You are on page 1of 18

pdf version of the entry

Suhrawardi
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/suhrawardi/ Suhrawardi
from the Fall 2016 Edition of the First published Wed Dec 26, 2007; substantive revision Wed Apr 4, 2012

Stanford Encyclopedia Trained in Avicennan Peripateticism, Shihab al-Din al-Suhrawardi (1154–


1191) became the founder of an Illuminationist (ishraqi) philosophical
of Philosophy tradition in the Islamic East. Since none of his works were translated into
Latin, he remained unknown in the West; but from the 13th century
onwards, his works were studied in a number of philosophical circles in
the Islamic East. In the mid-20th century, Henry Corbin worked
relentlessly to edit and study his writings, which led to renewed interest in
Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen R. Lanier Anderson Suhrawardi's works and thought, especially in the later part of the 20th
Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor century.
Editorial Board
http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html Suhrawardi provided an original Platonic criticism of the dominant
Library of Congress Catalog Data
Avicennan Peripateticism of the time in the fields of logic, epistemology,
ISSN: 1095-5054 psychology, and metaphysics, while simultaneously elaborating his own
epistemological (logic and psychology) and metaphysical (ontology and
Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem-
cosmology) Illuminationist theories. His new epistemological perspective
bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP
content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized led him to critique the Avicennan Peripatetic theory of definition,
distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the introduce a theory of ‘presential’ knowledge, elaborate a complex
SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries, ontology of lights, and add a fourth ‘imaginal’ world.
please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ .
1. Life and Works
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1.1 Life
Copyright c 2016 by the publisher
1.2 Works
The Metaphysics Research Lab
Center for the Study of Language and Information 1.3 Influences on Suhrawardi
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 2. Logic
Suhrawardi 2.1 Role of Logic
c 2016 by the author
Copyright
Roxanne Marcotte 2.2 Definition
All rights reserved.
3. Physics
Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/ 3.1 Psychology

1
Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

3.2 Epistemology In 1183, Suhrawardi arrived in Aleppo, the year Saladin (d.1193)
4. Metaphysics conquered that city and handed it over to his son al-Zahir (d.1216).
4.1 Essence and Existence Suhrawardi, a Shafi‘i Sunni, made a name for himself among religious
4.2 Ontology of Lights scholars of the city, such as Iftikhar al-Din. He eventually managed to
4.3 Imaginal World secure an audience at the palace and to befriend al-Zahir. In 1186, he
5. Politics and Ethics completed his most important work, the Philosophy of Illumination
6. Legacy of the Illuminationist Tradition (hereafter, PI), at the age of thirty-three. Unfortunately, he also succeeded
6.1 Post-Suhrawadian Traditions in alienating the powerful religious elite of Aleppo on whom the Ayyubids
6.2 Historiography depended for the legitimacy of their rule over the city.
Bibliography
Primary Sources: Editions, Translations, Commentaries A combination of religious and political factors led to Suhrawardi's
Secondary Sources downfall. On the one hand, he was accused of holding heretical beliefs, a
Academic Tools vague charge easily sustained with pre-Islamic Persian names and symbols
Other Internet Resources that some of his works contain, his claim to divine-like inspiration, and his
Related Entries questioning, in light of God's omnipotence, the logical finality of
Prophethood. On the other hand, his earlier and close relationships with
the rulers of the recently conquered Artuqids of southwest Anatolia or
1. Life and Works with al-Zahir, the Ayyubid ruler, may have been interpreted as political
intrigue. In the end, Suhrawardi's fate was sealed with accusations of
1.1 Life heresy (rather than treason). Biographers and historians remain at odds
over the exact charges and course of events that led to his execution at the
Biographical data on the life of Shihab al-Din al-Suhrawardi, the ‘master
end of 1191 (or early1192) (Marcotte 2001a).
of illumination’ (shaykh al-ishraq), is scarce. Born in the northwestern
Iranian village of Suhraward in 1154, he pursued his education in nearby 1.2 Works
Maraghah with Majd al-Din al-Jili, one of the teachers of Fakhr al-Din al-
Razi (d.1209). He then traveled to Isfahan, where he studied with the Suhrawardi's works are traditionally divided into four categories: several
logician Zahir al-Farisi with whom he read a text on logic written by Ibn early works, a number of mystical or allegorical texts, many written in
Sahlan al-Sawi (d.ca.1170). Suhrawardi then embarked on a journey that Persian (Suhrawardi 1976; 1993c; 1999b), minor works which often
led him to Anatolia. Shams al-Din al-Shahrazuri (d.ca.1288) identifies this present Peripatetic ideas and methods, but which also contain distinctive
period as his quest for spiritual guidance, a period when he would have Illuminationist theses, e.g., his Temples of Light (Suhrawardi 1996), and,
met a number of Sufi masters, such as Fakhr al-Din al-Maridini (d.1198), finally, his four major Arabic works which Suhrawardi intended to be
and would have sought patrons among the local rulers of Anatolia. studied in the following order: the Intimations (Suhrawardi, 2009 [logic,

2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 3


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

physics, metaphysics]; cf. Ibn Kammuna 2003, 2009), the Oppositions (d.1978) noted that there may not have been a purely Peripatetic period,
(Suhrawardi 1993a), the Paths and Conversations (Suhrawardi 1993a), though Suhrawardi confessed he once defended the Peripatetic approach.
and the Philosophy of Illumination (Suhrawardi 1993b; 1999a; 1986). In Very few of his works can, in fact, be dated; whereas a number of his
the latter work, Suhrawardi developed his Illuminationist philosophy in works were written simultaneously.
detail, wherein the symbolism of Light becomes central in his
reconfigurations of cosmology and ontology. Suhrawardi's works circulated mainly within the traditional philosophical
circles of learning of the Islamic East until the end of the 19th and the
Needless to say, such a classification, as well as the theory of two distinct beginning of the 20th centuries when, in the wake of the works of Carra de
periods in Suhrawardi's life and works — Peripatetic, followed by Vaux, Max Horten (1912), Louis Massignon, Otto Spies and Khatak
Illuminationist — poses some difficulties. The classification may well be (1935), and Helmut Ritter, the French Iranologist Henry Corbin began to
merely heuristic, as it fails to account for a number of works that expound study and edit a great number of his works. A first volume, published in
Peripatetic principles and methods and yet include a number of Istanbul in 1945, contained the metaphysics of Suhrawardi's first three
Illuminationist principles, e.g., in his Tablets Dedicated to ‘Imad al-Din major Arabic works (Suhrawardi 1993a). In 1952, Corbin then edited
(Suhrawardi 1976: 99-116) and in his Temples of Light (Suhrawardi 1996; Suhrawardi's magnum opus, the Arabic Philosophy of Illumination
1976: 139–47). Although Suhrawardi mentions that he was “once zealous (Suhrawardi 1993b; 1999a; 1986), together with two minor works. Corbin
in defense of the Peripatetic path” (PI, 108.8–9), a period during which then went on to write his major study on Suhrawardi et les platoniciens de
time he may have written such works as the Flashes of Light (a précis of Perse (Corbin 1971; cf. Abu Rayyan 1969). In 1970, Seyyed Hossein Nasr
Avicennan Peripatetic theses) whose attribution to a specifically edited fourteen of Suhrawardi's Persian texts (two attributed to him), many
identifiable ‘pre-inspiration’ period remains problematic; The Flashes of of which are allegorical or mystical in nature (Suhrawardi 1993c).
Light, however, mentions both the Intimations and the Philosophy of
Illumination as completed works (Suhrawardi 1993a: 70.3–7). Although 1.3 Influences on Suhrawardi
Suhrawardi asserts that his Intimations was a work written according to
Mapping Suhrawardi's intellectual trajectory and identifying the sources
the Peripatetic tradition, the work contains some of his more distinctive
which he may have used has proven exceedingly difficult (Walbridge
Illuminationist positions (Suhrawardi 1993a: 70–7 and 105–21).
2000, 2001; cf. Gutas 2003). Suhrawardi was undoubtedly instructed in
Suhrawardi composed most of his treatises over a very short span of time, the Avicennan Peripatetic tradition (in Maragha and Isfahan), but this
most probably during the course of about ten years. The brevity of this would have also included the study of the ideas of Aristotle, Plato and,
period would not have left him much time to undergo a radical most importantly, of the Neoplatonists and earlier philosophers who wrote
transformation through two different and successive stages in which he in Arabic. Avicenna's (d.1037) works were undoubtedly central. Much
would have espoused two distinct styles and modes of thought. For work still needs to be done to assess the real significance of Avicenna's
Suhrawardi, a great number of valid Peripatetic principles remain Discussions (1992) and his Notes on Aristotle's De anima (1984) on
necessary for understanding his Illuminationist Philosophy. Henry Corbin Suhrawardi, as well as the nature of the influence exerted on him by post-

4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 5


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Avicennan philosophers, in particular, Abu al-Barakat al-Baghdadi Prayers (Suhrawardi, 1976; cf. with occult and devotional works
(d.ca.1150), the original, yet eclectic critic of Avicenna's logic, psychology unearthed by Walbridge, 2011). His appeal to angels as embodiments of
and metaphysics, and the logician Ibn Sahlan al-Sawi. the intellective principles, for example, shares much with ancient
Zoroastrian angelology (Corbin 1972: 111–3, 124–5), but also with the
The influence of both Plato and Aristotle remains readily identifiable in angelology found in Abu al-Barakat al-Baghdadi's Considerations (1939,
Suhrawardi's works. Attempts have been made to trace the Greek vol. 2: 157; cf. Pines 1979: 253–5), the latter, however, being devoid of
influences of such figures as Empedocles, Pythagoras, and the Stoics, an any ancient Persian symbolism. Without any clear historical filiations to
exercise which has led to Suhrawardi being labeled a ‘Pythagoreanizing particular textual traditions, one can only rely on Suhrawardi's own claims
Neoplatonist’ (Walbridge 2000; 2001), but with more or less success (see to having intended to provide a synthesis of these ancient Western and
Gutas 2003: 308). Notwithstanding Suhrawardi's frequent appeals to the Eastern intellectual traditions. Why Suhrawardi “presented himself as
authority of Plato, another, more fruitful area of research might rest with following these ancient philosophers, and especially Plato, rather than
such works as the Arabic Theology of Aristotle (a paraphrase of parts of Avicenna” has yet to be elucidated and adequately explained (Gutas 2003:
Books IV-VI of Plotinus’ Enneads), in particular, the passages it contains 309).
from Enneads IV, 8.1, where the names of many philosophers of the Greek
tradition important to Suhrawardi are mentioned. 2. Logic
Charting Suhrawardi's intellectual journey and encounters with mysticism,
2.1 Role of Logic
ancient Greek Gnosticism and Hermeticism, or ancient Persian
Zoroastrian traditions, to whose symbols he often appeals, remains Very little has been written about Suhrawardi's logical treatises or his logic
exceedingly difficult. In addition, no one has as yet fully explored the in general. Ziai (1990) provides perhaps the only general overview of
possible influences of Ismailism or Sufism on Suhrawardi; his Suhrawardi's logic, his criticism of Peripatetic (Aristotelian) essentialist
Illuminationist doctrine could have more affinity with Ismaili thought definitions and his own elaboration of an Illuminationist theory of
(such as the hierarchical notion of being in the works of 10th century Abu definition. While Suhrawardi includes logical discussions in his major
Ya‘qub al-Sijistani) than with the doctrines of classical Sufis whom he Arabic works, in his Philosophy of Illumination, he ventures a criticism
claims to be following (Landolt 1987), although similarities with certain and a restructuring of some elements of Avicennan Peripatetic logic.
Sufi theories have been noted (Landolt 2007). Medieval biographers, on
the other hand, readily reported Suhrawardi's mystical inclination, his The Philosophy of Illumination does not follow the customary Avicennan
association with mystics, his ascetic practices and (hagiographic) tripartite division into logic, physics, and metaphysics which was standard
wondrous deeds. Suhrawardi himself considered spiritual exercises a in Post-Avicennan Peripatetic works. Instead, Suhrawardi begins with a
necessary preparation for the advent of presential knowledge and vision of small number of useful ‘Rules of Thought’ (PI, 14–105) that cover not
the Lights. He often appealed to ancient Zoroastrian motifs, terminology only logic, but also elements of physics and metaphysics which, according
and mythical figures, even Mazdean theology, e.g., in his Invocations and to his 13th century commentator Shahrazuri, are rules derived from the

6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 7


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Avicennan Peripatetic corpus (Ziai 1990: 41–76). Suhrawardi first Suhrawardi criticizes the Peripatetic theory of definition and the inductive
introduces elements of semantics, where he discusses problems of approach it advocates as a foundation for scientific knowledge and
meaning, conception, assent and the nature, the definition and the demonstration. He uses logical and semantic arguments to question
description of ‘reality’ (haqiqa), the latter being equated by Qutb al-Din ‘essentialist’ types of definitions (Aristotelian) on which Avicenna's own
Shirazi (d.1311) with quiddity (mahiyya). Suhrawardi also discusses ‘complete (essentialist) definition’ depends. He rejects the claims that it is
accidents, universals (adopting a more or less nominalist position), innate possible to obtain a complete definition that could encompass all the
(fitriyya) and non innate human knowledge and the notion of definition essential constituents needed to lead to the knowledge of that which is
and its elements (PI, 8.20–11.9). He then proceeds with short discussions previously unknown and in need of a definition (Ziai 1990: 77–114).
on the conditions of proofs, on defining propositions, their classes and Suhrawardi writes that “it is clear that it is impossible for a human being
modalities, and includes a number of discussions on contradiction, to construct an essential definition in the way the Peripatetics require—a
conversion, and some syllogisms (reductio ad absurdum and difficulty which even their master [Aristotle] admits. Therefore, we have
demonstrative syllogisms). Suhrawardi identifies some errors of formal definition only by means of things that specify conjunction” (PI, 11.5–9).
and material logic with the logic of the Peripatetics (an epitome of the He insists that a definition should enumerate, in some kind of unitary
Sophistical Refutations). He even includes brief discussions on dialectics, formula, all the essential elements of the described object. He therefore
rhetoric, and poetics whose premises he considers non-scientific and thus includes elements of definition by extension (enumeration of members of a
part of non demonstrative syllogisms (Ziai 1990: 41–74). He criticizes the ‘class’) and of definition by intension (enumeration of defining property or
Peripatetics’ understanding of negation, as well as the second and third properties), for example, that “the essence of man, which is the truth
figures of the syllogism. He reduces all types of propositions to necessary underlying the symbol ‘man’, is recoverable only in the subject. The act of
affirmative propositions and discusses some of the differences between the ‘recovery’ is the translation of the symbol to its equivalent in the
Peripatetics and the Illuminationists regarding a number of sophisms. consciousness or the self of the subject” (Ziai 2003: 448–9). Suhrawardi
Suhrawardi even revisits the classical theory of the ten Categories which explains his ‘conceptualist’ notion of definition at greater length in his
(as with the Stoics) he lumps together and reduces to five: substance, Paths and Conversations (Ziai 1990: 110). His epistemological critique of
quality, quantity, relation, and motion, of which the latter four are the Peripatetic theory of definition is undoubtedly inspired by Abu al-
accidental categories. The Categories now become ‘degrees of intensity’ Barakat al-Baghdadi's own critical evaluation of the Isagoge which was
(or perfection) of light that entities possess and that they emit, rather than developed in his Considerations (1939: vol. 1, 55–7; cf. Ziai 1990: 183–
being merely distinct ‘ontic entities’ (Ziai 2003: 452). As such, the degree 4), but also by Suhrawardi's own understanding of the epistemic role of
of intensity (with its corollary ‘weakness’) of light becomes a property of self-knowledge.
substances as well as of accidents.
Suhrawardi proceeds by introducing his reformulation of an
2.2 Definition Illuminationist theory of definition that signals what some have identified
as a ‘Platonic’ or ‘Neoplatonic’ turn (Ziai 1990: 114–128). Now, only
direct experience guarantees acquisition of true knowledge, such that

8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 9


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

epistemological considerations are at the heart of his reconceptualization 3. Physics


of the definition. Suhrawardi's theory of definition thus builds on a
Platonic epistemology. Knowledge of the reality of things occurs through Suhrawardi's Intimations, Paths and Conversations, and Oppositions
the direct apprehension of the intrinsic light-nature (the thing as it is) of all contain substantial sections on physics, although all have remained
entities (see metaphysics below). Direct knowledge occurs through unstudied. At present, only the physics of the Intimations has been edited,
‘vision-illumination’, as a person realizes that what is to be defined together with a commentary by Ibn Kammuna (2003). In the Philosophy of
becomes available to one's self through self-consciousness. At such time, Illumination, Suhrawardi deals mainly with some general principles of
the soul becomes directly aware of the reality of that which is to be physics, but not with any kind of detail. With his philosophy of lights, he
defined. The soul is then able to grasp directly these essences whose manages, nonetheless, to reconfigure some elements of physics. He
elements can then be translated using proofs and demonstrations to criticizes, for example, the Peripatetic hylomorphic division of matter and
develop a discursive type of knowledge about that original apperception of form, since hylomorphism becomes incompatible with the ontic
reality. luminosity of reality. Immaterial entities and material bodies that are
composed of varying degrees of light remain ‘unitary concrete entities’.
Suhrawardi writes that, in and of itself, light is not in need of any The physical world is composed of dusky substances with dark accidents,
definition, because all that is required is for light to be experienced, as while self-subsistent magnitude appears to replace prime matter which,
there is nothing more evident than light. In his Paths and Conversations, like a number of traditional physical notions, becomes a mere mental
Suhrawardi writes that to define something is to actually ‘see’ the thing as concept that has no reality outside the mind. It is no longer the perception
it really is (Ziai 1990: 104–14). Suhrawardi begins the second part of his of the form of objects, but their constitutive lights that becomes the true
Philosophy of Illumination by stating that “anything in existence that object of knowledge (Walbridge 2000: 22–3).
requires no definition or explanation is evident. Since there is nothing
more evident than light, there is nothing less in need of definition” (PI, 3.1 Psychology
76), thereby establishing the centrality of the concept of light for his
Illuminationist ontology and epistemology. Suhrawardi argues that only Suhrawardi equally revisits Avicenna's psychology. The soul remains an
direct intuitive experience can lead to knowledge of the reality (haqiqa) of immaterial, self-subsisting, living, knowing substance, capable of ruling
things, which definitions can only attempt to describe and explain via a over the body, but now defined in terms of its luminosity. A relation of
posteriori rational investigations or demonstrations (Ziai 1990: 81). Qutb dominion and desire is established between the luminous substance of the
al-Din Shirazi noted that Illuminationist epistemology relied on this type soul and the tenebrous substance of the body. Between the two, the
of personal and intuitive knowledge, itself not in need of any definition psychic pneuma functions as an intermediary that is able to receive
(Ziai 1990: 133). images, forms or ‘icons’ of metaphysical realities that it then reflects and
manifests into the soul.

10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 11


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Vision remains the most important sense. It is integrated into Suhrawardi's The faculty of representation perceives particulars, while the ruling light,
Illuminationist theory of vision and incorporated into his theory of the Isfahbad-light principle guaranteeing the unity of the soul, perceives
knowledge by presence. Suhrawardi begins with a criticism and a rejection universals and immaterial entities. The new emphasis on the totality of the
of the prevalent ‘extramissive’ and ‘intromissive’ theories of vision on soul, as the main perceiving entity, and the reduction of the Avicennan
account of the materialist implications of the imprinting of forms in the faculties traditionally responsible for representation to a single faculty
material substratum of the eye. Although mediated by a physical organ, could find their origin in Abu al-Barakat al-Baghdadi's Considerations
vision remains primarily an activity of the human soul, whereby the soul (1939, vol. 2: 318-24; cf. Pines 1979: 227–31). As for recollection,
accesses directly the reality of the objects of vision. In the Philosophy of Suhrawardi defines it in a rather Platonic manner, whereby it becomes the
Illumination, the vision of physical objects requires, first, a ‘presential’ retrieval of images (or concepts) whose existence lies in the ‘world of
face-to-face encounter of that which perceives, both the physical organ memorial’, accessible only to the luminous part of the soul.
and the human soul, and the illuminated object; second, the absence of
obstacles between subject and object, often described in mystical terms as Illumination becomes a metaphor for the intellective process. Illuminative
the absence of veils, whereby the soul becomes illuminated by the relations are established between metaphysical active light principles and
(substantial or accidental) light of the object; and finally, the presence of the human soul. Whereas only the (rational) Isfahbad-light part of the soul
light, the necessary condition for the establishment of an Illuminationist is immortal, Suhrawardi, nevertheless, notes the possibility for the
relation. Vision thus unfolds simultaneously on two different planes, imaginative faculty of souls that have not yet achieved perfection to
physical visual perception being reduced to the soul's perception or perhaps survive, something that is required for the experiencing of divine
awareness of the intrinsic and essential light possessed by the object. True retribution and for the perfecting of souls in the afterlife. The spheres of
vision does not require the presence and transmission of forms, but occurs Ether and Zamharir, both situated below the Moon and associated with the
through the soul's ability to be aware of the essential light-reality of the world of elements, are identified as possible ‘pneumatic’ substrata for the
object. Physics and metaphysics thus merge, as objects have the ability to posthumous activities of the imaginative faculties of those souls
receive and emit light, though only in an accidental manner, light being (Suhrawardi 1993c: 245.5–7). Suhrawardi attempted, therefore, to
precisely what the light-soul, the Isfahbad-light, is able to perceive, postulate the existence of an independent eschatological realm with the
whether it be through the senses, the intellect, intuition, or dreams (PI, assistance of which sensitive perceptions could occur in the form of
240.4–241.4). imaginal representations (Marcotte, 2011). Finally, he does not appear to
completely reject the possibility of some kind of transmigration of souls,
Suhrawardi criticizes the localization of the internal faculties in different especially of miserable souls, in spite of the fact that he does not overtly
parts of the brain, as their localization in a material organ again naturalizes affirm it and that many other passages seem to deny it (Schmidtke 1999).
the process of representation. Internal faculties now become shadows (or
functions) of the soul, lumped together into a single faculty responsible for 3.2 Epistemology
representation. The Isfahbad-light principle accesses the supernal lights,
rules over the active imagination, and reflects onto it the lights it receives.

12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 13


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Suhrawardi's Illuminationist epistemology revolves around his theory of knowledge provides yet another illustration of the type of epistemic
‘presential’ (huduri) knowledge that one is able to achieve through process that Suhrawardi considers being at the heart of intuitive
intuitive apprehension or contemplative vision (mushahada). Qutb al-Din knowledge. The unmediated nature of this process characterizes both the
Shirazi noted the importance of continuous practice of spiritual exercises soul's self-knowledge and the soul's knowledge of supernal entities and the
for the occurrence of such intuitive and mystical aptitudes to access true glimpses of the Light of Lights it may obtain (Marcotte 2006; see the more
reality. The ‘Plotinian’ (cf. Enneads V 3.6) Aristotle figure of Suhrawardi's recent studies of Kaukua, 2011 and Eichner, 2011).
famous dream-vision found in his Intimations (cf. Walbridge 2000: 225–9)
provides us with an illustrious example of what constitutes, for In Suhrawardi's ‘science of lights’, the object of perception — light —
Suhrawardi, real knowledge based on immediate and intuitive knowledge. cannot be known discursively, but only through an immediate presence or
Whereas the Peripatetics had extolled intellection, Suhrawardi brings awareness of its luminosity. Mystical vision and contemplation operate
direct intuition or mystical contemplation (heightened by ascetic through this intuitive process of knowing metaphysical lights. Individuals
components) to the forefront, as an alternative — albeit more reliable — achieve such states through spiritual and ascetic practices that enable them
foundation of certainty. Intuitive knowledge provides access to a priori to detach themselves from the darknesses of the world in their quest for
truths of which discursive knowledge can only be subsequently validated the apperception of those lights. Intuitive knowledge thus constitutes a
through a posteriori demonstrations (Dinani 1985; Ha’iri Yazdi 1992; superior means of accessing the luminous reality and the divine realm of
Aminrazavi 1997; 2003). metaphysical truths.

Suhrawardi explores some of the issues raised by the hypothetical example Suhrawardi appears to spiritualize Avicenna's Peripatetic epistemology
of the ‘suspended’ person found in Avicenna's Discussions and his Notes with a greatly Platonic reading, now that the access to the ultimate reality
on Aristotle's De anima, and his treatments of the soul in the Cure and the is guaranteed through divine photic illumination. His classification of
Salvation. He analyzes the notions of apperception and self-awareness and learned men according to their respective merits in discursive (philosophy)
alludes to a pre-logical mode of perception that remains distinct from and intuitive (mystical) knowledge is revealing. Direct intuition or
intellection. He discusses the primary awareness of the soul's existence, its mystical contemplation plays a predominant role, even for prophets.
self-identity, the unmediated character of this particular type of knowledge Prophetic knowledge relies on the functions of the faculty of imagination,
and issues of individuation. He provides various arguments to demonstrate i.e., its mimetic function and its role in the particularization of universal
the existence of a type of knowledge that is self-evident, a priori and truths. Prophecy becomes the ‘direct’ experience of the world of lights.
unmediated through any type of abstraction and representation of forms, Suhrawardi also introduces an independent imaginal realm to account for
whether it be through an image, a form, a notion or an attribute of the self. the ability of prophets and other gifted individuals to access divine
The perception of pain becomes paradigmatic of self-knowledge as metaphysical realms where imaginal forms already exist. Such individuals
unmediated perception, i.e., a non discursive, non-conceptual and non- are either commissioned or uncommissioned to receive and transmit God's
propositional type of knowledge that, nonetheless, does constitute a mode message, the prophets being those who are among the privileged
of knowing distinct from discursive knowledge. Similar to pain, self- commissioned.

14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 15


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Direct intuition lies at the heart of Suhrawardi's prophetology, inasmuch as practical components, where the practical includes ethics, economics and
only the most perfect sage who witnesses those truths, whether he be a politics, while the theoretical is concerned with immaterial realities, the
prophet or not, deserves God's viceregency, by being either a living proof highest theoretical component being concerned with absolute being
or in occultation. Individuals who have access to those metaphysical lights (wujud).
can be invested with the viceregency of God, depending on the degree of
their receptivity and the purity of their hearts. On the whole, however, the 4.1 Essence and Existence
epistemic process by which mystics such as Abu Yazid al-Bistami (d.874),
The concept of light manages to ‘disrupt’ classical Peripatetic ontology by
Sahl al-Tustari (d.896) and Hallaj (d.912), sages such as Zarathustra and
somehow rendering irrelevant the Avicennan distinction between essence
Empedocles, philosophers such as Pythagoras and Plato, or Suhrawardi
and existence in contingent beings (Rizvi 2000). Perhaps following
himself have all had access to those metaphysical truths and divine realms
Aristotle, Avicenna favored the primacy of essence over existence, the
remains quite similar to the process by which prophets have accessed the
latter considered an abstract concept. Suhrawardi criticized and rejected
same divine and metaphysical truths. Liberated from the enslavement of
the Peripatetic logical distinction between the two concepts, insisting that
the material world, their Isfahbad-light souls become receptive to
the concept of existence is added to quiddity in re, such that the general
illumination and perceive truths similar to those perceived by prophets.
extension of the concept of existence remains a mental predicate, not a
Prophetic and mystical knowledge only occur once the human soul is able
real one. For Suhrawardi, concepts such as essence and existence
to conjoin with those metaphysical lights. The soul is able to acquire a
considered a priori and real were “merely mental considerations (i‘tibari)
luminous and theurgic power, mediated by the active imagination which
with no corresponding reality” (Rizvi 1999: 222).
existentiates images and forms that have been reflected, in a mirror-like
manner, onto it. It can imitate and reproduce forms that it has received The primacy of light signals a shift in the understanding of the very nature
from non-sensible realms, as it short-circuits all incoming external and of the ‘essence’ of things. The degree or intensity of light of essences
sensible data. The faculty of active imagination then projects those matters makes them distinct from one another, although they all share in the same
onto the ‘common sense’ which provides a sensible form to those divine light whose origins remain with the Light of Lights. Everything partakes
metaphysical realities that they did not originally possess. in and of light, in an almost infinite manner. The distinction between
essence and existence no longer becomes appropriate to assert
4. Metaphysics contingency and only remains notional, since the difference between
necessary and contingent beings now depends on whether a being
In his Philosophy of Illumination, Suhrawardi develops a complex
possesses light in itself or light for other than itself (Rizvi 1999: 223). In
metaphysic of ‘divine’ lights. Light, the lynchpin of his metaphysics,
his Philosophy of Illumination (83.24–7), Suhrawardi writes: “Light is
structures his ontology and cosmology at the heart of which lies a
divided into light of itself and in itself and light of itself but in another.
spectrum of light and darkness that shapes the whole of reality. In his
You know that accidental light is light in another. Thus, it is not a light in
Intimations (1993a: 2.11–3.16), philosophy is divided into theoretical and
itself although it is a light of itself”.

16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 17


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Rizvi showed how later philosophers ascribed the ontological primacy of being, blending Avicenna's ontology of contingency with Suhrawardi's
essence (or quiddity) thesis to Suhrawardi and noted that he “clearly states Illuminationist hierarchy of lights (Rizvi 1999: 225).
that quiddity/essence in itself is a conceptual and unreal a notion as
existence” (Rizvi 1999: 224), Suhrawardi noting that “the quiddity of 4.2 Ontology of Lights
luminosity [i.e., the same as light] is a mental universal” (PI, 92.4–5). But
In the Niche of Lights (1998), Muhammad al-Ghazali (d.1111) discussed
it is also true that Suhrawardi's “phenomenological epistemology of
mystical epistemology using Qur’anic light terminology, whereas
eidetic vision” could easily imply a primacy of essence (Rizvi 1999: 224).
Suhrawardi, in his Philosophy of Illumination, developed a truly original
Suhrawardi's position, therefore, is greatly nominalist, now that both
light ontology. While light always remains in itself identical, its proximity
existence and essence are considered mere mental concepts, reality having
or distance from the Light of Lights determines the ontic light reality of all
been redefined with the new primacy of light. Light and essence cannot,
beings. Light operates through the activities of dominion of the higher
however, be synonymous. Both light and darkness exist: “light is the being
‘triumphal’ or ‘victorial’ lights, as well as the desire of the lower lights for
of things as their instantiating principle in concreto and not their essences”
the higher ones, operating at all levels and hierarchies of reality (PI, 97.7–
(Rizvi 1999: 224). By the same token, light is not identical with substance,
98.11). Reality proceeds from the Light of Lights and unfolds via the First
since both dark substances and accidental lights exist (Walbridge 2000:
Light and all the subsequent lights whose exponential interactions bring
24). Rizvi (1999: 224) notes that entities grasped as essences through
about the existence of all entities. As each new light interacts with other
presential knowledge are “apparent aspects of what one might regard as
existing lights, more light and dark substances are generated. Light
‘light monads’”, an idea whose source appears to be greatly Platonic.
produces both immaterial and substantial lights, such as immaterial
For Suhrawardi, being is grasped through the (non-sensible) vision of intellects (angels), human and animal souls. Light produces dusky
lights that lie beyond the essences, as even the existence of bodies depends substances, such as bodies. Light can generate both luminous accidents,
upon incorporeal lights (PI, 78.10–79.18). In his Philosophy of such as those in immaterial lights, physical lights or rays, and dark
Illumination (79.19–22), Suhrawardi writes that “Nothing that has an accidents, whether it be in immaterial lights or in bodies (PI, 77.1–78.9).
essence [dhat] of which it is not unconscious is dusky, for its essence is
Suhrawardi's metaphysics of lights rests on at least two central principles
evident to it. It cannot be a dark state in something else, since even the
which account for all the basic classes of beings (light and darkness,
luminous state is not a self-subsistent light, let alone the dark state.
substance and state, independent and dependent beings). A first principle,
Therefore, it is nonspatial pure incorporeal light”. Access to this ultimate
Walbridge notes, “is a form of the principle of sufficient reason, ‘the
reality of beings is achieved through the direct experience of its ontic light
principle of the most noble contingency’ […] which asserts that nothing
reality, rendering intuitive and non-discursive knowledge (logically) prior
can exist without a cause of higher ontological level” (PI, 90.1–92.25). A
to any other type of knowledge. Later, Mulla Sadra (d.1640) noted
second principle is the Aristotelian “impossibility of an ordered, actual
Suhrawardi's confusion between the concept of existence and the reality of
infinity” which, with the first principle, guarantees that “there cannot be an
existence and replaced Suhrawardi's notion of light with the notion of
infinite number of levels of being and that there must be one being whose

18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 19


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

existence is necessary in itself—Avicenna's ‘Necessary of Existence’ higher lights and the principle of domination that the higher lights have
(wajib al-wujud)”, the Light of Lights (Walbridge 2000: 24–5; PI, 87.1– over the lower ones (PI, 101.12–103.31). The two dimensional hierarchy
89.8). of lights introduces a new non linear notion of metaphysical causation.

With the notion of intensity of light, Suhrawardi then develops his two- The multiplication of metaphysical entities serves to increase the
fold process of light production. A vertical and a horizontal hierarchy of ontological distance that exists between the Light of Lights and the
pure immaterial lights structure his Illuminationist metaphysics. From the sublunar world, while simultaneously providing a greater holistic view of
Light of Lights proceeds a first vertical hierarchy of lights: from the Light reality, since light lies at its core. Notions of intensity and gradation of
of Lights proceeds a First Light (following the classical principle that from light, together with notions of presence and self-manifestation, are thus
the one only the one proceeds) from which proceeds a Second Light and central to Suhrawardi's metaphysics. The intensity of light corresponds to
the all-encompassing barzakh (i.e., a ethereal body), from the second a the degree of their self-awareness, such that the self-awareness of the
Third Light and the Second barzakh, or the Sphere of Fixed Stars, and so Light of Lights encompasses all of reality (in terms of intensity). Later,
forth. The first vertical hierarchy of lights mirrors the Avicennan Mulla Sadra (d.1640) takes up Suhrawardi's insight about the gradation
Peripatetic process of emanation of Intelligences. Suhrawardi, however, and intensity of light and develops an ontology based on the gradation of
increases the number of active principles, something that Averroes existence (rather than light) of all beings, somehow reversing Suhrawardi's
denounced in Avicenna's Neoplatonic ontology. Suhrawardi's ‘triumphal’ ontology with his primacy of existence and his understanding of essence
or ‘victorial’ lights are now as numerous as there are stars in the fixed as a mental concept.
heavens. While no longer limited to the ten Peripatetic Intelligences and
now indefinite in number, they are not infinite (PI, 99.20–100.19). 4.3 Imaginal World

The vertical hierarchy of lights interacts with a horizontal hierarchy of About half a century earlier than Ibn ‘Arabi (d.1240), Suhrawardi
lights. This second hierarchy of ‘ruling’ lights incorporates, amongst other introduced his own independent ‘imaginal world’, what Corbin has called
things, ancient angelologies (Semitic angelic hierarchies and Zoroastrian the mundus imaginalis, a fourth ‘imaginal’ world, alongside the
mythology) and some type of Platonic Forms. Each of these horizontal intelligible, the spiritual and the material. This imaginal world, a substance
lights becomes a ‘Lord of Species’, i.e., a luminous self-subsisting and made of shadows, operates like an ‘isthmus’ or an intermediary realm
fixed species, whose function is analogous to the Platonic Forms in so far between the world of pure light and the physical world of darkness, lying
as it ‘governs’ the species under it (rather than being a mere universal), somewhere between this physical world and the world of the species and
such as the species of bodies that move the celestial spheres and all of Platonic Forms (the horizontal lights), perhaps at the lower threshold of
matters sublunar, including human souls. Out of the interaction of the the world of souls.
vertical and the horizontal lights, the bodies of the lower world are
In the imaginal world, entities somehow possess an existence of their own
generated. These horizontal or vertical lights are all structurally
(some, prior to their coming into existence in this world). The imaginal
interrelated through the principle of love that the lower lights have for the

20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 21


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

world contains images that are not embedded in matter, a plane of “ghosts, passages relating to these Illuminationist political doctrines need further
of the forms in mirrors, dreams, and worlds of wonder beyond our own” examination.
which light can existentiate (Walbridge 2000: 26). The imaginal world
provides the material for the miraculous. It is where the ‘metahistorical’ The ethics underlying Suhrawardi's Illuminationist system has yet to be
(Corbin's term) visions of Imams occur, where eschatological forms and adequately investigated, but the political doctrines can provide indications
images will perhaps be existentiated for the souls of the deceased, so that of the conditions that would guarantee the reign of a just rule, thus
they may continue to perfect their souls (PI, 148.29–150.17), as well as providing some elements of an Illuminationist political ethic. Suhrawardi's
where elements not fitting conveniently into the Aristotelian scheme of particularly Platonic understanding of the mystic qua ruler and his
forms in matter are found. Suhrawardi did not, however, systematically political role, coupled with the role of intuitive or ‘mystical’ access to the
develop the concept. This was left to his followers. ‘divine’ lights by prophets, mystics and sages might, however, not leave
Suhrawardi immune to the same criticism Popper leveled against Plato.
5. Politics and Ethics One needs to turn to Suhrawardi's eschatology and his discussions on the
fate of the soul in the afterlife to obtain a glimpse of what might constitute
Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination carries a political dimension. Ziai
a ‘good’ and ethical life in this world. In line with Avicenna's classification
(1992) provides an overview of what he calls the ‘Illuminationist political
of souls in the hereafter according to their worldly acquisition of practical
doctrine’ which establishes a connection between political authority, just
and theoretical knowledge, the moral qualities developed in this life
rule, and the ruler's access to divine light. This is particularly manifest in
determine the fate of souls in the afterlife (PI, 148.27–150.17). In search
the Tablets Dedicated to ‘Imad al-Din (Suhrawardi 1993c: 184.12–188.4)
of felicity, souls must attempt to detach themselves from their tenebrous
and the Book of Radiance (Suhrawardi 1998: 84–5), where Suhrawardi
bodies and all that is worldly and material and to access the world of
appeals to ancient Persian notions of royal glory (kharrah) and of
immaterial lights. Souls engrossed in matter in this life partially determine
luminous divine light (farrah), two signs of the divine authority of ancient
their fate in the afterlife and Suhrawardi, in this respect, does not depart
kings of Iranian mythology, the divine lights that instructed Kay Khusraw
greatly from Peripatetic eschatology.
and Zarathustra (PI, 156.3–157.3).
Prophets, saints and exceptionally gifted mystics are able to achieve
Suhrawardi may, in fact, appeal to a somewhat ‘mythological’ genealogy
conjunction with the world of pure lights. Ascetic practices in this life
of the transmission of ancient Illuminationist philosophies from the
become a means to attain self-consciousness of the ontic luminosity of the
Greek/West and the Iranian/East which he claims to revive. Ziai speculates
soul. Some of Suhrawardi's allegorical and mystical treatises, such as The
that Suhrawardi tried to put into practice the political dimension of his
Treatise of the Bird, A Tale of Occidental Exile or A Day with a Group of
Illuminationist philosophy (Ziai 1992: 337; cf. Walbridge 2000: 201–10),
Sufis (Suhrawardi 1982; cf. Landolt 1987), provide examples of the
based mainly on passages from Suhrawardi's works and the possible
pedagogical role and instruction of the guide figure, of the Lord of the
circumstances of his demise and execution. Historical data supporting the
human species, or of spiritual entities to the novice in his or her quest for
thesis, Suhrawardi's relationship with his many patrons and the purpose of

22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 23


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

the immaterial world of lights in which salvation lies. The posthumous life Din Shirazi wrote his own commentary on the Philosophy of Illumination
of individual souls and their ability to perceive the promised other-worldly (Shirazi 2001; Suhrawardi 1986), based on Shahrazuri's work (Walbridge
rewards and punishments become conditions for divine retribution. 1992).

6. Legacy of the Illuminationist Tradition Authors that incorporated Illuminationist ideas include Muhammad Ibn
Rizi (fl.ca.1280), in his Life of Souls (Marcotte 2004); Athir al-Din al-
6.1 Post-Suhrawadian Traditions Abhari (d.1242) in his Uncovering of the Realities; Ibn Abi Jumhur Ahsa’i
(d.1501) (Schmidtke 2000); the two theologians Jalal al-Din Dawwani
The tragic end of Suhrawardi marked the birth of the Illuminationist (d.1501) and Ghiyath al-Din Dashtaki (d.1541) who both wrote
tradition. By the end of the 13th century, at least two of Suhrawardi's commentaries on Suhrawardi's Temples of light (Dawwani 1953; Dashtaki
works were readily available and studied in the major centers of learning 2003; Suhrawardi 1996); and Mir Damad (d.1631), especially in his
of Syria (Damascus and Aleppo), Iraq (Baghdad) and Iran (Maraghah), Spiritual Attractions (2001) and his Embers (1977). Mulla Sadra (Sadr al-
some of which circulated most probably even before his death. Ziai (2003: Din al-Shirazi) (d.1640) was most interested in Suhrawardi's critique of
473–87) identifies at least two trends within the Illuminationist tradition of Avicennan Peripateticism (existence as a being of reason, the Platonic
the 13th century that were to shape later developments: Ibn Kammuna Forms, and knowledge by presence) and wrote marginal glosses on Qutb
(d.1284), on the one hand, emphasized the purely discursive and the more al-Din al-Shirazi's commentary on the Philosophy of Illumination (Mulla
systematically philosophical aspects of Suhrawardi's Illuminationist Sadra, 2010; cf. with Suhrawardi 1986). Mulla Sadra positioned himself in
philosophy, while Shahrazuri, on the other hand, focused and expanded on opposition to what he understood to be Suhrawardi's view that quiddity
the symbolic and the allegorical aspects of the tradition. Ibn Kammuna, a was primary, a view shared by Mir Damad (d.1631), and instead held,
Jewish philosopher greatly influenced by both Avicenna and Suhrawardi is such as Hadi Sabzawari (d.1873) after him, that existence was primary.
the first commentator (Langermann 2005: 297–301; Pourjavady and
Schmidtke 2006: 23–32). While in Baghdad, Ibn Kammuna (2003) wrote During the same period, Suhrawardi's works entered the Turkish Ottoman
his commentary on the physics and the psychology of Suhrawardi's and Persian Indian philosophical traditions. In the Ottoman world, Isma‘il
Intimations (in 1268). Having resided in Aleppo, Ibn Kammuna could well Ankaravi (d.1631), a member of the Mevlevi Sufi order, translated and
be, with such works as his al-Kashif (al-Jadid fi al-Hikma) completed in commented Suhrawardi Temples of Light (Kuspinar 1996). In the 17th
1278, the link between Suhrawardi and Shahrazuri (d.ca.1288) who wrote century, the enigmatic Ahmad Ibn al-Harawi (probably from Herat) living
the earliest commentary on the Philosophy of Illumination (Shahrazuri in the Indian subcontinent, translated into Persian the Philosophy of
1993; cf. Marcotte 2002) and whose encyclopedic The Divine Tree Illumination on which he wrote a commentary (Harawi 1979). Azar
(Shahrazuri, 2004 and 2005 [a better edition]; Marcotte 2001b) and his Kayvan (d.ca.1615), a Zoroastrian high priest from Fars who emigrated to
Book of Symbols (Privot 2004) can readily be labeled Illuminationist Gujurat in Mughal India during the reign of Emperor Akbar (ruled 1556–
works, although much work is needed to determine the extent of 1605), started a Zoroastrian Illuminationist school (Walbridge 2001: 91–
Shahrazuri's contribution to the Illuminationist tradition. In 1295, Qutb al- 3). Even thinkers of the twentieth century, such as Muhammad Kazim

24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 25


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

‘Assar, have been influenced by the Illuminationist tradition (Ziai 2003: Some, such as Fakhry (1982), have gone so far as to question the
472). Cataloguing and making accessible hundreds of philosophical works originality of Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination, deeming it a mere
in Arabic and Persian from the 12th-19th century, such as the recent transposition of Avicennan philosophy into a light terminology. Izutsu
publication of the Persian work of Shihab al-Din Kumijani (d.1895), the (1971) was one of the first to explore the analytical aspect of Suhrawardi's
Nur al-Fu'ad, or the Inner Light, are bound to shed new light on the legacy work, followed especially by Ziai (1990), but also by Walbridge (2000,
of Suhrawardi's works. On the whole, however, almost nothing has been 2001) who have focused on some of the analytical and philosophical
written on the history of the philosophical legacy of Suhrawardi's elements of Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination. While some, such as
Philosophy of Illumination. Henry Corbin and Mohammad Mo’in, have viewed Suhrawardi as the
reviver of some ancient form of Persian philosophy, others, such as Ziai
6.2 Historiography (2003: 443), are more skeptical and note the absence of textual evidence
for such an independent Persian philosophical tradition. Similarly, Gutas
Historiography of the Illuminationist tradition has been dominated by two
(2003) notes the absence of textual evidence to support the claim that
main schools of thought. The first, older and more prevalent school, views
Suhrawardi attempted to revive ancient Western Greek, Gnostic and
Suhrawardi as the founder of a mystical, esoteric and ‘theosophical’
Hermetic traditions. Research should perhaps focus on the reasons why
tradition. Its roots are found in Corbin's mystical or ‘theosophical’
Suhrawardi appealed to the authority of the ‘Ancients’, East and West,
paradigm (Gutas 2002: 16–9). The adoption of an ‘esoteric’ wisdom or
rather than on trying to find ‘real’ historical filiations to sources to which
‘theosophy’ (Corbin), or even a philosophia perennis approach (Nasr), to
Suhrawardi might have had access.
Suhrawardi's work often overemphasizes the mystical at the expense of
the philosophical and somehow blurs the distinction between philosophy, More studies are needed on the works of authors who belonged to, or who
theology and mysticism. Proponents of this approach highlight were influenced by the Illuminationist tradition (see e.g., Schmidtke 2000;
Suhrawardi's aim to expound on Avicenna's incomplete project to develop Pourjavadi & Schmidtke 2006). This will provide the much needed
an ‘Eastern’ (not ‘illuminative’) philosophy of Khurasan (mashriqiyya), in accounts of the complex historical and philosophical developments of the
spite of the fact that Avicenna's ‘Eastern’ philosophy was not a mystical Illuminationist tradition. Although recent scholarship highlights
enterprise, but merely a philosophical tradition distinct from the one of the Suhrawardi's critique of Avicennan Peripatetic logic, epistemology and
school of Baghdad (Gutas 2000). More generally, the proponents of the metaphysics (Ziai 1990) and even psychology, more studies are needed
mystical approach interpret Illuminationist philosophy as a break or a that explore specific logical, epistemological, physical, and metaphysical
departure from Avicennan Peripateticism (Mehdi H. Yazdi, Hossein Nasr, issues found in Suhrawardi's four major Arabic texts and that compare
Ashtiyani), rather than seeing it as its extension and critique. Scholars systematically Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination with Avicenna's
have often overlooked the fact that Suhrawardi's major works are largely major works, such as the Cure. This will undoubtedly provide new insight
devoted to technical philosophical questions, of which his allegorical or into Suhrawardi's greatly Platonic reworking of Avicennan Peripateticism,
minor works are not devoid. what Gutas (2002) has identified as Suhrawardi's Illuminationist
Avicennism.

26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 27


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Bibliography Century Persian Text in Illuminationist Philosophy, ed., intro. and


notes H. Siai and M.K. Zanjani Asl, Costa Mesa(CA): Mazda.
Primary Sources: Editions, Translations, Commentaries Kuspinar, B. (1996). Isma‘il Ankaravi on the Illuminative Philosophy,
Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC [Ottoman text of Ankaravi with English
Al-Baghdadi, Abu al-Barakat (1939). Al-Mu‘tabar fi al-Hikmah, 3 vols, translation of Suhrawardi's Temples of Light].
ed. S. Yaltkaya, Haydarabad: Jam‘iyyat Da’irat al-Ma‘arif Mir Damad (1977). Al-Qabasat, ed. M. Mohaghegh, T. Izutsu et al.,
al-‘Uthmaniyya. Tehran: University of Tehran/McGill University, Institute of Islamic
Avicenna (Ibn Sina) (1992). Al-Mubahathat, ed. and commentary M. Studies, Tehran Branch.
Bidar, Qum: Bidar. ––– (2001). Jadhawat wa Mawaqit, ed. A. Nuri and A. Awjabi, Tehran:
––– (1984). Al-Ta‘liqat, ed. and commentary A. Badawi, Qum: Maktab al- Mirath-i Maktub.
I‘lam al-Islami [reprint of the Cairo ed.]. Mulla Sadra (Sadr al-Din al-Shirazi) (2010), Addenda on the commentary
Dawwani, M. (1953). Shawakil al-Hur fi Sharh Hayakil al-Nur, ed. T. on the Philosophy of illumination: Part One on the Rules of Thought
Chandrasekharan, critical ed. M. Abdul Haq and M. Y. Kokan, (al-Taʻliqat ʻala Sharh Hikmat al-Ishraq), critical ed., into. Hossein
Madras: Government Oriental Manuscripts Library. Ziai, Costa Mesa, CA: Mazda.
Dashtaki, G. D. (2003). Ishraq Hayakil al-Nur li-Kashf Zulumat Shawakil Shirazi, Qutb al-Din (2001). Sharh-i Hikmat al-Ishraq, ed. A. Nourani and
al-Gharur, ed. A. Awjabi, Tehran: Mirath-i Maktub. M. Mohaghegh, Tehran: University of Tehran/McGill University,
Al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid Muhammad (1998). The Niche of Lights [Mishkat Institute of Islamic Studies, Tehran Branch [commentary on
al-Anwar], A Parallel English-Arabic Text, trans., intro., and notes D. Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination].
Buchman, Provo (UT): Brigham Young University Press. Shahrazuri, Shams al-Din (2005), Rasa'il al-Shajara al-Ilahiyya fi ‘ulum
Harawi, M. (1979). Anwariyya: Tarjuma va Sharh-i Hikmat al-Ishraq-i al-Haqa'il al-Rabbaniyya, 3vols, ed., intro and notes Najafquli
Suhrawardi, ed. H. Ziai, Tehran: Amir Kabir [Persian translation and Habibi, Tehran: Iranian Institute of Philosophy.
commentary of Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination]. ––– (2004), , Rasa'il al-Shajara al-Ilahiyya fi ‘ulum al-Haqa'il al-
Ibn Kammuna (2009), Sharh al- al-Tawihat al-Lawhiyya wa al-‘Arshiyya, Rabbaniyya, 3 vols., ed., Necip Görgün, Istanbul: Elif Yayınları.
3 vols, ed. and into. Najaf Quli Habibi, Tehran: Mirath-I Maktub. ––– (1993). Sharh-i Hikmat al-Ishraq, critical ed., intro. and notes H. Ziai,
––– (2008), al-Kashif (al-Jadid fi al-Hikma), ed. and intro. Hamid Naji Tehran: Mu’assasah-yi Mutali‘at wa Tahqiqat-i Farhangi
Isfahani, Tehran: Institute of Islamic Studies, Free University of [commentary on Suhrawardi's Philosophy of Illumination].
Berlin / Mu'assasa Pazuhishi Hikmat va Falsafa-yi Iran. Spies, O. and S. K. Khatak (1935). Three Treatises on Mysticism by
––– (2003). Al-Tanqihat fi Sharh al-Talwihat (Refinement and Shihabuddin Suhrawerdi Maqul; with an account of his Life and
Commentary on Suhrawardi's Intimations. A Thirteenth Century Text Poetry, ed. and trans. O. Spies and S. K. Khatak, Stuttgart:
on Natural Philosophy and Psychology), critical ed., intro. and Kohlhammer.
analysis H. Ziai and A. Alwishah, Costa Mesa (CA): Mazda. Suhrawardi, Shihab al-Din (2009), al-Tawihat al-Lawhiyya wa
Kumijani, Shihab al-Din (2012). Inner Light [Nur al-Fu'ad]: A 19th

28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 29


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

al-‘Arshiyya , ed. and intro. Najaf Quli Habibi, Tehran: Mu'assasa-yi Abu Rayyan, M. (1969). Usul al-Falsafa al-Ishraqiyya, Beirut: Dar al-
Pazhuhishi Hikmat va Falsafa-yi Iran. Talaba al-‘Arab.
–––(1999a). The Philosophy of Illumination. A New Critical Edition of the Aminrazavi, M. (2003), “How Ibn Sinian is Suhrawardi's Theory of
Text of Hikmat al-Ishraq, with English trans., notes, commentary and Knowledge?” Philosophy East and West, 53(2): 203–14.
intro. J. Walbridge and H. Ziai, Provo (UT): Brigham Young ––– (1997). Suhrawardi and the School of Illumination, London: Curzon.
University Press. Corbin, H. (1971). Sohravardi et les platoniciens de Perse, Paris:
––– (1999b). The Philosophical Allegories and Mystical Treatises. A Gallimard [vol. 2 of H. Corbin (1971–2). En Islam iranien, 4 vols,
Parallel Persian-English Text, ed., trans. and intro. W. M. Thackston, Paris: Gallimard]
Costa Mesa (CA): Mazda. Dinani, I. (1985). Shu‘a‘-i Andisha va Shuhud dar Falsafah-yi
––– (1998). The Book of Radiance (Partu-Nama). A Parallel English- Suhrawardi, Tehran: Hikmat.
Persian Text, ed., trans. and intro. H. Ziai, Costa Mesa (CA): Mazda. Eichner, H. (2011), “‘Knowledge by Presence’, Apperception in the Mind-
––– (1996). Temples of Lights, trans. Bilal Kuspinar, Kuala Lumpur: Body Relationship: Fakhr al-Dīn al-Razi and al-Suhrawardi as
ISTAC. Representatives and Precursors of a Thirteenth-Century Discussion“,
––– (1993a). [1945] Opera metaphysica et mystica I, ed. and intro. H. in The Age of Averroes: Arabic Philosophy in the Sixth/Twelfth
Corbin, Tehran: Mu’assasah-yi Mutali‘at va Tahqiqat-i Farhangi Century , ed. P. Adamson, London: Warburg Institute / Turin: Nino
[reprint of the 1945 ed.]. Aragno Editore, 117–40.
––– (1993b). [1952] Opera Metaphysica et mystica II, ed. and intro. H. Fakhry, M. (1982). “Al-Suhrawardi's Critique of the Muslim Peripatetics
Corbin, Tehran: Mu’assasah-yi Mutali‘at va Tahqiqat-i Farhangi (al-Mashsha’un)”, in Philosophies of Existence, Ancient and Modern,
[reprint of the 1952 ed.]. ed. P. Morewedge, New York: Fordham University Press, 279–84.
––– (1993c). [1970] Opera Metaphysica et mystica III, ed. and English Gutas, D. (2003). “Essay-Review: Suhrawardi and Greek Philosophy”,
intro. S. H. Nasr, French intro. H. Corbin, Tehran: Mu’assasah-yi Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 13: 303–9.
Mutali‘at va Tahqiqat-i Farhangi [reprint of the 1970 ed]. ––– (2002). “The Study of Arabic Philosophy in the Twentieth Century.
––– (1986). Le livre de la Sagesse Orientale (Kitab hikmat al-ishraq) An Essay on the Historiography of Arabic philosophy”, British
commentaires de Qotboddin Shirazi et Molla Sadra Shirazi, trans. Journal of Middle Eastern Studies, 29(1): 5–29.
and notes H. Corbin, with intro. C. Jambet, Paris: Verdier. ––– (2000). “Avicenna's Eastern (“Oriental”) Philosophy. Nature,
––– (1982). The Mystical and Visionary Treatises of Shihabuddin Yahya Contents, Transmission”, Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 10: 159–
Suhrawardi, trans. W. M. Thackston, London: The Octagon Press. 180.
––– (1976). L'archange empourpré: quinze traités et récits mystiques, Ha’iri Yazdi, M. (1992). The Principles of Epistemology in Islamic
trans., intro. and notes H. Corbin, Paris: Fayard. Philosophy: Knowledge by Presence, Albany (NY): State University
of New York Press.
Secondary Sources Horten, M. (1912). Die Philosophie der Erleuchtung nach Suhrawardi

30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 31


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

(1191), Halle: Strauss and Cramer [reprint in Hildesheim: Georg ca. 1288) du Hikmat al-Ishrâq de Suhrawardî (m. 1191) – notes
Olms, 1981]. préliminaires”, in Iran. Questions et connaissances, 3 vols, ed. M.
Izutsu, T. (1971). The Concept and Reality of Existence, Tokyo: Keio Szuppe, Leuven: Peeters, vol. 2, 411–25.
Institute of Cultural and Linguistic Studies. ––– (2001a). “Suhrawardi al-Maqtul, The Martyr of Aleppo”, Al-Qantara,
Kaukua, J. (2011), “I in the Light of God: Selfhood and Self-Awareness in 22(2): 395-419.
Suhrawardi's Hikmat al-ishraq “, The Age of Averroes: Arabic ––– (2001b). “L'anthropologie philosophique de Shams al-Dîn Shahrazûrî
Philosophy in the Sixth/Twelfth Century , ed. by Peter Adamson, et ses racines suhrawardiennes — les facultés internes”, Quaderni di
London: Warburg Institute / Turin: Nino Aragno Editore), 141–157, Studi Arabi, 19: 135–46.
esp. 141 n.3. Pines, S. (1979) “La conception de la conscience de soi chez Abu ‘l-
Landolt, H. (2007). “Les idées platoniciennes et le monde de l'image dans Barakat al-Baghdadi,” in Studies in Abu’l-Barakat al-Baghdadi.
la pensée du Šaykh al-išrāq Yahyā al-Suhrawardi (ca.1155–1191)”, in Physics and Metaphysics, S. Pines (Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, the
Miroir et Savoir. La transmission d’un thème platonicien, des Hebrew University), 181–59/
Alexandrins à la philosophie arabo-musulmane , eds. D. De Smet Pourjavadi, R. and S. Schmidtke (2006), A Jewish Philosopher of
and M. Sebti, Leuven: Peeters. Baghdad; ‘Izz al-Dawla Ibn Kammuna (d. 683/1284), Leiden: Brill.
––– (1987). “Suhrawardi's Tales of Initiation’.” Journal of the American Privot, M. (2004). “Le moi d’Ibn Sina au Kitab al-rumuz d’al-Šahrazuri al-
Oriental Society, 107(3): 475–86 [review essay on Thackston's išraqi. Éléments de comparaison”, in Ultra Mare. Mélanges de
translation of Suhrawardi's (1982) Mystical and Visionary Treatises]. langue arabe et d’islamologie offerts à Aubert Martin, ed. F. Bauden,
Langermann, Y. T. (2005). “Ibn Kammuna and the “New Wisdom” of the Louvain: Peeters, 289–99.
Thirteenth Century”, Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 15: 277–327. Rizvi, S.H. (2000). “Roots of an Aporia in Later Islamic Philosophy: the
Marcotte, R.D. (2011), “ Suhrawardi's Realm of the Imaginal“, in Ishraq: Existence-Essence Distinction in the Philosophies of Avicenna and
Islamic Philosophy Yearbook (No. 2), ed. Y. Eshots, Moscow: Suhrawardi”, Studia Iranica, 29: 61–108.
Vostochnaya Literatura, 2011), 68–79. ––– (1999). “An Islamic Subversion of the Existence-Essence Distinction?
––– (2006). “L'aperception de soi chez Shihab al-Din al-Suhrawardi et Suhrawardi's Visionary Hierarchy of Lights”, Asian Philosophy, 9(3):
l'héritage avicennien”, Laval théologique et philosophique, 62(3): 219–27.
529–51. Schmidtke, S. (2000). Theologie, Philosophie und Mystik im
––– (2004). “Resurrection (ma‘ad) in the Persian Hayat al-Nufus of zwölferschiitischen Islam des 9./15. Jahrhunderts: die
Isma‘il Muhammad Ibn Rizi (fl. ca. 679 / 1280): The Avicennan Gedankenwelten des Ibn Abi Gumhur al-Ahsai (um 838/1434-35-
Background”, in Interpreting Avicenna: Science and Philosophy in nach 905/1501), Leiden: Brill.
Medieval Islam, ed. J. McGinnis, with D. Reisman, Leiden: Brill, ––– (1999). “The Doctrine of Transmigration of the Soul according to
213–35. Shihab al-Din al-Suhrawardi (killed 587/1191) and his Followers”,
––– (2002). “Les facultés internes selon le commentaire de Shahrazûrî (m. Studia Iranica, 28: 237–54.

32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 33


Suhrawardi Roxanne Marcotte

Walbridge, J. (2011). “ The Devotional and Occult Works of Suhrawardi Suhrawardi Bib, and Suhrawardi Bib-II Suhrawardi Bibliography
the Illuminationist “, in Ishraq: Islamic Philosophy Yearbook, No 2, (maintained by Stephen N. Lambden).
ed. Y. Eshots, Moscow: Vostochnaya Literatura, 2011), 80–97.
––– (2001) The Wisdom of the Mystic East: Suhrawardi and Platonic Related Entries
Orientalism, Albany (NY): State University of New York Press.
––– (2000). The Leaven of the Ancients: Suhrawardi and the Heritage of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy, special topics in: illuminationism | Ibn
the Greeks, Albany (NY): State University of New York Press. Kammuna | Ibn Sina [Avicenna] | Mulla Sadra
––– (1992). The Science of Mystic Lights: Qutb al-Din Shirazi and the
Copyright © 2016 by the author
Illuminationist Tradition in Islamic Philosophy, Cambridge: Harvard
Roxanne Marcotte
Center for Middle Eastern Studies.
Ziai, H. (2003). [1996]. “The Illuminationist Tradition”, in History of
Islamic Philosophy, eds. S. H. Nasr and O. Leaman, London:
Routledge, 465–96.
––– (1992). “The Source and Nature of Political Authority in Suhrawardi's
Philosophy of Illumination”, in Aspects of Islamic Philosophy, ed.
Charles Butterworth, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
––– (1990). Knowledge and Illumination: A Study of Suhrawardi's Hikmat
al-Ishraq, Atlanta: Scholars Press.

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP
Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links
to its database.

Other Internet Resources

34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 Edition 35

You might also like