You are on page 1of 23

Kant as a Problem for Weber

Author(s): Martin Barker


Source: The British Journal of Sociology , Jun., 1980, Vol. 31, No. 2 (Jun., 1980), pp.
224-245
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The London School of Economics and Political Science

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/589689

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

Wiley and The London School of Economics and Political Science are collaborating with JSTOR
to digitize, preserve and extend access to The British Journal of Sociology

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Martill Barker

Kant as a problem for Weber

Discussions of Weber's methodology have tended too often to revolve


arounct three issues only. These have been: Weber's defen(e of (a
cir( urnscribecl version of ) value-freedom; 'Verstehen'; and his tnetho(l
of 'ideal-types'. The over concentration on these has blinde(t us to the
f:a( t that these issues for Weber make little or no sense in isolation fronz a
set of general philosophical assumptions. It is nzy contention when
explored, t}zat these underpinning assumptions reveal a nzarke(l an(l
major paradox in the structure of Weber's sociology and that the roots
of that paradox derive from a systematic misuse that Weber rnake s of a
Kantian heritage within which he developed his own ideas.
The one-sided picture of Weber has distorted even the particulat-
issues which have come under close examination. I f we look at a
common view of the motives behind Weber's defen(e of value-fre e donz
it is claimed to derive from the relatively a(-cidental politi( al
involvement of academics in late nineteenth- and early twentietEl-
century Germany. Weber himself says, of course:

An unprecedented situation exists when a large nutnber of oflicially


accredited prophets do not do their preaching in the streets or in
other public places or in sectarian conventicles, but ratller k- e l
themselves competent to enunciate their evaluations on ultinlate
uestions 'in the name of science' in governrnentally privilegecl
lecture-halls in which they are neither controlled, checke(l by
discussion, nor sub ject to contradiction. i

Gouldner in an influential interpretation2 contends that this is


explanation enough. Apparently, Weber disliked the professorial
attitude, so he developed a whole theory to justif-y his dislike. Gouldner
does not think it worth asking whence Weber and the other editors of the
Archiv fur Sozialwis.senschaft derived their dislike of preaching professors.
It is part of my argument that his stance in favour of value-freedorn
comes directly out of his version of neo-Kantianism.
Evaluations have tended not to make much of the influence of
Immanuel Kant's system on Weber, even though it is recognized that the
German intellectual environment was impregnated wi.h that system. It

BritishJournalofSociology Volume3s Number2 June sgNo


t) R.K.P. 1980 ooo7 1315/80/3102-o224 Sl.50/l

224

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant as a problem for Weber 225

is noted that he read Kant as a student, and that his intellectual


development was closely bound up with such leading neo-Kantians as
Wilhelm Windelband, Wilhelm Rickert and Ernst Troeltsch. But
surprisingly little attention has been paid in a multiplicity of intellectual
biographies and critical studies to the actual impact and the specific
results of these influences.
A full length study which followed the lines I want to suggest would, I
believe, show that a large part of Weber's sociology can be seen as
supplying pessimistic answers to questions set for the German tradition
by Kant. Since this article is well short of such a study, I want here only to
indicate by a particular route why there is such a pessimistic streak in
Weber's thought and how it derives from the quite specific answers he
gave to one particular Kantian question. The route I follow is via his
not-ion of rationality. For there is a paradox within Weber's treatment of
this notion to which, so far as I have been able to discover, only Talcott
Parsons has given attention, and that attention, not untypically, has
much in common with the attention of the Ugly Sisters to the glass
slipper; Weber was 'fitted' to his needs. Weber's pessimism is relevant to
my argument. It is well summed up in one sentence:
The historical origin of modern freedom has had certain unique
conditions which will never repeat themselves.3

It is a point that has received less attention than it deserves, that Weber's
pessimism evolved directly around a concept of freedom.4 It has of
course been pointed out by all commentators that his unhappiness
about the future is connected with his perception of an irreversible
rationalization of society. But what the alternative to this might have
been has been left strangely unexplored.
Weber is traditionally seen as attempting to salvage liberalism from
the embattled Germany of the turn of the century, given the rising feud
between conservative - and often cowardly and inconsistent - ruling
circles and the maturing working class. He therefore tried to find some
thoeretical space between the manoeuvring of the Right, and the
marxism of the Left (especially given the crude economism of much of
the latter, which can be grasped from the deterministic model of
Marxism that Weber saw himself opposing). He went to considerable
lengths to attack the pretensions of both parties. But of course the
emerging conflict continued to emerge, for all his efforts. Gerth and
Mills have noted how in later life Weber debated with himself his
relationship to the socialist movement, but always drew back from
commitment - and always, when it came to a test, took up his pen to
draw the pessimistic conclusions. In 1905, he argued that a successsful
revolution would bureaucratize inexorably. In 1918, he attacked the
ambitions of the workers councils. His pessimism was more than a
mood. It drew its strength from the heart of his theoretical position.
How did this come from a reaction to Kantianism, since Kant himself

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Martin Barker
226

saw faith in the possibility of a rational, moral order as a condition of


moral life?
Weber, in fact, in one essay states his relationship to Kantianism (at
one level) quite simply:

All theology represents an intellectual rationalisation of the possession


of sacred values. No science is absolutely free from presuppositions,
and no science can prove its fundamental value to the man who re jects
those presuppositions. Every theology, however, adds a few specific
propositions for its work and thus for the justification of its existence.
Their meaning and scope vary. Every theology, including for instance
Hinduist theology, presupposes that the world must have a meaning,
and the question is how to interpret this meaning so that it is
intellectually conceivable.
It is the same with Kant's epistemology. He took for his point of
departure the.presupposition: 'Scientific truth exists and it is valid',
and then asked: 'Under which presuppositions of thought is truth
possible and meaningful ?'5

Kantianism now appears as another relative doctrine, along with all


other 'religious' doctrines. It is just another attempt to find meaning in
the world, and just as arbitrary. This might seem the end of Kant as far as
Weber is concerned. In fact, it is only the beginning.
First, it must be recalled that for Weber to be able to argue in this way,
he has to draw on an approach to epistemology which Kant was the first
to systematize. In order to argue that man seeks to find meaning in the
world, and therefore to view religions as rationalizations of the need for
meaning, one must first have an epistemology in which men construct
their view of the world. That is one vital element in the Kantian heritage.
At this level, Weber uses Kantianism to prove that it itself is just such a
construct. An illustration of this is in his explanation of the 'ideal-type'
approach:

If one perceives the implications of the fundamental idea of modern


epistemology which ultimately derives from Kant; namely, that
concepts are primarily analytic instruments for the intellectual
mastery of empirical data and can be only that, the fact that precise
genetic concepts are necessarily ideal-types will not cause him to
desist from constructing them.6

The logic is wonderful. From Kant we get the idea that concepts are
given prior to experience; but now we know that this priority to
experience is socially given, and therefore, for science, takes the form of
ideal-types. These are the only things that can be constructed. In
consequence we are entitled to see the theory that makes this
understanding possible, itself as an ideal-typical construct. Kant is thus
relativized; and the objectivist component of his categorial system
swallows itselfup.

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant as a problem for Weber 227

BeYOI1(l tllis general epistenzological debt, there is another which


Wel)er never records explicitly. From it llow the relativism and the
pessinliKsnl of Wel)er's own outlook. It concernis the treatment of'Kant's
(listiIl( tion between a noumenal and phenomenal world. This
distinction was for Kant, the basis of'his assertion of'the transcendental
posisit)ility of' I'reedonz.7 In order to show how and why Weber miKsuseKs
tllis (listirl( tion, I have to (letour through his general methodology.

Wel)er clenlands as his first principle that sociology should orient itself'
towards tlle sut)jective meanings that social actors attach to the
Ksituations in wllich they act. I ndeed, his very definition of'a social action
is that tlle actors attach meaning to it. At the heart of the definition of'hi
subject-nzatter is this ontological assertion - ontological, in the sense
that Wet)er believes that this is not merely a methodological point; the
principle iKs l-ooted in the nature of' what is to be studied. As a
conKsecluerlce of'it, he has to try to classify the types of orientation which
in(livicluals may adopt towards their actions:

Social action, like other f'orms of action, may be classified in the


following types according to its mode of orientation: (1) in terms of
rational orientation to a system of discrete individual ends, that is,
through expectations as to the behaviour of' objects in the external
situation and of other human individuals, making use of these
expectations as 'conditions' or 'means' for the successful attainment
of' the actor's own rationally chosen ends: (2) in terms of rational
orientation to an absolute value of some ethical, aesthetic, religious,
or other form of' behaviour, entirely f'or its own sake and
independently of any prospects of' external success: (3) in terms of'
afFective orientation, especially emotional, determined by the specific
affects and states of f'eeling of' the actor; (4) traditionally oriented,
througll the habituation of long practice.8

Weber inKsists that all the 'types' that he enunciates are fictional, in the
sense that they will rarely if'ever correspond with what we find:

(None the less) theoretical analysis in the field of sociology is possible


only in terms of such types.9

Since this is the case, there can be no doubt that this classification of
types of orientation of action is not empirically arrived at, but is derived
fronl his Inethodological and ontological premises.
Being a sociologist, however, or in other words because he is
concerned with the way these orientations make their appearance in
social relations, he moves quite logically from this classification to a
discussion of the possible responses to these- that is, how these types of

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
228 Martin Barker

orientation can gain legitimacy. He therefore gives a fourfold


corresponding definition of types of legitimacy:

Legitimacy may be ascribed to an order by those acting sub ject to it in


the following ways:
(a) By tradition; a belief in the legitimacy of what has always existed;
(b) by virtue of affectual attitudes, especially emotional, legitimising
the validity of what is newly revealed as a model to imitate;
(c) by virtue of rational belief in its absolute value;
(d) because it has been established in a manner which is recognised to
be legal.'°

He has, then, four types of orientation of action, and four


corresponding ways in which social actions can be legitimized; by
rational orientation to a goal; by technical means-end rationality; by
the justification of tradition; and by the rationale of an individual's
powerful drive and affective force.
It is in the transition to the next stage that the paradox arises. I call it a
paradox because it seems indubitably so to me, although for some
reasons sociologists - with one exception - have been unwilling to
investigate its paradoxical nature. The exception, Parsons, has always
been quoted to me as providing the solution to the paradox by those
who are otherwise totally suspicious of the Parsonian 'fixing' of other
theorists, and of his total functionalist commitment. The paradox is
this: when Weber passes on from his types of orientation and of
legitimacy, to his 'Pure Types of Legitimate Authority', while there were
four types of the two former modes, there are only three types of legitimate
authority.

There are three pure types of legitimate authority. The validity of their
claims to legitimacy may be based on:
( 1 ) Rational grounds - resting on a belief in the 'legality' of patterns
of normative rules and the right of those elevated to authority
under such rules to issue commands (legal authority);
(2) Traditional grounds - resting on an established belief in the
sanctity of immemorial traditions and the legitimacy of the status
of those exercising authority over them (traditional authority); or
finally,
(3) Charismatic grounds - resting on devotion to the specific and
exceptional sanctity, heroism or exemplary character of an
individual person, and of the normative patterns or order
revealed or ordained by him (charismatic authority). "

Where has the fourth type gone? Bearing in mind that Weber has just
derived four types of legitimacy from his types of orientation of action,
the theoretical space between legitimacy of action and.legitimacy of
authority seems rather small for a whole type to get lost. But prima facie
there can be little doubt that it has happened. What appears to have

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant a.s a problem for Weber 229

happened is that what Weber called Wertrationalitat, orientation to an


absolute value, has failed to find a corresponding form of legitimate
authority. How is this to be explained ?
I want to consider two possible explanations, one from Parsons, the
other of which has been suggested to me by colleagues. Parson's account
is the traditional one. In discussing the original fourfold classification,
and sensing the difficulty which is about to arise, he argues:

The key to Weber's meaning is given in the distinction that Dr. Von
Schelting discusses between the two possible 'formal' types of ethical
attitude which Weber called Verantwortungsethik and Gesinnungsethik.
Zweckrationalitat is the normative type of action logically implied by
the former position, and Wertrationalitat by the latter. The distinction
is essentially as follows: The actor either recognises a plurality of
legitimate directions of value achievement, though perhaps not all are
equally important, or he orients his total action to a single specific
value, e.g. salvation which is absolute in the sense that all other
potential values become significant only as means and conditions,
possible aids and hindrances, to the attainment of this central value. 12

What is central to this intepretation is the denial that Weber is intending


a distinction between goal-rationality and means-rationality. Instead, it
is read as a distinction between single-goal rationality and multiple-goal
rationality, by Parsons. It is interesting, however, that in his Editor's
notes to the 'Theory of Social and Economic Organizations'. Parsons
adds to this:

It should be pointed out that, as Weber's analysis proceeds, there is a


tendency of the meaning of these terms to shift, so that
Wertrationalitat comes to refer to a system of ultimate ends,
regardless of their degree of absoluteness, while Zweckrationalitat
refers primarily to considerations respecting the choice of means and
ends which are in turn means to further ends, such as money. 13

It is my contention that there is no shift in meaning, because that is what


Wertrationalitat meant all along; and that therefore, Parsons being
wrong, we have a real paradox requiring explanation.
What is wrong with Parsons' interpretation? First, it doesn't fit
Weber's actual statement. He talks of Wertrationalitat as 'orientation to
an absolute value of some . . . form of behaviour' 14 (my emphasis). He is
re-emphasizing that the actions are performed for their own sake,
whereas Zweckrationalitat is marked out sharply as a means-end
orientation. He makes this even clearer in his further explication of his
types. He exemplifies his type, Wertrationalitat, as pursuit of duty,
honour, beauty, a religious calling, or personal loyalty. According to
Parsons' account, the point of Wertrationalitat is its unconditional
commitment to a single goal. But there is no reason to suppose that
these could not exist in combination; for example, beauty and personal

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
230 Martin Barker

loyalty. Further, Weber explicitly states his own contrast between the
two types:

From the latter point of view (Zweckrationalitat), however, absolute


values are always irrational.... the more unconditionally the actor
devotes himself to this value for its own sake, to pure sentiment or
beauty, to absolute goodness or devotion to duty, the less is he
influenced by considerations of the consequences of his actions. 15

Weber does not say that we ignore all other possible ends, but that we
ignore consequences, if we are committed unconditionally to an end. But
he points out firmly that the opposite extreme - consideration of means
without some determination of ends - is virtually inconceivable. That is
the exact reverse of the Parsonian picture. Where he would have us see
Zweckrationalitat as a pluralist commitment to both means and ends, and
Wertrationalitat as the near impossible commitment to a single goal,
Weber argues the opposite. We can be committed to the point of
singleminded madness to a goal, with never a thought for the rationality
of the means nor for the consequences - these are just the inevitable
concomitants of pursuit of the goal. This can have all the nastiest
consequences in the book. All this is quite conceivable to Weber, and fits
his classification of types well. But he cannot conceive a devotion to
means without some considerations of ends.
All this makes it very clear that the Wertrationalitat/Zweckrationalitat
distinction is one between orientation to means, and to ends. This
becomes clearer still if we examine his account of types of legitimacy,
where he has still retained the fourth type equivalent to Wertrationalitat.
There, in his account of it, he says:

The type-case of legitimacy by


virtue of rational belief in an absolute
value is that of 'Natural Law'.
However limited its actual effect, as
compared with its ideal claims,
it cannot be denied that its logically
developed reasoning has had an
influence on social action which is far
from negligible. This mode of influence should be clearly
distinguished from that of a revealed law, of one imposed by an
authority, or one that is merely traditional.'6

Weber is clearly indicating that it is possible in general for an individual


to be oriented to action on the basis of a rational commitment to an
ideal, and can legitimate his or her actions by reference to the ideal.
Natural Law justifications are a prime example. But in no meaningful
sense is Natural Law a single ideal which drives out all other modes of
justification. It is itself a general mode of justification, requiring
development and application.
Why then did he use this example? We must recall his oft-repeated
methodological assertion that values and ideals are non-rational, in the
sense of not being open to scientific proof. If we combine this with his

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant a.s a problem for Weber 231

(tenzan(t that we exanzine all actions t'rom the point of'view ol'the a(tor
ll imsezlf' or llersezlf':

II1 general, it should be kept in mind that tlle basis of'every systenl of'
authority, anct correspondingly of'every kind of'willingness to obey, is
a belief t)y virtue ol' which persons exercising authority are k^Ilt
prestige. l 7

It beconles clear that Wcber is saying that, I'rom the point of'view of'the
individual, (ommitment on the basis ol' Natural Law is rational; but to
tlle sociologist at least if'he is a Weber, it cannot be; to him, it is a c hoi(^e,
a conlmitnzent to an ultimate orientation. Only to the indivicluals
involvecl in the social situation of' the commitment can it appear as a
s(-ientifically hase(l (lecision. This reading is borne out by Weber's
carel'ul c hoi(-e ol'words in introducing his types ol'legitirnacy:

. . . legitimacy may be ascribed to an order by those acting suF)ject t()


it . . .18 (tnYen1PhaSiS).

But in a f'unny way, that redoubles the paradox. For thc re is no apparent
'a priori' reason wlly, if'it is possible to ascribe legitinza(y to an or(let on
the part of'those sub ject to it in this way, it should not be possit)le for tlle
authority actually to t)e legitimate in the same way. Why, when we pass
to types of legitimate authority, do we have only three types.4
This leads me to the second possible interpretation whi(-h naight
renlove the paradox. It anaounts to a 'common-sensc interpl-etatioll of'
Weber. On this reading,l9 the two types simply become absorbed into
one when we pass to the description of' types of' legitimate authority.
Apparently, the application of' Wert- and Zweckrationalitat to authority as
such results in a single type of'legitimate authority, the type which Weber
calls legal-rational authority. This interpretation does not seem to me to
answer the point at all. First, we should recall Weber's insistence t}at he
is presenting pure types, not empirically discoverable phenornena. W}v
should he introduce a hybrid type of'authority unless there is a reason, a
theoretical reason, to suppose that the pure type cannot be state(l in a
comprehensible form? It is no objection to the pure type that we could
never meet with it in the world. Secondly, it becomes crystal-clear w}zen
Weber comes to apply his case of' legal-rational authority that its most
exemplary case is bureaucracy - which Weber precisely sees as
continually, and worryingly, approximating to a purely means-oriented
system. In other words, Weber's use of' his pure type of' legal-rational
authority leaves no room f'or this interpretation.
We must therefore look f'or a purely theoretical reason why a pure
type of legitimate authority cannot be stated.

By way of elaboration of my thesis, I have to explore further the 'fit'

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 of:ffff:ffff on Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
232
Martin Barker

between the various aspects ot Weber's work. It is neces


the shape of his methodology. In several places, Weber
the rules of logic and method are universally valid. I
point because from this one might have expected t
general methodological rules, understood to be
dependently of the sub ject-matter to be examined. In la
of reasons, Weber saw it to be impossible to derive
methodology from the universal rules ot logic.
First, there was, of course, the fact that even if logic
valid, this does not guarantee its recognition:

. . . even the knowledge of the most certain propo


theoretical sciences; e.g. the exact natural sciences and
is, like the cultivation and refinement of our conscienc
culture.20

Only some cultures develop a scientific mode of questioning, acc


to Weber. But even for those that do, the problems are consi
Two of these problems are suggested well in the following asser

Even with the widest imaginable knowledge of laws, we are help


the face of the question: how is the causal explanation of an ind
fact possible - since a description of even the smallest part of
can never be exhaustive.2'

The sheer infinity of facts makes theory necessary. To this Web


the observation that if our perception gave us direct access to ca
there would be no need lor science at all; we would simply look a
But in the case of human social history, we face a further difficulty
human history is an accumulation and interaction of meani
actions. History, sociology or any other human study is premised
'perception of its meaningfulness for us'. Meanings are not d
given to us. They have to be discovered through subjective
pretations. There isn't, in individual cases, any particular difficu
sub jective interpretation (indeed, if there were, human society c-o
function). On particular occasions, we find it useful to i
ourselves in the situation of the actor(s), but this is not essentia
interpret subjectively the meaning of an action, an institution,
human social situation, is to grasp the structure of meanin
intentions that caused them.
How does one get at meanings, since they are not directly give
developing conceptual constructs that reveal some of their es
characteristics. These are Weber's famous 'ideal-types', his 'on
accentuations of reality'. They are not hypotheses, but aid us in f
hypotheses, and so on. But in that case, how do we know when w
formed useful, viable ones ? This seems to me one of the
unexplored questions of this method. After all, Weber has warn

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant as a problem for Weber 233

against using theories as Procrustean beds into which history may be


forced.
The answer Weber gives, assumes an essential fit between the structure
of icleal-types, and the structure of all human thinking:

For purposes of a causal imputation of empirical events, we need the


rational, empirical-technical and logical constructions, which help us
to answer the question what a behaviour-pattern or thought-pattern
(e.g. a philosophical system) would be like if it possessed completely
rational, empirical and logical 'correctness' and 'consistency'. From
the logical viewpoint, the construction of such a rationally 'correct'
'utopia' or 'ideal' is, however, only one of the various possible forms
of the ideal-type- as I have called such logical constructs. For not
only are there cases in which an incorrect inference or a self-defeating
action would be more serviceable as ideal-types, but there are whole
spheres of action (the sphere of the 'irrational') where the simplicity
ofFered by isolating abstraction is more convenient than an ideal-type
of optimal logical rationality.22

This (apparently puzzling) description of ideal-types comes directly after


a defence otWeber's views on the fact-value distinction. He has just been
attacking those who would extract values, supposedly logically, from
ideas of progress or adaptation. What it reveals, is that Weber's idea of
irrationality is a complex one. On the one hand, he sometimes calls
actions based on emotions (affectivity) irrational. On the other hand, he
says:

when the historian . . . speaks of the 'irrationality' of human action as


a disturbing factor, he is comparing historical-empirical action not
with the phenomena of nature, but with the ideal of purely rational,
i.e. absolutely purposeful, action which is also absolutely oriented
towards the adequate means23

Are these views of irrationality compatible? They are in fact welded


together. For Weber's view is that people are capable of living by more
or less well-developed and coherent views of the world. These constitute
. . . . .

t lelr su Dlectlve orlentatlon.


Weber's definition of irrationality turns on identifying those factors
that may prevent the fuller development of a coherent world-outlook.
The two approaches to irrationality merge. For they are two sides of the
same coin. The structure of the ideal-types reveals this to us. For an
ideal-type is a logically constructed 'utopia', a weltanschauang from
which all irrational elements have been abstracted.
How does this account for ideal-typical constructs of afFectivity.>
These are themselves to be 'purified', in the sense of being presented
with elements of other orientations removed. To that extent they are
'utopian' presentations. The irrational elements to be removed in this
case, are elements of consideration of means, or consequences, etc. - in

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
234 Martin Barker

other words, the rational elements in our ordinary considerations


become for these purposes 'irrational'. This is, however, not possible as
a living strategy; and the necessary reintroduction of consideration ol
means and consequences is precisely what Weber describes in his
discussion of the 'routinisation of charisma'. As a consequence, afFective
orientations are systematically unstable; and for this reason we are
entitled to call ideal-types of them 'irrational'.
Bear in mind that this connects with the other crucial eletnent in
Weber's account of ideal-types. They are only logically ideal, not
evaluatively. Because values are unbridgeably distinct from facts- they
are 'worlds apart' - there can be no scientific justification of values. They
are, and will always remain, matters of choice and faith. So the job ol
sociology with respect to values is restricted:

. . . as soon as we seek to derive concrete directives from practical-


political evaluations, ( 1 ) the indispensable means, and ( 2 ) the
inevitable repercussions, and (3) the thus conditioned competition ol
numerous possible evaluations in theirpractical consequences, are all
that an empirical discipline can demonstrate with the means at its
disposal.24

Philosophical disciplines can go further by describing the ultimate


structure of these competing evaluations. But all questions ol evaluation
per se are matt-ers of choice, compromise and commitment. They are
non-rational.
This point is very important. The non-rationality of choi
is not the same as the 'irrationality' of interferences whic
wholly consistent world-view, or of afFectivity. Therefore
Weber's expanded statement of this same principle, now d
with ideal-type explanation. He is concerned to show the li
social science in testing evaluations. Empirical discussions of value-
judgements, he says, can only have the following functions:

(a) the elaboration and explication of the ultimate, internally


'consistent' value-axioms, from which the divergent attitudes are
derived.... This procedure is essentially an operation which
begins with concrete particular evaluations and then moves to the
more general level of irreducible explanations. It does not use the
techniques of an empirical discipline and it produces no new
knowledge offacts. Its 'validity' is similar to that of logic.
(b) The deduction of 'implications' (for those accepting certain
value- judgements) which follow from certain irreducible value-
axioms, when the practical evaluation of factual situations is
based on these axioms alone....
(c) The determination of the factual consequences which the
realisation of a certain practical evaluation must have: (1) in

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
K(znt (1.s (z pr()hlem for Weher 235

collse(luell(e of l)eillg bound to certain iladispensable lllUllS, (2)


ill collse(luellce ol certain, not directly desired conse(luen(es.25

H e sulllnlari7es this t)y an exanaple:

The task ol a1a etilically 1leutral science is completed w}lerl it has


re(luceel ttle sylaelicalist standpoint to its most rational and internally
colasistelat lorm and has enapirically investigated the pre(on(litiolls
lor its existence and its practical (onsequences. Whether one shoul(l
or shoulel not t)e a syndicalist (an never be proved without releren(e
to very elelinite naetaphysical premises which are not demonstrable by
science.2fi

The process is therefore one of comparing an ideal construct, whic


will have lound what would happen if men and women behaved in a
wholly ratiolaal and 'complete' way, with what actually happens. Thus
we can validly impute causes to behaviour. But we can only do this on the
as.sumption that human behaviour approximates to the logically ideal
situation. Otherwise, the ideal constructs would be arbitraly
inapositiolls. Of course, the approximation need not be close; but it
must be there, nonetheless. Weber's whole method relies on a pre-
observatiolaal beliel that human behaviour is rnore or less rational in his
sellse of the term.
I have stressed this, because it is essential to see that Weber's
methodology is mirrored on his picture of society. He sees in every
individual the capacity to think and behave rationally. This will never be
lully developed, perhaps; human beings are passionate, prone to error
and are anyway born into specific cultures. But the template is there. The
naethod is only appropriate because the world is like that. His critique ol
psychological explanation must be understood in this light.27
Weber is not opposing himself to the notion that there is an individual
root to social developments. Rather, he is attacking (a) reductionism,
that sees men and women as forming their world-views freely, and only
subsequently 'meeting' to lorm society; and (b) a form of abstract
il-ldividualisna that would see all men as having the same concrete
psychic structure of motives. ( He refers elsewhere to the failure of such a
view to account for the variety of cultural forms). So an ideal-type is far
from incompatible with a view that sees society on a template of the
individual. Indeed there is no other way it could be had:

It is a matter here of constructing relationships which our


imagination accepts as plausibly motivated, and hence as 'ob jectively
possible', and which appear as adequate from the nomological
standpoint.28

In summary, then: Weber has produced a methodology which acquires


its validity from an 'a priori' assumption about the nature of society,
which it is designed to mirror. Human commitments to values and goals

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
236 Martin Barker

are non-rational; being values, they are not reducible to, or relatable to,
lacts.
Values are by and large a matter of faith. The most that an empirital
s(ience of humans can do, is to look at faith in operation. But faiths,
1 . . . . . . ..

Oelng su Dlectlve, zelng commltments, are not glven entltles open to


perceptual inspection. To read history, therefore, we have to take what
are people's apparent motives, their faiths, and make constructs ol
them; logical constructs that treat them as though they were whollv
consistent. By contrasting the construct with the world, we can see what
to put down to the intrusion of 'irrationality' - that-is, error, emotional
afFect, or residues ot other beliefs and faiths.
So Iar, there is nothing extraordinary in this interpretation. While I
tnay have stressed more than many the groundedness of the
methodology, and the image of society it is directed towards, there is
nothing obviously paradoxical in it. However, what I shall show is that
t}le disappearance of the fourth type of rationality also involves a breach
of the rule derived from the general methodology, that methodology
naust be neutral towards taiths. The most that it should be able to do, is
to point out to adherents the consequences of their faiths, and the
means they will have to employ. Weber claims that the neutrality goes
even further:

Sciences are founded and their methods are progressively developed


only when substantive problems are discovered and solved. Purely
epistemological and methodological reflections have never yet made
a decisive contribution to this project.29

Weber has misunderstood his own methodology at this point. For I will
show that it alone, with its template of an image of society, makes 'a
priori' impossible some specific forms of society. And consequently, its
outcome must be to recommend against people being foolish enough to
seek to establish that which is logically impossible- a society in which
values are collectively decided upon, on the basis of shared, rationally
arrived-at ultimate goals. We shall see that this is not simply because
Weber believes that ends cannot be rationally chosen; for he still grants
that to the actor they can appear rational. But at the level of legitimation
of authority, this possibility disappears. Why?

We have, then, a problem requiring solution. Retracing the steps of


Weber's theorizing from initial premises and definitions, it is clear that
while we remain at the level of individual perception of social action
situations, actors can accept that a system of authority derives legitimacy
from a rational ultimate goal or value. Where this possibility ceases is at
the point when we pass from individual perception of legitimacy to the

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant aa a problem for Weber 237

legitimation process itselt: The solution must therelore lie with what is
added here: and that is power.
Weber defines power as:

the probability that one actor within a social relationship will be in a


position to carry out his own will despite resistance regardless ol the
basis on which this probability rests.30

Power then consists in the ability to bring about by any means the
situation where others are persuaded or forced to accept my wishes for
the situation. But in a curious and significant way, this leaves all the
questions unanswered. We will need to know what will make it probable
that I will succeed. We need to know what will be classed as resistance,
and what is the significance of there being (likely to be) resistance. And
given the earlier insistence of Weber that authority, to be recognized,
need not have more than the possibility of disapprobation (which could
even take the internal form of 'conscience' ) in the way of sanctions, what
is it that sets up the need, or pressure, for the power-relation in the first
place ?
The only premise on which these questions would not need an answer
would be a Hobbesian one; that society is a sort of market-place in
which essentially private individuals meet in order to bend each to the
others' will. But there is no evidence that Weber ever operated with this
notion of a pre-social individual. Therefore, the role that the concept of
power is to play has to be explained. And Weber does give an
explanation. But the explanation is a very odd one. In his writings on
law, Weber gives a definition of domination which is at first sight more
concealing than revealing:

The manifested will (command) of the ruler or rulers is meant to


influence the conduct of one or more others (the ruled) and actually
does influence it in such a way that their conduct occurs to a socially
relevant degree as if the ruled had made the content of the command
the maxim of their conduct for its own sake.3'

The first thing that strikes one is that the Kantian language of the
definition is so precise that it cannot be accidental. That will be explored
in a moment. But the next thing is the apparently unnecessary
complexity and cumbersome nature of the definition- unless it is saying
something more than the surface is revealing. Weber, realizing that it
could not stand without comment, immediately follows the definition
by saying:

The definition just stated sounds cumbersome, especially becabse of


the use of the 'as if' formula. This fact is inevitable, however. The
merely external fact of the order being obeyed is not sufficient to
signify domination in our sense; we cannot overlook the fact that the
meaning of the command is accepted as a valid norm.32

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
238 Martin Barker

This, of course, connects closely with a point that is often made by


interpreters: that power in Weber's thought is only in the last instance
thought of as requiring physical force. In a sense, the use of physical
power is an admission ot failure of real domination: for that comes
about through the internalization of the commands of the rulers. So on
the basis of this odd wording for his definition, he is able to progress to a
threefold typology of domination:

The 'pure' types of domination correspond to these three possible


types of legitimation. The forms of domination occurring in
historical reality constitute combinations, mixtures, adaptations or
modifications of these 'pure' types.
Rationally consociated conduct of a dominational structure finds its
typical expression in bureaucracy.
Social conduct bound in relationships of traditional authority is
typically represented bypatriarchalism.
The charismatic structure of domination rests upon that authority of
a concrete individual which is based neither upon rational rules nor
upon tradition.33

Once again in this threefold classification of types of domination, we


have lost a type corresponding to Wertrationalitat. The identification of
rationality with the presence of defined meansnds rules and procedures
is now complete. But this identification is not the result of an arbitrary
shift in meaning, as Parsons suggested. It is the logical result of the
earlier definition of what constitutes a social action, coupled with the
decisive new element - what constitutes a power-relation, how it is
established, and why it is brought into being. For the fact is that i! is
impossible to construct a type corresponding to Wertrationalitat once we take note of
hi.s detnition of domination.
Let us try to imagine for a moment what such a type would look like.
Wertrationalitat is defined as 'a rational orientation to an absolute
value'.34 The corresponding type of legitimacy which can be ascribed to
an authoritative structure or individual is defined by a 'rational belief in
its absolute value'.35 We can begin to see the scope of the problem from
this. For at these levels Weber was dealing with individual perceptions,
treated as though they were independent of each other. At this stage of
the analysis, the question of the possible social sources of these
sub jective orientations did not concern him. But power is defined by its
capacity to make 'the ruled' internalize the will of the ruler, as though it
were their own. The independence of the various subjective orientation
is only apparent. The types of orientation are not pre-social, in any
Hobbesian sense; they are pre-domination. They suppose, what may
rarely if ever be the situation, that the individual is given the social space
to construct his or her meaningful interpretation of the world, and to
. .

attempt to lve lt out.


But then, supposing this is correct, we can see another assumption at

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
K(znt d.5 a prohlem for Weher 239

work. Let us Lsuppose that these pre-dominational indivi(lualLs (lo nleet,


bringillg with thena their already constructe(l or half'-constl ucte({
oric lItations onto the world. Weber is assuming that t he y c annot
c onabine thc ir orientation into a shared system ol'goals an(t orielltati
on a rational basis, that is, without the subordination of' sollle of' thes
in(lividuals to one or more others by a process of'internali7ation of'theil
nornls as though they were the chosen orientation ol' the sut)or(linates.
For it to be possible to conlbine their orientations we woul({ llave to
alter sut)stantially Weber's notion of' a '(otnnlan(l relationship'. An(l
that is the Iliaill reason why we cannot even phrase the possit)ility of'tEle
fourth type in Weber's theory. Within that theory, it is never c onc e ive(l as
possit)le that a .s()cial rea.s()n might f'un(tion to allow a f'ree, ratiollal, (o-
operativc alld non-donlinatory so(iety to clevelop. The sort of'.so(iety
whose logical possibility is written out of'Weber's ac c ountX is pre c isely a
(le nlocratic society, in which without domination Inen an(l wolllen
deci(le collectively on goals, and the means to those goals, on the t)asis of
rational (onsideration.36
If we reconsider that definition of dorninationX and its uise of Kantian
language, we call spell out its relation to what now appears as the
impossibility of 'collective rationality'. What Weber has (lone, is Illake
what is in Kantian terms a (luite illegitimate use of the (on(ept of 'zvill'.
In Kant's ethics, the free(lom of the will is a precondition of mol ality. To
make the content of a command the maxim of your a(tion for its owll
sake woul(l be to act freely, that is rationally, rnorally, or out of (luty. For
the conlmand, in Kant's terms, can only be a coJnman(l of reasoll.
Obeying the cornmand is always a tree act, because it is arrive(l <It
rationally. Rationality and freedom are syrnbiotic (on(epts in Kant.
Weber's transmogrification totally subverts this. Now, to act 'as if ' the
c ontent of the command had become the maxim of my action for its own
sake, is to be dominated. It is not even enough that I do it in order, for
cxanlple, to escape punishment; domination is always more than this.
Internalization of a command now constitutes 'doing something for
its own sake'. Domination consists in the ability to make others a(t and
think as though my commands were the result of their own processes of
thought and decision-making. Provided that end is achieved, the nleans
to the end are utterly irrelevant: whether by force, persuasiollX
exhortation, example or anything else. The irrelevance of these shows
where the heart of the definition of power lies. It is in the ability to get
someone else to accept my orientation onto the world as though it was
theirs.
This helps us to make sense of something peculiar in Weber's opening
definition of types of orientation of action:

Social action may be classified . . . ( 1 ) in terms of rational orientation


to a system of discrete individual ends, that is, through expectations as
to the behaviour of objects in the external situation and ol other human

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
240 Martin Barker

individuals, making use ot these expectations as 'conditions' ol


'means' for the successful attainment ot the actor's own rationally
chosen ends.37 (my emphasis)

With the advantage of hindsight, we can now see three elements alrea(ty
working within this definition. Before stating these, we must make it
wholly clear that we are dealing with the development of a set ot
postulates about society, not with a series of real historical events. The
order of the points to be stated is a logical order, not an histori(al one.
Social action is seen first and foremost in terms of individuals' ple-
domination orientations; for the choice of means is seen in terms ot
already chosen ends. But it is precisely the fact that the orientation has to
take into account the likely behaviour of others, that turns it into soe ial
action. Otherwise it would be solipsistic, pre-social action, in which we
would simply 'bump into' each other, probably not even recogni7ing
each other as human. But then, the definition supposes the possibility ol
using other human beings as means to the individual's ends. That is
precisely what domination consists in. In other words, the 'fit' between
the founding definition ot social action, and the type of dominationn is
even closer than at first appeared. Indeed, the tendency towards some
fortn of domination appears to be written into the account ot what
constitutes social action at all.
But while it follows logically within Weber's account, it is still a very
large assumption to require that pursuit of my ends is impossible
without the subordination of others, without their domination, without
their acting 'as if' my commands were their own freely chosen aims. For
the possibility of genuinely rational co-operation is written out by an(t
large on this account.
Weber's answer to this final point is revealingly offered when, writing
in a far more journalistic style than was his wont, he added to the end ot
his account of domination:

For a domination, this kind of justification of its legitimacy is much


more than a matter of theoretical or philosophical speculation;
rather it constitutes the basis of very real differences in the empirical
structure of domination. The reason tor this fact is a generally
observable need of any power, or even any advantage of life, to justity
itself.
The fates of human beings are not equal. Men differ in their states
of health or wealth or social status or what not. Simple observation
shows us that in every such situation he who is more favoured feels the
never-ceasing need to look upon his position as in some way
'legitimate', upon his advantage as 'deserved', and the other's
disadvantage as being brought about by the latter's 'fault'. That the
purely accidental causes of the differences may be ever so obvious
makes no difference.38

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant as a problem tor Weber 241

At the heart, then, of'Weber's world-view is a belief- one resulting f'rom


'simple observation' - that even if' overt conflict is not inevitable,
inequalities of all sorts make action to avoid it continually necessary.
That action takes the f'orm initially and continually of attempts to form
relationships of domination. How does domination work? By making
others act through the guise of'beliefs which originate in my wishes f'or
the construction of the world; these are not recognized as such, but are
taken over by the dominated as though they were their own.39
Once this has been seen, there are two related senses in which a form
of .society arising from Wertrationalitat is impossible. First, to the extent
that my domination is effective over you, you have accepted my values
for their OWI1 sake, that is, as ends-in-themselves, and you therefore act
in ways appropriate to my orientation. You now act as means to my ends.
That is not, of'course, how it appears to the individuals concerned, who
regard the orientation as their own. But to the sociologist, it is apparent
that they are internalized as the result of processes of domination. For
that reason, th'ey cannot be regarded by the sociologist as being rationally
directed towards a goal.
Not only that, but in a connected way they cannot be regarded as
rationally directed towards a goal, an absolute value in the sense
indicated by Wertrationalitat. Weber has told us that in the relation of'
domination, the individuals act as (f they adopted the command for its
own sake; that is how it appears to them. But again sociologists must
regard it otherwise, because it is a relation of domination. On analysis,
therefore, it reveals itself'as a relation of means to an end, not as end for its
own sake.
All this is the case, once a relation of domination has been established.
And according to Weber, f'or whom as we saw 'the concept of power is
highly comprehensive from the point of view of sociology',40 we must
accept the near inevitability of' domination. The world is chaotic and
dangerous to the individual, and therefore meaning must be made out
of it so that the individual can guide his life-chances.4 All the accidents
of birth mean that elements of conflict become the foci for organizing
our relations with each other. These between them make impossible the
notion of a universal rational organization, consciously designed by
men and women. Where Kant, in his 'Idea for a Universal History',
called for 'great experience' before the rational world could be brought
into being, and saw that one individual on his or her own could not live
long enough to develop that experience, Weber, by denying in eff'ect the
possibility of collaboration, makes it wholly impossible.42
We can see from this the distortion that Weber has introduced into the
Kantian scheme. In Kant, the high-point of theory which provides the
answer to his question: 'What can I hope ?', is provided by exploring the
possibility of humans living according to the rational law- that each
should act so that the treatment of other as ends rather than means only
could become the maxim of their action. A world could be thought,

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
242 Martin Barker

even if it might never be realised, in which men and women, living b


rational-moral considerations, would end irrational forms ot
domination. For Kant, this transcendental hope was a prerequlsite for
the meaningfulness of morality. By the subversion of one piece ot this
argument, Weber brings pessimism crashing down on his head. For he
denies the possibility of that rational hope. All constructions of world-
views are equally ideological, including Kant's; for there is no such thing
in Weber's view as rational understanding of the world. The world is
beyond human understanding. There are only versions of the world
which enable us to survive.
The distinction between noumenon and phenomenon, which is at the
heart of the Kantian scheme of things, sets up the possibility of a rational
kingdom of ends. It is missing in Weber. Everything is phenomena. All
we have for purposes of understanding, are useful fictions; and that is all
we have for living. The best that we can do is to achieve some form ot
realization of our limitations. In Kant, the noumenal world is a beacon
inviting eflort; in Weber, it isn't worth trying.
Weber's definition of domination shows that it is not simply that he
has not thought about the possibility of rational understanding an(t
collective decision-making. On the contrary, he takes the very language
of its possibility, and ben(ls it to opposite purposes. But what in Kant is
presented as the world-as-it-could-be, the noumenal world of free,
rational beings, appears in Weber as the world-as-rulers-would-like-it-
to-be. And the difference is not simply that in Weber values are
non-rational; it is that they are (terived from men's accidental situation
and nature. Alld whereas in Kant, the realization of this world woul(t
bring freedom under ratiorxally valid law, in Weber, it would bring
rationalized inequalities and subordination. My treedom is achieved not
by developing the freedom of others, but by subverting their treedom,
by making it appear that what I want is what they want.
Weber's pessinlism, the disappearance of the fourth type of
rationality, and his relationship with Kant are all summed up in this one
thing. In a way, rationality itselfdisappears in the process, to be replaced
by a rationale per person. Social relations consist in making it so that others
l)ecome means to my ends, if I can. The power-relation is therefore the
natural relation anlong men and women. The general, human problem
in Kant of creating a just, rational society dissolves into pessimism and
the politics of domination. The 'problem of the educators', which the
Categorical Imperative had helped Kant to solve, solves itself now. Who
educates the educator? No one. But domination makes it appear that
everyone does. Education is domination. And that is Weber's
philosophical anthropology.43

Martin Barker
Department of Humanities
Bristol Polytechnic

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant a.s a problem for Weber 243

N OTES

1. M. Weber, 'The Meaning of 'Ethical Parsons, it should be noted that


Neutrality' in Sociology and Economics', Gouldner, although not interested in the
in The Methodology of the Social Sciences, Shils theoretical question why such a problem
and Finch (eds), Free Press, 1949, p. 4. might arise in Weber, goes a long way to
2. A. Gouldner, 'Anti-Minotaur- the recognizing its existence. See his Patterns in
Myth of a Value-Free Sociology', in For Industrial Bureaucracy, Free Press, 1954.
Sociolo,gy, Allen Lane, 1973. Gouldner concludes that in bureau-
3. M. Weber, quoted in Gerth and cracy are collapsed two types of authority
Mills, From Max Weber, Routledge & Kegan - a 'representative' form where agreement
Paul,lg48,p. 71. is given voluntarily: and a punishment-
4. This is despite the fact that Weber, in centred form, where rules are obeyed for
one of his earliest empirical studies - of their own sake. This picks up on the point
the peasant problem in Eastern Germany I have been concerned to demonstrate,
- specifically cites the desire for freedom that one form has been made to
as a central motivating force in the actions disappear. And its disappearance is total;
of the peasants: that is why Gouldner is right to note that
for Weber,
From the standpoint the farm labourers
this classification presents us with a set
appeared to (Weber) more worthy of
of alternatives from which, as if by
respect than either the landowners or
conceptual magic, the democratic form
the industrialists:
has utterly vanished, pp. 222-3.
We want to cultivate what appears to
. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 115.
us as valuable in man: his personal
. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 117.
responsibility, his basic drive towards
6. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 131.
higher things, towards the spiritual
. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 332.
and moral values of mankind, even
8. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 130.
when this drive confronts us in its
. . . n 19. I have not found this reading
most prlmltlve torm....
anywhere in published form though a
A farmworker's preference for personal
number of colleagues have suggested it to
independence despite the financial loss
me.
involved was evidence of this 'basic
20. M . Weber, ' " Objectivity" in Social
drive towards higher things'.
Policy', in op. cit., p. 55.
R. Bendix, Max Weber - an Intellectual 21. M . Weber, ' " Objectivity" in Social
Portrait, Methuen, 1966, p. 44. Policy', in op. cit., p. 78.
5. M. Weber, 'Science as a Vocation', in 22. M . Weber, 'The Meaning of
Gerth and Mills, op. cit., pp. 153-4. " Ethical Neutrality" ', in op . cit.,
6. M . Weber, ' Objectivity' in Soclal pp. 42-3
Policy', in Shils and Finch (eds), op. cit., 23. M. Weber, 'Critical Studies in the
p. 106. Logic of the Cultural Sciences', in Shils
7. On this distinction in Kant, see my and Finch (eds), op. cit., p. 125.
'Kant as a Problem for Marxism', Radical 24. M . Weber, 'The Meaning of
Philosophy, 1 9, 1978. "Ethical Neutrality" ', in op. cit., p. 18.
8. M. Weber, The Theory of Social and 25. M. Weber, 'The Meaning of
Economic Organisation, Free Press, 1964, " Ethical Neutrality" ', in op . cit.,
p. 110 pp. 20-1.
9. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 110. 26. M . Weber, 'The Meaning of
lo. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 130. "Ethical Neutrality"', in op. cit.,
. M.Weber,op.cit.,p. 328. pp. 24-5
12. T. Parsons, The Structure of Social 27. See, for example, M. Weber,
Action, Free Press, 1937, p. 643. ' " Objectivity" in Social Policy', in op.
13. T. Parsons, footnote in M. Weber, cit.,p. 88.
op. cit., p. 115. As a counteIweight to 28. M. Weber, ' "Objectivity" in Social

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Martin Barker
244

Policy', in op. cit., p. 92. First emphasis 36. Note that, in order to make this
mine, MB. impossible, it is not enough only to
29. M. Weber, quoted in G. Oakes, assume that values are non-rational. For
'The Verstehen Thesis', History and Theory, in the absence of the relation of
g77,p- 15 domination, there is no 'a priori' reason
30. M. Weber: 'The Theory of Social why men and women should not choose
and Economic Organisation', p. 152. This non-rationally to pursue the same goals -
is the logical point to bring out clearly the unless afurther assumption is built in that they
dispute there has been over the translation would necessarily have conflicting goals,
of Weber's term herrschaft. This rendered or come into conflict in trying to act them
by Parsons as 'authority', by others as out.
'domination'. The literal translation is 37. M. Weber, op. cit., p. 1 15.
'lordship'. Clearly, the implications of 38. M. Weber, 'On Law in Economy
each term are markedly diffierent. Not and Society', p. 335.
being a German scholar, I am not 39. This helps make sense of another
qualified to comment on the problem as passage that has puzzled commentators.
one of translation. However, it will In his critique of value - judgements
become clear that my understanding of derived from 'adaptation', Weber wrote:
the use that Weber makes of the term, puts
Depending on how one used the term,
me firmly on the side of those who use
either everything or nothing in society is
such a word as 'domination'.
'adapted'. Conflict cannot be excluded
31. M. Weber, On Law in Economy and
from social life. One can change its
Society, Harvard, 1 954, p. 3 2 8.
means, its objects, even its fundamental
32. M. Weber, loc. cit. I cannot pass
direction and its bearers, but it cannot
this point without wondering whether this
be eliminated. There can beS instead of
use of the 'as if' construction does not
an external struggle of antagonists for
exactly mirror that of Hans V-aihinger, The
external objects, an inner struggle of
Philosophy of 'As If, Routledge & Kegan
mutually loving persons for subjective
Paul, 1924, one of the most important
values and therewith instead of external
neo- Kantian interpreters of Kant.
compulsion, an inner control (in the
Vaihinger adopts a stance remarkably
form of erotic or charitable devotion).
similar to Weber on a whole number of
Or it can take the form of a subjective
points. His book is an exposition of the
conflict in the individual's own
notion of necessary fictions. Note how
mind.... 'Peace' is nothing more than
close to Weber's discussion of the 'ideal-
a change in the form of the conflict or in
type' the following is:
the antagonists or in the objects of the
conflict, or finally in the chances of
If we mean by a mistake a deviation from
selection.... Only one thing is
reality, and by an error a contradictory
indisputable; every type of social order,
concept, then we can call semi-fictions
without exception, must, if one wishes
'conscious mistakes', and the real
to evaluate it, be examined with
fictions 'conscious errors' or 'conscious
reference to the opportunities which it
contradictions', the one group tending
affords to certain types o/persons to rise to
to serve purely practical purposes, the
positions of superiority through the
other theoretical. The former are used
operation of the various objective and
more for 'logical operations', the latter
subjective selection factors. 'The
for 'understanding'; and while the
Meaning of "Ethical Neutrality"',
semi-fiction leads us back to
pp. 26-7.
methodological motives, the real fiction
leads to those connected with the theory This passage has clearly caused difficulty.
of knowledge, p. 80. It refers to the inevitability of conflict: it
33. M. Weber, op. cit., pp. 336-7. calls this an evaluation: it sees a conflict of
34 M. Weber, 'The Theory of Social subjective values even in lovers. However
and Economic Organisations', p. 1 15. one reads it, it offends against his rule that
35. M.Weber,op.cit.,p. 130. methodological assertions should not

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant as a pr()hlem f()r Weber 245

impinge oll substantive judgements. But 42. On Kant, .see again my 'Kant as a
on my analysis, it makes perfeet sense. Problem for Marxism', loc. cit
40. M. Weber, 'The Theory of Social 43. The reference is, of course, to
and Economie O rgani sations ', p . 1 53 . Marx's Third Thesis on Feuerbach, whose
4 1. And it is because the world is applications as a problem go way beyond
( haoti( that the orientations we adopt are Feuerbach, or even the Marxist tradition.
impo.sition.s on the world, not derived from it
This ties ba(k in with his assertions of the
llon-rationality of' value- judgements.

This content downloaded from


186.216.182.21 on Fri, 27 Nov 2020 19:01:55 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like