You are on page 1of 16

730 V.

Geschichtsschreibung dcr Semintik

34. History and historiography of semiotics


1. On the subject matter certain requirements of originality, perc¢ptiv­
1.1. Natural versus human sciences ity, and suggestive force.
1.2. Semiotics Unfortunately, those attempting to inYesti­
1.3. Reasons for an ostracism gate semiotic ideas can easily discover that
2. Sources
2.1. Explicit general semiotics many authors who arc certainly concerned
2.2. Explicit particular semiotics with signs (at least from the point of view of
2.3. Cosmological semiotics the investigator) (i) do not mention the ,.:-on­
2A. Implicit semiotics cept of sign; (ii) challenge the very notic111 of
2.5. Insights from semiosic experiences sign; (iii) say that semiotics is concerned with
3. The comparability of theories something different from signs; (iv) maintain
3.1. An example: symbol � a web of that signs are only a subspecies of semiotic
ambiguities entities and that semiotics concerns a broader
3.2. Greece field of interrelated phenomena; (v) blatantly
3.3. Mediaeval pan-semiotic metaphysics
3A. Scriptural interpretation deny the existence of a unified field of mter­
3.5. The Thomistic reaction ests labelled as semiotics; (vi) are polemically
3.6. Dante assuming that their approach has nothing to
3.7. Renaissance Hermetism do with semiotics.
4. Secondary sources
5. Conclusion 1. l. Natural versus human sciences
6. Selected references The natural sciences are in a better situation.
6.1. Sources Take for instance the case of chemistry (cf.
6.2. Secondary literature Art. 135). The members of the scientific com­
munity have a clear idea about the nature of
I. On the subject matter chemical phenomena as they are recognized
and studied today. They also know where
A history of semiotics should be a critical their discipline overlaps other sciences, that
survey of all the cases in which a given au­ is, they know that there are certain bound­
thor or a group of authors have explicitly or aries to their science which remain or are
implicitly dealt with the proper object of increasingly becoming sub iudice, and others
semiotics. that are definitely accepted as unchallenge­
111is definition sounds merely truistic since able (at least until the unpredictable adwnt
one knows that there is a continuing debate of change of paradigm). Thus a historian of
on the definition of the object. It would cer­ chemistry knows that he can take into ac­
tainly be sufficient to accept the guideline count the history of alchemy insofar as Iii it
proposed by the editors of this Handbook represents a series of unscientific attempts
(cf. Art. 1) and to recognize as a characteriza­ which encouraged or delayed the arrival of
tion of the proper object of semiotics the no­ modern chemistry, (ii) it can be revisited in
tion of sign. Semiotics should therefore be order to discover that it in some way posired
identified as a theoretical approach to the no­ problems which are still unsolved or suggest
tion of sign. In this sense a semiotic investiga­ possible criticism to the present state of the
tion is witnessed every time someone is theo­ art.
retically concerned with the definition of The humanities enjoy (or suffer fromJ a
signs, their structure and function, and the different situation, for here the state of the
processes in which signs are involved. In art as a whole is constantly in question , .:f.
other words it could be said that a history of Art. 33). The natural sciences are bodie� �1f
semiotics is interested in all the cases in which notions that can be studied and enlarged ::1-
an author critically focuses on the process of dependently of their own history. It is p,Js�
semiosis and/or the sign-systems that make sible to be a good researcher in chemistry ( if
semiosis possible. Every instance of such crit­ probably not the best mind in the field) wuh­
ical attention can then be defined as a (partial out knowing the story of the now obsoltte
or global) semiotic approach. The historian phlogiston theory. It is impossible for a gol•d
is entitled to consider also the cases in which student in historiography to ignore the hi:-­
the semiotic approach is neither systematic tory of historiography, just at it is impossibl e
nor explicitly presented as such but meets for a good cultural anthropologist to ign�'tl'
34. History and historiography 731

the way in which the first European explorers pened in a given part of the world. FurtherM
approached and described non-European more the historian will be interested in distin­
cultures. The erroneous theory of phlogiston guishing between different ways of telling the
did not affect the present structure of physi­ past, different criteria for ascertaining the
cal bodies, while the behavior of Hernando historical truth, for trusting or distrusting
Cortez, of Walter Raleigh or of the Jesuit traditional data, or for identifying a docu­
missionaries affected the actual structure of ment as being authentic. However, he will
non-European societies. A human science is probably not deny that Xenophon and Thu­
always obliged to comprehend its own his­ cydides ought to be duly considered in the
tory. first chapters of his work, and that Homer
The development of the natural sciences is should be discussed in a chapter on the bor­
cumulative but very seldom does such a cu­ derlines between historiography, myth and
mulation proceed by a piling up of notions: poetry (cf. Art. 147 as well as Art. 89 § 6.1.).
usually a science proceeds by subtraction and A historian of philosophy will have a more
addition. At every step certain notions are re­ difficult task (cf. Art. 40, 49, 62, and 74). Ac­
jected as obsolete, some are radically revised, cording to present standards, Aristotle was
many are added ex nova. In the natural sci­ undoubtedly a philosopher (even though it is
ences it is clear what has been rejected and debatable whether his Historia animalium is
what has been added, and according to the as philosophical or less or more philosophical
dominant paradigm it is unusual to recover a than his Rhetorics). Porphyry's Isagoge is a
rejected scientific principle. It is improbable philosophical text but few histories of philos­
that modern astronomers will return to the ophy take into account his De antro Nympha­
Ptolemaic system; at most one rediscovers rum, which appears to be a piece of literary
neglected ideas and cautiously considers the criticism ante litteram or of mythological in­
possibility of alternative approaches (for in­ terpretation. In spite of this common opin­
stance, Chinese acupuncture can be seriously ion, De antro Nympharum had a remarkable
·'·'.�
considered as complementary to some pro­ impact on the development of the allegorical
cedures of Western medicine). tradition, and within this tradition many
In the human sciences the process is far philosophical problems were debated, from
more ambiguous. From an idealistic point of Philo of Alexandria to contemporary and
view the history of a discipline, like history modern hermeneutics.
as the whole process of human events, has What should a historian of philosophy do
been seen as a dialectics between revision and with an author who speaks against philoso­
reformulation: human thinking challenges an phy? Certainly the historian can decide, on
old idea and produces a new one which, in a the grounds of an explicit theoretical assump­
certain sense, does not destroy the previous tion, that even the assertion "philosophy is
one but re-elaborates it at a higher degree of impossible" is a philosophical one. As for au­
theoretical awareness. thors who do not define themselves as philo­
Modern historians are less confident in a sophers, the historian can decide that, in the
linear progress of both human thought and light of his own preliminary definition of phi­
social history. It is readily agreed that con­ losophy, they are in fact contributing to the
temporary physics is better (more explana­ progress of philosophical research, or that
tory) than Greek physics, but any ethical or they have in some way profoundly influenced
political science can today discover that the other philosophical theories. But he must
Greek idea of polis or the Aristotelian idea of also decide how indirect an influence can be
prudence are still more appropriate that tolerated in order to be recognized as a 'phil­
many modern doctrines. The idea of eros in osophical' influence. Comenius's thought was
Plato is not necessarily obsolete if compared undoubtedly influenced by the death of his
with the idea of eras in de Sade. The most wife and children during the Thirty Years'
advanced contemporary views on rhetoric War but no one would recognize these events
are more similar to the classical views than as having had a philosophical influence.
to those of the I 9th century. However, Comenius was also influenced by
The human sciences have dealt with these the Rosicrucian controversy. Is the RosicruM
problems in various ways. A historian of cian utopia a philosophical matter? Should
historiography can start from the very toler­ the Fama and the Confessio (cf. Andreae
ant assumption that there is historiography 1614-15 = 1972-73) be quoted and ana­
every time an author relates what has hap- lyzed within a history of philosophy' Alchc-
732 V. Gcschichtsschreibung dcr Semiotik

mists call themselves "The Philosophers", int? serious c?nsideration oply those cases in
even when they are only speaking of practical wh1ch .
the .obJect of �esthet1cs comcide
_ s with
procedures for distilling herbs. Is that termi­ philosophical reflectron on art, and disposes
nological self-appointment a sufficient reason of every theory of natural beauty and practi:
for devoting a consisten·t chapter to them? cally every theory of art before Baumgarten
Most of the histories of philosophy either ig­ as a sort of naive attempt to discover the verv
nore them, or mention them only in passing. nature of aesthetic experience.
On the other hand, the same handbooks deal On the other hand, Bosanquet (189"·
consistently with mystics, or with scientists ch. l) assumes that even if "it was not bef'o�
who have never proclaimed themselves to be the latter half of the eighteenth century thai
philosophers. the term 'Aesthetics' was adopted with the
Thus a history of philosophy usually opens meaning now recognized [...} the thing ex­
with a sort of comprehensive, tolerant and isted before the name [...]. If, then. 'Aesthet­
frequently tentative definition of its own ob­ ics' means the Philosophy of the Beautiful.
ject, and deals with different, if not mutually the History of Aesthetics must mean the His­
incompatible ideas of philosophy. In other tory of the Philosophy of the Beautiful; and
cases the historian assumes that the subject it must accept as its immediate subject-matter
the succession of systematic theories b,·
matter of philosophy is the ens in quantum
which philosophers have attempted to ex­
ens, and drastically reduces the scope of his
plain or connected together the facts that re­
reconstruction. late to beauty".
However, a historian of philosophy is Notwithstanding, Bosanquet was bound to
helped by the fact that - at least from the the reconstruction of explicitly philosophical
time of Aristotle - when people argue about views, and had a very peculiar idea of what
the definition of philosophy they use the a philosophical discourse is. Thus he devoted
name, and are generally agreed that philo­ no more than ten pages to the period from
sophers do indeed exist. Moreover, people Augustine to Dante. De Bruyne (I 946) wrote
continue to follow the Greek tradition in three impressive volumes on the same period
their acceptance of the idea that philosophy which showed that important ideas about
is a way, albeit obscure and never definitely artistic, natural and divine beauty, as well as
defined, of approaching our human experi­ about artistic procedures, can be found in the
ence. work of the Schoolmen, of the rhetoricians.
A more dubious case is that of a history of the artists reflecting on their own work. In
of aesthetics (cf. Art. 50, 63, 75). Aesthetics this sense De Bruyne not only wrote a history
as a discipline, or at least as the investigation of philosophical doctrines, but also of gene­
of a certain field of phenomena, is a rather ral aesthetic sensibility and of the implicit
recent approach and the word itself was only theoretical awareness displayed by artists
coined during the 18th century. Naturally, concerned with the nature of their practical
since we know that America existed long be­ activity.
fore it was discovered and named, we are en­ In spite of the many difficult methodologi­
titled to ask what happened beyond the At­ cal choices that historians of aesthetics must
lantic ocean before Columbus' travels: we ac­ make, there are at least two facts that can
cept the idea of a history of the American help them: even though the sense of many
continent before its so-called discovery. But terms has changed during the course of his­
a discipline is not a continent. In order to tory, it is certain that Western culture has con­
say that Plato speaking of the beauty of the stantly spoken of the experience of Beauty and
natural world, Aristotle speaking of the rules of the practice of Art. Certainly the Greek.
Latin, and Mediaeval cultures did not distin­
for a good tragedy and Pseudo-Longinus
guish between art, crafts and technique, and
speaking of the feelings aroused by poetry frequently did not clearly distinguish between
were all discussing aesthetic problems (with­ the beautiru! and the merely pleasurable.
out using such a denomination), the historian However the historian is entitled to identify
must provide a definition of aesthetics. We an aesthetic discussion every time a given au­
know how controversial any definition of thor speaks in terms of beauty or of art.
aesthetics can be. Croce (1902) assumed that
aesthetics is the philosophical speculation 1.2. Semiotics
about creative intuition or about "the lyrical Semiotics is in an even more difficult situa­
expression of human feelings": thus his his­ tion because of a double embarassment:
torical reconstruction of the discipline takes (i) modern semioticians are still questioning
34. History and historiography 733

the main categories of the field and (ii) there As for a comparison between (i) and (ii),
has been no common agreement in the course many contemporary authors complain about
of so-called semiotic investigations about a the undue extension of the notion of linguis­
reduced list of basic categories (as happened tic sign to other semiotic systems (for in­
for art and beauty in aesthetics). stance Segre 1969: 43) while others (see Eco
With regard to (i), many contemporary au­ 1984: ch. l), maintain that the opposite hap­
thors (for instance, Malmberg 1977: 21) have pened, namely. that at the beginning there
decided to call every element representing was the original concept of a natural and
something else "a symbol" and to retain the nonlinguistic sign which was further ex­
term "sign" to refer to "those units which, tended in order to explain even linguistic phe­
like the signs of language, have a double ar­ nomena.
ticulation and owe their existence to an act If such is the state of the art, a historian
of signification." Prieto (1966) has widened of semiotics must initially spell out what he
the field of sign analysis by documenting the is looking for in the course of his exploration
existence of systems without articulation and through different disciplines and mutually
systems which have only a single articulation. conflicting theories.
Buyssens (1943) maintains that for a semiotic Let us say that semiotics is a Doctrine of
theory the format of the sign is far too min­ Signs (for historical reasons for this choice
ute and that the problems of communication see Jakobson 1974 and Sebeok 1976). But in
must be investigated at least on the level of order to proceed in this direction one should
larger units called "semes", which correspond provide a very tolerant notion of sign to take
to sentences if not, as some would say today, into account even those approaches where
to large textual units (see Kristeva 1969: the notion of sign is either ignored or chal­
69 fl). Cassirer ( 1923-29) identifies general lenged.
semiotics with a theory of every symbolic A starting point could be the assumption
form. Harman (1977: 23) says that general made by Jakobson (1974) when opening the
theories of signs like that of Peirce "comprise First Congress of the International Associa­
at least three rather different subjects: a the­ tion for Semiotic Studies. Semiotics is any
ory of the intended meaning, a theory of evi­ type of study interested in a "relation de ren­
dence, and a theory of pictorial depiction". voi" ('a relation of referral'): wherever aliquid
As for (ii), the sign was not a comprehen­ stat pro aliquo there is a semiotic problem.
sive semiotic category from the beginning of This definition is not dissimilar from that of
Western thought (not to speak of other civili­ Peirce (1931-66: § 2.228.), according to
zations; cf. Art. 89-99). From early Greek which a sign is "something which stands to
thought until Augustine there is a sharp divi­ somebody for something in some respect or
sion between semeia (let us call them "natural capacity". The word dog stands for some­
signs") and on6mata (linguistic signs or thing else in the same way as the whole Iliad
words); see for instance Eco 1984: 26-34. stands for a series of facts, feelings and val­
Many scholars today recognize that the ues. At this point, no preliminary decision is
Sophists (cf. Untersteiner I 949-54) elabo­ necessary as to whether the something else is
rated in their own terms the first approach to a state of affairs, a thing, a truth or an idea, a
pragmatics, and at least from the time of third-world entity, or a cultural unit resulting
Morris (1938) there has been a line of from the ideal segmentation of our world ex­
thought ranking pragmatics among the perience.
branches of semiotics: but the Sophists - Neither is it important to reach a prelimi­
who were interested in language - were not nary decision as to what is the format of any
interested in sc-;meTa as elementary linguistic something which stands for something else.
units, but rather in the perlocutionary force In order to recognize a relation of referral it
of discourses. is irrelevant whether the referring unit is a
In the Hippocratic tradition and subse­ minimal element (like a lcxematic unit in verM
quently in Galen (cf. Galen 1821-33 and Ed­ bal language) or a maximal textual body. A
low 1977) there are many important observa­ straight line in Euclidean geometry is as
tions about symptoms, but no attention was much a sign as the Sistine Chapel. A simple
given to linguistic phenomena. (Galen would communicational strategy (like a courtesy
undoubtedly have been surprised to learn gesture) is as much a sign as a complex ritual.
that his ti:cl111i! stmehJtikiJ was connected with This does not mean that semiotic theories
the study of language.) are not interested in ascertaining when semi-
734 V. Geschichtsschreibung der Scmiotik

otic units can be split into minor constituent author has proposed a Doctrine of Signs or
clements. Ii only means that one is entitled to even a name like semiology or semiotics (and
recognize primafacie a semiotic phenomenon the list of such proposals is impressively
every time one witnesses a relation of refer� large, from Roger Bacon to Wilkins, from
ral, and a semiotic investigation every time Locke to Peirce and Husserl), the proposal
an author is concerned with the nature of has been further repressed (in the Freudian
such relations (cf. Art. l -4). sense of Verdriingung).
Such a tolerant notion of sign can entitle The task of a history of semiotics is to re�
a historian to explore the whole of human discover the various discussions on the na­
culture in order to identify all the cases in ture and function of semiosis, but its duty is
which a relation of referral has become the also to show: (i) when a given theory was in
object of theoretical awareness, irrespective some way transversally obsessed by the semi­
of whether such an awareness is the explicit otic problem without daring to recognize it
subject matter of a theory, or should be in­ as such; (ii) when a given theory explicitly ad­
ferred by the historian as an evident back­ vocated semiotic endeavor and the subse­
ground assumption and/or as the unavoid� quent interpretations of that theory focused
able consequence of other discourses. only on its non-semiotic aspects (as was the
case of Locke and of many interpreters of
1.3. Reasons for an ostracism Peirce); (iii) why in both cases the semiotic
It seems rather evident that human cultural awareness was repressed.
life (not to speak of more controversial phe­ A history of semiotics could then become
nomena taking place in the processing of in­ either the story of a millenary attempt to
formation machines, in animal or vegetal so­ avoid a definite commitment to the central
cieties, or at inter-organic levels) is mainly problem of human experience or the explana­
based upon referral relations (cf. Posner tion of the reasons why such a commitment
l 989). In other words it seems obvious that is far too difficult, or even impossible.
the ability to produce, exchange and under­
stand signs represents a central feature of
mankind (so that even when one speaks of 2. Sources
semiosic processes in machines or animals,
one can do so in so far as one compares them We should now decide what is meant by im­
to a higher human semiosic behavior). plicit and explicit primary semiotic sources.
At the beginning of Western philosophical
speculation, when Aristotle establishes that 2.1. Explicit general semiotics
the subject matter of his "first philosophy" is Certain authors have explicitly recognized
Being, the definition of such an object is a semiosis and signs as phenomena which recur
semiotic one. It is told in Metaphysics (IV in the whole of culture (and maybe of nature)
l003 a2l ff) that "there is a science which and have chosen these phenomena to be the
studies Being qua Beinf' and that "ro Os 6v main subject of their inquiry (or a relevant
Uysra, µiv ,ro)J,aK6s", that is, that Being part of it). Thus they have outlined a general
is what is said in different ways. This state­ theory of signs or a project for it, considering
ment can be taken as the simple symptom of su.ch a theory as a crucial node for the human
a linguistic difficulty but can also be taken as sciences. The Stoics, Augustine, Roger Ba­ f,
the assertion that Being is a semiotic effect. con, Kircher, Locke, Lambert, Peirce, Saus­
In both cases, at the dawn of Western philo­ sure, Hjclmslev, and Husserl as the author of
sophical speculation, there is a semiotic ques­ Semiotik, among others, belong to this
tion, and this question concerns the basic re­ group.
lationship of thought, being, and language.
This should have been sufficient to show how 2.2. Explicit particular semiotics
indispensable the existence of a discipline Certain authors have limited their study of
studying every instance of such a constitutive semiosis and signs to a few cultural systems
relationship is. (for instance only to verbal language) and
It cannot be said that this problem has may not have realized that their results can
been eluded in the course of the following be applied to other systems (they might even
two thousand years. But it is interesting to have expl!citly denied that application to
note that it was not usually approached un­ other systems was possible). In any case they
der the heading of semiotics. Every time an were aware of the existence of semiotic phc-
34. History and historiography 735

norne na in spite of the limits of their investi­ theories of visual perception (from the
gations. Vitruvian discussions through the theories
We can rank in this category various au­ of perspective and anarnorphosis until Ge­
thors and cultural currents coming from dif­ stalttheorie);
ferent domains. To give only a few examples: theories of poetry and literature:
theories of performing arts, from Aris­
philosophers of verbal language, from totle, through his Renaissance commenta­
Plato, Aristotle, the Sophists, through tors up to Ejzenstein, etc.
Boethius, Abelard, and Ockham to Frege This list is obviously not complete.
as well as Husserl as the author of Lo­
gische Untersuchungen, Wittgenstein, Car­ 2.3. Cosmological semiotics
nap, and Analytic Philosophy in general; There are entire philosophical, religious, and
classical, medieval and modern rhetorics; cosmological world-views that are based
most of the classical (Western and East­ upon the assumption that the whole universe
ern) and modern linguistics, as well as the is a semiosic process. These theories fre­
medieval modistae and any advocate of a quently use terms such as "sign", "symbol",
universal grammar; "cosmis" or "divine language", but even
patristic and scholastic theories of scrip­ when they do not do so, they imply that the
tural interpretation; universe is a divine writing (fiber scriptus di­
divination, oneiromancy, chiromancy, gito Dei) or a self-expressing system.
metoscopy, physiognomies, and other Among these world-views let us mention
forms of interpretation by symptoms, in­ at least:
cluding medicine; Platonism as an interpretation of the
language of visions, prophecy, glossolaly; physical world as an image or an imita­
the whole tradition of formal logic; tion of the ideal world;
the Baroque theorists of wit, Witz, esprit, the Hermetic tradition, from the Corpus
aqudeza, concettismo, such as Tesauro Hermeticum (see Nock and Festugiere
and Garcian; 1945-54) to the late alchemists, with their
iconology and emblematology; attempt to interpret through symbols the
the theorists of the ars magna from Lullus correspondences between micro- and mac­
to Leibniz, those searching for a lingua ad­ rocosm;
amica, of a characteristica universa/is /in­ various forms of neoplatonism (Pseudo­
guarum, the inventors of cryptographies, Dionysius, Scotus Erigena, Ficino and
steganographies, new general taxonomies Pico);
and of the around 200 international lan­ astrological traditions, theurgy, the theory
guages coined in the last two centuries, of talismans as a powerful operative link
etc.; between the upper and lower worlds;
artes memoriae (from Rhetorica ad Heren­ primitive magic and Renaissance magic in
nium to the 17th century); particular, as far as it was concerned with
philosophers of science of any age who the whole universe as a network of signa­
discussed analogy, metaphor, models, etc. turae (Paracelsus, Agrippa, Della Porta,
as tools for scientific discovery; Crollius and so on);
scientific formalization of languages; Greek, Jewish, Patristic and Mediaeval
ancient zoosemiotics; theories of universal symbolism and alle­
all the other anticipations of contempo­ gorism (as well as their Eastern conge­
rary particular semiotics, such as kinesics, ners);
Kahhalah;
proxcmics, musical, medical or architec­
tural semiotics, etc.; pansophic visions and projects of a the­
ater of the world (Camillo, Bruno, Fludd);
psychoanalysis and psychological (as well Berkeley and many idealistic systems:
as neurological) investigation on lan­ contemporary interpretations of the cos­
guage; mological structure in terms of a mathe·
military strategy; matics of fractals.
scientific discussions on the revealing
power of visual prostheses (mirrors, tele­ 2.4. Implicit semiotics
scope, microscope, radar, etc.): It is possible to infer a series of background
Baroque optical theaters and visual ma­ assumptions about signification and corn·
chines (from Kircher to Baltrusaitis); munication from every philosopher. even
736 V. Geschichtsschreibung dcr Semiotik

when he never spoke ex professo of language bestiaries and herbaries, the Renaissance art­
and other semiotic matters. ists' reflexions on perspective, many arfes
A typical example is provided by Kant. At poeticae, the discussions on theater, cinema
first glance it seems difficult to extrapolate or other arts. are rich in theoretical remarks.
from his work a Kantian semiotics (cf. Art. We know that many pages of Leonardo, Poe.
35 § 3.3.). However, the whole of the third Strawinsky or Klee contain precious and per�
Kritik can be viewed as a theory of inter­ ceptive theoretical insights.
pretation, and the notion of reflecting judge­ The historian of semiotics should not only
ment can now be re-examined in the light of analyze what artists have written about their
the semiotic notion of abduction. Moreover, art; equally perceptive insights on significa­
many contemporary semantic theories, espe­ tion and communication can be extrapolated
cially after the experiences of Artificial Intel­ from their poetic, narrative, pictorial or the­
ligence, are speculating again about the set atrical works. It is not preposterous to say
of mental categories which at the same time that important ideas on the way we under­
govern our perceptual activity and the un­ stand signs are provided by narrative pages
derstanding of meaning. Independently of of Proust or Mann, that Joyce's Finnegan '.1·
whether these categories are intended as a Wake contains provocative suggestions about
priori universals or as the effect of cultural the nature of language, that every play by
heritage, one can say that Kant posited (in a Pirandello represents an explicit reflection on
nonsemiotic way) problems that are crucial pragmatic and semantic problems, that the
for a semiotic enquiry (cf. Art. 74 § 2.). last novels of Calvino are clear instances of
It is difficult to say whether similar theo­ meta.narrative discourse, that Borges' stories
ries presuppose an implicit semiotics as their say more about intertextuality than many
background or suggest a possible semiotics as theoretical treatises.
their consequence. In any case many of them
are more important than a good deal of the
explicit but repetitive semiotic theorizing. 3. The comparability of theories
The research on implicit semiotics should
start from a clear methodological assump­ One of the tasks of a history of semiotics will
tion: frequently a past theory becomes semi­ certainly be to show how and to what extent
otically relevant from the point of view of certain ideas, frequently believed to be very
our present problems. Thus a historical re­ modern, have a millenary pedigree. It is fasci­
construction of semiotics should follow a nating to discover that certain discussion� on
twofold path: (i) from the past to the present, similitude and identity, on the differences be­
to discover archaeological evidence that can tween to-be-similar-to and to-be-an-image­
better explain the present situation; (ii) from of, as well as on the difference between vari·
the present to the past, to understand the ous forms of so-called iconicity (imprints,
semiotic purport of theories which, when symptoms, ostension, and images) took place
they were elaborated, were extraneous to the during the Middle Ages (cf. Art. 60 § 4. 7. and
development of semiotics. Art. 61 § 3.). The same set of basic concepts,
borrowed from Greek philosophy (cf. Art. 40
2.5. Insights from semiosic experiences § 3.), nourished the work of many different
Every semiosic practice presupposes an ideal authors. It is fascinating to discover that the
awareness of its semiotic laws. This is true difference between signifier and signified was
not only for verbal language but for every absolutely clear to the Stoics, as well as the
kind of signification system. notion of linguistic articulation ( cf. Art. 42
It is not necessary for the historian to § 2.1.4.).
study the nature and function of every pos­ But if the first task is to show the unity of
sible system or signification, from visual lan­ the semiotic tradition, the second is to stress
guage to lithurgy, from card games to eti­ the differences, that is, to show when and in
quette. This is the task of particular semio- which sense the same linguistic term con­
tics. veyed ideas that. once inserted in a particular
However, in many cases certain authors theoretical framework, became very different
who provided rules and examples of specific from each other (cf. Art. 35 § 2. -4.).
semiosic practices displayed a strong aware­ There certainly is a semiotirn perennis, but
ness of their procedures. The Mediaeval trea­ mainly in the sense that certain basic prob­
tises on liturgy or on the interpretation of lems were discu)scd in c\ cry historical period
raphy 737
34. History and historiog

(cf. Art. 35 § 1.). Such a continuous appear­ which art, aiming at expressing the infinite,
ance of the same questions_ is surely proof shows the inadequacy of its own images and
that they were and are crucial to the under­ alludes to something greater and higher,
standing of human and natural experience. without being able to express it fully.
But there is a difference between the continu­ In present times when we speak of symbols
ity of a question and the continuity of a solu­ in poetry, in psychoanalysis, and even in the
tion. The permanence of a term can fre­ criticism of our unconscious ideological atti­
quently be evidence of the continuity of the tudes, it seems we use this term in the Ro­
question but not of the contmmty of the re­ mantic sense. But when we speak of symbols
sponse. in logic or mathematics we use it in a totally
Many examples could be given. Let us fol­ different way.
low as a mere example for some centuries the In order to understand the ambiguity of
tortured story of the category of symbol. the word "symbol" it is necessary to revisit
its origins. In this sense a historiographical
3.1. An example: reconstruction helps us to understand what
symbol - a web of ambiguities happened in the past and also what is hap­
If we understand the term "symbol" in the pening in the present.
same sense as logicians and mathematicians,
then a symbol is known (i) as that which is a 3.2. Greece
signifier correlated to its meaning by a law Such ambiguity has its roots in the Greek
(by a precise convention) and as such is inter­ etymology (cf. Art. 39). Originally a symbol
pretable through other signifiers, or (ii) as a was a token, the present half of a broken ta­
variable that can be bound in many ways but, ble or coin or medal, that performed its so­
once it has acquired a given value, cannot cial and semiotic function by recalling the ab­
represent other values within the same sent half to which it could potentially be re­
context. If we take symbol in the sense of connected. This potential was indeed crucial
Hjelmslev (1943), then examples are the because as the two halves could have been
Cross, the Hammer and the Sickle, emblems reconnected if was no longer necessary to
and heraldic images. In this sense symbols yearn for reconnection. But the present half
are allegories (cf. Art. 58 § 2. and 3. as well of the broken medal evoked the ghost of its
as Art. 60 § 4.3.). absent companion and of the original whole­
There is, however, a further sense of the ness, thus encouraging the formation of other
word, according to which symbols are signifi­ senses of "symbol". The verb symba/lein
ers that convey imprecise clouds or nebulae meant 'to meet', 'to try an interpretation', 'to
of meanings that are left unexploited or are make a conjecture', 'to solve a riddle', 'to in­
unexploitable. fer from something imprecise, because in­
According to Goethe "symbolism trans­ complete, something else that is suggested,
forms the experience into an idea and the evoked, revealed, but is not conventionelly
idea into an image, so that the idea expressed said'. In this sense a symbol was an ominous
through the image remains infinitely active and sudden experience that allowed vague
and unattainable [...]. Allegory transforms consequences to be tentatively forecast. It
an experience into a concept and the concept was a semeion, but a Semefon of an impalpa­
into an image, but so that the concept re­ ble quality.
mains always defined and expressible by the When in the Stoic milieu the first attempts
image" (Maximen und Reflexionen 1112 and were made to read allegorically the old poets
1113 in Goethe 1948- 71: IX, 639; cf. Posner in an effort to find evidence of natural truths
1982: 171 ff). hidden within the myths, or when Philo of
Goethe's definition seems perfectly in tune Alexandria started lhe allegorical reading of
with that advanced by idealistic philosophy, the Bible1 there was no clear-cut distinction
even though the idealists did not fully agree between symbol and allegory. Pepin (l 969)
on the nature of the symbolism: for instance, and Auerbach (1944) say that the classical
the symbol was identified by Schelling with world took "symbol" and "allegory" as syn­
the higher form of art, while for Hegel it was onymous expressions and that they also
the form that art assumes at its lower and called "symbols" certain coded images pro­
more primitive stages. However, for both duced for educational purposes. Behind such
symbolism was either the meeting point of a linguistic usage there was the idea that sym­
the finite and the infinite, or the moment in bols, too, were rhetorical devices endowed
738 V. Geschichtsschreibung der Semiotik

with a precise meaning: obscurely given, but deep contradictoriness of reality (cf. Art. 62
precise when found. And the same was true § 5.). Against . that_, for mediaeval theology
within the tradition of the Church Fathers both contradtctormess and ambigu _
ity are
and within Mediaeval culture. merely semiotic, not ontological.
Naturally, if we want to speak of the Un.
3.3. Mediaeval pan-semiotic metaphysics speakable, we name it "Goodness", "Truth "
ln the patristic and medieval tradition there "Beauty", "Light", ''Jealousy" and so on, bui
is an idea of symbolism as a way of speaking these terms, says Dionysius, can be applied
of something unknowable: in the nee-Pla­ to Him only "supersubstantially". And what
tonic line of thought, as represented by is more: since the names that we attribu te to
Pseudo-Dionysius, the divine source of all God will always be inadequate, it is indis­
beings, the One, is defined as "the luminous pensable to choose them accordin g to a
dimness, a silence which teaches secretly, a criterion of dissimilarity (cf. Art. 52 §2.).
flashing darkness which is neither body nor It is dangerous to name God "Beauty" or
figure nor shape, which has no quantity, no "Light", because one can believe that such
quality, no weight, which is not in a place and appelations do convey some of His real quali­
does not see, has no sensitivity, is neither soul ties, which they do not. We should rather call
nor mind, has no imagination or opinion, is Him "Lion", "Panther", "Bear", "Monster"
neither number nor order, nor greatness, is we should apply to Him the most provokin�
not a substance, not eternity, not time, not adjectives so that it be clear that the sim­
obscurity, not error, not light, not truth[ .. .]" ilarity we are looking for escapes us or can
(Theo/. myst., passim; cf. Art. 50 § 3. and only be glimpsed at the cost of a dispropor­
Art. 55 § 2.). tioned proportion (De coel. hier. 2; cf. animal
How can one speak of such a non-entity symbolism in the Germanic and in the Judaic
and non-identity if not by a language whose tradition, Art. 37 § 7.1. as well as Art. 55
signs have no literal and univocal meaning § 4.2. and Art. 61 § 2.1., respectively).
but are open to contrasting interpretations? However, this symbolical way of speaking
In his negative theology, Dionysius includes has nothing to do with the sudden illumina­
symbols which are non-translatable allego­ tion, with the cognitive ecstasy, with the
ries. Since the neo-Platonists regard the flashing vision of which the modern theories
source of the cosmic emanation as being be­ of symbolism speak. The mediaeval meta·
yond any rational knowledge and appearing physical symbol is neither epiphany nor reve­
to us as a mere Nothingness, we cannot help lation of a truth concealed under the clothes
but say something which is true and false at of a myth. Symbolism must make rationally
the same time, when we speak of It (cf. conceivable the inadequacy of our reason and
Art. 61 §I.and 2.). With its contradictoriness of our language. Challenged by this diffi­
the neo-Platonic symbol seems to have the culty, Dionysius' commentators tried to
same ambiguity as the Romantic symbol. translate his approach into rational terms:
Nevertheless, the neoplatonism of Diony­ when Scotus Erigena (De divisione naturae
sius - and furthermore that of his commen­ 5,3) says that "nihil enim visibilium rerum,
tators such as Thomas Aquinas - is not a corpora/iumque est, ut arhitro1; quod non in­
'strong' one: mediaeval neoplatonist philo­ corpora/e quid et intel/igibile sign/ficet" C'!
sophers tried to translate the pantheistic idea contend there is nothing among the visibk
of emanation into one of participation. For and corporeal things which does not signify
them, it is true that the One is absolutely something uncorporeal and intelligible"), he
transcendent and infinitely far from us, that is no longer speaking of a network of un­
we are made or different fabric since we arc graspab\c similitudes, but rather of the unin­
the mere litter of His creative energy, but He terrupted sequence of causes and effects that
is not contradictory in Himself. will later be called the "Great Chain of
Contradictoriness belongs to our own dis­ Being".
courses about Him and arises from our im­ Thomas Aquinas was to definitively trans­
perfect knowledge of Him. But the knowl­ form this approach into the doctrine of ana·
edge He has of Himself is totally unambigu­ logia entis, which aimed at being a propor­
ous. This is a very important point because, tional calculus.
as we shall see, the Hermetic Platonism of the Thus at the very root of mediaeval
Renaissance maintained that the very core of pansemiotical metaphysics, which was some­
every secret knowledge is the belief in the times characterized as universal symbolism.
34, History and historiography 739

there is the quest for a code and the will to and increasingly enrich this immense treasury
transform a poetic approximation into a phil­ of divine wisdom; everyone, according to
osophical statement (cf. Art. 50). one's own intellectual ability, can glean some­
thing from this inexhaustible storage of
3.4. Scriptural interpretation senses.
Parallel to the neo-Platonic line of thought Once again we confront here something
there is the hermeneutic tradition of scrip­ which recalls the modern fascination of an
tural interpreters, interested in the symbolic open textual reading and even the post-Hei­
language by which the Holy Scriptures speak deggerian (see Gadamer 1960) hermeneutic
to us (cf. Art. 58 § 4., Art. 60 § 4.3. and idea that a text magnetizes upon itself, so to
Art. 61 § 1. and 2.). speak, the whole of the readings it has elic­
The Holy Scriptures were two in number: ited in the course of history. But the Patristic
the Old and the New Testament. Initially the and Mediaeval problem was how to reconcile
Gnostics assumed that only the New Testa­ the infinity of interpretation with the univo­
ment was true, and Origenes wanted to keep cality of the message; i. e., how to read the
the continuity between the two testaments, books by discovering in them not new things
but he had to decide in which way they said but the same everlasting truth rephrased in
the same things, since they seemed to be ever new ways: non nova sed nove.
speaking differently. Thus he made the deci­ The task of the Church Fathers was to re­
sion to read them in a parallel way: the Old duce the openness of the symbolic language
is the signifier, the letter of which the New is by providing rules for a non-literal inter­
the signified or the spirit. At the same time pretation. Augustine was the first to put forth
the New was the letter whose spirit concerned a list of interpretative procedures for ascer­
salvation and moral duties. taining whether und when a fact told by the
Since the Holy Books were fundamentally Scriptures had to be taken not literally but
polysemic, their symbolical nature had to be figuratively (cf. Art. 40 § 4.L and Art. 49
tamed, and in order to do so the symbolic § 2. L). Augustine knew that verbal tropes
mode had to be identified with the allegorical such as metaphor can be easily detected be­
one. This is a very delicate point, because cause, if we take them literally, the text would
without this profound need of a code, the look mendacious. But what was to be done
scriptural interpretation would look very with a report of events that make sense li­
similar to our modern interpretative drift, terally but could still be interpreted symboli­
misprision, libidinal reading, free jouissance. cally? Augustine says that one is entitled to
The Scriptures had potentially every pos­ smell a figurative sense every time the Scrip­
sible meaning, but their reading had to be tures say things that are literally understand­
governed by a code and that is why the Fa­ able but contradict the principles of faith and
thers proposed the theory of the allegorical morals. Jesus at one point allows himself to
senses. Later, according to verses attributed be honored and ointed by a courtesan, and it
to Nicholas of Lyra, "/ittera gesta docet quid is impossible that our Savior encouraged
credas, allegorialmoralis quid agas, quo tendas such a lascivious ritual. Therefore the story
anagogia" ("the letter teaches what you stands for something else. In the same way
should believe, the moral allegory teaches one should smell a second sense when the
what you should do and the anagogy teaches Scriptures play upon inexplicable superflui­
where you should head"). ties or use literally poor expressions, such as
The theory of the four senses (cf. Art. 55 proper names or series of numbers. This ea­
§ 2.4., Art. 58 § 4. and Art. 60 § 4.3.) provided gerness to conjecture the presence of a sym­
a sort of guarantee for the correct decoding bolical mode when facing trivial events or
of the Books. But the Patristic and Scholastic blatantly useless details cannot but recall
mind could never avoid the feeling of inex­ modern poetic devices such as the Joycean
haustible profundity of the Scriptures, fre­ epiphany or Eliot's objective correlative. We
quently compared to a forest or to an ocean. look for the symbolic mode not at the level
Gilbert of Stanford (In Cant. 20, 225) of rhetorical figures but at the level of a more
compared the Holy Scriptures with a rapid macroscopic textual strategy, when a text dis­
river that flows by producing new senses plays a sort of uncanny liberality, of other­
which. as waves and whirls, come one after wise inexplicable descriptive generosity.
the other in such a way that no single one It should be clear from this that Augustine
annuls the others; instead they accumulate looked for symbols not in the case of verbal
740 V. Geschichtsschreibung der Seiniotik;..;

machineries but in the case of trivial events. Such an attitude could not be accepted by th e <
From the beginning, scriptural symbolism naturalism of the 13th century.
aimed at privileging the allegoria in factis Thomas Aquinas was harshly critical of '
over the allegoria in 11erbis. The words of the profane poetry and allegorism in verbis. B ut · ;
Psalmist can certainly be read as endowed since he was a poet himself, and a gifted one :
with a second sense - because the Holy he admitted that sometimes divine mysteries' i:
Scriptures frequently recur to rhetorical de� insofar as they exceed our comprehe nsion' f
vices; but what must necessarily be read be� must be revealed by rhetorical figures (Sum,n� :J
yond the letter are the series of historical Th. I, I, 9). However, concerning the Holy
events told by the Scriptures. God has predis­ Text, he recommends looking first of all for
posed the sacred history as a book written by its literal or historical sense. When the Bible
Himself, and the characters of the Old Testa­ says that the Hebrew people escaped from
ment were pulled to act as they did in order Egypt, it literally tell& the truth. Only when
to announce the characters and the events of one has grasped this literal sense can one
the New one. catch, through it and beyond it, the spiritual
Augustine took from the classical tradition senses, that is, the senses that the scriptural
the rhetorical rules allowing him to decode tradition assigned to the sacred books
the allegories in verbis, but he did not have namely the allegorical, the moral and the an'. ''
precise rules for the allegories in factis. Thus agogical or mystic ones.
in order to understand the meaning of the Up to this point Aquinas does not seem
facts told by the Bible, Augustine had to to have been so original with respect to the
understand the meaning of the things that the previous tradition (cf. Art. 49 § 10.). But he
Bible mentions. This is the reason why the makes two important statements:
Mediaeval civilization, extrapolating from (a) The spiritual sense only holds fo r the
the Hellenistic Physiologus or Pliny's Natu­ facts told by the Scriptures. Only in the
ra/is historia, elaborated its own encyclope­ course of the sacred history has God acted
dical repertories, bestiaries, herbaries, lapi­ upon mundane events so as to make them
daries, imagines mundi, in order to assign a signify something else. There is no spiritual
symbolic meaning to every piece of the furni­ sense in profane history, nor in the individ­
ture of the real world (cf. Art. 57 and 58). uals and facts of the natural world. There is
In these encyclopedias the same object or no mystical meaning in what happened after
creature can assume contrasting meanings, the Redemption. Human history is a se­
but the work of the mediaeval commentators quence of facts and not of signs (Quad/. VII,
was to provide rules for a correct textual 6, 16).
disambiguation. Symbols were ambiguous The universal allegorism is thus liquidated.
within the paradigm, never within the syn­ Mundane events are restituted to their natu­
tagm. An elephant, a unicorn, a jewel, a rality. If they are meaningful, then only in the
stone, a flower can assume many meanings eyes of the philosopher who sees them as nat­
but when they show up in a given context ural proofs of the existence of God, not as
there is only one possible way of decoding symbolic messages. With Aquinas one wit­
them correctly. nesses a sort of secularization of the post-bib­ ·.�l
Thus the rise of a scriptural hermeneutics lical history and of the natural world.
encouraged the growth of a universal sym­ (b) If there is a spiritual sense in the Holy
bolism and the real world became as much Scriptures, where facts mean something else,
'perfused with signs' as the Holy Scriptures; there is no spiritual sense in profane poetry.
but in both cases one should more rigorously Poetry displays only its literal sense. The po­
speak of scriptural and universal allegorism. etical second sense is a subspecies of the li­
The Middle Ages could not understand the teral one, and Aquinas calls it "parabolic".
antinomy outlined by Goethe. This sense (the one of tropes and allegories)
"non supergreditur modum litteralem" ("does
3.5. The Thomistic reaction not transcend the literal mode") (Quodl. VII,
This the universal allegorism did, however, 6, 16). It is simply a variety of the literal
implement a sort of hallucinatory experience sense. When the Scriptures represent Christ
of the world according to which mundane using the image of a goat one is not facing a
creatures and historical facts did not count as case of allegoria in factis but of simple alle­
'these' creatures and 'these' facts, but insofar goria in 11erbis. In this case, "goat" is not a
as they \Vere standing for something else. fact that symbolizes future events but only a
J4. History and historiography 741

word that parabolically (literally) stands for is taking a way of reading the Bible as an
the name "Christ" (Summa Th., I, I, 10 ad 3). example of how to read his own mundane
This statement seems undoubtedly too poem!
crude and radical; however, in order to The most obvious solution according to
understand this point, one must understand some interpreters, is that the letter had to be
what Aquinas meant by "literal sense". He a forgery. This was indeed the case. but the
meant the sense "quem auctor intendit". The forgery had been taken as authentic from the
literal sense is not only the meaning of a sen­ beginning, which means that it did not sound
tence, but also the meaning of its utterance. repugnant to the ears of Dante's contempo­
Clearly for Aquinas sentence meaning and raries. Moreover, the Convll'io is certainly not
utterance meaning belong both to the literal a forgery and in this treatise Dante provides
sense, since they represent what the utterer of clues for interpreting allegorically his own
the sentence had in his mind. Thus the sense poems - even though maintaining a distincw
conveyed by tropes and allegories, insofar as tion between the allegory of poets and the
it represents exactly what the author wanted allegory of theologians, which the "Epistula
to say, can be easily reduced to the literal XIII" disregards.
sense. In the Convivio Dante explains what he in­
The spiritual senses of the Scriptures are tentionally meant in writing his poems (the
not equally literal because the biblical au­ allegorical sense of his poems is still a para­
thors were unaware of conveying through bolic one because it represents Dante's in­
their historical report the senses that (in the tended meaning). As against that, the exam­
mind of God) facts should assume for the fu­ ples he gives in the letter make one think of
ture reader able to read, in the Old Testa­ blatant cases of a//egoria in factis. Further­
ment, the forecast of the New. The authors of more, we know that Dante had always read
the scriptures wrote under divine inspiration, the facts told by mythology and the works of
ignorant of what they were really saying. classical poets as if they were a//egoriae in
It does not seem that Aquinas' proposal factis. In such terms he speaks of the poets
was very influential, however. A first disqui­ in De vulgari e/oquentia, and in the Comedy
eting instance of it is given by the theory of it is said that Statius is "as the one who pro­
allegorical reading put forth by Dante in the ceeds in the night and bears a light, not for
"Epistula XIII" of his Divina Comedia. himself but for those who follow him" (Pur­
gatory XXII, 67-69). This means that Stat­
3.6. Dante ius was conceived by Dante as a seer: his po­
When presenting his poem to Cangrande etry, and pagan poetry in general, conveyed
della Scala, Dante makes immediately clear spiritual senses of which the authors were
that it has to be read as a "polisemos" ('poly­ not aware.
semic') message. One of the most celebrated Thus for Dante poets are continuing the
examples of what Dante means by polysemy work of the Holy Scriptures, and his poem is
is given in his analysis of some verses of a new instance of prophetical writing. His
Psalm 113, In exitu Israel de Aegypto. Fol­ poem is endowed with spiritual senses in the
lowing the mediaeval theory, Dante says con­ same way in which the Scriptures were, and
cerning the first verse of the Psalm: "If we the poet is divinely inspired. If the poet writes
look at the letter it means the exodus of the what love inspires in him, his text can be sub­
sons of Israel from Egypt at the time of Mo­ mitted to the same allegorical reading as the
ses; if we look at the a!legory, it means our Holy Scriptures, and the poet is right in invit­
redemption through Christ; if we look at the ing his reader to guess what is hidden ··.1·otto
moral sense it means the conversion of the ii velame delli versi strani" ("'under the veil of
soul from the misery of sin to the state of the strange verses").
grace; if we look at the mystical sense it Thus, just at the moment when Aquinas
means the departure of the sanctified spirit devaluates the poetical mode, poets, escaping
from the servitude of this corruption to the from his intellectual influence, start a new
freedom of the eternal glory." mystical approach to the poetic text, opening
Apparently there is nothing, in this analy­ a new way of reading that, through various
sis, which contradicts the main lines of the avatars, will survive until our times (cf.
scriptural tradition. But many interpreters Art. 33 § 1.3.J.
sensed something uncanny. Here Dante (who What makes Dante remain mediaeval is
is usually supposed to be a faithful ThomistJ the fact that he still believes that a poem has
742 V. Geschichtsschreibung der Se, ·
n10 �

no infinite or indefinite meanings; Dante Renaissance and permeated Romantic h)


seems to maintain that there are four spiri­ los?phy and man� contemporary theorie� �.
. _
tual meanings, and that they can be encoded art1st1c mterpretatwn, are:
and decoded according to encyclopedical
a rejection of the metric measure, and a� -'
conventions.
opposition of the quantitative to the quat'!}
3.7. Renaissance Hcrmetism itative, as well as the belief that nothing it_
A relevant epistemological break (cf. Art. 35 stable and that every element of the uni�- J
verse a.cts over any other through re cipro� :;
§ I .) was to take place during the Renais­ i--;,
cal actwn;
sance. The heraldic world of bestiaries and
a rejection of causalism so that the rccip- -_
lapidaries had not fully lost its appeal. The
rocal action of the various elements of the
natural sciences were on the verge of becom­
universe does not follow the linea r se­
ing more and more mathematically oriented; quence of cause and effect .but rather �
Aristotle seemed not to have anything more
sort of spiral-like logics of mutually sym.
to say, but the new philosophers begin ex­
ploring a new symbolical forest where living
pathetic clements (if the universe is a net� t
work of similitudes and cosmic sympaM '.�
columns whisper, in Baudelarian terms, con­
thies, there are no longer privileged
fused but fascinating words, coming from a
causa1 chains);
Platonism revisited under the influence of the
a rejection of dualism, so that the very
Kabba/ah and of the Corpus Hermeticum. In
identity principle collapses, as well as the
this new philosophical milieu the very idea of
one of the excluded middle, and tertium
symbol underwent a profound change (cf.
Art. 61).
datur;
a rejection of agnosticism (Hermetic
In order to conceive of a symbol as some­
thought is 'gnostic', in the sense that it reM
thing that sends one back to a mysterious re­
spects the whole of traditional wisdom so
ality that cannot be conceptually expressed
that even where there is contradiction be�
since it is self-contradictory, one needs a 1very
tween different assumptions, each of them
strong' neoMPlatonism. The mediaeval neoM
can bear part of the truth, truth being the
Platonism was not strong enough, because it
whole of a field of contrasting ideas).
was moderated by a strong idea of the divine
transcendence. On the contrary the original The Hermetic tradition is based on the
neo-Platonism, at least until Proclus, and its principle of similitude: sicut superius sic infeM
gnostic versions, is 'strong' because it holds rius ('as above, so below'). And once one has
that at the top of the Great Fall of Beings decided to fish for similitudes, one can find
there is a One who is not only unknowable them everywhere: under a certain description,
and obscure but who, being independent of everything· can be seen as similar to everyM
any determination, can contain all of them thing else.
and is consequently the place of all contra­ Renaissance symbols were thus inexhaustM
dictions. ible (like the old ones, and unlike the mediae­
If we merge these three lines of influence, val allegories), full of half glimpsed mean­
namely, (i) the neo-Platonic doctrine of ema­ ings, self-contradictory. They were so fraught
nation (where there is a continuity between with meanings that one could never say what
every element of the world and the original they definitely mean. Such a vagueness was
One), (ii) the idea that this One is self-contra­ so constitutive of their nature that, according
dictory and that in it one can find coinciM to traditional Hermetic principles, in order to
dent/a oppositorum, and (iii) the idea that the preserve their unrevealed secret they had to
One can only be expressed by negation and borrow from exotic cultures. since an exotic
approximation (so that every possible repreM image or sentence, insofar as it looks unfa­
sentation of It cannot help but refer back to miliar, stil! keeps an aura, a mona. If a so­
another representation, equally obscure and called symbol became univocally interpret­
contradictory), then we meet the requireM able, it had lost its pmver. So the Renaissance
ments for the development of a philosophy, Magus re-discovered the leroglyphica of
of an aesthetics, and of a secret science of Horapollus (see Boas 1950) or the Chaldaic
symbols as intuitive revelations that can be Oracles and worshipped everything written
neither verbalized nor conceptualized. or spelled in Hebrew.
The main features of the so-called Her­ Thus a new symbolism grew up in the Her­
metic tradition, which spread out from the metic atmosphere, from Pico dclla Mirandola
oriography
34. History and hist
743

. from Reuch­ tano's Von der mannigf'achen Bedeutung des


, , and Ficino to Giordano Bruno, Seienden nach Aristote/es (1862). Semioticians
lin and Robert Fludd up to French Symbol­
ism, Yeats and many contemporar y theories. will find many clues (concerning sixteen cen­
Speaking of_ the uns_haped, symbols cannot turies of Western and Arab cultural history)
have a definite meanmg. in the seminal History of Magic and Experi­
At the very moment in which theology, mental Science by Thorndike ( I 923-58). In
with Thomas Aquinas, was destroying the order to understand at least half of the semi­
bases of universal symbolism and allegorism, otic problems that haunted the Mediaeval
and the new science began to speak of the mind, three historiographical works may
world in quantitative terms, a new feeling was prove useful: De Bruyne's Etudes d'Esthe­
born among poets, Platonic philosophers,'reli­ tique Medievale (1946), De Lubac's Exegese
gious thinkers, magicians and Kabbalists. Medievale (1959) and Bochenski's Forma/e
The new symbolism meant a new quest for Logik (1956, parts 1-3). None of these three
analogy and universal kinship that influenced studies deals explicitly with semiotics.
the new theories or the new practices of po­ To understand many fundamental semiotic
etry and art, as well as new theories of myth. aspects of Jewish Kabbalism, one should
It definitely provided a new religion for many start with Scholem's Kabba/ah (1974) as well
laymen who, in a secularized world, no as with all the other works of this author.
longer believed in the symbols of theology This list could be continued ad libitum.
and needed some other form of worship (cf. One could say that the same holds for the
Art. 62 § 5. and Art. 63). history of philosophy, of literature, of art.
Naturally, no discipline is straightforwardly
separated from the rest of culture and every
4. Secondary sources thinker in every domain receives innumerable
and imponderable influences from every­
This overview of the concepts of symbol and where. A history of philosophy must take
allegory aimed at being a mere example of into account scientific sources, and a history
the incompatibility of theories which at first of literature must take into account the fact
glance make use of the same terms. that many Romantic novelists were influ­
At the same time this example shows at enced by Lavater.
least two other things: (i) a historical recon­ However in our case it is not only a ques­
struction of semiotic concepts is not only an tion of documenting remote influences. The
erudite contribution to archives for histori­ secondary sources mentioned above do not
ans, but is one of the ways to clarify many of document lines of thought that in some way
our present theoretical puzzles; (ii) in order influenced semiotic writers. They deal with
to understand what happened to the concept genuine semiotic problems, sometimes explic­
of symbol between the Middle Ages and Re­ itly recognized as such, sometimes implicit,
naissance one is obliged to take into account, disguised, repressed, concealed. They are do­
among other things, philosophical and ing what a still non-existent historiography
theoretical texts, pieces of scriptural inter­ of semiotics did not do.
pretations, and reflection of poets on their Since they are doing it marginally, and
own work. in an incomplete way, they remain only
A historical reconstruction of semiotics 'sources' for the future historians of semi­
must be an interdisciplinary enterprise which otics. But they can tell them many things that
requires the identification of many primary present-day semiotic theories have forgotten
sources that escape the competence of a sin­ or are still searching for.
gle scholar. This means that the complete
identification of the primary sources must be
mediated by a comprehensive survey of sec­ 5. Conclusion
ondary sources, that is, many historical
works in various disciplinary fields. It is probably too early to expect a complete
It ought to be stressed that many second­ and coherent historiographical monument in
ary sources relating to non-semiotic disci­ our field, since a complete history of semio­
plines are more revealing than the few exist­ tics cannot be undertaken by a single author.
ing semiotic sources. But the above remarks can he read as guide­
One of the best introductions to the rela­ lines for a collective work in progress, a col­
tionship between language and Being is Bren- lection of documents, a still uneven map of a
744 V. Geschichtsschrcibung der Semiotik

still largely unknown land (cl'. Chapter VI­ Dante Alighcri ( 1956 ff), Opere di Dante ( Aligheri).
X!, Art. 36-99 of this Handbook). Ed. Vittore Branca, Francesco Maggini and Bruno
We should not expect this work to be de­ Nardi. - Vol. 4 and 5: ConviJ,io. Vol. 6: De vufgari
finitive, because the field will u ndoubtedly e!aquentia. Florence.
change under the pressure of new historical Dante Aligheri ( 1977), The Divine Comedy. Italian
discoveries: the historical survey modifying and English. Translated, with commentary, by
the present status of semiotics, this latter will Charles S. Singleton. 6 parts in 3 vols. Princeton
in turn intluence the future of the former. NJ.
De Bruyne, Edgar ( l 946), Eludes d'Esthhique
MMil!rale. Brugge.
6. Selected references De Lubac, Henri {1959), Exc;gi::se Medii:vale. Les
quatre sens de l'Ccriture. 4 parts in 2 vols. Paris.[===
6.1. Sources Theologie. 59]
Andreae, Johann Valentin (1614f), Fama Fraterni­ Edlow, R. B. (1977), Galen on Language and Am·
tatis R. C 2nd edition 1614. - Confessio Fraterni­ biguity. An English translation of Galen's "De cap·
tatis. 1615. - Both works are included in: Johann tionibus (On Fallacies)" with Introduction, Text
Valentin Andreae (I972-1973): Werkausgabe in and Commentary. Leiden.
drei Biinden. Ed. and introduced by Richard von Gadamer, Hans.Georg (1960), Wahrlieit und Me·
Diilmen. Stuttgart. thode. GnmdzUge einer philosophischen Hermeneu�
Aristotle (1965-1970), Historia animalium. In tik. Ti.ibingen.
three volumes. With an English translation by Galen (1821-1833), Opera omnia. 20 vols. Ed.
A. L. Peck. Vol. I 1965. Vol. II 1970. London: C. G. Ki.ihn. Leipzig. Reprint Hildesheim 1964-
Heinemann, and Cambridge MA: Harvard Univer· 1965.
sity Press 1965-70. [� The Loeb Classical Library] Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von (1809-1832), Ma­
(The Historia animalium, m:pi �©cov io"top{a, is a ximen und Rejlexionen. In: J. W. von Goethe, Ge·
medieval collection of zoological writings; most of denkausgabe der Werke, Briefe und Gespriiche. 27
them are by Aristotle but there are also some which vols. Zurich and Stuttgart 1948-71.
are nowadays considered to be of other origin.)
Hippokrates (1923-1931), Hippocrates. 4 vols. Ed.
Aristotle (1967), Rhetorica. Ed. L. Cooper. New W. H. S. Jones and E. T. Withington, with an Eng­
York. lish translation. London.
Aquinas, cf. Thomas Aquinas. Hjelmslev, Louis (1943), Omkring sprogteoriens
Augustine (1841-I864), Opera omnia. In vols. grundlaeggelse. Copenhagen. English by F. J.
32-47 of Patrologiae cur.ms completus. Series I: Whitfield: Prolegomena to a Theory of Language.
Ecclesia latina. Ed. by J. P. Migne. Paris. Madison 1961.
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb (1750-1758), Husserl, Edmund (1890), "Zur Logik der Zeichen
Aesthetica. 2 vols. Frankfurt a. M. Reprint Hildes· (Semiotik)". Published in: Husserliana. Vol. 12.
heim 1961. The Hague 1970: 340-373.
Boas, George (1950), The Hieroglyphics of Hora· Husserl, Edmund (1900-1901), Logische Unter­
po!lo, Translated. New York. suchungen. - Vol. I: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik.
Halle 1900. 2nd ed. 1913. - Vol. II: Unter­
Bochenski, Joseph I. M. (1956), Formate Logik. suchungen zur Phiinomenologie und Theorie der Er·
Freiburg and Munich[= Orbis Academicus. III.2.] kennrnis. I. Tei!. Halle 1901. 2nd ed. 1913. 2. Tei!
- English translation: History of Formal Logic. Ed. (Elemente einer phiinomenologischen Aujkliirung der
and translated by Iva Thomas. Notre Dame 1961. Erkenntnis). Halle 1901. 2nd ed. Halle 1921. -
Bosanquet, Bernard (1892), A History of Aesthet· Engl. translation: Logical Investigations. 2 vols.
ics. 2nd edition 1904. London. Reprint New York London and New York 1970.
1966. Kant, Immanuel (1790), Critik der Urtheilskrajf.
Brentano, Franz {1862), Von der mannigfachen Be· Berlin and Ubau. 2nd edition Berlin 1793. 3rd edi·
deurung des Seienden nach Aristoteles. Freiburg. tion Berlin 1799. - Kritik der Urteilskraft. 7th edi·
Reprint Hildesheim. New York and Darmstadt tion. Hamburg 1990.
1962. Lavater, Johann Caspar (1834-1838), Siimmt!iche
Werke. 6 vols. Augsburg and Lindau.
Cassirer, Ernst ( 1923-1929), Philosophie der
symbolischen Formen. 3 vols. Berlin. Morris, Charles W. (1938), "Foundations of the
Theory of Signs". In: Otto Neurath (ed.), lnterna·
Cornificius (1969), Rherorica ad C. Herennium. Ed. tional Encyclopedia of Un{/ied Science, vol. 1,
G. Calboli. Bologna. no. 2. Chicago.
Croce, Benedetto (1902). Estetica come scienza def. Nock, Arthur D. and Andre J. Festugiere
/'espressione e lb1K11istica genera!e. Teoria e storia. (1945-1954), Corpus Hermeticum. 4 vols. Paris.
Milano. 2nd edition 1962.
Semiotik
Semiotics
Ein Handbuch zu den zeichentheoretischen
Grundlagen von Natur und Kultur
A Handbook on the Sign-Theoretic
Foundations of Nature and Culture
.�rr:.:-��:..;·"<.';=-A�
Herausgegeben von / Edited by
Roland Posner, Klaus Robering, Thom ;{j ,,,. k
/fA.)r11101 J,; r!f.'
3. Teilband / Volume 3 -'i1.:>1ro1u:,1
= 4
lffllll?H·,ilf
lJ
l/l"'-!'lfi
AT

Walter de Gruyter · Berlin · New York


2003

You might also like