You are on page 1of 41

The Concept of the Self

Socrates’s
Plato’s
Aquinas’s and neuroscientists today, medieval thinkers were
just as curious about why the mind is so intimately
“Who am I?” If Google’s autocomplete is any familiar, and yet so inaccessible, to itself.  (In fact,
indication, it’s not one of the questions we long before Freud, medieval Latin and Islamic
commonly ask online (unlike other existential thinkers were speculating about a subconscious,
questions like “What is the meaning of life?” or inaccessible realm in the mind.)  The more we study
“What is a human?”). But philosophers have long the medieval period, the clearer it becomes that
held that “Who am I?” is in some way the central inquiry into the self does not start with Descartes’ “I
question of human life. “Know yourself” was the think, therefore I am.”  Rather, Descartes was
inscription that the ancient Greeks inscribed over taking sides in a debate about self-knowledge that
the threshold to the Delphic temple of Apollo, the had already begun in the thirteenth century and
god of wisdom. In fact, self-knowledge is the earlier.
gateway to wisdom, as Socrates quipped: “The wise For Aquinas, we don’t encounter ourselves as
person is the one who knows what he doesn’t isolated minds or selves, but rather always as agents
know.” interacting with our environment.
The reality is, we all lack self-knowledge to some Aquinas begins his theory of self-knowledge from
degree, and the pursuit of self-knowledge is a the claim that all our self-knowledge is dependent
lifelong quest—often a painful one. For instance, a on our experience of the world around us.  He
common phenomenon studied in psychology is the rejects a view that was popular at the time, i.e., that
“loss of a sense of self” that occurs when a familiar the mind is “always on,” never sleeping,
way of thinking about oneself (for example, as “a subconsciously self-aware in the background. 
healthy person,” “someone who earns a good Instead, Aquinas argues, our awareness of ourselves
wage,” “a parent”) is suddenly stripped away by a is triggered and shaped by our experiences
major life change or tragedy.  Forced to face oneself of objects in our environment.   He pictures the
for the first time without these protective labels, one mind as as a sort of undetermined mental “putty”
can feel as though the ground has been suddenly cut that takes shape when it is activated in knowing
out from under one’s feet: Who am I, really? something.  By itself, the mind is dark and formless;
But the reality of self-ignorance is something of a but in the moment of acting, it is “lit up” to itself
philosophical puzzle.  Why do we need to work at from the inside and sees itself engaged in that act. 
gaining knowledge about ourselves?  In other cases, In other words, when I long for a cup of mid-
ignorance results from a lack of experience.  No afternoon coffee, I’m not just aware of the coffee,
surprise that I confuse kangaroos with wallabies: but of myself as the one wanting it.  So for Aquinas,
I’ve never seen either in real life.  Of course I don’t we don’t encounter ourselves as isolated minds or
know what number you’re thinking about: I can’t selves, but rather always as agents interacting with
see inside your mind.  But what excuse do I have our environment.  That’s why the labels we apply to
for being ignorant of anything having to do with ourselves—“a gardener,” “a patient person,” or “a
myself?  I already am myself!  I, and I alone, can coffee-lover”—are always taken from what we do
experience my own mind from the inside.  This or feel or think toward other things.
insider knowledge makes me—as communications
specialists are constantly reminding us—the But if we “see” ourselves from the inside at the
unchallenged authority on “what I feel” or “what I moment of acting, what about the “problem of self-
think.”  So why is it a lifelong project for me  to opacity” mentioned above?  Instead of lacking self-
gain insight into my own  thoughts, habits, impulses, knowledge, shouldn’t we be able to “see”
reasons for acting, or the nature of the mind itself? everything about ourselves clearly?  Aquinas’s
This is called the “problem of self-opacity,” and answer is that just because we experience
we’re not the only ones to puzzle over it: It was also something doesn’t mean we instantly understand
of great interest to the medieval thinker Thomas everything about it—or to use his terminology:
Aquinas (1225-1274), whose theory of self- experiencing that something exists doesn’t tell
knowledge is documented in my new book Aquinas us what it is. (By comparison: If someday I
on Human Self-Knowledge.  It’s a common encounter a wallaby, that won’t make me an expert
scholarly myth that early modern philosophers about wallabies.)  Learning about a thing’s nature
(starting with Descartes) invented the idea of the requires a long process of gathering evidence and
human being as a “self” or “subject.”  My book tries drawing conclusions, and even then we may never
to dispel that myth, showing that like philosophers fully understand it.  The same applies to the mind.  I
am absolutely certain, with an insider’s perspective
that no one else can have, of the reality of my
experience of wanting another cup of coffee.  But
the significance of those experiences—what they
are, what they tell me about myself and the nature
of the mind—requires further experience and
reasoning.  Am I hooked on caffeine?  What is a
“desire” and why do we have desires?  These
questions can only be answered by reasoning about
the evidence taken from many experiences.
Aquinas, then, would surely approve that we’re not
drawn to search online for answers to the question,
“Who am I?”  That question can only be answered
“from the inside” by me, the one asking the
question.  At the same time, answering this question
isn’t a matter of withdrawing from the world and
turning in on ourselves.  It’s a matter of becoming
more aware of ourselves at the moment of engaging
with reality, and drawing conclusions about what
our activities towards other things “say” about us. 
There’s Aquinas’s “prescription” for a deeper sense
of self.

Rene Descartes’s
David Hume’s prove. Hume allows that we can still use
induction, like causation, to function on a daily
The Uncertainty of Causation basis as long as we recognize the limitations of
Hume observes that while we may perceive our knowledge.
two events that seem to occur in conjunction,
there is no way for us to know the nature of Religious Morality Versus Moral Utility
their connection. Based on this observation, Hume proposes the idea that moral principles
Hume argues against the very concept of are rooted in their utility, or usefulness, rather
causation, or cause and effect. We often than in God’s will. His version of this theory is
assume that one thing causes another, but it is unique. Unlike his Utilitarian successors, such
just as possible that one thing does not cause as John Stuart Mill, Hume did not think that
the other. Hume claims that causation is a moral truths could be arrived at scientifically,
habit of association, a belief that is unfounded as if we could add together units of utility and
and meaningless. Still, he notes that when we compare the relative utility of various actions.
repeatedly observe one event following Instead, Hume was a moral sentimentalist who
another, our assumption that we are witnessing believed that moral principles cannot be
cause and effect seems logical to us. Hume intellectually justified as scientific solutions to
holds that we have an instinctive belief in social problems. Hume argues that some
causality, rooted in our own biological habits, principles simply appeal to us and others do
and that we can neither prove nor discount this not. Moral principles appeal to us because they
belief. However, if we accept our limitations, promote our interests and those of our fellow
we can still function without abandoning our human beings, with whom we naturally
assumptions about cause and effect. Religion sympathize. In other words, humans are
suggests that the world operates on cause and biologically inclined to approve and support
effect and that there must therefore be a First whatever helps society, since we all live in a
Cause, namely God. In Hume’s worldview, community and stand to benefit. Hume used
causation is assumed but ultimately this simple but controversial insight to explain
unknowable. We do not know there is a First how we evaluate a wide array of phenomena,
Cause, or a place for God. from social institutions and government policies
to character traits and individual behavior.
The Problem of Induction
Induction is the practice of drawing general
conclusions based on particular experiences. The Division of Reason and Morality
Although this method is essential to empiricism Hume denies that reason plays a determining
and the scientific method, there is always role in motivating or discouraging behavior.
something inherently uncertain about it, Instead, he believes that the determining factor
because we may acquire new data that are in human behavior is passion. As proof, he
different and that disprove our previous asks us to evaluate human actions according
conclusions. Essentially, the principle of to the criterion of “instrumentalism”—that is,
induction teaches us that we can predict the whether an action serves the agent’s purpose.
future based on what has happened in the Generally, we see that they do not and that
past, which we cannot. Hume argues that in human beings tend to act out of some other
the absence of real knowledge of the nature of motivation than their best interest. Based on
the connection between events, we cannot these arguments, Hume concludes that reason
adequately justify inductive assumptions. alone cannot motivate anyone to act. Rather,
Hume suggests two possible justifications and reason helps us arrive at judgments, but our
rejects them both. The first justification is own desires motivate us to act on or ignore
functional: It is only logical that the future must those judgments. Therefore, reason does not
resemble the past. Hume pointed out that we form the basis of morality—it plays the role of
can just as easily imagine a world of chaos, so an advisor rather than that of a decision-maker.
logic cannot guarantee our inductions. The Likewise, immorality is immoral not because it
second justification is that we can assume that violates reason but because it is displeasing to
something will continue to happen because it us. This argument angered English clergy and
has always happened before. To Hume, this other religious philosophers who believed that
kind of reasoning is circular and lacks a God gave humans reason to use as a tool to
foundation in reason. Despite the efforts of discover and understand moral principles. By
John Stuart Mill and others, some might argue removing reason from its throne, Hume denied
that the problem of induction has never been God’s role as the source of morality.
adequately resolved. Hume left the discussion
with the opinion that we have an instinctual Finding God in an Orderly Universe
belief in induction, rooted in our own biological Hume argues that an orderly universe does not
habits, that we cannot shake and yet cannot necessarily prove the existence of God. Those
who hold the opposing view claim that God is
the creator of the universe and the source of
the order and purpose we observe in it, which
resemble the order and purpose we ourselves
create. Therefore, God, as creator of the
universe, must possess intelligence similar,
though superior, to ours. Hume explains that
for this argument to hold up, it must be true
that order and purpose appear only as a direct
result of design. He points out that we can
observe order in many mindless processes,
such as generation and vegetation. Hume
further argues that even if we accept that the
universe has a design, we cannot know
anything about the designer. God could be
morally ambiguous, unintelligent, or even
mortal. The design argument does not prove
the existence of God in the way we conceive
him: all-knowing, all-powerful, and entirely
beneficent. The existence of evil, Hume holds,
proves that if God exists, God cannot fit these
criteria. The presence of evil suggests God is
either all-powerful but not completely good or
he is well-meaning but unable to destroy evil,
and so not all-powerful.

The Bundle Theory of the Self


Hume asks us to consider what impression gives us
our concept of self. We tend to think of ourselves as
selves—stable entities that exist over time. But no
matter how closely we examine our own
experiences, we never observe anything beyond a
series of transient feelings, sensations, and
impressions. We cannot observe ourselves, or what
we are, in a unified way. There is no impression of
the “self” that ties our particular impressions
together. In other words, we can never be directly
aware of ourselves, only of what we are
experiencing at any given moment. Although the
relations between our ideas, feelings, and so on,
may be traced through time by memory, there is no
real evidence of any core that connects them. This
argument also applies to the concept of the soul.
Hume suggests that the self is just a bundle of
perceptions, like links in a chain. To look for a
unifying self beyond those perceptions is like
looking for a chain apart from the links that
constitute it. Hume argues that our concept of the
self is a result of our natural habit of attributing
unified existence to any collection of associated
parts. This belief is natural, but there is no logical
support for it.
Immanuel Kant’s
Gilbert Ryle’s Second, and importantly, Ryle is not a philosophical
behaviourist—at least he does not subscribe to any
Gilbert Ryle of the main tenets associated with that doctrine as it
is known today. One may be confused by this if one
First published Tue Dec 18, 2007; substantive is also confused about Ryle's conception of
revision Wed Feb 4, 2015 philosophy. Although there is some truth in
identifying him as an analytic philosopher—he
Although Gilbert Ryle published on a wide range of announces (1932, 61) that “the sole and whole
topics in philosophy (notably in the history of function of philosophy” is philosophical analysis—
philosophy and in philosophy of language), this is likely to be misunderstood today if one thinks
including a series of lectures centred on that the proper goal of philosophy (attainable if not
philosophical dilemmas, a series of articles on the in practice at least in ideals) is definitional analysis.
concept of thinking, and a book on Plato, The It is this that encourages the association with
Concept of Mind remains his best known and most behaviourism (in at least one of its many senses).
important work. Through this work, Ryle is thought But Ryle was not an analytical philosopher in this
to have accomplished two major tasks. First, he was sense. True, Ryle acknowledges the influence of
seen to have put the final nail in the coffin of Moore's emphasis on common sense (and thus on
Cartesian dualism. Second, as he himself ordinary language); true, he takes himself to be
anticipated, he is thought to have argued on behalf pursuing the type of philosophical investigation
of, and suggested as dualism's replacement, the (exemplified by Russell's Theory of Descriptions)
doctrine known as philosophical (and that involves uncovering the logical form of
sometimes analytical) behaviourism. Sometimes grammatically misleading expressions. But it is
known as an “ordinary language”, sometimes as an important to take account of the differences that
“analytic” philosopher, Ryle—even when separate Ryle from the early Moore and Russell for
mentioned in the same breath as Wittgenstein and it is their conception of philosophy that has been
his followers—is considered to be on a different, inherited by many of us working within the
somewhat idiosyncratic (and difficult to “analytic” tradition in philosophy today. That is the
characterise), philosophical track. third point. For Ryle does not believe
in meanings (concepts or propositions) as these
Philosophical behaviourism has long been rejected;
have been traditionally construed (as stable objects
what was worth keeping has been appropriated by
or rules, the grasp of which is logically prior to, and
the philosophical doctrine of functionalism, which
thus may be used to explain, the use of
is the most widely accepted view in philosophy of
expressions). Indeed, Ryle's conception of
mind today. It is a view that is thought to have
philosophy was not fundamentally different from
saved the “reality” of the mental from the
that of Wittgenstein. Ryle sets out in print as early
“eliminativist” or “fictionalist” tendencies of
as 1932 a philosophical agenda that prefigures the
behaviourism while acknowledging the insight
published work of the later Wittgenstein; the
(often attributed to Ryle) that the mental is
“elasticity of significance” and “inflections of
importantly related to behavioural output or
meaning” Ryle finds in most expressions appear to
response (as well as to stimulus or input).
be the family of structures, more or less related,
According to a reasonably charitable assessment,
noticed by Wittgenstein; and Ryle's attack on the
the best of Ryle's lessons has long been assimilated
“intellectualist legend” shares Wittgenstein's
while the problematic has been discarded. If there
concern to understand a proper—non-exalted—
are considerations still brewing from the 1930s and
place for rules in an explanation of various
40s that would threaten the orthodoxy in
philosophically interesting achievements. In spite of
contemporary philosophy of mind, these lie
the fact that some of Wittgenstein's protégés were
somewhere in work of Wittgenstein and his
dismissive of Ryle's work,[1] the best way to
followers—not in Ryle.
understand Ryle is to see him, if not as following in
But the view just outlined, though widespread, Wittgenstein's footsteps, then as walking some
represents a fundamental misapprehension of Ryle's stretches of philosophical terrain down a parallel
work. First, Cartesianism is dead in only one of its path.
ontological aspects: substance dualism may well
have been repudiated but property dualism still
claims a number of contemporary defenders. The
problem of finding a place for the mental in the 1. Biography
physical world, of accommodating the causal power
of the mental, and of accounting for the phenomenal Gilbert Ryle was born in Brighton, Sussex, England
aspects of consciousness are all live problems in the on 19 August 1900. One of ten children, he came
philosophy of mind today because they share some from a prosperous family and enjoyed a liberal and
of the doctrine's ontological, epistemological, and stimulating childhood and adolescence. His father
semantic assumptions. was a general practitioner but had keen interests in
philosophy and astronomy that he passed on to his
children and an impressive library where Ryle phenomena” (1971b, vii). Although the turn away
enjoyed being an “omnivorous reader” (Ryle, 1970, from psychologism was laudable, philosophers
1). Educated at Brighton College (where later in life succumbed instead to what Ryle considered to be a
he would return as a governor) Ryle went to regrettable temptation to look for Objects which
Queen's College, Oxford in 1919 initially to study were neither mental nor material. Such objects were
Classics, but he was quickly drawn to Philosophy, to be for philosophy what beetles and butterflies are
graduating in 1924 with first-class honours in the for entomology:
new Modern Greats School of Philosophy, Politics
and Economics. While not particularly sporting, his Platonic Forms, Propositions, Intentional Objects,
undergraduate studies were relieved by rowing for Logical Objects…[and even] Sense Data were
his college eight, of which he was captain, and he recruited to appease our professional hankerings
was good enough to have trials for the University to have a subject matter of our own (1971b, vii).
boat. After his graduation in 1924 he was appointed
to a lectureship in Philosophy at Christ Church Ryle's campaign against the tendency of
College and a year later became tutor. He would philosophers to “hypostasise their own terms of art”
remain at Oxford for his entire academic career lasted throughout his career. Even his very first
until his retirement in 1968; in 1945 he was elected articles carried the “Occamizing” message that
to the Waynflete Chair of Metaphysical Philosophy. “[p]hilosophical problems are problems of a certain
With the outbreak of war Ryle volunteered. He was sort; they are not problems of an ordinary sort about
commissioned in the Welsh Guards, serving in special entities” (1971b, vii; these early articles
intelligence, and by the end of the War had been include 1929, 1930, 1933a, and 1933b).
promoted to the rank of Major. He became the
Editor of Mind after G.E. Moore's retirement in Instead, think of a philosopher, by analogy, as a
1947; a post he held until 1971. Ryle was unstinting cartographer. According to Ryle, competent
in his advice and encouragement to generations of speakers of language are to a philosopher what an
students. With colleagues he was “tolerant (and) ordinary villager is to a mapmaker. A local villager
uncensorious” (Warnock, xiv), but in philosophical knows his way by wont and without reflection to
debate he could turn into a formidable opponent, the village church, to the town hall, to the shops and
expressing an intense dislike of pomposity, pretence back home again from the personal point of view of
and jargon (Urmson, 271; Gallop, 228). He was also one who lives there. But, asked to draw or to
ever ready to challenge both the excessive consult a map of his village, he is faced with
veneration paid by others to Plato and Classical learning a new and different sort of task: one that
authors as well as the philosophical positions held employs compass bearing and units of
by such contemporary colleagues as Collingwood in measurement. What was first understood in the
Oxford or Anderson in Australia. He befriended personal terms of local snapshots now has to be
Wittgenstein whose work, if not his effect on considered in the completely general terms of the
colleagues and students, he greatly admired. cartographer. The villager's knowledge by wont,
“Outstandingly friendly (and) sociable” (Warnock, enabling him to lead a stranger from place to place,
xiv), he is remembered as an entertaining is a different skill from one requiring him to tell the
conversationalist. Despite having turned away from stranger, in perfectly general and neutral terms, how
literary studies during his first year at Oxford, to get to any of the places, or indeed, how to
sensing he had little aptitude for them, and even understand these places in relation to those of other
though he read little other than the novels of Jane villages (1962a, 441).
Austen (about whom he wrote authoritatively) and We are like the villager with respect to our
P. G. Wodehouse, the style of Ryle's writing is employment of words and phrases. Knowledge by
often literary and instantly recognizable even after a wont of the use of expressions and of concrete ideas
few sentences (Urmson, 271; Mabbott, 223). A is something everybody learns in the course of
confirmed bachelor, he lived after his retirement growing up speaking and understanding a language:
with his twin sister Mary in the Oxfordshire village “their ‘logical geography’ is taught by one's daily
of Islip. Gardening and walking gave him immense walks” (1945, 207). So too do people know how to
pleasure, as did his pipe. He died on 6 October 1976 operate with ordinary, non-technical, and even
at Whitby in Yorkshire after a day's walking on the semi-technical and technical expressions as well as
moors. “Philosophy irradiated his whole life” with relatively concrete and some abstract ideas
(Mabbott, 224). He is reputed to have said that the without being able to codify the rules, permissions,
only completed portrait of him made him look like a or sanctions that govern their operations.
“drowned German General” (Mabbott, 224).
Now, almost every word or phrase we use
2. Philosophy as Cartography contributes to what we say in a way such that had it
When Ryle became a young don in the 1920s, been replaced by a word or phrase with a different
philosophers could no longer “pretend that significance, it would have had different
philosophy differed from physics, chemistry and “implication threads”:
biology by studying mental as opposed to material
It would have been a different statement, different convictions, an answer to the question how this
in having different implications, in requiring could be, belongs to philosophy.
different tests for truth or falsehood, in being We have now to operate upon what we ordinarily
compatible and incompatible with different operate readily and unquestioningly with. We now
affiliated statements, in being evidence for or need the theory of our daily practice, the
against different corollaries, and so on. (1962a, geography of our daily walks. When two or twenty
442-3) familiar implication threads seem to pull across and
against one another, it is no longer enough to be
To the extent that I understand what I am saying, I
understand the particular differences that the able unperplexedly to follow along each one by
expression contributes to the statements, questions, itself. We need to be able to state their directions,
commands, etc. that I make with it. In making their limits and their interlockings; to think
everyday (non-philosophical) statements, or in systematically about what normally we merely
asking ordinary factual questions, or in giving
think competently with. (1962a, 444)
concrete, practical advice I am like, Ryle says, the
villager who simply walks to his destination without
3. Systematic Ambiguity and Type Trespasses
having to think about what he is doing or turning
back in his tracks. But even in making everyday, Ryle's concern in much of his work was not simply
non-philosophical statements, I employ a plurality the charting of the logical bearings of ideas. It was
of expressions. The implication threads of some of rather to apply this method as a way of testing (and
these expressions may “pull against” the implication often destroying) philosophical theories themselves.
threads of others. For example, When we put on our philosophical hats and begin to
operate not only upon concrete ideas, but abstract
…I might truly and intelligibly describe a weary ideas or abstractions, we tend to get into trouble.
sailor in a storm as having toiled voluntarily, Not only is it the case that every word or phrase we
although reluctantly; and then I find myself in a use contributes to what we say in a way such that
perplexity. For I seem to be saying that he toiled had it been replaced by a word or phrase with a
different significance, it would have had different
not under compulsion but because he volunteered
implication threads; had we used the same word or
to do it, despite the fact that he did not want to do phrase in a different context what we would have
it. The natural implication threads of ‘voluntarily’ said is also likely to have had a different
seem to pull away from the natural implication significance with different implication threads.
threads of ‘reluctantly’. (1962a, 443) A given word will, in different sorts of context,
express ideas of an indefinite range of differing
To resolve this complexity it is not enough that I be
familiar with the separate contributions of the two logical types and, therefore, with different logical
adverbs. To resolve it, I need to be satisfied that the powers. And what is true of single words is also
conflict is only apparent. I am confronted with a true of complex expressions and of grammatical
conceptual problem that requires that I be able constructions. (1945, 206)
to say how the implication threads of the one bear
on the implication threads of the other. This Thus, even if we were to put aside ambiguity of the
requires abstracting from or ignoring the particular kind that logicians ignore (Ryle calls such
reference to this sailor or that storm; it requires that expressions “pun words”), we are faced with
I operate upon general notions of actions, motive, another sort of elasticity of significance which
preference, strength of desires, choice and so on. characterizes the use, according to Ryle, “not of a
The most philosophically interesting questions arise few but of most or of all expressions…”(1945, 205).
for those cases of conflict that present themselves Unlike ambiguous words such as ‘bank’ or ‘report’
again and again. We speak in the same breath of a or ‘stud’, the inflections of meaning to which most
responsible human agent who is, and acts, in a of our expressions are susceptible nonetheless have
world that is a field of physical, chemical, and affinities: the ideas expressed by these expressions
biological causes and effects. “Men must, we feel, in their various uses are “intimately connected”
be free; yet they must, we feel, be amenable to with each other; they are “different inflections of
prediction and explanation. Their actions cannot be the same root” (1945, 206). The paraphrases and
mechanical. Yet also they cannot be unmechanical” translations of these expressions will normally have
(1962a, 444). From the point of view of laymen and “a precisely similar” flexibility. This means that if
scientists who are actually exploring the world, we we were to paraphrase the expression as it is used in
find out what there is by perceiving it; yet from the one context in order to make clear its implication
point of view of the inquirer into the mechanism of threads in that context, we can expect the
perception, what we perceive never coincides with paraphrase, like the original expression, to express a
the world (1954, 2). The reconciliation of these different idea in a different context. To use a
contemporary idiom, the paraphrase, like the The meaning of an expression is not an entity
original expression, is “context-sensitive”. denoted by it and not the nominee of any thing. It
would be a related mistake to suppose, Ryle tells us,
The philosophical task Ryle recommends involves
that a particular concept is precisely indicated by a
tracing the inflections of significance that are
particular expression: as if the idea of equality could
conveyed by expressions with a common root in
be identified as that for which the word ‘equality’
their various uses. On this way of looking at it, it is
stands (1945, 206). For Ryle, agreeing here with
not wrong to say that the philosopher studies or
Wittgenstein, “concepts are not things that are there
investigates the idea or the concept of, say, justice.
crystallised in a splendid isolation”; rather
But putting it this way may be misleading if it
obscures the fact that the logical force of the they are discriminable features, but not detachable
relevant words (‘is just’) may change with the atoms, of what is integrally said or integrally
context in which it is used. Again, Ryle thought this
thought. They are not detachable parts of, but
to be so for most single words and complex
expressions and not only the ambiguous “pun- distinguishable contributions to, the unitary senses
words”. Indeed, “[u]nnoticed systematic of complete sentences. To examine them is to
ambiguities are a common source of type- examine the live force of things that we actually
confusions and philosophic problems” (1945, 207). say. It is to examine them not in retirement, but
Systematic ambiguity affects not only single words doing their co-operative work. (1962b, 185) [3]
and complex expressions. It affects grammatical
constructions as well. Since expressions of the same The idea that expressions have meaning insofar as
grammatical constructions function to express they stand for things should be rejected. Indeed,
thoughts of multifarious logical sorts, those starting some expressions denote (in one of a variety of
to philosophise (those operating upon ideas and not ways) because they are significant. To learn the
merely with them) “tend to be blind to the fact that meaning of an expression is to learn to operate
different ideas have different logical powers…” correctly with it; more like learning a piece of drill
(1945, 200). Assimilation of the functions or uses than like coming across a previously unencountered
can lead to trouble, and this can be shown by object (1957, 365).
eliciting contradictions, absurdities, and paradoxes.
Concepts are instead to be understood as that which
The inevitable consequence is that naïve is conveyed by a word or phrase independently of
intellectual operations with those ideas lead the language (English or French) in which the word
is written or spoken. Although we tend to make use
directly to logically intolerable results. Concepts of
of abstract nouns to talk about that which is
different types cannot be coerced into similar conveyed by various words, this should not mislead
logical conduct. Some sort of contradiction arises us. Russell and Moore may have described their
from the attempt and this, in fortunate cases, pursuits as the investigation of supra-mundane
compels the thinker to turn back in his tracks and entities, but this was not, claims Ryle, the way they
or any other philosopher set about their task.
try to change his treatment of the outraged Aristotle, for example, when studying Plato's
concept. (1945, 201)[2] account of Pleasure, did not “stare hard” at an entity
or Essence designated by this abstract noun:
4. Concepts, Propositions, and Meaning “Instead he rightly considered what we are asserting
The implications of this view for the concept of or denying in concreto when we say that someone
meaning or for nominalisations of the verb ‘to did or did not enjoy the concert; or that someone
mean’ are important. We are not at all likely to be enjoys this piece of music more than that piece”
misled by expressions of the form ‘x means (1962b, 185). Unlike the abstract noun “Pleasure”,
what y means.’ But when we use the expression the live verb is making specific contributions to
quasi-descriptively, as in ‘The meaning of x is the sense. Similarly, an analysis of the concept, say,
same as the meaning of y’ or ‘The meaning of x is of existence “cannot consist just in acts of
doubtful’ we are liable to be misled into thinking contemplating a rarefied object, withdrawn, like a
that we are referring to some queer new object. Ryle coin in a museum, from its native commercial
generalises the point to suggest that all the mistaken transactions” (1962b, 185).
doctrines of concepts, ideas, terms, judgment, 5. Ordinary Language
contents, and the like derive from the fallacy
Ryle is often described as an ordinary language
that there must be something referred to by such philosopher or as recommending that philosophy
expressions as ‘the meaning of the word (phrase or should concern itself with the ordinary use of
sentence) x’ [which is analogous to the policeman] language. In a certain sense this is apt; in another it
who is referred to by the descriptive phrase ‘Our is not.
village policeman is fond of football’. (1932, 56) Philosophers may well study the stock use of
various expressions. But these may be highly
technical or semi-technical expressions, as well as dream” the conviction that the investigation can be
vernacular ones. Berkeley, for example, in regularised in such a way as to replace what was
examining the stock (and possibly the only) use of philosophically puzzling by logical problems
‘infinitesimals’, was examining the way in which amenable to known and teachable procedures of
this word was employed by mathematicians. calculation. Indeed, he denies not only that the logic
Philosophers of law, biology, mathematics, formal of everyday statements but even the logic of the
logic, theology, psychological and grammar are all statements of scientists, lawyers, historians and
required to examine technical terms or concepts. So bridge-players can in principle be adequately
if ‘ordinary’ is contrasted with ‘technical’ or represented by the formulae of formal logic.
‘specialised’ then some philosophy is and some
Of course, he concedes, the logical behaviour of the
philosophy is not concerned with ordinary language
terms of non-notational discourse may be assisted
(1953, 304).
by studies in formal logic; so may chess-playing
But one reason it may be true that philosophy assist generals. But waging a campaign can no more
should be couched in vernacular terms has to do be replaced by playing games of chess than the
with philosophy's special task. Just as the study of the logical behaviour of the terms of non-
cartographer was required to use a different, more notational discourse can be replaced by doing
general vocabulary to plot the geography of the formal logic. Thus in the slogan ‘Back to ordinary
local village, so too should the philosopher use a language’, ‘ordinary’ may be contrasted with
more general vocabulary than the specialist's to plot ‘notional’. The slogan can then be used by those
the “cross-bearings” between the concepts of who have awoken from the formaliser's dream. So
different theories. The tangles and knots that a used, he says, it should be repudiated only by those
philosopher has to unpick are set not by some who hope to replace philosophising by reckoning
branch of specialist theory, but “in the thought and (1953, 316-7).
the discourse of everyone, specialists and non-
specialists alike” (1953, 304). 6. The Official Doctrine and its contemporary
offshoots
Talk about the use of an expression, like the use of
safety-pins and table-knives, helps us to avoid Ryle's writings on the question of what constitutes a
thinking that we are talking about any queer philosophical problem, and of the way to solve it,
relations or queer entities; to suppose or half- occupied him in the 1920s and 30s. The Concept of
suppose that “studying the meaning of the phrase Mind was written after this “long spell of
‘the solar system’ [is]… the same thing as studying methodological talk”: what was needed was “an
the solar system” (1953, 306). It reminds us, for example of the method really working” (1970, 12).
example, that when enquiring into the problems of Although entitled The Concept of Mind, the book,
perception or in discussing the concepts of seeing, Ryle tells us, is
hearing, and smelling, we are not tackling the an examination of multifarious specific mental
questions of opticians, neuro-physiologists or concepts, such as those of knowing, learning,
psychologists. We are rather after accounts of how
certain words work, “namely words like ‘see’, discovering, imagining, pretending, hoping,
‘look’, ‘overlook’, ‘blind’, ‘visualise’, and lots of wanting, feeling depressed, feeling a pain,
other affiliated expressions” (1953, 317). resolving, doing voluntarily, doing deliberately,
A philosopher of Ryle's ilk is interested in the perceiving, remembering and so on. (1962b, 188)
informal logic of the employment of expressions;
the nature of the logical force that expressions have As the analogy of philosophy with cartography
as components of theories and as pivots of concrete suggests, Ryle investigates the workings not just of
arguments. That is why, he says, in our discussions one concept by itself, but “all of the threads of a
we argue with expressions and about those spider's web of inter-working concepts” (1962b,
expressions in one and the same breath. We are 189).
trying to register what we are exhibiting; to codify The book focuses on the “type-errors” or “category
the very logical codes which we are then and there mistakes” which philosophers of mind are prone to
observing (1953, 318). make when they consider the logical form of
Often the appeal to what we do and do not say, or “mental conduct verbs”, especially if they use as
can or cannot say is resisted, Ryle says, by those their starting-point the “Janus-faced account of
who hold that philosophical disputes can be settled human life” suggested by a Cartesian conception of
by formalising the warring theses, or translating the mind.
them out of the natural language in which they were Ryle's explicit target in The Concept of Mind is
originally constructed into the notation, perhaps, of what he calls the “Official Doctrine”, which results,
a Principia Mathematica. As we should expect from he tells us, at least in part from Descartes'
a philosopher who sees his job as the plotting of the appreciation that Galilean methods of scientific
logical force of expressions as they appear in discovery were fit to provide mechanical
different contexts, Ryle describes as a “formaliser's explanations for every occupant of space, together
with Descartes' conviction that the mental could not The episodes supposed to constitute the careers of
simply be a more complex variety of the mind have one sort of existence, while those
mechanical. This “two-world”, Cartesian view has
constituting the careers of bodies have another
distinctive ontological, epistemological, and
semantic commitments that each lead to particular sort; and no bridge-status is involved…Minds, as
philosophical puzzles. the whole legend describes them, are what must
exist if there is to be a causal explanation of the
6.1 The ontological commitment
intelligent behaviour of human bodies; and minds,
The ontological commitment of the view is that as the theory describes them, live on a floor of
there are two different kinds of things, body and
mind, that are somehow harnessed together. The existence defined as being outside the causal
one exists in space and is subject to mechanical or system to which bodies belong. (1949a, 65)
physical laws; the other is not in space and is not
subject to these laws. And yet the mind and body It would be difficult to find a better anticipation of
influence each other. The view that mind and body the mind-body problem as we know it today. The
are somehow fundamentally different or distinct, problem of mental causation may not be exactly the
but nonetheless interact, leads to the philosophical same as Descartes' problem, but it is nonetheless
conundrum known as the mind-body problem. For inherited by anyone who insists that mental
contemporary philosophers of mind, the mind-body properties must, on the one hand, make a causal
problem no longer involves construing the mind as difference and by those who, on the other, think that
an independent substance. But working out the physics is a closed causal system. Just as mind-body
relation between mental and interaction was a problem for substance dualism, so
physical properties remains an urgent project (Kim, is mental causation still the problem facing the
2). [4] many varieties of (both reductive and non-
reductive) physicalism (Kim, 29-30).
In contemporary philosophy of mind, Ryle is
credited with having established an important It seems then that the two ontological aspects of the
connection between mental predicates and Official Doctrine—finding a place for the mental in
behaviour; but many of his successors (Place, the physical world and the problem of mental
Armstrong, Putnam, and Fodor) thought he causation—still survive today.
misconstrued the nature of that connection. When 6.2 The epistemological and semantic
strict physicalist positions were beset by objections commitments
from the multiple realisability of mental predicates,
“token-physicalist” versions of functionalism (or The ontological commitments of the Official
“ontic-neutral” versions of the causal theory of Doctrine lead to the mind-body problem; the
mind) stepped up to the plate, and advertised that, in epistemological commitments of the Official
acknowledging behavioural outputs as well as Doctrine lead to the problem of other minds.
stimulus conditions, they were retaining what was According to the traditional view, bodily processes
right about Ryle's emphasis on behaviour (in the are external and can be witnessed by observers, but
circumstances), but rejecting what they considered mental processes are private, “internal” as it is
the “explanatory vacuity” of conceptual or metaphorically described (since mental processes
definitional links between mental predicates and are not supposed to be locatable anywhere). Mental
behavioural ones. These were replaced with causal processes or events are supposed, on the official
links between the alleged referents of the mental view, to be played out in a private theatre; such
terms and the action to be explained. events are known directly by the person who has
them either through the faculty of introspection or
But to suppose the explanatory power of mental the “phosphorescence” of consciousness. The
conduct terms depends on their designating an event subject of the mental states is, on this view,
or state that is causally related to the performance is incorrigible—her avowals of her own mental states
to accept another version of the “paramechanical” cannot be corrected by others—and she is infallible
hypothesis, even though it is now couched in ontic- —she cannot be wrong about which states she is in.
neutral or physicalist terms.[5] [6]
 Others can know them only indirectly through
Although Ryle's own target is the attempt to staple “complex and frail inferences” from what the body
an elusive mental event construed as a conscious does.
“experience” onto a respectable biological But if all that is mental is to be understood in this
(muscular, neurophysiological) causal chain, it is way, it is unclear how we are justified in believing
nevertheless clear that the problems he sees will that others have the requisite episodes or mental
also apply to modern-day variations on the dualist accompaniments. It would be possible, on this view,
theme. That is, it will also apply to weak, non- for others to act as if they are minded, but for them
reductive identity theories that wish to preserve a to have none of the right “conscious experiences”
causal role for mental properties. For consider: accompanying their actions for them to qualify as
such. Perhaps we are in much the same position as
Descartes who thought it made sense to wonder Ryle is often given credit for having shown some of
whether such creatures are automata instead. the many difficulties in substance or Cartesian
dualism. But the arguments in The Concept of
The problem of other minds is compounded by even
Mind warn of difficulties for any account that takes
more serious difficulties given certain assumptions
mental conduct terms to discharge their explanatory
about the way language works. Proponents of the
role by signifying inner processes: whether
Official Doctrine are committed to the view that
irreducibly mental or at bottom physical. Ryle's
mental discourse serves to designate items that
target was not merely the ghostliness of the mental
carry the metaphysical and epistemological load of
processes hypothesized by the Cartesian; it was
that doctrine.
their essential hidden-ness. The thrust of Ryle's
The verbs, nouns and adjectives, with which in polemic is that theories about the nature of the
ordinary life we describe the wits, characters and alleged referents of the mental concepts we employ
in our ordinary everyday commonsense practices
higher-grade performances of the people with
cannot make a mystery of this employment without
whom we have do, are required to be construed as threatening to rob the theories of their subject
signifying special episodes in their secret histories, matter. Our practice of employing such mental
or else as signifying tendencies for such episodes to concepts would be a complete mystery on a view
occur. (1949a, 16-17) that takes the “truth-makers” of our mental
statements to be not only items within an occult (to
Ryle's criticism of the Official Doctrine begins by others) stream of consciousness, but also on a view
pointing out an absurdity in its semantic that takes them to be items within an occult (to most
consequences. If mental conduct verbs pick out of us) series of computations or neurological events.
“occult” causes then we would not be able to apply Both picture the truth-makers of our claims about
those verbs as we do; so something must be wrong other minds or our ascriptions of mental predicates
with a theory of mental phenomena that renders so as hidden and thus in practice (if not in principle) as
inadequate our everyday use of these verbs. For, inaccessible.
according to the Official Doctrine 7. The Intellectualist Legend
when someone is described as knowing, believing To highlight the general difficulties with
or guessing something, as hoping, dreading, Cartesianism is only part of Ryle's destructive
intending or shirking something, as designing this strategy. The other part is to show how logical
absurdities arise with one particular offshoot of the
or being amused at that, these verbs are supposed
Official Doctrine: one he dubs “the intellectualist
to denote the occurrence of specific modifications legend”. This involves the type-error or category
in his (to us) occult stream of consciousness. (1945, mistake of supposing that what distinguishes certain
17) performances from others that are perceptually
similar (in one sense of ‘perceptual’) is the addition
Ryle's criticism of the view is that if it were correct, of some non-perceptual feature. The Official
only privileged access to this stream of Doctrine construes this feature as a special mental
consciousness could provide authentic testimony accompaniment.[7] The intellectualist legend,
that these mental-conduct verbs were correctly or accepting this construal of the Official Doctrine,
incorrectly applied. “The onlooker, be he teacher, says that intelligent or rational behaviour can be
critic, biographer or friend, can never assure himself accommodated or explained by some sort of
that his comments have any vestige of truth.” And theoretical operations involving these hidden
yet, accompaniments. But if this is a mistake, it is a big
one; for it is made not only throughout various sub-
it was just because we do in fact all know how to branches of philosophy but also in collaborating
make such comments, make them with general disciplines. (The idea, for example, that intelligence
correctness and correct them when they turn out involves physically realised, (non-introspectible)
to be confused or mistaken, that philosophers theoretical (computational) operations is one of the
founding blocks of the cognitive sciences.)
found it necessary to construct their theories of the
nature and place of minds. Finding mental-conduct This picture of how rational abilities in general are
concepts being regularly and effectively used, they to be explained, including the ability to speak a
language, was called into question by Ryle in a
properly sought to fix their logical geography. But number of early papers (especially in 1946a,
the account officially recommended would entail ostensibly reworked as the second chapter of 1949a,
that there could be no regular or effective use of and in 1946b and 1950). It was also called into
these mental-conduct concepts in our descriptions question by Wittgenstein in his discussion of rules
(Wittgenstein, §§143-155 and 179-202).
of, and prescriptions for, other people's minds.
(1949a, 17) In broad brush-strokes, Ryle's argument-strategy
against the supposition that generally intelligent or
rational abilities can be explained in terms of prior level as the internal processes that explain (again, in
theoretical operations (involving the apprehension a different sense) vocalisations. But just this type of
of the relevant truths) is to exhibit how the category error seems to be made by those who
supposition leads to logically vicious regresses. construe the relevant mental phenomena, including
Intelligent behaviours cannot be explained, in understanding, as inner causal events.[9]
general, by assuming that theoretical operations
have gone on behind the scene, since those 8. Behaviourism
operations themselves can be intelligent or non- Ryle's view is standardly characterised as a weaker
intelligent. The supposition that intelligent or “softer” version of this doctrine (Smith and
behaviour always requires prior (or even Jones, 144). According to this standard
contemporaneous) theoretical operations launches a interpretation, Ryle's view is that statements
vicious regress of theoretical operations. Thus, it containing mental terms can be translated, without
must be allowed that some intelligent behaviour is loss of meaning, into subjunctive conditionals about
not the outcome of prior theoretical operations. what the individual will do in various
circumstances. So Ryle (on this account) is to be
The role of the rules, standards, or norms that
construed as offering a dispositional analysis of
govern our practices should neither be exaggerated
mental statements into behavioural ones. It is
nor underestimated. For Ryle (as for Wittgenstein),
conceded that Ryle does not confine his
rules are codifications or distillations of normative
descriptions of what the agent will do (under the
practices that are already up and running. As Ryle
circumstances) to purely physical behaviour—in
aptly quips,
terms, say, of skeletal or muscular descriptions—
[t]here were reasoners before Aristotle and but is happy to speak of full-bodied actions like
strategists before Clausewitz. The application of scoring a goal or paying a debt.[10] But the “soft”
behaviourism attributed to Ryle still attempts an
rules of reasoning and strategy did not have to
analysis (or translation) of mental statements into a
await the work of their codifiers. Aristotle and series of dispositional statements which are
Clausewitz were, in fact, only able to extract these themselves construed as subjunctive conditionals
rules, because they were already being applied. describing what the agent will do (albeit under the
(1946b, 233) relevant action description) under various
circumstances. Even this “soft” behaviourism is
The crystallisation of performance-rules in rule- bound to fail, however, since mentalistic vocabulary
formulae is, in some cases, a product of studies in is not analysable or translatable into behavioural
the methodology of the practices in which they have statements even if these are allowed to include
already been applied and not the condition of their descriptions of actions. For the list of conditions
being applied. In other words: there must be a way and possible behaviour will be infinite since any
of applying a rule that does not require the prior one proffered translation can be defeated by slight
consultation of an expression of that rule. alteration of the circumstances; and the defeating
conditions in any particular case may involve a
Close attention to the cases in which we credit reference to facts about the agent's mind, thereby
someone for her performance shows that it is often rendering the analysis circular. In sum, the standard
enough for her (merely) to have satisfied certain interpretation of Ryle construes him as offering a
criteria or for her performance to have lived up to somewhat weakened form of reductive
the relevant standard. Close attention to the cases in behaviourism whose reductivist ambitions, however
which we require not only that she satisfy certain weakened, are nonetheless futile.
criteria but also that she apply the criteria by using
an expression of a rule to guide her shows that the But this characterisation of Ryle's programme is
latter is in fact a separate skill, which we only simply wrong. Although it is true that Ryle was
sometimes (but importantly not always) demand of keen to point out the dispositional nature of many
the one we wish to credit for her performance.[8] mental concepts, it would be wrong to construe him
as offering a programme of analysis of mental
The ability to apply criteria in order to ensure that predicates into a series of subjunctive conditionals.
one's performance is successful is like showing a The relationship between mental predicates and the
ticket in order to ensure one's right to travel by rail “hypothetical” and “semi-hypothetical” sentences
(1950, 239-40). It would be a category mistake to with which we can “unpack” them is other than that
imagine that the ticket itself plays a role in the required by this kind of analysis.
explanation of the train journey on the same level as
the pistons, levers, and tracks. So, too, would it be a It will be helpful to keep in mind that Ryle's target
category mistake to imagine that reasons, for is the Official Doctrine with its attendant
example, play a role in the explanation of action on ontological, epistemological, and semantic
(almost) the same level as the internal processes that commitments. His arguments serve to remind us
explain (in a different sense) the body's motions; or that we have in a large number of cases ways of
that meanings or understandings play a role in the telling or settling disputes, for example, about
explanation of language use on (almost) the same someone's character or intellect. If you dispute my
characterisation of someone as believing or wanting introspection) but also against what is hidden from
something, I will point to what he says and does in the viewpoint of a third-party observer. But, in
defending my particular attribution (as well as to focussing on what is observable, he does not
features of the circumstances). But our practice of commit himself to reducing what is observable
giving reasons of this kind to defend or to challenge itself to sequences of “muscular behaviour”. Those
ascriptions of mental predicates would be put under who attribute to Ryle a “soft” behaviourism are at
substantial pressure if the Official Doctrine were least correct that the reminders he issues to ward off
correct. Cartesianism include frank appeal to what he later
will describe as actions much higher up on the
For Ryle to remind us that we do, as a matter of
“sophistication ladder” like paying a bill, or scoring
fact, have a way of settling disputes about whether
a goal, as well as to what he will later call
someone is vain or whether she is in pain is much
“concrete”, “per se”, or “infra” doings like
weaker than saying that a concept is meaningless
scribbling numbers on a cheque book or kicking a
unless it is verifiable; or even that the successful
ball between two posts.
application of mental predicates requires that we
have a way of settling disputes in all cases. Showing Surely, as his earlier critics pointed out (and as
that a concept is one for which, in a large number of those who see him as a behaviourist ignore) some of
cases, we have agreement-reaching procedures the phenomena he allows will reintroduce a realm
(even if these do not always guarantee success) of private occurrences (dreams and imaginings will
captures an important point, however: it counts be the paradigm case). But as Ayer suspects, this
against any theory, say, of vanity or pain that would sort of “ghost” is an honest ghost. Not simply (as
render it unknowable in principle or in Ayer suggests) because the phenomena do not
practice whether or not the concept is correctly command the stage of a private theatre: in the sense
applied in every case. And this was precisely the that no one else can tell us about them they are in
problem with the Official Doctrine (and is still a that respect private.[12] As Ryle himself admits, “the
problem, as I suggested earlier, with some of its technical trick of conducting our thinking in
contemporary progeny). auditory word-images, instead of spoken words,
does indeed secure secrecy for our thinking…”
Ryle points out in a later essay that there is a form
(1949a, 35).
of dilemma that pits the reductionist against
the duplicationist[11]: those whose battle cry is It is an “honest ghost” since privacy or secrecy of
“Nothing but…” and those who insist on certain episodes will not lead to privacy for them
“Something else as Well…”. Ryle attempts a all; and thus the epistemological concomitant to the
dissolution of these types of dilemma by rejecting Official Doctrine that would lead to the problem of
the two horns; not by taking sides with either one, other minds is not a threat. Nor does this sort of
though part of what dissolution requires in this case, privacy usher in the semantic consequences of the
as in others, is a description of how both sides are to Official Doctrine. The privacy attending our dreams
be commended for seeing what the other side does and imaginings does not impugn our right to draw
not, and criticised for failing to see what the other on observable (in the robust sense of the term)
side does. phenomena to defend our right to employ mental
predicates for a large number of cases, for “this
The attraction of behaviourism, he reminds us, is
secrecy is not the secrecy ascribed to the postulated
simply that it does not insist on occult happenings
episodes of the ghostly shadow-world” (1949a, 35).
as the basis upon which all mental terms are given
meaning, and points to the perfectly observable There will indeed be cases in which only the agent
criteria that are by and large employed when we are can say whether she is pondering, imagining,
called upon to defend or correct our employment of dreaming, letting her mind wander, calculating,
these mental terms. The problem with behaviourism solving, planning, or rehearsing. But the sort of
is that it has a too-narrow view both of what counts privacy in which only she can say whether she was
as behaviour and of what counts as observable. The doing any of these or other particular things is not
attraction of Cartesianism is that it recognizes in a the sort of privacy that gives rise to philosophical
way the behaviourist does not that there may be conundrums like the problem of other minds and the
crucial differences between creatures who—on a problem of necessarily private languages. On the
certain restrictive notion of behaviour—do indeed contrary, the ability to describe one's dreams (as
behave identically. The problem with Cartesianism well as one's sensations) presupposes a language
is that it attempts to account for these differences by whose terms have established and public criteria for
hypothesizing the existence of occult or hidden their correct use.
causes.
9. Dispositions
In an attempt to defeat the Cartesian or Platonist
A constant irritant for Ryle, throughout his writings,
and remind us that mental predicates have perfectly
is “the preposterous assumption that every true or
ordinary standards of application, Ryle focuses on
false statement either asserts or denies that a
what is observable. It is part of his war against what
mentioned object or set of objects possesses a
is not only occult (and observable only through
specified attribute” (1949a, 115).[13] As an example translate highly technical treatises. We expect no
of a kind of sentence whose primary job is other more than that he will ordinarily cope pretty well
than fact-stating, consider laws. Although we speak
with the majority of ordinary French-using and
of law-sentences as true or false, “they do not state
truths or falsehoods of the same type as those French-following tasks. ‘Knows French’ is a vague
asserted by the statements of fact to which they expression and, for most purposes, none the less
apply or are supposed to apply” (1949a, 116-7). The useful for being vague. (1949a, 119)
way to bring out the difference is to note that part of
the point of trying to establish laws is to find out To adopt a couple contemporary turns of phrases,
how to infer from particular matters of fact to other the warrants or inference tickets provided are
particular matters of fact, how to explain particular therefore pro tanto and occasion-sensitive. The
matters of fact by reference to other matters of fact, latter is yet another feature of Ryle's view that puts
and how to bring about or prevent particular states him at a safe distance from ideals of analytical
of affairs. behaviourism.
A law, Ryle tells us, is “an inference ticket (a Ryle concedes that what he says about dispositions
season ticket) which licenses its possessors… to is likely to be contested by the “addicts of the
move from one assertion to another, to provide superstition that all true indicative sentences either
explanations of given facts, and to bring about describe existents or report occurrences” (1949a,
desired states of affairs by manipulating what is 119). How could the statement ‘This wire conducts
found existing or happening” (1949a, 117). electricity’ be true unless there were something now
going on, albeit unfortunately behind the scenes?
A dispositional sentence such as ‘Jones believes the
But consider Ryle's argument against this. Even
earth is round’ is unlike a law-sentence insofar as it
those who are attracted by this picture will have to
mentions an individual, Jones. But it is like a law-
admit that we often do know that a wire conducts
sentence insofar as its role is not (or not primarily)
electricity, that an individual knows French, that a
one of describing or reporting, or stating that some
person is proud, that a sugar cube is soluble,
object has such-and-such an attribute or stands in
without having discovered anything in the
such-and-such a relation with another object. Its
appropriate sense “hidden” (read: accessible via
“truth-maker”, to use a contemporary expression,
introspection or laboratory experiment). In any case
has to be understood in terms of what would satisfy
what would be the point or the theoretical utility of
it as opposed to what it purportedly describes.
[14] discovering what is hidden? Ryle suggests the
 What would satisfy a law is not specified or
utility would consist only in its entitling us to do
mentioned in the law-sentence; similarly, what
just that predicting, explaining, and modifying
would satisfy a disposition is not specified or
which we already do and often know that we are
mentioned in the disposition-sentence. Nor could it
entitled to do. Even if these postulated processes
be. What would satisfy ‘Jones believes the earth is
were conceded, they themselves are hypotheses or
round’ is an open-ended (infinite) list of inferrings,
inferences (to the “best explanation”): things the
imaginings, saying, and doings (etc.) on the part of
existence of which are inferred from the fact that we
Jones (1949a, 44). (And note again, a propos of
can predict, explain, and modify the observable
behaviourism, that if ‘imagining’ is construed in
actions and reactions of individuals. So if a theorist
one of its ordinary senses, as something someone
demands actual “rails” to ground ordinary
may be doing just by sitting, unmoving, with his
inferences, this theorist will have to provide some
hand on his chin, there is explicit reference to an
further “rails” to justify his own peculiar inference
irreducible-to-behaviour mental occurrence in this
(to the best explanation) from the legitimacy of
specification of what would satisfy the sentence as
ordinary inferences to the purported “rails” that he
well as the explicit denial of the finiteness of the
supposes to ground them. “The postulation of such
long list that would unpack the sentence by alluding
an endless hierarchy of ‘rails’ could hardly be
to its satisfaction conditions.)
attractive even to those who are attracted by its first
Ryle suggests that ‘John knows French’ is a warrant step” (1949a, 120).
which gives us the right to infer that John
understands what he reads in Le Monde or that he is 10. Self-knowledge
communicating successfully when telephoning in The editors of a recent volume on self-knowledge
French. Immediately on specifying what we are write:
entitled to do with the inference ticket ‘John knows
French’, Ryle admits that the examples of what Each of us effortlessly knows an enormous amount
would satisfy the sentence are too precise, for about those of our attributes which go with our
rationality, sentience, and affective susceptibilities:
[w]e should not withdraw our statement that he
our beliefs, hopes, desires, and fears, whether we
knows French on finding that he did not respond
have a headache or an itchy toe, whether we are
pertinently when asleep, absentminded, drunk, or
elated or depressed, whom we love and hate, what
in a panic; or on finding that he did not correctly
attracts or repels us. (Wright, et. al., 1)
Whereas knowledge of others' sensations, emotions, dispositional one there is another sense of ‘know’
and intentional states demands reliance on which has to do with what a person is presently
independently articulatable grounds, self-knowledge thinking, feeling or doing. He does not deny the
is, by contrast, characteristically immediate. This existence of mental processes of this kind (again, a
immediacy is already enough to be philosophically reason to resist calling him a ‘behaviourist’); nor
perplexing, but not only do we does he deny that I am the only one in position to
know differently from others what we think, hope, say what, for example, my musings, ponderings, or
and feel, we are also, in normal circumstances, dreams are about. Nor does Ryle deny that usually
regarded as knowing best. Furthermore, if we do when we witness something, or feel something, or
enjoy certain mental attributes, we are expected to act in such-and-such a way we are able, when
know that we do: our mental states are salient to us. asked, to give a correct account of it. He denies,
According to the editors, “[t]hese three features of rather, that either the “luminous” or “refulgent”
the epistemology of self-knowledge— view of consciousness or one that buys into the
immediacy, authority, and salience— combine to intellectualist legend is required to accommodate
set a certain explanatory problem…”. this ability. He acknowledges that the concept of
visualizing, imagining, or “seeing” in the mind's
To what extent does this explanatory puzzle arise
eye, and “hearing” in the mind's ear are useful
because of a tacit allegiance to Cartesianism? We
concepts. He denies that these uses commit us to the
have already seen how the epistemological
existence of pictures or images that we contemplate
consequences of the Official Doctrine lead to the
or tunes that we hear: rather than construe someone
problem of other minds. The other side of the
who pictures his nursery as the spectator of a
Cartesian coin seems to put us in an especially
resemblance of his nursery, he should be construed
privileged position with respect to our own minds.
as resembling a spectator in his nursery (1949a,
For, if ascribing mental predicates to others is
234).
problematic, according to the Official Doctrine,
ascribing them to ourselves is problem-free. Ryle's discussion of avowals introduces, in effect, a
Immediacy, authority, and salience are features of different elasticity in our use of ‘know’, when we
the epistemology of self-knowledge that the say, for example, that usually a person knows what
Cartesian view is best-placed to accommodate. she is on about. This has to do with her propensity
to avow moods, feelings, inclinations, intentions,
Ryle would see this contemporary expression of the
desires, and so forth. One striking feature of
problem of self-knowledge as a result of the
avowals is that they seem to enjoy a special kind of
conflation of various suspect philosophical
security from epistemic assessment or criticism.
tendencies. One of these has its roots in the
“How do you know?” or “I think you must be
epistemological strand of the Official Doctrine;
mistaken” or “You have been careless in your
another is the tendency of philosophers to
observations” do not make sense as rejoinders to
underestimate the many-layered complexity of
avowals. For Ryle,
mental discourse. This includes the refusal to
acknowledge that the same sentence may have [i]f the avowal [“I feel depressed”] is to do its job, it
different “elasticities” or kinds of jobs, as well as must be said in a depressed tone of voice; it must
the tendency to favour sentence-jobs of informing,
be blurted out to a sympathizer, not reported to an
describing or reporting over those, for example, of
explaining, exhorting, encouraging, or admonishing. investigator. Avowing “I feel depressed” is doing
one of the things, namely one of the conversational
For if self-knowledge is to be construed as a sort of
perception of inner states or events that are (by the things, that depression is the mood to do. It is not a
special faculty of introspection or by the piece of scientific premises-finding, but a piece of
“refulgence” of consciousness) “visible” to me but conversational moping. (1949a, 99)
not to others, then Cartesianism, though seeming to
leave knowledge of our own minds intact, instead Ryle warns against construing the fact that avowals
presents an untenable picture of what this are unassailable as indicating that there is special
“knowledge” can be. Sorting out this confusion puts kind of knowledge in play. From the fact that these
what can genuinely be called self-knowledge on utterances are protected from epistemic assessment
relative parity with other-knowledge. It will also or criticism it does not follow that we have a special
leave room for the importance of “unstudied talk”, kind of knowledge about them; any more, says
“ego-pronouncements”, or “avowals”, which do Ryle, than it follows from the fact that someone is
enjoy protection from epistemic criticism. But once not a quack doctor that he is a good doctor: for he
the nature of this protection is understood, may not be a doctor at all (1993b, 216). For with the
philosophical perplexity should be extinguished, not idea of knowledge comes the idea of truth, of
kindled. justification, of representation, of description, of
taking closer looks, etc.
Ryle accepts the sort of privacy or secrecy that
attends our dreams, imaginings and silent The standards for assessing “ego-pronouncements”
soliloquies and he concedes that besides the run along lines of sincerity/insincerity where these
in turn are cashed out in terms of lying, feigning thinking, in which there may be no performances
(for fun), acting (in a play), putting on (for for others to witness. Certainly, the concept of
sympathy), etc. When lying, feigning, etc., are ruled thinking applies to observable performances. But it
out, then someone's saying so may be on some also applies to the many thinking-activities we may
particular occasion what justifies us in accepting or imagine of Rodin's Le Penseur who is merely
what gives us a reason to accept what he says. The sitting on a rock with his chin in his hand. Ryle's
question of his being wrong (as measured against professed long-range objective in much of his later
some additional standard) may not arise. If he is not work was to come to an understanding of the
wrong in saying that he is in pain (because he can various sorts of thinking qua pensive without
only be lying or insincere in the ways that we are committing either the “Category-howler of
imagining have been ruled out) it does not follow Behaviourism or the Category-howler of
that he has a special kind of knowledge. Rather, it Cartesianism” (1979a, 17). In these later articles, he
would be more appropriate to say that questions of suggests that what is needed besides the choice
knowledge are here out of place. The discussion of between “not muscular, therefore inner” or “not
avowals, then, illustrates yet another elasticity or inner, therefore muscular” is a way of enlarging the
sentence-job for certain mental expressions. None domain of the mental so that it includes not only
of this is to deny that “I am in pain”, for example, actions or performances but also certain omissions
may have a use which, on some occasion, counts as or failures to act that are conceived on a relatively
a description. Indeed, it may be both a description high step of the ladder of sophistication of mental
and a complaint (1993a, 214). discourse (1979c, 119).
Many contemporary discussions in philosophy of Like all or at least most philosophically interesting
mind and self-knowledge, accepting a modern concepts, Ryle thought there was no general answer
variant of the assumptions of Cartesianism, are to the question ‘What does thinking consist of?’
committed to the view that in using mental (any more that there is a general answer to the
predicates, we (or the subject) attribute(s) to the question ‘What does working consist of?’).
subject a mental state or condition of which her
subsequent behaviour is a causal, contingent When we start to theorise about thinking, we
manifestation. But once the assumption is made that naturally hanker to follow the chemist's example,
mental verbs function to pick out such underlying namely, to say what thinking consists of and how
states or properties, then seemingly incompatible the ingredients of which it consists are combined….
demands are placed upon these states and the
But modelling thinking on processes like perspiring,
traditional philosophical problem of self-knowledge
is revealed. Construed as speaking from and digesting, counting, and apple-picking, which can
expressing an occurrent state the speaker is be broken down into ingredient processes which
authoritative; construed as speaking from or have been coordinated in a certain way is a
referring to a dispositional state she is not. mistake…. (1951b, 260)
In Ryle's (and in Wittgenstein's) hands, pointing to
the non-descriptive use of an utterance such as “I There is a host of widely different sorts of toiling
intend to go to the store” or “I am bored” is and idlings, engaging in any one of which is
supposed to put to rest the mystery of the avower's thinking.
authority (on those occasions when Ryle rejects the view that thinking is symbol
she is authoritative); it is not supposed to invite the manipulation: indeed, he denies that words, phrases
development of a philosophical account to explain or sentences are symbols, if symbols are to be
it. It constitutes a step not only in rebutting the understood as proxies or as representations for
Cartesian's accommodation of this authority, but something else (perhaps that which the word is
also in denying that there is only one use of the alleged to designate). Thinking, in the sense of
relevant expression—namely, to designate a state, pondering, calculating, and musing, is not reserved
occurrence, or property—in the first place. for the labour of trying to decide things. Nor do we
11. Thinking reserve the title ‘thinking’ for inner processes. An
architect can think out his plan while manipulating
Ryle's express target in The Concept of Mind was toy bricks as can a sculptor plan a statue in marble
the Cartesianism of the Official Doctrine, and the by modelling a piece of plasticine. Additional
ontological, epistemological and semantic labours might be necessary to put these plans into
predicament we would be confronted with if the words. In general, thinking should not be equated
view were correct. Because of this target, many of with using language.
his reminders about how mental expressions are
used point to the kinds of circumstances and Our ordinary ways of describing our ponderings and
performances that would satisfy them: often these musings tend to be graphic and not literal. They
include what others suitably trained have no trouble should be histories, not chronicles, and as such the
seeing. But he was dissatisfied that in this work he plot should be told in abstraction from any
left out some of the cardinal uses of concepts of particular stream-of-consciousness reports of detail
we may recall. In only some cases of thinking the Even if it is true that Le Penseur is saying things to
accomplishment of a task, if there is one, involves himself, this description fails because it stops just
the thinker's being equipped to declare his policy, where it ought to begin. ‘Murmuring syllables’ to
scheme or theory. But there can be thinking where himself is the thinnest possible description of what
there is no talking or even the attempt to talk. he is engaged in. A thick description may be that he
Mozart's thinking results in something playable, not is trying to find out whether or not the things that he
statable; Cezanne may make mistakes but is not in is saying will lead him where he wants to go:
error. A symphony is not composed in English or
German, it has no translation, and there is no …in his pondering, reflecting, deliberating, etc., the
evidence for or against it. Thus, although it is an thinker is not guiding himself anywhere, but trying
important truth that the products of thinking may be to find out whether this or that track of his own
publishable truths or falsehoods (and not making would or would not qualify as a guiding, as
unshareable introspectibles), this is true for only
opposed to a mis-guiding, or non-guiding, track.
some types of thinking (1979b, 85).
(1968, 494)
When the thinking does result in propositions or
sayings, however, the temptation is on the one hand Exploring is on a higher-sophistication level than
toward excessive inflation, and on the other toward piloting; and piloting is on a higher sophistication
excessive deflation. For the result is not merely a level than following a pilot's lead. If Le Penseur is
string of words linked together in a grammatically trying to find the proof of a new theorem then he is
well-formed sentence. In recognising this truth, working on a higher accomplishment-level than he
however, we are tempted toward the view that bits is in trying to teach his student his proof when he
of language are only necessary as the interpersonal has got it; just as trying to teach it is on a higher-
vehicles of objective Meanings that are thinkable, in sophistication level than that on which his students
principle, to any hearers or readers of any are working in trying to master it.
nationalities.
On its thinnest description, Le Penseur may be
These Meanings are for the Duplicationist those muttering to himself a few geometrical words or
significance-cargoes that are carried indifferently phrases, just as on its thinnest description a penny is
a piece of metal. But to say that that is not all he is
by your French and my English internal locutions—
doing (or that that is not all the penny is) is
though the challenge to exhibit to his Reductionist consistent with saying it is the only thing he is
critic even one such cargo, prised off its French or doing or with denying that the penny is a piece of
English vehicle, is as usual unwelcome to him. metal and something else as well.
(1979b, 87) A statesman signing his surname to a peace-treaty
Ryle's solution is to reject the vehicle-cargo model. is doing much more than inscribe the seven letters
In owning a penny, the duplicationist is right in of his surname, but he is not doing many or any
saying I own more than a mere metallic disc; but the more things. He is bringing war to a close by
reductionist is also right in rejecting the idea that I inscribing the seven letters of his surname. (1968,
own two things: a mere disc and a non-metallic,
496)
unpocketable yet marketable cargo. The word I
employ is not a noise and something else as well; Thinking can be saying things to oneself under a
nor is just a noise. In learning a word's meaning, I thin description. Under a thicker description it may
become enabled to conduct with it a host of inter be saying things to oneself with the specific
alia informative, calculative, recording, anagram- heuristic intention of trying to open one's eyes or
solving, and versifying transactions of quite specific consolidate one's grasp. It is this specific,
kinds. Just as a penny is not just a disc and nor is it experimental intention that is obliterated, Ryle tells
a disc and something else as well, so a word is not us, by sweeping generic slogans such as “Thought
just noise, but nor is it a noise and something else as is Language” or “Thinking is Saying Things to
well. The penny is an institutionally-qualified Oneself”, whether or not this is supplemented by
enabling instrument that I can use for specific sorts “…and Something Else as Well.” The adverb
of transactions. The word is a complexly qualified ‘experimentally’ adds not an extra action but the
noise, endowed with a quite specific saying-power, intention-to-find-out-what-happens-when….
endowed by institutional regulations, accumulating Neither the Reductionist nor the Duplicationist (the
public custom, pedagogic disciplines, and so on. Behaviourist or the Cartesian) can account for the
The formulation of the qualifications of both penny adverb ‘experimentally’.
and word would “require not just some simple
auxiliary nouns, simple adjectives or simple verbs They had tried to tell us what pondering is, eluding
but a whole batch of syntactically variegated that little knot of subordinate clauses, such as ‘…in
subordinate clauses” (1979b, 88). order to…’, ‘what happens…’, and ‘…when..’
without which the notion of experimenting cannot
be unpacked; no more than burglary, treaty- rough, smooth, slippery, or sticky some things are
signing, or goal-scoring can deliberately be or whether they are vibrating, stiff, resilient, or
loose.
described in simple adjectives plus simple verbs,
whether mundane or transcendent. What qualifies Pace Berkeley, the difference between these types
an undertaking as one of pondering or, not very of states is not merely a matter of degree: feeling
the warmth of a fire is not like a feeling of pain.
differently, as one of discussing, is not any Feeling the fire is hotter than it was before is a
catalogue of simple qualities and simple relations, matter of perception, discrimination, or finding out
whether rude or refined, but some nexus of a difference. People can be better at it than others:
statable because statement-shaped conditions. doctors acquire the skill of feeling pulses that an
untrained person cannot and race drivers feel a car
(1979b, 82)
going into a skid well before an ordinary motorist
12. Sensation can. Feeling pain, giddy, nauseous, or high, by
contrast are not a matter of perception, an acquired
Ryle was unhappy with the treatment he gave of the skill or that which training can fine-tune. Mistakes
concepts of sensation and perception in The due to carelessness are ruled out when we talk of
Concept of Mind. In both the Foreword and the sensations qua pain or elation; they are not ruled out
Afterword of the chapter entitled “Sensation and when it comes to perception as discrimination or
Observation”, he expresses his dissatisfaction at detection.
having given too much to the opposition by having
“fallen in” with the Official story that perceiving Armed with these two sets of implication threads
involves having sensations. (and in this sense, different understandings of, or
things we count as) sensation or feeling, it can be
In a later paper (1956) Ryle corrects this. The idea seen that perception requires neither of these.
that perceiving involves “having sensations” is Seeing a cat does not require that I feel anything in
called into question with an investigation of the the sense of pain, discomfort, tickle, giddiness, or
ordinary concepts of sensation and feeling and their calm (nor, we can add, relief, amusement, surprise,
relation to the technical notions of sense-impression or rapture). Nor, however, does seeing a cat or
and sense-data. (Arguably, today’s notion of hearing a violin require that I tactually or
“perceptual experiences” – conceptual or non- kinaesthetically feel with my eye or with my ear
conceptual—also figure as a target of Ryle’s that which I also perceive. Nor does smelling
arguments.) In this section, I shall discuss the require that I feel, in this sense, with my nose. And
negative thesis that perception does not require the though the tongue is a double-sense organ insofar as
postulation of sensations construed in its ordinary I can tactually and kinaesthetically detect the
sense and why one motivation for postulating sense- texture and the temperature of food in my mouth, as
data or sense-impressions should be resisted. In the well as taste it, tasting food does not depend upon
next, I discuss a different motivation and show why my being able to feel these other properties of the
the thickness of perceptual concepts thwarts food with my tongue.
attempts to discover the “nature” of perception in
physiological, optical, acoustic, etc. phenomena. So, Ryle says, when philosophers and psychologists
assert that all perceiving involves the having of
Both philosophers and physiologists “pass without sensations or the feeling of something, either they
apology” from saying that without optical or are wrong or they are using a third, different
auditory sense-impressions there is no seeing or understanding of “sensation” or “feeling”.
hearing to saying that seeing and hearing involve
the having of sensations. But can the sense- Let us examine this different sense of “feeling” or
impressions which are supposedly required for “sensation”. It does not seem to derive from
perception be identified with sensations or feelings ordinary use, which, we might suggest, would not in
in one of their non-technical senses? itself be a problem, as long as the implication
threads of one understanding are not crossed with
Ryle suggests not. On one understanding of those of another. Consider the epistemologist’s
“feeling” or “sensation” we include pains, nausea, notion of sense-data or sense-impressions which are
tickles, suffocation, and thirst, which are distressing posited as candidates for grounding knowledge or
in some way. (In the Concept of Mind he notes that certainty in what is supposedly given in perception.
not all “agitations” are disagreeable: “People Suppose this third understanding
voluntarily subject themselves to suspense, fatigue, of sensation or feeling derives from sense-data or
perplexity, fear, and surprise…”(95).) sense-impressions thus understood. Whatever the
A different understanding of “feeling” or merits or demerits of this view, in order for
“sensation” comes with tactual sensations of sensations—now understood as sense-impressions
external objects and kinaesthetic sensations (of or sense-data—to play this foundational role, we
anatomically internal things and events). Instances must be conscious of them. Curiously enough,
of the latter include the feeling of warmth, say, as however, we do not report them. Instead, we report
my hand approaches a fire or feeling how cold, what we see under different descriptions, which
carry different luggage-loads. (Or, as Austin said, therefore to any exploitation of knowledge or
we report what we see under different descriptions beliefs previously acquired. A datum, as it is used
which depend, in part, on how far we are willing to here, is something that we reason from and does not
stick our neck out.) Someone who claimed to see have to be reasoned to.
something green might subsequently, when he
Ryle dismisses this motivation for introducing
learns of the presence of a cat, claim that what he
sensation thus understood on the grounds that not
saw was the eyes of a cat. The “luggage” that Ryle
all thinking is inferring. Multiplying, for example, is
speaks of here includes the logical threads
thinking but our calculations are not conclusions
(including implication and evidence, etc.) that
and our mistakes are not fallacies. If it is not true
accompany certain descriptions rather than others.
that the thinking that enters into perceptual
(There are more ways to be wrong, as Austin says,
recognition, identification, comparison, etc. is
the more we stick our necks out.) We shall come
inferring then the search for its fund of premises is
back to this in the next section. But now we are
the search for nothing.
investigating a third, new sense of “sensation” or
“feeling” which derives, not from ordinary use, but But worse, why suppose that seeing the misprint or
from the (alleged) needs of epistemology. But what seeing a crop of wheat (as opposed to a word, or a
supports the idea that we see have such planted field) is thinking at all? It may be discerned
experiences? in a flash; there may be no moment, however short,
in which one might be described as pondering,
Not the fact that we report appearances, for, as
reflecting, or putting two and two together. All the
Ryle reminds us, we use the locution “it appears
argument has shown so far is that without a
that…” all the time without committing ourselves to
particular training, recognising a misprint or a crop
having any particular experiences. “15 x 16 appears
of wheat would be impossible. Why suppose the
to make 220” or “It looks as if the river is twice the
exploitation of the knowledge resulting from this
size of the road” commit me to no special sense-
training involves thinking qua reflecting, pondering,
experiences. So, argues Ryle, we cannot adduce
or inferring?
idioms of the patterns “It looks as if…” or “It
appears…” as evidence of the untutored, Here the fact that the misprint is immediately
uninferential manner in which the postulated sense- obvious to him is supposed to need to be explained
impressions are delivered to consciousness. But this not just by reference to his prior education, but also
leaves us with a problem. by the postulation of the performance by him of a
piece of thinking, with the queer property of not
We have, in fact, no special way of reporting the
requiring any time for its performance. (1956, 345)
occurrence of these postulated impressions; we are,
therefore, without the needed marks of our being According to Ryle, seeing a misprint involves the
conscious of such things at all. For there is surely possession of the exploitation of knowledge already
something absurd in maintaining that we are acquired. But this exploitation of knowledge
constantly conscious of some things in the way in required for perceptual recognition, identification,
which we are conscious of pains, and yet have no etc. need not embody any thinking; a fortiori, it
way of telling ourselves or other people anything need not embody inferential thinking. “So the
whatsoever about them. (1956, 343) argument for the occurrence of sense-impressions to
be the data or premises for the inferential thinking
This particular theoretical allegiance that drives
embodied is doubly broken-backed” (1956, 345).
some epistemologists to posit sensations understood
in the technical sense of sense-data has as its source Readers interested in Ryle's thoughts about
the idea that there are two kinds of space, which we perception and imagination are referred to the
know today, thanks to Sellars, as the space of following supplementary documents:
reason and the space of natural law. In the first, the
notion of inference, evidence, premises, evidence, Copyright © 2015 by
and conclusions have their home; in the other is the Julia Tanney <drjuliatanney@gmail.com>
raw “data” understood in the sense of that which is
given or accepted without argument.
The allegiance to this picture has its source in the
view that all thinking intended to result in the
discovery or establishment of truths is inferring. A
child sees a word on a page, an adult sees a
misprint, and an illiterate sees a black mark. Each
has eyes in perfect working order. According to this
view, the difference between seeing black marks, a
word, or a misprint has to do with the reasoning we
bring to what is perceptually given. And sense-data
(or, we may add, perceptual experience) play the
role of what is given prior to any thinking, and prior
Maurice Merleau-Ponty on the one hand, and empiricism or realism, on the
other, by critiquing their common presupposition of
First published Wed Sep 14, 2016
a ready-made world and failure to account for the
Maurice Jean Jacques Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961), historical and embodied character of experience. In
French philosopher and public intellectual, was the his later writings, Merleau-Ponty becomes
leading academic proponent of existentialism and increasingly critical of the intellectualist tendencies
phenomenology in post-war France. Best known for of the phenomenological method as well, although
his original and influential work on embodiment, with the intention of reforming rather than
perception, and ontology, he also made important abandoning it. The posthumous writings collected
contributions to the philosophy of art, history, in The Visible and the Invisible aim to clarify the
language, nature, and politics. Associated in his ontological implications of a phenomenology that
early years with the existentialist movement through would self-critically account for its own limitations.
his friendship with Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de This leads him to propose concepts such as “flesh”
Beauvoir, Merleau-Ponty played a central role in and “chiasm” that many consider to be his most
the dissemination of phenomenology, which he fruitful philosophical contributions.
sought to integrate with Gestalt psychology, Merleau-Ponty’s thought has continued to inspire
psychoanalysis, Marxism, and Saussurian contemporary research beyond the usual intellectual
linguistics. Major influences on his thinking include history and interpretive scholarship, especially in
Henri Bergson, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, the areas of feminist philosophy, philosophy of
Max Scheler, and Jean-Paul Sartre, as well as mind and cognitive science, environmental
neurologist Kurt Goldstein, Gestalt theorists such as philosophy and philosophy of nature, political
Wolfgang Köhler and Kurt Koffka, and literary philosophy, philosophy of art, philosophy of
figures including Marcel Proust, Paul Claudel, and language, and phenomenological ontology. His
Paul Valéry. In turn, he influenced the post- work has also been widely influential on researchers
structuralist generation of French thinkers who outside the discipline of philosophy proper,
succeeded him, including Michel Foucault, Gilles especially in anthropology, architecture, the arts,
Deleuze, and Jacques Derrida, whose similarities cognitive science, environmental theory, film
with and debt to the later Merleau-Ponty have often studies, linguistics, literature, and political theory.
been underestimated. Merleau-Ponty published two
major theoretical texts during his lifetime: The
Structure of Behavior (1942 SC)
and Phenomenology of Perception (1945 PP). Other
important publications include two volumes of 1. Life and Works
political philosophy, Humanism and Terror (1947 Merleau-Ponty was born in Rochefort-sur-Mer, in
HT) and Adventures of the Dialectic (1955 AdD), as the province of Charente-Maritime, on March 14,
well as two books of collected essays on art, 1908.[1] After the death in 1913 of his father, a
philosophy, and politics: Sense and Non- colonial artillery captain and a knight of the Legion
Sense ([1948]1996b/1964) and Signs (1960/1964). of Honor, he moved with his family to Paris. He
Two unfinished manuscripts appeared would later describe his childhood as incomparably
posthumously: The Prose of the World (1969/1973), happy, and he remained very close to his mother
drafted in 1950–51; and The Visible and the until her death in 1953. Merleau-Ponty pursued
Invisible (1964 V&I), on which he was working at secondary studies at the Parisian lycees Janson-de-
the time of his death. Lecture notes and student Sailly and Louis-le-Grand, completing his first
transcriptions of many of his courses at the course in philosophy at Janson-de-Sailly with
Sorbonne and the Collège de France have also been Gustave Rodrigues in 1923–24. He won the
published. school’s “Award for Outstanding Achievement” in
philosophy that year and would later trace his
For most of his career, Merleau-Ponty focused on
commitment to the vocation of philosophy to this
the problems of perception and embodiment as a
first course. He was also awarded “First Prize in
starting point for clarifying the relation between the
Philosophy” at Louis-le-Grand in 1924–25. He
mind and the body, the objective world and the
attended the École Normale Supérieure from 1926
experienced world, expression in language and art,
to 1930, where he befriended Simone de Beauvoir
history, politics, and nature. Although
and Claude Lévi-Straus. Some evidence suggests
phenomenology provided the overarching
that, during these years, Merleau-Ponty authored a
framework for these investigations, Merleau-Ponty
novel, Nord. Récit de l’arctique, under the
also drew freely on empirical research in
pseudonym Jacques Heller (Alloa 2013b). His
psychology and ethology, anthropology,
professors at ENS included Léon Brunschvicg and
psychoanalysis, linguistics, and the arts. His
Émile Bréhier, the latter supervising his research on
constant points of historical reference are Descartes,
Plotinus for the Diplôme d’études supérieures in
Kant, Hegel, and Marx. The characteristic approach
1929. Bréhier would continue to supervise Merleau-
of Merleau-Ponty’s theoretical work is his effort to
Ponty’s research through the completion of his two
identify an alternative to intellectualism or idealism,
doctoral dissertations in 1945. During his student
years, Merleau-Ponty attended Husserl’s 1929 Condorcet in Paris, replacing Sartre during the
Sorbonne lectures and Georges Gurvitch’s 1928– latter’s leave from this position. Merleau-Ponty
1930 courses on German philosophy. He received defended his two dissertations in July 1945,
the agrégation in philosophy in 1930, ranking in fulfilling the requirements for the Docteur ès lettres,
second place. which was awarded “with distinction”. In October
1945, Les Temps Modernes published its inaugural
After a year of mandatory military service,
issue; Merleau-Ponty was a founding member of the
Merleau-Ponty taught at the lycee in Beauvais from
journal’s governing board, managed its daily affairs,
1931 to 1933, pursued a year of research on
and penned many of its editorials that were signed
perception funded by a subvention from the Caisse
simply “T.M.”, even though he refused to allow his
nationale des sciences (the precursor of today’s
name to be printed on the cover alongside Sartre’s
Centre national de la recherche scientifique) in
as the review’s Director. That fall, Merleau-Ponty
1933–34, and taught at the lycee in Chartres in
was appointed to the post of Maître de
1934–35. From 1935 to 1940, he was a tutor
conférences in Psychology at the University of
(agégé-répétiteur) at the École Normale Supérieure,
Lyon, where he was promoted to the rank of
where his primary duty was to prepare students for
Professor in the Chair of Psychology in 1948. From
the agrégation. During this period, he attended
1947 to 1949, he also taught supplementary courses
Alexandre Kojève’s lectures on Hegel and Aron
at the École Normale Supérieure, where his students
Gurwitsch’s lectures on Gestalt psychology. His
included the young Michel Foucault. Student notes
first publications also appeared during these years,
(taken by Jean Deprun) from Merleau-Ponty’s
as a series of review essays on Max
1947–48 course on “The Union of the Soul and the
Scheler’s Ressentiment (1935), Gabriel
Body in Malebranche, Biran, and Bergson”—a
Marcel’s Being and Having (1936), and
course that he taught at both Lyon and E.N.S. to
Sartre’s Imagination (1936).[2] In 1938, he
prepare students for the agrégation and which was
completed his thèse complémentaire, originally
attended by Foucault—were published in 1968
titled Conscience et comportement [Consciousness
(1997b/2001).
and Behavior] and published in 1942 as La
structure du comportement [The Structure of In 1947, Merleau-Ponty participated regularly in the
Behavior, SC]. He was the first outside visitor to the Collège philosophique, an association formed by
newly established Husserl Archives in Louvain, Jean Wahl to provide an open venue for intellectual
Belgium, in April 1939, where he met Eugen Fink exchange without the academic formality of the
and consulted Husserl’s unpublished manuscripts, Sorbonne, and frequented by many leading Parisian
including Ideen II and later sections of Die Krisis. thinkers. Merleau-Ponty published his first book of
political philosophy in 1947, Humanisme et terreur,
With the outbreak of World War Two, Merleau-
essai sur le problème communiste [Humanism and
Ponty served for a year as lieutenant in the
Terror: An Essay on the Communist Problem, 1969,
5th Infantry Regiment and 59th Light Infantry
HT], in which he responded to the developing
Division, until he was wounded in battle in June
opposition between liberal democracies and
1940, days before the signing of the armistice
communism by cautioning a “wait-and-see” attitude
between France and Germany. He was awarded
toward Marxism. A collection of essays concerning
the Croix de guerre, recognizing bravery in combat.
the arts, philosophy, and politics, Sens et non-
After several months of convalescence, he returned
sense [Sense and Non-Sense, 1996b/1964],
to teaching at the Lycée Carnot in Paris, where he
appeared in 1948. In the fall of 1948, Merleau-
remained from 1940 until 1944. In November 1940,
Ponty delivered a series of seven weekly lectures on
he married Suzanne Jolibois, and their daughter
French national radio that were subsequently
Marianne was born in June 1941. In the winter of
published as Causeries 1948 (2002/2004).
1940–41, Merleau-Ponty renewed his acquaintance
with Jean-Paul Sartre, whom he had met as a Merleau-Ponty declined an invitation to join the
student at the École Normale, through their Department of Philosophy at the University of
involvement in the resistance group Socialisme et Chicago as a Visiting Professor in 1948–49, but
Liberté. The group published around ten issues of instead received a leave from Lyon for the year to
an underground review until the arrest of two present a series of lectures at the University of
members in early 1942 led to its dissolution. After Mexico in early 1949. Later in 1949, Merleau-Ponty
the conclusion of the war, in 1945, Merleau-Ponty was appointed Professor of Child Psychology and
would collaborate with Sartre and Beauvoir to Pedagogy at the University of Paris, and in this
found Les Temps Modernes, a journal devoted to position lectured widely on child development,
“littérature engagée”, for which he served as psychoanalysis, phenomenology, Gestalt
political editor until 1952. psychology, and anthropology. His eight courses
from the Sorbonne are known from compiled
At the end of the 1943–44 school year, Merleau-
student notes reviewed by him and published in the
Ponty completed his main thesis, Phénoménologie
Sorbonne’s Bulletin de psychologie (1988/2010).
de la perception [Phenomenology of Perception,
Merleau-Ponty held this position for three years
PP], and in 1944–45 he taught at the Lycée
until his election, in 1952, to the Chair of
Philosophy at the Collège de France, the most October and November of 1957, as his second
prestigious post for a philosopher in France, which commission from Alliance française, he lectured in
he would hold until his death in 1961. At forty-four, Madagascar, Reunion Island, and Mauritius, citing
Merleau-Ponty was the youngest person ever as a primary motivation for accepting the
elected to this position, but his appointment was not commission his desire to see first-hand the effects
without controversy. Rather than following the of reforms in French policies governing overseas
typical procedure of ratifying the vote of the territories. The last book Merleau-Ponty published
General Assembly of Professors, who had selected during his lifetime, Signes [Signs, 1960/1964],
Merleau-Ponty as their lead candidate, appearing in 1960, collecting essays on art,
the Académie des sciences morales et language, the history of philosophy, and politics
politiques made the unprecedented decision to that spanned more than a decade. His last published
remove his name from the list of candidates; essay, “L’Œil et l’esprit” [“Eye and Mind”, 1964a
the Académie’s decision was subsequently OEE] addressing the ontological implications of
overturned by the Minister of Education himself, painting, appeared in the 1961 inaugural issue
who allowed the faculty vote in favor of Merleau- of Art de France. Merleau-Ponty died of a heart
Ponty to stand. Merleau-Ponty’s January 1953 attack in Paris on May 3rd, 1961, at the age of 53,
inaugural lecture at the Collège de France was with Descartes’ Optics open on his desk.
published under the title Éloge de la
Merleau-Ponty’s friend and former student Claude
Philosophie [In Praise of Philosophy, 1953/1963].
Lefort published two of his teacher’s unfinished
Many of his courses from the Collège de France
manuscripts posthumously: La prose du
have subsequently been published, based either on
monde [The Prose of the World, 1969/1973], an
student notes or Merleau-Ponty’s own lecture notes
exploration of literature and expression drafted in
(1964b, 1968/1970, 1995/2003, 1996a, 1998/2002,
1950–51 and apparently abandoned; and Le visible
2003/2010, 2011, 2013).
et l’invisible [The Visible and the Invisible, 1968
In the face of growing political disagreements with V&I], a manuscript and numerous working notes
Sartre set in motion by the Korean War, Merleau- from 1959–1961 that present elements of Merleau-
Ponty resigned his role as political editor of Les Ponty’s mature ontology. The latter manuscript was
Temps Modernes in December of 1952 and apparently part of a larger project, Être et
withdrew from the editorial board altogether in Monde [Being and World], for which two additional
1953. His critique of Sartre’s politics became public unpublished sections were substantially drafted in
in 1955 with Les Aventures de la 1957–1958: La Nature ou le monde du
dialectique [Adventures of the Dialectic, 1973 silence [Nature or the World of Silence]
AdD], in which Merleau-Ponty distanced himself and Introduction à l’ontologie [Introduction to
from revolutionary Marxism and sharply criticized Ontology] (Saint Aubert 2013: 28).[3] These
Sartre for “ultrabolshevism”. Beauvoir’s equally manuscripts, along with many of Merleau-Ponty’s
biting rebuttal, “Merleau-Ponty and Pseudo- other unpublished notes and papers, were donated to
Sartreanism”, published the same year in Les Temps the Bibliothèque Nationale de France by Suzanne
Modernes, accuses Merleau-Ponty of willfully Merleau-Ponty in 1992 and are available for
misrepresenting Sartre’s position, opening a rift consultation by scholars.[4]
between the three former friends that would never
entirely heal. Merleau-Ponty’s intellectual circle 2. The Nature of Perception and The Structure of
during his years at the Collège de France included Behavior
Lévi-Straus and Jacques Lacan, and for several Merleau-Ponty’s lifelong interest in the
years he was a regular contributor to the popular philosophical status of perception is already
weekly magazine L’Express. In October and reflected in his successful 1933 application for a
November 1955, on a commission from Alliance subvention to study the nature of perception, where
française, Merleau-Ponty visited several African he proposes to synthesize recent findings in
countries, including Tunisia, French Equatorial experimental psychology (especially Gestalt
Africa, the Belgian Congo, and Kenya, where he psychology) and neurology to develop an
delivered a series of lectures on the concept of race, alternative to dominant intellectualist accounts of
colonialism, and development. In 1956, he perception inspired by critical (Kantian) philosophy.
published Les Philosophes célèbres [Famous Interestingly, this early proposal emphasizes the
Philosophers], a large edited volume of original significance of the perception of one’s own body for
introductions to key historical and contemporary distinguishing between the “universe of perception”
thinkers (beginning, interestingly, with philosophers and its intellectual reconstructions, and it gestures
from India and China) whose contributors included toward the “realist philosophers of England and
Gilles Deleuze, Gilbert Ryle, Alfred Schutz, and America” (presumably William James and A. N.
Jean Starobinski. In April 1957, Merleau-Ponty Whitehead, as presented in Jean Wahl’s 1932 Vers
declined to accept induction into France’s Order of le concret) for their insights into the irreducibility of
the Legion of Honor, presumably in protest over the the sensory and the concrete to intellectual relations.
inhumane actions of the Fourth Republic, including While this initial proposal makes no mention of
the use of torture, during the Battle of Algiers. In
phenomenology, Merleau-Ponty’s subsequent 1934 the phenomenological concept of “experience” (in
report on the year’s research, noting the limitations explicit contrast with the American school of
of approaching the philosophical study of behaviorism), is a privileged starting point for the
perception through empirical research alone, analysis thanks to its neutrality with respect to
emphasizes the promise of Husserlian classical distinctions between the “mental” and the
phenomenology for providing a distinctively “physiological” (SC: 2/4).
philosophical framework for the investigation of
The Structure of Behavior first critiques traditional
psychology. In particular, Merleau-Ponty mentions
reflex accounts of the relation between stimulus and
the distinction between the natural and
reaction in light of the findings of Kurt Goldstein
transcendental attitudes and the intentionality of
and other contemporary physiologists, arguing that
consciousness as valuable for “revising the very
the organism is not passive but imposes its own
notions of consciousness and sensation” (NP:
conditions between the given stimulus and the
192/78). He also cites approvingly Aron
expected response, so that behavior remains
Gurwitsch’s claim that Husserl’s analyses “lead to
inexplicable in purely anatomical or atomistic
the threshold of Gestaltpsychologie”, the second
terms. Merleau-Ponty instead describes the nervous
area of focus in this early study. The Gestalt is “a
system as a “field of forces” apportioned according
spontaneous organization of the sensory field” in
to “modes of preferred distribution”, a model
which there are “only organizations, more or less
inspired by Wolfgang Köhler’s Gestalt physics (SC:
stable, more or less articulated” (NP: 193/79).
48/46). Both physiology and behavior are “forms”,
Merleau-Ponty’s brief summary of Gestalt
that is,
psychology, anticipating research presented in his
first two books, emphasizes the figure-ground total processes whose properties are not the sum of
structure of perception, the phenomena of depth and those which the isolated parts would possess….
movement, and the syncretic perception of children. [T]here is form wherever the properties of a system
Nevertheless, Merleau-Ponty concludes—again are modified by every change brought about in a
citing Gurwitsch—that the epistemological single one of its parts and, on the contrary, are
framework of Gestalt psychology remains Kantian, conserved when they all change while maintaining
requiring that one look “in a very different the same relationship among themselves. (SC: 49–
direction, for a very different solution” to the 50/47)
problem of the relation between the world described
naturalistically and the world as perceived (NP: Form or structure therefore describes dialectical,
198/82). non-linear, and dynamic relationships that can
function relatively autonomously and are
Merleau-Ponty’s first book, The Structure of irreducible to linear mechanical causality (see
Behavior (SC), resumes the project of synthesizing Thompson 2007).
and reworking the insights of Gestalt theory and
phenomenology to propose an original The critique of physiological atomism is also
understanding of the relationship between extended to theories of higher behavior, such as
“consciousness” and “nature”. Whereas the neo- Pavlov’s theory of conditioned reflexes. Merleau-
Kantian idealism then dominant in France (e.g., Ponty argues that such accounts rely on gratuitous
Léon Brunschvicg, Jules Lachelier) treated nature hypotheses lacking experimental justification and
as an objective unity dependent on the synthetic cannot effectively explain brain function or
activity of consciousness, the realism of the natural learning. In the case of brain function, experimental
sciences and empirical psychology assumed nature work on brain damage demonstrates that
to be composed of external things and events localization hypotheses must be rejected in favor of
interacting causally. Merleau-Ponty argues that a global process of neural organization comparable
neither approach is tenable: organic life and human to the figure-ground structures of perceptual
consciousness are emergent from a natural world organization. Similarly, learning cannot be
that is not reducible to its meaning for a mind; yet explained in terms of trial-and-error fixing of
this natural world is not the causal nexus of pre- habitual reactions, but instead involves a general
existing objective realities, since it is fundamentally aptitude with respect to typical structures of
composed of nested Gestalts, spontaneously situations. Merleau-Ponty proposes an alternative
emerging structures of organization at multiple tripartite classification of behavior according to the
levels and degrees of integration. On the one hand, degree to which the structures toward which it is
the idealist critique of naturalism should be oriented emerge thematically from their
extended to the naturalistic assumptions framing content. Syncretic behaviors, typical of simpler
Gestalt theory. On the other hand, there is a justified organisms such as ants or toads, respond to all
truth in naturalism that limits the idealist stimuli as analogues of vital situations for which the
universalization of consciousness, and this is organism’s responses are instinctually prescribed by
discovered when Gestalt structures are recognized its “species a priori”, with no possibility for
to be ontologically basic and the limitations of adaptive learning or
consciousness are thereby exposed. The notion of improvisation. Amovable behaviors are oriented
“behavior”, taken by Merleau-Ponty as parallel to toward signals of varying complexity that are not a
function of the organism’s instinctual equipment toward structures as such, which is the condition for
and can lead to genuine learning. Here the such characteristically human symbolic activities as
organism, guided by its vital norms, responds to language and expression, the creation of new
signals as relational structures rather than as structures beyond those set by vital needs, and the
objective properties of things. Drawing on Köhler’s power of choosing and varying points of view
experimental work with chimpanzees, Merleau- (which make truth and objectivity possible). In
Ponty argues that even intelligent non-human short, mind as a second-order or recursive structure
animals lack an orientation toward objective things, is oriented toward the virtual rather than simply
which emerges only at the level toward the real. Ideally, the subordinate structure of
of symbolic behavior. While amovable behavior life would be fully absorbed into the higher order of
remains attached to immediate functional structures, mind in a fully integrated human being; the
symbolic behavior (here limited to humans) is open biological would be transcended by the “spiritual”.
to virtual, expressive, and recursive relationships But integration is never perfect or complete, and
across structures, making possible the human mind can never be detached from its moorings in a
orientation toward objectivity, truth, creativity, and concrete and embodied situation.
freedom from biologically determined norms.
Merleau-Ponty emphasizes throughout The
More generally, Merleau-Ponty proposes that Structure of Behavior that form, even though
matter, life, and mind are increasingly integrative ontologically fundamental, cannot be accounted for
levels of Gestalt structure, ontologically continuous in the terms of traditional realism; since form is
but structurally discontinuous, and distinguished by fundamentally perceptual, an “immanent
the characteristic properties emergent at each signification”, it retains an essential relationship
integrative level of complexity. A form is defined with consciousness. But the “perceptual
here as consciousness” at stake here is not the
transcendental consciousness of critical philosophy.
a field of forces characterized by a law which has
The last chapter of The Structure of
no meaning outside the limits of the dynamic
Behavior clarifies this revised understanding of
structure considered, and which on the other hand
consciousness in dialogue with the classical
assigns its properties to each internal point so much
problem of the relation between the soul and the
so that they will never be absolute properties,
body in order to account for the relative truths of
properties of this point. (SC: 148/137–38)
both transcendental philosophy and naturalism. The
Merleau-Ponty argues that this understanding issue concerns how to reconcile the perspective of
extends to all physical laws, which “express a consciousness as “universal milieu” (i.e.,
structure and have meaning only within this transcendental consciousness) with consciousness
structure”; the laws of physics always refer back to as “enrooted in the subordinated dialectics”, that is,
“a sensible or historical given” and ultimately to the as a Gestalt emerging from lower-order Gestalts
history of the universe (SC: 149/138, 157/145). At (i.e., perceptual consciousness) (SC: 199/184). In
the level of life, form is characterized by a the natural attitude of our pre-reflective lives, we
dialectical relation between the organism and its are committed to the view that our perceptual
environment that is a function of the organism’s experience of things is always situated and
vital norms, its “optimal conditions of activity and perspectival (i.e., that physical objects are presented
its proper manner of realizing equilibrium”, which through “profiles”, Husserl’s Abschattungen), but
express its style or “general attitude toward the also that we thereby experience things “in
world” (SC: 161/148). Living things are not themselves”, as they really are in the mind-
oriented toward an objective world but toward an independent world; the perspectival character of our
environment that is organized meaningfully in terms opening onto the world is not a limitation of our
of their individual and specific style and vital goals. access but rather the very condition of the world’s
disclosure in its inexhaustibility. At the level of this
Mind, the symbolic level of form that Merleau- prereflective faith in the world, there is no dilemma
Ponty identifies with the human, is organized not of the soul’s separation from the body; “the soul
toward vital goals but by the characteristic remains coextensive with nature” (SC: 203/189).
structures of the human world: tools, language,
culture, and so on. These are not originally This prereflective unity eventually splinters under
encountered as things or ideas, but rather as our awareness of illness, illusion, and anatomy,
“significative intentions” embodied within the which teach us to separate nature, body, and thought
world. Mind or consciousness cannot be defined into distinct orders of events partes extra partes.
formally in terms of self-knowledge or This culminates in a naturalism that cannot account
representation, then, but is essentially engaged in for the originary situation of perception that it
the structures and actions of the human world and displaces, yet on which it tacitly relies; perception
encompasses all of the diverse intentional requires an “internal” analysis, paving the way for
orientations of human life. While mind integrates transcendental idealism’s treatment of subject and
within itself the subordinate structures of matter and object as “inseparable correlatives” (SC: 215/199).
life, it goes beyond these in its thematic orientation But transcendental idealism in the critical tradition
subsequently goes too far: by taking consciousness during his lifetime and that established him as the
as “milieu of the universe, presupposed by every leading French phenomenologist of his generation.
affirmation of the world”, it obscures the original Here Merleau-Ponty develops his own distinctive
character of the perceptual relation and culminates interpretation of phenomenology’s method,
in “the dialectic of the epistemological subject and informed by his new familiarity with Husserl’s
the scientific object” (SC: 216/200, 217/201). unpublished manuscripts and his deepened
Merleau-Ponty aims to integrate the truth of engagement with other thinkers in this tradition,
naturalism and transcendental thought by such as Eugen Fink and Martin
reinterpreting both through the concept of structure, Heidegger. Phenomenology of Perception again
which accounts for the unity of soul and body as draws extensively on Gestalt theory and
well as their relative distinction. Against the contemporary research in psychology and
conception of transcendental consciousness as a neurology; the case of Schneider, a brain-damaged
pure spectator correlated with the world, Merleau- patient studied by Adhémar Gelb and Kurt
Ponty insists that mind is an accomplishment of Goldstein, serves as an extended case-study.
structural integration that remains essentially Psychological research complements and, at times,
conditioned by the matter and life in which it is serves as a counterpoint to phenomenological
embodied; the truth of naturalism lies in the fact descriptions of perceptual experience across a wide
that such integration is essentially fragile and range of existential dimensions, including sexuality,
incomplete. Since “integration is never absolute and language, space, nature, intersubjectivity, time, and
always fails”, the dualism of mind and body freedom. In Phenomenology, Merleau-Ponty
develops a characteristic rhythm of presenting, first,
is not a simple fact; it is founded in principle—all
the realist or empiricist approach to a particular
integration presupposing the normal functioning of
dimension of experience, followed then by its
subordinated formations, which always demand
idealist or intellectualist alternative, before
their own due. (SC: 226–27/210)
developing a third way that avoids the problematic
The Structure of Behavior concludes with a call for assumption common to both, namely, their
further investigation of “perceptual consciousness”, “unquestioned belief in the world”: the prejudice
a task taken up by its sequel, Phenomenology of that the objective world exists as a ready-made and
Perception. In the concluding pages of Structure, fully present reality.
Merleau-Ponty offers a preliminary sketch of
Phenomenology of Perception introduces its inquiry
phenomenologically inspired approaches to the
with a critique of the “classical prejudices” of
“problem of perception” that set the stage for his
empiricism and intellectualism. Merleau-Ponty
subsequent work, emphasizing (a) the difference
rejects the empiricist understanding of sensation,
between what is directly given as an aspect of
with its correlative “constancy hypothesis”, and the
individual lived experience and intersubjective
role empiricism grants to association and the
significations that are only encountered virtually;
projection of memory for treating the basic units of
and (b) the distinctiveness of one’s own body,
sensation as determinate atoms rather than as
which is never experienced directly as one objective
meaningful wholes. These wholes include
thing among many. The book concludes by
ambiguities, indeterminacies, and contextual
identifying the “problem of perception” as its
relations that defy explanation in terms of the causal
encompassing concern:
action of determinate things. Intellectualism aims to
Can one conceptualize perceptual consciousness provide an alternative to empiricism by introducing
without eliminating it as an original mode; can one judgment or attention as mental activities that
maintain its specificity without rendering synthesize experience from the sensory givens, yet
inconceivable its relation to intellectual it adopts empiricism’s starting point in dispersed,
consciousness? (SC: 241/224) atomic sensations. Both approaches are guilty of
reading the results of perception (the objective
The solution requires a “return to perception as to a world) back into perceptual experience, thereby
type of originary experience” by means of an falsifying perception’s characteristic structure: the
“inversion of the natural movement of spontaneous organization or configuration of
consciousness”, an inversion that Merleau-Ponty perceived phenomena themselves, with their
here equates with Husserl’s phenomenological indeterminacies and ambiguities, and the dynamic
reduction (SC: 236/220). If successful, this character of perception as an historical process
rehabilitation of the status of perception would lead involving development and transformation. By
to a redefinition of transcendental philosophy “in treating perception as a causal process of
such a way as to integrate with it the very transmission or a cognitive judgment, empiricism
phenomenon of the real” (SC: 241/224). and intellectualism deny any meaningful
3. Phenomenology of Perception configuration to the perceived as such and treat all
values and meanings as projections, leaving no
Completed in 1944 and published the following basis in perception itself for distinguishing the true
year, Phenomenology of Perception (PP) is the from the illusory.
work for which Merleau-Ponty was best known
In contrast, Merleau-Ponty argues that the basic world is essentially temporal, involving a dialectic
level of perceptual experience is the gestalt, the between the present body (characterized, after
meaningful whole of figure against ground, and that Husserl, as an “I can”) and the habit body, the
the indeterminate and contextual aspects of the sedimentations of past activities that take on a
perceived world are positive phenomenon that general, anonymous, and autonomous character.
cannot be eliminated from a complete account. While the body’s relation to the world serves as the
Sensing, in contrast with knowing, is a “living essential background for the experience of any
communication with the world that makes it present particular thing, the body itself is experienced in
to us as the familiar place of our life” (PP: 79/53), ways that distinguish it in kind from all other
investing the perceived world with meanings and things: it is a permanent part of one’s perceptual
values that refer essentially to our bodies and lives. field, even though one cannot in principle
We forget this “phenomenal field”, the world as it experience all of it directly; it has “double
appears directly to perception, as a consequence of sensations”, such as when one hand touches
perception’s own tendency to forget itself in favor another, that enact a form of reflexivity; it has
of the perceived that it discloses. Perception orients affective experiences that are not merely
itself toward the truth, placing its faith in the representations; and its kinesthetic sense of its own
eventual convergence of perspectives and movements is given directly.
progressive determination of what was previously
This kinesthetic awareness is made possible by a
indeterminate. But it thereby naturally projects a
pre-conscious system of bodily movements and
completed and invariant “truth in itself” as its goal.
spatial equivalences that Merleau-Ponty terms the
Science extends and amplifies this natural tendency
“body schema”. In contrast with the “positional
through increasingly precise measurements of the
spatiality” of things, the body has a “situational
invariants in perception, leading eventually to the
spatiality” that is oriented toward actual or possible
theoretical construction of an objective world of
tasks (PP: 129/102). The body’s existence as
determinate things. Once this determinism of the “in
“being-toward-the-world”, as a projection toward
itself” is extended universally and applied even to
lived goals, is therefore expressed through its
the body and the perceptual relation itself, then its
spatiality, which forms the background against
ongoing dependence on the “originary faith” of
which objective space is constituted. Merleau-Ponty
perception is obscured; perception is reduced to
introduces here the famous case of Schneider,
“confused appearances” that require methodical
whose reliance on pathological substitutions for
reinterpretation, and the eventual result is dualism,
normal spatial abilities helps to bring the body’s
solipsism, and skepticism. The “fundamental
typical relationship with lived space to light.
philosophical act” would therefore be to “return to
Schneider lacks the ability to “project” into virtual
the lived world beneath the objective world” (PP:
space; more generally, his injury has disrupted the
83/57). This requires a transcendental reduction: a
“intentional arc” that
reversal of perception’s natural tendency to cover
its own tracks and a bracketing of our unquestioned projects around us our past, our future, our human
belief in the objective world. Yet this cannot be a milieu, our physical situation, our ideological
recourse to any transcendental consciousness that situation, and our moral situation, or rather, that
looks on the world from outside and is not itself ensures that we are situated within all of these
emergent from and conditioned by the phenomenal relationships. (PP: 170/137)
field. Rather than a transcendental ego, Merleau-
Ponty speaks of a “transcendental field”, The body’s relationship with space is therefore
emphasizing that reflection always has a situated intentional, although as an “I can” rather than an “I
and partial perspective as a consequence of being think”; bodily space is a multi-layered manner of
located within the field on which it reflects. relating to things, so that the body is not “in” space
but lives or inhabits it.
The first of the three major parts
of Phenomenology concerns the body. As we have Just as bodily space reflects an originary form of
seen, perception transcends itself toward a intentionality—a pre-cognitive encounter with the
determinate object “in itself”, culminating in an world as meaningfully structured—the same is
objective interpretation of the body. Part One shows shown to be the case for sexuality and for language.
the limits of this objective account and sketches an Sexuality takes on a special significance because it
alternative understanding of the body across a series essentially expresses the metaphysical drama of the
of domains, including the experience of one’s own human condition while infusing the atmosphere of
body, lived space, sexuality, and language. Through our lives with sexual significance. Like space and
a contrast with pathological cases such as phantom sexuality, speech is also a form of bodily
limbs, Merleau-Ponty describes the body’s typical expression. Language does not initially encode
mode of existence as “being-toward-the-world”—a ready-made thoughts but rather expresses through
pre-objective orientation toward a vital situation its style or physiognomy as a bodily gesture. We
that is explicable neither in terms of third-person mistake language for a determined code by taking
causal interactions nor by explicit judgments or habitual or sedimented language as our model,
representations. The body’s orientation toward the thereby missing “authentic” or creative speech.
Since language, like perception, hides its own a pre-given container in which things are arranged)
operations in carrying us toward its meaning, it nor “spatializing” (like the homogenous and
offers an ideal of truth as its presumptive limit, interchangeable relations of geometrical space).
inspiring our traditional privileging of thought or Drawing on psychological experiments concerning
reason as detachable from all materiality. But, at a bodily orientation, depth, and movement, Merleau-
fundamental level, language is comparable to music Ponty argues that empiricist and intellectualist
in the way that it remains tied to its material accounts of space must give way to a conception of
embodiment; each language is a distinct and space as co-existence or mutual implication
ultimately untranslatable manner of “singing the characterized by existential “levels”: our orientation
world”, of extracting and expressing the “emotional toward up and down, or toward what is in motion or
essence” of our surroundings and relationships (PP: stationary, is a function of the body’s adoption of a
228/193). certain level within a revisable field of possibilities.
Lived inherence in space contrasts with the abstract
Having rediscovered the body as expressive and
space of the analytical attitude, revindicating the
intentional, Merleau-Ponty turns in Part Two
existential space of night, dreams, or myths in
of Phenomenology to the perceived world, with the
relation to the abstract space of the “objective”
aim of showing how the pre-reflective unity of co-
world.
existence that characterizes the body has as its
correlate the synthesis of things and the world; The properties of things that we take to be “real”
“One’s own body is in the world just as the heart is and “objective” also tacitly assume a reference to
in the organism” (PP: 245/209), and its expressive the body’s norms and its adoption of levels. An
unity therefore also extends to the sensible world. object’s “true” qualities depend on the body’s
Merleau-Ponty develops this interpretation of the privileging of orientations that yield maximum
sensible through detailed studies of sensing, space, clarity and richness. This is possible because the
and the natural and social worlds. Sensing takes body serves as a template for the style or logic of
place as the “co-existence” or “communion” of the the world, the concordant system of relations that
body with the world that Merleau-Ponty describes links the qualities of an object, the configuration of
as a reciprocal exchange of question and answer: the perceptual field, and background levels such as
lighting or movement. In this symbiosis or call-and-
a sensible that is about to be sensed poses to my
response between the body and the world, things
body a sort of confused problem. I must find the
have sense as the correlates of my body, and reality
attitude that will provide it with the means to
therefore always involves a reference to perception.
become determinate … I must find the response to a
Yet, to be real, things cannot be reducible to
poorly formulated question. And yet I only do this
correlates of the body or perception; they retain a
in response to its solicitation… . The sensible gives
depth and resistance that provides their existential
back to me what I had lent to it, but I received it
index. While each thing has its individual style, the
from the sensible in the first place. (PP: 259/222)
world is the ultimate horizon or background style
As co-existence, sensing is characterized by an against which any particular thing can appear. The
intentionality that sympathetically attunes itself to perspectival limitations of perception, both spatially
the sensed according to a dialectic in which both and temporally, are the obverse of this world’s
terms—the perceiving body and the perceived thing depth and inexhaustibility. Through an examination
—are equally active and receptive: the thing invites of hallucination and illusions, Merleau-Ponty argues
the body to adopt the attitude that will lead to its that skepticism about the existence of the world
disclosure. Since the subject of this perception is makes a category mistake. While we can doubt any
not the idealist’s “for itself”, neither is the object of particular perception, illusions can appear only
perception the realist’s “in itself”; rather, the agent against the background of the world and our
of perception is the pre-reflective and anonymous primordial faith in it. While we never coincide with
subjectivity of the body, which remains enmeshed the world or grasp it with absolute certainty, we are
in and “connatural” with the world that it perceives. also never entirely cut off from it; perception
The senses are unified without losing their essentially aims toward truth, but any truth that it
distinctness in a fashion comparable to the reveals is contingent and revisable.
binocular synthesis of vision, and their anonymity is
Rejecting analogical explanations for the experience
a consequence of the “historical thickness” of
of other people, Merleau-Ponty proposes that the
perception as a tradition that operates beneath the
rediscovery of the body as a “third genre of being
level of reflective consciousness (PP: 285/248). For
between the pure subject and the object” makes
first-person awareness, one’s anonymous perceptual
possible encounters with embodied others (PP:
engagement with the world operates as a kind of
407/366). We perceive others directly as pre-
“original past, a past that has never been present”
personal and embodied living beings engaged with
(PP: 252/252).
a world that we share in common. This encounter at
The pre-historical pact between the body and the the level of anonymous and pre-personal lives does
world informs our encounters with space, revealing not, however, present us with another person in the
a synthesis of space that is neither “spatialized” (as full sense, since our situations are never entirely
congruent. The perception of others involves an very act of temporalization. As with the tacit cogito,
alterity, a resistance, and a plenitude that are never the auto-affection of time as ultimate subjectivity is
reducible to what is presented, which is the truth of not a static self-identity but involves a dynamic
solipsism. Our common corporeality nevertheless opening toward alterity. In this conception of time
opens us onto a shared social world, a permanent as field of presence, which “reveals the subject and
dimension of our being in the mode of the the object as two abstract moments of a unique
anonymous and general “someone”. The perception structure, namely, presence” (PP: 494/454–55),
of others is therefore a privileged example of the Merleau-Ponty sees the resolution to all problems of
paradox of transcendence running through our transcendence as well as the foundation for human
encounter with the world as perceived: freedom. Against the Sartrean position that freedom
is either total or null, Merleau-Ponty holds that
Whether it is a question of my body, the natural
freedom emerges only against the background of
world, the past, birth or death, the question is
our “universal engagement in a world”, which
always to know how I can be open to phenomena
involves us in meanings and values that are not of
that transcend me and that, nevertheless, only exist
our choosing. We must recognize, first, an
to the extent that I take them up and live them. (PP:
“authochthonous sense of the world that is
422/381)
constituted in the exchange between the world and
This “fundamental contradiction” defines our our embodied existence” (PP: 504/466), and,
encounters with every form of transcendence and second, that the acquired habits and the sedimented
requires new conceptions of consciousness, time, choices of our lives have their own inertia. This
and freedom. situation does not eliminate freedom but is precisely
the field in which it can be achieved. Taking class
The fourth and final section consciousness as his example, Merleau-Ponty
of Phenomenology explores these three themes, proposes that this dialectic of freedom and
starting with a revision of the concept of the cogito acquisition provides the terms for an account of
that avoids reducing it to merely episodic history, according to which history can develop a
psychological fact or elevating it to a universal meaning and a direction that are neither determined
certainty of myself and my cogitationes. Merleau- by events nor necessarily transparent to those who
Ponty argues that we cannot separate the certainty live through it.
of our thoughts from that of our perceptions, since
to truly perceive is to have confidence in the The Preface to Phenomenology of
veracity of one’s perceptions. Furthermore, we are Perception, completed after the main text, offers
not transparent to ourselves, since our “inner states” Merleau-Ponty’s most detailed and systematic
are available to us only in a situated and ambiguous exposition of the phenomenological method. His
way. The genuine cogito, Merleau-Ponty argues, is account is organized around four themes: the
a cogito “in action”: we do not deduce “I am” from privileging of description over scientific
“I think”, but rather the certainty of “I think” rests explanation or idealist reconstruction, the
on the “I am” of existential engagement. More basic phenomenological reduction, the eidetic reduction,
than explicit self-consciousness and presupposed by and intentionality. Phenomenology sets aside all
it is an ambiguous mode of self-experience that scientific or naturalistic explanations of phenomena
Merleau-Ponty terms the silent or “tacit” cogito— in order to describe faithfully the pre-scientific
our pre-reflective and inarticulate grasp on the experience that such explanations take for granted.
world and ourselves that becomes explicit and Similarly, since the world exists prior to reflective
determinate only when it finds expression for itself. analysis or judgment, phenomenology avoids
The illusions of pure self-possession and reconstructing actual experience in terms of its
transparency—like all apparently “eternal” truths— conditions of possibility or the activity of
are the results of acquired or sedimented language consciousness. The phenomenological reduction, on
and concepts. his interpretation, is not an idealistic method but an
existential one, namely, the reflective effort to
Rejecting classic approaches to time that treat it disclose our pre-reflective engagement with the
either as an objective property of things, as a world. Through the process of the reduction, we
psychological content, or as the product of discover the inherence of the one who reflects in the
transcendental consciousness, Merleau-Ponty world that is reflected on, and consequently, the
returns to the “field of presence” as our essentially incomplete character of every act of
foundational experience of time. This field is a reflection, which is why Merleau-Ponty claims that
network of intentional relations, of “protentions” the “most important lesson of the reduction is the
and “retentions”, in a single movement of impossibility of a complete reduction” (PP:
dehiscence or self-differentiation, such that “each 14/lxxvii). Similarly, the “eidetic reduction”,
present reaffirms the presence of the entire past that described by Husserl as the intuition of essential
it drives away, and anticipates the presence of the relations within the flux of conscious experience, is
entire future or the ‘to-come’” (PP: 483/444). Time necessary if phenomenology is to make any
in this sense is “ultimate subjectivity”, understood descriptive claims that go beyond the brute facts of
not as an eternal consciousness, but rather as the a particular experience. But this does not found the
actual world on consciousness as the condition of the years immediately
the world’s possibility; instead, “the eidetic method following Phenomenology (in Merleau-Ponty
is that of a phenomenological positivism grounding 1996b/1964). These include Merleau-Ponty’s first
the possible upon the real” (PP: 17/lxxxi). Lastly, essay on painting, “Cézanne’s Doubt”, which finds
Merleau-Ponty reinterprets the phenomenological in Cézanne a proto-phenomenological effort to
concept of intentionality, traditionally understood as capture the birth of perception through painting.
the recognition that all consciousness is Cézanne epitomizes the paradoxical struggle of
consciousness of something. Following Husserl, he creative expression, which necessarily relies on the
distinguishes the “act intentionality” of judgments idiosyncracies of the artist’s individual history and
and voluntary decisions from the “operative psychology, as well as the resources of the tradition
intentionality” that “establishes the natural and pre- of painting, but can succeed only by risking a
predicative unity of the world and of our life” (PP: creative appropriation of these acquisitions in the
18/lxxxii). Guided by this broader concept of service of teaching its audience to see the world
intentionality, philosophy’s task is to take in the anew. Similarly, Leonardo da Vinci’s artistic
“total intention” of a sensible thing, a philosophical productivity is explicable neither in terms of his
theory, or an historical event, which is its “unique intellectual freedom (Valéry) nor his childhood
manner of existing” or its “existential structure” (Freud) but as the dialectic of spontaneity and
(PP: 19–20/lxxxii–lxxxiii). Phenomenology thereby sedimentation by which Merleau-Ponty had
expresses the emergence of reason and meaning in a formerly defined history.
contingent world, a creative task comparable to that
In 1951, Merleau-Ponty summarizes his research
of the artist or the political activist, which requires
after Phenomenology as focused on a “theory of
an ongoing “radical” or self-referential reflection on
truth” exploring how knowledge and
its own possibilities. On Merleau-Ponty’s
communication with others are “original formations
presentation, the tensions of phenomenology’s
with respect to perceptual life, but … also preserve
method therefore reflect the nature of its task:
and continue our perceptual life even while
The unfinished nature of phenomenology and the transforming it” (UMP: 41–42/287). Expression,
inchoative style in which it proceeds are not the language, and symbolism are the key to this theory
sign of failure, they were inevitable because of truth and provide the foundation for a philosophy
phenomenology’s task was to reveal the mystery of of history and of “transcendental” humanity.
the world and the mystery of reason. (PP: 21– Whereas the study of perception could only provide
22/lxxxv) a “bad ambiguity” that mixes “finitude and
universality”, Merleau-Ponty sees in the
4. Expression, Language, and Art phenomenon of expression a “good ambiguity” that
The concepts of expression and style are central to “gathers together the plurality of monads, the past
Merleau-Ponty’s thought and already play a key and the present, nature and culture, into a single
role in his first two books, where they characterize whole” (UMP: 48/290). Many of Merleau-Ponty’s
the perceptual exchange between an organism and courses from 1947 through 1953 at the University
its milieu, the body’s sensible dialogue with the of Lyon, the Sorbonne, and the Collège de France
world, and even the act of philosophical reflection focus on language, expression, and literature.[6]
(see Landes 2013). In both works, Merleau-Ponty
The manuscript partially completed during these
draws on a range of literary and artistic examples to
years and published posthumously as The Prose of
describe the creative and expressive dimensions of
the World (1969/1973) pursues these themes
perception and reflection, emphasizing in particular
through a phenomenological investigation of
the parallels between the task of the artist and that
literary language and its relationship with scientific
of the thinker: as the concluding lines of the Preface
language and painting. Critiquing our commonsense
to Phenomenology of Perception note,
ideal of a pure language that would transparently
Phenomenology is as painstaking as the works of encode pre-existing thoughts, Merleau-Ponty argues
Balzac, Proust, Valéry, or Cézanne—through the that instituted language—the conventional system
same kind of attention and wonder, the same of language as an established set of meanings and
demand for awareness, the same will to grasp the rules—is derivative from a more primordial
sense of the world or of history in its nascent state. function of language as genuinely creative,
(PP: 22/lxxxv) expressive, and communicative. Here he draws two
insights from Saussurian linguistics: First, signs
Expression, particularly in language and the arts, function diacritically, through their lateral relations
plays an increasingly central role in Merleau- and differentiations, rather than through a one-to-
Ponty’s thought in the years one correspondence with a conventionally
following Phenomenology, when he aimed to established meaning. Ultimately, signification
formulate a general theory of expression as the happens through the differences between terms in a
grounding for a philosophy of history and culture. referential system that lacks any fixed or positive
[5]
 This interest is first reflected in a series of essays terms. This insight into diacritical difference will
addressing painting, literature, and film published in later prove important to Merleau-Ponty’s
understanding of perception and ontology as well elevated to a metaphysical status by contemporary
(see Alloa 2013a). Second, the ultimate context for science, it culminates in an understanding of being
the operation of language is effective as purely positive and absolutely determinate. The
communication with others, by which new thoughts ontological significance of modern painting and the
can be expressed and meanings shared. Expression plastic arts—e.g., Klee, de Staël, Cézanne, Matisse,
accomplishes itself through a coherent Rodin—lies in the alternative philosophy that they
reorganization of the relationships between acquired embody, as revealed through their treatment of
signs that must teach itself to the reader or listener, depth, color, line, and movement. Ultimately, such
and which may afterwards again sediment into a works teach us anew what it means to see:
taken-for-granted institutional structure.
Vision is not a certain mode of thought or presence
In a long extract from the manuscript that was to self; it is the means given me for being absent
revised and published in 1952 as “Indirect from myself, for being present from the inside at the
Language and the Voices of Silence” (in Merleau- fission of Being only at the end of which do I close
Ponty 1960/1964), Merleau-Ponty brings this up into myself. (OEE: 81/374)
understanding of language into conversation with
Sartre’s What is Literature? and André 5. Political Philosophy
Malraux’s The Voices of Silence. Sharing Malraux’s From the first issue of Les Temps Modernes in
criticisms of the museum’s role in framing the October 1945 until his death, Merleau-Ponty wrote
reception of painting, but rejecting his interpretation regularly on politics, including reflections on
of modern painting as subjectivist, Merleau-Ponty contemporary events as well as explorations of their
offers an alternative understanding of “institution” philosophical underpinnings and the broader
(from Husserl’s Stiftung) as the creative political significance of his times. During his eight-
establishment of a new field of meaning that opens year tenure as unofficial managing editor of Les
an historical development. The style of an artist is Temps Modernes, he charted the review’s political
not merely subjective but lived as a historical direction and penned many of its political editorials.
trajectory of expression that begins with perception After leaving Les Temps Modernes in 1953,
itself and effects a “coherent deformation” in Merleau-Ponty found new outlets for his political
inherited traditions. Rather than opposed as silent writings, including L’Express, a weekly newspaper
and speaking, painting and language are both devoted to the non-communist left. Both of the
continuations of the expressivity of a perceptual essay collections that he published during his
style into more malleable mediums. The unfinished lifetime, Sense and Non-Sense and Signs, devote
character of modern painting is therefore not a turn significant space to his political writings. He also
from the objectivity of representation toward published two volumes devoted entirely to political
subjective creation but rather a more authentic philosophy, Humanism and Terror (HT)
testament to the paradoxical logic of all expression. and Adventures of the Dialectic (1955 AdD).
Always writing from the left, Merleau-Ponty’s
Merleau-Ponty returns to the analysis of painting in
position gradually shifted from a qualified
his final essay, “Eye and Mind” (1964a OEE),
Marxism, maintaining a critical distance from
where he accords it an ontological priority—
liberal democracy as well as from Soviet
between the linguistic arts and music—for revealing
communism, to the rejection of revolutionary
the “there is” of the world that the operationalism of
politics in favor of a “new liberalism”. His political
contemporary science has occluded. It is by
writings have received relatively scant attention
“lending his body to the world that the artist
compared with other aspects of his philosophy,
changes the world into paintings” (OEE: 16/353),
perhaps because of their close engagement with the
and this presupposes that the artist’s body is
political situations and events of his day.
immersed in and made of the same stuff as the
Nevertheless, scholars of his political thought
world: to touch, one must be tangible, and to see,
emphasize its continuity with his theoretical
visible. Merleau-Ponty describes this as an
writings and ongoing relevance for political
“intertwining” or “overlapping”, in which the
philosophy (see Coole 2007; Whiteside 1998).
artist’s situated embodiment is the other side of its
opening to the world. There is as yet no sharp The 1947 publication of Humanism and
division between the sensing and the sensed, Terror responded to growing anti-communist
between body and things as one common “flesh”, sentiment in France fueled in part by the fictional
and painting arises as the expression of this relation: account of the Moscow trials in Arthur Koestler’s
it is a “visible to the second power, a carnal essence popular novel Darkness at Noon. Merleau-Ponty
or icon” of embodied vision (OEE: 22/355). sought to articulate an alternative to the choice
Descartes’s efforts, in the Optics, to reconstruct Europe apparently faced in the solidifying
vision from thought leads him to focus on the opposition between the United States and the Soviet
“envelope” or form of the object, as presented in Union. Humanism and Terror criticizes Koestler’s
engraved lines, and to treat depth as a third portrayal of the fictional Rubochov, modeled on
dimension modeled after height and width. This Nikolai Bukharin, for replacing the “mutual praxis”
idealization of space has its necessity, yet, once of genuine Marxism (HT: 102/18) with an
opposition between pure freedom and determined history’s movement, this need not compromise their
history, the “yogi” who withdraws into spiritual objectivity. The historical events and periods within
ideals or the “commissar” who acts by any means which the historian traces a particular style or
necessary. Turning to an examination of Bukharin’s meaning emerge in conjunction with historical
1938 trial, Merleau-Ponty finds there an example of agents, political actors or classes, who exercise a
“revolutionary justice” that “judges in the name of creative action parallel to the expressive gesture of
the Truth that the Revolution is about to make true” the artist or the writer. History may eliminate false
(HT: 114/28), even though the historical paths, but it guarantees no particular direction,
contingency that this entails is denied by the leaving to historical agents the responsibility for the
procedures of the trials themselves. On the other continuation or transformation of what is inherited
hand, Trotsky’s condemnation of Stalinism as from the past through a genius for inventing what
counter-revolutionary similarly misses the the times demand: “In politics, truth is perhaps only
ambiguity of genuine history. Ultimately, the this art of inventing what will later appear to have
dimension of terror that history harbors is a been required by the time” (AdD: 42/29). Merleau-
consequence of our unavoidable responsibility in Ponty finds a similar position articulated by the
the face of its essential contingency and ambiguity. young Georg Lukacs, for whom “There is only one
knowledge, which is the knowledge of our world in
Although violence is a consequence of the human
a state of becoming, and this becoming embraces
condition and therefore the starting point for
knowledge itself” (AdD: 46/32). History forms a
politics, Merleau-Ponty finds hope in the theory of
third order, beyond subjects and objects, of
the proletariat for a fundamental transformation in
interhuman relations inscribed in cultural objects
the terms of human recognition:
and institutions, and with its own logic of
The proletariat is universal de facto, or manifestly sedimentation and spontaneity. The self-
in its very condition of life…. [I]t is the sole consciousness that emerges within this third order is
authentic intersubjectivity because it alone lives precisely the proletariat, whose consciousness is not
simultaneously the separation and union of that of an “I think” but rather the praxis of their
individuals. (HT: 221/116–17) common situation and system of action. Historical
truth emerges from the movement of creative
A genuinely historical Marxism must recognize that expression whereby the Party brings the life of the
nothing guarantees progress toward a classless proletariat to explicit awareness, which requires, in
society, but also that this end cannot be brought return, that the working class recognize and
about by non-proletarian means, which is what understand itself in the Party’s formulations.
Soviet communism had apparently forgotten.
Despite the failures of the Soviet experiment, With this understanding, Lukacs aims to preserve
Merleau-Ponty remains committed to a humanist the dialectic of history, to prevent it from slipping
Marxism: into a simple materialism, and thereby to discover
the absolute in the relative. But Lukacs backtracks
Marxism is not just any hypothesis that might be on this position after its official rejection by the
replaced tomorrow by some other. It is the simple communist establishment in favor of a metaphysical
statement of those conditions without which there materialism, and Merleau-Ponty finds a parallel in
would be neither any humanism, in the sense of a Marx’s own turn away from genuine dialectic
mutual relation between men, nor any rationality in toward a simple naturalism that justifies any action
history. In this sense Marxism is not a philosophy of in the name of a historical necessity inscribed in
history; it is the philosophy of history and to things. For the lack of a genuine concept of
renounce it is to dig the grave of Reason in history. institution that can recognize dialectic in embodied
(HT: 266/153) form, Marxist materialism repeatedly abandons its
Even if the proletariat is not presently leading world dialectical aspirations, as Merleau-Ponty further
history, its time may yet come. Merleau-Ponty illustrates through the example of Trostky’s career.
therefore concludes with a “wait-and-see” Marxism In the final chapter of Adventures, Merleau-Ponty
that cautions against decontextualized criticisms of turns his sights toward Sartre’s endorsement of
Soviet communism as well as apologetics for liberal communism in The Communists and Peace. On
democracies that whitewash their racist and colonial Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation, Sartre’s ontological
violence. commitment to a dualism of being and nothingness,
Revelations about the Gulag camps and the where the full positivity of determinate things
outbreak of the Korean War forced Merleau-Ponty juxtaposes with the negating freedom of
to revise his position on Marxism and revolutionary consciousness, eliminates any middle ground for
politics, culminating in the 1955 Adventures of the history or praxis. Since consciousness is
Dialectic (AdD). The book begins with the unconstrained by any sedimentation or by the
formulation of a general theory of history in autonomous life of cultural acquisitions, it can
conversation with Max Weber. Historians recognize no inertia or spontaneity at the level of
necessarily approach the past through their own institutions, and therefore no genuine historical
perspectives, but, since they are themselves a part of becoming. More centrally, by interpreting the
relation between the Party and the proletariat of essays. The first three chapters progressively
through his own conception of consciousness as develop an account of “philosophical interrogation”
pure freedom, Sartre rules out in principle any in critical dialogue with scientism, the philosophies
possibility for their divergence. This leads Sartre to of reflection (Descartes and Kant), Sartrean
an “ultrabolshevism” according to which the Party’s negation, and the intuitionisms of Bergson and
position is identified with the revolutionary agenda, Husserl. These are followed by a stand-alone
any opposition to which must be suppressed. chapter, “The Intertwining—The Chiasm”,
presenting Merleau-Ponty’s ontology of flesh. The
In the Epilogue that summarizes Merleau-Ponty’s
published volume also includes a brief abandoned
own position, he explains his rejection of
section of the text as an appendix and more than a
revolutionary action, understood as
hundred pages of selected working notes composed
proletarian praxis, for remaining equivocal rather
between 1959 and 1961.[7]
than truly dialectical. The illusion that has brought
dialectic to a halt is precisely the investment of Merleau-Ponty frames the investigation with a
history’s total meaning in the proletariat, ultimately description of “perceptual faith”, our shared pre-
equating the proletariat with dialectic as such, reflective conviction that perception presents us
which leads to the conviction that revolution would with the world as it actually is, even though this
liquidate history itself. But it is essential to the very perception is mediated, for each of us, by our bodily
structure of revolutions that, when successful, they senses. This apparent paradox creates no difficulties
betray their own revolutionary character by in our everyday lives, but it becomes
sedimenting into institutions. Drawing on the incomprehensible when thematized by reflection:
extended example of the French revolution,
The “natural” man holds on to both ends of the
Merleau-Ponty argues that every revolution
chain, thinks at the same time that his perception
mistakes the structure of history for its contents,
enters into the things and that it is formed this side
believing that eliminating the latter will absolutely
of his body. Yet coexist as the two convictions do
transform the former. Thus, “The very nature of
without difficulty in the exercise of life, once
revolution is to believe itself absolute and to not be
reduced to theses and to propositions they destroy
absolute precisely because it believes itself to be so”
one another and leave us in confusion. (V&I: 23–
(AdD: 298/222). While Soviet communism may
24/8)
continue to justify itself in absolute terms, it is
concretely a progressivism that tacitly recognizes For Merleau-Ponty, this “unjustifiable certitude of a
the relativity of revolution and the gradual nature of sensible world” is the starting point for developing
progress. The alternative that Merleau-Ponty an alternative account of perception, the world,
endorses is the development of a “noncommunist intersubjective relations, and ultimately being as
left”, an “a-communism”, or a “new liberalism”, the such. Neither the natural sciences nor psychology
first commitment of which would be to reject the provide an adequate clarification of this perceptual
description of the rivalry between the two powers as faith, since they rely on it without acknowledgment
one between “free enterprise” and Marxism (AdD: even as their theoretical constructions rule out its
302–3/225). This noncommunist left would occupy possibility. Philosophies of reflection, exemplified
a “double position”, “posing social problems in by Descartes and Kant, also fail in their account of
terms of [class] struggle” while also “refusing the perception, since they reduce the perceived world to
dictatorship of the proletariat” (AdD: 304/226). an idea, equate the subject with thought, and
This pursuit must welcome the resources of undermine any understanding of intersubjectivity or
parliamentary debate, in clear recognition of their a world shared in common (V&I: 62/39, 67/43).
limitations, since Parliament is “the only known
institution that guarantees a minimum of opposition Sartre’s dialectic of being (in-itself) and
and of truth” (AdD: 304/226). By exercising nothingness (for-itself) makes progress over
“methodical doubt” toward the established powers philosophies of reflection insofar as it recognizes
and denying that they exhaust political and the ecceity of the world, with which the subject
economic options, the possibility opens for a engages not as one being alongside others but rather
genuine dialectic that advances social justice while as a nothingness, that is, as a determinate negation
respecting political freedom. of a concrete situation that can co-exist alongside
other determinate negations. Even so, for Sartre,
6. The Visible and the Invisible pure nothingness and pure being remain mutually
exclusive, ambivalently identical in their perfect
The manuscript and working notes published
opposition, which brings any movement of their
posthumously as The Visible and the Invisible (1964
dialectic to a halt. The “philosophy of negation” is
V&I), extracted from a larger work underway at the
therefore shown to be a totalizing or “high-altitude”
time of Merleau-Ponty’s death, is considered by
thought that remains abstract, missing the true
many to be the best presentation of his later
opening onto the world made possible by the fact
ontology. The main text, drafted in 1959 and 1960,
that nothingness is “sunken into being” (V&I: 121–
is contemporaneous with “Eye and Mind” and the
122/88–89). This “bad” dialectic must therefore
Preface to Signs, Merleau-Ponty’s final collection
give way to a “hyperdialectic” that remains self-
critical about its own tendency to reify into fixed but is closest to the notion of an “element” in the
and opposed theses (V&I: 129/94). classical sense (V&I: 184/139). Merleau-Ponty
denies that this is a subjective or anthropocentric
The philosophy of intuition takes two forms:
projection:
the Wesenschau of Husserl, which converts lived
experience into ideal essences before a pure carnal being, as a being of depths, of several leaves
spectator, and Bergsonian intuition, which seeks to or several faces, a being in latency, and a
coincide with its object by experiencing it from presentation of a certain absence, is a prototype of
within. Against the first, Merleau-Ponty argues that Being, of which our body, the sensible sentient, is a
the world’s givenness is more primordial than the very remarkable variant, but whose constitutive
ideal essence; the essence is a variant of the real, paradox already lies in every visible. (V&I:
not its condition of possibility. Essences are not 179/136)
ultimately detachable from the sensible but are its
The generality of flesh embraces an intercorporeity,
“invisible” or its latent structure of differentiation.
an anonymous sensibility shared out among distinct
Against a return to the immediacy of coincidence or
bodies: just as my two hands communicate across
a nostalgia for the pre-reflective, Merleau-Ponty
the lateral synergy of my body, I can touch the
holds that there is no self-identical presence to
sensibility of another: “The handshake too is
rejoin; the “immediate” essentially involves
reversible” (V&I: 187/142).
distance and non-coincidence. Consequently, truth
must be redefined as “a privative non-coinciding, a Sensible flesh—what Merleau-Ponty calls the
coinciding from afar, a divergence, and something “visible”—is not all there is to flesh, since flesh also
like a ‘good error’” (V&I: 166/124–25). “sublimates” itself into an “invisible” dimension:
the “rarified” or “glorified” flesh of ideas. Taking as
In the final chapter, “The Intertwining—The
his example the “little phrase” from Vinteuil’s
Chiasm”, Merleau-Ponty turns directly to the
sonata (in Swann’s Way), Merleau-Ponty describes
positive project of describing his ontology of
literature, music, and the passions as “the
“flesh”. Intertwining [entrelacs] here translates
exploration of an invisible and the disclosure of a
Husserl’s Verflechtung, entanglement or
universe of ideas”, although in such cases these
interweaving, like the woof and warp of a fabric.
ideas “cannot be detached from the sensible
Chiasm has two senses in French and English that
appearance and be erected into a second positivity”
are both relevant to Merleau-Ponty’s project: a
(V&I: 196/149). Creative language necessarily
physiological sense that refers to anatomical or
carries its meaning in a similarly embodied fashion,
genetic structures with a crossed arrangement (such
while the sediments of such expression result in
as the optic nerves), and a literary sense referring to
language as a system of formalized relations. What
figures of speech that repeat structures in reverse
we treat as “pure ideas” are nothing more than a
order (AB:BA). For Merleau-Ponty, the chiasm is a
certain divergence and ongoing process of
structure of mediation that combines the unity-in-
differentiation, now occurring within language
difference of its physiological sense with the
rather than sensible things. Ultimately we find a
reversal and circularity of its literary usage (see
relation of reversibility within language like that
Toadvine 2012; Saint Aubert 2005). A paradigmatic
holding within sensibility: just as, in order to see,
example of chiasmic structure is the body’s
my body must be part of the visible and capable of
doubling into sensible and sentient aspects during
being seen, so, by speaking, I make myself one who
self-touch. Elaborating on Husserl’s descriptions of
can be spoken to (allocutary) and one who can be
this phenomenon, Merleau-Ponty emphasizes three
spoken about (delocutary). While all of the
consequences: First, the body as sensible-sentient is
possibilities of language are already outlined or
an “exemplar sensible” that demonstrates the
promised within the sensible world, reciprocally the
kinship or ontological continuity between subject
sensible world itself is unavoidably inscribed with
and object among sensible things in general.
language.
Second, this relationship is reversible, like “obverse
and reverse” or “two segments of one sole circular This final chapter of The Visible and the
course” (V&I: 182/138). Third, the sentient and Invisible illustrates chiasmic mediation across a
sensible never strictly coincide but are always range of relations, including sentient and sensed,
separated by a gap or divergence [écart] that defers touch and vision, body and world, self and other,
their unity. fact and essence, perception and language. There is
not one chiasm but rather various chiasmic
Chiasm is therefore a crisscrossing or a bi-
structures at different levels. As Renaud Barbaras
directional becoming or exchange between the body
notes,
and things that justifies speaking of a “flesh” of
things, a kinship between the sensing body and It is necessary … to picture the universe as intuited
sensed things that makes their communication by Merleau-Ponty as a proliferation of chiasms that
possible. Flesh in this sense is a “general thing” integrate themselves according to different levels of
between the individual and the idea that does not generality. (1991, 352/2004, 307)
correspond to any traditional philosophical concept,
The ultimate ontological chiasm, that between the
sensible and the intelligible, is matched by an
ultimate epistemological chiasm, that of philosophy
itself. As Merleau-Ponty writes in a working note
from November 1960,
the idea of chiasm, that is: every relation with being
is simultaneously a taking and a being held, the hold
is held, it is inscribed and inscribed in the same
being that it takes hold of. Starting from there,
elaborate an idea of philosophy… . It is the
simultaneous experience of the holding and the held
in all orders. (V&I: 319/266; see also Saint Aubert
2005: 162–64)

Copyright © 2016 by
Ted Toadvine <tat30@psu.edu>

You might also like