You are on page 1of 5

The Behavior Analyst 1987, 10, 183-187 No.

2 (Fall)

Rules: Function-Altering Contingency-Specifying Stimuli


Elbert Blakely and Henry Schlinger
Western Michigan University
Behavior analysts have traditionally defined rules as discriminative stimuli. Three problems with this
interpretation are discussed. First, because the effects of rules are often delayed, and the effects of dis-
criminative stimuli are immediate, classifying rules as discriminative stimuli violates the definitional
requirements of the latter. Second, when rules are defined as discriminative stimuli, other truly unique
effects of rules may be obscured. Finally, both rules and contingencies develop new behavioral relations;
however, when rules are interpreted as discriminative stimuli, their effects are not readily compared with
those of contingencies. As an alternative, we suggest that rules be interpreted as function-altering contin-
gency-specifying stimuli. Implications of this function-altering interpretation for terminology and research
strategy are discussed.
Key words: rules, rule-governed behavior, contingency-specifying stimuli, discriminative stimuli, func-
tion-altering effects

In a recent paper, we described how formal properties. Specifically, CSSs must


contingency-specifying stimuli (CSSs) al- describe at least two components of a
ter the functions of other events, and sug- contingency, that is, either a relation be-
gested that the analysis of the function- tween behavior and consequences, be-
altering effects of CSSs had implications havior and antecedent stimuli, two or
for use of the terms "rules" and "rule- more stimuli, or antecedent stimuli, be-
governed behavior" (Schlinger & Blake- havior, and consequences. By definition,
ly, 1987). In this paper, we describe those then, CSSs are verbal stimuli; nonverbal
implications and argue that, in behavior stimuli cannot be contingency-specify-
analysis, the term "rule" should be re- ing. Although nonverbal operations (e.g.,
served for function-altering CSSs. reinforcement, stimulus-stimulus corre-
lation) can be function-altering, we ad-
FUNCTION-ALTERING CSSs: dressed only the function-altering effects
A RECAPITULATION of CSSs. Moreover, we argued that the
We previously described how CSSs can effects of function-altering CSSs are dif-
alter the function of discriminative and ferent than those ofSDs: Function-alter-
eliciting stimuli (SDs and CSs), estab- ing CSSs alter stimulus functions, where-
lishing operations (EOs), reinforcing and as SDs evoke behavior.
punishing stimuli, and stimuli that can The term "contingency-specifying
function in second-order respondent stimulus" is sometimes used synony-
conditioning. For example, the descrip- mously with "rule" (e.g., Skinner, 1969,
tive CSS, "Points can be exchanged for chap. 6). We, however, used "CSS" alone
money," might endow the points with because it was more descriptive and had
the capacity to reinforce behavior. The fewer connotations. Although not a tech-
CSS, "When you hear the bell, a shock nical term in behavior analysis (Brown-
will follow," can endow the bell with elic- stein & Shull, 1985), "rule" is neverthe-
iting properties similar to those of the less firmly entrenched in the behavioral
shock. lexicon. Therefore, an interpretation of
We also stated that to alter the function rules based on their observed effects is
of other stimuli, CSSs must have certain important. Because rules have been de-
fined with respect to their form as CSSs
(Skinner, 1969), our previous analysis
The authors thank Ellen Sharenow and Jayson suggests that they might be profitably in-
Wilkenfield for their helpful comments on an earlier
version of this paper. Send requests for reprints to terpreted as function-altering. A func-
either author, Department of Psychology, Western tion-altering interpretation of rules, how-
Michigan University, Kalamazoo, MI 49008. ever, differs from the prevailing view that

183
184 ELBERT BLAKELEY & HENRY SCHLINGER

classifies them as SDs. In what follows, tania, 1984; Galizio, 1979; Hayes et aI.,
we briefly discuss the origins of the cur- 1986; Shimoff, Catania, & Matthews,
rent conception of rules as SDs, and then 1981; Vaughan, 1985; Zuriff, 1985).
critique that interpretation. We then ar- Because behavior-analytic interpreta-
gue that the problems with rules as SDs tions are in general constrained by the
are resolved by interpreting rules as func- basic principles of behavior (Palmer,
tion-altering CSSs. Finally, we describe 1986), the analysis of rules as SDs is not
some implications of this interpretation surprising. Rules undoubtedly control
for terminology and research. behavior as antecedent stimuli, and the
relations are apparently operant. Thus,
RULES AS SDs: Skinner and others could logically as-
A BRIEF HISTORY sume that rules function as SDs because
The current interest in rules and rule- no other operant antecedent function lent
governed behavior can be traced to Skin- itself to an analysis of such events. How-
ner's (1966) paper" An Operant Analysis ever, there are difficulties with this in-
of Problem Solving," where he provided terpretation.
the first formal behavioristic reply to the
assertion by some psychologists that per- RULES AS SDs: A CRITIQUE
haps all behavior was rule-governed (e.g., At least three problems follow from
Brewer, 1974; Bruner, Goodnow, & Aus- classifying rules as SDs. First, many ver-
tin, 1956; Chomsky, 1957). Skinner ar- bal stimuli that are termed "rules" do
gued that in verbal humans, behavior not meet the definitional requirements of
could arise either from direct contact with SDs. Most definitions of the SD contain
environmental contingencies or from two features: the stimulus function and
verbal descriptions of those contingen- the history responsible for that func-
cies, the latter of which he termed "rules." tion. Specifically, an SD immediately
Skinner's distinction between "contin- strengthens (i.e., evokes) behavior (Mi-
gency-shaped" and "rule-governed" im- chael, 1983, 1986)1 due to a history of
plied that the behavior of nonverbal or- differential reinforcement in the presence
ganisms could arise only from direct of the stimulus. If rules are interpreted
contact with contingencies and, by his as SDs, then their effects and history
definition, could not be rule-governed. should conform to those of SDs. Not-
After distinguishing contingency- withstanding the difficulty in discerning
shaped from rule-governed behavior, the relevant history, rules should at least
Skinner (1966) defined rules, with respect evoke the behavior of interest.
to their form, as contingency-specifying Often, however, the effects of rules are
stimuli that describe behavior and the observed only after long delays. For ex-
controlling environment (e.g., anteced- ample, suppose a repairman tells his ap-
ent and consequent stimuli). Thereafter, prentice to "Say 'on' when the indicator
others have described these stimuli var-
iously as "instructions" (e.g., Catania,
I Most accounts of stimulus control hold that be-
1984; Hayes, Brownstein, Zettle, Rosen- havior is more probable in the presence ofthe con-
farb, & Korn, 1986; Skinner, 1969), "re- trolling stimulus (see, e.g., Mackintosh, 1977; Mi-
lational autoclitics" (Brownstein & Shull, chael, 1980; Rilling, 1977; Terrace, 1966). This
1985), and "directions" (Skinner, 1969). requirement does not easily lend itself to classifying
Skinner (1969) functionally defined rules stimuli of short duration, such as auditory CSSs,
the effects of which are observed after stimulus-
as SDs: "How does a rule control behav- offset. Nevertheless, these definitions imply an im-
ior? ... As a discriminative stimulus, a mediate effect on behavior. Although defining the
rule is effective as a part of a set of con- temporal parameters of "immediate" is an empir-
tingencies of reinforcement" (p. 148). Be- ical issue and beyond the scope of this paper, in-
creases in the probability of behavior observed hours
havior analysts have, subsequently, gen- or days after a discrete stimulus are not safely
erally supported this interpretation of interpreted as discriminative effects. Other pro-
rules (e.g., Baldwin & Baldwin, 1981; Ca- cesses are probably involved.
RULES 185

light comes on," and the apprentice re- as function-altering CSSs, their effects are
sponds appropriately one hour later when comparable to, though separable from,
the light is illuminated. Thus, the light, those of contingencies. We should note
and not the rule, evokes saying "on." that the behavior generated by rules and
Moreover, the evocative effect of the light contingencies constitute distinct re-
becomes more apparent as the delay be- sponse classes; nevertheless, both are due
tween the rule and light-onset increases. to histories involving function-altering
For example, if the light were on when operations.
the rule was stated, the apprentice would An example illustrates this last point.
have immediately said "on," making it One can bring button-pushing under
appear that the rule evoked the behavior. evocative control of a red light by differ-
Systematically introducing delays be- entially reinforcing the response in its
tween the rule and light onset, however, presence. A similar effect can be pro-
would demonstrate that the light and not duced by the CSS, "Push the button only
the rule evokes the behavior. The essen- when the red light is on and you will
tial point is this: When a long delay be- receive money." Both the discrimination
tween a rule and the behavior of interest training and the rule endow the red light
is observed, this delayed effect is unlike with an evocative function. Interpreting
that of an SD. the rule as function-altering emphasizes
A second problem is that when rules the functional similarity of the rule and
are classified as SDs, their important the contingency.
function-altering effects may be ob- Although the discussion above ad-
scured. As already stated, an SD only dresses the problems of classifying rules
evokes behavior that has in the past been as SDs, the reverse is also at issue: Many
differentially reinforced in its presence. verbal stimuli that specify only behavior
In contrast, rules alter the functions of (e.g., "Come here," "Sit down," or
the stimuli they describe. In the example "Watch out"!) are sometimes called
above, the rule endowed the light with "rules" (Catania, 1984; Skinner, 1969,
an evocative function. But classifying the 1974). But such stimuli, in these cases
rule as an SD presumes that the effect is commands, have only evocative effects
evocative, therefore obscuring the im- due to a history of differential reinforce-
portant function-altering effect. ment or because they are members of
A third and more subtle problem must functional stimulus classes (e.g., Hayes,
also be considered. Classifying rules as 1986). Therefore, the term "SD" seems
SDs obfuscates the essential similarity sufficient and consistent with the ob-
between contingencies and rules first sug- served effects. Moreover, we would not
gested by Skinner (1966). In our view, expect these non-CSSs to be function-al-
that similarity may be described as fol- tering; it is unlikely that they can alter
lows: Both rules and contingencies alter the functional status of stimuli not de-
the functions of stimuli and, thus, the scribed. Thus, we see no reason to confer
behavioral relations involving those on such stimuli the special status implicit
stimuli (Schlinger & Blakely, 1987; see in the term "rule."
also Vaughan, 1987). This function of
rules and contingencies differs from that
of SDs, which do not alter the functions CONCLUSIONS
of other stimuli but only evoke behavior The critique just presented has impli-
that has in the past been differentially cations for the use of the terms "rule"
reinforced in their presence. Because the and "rule-governed" behavior. We have
effects of SDs and contingencies are very proposed a function-altering interpreta-
different, it seems inappropriate to com- tion of rules which is a departure from
pare the effects of rules, when they are other views that classify rules exclusively
interpreted as SDs, with those of contin- as SDs (but see Hayes, 1986; Brownstein
gencies. But when rules are interpreted & Shull, 1985; Vaughan, 1987). We sug-
186 ELBERT BLAKELEY & HENRY SCHLINGER

gest, though, that this change should not SUMMARY


be unwelcome. Rules can alter the func-
tion of stimuli in many ways, and these Rules and rule-governed behavior
function-altering effects would be more continue to be widely discussed by be-
evident if the interpretation of rules fo- havior analysts (e.g., Brownstein & Shull,
cused on such effects. Furthermore, for 1985; Devany et aI., 1986; Hayes, 1986;
greater precision and simplicity, stimuli Schlinger & Blakely, 1987).. Regardl~ss of
that function only as SDs should be de- how behavior analysts ultImately mter-
scribed as SDs. pret rules, however, the terminology
The perspective of "rule-governed be- should reflect the specificity of the phe-
havior" may also change. If the interpre- nomena of interest (Brownstein & Shull,
1985; Michael, 1986). Thus, in the pres-
tation of such behavior is predicated on
the traditional definition of rules (Le., as ent paper, we argued that when. events
function in ways adequately descnbed by
SDs), then the term should be syno~y­ the basic behavioral principles, they
mous with "rule-evoked." Considenng
our objections to classifying rules as SDs, should be described with the appropriate
"rule-governed behavior" would be a technical terminology (e.g., when events
misnomer. Behavior is not "governed" function as SDs, call them SDs, etc.).
by rules in the sense that it is evoked by Moreover, we attempted to show that as-
them. Rather, behavior is evoked by the signing a special term - ··rule" - to fu.nc-
tions for which we already have techmcal
events described by the rules (e.g., CSs,
EOs and SDs). If anything is "governed" terms might impede the analysis of com-
or determined by rules, it is the func- plex events. In addition, classifying rules
tional relation between these events and as SDs belies the functional difference be-
behavior. But because the term "rule- tween the two kinds of stimuli; as a result,
governed behavior" may be irrevocably research may not investigate the relevant
embedded in the behavioral vernacular, variables and mechanisms involved in
the effects of rules. As an alternative, we
we do not suggest modifying it. We sug-
proposed a function-altering interpreta-
gest only that when rule-governed be- tion of rules that we believe is consistent
havior is considered, what may be "rule- with, and descriptive of, the observed ef-
governed" is a complete functional. re- fects.
lation between a stimulus and behaVIOr.
Finally, the definition of rules may in-
fluence the course and interpretation of REFERENCES
research. When rules are defined as SDs, Baldwin,1. D., & Baldwin, J. I. (1981). /J.ehavior
research would not need to focus on their principles in everyday life. Englewood GIffs, NJ:
function the function presumably being Prentice-Hall.
Brewer W. F. (1974). There is no convincing evi-
an imm~diate strengthening of behavior den~ for operant or classical conditioning in nor-
like that of all SDs. The requisite history mal adult human beings. In W. Weimer & D.
would also be clear. The effects, like those Pal~rmo (&is.), Cognition and the symbolic pro-
of all SDs, would be due to a history of cesses (pp. 1-42). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Brownstein, A. J., & Shull, R. L. (1985). A rule
differential reinforcement with respect to for the use of the term, "Rule-governed behav-
similar stimuli. When rules are defined ior." The Behavior Analyst, 8, 265-267.
as function-altering CSSs, however, the Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J., & Austi~, G. (1956).
mechanism of action is not readily dis- A study o/thinking. New York: Wiley. .
cerned. How a rule alters the function of Catania, A. C. (1984). Learning. Englewood ClIffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall.
stimuli, and the requisite hi~tory for such Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactical structures. The
effects, are among the questIons to be re- Hague: Mouton.
solved. Recent reports (e.g., Devany, Devany, J. M., Hayes, S. C., & Nelson, R. O. (1986).
Hayes & Nelson, 1986) suggest that this Equivalence class formation in language-able and
language-disabled children. Journal 0/ the Ex-
resear~h would be of a very different na- perimental Analysis 0/ Behavior, 46, 243-257.
ture, and may address the truly unique Galizio, M. (1979). Contingency-shaped and rule-
and important effects of rules. governed behavior: Instructional control of hu-
RULES 187

man loss avoidance. Journal ofthe Experimental Schlinger, H., & Blakely, E. (1987). Function-al-
Analysis of Behavior. 31. 53-70. tering effects of contingency-specifying stimuli.
Hayes, S. C. (1986). The case of the silent dog- The Behavior Analyst, 10,41-46.
verbal reports and the analysis of rules: A review Shimoff, E., Catania, A. c., & Matthews, B. A.
of Ericsson and Simon's protocol analysis: Verbal (1981). Uninstructed human responding: Sen-
reports as data. Journal of the Experimental sitivity oflow-rate performance to schedule con-
Analysis of Behavior. 45. 351-363. tingencies. Journal of the Experimental Analysis
Hayes, S. c., Brownstein, A., Zettle, R. D., Rosen- of Behavior. 36. 207-220.
farb, 1., & Korn, Z. (1986). Rule-governed be- Skinner, B. F. (1966). An operant analysis ofprob-
havior and sensitivity to changing contingencies. lem-solving. In B. Kleinmuntz (Ed.), Problem
Journal ofthe Experimental Analysis ofBehavior. solving: Research. method. teaching(pp. 225-257).
45. 237-256. New York: Wiley.
Mackintosh, N. J. (1977). Stimulus control: At- Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies of reinforce-
tentional factors. In W. K. Honig & J. E. R. Stad- ment: A theoretical analysis. Englewood Cliffs,
don (Eds.), Handbook of operant behavior (pp. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
481-513). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New
Michael, 1. (1980). The discriminative stimulus York: Knopf.
or SD. The Behavior Analyst. 3, 47-50. Terrace, H. S. (1966). Stimulus control. In W. K.
Michael, 1. (1983). Evocative and repertoire-al- Honig (Ed.), Operant behavior: Areas of research
tering effects ofan environmental event. VB News. and application (pp. 271-344). New York: Ap-
2.21-23. pleton-Century-Crofts.
Michael, J. (1986). Repertoire-altering effects of Vaughan, M. E. (1985). Repeated acquisition in
remote contingencies. The Analysis of Verbal Be- the analysis of rule-governed behavior. Journal
havior.4. 10-18. ofthe Experimental Analysis ofBehavior. 44. 175-
Palmer, D. C. (1986, June). A behavioral interpre- 184.
tation of memory. (Paper presented at the Sum- Vaughan, M. E. (1987). Rule-governed behavior
mer Institute on Verbal Relations, Bad Kreuz- and higher mental processes. In S. Modgil & c.
nach, Germany.) Modgil (Eds.), B.F. Skinner: Consensus and con-
Reynolds, G. S. (1975). A primer of operant con- troversy (pp. 257-264). Barcombe, England: Fal-
ditioning (rev. ed.). Glenview, IL: Scott, Fores- mer Press.
man. Zurilf, G. E. (1985). Behaviorism: A conceptual
Rilling, M. (1977). Stimulus control and inhibi- reconstruction. New York: Columbia University
tory processes. In W. K. Honig & J. E. R. Staddon Press.
(Eds.), Handbook of operant behavior (pp. 432-
480). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

You might also like