, S. M., & Ross, L. (2004). The name of the game:
Martin, J., Scully, M., & Levitt, B. (1990). Injustice and the legitimation of
Predictive power of reputations versus situational labels in determining
revolution: Damning the past, excusing the present, and neglecting the
prisoner’s dilemma game moves. Personality and Social Psychology
future. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 281–290.
Bulletin, 30, 1175–1185.
Masterson, S. S., Lewis, K., Goldman, B. M., & Taylor, M. S. (2000).
Liebrand, W. B., Jansen, R. W., Rijken, V. M., & Suhre, C. J. (1986). Might
Integrating justice and social exchange: The differing effects of fair pro-
over morality: Social values and the perception of other players in experi-
cedures and treatment on work relationships. Academy of Management
mental games. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 22, 203–215.
Journal, 43, 738–748.
Lind, E. A., Kanfer, R., & Earley, P. C. (1990). Voice, control, and pro-
Matania, E. & Yaniv, I. (2007). Resource priority, fairness, and equality-
cedural justice: Instrumental and noninstrumental concerns in fair-
efficiency compromises. Social Justice Research, 20, 497–510.
ness judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59,
952–959. McClintock, C. G., & Allison, S. T. (1989). Social value orientation and
helping behavior. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 19, 353–362.
Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural
justice. New York: Plenum. McCoy, S. K., & Major, B. (2007). Priming meritocracy and the psy-
chological justification of inequality. Journal of Experimental Social
Lind, E. A., & Van den Bos, K. (2002). When fairness works: Toward
Psychology, 43, 341–351.
a general theory of uncertainty management. In B. M. Staw &
R. M. Kramer (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior McFatter, R. M. (1982). Purposes of punishment: Effects of utilities of
(pp. 181–223). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. criminal sanctions on perceived appropriateness. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 67, 255–267.
Link, B. G., & Phelan, J. C. (2001). Conceptualizing stigma. Annual
Review of Sociology, 27, 363–385. McGuire, W. J. (1965). Discussion of William N. Schoenfeld’s paper.
Lipkus, I. M., & Bissonnette, V. L. (1996). Relationships among belief In O. Klineberg & R. Christie (Eds.), Perspectives in social psychology
in a just world, willingness to accommodate, and marital well-being. (pp. 135–140). New York: Holt.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 1043–1056. McGuire, W J. (1985). Attitudes and attitude change. In G. Lindzey &
Lipkus, I. M., Dalbert, C., & Siegler, I. C. (1996). The importance of E. Aronson (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (3rd ed., Vol. 2, pp.
distinguishing the belief in a just world for self versus for others: 233–346). New York: Random House.
Implications for psychological well-being. Personality and Social McKee, I. R., & Feather, N. T. (2008). Revenge, retribution, and values:
Psychology Bulletin, 22, 666–677. Social attitudes and punitive sentencing. Social Justice Research, 21,
Loewenstein, G. F., Thompson, L., & Bazerman, M. H. (1989). Social 138–163.
utility and decision making in interpersonal contexts. Journal of McPhail, C. (1971). Civil disorder participation: A critical examination of
Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 426–441. recent research. American Sociological Review, 36, 1058–1073.
References 1161

Messick, D. M., & McClintock, C. G. (1968). Motivational bases of choice Mullen, E., & Skitka, L. J. (2006). Exploring the psychological underpin-
in experimental games. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 4, nings of the moral mandate effect: Motivated reasoning, group differ-
1–25. entiation, or anger? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90,
Messick, D. M., Wilke, H., Brewer, M. B., Kramer, R. M., Zemke, P. E., & 629–643.
Lui, L. (1983). Individual adaptations and structural change as solu- Murphy, K., & Harris, N. (2007). Shaming, shame and recidivism: A test of
tions to social dilemmas. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, reintegrative shaming theory in the white-collar crime context. British
44, 294–309. Journal of Criminology, 47, 900–917.
Michelbach, P. A., Scott, J. T., Mattland, R. E., & Bornstein, B. H. (2003). Nagel, T. (1991). Equality and partiality. New York: Oxford University
Doing Rawls justice: An experimental study of income distribution Press.
norms. American Journal of Political Science, 47, 523–539. Napier, J. L., & Jost, J. T. (2008a). Why are conservatives happier than
Mikula, G. (1984). Justice and fairness in interpersonal relations: Thoughts liberals? Psychological Science, 19, 565–572.
and suggestions. In H. Tajfel (Ed.), The social dimension (pp. 204– Napier, J. L., & Jost, J. T. (2008b). The “antidemocratic personality” revis-
227). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. ited: A cross-national investigation of working-class authoritarianism.
Mikula, G., & Wenzel, M. (2000). Justice and social conflict. International Journal of Social Issues, 64, 595–617.
Journal of Psychology, 35, 126–135. Napier, J. L., Mandisodza, A. N., Andersen, S. M., & Jost, J. T. (2006).
Miles, E. W., Hatfield, J. D., & Huseman, R. C. (1994). Equity sensitiv- System justification in responding to the poor and displaced in the
ity and outcome importance. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 15, aftermath of Hurricane Katrina. Analyses of Social Issues and Public
585–596. Policy, 6, 57–73.
Mill, J. S. (1869). On liberty. London: Longman, Roberts, & Green. Napier, J. L., & Tyler, T. R. (2008). Does moral conviction really override
(Original work published 1859.) concerns about procedural justice? A reexamination of the value pro-
tection model. Social Justice Research, 21, 509–528.
Mill, J. S. (1910). Utilitarianism, liberty and representation. New York:
E.P. Dutton. Neuberg, S. L., Cialdini, R. B., Brown, S. L., Luce, C., Sagarin, B. J., &
Lewis, B. P. (1997). Does empathy lead to anything other than superfi-
Miller, D. (1999). Principles of social justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
cial helping? Comment on Batson et al. (1997). Journal of Personality
University Press.
and Social Psychology, 73, 510–516.
Miller, D. T. (1977). Personal deservingness versus justice for others:
Nielsen, K. (1985). Equality and liberty: A defense of radical egalitarian-
An exploration of the justice motive. Journal of Experimental Social
ism. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.
Psychology, 13, 1–13.
Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcom-
Miller, D. T. (2001). Disrespect and the experience of injustice. Annual
ings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Review of Psychology, 52, 527–553.
Nosek, B. A., Banaji, M. R., & Jost, J. T. (2009). The politics of intergroup
Miller, F. D., Jr. (1995). Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle’s politics.
attitudes. In J. T. Jost, A. C. Kay, & H. Thorisdottir (Eds.), Social and
New York: Oxford.
psychological bases of ideology and system justification (pp. 480–506).
Mishel, L., Bernstein, J., & Allegretta, S. (2005). The state of working New York: Oxford University Press.
America 2004/2005. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.
Mitchell, G., & Tetlock, P. E. (2006). Antidiscrimination law and the perils
O’Neill, B. S., & Mone, M. A. (1998). Investigating equity sensitivity as a
of mindreading. Ohio State Law Journal, 67, 1023–1121.
moderator of relations between self-efficacy and workplace attitudes.
Mitchell, G., Tetlock, P. E., Mellers, B. A., & Ordóñez, L. D. (1993). Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 805–816.
Judgments of social justice: Compromises between equality and effi-
O’Brien, L. T., & Major, B. (2005). System-justifying beliefs and psycho-
ciency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 629–639.
logical well-being: The roles of group status and identity. Personality
Mitchell, G., Tetlock, P. E., Newman, D. G., & Lerner, J. S. (2003). and Social Psychology Bulletin, 31, 1718–1729.
Experiments behind the veil: Structural influences on judgments of
Olson, J. M., & Hafer, C. L. (2001). Tolerance of personal deprivation.
social justice. Political Psychology, 24, 519–547.
In J. T. Jost & B. Major (Eds.), The psychology of legitimacy: Emerging
Monroe, K. R. (2004). The hand of compassion: Portraits of moral choice perspectives on ideology, justice, and intergroup relations. (pp. 157–
during the Holocaust. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 175). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Montada, L. (2002). Doing justice to the justice motive. In M. Ross & Olson, J. M., & Hazlewood, J. D. (1986). Relative deprivation and social
D. T. Miller (Eds.), The justice motive in everyday life (pp. 41–62). comparison: An integrative perspective. In J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman,
New York: Cambridge University Press. & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative deprivation and social comparison: The
Montada, L. (2003). Justice, equity, and fairness in human relations. Ontario symposium (Vol. 4, pp. 1–15). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
In T. Millon & M. J. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of psychology: Olson, J. M., Roese, N. J., Meen, J., & Robertson, D. J. (1995). The pre-
Personality and social psychology (Vol. 5, pp. 532–568). Hoboken, NJ: conditions and consequences of relative deprivation: Two field studies.
John Wiley & Sons. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 25, 944–964.
Montada, L., & Schneider, A. (1989). Justice and emotional reactions to Opotow, S. (1995). Drawing the line: Social categorization, moral exclu-
the disadvantaged. Social Justice Research, 3, 313–344. sion, and the scope of justice. In B. Bunker & J. Z. Rubin (Eds.),
Moore, B. Jr. (1978). Injustice: The social bases of obedience and revolt. Conflict, cooperation, and justice: Essays inspired by the work of
White Plains, NY: Sharpe. Morton Deutsch (pp. 347–369). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Mowday, R. T. (1991). Equity theory predictions of behavior in organi- Orbell, J. M., van de Kragt, A. J. C., & Dawes, R. M. (1988). Explaining
zations. In R. M. Steers & L. W. Porter (Eds.), Motivation and work discussion-induced cooperation. Journal of Personality and Social
behavior (3rd ed., pp. 91–112). New York: McGraw-Hill. Psychology, 54, 811–819.
Mulder, L. B., van Dijk, E., De Cremer, D., & Wilke, H.A.M. (2006). Pancer, S. M. (1988). Salience of appeal and avoidance of helping situa-
Undermining trust and cooperation: The paradox of sanctioning sys- tions. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science, 20, 133–139.
tems in social dilemmas. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Parfit, D. (1998). Equality and priority. In A. Mason (Ed.), Ideals of equal-
42, 147–162. ity (pp. 1–20). Oxford: Blackwell.
1162 Social Justice

Park, J. H., Schaller, M., & Van Vugt, M. (2008). Psychology of human Ring, K. (1967). Experimental social psychology: Some sober ques-
kin recognition: Heuristic cues, erroneous inferences, and their impli- tions about some frivolous values. Journal of Experimental Social
cations. Review of General Psychology, 12, 215–235. Psychology, 3, 113–123.
Payne, B. K., & Cameron, C. D. (in press). Divided minds, divided mor- Roberts, J. V., & Stalans, L. J. (2004). Restorative sentencing: Exploring
als: How implicit social cognition underpins and undermines our sense the views of the public. Social Justice Research, 17, 315–334.
of social justice. In B. Gawronski & B.K. Payne (Eds.), Handbook of Roch, S. G., & Samuelson, C. D. (1997). Effects of environmental uncer-
implicit social cognition: Measurement, theory, and applications. New tainty and social value orientation in resource dilemmas. Organizational
York: Guilford. Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 70, 221–235.
Pelham, B. W., & Hetts, J. J. (2001). Underworked and overpaid: Elevated Roche, D. (2006). Dimensions of restorative justice. Journal of Social
entitlement in men’s self-pay. Journal of Experimental Social Issues, 62, 217–238.
Psychology, 37, 93–103.
Rodriguez, N. (2007). Restorative justice at work: Examining the impact
Perugini, M., & Gallucci, M. (2001). Individual differences and social of restorative justice resolutions on juvenile recidivism. Crime &
norms: The distinction between reciprocators and prosocials. European Delinquency, 53, 355–379.
Journal of Personality, 15, 19–35.
Ross, L., & Ward, A. (1996). Naïve realism in everyday life: Implications
Peters, S. L., Van den Bos, K., & Bobocel, D. R. (2004). The moral supe- for social conflict and misunderstanding. In E. S. Reed, E. Turiel, &
riority effect: Self versus other differences in satisfaction with being T. Brown (Eds.), Values and knowledge (pp. 103–135). Hillsdale, NJ:
overpaid. Social Justice Research, 17, 257–273. Erlbaum.
Pettigrew, T. F. (1967). Social evaluation theory: Convergences and appli- Rossi, P. H. & Berk, R. A. (1997). Just punishments: Federal guidelines
cations. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 15, 241–311. and public views. New York: De Gruyter.
Pettigrew, T. F. (2002). Summing up: Relative deprivation as a key social Rubin, Z., & Peplau, L. A. (1975). Who believes in a just world? Journal
psychological concept. In I. Walker & H. J. Smith (Eds.), Relative depri- of Social Issues, 31, 65–89.
vation: Specification, development, and integration. (pp. 351–373).
Rudman, L. A., & Ashmore, R. D. (2007). Discrimination and the Implicit
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Association Test. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 10,
Pettigrew, T. F., Christ, O., Wagner, U., Meertens, R. W., van Dick, R., & 359–372.
Zick, A. (2008). Relative deprivation and intergroup prejudice. Journal
Rudman, L. A., Feinberg, J., & Fairchild, K. (2002). Minority members’
of Social Issues, 64, 385–401.
implicit attitudes: Automatic ingroup bias as a function of group status.
Pettigrew, T. F., & Meertens, R. W. (1995). Subtle and blatant prejudice in Social Cognition, 20, 294–320.
Western Europe. European Journal of Social Psychology, 25, 57–75.
Rummel, R. J. (1997). Death by government. New Brunswick, NJ:
Piaget, J. (1965). The moral judgment of the child. New York: Free Press. Transactions.
(Original work published 1932).
Runciman, W. G. (1966). Relative deprivation and social justice: A study
Piven, F. F., & Cloward, R. A. (1978). Poor people’s movements: Why they of attitudes to social inequality in twentieth-century England. Berkeley:
succeed, how they fail. New York: Vintage Books. University of California Press.
Pojman, L. P., & Westmoreland, R. (Eds.). (1997). Equality: Selected read- Ryan, W. (1971). Blaming the victim. New York: Pantheon Books.
ings. New York: Oxford University Press.
Sampson, E. E. (1983). Justice and the critique of pure psychology. New
Pratto, F., Sidanius, J., Stallworth, L. M., & Malle, B. F. (1994). Social York: Plenum.
dominance orientation: A personality variable predicting social and
Samuelson, C. D. (1991). Perceived task difficulty, causal attributions, and
political attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67,
preferences for structural change in resource dilemmas. Personality
741–763.
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17, 181–187.
Puhl, R., & Brownell, K. D. (2003). Ways of coping with obesity stigma:
Sandel, M. J. (1998). Liberalism and the limits of justice (2nd ed.). New
Review and conceptual analysis. Eating Behaviors, 4, 53–78.
York: Cambridge University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity
Schaller, M., & Cialdini, R. B. (1988). The economics of empathic help-
and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.
ing: Support for a mood-management motive. Journal of Experimental
Quinn, D. M., & Crocker, J. (1999). When ideology hurts: Effects of belief Social Psychology, 24, 163–181.
in the Protestant ethic and feeling overweight on the psychological
Schmitt, M., Behner, R., Montada, L., Müller, L., & Müller-Fohrbrodt, G.
well-being of women. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
(2000). Gender, ethnicity, and education as privileges: Exploring
77, 402–414.
the generalizability of the existential guilt reaction. Social Justice
Rabin, M. (1993). Incorporating fairness into game theory and economics. Research, 13, 313–337.
American Economic Review, 83, 1281–1302.
Schmitt, M., & Dorfel, M. (1999). Procedural injustice at work, justice
Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. sensitivity, job satisfaction and psychosomatic well-being. European
Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Journal of Social Psychology, 29, 443–453.
Reich, W. (1970). The mass psychology of fascism (V. R. Carfagno, Trans.). Schroeder, D. A., Steel, J. E., Woodell, A. J., & Bembenek, A. F. (2003).
New York: Farrar, Straus, & Giroux. (Original work published 1946). Justice within social dilemmas. Personality and Social Psychology
Reichle, B., & Schmitt, M. (2002). Helping and rationalization as alterna- Review, 7, 374–387.
tive strategies for restoring the belief in a just world: Evidence from Schulz, U., & May, T. (1989). The recording of social orientations with
longitudinal change analyses. In M. Ross & D. T. Miller (Eds.), The ranking and pair comparison procedures. European Journal of Social
justice motive in everyday life (pp. 127–148). New York: Cambridge Psychology, 19, 41–59.
University Press. Schwinger, T. (1986). The need principle of distributive justice. In
Reis, H. T. (1984). The multidimensionality of justice. In R. Folger (Ed.), H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice in social
The sense of injustice: Social psychological perspectives (pp. 25–61). relations (pp. 211–226). New York: Plenum.
New York: Plenum Press. Scott, J. T., Matland, R. E., Michelbach, P. A., & Bornstein, B. H. (2001).
Rim, Y. (1988). Attitudes and the confluence model. Small Group Behavior, Just deserts: An experimental study of distributive justice norms.
19, 153–161. American Journal of Political Science, 45, 749–767.
References 1163

Sears, D. O., van Laar, C., Carrillo, M., & Kosterman, R. (1997). Is it really In R. Spears, P. J. Oakes, N. Ellemers, & S. A. Haslam (Eds.), The social
racism? The origins of White Americans’ opposition to race-targeted psychology of stereotyping and group life (pp. 336–358). Malden, MA:
policies. Public Opinion Quarterly, 61, 16–53. Blackwell Publishing.
Sen, A. (1979). The welfare basis of real income comparisons. Journal of Staub, E. (1992). The roots of evil: The origins of genocide and other group
Economic Literature, 17, 1–45. violence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Shah, J. Y., & Gardner, W. L. (Eds.). (2008). Handbook of motivation sci- Stenner, K. (2005). The authoritarian dynamic. New York: Cambridge
ence. New York: Guilford Press. University Press.
Shapiro, D. L., & Brett, J. M. (2005). What is the role of control in organi- Stich, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT
zational justice? In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook of Press.
organizational justice. (pp. 155–177). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Stiglitz, J. E. (2004). The roaring nineties. New York: Norton.
Shapiro, I. (2003). The moral foundations of politics. New Haven, CT: Yale
Stouffer, S. A., Suchman, E. A., Devinney, L. C., Star, S. A., & Williams,
University Press.
R. M., Jr. (1949). The American soldier: Adjustment during army life
Shnabel, N., & Nadler, A. (2008). A needs-based model of reconciliation: (Studies in social psychology in World War II, vol. 1). Princeton, NJ:
Satisfying the differential emotional needs of victim and perpetrator as Princeton University Press.
a key to promoting reconciliation. Journal of Personality and Social
Strang, H., Sherman, L., Angel, C. M., Woods, D. J., Bennett, S., Newbury-
Psychology, 94, 116–132.
Birch, D., et al. (2006). Victim evaluations of face-to-face restorative
Sidanius, J., Mitchell, M., Haley, H., & Navarrete, C. D. (2006). Support justice conferences: A quasi-experimental analysis. Journal of Social
for harsh criminal sanctions and criminal justice beliefs: A social domi- Issues, 62, 281–306.
nance perspective. Social Justice Research, 19, 433–449.
Struch, N., & Schwartz, S. H. (1989). Intergroup aggression: Its predictors
Sidanius, J., & Pratto, F. (1999). Social dominance: An intergroup theory and distinctness from in-group bias. Journal of Personality and Social
of social hierarchy and oppression. New York: Cambridge University Psychology, 56, 364–373.
Press.
Sunstein, C. R. (Ed.) (2000). Behavioral law and economics. New York:
Sidanius, J., Pratto, F., & Bobo, L. (1996). Racism, conservatism, affir- Cambridge University Press.
mative action, and intellectual sophistication: A matter of principled
conservatism or group dominance? Journal of Personality and Social Sutton, R. M., Douglas, K. M., Wilkin, K., Elder, T. J., Cole, J. M., &
Psychology, 70, 476–490. Stathi, S. (2008). Justice for whom, exactly? Beliefs in justice for the
self and various others. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Simon, H. A. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley. 34, 528–541.
Simpson, B. (2004). Social values, subjective transformations, and coop-
Sweeney, P. D., & McFarlin, D. B. (1993). Workers’ evaluations of the
eration in social dilemmas. Social Psychology Quarterly, 67, 385–395.
“ends” and the “means”: An examination of four models of distributive
Skitka, L. J. (2002). Do the means always justify the ends, or do the ends and procedural justice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
sometimes justify the means? A value model of justice reasoning. Processes, 55, 23–40.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 588–597.
Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1986). The social identity theory of intergroup
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G. (2005). Moral conviction: behavior. In S. Worchel & W. G. Austin (Eds.), The psychology of inter-
Another contributor to attitude strength or something more? Journal of group relations (pp. 7–24). Chicago: Nelson-Hall.
Personality and Social Psychology, 88, 895–917.
Tangney, J. P. (1995). Recent advances in the empirical study of shame and
Skitka, L. J., & Houston, D. A. (2001). When due process is of no conse- guilt. American Behavioral Scientist, 38, 1132–1145.
quence: Moral mandates and presumed defendant guilt or innocence.
Tenbrunsel, A. E., & Messick, D. M. (1999). Sanctioning systems, deci-
Social Justice Research, 14, 305–326.
sion frames, and cooperation. Administrative Science Quarterly, 44,
Skitka, L. J. & Mullen, E. (2002). Understanding judgments of fairness 684–707.
in a real-world political context: A test of the value protection model
of justice reasoning. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, Thaler, R. H. (1991). Quasi rational economics. New York: Russell Sage
1419–1429. Foundation.
Skitka, L. J., & Tetlock, P. E. (1993). Providing public assistance: Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975). Procedural justice. Hillsdale, NJ:
Cognitive and motivational processes underlying liberal and conserva- Erlbaum.
tive policy preferences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1986). A theory of procedure. California Law
65, 1205–1223. Review, 66, 541–566.
Smeesters, D., Warlop, L., Van Avermaet, E., Corneille, O., & Yzerbyt, V. Thompson, J. L. (1989). Deprivation and political violence in Northern
(2003). Do not prime hawks with doves: The interplay of construct Ireland, 1922–1985. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 33, 676–699.
activation and consistency of social value orientation on cooperative Tomaka, J., & Blascovich, J. (1994). Effects of justice beliefs on cognitive
behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 972–987. appraisal of and subjective, physiological, and behavioral responses
Smith, A. (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of to potential stress. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67,
nations. London: Dent. 732–740.
Smith, H., Tyler, T., Huo, Y., Ortiz, D., & Lind, E. A. (1998). The self- Törnblom, K. Y. & Foa, U. G. (1983). Choice of a distribution principle:
relevant implications of the group-value model. Journal of Experimental Crosscultural evidence on the effects of resources. Acta Sociologica,
Social Psychology, 34, 470–493. 26, 161–173.
Solomon, R. C., & Murphy, M. C. (Eds.). (2000). What is justice? Classic Törnblom, K. Y., Mühlhausen, S. M., & Jonsson, D. R. (1991). The alloca-
and contemporary readings. New York: Oxford University Press. tion of positive and negative outcomes: When is the equality principle
Sprecher, S., & Schwartz, P. (1994). Equity and balance in the exchange fair for both? In R. Vermunt & H. Steensma (Eds.), Social justice in
of contributions in close relationships. In M. J. Lerner & G. Mikula human relations (Vol. 1, pp. 59–100). New York: Plenum.
(Eds.), Entitlement and the affectional bond: Justice in close relation- Tougas, F., Rinfret, N., Beaton, A. M., & de la Sablonnière, R. (2005).
ships. (pp. 11–41). New York: Plenum Press. Policewomen acting in self-defense: Can psychological disengagement
Stangor, C., & Jost, J. T. (1997). Individual, group and system levels of protect self-esteem from the negative outcomes of relative deprivation?
analysis and their relevance for stereotyping and intergroup relations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 88, 790–800.
1164 Social Justice

Toynbee, A. (1976). The Toynbee-Ikeda dialogue: Man himself must choose Van den Bos, K., & Lind, E. A. (2002). Uncertainty management by means
(Trans. R. L. Gage). Tokyo: Kodansha International. of fairness judgments. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimen-
Tucker, R. (1969). The Marxian revolutionary idea. New York: Norton. tal social psychology (Vol. 34, pp. 1–60). San Diego, CA: Academic
Press.
Tyler, T. R. (1987). Conditions leading to value expressive effects in
judgments of procedural justice: A test of four models. Journal of Van den Bos, K., Lind, E. A., Vermunt, R., & Wilke, H.A.M. (1997). How
Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 333–344. do I judge my outcome when I do not know the outcome of others? The
psychology of the fair process effect. Journal of Personality and Social
Tyler, T. R. (1989). The psychology of procedural justice: A test of the group-
Psychology, 72, 1034–1046.
value model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 830–838.
Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., & Lind, E. A. (1998). When do we
Tyler, T. R. (1994). Psychological models of the justice motive: Antecedents
need procedural fairness? The role of trust in authority. Journal of
of distributive and procedural justice. Journal of Personality and Social
Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 1449–1458.
Psychology, 67, 850–863.
Tyler, T. R. (2006). Psychological perspectives on legitimacy and legitima- Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., Lind, E. A., & Vermunt, R. (1998).
tion. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 375–400. Evaluating outcomes by means of the fair process effect: Evidence for
different processes in fairness and satisfaction judgments. Journal of
Tyler, T. R. (2007). Psychology and the design of legal institutions. Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1493–1503.
Netherlands: Wolf Legal.
Van Dijk, E., Wilke, H., Wilke, M., & Metman, L. (1999). What infor-
Tyler, T. R., & Bies, R. (1990). Interpersonal aspects of procedural justice.
mation do we use in social dilemmas? Environmental uncertainty and
In J. S. Carroll (Ed.), Applied social psychology in business settings
the employment of coordination rules. Journal of Experimental Social
(pp. 77–98). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Psychology, 35, 109–135.
Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. L. (2000). Cooperation in groups: Procedural
Van Lange, P. A. M. (2000). Cooperation and competition. New York:
justice, social identity, and behavioral engagement. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Psychology Press.
Van Lange, P. A. M., De Cremer, D., Van Dijk, E., & Van Vugt, M. (2007).
Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. L. (2003). The group engagement model:
Self-interest and beyond: Basic principles of social interaction. In
Procedural justice, social identity, and cooperative behavior. Personality
A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook
and Social Psychology Review, 7, 349–361.
of basic principles (2nd ed., pp. 540–561). New York: Guilford.
Tyler, T. R., & Boeckmann, R. J. (1997). Three strikes and you are out, but
Van Prooijen, J., Karremans, J. C., & van Beest, I. (2006). Procedural jus-
why? The psychology of public support for punishing rule breakers.
tice and the hedonic principle: How approach versus avoidance moti-
Law & Society Review, 31, 237–265.
vation influences the psychology of voice. Journal of Personality and
Tyler, T., Degoey, P., & Smith, H. (1996). Understanding why the justice Social Psychology, 91, 686–697.
of group procedures matters: A test of the psychological dynamics of
Van Prooijen, J., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2002). Procedural
the group-value model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
justice and status: Status salience as antecedent of procedural fairness
70, 913–930.
effects. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1353–1361.
Tyler, T. R., & Jost, J. T. (2007). Psychology and the law: Reconciling
normative and descriptive accounts of social justice and system legiti- Van Prooijen, J., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2004). Group
macy. In A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Social psychology: belongingness and procedural justice: Social inclusion and exclusion
Handbook of basic principles (pp. 807–825). New York: Guilford. by peers affects the psychology of voice. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 87, 66–79.
Tyler, T. R., & Lind, E. A. (1992). A relational model of authority in groups.
In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. Van Vugt, M., & De Cremer, D. (1999). Leadership in social dilemmas:
25, pp. 115–191). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. The effects of group identification on collective actions to provide pub-
lic goods. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 587–599.
Tyler, T. R., & Mitchell, G. (1994). Legitimacy and the empowerment of
discretionary legal authority: The United States Supreme Court and Van Vugt, M., Jepson, S. F., Hart, C. M., & De Cremer, D. (2004).
abortion rights. Duke Law Journal, 43, 703–814. Autocratic leadership in social dilemmas: A threat to group stability.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 40, 1–13.
Tyler, T. R., Rasinski, K. A., & Spodick, N. (1985). Influence of voice on
satisfaction with leaders: Exploring the meaning of process control. Van Vugt, M., Meertens, R. M., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (1995). Car versus
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 72–81. public transportation? The role of social value orientations in a real-life
social dilemma. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 25, 258–278.
Tyler, T. R., & Smith, H. J. (1998). Social justice and social movements. In
D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social Van Yperen, N. W., & Buunk, B. P. (1990). A longitudinal study of equity
psychology (4th ed., pp. 595–629). Boston: McGraw-Hill. and satisfaction in intimate relationships. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 20, 287–309.
Uhlmann, E., Dasgupta, N., Elgueta, A., Greenwald, A. G., & Swanson, J.
(2002). Subgroup prejudice based on skin color among Hispanics in the Van Zomeren, M., Postmes, T., & Spears, R. (2008). Toward an integra-
United States and Latin America. Social Cognition, 20, 198–226. tive social identity model of collective action: A quantitative research
synthesis of three socio-psychological perspectives. Psychological
Utne, M. K., Hatfield, E., Traupmann, J., & Greenberger, D. (1984). Equity,
Bulletin, 134, 504–535.
marital satisfaction, and stability. Journal of Social and Personal
Relationships, 1, 323–332. Vermunt, R. (2007). Social justice and the art of reducing stress. Lecture
Utz, S., Ouwerkerk, J. W., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (2004). What is smart in delivered on September 28, 2007, at the University of Leiden,
a social dilemma? Differential effects of priming competence on coop- Holland.
eration. European Journal of Social Psychology, 34, 317–332. Vidmar, N. (2000). Retribution and revenge. In J. Sanders & V. L. Hamilton
Van den Bos, K. (2001). Uncertainty management: The influence of uncer- (Eds.), Handbook of justice research in law (pp. 31–63). New York:
tainty salience on reactions to perceived procedural fairness. Journal of Kluwer/Plenum.
Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 931–941. Vidmar, N. (2002). Retributive justice: Its social context. In M. Ross &
Van den Bos, K. (2005). What is responsible for the fair process effect? D. T. Miller (Eds.), The justice motive in everyday life. (pp. 291–313).
In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook of organizational New York: Cambridge University Press.
justice. (pp. 273–300). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Viereck, P. (1956). Conservatism. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand.
References 1165

Vlastos, G. (1997). Justice and equality. In L. P. Pojman & R. Westmoreland Weick, K. E., Bougon, M. G., & Maruyama, G. (1976). The equity context.
(Eds.), Equality: Selected readings (pp. 120–133). New York: Oxford Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 15, 32–65.
University Press. (Original work published 1962). Weiner, B., Perry, R. P., & Magnusson, J. (1988). An attributional analysis
Wakslak, C. J., Jost, J. T., Tyler, T. R., & Chen, E. S. (2007). Moral outrage of reactions to stigmas. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
mediates the dampening effect of system justification on support for 55, 738–748.
redistributive social policies. Psychological Science, 18, 267–274. Wenzel, M. (2000). Justice and identity: The significance of inclusion
Walker, I., & Mann, L. (1987). Unemployment, relative deprivation, for perceptions of entitlement and the justice motive. Personality and
and social protest. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 13, Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 157–176.
275–283. Wenzel, M. (2001). A social categorization approach to distributive justice:
Walker, I., & Pettigrew, T. F. (1984). Relative deprivation theory: An over- Social identity as the link between relevance of inputs and need for
view and conceptual critique. British Journal of Social Psychology, 23, justice. British Journal of Social Psychology, 40, 315–335.
301–310. Wenzel, M. (2002). What is social about justice? Inclusive identity and
Walker, I. & Smith, H. J. (Eds). (2002). Relative deprivation: Specification, group values as the basis of the justice motive. Journal of Experimental
development, and integration. New York: Cambridge University Press. Social Psychology, 38, 205–218.
Walker, L., Lind, E. A., & Thibaut, J. (1979). The relation between proce- Wenzel, M., Okimoto, T. G., Feather, N. T., & Platow, M. J. (2008).
dural and distributive justice. Virginia Law Review, 65, 1401–1420. Retributive and restorative justice. Law and Human Behavior, 32,
Wallace, H. M., Exline, J. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Interpersonal con- 375–389.
sequences of forgiveness: Does forgiveness deter or encourage repeat Wenzel, M., & Thielmann, I. (2006). Why we punish in the name of jus-
offenses? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 453–460. tice: Just desert versus value restoration and the role of social identity.
Walster, E., Berscheid, E., & Walster, G. W. (1973). New directions in Social Justice Research, 19, 450–470.
equity research. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 25, White, R. J. (Ed.) (1950). The conservative tradition. New York: New York
151–176. University Press.
Walster, E., Walster, W., & Berscheid, E. (1978). Equity: Theory and Williams, B. (2000). Equality. In R. C. Solomon & M. C. Murphy (Eds.),
research. Boston: Allyn & Bacon. What is justice? Classic and contemporary readings (pp. 188–194).
Walton, G., & Dweck, C. (2009). Solving social problems like a psycholo- New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1976).
gist. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 101–102. Wit, A., & Kerr, N. L. (2002). “Me versus just us versus us all” categoriza-
Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice. New York: Basic Books. tion and cooperation in nested social dilemmas. Journal of Personality
Watson, A. C., Ottati, V., & Corrigan, P. C. (2003). From whence comes and Social Psychology, 83, 616–637.
mental illness stigma? International Journal of Social Psychiatry, 49, Wit, A., & Wilke, H. (1998). Public good provision under environmen-
142–157. tal social uncertainty. European Journal of Social Psychology, 28,
Weber, J. M., Kopelman, S., & Messick, D. M. (2004). A conceptual review 249–256.
of decision making in social dilemmas: Applying a logic of appro- Wood, A. (1980). The Marxian critique of justice. In M. Cohen, T. Nagel, &
priateness. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, 281–307. T. Scanlon (Eds.), Marx, justice, and history (pp. 3–41). Princeton, NJ:
Weber, M. (1958). The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1972).
(T. Parsons, Trans.). New York: Scribner. Yamagishi, T. (1988). Seriousness of social dilemmas and the provision of
Wegener, B., & Liebig, S. (2000). Is the “inner wall” here to stay? Justice a sanctioning system. Social Psychology Quarterly, 51, 32–42.
ideologies in unified Germany. Social Justice Research, 13, 177–197. Zagefka, H., & Brown, R. (2005). Comparisons and perceived deprivation
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: in ethnic minority settings. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
MIT Press. 31, 467–482.

You might also like