You are on page 1of 15

Embedded democracy

Embedded democracy is a form of government in which democratic


governance is secured by democratic partial regimes.[1][2][3] The term
"embedded democracy" was coined by political scientists Wolfgang
Merkel, Hans-Jürgen Puhle, and Aurel Croissant, who identified "five
interdependent partial regimes" necessary for an embedded
democracy: electoral regime, political participation, civil rights,
horizontal accountability, and the power of the elected representatives 2008 map of world democracies
to govern.[4] The five internal regimes work together to check the
power of the government, while external regimes also help to secure
and stabilize embedded democracies.[5] Together, all the regimes ensure that an embedded democracy is
guided by the three fundamental principles of freedom, equality, and control.[6][7]

Contents
Embedded democracy
Internal regimes of embedded democracy
Democratic electoral regime
Political participation
Civil rights
Horizontal accountability
Power of elected representative to govern
External factors of embeddedness
Socio-economic
Civil society
International integration
Defective democracy
Illiberal democracy
Domain democracy
Exclusive democracy
Delegative democracy
Alternative models for assessing democracies
References

Embedded democracy
The ideal embedded democracy is guided by the three fundamental democratic principles of freedom, equality,
and control.[8] Merkel uses Robert Dahl's definition of political equality, which includes equality "before the
law and in the political process."[9] While equality can infringe upon freedom, an embedded democracy
should establish a balance between equality and freedom; to preserve the equality-freedom equilibrium, there
must be checks on government power (horizontal and vertical accountability).[10]
Internal regimes of embedded democracy

Democratic electoral regime

Merkel writes about five different forms of internal embeddedness, with democratic electoral regime
occupying the central position because "it is the most obvious expression of the sovereignty of the people, the
participation of citizens, and the equal weight allotted to their individual preferences."[11] Democratic electoral
regime is the backbone of an embedded democracy because it differentiates between authoritarian regimes and
democratic regimes.[12] For a democratic regime, equal political rights are a requirement,[13][14] and "the
citizens of the state should be included"[15] in the political process.

Four factors support the democratic electoral regime: "universal, active suffrage, universal, passive right to
vote, free and fair elections and elected representatives."[16] In order to maintain a democratic electoral regime,
all four factors must be present.[17] Voters must all be able to vote in free and fair elections, without coercion,
to elect representatives for themselves in the government.[18][19] An electoral democracy is a form of
government in which the democratic electoral regime is present, but other attributes of liberal embedded
democracies are lacking.[20] Merkel writes that the "electoral democracy merely entails that the election of the
ruling elite be based on the formal, universal right to vote, such that elections are general, free and regular."[21]

Freedom House uses its own set of criteria for determining whether or not a state is democratic, which include
the existence of free and fair elections[22] Furthermore, "the most popular definition of democracy equates it
with regular elections."[23] The principle of democratic electoral regimes is an important one for embedded
democracy because electoral regimes are the base of democracies; electoral regimes act as the foundation for
the other internal regimes due to the importance of elections for democratic processes.[24][25]

Political participation

The internal regime of political participation is closely related to the electoral regime.[26] According to Merkel,
participatory rights "make the public arena an independent political sphere of action, where organizational and
communicative power is developed."[27] Political participation is facilitated by freedom of expression, freedom
of assembly, the right to petition, and freedom of the press.[28] In Merkel's vision of embedded democracy,
citizens are able to form independent interest groups and organize parties to help them express their political
preferences.[29] Political participation is not limited to traditional institutionalized channels for expression; it
can take place in arenas like the private media and civil society.[30] Some scholars of democracy disagree with
Merkel's assertion that frequent political participation is the ideal for a representative democracy.[31] Joseph
Schumpeter sees direct participation as limited to elections in a representative democracy; in the intervals
between elections, citizens allow representatives to speak for them.[32][33] Robert Dahl argues that only a
small portion of the population will be active in political participation and warns that mass participation in a
representative democracy could lead to dictatorship.[34][35]

In weak or failed states, "low-intensity citizenship" is often commonplace. This means that many people are
denied their full political rights or choose not to exercise them.[36][37] Political participation in modern
democracies is frequently weakened by public apathy and disinterest in government.[38][39] As government
bureaucracies have grown in size, people have generally participated in political processes less frequently,
especially those in low socioeconomic groups.[40] Some countries have more equitable voting patterns than
others; for instance, Denmark has less income inequality than the United States as well as higher rates of
political participation.[41] However, political participation does not depend solely on income distribution: it is
also influenced by individual motivation and group affiliation.[42] In some cases, individuals whose economic
status predisposes them to political apathy are more likely to participate if motivated by identification with a
large group.[43]
Proponents of deliberative democracy believe that the ideal democracy allows individuals to participate equally
in discussions.[44][45] In Fishkin's vision of deliberative democracy, interest groups or parties do not dominate
a discussion.[46] Fishkin acknowledges difficulties in achieving mass participation: people view their opinions
as statistically insignificant, and they are often uneducated about political topics and easily influenced by the
media. In modern democracies, most citizens avoid discussing politics with people they disagree with, which
limits the potential for conciliation and compromise. While the internet can provide a forum for deliberation
and potentially change participation patterms, it may also increase political polarization.[47][48] Deliberative
polling may offer one means for political participation.[49][50]

Civil rights

The first two partial regimes of embedded democracy, the democratic electoral regime and political rights of
participation, must be supplemented by civil rights[51][52][53] Civil rights are central to the rule of law in an
embedded democracy.[54][55] Merkel defines the rule of law as “the principle that the state is bound to uphold
its laws effectively and to act according to clearly defined prerogatives.” [56] The rule of law contains and
limits state power.[57]

The core of liberal rule of law lies in constitutional rights.[58] These rights protect individuals against executive
and legislative actions that infringe on an individual's freedom.[59] Independent courts are also an important
aspect of the rule of law.[60] Courts need the authority to review the behaviors of the executive and legislative
branches.[61] Merkel calls the courts “constitutional custodians of the legislature and supervisors of executive
conformity to law.” [62]

Civil rights are negative rights of freedom against the state.[63][64] These rights need to be protected from any
majority of citizens or parliament to prevent a tyranny of the majority.[65][66] To avoid this, the executive and
legislative branches need barriers in place that prevent individuals, groups, or the political opposition from
being oppressed by majority decisions.[67] Civil rights are a basic condition for the existence of citizenship.[68]
Individual rights to protection include the rights of life, liberty, and property- which are Locke's description of
natural rights.[69][70]

In an embedded democracy, rights are also established to protect against illegitimate arrest, exile, terror, torture
or unjustifiable intervention into personal life.[71] Other basic civil rights include equal access to the law and
equal treatment by the law.[72] According to Merkel, “these civil rights tame majoritarian democratic cycles
and thereby support-seemingly paradoxically-the democratization of democracy”[73] Securing civil rights
creates a barrier against the state infringing on individual freedoms.[74] However, the guarantee of civil rights
alone cannot sufficiently make up or support a constitutional democracy, because there has to be support from
the other partial regimes.[75][76]

Horizontal accountability

Horizontal accountability requires a system of checks and balances between the three branches of government:
executive, legislative, and judicial.[77] In an embedded democracy, the branches of government should be able
to function with a reasonable amount of autonomy despite the fact that they are not wholly separate but instead
"check each other reciprocally, without one body dominating or interfering with the constitutionally defined
core-sphere of the others."[78]

Within Merkel's model of embedded democracy, the regime of horizontal accountability works to
constitutionally ensure that an appropriate amount of power is shared among the different institutions, which
helps secure the civil rights of the people of the state. There should be agencies with the legal power to expose
and punish governmental institutions for corruption or other unlawful actions.[79] This ensures that no one
branch gains a preponderance of power and is able to unduly influence the policies and governance of the
state.[80] This horizontal accountability works in tandem with vertical accountability, which is the systems by
which citizens check the power of the government elections, the media, or civil society.[81] However,
horizontal accountability carries more weight in ensuring the internal embeddedness of democracy, as it is
more frequently used than vertical accountability[82] and has a more substantial support from the constitution
of a state. If it is indeed constitutionally mandated, horizontal accountability can "close a central gap of control
in the basic democratic structure, one that is not covered by the first three partial regimes"[83]

Power of elected representative to govern

The power of elected representatives to govern, or what Merkel refers to as the “effective power to
govern,”[84] is the final partial regime. Effective power to govern is necessary in an embedded democracy that
is representative of “not only the procedural aspect but also the goals of democratic elections.”[85] Within the
different dimensions of embedded democracy, as defined by Merkel, effective power to govern falls under the
“dimension of effective agenda control.” [86]

Effective power to govern is a necessity for functioning democracies, but Merkel emphasizes that this is not
the case for countries that have only recently democratized.[87][88][89] In particular, nations that hold
democratic elections but still host military forces with some degree of autonomous power cannot fully meet the
requirements of effective power to govern, since unelected military officials may have undue sway over
governmental operations.[90] In these kinds of democracies, the underpinnings of political participation are
compromised as the general populace is only allowed “low intensity citizenship,” with most decisions left to
extra-governmental, non-democratic forces.[91] However, some arms of the government, such as a central
bank or constitutional court, may be left autonomous or nearly autonomous and still meet the requirements of
effective power to govern.[92] This is only possible if these autonomous bodies are established with
“constitutional consent,” fulfilling the social contract between the state and the people[93]

In keeping with Merkel's assertion that “mutual embeddedness means that some partial regimes support the
functioning of another partial regime,”[94] effective power to govern is closely tied to the electoral regime. By
ensuring that democratic elections are meaningful and democratically elected officials are afforded the
representative powers expected by voters, maintenance of the effective power to govern provides "the
necessary complementary support"[95] to the electoral regime in "mak[ing] up liberal ‘embedded
democracies.'"[96]

Merkel's notion of effective power to govern has been traced to Robert Dahl's minimalist conception of
democracy.[97] Dahl's definition of democracy requires that governmental “institutions...depend on elections
and other expressions of the citizens’ preferences,”[98] just as Merkel insists that the power to make policy
must ultimately rest with democratically elected representatives of the people.[99]

External factors of embeddedness

Socio-economic

If a nation is more socio-economically developed, there is a greater chance that it will sustain a
democracy.[100] The evidence supports the link between the economy and democratic sustainability.[101][102]
Arguments against this idea are that economic prosperity is not the only necessary requirement for a successful
democracy, nor can economic development be used to predict the permanence of
democratization.[103][104][105] Merkel gives the example that the United States cannot claim to have a higher
quality democracy than Finland's democracy, even though the United States has a higher GDP per capita.[106]
There is also a connection between inequality and democratic government.[107] When unequal distributions of
economic resources lead to wider wealth and income gaps, which in turn lead to more poverty, there is a
negative impact on democracy.[108] Hermann Heller stresses that a sufficiently homogeneous economic basis
among citizens provides for equal participation in the democratic process.[109] Once citizens have reached an
adequate social and economic standing, they can form their own independent opinions and participate equally
in the democratic process.[110] Scholars agree that real political equality cannot be produced if there is severe
socio-economic inequality.[111][112][113]

Civil society

Merkel states that civil society serves four functions in strengthening a democracy: protection of the individual
from the arbitrary use of state power, support for the rule of law and the balance of powers, education of
citizens and recruitment of political elites, and institutionalization of the public sphere as a medium of
democratic self-reflection.[114]

In the case of protection from state power, the philosopher John Locke's idea of civil society as separate from
the political sphere[115] is referenced.[116] Civil society facilitates the development of individual autonomy
alongside natural rights and property rights to further the embeddedness of democracy.[117][118] Merkel also
references Montesquieu's concept of institutionalized civil society to check the power of the government and to
promote balance within a state.[119][120] Alexis de Tocqueville's concept of civil society and social capital
explains how a civil society can work to normalize and solidify the democratic process and establish an
embedded democracy.[121][122] Local associations are meant to create trust and foster a sense of civic
responsibility that is carried out into the national level as well as the political sphere.[123][124] According to
Habermas, civil society can also provide a platform for the economically and socially disadvantaged to air
grievances with the government and improve their state.[125]

International integration

Integration into international organizations provides a source of external stability that democratic regimes
cannot produce by themselves.[126] In particular, social, economic, and political organizations (as opposed to
military organizations) are necessary, since authoritarian regimes and defective democracies are able to
function and potentially thrive within the confines of even democratically-dominated military alliances.[127]
Merkel points to the European Union as the "most successful [organization] in the international embedding of
democracies."[128] International integration ultimately serves to protect the integrity of a democracy's internal
partial regimes by subjecting them to external scrutiny.[129] At the same time, better-established internal
regimes also allow the state to be more effective in repelling threats from external actors.[130] Therefore,
international integration works in multiple ways to further embed and normalize democracy through the
internal regimes.[131]

Defective democracy
Unlike embedded democracies, defective democracies are missing one or more of the internal factors of
embeddedness.[132][133] These factors vary on a case-by-case basis, which results in some confusion
regarding the classification of non-embedded regimes.[134][135] Merkel named four notable types of defective
democracy: exclusive democracy, illiberal democracy, delegative democracy, and domain democracy.[136]

see also page Defective democracy

Illiberal democracy
See also main article on illiberal democracy.

Illiberal democracy is one of the four subtypes of defective democracy.[137] Differentiating illiberal
democracies from other types of democracy is difficult.[138][139] One method used to differentiate is by using
numerical thresholds provided by the ‘‘civil rights scale,’’ which is one of two measurement scales used by
Freedom House.[140][141] Every regime with a score of 3.5-5.5 on a scale of 1-7, with 7 being a completely
totalitarian regime, is considered an illiberal democracy.[142][143] However, Freedom House offers no
justification for these thresholds, and the scales used are often outdated.[144]

Illiberal democracies are in a weak, incomplete, and damaged constitutional state.[145] The executive and
legislative control of the state is only weakly limited by the judiciary.[146][147] Additionally, constitutional
norms in an illiberal democracy have little impact on government actions, and individual civil rights are either
partially repressed or not yet established.[148] The legitimacy of the rule of law is damaged.[149][150] Illiberal
democracy is the most common type of defective democracy, constituting 22 of 29 defective democracies as
defined by Merkel.[151] Examples of illiberal democracies include many Latin American countries, as well as
some countries in Eastern Europe and Asia.[152] The following are illiberal democracies: Brazil, Bolivia,
Guatemala, El Salvador, Honduras, Mexico, Nicaragua, Panama, Paraguay, Peru, Albania, Bulgaria, Croatia,
Macedonia, Moldova, Romania, Russia, Ukraine, Thailand, Philippines, Bangladesh, and Nepal.[153]

Domain democracy

A domain democracy is a form of defective democracy in which actors who were not democratically elected
as representatives of the people hold veto power in policy matters.[154] Actors of this type "take certain
political domains out of the hands of democratically elected representatives,"[155] hence the term domain
democracy. Domain democracies are considered to be highly regional phenomena, with many found in Latin
America and Southeast Asia, but few in Central Asia or Eastern Europe.[156] Paraguay, Thailand, and
Colombia are commonly set forth as examples of domain democracies, specifically during their times of
economic rule by guerrilla forces[157]

Exclusive democracy

Exclusive democracies are one form of defective democracies in which "one or more segments of the adult
population are excluded from the civil right of universal suffrage."[158] This form of defective democracy is
defective because the internal regime of civil rights as well as the internal regime of elections (including free
and fair) are not allowed within the government system.[159] As part of their civil rights, citizens need to be
guaranteed sovereignty and the ability to vote and the exclusion of some citizens from electoral processes
creates an exclusive democracy. Apartheid South Africa is an example of an exclusive democracy because not
all members of the adult population were guaranteed the right of universal suffrage.[160]

Delegative democracy

A delegative democracy occurs when there is a lack of horizontal accountability and one branch of
government become powerful enough to control the entire government. In a delegative democracy, the
judiciary and legislative branches are often unable to properly check the power of the executive branch.[161]
This lets the executive shift the balance of power into its favor.[162]

However, the power of the executive in a delegative democracy is still restricted in the sense that the president
has heavy control of the state only for the length of his term.[163] This creates a high-stakes election process
wherein the winner is granted power that is only checked by non-institutionalized power structures,[164] such
as those systems that create vertical accountability. Most of the research on delegative democracies has
concerned the populist leaders of Central and South America who used the executive branch to govern the
country as they saw fit.[165][166][167][168]

Alternative models for assessing democracies


Defective democracy is an alternative to terms such as electoral democracy, illiberal democracy, or partial
democracy, all of which describe governing systems that meet only some of the conditions required for a full
democracy.[169] Merkel argues that using embedded democracy as the basis for assessing real regimes is a
more nuanced method than the quantitative rankings released by organizations like Freedom House (https://fre
edomhouse.org) which are often used to categorize a democracy as liberal, semi-liberal, or illiberal.[170]

Embedded and defective democracies are primarily categorized based on their institutions rather than their
purposes or outcomes.[171] This is in keeping with the procedural approach to democratic scholarship
followed by scholars such as Schmitter and Huntington.[172][173]

An embedded democracy can be considered a type of consolidated democracy, meaning that the democratic
regime in an embedded democracy is seen as legitimate and stable.[174] Political scientists debate the definition
of democratic consolidation, but at minimum, a consolidated democracy is entrenched so that democracy is
considered "the only game in town."[175][176] Some scholars, like Merkel, take a maximalist approach to
defining consolidated democracy by specifying the partial regimes of consolidation.[177] Gunther considers
three dimensions of consolidation—institutional, attitudinal, and behavioral—while Linz and Stepan highlight
five arenas for consolidation: civil society, political society, rule of law, the state apparatus and economic
society.[178][179][180]

Other scholars have developed multidimensional models of democracy that are similar to Merkel's embedded
democracy model.[181] For instance, Dahl defines polyarchy based on seven distinct criteria: elected officials,
free elections, inclusive suffrage, the right to run for office, freedom of expression, alternative information, and
associational autonomy.[182][183]

Some scholars critique Merkel's model for merely describing the institutional elements found in a liberal
embedded democracy and then categorizing other "hybrid regimes" as diminished subtypes of
democracy.[184][185] Jayasuriya and Rodan point out that Merkel's model fails to account for how and why
regimes form.[186] Møller and Skanning praise Merkel's work for creating a cohesive system of democratic
subtypes but argue that Merkel suffers from the "radial delusion," meaning that it lacks a hierarchical structure,
which makes it difficult to conduct consistent empirical analyses of democratic regimes.[187] According to
Møller and Skanning, there are also inconsistencies between Merkel's original papers on embedded and
defective democracy and later works by his colleagues Aurel Croissant and Hans-Jürgen Puhle.[188][189]

References
1. Merkel, Wolfgang (December 2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (http://homepag
e.univie.ac.at/vedran.dzihic/merkel_embedded_democracies_2004.pdf) (PDF).
Democratization. 11 (5). Retrieved 6 November 2014.
2. Buhllman, Mark; Merkel, Wolfgang; Wessels, Bernhard (April 2008). "The Quality of
Democracy: Democracy Barometer for Established Democracies". Hertie School of
Governance - Working Papers.
3. Merkel, Wolfgang; Croissant, Aurel (December 2004). "Conclusion: Good and Defective
Democracies". Democratization. 11 (5): 199–213. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304651 (http
s://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340412331304651).
4. Merkel (2004) p.33
5. Merkel (2004) p.36-27
6. Merkel (2004) p.43-45
7. Buhllman et. al (2008) p.7
8. Merkel (2004) p.43-45
9. Buhllman et. al p.7
10. Buhlmann et. al p.9
11. Merkel (2004) p.38
12. Merkel (2004) p.38
13. Munck, Gerardo (2002). "Conceptualizing and Measuring Democracy: Evaluating Alternative
Indices". Comparative Political Studies. 35 (1): 5–34. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.469.3177 (https://citese
erx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.469.3177). doi:10.1177/001041400203500101 (h
ttps://doi.org/10.1177%2F001041400203500101). S2CID 73722608 (https://api.semanticschol
ar.org/CorpusID:73722608).
14. Bhlmann, Marc; Merkel, Wolfgang; Wessels, Bernhard (April 2008). "The Quality of Democracy:
Democracy Barometer for Established Democracies". Hertie School of Governance Working
Papers (22): 7.
15. Hadenius, Axel (1992). Democracy and Development (https://archive.org/details/democracydev
elop00hade). Cambridge University Press. p. 16 (https://archive.org/details/democracydevelop
00hade/page/n27).
16. Dahl, Robert (1989). Democracy and Its Critics (https://archive.org/details/democracyitscrit00da
hl_0). Yale University Press. p. 221 (https://archive.org/details/democracyitscrit00dahl_0/page/
221).
17. Dahl (1989) p.221
18. Brownlee, Jason (July 2009). "Portents of Pluralism: How Hybrid Regimes Affect Democratic
Traditions". American Journal of Political Science. 53 (3): 517. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.567.4638 (http
s://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.567.4638). doi:10.1111/j.1540-
5907.2009.00384.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1540-5907.2009.00384.x).
19. Bjornlund, Eric C. (2004). Beyond free and fair : Monitoring Elections and Building Democracy
(https://archive.org/details/beyondfreefairmo0000bjor). Baltimore, Md.: The Johns Hopkins
University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-8048-3.
20. Diamond, Larry (1996). "Is the Third Wave Over?". Journal of Democracy. 7 (3): 20–37.
doi:10.1353/jod.1996.0047 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1996.0047). S2CID 30183416 (http
s://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:30183416).
21. Merkel (2004) p.38
22. "Methodology" (https://freedomhouse.org/report/freedom-world-2012/methodology#.VFrzZOfHL
FY). Freedom House. 2012-01-19. Retrieved 8 November 2014.
23. Schmitter, Phillippe; Karl, Terry (Summer 1991). "What Democracy is and is Not". Journal of
Democracy. 2 (3): 75–88. doi:10.1353/jod.1991.0033 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1991.003
3). S2CID 144289532 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144289532).
24. Merkel (2004) p.40
25. Wessels, Bernhard; Schmitt, Hermann (March 2008). "Meaningful Choices, Political Supply,
and Institutional Effectiveness". Electoral Studies. 27 (1): 19–30.
doi:10.1016/j.electstud.2007.11.010 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2Fj.electstud.2007.11.010).
26. Merkel (2004) p.38
27. Merkel (2004) p.39
28. Merkel (2004) p.39
29. Merkel (2004) p.39
30. Merkel (2004) p.39
31. Pateman, Carol (1970). Participation and Democratic Theory (https://archive.org/details/particip
ationdem00caro). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
32. Schumpeter, Joseph (1943). Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. Routledge.
33. Pateman (1970) p.3
34. Dahl, Robert (1956). A Preface to Democratic Theory (https://archive.org/details/prefacetodemo
cra0000robe). University of Chicago Press.
35. Pateman (1970) p.9
36. Merkel, Wolfgang; Croissant, Aurel (December 2004). "Conclusion: Good and Defective
Democracies". Democratization. 11 (5): 199–213. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304651 (http
s://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340412331304651).
37. O'Donnell, Guillermo. "Poverty and Inequality in Latin America: Some Political Reflections," in
Vi'ctor E. Tokman and Guillermo O’Donnell (eds), Poverty and Inequality in Latin America
(Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), p.195–215
38. Pateman (1970) p.1
39. Rosenberg, Morris (1954). "Some Determinants of Political Apathy". Public Opinion Quarterly.
18 (4): 349–366. doi:10.1086/266528 (https://doi.org/10.1086%2F266528).
40. Pateman (1970) p.2
41. Merkel, Wolfgang; Croissant, Aurel (December 2004). "Conclusion: Good and Defective
Democracies". Democratization. 11 (5): 199–213. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304651 (http
s://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340412331304651).
42. Kim, Sidney Verba, Norman H. Nie, Jae-on (1987). Participation and political equality : a
seven-nation comparison (https://books.google.com/books?id=7SksV_EPkiQC) ([Repr.] ed.).
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 9780226852980. Retrieved 4 November 2014.p.
43. Verba et. al (1987)
44. Fishkin, James (2009). When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy and Public
Consultation (https://books.google.com/books?id=wSJeokRZUhMC&pg=PT148&lpg=PT148&
dq=Fishkin,+James+S.+1991.+When+the+People+Speak:+Deliberative+Democracy+and+Pu
blic+Consultation.#v=onepage). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780191610158.
Retrieved 4 November 2014.
45. Gutmann, Amy; Thompson, Dennis (2009). Why Deliberative Democracy?. Princeton
University Press.
46. Fishkin (2009)
47. Fishkin (2009)
48. Krueger, Brian (2002). "Assessing the Potential of Internet Political Participation in the United
States: a Resource Approach". American Politics Research. 30 (5): 476–498.
doi:10.1177/1532673x02030005002 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1532673x02030005002).
S2CID 153537226 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:153537226).
49. Fishkin (2009)
50. Democracy, Representative and Participatory. (2008). In W. A. Darity, Jr. (Ed.), International
Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (2nd ed., Vol. 2, pp. 283-285). Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA.
51. Merkel (2004) p.39
52. Buhlmann et. al p.15
53. Schmidt, Siegmar. "New Kids on the Block: Embedded Democracy, Defective Democracy and
Failing States" (http://www.cameco.org/mez/pdf/2006/1schmidt.pdf) (PDF): 15.
54. Elster, Jon (1988). Constitutionalism and Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
55. Merkel (2004) p.39
56. Merkel (2004) p.39
57. Elster, Jon (1988). Constitutionalism and Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
58. Nino, Carlos (1996). The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy. Yale University Press.
59. Reitz, John (1997). "Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law". Democratic Theory: 111–143.
60. Buhlmann et. al p.18
61. Beetham, David (1994). Defining and Measuring Democracy. London Sage. pp. 25–43.
62. Merkel (2004) p.39-40
63. Merkel (2004) p.39
64. Tocqueville, Alexis de (1835). Democracy in America.
65. {{Buhlmann et. al p.39
66. Merkel (2004) p.39
67. Linz, Juan; Stepan, Alfred (1996). Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation,
Southern Europe, South America, and Post-Communist Europe. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press. p. 10.
68. Merkel (2004) p.45
69. Buhlmann et. al p.18
70. Merkel (2004) p.40
71. Merkel (2004) p.40
72. Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (http://homepage.univie.ac.
at/vedran.dzihic/merkel_embedded_democracies_2004.pdf) (PDF): 40.
73. Merkel (2004) p.40
74. Merkel (2004) p.41
75. Merkel (2004) p.40
76. Buhlmann et. al p.15
77. Merkel (2004) p.40
78. Merkel (2004) p.40
79. O'Donnell, Guillermo (1998). "Horizontal Accountability in New Democracies". Journal of
Democracy. 3 (9): 112–126. doi:10.1353/jod.1998.0051 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1998.0
051). S2CID 154954940 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154954940).
80. O'Donnell (1998) p.117
81. Stapenhusrt, Rick. "Accountability in Governance" (http://siteresources.worldbank.org/PUBLIC
SECTORANDGOVERNANCE/Resources/AccountabilityGovernance.pdf) (PDF). World Bank.
82. Merkel (2004) p.40
83. Dahl, Robert (1989). "Democracy and its Critics" (https://archive.org/details/democracyitscrit00
dahl_0): 221 (https://archive.org/details/democracyitscrit00dahl_0/page/221).
84. Merkel, Wolfgang (2012). "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?"
(https://web.archive.org/web/20140811151616/http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePe
ople.pdf#page=197) (PDF). By the People, for the People, Without the People?: 197. Archived
from the original (http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePeople.pdf#page=197) (PDF) on
2014-08-11. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
85. Merkel, Wolfgang (2012). "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?"
(https://web.archive.org/web/20140811151616/http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePe
ople.pdf#page=190) (PDF). By the People, for the People, Without the People?: 190. Archived
from the original (http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePeople.pdf#page=190) (PDF) on
2014-08-11. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
86. Merkel (2004) p.42
87. Merkel (2004) p.41
88. Collier, David; Levitsky, Steven (1997). "Democracy with Adjectives: Conceptual Innovation in
Comparative Research" (https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5ft9n1jx). World Politics. 49 (3): 430–
451. doi:10.1353/wp.1997.0009 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fwp.1997.0009). S2CID 11541730
(https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:11541730).
89. Grande, Edgar (2000). Democracy Beyond the State?: The European Dilemma and the
Emerging Global Order. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 115.
90. Merkel, Wolfgang (2012). "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?"
(https://web.archive.org/web/20140811151616/http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePe
ople.pdf#page=197) (PDF). By the People, for the People, Without the People?: 197. Archived
from the original (http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePeople.pdf#page=197) (PDF) on
2014-08-11. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
91. O'Donnell, Guillermo (1999). Counterpoints. Selected Essays on Authoritarianism and
Democratization. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
92. Bastian, Sunil; Luckham, Robin (2003). Can Democracy be Designed?: The Politics of
Institutional Choice in Conflict-Torn Societies. London: Zed Books. p. 149.
93. Merkel (2004) p.42
94. Merkel, Wolfgang (2012). "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?"
(https://web.archive.org/web/20140811151616/http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePe
ople.pdf#page=197) (PDF). By the People, for the People, Without the People?: 199. Archived
from the original (http://en.idi.org.il/media/1430593/EB1ByThePeople.pdf#page=197) (PDF) on
2014-08-11. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
95. Croissant, Aurel; Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Introduction: Democratization in the Early Twenty-
first Century" (http://www.uni-heidelberg.de/imperia/md/content/fakultaeten/wiso/ipw/croissant/p
ublications/croissant_merkel_2004_democracy_in_21_century.pdf) (PDF). Democratization. 11
(5): 4. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304570 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340412331304
570). S2CID 56153934 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:56153934).
96. Croissant, Aurel; Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Introduction: democratization in the early twenty-
first century" (http://www.uni-heidelberg.de/imperia/md/content/fakultaeten/wiso/ipw/croissant/p
ublications/croissant_merkel_2004_democracy_in_21_century.pdf) (PDF). Democratization. 11
(5): 5. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304570 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340412331304
570). S2CID 56153934 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:56153934).
97. Zittel, Thomas (2008). "Participatory Engineering: Promises and Pitfalls". CONNEX Report
Series. 5: 127.
98. Dahl, Robert (1972). Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition (https://archive.org/details/polyarc
hypartici0000dahl). New Haven: Yale University Press. p. 3 (https://archive.org/details/polyarch
ypartici0000dahl/page/3).
99. Schmidt, Siegmar (2005). "New Kids on the Block: Embedded Democracy, Defective
Democracy and Failing States" (http://www.cameco.org/mez/pdf/2006/1schmidt.pdf) (PDF).
Democratization - A Central Task of Media Development Cooperation: 7.
00. Lipset, Seymour (1959). "Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and
Political Legitimacy". American Political Science Review. 53 (1): 69–105. doi:10.2307/1951731
(https://doi.org/10.2307%2F1951731). JSTOR 1951731 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/1951731).
01. Cutright, Philips (1963). "National Political Development Its Measures and Analysis". American
Sociological Review. 28 (2): 253–264. doi:10.2307/2090612 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F20906
12). JSTOR 2090612 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2090612).
02. Przeworski, Adam; Limongi, Fernando (1997). "What Makes Democracies Endure". World
Politics. 49 (1).
03. Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (https://web.archive.org/we
b/20140112192343/http://www.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/personen/merkel.wolfgang.289/merkel
_embedded_and_defective_democracies.pdf) (PDF): 44. Archived from the original (http://ww
w.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/personen/merkel.wolfgang.289/merkel_embedded_and_defective_
democracies.pdf) (PDF) on 2014-01-12. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
04. Przeworski, Adam; Limongi, Fernando (1997). "What Makes Democracies Endure". 49 (1).
05. Huntington, Samuel (1991). The Third Wave Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century.
Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press.
06. Merkel (2004) p.44
07. Merkel (2004) p.44
08. O'Donnell, Guillermo (1998). "Horizontal Accountability in New Democracies". Journal of
Democracy. 3 (9): 112–126. doi:10.1353/jod.1998.0051 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1998.0
051). S2CID 154954940 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154954940).
09. Heller, Hermann (1971). "Democracy and Social Homogeneity". 2.
10. Lipset, Seymour (1959). "Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and
Political Legitimacy". American Political Science Review. 53 (1): 69–105. doi:10.2307/1951731
(https://doi.org/10.2307%2F1951731). JSTOR 1951731 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/1951731).
11. Merkel (2004) p.44
12. Heller, Hermann (1971). "Democracy and Social Homogeneity". 2.
13. Kruck, Mirko (2004). "Social Justice and Democracy: Investigating the Link". International
Politics and Society. 1: 134–158.
14. Merkel (2004) p.47
15. Dunn, J.M. (July 1989). " 'Bright Enough for All Our Purposes': John Locke's Conception of a
Civilized Society". Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London. 43 (2): 136.
doi:10.1098/rsnr.1989.0011 (https://doi.org/10.1098%2Frsnr.1989.0011). S2CID 144051600 (htt
ps://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144051600).
16. Merkel (2004) p.45
17. Held, David (1996). Models of Democracy (https://archive.org/details/modelsofdemocrac00hel
d). Cambridge Polity Press.
18. Merkel (2004) p.46
19. Montesquieu, Charles (1838). Oeuvres comple'tes. Paris: Didot. p. 280.
20. Merkel (2004) p.45
21. Putnam, Robert (1993). Making Democracy Work. Civic Traditions in Modern Italy (https://archiv
e.org/details/makingdemocracyw00putn_823). Princeton: Princeton University Press. p. 163 (ht
tps://archive.org/details/makingdemocracyw00putn_823/page/n179).
22. Putnam, Robert (2000). Bowling Alone (https://archive.org/details/bowlingalone00robe). New
York: Simon & Shuester.
23. Putnam (2000). Bowling Alone (https://archive.org/details/bowlingalone00robe).
24. Merkel (2004) p.46
25. Habermas. Faktizita¨t und Geltung.
26. Schiff, Maurice; Winters, L. Alan (2002). Regional Cooperation, and the Role of International
Organizations and Regional Integration. Washington, DC: The World Bank Research
Development Group.
27. Merkel (2012) p.206
28. Merkel (2004) p.48
29. Moravcsik, Andrew (1994). Why the European Community strengthens the state: Domestic
politics and international cooperation. Cambridge, MA: Minda de Gunzburg Center for
European Studies, Harvard University. p. 52.
30. Merkel (2012) p.206
31. Levitsky, Steven; Way, Lucan (2005). "International linkage and democratization". Journal of
Democracy. 16 (3): 29. doi:10.1353/jod.2005.0048 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.2005.0048).
S2CID 154397302 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154397302).
32. Merkel (2004) p.33
33. Puhle, Hans-Jürgen (2005). "Democratic Consolidation and Defective Democracies".
Estudio/Working Paper 47
34. Merkel (2004) p.49
35. Boggards, Matthijs (2009). "How to Classify Hybrid Regimes? Defective Democracy and
Electoral Authoritarianism". Democratization. 16 (2).
36. Merkel (2004)p.49
37. Fareed, Zakaria (1997). "The Rise of Illiberal Democracy". Foreign Affairs. 76 (6): 22–43.
doi:10.2307/20048274 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F20048274). JSTOR 20048274 (https://www.j
stor.org/stable/20048274).
38. Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (https://web.archive.org/we
b/20140112192343/http://www.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/personen/merkel.wolfgang.289/merkel
_embedded_and_defective_democracies.pdf) (PDF): 49. Archived from the original (http://ww
w.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/personen/merkel.wolfgang.289/merkel_embedded_and_defective_
democracies.pdf) (PDF) on 2014-01-12. Retrieved 2014-11-23.
39. Merkel, Wolfgang. "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?" (http://
www.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/u289/merkel.pdf) (PDF): 187.
40. Karatnycky, Adrian (1999). "The Decline of Illiberal Democracy". Journal of Democracy. 9 (1):
112–123. doi:10.1353/jod.1999.0011 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1999.0011).
S2CID 154900125 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154900125).
41. Merkel (2004) p.34
42. Collier, David; Levitsky, Steven (1997). "Democracies with Adjectives. Conceptual Innovation
in Comparative Research" (https://cloudfront.escholarship.org/dist/prd/content/qt5ft9n1jx/qt5ft9n
1jx.pdf?t=p6891s) (PDF). World Politics. 49 (2): 430–451. doi:10.1353/wp.1997.0009 (https://do
i.org/10.1353%2Fwp.1997.0009). S2CID 11541730 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:
11541730).
43. Merkel (2004) p.34
44. Merkel (2004) p.34
45. Merkel, Wolfgang (2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (http://homepage.univie.ac.
at/vedran.dzihic/merkel_embedded_democracies_2004.pdf) (PDF): 49.
46. Fareed, Zakaria (1997). "The Rise of Illiberal Democracy". Foreign Affairs. 76 (6): 22–43.
doi:10.2307/20048274 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F20048274). JSTOR 20048274 (https://www.j
stor.org/stable/20048274).
47. Merkel (2012) p.186
48. Merkel (2004) p.48
49. Merkel (2004) p.50
50. Schmidt, Siegmar. "New Kids on the Block: Embedded Democracy, Defective Democracy and
Failing States" (http://www.cameco.org/mez/pdf/2006/1schmidt.pdf) (PDF): 13.
51. Merkel (2004) p.50
52. Merkel (2012) p.208
53. Merkel (2004) p.51
54. Schmidt (2005) p.8
55. Merkel (2004) p.49
56. Merkel (2012) p.208
57. Schmidt, Manfred (2002). "Political performance and types of democracy: Findings from
comparative studies" (http://www.hks.harvard.edu/fs/pnorris/Acrobat/stm103%20articles/schmid
t_Types_of_demo_and_perf.pdf) (PDF). European Journal of Political Research. 41: 158.
doi:10.1111/1475-6765.00007 (https://doi.org/10.1111%2F1475-6765.00007).
58. Merkel, Wolfgang (December 2004). "Embedded and Defective Democracies" (http://homepag
e.univie.ac.at/vedran.dzihic/merkel_embedded_democracies_2004.pdf) (PDF).
Democratization. 11 (5): 49. doi:10.1080/13510340412331304598 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F
13510340412331304598). S2CID 149654333 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:14965
4333). Retrieved 6 November 2014.
59. Boggards, Matthijs (2009). "How to Classify Hybrid Regimes? Defective Democracy and
Electoral Authoritarianism". Democratization. 16 (2).
60. Kaplan, David (October 1980). "The South African State: The Origins of a Racially Exclusive
Democracy" (http://crs.sagepub.com/content/10/2/85.extract). Critical Sociology. 10 (2): 85–96.
doi:10.1177/089692058001000207 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F089692058001000207).
S2CID 144845907 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144845907).
61. Merkel (2004) p.50
62. O'Donnell, Guillermo (1994). "Defective Democracy". Journal of Democracy. 5 (1): 56–59.
doi:10.1353/jod.1994.0010 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1994.0010). S2CID 8558740 (http
s://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:8558740).
63. Larkin, Christopher (July 1998). "The Judiciary and Delegative Democracy in Argentina".
Comparative Politics. 30 (4): 423–442. doi:10.2307/422332 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F42233
2). JSTOR 422332 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/422332).
64. O'Donnell, Guilermo (April 1993). "Delegative Democracies?" (https://kellogg.nd.edu/publicatio
ns/workingpapers/WPS/172.pdf) (PDF). World Development.
65. Panizza, Frank (October 2000). "Beyond 'Delegative Democracy': 'Old Politics' and 'New
Economics' in Latin America". Journal of Latin American Studies. 32 (3): 737–763.
doi:10.1017/s0022216x00005927 (https://doi.org/10.1017%2Fs0022216x00005927).
66. Schmidt, Gregory (Spring 2000). "Delegative Democracy in Peru? Fujimori's 1995 Landslide
and the Prospects for 2000". Journal of Interamerican Studies and World Affairs. 42 (1): 99–
132. doi:10.2307/166467 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F166467). JSTOR 166467 (https://www.jst
or.org/stable/166467).
67. Walker, Lee (October 2009). "Delegative Democratic Attitudes and Institutional Support in
Central America". Comparative Politics. 42: 83–101.
doi:10.5129/001041509x12911362972872 (https://doi.org/10.5129%2F001041509x12911362
972872).
68. O'Donnell (1998) p.112}}
69. Merkel (2004) p.34
70. Merkel (2004) p.35
71. Merkel, Wolfgang. "Embedded and Defective Democracies: Where Does Israel Stand?". New
Politics, No Politics, and Antipolitics: 186–225.
72. Schmitter, Philippe C.; Karl, Terry (1991). "What Democracy Is...and Is Not?". Journal of
Democracy. 2 (3): 75–88. doi:10.1353/jod.1991.0033 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1991.003
3). S2CID 144289532 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144289532).
73. Huntington, Samuel (1991). The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century.
Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press.
74. Merkel (2004) p.33
75. Linz, Juan; Stepan, Alferd (1996). "Toward Consolidated Democracies". Journal of Democracy.
7 (2): 14–33. doi:10.1353/jod.1996.0031 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1996.0031).
S2CID 154644233 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154644233).
76. Schedler, Andreas (1998). "What is Democratic Consolidation". Journal of Democracy. 9 (2):
91–107. doi:10.1353/jod.1998.0030 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1998.0030).
S2CID 154088037 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:154088037).
77. Puhle, Hans-Jürgen (2005). "Democratic Consolidation and Defective Democracies".
Estudio/Working Paper. 47.
78. Puhle and Hans-Jürgen (2005)
79. Gunther, Richard; Diamandourous, P. Nikiforos; Puhle, Hans-Jürgen (1995). The Politics of
Democratic Consolidation: Southern Europe in Comparative Perspective (https://archive.org/de
tails/politicsofdemocr00rich). Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
80. Linz, Juan J.; Stepan, Alfred (1978). The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes. Baltimore: The
Johns Hopkins University Press.
81. Jayasuriya, Kanishka (2007). "Beyond Hybrid Regimes: More Participation, Less Contestation
in Southeast Asia". Democratization. 14 (5): 773–794. doi:10.1080/13510340701635647 (http
s://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340701635647). S2CID 143602074 (https://api.semanticscholar.
org/CorpusID:143602074).
82. Dahl, Robert (1989). Democracy and its Critics (https://archive.org/details/democracyitscrit00da
hl_0). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
83. O'Donnell, Guillermo (1996). "Illusions About Democratization". Journal of Democracy. 7 (2):
34–51. doi:10.1353/jod.1996.0034 (https://doi.org/10.1353%2Fjod.1996.0034).
S2CID 153457880 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:153457880).
84. Jayasuriya, Kanishka; Rodan, Garry (2007). "Beyond Hybrid Regimes: More Participation,
Less Contestation in Southeast Asiaa". Democratization. 14 (5): 773–794.
doi:10.1080/13510340701635647 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340701635647).
S2CID 143602074 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:143602074).
85. Møller, Jørgen; Skanning, Svend-Erik (June 2010). "Beyond the Radial Delusion:
Conceptualizing and Measuring Democracy and Non-Democracy" (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F
0192512110369522). International Political Science Review. 31 (3): 261–283.
doi:10.1177/0192512110369522 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0192512110369522).
86. Jayasuriya, Kanishka (2007). "Beyond Hybrid Regimes: More Participation, Less Contestation
in Southeast Asia". Democratization. 14 (5): 773–794. doi:10.1080/13510340701635647 (http
s://doi.org/10.1080%2F13510340701635647). S2CID 143602074 (https://api.semanticscholar.
org/CorpusID:143602074).
87. Møller, Jørgen; Skanning, Svend-Erik (June 2010). "Beyond the Radial Delusion:
Conceptualizing and Measuring Democracy and Non-Democracy" (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F
0192512110369522). International Political Science Review. 31 (3): 261–283.
doi:10.1177/0192512110369522 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0192512110369522).
88. Møller, Jørgen; Skanning, Svend-Erik (June 2010). "Beyond the Radial Delusion:
Conceptualizing and Measuring Democracy and Non-Democracy" (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F
0192512110369522). International Political Science Review. 31 (3): 261–283.
doi:10.1177/0192512110369522 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0192512110369522).
89. Puhle, Hans-Jürgen (2005). "Democratic Consolidation and Defective Democracies".
Estudio/Working Paper. 47.

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Embedded_democracy&oldid=1026742872"

This page was last edited on 4 June 2021, at 01:06 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this
site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like