You are on page 1of 2

Eye on the Present—The Whig History of Science

Steven Weinberg

It was the Cambridge historian Her-


bert Butterfield who described and
condemned what he called “the Whig
interpretation of history.” In a book
with that title, the young Butterfield
in 1931 declared that “the study of the
past with one eye, so to speak, upon
the present is the source of all sins and
sophistries in history. . . .”1 He spread
special scorn on those historians, in-
cluding Lord Acton, who subject the
past to contemporary moral judgments,
who for instance are unable to see the
Whig Charles James Fox as anything
but a savior of British liberties. Not that
Butterfield was personally unwilling to
make moral judgments; he just did not
think it was the business of historians.
According to Butterfield, the whig his-
torian studying Catholics and Protes-
tants in the sixteenth century feels that
some “loose threads are still left hang-
ing unless he can show which party was
in the right.”
Butterfield’s strictures were fer-
vently taken up by later generations of
historians. Being called “whig” came
to seem as terrifying to historians as
being called sexist, or Eurocentric, or
Orientalist. Nor was the history of sci-
ence spared. The historian of science
Bruce Hunt recalls that when he was
in graduate school in the early 1980s,
“whiggish” was a common term of
abuse in the history of science. To avoid
that charge, people turned away from
telling stories of scientific progress or
from giving “big picture” stories of any
kind, and shifted to accounts of small
episodes, tightly focused in time and
space.
Nevertheless, in teaching courses on ‘Scenography of the Copernican World System’; engraving from Andreas Cellarius’s Harmonia macrocosmica, 1660
the history of physics and astronomy,
and then working up my lectures into the working scientist’s understanding dards, not individuals. Above all, we because scientific history with an eye to
a book, I have come to think that what- of present science. On the other hand, must not imagine that our predecessors present knowledge is needed by scien-
ever one thinks of whiggery in other it must be admitted that a scientist like thought the way we think, only with tists. We don’t see our work as merely
sorts of history, it has a rightful place myself cannot match the professional less information. an expression of the culture of our time
in the history of science. It is clearly not historian’s mastery of source material. and place, like parliamentary democ-
possible to speak of right and wrong in So who should write the history of sci- racy or Morris dancing. We see it as the
the history of art or fashion, nor I think ence: historians or scientists? The an- It is Butterfield’s injunction against latest stage in a process, extending back
is it possible in the history of religion, swer seems to me obvious: both. presentism, “the study of the past with over millennia, of explaining the world.
and one can argue about whether it is I should disclose that I have a dog, one eye, so to speak, upon the present,” We derive perspective and motivation
possible in political history, but in sci- or at least a book, in this fight. In To that still represents a serious challenge from the story of how we reached our
entific history we really can say who Explain the World: The Discovery of to whiggish historians of science. In present understanding, imperfect as
was right. According to Butterfield, Modern Science, based on my lectures laying out maxims for a history of sci- that understanding remains.
at the University of Texas at Austin, I ence that emphasizes its internal devel- Certainly history should not ig-
we can never say that the ulti- acknowledged that “I will be coming opment, Thomas Kuhn in 1968 argued nore those influential past figures who
mate issue, the succeeding course close to the dangerous ground that is that “insofar as possible (it is never en- turned out to be wrong. Otherwise we
of events, or the lapse of time most carefully avoided by contempo- tirely so, nor could history be written if would never be able to understand
have proved that Luther was right rary historians, of judging the past by it were), the historian should set aside what it took to get things right. But
against the Pope or that Pitt was the standards of the present.” Reviews the science that he knows.”2 A more the story makes no sense unless we
wrong against Charles James Fox. were generally favorable, but one in uncompromising stand against using recognize that some were wrong and
The Wall Street Journal (by a profes- present knowledge was taken by sev- some right, and this can be done only
But we can say with complete confi- sional historian) took me to task for eral sociologists who study science as a from the perspective of our present
dence that the lapse of time has shown my attention to the present. The review social phenomenon, including the well- knowledge.
that, about the solar system, Coperni- was headed “The Whig Interpretation known Sociology of Scientific Knowl- Right and wrong about what? A
cus was right against the adherents of of Science.” edge group at the University of Bath. whig history of science that amounts
Ptolemy, and Newton was right against Now, some criticisms of whiggery, Meanwhile, whiggery in the his- just to a totting up of plus and minus
the followers of Descartes. by Butterfield and others, are either ir- tory of science has not lacked defend- scores for whatever facts a past scien-
Though the history of science thus relevant to the history of science or not ers. They are found especially among tist has gotten right or wrong would
has special features that make a whig controversial. Certainly we should not those, like Edward Harrison, Nicho- not be very interesting. Much more im-
interpretation useful, it has another as- oversimplify or pass moral judgments, las Jardine, and Ernst Mayr, who have portant, it seems to me, is to trace out
pect that makes the idea of keeping an designating some past scientists as worked as scientists. 3 I think that this is the slow and difficult progress that has
eye on the present troublesome to some spotless heroes or infallible geniuses, been made over the centuries in learn-
professional historians. Historians who and others as villains or fools. For in- 2
Thomas S. Kuhn, “The History of Sci- ing how to learn about the world: What
have not themselves worked as scien- stance, we must not gloss over Galileo’s ence,” in International Encyclopedia of sort of questions can we hope to an-
tists may feel that they cannot match getting it all wrong in a debate over the Social Sciences (Macmillan, 1968), swer? What sort of notions help us to
comets with the Jesuit Orazio Grassi, Vol. 14, p. 76. these answers? How can we tell when
1
In this essay, I will follow Butterfield or Newton’s fudging his calculations to 3
Edward Harrison, “Whigs, Prigs and
in capitalizing “Whig” when it refers to achieve agreement with observations Historians of Science,” Nature, Vol. 329 of Science, Vol. 41, No. 2 (June 2003);
a political party, and leaving the w in of the precession of the earth’s axis. (September 1987); Nick Jardine, “Whigs Ernst Mayr, “When Is Historiography
lower case when referring to an intel- In any case, it is ideas and practices and Stories: Herbert Butterfield and Whiggish?,” Journal of the History of
lectual tendency. that we should hold up to present stan- the Historiography of Science,” History Ideas, Vol. 51, No. 2 (April/June 1990).

82 The New York Review


an answer is correct? We can identify and adherents of Aristotle, often called T o me this is nonsense. The point of also runs in the opposite direction. The
which historical practices set future sci- physicists. Ptolemy was wrong about science is not to answer the questions sociologist Robert Merton argued that
entists on the right path, and which old actual motions in the solar system, but that happen to be popular in one’s Protestantism had a major part in fos-
questions and methodologies had to be right about the need for quantitative time, but to understand the world. Not tering the great scientific advances of
unlearned. This can’t be done without agreement with observation. that we know in advance what kinds of seventeenth-century England. I don’t
taking account of our present under- It was one of the great achievements understanding are possible and satisfy- know if that is true, but it’s certainly
standings, so painfully acquired. of the scientific revolution of the six- ing. Learning this is part of the work worthy of interest.
For an example of a whiggish judg- teenth and seventeenth centuries to of science. Some questions like “What But there is an element of whiggery
ment of the past, take the ancient fun- work out the modern relation of math- is the world made of?” are good ques- even here. Why should a historian of
damental question: Of what substance ematics and science. Mathematics had tions, but are asked prematurely. No science focus on the intellectual en-
is the world made? Much credit is often been important to the Pythagoreans one could make progress in answering vironment of, say, Hellenistic Greece
given to Democritus of Abdera, who as a form of number mysticism, and to this question until the advent of accu- or seventeenth-century England, if it
around 400 BC proposed that mat- Plato as a model for a purely deduc- rate measurements of chemical weights were not that something was happen-
ter consists of atoms moving in the tive science that experience has shown at the end of the eighteenth century. In ing then that advanced science toward
void. One of the leading universities in could never work. The modern rela- the same way, the effort at the start of the present? The history of science is
Greece today is named after Democri- tion between mathematics and natural the twentieth century of Hendrik Lo- not merely a tale of intellectual fash-
tus. Yet from a modern perspective, science was spelled out by Christiaan rentz and other theoretical physicists ions, succeeding one another with-
the good guess of Democritus about Huygens, in the 1690 pref- out direction, but a history
atoms represented no progress in the ace to his Treatise on Light: Albert Einstein of progress toward truth.
methods of science. None of the many Though this progress was
surviving fragments of Democritus’s There will be seen in [this denied by Thomas Kuhn, it
writings describe any observation that book] demonstrations of is felt strongly by working
could suggest the existence of atoms, those kinds which do not scientists. Thus whig history
and there was nothing that he or any- produce as great a certi- is not just one of several in-
one else in the ancient world could do tude as those of Geometry, teresting kinds of scientific
with this idea that would confirm that and which even differ much history. The evolution over
matter really does consist of atoms. therefrom, since whereas many centuries of modern
Though right about matter, Democri- the Geometers prove their science is a great story, as
tus was wrong about how to learn about Propositions by fixed and important and interesting as
the world. In this he was not alone; no incontestable Principles, anything else in the history
one before Aristotle seems to have here the Principles are of human civilization.
understood that speculative theories verified by the conclusions Butterfield himself seems
about matter need to be confirmed by to be drawn from them; to have had a sense of the
observation. the nature of these things legitimacy of whiggery in
One’s judgment of Aristotle provides not allowing of this being the history of science. In his
a good test for one’s attitude toward done otherwise. 1948 lectures at Cambridge
the history of science, for Aristotle on the history of science,
was in a limited sense the first scientist, The remarkable thing is not he attributed a historical
and much of the subsequent history of that Huygens understood importance to the scientific
science consisted of responses to his this, but that, well into the revolution that he would
teaching. Aristotle argued that the seventeenth century, it still never grant to England’s
earth is a sphere, not only on the theo- needed to be said. Glorious Revolution, so be-
retical grounds that this shape allows Aristotle saw no need for loved of the Whigs. 5 I found
the greatest amount of the element experiment in the sense of his account of the scientific
earth to get closest to the center of the the artificial arrangement of revolution thoroughly whig-
cosmos, but also on the basis of obser- circumstances that are more gish, and that impression
vations: the shadow of the earth on the revealing than what we was shared by others, in-
moon during a lunar eclipse is curved, encounter naturally. This cluding A. Rupert Hall, a
and the starry night sky changes its ap- presumably was because student of Butterfield’s.6
pearance as one travels north or south. he thought there was a pro- Much earlier, in The Whig
However, Aristotle’s work shows no found difference between Interpretation of History,
understanding that mathematics should the natural and the artifi- Butterfield had already
be an important part of the study of na- cial, with only the natural world worth to understand the structure of the re- shown himself potentially receptive to
ture. For instance, he made no attempt study. Like Plato, he thought that it cently discovered electron was prema- a whig interpretation of history under
to use observations of the night sky at is only possible to understand things ture: no one could make progress on the some conditions. He acknowledged
different latitudes to estimate the cir- when one knows their purpose. These electron’s structure until the advent of that if morality were “an absolute sys-
cumference of the earth. His theory that ideas stood in the way of learning how quantum mechanics in the 1920s. Other tem, equally binding on all places and
the planets ride on spheres pivoted on to learn about the world. questions like “What is the natural times,” then the historian would “be
other spheres, all with the earth at their Such judgments on Aristotle and on place of fire?” or “What is the purpose driven now to watch the story of men’s
center, agreed only qualitatively with his followers are just the sort of thing of the moon?” are bad in themselves, growing consciousness of the moral
their observed apparent motions; but that is still often condemned by some leading away from real understanding. order, or their gradual discovery of
the failure to get quantitative agree- historians—keeping one eye on the Much of the history of science has been it.” Though a devout Methodist, But-
ment with observation did not bother present in studying the past. For in- a matter of learning what sort of ques- terfield did not believe that there is an
him or many of his followers. stance, a distinguished historian of tions should and should not be asked. absolute moral order that is revealed
science, the late David Lindberg, com- I am not arguing that whig history to us by history or religion or anything
mented that is the only interesting sort of history else.7 But he did not doubt that there
Mathematics began to be used con- of science. Even a whig historian may are laws of nature, equally binding on
structively in scientific theories in the it would be unfair and pointless to be interested in exploring the impact all places and times. It is precisely the
Hellenistic Age and then in the Greek judge Aristotle’s success by the de- of general culture on developments in story of the growing consciousness of
part of the Roman Empire. Around gree to which he anticipated mod- science, or vice versa, without need- the laws of nature that the whig his-
150 AD Claudius Ptolemy put the final ern science (as though his goal was ing to worry about the role that these torian of physics hopes to tell, but the
touches on a mathematical theory of to answer our questions, rather developments played in progress to- story cannot be told without keeping
the solar system that agreed pretty well than his own).4 ward modern science. For instance, the an eye on our present knowledge of the
with observation. (In the simplest ver- atomic theory of Democritus offered natural world.
sion of Ptolemy’s theory, planets travel And in a second edition of the same an illustration of how the world might
along circles called epicycles, whose work: “The proper measure of a philo- work without the intervention of the
centers travel around larger circles that sophical system or a scientific theory is gods, and thereby had a great influence
5
have the earth at their center.) With not the degree to which it anticipated a century later on the Hellenistic phi- Herbert Butterfield, The Origins of
the benefit of present knowledge this modern thought, but its degree of suc- losopher Epicurus and later still on the Modern Science (1950; revised edition,
agreement is not surprising, because cess in treating the philosophical and Roman poet Lucretius, an influence Free Press, 1957).
in its simplest version Ptolemy’s theory scientific problems of its own day.” that did not depend on whether the 6
See the closing lines of A. Rupert
gives precisely the same predictions for theory was well grounded by modern Hall, “On Whiggism,” History of Sci-
the apparent motions of the sun, moon, 4 standards, which it wasn’t. Likewise, ence, Vol. 21, No. 45 (1983).
David C. Lindberg, The Beginnings
and planets as the simplest version of of Western Science: The European Sci- you can feel the impact of the scientific 7
For Butterfield’s religious views, see
the later theory of Copernicus. Yet for entific Tradition in Philosophical, Re- revolution on general culture in such Michael Bentley, The Life and Thought
a millenium and a half there continued ligious, and Institutional Context, 600 works as the poetry of Andrew Marvell of Herbert Butterfield: History, Science
a debate between followers of Ptolemy, BC to AD 1450 (University of Chicago (I think particularly of his poem “The and God (Cambridge University Press,
called astronomers or mathematicians, Press, 1992). Definition of Love”). The influence 2011).

84 The New York Review

You might also like