You are on page 1of 12

ZDM Mathematics Education (2014) 46:635–646

DOI 10.1007/s11858-014-0604-0

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle in the learning


of calculus
Pierre Job • Maggy Schneider

Accepted: 17 June 2014 / Published online: 6 August 2014


 FIZ Karlsruhe 2014

Abstract Using Chevallard’s anthropological approach derivative, etc. (Bezuidenhout 2001; Martinez-Planell et al.
to the didactics of mathematics considered as an evolution 2012; Monaghan 1991; Orton 1983; Zandieh 2000).
of Brousseau’s theory of didactic situations, we envision Attention has mostly been given to first-year university
the development of calculus as an epistemological transi- students and last-year secondary school students because of
tion between two types of praxeologies, pragmatic and a problematic transition between informal and more formal
deductive, a praxeology being an anthropological and aspects of calculus that often takes place in and between
epistemological model of knowledge. This allows us to those two institutions.
depart from a form of dichotomy between formal and Within this research, particular attention has been paid
intuitive aspects of limits where a mathematical activity to limits because of the role this plays as a central concept
should finally become rigorous on some formal definition: in calculus (Artigue 2000; Bezuidenhout 2001). Two main
we give credit to limits being a pragmatic model of mag- trends can be identified in such research: one focusing on
nitudes relying on mental objects. This understanding of students’ concept images and the other focusing on more
limits is used to argue the relevance of empirical positiv- formal aspects involving the limit definition.
ism, an epistemology held by Belgian students, as well as The studies based on students’ concept images of limits
pupils, as an obstacle to learning calculus, and show how it indicate how much these can interfere with formal aspects
is reinforced by learning institutions as a consequence of of limits. Students’ concept images of limits are based on
their inability to give credit to a pragmatic level of dynamic motion as opposed to its static definition (Bagni
rationality. 2005; Tall 1980; Tall and Vinner 1981; Williams 1991).
Limits are considered unreachable (Tall and Schwarzen-
Keywords Calculus  Limit  Epistemological obstacle  berger 1978) and/or as a bound (Cornu 1991) and/or as an
Empirical positivism  Pragmatic praxeology  Deductive approximation (Parameswaran 2007). In conjunction with
praxeology these elements, research has also demonstrated a strong
connection between students’ difficulties with limits and
difficulties related to concepts such as real numbers,
1 Introduction functions and infinity (Parameswaran 2007; Sierpinska
1987).
Much research has been conducted to understand students’ Researchers have also taken an interest in trying to
difficulties with basic concepts of calculus such as limit, understand students’ dealing with formal aspects of limits
and trying to help them (re)build formal definitions of
limits (Przenioslo 2005; Swinyard 2011) but overall there
P. Job (&)  M. Schneider
is less empirical data to rely on than for concept images.
Ladimath, Département de mathématiques, University of Liège,
Grande Traverse, 12 (B37), 4000 Liège, Belgium Our research lies in between these two trends. Using
e-mail: pierre.job@ulg.ac.be Chevallard’s anthropological theory of the didactic (Che-
M. Schneider vallard 1999) we analyse the history of calculus to build an
e-mail: mschneider@ulg.ac.be epistemological model based on pragmatic and deductive

123
636 P. Job, M. Schneider

praxeologies. This model is put to use to develop an unu- into account the institutional relativity of calculus and of
sual view of limits, a bridge between concept images and mathematical concepts in general in a much tighter way
formal aspects: limits are envisioned as pragmatic models than Brousseau did, giving birth to a fundamental situation
of magnitudes considered as mental objects (Freudenthal being understood as an epistemological reference model
1973, p. 63) giving birth to a mathematical activity having which, in the case of calculus, translates into two types of
its own legitimate level of rationality although different praxeologies (pragmatic and deductive) as will be
from the standard one underlying formal aspects of limits, explained in the next section.
for example ‘static’ definitions using quantifiers. This renewed understanding of fundamental situations,
This model allows us to argue for the usefulness of freed from the adidactic constraint, allows us to better
taking into account an epistemological obstacle called integrate epistemological obstacles (empirical positivist)
empirical positivism as a grid of interpretation of students’ and their cultural aspects, as debated by Johsua (1996),
reactions to tasks involving limits whether on their own or Radford (1997) and Sierpinska (1987); thus incorporating
in relationship with other concepts such as derivatives, approaches relying on epistemological obstacles such as
integrals, etc. The scientific value of this epistemological Sierpinska’s (1987). This delineates a first important dif-
obstacle lies in its ability to encompass and make sense of ference: taking into account epistemological obstacles.
broader and broader types of mistakes. Let us recall that a praxeology (Chevallard 1999) is a
Lastly, we will show how Belgian teaching institutions model of (mathematical) knowledge that postulates that any
tend to (unwillingly) reinforce the empirical positivism activity, including mathematical ones, can be conceptual-
obstacle by not being able to give credit to the pragmatic ized as a task, something to do, a technique used to solve it,
level of rationality. This will shed new light on the cultural and a justification of the technique used to solve the task
side of the epistemological obstacle pointed out by Radford that can be split into a technology and a theory, a theory
(1997) as well as renewing Sierpinska’s work (1987) pio- being a more abstract level of justification than the
neering epistemological obstacles regarding limits, an technology.
approach to limits that has drawn much less attention in The use of technology and theory constitutes a second
recent years. difference. Whereas Hardy and Barbé et al. point out a
disconnect between theory and technology in school
praxeologies, we envision technology as a form of justifi-
2 Theoretical framework cation not entirely subordinated to theory, each belonging
to intertwined but epistemologically different praxeologies,
The primary tool we rely on is the anthropological theory pragmatic and deductive, each having their own legitimacy
of the didactic (ATD). Given the wide-spread use of this as argued in the next section.
theory and its international recognition,1 we recall only the
relevant parts of ATD used in this paper by contrasting it
with recent research in the field also making use of ATD 3 From calculus to analysis
(Barbé et al. 2005; Hardy 2009).
The scale of levels of codetermination (Chevallard Based on a historical and epistemological study, we show
2002) is at the core of ATD. Using it allows us to envision that it is legitimate to consider calculus as a pragmatic
the didactic of calculus from different perspectives. Barbé praxeology that evolved into a deductive one. The main
et al. discuss restrictions on the knowledge actually taught difference between the two lies in the type of task they
in classrooms imposed by the knowledge to be taught; address and the type of validation they make use of
while Hardy contrasts students’ and instructors’ percep- (technology in a pragmatic praxeology, theory in a
tions of the knowledge to be learned based on a distinction deductive one). From now on, the term calculus will be
between rules and norms inherited from Institutional used to refer to the pragmatic aspect of calculus and ana-
Analysis and Development theory (Ostrom 2005) being lysis to the deductive aspect.
incorporated into ATD. Our research differs from these two
by being located at a different level of the scale which 3.1 Calculus
translates into two differences.
We see ATD as an evolution of Brousseau’s seminal Calculus is focused on the fundamental task of computing
theory of didactical situations (Brousseau 1998). We features of objects (velocities, etc.) using techniques often
extend the concept of a fundamental situation by taking relying on considerations of infinitesimals (Cavalieri’s in-
divisibles) that will subsequently lead to the concepts of
1
Chevallard received the Freundenthal Medal in 2009 for the integrals, derivatives and limits. A characteristic of these
creation and promotion of ATD. objects is that they have not been mathematically defined

123
Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle 637

yet but exist anyway as mental objects shared, or believed end of treatises (Edwards 1982, pp. 68–72). For this new
to be, by some institutions. They are brought into existence foundation to be completed it is necessary to justify the
outside people’s mind by a mechanism of preconstruction, arguments of calculus on an internal basis, getting rid of
using various materializations they are involved in (nota- pragmatic arguments that were until then the standard
tions, linguistic expressions and so on) in a way that eludes practice. This major cleaning is not done instantly. It
any questioning, making those objects’ existence appear results from diverse elements that forbid mathematicians to
obvious (Chevallard 1991). further postpone the study of foundational aspects of their
Justifications given to techniques developed to address discipline. Among these the following play an important
the fundamental task often rely on pragmatic arguments. A role:
technique is validated if the results obtained are in accor-
• Mathematicians have to teach calculus to absolute
dance with results derived using other valid techniques that
beginners and therefore have to clarify the subject by
may even belong to other fields of sciences. For instance,
writing textbooks.
early infinitesimals techniques were used based on their
• The study of functions gives birth to ‘monsters’
accordance with results obtained using arguments of a
showing the limits of kinematic and geometric
kinematic nature (Edwards 1982, pp. 98–99).
intuitions.
These aspects of calculus outline what we will call a
• Major contradictions arising from an unquestioned use
pragmatic praxeology (Schneider 2008, pp. 68–75), a
of infinitesimals have to be smoothed away.
praxeology whose task is to compute features of objects
• Lagrange’s call for the building of a sound basis for
that have not yet been formally defined, that exist as mental
calculus had a noticeable impact. He made this question
objects and préconstruits and whose techniques are justi-
the theme of the then famous Berlin prize that could
fied using pragmatic arguments. We will call such kind of
launch a career.
validation a technology to contrast with the kind of vali-
dation pertaining to the second aspect of calculus, analysis. Various ways of carrying out that goal are considered
It is important to note that such a praxeology is far away before limits: mainly infinitesimals (Carnot 1797) and
from today’s standards of rigour but cannot be considered power series (Lagrange 1797). None of these are consid-
non-rigorous for that reason. It is another type of rigour that ered sound enough. We have to wait until Cauchy. He is
prevailed for most of the history of calculus. Current considered by many to be the true creator of analysis and
standards are conventions that could be chosen differently. the modern concept of limit even if Weierstrass brought
As an example, a forerunner of the derivative defined by subsequent improvements (Dugac 2003, p. 93). Cauchy’s
a limit appears in Fermat’s work, among others (Edwards definition is a tool created to support the entire architecture
1982, pp. 122–125): it is what we get from suppressing of analysis, using for the first time on a large scale the
terms in an algebraic expression. The suppressing tech- famous so-called e - d technique (Grabiner 2005, p. 115).
niques may differ according to the subject at hand, for The way we have outlined analysis defines a second
example suppressing common roots in a ratio. The unity kind of praxeology we shall call deductive (Schneider
lies in the use of linguistic forms such as ‘as close as we 2008, pp. 68–75). This kind of praxeology contrasts with
want’ or ‘close enough to’. The limit appears as a prag- calculus in that the fundamental task at hand is to define the
matic model of the derivative. mental objects used in calculus in the first kind of praxe-
ology and build a deductive theory that would be self-
3.2 Analysis and the deductive praxeological level contained with no references to other fields. Often the
techniques used in a pragmatic praxeology are used in
After centuries of discovery, a new train of thought deductive ones as definitions. The definition of integral
emerged that intended to give calculus a foundation that given by Cauchy is a good example of such a procedure: an
would at least equate to the ancient Greeks’ level of rigour, approximation procedure is turned into a definition that, in
still being considered a reference of the genre. There were turn, is used to prove theorems about integrals (existence,
many reasons for this change but a prominent one was the etc.).
emergence of a new concept, that of function. This concept In such praxeologies, the status of a definition can be
allows mathematicians to formulate problems that origi- very different from that in pragmatic ones. In pragmatic
nated in physics or geometry in a way independent from praxeologies, a concept is, in the first place, an instru-
them. This conceptual revolution permits mathematicians mental model of an object whatever its membership,
to envision calculus as a new discipline called analysis on mathematical or not, which requires some kind of detach-
which geometry and physics would rely, inverting its his- ment between the model and the modelled objects. In
torical genesis. Starting with Euler, geometry and physics deductive praxeologies a definition is chosen according to
are seen as applications of calculus and thus pushed at the its ability to build a deductive architecture which is

123
638 P. Job, M. Schneider

coherent with fewer concepts that are the most general reference to Cavalieri’s work. He deduces, for instance, the
possible. ratio between the volumes of two solids lying between two
The creation of analysis by Cauchy was a crucial parallel planes from the constancy of the ratio between the
moment in the history of calculus. It turned it into analysis, measures of their respective indivisibles, for example the
moving from a pragmatic praxeology to a deductive one, surfaces obtained by the intersection of the two solids with
and at the same time established the skeleton of calculus planes parallel to the aforementioned ones. This compari-
courses for generations to come, where one starts with son is bold because some information about volumes is
limits and then builds others upon this. It constitutes a deduced from another about areas, getting from a dimen-
radical twist from the historical development and genesis sion to another one. Nevertheless it is valid in this case.
of calculus. We understand with calculus and analysis how This procedure becomes an obstacle in other cases, for
much research and didactic are intertwined. The obligation instance when two volumes of revolution are thought to be
to teach calculus to beginners combined with the need to in the same ratio as the ratio of the generating areas
establish solid foundations of the subject historically led to (Fig. 1).
a didactical inversion (Freudenthal 1961, p. ix). Along the same lines, some pupils doubt that a curvi-
linear area can be exactly matched by a sequence of rec-
tilinear areas because the curvilinear area is not covered by
4 Empirical positivism, an obstacle in the learning the rectilinear areas except when they become lines, but
of calculus and analysis then their areas are 0. Isn’t it the same process at work in
the nineteenth century that dictates the erroneous definition
We illustrate how errors pertaining to calculus and ana- of the area of a surface as the limit of the areas of inscribed
lysis, found among pupils and students, can be interpreted polyhedral surfaces, a definition Schwartz will stand
as a by-product of an empirical positivist attitude (EP). The against using a rather sophisticated argument?
soundness of this approach lies in the ability of this model Let us be more specific on this example. With the help
to encompass, in a coherent framework, broader and of their teacher, pupils, as a prelude to learning the integral
broader epistemological obstacles, namely the well-known concept, approach the measure m of the area under the
geometric obstacle of limit (GOL) and the heterogeneity of curve y = x3 between 0 and 1 with sums of measures of
dimension obstacle (HDO): GOL  HDO  EP. areas of rectangles
We first explain what empirical positivism is and then ð1  2n þ n12 Þ ð1 þ 2n þ n12 Þ
provide several examples of the aforementioned genealogy. \m\
4 4
According to empiricism, knowledge has its roots in
sensory experiences. This philosophy goes against ratio- At this point, most pupils agree that 14 is a good approxi-
nalism, which asserts that knowledge comes from human mation of m. Some of them, using limits, even advocate 14 to
reason. Following, in the epistemology of sciences,
empirical positivism is a position that envisions scientific
laws and concepts as an exact reflection of objects found in
the ‘real’ world (Fourez et al. 1997, p. 80):
Positivism asserts…we can discover scientific laws
independently from any context or project…models,
notions and scientific laws exist by themselves and
would be an exact copy of the world…physics’ laws
exist by themselves and are in no way models devised
by humans to understand the world that surrounds
them.
The empirical positivist attitude allows us to make sense
of reactions related to geometric objects or magnitudes
defined using limits. The tangent for instance is thought of Fig. 1 Despite the arguments being given to them, pupils insist that
by some pupils as a limit of secants without any topology the result is correct and argue using magnitudes arguments (solids are
being defined on lines (Sierpinska 1987). The tangent being made of their radial sections) as if the measures of magnitudes did not
for them the primary object, its slope being only a property, exist on their own, measures being only a reflection of what we ‘see’
about magnitudes. This obstacle can thus be seen as a consequence of
a tangent cannot be defined by its slope (Schneider 2008). some sort of empirical positivism. This interpretation translates well
Let us move to comparison of magnitudes using ‘indi- to give some meaning to similar errors found not only among pupils
visibles’ (Schneider 1991). The term indivisible is a but also among future teachers (Schneider 1991)

123
Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle 639

ð12þ 1 Þ
n n2 ð1þ2þ 1 Þ
n n2 As an illustration, technique 3 leads to investigating the
be the exact value of m, because 4 and 4 both
following equality for the first pair, the left-hand side being
have the same limit. On the contrary, other pupils are
the mean velocity for p1 on the interval [t, Dt] and the right-
reluctant to accept such conclusions. They argue that
hand side the mean velocity for p2 on the same interval:
however large n is, the rectangles will never entirely cover
the required area. There will always be something left. And pffiffiffi ðt þ DtÞ2  t2

when those rectangles become segments they have an area Dt
whose measure is 0. It is therefore impossible to have a
This equality can be developed into
sum of these that is not zero. Pupils have a hard time pffiffiffi
considering 14 the limit of the two sequences as something 3 ¼ 2t þ Dt
outside the realm of areas. They act as if the limit process
Taking [t, Dt] to be smaller and smaller, it leads to taking
was carried out on geometric objects and not on numbers, pffiffiffi pffiffi
the measures of these objects (Schneider 1991). Dt = 0 in 3 ¼ 2t þ Dt giving t ¼ 23. The instantaneous
Some pupils are reluctant to accept that the derivative velocity of a position law p at time t is obtained by taking
concept will provide an exact value for an instantaneous Dt = 0 in
velocity and other instantaneous rates of change such as an pðt þ DtÞ  pðtÞ
instantaneous flow. Empirical data can be given, taken Dt
from recent experimentations, to illustrate this aspect. We
only present the part that is relevant to our subject. The after all the algebraic simplifications have been carried out.
reader is invited to refer to Gantois and Schneider (2012) Technique 3 can thus be understood as the limit concept
for further details. The engineering is built using Brous- being ‘caught in the act’ serving as a pragmatic model
seau’s theory seen from the angle of ATD. The general of instantaneous velocity.
context is the following. Pupils are asked (task T) to Let us look at what happened with the pupils at this
algebraically determine when two vehicles driving along a stage when they had to deal with technique 3. They first
rectilinear path have the same velocity. A milieu2 (Brous- start by computing mean velocities on numerical intervals
seau 1998) is designed to promote the development of an hoping to find some interval on which they are equal but
infinitesimal technique (technique 3) that enables students doubt they will achieve the desired goal. The algebraic
to answer this question and which can be interpreted as a register is then considered based on a harmless question of
forerunner of the derivative concept based on limits. This is the experimenter (‘Try to remember…What are you look-
done in three main parts. The two first parts, which we will ing for?’). After some time pupils come to the following
not elaborate on, are concerned with connecting the char- derivation. They choose to use t1 and t2 to denote the ends
of an interval in which the looked-for instant lies. The
acteristics of movements (acceleration, etc.) with the  
characteristics of their graphical representations (concav- mean velocity can then be written t22  t12 =ðt2  t1 Þ,
ity, etc.) and designing graphical techniques to answer T. which can be simplified to t2 ? t1. There then follows an
pffiffiffi
Three techniques arise, based on well-chosen didactic equation with two variables, t2 þ t1 ¼ 3, about which the
variables. The following algebraic version of T is then pupils do not feel at ease because they have ‘one equation
presented to the pupils. First they have to deal with p1 ðtÞ ¼ and two unknowns’. The idea that one instant is looked for
pffiffiffi pffiffiffi tells the pupils to equate t1 and t2. The solution is then
3t and p2 ðtÞ ¼ t2 , then with p1 ðtÞ ¼ 3t and p2 ðtÞ ¼ t3 . pffiffiffi
The first two techniques serve one main purpose. They quickly found by solving the equation 2t ¼ 3. Pupils then
allow a pragmatic validation of technique 3, because try to justify their technique to other pupils and the teacher
results obtained on the first pair are in accordance with from which they seek approval.
technique 3. These first two are ruled out because, unlike It is interesting to note at the same time their use of
technique 3, they cannot be used to cope with the second infinitesimal techniques and persisting interrogations
pair as they were for the first one. This allows focusing on about their validity (‘It looks strange to equate t2 and t1’).
technique 3. Technique 3 sums up to finding smaller and These questionings about validity and meaning are
smaller intervals where p1 and p2 have the same mean focused on Dt being zero or not. This emphasis can be
velocity because, based on continuity assumptions, they interpreted in the following manner. Dt and Dp have a
should then have the same instantaneous velocity at some meaning independent of their ratio as is the case with the
point in the interval. mean velocity concept and in the sensory world. These are
thus the primary objects on which their attention is
focused. The ratio only comes later. As a consequence, the
2
A task for which the students know there is a rational way for instantaneous velocity is not envisioned as the limit of a
solving it, which makes it possible for them not to rely on didactic
ratio but as a ratio of limits, reminding us of endless debate
tricks.

123
640 P. Job, M. Schneider

around Leibniz and Newton’s calculus and infinitesimal important it is for students to be given the opportunity to
procedures. The functional link between Dp and Dt is not investigate pragmatic praxeologies as a necessary step in
perceived: both are autonomous. The reader is asked to questioning their epistemological beliefs as well as a
refer to Gantois and Schneider (2012) for more details. stepping board to deductive praxeologies.
With these excerpts we find interrogations on the pupils’ To further illustrate our point, we give an example,
side going in the same direction as those found in taken from a paper to be published (Job 2014), explaining
Schneider (1992). In this paper, they consider the instan- the relationship entertained by students engaged in a
taneous velocity concept to be an extension of the mean teaching qualification and already having, or soon to have,
velocity concept and thus consider a 0 by 0 ratio to be a degree in mathematics or engineering, with limits and the
physically meaningless: ‘In no time, no volume is poured real numbers. This experiment was conducted by us in two
and we cannot have a flow with no volume’ (Schneider different Belgian universities (Université de Namur, Uni-
1992, p. 341). They also argue that instantaneous velocity versité de Liège) across several years.3 Results shown
‘doesn’t exist’ because it is impossible to compute exactly below have remained consistent through the years. Stu-
using observations and measurements; for example, dents were asked the following question:
velocity is denied the status of an intellectual concept, it ‘When writing 8e [ 0 : jx  aj\e, should we specify
doesn’t exist because it cannot be carried out in the ‘real’ that e is very small?’
world (Schneider 1992). For many students, working within the framework of
To conclude: instantaneous rates of change are denied real numbers,
any legitimacy by these students and pupils alike because 8e [ 0 : jx  aj\e
they are thought of in reference to the sensory world to
which they cannot belong and the fact that mathematics is means that ‘x tends towards a but is never equal to a’. So if
considered to be an extrapolation of this sensory world. anything is to be specified, from the student’s perspective,
Instantaneous rates of change can thus neither belong to it is that x must be different from a.
physics nor can they to mathematics. When a proof is given by us that ‘x = a’, using the
Empirical positivism also acts as an obstacle towards the density of real numbers, some students keep going in the
learning of analysis. In Job (2011) we study the teaching of same direction, insisting that e is different from 0 so x
limits in a deductive praxeology and show how much a cannot be equal to a and/or modifying the above writing as
deductive approach to this concept is a demanding task for follows:
students. To sum up, students are asked to propose defi- 8e [ 0 : 0\jx  aj\e:
nitions of certain behaviour of sequences of real numbers
and then prove properties related to this behaviour. Stu- Students, soon to become teachers, thus have a hard time
dents are mostly unable to make their definitions evolve. understanding basic properties of real numbers, in con-
They stay stuck with definitions that are ‘descriptions’ of nection with limits. They envision the above statement as a
what they see of the studied behaviour. They are not able to mere description, using mathematical symbols, of what
envision their definitions as something to be chosen to they see of limits: x takes values closer and closer to a, as
allow proofs despite the many contradictions pointed out close as we want. It is interesting to cross these data with
by the teacher. Students see a definition as a description of two elements. First, in the reference4 textbook Espace
some mental concept they believe every one of them share. Math (Adam and Lousberg 2000, p. 65), limits are defined
They therefore do not understand the rules of the game they likewise:
are asked to play, feeling they are asked something A variable p gets closer and closer to the constant real
unnecessarily complicated because ‘everyone agrees with k or p tends to k if and only if the absolute value of
the found properties’, ‘nothing has to be proved’. Along the difference between p and k can be made smaller
these lines it should be stressed that the students are placed than any strictly positive real number or jp  kj\a
in some kind of paradox relating the two praxeological where a is a strictly positive real number that can be
levels. On the one hand they question the validity of pro- chosen as we want.
cedures used to compute the measures of curvilinear areas
and on the other hand the same empirical positivist attitude Thus incoherent definitions of limits are also found in
deprives them of understanding the fundamental task of a reference textbooks. Second, such ‘definitions’ of limits are
deductive praxeology (building a deductive structure) and endorsed by in-service teachers. They see in it the
why their initial questioning is meaningless in this new 3
More than 5 years. This experiment is in fact part of a course in the
framework (the measure of an area is defined by the limit didactic of mathematics we are in charge of and is repeated each year.
process so the limit process gives without any doubt the 4
See below for more details on Espace Math’s importance in the
measure of that area). From this we understand how French-speaking part of Belgium.

123
Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle 641

possibility of stripping a more regular definition of limits designed is a very similar way) given more than 20 years
from what they consider too difficult for their pupils, its of experience in the training of pre- and in-service teachers.
intertwining between f(x) and x. Using the above ‘defini-
tion’, they can split a regular definition into two distinct 5.1 Secondary school
parts that are supposedly easier for the pupils to grasp: the
limit of a function f at a is b when f(x) tends to b whenever In secondary school, the current praxeology related to
x tends to a. The ‘tends’ in ‘x tends to a’ and the ‘tends’ in calculus–analysis belongs neither to the pragmatic level
‘f(x) tends to b’ are considered meaningful on their own, nor the deductive one. It lies in some nowhere land as to
only being connected by an implication (‘whenever’). Thus the mathematical standpoint. We will therefore call that
experienced teachers and reference textbooks ‘behave’ like praxeology a didactic one to contrast with sound mathe-
our pre-service teachers. The secondary school system as a matical ones. It consists of a mixture of the two praxeo-
whole is blindly teaching incoherent mathematical defini- logical levels that gives birth to a didactic praxeology with
tions of limits based on ‘didactical’ considerations. Those ‘holes’ (Rouy 2007, p. 236). That is, a praxeology where
definitions again resonate with the empirical positivism the logos part is missing or at least almost irrelevant
obstacle at the level of notations, as already mentioned compared with the praxis one. Let us give an example
above, because they once more give credit to notations and focusing on limits but paradigmatic of the teaching of
pseudo-concepts that allow pupils to consider mathemati- analysis (Job 2011, pp. 197–215).
cal definitions as mere extrapolations of sensory experi- Secondary school is in a somewhat peculiar situation
ences, creating a contradiction. Instantaneous velocity is with respect to mathematics. Its goal is not to produce
understood as mean velocity pushed ‘to the limit’. It is thus mathematics but to teach it. The legitimacy of mathematics
a ratio. This vision is backed up by the limit definitions taught in secondary school is drawn from the institution of
found in reference textbooks: instantaneous velocity is a mathematicians, an institution teachers encounter during
ratio of limits of variables (and not the limit of a ratio). But their degree. Those teachers often consider deductive
this understanding of instantaneous velocity is troublesome aspects of mathematics and the accompanying idea of
because a ratio of zero by zero is meaningless in mathe- ‘rigour’ to be the very essence of the subject to be taught.
matics and has no counterpart in the sensory world. In our case calculus–analysis gets reduced to analysis. The
pragmatic praxeological level of calculus is ignored.
Unfortunately, secondary school fails to teach analysis
5 The empirical positivism obstacle reinforced to pupils in part because of their empirical positivist atti-
tude towards mathematics. Confronted with the obligation
In this section, we show how a blurred distinction of succeeding in teaching mathematics, secondary school
between the pragmatic and deductive praxeological lev- has no other choice than to make its didactic praxeology
els by learning institutions (secondary school and uni- appear, from an outside perspective, as a valid deductive
versity) tends to reinforce the empirical positivist attitude one, lighter than the one used in analysis by mathemati-
as an epistemological obstacle to learning calculus and cians but anyway having a logical coherence. To do so,
analysis. secondary school makes use of enough definitions, results
We shall review in turn what is going on in secondary and notations that are considered emblematic of analysis to
school and at university level, but let us emphasize first that pretend that a meaningful mathematical activity is con-
these results are dealing with the Communauté Française ducted in the classrooms. Among these blazons, the defi-
(CF), the French-speaking part of Belgium. This geo- nition of a limit plays a key role as the central concept of
graphical restriction is of importance because CF has its analysis.
own set of rules (as far as education is involved) and it has From an inside perspective, the situation looks quite
a rather small area. We are thus facing a manageable different. Secondary school tries to teach the limit defini-
institution in terms of schools and universities. There are tion using various tricks to make students believe that this
only five universities, which allows an exhaustive review definition is a somewhat complicated (mathematical) way
of mathematical courses dealing with calculus (see below of saying something very natural. For instance, it gives
for a more accurate description of the studied courses). As students tables with values of x and f(x) for a given func-
for schools, they are in greater number than universities, tion, waiting for the students to recognize some sort of
but there are fewer than 10 reference textbooks in use behaviour that could be put into sentences such as ‘as
dealing with the subject of calculus. Of these reference x tends to … f(x) approaches …’ (see Espace Math).
textbooks, one of them, Espace Math, is an all-time best- Starting from such sentences, teachers gradually turn these
seller that gives us a rather faithful image of what the into the required form ‘f(x) can be made as close as one
teaching of calculus looks like in CF (others being wishes to …’ using arguments and ranges of graphics that

123
642 P. Job, M. Schneider

belong more to rhetoric than mathematics. In other words, 5.2 University level
the very way limits are introduced runs along the lines of
empirical positivism: concepts are just a (sometimes At university level, in CF, in most courses devised for
complicated) way of saying what everyone can see on a students in mathematics, physics and engineering, the
graphic or in a table. focus is put straightaway on the deductive aspects of
Such an approach is misleading in nature, for limits praxeologies (e.g. analysis) using axiomatic presentations,
were designed by Cauchy to conduct proofs and define but in a much more visible way than in secondary school:
other key concepts of analysis such as the derivative. But you are taught all the definitions and proofs making the
except for a few trivial ones, proofs in secondary school are deductive architecture of analysis.5 The reason for this
left aside. So the very use of limits in the deductive emphasis is obviously different from the one prevailing in
praxeology (where it belongs) is left aside. The school secondary school. Teachers at university level are profes-
praxeology thus bears no fundamental character sional mathematicians, the ones who (as an institution)
whatsoever. designed analysis. They are thus their own reference and do
Such a fool’s game is not the consequence of any not have, as long as the scientific side is involved, to obey
malicious thoughts on the side of secondary school, but the anybody except their own institution. This prevalence of
result of antagonist constraints. On the one hand, it has to deductive aspects and axiomatic presentations is to be
teach limits in a way mathematicians would recognize as linked with empirical positivism and another epistemo-
valid, which is a daunting task. On the other hand it must logical attitude, more or less consciously held by profes-
succeed in that task. The only way secondary school has at sional mathematicians: the Platonic epistemology.
its disposal to reconcile the two is to take the deductive Following Bouveresse (1998, p. 1), mathematical Pla-
praxeology, strip it of most of its content and wrap it in a tonism is a philosophical conception which postulates that
discourse that can be accepted by pupils even if the cost is mathematical objects exist independently of our thought
to propose tasks that have no fundamental character. This activities and knowledge. Mathematical concepts are thus
wrapping is partly a consequence of its unawareness of the not invented, they are discovered. The discovery is made
existence of another praxeology (a pragmatic one) where possible using mathematical intuition. Charles Hermite’s
the limit concept is legitimate. So secondary school’s words are very exemplary of this epistemology. He deeply
praxeology with respect to limits lies in a no-man’s land, believes we simply have to use ‘the eyes of the mind’ to
being neither in a deductive nor a pragmatic praxeology. discover new mathematical objects (Dugac 2003, p. 197).
Similar conclusions are drawn in Rouy (2007) regarding Our interest in that philosophy lies both in the fact that
the derivative. according to Davis and Hersch (2012, p. 359), ‘‘Most
This awkward situation tends to reinforce an empiricist writers on the subject seem to agree that the typical
positivist attitude among pupils. It is indeed very inter- working mathematician is a Platonist’’ and its connections
esting to note how the derivative concept is taught. Any with mathematical teaching, in particular with empirical
textbook in Communauté Française de Belgique proceeds positivism related to pragmatic and deductive praxeologies.
along the same lines; and this is confirmed by our expe- Part of the connection between these two epistemologies
rience in the field when visiting pre- and in-service is rather obvious. The two share the idea that we simply
teachers. The derivative f 0 ðaÞ is introduced as the slope of have to observe objects whether they are from the ‘real’
the tangent T to the graphic of f at (a, f(a)). It is then world or from the mathematical world to gain some
suggested that the derivative can be computed by a limit awareness/insight about them: they are not concepts
process using graphics where the pupils can see a invented by man to structure their sensations, they both
sequence of lines rotating around a fixed point (a, f(a)). exist in ‘nature’. Hermite further illuminates us as to the
The tangent is then ‘defined’ using the derivative, which connections between Platonism and empirical positivism
creates a vicious circle. The primary object from which from a mathematician’s perspective. He believes that
the derivative is ‘defined’ is the tangent, which is in turn mathematical objects are ‘more real’ than objects from the
defined using the derivative. The limit involved in the ‘real’ world. Observing mathematical objects better
derivative is thus not a concept about numbers but informs us as to the nature of the ‘real’ world than objects
something acting on geometrical objects, graphics and from the ‘real’ world itself (Dugac 2003, p. 197).
tangents. It is therefore no surprise that pupils have a hard For a mathematician holding that kind of epistemology,
time envisioning mathematical concepts from a different once a concept has been discovered, teaching that concept
perspective than sensory perceptions put into symbols,
symbols that have to share the same exact properties as 5
The only noticeable exception is the course given by the teacher in
those they ‘observe’ in ‘concrete’ objects: that is exactly charge of first year students in mathematics and physics at the
how they are taught. University of Louvain-la-Neuve.

123
Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle 643

mainly becomes showing it, that is, presenting its axiom- extended real line using some sort of microscope (Pétry
atic definition and use in various theorems. Either you are 2010, pp. 40–45). Questions pertaining to the nature of
able to see what has to be seen because you have the infinitesimals are put aside using a visual token allowing
required mathematical insight or you are not. As a conse- students to make use of their sensory perceptions: what you
quence there is no real point in paying attention to students’ have to understand is what I show you on the board with
mental objects and concept images, even if they are in my microscope.
contradiction with the mathematical concepts to be taught.
The pragmatic praxeological level of calculus is thus left
aside and the empirical positivism held by students is never
6 Conclusion
confronted, allowed to survive in some confusing episte-
mological imbroglio. A student may well be aware of
The blurred distinction, for learning institutions, whether it
contradictions between his mental objects and the mathe-
is Belgian secondary school or university, between the
matical ones. He will simply get past the contradiction by
pragmatic and deductive praxeological levels tends to
assuming that his constructions are not mathematical. So
reinforce an already well-established epistemological atti-
there is no comparison to be made. This state of affairs is
tude among learners, the empirical positivist attitude, as an
closely related to what Chevallard (2005, p. 13) denounces
epistemological obstacle towards the learning of calculus
when he is speaking about monumentalism: mathematical
and analysis. Such a learning framework allows students
courses sum up to a museum visit, showing concept after
and pupils alike to never face their deep unconscious
concept.
epistemological beliefs about mathematics, beliefs that
Among axiomatic presentations of analysis in CF, two
may survive through an entire degree in mathematics.
stand out from the others because they make use of non-
As an implication for teaching, it appears interesting to
standard analysis (NSA). Our aim is to have a look at the
engage students, but not exclusively, in tasks allowing
way this theory can be used in CF, as a didactic tool to
them to develop meaningful (to them) and significant
teach analysis, in connection with empirical positivism.
mathematics (from the mathematical point of view), based
This will further illuminate us as to why empirical posi-
on mental objects related to calculus (thus belonging to the
tivism is reinforced by universities. Having this goal in
pragmatic praxeological level of rationality) and then other
mind we focus on two different courses designed by A.
tasks offering them the possibility to realize the limits and
Pétry on the one hand (Pétry 2010) and J. Bair and V.
paradoxes of those mental objects and thus the need to
Henry on the other hand (Bair and Henry 2008). Both have
develop a new level of rationality, a safer ground on which
in common the belief that NSA is a formalism that is easier
mathematics can be developed. In a paper to be published
to understand than the standard one, because it is felt by
(Job 2014), we present and analyse a task designed for
their authors as more ‘intuitive’ and ‘closer to the way
secondary school to help pupils lessen the gap between
mathematicians and engineers think’ (Pétry 2010). Bair and
calculus and analysis when they enrol in university to
Henry (2006, p. 1) explicitly endorse a positivist attitude
follow a degree in mathematics.
towards mathematics: NSA is a better way to teach analysis
At the same time, the teachers should be acquainted with
because it is a better extrapolation of the sensory world
enough of the epistemological evolution of calculus, in
than the standard formalism is. We are thus confronted
particular the possibility to do some mathematics without
with an explicit will to teach along the lines of a positivist
an already well-established formal framework, for example
epistemology. The adopted formalism feels to us like a
relying on mental objects, to raise some degree of aware-
trompe l’oeil. Going back to what we previously said, it
ness about the importance of the aforementioned tasks.
gives credit to instantaneous velocity understood as a ratio
This seems feasible at the school level through pre- and in-
of infinitesimals, depriving students of the opportunity to
service teachers’ courses, but it might be more difficult at
consider mathematical concepts as not just an extrapolation
the university level when as pointed out for instance by
of sensory experiences (unquestionable ‘facts’ for these
Barquero et al. (2013, p. 325) we are facing institutional
authors) but as intellectual constructions whose aim is to
constraints such as a tendency to
structure the world. Considering the highly sophisticated
definitions of hyper-reals and the like found in NSA, it is organise its [mathematics] teaching according to the
doubtful that any first-year student would be able to internal logic of concepts (instead of those of prob-
understand these constructions. The problem is eluded by lems), eliminate the rationale of the taught mathe-
Pétry using a technological metaphor that again goes in the matical praxeologies, presenting them as ‘lifeless
direction of empirical positivism despite the fact that he is monuments’ that must be studied without showing its
not endorsing this epistemology. To him, hyper-reals, functionality. In addition, all these pre-established
whether infinitely small or large, can be ‘seen’ on an answers are supposed to be transparent and not

123
644 P. Job, M. Schneider

problematic, promoting ‘authoritarianism’ [which is] limits, and try to determine how much of these conceptions
reinforced by ‘applicationism’. can be interpreted not as inherent to the students them-
selves but as a by-product of teachers’ and researchers’
Our two praxeological levels (pragmatic and deductive)
(implicit) epistemologies preventing them from under-
also allow us to look at some research in the field of cal-
standing how much the tasks they enrol students in may
culus with a different eye, asking new questions pertaining
contribute to create these ‘misconceptions’.
to learning and teaching calculus. We shall consider two
Let us turn to Przenioslo (2005) and Swinyard (2011).
different questions. This concluding thought may be
Both propose a type of task (T) designed to make students
understood as an echo of what we underlined in the
build their own definition of limit using similar principles.
introduction, what we felt was an in-between positioning
Starting from an initial definition, students are asked to
among other research.
create new ones encompassing more and more examples
Let us start with Edwards and Ward (2004). They con-
and ‘counter-examples’ (graphic or analytic) given by
clude (p. 419) that ‘the special nature of mathematical
either the teacher or other students. For instance a student
definitions should be addressed more directly in mathe-
saying ‘limx!a f ð xÞ ¼ b when f(x) gets closer and closer to
matics courses at all levels’. Our research is in agreement
b as x gets closer to a’ could be confronted with the fol-
with this conclusion. We nevertheless are more cautious as
lowing argument: ‘according to your definition |x| has -5
to their reasoning relying on the distinction (p. 412)
as a limit in 0 because |x| is getting closer and closer to -5
between an ‘extracted’ definition ‘based on examples of
as x is getting closer to 0 but also 0 and in fact any number
actual usage’ and a ‘stipulated’ one, an ‘explicit and self-
smaller than 0. Thus following your definition |x| should
conscious setting up of the meaning-relation between some
have an infinite number of limits in 0’.
word and some object’. They believe that ‘mathematical
Distinguishing between pragmatic and deductive
definitions [are] stipulated’, whereas most ‘everyday lan-
praxeologies makes us question the mathematical rele-
guage’ definitions are ‘extracted’ and thus argue that fail-
vance of T:
ure on the students’ side to distinguish between
‘extracted’ and ‘stipulated’ definitions ‘affects their • T does not fit into pragmatic praxeologies. We are not
understanding of the concept themselves’, they have a trying to determine any kind of magnitude.
tendency to ‘rely on their concept image instead of the • T does not fit into deductive praxeologies either. If
related concept definitions’. We are reluctant to agree with we look again at the constitution of this last kind of
this, based on the following ground. As we have seen, in praxeology we recall that Cauchy built his definition of
pragmatic praxeologies (that is, in calculus as we defined limit not to comply with a set S of functions sharing a
it) most definitions can obviously not be considered ‘stip- common feature given beforehand but to be able to
ulated’. We should then conclude following these authors prove theorems about derivatives and the like. The
that no meaningful mathematical work has been done common feature comes afterward as a consequence of
during the calculus era, which is not tenable. Moreover, the definition.
following Lakatos’ seminal work (1976), definitions in
If T does not fit into either a pragmatic or a deductive
deductive praxeologies are often proof-generated, as is the
praxeology we are then entitled to raise some concerns
case for the limit definition (Burn 2005), and thus have
about its mathematical soundness because these praxeolo-
some ‘extracted’ side being the result of an iterative pro-
gies make up the epistemological skeleton of calculus and
cess based on usage, trying to prove a theorem. We thus
analysis.
have to reject the distinction between ‘extracted’ and
Our interrogations are further deepened for at least two
‘stipulated’ as a means to characterize what mathematical
reasons.
definitions are. Finally, mathematical definitions in calcu-
First, as a sort of side-effect, Cauchy’s approach to
lus and analysis have a history that cannot be reduced to
creating definitions and proof-generated definitions in
their latest evolution, because this latest trend can only be
general may lead a definition to encompass objects that
understood in the light of the previous understandings of
would not at first, from a ‘naı̈ve’ point of view, be con-
those definitions. Somehow Edwards and Ward give, at the
sidered to fall under the scope of that definition. For
researchers’ level, an example of the blurred distinction
instance, with Cauchy’s definition we are forced to accept
between pragmatic and deductive praxeologies, the
the limit of a constant function to be that constant, an
importance of which we have argued, by not being able to
incorporation which is felt by more than one student as
give credit to definitions the way they were used in calculus
unsound (Antibi 1988, pp. 183–185). So if we want to play
and its very relevance in the subsequent constitution of
T with S including constant functions we are likely to get
analysis. More broadly we ask the question of reconsider-
into trouble. It means that in general terms S should be
ing the so-called ‘misconceptions’ of students regarding

123
Empirical positivism, an epistemological obstacle 645

filled only with limits of functions that do not interfere too Barquero, B., Bosch, M., & Gascón, J. (2013). The ecological
much with students’ concept image, which is not likely to dimension in the teaching of mathematical modelling at
university. Recherches en Didactique des Mathématiques,
help them in making a transition towards deductive 33(3), 307–338.
reasoning. Bezuidenhout, J. (2001). Limits and continuity: some conceptions of
Second, we may contrast T with deductive praxeologies first-year students. International Journal of Mathematical Edu-
from another point of view. In deductive praxeologies you cation in Science and Technology, 32(4), 487–500.
Bouveresse, J. (1998). Sur le sens du mot « platonisme » dans
have, at least in principle, a rather clear termination cri- l’expression « platonisme mathématique » . Conférence du 19
terion: your definition is good enough when it allows you novembre 1998 donnée à l’Université de Genève pour le groupe
to prove the theorem you want to prove. Using T the ter- genevois de la Société romande de philosophie.
mination criterion becomes rather loose. The iterative Brousseau, G. (1998). Théorie des situations didactiques. Grenoble:
La Pensée Sauvage.
process of building a definition ends when either the tea- Burn, B. (2005). The vice: some historically inspired and proof-
cher or the students are not able to propose new ‘counter- generated steps to limits of sequences. Educational Studies in
examples’. And when we reach that ending step we haven’t Mathematics, 60(3), 269–295.
proved anything yet. Thus what have we done? Taking a Carnot, L. (1797). Oeuvres complètes (Réflexions sur la méthaphy-
sique du calcul infinitésimal). (J. Decker, Éd.) Basle.
step back, we feel that T is a rather elaborate kind of os- Chevallard, Y. (1991). La transposition didactique: Du savoir savant
tension (Brousseau 1998, p. 46): with T students are asked, au savoir enseigné. Grenoble: La Pensée Sauvage.
even if it is under a sophisticated guise looking like a proof Chevallard, Y. (1999). L’analyse des pratiques enseignantes en
and refutation game, to build the definition the teacher théorie anthropologique du didactique. Recherches en Didac-
tique des Mathématiques, 19(2), 221–266.
wants them to build and not the definition required by an Chevallard, Y. (2002). Organiser l’étude. 3. Écologie & régulation. In
‘outside’ relevant mathematical problem. J.-L. Dorier, M. Artaud, M. Artigue, R. Berthelot & R. Floris
Based on these two reasons we are asking our second (Eds.), Actes de la XIe école d’été de didactique des mathéma-
question: how sound are researches claiming that they have tiques (pp. 41–56). Grenoble: La Pensée Sauvage.
Chevallard, Y. (2005). La place des mathématiques vivantes dans
been able to make students build the conventional limit l’éducation secondaire. Publication de l’APMEP, 168, 239–263.
definition; what mathematical and epistemological value Cornu, B. (1991). Limits. In D. Tall (Ed.), Advanced mathematical
have the tasks they rely on? thinking (pp. 153–166). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
As a last interrogation, it would be most interesting to Davis, P., & Hersch, R. (2012). The mathematical experience. Boston:
Birkhäuser.
determine if our conclusions hold in other countries and, if Dugac, P. (2003). Histoire de l’analyse. Paris: Vuibert.
not, why not. Edwards, C. (1982). The historical development of the calculus. New
York: Springer.
Acknowledgments We thank the reviewers and editor-in-chief for Edwards, B., & Ward, M. (2004). Surprises from mathematics
their help in the revision process. education research: student (mis)use of mathematical definitions.
The American Mathematical Monthly, 111(5), 411–424.
Fourez, G., Englebert-Lecomte, V., & Mathy, P. (1997). Nos savoirs
sur les savoirs. Bruxelles: De Boeck.
References Freudenthal, H. (1961). The concept and the role of the model in
mathematics and natural and social sciences. In Proceedings of
Adam, A., & Lousberg, F. (2000). Espace Math 56, Livre de l’élève. the Colloquium Sponsored by the Division of Philosophy of
Bruxelles: De Boeck-Wesmael. Sciences of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
Antibi, A. (1988). Étude sur l’enseignement de méthodes de Sciences of the International Union of History and Philosophy of
démonstration. Enseignement de la notion de limite: réflexions, Sciences of the International Union of History and P. Dordrecht:
propositions. Thèse de doctorat, Université Paul Sabatier. Reidel.
Artigue, M. (2000). Teaching and learning calculus: what can be Freudenthal, H. (1973). Mathematics as an educational task. New
learned from education research and curricular changes in York: Springer.
France? In E. Dubinsky, A. Schoenfeld, & J. Kaput (Eds.), Gantois, J.-Y., & Schneider, M. (2012). Une forme embryonnaire du
Research in collegiate mathematics education (Vol. IV, concept de dérivée induite par un milieu graphico-cinématique
pp. 1–15). Providence: American Mathematical Society. dans une praxéologie ‘modélisation’. Recherches en Didactique
Bagni, G. T. (2005). The historical roots of the limit notion: cognitive des Mathématiques, 32(1), 57–99.
development and development of representation registers. Grabiner, J. (2005). The origins of Cauchy’s rigorous calculus. New
Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics, and Technology York: Dover.
Education, 5(4), 453–468. Hardy, N. (2009). Students’ perceptions of institutional practices: the
Bair, J., & Henry, V. (2006). Une vision positiviste de nombres case of limits of functions in college level calculus courses.
hyperréels au moyen d’angles. Liège: École de Gestion de Educational Studies in Mathematics, 72(3), 341–358.
l’Université de Liège. Job, P. (2011). Étude du rapport à la notion de définition comme
Bair, J., & Henry, V. (2008). Analyse infinitésimale: Le calculus obstacle à l’acquisition du caractère lakatosien de la notion de
redécouvert. Editions Academia. limite par la méthodologie des situations fondamentales/
Barbé, J., Bosch, M., Espinoza, L., & Gascón, J. (2005). Didactic adidactiques. Thèse de doctorat, Université de Liège.
restrictions on the teacher’s practice: the case of limits of Job, P. (2014). L’entrée dans les praxéologies déduction. Le cas du
functions in Spanish high schools. Educational Studies in concept de limite. Séminaire National de Didactique. Manuscript
Mathematics, 59, 235–268. accepted for publication.

123
646 P. Job, M. Schneider

Johsua, S. (1996). Le concept de contrat didactique et l’approche universitaire. Le cas éclairant du thème des dérivées. Thèse de
vygotskienne. In C. Raisky & M. Caillot (Eds.), Au-delà des doctorat, Université de Liège.
didactiques, le didactique. De Boeck: Bruxelles. Schneider, M. (1991). Un obstacle épistémologique soulevé par des
Lagrange, J.-L. (1797). Théorie des fonctions analytiques contenant ‘découpages infinis’ des surfaces et des solides. Recherches en
les principes du calcul différentiel dégagés de toute considéra- Didactique des Mathématiques, 11(2.3), 241–294.
tion d’infiniment petits et d’évanouissans, de limites ou de Schneider, M. (1992). A propos de l’apprentissage du taux de
fluxions et réduits 92. à l’analyse algébrique des quantités finies. variation instantane. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 23(4),
Imprimerie de la République. 317–350.
Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical Schneider, M. (2008). Traité de didactique des mathématiques. Liège:
discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Presses Universitaires de Liège.
Martinez-Planell, R., Carmen Gonzalez, A. C., & DiCristina, G. A. V. Sierpinska, A. (1987). Humanities students and epistemological
(2012). Students’ conception of infinite series. Educational obstacle related to limits. Educational Studies in Mathematics,
Studies in Mathematics, 81, 235–249. 18, 371–397.
Monaghan, J. (1991). Problems with the language of limits. For the Swinyard, C. (2011). Reinventing the formal definition of limit: the
Learning of Mathematics, 11(3), 20–24. case of Amy and Mike. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 30,
Orton, A. (1983). Students’ understanding of integration. Educational 93–114.
Studies in Mathematics, 14, 1–18. Tall, D. (1980). Mathematical intuition, with special reference to
Ostrom, E. (2005). Understanding institutional diversity. Princeton: limiting processes. In: Proceedings of the Fourth International
Princeton University Press. Congress on Mathematics Education, 1 (pp. 170–176). Berkeley.
Parameswaran, R. (2007). On understanding the notion of limits and Tall, D., & Schwarzenberger, R. (1978). Conflicts in the learning of
infinitesimal quantities. International Journal of Science and real numbers and limits. Mathematics Teaching, 82, 44–49.
Mathematics Education, 5(2), 193–216. Tall, D., & Vinner, S. (1981). Concept image and concept definition
Pétry, A. (2010). Analyse infinitésimale une présentation non in mathematics, with particular reference to limits and continu-
standard. Liège: Éditions du Céfal. ity. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 12(2), 151–169.
Przenioslo, M. (2005). Introducing the concept of convergence of a Williams, S. R. (1991). Models of limit held by college calculus
sequence in secondary school. Educational Studies in Mathe- students. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 22(3),
matics, 60(1), 71–93. 219–236.
Radford, L. (1997). On psychology, historical epistemology, and the Zandieh, M. (2000). A theoretical framework for analyzing student
teaching of mathematics: towards a socio-cultural history of understanding of the concept of derivative. In E. Dubinsky, A.
mathematics. For the Learning of Mathematics, 17(1), 26–33. Schoenfeld, & J. Kaput (Eds.), Research in collegiate mathe-
Rouy, E. (2007). Formation initiale des professeurs de l’enseigne- matics education IV (pp. 103–127). Providence: American
ment secondaire supérieur et changements de rationalité math- Mathematical Society.
ématique entre l’institution secondaire et l’institution

123

You might also like