You are on page 1of 8

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/313221261

Review of 'The Social Psychology of Morality'

Article · November 2016

CITATIONS READS
0 288

1 author:

Michael Klenk
Delft University of Technology
28 PUBLICATIONS   53 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

The (Meta-)Ethical Implications of Evolutionary Explanations of Morality View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Michael Klenk on 02 February 2017.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

Review of: Forgas, Joseph P.; Jussim, Lee; Van Lange, Paul A.M. (eds): The Social Psychology of

Morality. The Sydney Symposium of Social Psychology Series, Volume 18. Routledge, New York,

2016. Online at Metapsychology Online


Reviews

If you put chimpanzees from different communities together you can expect mayhem - they are not keen

on treating each other nicely. There is closely related species of apes, however, whose members have

countless encounters with unrelated specimen on a daily basis and yet almost all get through the day in

one piece - that species is us, homo sapiens. But what makes us get along, most of the time?

The first message of Fargas, Jussim, and Van Lange, the editors of this collection of essays on the

social psychology of morality, is that we get along because we have the ability to think and act in terms of

overarching moral rules; an ability they regard as one “defining hallmark[s] of our species”, so much that

we might as well be called “homo moralis,” the moral man (1). Their second message is that social

psychology occupies a “pivotal role” and a “privileged position” when it comes to understanding morality

because the foundations of morality are based on “predominantly social concerns”, such as fairness or

loyalty (2). Their aim is to provide an “informative and interesting” overview of the current status of this

“fascinating area of inquiry” (2, 16).

Morality as such is, perhaps surprisingly, not a mainstream research topic in social psychology.

Most textbooks in the field do not even mention the term morality at all (and focus on ‘prosociality’

instead). This relative lack of ‘coverage’ might have to do with the difficulty of operationalising

‘morality’ in a fitting way (more on this below). However, morality certainly is a social phenomenon and

therefore the collection of Fargas, Jussim, and Van Lange is certainly a step in the right direction; it offers

an extensive overview of the field and is suggestive of the vast potential of studying morality through the

lens of social psychology.

In the introduction, the editors provide useful background information about current social

psychological perspectives on morality as well as brief summaries of the seventeen essays contained in

1
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

the volume. The contributed essays are aimed at an academic, specialist audience and presuppose

knowledge of technical terms from social psychology and, in some articles, a basic understanding of

statistics. They are grouped under four headings: ‘The Nature of Moral Values and Decisions,' ‘Moral

Aspects of Interpersonal Behaviour,' ‘Ironic and Paradoxical Effects of Morality,’ and finally ‘Morality

and Collective Behaviour.’ Given the generality of these themes, the groupings are mostly justified but

not very informative. For example, all chapters somehow relate to the ‘Nature of Moral Values and

Decisions’ and obviously, this being social psychology, to the ‘Moral Aspects of Interpersonal

Behaviour’ and to ‘Morality and Collective Behaviour.' Aside from that, speaking about ‘Ironic and

Paradoxical Effects of Morality’ suggests that chapters under this heading contain normative claims about

certain outcomes being ‘immoral,' ‘ironic’ or ‘paradoxical,' which none of the essays actually does.

However, all chapters share a methodological commitment to study morality descriptively; that is,

none tells you what you should do but rather how and why people like you behave, feel, or think about

moral matters in social contexts in such-and-such ways. Most chapters address either of two major

themes.

The first is the study of the influencing factors on overt moral behaviour. Gawronski et al. use

experimental designs based on the trolley-dilemma to examine how individual’s action tendencies affect

decisions in moral dilemmas (’Understanding Responses to Moral Dilemmas’). Simpson et al. lay the

conceptual groundwork to study the interpersonal influences on moral behaviour by proposing testable

hypotheses about the determinants of moral intuitions in intimate relationships (’A Relational Perspective

of Social Influence on Moral Issues’). Galinsky & Lee review existing experimental findings of the

contextual influences on decisions in economic games, arguing that perspective-taking in competitive

contexts with conflicting interests leads to ‘unethical’ behaviour (’When Perspective Takers Turn

Unethical’). Forgas studies outcomes in games from experimental economics, like the ultimatum or the

dictator game, and shows persuasively that subjects induced with negative moods show less selfish

behaviour, measured by the amount of resources they share with others (’Affective Influences on Moral

Decisions’). Graziano & Schroeder speculate about possible determinants of prosociality (‘Sin, Morality,
2
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

and Opponent Motives for Prosocial Behaviour’). Crockett presents a computational model of moral

decisions, based on experiments with economic games, which models moral decisions on three

parameters (’Computational Modeling of Moral Decisions’). Von Hippel et al. focus the determinants of

leadership styles in groups and argue, based on a review of ethnographic and sociobiological findings,

that the presence of inequality within a group leads to ‘immoral’ leadership styles (’Of Baboons and

Elephants’).

The second theme is the study of the origins and correlational determinants of covert moral rules.

Laham & Corless employ exploratory factor analysis to determine the influence of threat-sensitivity on

neuroticism, a personality trait often reported to influence the moral and political values of individuals

(’Threat, Morality, and Politics’). Brandt et al. review existing studies and discuss the relation of self-

concepts on moral convictions (‘Moralization and Intolerance of Ideological Outgroups’). Psyzczynski

argues that the origins of moral rules can be partly explained by terror-management theory (‘God Save

Us’). Firmer assesses how groups create moral idols to motivate and navigate the members of the group;

an exemplary case of the pragmatic utility of adopting a moral system (’Groups Create Moral

Superheroes to Defend Sacred Values’). Miller & Monin offer a fine conceptual analysis of two separate

motivations to adhere to moral rules (’Moral Opportunities Versus Moral Tests’).

The remaining contributions do not fit the two major themes: Cooper presents own experimental

data and explains how social-psychological factors can lead people to confess to immoral acts – warning

us that people can be lead to make self-incriminating confessions even if the stakes are very high

(’Confessing To An Immoral Act’). Jussim et al. review research findings on controversial, normatively

‘loaded’ topics, like research on sex differences, and persuasively argue that moral rules can bias

researchers in interpreting their findings (’Can High Moral Purposes Undermine Scientific Integrity?’).

Fiedler takes the conduct of researchers in response to what he deems “haphazard standards and

instructions” (218) about good scientific conduct as a test case for the explanatory power of Kohlberg’s

moral rationalism (cf. Kohlber & Hersh 1977) and Moral Foundations Theory (cf. Graham et al. 2013),

arguing that neither fares very well in explaining this case (’Ethical Norms and Moral Values’). Haslam
3
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

similarly applies social psychology on a meta-level as an explanation of what he calls ‘concept creep’: his

review of the use of concepts like ‘abuse’ or ‘bullying’ shows that they are applied more phenomena and

to milder instances of their original referents, which he explains in terms of an expansion of the ‘moral

circle’ and an increased sensitivity to harm (’Concept Creep’). Bastian & Crimston assess what leads

people to assign moral values to resources and infer practical implications of this manifest tendency (’The

Moral Psychology of Resource Use’).

Naturally, each of the seventeen individual chapters offers more than what I could briefly

summarise here. Taken together, they form an impressive showcase of the manifold of topics related to

morality that is now being approached, in a nuanced manner, with the tools of social psychology. Below I

register a general concern about this approach and then highlight a contribution that exemplifies this error,

as well as one that stands out for being exceptionally insightful and suggestive of further research.

My general concern is the menacing problem of operationalising what counts as moral when

studying behaviour, convictions, or action-guiding rules. In short, we need to be careful about what we

end up studying when we ask about moral behaviour and the variety of dissimilar, and thus potentially

problematic, operationalisations of the concept found in this volume counsel caution about premature

optimism. For instance, the seven essays that address influences on overt moral behaviour work with four

different operationalisations of morality. ‘Morality’ is taken to be about actions or decisions taken in

scenarios that involve bodily harm to other people (e.g. in the trolley dilemma); about selfish vs. unselfish

behaviour in economic games, where keeping resources to yourself is dubbed ‘selfish’; about group-

serving vs. ‘self-serving’ behaviour in groups, where it is not clear what either concept amounts to; and

finally about prosociality, understood as actions valued by others.

I have no qualms with counting considerations about harm as moral. However, why think that

keeping all the money that you receive in a dictator game (where you are given, say, 10€ and are free to

decide how much to give to someone else) is immoral? It is selfish, sure, but drawing valid conclusions

about moral behaviour depends on whether we agree, on normative grounds, that we have a moral

obligation to share almost unconditionally. Hence, it is certainly a challenge for those interested in
4
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

research on morality to find out how empirically investigate morality, the real deal, and not just a masked

version of, say, pro-sociality.

The problem with unclear terms is evident in the contribution of Galinsky and Lee. They argue that

perspective taking (e.g. imagining the thoughts, feelings, and motivations of another person) can lead to

“unethical” behaviour in competitive contexts (133). What they find is, roughly, that subjects who gauge

the competitive intentions of their competitors are more likely to behave themselves competitively, too.

What is ‘unethical’ about that? Galinsky and Lee do not seem to be quite sure either, and so they describe

the apparent “immoral” (127) behaviour also in less-loaded terms such as “egoistically” (127), “selfish”

(131), or “antisocial” (134). Arguably, however, something being ‘antisocial,' understood along the lines

of ‘not welcome by other people’, is quite different from being ‘unethical’ - particularly in competitive

contexts. After all, everyone strives to do things unwelcome to their opponents, but few strive to behave

unethically.

Moreover, even if we agree that perspective taking sometimes leads to unethical behaviour, that

finding should not be surprising at all. The authors seem to be fighting a straw-men who, mistakenly,

suggests that perspective taking always leads to moral behaviour, or, worse still, that perspective-taking is

morally good in itself. But perspective taking in itself is normatively neutral: if you see a person with a

face-mask and a knife entering a shop, you might gauge the criminal intentions and call the police or you

might run away. But what is or isn’t ethical in that situation is what you do after you ‘took the

perspective’ of the would-be robber. Surely the authors would agree; and since they do not show that

anyone actually believes that perspective taking itself is a “royal road to morality,” their main claim is

rather blunt (126).

In contrast, a contribution that struck me as exceptionally insightful and relevant is by Gawronski

et al. Their findings challenge a widely held view about the determinants of utilitarian (outcome-based)

and deontological (norm-based) decisions through careful consideration of the operationalisations used in

experimental designs. They use an experimental design to study responses to the trolley dilemma: a

trolley is on track to five number of people standing on the track and respondents have to decide about
5
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

diverting the trolley to another track on which it would kill only one person (there are multiple variations

of this basic scenario). Usually, switching tracks, that is killing one instead of five, is interpreted as

making a ‘utilitarian,' outcome-based decision. Not switching is taken to be a deontological decision,

because, the reasoning goes, subjects judge that switching tracks would be akin to killing, which is

proscribed by forceful norms. Many findings suggested that cognitive load, for instance having to

memorise numbers during the task, increased the proportion of deontological judgements in trolley cases,

which is part of the evidence for the claim that characteristically deontological judgements are based on

emotional processes (e.g. Green 2008). However, Gawronski et al. included a check for general action

tendencies (that is, whether subjects prefer to act or stay passive) in their experiments and found that a

tendency for inaction often explained decisions that other researchers attributed to a preference for

deontological moral judgements. In contrast to that, Gawronski et al. show that “limited cognitive

resources influence moral judgements by inducing a general preference for inaction … rather than by

disrupting utilitarian assessments of outcomes or deontological assessments of norm violations” (105),

which should give some food for thought to fans of ‘trolleyology.’

In conclusion: the book is well worth reading for anyone interested in empirical approaches to

studying morality and for those who want to get an impression of the breadth of recent social

psychological research on the matter. All chapters reward the reader with interesting insights, based both

on new empirical data and novel reviews of existing findings. And while the problems mentioned above

suggest that we should not be satisfied yet with social psychology assuming its role as “the core discipline

for understanding morality,” the editors certainly achieved their goal of showcasing the current status of

social psychological research as “a thriving and productive field of inquiry” (16).

References

Graham J, Haidt J, Koleva S, Motyl M, Iyer R, Wojcik SP, Ditto PH (2013) Moral foundations theory:

The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 47:55–130

6
Michael Klenk, Utrecht University, m.b.o.t.klenk@uu.nl Review Forgas, Jussim, Lange 2016

Greene JD (2008) The secret joke of Kant's soul. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology: The

neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass,

pp 35–79

Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment.

Psychological Review 108(4):814–834.

Kohlberg L, Hersh RH (1977) Moral Development: A review of the theory. Theory Into Practice 16:53-

59 Kohlberg L, Hersh RH (1977) Moral Development: A review of the theory. Theory Into Practice

16:53-59

Michael Klenk, Ph.D. Candidate in Philosophy, Utrecht University, The Netherlands.

View publication stats

You might also like