You are on page 1of 21

r Academy of Management Review

2021, Vol. 46, No. 1, 172–191.


https://doi.org/10.5465/amr.2018.0161

A THEORY OF ETHICAL ACCOUNTING AND ITS


IMPLICATIONS FOR HYPOCRISY IN ORGANIZATIONS
PETER H. KIM
SCOTT S. WILTERMUTH
DAVID T. NEWMAN
University of Southern California

Management scholars have typically regarded the widespread instances of hypocrisy


across business, religious, and political institutions to be motivated and strategic. We
suggest, however, that hypocrisy may stem not only from people’s motivation to inter-
pret and utilize information in a self-serving manner but also from fundamental dif-
ferences in people’s access to that information itself. More specifically, we present a
multi-stage theory of ethical accounting (TEA) that describes how this differential access
to information, specifically about the self versus others, can create an interrelated series
of cognitive distortions in how people account for the same unethical behavior. TEA
posits that such distortions can allow people to believe they are being fair and consistent
when appraising the morality of the self and others while actually being inconsistent in
how they do so, and describes how this can ultimately make it harder to address not only
hypocrisy but also unethical behavior more broadly in organizations.

I. . . lived my life in a certain way to make sure that I objectionable than the same transgressions enacted
would never violate any law... certainly never any by others” (Valdesolo & DeSteno, 2008: 1334), has
criminal laws... and always maintained that most led scholars to provide a number of motivational
important to me was my integrity, was my character, explanations for this behavior. Evidence has indi-
were my values. cated, for example, that people can engage in moti-
—Kenneth Lay, Enron (CNN, 2004) vated reasoning that allows them to see their own
It is easy to assume that unethical actors are aware behavior in a more positive light compared to similar
of their own corruption. Yet there are many cases in behavior from others (Lammers, 2012). Findings
which these bad actors not only claim moral virtue have also suggested that people may condemn others
but condemn those who commit similar transgres- for behaviors they too have committed to show that
sions. In fact, we can readily find myriad examples of they have genuinely repented for their actions
such hypocrisy from members of our business, reli- (Barden, Rucker, & Petty, 2005). Moreover, other
gious, and political institutions. Kenneth Lay, the studies have portrayed hypocritical condemnation as
former CEO and chairman of Enron Corporation, for a form of “cheap talk” in which people seek to appear
example, repeatedly underscored the importance of moral while avoiding the cost of being moral (Batson,
integrity and moral values despite his engagement in Kobrynowicz, Dinnerstein, Kampf, & Wilson, 1997;
numerous counts of securities fraud (Johnson, 2003). Batson & Thompson, 2001; Batson, Thompson,
Jim Bakker, a former head of the PTL Christian Seuferling, Whitney, & Strongman, 1999; Mazar,
nonprofit broadcasting network, became famous for Amir, & Ariely, 2008), or to shift attention away from
preaching moral values despite his involvement in a their own improprieties to avoid punishment
sex scandal and accounting fraud (History, 2009). (Lönnqvist, Rilke, & Walkowitz, 2015). This evidence
Likewise, Newt Gingrich, former speaker of the thus clearly supports the notion that motivational
House of Representatives, led a Republican move- concerns can drive hypocrisy in many situations.
ment that underscored the importance of family We suggest, however, that such motivational in-
values despite his engagement in extramarital affairs fluences may not actually be necessary for this kind
(Tapper, 2007). of hypocrisy to occur. More specifically, we inves-
The pervasiveness of such hypocrisy, which has tigate whether: (a) differences in people’s access to
been defined as “a phenomenon in which individ- information about the self versus others can also
uals judge their own transgressions to be less morally drive hypocrisy by creating cognitive distortions in
172
Copyright of the Academy of Management, all rights reserved. Contents may not be copied, emailed, posted to a listserv, or otherwise transmitted without the copyright holder’s express
written permission. Users may print, download, or email articles for individual use only.
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 173

how people account for the same unethical behavior, raised to internalize their society’s moral standards
(b) such distortions can promote interpersonal hy- (Bandura, 1991), and that they are motivated to
pocrisy in ways that are unassociated with motiva- maintain the sense that, on the whole, they are good
tion, and (c) such effects can ultimately blind people people (Bryan, Adams, & Monin, 2013; Mazar et al.,
to the sense that they are acting hypocritically. These 2008; Monin & Miller, 2001; Sherman & Cohen,
possibilities are based on research documenting how 2002). Thus, violating moral principles can prove
actors and observers can differ in how they explain costly to the violator by threatening that sense of self-
the same behavior; findings have shown that such worth (Lanaj, Kim, Koopman, & Matta, 2018).
differences can arise not only from people’s inclina- Indeed, it is precisely for this reason that such vi-
tions to interpret information in a self-serving man- olators have been observed to engage in a variety of
ner but also from their differential access to that defensive rationalization efforts to diffuse that threat
information itself (Barresi, 2004; Knobe & Malle, in some way (Tsang, 2002). Bandura’s (1990, 1991)
2002; Malle, 2004, 2005). Indeed, these consider- theory of moral disengagement, for example, de-
ations raise the possibility that while hypocrisy may scribes how people may attempt to diffuse the threat
indeed be self-serving, nonmotivational factors posed by their own immoral behavior through a va-
based on this differential access to information may riety of techniques, including efforts to reframe the
ultimately drive hypocrisy as well. act in a more positive light, obscure one’s responsi-
We seek to illuminate these possibilities by propos- bility for the violation, or minimize the harm inflic-
ing a multi-stage theory of ethical accounting (TEA) ted on others (Bandura, Barbaranelli, Caprara, &
that describes how and when people’s greater infor- Pastorelli, 1996). Likewise, self-affirmation theory
mation regarding their own behavior can lead them to (Aronson, Cohen, & Nail, 1999; Sherman & Cohen,
consider that conduct to be less unethical than the 2002; Steele, 1998) describes how people can miti-
same behavior exhibited by others. We contend that gate this threat to self-worth not only by altering how
past research on hypocrisy has largely overlooked the their behavior is viewed but also by emphasizing
role of information-based differences in moral judg- positive aspects of the self that are unrelated to the
ment because studies in this literature have tended to provoking threat. Moreover, research on “bounded
focus either on how people evaluate their own actions ethicality,” which examines the psychological pro-
or how they evaluate the actions of others (e.g., Batson cesses that can lead people to act in ways that are
et al., 1999; Monin & Merritt, 2012), rather than on how inconsistent with their ethical values, has described
people might reconcile potential contradictions in how people can be motivated to protect themselves
these judgments. Indeed, by addressing this limitation through several processes, including the kinds of
our theory reveals that moral hypocrisy may not re- moral disengagement techniques detailed above (e.g.,
quire the kind of strategic pretense or willingness to Chugh, Bazerman, & Banaji, 2005; Moore, Tetlock,
be a hypocrite that prior accounts have suggested Tanlu, & Bazerman, 2006; Tenbrunsel, Diekmann,
(e.g., Lammers, Stapel, & Galinsky, 2010), and details Wade-Benzoni, & Bazerman, 2010).
how this can allow those engaging in hypocrisy to be- We suggest that these kinds of efforts to discount
lieve they are actually ethical. Thus, we suggest that one’s ethical transgressions may be complicated,
people can maintain this belief not only by rationaliz- however, when others engage in the same type of
ing their own unethical behavior (e.g., Bandura, 1990, behavior. Transgressors may certainly feel better
1991; Tsang, 2002) but also by making honest efforts to when they rationalize their own behavior, because
be fair and consistent when evaluating their own and they are alleviating the costs of self-sanction posed
others’ behavior that nevertheless fail. Finally, we ex- by violating their internalized moral standards.
plore how organizational contexts may influence However, they are unlikely to feel as good about
the way in which this ethical accounting unfolds and, others doing the same thing, because others’ moral
ultimately, what kinds of hypocrisy will arise in transgressions can also threaten the self (Wojciszke,
organizations. 2005). Indeed, a rapidly growing body of evidence
has underscored how people are not only less willing
to trust but also hardwired to punish others who vi-
THE (WOULD-BE) HYPOCRITE’S DILEMMA
olate ethical standards, due to the harm such trans-
One theoretical starting point for considering gressions can pose (de Quervain et al., 2004; Dirks,
these issues may be found in the notion that people Kim, Ferrin, & Cooper, 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002;
find the prospect of their own unethicality threat- Kim, Dirks, Cooper, & Ferrin, 2006; Kim, Ferrin,
ening. Scholars have observed that people have been Cooper, & Dirks, 2004). Moreover, it is difficult to
174 Academy of Management Review January

imagine how the threat posed by others’ transgres- one might explain the moral transgressions of an
sions would be assuaged by the notion that those individual (Bandura, 1990, 1991; Tsang, 2002), much
transgressors have somehow rationalized their ac- remains to be understood about how people can
tions. If anything, those rationalizations are likely to manage this dilemma of addressing the ethical con-
compound concerns about being harmed by such cerns posed by the self and others in the interper-
transgressions in the future. sonal domain. In this regard, the fact that past
These concerns create a dilemma where the same research has identified two broad psychological ex-
rationalization techniques one might use to avoid planations for why actors and observers might differ
self-condemnation for one’s own unethical behavior in how they explain the same behavior—motivation
can make it harder to condemn others for committing and information access (Barresi, 2004; Knobe &
the same kind of transgression, as it is unclear why Malle, 2002; Malle, 2004, 2005)—offers a clear path
those rationalizations would not apply to others as forward by suggesting that the hypocrisy literature
well. In such cases, it is certainly possible that people expand its focus beyond motivational explanations
may choose to prioritize either the desire to absolve to consider how people’s differential access to in-
themselves from blame or the desire to decry others’ formation might play a role.
transgressions. For example, people may persist in
rationalizing their unethicality for the sake of miti-
A MULTISTAGE THEORY OF
gating the threat of self-condemnation and simply
ETHICAL ACCOUNTING
accept that such rationalizations could allow others
to commit the same type of transgression (e.g., by We seek to address the abovementioned limitation
internalizing the norm that “everyone is doing it” through a multistage theory of ethical accounting.
[see Cialdini, Reno, & Kallgren, 1990]). Or they may More specifically, we begin with the long-standing
choose to focus on addressing the threat of harm from premise that people maintain a “balance sheet” of
others’ unethicality by condemning such behavior moral credits and debits to evaluate both the self and
and rejecting attempts to rationalize it, at the cost of others (Nisan, 1990). This moral balance sheet is
precluding the ability to rationalize their own ac- based on the notion that although people consider
tions. Indeed, suffering for one’s misdeed has been morality important, they do not require it to be per-
found to legitimize the right to warn others against fect. Instead, they treat behavior over time much like
committing it (Effron & Miller, 2015). Alternatively, a personal bank account, in the sense that a party can
people may choose to engage in deliberate moral earn moral credits (which add to this account) by
hypocrisy by knowingly rationalizing their own un- acting ethically, and incur moral debits (which are
ethical behavior while condemning the same be- charged to the account) by acting unethically, as long
havior from others, at the cost of the cognitive as the balance in that account does not fall below a
dissonance that would arise from such blatant in- baseline. This basic idea is at the core of the empir-
consistency (Stone, Wiegand, Cooper, & Aronson, ical work on moral credentialing (e.g., Effron, Miller,
1997) and at least an implicit awareness that they & Monin, 2012; Yam, Klotz, He, & Reynolds, 2017),
have been hypocrites. which has shown that individuals’ past moral be-
However, each of these choices also entails a sa- havior can license people to act in ambiguously
lient cost that makes it less than ideal. Although the racist and sexist ways. It is also consistent with
first and second options avoid moral hypocrisy, the Mazar and colleagues’ (2008) theory of self-concept
risk of harm from others committing the same type of maintenance, which asserts that people behave dis-
transgression and the challenge of facing one’s own honestly enough to profit but not so dishonestly that
immorality, respectively, are likely to remain nag- they would be forced to see themselves as dishonest.
ging concerns. In addition, though the option of en- The advantages of this ethical accounting system for
gaging in deliberate moral hypocrisy alleviates both a given individual arise not only from the opportu-
of these concerns, the cognitive dissonance this nity it affords that individual to engage in behaviors
would create can lead people to avoid that option that might otherwise threaten the individual’s moral
entirely (Stone et al., 1997). Hence, the motivation to identity, but also from the ability to use the exact
preserve a sense of self-worth may actually be self- same system to evaluate others and thereby legiti-
defeating as a cause of hypocrisy in judging others. mize the allowances the individual has made for
Accordingly, we suggest that although the types of themselves as consistent with generally held prin-
self-serving rationalizations that the ethics literature ciples rather than self-serving ones applicable only
has identified provide important insight into how to the self.
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 175

Our theory then extends this foundation by sug- perceivers’ general predisposition to trust as well as
gesting that this system of ethical accounting can be rapid cognitive cues arising from group membership,
influenced in at least four ways, via a sequence of reputations, and stereotypes (McKnight, Cummings,
self–other distortions that can allow a transgressor & Chervany, 1998). The trust literature has thus
to protect the self while attacking the immorality of considered how both informational factors and fac-
others. As we will detail, these self–other distortions tors more pertinent to perceivers’ motivated cog-
differ from the kinds of rationalizations that have nitions can affect this phenomenon, and thereby
been proposed by past research on hypocrisy in that constructed a more complete account of its causes by
they arise not from people’s self-serving motivations developing distinct theories to evaluate each side of
to protect the sense that they are good people but the coin. In contrast, while the ethics literature has
rather from more fundamental limitations in peo- recognized that both motivational and nonmotiva-
ple’s access to information about others as compared tional mechanisms can affect moral judgment (e.g.,
to the self. We therefore build on research showing Bazerman & Tenbrunsel, 2011), research on hypoc-
how judgments of the self and others may differ for risy has focused almost exclusively on the implica-
reasons other than the desire to see oneself positively tions of motivation-based rationalizations.1 Thus, to
(e.g., Kruger & Gilovich, 2004), as well as evidence the extent that both motivational and nonmotiva-
that actors’ and observers’ explanations for the same tional mechanisms can affect hypocrisy, our theory’s
behavior can differ because actors generally have concerted attention to nonmotivational influences
greater insight into their reasons for acting than do seems long overdue.
observers (Buss, 1978; Locke & Pennington, 1982; We can represent this multistage TEA diagram-
Malle et al., 2007). Thus, our theoretical model as- matically as a series of four evaluations (see Figure 1).
sesses how these kinds of differences in people’s The first evaluation (Unethicality) differentiates ac-
access to information about the self versus others tions by distinguishing those that are ethical from
can prompt cognitive distortions in their ethical ac- those that are unethical and thus considered debits
counting and subsequently cause moral hypocrisy in that might be charged to one’s moral account. The
ways the literature has largely failed to consider. second evaluation (Liability) then differentiates un-
We further suggest that such distortions allow ethical actions (moral debits) by distinguishing those
people to believe they are being fair and consistent for which one is not accountable from those for
when appraising the morality of the self and others, which one is accountable and thus are actually en-
even while their judgments are inconsistent insofar tered as liabilities against one’s character in one’s
as they are harsher on others than they are on the self moral balance sheet. The third evaluation (Insol-
for the same behavior. We posit that this system of vency), in turn, differentiates unethical actions for
ethical accounting can, in effect, allow people to which one is accountable (moral liabilities) by dis-
become moral hypocrites without being aware of it, tinguishing those that would not be weighed more
and thus gain the benefits of such hypocrisy (i.e., by heavily than the moral credits in one’s moral balance
alleviating the threat posed by one’s own immoral sheet from those that would be weighed more
behavior) without its typical costs (i.e., arising from heavily than this past history of ethical behavior
the knowledge that one has indeed been a hypocrite). and thus bring the value of one’s moral balance
These notions do not entail that more inten- sheet below zero (i.e., such that the transgressor be-
tional, motivation-based mechanisms are irrelevant. comes morally bankrupt). Finally, the last evaluation
Rather, our theory recognizes that both motivational
and nonmotivational influences can cooccur and
1
work in conjunction to drive hypocrisy in a manner Even in the one case we could find where this litera-
similar to what has been described by the literature ture has considered the potential implications of a non-
on trust. More specifically, the trust literature has motivational mechanism for hypocrisy (i.e., construal
observed that people strive to evaluate trustworthi- level theory), this mechanism was simply subsumed
within a broader motivation-based argument based on
ness based on information about the target’s trust-
people’s desire to see themselves in a positive light
relevant characteristics, such as the party’s compe-
(Tenbrunsel et al., 2010:163). Such efforts to force-fit this
tence, integrity, and benevolence (Mayer, Davis, & kind of nonmotivational mechanism into a motivation-
Schoorman, 1995). However, this literature has based argument, and the theoretical confusion this can
also revealed that trust can be formed quite quickly, cause, further highlights the need to consider explicitly the
even in the absence of any real information about nonmotivational mechanisms that can drive hypocrisy, as
the target, due to a host of other factors, including our theory strives to do.
176 Academy of Management Review January

FIGURE 1
A Theory of Ethical Accounting
Core Questions

Unethicality
Is the behavior
unethical?

Liability
Is the actor liable?
Cognitive and Strategic and
informational motivated
limitations Insolvency reasoning
Do the actor’s moral
credits offset the
transgression?

Incompensability
Could condemning
others compensate
for the behavior?

(Incompensability) differentiates unethical actions each evaluation is set. More specifically, for judg-
for which one is accountable and that would out- ments of the self the threshold for each evaluation
weigh the moral credits in one’s moral balance sheet can be relatively high in the sense that people’s dif-
(causing insolvency) by distinguishing those which ferential access to information about the self versus
may be counterbalanced by condemning others from others can make each stage a meaningful hurdle to be
those that cannot. surmounted. In contrast, for judgments of others the
The sequential nature of these evaluations thus threshold for each evaluation can be relatively low in
reflects the notion that each evaluation does not be- the sense that these same differences in people’s
come relevant until an action meets the threshold of access to information can make each stage compar-
the evaluation immediately preceding it. For exam- atively easy to breach. The ultimate effect of such
ple, if the action is not deemed to be unethical differences is that although the exact same system of
(debitable), there is little need to determine whether ethical accounting may be used to evaluate the self
the focal actor is liable. Likewise, if the action is and others, and thus foster the view that one has been
unethical, but the transgressor is not considered li- fair, consistent, and impartial, its implications for
able for that action, there would be little reason to how the self versus others are viewed may ultimately
consider whether it would outweigh the moral differ, for the reasons detailed further below.
credits in that transgressor’s balance sheet. More- Of course, this proposed framework does not pre-
over, only when an action is considered unethical, clude the notion people may also be motivated
the transgressor is considered liable, and the action to engage in self-serving rationalizations. In fact,
brings the transgressor’s moral balance sheet below greater insight into such influences may be obtained
zero does the need to compensate for that moral de- by treating the sequence of evaluations in our theory
ficiency arise. of ethical accounting as a recursive process through
Finally, we suggest that the manner in which which conclusions drawn from prior evaluations can
people evaluate potentially unethical actions vis- ultimately affect subsequent iterations of the ethical
à-vis these four stages differs for judgments of the self accounting cycle. That is, even if people begin with
as compared to others, as a result of differences in an open mind when evaluating an ethically ques-
people’s access to information about each, and that tionable behavior and its implications for the tar-
these differences can affect where the threshold for get person, the outcomes of those evaluations may
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 177

ultimately affect their judgments of that party’s sub- utilitarianism may thus conclude that it would be
sequent actions by creating the motivation for people morally acceptable to lie, for example, if doing so
to confirm their earlier assessments (Nickerson, keeps the inquirer from committing a murder. In
1998). This could occur by inducing people to alter contrast, deontological perspectives might hold that
their own behavior to make such conclusions more the lie would be wrong regardless of the life that
likely (e.g., by attending to different kinds of infor- would be saved, because lying would not be a prac-
mation about the target, changing the kinds of situ- tice that people would want others to follow. Lying,
ations they seek out, acting in ways that might affect even in that instance, might contradict Kant’s cate-
the kinds of information they elicit from others, and gorical imperative, which commands: “Act only in
adjusting the thresholds they set for each of the four accordance with that maxim through which you can
stages of evaluation in our theory). People may also at the same time will that it become a universal law”
make inferences about a target for reasons that have (Kant, 1785: 402). As such, the debate between these
little to do with that party’s past behavior (e.g., due to two ethical perspectives has generally been presented
inherent predispositions to see that target in a more as an either–or decision between two (sometimes
or less positive light, as well as rapid cognitive cues incompatible) views about how moral appraisals
arising from group membership and stereotypes). By should occur.
doing so, they will have, in effect, acted as if they had We suggest, however, that the long-standing de-
engaged in prior iterations of the ethical accounting bate regarding which of these two normative per-
process even when they had not. This too should spectives should be used to determine the ethicality
motivate people to confirm those initial inferences of an act offers less insight into how people might
when evaluating that target through their subsequent appear to use them in practice. To be sure, past re-
information acquisition and evaluation behavior. search has considered how certain behavioral con-
Our theory therefore not only acknowledges, but siderations, such as individuals’ emotions and
can also account for, the notion that motivational and intuitions, can lead them to behave in a manner that
informational factors can interact to produce hy- is inconsistent with the normative perspective they
pocrisy. However, the central issue we seek to ex- might otherwise advocate (Greene, Summerville,
plore in this paper is that interpersonal hypocrisy Nystrom, & Cohen, 2001; Haidt, 2001). However, the
does not require such motivations, and may even be notion that individuals may believe they are con-
more easily sustained without them, given that this sistent in their approach to evaluating morality but
can help individuals avoid the discomforting reali- ultimately act as if they endorse different normative
zation that they have been hypocrites. We will perspectives when judging remarkably similar ac-
therefore begin our consideration of these issues by tions is underexplored. Notably, we are agnostic as to
discussing each of the four stages of evaluation in our whether people are actually inconsistent in their
proposed theory of ethical accounting in turn. underlying endorsement of these normative per-
spectives; our central claim here is that this may
simply appear to be the case based on their behavior.
Unethicality
Thus, we suggest that even if people use the same
The first stage in this system concerns the assess- consequentialist reasoning for the self and others,
ment of whether a given action is ethical or unethi- differences in their access to information about their
cal. In this regard, both normative theories of ethics own and others’ behavior may still produce differ-
in philosophy and contemporary models of moral ences in how they evaluate the same action by each.
judgment in the social sciences have focused on two In particular, we propose that whereas individuals
dominant perspectives for evaluating the morality tend to act in a manner that makes it appear as if they
of an act—consequentialism and deontology. Con- evaluate their own actions as consequentialists
sequentialist perspectives, such as utilitarianism, (i.e., by seeming to focus on the net overall implica-
contend that an act should be considered right or tions of that action), they also tend to act as in a
wrong based solely on its net outcomes (e.g., whether manner that makes it appear as if they evaluate
it does more good than bad on the whole) (Bentham, others’ actions as deontologists (i.e., by seeming to
1781), whereas deontological perspectives contend focus on whether the action violates a moral duty)
that the morality of an act should instead be based on (Proposition 1).
whether it adheres to a set of rules, duties, and obli- This claim is based on several considerations.
gations that are considered foundational to morality First, individuals have been found not only to be
(Kant, 1785). A consequentialist perspective such as more familiar with the situational factors affecting
178 Academy of Management Review January

their own decisions than the decisions of others action (Tversky & Kahneman, 1991). Observers, on
(e.g., Ross, 1977), but also to have more insight into the other hand, may find it harder to appreciate the
the immediate reasons behind their behavior (Malle negative outcomes that might have occurred or to
et al., 2007). Hence, individuals may have a better believe that the ethically questionable action was the
sense of not only the potential costs of engaging in an only way in which that negative outcome could have
ethically questionable action but also the potential been avoided. Indeed, even if the actor tries to justify
benefits. As a result, they should be more likely to their actions by underscoring these overlooked or
account for those potential benefits when they are underappreciated implications, observers are likely
judging themselves than when they are judging to discount those justifications as self-serving (Kim
others for the same behavior. For example, a manager & Harmon, 2014).
may embezzle funds to pay for a relative’s medical Finally, even when the same information is avail-
care and consider this justified in light of the benefits able to actors and observers regarding an ethically
to that relative outweighing the losses to the firm. questionable action, they may nevertheless differ
However, observers who discover the embezzlement in their ability to consider it. Research on construal
are less likely to be aware of how those stolen funds level theory has suggested that a sense of psy-
would be used and would therefore be more likely chological distance can lead individuals to view a
than the manager to evaluate the morality of the act situation more abstractly (i.e., in terms of its super-
based primarily on the wrong that was committed. In ordinate mental representations that focus on its
this way, one might observe that even if individuals central features) and pay less attention to specific,
support the use of consequentialism to evaluate both concrete details and particularities (Trope &
their own and others’ behaviors as a normative Liberman, 2010). Thus, given that individuals are
principle, the information asymmetry we have de- also more psychologically distant from the actions of
scribed may ultimately lead them to behave more others than from their own, they should be less likely
like consequentialists for the self than for others in to attend to the particular positive and negative im-
practice. plications or details of an ethically questionable ac-
This apparent tendency to evaluate the self conse- tion, and more likely to focus instead on the question
quentially but others deontologically may further- of whether it violates a core moral principle (i.e., an
more be exacerbated by the fact that the costs and abstraction), when the action has been committed by
benefits of an ethically questionable action may differ others as opposed to by the self. Hence, the proposed
in time, certainty, and observability. A CEO, for ex- tendency for individuals to appear as if they evaluate
ample, might mislead a prospective investor to give their own actions as consequentialists, but evaluate
the struggling company a better chance of survival and others’ actions as deontologists, may arise from dif-
thereby keep hundreds of people employed. Yet this ferences not only in the objective availability of, but
decision involves initiating an unquestionably harm- also cognitive access to, information.2
ful action with only the hope of a beneficial return. These considerations collectively help to explain
Even if this action seems morally justifiable when an how people’s evaluations of ethically questionable
individual makes that decision, it can seem morally acts can fundamentally differ depending on whether
unjustified by those who learn of it afterward, partic- they were committed by the self or others. Indeed,
ularly if the anticipated benefits of that action fail to they suggest that, even if people strive to be fair,
occur and observers overestimate the extent to which
the actor should have known this would be the case 2
This principle is also consistent with other research on
(Roese & Vohs, 2012). In such circumstances, ob- moral judgment, which has suggested that people are more
servers may evaluate such actions not in terms of likely to think deeply about, and thereby exhibit more
their anticipated costs and benefits but rather in terms consequentialist reasoning for, their own ethical dilemmas
of the outcomes that actually occurred. than the ethical dilemmas of others (Greene et al., 2001).
Moreover, even if the anticipated benefits from an And though another paper has suggested that people may
instead use more consequentialist reasoning for judgments
ethically questionable action are achieved, those
of others than the self (Aguilar, Brussino, & Fernández-
realized benefits may go unnoticed or underappre-
Dols, 2013), this appears to be due to the specific manner in
ciated by observers, to the extent that those benefits which Aguilar and colleagues (2013) operationalized their
concern the avoidance of negative outcomes and the studies (i.e., by focusing on ethical dilemmas in which
maintenance of the status quo. For those making removing personal involvement, by imagining another
such decisions, the potential for losses may loom party in that role, they allowed respondents to feel less
quite large when evaluating the net outcomes of an responsible for the harm they might cause).
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 179

consistent, and impartial, and to avoid self-serving of the actor’s moral character (and thereby count it as a
rationalizations, they are likely to keep their own moral liability in the proposed ethical accounting
ethically questionable actions from reaching the system) when the act was committed by others rather
threshold of unethicality at the first stage in our the- than by the self (Proposition 2).
ory, even as they judge others’ similar actions to be This proposition is based on the potential for
unethical, with the latter assessment subsequently actor–observer differences to arise through at least
raising the question of liability as detailed below. three mechanisms that have been found to affect peo-
ple’s ability to make character inferences (Uhlmann
et al., 2015). First, acts that are considered statistically
Liability
rare or otherwise extreme are generally perceived to be
The matter of liability, depicted by the second more informative of the actor’s underlying character
stage in Figure 1, concerns whether the unethical than are acts that are more common (Ditto & Jemmott,
behavior is one for which the actor should be 1989; Fiske, 1980). However, research on the “false
held responsible (Pizarro & Tannenbaum, 2011), and consensus effect” has shown that people tend to
is thus counted as a moral liability on the actor’s overestimate the extent to which their own opinions,
balance sheet in the proposed ethical accounting beliefs, preferences, and values are normal and widely
system. This question moves beyond the traditional shared (Gilovich, 1990; Marks & Miller, 1987). For this
focus by normative theories of ethics on the moral- reason, they are likely to assume that their own ex-
ity of a given act (i.e., based on the principles treme behaviors, such as their transgressions, are more
of consequentialism or deontology) to consider common than is really the case, and thus consider
whether the act tells us something about the actor’s those behaviors to be less informative of their own
moral character (Morse & Cohen, 2017; Pizarro & underlying character, compared to the same extreme
Tannenbaum, 2011). Up to now, this latter consid- behaviors initiated by other people.
eration has been presented as a third perspective on Second, acts that can be more easily attributed to
morality, a person-centered approach known as vir- multiple possible causes, and are thus high in attri-
tue ethics, that represents an alternative to the con- butional ambiguity, tend to be considered less in-
sequentialist and deontological perspectives that formative of an actor’s underlying character (Snyder,
dominate ethics scholarship (Uhlmann, Pizarro, & Kleck, Strenta, & Mentzer, 1979). However, research
Diermeier, 2015). However, we suggest that this on the “fundamental attribution error” has revealed
question of what an act might tell us about the actor’s that people are more likely to be aware of multiple
moral character should be treated as a complement, influences on their own behavior than on the be-
rather than an alternative, to the matter of evaluating havior of others (Gilbert & Malone, 1995). Accord-
the morality of the act itself. ingly, one might expect that people would ultimately
More specifically, our proposed theory of ethical perceive greater attributional ambiguity when judg-
accounting suggests that the assessment of whether a ing their own behavior, and thus consider that be-
given action is ethical or unethical (i.e., the Unethi- havior less informative of underlying character, than
cality stage in Figure 1) does not obviate the need to they would when judging the behavior of others.
consider what that act might tell us about the actor’s Finally, acts that seem to arise quickly and easily
character, or vice versa. Rather, it is only by consider- are considered more informative of the actor’s un-
ing an act to be ethical or unethical that one may sub- derlying character than are those that involve more
sequently ask whether that act sheds light on how good difficult reflection (Crichter, Inbar, & Pizarro, 2013;
or bad the actor is. Even if an act is considered uneth- Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Green, & Lerner, 2000). Yet, if
ical (e.g., under consequentialist or deontological the reasoning underlying Proposition 1 is correct,
principles) and thus crosses the threshold for unethi- people are more likely to be aware of the costs and
cality, the question remains as to whether that moral benefits pertinent to their own, rather than others’,
debit should be counted against the actor’s moral ethically questionable actions. In that case, these
character (i.e., as a moral liability). In this regard, we people may in turn believe that those actions are on
likewise suggest that individuals address this latter the whole more indicative of situational consider-
question in inherently different ways for the self versus ations, and thus less informative of underlying
others, even when they avoid the motivated ration- character, when evaluating their own behavior ver-
alizations entailed by deliberate acts of hypocrisy. In sus the behavior of others.
particular, we propose that individuals are likely to All of these factors combine to suggest that people
consider the same unethical act to be more informative are less likely to consider their own unethical actions
180 Academy of Management Review January

to be informative of their moral character (and thus behaviors depending on their incentives and op-
less likely to count them as liabilities on their moral portunities. For this reason, a single ethical act is
balance sheet) compared to the actions of others. typically discounted as a signal of morality, given
Hence, for the self, people are less likely to treat the that those who are moral or immoral can each act
unethical action as something for which they are morally in certain situations (e.g., when there are
responsible and thereby succeed in keeping that ac- benefits for acting morally or sufficient surveillance
tion from posing further threats to their moral iden- to deter immoral acts). However, a single unethical
tity. However, for others, the action is more likely to act is typically considered a reliable signal of im-
be considered a moral liability and thus raise the morality, given the belief that only immoral indi-
subsequent question of insolvency detailed below. viduals would behave in unethical ways.
While this reasoning has been well-supported and
found to play an important role in determining how
Insolvency
people evaluate others (Pizarro & Tannenbaum,
The question of insolvency, depicted by the third 2011; Tannenbaum, Uhlmann, & Diermeier, 2011),
stage in Figure 1, concerns the manner in which an we suggest that people may weigh ethical and un-
actor’s history of ethical and unethical behaviors, for ethical behavior less asymmetrically when evaluat-
which that actor is liable, is ultimately weighed to ing the self. This is because much of what drives
assess the actor’s moral character (specifically, to people’s tendency to weigh negative information
assess whether that moral balance sheet is negative). about morality more heavily than positive informa-
As such, this question moves beyond the evaluation tion about morality when evaluating others stems
of single acts to consider how the transgression from informational constraints that are less likely to
under evaluation combines with other acts to deter- arise when evaluating one’s own behavior. In par-
mine a person’s overall moral character. In particular, ticular, classic attribution theories suggest that when
it raises the notion that because any person’s past be- considering whether others’ ethical or unethical acts
havior is likely to comprise both ethical acts (which, if are due to dispositional or situational factors, per-
considered informative of character, might be entered ceivers attempt to subtract the effect of the situation
into the balance sheet as moral assets) and unethical and attribute what remains to the individual (Kelley,
acts (which, if considered informative of character, 1973). However, because societal laws, rules, and
might be counted as moral liabilities), one must ulti- norms are generally designed to promote ethical
mately determine how such behaviors should be principles (Haidt & Kesebir, 2010), this makes it
reconciled when evaluating whether someone is easier to identify situational explanations when be-
moral or immoral on the whole (i.e., whether the target haviors are ethical than when they are unethical, and
person’s balance sheet of moral assets and liabilities is thereby to infer that ethical behaviors are less infor-
ultimately positive or negative). mative (versus unethical behaviors) of the actors’
This matter of how people weigh positive and moral character.
negative information about morality has received We have also previously noted (in the section ti-
marked attention by research on interpersonal per- tled Liability) that people are much more aware of
ception and a growing body of research on trust re- the extent to which situational forces affect their
pair (e.g., Dirks et al., 2011; Kim, Cooper, Dirks, & own behavior than the behavior of others (Gilbert &
Ferrin, 2013; Kim, Diekmann, & Tenbrunsel, 2003; Malone, 1995). Moreover, evidence has indicated
Madon, Jussim, & Eccles, 1997; Martijn, Spears, Van that people are more aware of their own, versus
der Plight, & Jakobs, 1992). More specifically, this others’, intentions (Kruger & Gilovich, 2004). Hence
literature has observed that people tend to weigh individuals should: (a) be better able to identify sit-
negative information about morality much more uational influences that may affect not only their
heavily than positive information about morality own ethical behavior, but also their own unethical
due to their reliance on hierarchically restrictive behavior; (b) be more aware of the intentions un-
schemas, which assume that being at one end of a derlying such ethical and unethical actions; and (c)
continuum will restrict one’s behavior, whereas be- thus tend to give their ethical and unethical actions
ing at the other end will not (Reeder & Brewer, 1979). more equal weight when assessing their own versus
In particular, people intuitively believe that those others’ moral character. We therefore propose that
with high morality will refrain from unethical be- whereas individuals are likely to weigh unethical
haviors in any situation, whereas those with low behaviors (moral liabilities) more heavily than ethi-
morality may exhibit either ethical or unethical cal behaviors (moral assets) when evaluating the
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 181

morality of others (i.e., by weighing unethical be- Incompensability


haviors more heavily than ethical behaviors), they
Finally, the matter of incompensability, depicted
will weigh unethical and ethical behaviors more
by the fourth stage in Figure 1, concerns the question
symmetrically when evaluating the morality of the
of whether one can rectify one’s own moral inade-
self (Proposition 3). Note that we are not proposing
quacy (insolvency) by condemning others who have
that people weigh their own ethical acts and uneth-
been similarly unethical. In particular, it builds on
ical acts equally when judging themselves, but in-
the notion that people evaluate a person’s moral
stead that the difference between the weights will be
character according to that party’s balance sheet of
smaller for the self than for others. Therefore, when
moral assets and liabilities (i.e., arising from that
people evaluate others, unethical behaviors are more
individual’s responsibility for ethical and unethical
likely to overrun the moral balance sheet into the
negative, whereas people are less likely, as a general behaviors, respectively) by raising the question of
rule, to see themselves as ethically insolvent. whether a moral shortcoming (liability) in that bal-
Insolvency concerns thus go beyond simply de- ance sheet can be rectified, not only by engaging in
termining whether an individual should be held re- ethical acts (as discussed in the section titled Insol-
sponsible for an unethical action, to suggest that vency) but also by condemning others’ similar moral
people also gauge the importance of transgressions shortcomings. This possibility is raised by the notion
relative to the transgressor’s past history of behaviors that the condemnation of unethical acts may not only
to assess that individual’s moral character. This no- deter others from this kind of behavior in the future
tion is consistent with the premise that people per- but also signal that one has become less tolerant of,
form a mental calculus in which they count ethical and thus more likely to have corrected, this kind of
behaviors as moral assets and unethical behaviors as shortcoming in the self. Hence, those engaging in
moral liabilities when evaluating morality (Nisan, such condemnation after committing an unethical
1990), but then raises the further possibility that act might believe that the moral liability in question
people weigh moral liabilities more heavily than has been counterbalanced (i.e., by having earned a
moral assets for others but not for the self. In this moral asset from discouraging others from doing the
regard, one might note that people may also simply same thing) or erased (i.e., by having corrected this
care about others’ immorality more than they care shortcoming and thereby no longer considering it a
about their own (Wojciszke, 2005), because the for- reflection of their own moral identity).
mer may pose a greater threat to their self-interest, We suggest, however, that efforts to condemn others
and that this interest-based mechanism may also to address one’s own moral shortcomings may prove
lead people to weigh others’ immoral behavior more far less acceptable when that same tactic is used by
heavily. However, this kind of interest-based ac- others. Indeed, rather than compensate for or erase the
count does not address the fact that people also seek shortcoming, such efforts may actually compound
to avoid the sense that they have been hypocrites perceivers’ concerns about being harmed by those
(Stone et al., 1997). It is only by moving beyond this others and strike perceivers as the epitome of moral
kind of motivational explanation to consider how hypocrisy. This notion is supported by evidence that
differences in people’s access to information can af- people believe others are less entitled to advise against
fect evaluations of the self versus others that one can committing a transgression when those others have
see how they might weigh information about ethical themselves committed the transgression, and thus
and unethical behaviors differently for such targets respond with anger and derogation, especially if those
while nevertheless believing they have been fair others have not paid a price for the transgression they
and consistent in assessing their own and others’ had committed (Effron & Miller, 2015).
morality.3 We further propose that the potential for people to
differentially evaluate their own versus others’ con-
3
demnation of those who have engaged in similar
In fact, the kinds of differences in people’s access to transgressions may arise from an egocentric differ-
information we have described that lead people to consider
ence in how people conduct their ethical accounting
negative information about morality more diagnostic than
positive information about morality when evaluating
for such actions. More specifically, past research on
others, but not the self, may actually help explain why how people manage their moral assets and liabilities
one’s own immoral behavior has been observed to pose less to maintain a sense of self-worth has typically treated
of a threat to one’s self-interest than the immoral behavior this process as a matter of weighing the good and bad
of others (Wojciszke, 2005). a focal individual has done vis-à-vis a “generalized”
182 Academy of Management Review January

other. For example, people may believe that by distortions can lead people to believe that they are
earning a moral asset through the ethical treatment of being fair and consistent when appraising the mo-
one person they are freer to incur a moral liability by rality of the self and others, while actually being in-
behaving unethically toward an entirely different consistent in how they do so. It details how people
individual (e.g., Monin & Miller, 2001). Accordingly, may engage in the exact same sequence of evalua-
people may likewise believe they can compensate for tions regardless of the target. Moreover, it considers
an unethical act they have committed toward one how differences in not only the objective availability
person by condemning other individuals who en- of but also cognitive access to information can lead
gage in unethical acts, and thereby reduce the pros- individuals to reach more favorable conclusions in
pect of those other individuals engaging in future each assessment for the self than for others. By doing
transgressions, despite the fact that this condemnation so, it describes how each of the four stages of evalu-
may do little to help the person they have personally ation represents a significant line of defense that can
harmed. Hence, when people face a shortcoming that not only lead people to believe in their own moral
threatens to bring about moral insolvency, they may adequacy but also help foster the sense that others
consider it reasonable to compensate by condemning who may have engaged in the same kind of poten-
the unethical actions of others. tially unethical behavior are irredeemably immoral.
Yet research on the egocentric bias (e.g.,
Thompson & Loewenstein, 1992) has suggested that
ORGANIZATIONAL CONSIDERATIONS
when the individual seeking to compensate is not the
self, but rather another transgressor, the relevant These concerns warrant particular attention from
consideration may shift from how that individual those seeking to deter the rise of hypocrisy in or-
has managed their moral assets and liabilities with a ganizations at both individual and organizational
“generalized” other to how that party has managed levels.
this balance with the self. In particular, given that the
moral transgressions of others can threaten the self,
Individual-Level Implications
those evaluating such transgressors may expect such
transgressors to make up for that behavior in some At the individual level, a range of organizational
way. However, if those transgressors attempt to do so factors could affect how hypocrisy develops. As-
by condemning the unethical behavior of others, sessments of unethicality, for example, may be af-
such attempts may threaten the self as well, to the fected by one’s level in the organizational hierarchy.
extent that the self too can often fall short of moral Most firms rely on at least some form of hierarchy,
perfection and may be subject to criticism (Nisan, in which some members are ranked above others
1990). In such cases, rather than consider a trans- according to their status or authority (Galbraith,
gressor’s attempt to condemn the unethical behavior 1977). This design is intended to allow higher-
of others to be beneficial (and thus a moral asset that ranking members to oversee and coordinate the ef-
may reduce the transgressor’s ethical liability), peo- forts of lower-ranking members who are tasked with
ple may feel that such an effort actually compounds completing a narrower and more specific set of
the harm that the initial transgression posed. These duties. One might consequently expect that being
considerations ultimately suggest that although further up in an organizational hierarchy is likely
people may believe that they can gain moral assets or to increase the range of demands, goals, and stake-
erase their own moral liabilities by condemning the holders that must be considered, and thereby
unethical actions of others, people are less likely to heighten the need to consider the potential tradeoffs
believe that others may gain moral assets or erase (both costs and benefits) of one’s actions. In such a
their moral liabilities through the same kind of con- case, higher-ranking organizational members may be
demnation (Proposition 4). For this reason, acts that more likely to evaluate their own actions as con-
threaten to cause moral insolvency are more likely to sequentialists compared to members lower in the
be seen as incompensable when they are committed hierarchy, even if the tendency to evaluate others’
by others than when they are committed by the self. actions as deontologists remains unchanged. Thus,
possessing a more elevated hierarchical position
may increase the extent to which organizational
Summary
members exhibit moral hypocrisy in their assess-
The theory of ethical accounting we have pro- ments of unethicality (in the manner detailed by
posed thus describes how a series of self–other Proposition 1).
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 183

Relatedly, differences in organizational members’ tendency should, furthermore, be particularly sig-


span of control may affect their assessments of lia- nificant for those who have established a longer
bility. Span of control concerns the range of duties history of ethical behavior and thereby accumulated
organizational members are charged with perform- a larger number of moral assets that would be erased
ing. Though members’ span of control may correlate or discounted. Hence, people may discount more
to some degree with their hierarchical position, positive information about ethicality, relative to
the span of control can also be altered even when negative information about ethicality, when evalu-
their position in the hierarchy remains unchanged ating others whose history of ethical behavior is long
(Galbraith, 1977). Differences in span of control versus short, even though their tendency to weigh
warrant consideration because organizational mem- their own ethical and unethical behaviors more
bers may find it easier to see themselves as just a symmetrically remains unchanged. Thus, organiza-
small part of a larger system as their span of control tional members may exhibit greater moral hypocrisy
narrows. Moreover, to the extent that a narrower with regard to the assessment of insolvency (in the
span of control represents a type of situational con- manner detailed by Proposition 3) when evaluating
straint, and people tend to be more aware of the those who have established a longer track record of
situational constraints impinging on their own be- prior ethical behavior in the organization.
havior than the behavior of others (e.g., Ross, 1977), Another issue that warrants consideration is how
they should in turn be more likely to consider a members’ degree of network centrality may affect their
narrow span of control a mitigating factor when assessments of incompensability. Network centrality
gauging responsibility for their own versus others’ concerns the extent to which one is connected to other
unethical behavior. Hence, organizational members members in a network, and is generally treated as an
may be less likely to consider themselves responsi- indicator of one’s importance in that social system
ble for unethical behavior as their span of control (Ibarra & Andrews, 1993). As such, those with greater
narrows, even if their tendency to consider others network centrality may believe that they can exert a
responsible for similar acts remains unchanged. broader influence on that network, and thereby expect
Thus, possessing a narrower span of control may that their efforts to condemn unethical behavior would
ultimately increase the extent to which these mem- exert a broader deterrent effect. If so, those who are
bers exhibit moral hypocrisy in their assessments of more central in a network may be more likely to treat
liability (in the manner detailed by Proposition 2). their condemnation of others’ unethical behavior as a
Furthermore, differences in members’ track record moral asset that may counterbalance the moral liabili-
of prior ethical behavior in the organization may af- ties incurred by their own unethical acts, relative to
fect assessments of insolvency. A track record of those who are less central, while in each case dis-
prior ethical behavior entails a greater accumulation missing the notion that others’ efforts to condemn un-
of moral assets, which may then be used to justify ethical behavior would serve as similar compensation.
subsequent ethical violations (e.g., Monin & Miller, Hence, greater network centrality may ultimately
2001). In addition, as previously noted, these moral increase the extent to which organizational members
assets may license people to perform subsequent exhibit moral hypocrisy in their assessments of
unethical acts, so long as their moral balance sheet incompensability (in the manner detailed by Prop-
of assets and liabilities is not “overdrawn” (Nisan, osition 4).
1990). Yet, to the extent that even a single unethical Finally, the level of members’ group or organiza-
act by others can lead to the judgment that those tional identification may affect the very basis upon
others are immoral (see Proposition 3), people may which these distinctions between the self and others
ultimately view those others’ prior ethical behaviors are made. More specifically, identifying with a broader
in a different way. In particular, the conclusion that collective may increase the tendency to see that
others are immoral may lead us to wonder whether broader collective as part of the self (e.g., Petriglieri,
their prior ethical behaviors were actually attempts 2015). This may in turn lead people to interpret acts by
to set us up for the unethical act they planned all that collective more similarly to how they would in-
along, given that we are simply less aware of the in- terpret their own actions (reflecting, for example, a
tentions underlying the actions of others (Kim, Han, greater understanding of situational forces that may
Mislin, & Tuncel, 2019). In such a case, this retro- affect that collective’s behaviors, a better understand-
spective imputation of nefarious intent may lead to ing of the collective’s intentions, or less of an inclina-
those prior moral credits being discounted, or even tion to perceive that collective’s actions as threats)
erased, from those others’ moral balance sheets. This (Effron, Markus, Jackman, Muramoto, & Muluk, 2018).
184 Academy of Management Review January

This may ultimately shift the focus of each of the (HO), to the extent that they view their own group’s
self–other distinctions we have described in Figure 1 unethical behaviors in a more favorable light than the
from the individual self versus any other to those unethical behaviors of groups acting on behalf of other
within the collective versus outside that collective. organizations. This tendency may, furthermore, be
heightened when members exhibit greater organiza-
tional identification (as we described in our analysis of
Organization-Level Implications
individual-level organizational factors), to the extent
At the organizational level, hypocrisy might arise that this identification leads such members to view
in two distinct ways, along the lines of past theoriz- others within the organization as part of the self. Thus,
ing on organizational corruption (Pinto, Leana, & Pil, the kinds of self–other distortions our theory details
2008). Pinto et al. (2008) described how corruption at could operate at the boundaries of organizations, rather
the organizational level can manifest through two than between individuals, and this could lead organi-
very distinct organizational phenomena. The first zations to exhibit a hypocritical tendency to downplay
is an organization of corrupt individuals (OCI), in their own unethical conduct while regarding the same
which a significant portion of an organization’s behaviors by other organizations as unethical.
members act in a corrupt manner primarily for their Each type of organization-level hypocrisy might,
personal benefit. The second is a corrupt organiza- furthermore, be affected by the organization’s prac-
tion (CO), in which a group collectively acts in a tices and characteristics. For example, to the extent
corrupt manner for the benefit of the organization. that an OHI can arise from the contagion of
Pinto and colleagues (2008) considered the first type individual-level hypocritical behaviors, managers
of corruption (OCI) an organization-level phenome- may seek to limit that contagion by altering the
non even though individuals are the primary, and organization’s structure to separate and create
often sole, beneficiaries of such behavior because: (a) boundaries around some of its most vital functions
the behaviors are sufficiently widespread to charac- (Galbraith, 1977), and thereby protect those func-
terize the organization as a whole, and (b) internal tions from being infected by hypocrisy elsewhere in
meso-level processes are responsible for either fa- the company. Likewise, to the extent that meso-level
cilitating or failing to inhibit the contagion of these processes can either facilitate or fail to inhibit the
behaviors. Moreover, they consider the second type contagion of hypocritical behaviors (Pinto et al.,
of corruption (CO) an organization-level phenome- 2008), organizations may also seek to alter these
non because the organization is not only the primary meso-level processes to reduce the likelihood that an
beneficiary but also the primary entity that is cul- OHI would arise. This might be accomplished, for
pable, even if individual members are also at fault. example, by formalizing a range of organizational
This same reasoning regarding organization-level practices to encourage greater perspective-taking
corruption can also be applied to matters of organi- (e.g., by fostering dialectical modes of discourse and
zational hypocrisy, especially in light of the fact that analysis or by routinizing the use of devil’s advocates
hypocrisy can involve corruption as well. To the for ethically questionable decisions) (Heath et al.,
extent that a greater number of organizational 1998) in order to prevent hypocritical behavior from
members fall prey to the kind of hypocrisy we have becoming more widespread.
described (e.g., due to the individual-level organi- Similarly, to the extent that hypocrisy can mani-
zational considerations mentioned above), such fest at the organizational level in the form of a HO due
hypocrisy can become sufficiently widespread to to groups acting on behalf of the organization in ways
characterize the organization as a whole (i.e., as an that those outside the organization would consider
organization of hypocritical individuals, OHI). This hypocritical, attempts to address this type of hy-
may in turn pervade the culture of the organization pocrisy may ultimately require some form of out-
by signaling a general tolerance for such behavior reach to those outside the organization to help them
(Key, 1999; Treviño, Butterfield, & McCabe, 1998; evaluate whether a potentially unethical act would
Treviño & Youngblood, 1990), and ultimately dam- be appropriate. This implication is consistent with
age attitudes toward, and heighten intentions to the recommendations of prior organizational re-
leave, the organization (Kouzes & Posner, 1995; search examining social projection in the moral do-
Philippe & Koehler, 2005). main (e.g., Flynn & Wiltermuth, 2010). To the extent
Organizational members acting as a group on behalf that observers can view the same behavior differ-
of the organization may also exhibit organization-level ently from those who might initiate that action, as a
hypocrisy, specifically as a hypocritical organization result of the cognitive distortions our theory has
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 185

articulated, greater awareness of how such observers rationalizations would not apply to those others as
would evaluate that behavior may help organiza- well.4 Indeed, a purely motivational account based
tional actors avoid serious pitfalls in their decisions. on people’s desire to rationalize their own unethical
Therefore, just as efforts to reduce hypocrisy at the behavior ultimately raises a discomforting dilemma
individual level in an organization might benefit in which an individual may: (a) choose to rational-
from exposing members to the potentially divergent ize that behavior to mitigate the threat of self-
views of other members within the organization, so condemnation, at the cost of accepting that such
too may efforts to avoid the HO form of organization- rationalizations may encourage the same type of be-
level hypocrisy benefit by exposing groups seeking havior from others, (b) choose instead to condemn
to act on behalf of their organization to the poten- others who engage in such behavior and reject their
tially divergent views of those from other organiza- attempts to rationalize it, at the cost of precluding the
tions. Moreover, because such outside evaluations ability to rationalize one’s own unethical behavior,
can hinge on the outsiders’ access to information, as or (c) engage in deliberate moral hypocrisy by
our theory has detailed, managers might also seek to knowingly rationalizing one’s own unethical behav-
avoid the HO form of hypocrisy by increasing the ior while condemning the same unethical behavior
organization’s level of transparency for its ethically from others, at the cost of cognitive dissonance from
questionable decisions (Halter, de Arruda, & Halter, such blatant behavioral inconsistency (Stone et al.,
2009), so that the informational bases upon which 1997).
those within and outside the organization judge We suggest that people may be able to resolve the
these ethically questionable actions are less likely to dilemma in a different way, grounded not in moti-
diverge. vated rationalizations but rather in more funda-
mental differences in both the objective availability
of and cognitive access to information that can dis-
Summary
tort how people perceive the self versus others. In
This analysis ultimately raises the notion that particular, our framework describes how people’s
various organizational considerations may combine susceptibility to an interrelated sequence of four
to affect, and thereby provide the basis for predicting, self–other distortions (in their evaluations of une-
different forms of moral hypocrisy in organizations. thicality, liability, insolvency, and incompensability)
Hence, to the extent that such organizational factors can allow them to believe they are being fair and
can play a role in affecting whether and how hy- consistent when they appraise the morality of the self
pocrisy might occur, these insights might in turn and others while actually being inconsistent in how
assist efforts by managers and organizations to detect they do so, and thereby gain the benefits of such hy-
and deter such behavior. Our theory of ethical ac- pocrisy (i.e., by alleviating the threat posed by their
counting may therefore provide the basis for an array own immoral behavior) without its typical costs
of practical interventions to mitigate the rise of both (i.e., arising from the knowledge that they have indeed
individual- and organization-level hypocritical be- been a hypocrite).
havior, as well as the damage such behavior can in- Our analysis, therefore, advances research on
flict on organizational commitment, trust, and work moral hypocrisy beyond its typical focus on
relationships (Simons et al., 2011). individual-level considerations by providing in-
sights that can only be gained from theorizing at an
interpersonal level. Past research in this domain has
THEORETICAL IMPLICATIONS
tended to treat people’s attitudes toward their own
Our proposed theory of ethical accounting also unethical behavior and the unethical behavior of
offers a broad range of theoretical implications. First, others as discrete considerations (e.g., Batson et al.,
it is important to reiterate that we do not dispute that 1997), rather than consider the potential interplay
people may often seek to rationalize their unethical between such judgments. As a result, although the
behavior. Such rationalizations can certainly occur literature has offered important insights into the
and operate in conjunction with the informational
mechanisms our theory considers, as we have de- 4
This notion is also consistent with research on guilt,
tailed earlier in this paper. Yet our analysis sug- which has found that those who feel guilty are more in-
gests that such rationalizations may also prove clined to forgive others (presumably because they would
problematic when others engage in the same kinds like to be forgiven themselves) (Jordan, Flynn, & Cohen,
of unethical actions, as it is not clear why those 2015).
186 Academy of Management Review January

nature of hypocrisy, those explanations have remained deontological perspectives, our analysis suggests
fragmented and incomplete, to the extent that they that people may not simply subscribe to one per-
have involved fundamentally different theoretical spective or the other and maintain that preference
rationales to account for how people deal with moral over time (Helzer, Fleeson, Furr, Meindl, & Barranti,
judgments of others versus the self, or simply pre- 2017), but rather act in a manner that makes them
sumed that people are comfortable being moral appear as if they switch back and forth between them
hypocrites. The present framework seeks to address depending on whether the target of evaluation is the
this limitation by providing a broader and more co- self versus others. With regard to person-centered
herent account of the interpersonal considerations accounts of moral judgment (Uhlmann et al., 2015),
that can allow people to reconcile these judgments. which consider how acts may be more or less diag-
Through this effort, it ultimately integrates the liter- nostic of moral character, our analysis highlights
ature’s disparate explanations for how people ad- how this moral judgment may actually occur through
dress just one side of the coin or the other into a not one, but rather two, distinct stages that are sus-
cohesive whole. ceptible to self-other differentiation: (a) the extent to
This integration, furthermore, moves beyond the which acts are considered moral liabilities (Liability)
simultaneous assessment of the self and others to and (b) the extent to which these moral liabilities
combine an array of perspectives on moral judgment should be weighed against one’s past history of eth-
that have either been considered in isolation or ex- ical behavior to form an overall assessment of moral
plicitly treated as incompatible. For example, it character (Insolvency). With respect to research on
suggests that the debate over whether assessments of how multiple (ethical and unethical) acts are com-
morality should be based on normative theories that bined to form an overall assessment of moral char-
focus on the nature of the act (consequentialist or acter (Nisan, 1990), our analysis suggests that
deontological ethics) or the nature of the person who people’s moral assets and liabilities are not immu-
committed the act (Uhlmann et al., 2015) may be table, but may actually be reevaluated over time
better resolved by considering how people’s ap- based on subsequent events that prompt new in-
praisals of both the act and the actor may build on, ferences about those past incidents, in a manner
rather than substitute for, one another. Our frame- similar to the reconstructive nature of memory
work likewise moves beyond considering a single act (Loftus, 1975). Finally, with regard to the matter of
and the person who committed it to incorporate what incompensability—specifically how people may
has hitherto been treated as an entirely different make amends for their unethical actions—our anal-
perspective that has focused on how multiple acts ysis suggests that people may consider these reme-
should be weighed and counterbalanced (Monin & dies not impartially but rather in a fundamentally
Miller, 2001; Nisan, 1990). Finally, our analysis egocentric manner, and that this tendency may make
broadens its focus from the question of how one it far more difficult to forgive others than to forgive
might be unethical to consider how the unethical ourselves.
might subsequently be redeemed, and thereby This latter consideration, furthermore, under-
highlights the relevance of yet another distinct lit- scores the potential for this analysis to inform an
erature on how people’s underlying cognitions can entirely distinct literature that has investigated how
affect the extent to which ethical violations might trust might be repaired after a violation (e.g., Bottom,
be overcome (McCullough, Bono, & Root, 2007; Gibson, Daniels, & Murnighan, 2002; Ferrin, Kim,
Santelli, Struthers, & Eaton, 2009; Wohl & Branscombe, Cooper, & Dirks, 2007; Harmon, Kim, & Mayer, 2015;
2005). As such, our proposed theory underscores Kim et al., 2017; Maddux, Kim, Okumura, & Brett,
how what had previously been treated as distinct, 2011). In particular, past research has framed the
and even competing, theoretical perspectives may trust-repair process as a matter of resolving discrep-
more aptly be considered a set of compatible and ant beliefs about the target, with perceivers believing
cumulative frameworks through which ethicality that trust is not warranted and the target believing
can be viewed. that greater trust would be deserved (Kim, Dirks, &
Beyond merely integrating these ethical perspec- Cooper, 2009). Our framework can help explain why
tives, our proposed theory of ethical accounting this might be the case in the aftermath of a trans-
offers insights that can advance research on many gression by revealing a number of inherent reasons
of these specific perspectives as well. With regard to why people might evaluate others for such actions
the longstanding debate in normative ethics regard- differently from how they evaluate themselves. By
ing the appropriateness of consequentialist versus doing so, this analysis underscores how those who
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 187

commit ethical violations may fail to recognize how 127–147. Washington, DC: American Psychological
their transgressions are interpreted, and thereby Association.
helps explain why their subsequent attempts to ad- Bandura, A. 1990. Selective activation and disengagement
dress such incidents, and ultimately repair trust, of moral control. Journal of Social Issues, 46: 27–46.
may so often fall short. Bandura, A. 1991. Social cognitive theory of moral thought
and action. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.),
CONCLUSION Handbook of moral behavior and development:
Vol. 1: Theory: 45–104. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
We hope it is clear that the purpose of this paper is Bandura, A., Barbaranelli, C., Caprara, G. V., & Pastorelli,
not to diminish everyone as hypocrites. Instead, it C. 1996. Mechanisms of moral disengagement in the
aims to suggest that if interpersonal hypocrisy can exercise of moral agency. Journal of Personality and
arise from fundamental differences in people’s ac- Social Psychology, 71: 364–374.
cess to information (as opposed to motivational fac- Barden, J., Rucker, D. D., & Petty, R. E. 2005. “Saying one
tors that affect how that information is interpreted thing and doing another”: Examining the impact of
and utilized), then efforts to deter its incidence and event order on hypocrisy judgments of others. Person-
ensuing implications for ethics in organizations may ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 31: 1463–1474.
require more systematic attention than the literature
Barresi, J. 2004. Intentional relations and divergent per-
has heretofore presumed. For example, the present spectives in social understanding. In S. Gallagher and
analysis may help inform the question of why formal S. Watson (Eds.), Ipseity and alterity: Interdisci-
efforts to promote ethics in organizations so often fail plinary approaches to intersubjectivity: 74–99.
(e.g., Chugh et al., 2005; De Cremer, Tenbrunsel, & Rouen, France: Presses Universitaires de Rouen.
van Dijk, 2010). In particular, our analysis helps re-
Batson, D. C., Kobrynowicz, D., Dinnerstein, J. L., Kampf,
inforce the notion that, to the extent that such ethics H. C., & Wilson, A. D. 1997. In a very different voice:
interventions hinge on organizational members be- Unmasking moral hypocrisy. Journal of Personality
ing aware of the ethical implications of their actions, and Social Psychology, 72: 1335–1348.
they are relying on an assumption of self-awareness
Batson, D. C., & Thompson, E. R. 2001. Why don’t moral
(regarding the unethicality of their own behavior)
people act morally? Motivational considerations.
that often may not hold. Consequently, our proposed Current Directions in Psychological Science, 10:
theory of ethical accounting ultimately entails that 54–57.
our ability to avoid hypocrisy, improve ethics in or-
Batson, D. C., Thompson, E. R., Seuferling, G., Whitney, H.,
ganizations, and limit the kinds of transgressions
& Strongman, J. A. 1999. Moral hypocrisy: Appearing
that can violate trust and damage productive work
moral to oneself without being so. Journal of Per-
relationships requires that we acknowledge not only sonality and Social Psychology, 77: 525–537.
our own susceptibility to such actions but also the
Bazerman, M. H., & Tenbrunsel, A. E. 2011. Blind spots.
inconsistency with which we assess our own and
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
others’ involvement in such behaviors. In the end, it
may only be through the recognition that people may Bentham, J. 1781. The principles of morals and legisla-
evaluate this behavior quite differently for the self tion. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.
and others, despite believing they have been fair and Bottom, W. P., Gibson, K., Daniels, S., & Murnighan, J. K.
consistent, that we may come to understand how 2002. When talk is not cheap: Substantive penance
people so often rail against unethicality while en- and expressions of intent in rebuilding cooperation.
gaging in it so readily. Organization Science, 13: 497–513.
Bryan, C. J., Adams, G. S., & Monin, B. 2013. When cheating
would make you a cheater: Implicating the self pre-
REFERENCES vents unethical behavior. Journal of Experimental
Aguilar, P., Brussino, S., & Fernández-Dols, J.-M. 2013. Psychology: General, 142: 1001–1005.
Psychological distance increases uncompromising Buss, A. R. 1978. Causes and reasons in attribution theory:
consequentialism. Journal of Experimental Social A conceptual critique. Journal of Personality and
Psychology, 49: 449–452. Social Psychology, 36: 1311–1321.
Aronson, E., Cohen, G. L., & Nail, P. R. 1999. Self- Chugh, D., Bazerman, M. H., & Banaji, M. R. 2005. Bounded
affirmation theory: An update and appraisal. In E. ethicality as a psychological barrier to recognizing
Harmon-Jones & J. Mills (Eds.), Cognitive dissonance conflicts of interest. In D. A. Moore, M. Cain, G.
theory: Revival with revisions and controversies: Loewenstein, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Conflicts of
188 Academy of Management Review January

interest: Problems and solutions from law, medi- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 38:
cine, and organizational settings: 74–95. London, 889–906.
U.K.: Cambridge University Press. Flynn, F. J., & Wiltermuth, S. S. 2010. Who’s with me? False
Cialdini, R. B., Reno, R. R., & Kallgren, C. A. 1990. A focus consensus, brokerage, and ethical decision making in
theory of normative conduct: Recycling the concept of organizations. Academy of Management Journal,
norms to reduce littering in public places. Journal of 53: 1074–1089.
Personality and Social Psychology, 58: 1015–1026.
Galbraith, J. R. 1977. Organization design. Boston, MA:
CNN. 2004. CNN Larry King live: Encore presentation of Addison Wesley.
2004 interview with Ken Lay. Retrieved from http://
Gilbert, D. T., & Malone, P. S. 1995. The correspondence
transcripts.cnn.com/TRANSCRIPTS/0607/08/lkl.01.html.
bias. Psychological Bulletin, 117: 21–38.
Crichter, C., Inbar, Y., & Pizarro, D. A. 2013. How quick
Gilovich, T. 1990. Differential construal and the false
decisions illuminate moral character. Social Psycho-
consensus effect. Journal of Personality and Social
logical and Personality Science, 4: 308–315.
Psychology, 59: 623–634.
De Cremer, D., Tenbrunsel, A. E., & van Dijk, M. 2010.
Greene, J. D., Summerville, R. B., Nystrom, J. M., & Cohen,
Regulating ethical failures: Insights from psychology.
J. D. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional en-
Journal of Business Ethics, 95: 1–6.
gagement in moral judgment. Science, 293: 2105–
de Quervain, D. J. F., Fischbacher, U., Trever, V., 2108.
Schellhammer, M., Schnyder, U., Buck, A., & Fehr, E.
Haidt, J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A
2004. The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Sci-
social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psy-
ence, 305: 1254–1258.
chological Review, 108: 814–834.
Dirks, K. T., Kim, P. H., Ferrin, D. L., & Cooper, C. D. 2011.
Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. 2010. Morality. In S. T. Fiske, D. T.
Understanding the effects of substantive responses on
Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social
trust following a transgression. Organizational Be-
havior and Human Decision Processes, 114: 87–103. psychology (5th ed.): 797–832. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

Ditto, P. H., & Jemmott, J. B., III. 1989. From rarity to eval- Halter, M. V., de Arruda, M. C. C., & Halter, R. B. 2009.
uative extremity: Effects of prevalence information on Transparency to reduce corruption? Journal of Busi-
evaluations of positive and negative characteristics. ness Ethics, 84: 373–385.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57: Harmon, D. H., Kim, P. H., & Mayer, K. J. 2015. Breaking the
16–26. letter versus spirit of the law: How the interpretation of
Effron, D. A., Markus, H. R., Jackman, L. M., Muramoto, Y., contract violations affects trust and the management
& Muluk, H. 2018. Hypocrisy and culture: Failing to of relationships. Strategic Management Journal, 36:
practice what you preach receives harsher interper- 497–517.
sonal reactions in independent (vs. interdependent) Heath, C., Larrick, R. P., & Klayman, J. 1998. Cognitive re-
cultures. Journal of Experimental Social Psychol- pairs: How organizational practices can compensate
ogy, 76: 371–384. for individual shortcomings. Review of Organiza-
Effron, D. A., & Miller, D. T. 2015. Do as I say, not as I’ve tional Behavior, 20: 1–37.
done: Suffering for a misdeed reduces the hypocrisy of Helzer, E. G., Fleeson, W. W., Furr, M., Meindl, P., &
advising others against it. Organizational Behavior Barranti, M. 2017. Once a utilitarian, consistently a
and Human Decision Processes, 131: 16–32. utilitarian? Examining principledness in moral judg-
Effron, D. A., Miller, D. T., & Monin, B. 2012. Inventing ment via the robustness of individual differences.
racist roads not taken: The licensing effect of immoral Journal of Personality, 85: 505–517.
counterfactual behaviors. Journal of Personality and History. 2009. Televangelist Jim Bakker is indicted on fed-
Social Psychology, 103: 916–932. eral charges. Retrieved from https://www.history.com/
Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. 2002. Altruistic punishment in this-day-in-history/jim-bakker-is-indicted-on-federal-
humans. Nature, 415: 137–140. charges.
Ferrin, D. L., Kim, P. H., Cooper, C. D., & Dirks, K. T. 2007. Ibarra, H., & Andrews, S. B. 1993. Power, social influence,
Silence speaks volumes: The effectiveness of reticence and sense making: Effects of network centrality and
in comparison to apology and denial for responding to proximity on employee perceptions. Administrative
integrity- and competence-based trust violations. Jour- Science Quarterly, 38: 277–303.
nal of Applied Psychology, 92: 893–908. Johnson, C. 2003. Enron’s ethical collapse: Lessons for
Fiske, S. T. 1980. Attention and weight in person percep- leadership educators. Journal of Leadership Educa-
tion: The impact of negative and extreme behavior. tion, 2: 45–56.
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 189

Jordan, J., Flynn, F., & Cohen, T. R. 2015. Forgive them for Kouzes, J. M., & Posner, B. Z. 1995. The leadership chal-
I have sinned: The relationship between guilt and lenge: How to keep getting extraordinary things done
forgiveness of others’ transgressions. European Jour- in organizations. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
nal of Social Psychology, 45: 441–459. Kruger, J., & Gilovich, T. 2004. Actions, intentions, and
Kant, I. Grounding for the metaphysics of morals self-assessment: The road to self-enhancement is
(J. W. Ellington, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett paved with good intentions. Personality and Social
Publishing. Original work published 1785. Psychology Bulletin, 30: 328–339.
Kelley, H. H. 1973. The processes of causal attribution. Lammers, J. 2012. Abstraction increases hypocrisy. Jour-
American Psychologist, 28: 107–128. nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48: 475–480.
Key, S. 1999. Organizational Ethical Culture: Real or Lammers, J., Stapel, D. A., & Galinsky, A. D. 2010. Power
Imagined? Journal of Business Ethics, 20: 217–225. increases hypocrisy. Psychological Science, 21: 737–
Kim, P. H., Cooper, C. D., Dirks, K. T., & Ferrin, D. L. 2013. 744.
Repairing trust with individuals vs. groups. Organi- Lanaj, K., Kim, P. H., Koopman, J., & Matta, F. K. 2018.
zational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Daily mistrust: A resource perspective and its impli-
120: 1–14. cations for work and home. Personnel Psychology,
Kim, P. H., Diekmann, K. A., & Tenbrunsel, A. E. 2003. 71: 545–570.
Flattery may get you somewhere: The strategic im-
Locke, D., & Pennington, D. 1982a. Reasons and other
plications of providing positive vs. negative feedback
causes: Their role. Journal of Personality and Social
about ability vs. ethicality in negotiation. Organiza-
Psychology, 42: 212–223.
tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes,
90: 225–243. Loftus, E. F. 1975. Leading questions and the eyewitness
report. Cognitive Psychology, 7: 560–572.
Kim, P. H., Dirks, K. T., & Cooper, C. D. 2009. The repair of
trust: A dynamic bilateral perspective and multilevel Lönnqvist, J.-E., Rilke, R. M., & Walkowitz, G. 2015. On
conceptualization. Academy of Management Re- why hypocrisy thrives: Reasonable doubt created by
view, 34: 401–422. moral posturing can deter punishment. Journal of
Kim, P. H., Dirks, K. T., Cooper, C. D., & Ferrin, D. L. 2006. Experimental Social Psychology, 59: 139–145.
When more blame is better than less: The implications Maddux, W. W., Kim, P. H., Okumura, T., & Brett, J. M. 2011.
of internal vs. external attributions for the repair of Cultural differences in the function and meaning of
trust after a competence- vs. integrity-based trust vio- apologies. International Negotiation, 16: 405–425.
lation. Organizational Behavior and Human Deci- Madon, S., Jussim, L., & Eccles, J. 1997. In search of the
sion Processes, 99: 49–65.
powerful self-fulfilling prophecy. Journal of Person-
Kim, P. H., Ferrin, D. L., Cooper, C. D., & Dirks, K. T. 2004. ality and Social Psychology, 72: 791–809.
Removing the shadow of suspicion: The effects of
Malle, B. F. 2004. How the mind explains behavior: Folk
apology vs. denial for repairing ability- vs. integrity-
explanations, meaning, and social interaction.
based trust violations. Journal of Applied Psychol-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
ogy, 89: 104–118.
Malle, B. F. 2005. Self-other asymmetries in behavior ex-
Kim, P. H., Han, A. J., Mislin, A. A., & Tuncel, E. 2019. The
planations: Myth and reality. In M. D. Alicke, D. A.
retrospective imputation of nefarious intent. Acad-
emy of Management Proceedings. doi: 10.5465/ Dunning, & J. I. Krueger (Eds.), Studies in self and
AMBPP.2019.33. identity. The self in social judgment: 155–178. New
York, NY: Psychology Press.
Kim, P. H., & Harmon, D. H. 2014. Justifying one’s transgres-
sions: How rationalizations based on equity, equality, Malle, B. F., Knobe, J. M., & Nelson, S. E. 2007. Actor-
and need affect trust after its violation. Journal of Ex- observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior:
perimental Psychology: Applied, 20: 365–379. New answers to an old question. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 93: 491–514.
Kim, P. H., Mislin, A., Tuncel, E., Fehr, R., Cheshin, A., &
Van Kleef, G. A. 2017. Power as an emotional liability: Marks, G., & Miller, N. 1987. Ten years of research on the
Implications for perceived authenticity and trust after false consensus effect: An empirical and theoretical
a transgression. Journal of Experimental Psychology: review. Psychological Bulletin, 102: 72–90.
General, 146(10): 1379–1401. Martijn, C., Spears, R., Van der Plight, J., & Jakobs, E. 1992.
Knobe, J., & Malle, B. F. 2002. Self and other in the expla- Negativity and positivity effects in person perception
nation of behavior: 30 years later. Psychologica and inference: ability versus morality. European
Belgica, 42: 113–130. Journal of Social Psychology, 22: 453–463.
190 Academy of Management Review January

Mayer, R. C., Davis, J. H., & Schoorman, F. D. 1995. An influences judgments of moral blame. In M. Mikulincer
integrative model of organizational trust. Academy & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of moral-
of Management Review, 20: 709–734. ity: Exploring the causes of good and evil: 91–108.
Mazar, N., Amir, O., & Ariely, D. 2008. The dishonesty of Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
honest people: A theory of self-concept maintenance. Reeder, G. D., & Brewer, M. B. 1979. A schematic model of
Journal of Marketing Research, 45: 633–644. dispositional attribution in interpersonal perception.
McCullough, M. E., Bono, G., & Root, L. M. 2007. Rumi- Psychological Review, 86: 61–79.
nation, emotion, and forgiveness: Three longitudinal Roese, N. J., & Vohs, K. D. 2012. Hindsight bias. Perspec-
studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- tives on Psychological Science, 7: 411–426.
ogy, 92: 490–505. Ross, L. 1977. The intuitive scientist and his shortcomings.
McKnight, D. H., Cummings, L. L., & Chervany, N. L. 1998. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental so-
Initial trust formation in new organizational relation- cial psychology, vol. 10: 174–220. New York, NY:
ships. Academy of Management Review, 23: 473–490. Academic Press.
Monin, B., & Merritt, A. 2012. Moral hypocrisy, moral in- Santelli, A. G., Struthers, C. W., & Eaton, J. 2009. Fit to
consistency, and the struggle for moral integrity. In M. forgive: Exploring the interaction between regulatory
Mikulincer & D. R. Shaffer (Eds.), The social psy- focus, repentance, and forgiveness. Journal of Per-
chology of morality: Exploring the causes of good sonality and Social Psychology, 96: 381–394.
and evil: 167–184. Washington, D.C.: American Psy- Sherman, D. K., & Cohen, G. L. 2002. Accepting threatening
chological Association. information: Self-affirmation and the reduction of
Monin, B., & Miller, D. T. 2001. Moral credentials and the defensive biases. Current Directions in Psychologi-
expression of prejudice. Journal of Personality and cal Science, 11: 119–123.
Social Psychology, 81: 33–43. Simons, T., Tomlinson, E. C., & Leroy, H. 2011. Research on
Moore, D. A., Tetlock, P. E., Tanlu, L., & Bazerman, M. H. behavioral integrity: A promising construct for posi-
2006. Conflicts of interest and the case of auditor in- tive organizational scholarship. In G. M. Spreitzer &
dependence: Moral seduction and strategic issue cy- K. S. Cameron (Eds.), Oxford handbook of positive
cling. Academy of Management Review, 31: 10–29. organizational scholarship: 325–339. New York,
Morse, L., & Cohen, T. R. 2017. Virtues and vices in NY: Oxford University Press.
workplace settings: The role of moral character in Snyder, M. L., Kleck, R. E., Strenta, A. C., & Mentzer, S. J.
predicting counterproductive and citizenship behav- 1979. Avoidance of the handicapped: An attributional
iors. In A. J. G. Sison, G. R. Beabout, & I. Ferrero (Eds.), ambiguity analysis. Journal of Personality and So-
Handbook of virtue ethics in business and manage- cial Psychology, 37: 2297–2306.
ment: 761–771. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. Steele, C. M. 1998. The psychology of self-affirmation:
Nickerson, R. S. 1998. Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous Sustaining the integrity of the self. In L. Berkowitz
phenomenon in many guises. Review of General (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology,
Psychology, 2: 175–220. vol. 21: 261–302. New York, NY: Academic Press.
Nisan, M. 1990. Moral balance: A model of how people Stone, J., Wiegand, A. W., Cooper, J., & Aronson, E. 1997.
arrive at moral decisions. In T. E. Wren (Ed.), The When exemplification fails: Hypocrisy and the motive
moral domain: Essays in the ongoing discussion be- for self-integrity. Journal of Personality and Social
tween philosophy and the social sciences: 283–314. Psychology, 72: 54–65.
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Tannenbaum, D., Uhlmann, E. L., & Diermeier, D. 2011. Moral
Petriglieri, J. L. 2015. Co-creating relationship repair: signals, public outrage, and immaterial harms. Journal
Pathways to reconstructing destabilized organiza- of Experimental Social Psychology, 47: 1249–1254.
tional identification. Administrative Science Quar- Tapper, J. 2007, March 12. Gingrich admits to affair during
terly, 60: 518–557. Clinton impeachment. ABC News. Retrieved from
Philippe, T. W., & Koehler, J. W. 2005. A factor analytical https://abcnews.go.com/Politics/story?id=2937633.
study of perceived organizational hypocrisy. SAM Tenbrunsel, A. E., Diekmann, K. A., Wade-Benzoni, K. A.,
Advanced Management Journal, 70: 13–20. & Bazerman, M. H. 2010. The ethical mirage: A tem-
Pinto, J., Leana, C. R., & Pil, F. K. 2008. Corrupt organiza- poral explanation as to why we are not as ethical as we
tions or organizations of corrupt individuals? Two think we are. Research in Organizational Behavior,
types of organization-level corruption. Academy of 30: 153–173.
Management Review, 33: 685–709. Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O., Elson, B., Green, M., & Lerner, J.
Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D. 2011. Bringing character 2000. The psychology of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-
back: How the motivation to evaluate character offs, forbidden base rates, and heretical counterfactuals.
2021 Kim, Wiltermuth, and Newman 191

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78: Wojciszke, B. 2005. Morality and competence in person-
853–870. and self-perception. European Review of Social Psy-
Thompson, L. J., & Loewenstein, G. 1992. Egocentric in- chology, 16: 155–188.
terpretations of fairness and negotiation. Organiza- Yam, K. C., Klotz, A. C., He, W., & Reynolds, S. J. 2017.
tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 51: Turning good soldiers into bad apples: Examining
176–197. when and why citizenship behavior leads to deviance.
Treviño, L. K., Butterfield, K. D., & McCabe, D. L. 1998. Academy of Management Journal, 60: 1–24.
The ethical context in organizations: Influences on
employee attitudes and behavior. Business Ethics
Quarterly, 8: 447–476.
Treviño, L. K., & Youngblood, S. A. 1990. Bad apples in bad
Peter H. Kim (kimpeter@usc.edu) is a professor of man-
barrels: A causal analysis of ethical decision-making
agement and organization at the University of Southern
behavior. Journal of Applied Psychology, 75: 378–385.
California. He received his PhD in organizational behavior
Trope, Y., & Liberman, N. 2010. Construal-level theory of from Northwestern University. He studies the dynamics
psychological distance. Psychological Review, 117: of interpersonal perceptions and their implications for
460–463. negotiations, work groups, dispute resolution, and trust
Tsang, J. A. 2002. Moral rationalization and the integration of repair.
situational factors and psychological processes in im- Scott S. Wiltermuth (wiltermu@usc.edu) is an associate
moral behavior. Review of General Psychology, 6: 25–50. professor of management and organization at the Univer-
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. 1991. Loss aversion in risk- sity of Southern California. He received his doctorate from
less choice: A reference-dependent model. Quarterly Stanford University. He studies ethics and morality. His
Journal of Economics, 106: 1039–1061. research also investigates how interpersonal dynamics,
such as synchrony and dominance or submissiveness, in-
Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D. A., & Diermeier, D. 2015. A
fluence cooperation and coordination.
person-centered approach to moral judgment. Per-
spectives on Psychological Science, 10: 72–81. David T. Newman (dtnewman@usc.edu) is a PhD candi-
Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. 2008. The duality of virtue: date in management and organization at the University of
Deconstructing the moral hypocrite. Journal of Ex- Southern California. He earned his BA in psychology from
perimental Social Psychology, 44: 1334–1338. Yale University and his JD from Harvard Law School. He
studies ethics and moral psychology, especially the mo-
Wohl, M. J. A., & Branscombe, N. R. 2005. Forgiveneess and rality of technology.
collective guilt assignment to historical perpetrator groups
depend on level of social category inclusiveness. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 88: 288–303.
Copyright of Academy of Management Review is the property of Academy of Management
and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without
the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or
email articles for individual use.

You might also like