You are on page 1of 9

MUETAZILAH 6317

monasteries. By the close of his life, he was regarded as the MUETAZILAH. A religious movement in early Islam,
most eminent monk in Japan, had become the leader of a the MuEtazilah turned into a theological school that become
rapidly growing band of disciples, and had seven times been dominant in the third and fourth centuries AH (ninth to
the recipient of the prestigious title of kokushi, or National tenth century CE) and persisted in certain areas until the
Master. Mongol invasion at the beginning of the thirteenth century
Musō’s considerable contributions to medieval Zen and CE. The history of the movement is comprised of three differ-
Japanese culture were made in several areas. As a Zen master, ent phases: (1) an incubation period that lasted roughly
with a large following of monks and laymen, Musō advocat- through the eighth century; (2) a short period of less than
ed a kind of Zen practice that was readily accessible to the half a century (c. 815–850) when the MuEtazilı̄ school, after
Japanese of his day. Although he studied under Chinese Zen having defined its identity, developed an astonishing variety
masters, Musō himself never visited China. His Zen incorpo- of individual, sometimes contradictory ideas and permeated
rated the traditional Rinzai practices of seated meditation the intellectual life at the Abbasid court; and finally (3) sever-
and kōan study, but its Chinese character was tempered by al centuries of scholastic systematization channeled into two
his own early religious training, his continued devotion to branches or schools that were named after the towns of Basra
Japanese Esoteric Buddhism, and his strong interest in Japa- and Baghdad respectively.
nese poetry and culture. In his book Muchu mondo (Dia- Each of these phases presents its own problems for the
logues in a dream), Musō tried to explain Zen in straightfor- researcher: the first is badly documented and can only be re-
ward, everyday language as he responded to the questions constructed on the basis of later reports, which are frequently
raised by the warrior Ashikaga Tadayoshi. distorted and tendentious; the second is better attested but
Musō also played an important role as a monastic leader needs detailed monographical treatment; and the third has
and regulator who shaped the character of Rinzai Zen mo- only recently begun to attract scholarly attention. On the
nastic life in medieval Japan. Although his Zen was easily ac- whole, knowledge of this movement is still rudimentary. De-
cessible to monks and laymen, he set high standards for his tailed research is hampered by the lack of original texts. This
monks. He divided them into three categories: those few is due to the fact that, after the middle of the ninth century,
who singlemindedly pursued enlightenment, those whose the MuEtazilı̄ movement was gradually driven into the posi-
Zen practice was diluted by a taste for scholarship, and those tion of a heresy; in the areas where it was considered “unor-
who merely read about Zen and never threw themselves into thodox” its books were no longer copied. Therefore we have
a search for self-understanding. To help and discipline the to rely, at least up to the third phase, mainly on heresio-
practice of all his followers, Musō laid down strict rules for graphical reports. For the later centuries we possess a few
his communities in codes such as the Rinsen kakun, a set of texts, some of which reach the size of a summa theologica, but
regulations for Rinsenji. In this, Musō was setting himself they belong to a rather restricted period; outside of this limit,
in the tradition of such famous Chinese and Japanese monas- many of the thinkers still remain mere names to us.
tic leaders as Baizhang and Dōgen Kigen, both of whom had
devoted considerable attention to the proper practice of Zen HISTORY. The MuEtazilı̄ movement is usually traced back to
community life. the end of the Umayyad period, the years between 740 and
750. But during the first century of its existence the move-
Musō was also an intellectual and a man of culture. ment was far from the most important factor in the develop-
Schooled in Chinese, he wrote poetry in both Chinese and ment of Islamic theology.
Japanese. He is also renowned as a garden designer. In addi-
tion, Musō was a major political figure in his day. He served Origins. The MuEtazilah began in Iraq, but there the
as confidant and go-between for the emperor Go-Daigo, the Shı̄ Eah (in Kufa) and the Ibād: ı̄yah (in Basra and Kufa) ini-
Hōjō, and the Ashikaga, encouraged the sending of trading tially had the better thinkers, while the school of Abū
missions to China and the building of new Zen monasteries, Hanı̄fah, which combined juridical competence with an “ec-
and raised Rinzai Zen to a position of political prominence umenical” outlook in theology, enjoyed greater missionary
in medieval Japanese society. success. We are not even sure whether we can assume—as
all of our sources do—that a real continuity existed between
SEE ALSO Gozan Zen. the first and second phases: there seems to be almost no
doubt that the great thinkers of the second phase did not
BIBLIOGRAPHY have any precise knowledge about their spiritual ancestors.
Collcutt, Martin. Five Mountains: The Rinzai Zen Monastic Insti- When they moved from the old intellectual centers, Basra
tution in Medieval Japan. Cambridge, Mass., 1981. and Kufa, to the Abbasid court in Baghdad they felt the urge
Fontein, Jan, and Money L. Hickman, eds. Zen Painting and Cal- to preserve the memory of their past, but they evidently
ligraphy. Boston, 1970. could not rely on any established historical tradition of the
Kraft, Kenneth L., trans. “Musō Kokushi’s Dialogues in a “school.” The gap was widened by the fact that they dis-
Dream.” The Eastern Buddhist, n.s. 14 (Spring 1981): agreed with certain opinions held in the preceding genera-
75–93. tion and therefore tried to keep their immediate predecessors
MARTIN COLLCUTT (1987) out of the picture. Under these circumstances we must reck-

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


6318 MUETAZILAH

on with the possibility that they constructed a past which have derived from a certain feeling of inferiority: all of the
never belonged to them or was only partially true. We should participants were non-Arabs, that is, they did not enjoy the
also not forget that the historical reports that were transmit- natural prestige of the aristocracy but came, as “clients,” from
ted at that time were not collected and written down until Iranian or Aramaean families who had been converted to
some time later, from the middle of the second half of the Islam one or two generations before. They possessed consid-
ninth century onward. erable wealth and were, as a matter of fact, recognized in
their society, but they had to rely on Islam as the basis of
The lack of historical recollection is amply demonstrat- their identity. They knew something about Islamic law, for
ed by the discovery that no MuEtazilı̄ author had any precise Wās: il advised them to win the favor of their audience by de-
information about the original meaning of the name livering fatwās (“legal opinions”) to demonstrate their juridi-
Mu Etazilah. Our sources offer a number of explanations, but cal expertise. But they also deliberately distinguished them-
all of them are secondary guesses and beside the point; some selves from normal, “worldly” people: they clipped their
are blatantly tendentious. Modern scholarship has contribut- mustaches and wore turbans (which, at that time, were char-
ed a few more suggestions, but the question still remains acteristic of certain nomadic tribes but not of the urban pop-
open. All that we can prove is that the movement bore this ulation); they also wore special sandals and wide sleeves. This
name when it became involved in an insurrection against the was the attire of ascetics; it gave them a certain “alternative”
caliph al-Mans: ūr in 762. But the name does not seem to touch.
have been invented at that time, for it does not fit the situa-
tion. It means “those who dissociate themselves” or “those The organization was taken over by Wās: il’s colleague
who keep themselves apart” and thus calls for political neu- EAmr ibn EUbayd (d. 761), a prominent disciple of H: asan
trality rather than revolutionary activism. The name already al-Bas: rı̄, the great figure of religious life in Basra during the
existed in the first century AH (seventh century CE), with this preceding generation. EAmr had to cope with the new situa-
connotation, as a term designating some renowned compan- tion created by the Abbasid seizure of power. He seems to
ions of the Prophet who abstained from any participation in have given up all relations with the cells outside Iraq and in
the first civil war (the Battle of the Camel in 656 and the Basra, where he controlled a considerable number of adher-
Battle of S: iffı̄n in 657). It was then probably applied to the ents (who possibly formed youth groups), he kept quiet. This
first MuEtazilı̄ thinkers since they, too, did not side with any position became increasingly precarious at the end of his life
political party of their time. as discontent with the Abbasid government mounted in Iraq.
After his death the activists among the MuEtazilah followed
This attitude was distinctive insofar as it was adopted the call of the Shı̄ E ı̄ pretender Muh: ammad ibn EAbd Allāh
in a period when almost everybody had to make personal al-Nafs al-Zakı̄yah (or rather, that of his brother Ibrāhı̄m)
alignments clear, namely during the last years of the Umay- and took part in the revolt of 762. When the attempt failed,
yad caliphate, which saw the breakdown of the political order the MuEtazilah were persecuted and went into hiding; those
in Iraq and elsewhere. The founder of the movement, a cloth who had compromised themselves mostly fled to Morocco.
merchant from Basra by the name of Wās: il ibn EAt: āD, intend- This event seems to be a decisive turning point. We hear
ed to create a missionary organization working inside Islam; that afterward the MuEtazilah still possessed a mosque of
he sent his disciples, as “propagandists,” to the most remote their own in Basra, but we do not know of any leading per-
regions of the Islamic empire—the Arabian Peninsula, Ar- sonality for at least thirty years. Above all, there is no hint
menia, Iran, India (the Punjab), and the Maghreb—so that of any specific theological activity. Then, toward the end of
they could interpret the Muslim creed and win people over the eighth century, two figures emerged: al-As: amm in Basra
to his own cause. Unfortunately, we do not know what this and D: irār ibn EAmr in Kufa. But neither of them was a typi-
“cause” really implied. We cannot exclude the possibility that cal MuEtazilı̄; as a matter of fact, the later school kept a cer-
it was originally political, for Wās: il copied a model that clear- tain distance from them. Al-As: amm was obviously an Ibād: ı̄,
ly had a political character, that is, the network of agents whereas D: irār, a judge by profession and one of the most
built up by the Ibād: ı̄yah, with whom he lived closely in original thinkers of this period, differed from the communis
Basra. Most of our information, however, contradicts this opinio of the following generation in his ideas concerning
hypothesis: Wās: il wanted reform, not revolution. Islam, was, free will and therefore fell victim to a damnatio memoriae.
after all, still the religion of a minority; outside the great cen- The original concept of the MuEtazilah as a popular mission-
ters, the knowledge of what Islam really meant was rather ary movement seems to have survived best in Baghdad
limited, and its definition differed from area to area. It any where, during the same period, Bishr ibn al-MuEtamir, a
case, Wās: il did not live to see the fruit of his efforts; he died slave merchant by profession, exhorted the masses by ex-
in 749, one year before the triumph of the Abbasids. pressing his theological ideas in simple poetry. That was ap-
Wās: il’s “propagandists” were mostly merchants like propriate for the social climate in the newly founded capital;
himself, and when they traveled, they combined business the town had attracted many people who came to make their
with missionary zeal. This pattern explains how the move- fortune and ended up by being uprooted.
ment financed itself but does not say much about its spiritual The period of success. The MuEtazilah were propelled
impetus. The inner motivation of Wās: il’s circle seems to from provinciality to prime importance by the theological in-

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


MUETAZILAH 6319

terest which emerged at the Abbasid court. The change came deepened when those who still understood the MuEtazilah as
in two shifts, first through the influence of the Barmakids, a popular movement and kept to the old ascetic tradition
the viziers of Hārūn al-Rashı̄d (r. 786–802), and then, after started adopting S: ūfı̄ tendencies: they dressed in wool and
a short setback caused by their downfall, thanks to the initia- asserted that the Muslim community should abstain from
tive of the caliph al-MaDmūn (813–833). Both the Bar- electing a caliph (a merely symbolic viewpoint, for the com-
makids and al-MaDmūn were not so much interested in the- munity did not have any influence in this respect anyway).
ology itself as in listening to disputations: they liked to have In their view, however, court life was a scandal and the entire
representatives of different religions and confessions argue Muslim world corrupt, full of injustice and violence.
against each other. This predilection may have been stimu-
lated by a non-Iraqi environment: the Barmakids originally For the moment, the court party had the upper hand.
came from Balkh, and al-MaDmūn first resided in Merv; in But enjoying the favor of the caliph also meant supporting
Transoxiana, where both towns were situated, Islam co- his policies. When al-MaDmūn, in a decree sent throughout
existed with Zoroastrianism, Buddhism, Christianity, and the empire in 833, asked his governors to enforce the doc-
Judaism. trine of the createdness of the QurDān as a kind of state
dogma, the MuEtazilah were immediately identified with this
However, the main stimulus came from the intellectual measure. This evaluation was only partly justified. The ca-
atmosphere of the capital itself. Islam was no longer the reli- liph had certainly made the decision by himself, as a demon-
gion of a minority, as in the time of Wās: il, but a creed which stration of his spiritual leadership of the community, and his
had rapidly expanded at the expense of other religions. The main adviser had been a theologian by the name of Bishr
conversions to Islam had been prompted mostly by social al-Marı̄sı̄, who, through his belief in determinism, stood
considerations, but theology had to furnish an a posteriori apart from the MuEtazilah. But the MuEtazilah subsequently
justification: thus the outlook of the new theology was had to lend their intellectual support to the measure. When
strongly apologetic and its style predominantly dialectical. the policy of the caliphs led to a persecution (the so-called
The Muslims were not entirely unprepared; they had experi- mih: nah, or “inquisition”) the chief judge was a MuEtazilı̄:
enced enough internal strife between different “sects” in Ibn Abı̄ Duwād. The mih: nah lasted for fifteen years, and the
order to know what methods to use in disputes. Therefore, government succeeded in purging the ranks of the state offi-
the MuEtazilah were not the only ones to sharpen these weap- cials of any opposition. Resistance remained strong, howev-
ons for the fight with their pagan adversaries. But besides er, among the population of Baghdad who, with a clear anti-
being skillful dialecticians (mutakallimūn) they offered a intellectual bias, rejected rational theology in favor of the
concept of Islam which, by its rationality, transcended the prophetic tradition (h: adı̄th). Therefore the caliph al-
divisions among the old theologico-political factions (Shı̄ Eah, Mutawakkil, the third successor of al-MaDmūn, decided to
MurjiEah, and others) and therefore had broad appeal, at least steer another course. In 848 he ordered some traditionists to
among the intellectuals. The MuEtazilah thus became the preach about (spurious) sayings in which the Prophet alleg-
first overall, “orthodox” school of theology. edly condemned the MuEtazilah and similar groupings; a few
years later, any occupation with dialectical theology was pro-
Their path to success can still be traced. D: irār ibn EAmr hibited. The MuEtazilah were removed from the court.
took part in the sessions arranged by the Barmakids, but
there he was only one among many. In Merv, one generation But the movement was still very strong. Measures taken
later, the situation was different; the MuEtazilı̄ Thumāmah in Baghdad did not always have consequences outside the
ibn Ashras acted as a kind of counselor to al-MaDmūn, and capital, and the MuEtazilah had established themselves in al-
Bishr ibn al-MuEtamir was among those who put their signa- most all parts of the Islamic world: in Upper Mesopotamia
ture as witnesses to the document in which the caliph nomi- and in the Syrian Desert (among the Kalb); in several sub-
nated the Shı̄ E ı̄ imam EAlı̄ al-Rid: ā as his successor. The real urbs of Damascus and in Lebanon (for instance in Baalbek);
breakthrough came when, in 820, al-MaDmūn moved the in Bahrein and even in the Maghreb (again among certain
court back to Baghdad. Two figures dominated the scene tribes in what is today Morocco and Algeria); in Armenia;
there: the Basran theologian Abū al-Hudhayl al-EAllāf, who above all in western Iran, in the provinces of Kerman, Fārs
was already about seventy (he died a centenarian in about (for instance in Arradjān and in Sirāf), and Khuzistan (for
840), and his nephew al-Naz: z: ām. The latter showed all the instance in Shūshtar, Susa, EAskar Mukram, and
features of a courtier: he mocked at asceticism and excelled Gundē-shāpūr, at that time the seat of a famous medical
in light and imaginative poems which celebrated wine and academy directed by the Nestorians); and finally in India, in
the beauty of youths. He therefore acquired the reputation the area along the shore of the Indian Ocean to the west of
of being a drunkard and a homosexual. He was not necessari- the Indus Delta. In these centers the trend toward individu-
ly either, since poetry is not reality, but these characteriza- alistic thinking and dialectical pyrotechnics had certainly not
tions demonstrate that, with their success, the MuEtazilah been as predominant as in Baghdad. Many of the Iranian
also came under scrutiny. Al-Naz: z: ām’s open identification towns mentioned are situated on the main trade routes: it
with the ideals of high society did not tally with Bishr ibn seems that the common theological outlook created an atmo-
al-MuEtamir’s earlier attempt to convert the masses. The split sphere of confidence essential for better business.

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


6320 MUETAZILAH

This extended geographical base helped the MuEtazilah with his Kitāb al-mu Etamad (The Reliable Book), although
to survive. However, it also fostered misunderstandings and this book is concerned with the criteria of jurisprudence, not
tensions which came about through separate regional devel- those of theology.
opments. In Baghdad, the caliph al-Mutawakkil had not
For the school of Baghdad, on the contrary, we lack ex-
only acted against the MuEtazilah but also—and even more
tensive original documentation. But its ideas are relatively
violently—against the Shı̄ Eah. Consequently al-Jāh: iz:
clear to us thanks to a development that deeply influenced
(d. 869), a prominent MuEtazilı̄ author who had maintained
the later history of the MuEtazilah: the winning over of the
close relations with Ibn Abı̄ Duwād and other high state offi-
Shı̄ Eah. This process took place within two of the three main
cials, wrote a book in which he praised the MuEtazilah and
branches of Shı̄ E ı̄ theology; the Zaydı̄yah and the Twelver
at the same time attacked the Shı̄ Eah. This opportunistic turn
Shı̄ Eah. Only the IsmāE ı̄lı̄yah preferred to seek support in
irritated a colleague of his by the name of Ibn al-Rāwandı̄ Neoplatonic philosophy instead. Among the Zaydı̄yah the
(d. about 910), who had just come from the East, where he door had already been opened to MuEtazilı̄ thought by the
had acquired a sound reputation within and outside of his imam al-Qāsim ibn Ibrāhı̄m (d. 860), though he did not in-
school. Iran was governed by the dynasty of the Tahirids, tend to be a MuEtazilı̄ himself. The final decision was taken
who did not follow al-Mutawakkil’s anti-ShiEah policy. Ibn somewhat later and in two different regions: first by his
al-Rāwandı̄ therefore joined the Shı̄ Eah in Baghdad and re- grandson al-Hādı̄ ilā al-H: aqq (d. 911), who founded a
futed al-Jāh: iz: ’s book. But he did more than that: in a series Zaydı̄ principality, an imamate, in Yemen; second, though
of treatises he showed that some of the axioms accepted by with certain setbacks, by the Zaydı̄ pretenders in northern
the MuEtazilah, such as the createdness of the world or the Iran, in the area near the Caspian Sea. Among the Twelvers,
justice of God, that is, theodicy, were not based on solid MuEtazilı̄ theology was introduced by two members of the
premises and that the QurDān was full of contradictions. His Banū Nawbakht, a famous family of state officials and schol-
enemies within the school called him a freethinker for those ars: Abū Sahl IsmāE ı̄l al-Nawbakhtı̄ (d. 924) and his nephew
views, but he apparently wanted only to point out that, with H: asan ibn Mūsā (d. between 912 and 922). The trend origi-
respect to certain positions, the dialectical method allowed nally met strong resistance there, especially from the tradi-
for arguments pro and con which simply neutralized each tionist theologian Ibn Bābawayhı̄ (d. 991), but then it pre-
other. Thus the MuEtazilah, shortly after being deprived of vailed because of the influence of Shaykh al-Mufı̄d
political power, were also faced with the inadequacy of their (d. 1022).
intellectual instruments.
The motives for these dogmatic shifts are not altogether
The scholastic phase. Ibn al-Rāwandı̄’s pinpricks pro- clear. The MuEtazilah still retained, among their theological
duced a shock. His books were refuted by several authors, principles, the obligation to spread the right belief; this may
in Baghdad as well as in Basra. Although these two towns explain their usefulness for the Zaydı̄ pretenders. The
were far from the only strongholds of MuEtazilı̄ theology, Twelvers had lost their spiritual leader through the disap-
their names served as labels for the two different schools that pearance (ghaybah) of the twelfth imam in 874 and may have
took up Ibn al-Rāwandı̄’s challenge and, going beyond mere clung to rational theology for new reliable guidance. In
refutation, began systematizing the material accumulated in Baghdad, MuEtazilı̄ theologians had always had moderate
the past. At the beginning of the tenth century their main Shı̄ E ı̄ leanings, although they did not normally side with the
representatives were Abū al-Qāsim al-KaEbı̄ (d. 931), who Rawāfid: (i.e., the Twelvers). At the end of the ninth century,
was identified with Baghdad although he only studied there even a Basran like al-JubbāD ı̄ recognized EAlı̄’s son H: usayn
and then taught in his hometown of Balkh in eastern Iran, as a righteous ruler. Abū al-Qāsim al-KaEbı̄ was the secretary
and for Basra, al-JubbāD ı̄ (d. 915) with his son Abū Hāshim of an early Zaydı̄ pretender in Iran. Later on, the crisis of
(d. 933). In their efforts to build up a coherent theological the caliphate revived the hopes for political support. The
framework they had to care more than their predecessors MuEtazilah in Baghdad entertained relations with Sayf al-
about epistemological and terminological problems; this ac- Dawlah (r. 944–967), the Hamdanid ruler of Aleppo, and
counts for their growing interest in precise definitions and then with the Buyids; both dynasties had Shı̄ E ı̄ leanings. A
questions of logic. Buyid vizier, al-S: āh: ib ibn EAbbaād (d. 995), promoted the
qād: ı̄ EAbd al-Jabbār in Rayy.
The range of the Basran school, which, like the school
of Baghdad, gradually shifted to Iran, is well attested by the The Baghdad school exerted its strongest influence
work of the qād: ı̄ EAbd al-Jabbār (d. 1024/5), chief judge at among the Zaydı̄yah, though only in its Yemeni wing. The
Rayy (near modern Tehran). His Mughnı̄ ([The Book] That Caspian imams were under Basran influence, but their prin-
Makes [Other Books] Superfluous), a twenty-volume summa cipality did not survive. However, theological works of the
theologiae, has recently been edited as far as it is preserved and Iranian wing were taken over into the Yemen, for instance
also subjected to some research. Besides this valuable source, the great QurDān commentary written by al-H: ākim
further texts written by his pupils and other theologians who al-Jushamı̄ (d. 1101). Among the Twelvers, al-Mufı̄d fol-
followed his views are also available. For MuEtazilı̄ herme- lowed the Baghdad school, but in the generation after him
neutics our best source is Abū al-H: usayn al-Bas: rı̄ (d. 1044), a pupil of the qād: ı̄ EAbd al-Jabbār, Sharı̄f al-Murtad: ā

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


MUETAZILAH 6321

(d. 1044), turned to Basran ideas and determined the rather late, by Abū al-Hudhayl, who defined five principles
Twelver outlook for the centuries to come. On the whole, that he considered indispensable to MuEtazilı̄ identity. These
the Zaydı̄yah adopted MuEtazilı̄ doctrine more fully than the have determined the structure of MuEtazilı̄ theological works
Twelvers. for centuries, in spite of the fact that two or even three of
these principles did not retain much importance in later dis-
Outside of the Shı̄ E ı̄ areas, the MuEtazilah were in re-
treat. But their impact persisted in at least two places. I have cussion. One of them was already dated when Abū al-
mentioned the Berber tribes in the Maghreb; some of them Hudhayl took it up: the princple of “enjoining what is good
remained MuEtazilı̄ even after the Fatimid invasion, at least and forbidding what is evil” (al-amr bi-al-ma Erūf wa-al-nahy
up to the second half of the eleventh century. They called Ean al-munkar), that is, active admonition to follow the right
themselves Wās: ilı̄yah, with reference to Wās: il ibn EAt: āD. In path and resist impiety. This had been the device of the revo-
fact, they seem to have lost contact with the Iraqi MuEtazilah lution against al-Mans: ūr in 762 and was probably the justifi-
very early and did not participate in the move toward intel- cation for Wās: il’s missionary projects, but it was rather out
lectualism instigated by the Abbasid court. We find scarcely of place at the Abassid court.
any traces of theological activity; the claim to be Wasiliyah The second principle, concerned with the intermediate
merely constituted a symbol of identity, the implications of state of the Muslim sinner, was still valid at that time, but
which we do not know. In addition, MuEtazilı̄ theology con- derived its importance from an earlier debate that had its
tinued to exert a certain attraction in Baghdad and in Iran, roots in the period before Wās: il. It was a compromise be-
among jurists belonging to the school of Abū Hanı̄fah. In tween two attitudes that had arisen in the seventh century,
Baghdad, this combination became precarious after the on the one hand the rigorist belief that every Muslim who
weakening of Buyid power. In 1017, the caliph al-Qadı̄r commits a grave sin excludes himself or herself from the
forced the H: anafı̄ judges and witnesses to make a public dis- community, and on the other, an “ecumenical,” communi-
avowal; pressure from traditionist, especially Hanbali, circles tarian position which understood the revelation of the keryg-
increased steadily. Eastern Iran, with its fragmented political ma as the decisive event by which every Muslim, whether sin-
landscape, offered better conditions. MuEtazilı̄ thought ner or not, was ultimately saved. Wās: il was rigorist enough
flourished under the Khwārizm-shāhs up to the beginning to abhor any laxity or minimalism, but he lived late enough
of the thirteenth century. We even know about a MuEtazilı̄ to realize that the exclusiveness practiced by the rigorists
in the environment of Timur Lenk (Tamerlane, d. 1405). could not serve as the basis of the world religion that Islam
He, however, seems to have been an exception; generally had meanwhile become. He wanted the grave sinner to re-
speaking, the end of MuEtazilı̄ influence on Sunnı̄ circles in main a member of the Muslim community, with all the
Iran came earlier, with the Mongol invasion in the first half
rights that involved (safety of life and property, inheritance
of the thirteenth century.
from other Muslims, etc.), but he insisted that the sinner
In the contemporary Muslim world, MuEtazilı̄ ideas are would be condemned to eternal punishment in Hell like the
evaluated in different ways. In Iran, they still permeate theo- pagans if that person did not repent. Thus, the grave sinner
logical thinking, especially after the revival of Shiism. In is to be treated neither as an unbeliever nor as a true believer.
Yemen, they belong to the Zaydı̄ heritage, but have lost all This doctrinal position was apparently not far from that
reproductive vigor. In certain Sunnı̄ countries undergoing taken by Wās: il’s teacher, H: asan al-Bas: rı̄, but it was Wās: il
the impact of modernist movements, they have been thought who brought it into focus and sharpened it by changing the
of as giving witness to the essentially rational character of terminology. H: asan had called the Muslim sinner a munāfiq
Islam; this has led, especially in Egypt during the last two (“hypocrite”), using a word taken from the QurDān, where
generations, to a certain scholarly interest which was some- it referred to enemies of Muh: ammad who had not openly
times hailed as a “renaissance.” Modern fundamentalism, sided with the unbelievers. This led to exegetical problems;
however, has proved that view premature. MuEtazilı̄ ideas are the QurDanic context was not always appropriate for the
again pushed back into the corner of heresy. theological definition wanted. Therefore Wās: il used the term
DOCTRINE. That MuEtazilı̄ doctrine changed over the centu- fāsiq (“transgressor”) instead. This term was equally QurDanic
ries should go without saying. What is perhaps more impor- but had merely moral and no historical connotations.
tant is the fact that its function also changed. During the in- The eternal punishment of the “transgressor” was Abū
cubation phase doctrine was less important than group
al-Hudhayl’s third principle. It turned out to be somewhat
solidarity; at the Abbasid court, MuEtazilı̄ theology repre-
flexible. The school sometimes tolerated members who only
sented the first attempt at a rational and universal description
believed in a kind of prolonged purgatory; the dogma was
of Sunnı̄ Islam; and in the later centuries certain basic posi-
also mitigated among the Twelvers. This tolerance derived
tions, especially the doctrine of free will, served as a label
from the fact that the discussion shifted to a related issue that
which indicated that a person belonged to the MuEtazilı̄
had been Abū al-Hudhayl’s fourth (or, according to his own
“school.”
counting, second) principle: God’s justice. God does not do
The “five principles.” The decisive step toward creat- wrong: he punishes the sinner and rewards the good. He has
ing a reliable “dogmatic” framework was apparently taken the right to do so because he has put human beings under

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


6322 MUETAZILAH

an obligation; he has revealed the law, and men and women ly took the form of predicates or “names,” in sentences like
have the choice to obey or to disobey. This choice presup- “God is knowing,” “God is (all) mighty,” and so on. These
poses two things: freedom of decision and an instrument to sentences then had to be reformulated as, for example, “God
grasp this possibility of decision, that is, reason. However, has knowledge” and “God has power.” How could this be
the fact that man is an intelligent being then implies that the done without reifying the attributes and transforming them
obligation already existed before revelation; the prophets are into independent entities? And if knowledge really was God,
sent to confirm what reason knows, or should have known, as Abū al-Hudhayl seemed to say, how could it be differenti-
beforehand. To a certain extent, revelation is merely a sign ated from his power and other attributes? Finally, the ques-
of God’s mercy or favoring help which makes insight easier tion of whether there are attributes beyond revelation that
for man. It may, however, add new commandments; there have to be deduced rationally must be asked; predicates like
are rational laws (e.g., the interdiction of lying) and revealed “eternal” or “existent” were absent from the QurDān.
laws (e.g., the prohibition of the eating of pork). Since these questions referred to statements contained
Abū al-Hudhayl’s last principle was the unity of God. in the holy text, they were answered by linguistic analysis.
This had always been an indispensable postulate for Islam, The doctrine of attributes is based not on metaphysics but
as opposed to the Christian trinitarian beliefs and the dual- on grammar. Our understanding must therefore proceed
ism of Iranian religions such as Zoroastrianism or Manichae- from the Arabic language and medieval grammatical theory.
ism. But this unity had been understood in different ways. The first differentiation can already be found in the transla-
Early anthropomorphists such as the QurDān commentator tion of Abū al-Hudhayl’s statement mentioned above: in-
Muqātil ibn Sulaymān (d. 767 or later) had found it suffi- stead of “God has knowledge” we have to say “There is an
cient to assert that God is one and not two or three, which act of knowing belonging to God”; Arabic linguistic feeling
did not exclude his having human shape. They merely held and MuEtazilı̄ theology insisted that “knowledge” is “know-
that God’s body is compact, not hollow, for he neither eats ing,” that is, an infinitive rather than a noun, and as such
nor drinks. He is thus one in number and consistence but not necessarily permanent or independent. This was not,
he is not one in form, for he has limbs like man. The however, a definitive solution. One could still, as did certain
MuEtazilah, on the contrary, understood unity as incorpore- opponents of the MuEtazilah such as Ibn Kullāb (d. 855?),
ity, unity in essence: God is beyond time and place, he is un- conclude that this formulation referred to a separate entity
changeable. They did not even agree when some Shı̄ E ı̄ an- that subsists in God. Al-JubbāD ı̄ therefore rephrased Abū al-
thropomorphists in Kufa, Hishām ibn al-H: akam among Hudhayl’s doctrine in the following way: “The meaning of
others, refined their position so far as to conceive of God as one’s describing God as knowing is (1) the assertion of
a body of light that radiates like an ingot of silver. For the [God’s] reality, (2) that [God] is contrary to whatever cannot
MuEtazilah, God is not a body at all but only “something,” know, (3) that he who says that [God] is ignorant states a
a being that cannot be perceived by the senses but is exclu- false proposition, and (4) an indication that there are things
sively known to us through revelation or through reason, by that [God] knows.” Here, the act of knowing is completely
the effect of his creative will in nature. God will therefore not excluded: what is asserted is only God’s reality. This was
even be seen in Paradise: he is unlike all other beings. enough to protect God against any plurality, but there was
Divine attributes. Unity then also means that the attri- some reason for doubting whether it was enough to affirm
butes ascribed to God in the QurDān are identical with him his knowledge.
and not different entities or hypostases. This is true at least Al-JubbāD ı̄’s son Abū Hāshim then established a com-
for “essential attributes” such as knowledge, power, or life; promise by going back to the original QurDanic statements
they are eternal and unchangeable like God himself and and inserting a copula into them (which is normally absent
merely tell us something about certain aspects of his nature. from nontemporal statements in Arabic): Allahu Eālimun
“When one states that the Creator is knowing,” said Abū al- thus became kāna Allāhu Eāliman, “God is knowing.” The
Hudhayl, “he has asserted the reality of an act of knowing copula was then understood as a “complete verb,” that is, it
that is God and has denied ignorance in God and has indi- gained existential meaning: “God is”; the assertion of God’s
cated [that there is] some object known [to God] that has reality had been made explicit. The participle for “knowing,”
been or will be.” However, in addition to “essential attri- however, now put into the accusative instead of the nomina-
butes” there are also “attributes of action” such as willing, tive, was no longer interpreted as a predicate but as a h: āl, a
hearing, seeing, or speaking, which describe God’s temporal “state” of the subject instead of an attribute. In the words
relationship with his creation; they are other than God and of Abū Hāshim himself: “Since it is true that [God] has a
subject to change, for they come into being when God acts state in his being knowing, the knowledge that he is knowing
and cease when his action ceases. They do not subsist in him. is a knowledge of the thing itself [that is, the subject as] in
This is why the caliph al-MaDmūn declared the QurDān to be this state rather than a knowledge of the act of knowing or
created: the QurDān is God’s “speech” or “discourse” and of the thing itself.” This theory allowed the above statements
came into being at a certain historical moment. to be understood univocally of all knowers; a theological
This theory presented certain problems. The attributes problem had been put into the general frame of grammatical
were inferred from QurDanic statements, where they normal- analysis.

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


MUETAZILAH 6323

However, since the purpose of this description was on- cidents, by definition, are created by God. A body exists
tological we find the later authors unfolding a whole range therefore only as long as God allows this accident of compo-
of different ways of predication and attribution. There are, sition to endure. This is Greek atomism turned upside down.
for example, besides the “essential attributes” also “attributes Democritus and Epicurus intended to explain nature by the
of the essence,” that is, attributes which not only make some principle of chance (therefore the church fathers abhorred
statement about the essence but denote the essence itself and their philosophy). For the MuEtazilah, on the contrary, atom-
thus are not shared by anything else (in the case of God, a ism served as an accomplice of divine omnipotence. As mere
word like eternal). Then there are attributes grounded in the conglomerates, things do not possess any essence of their
presence of an accident. They were subdivided by the qād: ı̄ own; this demonstrates their dependence on God. However,
EAbd al-Jabbār into several categories: for example, those that although objects are reduced to purely material composites,
specifically qualify the substrate (or object) and necessitate this was not a materialistic theory. The Greek atomists were
a state in it as a whole, like motion or rest; and those which searching for the monad: they wanted to explain nature. The
specifically qualify the substrate but do not necessitate a state MuEtazilı̄ atomists were searching for the pivot of God’s will
of it as a whole, as, for example, colors (which may inhere and power: they wanted to explain creation.
in a few single atoms of the substrate, but not the whole of That is why, in contrast to the Greeks, the MuEtazilah
it). From them we may distinguish attributes determined by extended atomism to the realm of human action. The free-
the agent who causes the existence of the thing, like “well or- dom of choice that is necessary for human responsibility is
dered” or “skillfully wrought” (with respect to the creation, based upon a capacity which the individual receives from
for instance); attributes directly derived from his action, like God. This capacity is not a permanent quality, an inborn
“speaking,” “commanding,” and so on; and finally attributes power of acting, but a momentary capability to do one spe-
that are grounded neither in the essence nor in an accident, cific act. The MuEtazilah shared this basic assumption with
like “self-sufficient” said with respect to God (since this word their determinist or predestinarian opponents. What made
which, in Arabic, originally means “rich” is positive only in the difference was merely the fact that they did not think that
its form of expression whereas “its strict sense is the denial this capacity was given simultaneously with the act, as the
of need on the part of one who is specifically characterized determinists did, but one moment before, leaving an interval
by a state having which need and self-sufficiency are actually of one time atom so that people have the chance to make
possible”). their decisions, to choose whether to perform the action, to
The MuEtazilı̄ worldview. The way in which the theory leave it, or to do something else. There were MuEtazilah, es-
of the divine attributes developed shows that the achieve- pecially in the Baghdad school, who believed that the capaci-
ment of MuEtazilı̄ theology consisted not only in defining ty for action was not merely momentary since it was identical
basic tenets by which it distinguished itself from other with health and the intact functioning of the body, but even
schools but also in the conceptual and systematic framework they understood this continuum as a mere accumulation of
through which these tenets were expressed. Another case in single isolated moments.
point is the atomistic model by which the relationship be- Continuity was a factor that never came first in this
tween God and his creation was explained. This model had model. With respect to the physical world, consequences had
been conceived as early as the eighth century by D: irār ibn to be taken into account especially regarding the explanation
EAmr, but the theologian who gave it its final form was again of movement, for in the context of atomism movement
apparently Abū al-Hudhayl. He thought of atoms as mathe- meant only that the atoms of a moving body were, at differ-
matical points that do not have any spatial extension until ent moments, opposite to the subsequent atoms of the sur-
they touch each other. Atoms therefore are not three- face on which this body was moving. Consequently, one had
dimensional; only bodies are. Normally it is only in spatial to discuss the problem of when movement takes place at all,
existence, that is, in combination with each other, that atoms whether during the first moment, when it begins, or during
take on accidents: color, for instance, and consequently visi- the second, when it has already ceased to exist. Movement,
bility. Only a few accidents are connected with atoms when it could be said, is only a convention of language; in reality,
they are still isolated, namely those that, in the form of an bodies are always at rest, though at subsequently different
alternative, make combination possible: composition versus places. Continuity is then only an illusion of our senses, as
separation and, as the medium through which composition in a film.
and separation take place, motion versus rest. Motion then
means that the atoms join each other and receive extension, With respect to human existence, this lack of continuity
or that they part and thus lose their corporeity again; rest comes to the fore in the MuEtazilı̄ concept of person. For
means that they retain their status of being isolated and Abū al-Hudhayl the human being was first a mere complex
therefore cannot be perceived, or of being composite and of atoms and “accidents.” It is true that he or she is alive
therefore remain spatial. whereas other bodies are not, but life is again only an “acci-
dent,” a quality added to the conglomerate of atoms which
What is decisive, however, is that the atoms do not join form the body. There is something like a soul, but it is con-
by themselves, for their composition is an “accident,” and ac- ceived of merely as a kind of breath that permeates the body

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


6324 MUETAZILAH

as long as that body is alive. The soul may leave the body selves, as do their basic accidents. Characteristically enough,
during sleep; this explains the phenomenon of dreaming. But it was a Baghdadi like KaEbı̄ who relied on the concept of
the soul is not immortal: it guarantees life and it disappears the coutume de Dieu; like al-Naz: z: ām, he believed in the exis-
together with it. What Abū al-Hudhayl and his colleagues tence of natural qualities that determine the functioning of
wanted to explain was not the continuity or uniqueness of bodies and guarantee the preservation of the species. Howev-
the human person, but God’s power to create human beings er, his natural philosophy was closer to Greek concepts than
anew in the hereafter. God adds the “accident” of life to the was al-Naz: z: ām’s; he followed the classical doctrine of the ele-
atoms that form them when God creates them; God with- ments. In most of these points he was attacked by the follow-
draws this accident when he makes them die; and adds it ers of al-JubbāD ı̄, who stuck to the Basran system.
again when he resurrects them.
Epistemology. Arguments for the existence of God
This concept of a fundamentally disjointed world seems were used within the circle of the MuEtazilah at least from
to exclude causality. But the MuEtazilah usually did not go the time of Abū al-Hudhayl. The cosmological proof was
so far as to deny causality completely. To begin with, they known from Christian sources. But the MuEtazilah preferred
gave it a different name: “production,” which they defined by far the argument e novitate mundi; deriving the existence
as the dependence of one act on another. The examples they of God from the “accidental” character of creation corre-
adduced show, however, that they thought in terms of sponded to their atomistic worldview. Originally, the notion
human actions alone. They did not want to formulate a law of God had been considered as a priori, “necessary,” as one
of nature but to bind the human being to the consequences said. Abū al-Hudhayl even believed that the “proof” for
of his or her own behavior. They were mainly interested in God’s existence, namely the createdness of the world, was
man and his responsibility; their approach was juridical rath- also immediately evident. This insight then implied, as he
er than metaphysical, for they started from man’s obligation thought, the obligation to speculate further about God’s na-
toward God. Later on, they recognized that they could not ture and to look out for his commandments; it had juridical
neglect the universe completely and would have to give an consequences. When later theologians, in an attempt to
explanation for the phenomenon of a world that functions create an overall rational system, gave up the a priori charac-
in an orderly and foreseeable way in spite of its being depen- ter of the notion of God, they were confronted, just because
dent on God’s will at each moment. Abū al-Qāsim al-KaEbı̄ of the juridical aspect mentioned, with a very typical prob-
spoke of God’s “habit” in this respect, the coutume de Dieu lem: how can man be obliged to know God if he does not
that changes only in the case of a miracle. already know him, that is, is it not that the obligation to rec-
Abū al-Hudhayl’s worldview that I have described so far ognize God’s existence presupposes that man already possess-
mainly influenced the Basran school, through al-JubbāD ı̄. But es a notion of God? Al-JubbāD ı̄ then answered this question
during his lifetime he was already contradicted by his neph- by assuming that man necessarily feel the obligation to know
ew al-Naz: z: ām, who did not believe in atomism but pro- God because when he reaches intellectual maturity he be-
ceeded from the infinite divisibility of bodies. Al-Naz: z: ām comes aware of being constantly exposed to the merciful as-
also reduced God’s immediate omnipotence. According to sistance of an unknown reality and then realizes that in order
him, inanimate things now have a nature of their own that to be grateful for this anonymous help he should know where
is independent in its activity, although ultimately created by it comes from; otherwise his benefactor might become angry
God. They are still composites of different elements; howev- at being unduly ignored. Man, as it were, awakens with an
er, these elements do not simply agglomerate like atoms but existential feeling of fear that only ceases when he has recog-
mix and grow into organic units. Nor do they depend on nized that there is a God who will be just and merciful if his
God’s will at each moment of their existence; they are rather commandments are fulfilled. This cognition then grants that
created all at once and then behave according to their own “tranquillity of the soul” that always results from knowing
character. The human being, too, is no longer merely unique the truth.
because of outward form but possesses a soul which, though
Influence and originality. MuEtazilı̄ theology certainly
still material, persists beyond death; al-Naz: z: ām was the first
participated in the process of the hellenization of Arabo-
Islamic theologian to take over the Platonic proofs for the
Islamic thought that started in the eighth century. But we
immortality of the soul. This soul, a “subtle body,” perme-
should not forget that Abū al-Hudhayl and even al-Naz: z: ām
ates all the limbs and keeps them alive. It can mix with other
developed their ideas when most Greek texts were not yet
“bodies” that come to it from outside, such as sounds; this
available in Arabic or were just being translated. Obviously
explains sense perception.
neither Aristotle nor the Neoplatonists exerted any impact
For some time, al-Naz: z: ām’s alternative approach had on their thought. Al-Naz-zam’s system reminds us in some
enormous success. But there were certain excesses that dis- places of the Stoics (especially their theory of krāsis di holōn,
credited it. Ultimately it did not supplant atomism. Never- “total mixture”), but that influence was filtered through Ira-
theless, it was not without influence on the Baghdad school. nian intermediaries and reached him not in the form of a
The Baghdadis continued to believe in atomism, but they written translation but through his contacts with followers
held that the atoms have extension and endure by them- of Bardesanes or Manichaeans who lived in Iraq.

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION


MYERHOFF, BARBARA G. 6325

It will not be possible to judge the overall situation ade- delung’s Der Imām al-Qāsim ibn Ibrāhı̄m und die Glaubens-
quately until we have further studies of individual MuEtazilı̄ lehre der Zaiditen (Berlin, 1965). The relationship with the
thinkers and the “dark period” between the great Hellenistic Twelvers is analyzed in detail, at least as far as the beginnings
philosophers, up to the time of Proclus (410?–485 CE) and are concerned, by Martin J. McDermott in The Theology of
Iamblichus, and the arrival of Islam. What cannot be doubt- al-Shaikh al-Mufid (Beirut, 1978). Much information on in-
dividual thinkers is hidden in the relevant articles in The En-
ed, however, is the originality of the MuEtazilı̄ approach:
cyclopaedia of Islam, new ed. (Leiden, 1960–), and in the En-
D: irār’s and Abū al-Hudhayl’s atomistic theory is a case in cyclopaedia Iranica (Leiden, 1982–), but it is not easy for the
point. They took Greek spolia but used them for an edifice nonspecialist to find this.
that was entirely theirs, a theological system that was juridical
Studies of specific problems of MuEtazilı̄ theology tend to com-
in its outlook rather than metaphysical. They rarely quoted
pare the MuEtazilah with other “schools,” especially the
the QurDān because they wanted to rely on reason, but never- AshEarı̄yah. On the doctrine of attributes we have Michel Al-
theless they always took the QurDān as their guide. They of- lard’s Le problème des attributs divins (Beirut, 1965), which
fered a coherent worldview that was different from that of contains a chapter on al-JubbāD ı̄, and especially R. M.
the later Muslim philosophers. These therefore reacted with Frank’s Beings and Their Attributes (Albany, N. Y., 1978),
reticence and, finally, contempt. Al-Kindı̄ still tried to adjust which gives a subtle analysis of the teaching of the Basran
his thinking to MuEtazilı̄ axioms in certain points, but school. The arguments for and against the doctrine of free
al-Fārābi treated the MuEtazilı̄ theologians as “dialecticians” will are listed and treated in detail by Daniel Gimaret in Thé-
who used the wrong method. The MuEtazilah, on the other ories de l’acte humain en théologie musulmane (Paris, 1980).
hand, never changed their approach. A few of them, like Abū Gimaret’s interpretation of the MuEtazilı̄ model is modified
by R. M. Frank in his article “The Autonomy of the Human
al-H: usayn al-Bas: rı̄, became interested in Aristotelian philos-
Agent in the Teaching of Abd-al-Djabbar,” Le Muséon 95
ophy, but ultimately they did not adopt Aristotle’s basic cate- (1982): 323–355. The consequences for MuEtazilı̄ ethics are
gories in either logic or metaphysics. described in George F. Hourani’s Islamic Rationalism (Ox-
ford, 1971). The corresponding physical ideas become clear
SEE ALSO Attributes of God, article on Islamic Concepts; in Judith Katz Hecker’s “Reason and Responsibility: An Ex-
Free Will and Predestination, article on Islamic Concept; planatory Translation of Kitab al-Tawlid from al-Mughni fi
God, article on God in Islam; Kalām; Occasionalism. Abwab al-Tawhid wa-l-Adl by Qadi Abd-al-Jabbār al-
Hamadhani” (Ph. D. diss., University of California, Berke-
BIBLIOGRAPHY ley, 1975). For atomism, Salomon Pines’s Beiträge zur is-
There is no satisfactory work on the MuEtazilah as a whole. Albert lamischen Atomenlehre (Berlin, 1936) still retains its value; it
Nasri Nader’s Le système philosophique des Mu Etazila (Beirut, has now to be compared with Frank’s book on Abū al-
1956) treats the development up to the beginning of the Hudhayl. Carmela Baffioni’s Atomismo e antiatomismo nel
scholastic (third) phase, but this work is marred by philologi- pensiero islamico (Naples, 1982) attempts a new comparison
cal misunderstandings and gives almost no biographical in- with Greek atomism, but unfortunately ignores Frank’s
formation. W. Montgomery Watt’s The Formative Period of study. On epistemology, see Marie Bernand’s Le problème de
Islamic Thought (Edinburgh, 1973) is an introduction to la connaissance d’après le Mugni du cadi EAbd al-Ǧabbār (Al-
early Muslim theology where the MuEtazilah appear in the giers, 1982). MuEtazilı̄ polemics against dualism have been
context of the other theological movements existing during treated by Guy Monnot in Penseurs musulmans et religions
the first three centuries of Islam (until al-AshEarı̄). Harry A. iraniennes (Paris, 1974).
Wolfson’s The Philosophy of the Kalam (Cambridge, Mass., JOSEF VAN ESS (1987)
1976) follows the author’s earlier works on Philo and the
church fathers: it presents stimulating ideas but ignores some
recent editions and secondary literature. My article “Une lec-
ture à rebours de l’histoire du muEtazilisme,” in Revue des MUTILATION SEE BODILY MARKS
études islamiques 46 (1978): 163–240 and 47 (1979): 19–69,
gives a biographical and systematic account of the period be-
tween Wās: il and Ibn al-Rāwandı̄.
MYCENAEAN RELIGION SEE AEGEAN
For the rest, one has to resort to monographs, of which there are RELIGIONS
not many. Abū al-Hudhayl’s system has been analyzed in a
perceptive way by R. M. Frank in his study The Metaphysics
of Created Being according to abû l-Hudhayl al- EAllâf (Istan-
bul, 1966) and in an article in Le Muséon 82 (1969): 451– MYERHOFF, BARBARA G. (1935–1985), Ameri-
506, “The Divine Attributes according to the Teaching of can anthropologist and scholar of religion, myth, ritual, and
Abû l-Hudhayl al-EAllâf.” Hans Daiber’s Das theologisch-
symbolism. Born in Cleveland, Ohio, and raised there and
philosophische System des MuEammar ibn EAbbād as-Sulamı̄
(Beirut, 1975) treats another early thinker but also presents in Los Angeles, Myerhoff received her bachelor’s degree in
much material about his contemporaries. The qād: ı̄ EAbd sociology and her doctorate in anthropology from the Uni-
al-Jabbār has been dealt with most extensively in J. R. T. M. versity of California at Los Angeles; her master’s degree in
Peters’s God’s Created Speech (Leiden, 1976). For the human development was awarded by the University of Chi-
MuEtazilı̄ influence on the Zaydı̄yah, see Wilferd Ma- cago. Her entire professional career was spent as a member

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF RELIGION, SECOND EDITION

You might also like