You are on page 1of 228

Bernard Balzano

Theory of Science

Volume Three

Translated by Paul Rusnock and Rolf George


OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS Theory of Science: Overview of Contents
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 GDP,
United Kingdom
VOLUME ONE
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, INTRODUCTION
and educauon by_ pubIJShlllg worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford Urnvers1ty Press in the UK and in certain other countries BOOK ONE: THEORY OF FUNDAMENTALS
Paul Rusnock and Rolf George 2014 PART I: Of the Existence of Truths in Themselves
The moral rights of the authors have been asserted PART II: Of the Recognisability of Truth
First Edition published in 2014
BOOK TWO: THEORY OF ELEMENTS
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in Part I: Of Ideas in Themselves
a remeval system, or nansmittcd, in any form or by any means, without the
pnor perm1ss1on Ill wrnmg of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
Chapter 1: On the Concept of an Idea in Itself
. by law, by_ licence ~r under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics Chapter 2: Internal Attributes of Ideas in Themselves
nghts orgarnzat1on. Lngtunes concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
Chapter 3: Distinctions between Ideas that Stem from their Relation
address above to each other
You must not circulate this work in any other form Chapter 4: Distinctions among Ideas that Result from their Relation
and you must impose this same condition on any acguirer
to other Objects
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
I98 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 100I6, United States of America Appendix: Previous Treatments of the Subject Matter of this Part
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available VOLUME TWO
ISBN 978-0-19-968439-7 (Vol. 1)
ISBN 978-0-19-968440-3 (Vol. 2) BOOK TWO: THEORY OF ELEMENTS (continued)
ISBN 978-0-19-968441-0 (Vol. 3)
ISBN 978-0-19-968442-7 (Vol. 4) PART II: Of Propositions in Themselves
ISBN 978-0-19-968438-0 (Set)
As primed and bound by
Chapter 1: General Characteristics of Propositions
CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CRO 4YY Chapter 2: Differences between Propositions which Arise from their
. Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and Internal Constitution
for lllformat1on only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
Chapter 3: Distinctions among Propositions which are Based upon
their Relations to each other
Chapter 4: Several Types of Propositions Stating Relations between
other Propositions
Chapter 5: Some Further Propositions whose Linguistic Expression
Wairnnts Special Comment
Appendix: Previous Treatments of the Subject Matter of this Part
PART III: Of True Propositions
PART IV: Of Inferences
Appendix: Previous Treatments of the Subject Matter of this Part
VOLUME THREE

BOOK THREE: THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE


PART I: Of Ideas
PART II: Of Judgements
PART III: Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth
PART IV: Of Certainty, Probability, and Confidence in Judgements
Contents
BOOK FOUR: THE ART OF DISCOVERY
PART I: General Rules
PART II: Particular Rules
Introduction to Volume Three xiii
VOLUME FOUR

BOOK FIVE: THEORY OF SCIENCE PROPER


PART I: General Rules BOOK THREE: THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 1
PART II: On the Determination of the Extensions of the Sciences
§. 269. * Purpose, contents, and divisions of this book . . . . . . . .
PART III: On the Choice of a Class of Readers for a Treatise
PART IV: On the Propositions which Should Appear in a Treatise Part I: Of Ideas 2
Chapter 1:On the Essential Propositions of a Treatise
Chapter 2:On Supporting Propositions §. 270.* The concept of an idea in the subjective sense . . . . . . . 2
Chapter 3:On Occasional Propositions §. 271.* For every subjective idea there is a corresponding idea in itself 4
Chapter 4:Constituents of a Treatise whose Special §. 272.* Every subjective idea is something actual, but only in that
Character Derives from Other Factors it is a kind of property of a being . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
PART V: On the Divisions of a Treatise §. 273. What the author means by a single subjective idea, and by
PART VI: On the Order in which the Propositions Belonging saying that several subjective ideas are equal or unequal 6
to a Treatise Should Appear §. 274. Can several equal ideas exist in a being at the same time? 8
§. 275.* Strength or vividness of subjective ideas . . . . . . . . . . 9
Chapter 1: General Rules of Order
§. 276.* Classification of subjective ideas based upon the correspond-
Chapter 2: Particular Rules
ing classification of objective ideas . . . . 11
PART VII: Theory of Signs or, On the Signs Used in or
§. 277.* We have simple as well as complex ideas . 11
Recommended by a Treatise
§. 278.* We have intuitions as well as concepts 13
Chapter 1: On the Signs Recommended in a Treatise for §. 279. Sensible and supersensible ideas 14
the Reader's Own Use §. 280.* Clear and obscure ideas . . . . . . . . 15
Chapter 2: On the Signs Used in a Treatise §. 281.* Distinct and confused ideas . . . . . . 25
PART VIII: How the Author of a Treatise Should Behave §. 282. Whether each of our ideas has a beginning and an end . 29
PART IX: On Scientific Books that are not Genuine Treatises §. 283.* Whether every idea leaves a certain trace after it has
APPENDIX
disappeared . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31
§. 284. Effects which result from the traces of our ideas 35
§. 285. * Signs for our ideas . . . . . . . . . . 44

vii
Contents Contents

§. 286.* Description of the most important ways in which ideas §. 311.* Origin of true judgements. Understanding and reason 151
originate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56 §. 312. Whether we can recognise a truth without recognising its
§. 287. Other views on the subject . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61 grounds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154
§. 288. How the lack or cessation of an idea is to be understood 69 §. 313. Grounds for the recognition of truth . . . . . . . . . . . 156
§. 289.* Survey of the most important activities and states of our §. 314. Whether there are definite limits to our cognitive faculty 156
mind connected with ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69 §. 315. The doctrine of Critical Philosophy on this subject . 161
§. 316.* Survey of the most important distinctions between
Part II: Of Judgements 72
judgements, based on their relation to truth . . 174
§. 290.* The concept of a judgement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72
§. 291.* Some attributes common to all judgements . . . . . . . . . 72 Part IV: Of Certainty, Probability, and Confidence in
§. 292. What we call a single judgement, and when we say of two Judgements 177
or more judgements that they are equal or unequal . . . . . 74
§. 317. Definition of the concepts of certainty and probability with
§. 293.* Strength or vividness of judgements, and confidence in a
respect to thinking beings . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177
judgement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75
§. 318. Factors which determine the confidence of our judgements 184
§. 294.* Distinctions between judgements based upon parallel
§. 319. The most noteworthy levels of our confidence . . . . . . . 187
distinctions between propositions . 77
§. 320. How the various degrees of confidence can be represented
§. 295. Clear and obscure judgements . . . . . . . . . . . . 77
numerically . . . . . . 190
§. 296. Distinct and confused judgements . . . . . . . . . . 78
§. 321.* Knowledge and belief . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193
§. 297. Whether every judgement has a beginning and an end 79
§. 298. Whether every judgement leaves a trace after it disappears 80
§. 299. Effects of these traces of our judgements . . . . . . . . . . 81
§. 300.* Mediation of a judgement by other judgements . . . . . . 82 BOOK FOUR: THE ART OF DISCOVERY 197
§. 301.* The generation of judgements by the relation of probability 91
§. 322.* Purpose, contents, and divisions of this book. . . . . . . . 197
§. 302. How we come by our immediate judgements . . . . . 92
§. 323. The concept of reflection, in particular of reflection aimed
§. 303.* How we arrive at, or could arrive at, our most general
at the discovery of new truths . . . . . . 198
judgements of experience . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94
§. 324. The concept of instructions for thinking 202
§. 304. Other opinions on this subject . . . . . . . . . . . . 111
§. 305. The doctrine of the Critical Philosophy concerning this point 120
Part I: General Rules 204
§. 306.* Survey of the most important activities and states of mind
which concern the business of judging . . . . . . . . 134
§. 325.* I. Exact determination of the truth we actually seek, without
rejecting truths which present themselves unbidden . . 204
Part III: Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth 139
§. 326.* II. Preliminary consideration of whether answering the
§. 307.* More precise determination of the concepts: knowledge, question before us is impossible either as such or for us 206
ignorance, and error . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 §. 327.* III. Taking up suitable preliminary questions . . . . . . 208
§. 308. Grounds for the possibility of ignorance in man . . . . 141 §. 328.* IV. Deductions from already known truths or direct method 211
§. 309.* Grounds for the possibility of error, and circumstances §. 329.* V. Tentative acceptance or indirect method . . . . . . . . . 213
promoting error . . . . . . . . . . . 143 §. 330. VI. Combination of several methods . . . . . . . . . . . . 220
§. 310. Other treatments of the same subject 147 §. 331.* VII. Consultation of others' judgements and of experience 223

Vlll IX
Contents Contents

§. 332.* VIII. Examination of one's own previously formed §. 354. V. Whether an idea is redundant; purification of redundant
judgements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227 ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 271
§. 333. IX. Directing one's attention preferentially towards §. 355 VI. Investigating the relation between the extensions of given
individual judgements and ideas . . . . . . . . . . 236 ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 272
§. 334. X. Associating our ideas with suitable signs. Advantages of §. 356. VII. Discovering an idea that contains a similarity between
this association. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 237 given objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 275
§. 335. The nature of signs which are supposed to aid us in our own §. 357. VIII. Discovering an idea that furnishes a difference
reflection: 1) They must be sensible objects . . . . . . . . 239 between given objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 277
§. 336. 2) Which can be easily displayed anywhere . . . . . . . . 239 §. 358. IX. Discovering an attribute that belongs exclusively to given
§. 337. 3) An inner connection between the idea of the sign and the objects either with respect to a given multitude of objects or
designated idea must either exist or else be easily produced 240 in general . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 280
§. 338. 4) A suitable sign should not call forth any detrimental §. 359. X. Discovering an idea that subsumes a given multitude of
secondary ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 240 objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
§. 339. Special attributes of signs that are supposed to preserve our §. 360. XI. Discovering an idea that subsumes more than a given
thoughts: 1) They must be sufficiently long-lasting 241 multitude of objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 284
§. 340. 2) They should be easily recognised everywhere . . . . . . 242 §. 361. XII. Discovering an idea that subsumes fewer than a given
§. 341. 3) Identical signs should never have several easily confused multitude of objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 285
meanings . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 242 §. 362 XIII. Discovering an idea that exactly subsumes a given
§. 342. 4) Different ideas should never be expressed by means of multitude of objects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 289
signs which are too similar . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 242 §. 363. XIV. Discovering an idea that represents less than a given
§. 343. Some other recommended attributes of signs . . . . . . . . 243 multitude of objects but more than a given part of this
§. 344. Rules for the invention and use of signs for the purposes of multitude . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 290
one's own reflection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 245 §. 364. XV. Discovering an idea which subsumes both more and
§. 345. XI. The use of images connected with our ideas . . . . . . 252 less than a given multitude . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 292
§. 346.* XII. Consideration of the logical attributes and relations of §. 365. XVI. Discovering several ideas which only collectively
our judgements and ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 252 subsume a given multitude of objects . . . . . . 294
§. 347. XIII. Estimating the reliability of the answer we have §. 366. XVII. Defining a proposition that is given to our
discovered . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 consc10usness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297
§. 348.* XIV. Additional rnles concerning the conditions of thought 255 §. 367. XVIII. Investigating whether a given proposition is analytic
or synthetic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 298
Part II: Particular Rules 260 §. 368. XIX. Investigating the relations between given propositions 298
§. 369.* XX. Testing the truth of a given proposition . . . . . . . . 299
§. 349.* I. Discovering suitable problems . . . . . . . . 260 §. 370.* XXL Testing the force of conviction of a given proof . . . 302
§. 350.* II. Analysing an idea given to our consciousness 264 §. 371.* The most common flaws of proofs; a) with respect to matter 306
§. 351. Mistakes in carrying out this task . . . . . . . . 268 §. 372.* b) With respect to form . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 311
§. 352. III. Whether a given idea is real or imaginary, and whether §. 373.* Various indicators of the incorrectness of a proof: a) if the
it has an object . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 269 conclusion is false . . . . . . . . . . 312
§. 353. IV. Whether a given object-idea has only one or several §. 374.* b) If the proof proves too much . . . 312
objects . . . . . . . . . . ............. . 270 §. 375.* c) If it doesn't use all the conditions 314

x XI
Contents

§,. 376. * d) It· i't calls· t1pcl11 the experience at the wrong place, or INTRODUCTION TO VOLUME THREE
scorns it . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 316
§. 377. Examination of some famous sophisms from the writings
of logicians . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 316 Volume three of the Theory <~f Science contains two of the five main parts of
§. 378. XXII. Discovering the ground of a given truth . . . 328 the work, Book three, devoted to the Theory of Knowledge and Book four,
§. 379. XXIII. The discovery of causes for given effects . . 329 on the Art of Discovery. We shall discuss these parts separately.
§. 380. The most common mistakes in performing this task 343
§. 381. XXIV. Examination of purported causes . . . . . 344 Book Three: Themy of Knowledge
§. 382. Further rules to be observed when seeking causes 346
§. 383. XXV. Discovering suitable means for given ends . 347 Having set out the theory of propositions and ideas in themselves in Book
§. 384. XXVI. Discovering the effects of given causes . . 349 two, Bolzano turns in Book three to subjective ideas and propositions. A
§. 385. XXVII. Investigation of the judgements of other beings 352 subjective idea is characterised as the appearance or manifestation of its ob-
§. 386. XXVIII. Investigation of the intentions behind given actions 354 jective counterpart in a mind. These rather unhelpful expressions seem to
§. 387. XXIX. The interpretation of given signs . . . . . . . 359 mean that the mind forms a subjective idea with logical attributes that paral-
§. 388. XXX. Discovery of available testimony . . . . . . . lel those of the corresponding idea in itself (e.g., if they have objects, then
367
§. 389. XXXI. Investigating the credibility of given witnesses 369 they have the same extension and, if complex, are composed of equivalent
§. 390. XXXII. Determining the credibility of a proposition based parts put together in similar fashion, etc.). He will also say, again speaking
on the opinions of all those who either accept or reject it 374 figuratively, that when someone thinks a subjective idea, he grasps the corre-
§. 39 l. XXXIII. Discovering new truths about a given object 376 sponding objective idea. Finally, the objective idea is called the matter [Stoff]
of the corresponding subjective idea. 1 More than one subjective idea (either
in one and the same mind or in different minds) may correspond to a given
Bibliography 381 objective idea-such ideas are said to be equal as regards their matter. The
individuation of subjective ideas thus requires a different approach from the
Index of Names 391 one followed for objective ideas. 2 Similar remarks apply to propositions.
A few words on Bolzano's metaphysics may be helpful at this point. 3
Like Leibniz, he thought that the universe was composed ultimately of sub-
Index of Subjects 394 stances and their attributes, which he called adherences. 4 Bolzanian sub-
stances, like Leibniz's monads, are both simple and indestructible by natural
means, and hence in the normal case also eternal. Bolzano disagreed with
Leibniz on some important points, however, maintaining that substances are
in space and time (each one occupying a distinct point at any given instant),
I §§270-272; 291.
2 §273.
3 The main published sources for Bolzano's metaphysics are Athanasia, oder Griinde fiir
die Unsterblichkeit der Seele (!st ed. Sulzbach 1827; 2nd ed. Sulzbach, 1838); Paradoxien
des Unendlichen (Leipzig, 1851); Franz Pffhonsky, Atomenlehre des sel. Bo/zano (Bautzen,
1857); new edition by E. Morscher and Ch. Thiel in Franz Pffhonsky, Neuer Anti-Kant und
Atomenlehre des seligen Bolwno (St. Augustin: Academia. 2003).
4
Bolzano discusses his agreements and disagreements with Leibniz in one of his note-
books: Philosophische Tagebiicher 1827-1844, Bernard Bolz.ano-Gesamtausgabe (hereafter,
BBGA), Series 2 B, Vol. 18/2, pp. 37-48, 56-57.

Xll Xlll
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

and really (not merely ideally) interact. Substances thus exertforces, which these theories. Consider again, for example, his notion of an intuition. In
cause changes in other substances. Not themselves substances, forces are objective terms, these had been defined as ideas that are both simple (having
1
classed by Balzano as adherences. In addition to these externally directed 110 parts) and singular (having exactly one object). On the subjective side,
adherences, he also thinks that all substances have internal states. Again Balzano maintains that all human intuitions have psychological phenomena
following Leibniz, he on rare occasions calls these representations or ideas as objects-often sensations, but also judgements, desires, etc. In a typical
[Vorstellwzgen] in a very broad sense of this term. 1 It is appropriate in this case, an intuition has as its unique object a sensation that is present just now
respect to call every substance a mind or soul, again in a very broad sense in the mind that forms the intuition. Often, these sensations are caused by
of these terms, and Balzano accordingly calls forces as well as the internal external, physical objects (i.e., objects other than the mind experiencing the
states of substances psychological phenomena. 2 Minds in the stricter sense, sensation)-more precisely, by collections of infinitely many substances. The
i.e., beings capable of forming ideas and judgements, etc., are also simple sensation is not an idea in the strict sense-that is, it is not the sort of thing
substances in his view. that could ever be a part of a judgement. Rather, it is represented by an
He distinguishes five kinds of internal psychological phenomena: subjec- idea, the intuition. (Balzano thought that the subjective intuitions were the
tive ideas, judgements, sensations, desires (wishes) and resolutions (acts of immediate effects of the sensations that were their unique objects, and saw in
will). From the point of view of logic, the first two, corresponding to the this circumstance the explanation of how a simple idea might represent only
ideas and propositions in themselves studied in the Theory of Elements, are one object. 2 ) These intuitions, in turn, are often subsumed under general
the most noteworthy. We note in passing that Balzano has no separate cate- concepts such as "red", namely, when someone makes a judgement of the
gory for propositional acts of merely thinking that p, without taking it to be form "This is red." 3 We thus have something like the following picture:
true. He takes them to be acts of forming an idea of the proposition that p. 3
We saw in Volume one that Balzano took propositions rather than ideas
to be primary, and consequently rejected the widespread view according to
Causes . _C~a_us~e_s-+-I . . is subordinate to C
which ideas were a second set of objects in the mind resembling the objects Object ----Sensation ntmt1on oncept
uniquely (this) (e.g., red)
outside in some way or another. As a result, he deems the theory of subjec- represents

tive ideas to be far less important for epistemology than most early modern
philosophers had. All the same, he dutifully works through the traditional
distinctions, telling us what it means for ideas to be more or less vivid, clear Most, if not all, of this complexity is lacking in many early modern ac-
or obscure, distinct or confused, simple or complex, etc. 4 He speculates that counts of ideas. By and large, the notion of an intuition in Bolzano's sense
subjective ideas, even after they have ceased to be, leave behind them linger- is completely absent, and sensations are frequently confused with concepts,
ing effects on the minds in which they formerly existed. These effects, called i.e., the object of the idea with the idea itself. Locke, for example, spoke of
traces, are then appealed to in his accounts of memory and the association of "simple ideas of sensation" such as "yellow, white, heat, cold, soft, hard." 4
ideas. 5 These ideas, he claimed, come to us through the senses, and are individual
Although Bolzano's account of ideas is quite conservative in its general in character-they are particulars, thus much like Bolzano's sensations. But
approach, reflecting the then-widespread views of sense-data epistemology the very same ideas, according to Locke, also occur as parts of judgements,
and associationist psychology, it is noteworthy for the precision it brings to as when we judge that a pear is yellow or that buttercups are yellow-and
here, they seem to be general in character, like Bolzano's concepts. We thus
1
E.g., §283 [III.247]; cf. §35 [I.235], in Volume !. seem to have something like the following conception:
2 § 143, in Volume 2.
3 1§72,
§290. See W. Kiinne, "Propositions in Bolzano and Frege," Grazer Philosophische Stu- in Volume !.
dien 53 ( 1997) 203-240, for a discussion of these and related matters. 2 §74, no. 1, in Volume !.
4 §§275-28 l. 3 Cf. §59, no. 3, in Volume !.
5 §§283-284. 4
Essay, II, i, §3.

XIV xv
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

an object that the idea does not represent, or does not fit, is not
Causes
an object of that idea. 1
Object..._.._ _ _ Idea of sensation
represents (e.g., yellow) As careful as Bolzano is in setting out the distinctions between objects,
sensations, intuitions, and the concepts under which these are subordinated in
judgements, he sometimes appears to lose sight of them. In §303, for exam-
Ideas were thus held to be both the elements of judgements and the el- ple, he speaks of repeatedly experiencing certain intuitions, ~f what happens
ements of sensation. But it is not clear how anything can function in both whenever we have certain intuitions, etc. 2 But we had previously been told
of these capacities. Ideas were often described in terms not consistent with that the object of any humanly attainable intuition is "a change that occurs just
their roles as terms of judgements: they were said to be divisible, round, now" in the being that forms the intuition. Since these changes are present
3
moving, receding, etc. It is clear that mental occurrences of this sort, what- only once, however, it follows directly that intuitions are unrepeatable. To
ever we want to call them, are not what is required to fill the role of terms be more precise, he should have spoken of having, at different times, various
of judgements. If judgements are, as Bolzano supposed, mentally articulated sensations that are represented by various intuitions that stand under certain
propositions, their terms will have to be something other than sense-data and concepts, etc. Perhaps it was for the sake of brevity that he allowed himself to
the like. Sensations, etc., could be seen to be parts of judgements only under follow then customary usage in speaking of repeated intuitions, and running
very peculiar circumstances; they are, in any case, not eo ipso what is wanted too-ether intuitions and sensations, etc., as he did. It is also possible, however,
b

here. It seems, then, that any theory which envisages judgements as manifest that these passages are a relic of his earlier usage: in 1810, he appears to
mental events, and which also holds sensations to be mental events, must dis- have used the term 'intuition' for the object of the idea "X" in the judgement
tinguish subjective ideas from sensations, or at least must offer an explanation (i.e., for what he would later call a sensation), rather than for the idea "X"
of how one kind of entity can fill both of these roles. (Hume, for example, which represents that object-in any case, he does not appear to have clearly
4
did not separate these kinds. He claims reasoning to be the operation of our grasped the distinction between sensation and intuition at that time. Be that
thoughts and ideas, but it is not very plausible to call reasoning the operation as it may, readers will need to make a fair number of tacit emendations in this
of something that can be divided, or pointlike, etc.) section in order to understand Bolzano's theory.
Bolzano did not become a victim of that confusion. For him a subjective A related case of apparent confusion may be found in §271, where Bol-
idea is either part of a mental proposition, or at least could be such a part, zano argues for the thesis that for every subjective idea there is a correspond-
i.e., he concentrates on the logical functions of ideas; he never envisages ing objective one. He writes:
them as something that is at all like a sensation. This concentration on the
logical aspects of mental activity, one-sided though it may be, allows him If a certain subjective idea A is to be actually present in the mind
to avoid certain classical mistakes. In particular, the view that knowledge of a thinking being, then the proposition "This being has the idea
consists in the similarity or resemblance between our ideas and their objects A" is a truth, and indeed, even if there is no one who thinks this
is exposed as fallacious. The cluster of difficulties concerned with the so- truth, i.e., it is a truth in itself. So too the constituents of this
called adequation of ideas and their objects were thus dismissed by him as proposition are just so many ideas in themselves. But it is obvi-
pseudo-problems. The question whether an idea agrees with its object, in
1§29 [I.28], in Volume 1.
particular, is deemed utterly trivial:
2§303, nos. 12ff. A similar looseness or expression is evident in §303, no. 21, where B.
seems to use the terms 'intuition' and 'sensation' as if they were interchangeable, and in §304,
If one wished to say that agreement simply means that the ideas
no. 1, where he speaks of the "perception of intuitions".
fit their objects, i.e., actually represent them, then I would ask:
3Cf. §75, no. 1, in Volume 1.
which object do you mean by the object of an idea? If you mean 4Beytriige zu einer begriindeteren Darstellung der Mathematik (Prague, 1810); English
the objects to which the idea itself applies (and I usually take the translation by S. B. Russ in The Mathematical Works of Bernard Bolzano (Oxford University
expression in this sense) then every idea represents its object; for Press, 2004), Appendix, §4.

xvi XVll
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

ous that the idea A must itself occur in this proposition-not the He then turns to the question of the origin of judgements. Many of these
subjective idea, but rather the corresponding objective one. 1 do not arise in the mind of themselves, but rather only through the mediation
of others. There are only three ways that such mediation occurs, he claims,
Bolzano says that it is obvious that the idea "A" occurs in this proposition. corresponding to the relations of deducibility (§ 155), ground-consequence
But is it? It seems to be rather an idea of the idea "A" that is required here, a (§198), and (relative) probability (§161). Hence when a judgement Mis me-
point Bolzano himself recognises only a few pages later: diated by judgements A, B, C, ... , one of the three following cases holds:
... let us see what is necessary in order to form the judgement 1. M is deducible from A, B, C, ....
that we have a certain idea a. There is no occurrence, in this
judgement, of the idea a itself, but only of an idea of this idea. 2 2. M is a consequence of the grounds A, B, C, ....
1
Given Bolzano's consistent acuity, it is quite surprising to find two ap- 3. Mis probable with respect to A, B, C, ....
parently contradictory statements so close together. It therefore seems rea- He takes it as obvious that we also form some immediate judgements, because
sonable to look for some way to reconcile these two remarks. We think the "the existence of mediated ones can in the end be understood only because
problem could be resolved if we were to suppose that Bolzano assumes that there are also immediate judgements."2 Some of these are intuitional or em-
the idea "A" is part of the idea "the idea 'A"', just as an expression within pirical, but some are also perforce purely conceptual. 3
quotation marks is part of the expression consisting of the expression along A couple of important remarks follow. To begin with, in the case of de-
with the quotation marks, e.g.: ducibility, a rule of inference is sometimes included among the mediating
judgements A, B, C, ... , and sometimes not. But even when a rule of in-
Dog
ference does occur among the premises, the application of this rule (i.e., the
is part of actual act of inferring) must occur immediately, i.e., without an explicitly
stated rule. Otherwise, as he describes in detail, we end up with the infinite
"Dog" regress familiar from Lewis Carroll's paradox. 4 Second, Bolzano insists that
in the third case the conclusion that is drawn is not the proposition that M is
In this case, we could say that in a proposition of the form:
probable with respect to A, B, C, ... , but rather M itself (the former conclu-
This being has the idea A sion, he notes, would not merely be probable with respect to A, B, C, ... ,
but actually deducible from them). Later, he speculates that such probable
the idea "A" would not constitute the entire predicate, but rather only part of inferences come about due to the limitations of our cognitive powers, in that
it, i.e., part of the idea "the idea 'A"'. While this suggestion seems to fit with we begin by forming the judgement "M is probable" and, through inattentive-
what Bolzano says here and elsewhere, however, we know of no passage in ness, omit the part "is probable". This happens above all with propositions of
his works where he explicitly endorses such an account. the sort that are called morally certain:
The second part of book three, which is concerned with judgements, be-
[W]ith judgements expressing the probability of a proposition
gins with a discussion that parallels the first part of Bolzano's treatment of
M-provided that this probability is so high that we must guide
ideas, where he deals with the individuation of judgements, tells us what he
our action by M-the proposition itself is by far the most im-
means when he calls them clear or obscure, distinct or confused, etc., postu-
portant thing, while the fact that it is not decidedly true but only
lates traces left behind by judgements, sketches a theory of memory based on
traces, and so on. 3 1§300. In the first and third cases, it is understood that these relations hold with respect to

some variable parts or other.


1§271 [III.8-9]. 2§300, no. 3 [III.125].
2§280 [III.27-28]. 3§300, nos. 12. 13.
3 §§290-299. 4
~300, no. 9 [III.127-128].

xviii XIX
Intmduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

probable is not nearly as important. Now if we are unable to the moment in which a given psychological phenomenon occurs, and that we
keep in our mind all of the parts of M as well as the thought that can also recognise some cases of simultaneity (e.g., of the parts of a complex
this proposition is not completely certain, but merely so highly psychological phenomenon), he denies that we have any immediate grasp of
probable that we have to act upon it, then it seems natural that we before and after in time. One of the first tasks is thus to explain the origin of
omit the latter thought, since it is the less important, and concen- judgements bearing on the temporal sequence of events. Difference of times
trate our attention merely upon proposition M itself in order to can be established, he claims, partly by logical means:
grasp it completely and retain it. In this way it happens that the
[I]t would be an obvious contradiction to say that a judgement
judgement which attributes only a certain degree of probability
A as well as its actual contradictory, the judgement "A is false",
to proposition M gradually disappears from our clear conscious-
are formed simultaneously. Hence, if we are forced to admit the
ness (if it ever attained such a position), and judgement M alone
presence of certain contradictory phenomena in ourselves, we
remains. 1
conclude that they could occur only at different times. 1
It is thus entirely possible for the process of mediation to produce false (though
A similar technique can be used in certain cases to establish temporal order,
probable) conclusions from true premises. Probabilistic mediation is thus a
for if I am aware that both A and not-A are or have been present in my mind
source of error and indeed, as we shall see, the only one according to Bolzano.
and that A is present now, I may conclude that not-A was formed in the past.
With these preliminaries out of the way, Bolzano proceeds to develop
By recognising the simultaneity of A with B and not-A with C, etc., these
an account of how we come to make some of our most basic judgements of
basic judgements of temporal order can be parlayed into others. We then
experience. He is interested in particular in those judgements of experience
have a sketch of how a temporal metric, or measure of duration, might be
that we erroneously take to be immediate because "we are rarely conscious of
established.
the inferences which mediate them." 2 J. A. Coffa, in his book on the semantic
Bolzano thinks that we are able to recognise immediately whether the ob-
tradition, noted the resemblance of this project to what Carnap would later
ject of a given intuition had its cause inside or outside of the mind. 2 This ba-
undertake in the Aujbau. 3 It indeed seems fair to regard Bolzano's §303 as
sic ability is presupposed in his account of how we begin to make judgements
a detailed sketch of what Carnap called a constructional system, even if the
about objects outside of us, based largely on the purely conceptual principle
two differ profoundly in that Carnap tried to construct objects while Bolzano
that similar causes produce similar effects. We learn to distinguish various
aimed rather at our judgements about objects. 4 A final point of resemblance
external objects, among them our own bodies, and form various judgements
is that Bolzano, like Carnap, does not claim to produce an account that is
about their properties and relations.
factually accurate in all its details, but instead only a rational reconstruction:
Finally, Bolzano describes in some detail how we come to make judge-
I do not merely want to describe how these judgements are actu- ments about spatial relations. Earlier, space had been defined as the collection
ally formed, but rather how they could and should be formed if of all locations, and locations as "those determinations of [actual] things that
a rational man wanted to justify them. 5 we must think in addition to their forces in order to comprehend the changes
that they cause in one another." 3 Now even in the simplest case where there
His starting point is the construction of our judgements about temporal are only two substances A and B, it seems obvious that multiple solutions to
order. While he does think that the now is immediately recognisable, i.e., as Bolzano's problem will be possible-for from the point of view of A we are
1§301, not given the forces exerted by B, but only their effects, which depend upon
no. 2 [Ill.137-138].
2 §303 [III.141]. two unknowns (the forces exerted by B and its location relative to A). We
3 J. A. Coffa, The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- can thus save all the appearances in a variety of ways, provided that changes
versity Press, 1992), p. 207. So too Jan Berg, in his introduction to BBGA, Series I, Vol. 13/ I,
1§303, no. 3 (III.143-144].
p.21-22.
4 Cf. Coffa, p. 238. 2 §303, no. 10.
3
5 §303 [III.141 ]. §79 [I.366].

xx xxi
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

in location are matched by appropriate changes in the forces. The possibility because these are deducible from other propositions one is committed to;
of different physical geometries thus seems built right into the structure of rather, one must either have deduced these conclusions or else it must be
Bolzano's theory. Surprisingly and somewhat disappointingly, however, he certain that one will do so, if the attribution of knowledge or error is to be
does not appear to have seen this, and appears to assume that his problem has justified-no logical omniscience for us, then. l
a unique solution. He next embarks on an inquiry into the origin of e1rnr. Immediate judge-
The part on judgements concludes with a survey of various activities con- ments, he claims, are infallible. Characteristically, he attempts to show that
nected with judgement. Of particular interest here is Bolzano's definition of this is a purely conceptual truth which can be established without even citing
the notion of an a priori judgement: an example of an immediate judgement. 2 Bolzano does not state the com-
plete argument, but it can be reconstructed in the following manner: in the
If the propositions from which a judgement Mis deduced, as well
Theory of Fundamentals it was established that we know at least one truth.
as those from which the former follow, clown to the immediate
This knowledge must be either immediate or derived. In either case we must
judgements, are all purely conceptual propositions, then judge-
have some immediate knowledge. Assume that we know that not all but only
ment M can be called a judgement from pure concepts, or pure,
some of our immediate judgements are true. But if we know this, then we
or a priori. In all other cases it could be said to be drawn from
must have reasons why some of them are true, and others false, and if we
experience or a posteriori. l
have such reasons, then the judgements are not immediate. Balzano claims
It is clear from this definition that the notions of a purely conceptual judge- that if we hold some of them to be false, we must hold all of them to be false,
ment and of an a priori judgement are anything but coextensive. Indeed, since they all originate in the same way (namely, without further reasons for
because many purely conceptual judgements are only made after a long se- their truth or falsity). If valid, the argument would establish only the fact that
quence of inferences, in which memory (and hence empirical or intuitional we are in possession of a class of judgements that are infallible, but it does
judgements) is involved, a priori judgements in the strict sense defined above not identify these judgements. In casting about for likely candidates for that
would seem to be quite rare in Bolzano's estimation. role, Balzano, not surprisingly, settles upon judgements of the forms "I have
The third part of Book three (§§307-316) deals with knowledge, igno- the impression A" and "This (what I now experience) is an A." There must
rance, error, and related matters. Cognition, or knowledge in the broad sense be at least some immediate judgements of this form, Balzano argues, because
(Kenntnis or Erkenntnis) was roughly characterised in §34 as true judgement. "every derived judgement of this so1t presupposes another of the same kind."
Bolzano now broadens this characterisation to allow for cases where some- Hence "if the judgement 'The intuition X is an A' is not to be immediate, then
one does not currently judge that something is the case, but is in a position it must be deduced from a pair of other judgements, namely, 'The intuition X
and of a disposition to do so: is a B', and 'All B are A ')." 3 The judgement "The intuition A is a B" is either
immediate, or derives in the indicated fashion from another judgement of the
According to customary usage, we ascribe knowledge, and in- same form. Eventually, we must arrive at an immediate judgement. What is
deed continual knowledge of a truth A to someone, if he has remarkable about this argument is that Balzano does not argue from the phe-
formed the judgement A at some point in the past, and if under nomenal character of some judgements to their immediacy and infallibility,
circumstances which suffice for him to remember other judge- but argues for the infallibility of some forms of judgement from the fact that
ments he hasn't forgotten, he not only would be in a position to we know anything at all.
recall A, but would still be committed to it. 2 All mediate judgements are based on, i.e., mentally caused by, immedi-
Ignorance is then defined as a lack of awareness of a truth, and error as being ate judgements. As we saw, Balzano held that a given judgement Q can be
committed to a false proposition. Bolzano takes care to observe that one mediated by another, P, only if it is derivable from P (either in the sense of
cannot be said to know a truth A or be committed to a falsehood B simply
1§307, no. 3.
1§306, no. 12 [III.202]. 2 Cf.§42, 311.
2 §307, no. I [III.207]. 3 §300, no. 12 [III.131].

xx ii xxiii
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

§155 or §198) or P makes Q probable. He obviously envisaged the mind spect to given variable ideas and various kinds of subjective probabilities, as
as some sort of machine which produces judgements according to certain well as his attempt to characterise knowledge in the strong sense (Wissen).
rules. (Bolzano held the production of judgements to be involuntary. They In § J61, he had defined the probability of a proposition M relative to
are caused either by something that is presented to me, as in the case of im- propositions A,B,C, ... and with respect to variable ideas i,j,k, ... as the
mediate judgements, or by other judgements already present in the mind. I ratio of the number of substitutions for i, j, k, ... that make all of A, B, C, .. .
can only exercise a modest amount of control by the direction of my attention as well as M trne to the number of substitutions that make all of A, B, C, .. .
towards certain ideas.) The rules the mind follows in the production of judge- true. If M has probability =1 with respect to A, B, C, ... , it is said to be certain
ments belong to, and constitute much of, the objective part of logic. In other relative to them. These are objective relations, holding between propositions
words, Bolzano assumes that judgements stimulate and produce one another in themselves, as Bolzano remarks,
in the mind in confonnity with the objective rules of deducibility and prob-
ability. Enws can, of course, occur, but only if a judgement that is merely ... where it is a matter of indifference whether these propositions
probable on the basis of previously accepted judgements is accepted without are in themselves true or false or whether there is a thinking be-
qualification and turns out to be false. That is, we err when we forget that we ing who takes them to be trne or even thinks them. 1
derived a certain proposition through a probabilistic argument, and proceed
from 'The probability of Pis µ" to P itself. But 'certainty', Bolzano notes, is also used in a different, subjective sense,
With this exception, thought processes and ratiocination are claimed to as for instance when infallible judgements (e.g., immediate ones) are said to
conform to objectively valid arguments, so that neglecting probability-riders be certain for the being that forms them. Similarly, one may distinguish the
is the only possible source of error. But what could be the evidence that if P probability a proposition M has with respect to other propositions A, B, C, ... ,
and Q are present in the mind, and R is stimulated by them (how do we know in and of themselves from the probability it has with respect to other propo-
that R was stimulated by them?) then R is deducible from them? Bolzano sitions A', B', C', ... , that are held to be true by someone. In the latter case,
claims in effect that there is no evidence against this assumption, but it is fair furthermore, the person who takes A', B', C', ... , to be true may or may
to ask what such contrary evidence could be. It seems that evidence against not be aware of the relation of probability between them and M; Bolzano
Bolzano's claim would have to consist of an argument which is everywhere speaks in this connection of recognised and unrecognised probabilities. Fi-
accepted as valid but which is objectively invalid or, conversely, by an argu- nally, we may distinguish the probability a proposition M has with respect to
ment which is objectively valid but is generally rejected. In the nature of the only some of the propositions someone takes to be true, or with respect to
case, this evidence cannot be produced. Thus while there might be such argu- all, between relative and absolute probabilities attaching to a proposition for
ments, they cannot he brought forth as evidence. Hence, Bolzano's claim, if a given thinker.
it makes any sense at all, is not the kind of proposition that can be confirmed Probability in any of these senses is to be distinguished, Bolzano main-
or disconfirmed. tains, from the confidence with which someone forms a judgement. 2 Upon
It is important to recall in this connection that not every proposition that pain of infinite regress, this confidence cannot be fixed in every case by an
appears in the mind is a judgement, i.e., an accepted proposition. We can estimation of the probability of the proposition deemed to be true, since this
have the mere idea of a proposition in our mind without affirming it. Bol- estimation is itself a judgement with its own degree of confidence. Bolzano
zano 's theory as we have sketched it was concerned only with the origin of nonetheless thinks that confidence of a judgement M is a function of proba-
judgements; ideas, even ideas of propositions, can be generated in quite dif- bility, namely, of the given proposition with respect to all of the propositions
ferent ways, for example, by association. bearing on M currently in the judger's mind. Probability being a matter of
The final part of Book three (§§317-321) discusses the certainty, proba- degree, we can accordingly distinguish various degrees of certainty. Moral
bility, and confidence of judgements. Notable here are Bolzano's distinction
1§317, no.
between probability as a relation between propositions in themselves with re- I [III.264].
2 §318; cf. §293.

xxiv xxv
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

certainty is defined in terms of ordinary certainty along with the perceived On the other hand, it is entirely possible for us to accept a basic truth only
consequences of belief in M or its opposite. 1 after a series of inferences, so that a truth that is basic in the objective sense
The final section offers a definition of knowledge in the strong sense, may be derivative in the subjective.
or Wissen. Bolzano takes this to be confidence in a truth that we ourselves Next, consider Bolzano's exemplary clarity on the subject of the a priori.
perceive to be unshakable: To speak of a priori truth or a priori propositions is, on his principles, to
commit a category mistake, for only judgements and knowledge may strictly
Suppose that a truth M, either immediately or after we pay at- speaking be called a priori. Where Kant had said that all the judgements of
tention to its grounds, has become so evident to us that we as- pure mathematics are a priori, Bolzano says instead that all the truths (i.e.,
sume we could not persuade ourselves of the opposite even if we true propositions) of pure mathematics are purely conceptual, and that at least
wanted. In other words, we think that it is not in our power to
some of them can be known a priori. A priori knowledge in his strict sense,
destroy the confidence with which we are attached to judgement
Bolzano allows, is indeed completely certain, as had been claimed by many of
M. In this case I should like to call truth Man item of knowledge
his contemporaries. But this claim should not be confused with the claim that
[Wissen]. 2
all of our purely conceptual, in particular mathematical, judgements are infal-
Opposed to knowledge is belief, which may attach both to truths and to false- lible. Given the long chains of deductions required to move from immediate
hoods. Interesting here is that confidence in a truth in cases of knowledge judgements to most truths of mathematics via perfect (i.e., non-probabilistic)
might indeed be destroyed; what matters is that one thinks that it cannot. On inferences, memory is almost inevitably involved, and with it all the fallibility
the other hand, a proposition that someone knows must also be true, some- of empirical judgements. Moreover, even when we have formed a judgement
thing that holds completely independently of his judgements. a priori, it may be extremely difficult to become aware that we have done so. 1
There is no doubt that Bolzano's epistemology is open to attack on a As a consequence, judgements that are in fact infallible may not be recognised
number of fronts. All the same, it is worth noting some of the strong points, as such; while on the other hand, we may easily mistakenly believe a judge-
the fruits of the careful prior investigations of the Theory of Elements. To ment to be infallible when it is anything but. Bolzano's position thus allows
start with, the notion of an immediate judgement is carefully distinguished him to make sense of the claim that mathematical truths can in some cases be
from that of a basic truth, i.e., a truth that has no objective ground. Although known a priori while still doing justice to the fallibility of even the greatest
Bolzano assumes that all immediate judgements are true and indeed certain, mathematicians that should have been obvious to any attentive observer.
he takes pains to point out that the propositions in themselves that are their Finally, Bolzano's precise distinctions between physical objects, sensa-
matter need not, and usually are not, basic truths. This is most obvious in the tions, ideas, ideas of ideas, ideas subordinate to other ideas, etc., put him in a
case of so-called immediate judgements of perception, e.g., "I have sensation position to state received theories of perception far more distinctly than any of
A": his contemporaries. Though he sometimes lapses into the confused language
of the time, there can be no doubt that he introduced the concepts, and the
For a truth of the form "I have the idea or sensation A" cannot degrees of freedom that come with them, required to give an adequate char-
be among the truths which have no further ground; rather, just acterisation of traditional sense-data epistemology. Whatever one thinks of
as my own existence and the fact that I now have precisely these those theories, Bolzano's presentation of them has to rank as one of the most
ideas, sensations, etc., must have a cause, so too the truth stating clear and precise. And once one has mastered his distinctions, the confusions
the presence of these ideas and sensations in me must have a present in earlier writers (as well as his own occasional slips) become as plain
ground. 3 as day.
1§319.
2 §321 [III.288]. Bolzano later criticised this definition as inadequate. See BBGA, Se-
ries 2A, Vol. 12/l, p. 124 and 2Al2/2 p. 189 as well as Bolzano's Wissenschaftslehre w1d
Religionswissenschaft in einer beurtheilender Uebersicht (Sulzbach, 1841), p. 79-80.
3 §3 l 2 [III.229]. 1Cf. §332, no. 6.

XXVl xx vii
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

Book Four: The Art of Discove1y be employed. Prominent among these are the direct and indirect methods
(the synthetic and analytic methods of the ancients) and their subspecies, no-
Although Bolzano calls Book four the Art of Discovery, he admits from tably reduction to absurdity (§§328-329). These various methods may also
the start that this title is too grand for its contents. He does not, he tells us, be combined in a single inquiry (§330). Observation and experiment may
aim at producing a complete, all-purpose manual teaching us how to discover contribute something here, as may the judgements of other people or even
all truths and solve all problems, but only the parts of such an account that our own earlier judgements (§§331-332). Considerable stress is placed upon
bear directly on the aims of the Theory of Science, i.e., the organisation and the importance of devising a suitable notation (signs for our ideas) and the
presentation of scientific information. There is to be, in particular, no discus- errors that may arise due to an unsuitable choice (§§334-344).
sion of methods peculiar to any special science. In this respect, Bolzano's Art Once a possible solution to a problem has been found, we should examine
of Discovery is far less concrete than, for example, Polya's twentieth-century it, along with any proofs of its correctness, counterarguments, etc. (§§347-
classics on mathematical heuristics. 1 348; on proofs, cf. §§370-376). Should a proposed solution survive this test,
Now the art of problem-solving seems to resist being boiled down to a it is useful to consider whether it may be generalised (§391), etc.
handful of general principles. For different kinds of problems, different ap- This general presentation (Part I) is followed by a second part devoted to
proaches are often called for, something that can lend a treatment of heuristics specific kinds of problems. Here, we <u-e given advice on how to discover
the appearance of a miscellany. (Polya, in his How to Solve it, hit upon the suitable problems in the first place, and how to approach various kinds of
happy idea of including a "Dictionary of Heuristic".) There is ce1tainly less these.
systematic structure in this part of the The01y of Science than in the others, Several of these discussions are particularly noteworthy. §§350 and 366
something that will be reflected in our introductory remarks. deal with the analysis of subjective ideas and propositions; 1 §§367-368 with
Bolzano characterises his work in Book four as follows: the recognition of logical properties and relations such as analyticity, de-
ducibility, and equivalence. §352 tells us how to determine whether or not a
I in no way believe myself able to point out procedures to be fol- given idea has an object. Especially interesting here are Bolzano's extremely
lowed in reflection which have not been long observed by every liberal views on non-actual (or abstract) objects. Determining the causes of
competent thinker, nor do I promise anything novel. Rather, I given kinds of effects is the subject of several lengthy paragraphs (§§379 ff.).
have striven to set out in clear terms the various rules and pro- Here, we find a workmanlike presentation of techniques probably best known
cedures that talented thinkers have followed, for the most part as Mill's methods. 2 Finally, several sections are devoted to the problems of
without being aware of doing so. And although I do not flatter determining the judgements of others and interpreting signs (§§385 ff.), a
myself with the hope that I have been completely successful in subject to which we shall return.
this, I nevertheless believe that the little one finds here will not be Book four continues some of the epistemological discussions of Book
unwelcome to many, and shall find its application in the sequel. 2 three. Bolzano pushes back against the somewhat exaggerated individualism
of much early modern epistemology, repeatedly stressing the importance of
The main features of his method are set out in the first part (§§325-348).
consulting the judgements of others in inquiry. How we should do this is dis-
We are to begin by attempting to become as clear as possible concerning the
cussed in §331. By and large, he says, we will do well to attempt to solve the
aim of our reflection, what it is exactly that we are attempting to discover
problem ourselves before considering the opinions of others. If, after reach-
(§325). At this point, it is worth asking whether we can tell without a great
ing a conclusion on our own, we find that other people, known to be credible
deal of trouble whether the problem is beyond our capacities (§326). We
from other cases, agree with us, this will rightly strengthen our conviction.
then see if the problem before us might be reduced to several other, simpler
If we find dissenting views held by credible people, this should reduce our
ones and, if so, we work on these (§327). Here, a variety of methods may
1G. 1See also Bolzano's treatment in "On the Mathematical Method," §§ 10-11; pp. 59-68 in
Polya, How to Solve it (New York: Doubleday, 1957); Mathematics and Plausible
Reasoning, 2 Vols. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954), among others. On the Mathematical Method and Correspondence with Exner (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2004).
2 §322 [III.295]. 2
John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic, 2 Vols. (London, 1843), Book III, Chapter viii.

xx viii xxix
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

confidence in our judgement. "Here we should set ourselves the law never a statement of his view on the pronouncements of common sense already in
to assume that someone is wrong unless we know how to explain (or at least Heraclitus. The social character of inquiry is clear throughout, something that
have tried to explain) how the error might have arisen, or unless we have is especially striking in view of the fact that the topic of Book four is solitary
found that it would be far more improbable to say that it is not he who is in reflection.
error but those opposed to him." 1 He gives the following example: Cartesian skepticism is discussed at some length in §332. Here, Bolzano
Suppose that we have just calculated that the ratio of the diam- maintains that because judgement is not voluntary, doubt cannot be either.
eter of a circle to its circumference is 1 : 3 .14 l. ... We then In addition, there are some truths it would be highly unwise to doubt even
learn from a variety of books that others have sought this ratio in if we could. Descartes should rather have said (and perhaps meant) that we
the most diverse ways, and attained the same result, but that the ought to examine our previously formed judgements-not, indeed, all of them
few who have sought it and claimed to find a different answer do (which is impossible in any case), but at most those that can be examined
not agree with each other. Moreover, the former all claim to be using premises that are deemed more reliable than they.
able to indicate the place where the latter have erred, and even §§370-376 are dedicated to proofs and their flaws. The subject was some-
some of the latter have come to agree with them. In this case, I thing of a specialty for Balzano, a pioneer of foundational research in math-
claim, we may justifiably break off our examination without first ematics who made a habit of studying all the proofs of important theorems
having learned of the grounds that the opponents have put forth he could lay his hands on. After distinguishing formal and material flaws of
in support of their differing answer. For we may know in ad- proofs, he presents several indicators of the incorrectness of proofs. The first
vance that at best (i.e., if we cannot see their incorrectness) these of these runs as follows: if the conclusion of a proof is false, there must be
grounds would not have a high enough degree of probability as something wrong with the proof. 1 In the case of universal generalisations, he
those which we have already mustered for the correctness of our notes, a single contrary instance is enough to establish their falsity. This may
calculation. We could not reject this unless events completely strike most readers today as too obvious to bother stating. Not so-rather,
out of our control were to occur, namely, until people tell us with it reflects important changes in the practice of mathematics taking place in
the same or nearly the same degree of unanimity that the previ- the early nineteenth century, to which Bolzano contributed materially. In the
ous calculation was false, and explain at the same time how it eighteenth century, especially in the fields of algebra and infinitesimal analy-
could have come about that so many made the same mistake. 2 sis, the predominant mathematical culture was closer to that of engineering.
Procedures that did not work in absolutely every case were still taught and
A special case occurs when we encounter what Bolzano calls pronounce- accepted if they worked in many and especially the most important ones.
ments of common sense. He describes these as judgements concerning mat- Proofs would be offered for such theorems, while at the same time all in-
ters that all people are in a position competently to decide (not requiring spe- volved recognised that there were "exceptions" to the "generally valid" the-
cialised knowledge, equipment, or experiments, etc.), where the conclusion orem. Lagrange's entire approach to the calculus, as set out in his Theorie
reached does not "flatter our inclinations but rather places limits on them," des fonctions analytiques and Ler;ons sur le ca/cul des fonctions, for exam-
and where unanimity or near-unanimity reigns. In such cases, he argues, we ple, was based upon an assumption he knew full well to be false, namely, that
may feel a degree of confidence approaching certainty in our judgements. every function is representable as a power series (i.e., the Taylor series for the
This criterion is applied especially in the case of moral and religious judge- function):
ments.3
Bolzano's remarks here are reminiscent of Aristotle's observations on the f"(a) f(n) (a)
f(a+h) = f(a) +hf'(a) +h2 - - + ... +h11 + ...
opinions of the many and the opinions of the wise (b8o~u)-he himself finds 2! n!
1§331, no. 2 [III.335-6]. Around Bolzano's time, a number of mathematicians started looking at
2 §332, note [III.343.4]. things in a different way. Exceptions that were thought not to vitiate the
3 §331, no. 4; ef. Bolzano's Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft (Sulzbach, 1834; new ed.
by J. Louzil in BBGA, Series 1, Vols. 6-8), I, § 14, no. 7. 1
§373.

xxx xx xi
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

general validity of a theorem started to be looked upon as counterexamples Again, however, he had many good mathematical examples that he did
that did. 1 Looking for and constructing counterexamples thus became a stan- not mention. One of these was discussed in his 1816 paper on the bino-
dard part of mathematical research, important in foundational work but also mial series. In the works of eighteenth-century mathematicians, infinite se-
elsewhere. In his mathematical writings, Balzano showed himself to be a ries were subjected to a variety of transformations which often enough led
master of this art, using it to refine his definitions and arrive at more precise to important discoveries, Newton's general binomial series prominent among
statements of theorems. Among other things, he constructed functions that them. At same time, an attentive consideration of the proofs offered for this
are everywhere discontinuous or continuous at exactly one point, continuous and related theorems often revealed that all the steps were framed in such a
functions that oscillate infinitely often in a finite interval, functions that are way as to cover all values of the variable. Equations such as:
not monotone in any neighbourhood of a given point, or on any subinterval
l
of a given interval, and even a continuous, nowhere differentiable function -- = 1+x+x2 +x3 +x4 + · · ·
(perhaps the first fractal in the history of mathematics). 2 All of these coun- 1-x
terexamples showed widely held beliefs to be false, and any proofs offered for for example, were derived without any mention of conditions required for
them were at the same time revealed as inevitably flawed. Tracing the faults exact, numerical equality. Thus, alongside equations such as:
in these often quite convincing proofs became a means for making important
discoveries that could be applied not just to restate the given "theorem" and 1 1 1 1
- - =2= 1+-+-+-+···
give it a proper proof, but in other contexts as well. 1-~ 2 4 8
The second criterion is a traditional one: a proof that proves too much
proves nothing. 3 Bolzano's example in the The01y of Science is drawn from the proof would apparently also license us to conclude:
religion: l 1
An example where this indicator of untenability is easily per- --- = - = 1-10+ 100-1000+ ...
(-10) 11
ceived is the well-known proof whereby the opponents of Chris-
tian revelation wish to show that mankind has no need of this a claim before which, as Bolzano remarked, "sound human understanding
revelation, because if we did, it would already have to be uni- shrinks in horror." 1 Clearly, he thought, something had gone badly wrong-
versally known. In order to show that this inference is incorrect, the proof proves too much.
we need only inquire whether there is any knowledge that no one A third indicator follows: if a certain condition occurs in the statement
would deny to be necessary for the human race, and yet which is, of the theorem and this condition is essential in the sense that removing it
like Christianity, not universally acknowledged. The example of would result in a false proposition, the proof must appeal to this condition
natural religion occurs to us immediately, since its necessity for at some point; if it does not, something must be wrong. 2 Balzano spots this
mankind is acknowledged in precisely the same sense that the flaw in Euclid's proof of Elements, I, 22. This theorem states that, given three
necessity of revelation is claimed, even though natural religion straight lines A, B, C, any two of which are together longer than the third,
is only found in the appropriate purity and completeness in a few it is possible to construct a triangle with sides whose lengths equal those
people. Thus we see that the above proof for the dispensability of A,B,C. Euclid carefully notes that the stated condition is indispensable.
of revelation must be flawed, since, if it were correct, we could Yet, Balzano observes, he doesn't use it anywhere in his proof, which must
claim the dispensability of natural religion on equal grounds. 4 accordingly be flawed.
1
Cf. H. K. S0rensen, "Exceptions and counterexamples. Understanding Abel's comment In this case, as in many others, we see that the third indicator is inti-
on Cauchy's Theorem." Historia Mathematica 32 (2005) 453-480. mately related to the second-for Euclid's proof of I, 22 should apply to any
2 Cf. Bolzano's F11nctionenlehre (BBGA, Series 2A, Vol. 10/1); Eng. tr. by S. B. Russ in
three lines, and thus proves too much. Conversely, the flawed nature of many
The Mathematical Works of Bernard Balzano (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
3 §374. 1 Der binomische Lehrsat;:, (Prague, 1816), Preface.
4 2 §375.
§374 [III.474].

xx xii xx xiii
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

proofs of theorems about power series could also be detected by noting that of meanings: original and derivative, determinate and indeterminate, proper
they made no use of an essential condition on the variable x. In the example and improper, tropical (symbolic, figurative, metaphorical), etc.
mentioned above, for instance, the equation: In the most straightforward case, communication is conceived as a matter
of encoding and decoding, a speaker with certain thoughts producing signs
_I_I_= 1 +x+x2 +x3 +x4 + ... intended to be perceived by another, who then interprets them, with the result
x that certain thoughts arise in his mind. If the communication is successful
(the signs are understood), then speaker and listener have, if not identical, at
is only valid if the absolute value of x is less than one, and a correct proof
least equal ideas, in the sense that their respective subjective ideas correspond
must make use of this condition somewhere.
to the same ideas in themselves. Ideas containing intuitions, however, pose a
A final indicator involves appeals to empirical findings. 1 If a given ques-
difficulty for this conception, since they are both unrepeatable and incommu-
tion is of the sort that experience cannot decide (in line with prevailing us-
nicable. Bolzano addresses this point later, in Volume four:
age, Balzano calls these transcendental), a proof that makes essential use of
empirical premises must be flawed. On the other hand, a priori proofs for [I]t is certainly well-founded to say that a single empirical truth
propositions that can only be decided by experience must also contain some grasped by one person can never be completely grasped by a
mistake. Propositions of the first sort include the claims that substances are second person, nor indeed by the same person at another time.
eternal and that some of our actions are free in the sense that they have no Strictly speaking, it is no longer the same proposition that I put
determining cause; 2 the homeopathic principle is an example of the second forward when I now say that Alexander was born roughly 2190
kind of proposition. 3 years ago (before this instant) as when I said this an hour ago.
Volume three also contains a wealth of material on what would today For the intuition of that which I presently feel or think that lies
be called philosophy of language. In §285 of Book three, Balzano had in- in the words "before this instant" is now different from that of an
troduced the concept of a sign, which he defines as an object that is wont hour ago. Similarly for the propositions "Sirius is a fixed star,"
to stimulate a ce1tain idea (i.e., an idea of the sign) that is associated with inasmuch as the intuitions found in the idea "Sirius" are different
another idea (the signification [Bedeutung] of the sign). for every man. But these differences will be seen not to matter
here, and so can be disregarded. To say that we have commu-
nicated the truths contained in these propositions to the reader,
Sign it suffices that he form ideas that, if not composed of the same
intuitions as ours, are nevertheless equivalent to them, i.e., that
he thinks of the same object (the same subject), and attributes
stimulates signifies
the same property (the same predicate) to it that we do. Thus
in the first example it will be sufficient if our reader connects an
Idea awakens via Signified idea with the word "Alexander" that in fact refers only to this
of Idea
Sign --as-so-c-ia-tio_n_ _., Macedonian king, and learns that this man was born 2190 years
before the year this was written. Thus understood, there can be
no doubt that empirical truths can also be communicated .... 1
Towards the end of Book four, Balzano returns to the subject of interpre-
At that point, he defined a number of concepts (e.g., understanding or misun-
tation. This he defines as follows:
derstanding a sign, interpreting given signs), and distinguished several kinds
By inte1pretation I mean nothing other than an indication of the
1 §376.
ideas which someone intended to stimulate by producing certain
2 §369
3 §376. 1
§410, note [IV. 48-49).

xx xiv xx xv
Introduction to Volume Three Introduction to Volume Three

signs (§285); and the word "indicate" means either the produc- himself holds it to be true, is usually called test(fying in favour
tion of these ideas in one's own consciousness, or the production of this proposition. 1
of certain other signs which are better known than the given ones
or belong to a different system of signs, and at the same time As Carsten Gieske pointed out, Bolzano's conception bears more than a pass-
serve to stimulate the same ideas which the original producer of ing resemblance to Grice's much better known analysis of non-natural mean-
the former signs had intended. 1 ing.2 The notion is important for the purposes of Volume three because the
te;timony of others is the source of a significant proportion of our beliefs.
Thus translation or paraphrase counts as interpretation alongside decoding. Most of the ideas Bolzano presents here were originally worked out in
It is not the business of interpretation, he adds, to determine which ideas his Treatise of the Science of Religion. 3 There, he was concerned to clarify
the speaker had in mind, but rather which ideas he intended to produce in what might be meant by saying that that God communicates with someone, in
the minds of his listeners. We interpret a liar correctly, for example, when particular, when, if ever, it makes sense to speak of a divine revelation. Some
we determine which thoughts he meant us to form, even when he himself of this highly interesting material is touched upon towards the end of Volume
harbours quite different ones. three. 4 One point especially seems worthy of note here. If God is supposed
Bolzano presents a number of techniques of interpretation, and points out to be an absolutely perfect being, then all of His actions will of necessity
a number of variations on the theme of straightforward communication: the conform to the highest moral law, i.e., will promote the well-being of all His
speaker may intend to convey multiple meanings with given signs (as with creatures as much as possible. This also applies to any cases of supposed di-
a double entendre or when someone wants different parts of his audience vine communication. In particular, if God testifies to X, i.e., produces events
to understand him differently), he may be deliberately obscure or, still worse, with the intention that we, if we follow our best insight, will gather from
not really attempting to speak but rather merely trying to appear like someone observing them that it is God's will that we accept X, the consequences of
who does. 2 accepting this belief must be good. It follows immediately that if believing
So far, this is mostly standard fare. But something quite new and un- in a proposition produces demonstrably harmful consequences then it cannot
expected turns up when Bolzano comes to speak of what he calls testify- be divinely revealed. Someone cannot, for example, justifiably claim that he
ing. Roughly speaking, to testify in his sense is to attempt to communicate. 3 may hate his neighbour because "permission to do this had been granted by a
Somewhat more precisely, it is to perform actions with the intention of caus- special divine revelation." This has things backwards. "For in order to prove
ing someone else to form certain beliefs. He offers the following definition: the latter, we would have to prove the former, that hating one's neighbour is
permissible, and indeed morally good." 5 In a sermon from 1817, Bolzano
An act which someone performs with precisely the intention that had further developed this point:
we, if we follow our best insight, will conclude from perceiving
it that it is his will that we accept the proposition M, because he Only if we can recognise in advance that accepting and following
1§387
a teaching will bring benefit to ourselves and others can we look
[III.543).
2 upon it as something revealed by God. Thus we misinterpret di-
In these less polite days, the last case is sometimes called bullshitting. Balzano found it
increasingly common in the German philosophical literature of his time. vine revelation, we extend its teachings farther than is justified,
3 we falsely stamp with the seal of divine testimony opinions of
In modern English, the word 'testify' is clearly not an ideal choice for the concept Bal-
zano is interested in-perhaps 'assure' would be a better fit with his intentions. The word he
uses, bezeugen, is just as unsuitable in modern German. Adelung (Grammatisch-kritisches 1§306, no. 15 [III.203]; cf. §388.
Worterbuch der hochdeutschen Mundart (Vienna, 1808), Art. "Bezeugen"), however, records 2 C. Gieske, "Bolzano's notion of testifying," Grazer philosophische Studien 53 (1997)
a variety of archaic uses of this word that are much closer to Bolzano's meaning; the majority 249-266.
of his citations are from the Luther Bible. In the King James version, too, 'testify' is used 3
Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft, 4 Vols. (Sulzbach: Seidel, 1834; new ed. by J. Lol!Zil
occasionally in something like Bolzano's sense. As noted below, Balzano originally thought in BBGA, Series I, Vols. 6/1-8/3). See, especially, I, §§28ff, 135 ff.
about these matters in the course of his theological work. In this respect, his selection of 4
See especially §§386-388.
'bezeugen' is not surprising. 5
§371, no. 1 [III.464].

xx xvi xxxvn
Introduction to Volume Three

our own invention, as soon as we allow ourselves to deduce con-


sequences from revealed doctrine when it cannot be shown on
purely rational grounds that adopting and following them would
be beneficial. Nothing which cannot be shown to be good and
generally beneficial without the teachings of religion should be
claimed to be true on its behalf. 1
Dr. B. Bolzano's
Detailed critical and historical remarks constantly accompany Bolzano's
presentation of his own views in Volume three. Among other things, he dis-
cusses innate ideas, traditional empiricism, Molyneux's problem, the Carte-
sian method of doubt, and the alleged limits of our knowledge. Berkeley and
THEORY OF SCIENCE
Tetens are discussed at some length, as are the ideologues (mainly Destutt
de Tracy) and Herbart. Two extensive sections are devoted entirely to Kant, Attempt at a
and cover considerable parts of his system. 2 Along with his remarks else-
where in the The01y of Science, these constitute one of the most thorough and Detailed and in the main Novel Exposition
well-grounded responses to the Critical Philosophy ever written. 3
of

LOGIC
With Constant Attention to Earlier Authors

Edited

by

Several of his friends

Volume 3
1"Von den MiBbrauchen der Religion," Erbauungsreden, Vol. 3 (Prague and Vienna, 185 l ),
no. xiii, p. I I 1-112.
2 §§305, 315. Sulzbach
3 Bolzano's student Pffhonsky later collected these remarks, adding additional explanations
J. E. v. Seidel Publishing
as he saw fit, to produce his book Neuer Anti-Kant; ode1; Priifimg der Kritik der reinen Ver-
nunft nach den in Bolzano's Wissenschaftslehre niedergelegten Begrijfen (Bautzen, 1850); new 1837
edition by E. Morscher and Ch. Thiel in Franz Pffhonsky, Neuer Anti-Kant und Atomenlehre
des seligen Bolzano (St. Augustin: Academia, 2003).

xxxviii
Book Three:

THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

§.269.*

Purpose, contents, and divisions of this book

In §15, I already noted the twofold aim which I think makes it necessary
for a treatise of logic to say something about the conditions underlying
Sed nil dulcius est, bene quam munita tenere
the knowledge of truths, especially for us humans. Only as much as is
Edita doctrina sapientum temp/a serena:
required for this purpose shall be dealt with here, thus only enough to
Despicere unde queas alios, passimque videre
allow us to see the correctness of the rules that shall be set out in the
Errare, atque viam palantis quaerere vitae,
following parts concerning the discovery of individual truths through the
Certan: ingenio, contender-e nobilitate,
process of reflection, the division of these truths in special sciences, and
Noctes atque dies niti, praestante labore
the appropriate written presentation of them. But as every cognition is a
Ad summas emergere opes, rerumque potiri.
judgement, and every judgement in turn consists of ideas, I shall first have
LUCRETIUS, de natura rerum, II, v. 7-15. 1
to speak of ideas (namely, subjective ideas), then of judgements. Since,
in addition, only true judgements merit the name of cognitions, I shall
have to take into consideration the relation our judgements have to the
truth, inquire into the sources of errnr, and into the limits of our cognitive
faculties. Since, finally, the question of r-eliability arises for all our judge- 4
ments, and hence also for those we present in scientific expositions, I
shall say a few words about this matter. Accordingly, the doctrines of this
book are divided into four chapters, the first dealing with our ideas, the
second with our judgements, the third with the relations of our judgement
But nothing sweeter is than this: to dwell
to truth, and the fourth, finally, with the confidence of our judgements. I
In quiet halls and lofty sanctuaries must apologise for the title "theory of knowledge" just as I did previously
Well fortified by doctrines of the wise, for the title "theory of fundamentals". On this subject, the observations
And look thence down on others wandering made in § 17 could be repeated here. 5
And seeking all astray the path of life
The clash of intellects, the fight for honours,
The lust for wealth, the efforts night and day
With toil and sweat to scale the heights of power.

A new verse translation by Sir Ronald Melville (Oxford: Clarendon Press,


1997), p. 36.
Of Ideas

PART I HEGEL Jays out about concepts in general in 32 pages of the 3rd volume
. h .. Logic and try to make sense of it! I would rather make good here
0 f IS f
Of Ideas '
the promise I made in §52, no. 11 concerning HE.RBART's defirntlon o
. .

ideas. This definition is based upon two assumptions, namely, th~t ev-
§.270.*
ery simple substance can have only one single quality, ~nd th.at no ~nnple
The concept of an idea in the subjective sense being may undergo change. I have already spoken of .the first assump-
When attempting to reach an understanding concerning the concept of an tion in the note to §64. Concerning the second, many philosophers before
HERBART strove to find an inner contradiction in the concept of change.
idea in itself in §48, I already found it necessary to present the concept of
an idea in the subjective sense at the same time. There I explained what For example, they claimed to find a contradiction in the claim that the
I meant by the expressions: a subjective or thought idea, or an idea that altered thing "must be the same but not the same after the change." But
one has. Hence after all that has been said there it will scarcely be neces- does one really say this when one says that a thing A changes? In my
0 inion, the propositions expressed in such cases really run as foll.ows: 7
sary to recall that I by no means use the word idea in the narrower sense
according to which the object of an idea must always be absent, or even "~ at time t has the attribute b" and "A at time (t + 8) has the attribute
constituted more or less differently than the idea portrays it. In this sense, non-b." There is no contradiction between these propositions, since the
we might say "My brother, who stands before me, I see, but my sister, subject-ideas "A at time t" and "A at time (t + 8) are dif~erent .<§ 183).
who is elsewhere, I can only represent in an idea [vorstellen]"; or "It is They also say "what a changeable thing is cannot be deterr:imed eithe~, by
not just your imagination [Vorstellung], I actually .... " As necessary as the attribute that it has before the change nor by the one it has after. It
seems to me that one must distinguish different senses of the term "what"
it may be in many respects to distinguish ideas of this kind, those to which
either no object at all or else no present object coITesponds, from the oth- here. In one sense, it applies to any attribute that belongs to a thing at
ers which have such an object and which arise in our minds through the a given time. In this sense, both b and non-b can b.e said to b~ what ~he
activity of these objects, the aims of logic require that we take the word thing is. In another sense, what a thing is, or what its essence is, apph~s
idea in the wider sense which includes both of these kinds and in general only to attributes which belong to it at all times. In this sense, what ~ is
6 everything that can occur as a constituent in a judgement, without itself
is neither b nor non-b, but rather a, that is, the abstractum coffespondmg
forming a complete judgement. Just as in the earlier paii the qualification to the concretum A (§60). When they now say that "when the what disap-
"in itself" was not always added to the word "idea'', though we always pears, the being disappears as well," I counter that this only hol.ds ':hen
meant ideas in themselves, so too here I shall try always to use the word "what" means the essence, but this does not change when the thmg is al-
"idea" to think of subjective ideas, i.e., the grasping or appearance of tered. If one objects that every change requires us to think of an infinite
what I above called an idea in itself by and in the mind of a thinking sequence of conditions that have already passed, I say that this. thought
being. I mention in passing that the capacity of our souls to produce sub- contains nothing contradictory, provided that one abandons the mcoffect
jective ideas under certain circumstances is called its cognitive faculty or concept of an infinite multitude as one that can never be increased (§87).
cognitive power. If people find it absurd that "there are infinite sequences of causes, none
of which acts of itself, but which would only act if triggered," I say that
Note 1. The confusion in the use of idea and other related words such
as intuition and concept reached its pinnacle when it occurred to someone we need not think of causes that would act, but rather only such as do
to ascribe a ceitain movement to ideas, and to speak of ideas being trans- in fact act since the circumstances under which they can act are actu-
formed into their opposites. It would be a futile waste of time to attempt ally prese~t. If one thinks that "any interposition of so~1ething ~~tive in
to enter into a discussion of the concepts people connect with these ways something passive" is already nonsensical "because neither .act1.v1ty ~or
of speaking since, given the custom of our time never to define anything passivity can be thought of as the proper quality of that wh1c~ 1~ active
precisely, it is all but impossible to form a distinct notion of something or passive," I counter that it already lies in the concept of a fimte sub-
whose inventor never himself thought clearly. Read, for example, what stance that it is endowed with powers through which it can act to change

2 3
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 271. Of Ideas

others, and be changed in turn by their reaction-accordingly, one cannot idea I mean exactly the same thing as I do by the object of an objective
say that activity and passivity are not proper qualities of these substances. idea, namely, that which is represented through this idea. There are, as
8 Thus I find no tenable reason for the claim that the concept of change one knows, such objects for many, though not for all ideas (§66), and the
(properly understood) contains a contradiction. But even if this were the object of a subjective idea is always the same as the object of the cor-
case, I still would not understand how people could say that ideas are the responding objective idea. A subjective idea, however, can never lack a
only things which genuinely occur-for if there is no genuine change, matter, while an objective idea has no matter-rather it is the matter of
nothing genuinely occurs. And how can one speak of disturbances which the former. Thus the subjective idea of a round square indeed has a mat-
would happen, if it is impossible for one object to act upon and disturb an- ter, namely, the objective idea of a round square; yet there is no object
other? Here too, therefore, I must admit that I fear I have misunderstood to which either of these ideas (the subjective or the objective) applies.
HERBART. Still less should one confuse the matter of a subjective idea with its parts,
Note 2. When I use the words faculty and power as equivalent, this is which are other ideas.
not because I am unaware of the distinction between the two, but rather Note. Because the distinction between subjective and objective ideas
because that distinction is not worth bringing up here. For everything has only rarely been touched upon, the need for a term to designate the
that we call a power of a finite being is not the complete, but only the concept I here call matter was not felt. I concede in advance that the term
partial cause of what we call its effect, and hence the latter is not pro- is not really suitable, and only wish someone could find a better one. For lO
duced by the former alone, but only in the proper conditions. Concerning matter [Stoff] actually means the same as material [Materie] and content.
Professor HERBART's abhorrence of the terms powers of representation, But I have already used the latter to designate a quite different concept,
judgement, recall, etc., I admit that it is mistaken to believe that the mere and it is to be feared that the first expression will tend to make people
introduction of these terms provides an explanation of how ideas, judge- think of what they usually think by the last.
ments, memories, etc., arise. Yet these terms are not to be discarded for
this reason alone. §.272.*
§.271.* Every subjective idea is something actual, but only
For eve1y subjective idea there is a corresponding idea in itself in that it is a kind of property of a being

We must now consider several attributes which all subjective ideas have I) A second attribute that belongs to all subjective ideas is that they are
in common. One of the first is that for each such idea there is a corre- something actual, i.e., that they may make claim to existence at a deter-
sponding idea in itself, the former being the manifestation [Erscheinung] minate time in the mind of a determinate being. It indeed seems that this
of the latter. This was already contained in the concept of a subjective is occasionally denied, when people say "that such and such is not real,
idea we indicated above. It is also clear from the following considera- but only an idea." Closer consideration reveals, however, that such ex-
9 tions. If a certain subjective idea A is to be actually present in the mind pressions mean to say only that no outer object corresponds to the idea in
of a thinking being, then the proposition 'This being has the idea A" is a actuality. One does not intend to say that the idea itself is not the kind of
truth and, indeed, even if there is no one who thinks this truth, i.e., it is a thing that is actual. Rather, one here makes a kind of opposition between
truth in itself. So too the constituents of this proposition are just so many the mere idea and something actual only insofar as the idea is said not to
ideas in themselves. But it is obvious that the idea A must itself occur be the actual thing which would be its object (if it had one).
in this proposition-not the subjective idea, but rather the corresponding 2) To me at least it seems obvious that every subjective idea merits the
objective one. One may, as I have already done in §48 and elsewhere, name of an actual thing-but one which belongs to the species of actual
call the objective idea the matter of the subjective idea to which it corre- things which occur only as attributes* in some other actual thing, which
sponds (i.e., the appearance of the former in the mind), but one should not
*Where the word is taken in such a broad sense that even states which pass by very
confuse this matter either with the object the idea may apply to, nor with quickly are said to be attributes-namely, of the beings in which they occur during that
the parts of which the idea is composed. By the object of a subjective time.

4 5
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 273. Of Ideas

we accordingly do not call substances, but rather adherences. For there 1) Given that I say that a subjective idea is nothing other than the
ll can be no subjective ideas if there are no beings which have them, and appearance of an objective idea in the mind of a thinking being, it is ob-
they exist only as phenomena in the minds of these beings. Thus we may viously determined that we must assume that there are at least as many
well call them a kind of attribute found in such beings. But we cannot call subjective ideas as there are objective ideas which thus appear, and also
them substances, i.e., something that subsists (as one says) by itself (i.e., as many subjective ideas as there are beings in which they occur. I must
not in something else). This seems to me to be true quite generally, so that certainly distinguish the subjective idea I have of this tree from the sub-
I would even like to see it applied to the ideas that Goel has. Thus I can jective idea I have (perhaps at the same time) of the song of this lark, for I
in no way agree with those who ascribe a kind of substantiality to God's certainly look upon the objective ideas of these two objects as distinct. It
ideas, in that they claim that the substances of the universe are nothing is equally obvious that we must look upon the idea that I have of this tree,
other than these divine ideas. In my view, the world owes its existence not and the idea my companion has of this object, not as one single idea, but
to God's power of representation, but rather to his power of creation. His rather as two different ones, regardless of any agreement there might be
powers of representation encompass far more than the things which are between them. But because every subjective idea must be actual at some
actual, including the merely possible things whose elevation to existence determinate time, it may well be asked whether one should assume that
would be contrary to his purposes, and even the impossible. But it is only there are as many subjective ideas in me as there are moments at which
these ideas, and not their objects, which have actuality merely through it may be said that something appears in me? Obviously, it would be in- 13
His ideation. appropriate to assume that there are many subjective ideas in cases where
3) Since we distinguish two kinds of attributes, the inner and the outer, one and the same objective idea appears in the mind of a thinking being
or properties and relations (§80), it may be asked to which of these two throughout an entire finite interval of time (thus at infinitely many distinct
kinds the ideas of a being belong. I believe they belong to the inner instants), always in exactly the same way, and in the same combinations.
attributes, for what can be more internal to a being than its ideas? It In a being whose inner attributes cannot change in the slightest, as is the
sounds odd, I admit, to say that the ideas that a being has are attributes, case with God, we will recognise only as many subjective ideas as there
and indeed properties of this being, but this is the case because ordinary are objective ideas [corresponding to them]. Things are different with us
usage connects a certain associated concept with these words, which we humans, who are so changeable that we never remain in the same state
have omitted in order to produce a wider concept better suited to the needs for the smallest time. Even an idea which appears in our mind does not
of science. In ordinary speech, not everything that an object has at one remain completely unaltered for any period of time. It is clear from this
moment or another is called an attribute or a pmperty of the thing, but that it would not be appropriate to assume that there are as many subjec-
rather only that which it retains for a longer stretch of time and is more tive ideas in us as there are times or instants of which it may be said that
12 or less enduring. Since ideas are usually of short duration, and can be we then have one and the same idea albeit in different ways. It is best to
displaced by others, it is understandable that people have not called them look upon the time during which one and the same objective idea appears
attributes or properties. ·without interruption (even if it appears in different ways), as the dura-
tion of one single subjective idea; and only to speak of several subjective
§.273. ideas when either the same objective idea occurs in the same mind, but
with interruptions, when it appears in the minds of different beings, or
What the author means by a single subjective idea, and by when the objective ideas which constitute their matter are different.
saying that several subjective ideas are equal or unequal 2) Once we agree when to consider certain ideas numerically distinct,
there still remains the problem of when to call them equal or unequal.
The explanations we have given so far of the concept of a subjective idea
Obviously, we cannot call them equal if their matter is different. For
are not sufficient to determine what we must view as a single idea, and
since the matter to which a subjective idea c01responds, i.e., the objective 14
what as several ideas, nor when we may declare that several ideas are
idea which makes its appearance, is certainly the most important thing,
equal or unequal.

6 7
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 274. Of Ideas

no one would want to call a pair of subjective ideas equal if they belonged only finitely long, both must certainly admit that we have several ideas
to different objective ideas, no matter how similar they might be in other at the same time. For the former must claim this for all of our ideas,
respects. Thus when I speak of equal ideas in the future, the reader should while the latter can hardly deny, for instance, that whenever we form
think at the very least that these are ideas belonging to the same objective a judgement A has b, the idea b does not only enter the mind after A
idea. Circumstances may also arise where this equality is extended to has already disappeared, for then we obviously could not perceive the
cover some other attributes as well-which ones will be sufficiently clear relation which holds between them.* But if there are simultaneous ideas
from the context. Occasionally I shall permit myself the use of a common in general, one may also ask whether among them there be any of those
expression and say of two equal ideas appearing in the same being at dif- we called mutually equal in the previous section, i.e., those containing 16
ferent times that they are a single idea-to say, for instance, that someone the same objective idea. It is undeniable that one and the same objective
now has once again an idea he had before. By this I shall mean only that idea can appear repeatedly in many propositions. For example, in the
he now has an idea which is equal to one he had before, i.e., belongs to proposition "Every equilateral triangle is also equiangular", the concept
the same objective idea. of equality as well as that of angle occurs twice. Thus one might think
Note. It seems to me that the way I have applied the concepts of that if someone is to form this judgement, the ideas of equality and of
identity and equality to subjective ideas agrees completely with what has an angle must be present twice, once in the subject-idea, and once in the
been done elsewhere, even though people do not usually go into such de- predicative part of this judgement. After closer consideration, however, it
tail. When we read that there are no equal ideas at all, this is said not seems more probable that only a single subjective idea occurs here, rather
of subjective, but rather of objective ideas. But no one has ever denied than two equal ones. For why should we suppose there are many, when
that ideas in the subjective sense can be equal to one another, and indeed we may reasonably suppose that the work to be performed by a subjective
are so when one and the same object is thought of by several people by idea (like angle in the above example) can be carried out by a single idea
means of the same characteristics, or repeatedly by the same person at acting in several relations, in much the same way that one and the same
disconnected times. By contrast, when someone represents the same ob- point may belong to several intersecting lines?
ject throughout an uninterrupted interval of time, one usually says that he
has only a single idea, even in cases where the way in which this idea §.275.*
occurs does not remain the same (e.g., its clarity or vividness is altered).
Strength or vividness of subjective ideas
15 Even in such cases, I say, people speak of only one idea, which has un-
dergone various changes during the time it endured-it may, for instance, Since every subjective idea is, as such, something actual, and everything
have been obscure at first, and later become clear. actual acts, we may likewise attribute a kind of activity to all of our sub-
jective ideas. The nature of this activity will depend upon various cir-
§.274.
cumstances. Much, for example, will depend upon the constitution of its
matter, i.e., the constitution of the objective idea whose appearance in the
Can several equal ideas exist in a being at the same time?
mind of a thinking being is the subjective idea. Understandably, the idea
In the previous section I supposed that there are equal ideas in one and the of a flower-bed must have different effects upon us than that of a snake
same being, but I assumed this to be the case where these ideas appear in popping out of the flower-bed. Much, too, will depend on the nature of 17
the mind of the being at separate times. Thus it was tacitly assumed that the other ideas found in our soul alongside this one, and on the judge-
there are ideas which only endure for a limited time in finite beings. This ments we form concerning the objects which stand under these ideas, i.e.,
assumption might be questioned, and since I shall only later adduce the on our beliefs. Thus the sight of a snake will bring about quite different
reasons that show it to be correct, the reader may until that time accept effects in us depending upon whether we take it to be harmful or not, etc.
the above claims only conditionally. But even if someone ascribes an *It is well known that J. G. FICHTE denies this, and CHR. WEIB (Unto: iiber d. Seele,
infinite duration to all ideas while another thinks that some or all last p. 18) believes that it contradicts the simplicity of the soul.

8 9
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 275. Of Ideas

But because subjective ideas are quite different from the objective ideas it in memory are stirred up at the same time." The ideas which are con-
which constitute their matter (for the former are the appearance of the nected with a certain idea in memory, and thus stirred up at the same
latter), the subjective ideas must have some inner attribute by virtue of time as it, do not for this very reason belong to the idea itself, and can-
which two ideas with the same matter, accompanied by the same ideas, not therefore determine its degree of vividness, which is one of its inner
nevertheless produce different effects. I will call the strength or vividness attributes.
of a subjective idea that which, apart from the matter and the various other
ideas accompanying it, determines its activity. An idea which is stronger §.276.*
than another will have a greater effect, even if they have the same mat- Classification of subjective ideas based upon the
ter and are accompanied by the same ideas. If, for example, we imagine corre~1ponding class(fication of objective ideas
two men who have up to now had exactly the same ideas, and who now
acquire a new idea, which is the appearance of the same objective idea For every subjective idea there is a corresponding objective idea which is
(e.g., of a red beam of light), we may still imagine that their subjective its matter. Understandably, then, we may distinguish as many different
ideas are different, and consequently have different effects. This differ- kinds of subjective as objective ideas, and apply the same terms to the 19
ence might stem, for instance, from the different relations between the former as we did to the latter. Just as, for example, we distinguished ab-
outer object which produced these ideas and the two men. Perhaps the stract and concrete ideas in the theory of objective ideas, so too we may
object was closer to one of them, or acted upon his visual organs for a make this distinction with respect to subjective ideas, and everyone will
longer time. In any case, whenever we find that the two ideas produce gather from the name that by abstract or concrete subjective ideas we are
different effects in the minds of these men, we must conclude that there is to understand nothing other than the grasping of objective ideas which are
some inner difference between them; one must be declared stronger, the either abstract or concrete. Thus it is unnecessary to enumerate and de-
18 other weaker. fine divisions between subjective ideas which are based upon distinctions
Note. The concept to which I here give the name of strength or vivid- between objective ideas bearing the same names. I shall only adduce a
ness is in my opinion exactly the same that common usage connects with few explicitly, since it must be shown that we human beings have such
these words. But logicians have not always appropriately grasped it. Thus subjective ideas at our disposal.
ULRICH (Inst. Log. § 138, 146) considers vividness to be a kind of clarity.
Claritas duo sunt genera: distinctio et vividitas. 1 In my opinion, what I §.277.*
have here called the vividness of an idea is a completely different attribute We have simple as well as complex ideas
from clarity, which I ascribe to an idea only if we form an intuition of it
(§280). Although I admit that the vividness of an idea encourages the One of the most important distinctions for subjective as well as objective
formation of an intuition of it, and thus contributes to raising the idea to ideas is that between the simple and the complex. We must now show that
clarity, and even if I must admit that a certain degree of vividness will we are in possession of both simple and complex ideas.
always raise an idea to clarity, I must nevertheless distinguish the two, as It will not be easy for someone to deny that we are able to form com-
cause and effect. Still less can I approve of MAYER's claim (Uber den plex ideas given that we can point to so many examples of them. Who is
Vernunftschluj3, Vol. I, p. 107 ff.) that the vividness of an idea is iden- not aware, for example, that he has the idea of a rose or the concept of an
tical with its distinctness. The reasons MAYER gives prove at most that equilateral triangle? And are these ideas not indisputably complex? That
distinctness may proceed from vividness, and that both are often found we have simple ideas, however, follows in my opinion from the fact that
together. PLATNER, too, did not express himself completely correctly we have complex ones. For the latter are composed of the former, and it
when he said (Aph01: §402, note) that a concept is vivid "if many ideas cannot be said that someone has a certain complex idea in his mind if he
not belonging to its determination (and also sensations) connected with does not have all the simple parts of which it is composed. 20

1
It is a separate question whether such simple ideas are ever the only
There are two kinds of clarity: distinctness and vividness.
object occupying our mind at a given instant. This may well be doubted;

1(!) 11
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 277. Of Ideas

one might even admit that whenever our soul attempts to think a perfectly §.278.*
simple idea, e.g., the idea of something in general, other things besides
this simple idea also occur to it at the same time, e.g., the idea of the We have intuitions os well as concepts
word we usually use to designate the simple idea. This does not prevent
us from claiming, however, that there are also simple ideas in our souls, Another highly important distinction among subjective ideas is that be-
and in particular that whenever we attentively pronounce a word which tween intuitions and concepts. According to §§72 and 73 we understand
designates a simple concept, the designated concept occurs in our con- by sul~jective intuitions those subjective ideas which, although simple,
sciousness (provided we do not take the word to have a different sense). have only a single object, and by subjective concepts ideas which are nei-
For, as already remarked, if there were no simple ideas in us, how could ther intuitions, nor contain intuitions among their parts.
there be complex ones? It is clear that we have intuitions, since we quite often have ideas that
On this occasion, it may not be out of place to remark that although we look upon as the effects of a single actual entity, which is the object
the existence of simple ideas may be inferred from the existence of com- represented by it. At bottom, this object is nothing other than a certain 22
plex ideas, the existence of the latter cannot be inferred from the exis- change which occurs just then in our soul. We usually indicate [andeuten]
tence of several simple ideas, not even from their simultaneous existence. these objects with the word "this", connected with additions designating
In order to be permitted to say that someone has a certain complex idea, some of its attributes, e.g., this reel, this pleasant fragrance, etc. Such
it does not suffice that he has all the simple ideas of which it is com- complex expressions certainly betray the complexity of the idea which
posed, for he must also possess them in the appropriate combination. For then occurs in our mind. Yet closer consideration of the form of these
just as the order and connection of the simple parts matters in objective complex ideas shows that a certain unanalysable idea which we express
ideas-so much so that different objective ideas may be composed from by means of the "this" is the main part, and that this part, by itself, in
the same simple components-so too is this obviously the case with sub- fact represents the single object to which we apply it. For the fact that
jective ideas. Thus here too, in order to account for the production of a this object has the attributes indicated in the additions, e.g., that it is a
21 complex idea from given simple ones, we must suppose a special connec-
pleasant fragrance, already follows from the fact that it is precisely this
tion between them.* If one asks what the nature of this connection is, I object and not another which we represent. Thus the idea we designate
would say that it is a kind of mutual action between the ideas. If several by means of "this" is a simple idea which, for all its simplicity, has only
ideas are to be combined into one, they must engage in a particular kind a single object, and is thus precisely what we call an intuition.
of interaction. It is easier to show that we also possess concepts. For if the op-
But when this occurs, the ideas are altered, and so the question arises posite were the case, all of our ideas would have to be pure intuitions,
whether one can say that once the ideas a,b,c,d, ... have been com- a claim which refutes itself, since intuitions without concepts (e.g., the
bined into a complex idea M, one still has the simple ideas a, b, c, d, ... ? concept "and") cannot be combined into even a single composite idea.
Certainly not as isolated ideas. We will be able to say that we possess a Our soul's ability to form intuitions under certain circumstances is called
certain simple idea a in isolated form when we think it as a self-subsistent its intuitive or perceptual faculty, or sensibility; while the capacity to pro-
idea, e.g., when we form a judgement about it. The mere fact that in form- cure concepts is called understanding or the power of thought, where by
ing these thoughts or judgements other ideas are in our soul at the same "thought" one understands the forming of ideas.
time will not prevent us from claiming that we possess the idea a in iso- It is worth noting that among the many things of which our soul is
lated form-for these other ideas are not in this case combined with it to able to form ideas are several of its own ideas. The soul, I say, is able to 23
form a new idea. represent some of its own ideas, and indeed by means of ideas which are
simple and represent them uniquely, i.e., they can be intuited. This capac-
ity might be called the faculty of reflexion, provided that by reflexion one
*Just possessing the ideas "air", "ship", etc., simultaneously, for example, does not simply means intuiting, rather than other sorts of considerations bearing
mean we have the idea of an airship. on what occurs within us.

12 13
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 279. Of Ideas

§.279. among them all imaginary concepts. This, however, does not seem to
have been KANT' s view of the matter, nor is it an appropriate definition.
Sensible and supersensible ideas The concept which in recent times we have learned to connect with the
word "Idea" (mostly due to KANT's efforts), which PLATO also seems to
Each idea that appears in our mind may be looked upon as the result
have connected with this word, and which in any case merits a special des-
brought about by the activity of our soul in connection with all the sub-
ignation is, in my opinion, the following: ideas which we form, regardless
stances outside of it, including God. Now in most cases a significant
of whether or not an actual object corresponds to them, merely with the
change in a small part of the world, or in the relation of this part to us
intention of guiding our action, and producing an object which comes as
(e.g., coming appropriately close to the organs of our body), suffices to
close to it as possible, are called Ideas if abstract and ideals if concrete.
cause a change in our ideas, and in particular the production of many
Thus we call the concept of perfect beauty an Idea, and we say of Christ 25
specific intuitions. Such a part (which is always a collection of infinitely
that he realised the ideal of human perfection; we demand of the learned
many finite substances) is generally called the cause of the production of
that they aspire to and act according to ideals, etc. KANT (ibid.) claimed
these intuitions even though, strictly speaking, it is only a partial cause,
that all transcendental Ideas (of speculative reason) belong to one of three
since along with it our soul and a great many other outer factors need to
classes, in that they either have to do with the soul (the subject which is no
be present for these intuitions actually to be produced. Thus I call the
longer a predicate) or God (an unconditioned condition), or the world (an
watch in front of me the cause of the gentle ticking I hear, even though
aareuate
abb b
of the terms of a classification from which nothing is lacking).
the table, the air, and my auditory organs contribute to this phenomenon.
It is obvious that these concepts are not Ideas in the sense just defined.
Parts of the world whose nature is such that they may be causes of certain
Even when I disregard this meaning, however, I cannot glimpse a well or-
intuitions in the way just described or, more briefly, things that may be
dered whole in this constellation of three concepts: soul, God and world.
24 perceived, are called sensible. Things which cannot be the objects of a
For souls are parts of the world. It has also been shown, I believe ( § 190),
perception, by contrast, are called supersensible. Ideas of sensible objects
that the threefold classification of our judgements under the heading of
are themselves called sensible, ideas of supersensible objects, supersen-
relation (categorical, hypothetical, or disjunctive) is untenable; and these
sible. Thus the ideas: the fixed star Sirius, gold, lion, flower are sensible,
three Ideas were admittedly derived from it.
while God, holiness, immortality, etc., are supersensible.
In a broader sense we call an idea sensible if it is equivalent (in the
§.280.*
sense of§ 108) to an idea of the following form: "A sensible object, which
has the attributes a, b, c .... ,"regardless of whether it in fact has an object, Clear and obscure ideas
and indeed whether it can have an object; for example: "a winged horse".
The concept of a supersensible idea is broadened in similar fashion. An One distinction between ideas which is so striking that we often have
example is "a being which is so imperfect that it could not be more so." occasion to speak of it in ordinary life is that between clear and unclear,
Note. In the Critique of Pure Reason (A312/B368 ff.), KANT quite or obscure, ideas. Yet it can hardly be said that in ordinary life we always
rightly speaks of the concept of an Idea 1 as highly important. Accord- connect the same concepts with these words. Hence we are not only
ing to his definition, the essence of an Idea is that it is a concept that permitted, but indeed obliged, to determine their meaning here in a way
goes beyond the possibility of experience. If this only means that none of which best meets the requirements of science.
the objects standing under these concepts may be detected in experience, 1) Often the the words "clear" and "obscure" are taken in such a way
it seems to me that in addition to all the supersensible ideas, we would that the attributes they designate allow of a more or less or, what amounts
also have to give the name of Idea to all concepts which have no objects, to the same, have a quantity. We do this, for example, when we say that
1Here we can think of one thing more clearly than another, and of a third still
we use "Idea", capitalised, to translate Kant's "!dee", while "idea" is used for
"Vorste/lung", which is usually translated as "presentation" or "representation" in Kant's less clearly than the second, etc. But there is something vacillating about 26
works (tr.). this usage: whether we should call an idea clear will depend upon the

14 15
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§ . 280. Of ldeas

idea with which we compare it. This meaning will thus be of no use for the concept of a clear idea that it is constituted as it must be to enable us
the aims of science. to form the judgement that we have it, regardless of whether or not we
2) We say of many ideas that we are conscious of them; could it be form this judgement. For precisely because this judgement does not have
that the proper difference between clear and obscure ideas is connected to be formed , it seems that this need not be mentioned as one of the con-
with this? Is it reasonable to say that an idea is clear when we are con- stituents of the concept of a clear idea. It must be possible to express the
scious of it, and obscure when this is not the case? To decide this matter nature of a clear idea by using a characteristic which is found , not merely
we must first determine more precisely what we are to understand by this in some of them, but in all of them, and which not merely may be present,
consciousness, which is said to accompany every clear idea. If we judge but must be present.
of an idea that we have it, then there is no question that we have it, nor 3) In order to discover this characteristic let us see what is necessary
that we can be said to be conscious of it: if somebody says that he has a in order to form the judgement that we have a certain idea a. There is 28
certain idea how can we deny that he is conscious of it? But we cannot no occurrence, in this judgement, of the idea a itself, but only of an idea
turn this into a definition of the concept of a clear idea; we cannot require of this idea. Hence if somebody simply has an idea a, but not an idea
that for an idea to be clear, we must have formed the judgement that we of this idea, then he could not form the judgement that he has idea a.
have it; this definition would be much too narrow, and whether an idea However, it can happen, conversely, that somebody not only has a certain
should be called clear or obscure would depend upon a quite accidental idea a, but also an idea of it, without using the latter in order to form
characteristic, which has nothing to do with its inner attributes. For if we the judgement that he has a. But if it has come to the point that we not
imagine that we had a pair of ideas (perhaps at different times) so alike only have an idea a, but also an idea of it, then the only thing required
in their inner attributes that the only reason we form the judgement that for the formation of the judgement that we have a are certain changes
we have one of them but do not judge this of the other lies in different in external circumstances- no changes in a will be necessary. Could we
external circumstances, would it really be appropriate to call the former then not define a clear idea as an idea that we represent to ourselves? It is
clear and the latter obscure, given that these words certainly refer to an understood that the form of words "to represent something" is to be taken
27 inner difference? This difficulty could be avoided if we call an idea clear in the narrower sense of§ 101; hence we require for a clear idea that it be
if it has those characteristics which an idea must have to enable one to represented by an idea which applies exclusively to it. But this can still
judge that one has it, regardless of whether this actually occurs or else occur in two ways: the idea which is to become clear can be represented
external circumstances prevent it. Indeed, this seems to be what we want either by an intuition, or by some complex idea which happens to refer to
to say by the expressions "to be conscious of an idea", or "to know that it because of its particular composition. Now it seems to me that for an
we have an idea". For, if we attribute to somebody knowledge of some- idea to be clear this must occur by means of an intuition. For if I form a
thing, namely, knowledge of truth A, then we do not want to indicate that complex idea which has the property of fitting a single one of my ideas
he forms judgement A at the very moment we attribute this knowledge to not because any one of its parts does so, but only through the combination
him; rather, it is sufficient that he should have formed this judgement at of all of them, if, for example, I form the thought "of an idea which I had
some other time, and that he requires only a ce1tain external stimulation a hundred days ago at exactly the moment when the bell struck one a.m.",
in order to repeat it. Hence it is not the actual formation of judgement A, no one will say that the idea I had then is raised to clarity by means of
but only a certain capacity to form it, which we call knowledge of truth this new idea of it which I now form-when in fact I do not even need 29
A. Similarly, when we say that someone knows he has the idea a we do to know the idea in order to form this idea of it. All this leads to the
not require that he form the judgement "I have the idea a" at that very following definition: An idea is clear if we represent it to ourselves by
moment; rather, it suffices that this idea be in him in such a way that it way of an intuition. It will be called obscure whenever this is not the case.
does not depend upon the idea itself, but rather only on some other cir- 4) Someone might well object to this definition by pointing out that
cumstance, whether or not the judgement is formed. All of this may be it has the same flaw as the one discussed in no. 2. For as we ourselves
true; nevertheless, we can scarcely look upon it as a proper definition of admitted, for an idea to be clear one need not actually form the judgement

16 17
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 280. Of Ideas

that one has it; it suffices that one be in a position to form the judgement. has, it seem to me at least to correctly point to the essential difference
So too no actual intuition of the idea is required-the mere possibility between clear and obscure ideas. DESCARTES seems to have wanted to
of intuiting it is enough for us to accord it clarity. I nevertheless believe call ideas clear only if the soul directs its attention to them, and there is
that we are entitled to demand more of a clear idea than the mere pos- no doubt that this involves intuiting them. In the definition of the Ars cog-
sibility of intuiting it, namely, an actual intuiting. We do indeed usually itandi, too (Part I, ch. 9) (ldeam clarum dicere posswnus, cum vividwn,
apply the words obscure and non-obscure (or clear) to bodies not in or- ut ita dicam, sui sensum nobis imprimit. 1), the expression "vividus ideae 31
der to indicate whether or not we see them, but rather whether they have sensus" might be taken to mean a kind of intuition of an idea. LOCKE
an attribute by virtue of which they can or cannot be seen. Things stand (Ess., II, xxix, §4) gave this definition: " ... a clear idea is that whereof
otherwise with the words clear and unclear (or opaque), which, when ap- the Mind has such a full and evident perception, as it does receive from
plied to bodies, designate an attribute by virtue of which we can or cannot an outward Object operating duly on a well-disposed Organ .... " Who
see through them. From this it follows that there is no possible way to ad- can fail to sense the vagueness of these expressions? According to this
here to the customary meanings of the terms clear and obscure if we are definition, there would be no clear ideas except for those which apply to
to apply them to ideas, and indeed as contradictory opposites. If, finally, external objects, and indeed only if these objects had produced the ideas
we consider the intimate connection between an idea present in our mind through their action. Yet we nevertheless have clear ideas of objects that
and the intuiting of this idea; and reflect that, according to the law of are imperceptible, e.g., of virtue, vice, etc. The most widely acclaimed
action and reaction, when an idea is intuited something must change in definition was that which LEIBNIZ presented in the Act. erud. Lips. of
it, as indeed experience daily teaches us (e.g., that a pain becomes more 1684 (p. 537): Clara cognitio est, cum habeo, uncle rem repraesentantam
30 acute if we intuit it), the last remaining objection will disappear-Le., we cognoscere passim. 2 Similarly, in the New Essays (II, xxix, §2) we read:
may assume that the circumstance whether or not an idea is intuited by Une idee est claire, lorsqu 'elle siif.fit, pour reconnaftre la chose; et pour
us and thus, whether we ascribe clarity or obscurity to it, counts as one of la distinguer; sans cela l 'idee est obscure. 3 Essentially the same defini-
its inner attributes. tion was adopted by WOLFF (Log., §80), HOLLMANN (Log., §50, 51),
5) Finally, these definitions seem fully in accord with the aims of WYTTENBACH (L., §20), LAMBERT (N. 0., §80), REUSCH (L., § 112),
logic. First, there is no doubt that both of these concepts are objectual, SCHULZE (L., § 141), METZ (L., §86), ESSER (L., §30), BACHMANN (L.,
i.e., that there are ideas which are clear as well as ideas that are obscure in §67) among others. I do not reject their concept, but only its designation.
this sense. No proof is required for the first assertion (§278). The second First, one must recognise the ambiguity of the expression "object of an
becomes obvious as soon as one recalls that the intuition of an idea is idea''. This might be taken to mean what I call the objective idea, or the
itself an idea, from which it follows that a being all of whose ideas are matter of a subjective idea, but also what I call the object of an idea, as
clear would have to have an infinite number of them. The distinction is well as that to which a predicative idea is applied in a judgement, and fi-
not only well-founded, but also an important one. For the circumstance nally the actual, external object whose action has caused us to produce a
whether an idea is clear or obscure, i.e., whether we have produced an certain idea. The examples furnished by LEIBNIZ suffice to show that by
intuition of it or not, is certainly of importance, for as long as this has not the expressions "res repraesentata" and "la chose", he thought of some-
occurred we will seldom if ever be in a position to say something about thing completely different from the matter of the subjective ideas. But if
the idea which applies to it alone. "the object of an idea" is to be understood in my sense, I must observe
Note 1. Philosophers differ greatly among themselves on the defini- that not every clear idea has such an object, since there are objectless
tions of the concepts clear and obscure. DESCARTES, who was to my 1
We are able to speak of a clear idea when it impresses on us, as I say, a vivid sense
knowledge the first to introduce this distinction in science, gave the fol- of itself.
lowing definition (Prine. Phil., Part I, §45): Ideam clarum voco, quae 2
A cognition is clear if I have it in such a way that I can re-identify the thing
men ti attendenti praesens et aperta est. l As many flaws as the definition represented.
3
An idea is clear if it enables one to recognise the thing and to distinguish it from
1I call an idea clear that is present and open to a mind attending to it. others; otherwise, it is obscure.

18 19
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 280. Of Ideas

32 ideas that can be clearly grasped. I can, for example, form a clear idea aware that I have something very shiny before me, etc. I do not deny that
of "a man with a golden tongue" even if there is no such thing. But even ideas of this kind are frequently called obscure in ordinary life, indeed,
in cases where I have an objectual idea, e.g., of a celestial body which I myself make use of this expression when no misunderstanding is to be
has the form of a ring (the rings of Saturn), what does it mean to say that feared. Yet if one intends to speak precisely, it seems to me that one must
if this idea is clear I can distinguish its object from the objects of other express things otherwise, and only say of these ideas that they are defi-
ideas? To say that somebody can distinguish the object of a certain idea cient, and not sufficient to determine the object they stem from. It is also
from the objects of other ideas means that he is in a position to name obvious, incidentally, that this way of distinguishing between the clarity
certain attributes which hold of the one or several objects of the first idea and obscurity of ideas would depend not on the inner attributes of the
but not of the objects of the other ideas. But what happens if that idea is ideas, but rather on their relations. Several logicians speak not of distin-
the widest of all ideas, the idea of something in general? Since this idea guishing objects, but rather the ideas themselves. Thus BORN (Versu. iih.
covers every object, there can be no characteristic by which we can dis- d. Grundl. d. m. D., p. 11) writes: "An idea is called clear ifthe conscious-
tinguish its objects from those objects that do not stand under it. Hence, ness of it is sufficient to distinguish it from any other idea." GERLACH
according to that definition, it would be impossible to form a clear idea of (§62), HILLEBRAND (§288), and others say the same. It may well be true
something in general. Let us then try the third sense and let us understand that an idea that we not only can but actually do distinguish from others
by the object of an idea A not that thing which is actually represented by must be clear. For if we distinguish one idea from another, we ascribe
that idea, but that to which we apply it in a judgement of the form "this an attribute to it that we deny of the other, and thus we make a judge-
is A". I admit that if we take "object" in this sense, the concept which ment concerning it. In order to do this appropriately, we must first have
emerges is of great importance for logic: it is the concept of an idea which formed an idea that represents it and it alone, i.e., we must have intuited
suffices to distinguish the object to which we apply it from many or all it. Thus this definition boils down to the same thing as mine. Surpris-
other objects. But I would maintain the word "clear" would be far less ingly, some logicians have referred clarity merely to the content of ideas,
suitable for designating it than others such as "complete" or "exclusive", while others have referred it merely to their extension. Thus JAKOB (L.,
etc. (§§110, 112). By the clarity of an idea we usually mean a certain § 134) writes: "A concept is clear if the consciousness connected with it 34
relation between that idea and our consciousness; but whether a given is so strong that one may distinguish its content from the content of any
idea A suffices to distinguish the object to which we apply it depends not other concept." The same is found in SCHAUMANN's Logik (§299). By
upon the way in which this idea is represented in our consciousness, but contrast, RITTER (L., p. 80) has: "If I can distinguish that which belongs
on its relation to that object. One and the same idea would have to be to the extension of a concept from that which belongs to the extension
called clear if we apply it to one object, and obscure if we apply it to an- of another concept, one says I have a perfectly clear concept." Against
other; i.e., clearness and obscurity of an idea would depend upon which this, I remark that when one is conscious of the content of an idea, i.e.,
object we wish to apply it to with the intention of distinguishing it from of the parts of which it is composed, it is customary (and in my opinion,
all similar objects. Finally, if we take the expression "object of an idea" rightly so) not only to say that it is clear, but also that it is distinct. With
33 in its fourth sense, then an obscure idea is one through which the object respect to extension, I note that there are also clear concepts which have
which has caused it can barely be distinguished from other objects, i.e., no extension. It is clear from the foregoing what is to be made of defi-
an idea from which it is almost impossible to infer the properties of the nitions like that of PLATNER (Aph., §399), which unite the two aspects
object which caused it. I believe that the case which is here described of content and extension. KANT's definition (L., Intro.) seems to me one
could easily occur with ideas of which the mind is very clearly aware and of the best: "If I am conscious of an idea, it is clear, otherwise it is ob-
thus should not be called obscure. Thus, for example, the visual idea of scure." FRIES (S. d. L., p. 49 and K1: d. V) on several occasions even says
a distant object does perhaps not allow us to distinguish this object from that an idea becomes clear in us when we perceive it (through our inner
others; nonetheless, I can pay close attention to this idea and can be inti- sense). This coincides exactly with the above definition. Incidentally,
mately conscious that I have it, and what it is like; for example, I may be several very faithful followers of KANT, for instance KIESEWETTER (W

20 21
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 280. Of Ideas

A. d. L., p. 95 ff.), worried that there may be a kind of contradiction in the of clarity. For otherwise, it seems to me, we could not claim to have a
concept of an "unconscious idea", accordingly conceded that we are in- clear idea of a single concept. Does any concept ever appear in our mind
directly conscious of obscure ideas, in that we infer their existence from completely isolated from everything that does not belong to it'? Are not a
their effects. But is it indeed the case that we become conscious of all b
areat many related ideas associated with every concept, e.g ... the ideas of
our obscure ideas in this way? I would also like to ask those who take the sounds which make up the word which designates it, which certainly
offence at the existence of unconscious ideas if they have ever considered do not belong to it? MEHMEL (Denklehre, p. 169) and NDBLEIN (L.,
that one can only become conscious of an idea by forming another idea §280) completely reject the customary classification of concepts as either 36
of it? In KRUG' s presentation, too, I find his usual measure of clarity clear or obscure. HEGEL, too, says in his own way that the customary
and consistency lacking. For when he speaks of clarity (L., §32), he says classification should be discarded: "It must remain undetermined what
that it consists in a degree of consciousness which permits one to distin- an obscure concept is; for otherwise it would no longer be obscure, but
guish the object of the concept. Given this, one would expect obscurity clear." It is a mystery to me which principle could have given rise to this
to consist in a degree of consciousness which does not permit one to dis- inference. A definition always makes a concept distinct. But when one
35 tinguish the object. Instead of this, however, it is said that obscurity is asks for a definition of obscure concepts, one doesn't mean a definition
present in cases where consciousness is merely indirect. In note 1, the of the obscure concepts themselves, but rather of the general concept of
way in which one clear concept is distinguished from another is deter- them. And the latter can certainly become distinct without the former
mined more precisely by saying that this happens without entering into doing so.
the individual parts of the concepts. But if this stipulation is a necessary Note 2. In KIESEWETTER' s Logik (§54) as well as in other recent
feature of clarity, why wasn't it mentioned in the main part of the section? treatises one finds the odd statement that "obscure ideas do not really be-
In note 2, the way in which consciousness of obscure concepts is merely long in logic." How should we understand this claim? Does it only mean
indirect is at first explained by saying that one is conscious of them only that in presentations of logic one should strive to avoid obscurity in the
insofar as they are combined with others. Later, however, it is said that an concepts one sets out as much as possible, making everything clear and
obscure concept only enters into consciousness by being confused with distinct? If so, the remark is completely correct, but it holds not only of
a related concept-are these two things really the same? Furthermore, it logic but of any scientific presentation. But if it is supposed to mean that
is assumed in note 1 that anyone who is able to distinguish the object of logic should not even discuss obscure ideas and concepts, the claim would
one concept from those of other concepts is also able to distinguish the be incorrect. For logic should not only teach the concept of an obscure
concepts and that, conversely, whoever is incapable of the former is also idea (as indeed these logicians themselves do) but also should discuss it
incapable of the latter. This seems incorrect to me: for two concepts can at several points-indicating the influence such ideas have on our judge-
be distinct yet have the same object, as with the concepts of an equilat- ments, how obscure concepts can be raised to clarity and distinctness,
eral and an equiangular triangle. We can distinguish such concepts, even etc.
though we cannot distinguish their objects. E. REINHOLD (ErkenntnijJ!., Note 3. Most logicians claim that clarity as well as obscurity have
p. 278) distinguishes between logical and psychological clarity, defining degrees. Some, such as CROUSAZ, go so far as to claim that this entire
the latter roughly the way KANT does, while saying that the former only distinction is merely relative. Given their definitions of these concepts,
obtains if we are able to think a concept as a particular individual idea by they may well be right. Whoever, for example, thinks that clarity of an
means of a characteristic determination belonging to it. FRIES (S. d. L., idea consists in the ability to distinguish the object that produced it from
p. 116) requires, more precisely, that we must be able to think clear ideas others, can certainly suppose that there are different degrees of clarity,
separately by themselves. I too admit that when our soul thinks many according to whether our ideas allow us to distinguish the object that 37
ideas in combination (thus not separately), the ideas for the most part re- produced them from more or fewer objects. This is not the case with my
main obscure. Thus a certain degree of separation may be required in definition of this concept. If only those ideas of which we have formed
order to grasp an idea clearly. Yet this in no way constitutes the essence intuitions are called clear, and the rest are said to be obscure, then there

22 23
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 280. Of Ideas

are no degrees of clarity or obscurity, for it is not a matter of degree conscious of it, i.e., I must be able to combine it with myself, the subject
whether one intuits or not. Thus one should not be misled here by words. of consciousness. Thus there are no unconscious ideas." I cannot endorse
When in ordinary usage one speaks of more or less clarity, one takes the this inference either. For even if it were correct to say that every idea
word in a different sense, equivalent either to distinctness, completeness, must be a possible constituent of a cognition, indeed, even if one were
or vividness. forced to admit that every idea must occur as a constituent in one of the
Note 4. When I claimed in this section that there are also unconscious judgements I actually form, either in the subject or in the predicate; it
ideas, I professed a view which was much disputed in earlier times, and would still not follow that I would have to form an idea of this idea, still
which more recently has been (like many others) set aside rather than re- less an intuition, which is necessary if I am to be in a position to articu-
solved. DESCARTES first ventured to claim that our soul also has ideas of late the judgement that I have it, i.e., if one is to say I am conscious of
which it is not conscious, in that it constantly (even in the deepest sleep) it. (b) The second reason usually urged against the existence of uncon-
thinks. This was denied, notably by LOCKE; yet LEIBNIZ and WOLFF did scious ideas runs roughly as follows: "We can never claim that we have
not hesitate to admit the existence of ideas (repraesentationes) of which unconscious ideas, precisely because we are not supposed to be aware
we are unconscious, using the term perceptiones to distinguish them from that we have them." This inference seems to me to rest upon a confusion
conscious ideas or ideas properly so-called, which they called appercep- of two concepts which are not sufficiently distinguished by the words we
tiones. So too BAUMGARTEN (Acr. L., §14), TETENS (Versuch, Part I, p. have for them. When we say of an unconscious idea that we would not
265), PLATNER (Aph., I, §30), KANT (Logik, Intro., p. 33, 88 [Ak., 9.33, know that we had it, we only mean to say that we have no intuition of
39]) and others. Among their opponents CREUZ (Vers. iib. d. Seele) went such an idea, and thus cannot articulate the judgement: "I have this idea". 39
the farthest when, rather than admitting that there can be ideas without For in this judgement there occurs an intuition which applies to the idea
consciousness, claimed instead that there can be consciousness without (namely, in the words "this idea"). By contrast, when we claim in gen-
ideas, namely, pure self consciousness. In my view, self consciousness is eral that we have unconscious ideas, we form a judgement in which there
just consciousness of oneself, which accordingly has an object, and pre- occurs an idea under which all our unconscious ideas stand (provided we
supposes an idea (namely, of oneself). Most opposition to unconscious have any); however, this idea is no intuition of them, but rather a general
ideas, incidentally, is based upon the following two points: (a) many concept which englobes them all.
thought that there was an internal contradiction in the concept of an idea
one was not aware of-for, they said, if someone is not aware of repre- §.281.*
38 senting something, he does not represent anything. See, e.g., CROUSAZ' s
Logique (Part I, sec. 3, ch. 1). Here (as I have already said) it seems that Distinct and confused ideas
they forgot that knowledge of an idea presupposes an idea of the idea
1) If one may truly say that we have grasped in our mind a certain objec-
and a particular judgement concerning it. JAKOB (Seelenl., §§512, 516)
tive idea which is not simple, but rather composed of several parts, then
thought that the supposition of unconscious ideas was chimerical rather
all of the simple parts which, combined, make up the idea must also be
than contradictory, since an idea could not really be called ours if it was
grasped by us. For the objective idea is composed of precisely the same
not accompanied by the "I think", or consciousness. I would say that an
number of parts, and the same sort of parts, as are found in the subjective
idea would have to be accompanied by the "I think" at most in the case
idea which we call the appearance of the former in our soul. If our subjec-
where we are in a position to recognise it as our own. However, in or-
tive idea were simple, we would for that very reason call it the appearance
der for an idea to be our own (whether or not we are aware of it), this
of a simple objective idea. If it consists of several parts a, b, c, , ... then
consciousness is not required. SCHMID (See/en!., p. 297) defines ideas
we must look upon it as the appearance of an objective idea which is
(in the narrow sense of the word) as alterations of the self which are pos-
also composed of several parts, and indeed of precisely the simple parts
sible constituents of cognitions. From this definition he infers that "If
which correspond to the subjective ideas a, b, c, ... as their matter. It
something is to serve as a constituent of a cognition, I must at least be
in no way follows from this, however, that when a complex [objective]

24 25
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 281. Of Ideas

idea becomes clear for us (i.e., when we form an intuition of the subjec- myself to extend the concept of distinctness to cover both. In this broader
tive complex idea which is the appearance of the former in our mind), sense, an idea is called distinct if we know either the parts of which it is
we must also have formed similar intuitions of all of its individual parts. composed, or else that it has none. If we do not know this, I call the idea
In other words, it is false to say that a complex idea can only become indistinct. If it is also complex, I call it corifused.
clear for us if we clearly represent its individual parts. When I form an 3) Every distinct idea must also be clear, and should it be complex, we
40 intuition of some other actual object, e.g., this odour, it is not necessary must have clear ideas of at least its immediate parts. For if it belongs in
to form intuitions of its individual parts. Indeed, this may not even be the class of simple ideas, we must have formed the judgement "The idea
possible, since the number of parts may tend to infinity. Similarly, I can has no parts"; while if it is complex, we must have formed the judgement
form intuitions of many of my own ideas (which may also be complex ob- "It consists of such and such parts." To do this, we must have formed an
jects) without at the same time forming intuitions of the individual parts intuition of the idea itself and, if it is complex, also have formed intuitions 42
of which they consist. Even though it is not necessary to form clear ideas of its parts, since these intuitions occur in the judgements just mentioned.
of all the individual parts of a given complex idea in order to raise it to 4) But for an idea to be distinct, it is not necessary that we form
clarity, it is quite possible that both things may happen-that is, we may ideas of its parts which are distinct as well as clear. For, according to
have intuitions of the complex idea as well as of all of its parts. If this the definition given above, a complex idea may be called distinct if we
occurs, and we clearly represent a complex idea A not only as a whole, only know the immediate parts of which it is composed. Whether these
but also clearly represent its individual parts a, b, c, ... one can still ask be simple or complex, and of what parts they may be composed, we do
if it is known whether and in what manner a, b, c, ... are combined or not need to know. But if we also know this and hence have distinct ideas
whether this is unknown. Clearly, the latter is quite possible. We might, of the parts as well, so much the better. This gives us an opportunity to
for example, clearly represent the concept "triangle" as well as the several distinguish different degrees of distinctness. If an idea is distinct for us
concepts "figure", "side", etc. which, if appropriately combined, produce but its immediate parts are not distinct, then it is said to have distinctness
the former, without thinking of this, or indeed knowing that the former is of degree one; if an idea and its immediate components are also distinct,
composed of the latter. Sometimes we do know this, however, and are in but the latter are not, it has distinctness of degree two, and so on. Finally,
a position to form a true judgement of the following form: "The idea A if we have distinct ideas of every part of a given idea, that is, if we know
consists of the ideas a, b, c, ... , in such and such a combination." This is the analysis of the idea (in case it is complex) right down to the simple
a bit of knowledge which can be of great service, especially in scientific parts, which we recognise as simple, we say that the idea is pe1fectly
investigation. When we are in a position to make such a judgement about distinct.
an idea, we generally call it distinct; complex ideas whose components 5) Every simple idea which is distinct, i.e., if we merely know it is
41 we do not know are called indistinct or confused. The distinctness of an simple, is also perfectly distinct. With any complex idea, by contrast,
idea is accordingly a relation between it and our cognitive faculties, and there can be several degrees of distinctness. For even if the immediate
when we ascribe distinctness to an idea we mean to say only that we know parts of an idea are its ultimate parts, it is conceivable that someone might
its content, or, in other words, we know what its parts are and how they know that the idea in question is composed of these parts without knowing
are combined. that they are its ultimate parts, i.e., that they are simple. In this case his 43
2) Only complex ideas can be distinct according to this definition. For idea would only stand at the first degree of distinctness, and would only
if an idea is simple, we cannot know how it is composed of others, since become perfectly distinct if he learned that all the parts of the idea were
it isn't. Now as important as it is to know the parts of a complex idea, it is simple. Any idea which is composed of finitely many parts will allow
equally important to know of a simple idea that it has none at all. Thus it of only finitely many degrees of distinctness. For if one analyses it into
seems appropriate to have a single term for the ideas which occur in our its immediate parts and, if possible, analyses these into their immediate
minds in such a way that we are able to say either that they are simple or, parts, and so on, one must arrive after a finite number of iterations at
if not, how and of which parts they are composed. I accordingly permit nothing but simple parts. Every time he repeats this procedure, he attains

26 27
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 281. Of Ideas

a new level of distinctness in his ideas, and when he finally discovers that Note 2. Almost all logicians define the concept of distinctness so that
the components he has before him are utterly simple, his idea becomes it only applies to cornplex ideas. They must accordingly count simple
perfectly distinct. ideas among the indistinct or confused ideas. This doesn't even seem
Note J. The way the concept of distinctness is understood here, espe- to accord with ordinary usage. For does it not sound strange to say, as
cially the narrower sense of no. 2, seems to be the way it has always been one would have to, that even God himself has indistinct ideas? With the
understood, although the definitions that have been given do not entirely extension of this concept I gave in no. 2, this would be avoided, since
agree. The definition in BECK'S Logik (§13) is completely equivalent according to it simple ideas could also be called distinct. KRUG (L., §34,
to mine: "If we can analyse a concept, and indicate its parts, we show Note 2) indeed believes that according to his definition simple ideas may
that this concept is distinct for us." The definitions of SCHAUMANN (L., also be distinct, if not intensively, at least extensively: for though they
§303) and SCHMID (Emp. Psych., p. 299) are similar. In LEIBNIZ'S defi- have no content which can be analysed, they nevertheless have an ex-
nitions (Medit. de cogn. and Nouv. Ess., II, xxix), however, it seems to me tension which can be classified. But even supposing that a concept can
that the components of which the idea is composed are confused with the be made distinct by classifying its extension, there are simple concepts
attributes of the object represented by it. It is not the latter, but only the which either have no extension or else have an extension in which we
former, which belong to the definition of an idea, and it is only the latter cannot detect any multiplicity (§78).
that one needs to know in order to have a distinct idea. Several logicians Note 3. According to the definitions of §§275, 280 and 281, vivid-
define the concept of distinctness in terms of the concept of clarity. Thus ness, clarity and distinctness are quite different, even though one may say 45
in BAUMGARTEN's Acr. L., §102, we read: Conceptus clarus clararum that the first is required for the latter two. What KRUG calls cesthetic dis-
notarum distinctus est. 1 So too MAAB (G1:, §34), METZ (§86) and oth- tinctness or rather vividness is the combination of an idea with a vivid
ers. In my view, from the fact that one has clear ideas of the part-ideas image (on this, see §284.7 below). The distinction between analytic and
which constitute a certain other idea it does not follow that one knows synthetic distinctness which some have urged, finally, seems to me to be
that it is composed of them, something which is required for distinctness. of no use.
REIMARUS (Vernunftl., §69), PLATNER (Aph., §402), KRUG (L., §33,
44 34), GERLACH (L., §62) and others distinguish two kinds of distinctness: §.282.
intensive, which concerns the content of an idea, and extensive, which
concerns its extension. While by the former they mean roughly the same Whether each of our ideas has a beginning and an end
thing that I call distinctness in general, they understand by the latter the
1) Since in my view it is not necessary either to be conscious of an idea or
kind of perfection of our knowledge of a concept which is attained by
determining its extension. But if one wishes to take the word "distinct- to form the judgement that one has it in order to have it, I clearly have no
ness" in such a broad sense, then it seems to me that one will have to right to conclude from the fact that we have just now become conscious
count every bit of knowledge concerning a concept-not only knowledge of a certain idea that the idea was just formed in our mind, nor to infer
of its inner attributes, but also knowledge of its relations-as bearing on from the fact that we are no longer conscious of an idea that it has ceased
its distinctness. And since content and extension are far from exhausting to be. Whoever is of the opinion that substances neither come to be nor
everything that may be known of a concept, we would also have to distin- cease to be might be led from what was just said to wonder whether every
guish further kinds of distinctness-we would have to say, for example, one of our ideas has a beginning and an encl. In God's understanding,
that a concept becomes more distinct (better known) for us when we come every idea that there is is present at all times, and never changes. The
to know all the higher concepts it is subordinate to, or the concepts it is question thus presents itself whether the ideas which are found in human
coordinate with, or that it is pure or mixed, redundant, etc. minds-which are subject to many changes-are present at all times.
2) If we wished to claim that not a single human idea ever comes or
ceases to be, we would have to explain every change which occurs in the
1A clear concept of clear notes (characteristics) is distinct. state of our ideas in terms of their vividness, saying that now one, now

28 29
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 282. Of Ideas

another, become stronger in us. We would not be able to say that anything continual coming to be and ceasing to be. In addition, the ideas which are
else apart from the degree of vividness ever changed in our ideas. In produced in us through the actions of outer objects are not the only ones
46 particular, we would not be able to say that an idea undergoes a change we have. Rather, we also have ideas which apply to no outer objects. The
with respect to clarity, becoming clear when formerly it was obscure, or claim that these ideas have been in us forever is at least not supported by
vice versa. For if I have correctly grasped the nature of clarity (§280) as the reasons adduced in no. 3.
consisting in forming an intuition of an idea present in us, it is decided 5) If it be true that some of our ideas are formed through actions on
that none of our ideas could pass from obscurity to clarity unless a new our soul of a particular kind, it is already demonstrated that the condition
idea were formed in us, namely, an intuition of the idea. Similarly, no of our soul which we call representing is not permanent, but rather an
clear idea could become obscure unless an intuition of it, and thus one of alteration. For what occurs in our soul during the action of an outer object
our ideas, ceased to be. on it is certainly nothing permanent, but rather an alteration. But if at least
3) Still more, among the many ideas of which we are conscious there some of our ideas are alterations, then it is clear that they cease once the
are also intuitions, which we apply to certain objects, their causes, which action of the outer object which causes the idea ends. If we learn that at
are distinct from us. If someone wished to claim that all of our ideas are least some of our ideas are mere alterations, then it is extremely likely 48
without beginning or end, he would have to claim that that every object that this holds for all of them. For are not all ideas similar with respect
which through its action brings forth an intuition in us always has and to what may be inferred about their duration? Do we not find that ideas
always will act upon us, and indeed in the manner which is required to which we are aware of for a moment or two quickly disappear from our
produce an intuition. Now it might well be true that all finite substances consciousness? If it does not follow from this that they have completely
produce effects upon one another which are governed only by the dis- disappeared, it would at least seem to show that they must have become
tance between them, and which accordingly have different degrees at all weaker, and will soon disappear completely. In addition, the interaction
times. But one may surely dispute whether every one of these effects also which ideas may enter into, e.g., when they are united as constituents in
produces a singular idea in our minds, as well as whether there is no other a judgement, seems to prove that they are all of the same nature, variable
way in which ideas may be produced in us. rather than pennanent. And is it not precisely this variation in our ideas-
4) The former may be questioned because when we inquire more pre- of which we seem to be so intimately conscious-that we use to judge
cisely into the outer object to which we apply an intuition as its cause, we every other change and indeed use as our original means of measuring
find that it is never a simple substance, but always a body, i.e., a collec- time?
tion of simple substances which are actually infinite in number. The effect 6) Finally, it seems to me that it already lies in the concept of what we
47 produced by a single one of these simple substances is by itself not yet call an idea that in the case of a finite substance, i.e., one whose forces act
an idea, but rather something essentially different from an idea, the pro- only in time, an idea can only be a change within it. For doubtless by an
duction of which, for its part, requires the combined action of infinitely idea of such a being we mean something which can be looked upon as the
many such substances. It is also clear that the production of an idea never effect of its powers; and from this it follows that it must be an alteration.
occurs through the mere existence of these substances, but rather due to
§.283.*
the particular connection in which they presently stand. Thus I can only
have, e.g., the intuition of this red under certain conditions. There must Whether evoy idea leaves a certain trace after it has disappeared
be a body which is reel in colour sufficiently close to my eyes, it must
1) If there are ideas which cease to be, or disappear, indeed if this holds
be illuminated, and so on. But if things stand thus, if the cause of the
for all of our ideas, the question arises whether the condition of our soul
presence of a certain idea in us is not the mere presence of other sub-
is exactly the same after the disappearance of an idea as it would have
stances, but rather a certain connection between them, it is already shown
been had this idea never been produced in us. 49
that the ideas we presently have have not always existed in us. For the
2) In order to answer this question, one might pose the further ques-
connections between things are constantly changing, and are subject to a
tion whether any change in a simple being is entirely without effects, that

30 31
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 283. Of Ideas

is, one which takes such a course that the state of the being in which it oc- ery idea which is produced in it leaves behind a kind of trace, something
curred would be exactly the same at a certain time as it was beforehand, which was not there before.
or would have been if it had never occurred? If there were substances 4) Another proof of this is our ability under certain circumstances to
more or less like the matter of the mechanical philosophy, with no power recall if not all, at least some of our own ideas (roughly speaking, those
of representation, and no capacity to undergo an inner change, the ques- which had a high degree of vividness during their existence). In order to
tion would have to be answered in the affirmative. But could this also clarify this, I must say more precisely what a memory is. If we say of
be the case with substances endowed with the power of representation, someone that he recalls an idea he had once before, we must observe that
or those which undergo inner changes? It seems to me that there cannot he now has this idea again, and also that he forms the judgement that he 51
be an inner change in a substance which is completely without effects, so had it once before. But this is not enough. For we can form the judge-
that the occurrence or non-occurrence of this change would not affect the ment that we once had a certain idea without recalling it. It depends upon
future condition of the being in any way. For as no change is produced the basis from which we infer this judgement. When I infer that I saw
without a cause, so too an alteration can only persist as long as its cause a rock lying in my path yesterday merely from the fact that I didn't trip
(the action of other beings) lasts. Precisely on account of this, the con- over it, one cannot yet say that I recall my idea of this rock. If I infer
dition which exists at the last moment of this external action must persist from the swelling I observe in my arm that I must once have broken my
continually from that moment on unless some new action occurs. hand and felt severe pain, this by no means amounts to the recollection
3) But even if someone were unwilling to grant this for every change, of that pain. Still less is this this case when I form the judgement merely
I can produce particular reasons which show why it must hold at least because older people who were around in my childhood tell me about
of the kind of alterations we call ideas. Is it not the incontrovertible ev- it. Thus in order to be able to say that we recall an idea, the judgement
idence of experience that if we have had an idea once or several times, that we once had it cannot merely be derived from a perception of certain
it becomes easier to produce it again, and to raise it to higher degrees changes we produced in the external world which could not have occurred
of vividness? Does this not prove that an idea, even when it has ceased without that idea, and still less from the consideration of things still more
to be, nevertheless leaves something behind in our soul which was not distinct from ourselves. What remains to be said, then, other than that in
there formerly? One might indeed attempt to explain this phenomenon recollection we infer that we once had a certain idea A from the consid-
50 by claiming that something is left behind by an idea not in the soul but eration of something in our own mind? Indeed, the very word memmy
rather in the body, an increased capacity to produce the motions required [Erinnerung] already indicates knowledge obtained from the considera-
for the production of this idea in our soul. But if this were correct, one tion of what passes within. Now what must this be in our souls, whose
would have to say that all skill, development, and learning is based upon consideration enables us in the process of recollection to conclude that we
the body, and only it learns, while the soul remains the same. Who could formerly had the idea A? A consideration through which we come to form
believe this? In addition, we can observe of precisely those ideas in the an idea of the idea A must certainly be focussed on some enduring effect
production of which the body plays the greatest role, namely, intuitions of this idea. Experience teaches us that an idea we have had repeatedly 52
of outer objects, that rather than becoming more vivid through frequent becomes not only more vivid but also easier to produce, even without the
repetition they become more feeble and, far from becoming easier to pro- presence of all the conditions which were required in the first instance to
duce, require an ever stronger action of the external object. Only with bring it about. Consequently, we can define more precisely the nature of
ideas which are produced through a special activity of the soul (even if that which remains in the soul as being of a sort which promotes the pro-
this be accompanied by a certain change in the body) is it fully the case duction of that idea, and permits us to produce it more vividly and with
that they become more vivid and are easier to produce, the more often we greater ease. Calling this certain something a trace left behind by a past
repeat them. This clearly shows that frequent repetition renders our body idea may not be the most appropriate choice of terms. Nevertheless, no
less rather than more apt to carry out the motions necessary to produce a harm will come of retaining it, provided we adhere to the given definition
given idea. Thus it is the soul rather than the body which learns, and ev- and do not think of traces in the physical [sinnlich] sense of the word.

32 33
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 283. Of Ideas

Now if one admits, for the reasons cited above, that at least some of our "No idea that we have had once is ever completely lost." When, however,
ideas leave traces, he will soon have to concede that all of them do. For he adds in the same sentence, "at least not as a p~tency," he seem~ .to b_e
leaving a trace, one which makes it easier to reproduce the idea without ntrue to himself. For if an idea endures only with respect to ability, 1t
all the circumstances necessary at first, seems to be an effect that does not ~oes not itself endure; rather, this only means that the ability to produce it
depend on the matter of an idea, but rather on its strength and vividness, more easily arises and endures. HERBART also describes memory as the 54
i.e., on conditions allowing of more or less. mere emergence of an idea previously suppressed by others in our con-
5) One might still wonder whether the trace left behind by an idea en- sciousness. This view is opposed to the reasons I adduced in the previous
dures forever, or else disappears or becomes weaker after a certain time. paragraph against the opinion that our i~eas last forever. Yet there ~re
The former claim is clearly not one which can be proven by experience, scholars who explain the phenomena which I have here used to argue for
though the reason cited in no. 2 is decisive by itself. Nevertheless, some the existence of certain traces of ideas in our souls in a completely differ-
things that are certain based upon grounds of reason can also be refuted ent way, namely, as traces left in the body by the external impression of
by apparently contrary experiences. Thus the experience that ideas which the represented object. This was the opinion of BONNET who, in the Ess.
have not been activated for a long time can scarcely be recalled should by analyt. sur !es facultes de l 'ame and elsewhere, explained all of this by
53 no means be explained by saying that the trace it left behind has steadily the ~onstitution of our brain fibres, which, when once moved, leave be-
weakened. Rather, we should seek other explanations-perhaps the 1mm- hind a disposition or inclination (tendance) to undergo similar motions.
ber of ideas which make an equal claim on our recollection has grown Some of the reasons why I cannot accept this view are known from nos.
with time, or the traces that our ideas certainly also leave behind in our 2 and 3.
bodies can and must disappear with time since the body is a composite
object. §.284.
Note. What I have claimed in this paragraph is exactly LEIBNIZ' s
opinion, as stated in the Otio Hanov., p. 288, namely, that no impression Effects which result from the traces of our ideas
made on the soul is ever lost. And in the Nouv. Ess., one reads qu 'il y a
des dispositions, qui sont des restes des impressions passees dans l'ame I) Because they are actual, the traces left behind in our souls after our
aussi bien, que dans le corps, mais dont on ne s'apperf'Oit que lorsque la ideas disappear cannot fail to produce many effects. The most important
memo ire en trouve quelqu 'occasion. 1 The expression disposition proves of these is the appearance, under favourable circumstances, of an idea
sufficiently that LEIBNIZ did not take traces to be ideas. ABEL (See- which has the same matter as that which left the trace. Such ideas are for
lenl., § 139 and Quellen d. Vorst., p. 214-219) also claimed that every this reason called the same idea, but are more correctly called a renewal
idea must leave a trace after it ceases to be, and sought to prove this or repetition, a revival or reawakening of the idea. The soul's capacity
based in part upon the grounds that I adduced above, namely, "because to revive ideas under circumstances which differ from those necessary
every inner change in a being leaves some trace." PLATNER taught the to produce it in the first instance, is called memmy. In the special case
same thing (Aph., Part I, §242), but instead of traces preferred to speak of where the original idea was an intuition, and the object which caused it is
aptitudes to recall such ideas. BENEKE (Psych. Skizzen) coined the word no longer present or does not cause the revived idea, the revived idea is
Angelegtheiten [::::::::dispositions]. Yet some, e.g., CRUSIUS (W. z. G., §90) usually called an imagining [Einbildung] and the capacity to imagine is 55
would have it that the ideas themselves endure in the soul, either for- called the imagination.
ever or at least as long as experience can produce a recollection of them. 2) It is to be expected that we will not be able to raise every idea which
FRIES (Syst. d. L., p. 55) also explains memory as the capacity of ideas is revived to clarity, that is, (following the definition of §280), to procure
to endure; ideas are forgotten, in his view, when they become obscure. an intuition of it. If now an idea A is revived in our minds in such a way
that it remains obscure, then there is for this very reason no recollection
1
. There are dispositions, which are the traces of past impressions in the body as well (§283) of A either. For this recollection is a judgement to the effect that
as Ill the soul, that one is only aware of when the memory finds occasion to recall them. we have previously had the idea A, and for this we require an idea of this

34 35
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 284. Of Ideas

idea, and indeed an idea which applies to A alone, i.e., an intuition of A. which arise in us, it is to be expected that one of them is also present
Thus we must intuit the idea A which has been revived in us, and thus in the cases where we cannot notice any of them. Indeed, it is to be ex- 57
raise it to clarity. Yet when the revival of an idea we once had is raised to ected that they will be present when ideas are renewed without our even
clarity. it does not always follow that we form the judgement that it is an ~ein" aware of it. For this reason, the question of whether all of these
idea we had before, and that we have a memory of it. But if we do form ciret~nstances can be reduced to a single one becomes all the more im-
this judgement based on the consideration of grounds present in our soul, portant. And I believe they ~an. One circums~ance common to all those
it is called a memory; and the ability to form such judgements is [also] enumerated in no. 3, and with respect to which we can look upon the
called memory. articularities as accidental, is the presence of an idea that has the same
3) If we inquire into the circumstances under which ideas we have had ~zatter as another which was in the soul simultaneously with another.*
before are remembered, experience reveals the following rules: If we assume that such an idea is capable of reawakening the other, if
(a) if we have an idea of an object which we have previously thought not always, at least when certain other circumstances contribute, then all
of in connection with another, we usually also remember the latter. Usu- the experiences mentioned in no. 3 can be satisfactorily explained. For it
ally, when we form an idea of one part of a whole we have formerly seen becomes clear that between any two ideas to which we ascribe the capac-
we also form an idea of the remaining parts. The idea of one of the tusks ity to revive one another, there is a relation such that they have the same
of an elephant, for example, will tend to bring us to form an idea of the matter as two ideas once present in the soul simultaneously. (a) When we
remaining parts, e.g., the trunk. (b) When we have an idea of an ob- think of an object in connection with another, the ideas of both must have
56 ject which we have formerly thought of as having a certain attribute, we been in the soul simultaneously. (b) When we form the judgement that a
usually form an idea of this attribute as well. If, for example, we have certain attribute belongs to an object, we must have thought of the object
thought of Harpax (whether rightly or wrongly) as a cheapskate, we tend and the attribute simultaneously. (c) The same holds when we form the
to think of his stinginess when thinking of him. (c) When we have an idea judgement that a certain object is the ground or cause, or the consequence
of an object we have looked upon as the ground or cause, or else as the or effect, of another. (cl) If we are to say that a similarity between two ob-
consequence or effect of another, the latter tends to occur to us as well. jects is known, it must consist in an attribute which we ascribe to each
Thus, hearing a shot, the firearm occurs to us, and vice versa. (cl) When of them. The idea of this attribute is then one that has the same matter
we have an idea of an object which bears many similarities to another we as the two ideas which we (following (b) above) thought simultaneously
have recognised, the idea of the latter is revived in us. Thus when we with one, and with the other, of these objects. (e) Objects which one calls 58
see a wild rose, we recall the Cent(folia. (e) When we have an idea of an opposed, despite all the contrasts between them, have great similarity in
object which we have previously thought of as being opposed to another, other respects (§ 107). Thus a giant and a midget, besides all the simi-
the idea of the latter is revived. Thus, seeing a giant, we are reminded larities that come with their both being human, also have that of depart-
of a midget. (f) When we have an idea of a place, we think of events ing from the normal human size, one by excess, the other by deficiency.
which we have experienced there, or at least of events we know have oc- (f) The idea of the place in which an event occurred that we ourselves
curred there. We walk, for example, into a room in which a dear friend experienced, or that we know to have occurred, must for that very rea-
of ours has died after a long illness, and see him still in his death-bed. son have appeared in our soul at the same time as the idea of this event.
(g) If we have had a sequence of several ideas, where the next one always (g) Our assumption also permits us to explain the fact that an entire se-
begins before the previous one has completely disappeared, we recall the quence of ideas A,B,C,D, .. . , where the next one always begins before
entire sequence, in the same order, if only the first idea is produced. Thus the previous one has completely disappeared, is recalled in the same order
if someone recites the first verse of a poem we know by heart, the rest if only the first idea is produced. For note that most ideas, especially ideas
follows in order, etc.
4) As close consideration reveals that one or more of the circum- ''By simultaneous, I by no means intend to say that the ideas in question have the same
stances enumerated above is present in almost every case of memories beginning- and end-points, but rather only that one of them began before the other ceased
to be,

36 37
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 284. Of Ideas

like those just described, are composed of parts which must be thought in 6) On account of the law governing the awakening of simultaneous
a certain order. This explains why the idea A only recalls the idea B, and ideas, every idea that has been produced in us repeatedly acquires more
not the later ideas C and D, for in fact A and B, but not A and C or A and secondary ideas every time it is repeated, namely, those which came into
D, overlapped in time. The last parts of the idea A are simultaneous with our soul simultaneously with its earlier occurrences. Understandably, this
the first parts of the idea B, but before we reach C or D, A has disappeared renders it ever more efficacious. If, in particular, we have repeatedly
completely. This also explains why A awakens B but B does not awaken heard a given word pronounced, or have perceived some other sensible
A, and why we can renew the sequence from A to D, but not so easily object a (which men use as a sign for the idea) simultaneously with the
produce the reversed sequence form D to A. For if B is to remind us of production of the idea A in us, a connection is formed between the idea A
A, the last parts of B must be simultaneous with the first parts of A, rather and the idea of the sign a, which will bring it about that whenever the idea
than the last parts of A being simultaneous with the first parts of B. Ac- A is produced in us in the future, the symbol a will also occur to us, and
cordingly, we may set out the following principle: "If a pair of ideas has vice versa. But when I say that we have in this way an idea designated by
59 ever been produced simultaneously in our soul, and afterwards an idea is the word a, I do not mean that this idea occurs in our mind all by itself or
produced in us which is equal to one of them (has the same matter), then, separately, but rather only that this idea belongs to the collection of things
if not always, at least quite often, the other will also be renewed, i.e., an we are presently thinking, and I look upon the other things we think along
idea will be produced which has the same matter as the other." Permit me with it, no matter how intimately they may be connected with that idea, as
to call this proposition the law of awakening, renewal, or association of if they were not there. In fact there are always many other ideas present
our ideas, and to say of an idea responsible for the production of another along with the idea designated by A, notably, the idea of its sign a, but
that it is the stimulating [weckende] idea while saying of the other that it also many others which once were present in our mind at the same time,
is stimulated or renewed. either with A or the idea of its sign.
5) So far, I have intentionally refrained from saying that when two 7) In the particular case when we are conscious or simply falsely be-
ideas have occurred simultaneously in the soul one may reawaken the lieve that the ideaA is an object-idea, we quite rightly distinguish between
other eve1y time, saying instead that this occurs frequently. Experience the idea itself and the one or more objects it represents. We then form yet
teaches no more than this. Indeed, it seems that the assumption that all another idea of these objects (which admittedly is not necessary). This
ideas which have occtmed even once simultaneously in our soul must idea is composed of the ideas of all the attributes we know to belong to 61
reawaken one another as soon as one of them is produced would lead to these objects, or else those we falsely ascribe to them, but especially of
many contradictions. To mention but one: what an immense number of those that are important to us, or are easily perceptible. Such ideas are of
ideas, which could only confuse us, would have to be awakened in our the form "Something that unites the attributes b, b', b" .... " By virtue
souls at every moment? But if it only happens with some of our ideas, of the law of simultaneity, this idea of the object of A becomes so closely
and only some of the time, that the occurrence of one of them stimulates connected with the idea A itself that it appears whenever A is vividly
the other, we must desire to know what circumstances are either neces- present for a while. I allow myself, as others have done before me, to
sary, or at least make it easier, for this to happen. On this matter, I can call this idea which accompanies A its accompanying image (schema or
only set out the following conjectures. An idea is more easily renewed: phantasm). It is obvious from what has been said in §52.5 that the word
(a) the more vivid it was when it occurred; (b) the more often it has al- image is here used in an improper sense.
ready been renewed; (c) if the idea which reawakens it also has a certain 8) Not all of our ideas are accompanied by images in this sense. This
degree of vividness; (cl) the awakening idea will accomplish this all the only occurs if we also represent the idea to ourselves (i.e., the idea is
more certainly the more often it has already happened that a pair of ideas clear) and either are aware or else falsely believe that it has one or more
with the same matter as the awakening and awakened idea have been si- objects. It occurs precisely because we believe that in this way we are
60 multaneously present in the soul, etc. forming yet another idea of these objects, namely, an appropriate image
of them. In order to show the existence of such images accompanying

38 39
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 284. Of Ideas

our concepts, I will first turn to the concept of God. We all define this BERWASSER (Psych.,§ 123), HOFFBAUER (L., §90), MAAf3 (L., §528 and
as the concept of a being which has no further ground of its existence. Vers. 1ib. d. Einb., p. 24 f), among others. Heinrich SCHMID (Metaphy. d.
But can we deny that whenever we represent this concept vividly for a inn. N., p. 242) reduces all the laws to the soul's living unity. BENEKE' s
time, another idea appears, according to which we place this being (in- definition in his valuable Psych. Skizzen (I, p. 378 ff.) has a number of
deed, against our better judgement) in a certain space above us, ascribe a peculiarities. Others believe that there are several such laws which cannot
shape to Him, and the like? So too we never think the concept of a tri- be reduced to a single one. Thus PLATNER (Aph., I, §278) and JAKOB
angle without the idea of a determinate triangle occurring to us, perhaps (Psych., §268, 269) assume three laws: those of similarity, simultaneity,
one which is roughly equilateral. And even when we think an imaginary and order (or succession); others, e.g., GERARD, BEATTIE, ABEL add
62 concept, which as such has no object, for instance that of a decahedron (a
10 these a law of contrast; HUME adds a law of causality, and so on. It
solid bounded by ten equal faces), a certain solid appears before our eyes, seems to me that all of these laws spring from that of simultaneity. Per-
perhaps one bounded by triangles, etc. haps my readers will also agree that none of the other laws is as generally
Note I. The particular kind of idea which I called renewed (no. 4)- valid as is usually stated; rather, each requires a restrictive clause, which
i.e., those which arise due to the trace left by an older idea with the same makes it obvious that they are only particular applications of the law of
matter, even though the circumstances required to produce it in the first simultaneity. Concerning the law of similarity, it is not correct to state
place are not present-are usually called imaginings [Einbildungen] by that ideas of a pair of similar things reawaken one another; rather, the
others. Thus in UEBERWASSER' s Emp. Psych., Vol. I, § 120, we read: condition must be added that the similarity consists in attributes which
"The reawakened effects of former ideas which are elevated to new ideas" we think in our ideas of them, or which are at least known to us. But if
(which are what I call traces) "are called imaginings." According to this this is the case, and we think of certain attributes in the concept of the
definition, every idea, even when it was not caused by an external ob- thing X which we also think of in the concept of the thing Y, or if the
ject, indeed even if it has no object, could become an imagining, pro- idea of these equal attributes occurs to us when we represent them, be-
vided only that it is formed by renewal. The most common definition, cause we often think of the property along with the thing which possesses
by contrast, seems intended to narrow the concept of an imagining con- it, then it is obvious that our recollection of one thing when thinking of
siderably. According to it, an imagining is an idea of an object which the other can be explained by the law of simultaneity. And if someone
is absent. (See PLATNER'S Phil. Aph., Vol. I, §225; JAKOB'S Seelenl., agrees with me on this point, he will admit that the same holds for the
§246; KIESEWETTER's WA. d. L., Vol. II, p. 163, among others). As this law of contrast. For one only really says that there is a contrast between
definition seems to accord completely with common usage, I felt myself two things if they differ greatly in one or two respects while being quite 64
obliged to retain it (no. 1), though the troubles caused by the fact that the similar in many others. And it must also be added that this contrast is
word imagining is derived from image cannot be denied. known to us. The law of causality, finally, would be too generally and
Note 2. The laws governing the awakening of ideas (usually called the incorrectly expressed if one said that the cause recalls the effect and vice
laws of the association of ideas) are one of the most fruitful discoveries in versa. For if we are not acquainted with both the cause and the effect,
the field of psychology since the re-establishment of the sciences. There as well as with their original relationship to one another, thinking of one
is still disagreement, however, over whether these laws can all be reduced will certainly not bring the other to mind. But if we do know both, and
to the single law of simultaneity. The majority is on the side of the affir- indeed know their relationship, we must have represented both together
mative. MALEBRANCHE already assumed only this single law (Rech. s. at least once. The most difficult case, I admit, is to show the dependence
la verit., III, ii, ch. 3); for the influence over the course of our thought that of the law of succession, i.e., the law according to which entire sequences
63 he accorded to our own will, and finally to God, cannot be denied even of ideas are renewed in the order they first appeared in the soul. But as
by those who presuppose only a single law of association. Precisely this closer consideration reveals that the ideas which we here describe as suc-
law is found in WOLFF (Psycho!. emp., § 107), REUSCH (Syst. L., §4), ceeding one another do not perhaps appear in distinct time-intervals, but
CRUSIUS (Weg z. G., §90), KIESEWETTER (WA. d. L., II, p. 212), UE- instead the succeeding always begins before the previous one has ceased

40 Li 1
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 284. Of Ideas

to be, this law too may be explained in terms of the law of simultaneity, a procedure our imagination follows in a certain activity? It seems to me
as I attempted to show in no. 4. that these ideas would say nothing of our imagination, or of the proce-
Note 3. The distinction I drew in no. 7 between an idea and the ac- dures it follows on this or that occasion. It should be noted that FRIES
companying image has not always been understood in this way. LEIBNIZ (Syst. d. L., p. 61, 68.) also distinguishes between images and schemata,
seems to agree completely with my view when he writes (Nmtv. Ess., II, though in a different way than KANT, while KRUG uses the two words as 66
ix) that two geometers, one born blind, the other a paralytic, would ex- synonyms when he writes (Log., §45 a, note): "Moreover, corresponding
hibit equal concepts of spatial objects despite all the differences in the to concepts of genera and species there are certain internal intuitions or
images each had. Ce qui fait encore voir, he adds, combien il faut dis- images (schemata), which the imagination generates involuntarily, in that
tinguer !es images des idees exactes, qui consistent dans !es definitions. 1 the repeated intuitions of the individuals allow certain traits-wherein
This opinion is also distinctly expressed in the Ars. cogit., part I, ch. 1 their similarity consists-to be abstracted and assembled in a general im-
and 15. Finally, what KANT understood by the so-called constructions age." From this definition, I believe I may infer that this scholar connects
of pure concepts by means of intuitions, and what he called schemata of roughly the same concept with these words as I do, only I suppose that
65 the pure concepts of the understanding in the Critique of Pure Reason, there are images not only for concepts of genera and species, but also for
seem to be nothing other than images accompanying these concepts ac- any genuine or even merely supposed object-idea. Nor do all the ideas
cording to my definition. Now KANT distinguishes between the schema of which an image is composed have to be intuitions. Rather, some are
of a concept and an image and says, for example, that five points next concepts, since intuitions can only enter into combinations to form new
to one another would be an image but not a schema of the number five; ideas with the help of concepts.
by contrast, he defines the schema of a concept as "the idea of the gen- Note 4. According to these definitions there is an unmistakable dif-
eral procedure whereby the imagination produces its image." It seems ference between the sense of the word "image" [Bild] and another used in
to me, however, that if the words "image" or "schema" are supposed to poetry, when certain fictions [Dichtungen] are given the name of (poetic)
designate ideas, the five adjacent points should not be called either im- images. If I am not mistaken, we give the name of fictions (n:otY)f.m) to
age or schema. For these points are not ideas. I would call their sum an every idea 1 that we devise, not in order that those to whom we present it
object standing under the concept five, i.e., an example belonging with shall believe that an actual object corresponds to it, but rather only with
the concept. I cannot form any idea, however, of a procedure that our the aim and in the sense that its consideration shall bring forth certain
imagination is supposed to follow in order to provide our concepts with feelings and resolutions in them. Thus whoever discovered the fable of
images, where image is supposed to mean certain objects standing under the wolf and the lamb was inventing [dichten], since he brought certain
these concepts, for I cannot take the imagination in any sense of the word ideas to our minds without any intention that we should take them to rep-
to be an ability for producing anything other than ideas. But if by images resent actual events, but rather only in order to be able to produce certain
we simply mean ideas of such objects, one may indeed call the capacity feelings in us (namely, the abhorrence we rightly feel towards an oppres-
of providing our concepts with images the imagination. It is in no way sor of the innocent, especially when he tries to cover up his crime through
clear to me why the mere idea of the particular procedure the imagination false pretences). Such fictions (which usually occur at most as parts in
follows in this activity could be called a schema belonging to the con- larger fictions), which consist in the representation of certain sensible ob-
cept. Consider a few of the schemata adduced by KANT himself. The jects that we choose to consider because of their similarity to the ones we
schema of substance is supposed to be the persistence of the real in time, are actually concerned with, are called poetic images. Thus in the fable 67
the schema of interaction is supposed to be the simultaneity of determi- mentioned above we call the lamb an image of oppressed innocence, etc.
nations, and so on. Now are the ideas of the persistence of something
real for all time or of the simultaneity of several determinations, ideas of 1In his edition, Jan Berg reproduces the following marginal note from B's copy of the
WL: "Are fictions mere ideas? Are they not instead propositions, indeed entire collections
1Which again shows how much one must distinguish images from exact ideas, which of propositions whose truth is not in question, in that they are presented merely in order
consist in definitions. to bring forth certain feelings?"

42 43
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

Who could possibly confuse images of this kind with those discussed in person is wont to employ, especially those he uses t~ re~eal his thoughts
the present section? to others, is called the language of that person. A sign ts called a natu-
ra 1 ,SJ. ban of an idea if human nature, i.e., attributes which we all have in
§.285.* common, determines which idea it designates. All other signs are called
contingent; if a contingent sign was created by a decision, i.e., if the ob-
Signs for our ideas
ject A serves to designate an idea B because. we kno~ingly and willin~ly
connected them, and nothing more than accidental circumstances (which
1) As we saw in §284, our mind has the peculiarity that ideas that were
are not met with everywhere) determined this choice, it is called conven-
once connected with each other also mutually stimulate each other. We
tional. Thus, wringing one's hands is probably a natural sign, wagging a
use this peculiarity in the following way: certain ideas which can be easi~y
finger a contingent sign, and the way in which the Romans indicated that
stimulated are used as means to produce others (either in ourselves or m
a gladiator was to die is merely conventional. A sign is usually called. an
other people) that are more difficult to generate, but are associated with
expression if it is an external object, and the signified thing is somethmg
the former. An object which is used for this purpose, i.e., one through
internal, e.g., a thought, a sensation, etc. Thus, clapping one's hands is 69
whose idea we intend to stimulate in a thinking being some other, as-
generally taken to be a (natural) expression of delight. Most of the signs
sociated idea, is called a sign. The objective idea whose corresponding
~e use to produce ideas in other people consist in phenomena which can
subjective idea is supposed to be stimulated by the idea of the sign is
be perceived either by hearing or sight; the former may be called audible
called the signified idea, also the sign(fication [Bedeutung] of the sign. If
or auditory signs, the latter visible or visual signs. The former are usually
the signified idea has an object, then it is often called the sign(fied object,
produced with the organs of mouth, i.e., by the voice.
or aaain, the signification of the sign. Sometimes the words sense [Sinn]
and ~neaning [Verstand] are used synonymously with the word "signifi-
2) Ideas composed of other ideas, e.g., ideas of entire propositions,
are usually expressed by making use of signs for the individual ideas
cation". But a certain distinction could be made between them in the
of which they are composed, arranged in a certain order. When we use
following way. We could call the signification of the sign that particular
audible signs, their temporal order is roughly that of the order the simple
idea which it is intended to produce, and succeeds in producing; while
ideas they designate must be combined to form the complex idea. For
we could confine the words sense and meaning to those ideas which are
example, when we wish to produce an idea of an entire proposition, we
merely intended to be produced by a certain sign in a given case. Un-
first produce the sign which serves to produce its subject-idea, then the
derstandably, somebody who does not understand a sign can take it in a
sign which designates the copula, and finally the sign that is supposed to
sense or meaning which is quite different from its real signification. To
bring forth the predicate-idea. If we use visible signs, e.g., certain figures,
use certain signs in order to produce ideas in others is to speak or say
we place them one after the other in a certain direction (e.g., left to right,
something in the widest sense of these words. To inspect given signs in
top to bottom, etc.) and fix once and for all the order in which they are to
68 order to find out which ideas their author wanted to generate is called
be read.
reading in the widest sense. To grasp what ideas their author wanted to
3) According to the definition given in no. l, a collection of several
produce is to understand them. To assume that they have such and such
signs may also be called a single sign. Signs produced in the way de-
a sense, while they have another, is to misunderstand them. Finally, a
scribed in no. 2, for instance, are of this sort. In a more narrow sense,
proposition in which it is stated that certain signs have such and such a
I shall call single only signs that cannot be viewed as a collection. Such
sense is called an intopretation of these signs. An interpretation may be
single signs, especially those produced by the voice, are also called single 70
merely thought, or in its turn expressed with other signs, in which case
words. Such a single word or sign can, by the way, sometimes be called
it is called a verbal interpretation. If an object is used by everyone to
simple, and sometimes complex. I call it complex not merely when it is
designate a given idea, it is called a universally accepted sign, whereas
composed of parts, but when these parts make it easier for us to recall
if it is only used thus by some, e.g., by a certain people, it is said to be
the designated idea. When this is not the case, I call it simple. Thus the
merely customary for them. The collection of all signs which a given

44 45
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

expression "A flower that bears some similarity to a tulip and has a speck- 8) If a sign is used improperly, it usually occurs in connection with
led corolla" is a collection of several words; the expression "Tiger-lily" several others, so that the idea of an entire proposition is expressed. In
is a single, but complex word; while "considered", finally, I call a sim- such circumstances we give people to understand, either explicitly or tac-
ple word, even though it contains parts ("con", "side", "red") which by itly, that we wish them to ascribe a sense to the sign which is as similar
themselves designate something, because here they do not do so. to its proper sense as is possible if the sentence is to express something
4) A sign which is used to signify more than one idea is called am- reasonable and true. This noteworthy way of using a sign I shall call a 72
biguous. Thus the German word "Tor" is an ambiguous sign, since it tropical mode of speech. Thus the word "fox" in the sentence "Go and
signifies porta [door] as well asfatuus [fool]. tell that fox!" (Luke 13, 32) is used tropically, since the context clearly
5) Often the reason why we use an object to designate an idea B is that indicates that one is not to take it in its proper sense, but rather to mean
we earlier used this object to designate a certain other idea A. In this case the cunning King Herod. In many cases the context in which the tropi-
the signification B is said to be derived from A. A signification which is cally used sign occurs is such that the tacit condition to attribute a sense
not derivative is said to be original. Thus the signification of the word to the sign that comes as close to its proper sense as possible if the sen-
movement when it is used for a mental change, is obviously derivative tence is to be true will permit us to determine this meaning easily and
from another, which indicates change of location; the latter is likely to be precisely. Sometimes, however, this is not the case, and we are not sure
original. which idea we should connect with the sign. In cases of the first sort, I
6) A sign is said to be indeterminate for us if we do not know what call the use of the sign metonymic, in the second, symbolic, figurative, or
idea the speaker wanted to designate by it. If there are two or more sig- metaphorical. Thus the use of the word "fox" in the above citation was
nifications which are equally likely, the sign is called vacillating. If we metonymic, since the context indicates clearly enough which idea we are
71 cannot guess at any idea which could be signified, we call it completely to connect with the word, namely, that of the cunning of this man.
incomprehensible. The more readily and reliably we recognise the signi- 9) It is to be expected that when we use a sign in order to bring forth
fication of a sign, the more distinctness we ascribe to it. The distinctness a given idea, it shall also evoke others which have been connected with it
of signs must be carefully distinguished from the distinctness of ideas through simultaneity. I shall call the latter secondary ideas. It is clearly
(§281). Instead of "distinct", we sometimes use the terms clear, pellu- important to know the nature of these secondary ideas-whether they are
cid, etc. It is easy to see that a sign which is vacillating or indeterminate weak or vivid, whether they arouse certain feelings and desires in us,
or even completely incomprehensible for a given reader in a given con- whether they might exercise a detrimental influence on our judgement,
text, may be understandable and determinate for another reader or in a etc. If the secondary ideas which come with a certain sign have a detri-
different context. Thus many of the passages in CICERO' s letters which mental influence upon our judgements, I call them harmful, and the sign
are indeterminate or completely incomprehensible for us may well have itself I call impure. By contrast, a sign without such harmful secondary
been comprehensible and determinate for those to whom the letters were ideas I call a pure expression. 73
addressed, or indeed to all of the learned people of that time. l 0) Often, instead of using a sign a for a given idea A, we use yet an-
7) A sign is used in its proper signification when it is used to des- other object a which is merely a sign for a itself. Thus, for example, the
ignate an idea it was intended to; otherwise it is used in an improper or word "God" is a sign of the concept of a being whose actuality is uncon-
borrowed sense.* A meaning which is at first improper may in time grad- ditioned. If, however, the person in whose mind we wish to bring forth
ually become proper. this concept is too far away to hear our voice, we produce various visible
signs (letters), which designate the sounds of which the word "God" is
composed, and which in the proper order designate the word itself. The
*The borrowed sense must not be confused with the extended sense, which is more sight of these signs will immediately bring forth the idea of the word
proper. When natural historians class bats among the apes, they take the latter word in an "God", and afterwards the idea of the object that the word designates.
extended sense. If, however, we say that under certain circumstances, a man is an ape. Signs of this sort, i.e., signs of other signs, I call indirect with respect
we speak in a borrowed sense.

46 47
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

to the ideas the latter designate. Signs which are not indirect are called in general that a derived meaning must always be related to the original 75
direct. A sign which was at first indirect can become direct with use. For meaning as a subordinate to a superordinate concept. The meaning of
since the idea of the sign o. brings forth the idea of the sign a, and a brings the word "cock" as used in engineering, for example, is certainly derived
forth the idea A, o. and A often occur at the same time, and thus can be frorn the meaning the word has in natural history, but is certainly not sub-
directly connected, so that the idea of o. brings forth the idea A, without ordinate to it. This example also shows that it is not necessary to go back
the intervention of the idea a. If a does not draw enough of our attention, to the original meaning of a word in order to give a satisfactory definition
it gradually drops out altogether. Thus for the beginner in astronomy, the of a given derived meaning of a word. Thus I believed that I could define
symbol =:::: is a sign of a scale, and indirectly of a certain constellation or the meaning of the word sign which belongs to logic (no. 1) without first
of an equinox. More experienced astronomers think directly of the latter defining the other sense from which it is derived. Just so, it has never
two, and the scale never occurs to them. occurred to any logician,* when defining the meaning of the word "con-
11) Finally, it should be noted that once we are accustomed to speak- clude" [schliej3en] as he uses it, to begin with the meaning the word has
74 ing, we almost always accompany our thoughts with symbols, even when for a locksmith [=to lock]. If the reader nevertheless wishes to know how
we have no intention whatsoever of communicating these thoughts to oth- r define the word sign in its original sense, I would say the following. If
ers. Thus we either actually produce these symbols, in whole or in part, smoke is called a sign of fire, and blushing a sign of guilt, this merely
or else we content ourselves with merely representing them. This process means that these are attributes which allow us to infer the existence of
could be called speaking to oneself Sometimes we do this unintention- other attributes (i.e., fire, or a guilty conscience). One looks upon the for-
ally, simply because our ideas are already so tightly connected to their mer attributes as signs of the latter insofar as one thinks that they are more
signs that the latter are produced every time we think the former; some- easily perceptible (at least in certain cases). A sign in this sense would
times we do this intentionally, perhaps in order to bring about a more accordingly be defined as an attribute, the recognition of which permits us
precise connection between our ideas and the signs allotted for them, or to know the existence of some other attribute. On this definition, both the
to make our thoughts more vivid, etc. Signs consisting in certain outer sign and the thing signified would be mere attributes. It might seem that
changes, the production of which is more bother or which might be no- independently existing things can also be signs of others-e.g., smoke
ticed by others contrary to our intentions, e.g., audible sounds, are rarely might be a sign of a burning house. On closer consideration, however,
brought forth completely; rather, we only produce ideas of them, or make I believe I may observe that the smoke in and of itself only allows us to
only some of the bodily movements required to bring them about-e.g., infer the existence of a burning object if it is looked upon as the effect
we merely move our lips, taking care not to produce even a whisper in so of the latter. Accordingly, it would not be the independently existing ob-
doing, etc. ject, smoke, but rather this attribute of the smoke which serves as a sign. 76
Note 1. It seems to me that the word sign has two quite distinct mean- And what we infer from this attribute is not so much the existence of the
ings. For when we call smoke a sign of fire and a blush a (not always burning object as the attribute of being on fire. But I will not insist on
reliable) sign of guilt, we mean by "sign" something quite different from this point, and it is easy to gather how the definition would have to be
when we say that the word "God" is a sign in the English language of the changed if the above objection were recognised as well-founded, namely,
concept of a being whose actuality is unconditioned. I will not deny that it instead of speaking of attributes, one would speak of objects in general.
would be possible to find a concept covering both of these meanings, but If the word sign is taken in this sense, it is interchangeable with the word
I do not think that this would be one of the meanings of the word "sign", indicator (§ 112). One may also call smoke an indicator of fire, blushing
and certainly not the original meaning from which the others are derived. an indicator of guilt.
For, first of all, it may occur by pure chance that two concepts, e.g.,fatuus Since we have opened the question of the definition of this concept
[fool] andjanua [door] have the same sign (Tor). And who would want of a sign, we cannot dismiss the question of how the other meaning, the
to claim that the concept encompassing the ideas fatuus and janua is the one we are obliged to consider here, was derived from it. This is not dif-
original meaning of the word Tor? In the second place, it is false to say
*With the possible exception of HEGEL.

48 49
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

ficult to guess. Sounds and other objects, the ideas of which are deployed cially in reflection, we use them with the definite intention of perceiving
in order to stimulate certain other ideas associated with them in another our own thoughts, and present them to ourselves with the chosen signs in
thinking being are, if not always, at least in most cases signs (indicators) roughly the same way we would present them to others.
that the ideas in question are present in the mind of the being that pro- Note 3. Natural signs are usually opposed not to contingent, but rather
duces those sounds or other objects. In formulating the definition in no. to conventional signs. In my view, conventional signs are merely a kind of
1, I presupposed that we only directly present ideas, and not propositions contingent sign. It seems to me that JAKOB (Psych., §410), KIESEWET-
or judgements, by means of signs. Nevertheless, the latter seems to hap- TER (L., Part 2, §76), MAAS (G1: d. L., §482) define the concept of a 78
pen, in that we sometimes express an entire proposition not by means of natural sign too narrnwly when they require either that there be a causal
a combination of words, but instead by a single word, e.g., morior. 1 I relation between the sign and the signified thing or that some third thing
believe, however, that such words and combinations of words do not im- be the cause of both. Are not two raised fingers a natural sign of the num-
mediately present the proposition as such, but rather only an idea of it. ber two? But can they be looked at as cause or effect of this number?
Thus the sign only indirectly presents the proposition, just as the sign of Or is there a third thing which causes both? The most correct defini-
an objectual idea may be said to be a sign of the object itself. But if this tion of a conventional sign may well be HOFFBAUER'S ( L., §112): "A
is not so, this may not be of great importance. sign is conventional when its signification is fixed intentionally." For the
The concept of a sign is often defined in almost the same way I have sake of distinctness, however, I would add, that this intention was pro-
here defined it. One reads in JAKOB' s Psych. (§352): "Ideas used to re- duced through purely contingent circumstances, for intentions may also
tain or stimulate the effects of the understanding are called signs." More be present with natural signs.
77 distinctly, KIESEWETTER writes (Log., Part II, §74): "A sign is an object Note 4. It is difficult to determine what should be looked upon as
the intuition of which serves to bring another idea to mind." Compare a single, though complex, sign and what should be considered a collec-
also METZ (L., §214), CALKER (L., §211), among others. I have only tion of several signs. According to the definition of no. 3, a collection
two objections to these definitions. First, the way in which the idea stim- of several signs is a whole, the parts of which are themselves signs and
ulates the signified idea, namely, because the two are associated, should indeed signs of individual ideas, whose combination produces what the
be mentioned. Second, it is not necessary that the object used as a sign in whole collection indicates. A single but complex sign, by contrast, con-
fact serve to awaken the signified idea; rather, it is sufficient that it is used sists of parts which ar·e indeed chosen to remind us of the idea it is sup-
with this intention. A sign remains just that, even if it is misunderstood posed to signify, but these parts do not represent all the constituents of
or remains unheeded. Older logicians seem to have thought more of the this idea. Instead, they either bear some similarity to signs belonging
original meaning of the word in formulating their definitions. Signum est, to these constituents (e.g., hodie 1); or they only represent some of them
quad nos in rei cujusdam a se distinctce cognitionem deducit. 2 On this (e.g., providere 2 ); or they do not represent constituents of the concept at
definition, the sight of an achromatic telescope could be called a sign of all, but only certain attributes of its object (e.g., lectisternium 3 ), and the
Euler, if it reminded us that he was its inventor. It could also be called a like. Incidentally, there also seem to be exceptions to this definition. Ac-
sign of a comet, in case we used it to discover the comet. cording to it, for example, the name of the flower Noli me tangere would
Note 2. HOBBES (Log., ch. 2, §2 and ch. 6, § 11) considered words be only one word, though orthographers require that we divide it into
from two points of view, as characteristics (notae) of our thought, when three parts. It seems to me, however, that they do so only because the
we use them ourselves, and as signs (signa) when we use them to com- concatenation of so many letters in a single word would make it difficult
municate our thoughts to others. It seems to me that this distinction is to read. Though orthographers should incorporate this in their definitions
inessential. For even when we use words ourselves, this usually does not of what counts as a sign, the same can hardly be required of logicians.
occur from mere habit and is not completely unintentional. Rather, espe-
1
I.e., hoc die, this day.
1 2
I die. To see ahead, look ahead pro+videre.
2 3
A sign is something that leads us to knowledge of a thing distinct from itself. "Spreading a couch"-the name of a Roman propitiatory ceremony.

50 51
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

Nore 5. In my opinion, the concepts of tropical, metonymical and the other. A sign requires intention: either I must utter the word rose with
79 metaphorical use of language set out in no. 8 may be justified not by the intention of producing the idea of a rose in myself or in somebody
their agreement with prevailing usage, but rather on the basis of their else, or I must recognise that somebody else is acting with such an in-
importance. Even if the terms be found wanting, the concepts I desig- tention. But for such intentional actions, as well as for their recognition,
nate with them are certainly worthy of notice. It is undeniable that there judgements are required: thus it follows that even prior to the first sign
are innumerable cases where we use single words and turns of phrase in we invent, or that we recognise as invented by others, judgements must
the way I have called speaking tropically, namely, where we require our have taken place.
interlocutors to take a word in another sense, similar to its proper signifi- Note 7. Treatises on logic often investigate the problem of the origin
cation, when taking it in its proper signification would result in absurdity, of language. I should also like to make some suggestions on this subject.
and where the similarity is constrained only by the assumption that our It seems certain that man did not invent language in order to speak to him-
sentence expresses something true and reasonable. Is not this way of us- self, but to speak to others; hence it depends upon the social connections
ing a sign noteworthy enough to merit its own designation? And should which he has formed with other men. Man is so constituted that most of
one not distinguish the two sub-cases which might occur, one where the his thoughts, sensations, wishes, and intentions, even without his knowl-
meaning of the sign is sufficiently determined by this condition, and the edge and intent, are with more or less accuracy reflected and recognisable
other where it remains vacillating and indeterminate? It seems to me that in his facial expressions, gestures, sounds, etc. From the fact that he is
only in these cases should one strive to avoid improper expressions. fixing his eyes upon a certain object, we can see that he is thinking about
Note 6. It can be seen from no. 11 that and why (in my opinion) ev- this object; and it is even more obvious whether somebody experiences
erybody who has once learned a language also uses it even when he does pleasure or pain, desire or aversion, courage or fear, etc. We can see
not actually intend to communicate his thoughts to others. I should like these things in each other, and the outward appearance of another person 81
to add that if we did not use the medium of language, all of our thinking is for us an indicator of his inner life; this does not require the degree
would become very uncertain; particularly, it would be difficult to han- of sophistication which can be acquired only through language, for even
dle complex ideas which do not have a sensible object, unless we had deaf mutes, children, and idiots can achieve it; even animals, devoid of
definite signs for them.* However, I do not dare claim that without this language and reason, dogs, apes, and others can see from our facial ex-
medium no thinking, especially no judging, could take place at all. I do pressions whether we are angry or afraid, etc. A man, unless nature has
not find convincing the reasons adduced by the two REINHOLDS (father ravaged him, will acquire more capacities as he grows older: he will not
and son) in support of this (see Das menschliche ErkenntnijJvermogen only see what others experience inside, but he will also know by what
usw., Kiel, 1816 and Theorie des Erkenntnij3vermogens, Gotha, 1832). signs he sees it and, consequently, what others can see in him. It seems
80 For one thing, beings of a higher order than we are (at least God) do not that even among the animals some reach this degree of understanding,
need signs in order to think, but it is also the case that creatures less per- though not with clear consciousness. How else can we explain that they
fect than ourselves, namely, animals, do not need signs for their ideas in sometimes behave as if they did something without really doing it? In
order to form judgements. Now from what human characteristic does it any case, there is no doubt that children and mutes have this ability. But
follow that we of all beings require signs in order to judge? HOFFBAUER when man had come to the point of knowing that such and such facial
(Psych., § 126) has pointed out correctly that the use of signs presupposes expressions, gestures, sounds, movements, etc., made others believe that
thinking without signs. For in order for the word "rose" to become a sign he had such and such ideas in him, then he was in a position to use these
of the idea "rose", it is not enough that both ideas should have occurred external changes as signs in the proper sense of the word, i.e., as objects
simultaneously in my soul and should thereby have become associated. from whose perception others are to infer the presence of certain ideas in-
For there are thousands of associated ideas none of which is the sign of side him. This means that a certain language had been invented; it did not
consist of anything but certain voluntary motions of the body which fol-
* DAMIRON has many excellent remarks on the advantages of language in thinking low automatically upon certain changes in the soul, and which were now
(Psych., t. 2, p. 108 seq.).

52 53
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 285. Of Ideas

used merely to represent these changes. Men cried out when they wanted was initially merely a sign for the desire for this object. But once it was
to represent pain, and stomped their feet when they wanted to represent realised that others look at an object to which one extends his hand and
anger, etc. If we call this oldest language a language of gestures, we that a certain idea was thus generated in them, they must have had the
should not forget that sounds as well as looks and facial expressions of- idea of using this extension of hands even if they did not want to express
ten were connected with the gestures, at least those sounds which were their desire to have the object, but merely wanted others to look at it and
imitations of certain involuntary expressions of our inner life. form its idea. In order to avoid misunderstanding, they probably changed
Most objects found in the environment of man, especially those at- the gesture somewhat: the grasping of the object became a mere pointing
tracting his attention to a higher degree, namely, animals, made certain with the finger. This example was probably not the only one leading men
noises from time to time: the sheep bleated, the lion roared, the spring to the discovery that, in order to signify an object, it is not necessary to
82 murmured. From a mere desire to imitate, if for no other reason, man produce something that is similar to it; all that mattered was to make oth-
would attempt to copy these various tones and sounds. When he suc- ers understand that such and such an utterance indicated that they were
ceeded to some extent, he found that the idea of the entire object was to form an idea of a certain object. Once this discovery was made it be-
renewed in his mind as often as he produced the sound which was appro- came possible to invent new signs every clay; the only thing required was
priate to this object, or whenever he heard this sound. It is not astonishing to point to a certain object while uttering a certain sound or perform an
that, later on, the production of these sounds was used in order to cause in otherwise insignificant action. In this way a third kind of language, the
others the ideas of the corresponding objects; thus these sounds now be- conventional language, came into being. This language was a sound or
came signs of those objects. But the sound of a thing is not the only thing word language, i.e., most of its conventional signs were sounds or tones;
that can be copied. It was probably soon realised that other peculiarities this can be explained from more than one circumstance. Sounds are the
of things, e.g., their way of moving, their posture, etc., can sometimes be signs that can be most easily produced. When hands and feet are bound
imitated with the result that this imitation produces an idea of the thing or busy, the tongue is still free. Sounds can be perceived by clay and night.
itself. Hence these imitations, too, will have been accepted as signs, and a Sounds are signs with which we can force our thoughts upon somebody
limping person will have been signified by limping about, a blind person who does not, at the moment, pay attention to us, or even does not want 84
by groping to and fro with closed eyes, etc. Hence a second, much more to pay attention to us. Sounds are signs the author perceives in the same
complete language was invented, namely, the language of imitation or way as the others, a circumstance which makes learning easy. Sounds are
similarity; it is characteristic of this language that reference to an object is signs through which, aside from their actual meaning, merely through the
made by producing something resembling it. Just as the language of ges- way in which they are produced, we can express our state of mind; we
tures was not confined to gestures in the narrower sense, so the language can indicate whether we speak seriously or in a jocular way, whether we
of imitation did not use merely gestures and sounds, or mere motions of feel well or ill, whether we like the listener or dislike him, etc. Sounds,
the body, but probably also other objects which were at hand; for exam- finally, are signs whose modulation can influence the mood of the hearer,
ple, it is likely that drawings were made. The combination of these two can make him glad or sad, etc. It is understandable that, given all these
kinds of language-it is understood that the first was not given up after advantages of sounds, they were used almost exclusively, except when
the second was invented-made it possible not only to signify most inner the addressee was absent, or deaf. Considering that the subject of the ori-
states (namely, those whose high degree of vividness produced physical gin of human language cannot be exhausted in a note, but only hinted at,
changes), but also most external objects, so long as they had a property I break the discussion off at this point. DEGERANDO' s thoughts on the
which made them conspicuous and which could be somehow imitated. subject are similar (Des signes et de I' art de Pens er, 4 Vols., Paris 1798,
Things directly in front of them they probably indicated very early, sim- Vol. 1, p. 105 ff.).
ply by pointing with their hand or finger: a sign which, in a sense, is of a
83 special kind. It probably derives from the fact that one has to extend his
hand in order to grasp an object; consequently, the extension of the hand

54 55
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 286. Of Ideas

§.286.* 4) When we make use of our faculty of judgement, making judge-


ments about the various objects to whi~h the ideas we have formed apply,
Description of the most important ivays in ·which ideas originate ·rely new ideas sometimes appear 111 our soul, not yet separately, but
entl 'ts of these J. udgements. For example, the concept of"h avmg
· 1s
· l'k
1 e1y
l
~~· . . .
to have originated on the occasion of our first judgement, as the copula of
We must now consider in a few words the difficult problem of the origin
that judgement. .
of our ideas. To begin with, we must make a distinction between simple
5) We also have the ability to attend, i.e., to voluntarily cause an
and complex ideas.
idea now present in us to become more vivid than it would have be~n
J) We can say very little about the mode of origin of simple ideas
0
therwise. Although we accomplish this directly, or at least in certain
precisely because they are simple. All we can claim is that the mind
ses by voluntarily bringing about suitable changes in our bodies, it is
must have a faculty for producing them. This faculty becomes active only ~ .
certain that this attending does not immediately result in the production
under certain circumstances and stimuli. In particular, the kind of simple
of new ideas. Instead, ideas already present become more vivid. But as
ideas we called intuitions (§278) differs sharply from the other simple
more vivid ideas call forth greater numbers of associated ideas, and also
ideas (i.e., pure, simple concepts) in that they are the next and immediate
prompt our faculty of judgement to be more act.ive, it is under~tandable
85 (hence unexplainable) effect of certain changes within us; consequently,
that the voluntary direction we give to our attention has a very important
these changes are the objects represented by these ideas. Depending on
influence upon the formation of ideas.
whether these changes are themselves already ideas (or even judgements)
6) It sometimes happens that we wish to procure an idea we have
we can distinguish two kinds of intuition. Intuitions which have as their
never before had, or to renew one we had before. What we do to achieve
object another idea present in our mind may be called internal intuitions;
this can be called seeking out ideas. This is sometimes a matter of paying
if the object is a change which is not itself an idea, the intuition may
attention to ideas already present in us which we deem to be associated
be called external, because the question of the origin of such intuitions
with the one we seek. In other cases we attempt to bring about changes
leads us immediately to suppose that there is an external object which
in the outer world so that an object capable of producing the idea in us
effected this change in our mind. Experience shows that under certain
appears. Although such efforts do not always succeed, they do so at least 87
circumstances the most divergent external objects can cause intuitions
sometimes, and thus can be looked upon as a special means for generating
in us which are so similar that we can often detect no difference at all
ideas. Should someone object that the resolution to form a certain idea
between them. Thus we see red not only when we are confronted with
A presupposes the existence of this idea in our soul, I would reply as
a red body, but sometimes also without one, namely, when the eye is
follows: this resolution does not require the presence of the idea A itself,
pathologically affected in certain ways.
but only the presence of an idea of it, i.e., the existence of an idea which
2) Pure, simple concepts originate in a much different manner. Their
applies to it (either exclusively or not). For example, even if I do not
origin betrays a much greater activity of the mind. There is no doubt that
remember what bread is called in Russian (and thus cannot now form an
they are always occasioned by the presence of other ideas; it is likely that
idea of this), I can still resolve to find out, i.e., to bring to mind the idea
a new simple concept arises only when it proceeds from ideas currently
of this word.
in us in order to combine them to form a new idea or, instead, a complete
7) An activity which is opposed in a way to combination (no. 3) is
judgement.
that of separation or abstraction. The latter consists in directing one's
3) According to §277 it does not suffice for the explanation of the
attention to one of the individual parts found in a complex idea or even in
origin of complex ideas to assume merely that the several simple ideas
an entire judgement, and thus becoming aware of it as an idea in its own
that are its parts became active at the same time. Rather, we must as-
right and as such an object of our further reflection. Separation cannot
sume an activity of the mind made it happen that these several ideas were
indeed produce a new idea, but through it many ideas which are already
combined into a whole which is itself an idea. This formation of ideas is
86 called the formation of ideas by combination or synthesis.

56 57
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 286. Of Ideas

present without our being aware of it may become clear or even distinct. I do not detect even the most remote reference to a moment present or
Permit me to call such ideas abstracted. past. The more I think about it, the more probable it seems to me that the
8) It is true that all our complex ideas are synthesised by an activity of e:eneral ideas which are now under discussion are, all of them, nothing
our own, but it does not follow from this that we are always conscious of but concepts of certain laws that govern the changes in the mind that are
the parts of such ideas, even if we are conscious of the ideas themselves the objects of our intuitions. It seems obvious that the mental changes
(cf. §281). It is common, especially with ideas that we have formed in which take place when we see must be different from those that occur
88 early childhood and have frequently repeated since, that we can no longer when we hear or smell, they must be of a different kind when we see
identify their parts. This is because whenever we renew these ideas they something that we call red than when it is something we call yellow or
fly past our mind with such a speed that our intuitive faculty does not blue, etc. But should it be so unlikely that our mind brings the peculiarity
have enough time to grasp the individual parts. I believe that this holds of each of these changes under concepts? It judges, for example, that a
particularly for the lower generic ideas under which we subsume external certain state repeats itself several times, or that this repetition takes place
intuitions, i.e., the general ideas of colours, sounds, odours, etc., thus in equal or unequal or constantly increasing or decreasing intervals, etc.
particularly ideas like: red, blue, yellow, sweet, bitter, etc. I consider all If this is the case, would it not be understandable that it happens in a way
generic ideas of sensation to be complex, though I am still quite unable which makes it impossible for us ever to become distinctly aware of it, 90
to indicate the simple parts of even a single one of them. If any one since the speed with which the individual ideas pass by is much too fast
of these ideas were simple, it would have to be either an intuition or a to allow us to perceive them individually?
concept. But these ideas are not intuitions, since they are general ideas, 9) The preceding and §285 make it obvious that language and social
i.e., since they have not one, but several objects. But I can also not agree intercourse have a very great influence upon the origin and formation of
that they are simple concepts if for no other reason than that for every one our ideas. We designate our ideas with special words, i.e., we associate
of them there is another one incompatible with the first, but where the two idea and word through simultaneity; this has as a consequence that every
domains are so closely adjacent that it is often doubtful whether a given recurrence of the idea makes the word come to mind, and conversely.
intuition should be subsumed under one or the other. Thus red and yellow Through social relations with other persons, especially if we hear them
are so closely adjacent that we often do not know whether we should call call several objects by the same name, we are led to consider what the
a given intuition one or the other. The same holds for the colours blue common attributes of these objects are, and we form the concept of a
and green, green and yellow, etc. A similar point can be made regarding thing which has all these attributes as the one presumably designated by
sounds, odours, tastes, etc. This phenomenon is difficult to explain on the that name.
assumption that the indicated ideas are simple concepts; but it is easily 10) It is clear from this that most of our ideas originate without our
understood if we assume that they are complex ideas containing concepts wanting to produce them. We can call them only given ideas; those pro-
of quantity. Thus the only remaining question is whether these complex duced by a conscious and deliberate activity may be called factitious.
89 ideas are pure concepts, or whether they contain some intuitions as parts. Since the creation of a compound idea is conceivable only if its compo-
I must confess that I have of late been inclined toward the first alternative. nent simple ideas are already at hand, we may call simple ideas original,
I came to this conclusion by considering that each intuition of which man and compound ideas derivative.
is capable has as its proper object a change that occurs in the mind at 11) We have already seen that the simple ideas must be either pure
the same time, hence something that is in existence only for a very short intuitions or pure concepts. Now the external causes that play a role in
time. From this it follows that we can detect a certain reference to a point the generation of both kinds of idea have a much greater share in the
in time (a present or past now) in any idea that contains an intuition as production of intuitions (if they are external) than of concepts. From
a part. Thus the mixed nature of the idea "Socrates" becomes apparent, this it follows that intuitions indicate a certain object as their cause. For 91
because I think of a philosopher by that name about 2000 years before the sake of this difference it should be permissible to say of our simple
the present moment. But in the ideas: red, sweet, fragrant, and the like, concepts that they are innate, but of all other ideas, i.e., of intuitions, as

58 59
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 286. Of Ideas

well as of compound concepts and mixed ideas, that they are acquired. which everyone finds between such sensible concepts and others that are
This must not be interpreted as if all simple concepts are with us fro111 completely divorced from the senses, such as possibility, necessity, etc.
birth, but rather only that the external world plays a much smaller role in The former are concepts whose appearance is always accompanied by a
their origin than is the case with external intuitions. number of intuitions roused from their slumber, while the latter can call
Note. The claim made in no. 8 that general concepts of colours, upon none. Concerning animals, finally, we know far too little of what
sounds, odours, and so on are pure complex concepts may meet with the really occurs with their senses to raise an objection of this kind. It might
greatest resistance. It will be said that if this were the case, we should be correct to say that animals, too, have the capacity for concepts, only
all be able to communicate any such concept by verbally indicating the not the capacity to become conscious of them; in this case it would not be
simple concepts of which it is composed, without the help of a sensible strange that animals approach and even surpass man in the minuteness of
object producing an intuition standing under the concept. But it is well their sensory discrimination. But even without this assumption, is it more
known that this cannot be done: to convey what bitter means to someone, surprising that animals discriminate between colours, sounds and odours,
we must give him something bitter to taste. And a man born blind could than that they comprehend spatial relations, which man always represents
never form the idea we connect with the word red, no matter how long we through concepts? 93
spent describing it. It will be asked, further, if I do not sense the immense
difference between the ideas red, sweet, pleasantly fragrant, and the like §.287.
on the one hand and possibility, necessity, morally good, etc., which are
decidedly pure concepts, on the other. Finally, one will ask how I in- Other views on the subject
tend to explain how even the lowest species of animals could form such
intricately complex pure concepts (as sensible general concepts must be The question of the origin of our ideas has long been considered one of
on my account)-for it is well known that they often distinguish colours, the most difficult, and has received some decidedly odd answers.
sounds, odours and the like more precisely than we do. I reply that we 1) We find ridiculous the view of logicians who consider the soul a
would only be in a position to teach by words alone what red or blue, material substance, in which objects make impressions through the senses
sweet or bitter are when we have attained a distinct awareness of the con- and thus create ideas. Even disregarding the reasons in favour of the
92 cepts of which these generic ideas are composed. We have not yet, as I
simplicity of the soul, this explanation would still have to be rejected as
admitted, succeeded in doing so. But even if we knew these constituents, unsatisfactory, for we do not merely have intuitions, but also many other
I do not claim that the concepts we could communicate by such a defini- ideas, e.g., of supersensible objects, or indeed objectless ideas.
tion, e.g., the idea of redness we might produce in the mind of someone 2) In recent times, some have claimed it to be incomprehensible how
who was born blind, would be exactly the same as what we think by the the soul, being simple, should be capable of forming an idea of a complex
word red. For us, who have already had many intuitions subordinate to object. It seems to me that the difficulty they claim to have discovered is
this concept (i.e., have seen many red things), the articulation of this word merely imagined. The principle: "Like can only know like," even if it is
gives rise to more or less vivid recollections of all these earlier intuitions, older than EMPEDOCLES, is still unproven and false. For since the soul
since each is associated with the concept of red in general by the law of can think of contrary things, e.g., the round as well as the square, it would
simultaneity (it became so when we formed the judgement "This (what have to be both round and square according to this principle.
we see right now) is something red" at the time we had the intuitions). 3) Concerning the species of our ideas which apply to several sensi-
Such recollections of intuitions we had earlier, which stand under the ble objects, the sensible general ideas (e.g., man, flower, etc.) almost all
given concept, could never be associated by a blind man with his concept. philosophers have described their origin roughly as follows: "Through
Indeed, it might even be possible for him to have recourse to intuitions the impressions which individual objects make on our soul (via the or-
~ans of the body), intuitions arise. These either endure when the object
which stand under concepts that are merely similar and to compare, say,
red to the sound of a trnmpet. Now we understand the immense difference is no longer nearby, though they become weaker, or else they leave some 94
traces in the soul once they have disappeared, which are renewed when

60 61
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 287. Of Ideas

another, similar object appears. If the soul receives many intuitions of 4) Only the adherents of the Critical Philosophy believe they have
similar objects, it perceives in them certain common characteristics (no- proved that every intuition must contain a plurality, and indeed must con-
tas communes), and when it allows the other characteristics (which differ) tain infinitely many parts. KIESEWETTER adduces the following proof
to fade from consciousness, while combining the common ones, a con- (W A. d. L., §51, p. 165): "In the critique of the cognitive faculties it
cept is formed." PLATO (e.g., in Phileb.) and ARISTOTLE (De anim., is shown that all our inner intuitions must be situated in time, and all
Book 3, ch. 3, 4, and 8) already seem to have looked upon the matter our external intuitions in time and space. For these are the conditions
in this way. Among the moderns, KIESEWETTER (W A. d. L., I, p. 69 under which we can have intuitions. Now since time and space are di-
ff.; II, p. 171 ff.), KRUG (Fundam., §79) and many others, hold similar visible ad infinitum, our intuitions must also be divisible ad infinitum."
views. On this account, the intuition, i.e., the idea which is produced I too believe that every one of our ideas fills (not, indeed, a space!, but
immediately through the action of an external object, would have to be nevertheless) a certain time, and insofar as it does so must be composed
composed of a number of other ideas, namely, of all the concepts which of an infinite number of parts. These parts, however, are not coexistent,
one can procure from it through analysis. For if the characteristics: "a but only successive. From their presence it obviously cannot be inferred 96
Roman, a learned man, a writer, etc." occur in the ideas: Cicero, Caesar, that the objective idea, which appears to us in this subjective idea, is also
Horace, etc., in such a way that they can simply be separated from them, complex, as it would have to be, if the subjective idea were to be called
the latter ideas (Cicero, etc.) must contain the former (i.e., the ideas: a complex.
Roman, etc.) as constituents. Thus they must be complex. Indeed, since 5) Another peculiarity of the way the Critical Philosophy explains the
the number of such characteristics admittedly extends to infinity, they origin of our ideas, particularly the empirical ones, is the claim that the
must be composed of infinitely many parts. Now even if one doesn't find faculty of imagination must be active in the production of every idea, even
anything impossible in such infinitely complex ideas, it can in no way be intuitions. Thus KIESEWETTER writes (ibid.): "It takes time to compre-
assumed that such ideas could be produced by the immediate action of an hend a plurality; if we had no faculty of imagination we would not be able
external object on our soul. Rather, it seems indisputable to me that the to have any intuitions. For otherwise, in comprehending a plurality, the
production of every complex idea requires a special activity of our soul in ideas of the preceding part would have disappeared from consciousness,
order to unite the simple parts. Even supposing that the ideas "red, pleas- and no combination of the plurality would be possible." In my view, ev-
95 antly fragrant, prickly" were produced immediately through the action of ery idea, even the simplest, must exist for a certain finite time in the soul,
an external object, the idea which is supposed to be composed of all of for it is an alteration; several ideas can and must exist at the same time.
them (the idea, perhaps, of an object which possesses the collection of For this reason, I do not see why it follows from the reason cited that
all of these attributes) would not yet be present; its production would re- the imagination must be active in the production of every complex idea.
quire a special activity of my soul, and indeed would also require certain For why must one idea have disappeared from our consciousness before
ideas which most certainly were not immediately produced by that ob- we arrive at another? But even if this were the case, how could one say
ject, such as the concept of a being, that of possessing certain attributes, that we had produced the complex idea from the individual ideas which
of a collection, etc. In my opinion, the idea which the external object had already disappeared, for indeed, it would no longer be these ideas
produces in our soul through its action is always a simple idea (this), and themselves, but rather reminiscences or memories of them.
that, consequently, concepts such as "red, pleasantly fragrant" and so on, 6) A similar enw in the explanation of sensible general ideas, in my
under which we subsume the object indicated by the simple idea, are not opinion, is made by those who explain all abstracted ideas in a way which
characteristics of the object which are to be found as constituents of its claims that the abstracted idea first appears in the soul during the process
idea (not notae constitutivae), but rather only the kind we believe we may of abstraction. In my view, it must already be present when our soul-
ascribe to the object. This also explains why we are sometimes mistaken forms the complex idea from which it is abstracted-though I do allow 97
in doing this, which would be all but incomprehensible if these character- that we may not have been distinctly aware of it, especially if the complex
istics were the immediate effect of the external impression. idea was formed in our youth. Thus only when we speak of what we

62 63
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 287. Of Ideas

are distinctly conscious can I agree with the distinction E. REINHOLD consequently are not produced by reflection. On this definition, there
(Erk. L., p. 392) makes between concepts which are produced analytically would have to be innate ideas, but these would only be intuitions, which
and those which are produced synthetically-for a concept is produced are usually reckoned among the acquired ideas. DESCARTES defined
analytically only when we previously produced it synthetically, though innate (or natural) ideas as those, quae nee ab objectis, nee a volun-
without being aware of doing so. tatis determinatione procedunt; sed a sofa facultate cogitandi necessitate
7) The ideas which I said were complex in no. 8 of the preceding sec- quadam naturae ipsius 1nentis manant. 1 This definition seems quite close
tion are usually claimed quite firmly to be simple, so much so that they are to mine, and in any case, under it one has good reason to claim that such
adduced as indisputable examples of simple ideas. Even HERBART does concepts exist. Only the examples DESCARTES cites, the concept of God,
this (Lehrb. d. Psych., § 124 and elsewhere). It is obvious what has given of a mind, of a substance, etc., are not so well chosen, for none of them
rise to this opinion, namely, our inability to give a definition (analysis) is a completely simple concept. In addition, the appeal to intuitiveness
of these ideas, and the related inability to teach them verbally to anyone (intuitivitas et evidentia) as an indicator of innateness is insufficient. For 99
who is not acquainted with individual objects standing under them. It if one were to take this intuitiveness in its proper sense, and thus demand
will be admitted that this incapacity-which may well exist only in acer- that innate concepts apply to intuitions, it is not clear how the concept
tain respect and for a certain time-is no compelling proof. On the other of Goel, which might with still greater right be counted among the innate
hand, the opposing claim is supported not only by the reasons mentioned ideas (and this holds for many other concepts), could be intuitive. But
in the previous §,but by many other circumstances as well. We have actu- if by intuitiveness one just means vividness, the distinction between in-
ally succeeded in a certain measure in analysing some of these ideas, and nate and acquired ideas would be one of more or less, which is by no
these are so similar to the others that if they were simple, the others would means what they intend. LOCKE (Ess., I, iii) disputes the theory of in-
be as well. Thus much of what acoustics teaches us about the nature of nate ideas principally because he thought that a concept, if innate, must
certain souncls-e.g., that a pure tone is one which consists of uniform be present in the soul before it had any experience, something which is
oscillations-can be looked upon as a definition of these ideas (though admittedly absurd. He was completely right to claim that all our ideas
not an exhaustive one). The remarks of LEIBNIZ are also pertinent here arise through experience. But he overlooked that one may admit this and
(Nouv. Ess, II, ii). He noted that we are sometimes able to produce one of still make a distinction concerning the way that experience brings about
these supposedly simple ideas Min ourselves merely by putting ourselves ideas in us, a distinction which justifies us calling some of them innate.
98 in a position to be simultaneously affected by two or more objects, which LEIBNIZ (Nouv. Ess., p. 62) counters that when it is said that innate ideas
in isolation would have produced in us the ideas A,B,C. For instance, we are in our soul from birth, this should not be understood to mean that the
can obtain the idea of a green colour if we allow a pair of objects, one actual ideas are, but rather only a certain disposition to form them (des
of which would produce the idea "blue", the other the idea "yellow", to habitudes nature Iles, c 'est-cl-di re, des dispositions et attitudes actives et
affect our eyes either simultaneously or in rapid succession. This exper- passives, et plus que tabula rasa 2 ). He illustrates this with the image of
iment makes it quite probable that the idea M is somehow compounded a piece of marble which has not yet been chiseled into a statue, but in
from the ideas A, B, C. which there are already certain veins that betoken it. But when (ib., p. 34)
8) With respect to the famous debate over whether among our ideas he extended the concept of innate truths to all purely conceptual truths,
some are innate and others acquired, it all comes down to precisely defin- and at the same time extended the concept of innate ideas to cover all
ing what is meant, something with which people have not been very con- pure concepts (including the complex), he himself seems to have sensed
cerned. For when the PLATONISTS defined innate ideas as a kind of light
implanted in the soul by Goel, in which it intuits the objects of its knowl- 1which proceed neither from objects nor from a determination of the will, but rather
edge, it is obvious that not much can be done with such a figurative defini- flow from the faculty of thinking alone, by a certain necessity of the nature of the mind
tion. By contrast, the EPICUREANS and the STOICS understood by innate itself.
2 natural tendencies, that is, active and passive dispositions and attitudes, and more
ideas those that arrive in the soul immediately by way of the senses, and
than a tabula rasa

64 65
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 287. Of Ideas

that he went too far (Mais si quelqu 'un donne un autre sens aux paroles, the distinction defined in §73 between pure and mixed concepts, should
je ne veux point disputer des mots 1); for complex ideas are produced be rejected, and that the latter should take the place of the former.
through an activity of the soul (namely, combination), which is essen- 1()) The peculiar way in which HER BART (Lehrb. d. Psycho!.; also
lOO tially different from the activity involved in the appearance of any simple the larger work [on Psychology]) explains the origin of our ideas cannot
concept. ULRICH (Inst. Log., § 120) suggested a middle path, but one be evaluated in detail here. I shall confine myself to the following few
which is quite meandering. For can one not say of all our ideas, even the remarks. (a) From §§52, 270, and other places one knows the opinions
intuitions and the most complex of concepts, that they dwell in the soul which led HERBART to abandon the most common theses concerning the
merely virtually, as he demands? The theory of PLATNER is no clearer nature of our ideas, and why I cannot agree with these reasons. It is
(Aph., §661 ff.). In MAAJ3's G1: d. L. (§458), one reads: "A pure con- also not clear to me how the contradiction he claims to have discovered
cept (i.e., one which is not derived from experience) is called innate if it in the usual theory would be avoided in his theory. For simply declar-
is actually in the soul without having been produced or acquired through ing all ideas and, if you will, all other mental phenomena as well, to be
the soul's own activity." It is not up to Logic to decide whether or not mere self-preservation, i.e., powers through which the soul protects itself
there are any such innate concepts. Nevertheless, MAAJ3 gives us to un- against the disturbances which would occur in its simple nature [Qualiteit]
derstand (§459, note 1) that at most the concepts of the proper activities due to the action of an external object, by no means removes the neces-
of the understanding and those of the determination of things in general sity of ascribing many attributes (many acts of self-preservation) to the
are innate in this sense. In my opinion, however, one cannot suppose that soul, and indeed ascribing contrary attributes to it at different times-i.e.,
any idea is actual without assuming as its cause a certain activity in the alterations. And if it is contradictory to think that a being changes, or
being that has it. For everything actual, with the sole exception of the di- that one affects another, then there can be no acts of self-preservation (as
vine being, must have a ground of its actuality. And if what is actual is a I already pointed out in §270), for the concept of these presupposes the
change which occurs in a being, like an idea, the ground of this actuality possibility of action and change. It is something like the so-called force of 102
must lie at least in part in this being itself, i.e., this being must bring about inertia (vis inertiae ), which is defined as a force by means of which every
this change in part through its own activity. Thus if, as GEJ3NER claims body strives to remain in the state in which it has been put by an external
(Speculat. u. Traum, Vol. 2, p. 165), only that can be called innate which cause. Just as this force cannot exist without an external cause, for in that
a man has from nature, without contributing anything to it by means of case there is in actuality nothing which strives to change the state of the
his own activity, then there can certainly be no innate concepts. body, so too there can be no acts of self-preservation if there are no be-
9) The reader will readily gather what I think of the principle set out ings capable of disturbing the constitution of others through their action.
by GASSENDI, HOBBES, LOCKE and so many other philosophers both (b) It also seems incorrect to me to say that the mere simultaneous exis-
ancient and modern: Nihil in intellectu potest, quad non prius fuerit in tence of several acts of self-preservation suffices for the production of a
sensu. 2 To wit: I believe it is incoITect. For in my view, only simple complex idea, since I think that a certain combination of these is neces-
101 and unconnected ideas (intuitions) come to us through the senses, for sary to produce a proper whole. (c) From § 125 of the Lehrb. and other
example, this (which is a red colour), this (which is a pleasant fragrance), places in HERBART' s writings it seems to follow that it is not actually the
and so on. All other ideas, in particular all concepts and complex ideas acts of self-preservation themselves but rather effects of these produced
are not the products of the senses, but rather of ce1tain other activities, under certain conditions, which HERBART calls ideas. Now HERBART
as has already been made quite clear by the author of the Ars cogitandi does not at bottom deny that these effects, and thus the actual ideas, come
(I, 1). For this reason, I think that the classification of concepts as either to be and pass away. For when he says, e.g., that an idea is transformed
a priori or a posteriori, which is rooted in an incoITect understanding of into a mere striving to represent, it is clear that the idea itself is no longer
present. Now how do these changes come about, if a being's powers
1But if someone wants to attach different meanings to the words, I don't wish to enter
never change? In order to deal with this difficulty, HERBART places all
into a verbal dispute.
2 Nothing can be in the intellect which was not previously in the senses.
substances in an intelligible space, where they move about on various oc-

66 67
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 287. Of Ideas

casions. [t seems to me, however, that if nothing ever changes in the inner hich are red, sweet, etc. (I see things quite differently.) Finally, he
attributes of these beings, such motions in intelligible space (changes of ~inks that all ideas which come to exist in the human mind are produced
intelligible place) are inconceivable. (d) Nor do I understand how the and composed from the indicated simple ideas "this red, this sweetness",
mere simplicity of the soul is supposed to account for why opposed ideas etc., i.e., composed purely of intuitions. For my part, I think that merely
repel one another. If in eve1y plurality of ideas, each repelled the others, · order to combine two intuitional ideas in order to form a new idea, one
!11 .
one would be able to claim that the simplicity of the soul was incompat- or more conceptual ideas, in particular, that of a collection, are reqmred.
l03 ible with a plurality of ideas. But since on HERBART' s dispensation not
§.288.
all, but only certain ideas repel one another (principally those which be-
long to the same sense, e.g., ideas of colours, where blue and red repel How the lack or cessation <~fan idea is to be understood
each other more strongly than blue and violet), the basis for the explana- From the above description of the way ideas originate, it will not be dif-
tion must lie in something peculiar to such ideas. (e) It is equally difficult ficult to understand how ideas may also cease to be.
for me to see how the unity (or simplicity) of the soul implies the com- 1) If the immediate cause of the existence of an idea is a change
bination of all our ideas. (f) I find astonishing the claim that ideas and brought about in the soul by the action of an external object (as is the
concepts are only to be distinguished in a certain respect, that every idea case with all external intuitions), it is understandable that it will cease to
can also be called a concept insofar as it represents an object. (g) By be if the cause of this change ceases.
contrast, I quite agree with the remark that the kind of faculty of abstrac- 2) If, however, the idea is not such an immediate effect of a change
tion many logicians seem to imagine we have, one by means of which brought about by the influence of an external object, it will have been
the soul can dissolve associations that have come to exist between certain produced by a greater activity of the soul, and it is quite comprehensible l05
ideas as it pleases, simply does not exist. Our soul can combine, but it that it will cease to be when the activity required for its production does.
cannot dissolve, at least not immediately. But it can do this indirectly, It is clear that this happens as soon as we suppose that the activity of the
it seems to me, by ceasing to attend to the ideas whose connection is to soul has been directed towards something else. For given the finitude of
be dissolved. In this way the connection becomes steadily weaker, and the soul's powers, it follows that it cannot produce and sustain an infinite
gives way to stronger combinations. (h) It may well be true, as HERBART number of ideas at the same time.
says, that along with every general idea a number of individual objects 3) It is no harder to explain the fact that there are ideas which the soul
standing under it which we have known also occur to us by association. so far lacks, i.e., ideas which are not only not present now, but never have
But one should not look upon the ideas associated with a certain idea been previously either. For why should there not be infinitely many ideas
as constituents of the latter, as HERBART seems to do (Lehrb., §180). which we have never produced in the entire time of our existence, simply
(i) When he (ibid.) wants to explain the origin of general concepts through because the conditions required for their production have never been met?
judgements "which attribute and deny various kinds of characteristics to Countless intuitions, for example, must be lacking in us, simply because
the word one seeks to define," I counter that we cannot seek the definition we have never been in the spatial and temporal relations with a certain
of a word unless we already have the general idea it designates. Rather, external object which are necessary to stimulate the change needed for
l04 it is simply a matter of becoming distinctly aware of the constituents of the production of the intuition.
this concept. Moreover, the characteristics that are attributed or denied
in the production of a general concept are themselves general concepts. §.289.*
(k) A great many passages (e.g., Psych., §37, § 124) seem to show that this Survey of the most important activities and
scholar considers the ideas "this red", "this sweetness" to be simple (for states of our mind connected with ideas
me, they are only complex insofar as the ideas "red", "sweetness", etc.,
At the end of this chapter, let us present a brief overview of the activities
belong to their content). By contrast, he considers the general ideas "red
and states of our mind connected with ideas which are most important for
in general", etc., to be composed from the ideas of the individual things
the purposes of logic.

68 69
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 289. Of Ideas

I) First of alL ideas may be completely absent from our mind, i.e., not of its known attributes, particularly the sensible ones. If we succeed in
only are they not present now, but also were never present earlier. This this with ease and an image comes before our mind which contains many
relation can be called the complete absence of such ideas, also the lack or sensible ideas, we say that we are able to represent this object easily and
106 non-possession of ideas. intuitively. By contrast, when it is difficult for us to put together such
2) It may also happen that an idea, although not now present in our an image, we say (admittedly quite improperly) that we are incapable of
mind, was so formerly. In this case there exists a certain trace of this idea representing this object.* LOS
in our mind. I will call this condition a previous presence of the idea.
Here it is especially important whether the trace left by the idea is so
constituted that the mind, without knowingly and willingly directing its
attention to it, may form an intuition of this trace and thence a recollection
of the idea itself. If it is, we say that the idea is one we recall; if not, it
depends upon whether we can at least recall it when we want to, by means
of a certain inner activity of our mind (striving to recollect) and without
making use of external aids, or whether such activity remains fruitless. In
the former case, we can recall an idea only tvith difficulty, while in the
latter it has been forgotten. A forgotten idea may be one we can bring
to mind with the help of an external object, or it may be so completely
forgotten that even when it is produced in us again from without, we
no longer remember ever having had it. The former may be said to be
forgotten but for an external reminder and the latter utterly forgotten.
Here it should be noted that we often know quite well whether we shall
be able to recall an idea forthwith, or only with difficulty, or only with
the help of an external reminder, or not at all. One says, for example:
I haven't completely forgotten that man's name, but I can't remember it
just now.
107 3) If an idea is now present in our mind, it may be either obscure
or clear (§280), confused or distinct to a greater or lesser degree (§281),
more or less vivid (§275), etc.
4) There may be ideas which our mind forms easily and under stimuli
which do not suffice for the production of other ideas. These are called
familiar. It is clear that familiarity admits of degrees. Though it may
be true that only ideas which have been often produced in us become
familiar, this circumstance alone does not suffice to determine the degree
of familiarity-for many other circumstances have an influence as well.
Nor must it occur to us when a familiar idea is produced in us that it is an
idea we have often had before.
5) If we are aware that we have a certain idea and believe it to be
objectual, we usually set ourselves the task (§284) of producing an espe- *In a still more improper sense this expression is applied to entire propositions and
claims, when we say that we cannot imagine [vorstellen] them-i.e., we cannot take them
cially vivid and complete idea of the object of the idea by combining all
to be true.

70 71
Of Judgements

PARTII . S·oul ·
htS For how many different judgements may be formed by different
mbinations of the same parts!
Of Judgements co 1 . . d
4) If several subjective ideas a,b,c,d, ... are to resu t ma JU ge-
men t M' they must at least · be in the mind simultaneously in the sense
that before one of them has completely disappeared, another has already
§.290.* begun. For if this were not the case, if, for instance, we. had .forgott~n the
subject-idea of a proposition before we came to consider its pre~1cate­
The concept of a judgement a it would certainly not be possible to form the judgement. But JU St as
1'd e,,
the mere simultaneous presence of certain ideas in our mind by no means
The reader already knows from § § 19 and 34 what concept I connect with ensures that they constitute the parts of a single idea, so too it cannot en-
the word judgement. It is already clear enough from what was said there, ure that they constitute the parts of a single judgement. Rather the ideas
especially when compared to §48, that a judgement is completely differ- smust have a peculiar connection with each other. If I am asked what th'is 110
ent from a mere idea of a proposition (even a subjective one). Someone connection is, I can answer only that it must be a sort of mutual influence
who merely represents the proposition "The sun is a fireball" does not of these ideas upon each other. But I am unable to determine what sort of
have to take it to be true, and if he does not take it to be true, one cannot mutual influence there must be in order for a judgement to result from the
say that he forms the judgement "The sun is a fireball." Given that we presence of several subjective ideas; and perhaps it can only be conceived
form judgements, we may certainly attribute to ourselves the ability or as an activity which produces this result.
power to do so. We call this the power of judgement. 5) Our will has a certain influence upon the formation of our judge-
ments, since we can (§286, no. 5) direct our attention towards some ideas
§.291.*
and withdraw it from others. In this way we can completely change the
course of our thoughts. But no matter how significant this influence of
Some attributes common to all judgements
the will is, it never directly depends on our will alone whether or not we
form a judgement. The formation of judgements follows a ce1tain law of
1) Just as we suppose that for every subjective idea there is an objec-
necessity, and depends only upon the nature of the ideas that are present
tive idea which constitutes its matter, so too we must assume that every
in the mind at that time.
judgement is the appearance in the mind of some proposition, which is
Note. In many treatises one reads that a judgement is essentially noth-
the matter of this judgement.
ing other than a distinctly thought concept. KRUG (L., §51, note 1), for
!09 2) Actuality must be ascribed to judgements just as it is to subjective
instance, says this, and SCHULZE (L., §45) adduces the following exam-
ideas. They have actuality, namely, in the mind of the being that forms
ple: "The judgement 'The body is red' contains the same combination of
them, and during the time that it does. For judgements are composed of
concepts which occur in the concept of a red body." CRUSIUS (W z. G.,
ideas: and how could the parts be actual if the whole they constitute was
§202) had already said: "A proposition only differs from a complex idea
not? But just as ideas do not exist of themselves, but are only actual in
in the way it is considered and intended. With complex ideas one thinks
something else as an adherence, so too is this the case for judgements.
of one part and the other, and considers them together as a whole, e.g., the
They exist only in beings which form them.
immortal God; while with propositions one thinks of the ideas with the
3) But if every proposition is composed of parts that can be reduced
intention of representing the relation between them, e.g., God is immor-
to ideas, then every judgement, as the appearance of a proposition, must
tal." In my opinion, such claims are prompted by the fact that in many
also be composed of parts. Indeed the judgement must contain as many
cases there are great similarities between distinctly thought concepts and
parts as occur in the objective proposition that constitutes its matter. On
judgements, as well as by the fact that when our soul thinks a concept
the other hand, one cannot say that someone forms a certain judgement
distinctly, i.e., notices its constituents, it often forms judgements about
merely because all the ideas of which the judgement is composed occur in

72 73
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 292. Of Judgements

lll the objects standing under the concept and, conversely, many judgements in the same mind at broken intervals, or when it appears in the minds
provide the occasion for forming a distinct concept. When, for example, of different beings or, finally, when we are speaking of the appearance
we render the concept "world" more distinct and become aware that it of different propositions. It is equally obvious that we may say that the
contains the characteristic of contingency, this readily provides the occa- judgements we can distinguish numerically in the way just described must
sion for us to form the judgement: the world is a collection of contingent ·also be considered at least unequal if they are appearances of different
substances. When, on the other hand, we form the judgement: A trian- propositions. When I speak of equal judgements in the sequel, the very
gle may contain a right angle, this provides the occasion for forming the least one should gather from this is that they are judgements containing
(distinct) concept of a right-angled triangle. But one should not claim for the same proposition. Under other circumstances, this equality may also
this reason that a given judgement (and certainly not every judgement) be extended to cover other attributes.
is one and the same as a distinctly thought concept. Nothing is stated
through the concept, while a judgement states something. And if this §.293.*
were not the case, if any proposition contained the same constituents as
a concept, combined in the same way, how could it be true, as CRUSIUS Strength or vividness ofjudgements, and confidence in a judgement
says, that the two may be distinguished in the way they are considered and
intended, or that one thinks of the same characteristics as being united in Since each idea has a certain vividness, it is reasonable to attribute vivid-
a sum in the concept while considering only their relations in the propo- ness also to judgements, insofar as they are combinations of several ideas;
sition? But it isn't even true to say that the concept "the immortal God" but from this vividness, which results from the vividness of its individual
contains the same constituents as the proposition "God is immortal." For parts, we have to distinguish the strength or efficacy which results from
the former may be more distinctly expressed as follows: "God, who is the particular way in which those parts are combined to form a judge-
immortal"; from which one may gather that the concept of the relative ment. Since a judgement is not a mere sum of ideas, but consists in a
pronoun "who" occurs in it, but not in the proposition. The difference certain efficacious combination of them, and since this combination can
between the constituents of the concept "a red body" (i.e., a body which be more or less strongly felt, the efficacy of the judgement will depend
is red) and the proposition "The body (i.e., this determinate body) is red" upon this strength, even if the content and vividness of the individual l 13
is even more obvious. For the idea "this", which occurs in the proposi- ideas do not change. I am going to call this degree of efficacy or strength
tion, certainly does not appear in the concept. The more obvious what of a judgement the degree of confidence with which we form it. With
I said in no. 5 becomes to me through innermost self-consciousness, the respect to the proposition that forms the content of the judgement, the
more mysterious it becomes why many philosophers (I will mention only degree of confidence with which it is formed is also called the degree of
FICHTE and FRIES) describe judgement as a voluntary activity, and rea- approval (assensio) that is attributed to the proposition. Sometimes it is
son as the freest of human powers. called the degree of our certainty or acceptance. If two different persons
each form a judgement with the same content, so that both contain the
§.292. same proposition, and if the individual ideas of which these judgements
consist all have the same vividness, it is still possible for there to be a
What we call a single judgement, and when we say of two great difference in the degree of confidence with which each of them ex-
or more judgements that they are equal or unequal presses his judgement. The judgement will show greater effects in the
person who forms it with greater confidence than in the other person, and
Considerations similar to those set out in §273 make it clear that it is conversely where the efficacy of a judgement is more pronounced, given
l 12 most appropriate to look upon the entire time during which one and the the same degree of vividness, confidence must be higher.
same objective proposition appears uninte1rnptedly in a mind (even if this Note. It is necessary to distinguish the vividness of a judgement, i.e.,
occurs in different ways) as the duration of a single judgement, and only its efficacy insofar as it derives from the strength of its constituent ideas,
to speak of more than one judgement when the same proposition occurs from confidence, i.e., its efficacy derived from the degree of strength with

74 75
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 293. Of Judgements

which the individual parts are united to form a whole. This becomes par- in something" [sich zu einer Sache verselzen]. It also reminds us of some-
ticularly obvious when one of these two magnitudes almost disappears, thing which is seen or is visible [sichtlich]-yet for all that, "confidence"
while the other reaches a relatively high level. It turns out that in both does not remind us as vividly as the word "certainty" of the associated 115
cases the efficacy of the judgement is very small. Thus if we point out to concept of knowledge, i.e., a judgement which cannot be in error. Be-
a voluptuary that lust engenders pain, he will hardly be moved; not be- cause of its importance for logic, the concept of confidence, in the sense
cause the ideas of which this truth consists do not have enough vividness used here, is discussed in almost every treatise of that science. However,
for him, but because he does not form this judgement with sufficient con- I take exception to the fact that it is not sufficiently distinguished from
fidence. It occurs equally often that persons who have not the least doubt another related concept. This other concept is the concept of probabil-
concerning certain religious truths nonetheless show little effect of them ity. not in the sense of § 161, but in the sense in which it is employed in
in their behaviour, simply because the concepts of which these truths are ordinary life. We usually call a proposition probable if it stands to propo-
composed have no vividness in their souls. The term confidence seems sitions accepted by a certain being in the relation of probability in the
114 the best among the available alternatives. For conviction will be used sense of§ 161, and if, in addition, the degree of this probability is greater
in opposition to persuasion in order to convey that the judgement one is than one-half. Since I shall speak about this concept only later, I shall
convinced of is supported by valid reasons, and is therefore true. Cer- indicate the difference between it and the concept of confidence at that
tain(y is indeed often used with the same meaning that I here assign to time.
confidence, as when one says that someone judges with complete cer-
tainty, or that he is not very certain, and the like. I believe, however, that §.294.*
this word should be reserved to designate another concept which shall
be defined below and hence should not be used for the concept presently Distinctions between judgements based upon
under consideration. Nor is reliabiliry a word which might be used for parallel distinctions between propositions
our concept, for it indicates an attribute that does not apply so much to
our judgements as to the propositions which constitute their matter, and Since for every judgement there is a proposition which comes to appear
which can moreover only be ascribed to those which have a high degree in the mind of a thinking being via the judgement, it is clear that for
of probability. The most serviceable words would be assent or approval every particular kind of proposition there will be a corresponding kind
(assensio ); yet these do not designate the attribute of the judgements we of judgement, and that we may use the same terms in both cases. If in
are speaking of in abstracto, but rather the judgements which possess this the theory of propositions we distinguish between simple and complex,
attribute, i.e., the corresponding concretum. Thus we would hardly say true and false, analytic and synthetic, conceptual and intuitional, and so
that someone judges with this or that degree of assent, though we would on, so too may we extend such distinctions to cover judgements. It will
say that he gives his full or partial approval to this or that proposition. be obvious what is meant by a simple or complex, true or false, analytic
This expression makes it clear that we look upon approval not simply as or synthetic, conceptual or intuitional judgement. Let us add here that
an attribute of a judgement, but rather as a judgement. Admittedly, the judgements which contain an intuition, especially those which are held to
word "confidence" is far from perfect, for it is also true that in normal us- be true, are usually called experiences or judgements (~f experience in a
age we reserve it for judgements which have a high degree of probability. very broad sense of these terms. 116
But when we already have a word (namely, certainty) to designate such
high degrees of probability, it is permissible to give the other word an ex- §.295.
tended meaning, especially in view of the fact that its derivation is not at
odds with such an extension. Confident [Zuversichtlich] seems to mean Clear and obscure judgements
the same thing as trusted [Zuversehentlich]. Thus the word confidence
[Zuversicht] seems to be at the root of the expression "to place one's trust In common life we classify not only ideas but also our judgements as
either clear or obscure. We say, for example, that someone recognises

76 77
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 296. Of Judgements

something only obscurely, while he has understood something else clearly. its immediate parts are known to us, but not the parts of these parts, that
Obviously, we are speaking here of entire judgements and not just of is, if we know its subject- and predicate-ideas and its copula, but do not
ideas. It seems to me, however, that the distinction between clear and know whether these parts are simple or complex nor, if the latter is the
obscure judgements is best understood in the way I determined the differ- case, what those parts might be, we shall say the judgement is distinct to
ence between clear and obscure ideas in §280. For just as ideas appearing the first degree. If the immediate parts of the judgement are also distinct,
in our minds can, as something actual and present in us, become the object but only to the extent that we know their immediate parts, we may call it
of our powers of intuition, so too is this the case with our judgements. We distinct in the second degree, and so on. If, finally, there are no parts at
can also procure intuitions of the latter and, indeed, we must have such in- all of the judgement of which we do not have a distinct idea, if, namely,
tuitions whenever we are definitely aware of one of our own judgements, we are able to set out an analysis of the judgement into its simple parts,
and whenever we form a judgement to the effect that we judged this or and we recognise these parts as simple, we call it perfectly distinct. 118
that. Just as we call clear those ideas we intuit within ourselves, judge- 3) No judgement which is distinct merely in the first degree is per-
ments formed in such a way that we form intuitions of them deserve to be fectly distinct. For although we know what its immediate parts are, we
called elem: Those for which this is not the case may be called obscure. do not know whether these are simple or complex. A simple judgement,
Note. Given that common usage so often extends the concepts of clar- however, i.e., a judgement whose immediate constituents are simple, is
ity and obscurity to judgements, it is odd that most logicians only speak perfectly distinct if it attains the second degree of distinctness. For we
of the distinction with regard to concepts, just as if they assumed that only then already know the simple parts of which it is composed and know
concepts could be divided into the clear and the obscure. Some, though, that they are simple. Finally, every judgement which has only finitely
hold the opposite view, and maintain that the distinction between clarity many parts admits of only finitely many degrees of distinctness.
and obscurity is not limited to concepts alone, but rather extends to ideas Note. Although I cannot draw support for my attempt to apply the
in general, under which, as is well known, they include judgements along concept of distinctness to judgement from previous logical researchers, it
I l7 with what I call ideas. Thus FRIES (Syst. d. L., §9) speaks of obscure seems to me that common usage favours it along with the similar applica-
and clear ideas in a way which makes it unmistakable that judgements tion of the concept of clarity to judgements. For do we not often say that
are also covered. How else could he say (p. 51): "All of these cognitions we understand this or that quite distinctly or, in the contrary case, that we
are constantly present in me, but in every case only a fraction, sometimes only recognise something indistinctly?
this, sometimes that, is represented clearly." There is still a problem here
however, in that this distinction is never referred to in the theory of judge- §.297.
ments.
Whether every judgement has a beginning and an end
§.296.
Whoever admits that our ideas have a beginning and an end because they
Distinct and confused judgements
are merely changes occurring in our minds (§282) will also have to claim
1) The concept of distinctness may, I believe, be extended just as the the same for our judgements, since they are composed of ideas. Thus all
concept of clarity was. Recall that we called an idea distinct (§281) if we of our judgements are also of finite duration and by their nature not per-
know its content, and thus are able to indicate whether it has parts and, manent, but rather changes occurring in our souls, the effects of forces
if so, what these are. Similarly, we may say that a judgement is distinct that can only work in time. The contrary claim that none of our judge-
if we are able to determine its parts (it will of course have some parts in ments begins or ends stands in too stark a contradiction with our inner
every case). If we are unable to do this, it may be called indistinct or awareness. If it were true, when we say we have produced a judgement, 119
confused. really nothing more would have happened in our soul than that a judge-
2) Just as we distinguish degrees of distinctness in ideas, we may also ment which was already present there became more vivid; and when we
do so for judgements. If a judgement is distinct only to the extent that recall a judgement we formed earlier, it would simply be a matter of

78 79
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 298. Of Judgements

the judgement increasing in strength or confidence. If this were really too we recall from time to time. But this can only happen if we become
the case, if the phenomenon which we call the abandonment of an early aware, not of the judgement itself, but of a trace it left after its disappear-
judgement and the adoption of a new one contradicting it really were ance.
just a matter of one becoming stronger or more confident than the other, 4) Certainly, then, there are such traces, and not just in some cases: all
one would have to believe that a judgement we have contradicted could of our judgements leave traces after their disappearance, which are con-
never occur in our soul with the same confidence that another judgement, stituted differently depending upon whether the judgements were formed
which has never been contradicted, can. But this is not so. Rather, when with more or less vividness and confidence, were stronger or weaker, etc. 121
the reasons determining the previous judgement have been completely
eliminated, or when we see that they in fact speak in favour of the exact §.299.
opposite, namely, our newly adopted belief, the recollection of the ear-
lier error detracts in no way from the certainty of our present judgement, Effects of these traces of our judgements
except perhaps insofar as it prompts the thought that we might now be
!) It is easy to see that if our judgements leave traces, these will pro-
mistaken just as we were then. But this thought is a completely differ-
duce effects similar to those produced by the traces of our ideas. They
ent judgement from the one we made previously, one which moreover
too. as something actual within us, may under certain circumstances be
presupposes the falsity of the latter.
intuited. Permit me to call such intuitions of a previously formed judge-
§.298. ment a renewal, revival, or reawakening of the judgement; one should
not be misled into thinking that such an intuition of the trace of a previ-
Whether eve1y judgement leaves a trace after it disappears ous judgement is a kind of repetition of the judgement, i.e., forming anew
the judgement whose trace we now intuit. This cannot be, since we must
If my claim (§283) that every idea leaves an actual trace when it has also be able to use such intuitions when arriving at the judgement that we
ceased to be is correct, then we may assume the same to hold for all of previously formed a false judgement.
our judgements. 2) If the intuition we form of the trace of a former judgement is not
1) Concerning clear judgements, i.e., those of which we have formed itself intuited, it remains an obscure idea; otherwise it is clear. If we
120 an intuition: because the intuition, which is an idea, leaves a trace, it go further, recognising that the intuition we now have is the intuition of
also serves as a trace of the judgement itself. For if the trace left by the the trace of a judgement, and forming the judgement that we previously
intuition is so constituted that it permits us to recognise the intuition it formed that judgement, one may say that we recall the judgement. One
came from, it must also permit us to recognise the judgement, which is may surmise that the revival of a previously formed judgement will far
the object to which the intuition applies. more often be obscure than clear, and it will attain clarity far more of-
2) But judgements which do not become clear to us may also leave ten than it becomes a definite recollection. Since the terms imagination,
a trace after they disappear. For since every judgement is composed of memmy, fantasy are customarily used for our ability to intuit the traces
ideas in a certain combination and interaction, it cannot cease to be unless of ideas, permit me to extend the meanings of these terms to cover the 122
these ideas either cease to be or at least no longer stand in that combina- similar ability with respect to entire judgements. To this encl, we need
tion. But as this combination is something actual, it seems to follow, for simply say that memory [Gedtichtnij3] in general is the soul's ability, un-
the reasons I adduced in support of a similar claim regarding ideas (§283, der certain circumstances, to intuit traces left behind by its own activity.
no. 2), that this combination cannot cease to be without leaving behind a For similar reasons, we can extend the concept of the power of recollec-
certain trace in our soul. tion [Erinnerungskraft] so that it also covers our judgements, and indeed
3) We proved that each idea leaves a trace by appealing to our remark- all the activities of the soul: it is the ability to form the judgement that
able ability under certain circumstances to recall ideas we had previously. it has formerly performed some activity based upon the perception of a
But we also have such an ability with respect to our judgements. These trace of this activity in the soul.

80 81
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 300. Of Judgements

3) The laws governing the revival of judgements appear to be the M· rather, their presence must be the complete cause for the o~currence
same as those governing the revival of ideas. Activities which have been !M In speakino-b of a complete cause I do not mean that
~ . .
nothmg other
. .
performed simultaneously in t?e soul enter into such_ a connectio~ ~hat than the presence of A, B, C, D, ... , ~ot. even ~~n activity of the mmd, is
the repetition of one of them (i.e., the performance of an equal activity)
requi·i·ecl , but only that aside from the
. mdicated judgements
. A, B, .C, D,. ...
provides the occasion for forming an intuition of the traces left behind by other judgement is necessary m order to bnng about M. If, for ex-
the other. no1 le the judgement was formed that Caius is a scholar and it happens
anp, . . ,, t ·d
4) When we recall a judgement we have previously formed, it may that later on the judgement "Scholars a~·e often vam. comes ~ mm , ~e
happen that we still find it to be correct, in which case we repeat it in the should not consider the latter to be medi~ted by the ~ormer. 1t is conceiv-
proper sense of the word; or we may no longer hold it to be correct, in able that it was occasioned by that other judgement, 111.that the. con~ept of
which case we do not repeat it. When repeating a judgement, the degree
a SC hol '·ir brouo-ht
b
about the associated concept of vamty and m this way•
of confidence may be greater or smaller than it was the first time. In finally led us to the judgement "Scholars are often .v~in"; but the cause of
particular, the observation that we now judge as we formerly did may our forming this judgement (why we have a suspi~10n t~~t scholars are
123 cause us to form the judgement with greater confidence. And so on. vain) lies in judgements and experiences of an entirely differe~t co~tent
than the judgement that Caius is one of the scholars. The latter is entirely
§.300.* dispensable in this respect. If, by contrast, we express the j~1dg~ment.that
Caius is a man and then, immediately afterwards, that Cams is ~alhble,
Mediation of a judgement by otherjudgements
one cannot say that the former is superfluous-even though on its own
it does not suffice to produce the second judgement, the judgement that
1) We must now investigate the important question concerning the origin
all men are fallible also being required to act along with it. Thus, if we
of our judgements. It is obvious that not all judgements originate in the
wish to speak precisely, we will not say that the single judgement that
same way. The judgement that the ratio between the diameter and the
Caius is a man mediates the judgement that he is fallible, but rather that
circumference of a circle is irrational certainly comes about in a different
the combination of the two judgements that C. is a man and that all men 125
way than the judgement "I feel a pain just now", or a similar one.
are fallible does.
2) An especially noteworthy kind of origin of judgements is that
3) From this and similar examples it becomes obvious that this rela-
whereby one or more other judgements cause or, if you like, mediate
tion of mediation does indeed hold between some of our judgements, and
a given one. I say that a judgement M is caused or mediated by cer-
hence that there are mediated judgements. It is equally certain that there
tain others A, B, C, D, ... if the cause of us forming judgement M lies
are also immediate judgements; for the existence of mediated judgements
in the fact that we have just formed the judgements A, B, C, D, .... The
can in the end be understood only because there are also immediate ones.
judgement M in such cases is said to be caused, produced, mediated by
4) A judgement M which comes about through the mediation of A,B,
A,B,C,D, ... , which are said to cause, produce or mediate M. Often,
C,D, ... follows upon them in time, but in such a way that they ha~e
the action of the mind when it moves from judgements A, B, C, D, ... to
not altogether disappeared when it comes about. The correctness of this
judgement Mis called an inference, and Mis called inferred, concluded
claim is confirmed in part by the observations which each of us can make
or derived, while the judgements A, B, C, D, ... are called the premises,
with his own judgements, in part by the fact that between effect and cause
and frequently (though improperly) the grounds of M. The soul's abil-
there must be some simultaneity.
ity to find the cause of its belief in the proposition M in its belief in the
5) If certain judgements A,B,C,D, ... have mediated a judgement
propositions A,B,C,D, ... is called its power or faculty of inference.
M on one occasion, it does not follow that M will always be mediated
Judgements which are not mediated, whatever their cause may otherwise
by them, nor that the only way for us to form M is via the mediati~n
be, are called umnediated or immediate. To say truly that a judgement
of A,B,C,D, .... Still less may it be claimed that the judgements via
124 M was mediated by judgements A,B,C,D, ... , it is not enough that
which a certain other judgement M is mediated in us are necessary for
A, B, C, D, ... provided an occasion for the formation of the judgement

82 83
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 300. Of Judgements

the mediation of M in every other thinking being. Thus I can form the fices to bring about the acceptance of M. It may seem as if the acceptanc.e
judgement that Caius is learned based upon the assurances of someone of M can come about only if, in addition to the acceptance of propos~­
who knows him better than I do, but also from the way he habitually tions A,B,C,D, ... the truth that Mis deducible from A,B,C,D, ... 1s
speaks, and so on. also recognised. I admit that this is often the case. For example, not
6) Clearly, we would be very happy to be in a position to know of everybody who accepts as true the propositions:
each of our judgements whether it was unmediated or not and, in the All Pare M
latter case, by means of which other judgements. But this is not so easy. Some S are not M
126 For not all of the judgements we actually form attain clarity, that is, not
will progress to the judgement: "Some S are not P"; perhaps th~s in-
all are intuited by us. Rather, most of them remain obscure, and we are
ference will be drawn only by those who remember the rule of mfer-
accordingly unable either to recall or become aware of them, and still less
ence called Baroco in the schools. But this is not always the case. We
to indicate verbally what they are. Nevertheless, they bring about many
sometimes advance immediately from the acceptance of certain propo-
effects in our mind, and in particular can mediate other judgements. It
sitions A,B,C,D, ... to the acceptance of a deducible proposition M,
quite often occurs that we have derived a judgement from certain others,
without first thinking of the truth that a proposition of form M is de-
and yet are unable to indicate the latter. Indeed, it may even seem that a
ducible from propositions A,B,C,D, ... or without even being aware
judgement is unmediated, while in fact it is not. Thus from the mere fact
that there is such a truth; I think that this can be proved, since other-
that we cannot tell by what judgements a given judgement was mediated,
wise not a single inference could be drawn, i.e., not a single judgement 128
we must not conclude that it was immediate; we can do this only if closer
could be based upon other judgements as its cause. For, if the truth of
observation shows that the given judgement is of such a nature that it can
proposition M cannot be immediately recognised fr~~ the _accepted truth
never be mediated, or mediated only if we are conscious of it.
of propositions A, B, C, D, ... , but instead recogmt10n of the truth that
7) In order to judge this matter, we must first find out what the dif-
from propositions A,B,C,D, ... a proposition like M can be deduced
ferent kinds of mediation are. I believe that a judgement M can only
is also required, then there are actually two insights which precede the
be mediated by others A,B,C,D, . .. if one of the following three cases
recognition of M, namely: "Every collection of ideas whose substitution
occurs: (a) All of the propositions A, B, C, D, ... are true and are the
for i,j, ... makes propositions A,B,C,D, ... true also makes proposi-
objective grounds of the proposition M (cf. §198) or (b) proposition M,
tion M true" and "Propositions A,B,C,D, . .. as they stand, are true" or
if it is not a consequence of A,B,C,D, ... must still be deducible from
"Ideas i,j, ... which originally occur in propositions A,B,C,D, ... are
them in the sense of § 155; or, finally, (c) proposition M, if not completely
a collection of ideas which make A,B,C,D, ... true." Is it not obvious
certain, nevertheless has a certain degree of probability on the basis of
that the way in which judgement M follows from these two judgements
A, B, C, D, . . . in the sense of § 161. In order to show the correctness of
is again only the recognition of a conclusion from its premises? Hence
this claim, I must first establish that each of the three cases occurs, and
if no conclusion can be recognised from the truth of its premises with-
127 then that there is no other kind of mediation of one judgement by others.
out first recognising the rule according to which this inference is formed,
8) Nobody can deny that judgements can originate in the way de-
then the two judgements just formed still do not suffice to produce recog-
scribed under (a) above, if he admits at all that truths can stand in the re-
nition of proposition M. This not only contradicts the just-mentioned
lation of ground and consequence to each other, and that men can some-
supposition, but also shows that it is altogether impossible ever to derive
times recognise this relation. For if the truths, A, B, C, D, ... are the
a judgement from other judgements in this way, since an infinite number
ground for truth M, how can the recognition of M become more certain
of judgements would be required. For, what I just said concerning the
and complete than by recognising that A, B, C, D, ... are its ground?
necessity of adding a third judgement to the two given judgements (so
9) But there are also cases which fall under (b); the acceptance of cer-
that the proposition which we want to derive is really derivable as a con-
tain propositions A,B,C,D, ... from which another proposition M follows
clusion) also holds when this third proposition is already added. Now a
with respect to certain ideas i, j, ... sometimes, though not always, suf-
fourth proposition is required which shows that the three indicated propo-

84 85
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 300. Of Judgements

sitions really are related as premises to the (desired) conclusion and so on ways of generating a judgement. In order to find a true exception, we
ad infinitum. should have to claim that judgement M was immediately produced by a
10) Finally, it cannot be denied that sometimes judgements are gener- consideration of judgements A, B, C, D, ... and that the fallacious rule of
ated in the third manner mentioned under no. 7: the acceptance of certain inference was not tacitly assumed. But to bring this about, there would
129 propositions A,B,C,D, ... , which merely bestow probability upon an- have to be some kind of mechanism [Einrichtung] in our minds which
other proposition M, sometimes also leads to an acceptance of M. There brings it about that from judgements of the forms A, B, C, D, ... , ajuclge-
are many examples where the premises A,B,C,D, ... are accepted and rnent of the form M is generated although the latter does not stand to
are present in our mind, and where the conclusion is not merely that M is the former in a relation of ground and consequence, nor declucibility, nor
probable (this would be deducible from A, B, C, D, ... ), but where the even probability. But who can believe that such a mechanism is present
judgement M itself is formed. Thus we do not only say that it is proba- in our mind? Its existence should be claimed only if it could be shown
ble that in the coming year the surface of the earth will be covered with that certain judgements which we form with every care and precaution
plants and flowers, since this has happened a great many times, but we nonetheless contradict other judgements which we have formed just as
expect it, i.e., we form the judgement (with a greater or smaller degree of cautiously. But nobody has been able to prove this. On the other hand,
confidence) that this will indeed happen. if we wanted to assume without proof the existence of such an error-
11) We must now prove that these three ways are the only ways of producing mechanism in our mind merely because its impossibility has
generating a judgement from other judgements. The most likely alterna- not been established, then, for the same reason, we should not trust a sin-
tive is this: It might be argued that occasionally we proceed from certain gle one of our judgements, i.e., we should not form any judgements at all.
judgements A,B,C,D, . .. , which we have formed, to a new judgement But this would be a contradiction, since it is a consequence of trusting
M merely because we think that it stands in one of the three indicated those judgements which determined that very decision.
relations to A, B, C, D, ... , while this is not actually the case. Do we 12) Let me now adduce some examples of judgements which I take
not often perform invalid inferences and hence deduce propositions from to be immediate: I claim of the following two forms of judgement, not 131
others which are not in truth implied by them? My answer is this: oc- that all judgements that fall under this form must be immediate, but that
casionally we take an incorrect rule of inference for correct and use it in some of them are. (a) One of these forms is I-have-the impression A; the
order to proceed from certain judgements A, B, C, D, ... to a new judge- subject of all these judgements is the person who utters them (I) while
ment M, where Mis not actually implied by them; this cannot be denied. their predicate indicates the possession of an impression which is just
Suppose that this advance to the new judgement M does not flow immedi- now present in that person, for example the presence of an idea, a just-
ately from a consideration of propositions A, B, C, D, ... , but takes place formed judgement, a present sensation, an act of will, etc. The other form
only because we have mistaken an incorrect rule of inference for a cor- is this: This (what I just now observe)-is-an A; in this case the subject-
rect one, i.e., because we made the mistake of thinking that a proposition idea is an intuition which is just now present in the judging person, and
like Mis deducible from propositions like A,B,C,D, ... alone. It fol- is subsumed by this person under a certain concept A; this is the case,
lows that judgement M was not generated by A, B, C, D, ... alone, but for example, when somebody says: This (what I just now observe) is
130 by them together with the tacitly assumed judgement that a proposition something reel, a pleasant fragrance, etc. It is indeed true that judgements
like M can be deduced from propositions like A,B,C,D, .... In other of this kind are sometimes the product of an inference, for example when
words, the judgement M comes about because we form the following we infer from the perception of one of our own actions that we must have
two judgements: "If propositions A, B, C,D, ... are true then proposition had an idea of it, or when we judge of an intuition which we just now
M is also true" and "Propositions A, B, C, D, ... are true". But from have, that it is the effect of an external object of such and such a kind.
these two propositions, proposition M is not only apparently, but actu- But it is impossible that all judgements of these two forms are mediated
ally deducible; hence the way in which we here arrive at judgement M judgements, since every mediated judgement of this kind presupposes
is no exception to the claim of no. 7, but is there described as one of the another one of the same kind. In order to infer from a present action of

86 87
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 300. Of Judgements

mine that I must have had an idea which was necessary to perform this or changes, e.g., if it is in motion just now. For example, the judgement
action, I must first form the judgement: I have performed action A. And that there is a bird flying over there I take to be inferred. But since we are
if the judgement 'The intuition X is an A" is not to be immediate, then it not generally conscious of the premises upon which it rests, we tend to
must be deduced from a pair of other judgements, namely, "The intuition take it for an immediate perception and claim, for this reason, that we do
X is a B", and "All Bare A"). not infer the flight of this bird, but see it immediately. I admit that there
I wish to call all judgements which fall under one of these two forms is a great difference between the manner in which we recognise the flight
judgements of perception, provided that they were formed immediately; of this bird and, for example, the motion of the hour hand on a pocket
it would be still more precise to call them immediate judgements of per- watch. We recognise the latter when we realise that this hand is now in
ception. All mediated judgements, if they contain an intuition, can rea- a different position than when we saw it a short time ago, i.e., we are
132 sonably be called judgements of experience in the narrower sense of this conscious of the reasons from which we inferred its motion. To express
word (§294). this distinction, we say that we did not see the motion of the hand imme-
13) It will become clear, upon some reflection, that there must be far diately but inferred it. Although these expressions are not exact, we can
more immediate judgements than we have just described. In particular, still use them provided that no misunderstanding can arise from them or
among purely conceptual judgements there must be some which are not we can use them with explanatory comments to avoid misunderstanding.
mediated. For, if the judgements described in no. 12 were the only im- Note 1. The concept of an immediate judgement introduced in no. 2 is
mediate judgements, then all the rest of our judgements would have to be encountered frequently enough elsewhere, only it is not always given an
generated either immediately or mediately from them. But it is not con- appropriate definition, is sometimes confused with the related concept of
ceivable how this can be the case. Thus, from a proposition of the form "I a basic truth, and is often applied to propositions which are actually medi-
have intuition A" we can immediately draw the conclusion "There must ated. Thus the judgements TETENS (Phil. Vers., Vol. 1, p. 491) calls "fun-
therefore be something actual which has caused this intuition in me"; but damental judgements about our sensations" are nothing other than pure,
the judgement "Every intuition which comes about either within me or immediate judgements of perception, although he somewhat imprecisely
within any other finite being presupposes the existence of an actual ob- defines them as "judgements about the actual, immediate objects of con- 134
ject which generates it" can neither be inferred from the given judgement sciousness, which constitute the cognition of immediate consciousness."
nor from any other kind of judgement mentioned under no. 12, nor from He cites as examples the judgements "I hear, I see, I feel a pain, I think, I
a combination of them, either immediately or mediately. represent something," etc.-which are actually all immediate judgements
14) I have already mentioned in no. 6 that when we derive a judge- of perception. The claim that these judgements are just as necessary as
ment from other judgements we are often not conscious of the mode of the axioms of geometry (by which he presumably means that error is
derivation. This may be the case because the necessary inferences, by just as impossible with them as with the axioms of geometry, and that the
frequent repetition from early childhood, have become so familiar that other judgements are deduced from them) applies to all judgements of this
we carry them out with a speed too rapid for our intuitive faculty. But kind. STIEDENROTH (Theorie des Wissens, Gott., 1819), when he speaks
whatever the reason, these judgements must be distinguished from those of given judgements, seems to mean immediate judgements. He says (p.
which are derived consciously, often with great effort. Since the former 144): "Given judgements may not be judgements of reasoning, but must
are mostly looked upon as immediate precisely because the way they orig- be merely judgements of consciousness, i.e., they may not stem from re-
inated is unknown, I will, for want of a better word, allow myself to call flection, but must originate immediately, following complete perception,
l33 them immediate in the bmader or improper sense of the word in cases without our assistance, and with necessity." But when he adduces as an
where no misunderstanding is to be feared. The judgements mentioned example (p. 145) "the judgement of the moral worth of an action" one
in no. 12 shall be called immediate in the primmy, genuine, or strict sense. begins to distrust his definition. For judgements about the moral worth
To give an example: I do not think that we recognise immediately the ex- of an action are certainly mediated, even though we are seldom aware
istence of even a single (external) object, much less any of its properties of precisely which premises we have derived them from. I am happy to

88 89
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 300. UJ Ju(/gements

admit that the distinction introduced in no. 12 between the expressions 1


nore d t·t'fi cu lt , the more distinct they are made, and instead create discord
.
. natter they are able to influence." I know no other answer to this
judgements of perception and judgements of experience is somewhat ar- 1·n every I ' . . . . . . ..
bitrary. For it presupposes that by perception one understands a change 11
what I have already said 111 thts section. The contradictions some 136
in the mind which gives rise to the kind of judgement of perception de- tha_ to have observed are in my opinion merely apparent.
claim ' ·
scribed above, and that by experience one means a change which gives
§.301.*
rise to a so-called judgement of experience, while ordinary usage makes
no such distinction and treats the expressions as practically equivalent. I
The generation ofjudgements by the relation of probability
note in passing that KANT thought a distinction similar to this one to be
necessary for the aims of science.
l) The previous section acquainted us with three differen~ ways in which
Note 2. The claim made in no. 9 that we at least sometimes pass im-
'udgements may be produced through the mediation of others. .~h~re
mediately from a recognition of the truth of certain propositions A, B, C,
~s nothing unusual about the first and secon~ o~ these, but th~ ~~~r~ 111-
D, . .. to the recognition of another truth M which is deducible from them,
volves difficulties that cannot be passed over 111 silence. :"hen it ts asked,
without first recalling that a proposition of the form M is deducible from w it occurs that the consideration of certam truths A, B, C,
propositions of the forms A, B, C, D, ... and indeed without even knowing name ly, ho · b
D .... which contain the objective ground of another, M, can bn.ng. a out
135 that this is so, may be disputed by those logicians who will not admit that
the recognition of the latter as well; or how we pass from certa111 JUdge-
there are any immediate inferences. For they claim that the rule accord-
n1en ts. A , B , c , D , · · · to 'another ' M ' which is deducible from them, the .
ing to which the conclusion is deduced from the premises, if not expressly r is that these are the effects of our personal measure of cognz-
easy a ,nswe . 1
adduced, must nevertheless be tacitly thought. They will claim that in all
tive ability. For if we ascribe infinite cognitive powers to a bemg we a so
of our inferences, we never deduce the conclusion from the premises with must think of it as omniscient, i.e., in possession of the knowledge of all
full confidence unless we recognise the correctness of the rule of infer- truths, and consequently cognisant of all relations of ground-consequence
ence. And in fact if this recognition only means that we do not consider and deducibility; thus is it quite understandable that we humans, who
the rule of inference to be incorrect when someone presents it to us, then have at least a finite portion of these cognitive abilities, are abl~ to recog-
what is said here is certainly true, but it does not conflict with the claim . . if not all at least some easier cases of these relations. Thmgs stand
I made above. What I cannot admit is that the rule spoken of here must mse, , h' h
somewhat differently when certain judgements A,B,C,D, . · · , w ic
be thought at least tacitly. For if this claim were strictly adhered to, we
merely stand in a relation of probability to a pro~osition ~' lead us not
would require an infinite number of premises for every conclusion. to form the judgement that M is probable, but to form M itsel.f. Here we
Note 3. The claim (no. 11) that every kind of inference which we
simply cannot say that this is an effect of our cogr~itive !ac~tltze~. For t~e
have adopted instinctively and without the benefit of reflection must be
proposition Mis not in fact always a truth, and a be1~g wt.th 111fi111te cogm-
correct may well not be generally accepted. For a great many scholars tive powers would not judge as we do. It would certa111ly judge that M ~as
believe that all of our knowledge falls short of objective truth, or at least probable, but it would not form the judgement M itself. Thus the quest10n 137
that it cannot be proven to be objectively true. Thus they will be unwilling remains: how do we come to make this judgement? It won't do to assu.me
to grant the objective truth of the rules of inference we use in deducing a special simple faculty which leads us to such judgement_s; otherw1.se,
certain judgements form others. Others may allow that human inferential we should have to say that the most perfect being lacks a faculty wluch
faculties follow correct rules for those in good health, but wonder whether we have. Rather, we must explain the origin of such judgements as a phe-
this is also the case for the deranged, insane, or idiotic. Also somewhat nomenon which rests upon the limitation of our powers, and which could
pertinent here is KANT' s theory of the antinomies of pure reason in their
be brought about by a combination of several of the~. Th~ ~ase ~ould
speculative use as well as HERBART' s claim (Lehrb. z. Einl. in d. Phil., be similar to the faculty of desire which, in finite bemgs, d1V1des ~nto a
§6 and elsewhere) "that conceiving the world and ourselves" introduces faculty of wishing and of willing, the former of whi~h is not found m the
distinct concepts "which render the sought unification of our thought ever infinite being, since it results from a mere imperfection, namely, from the

90 91
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 302. Of Judgements

limitation of our own well-being; so also with the faculty of judgement; be said, precisely because they are not produced through the mediation of
in finite beings this faculty sometimes leads to a combination of ideas thers. These can be either intuitional or conceptual judgements 139
0
resulting not in certain, but merely in probable propositions. And just I) The two most important kinds of immediate intuitional judgement
as wishing can be considered an imperfect willing, so too the confidence were already introduced in §300, no. 12. The first of these, "l-have-
with which a finite being forms a judgement based on a merely proba- impression X", presupposes for its occurrence only the following two
ble proposition is imperfect compared with the confidence with which it things: the judging person must (a) have the capacity to undergo a change
states something that is completely certain. of the same type as impression X and (b) must raise this impression to the
2) So much, in my view, may one claim, without deciding anything level of clarity. If the cognising being considers a present impression A
further about the particular way in which this happens, which may turn (idea, sensation, etc.), then it is also in a position to form the judgement
out to be very difficult to work out. If I were to hazard a guess, however, that it has such an impression. The origin of judgements of the form
I would say that the origin of such judgements stems from a particular "This (what I just now perceive) is an A" is much more difficult to ex-
limitation of ours, due to which we can only maintain a certain number plain, especially if idea A (as I think is possible) is not simple, but highly
of ideas in the mind at one time. Because of this, in the case of somewhat complex (cf. §286, no. 8). The soul will hardly form such judgements the
complex ideas and judgements, we allow some of their constituents- first time it has an intuition of the kind A. But if (through the influence
those which draw less attention to themselves-to drop out of conscious- of various circumstances) the changes which are necessary to produce a
ness. Now with judgements expressing the probability of a proposition certain intuition which stands under the concept A occur repeatedly and
138 M-provided that this probability is so high that we must guide our ac- in a suitably short span of time, then there is nothing incomprehensible
tion by M-the proposition itself is by far the most important thing, while in the supposition that the soul, directing its entire attention upon these
the fact that it is not decidedly true but only probable is not nearly as im- changes, will eventually be in a position to form more and more precise
portant. Now if we are unable to keep in our mind all of the parts of ideas of their peculiar attributes; especially if changes take place in be-
M as well as the thought that this proposition is not completely certain, tween which follow an entirely different law, because the contrast will
but merely so highly probable that we have to act upon it, then it seems facilitate the comprehension of the changes in question. I do not consider
natural that we omit the latter thought, since it is the less important, and it difficult to conceive that the mind gradually forms a concept of these
concentrate our attention merely upon proposition M itself in order to specific attributes, even if they must be compounded from several parts.
grasp it completely and retain it. In this way it happens that the judge- For the compounding of a concept from several fitting parts is a capacity
ment which attributes only a certain degree of probability to proposition which we must attribute to the mind, since we are in the possession of
M gradually disappears from our clear consciousness (if it ever attained concepts of that sort. All this can be much more easily comprehended if
such a position), and judgement M alone remains. we presuppose that in doing this the mind does not form the judgement
that it does it, but that it performs these operations without being clearly 140
§.302. conscious of them.
2) If a judgement which we form without deriving it from other judge-
How we come by our immediate judgements ments is a purely conceptual judgement, the occasion for forming it may
be provided by certain other judgements we have previously formed.
Although no one can expect a treatise of logic to describe the way in
Through them or through the action of some outer objects, it may happen
which every one of our judgements originates, it is desirable that enough
that the concepts required for our judgement are produced in the soul; but
be said on this score as is necessary to understand the possibility of pro-
the complete ground of why we form precisely this judgement-why we
ducing the diverse kinds of judgements to be met with in our conscious-
judge, for example, that every object represented by a certain concept A
ness. I will attempt to do this to a certain extent in the following two
has an attribute represented by concept b-does not lie in these circum-
sections. From §300 we already know that some of our judgements arise
stances alone. Rather, part of the ground for forming this judgement must
immediately, while others do not. With respect to the former, little can

92 93
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of .Judgements

lie in the specific attributes of the two concepts A and b themselves. For the observed temporal order of certain external objects; but this can not
if this were not so, we might just as well think it necessary to separate always be the case; rather, the temporal order of external changes is, as a
A and b, rather than to combine them in the judgement "A has b". But rule, inferred from temporal sequences that take place within ourselves.
as the reason why we combine these concepts does not lie in any previ- It would be impossible for us to know what is earlier or later in the ex-
ous judgements we have made-otherwise, it would not be an immediate ternal world if we did not know beforehand what is earlier or later within 142
judgement-it is obvious that in order to explain the appearance of such ourselves. It is indeed possible that I am unable to say which of two ob-
a judgement in our mind, we may, in addition to what has already been jects, this chapel or that house, I have known longer, until I am told that
said, add no more than this: it occurs because the concepts we represent the former was erected a few years after the latter; but generally things
by A and b are precisely those we actually represent. are reversed: only by perceiving internal temporal sequences can I recog-
nise the temporal order of phenomena in the external world. From this
§.303.* it follows that if we want to explain the recognition of internal temporal
sequences, we cannot have recourse to our recognition of spatial rela-
How we arrive at, or could arrive at, our tions. The locations of things are no more than those determinations we
most general judgements of experience must assume them to have so that we can explain why they act upon each
other in just such and such temporal relations (given the forces which we
In contrast to immediate judgements, the origin of mediated judgements
recognise in them). It is obvious, therefore, that we can recognise spatial
can be more precisely explained. In order not to become too prolix, I want
relations only after we have first recognised certain temporal relations.
to describe only a single class of such judgements, namely, the judge-
This is not contradicted by the fact that we use space (certain movements
ments of experience that we usually take to be immediate, since we are
in it) in order to measure time, since closer consideration shows that the
141 rarely conscious of the inferences which mediate them. It must be noted
question whether a change in space took place at a certain time can in the
that it is not sufficient to indicate the modes of inference we use in or-
encl only be decided by reference to relations of simultaneity, which is an
der to form these judgements (this has already been discussed in another
easily recognisable temporal relation. It follows from all this that tem-
place), rather, we must discuss these inferences themselves, i.e., we must
poral relations between individual mental phenomena (especially ideas,
indicate the most important propositions of which they are composed. Fi-
sensations, etc.) can at least sometimes be determined from their inner
nally, I do not merely want to describe how these judgements are actually
characteristics. The question is, how is this clone? I think that it must
formed, but rather how they could and should be formed if a rational man
be possible for us to recognise immediately that a given idea, sensation,
wanted to justify them.
or appearance is at this moment present in ourselves. For, if we cannot
1) The greatest difficulty arises precisely where I think we must make
even recognise this immediately, then it is inconceivable how we could
the start, namely, when we have to explain how we form those judge-
bring it out by inferences. For it is clear that no moment in time can be
ments in which we determine temporal relations which hold between cer-
determined through concepts alone unless one such moment is given. But 143
tain phenomena that take place within ourselves, e.g., with the judgement
there is no reason whatever to consider a future or past moment as given
"Idea A precedes idea B within me", etc. It seems to me that judgements
rather than the present moment. But a moment is given by characterising
of this kind should not be considered immediate. We do not immediately
it as that moment at which a certain internal phenomenon takes place.
perceive in our ideas, sensations, etc., which of them are earlier, which
Thus it must at least sometimes be possible to recognise immediately that
later, etc.; rather, we must infer this from the observation of certain of
an idea or sensation is now occurring in us. Without doubt this will be
their properties or from other circumstances. But it is even more obvi-
possible only with those mental phenomena which have been raised to
ous that the temporal relations between mental changes are not always
the level of clarity (§280).
inferred from the perception of temporal relations among certain external
2) Furthermore, it must sometimes be possible for us to recognise
changes. It is true that we occasionally determine the temporal order in
immediately that a certain idea or judgement which we form contains as
which ideas and sensations follow each other in our mind by reference to

94 95
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

parts certain other ideas A, B, C, D .... But if this is the case, then we 7) The same also holds when phenomenon A is composed of several
can cone! ude that these several ideas A, B, C, D, . . . are in our mind at individual phenomena, e.g., ideas, sensations, etc. Consequently we can
the same time. Thus here is a method with which we can recognise the recognise that several ideas (or phenomena) A, A', A", ... have repeatedly
simultaneity of certain ideas; it is evident that similar considerations also occurred together. In this way I become aware of the fact that I repeatedly
hold of judgements, sensations, and other phenomena within ourselves, if had the idea of certain colours (namely, the colours of roses) and the
they appear as parts of a whole which can come about only through their sensation of a certain odour (the odour of a rose) at one and the same
interaction (hence their simultaneous presence). time.
3) It is also certain that we can often recognise the inconsistency 8) Now we already know several ways in which we can form judge-
of saying that two phenomena A and B are simultaneously in our mind. ments stating that a certain mental idea or phenomenon belongs to an
Sometimes we can see this immediately, sometimes for reasons quite in- earlier time. But there are several other ways. For example we can con-
dependent from the present investigation. Thus it would be an obvious clude, at least with probability, that a certain idea must have been present
contradiction to say that a judgement A as well as its actual contradictory, in our mind earlier, perhaps even several times, if we can generate it more
the judgement "A is false", are formed simultaneously. Hence, if we are easily and with less attention than is usually the case with ideas of a sim-
forced to admit the presence of certain contradictory phenomena in our- ilar composition, etc. In particular with respect to judgements we can
144 selves, we conclude that they could occur only at different times. Here surmise that the judgement "A is B" must have been formed once before,
then is a means by which we recognise that certain phenomena within if it appears in our consciousness and we are unable to indicate the rea-
ourselves are not simultaneous, but take place at different times. son why we have formed it, provided it does not belong to the class of
4) Finally, if we recognise that a phenomenon A is just now present, judgements that are recognised immediately. Thus I can conclude, justi-
then we know that its contradictory, B, which we also find in us, must fiably, that I have formed the judgement: Vi 1.414 ... once before if it
have taken place in the past. For example, if we recognise that we just appears within me without calculation.
now formed the judgement Neg.A, then we know that the judgement A, if 9) In order to generate a certain sum of ideas, judgements, or whatever
we have also formed it, must have been formed in the past. In this way other internal phenomena, a certain length of time is required; in order to
we can determine the relation of priority between one time and another. form the same sum of ideas or judgements a second time, we need about
5) It is likely that there are other such methods. There are several the same time or somewhat less. The same holds if these phenomena 146
phenomena in ourselves of which we can be certain that one of them form a certain series, i.e., if there is a certain order in which they follow
must be earlier or later than the other. For example, a wish must be in each other, as, for example, the ideas 1, 2, 3, 4, etc., when we count. Now
our mind earlier than the sensation of its fulfilment. Also, the individual let a, b, c, d, e, ... , y, z be such a series of phenomena in our mind; let A
ideas whose combination results in another idea must be earlier than the be a certain other mental phenomenon which is simultaneous with a, and
latter, etc. Now if we recognise by the criterion given in no. 2 that a cer- let B be a phenomenon simultaneous with z. In this case we know that
tain mental phenomenon occmTed at the same time as a wish, and another the two phenomena A and B are separated by the span of time which is
simultaneous with the feeling of its fulfilment, then we can form a judge- required to generate all of the ideas b, c, ... , y. If we repeat the series
ment about the temporal relation between these two other phenomena. after having once run through it, in such a way that after the final idea z
6) If an internal phenomenon A is a part of several phenomena M, the idea a comes about for the second time and if phenomenon C occurs
N, 0, ... , or if we realise in some other way that it was simultaneous in the mind as soon as we reach z for the second time, then we know that
with each of them, and if we also know that phenomena M, N, 0, ... phenomena A and C are about twice as far apart as A and B, etc. Here
contradict one another in some respect and hence cannot have been in the we have a method of estimating the relation between different lengths of
mind at the same time, or if we conclude this for some other reason, then time. We actually use this device if we count in order to measure the time
we discover that phenomenon A must have been in the mind at different lapses between phenomena A, B, C, D, ....
145 times, hence either continuously over a span of time, or repeatedly.

96 97
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

10) If we have a present intuition A, then we must recognise immedi- have the power arbitrarily to produce within us intuitions of certain ob-
ately whether it belongs to the class of external or internal intuitions (cf. jects, and to remove these intuitions. For example, if we have a rose in
§286), i.e., whether or not the change in our mind, which we presently our hands, we can produce the sensation of its fragrance in ourselves,
observe, must be thought of as the result of the influence of a certain ex- and we can also remove that sensation. According to no. 13, this pre-
ternal object. In this way we find out that there are also external objects supposes that a change takes place either in these objects themselves, or
that have the power to produce intuitions in us. in the spatial relations between them and ourselves, or in one of the sur-
l l) If we have certain similar intuitions, i.e., if they all stand under the rounding objects; thus we discover that we have the power to produce, at
same concepts (we must at least sometimes be able to recognise this im- will, a great many changes in the external objects surrounding us, or in
mediately, cf. §300, no. 12), we conclude from this, if not with certainty the spatial relations between them and ourselves.
then at least with probability, that the objects which caused them will also 15) This imposition of our will upon external objects, which we ex-
147 be similar. This inference is not certain, since dissimilar causes can some- perience in this way, is not always immediate; often external objects are
times have similar effects. Thus an intuition of yellow can sometimes be influenced by changes which we bring about in others. But there must
caused by the influence of a yellow object upon our eye, but sometimes by always be some external object upon which we act immediately. The to-
the humours of the eye itself, if they are coloured in an unnatural way, etc. tality of these is called the mental organ [Seelen01gan], and if we acid to it
But so long as no extraordinary circumstances obtain, it is more probable everything that stands to it in an organic connection it is called our body.
that similar effects proceed from similar causes. We will soon see in what way we gather more and more information con-
12) If it happens repeatedly that we experience simultaneously certain cerning the existence and attributes of this body.
intuitions which stand under the concepts A, B, C, D, ... , and we rarely, 16) If certain intuitions M, N, 0, ... (i.e., intuitions which stand un-
if ever, experience one of them without the other, then we conclude with der the concepts M,N, 0, ... ) never occur unless certain other intu-
a good deal of probability that it is one and the same actual object which itions A, B, C, D, ... preceded them in time, we conclude that things or
causes these intuitions in us. We may therefore attribute several powers changes which were necessary to bring about intuitions A,B,C,D, ...
to it, namely, the power to generate intuition A, to generate intuition B, are a condition for the occurrence of those things or changes belonging
etc. This method of inference allows us to discover, by and by, the dif- to intuitions M, N, 0, ..... If intuitions M, N, 0, ... always follow as L49
ferent powers which surrounding objects have. For example, if we have soon as intuitions A, B, C, D, ... have taken place, we conclude that the
repeatedly experienced a red colour together with a certain very pleasant things or changes which bring about intuitions A, B, C, D, ... contain a
fragrance, we conclude that it is one and the same object which caused sufficient ground or complete cause for the occurrence of those things or
both of these intuitions in us or, what comes to the same thing, that the changes that bring about intuitions M,N, 0, ..... Conversely, if intuitions
rose has a fragrance. M,N, 0, ... never occur without A,B,C,D, . .. but the latter sometimes
13) But now we must explain why the object whose presence we have occur without the former, we realise that the particular changes which
just assumed does not always cause the indicated intuitions A, B, C, D, . .. bring about A, B, C, D, ... are not the complete ground, but a mere condi-
in us. This can be explained in only one of three ways, namely, either this tion for the things or changes which bring about intuitions M,N, 0, .....
object changes from time to time, or there are certain other objects whose In this way we can judge the means or conditions which lead to the origin
interference prevents this influence, or the spatial relations between this of many objects.
object and ourselves change. 17) If certain phenomena M, N, 0, ... which I want to bring about
14) When we experience that in many cases some things happen after in my mind do not always occur, but only after I have succeeded in first
we have previously willed them, we conclude that our will is the cause producing A,B,C,D, ... , I conclude that my mind cannot immediately
148 of their occurrence and that we have the power to bring about results of bring about the changes leading to the phenomena M, N, 0, ... , but only
this kind. In this way we find out about several powers that reside within through mediation of those changes which lead to phenomena A,B,C,
ourselves. In particular, we realise that under certain circumstances we D, ... , hence only after the latter are actualised. Thus I want to expe-

98 99
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

rience the taste of an apple. I bring this about only after first producing 21) All these cognitions become much more determinate when we
all those intuitions which follow upon looking at the apple, bringing it begin to assess the spatial relations in which external objects stand to
to my mouth, etc.; therefore I conclude that the appearance of that taste ourselves and to each other. I imagine that this happens in the following
within me did not come about immediately but only by mediation. On way, or could happen in the following way if we proceeded in a par-
the other hand, if there are certain phenomena M, N, 0, ... , in my mind ticularly strict manner. Some of my intuitions refer to external objects.
that always, or almost always, come about when I wish, I conclude that Whenever these intuitions change, I must assume that the cause of this
150 the objects which are necessary for their production can be immediately change is either a change within myself, or in some of the external ob-
influenced by my mind or are intimately connected with those that are so jects; the latter can be a change either in their spatial relations to me or
influenced. I therefore count them as part of my own body. in their inner attributes, or (what is probably more cmTect) in all of these
18) I have intuitions of colours; I cannot arbitrarily create them but things at once, only in varying degrees. Since my intuitions which refer
I can arbitrarily remove them (namely, by shutting my eyes). I conclude to an external object are changes within me brought about by the influ-
from this that these intuitions do not arise within me immediately, but ence of an external object, the character of these intuitions is determined
only through the mediation of an object which depends upon my will, by my attributes, the attributes of the external object, and the spatial re-
i.e., a part of my body. This part I call my eyes. In a similar way I find lation between us. Without a change in one of these three parts there
out that I have organs through which I receive fragrances, intuitions of can be no change in those intuitions. But if one of these things changes,
taste, intuitions of sounds, etc. then, because of the interaction between all things in the world, all other
19) By the well-known laws of association of ideas, the sight of a rose things change as well, except that the change in one or the other can be
in front of me awakens within me the memory of that pleasant fragrance so insignificant that we can neglect it. Now, according to no. 11, if the
which I have repeatedly experienced along with the sight of a rose; occa- same collection of intuitions A, B, C, D, ... occurs within me repeatedly,
sionally, there is also a desire to repeat this sensation. But this desire is I conclude that it is one and the same object which brings them about. I
not satisfied until I have picked the rose (perhaps for no particular reason) do not know, so far, what happened to the object in the interim, when I 152
and moved it to my nose. During this activity I see the changes which take did not have intuitions A, B, C, D, ... , whether it was changed, or perhaps
place with my hand, i.e., several intuitions arise within me for whose ex- destroyed, and only regenerated at the moment when these intuitions re-
planation I must assume certain changes that take place in that part of curred, or whether the disappearance and reappearance of its intuitions
my body. Since this change resulted in the satisfaction of that desire (to stemmed merely from a change in its spatial relation to me. If I now un-
smell the rose), I conclude that that part of my body which brought about dertake several actions through which we can usually ensure that a certain
the various different intuitions was through its change (motion) also the sum of intuitions A,B,C,D, ... disappears without returning, i.e., diverse
cause (partial cause) of the satisfaction which followed. In this fashion I activities through which objects are usually changed, but find that no such
learn more and more about the services which can be performed by my change occurs in this case, then I surmise that the disappearance and reap-
hands and the other members of my body. pearance was not caused by a change in the object in question, but only
20) I daily experience pleasant and unpleasant sensations occurring by a change in its spatial disposition relative to me, or by the interference
151 simultaneously with changing appearances of this or that part of my body, of another object. In this case I must ascribe to the object a certain power
and which can become more vivid or more faint depending upon certain to remain in a given condition (a certain connection of its parts), i.e., a
influences that are exercised upon this part. From this I conclude that the certain solidity. For example, if I grasp a piece of wood with my hands
cause of these sensations lies in a change of these parts. Thus I can have a and touch it in various ways, then the same intuitions recur from time to
strong toothache without knowing which tooth contains the cause of this time (as often as this body is brought into the same position between my
pain, until I find out that there is a change in the pain when one of my fingers); on the other hand, in the case of a soft or liquid body the sensa-
teeth is touched. tions which it causes change constantly, and earlier ones do not recur. (In

100 101
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgenients

a similar way we convince ourselves that our hands themselves, or rather 27) I frequently notice that a body, as long as it is found to be in
their parts, are solid bodies of this kind.) contact or connection with a certain other body, for example with my
22) Assume that two sums of intuitions A,B,C,D, ... and M, N, O, hand (i.e., if it is cmTied or held by it), does not change its spatial relation
P, ... are given, where the first is taken as the effect of body X, the second to me; I also experience a certain effort on this occasion which becomes
as the effect of body Y. If these sums occur either simultaneously or in more unpleasant the longer it lasts. I therefore conclude that this effort
quick succession, either A,B,C,D, ... after M,N,O,P, ... or vice versa, caused the body to remain in its position; from this it follows that it must
then I surmise that the locations of these two bodies are very close to- have a certain propensity to change its location. In this way I discover
gether, or that the bodies touch each other. This conclusion is not certain; that certain bodies attract or repel each other, and hence the general law
for example, two stars which are always seen simultaneously can still be of gravity.
153 very far apart. But so long as there is no circumstance which indicates 28) Occasionally I notice that a certain body A (for example a ball)
an exception, this assumption is probable, especially if the bodies do not can touch another body B (for example a horizontal board), in a variety of
only appear to the eye, but also to the other senses, i.e., touch, hearing, different ways, although the latter stays at rest, and although the parts with
smell, etc., at almost the same time. which both bodies touch, at least in the case of B, change constantly. I
23) If a certain appearance which I ascribe to the influence of an ex- furthermore find out that it takes about the same expenditure of effort and
ternal object becomes either stronger or weaker from moment to moment, time to move body A from its initial position on B to any other position so
then I may surmise in the first case that this object approaches or, in the long as they are equidistant. Now if body A is at rest and I give it a push
second, that it recedes. with another body, for example my hand, in such a way that in the ensuing
24) Assume bodies, M, N, 0, P, Q, ... and A are all found to be solid. motion it continues to be in contact with B (is not propelled above B), then
Furthermore body A has been found to have two different parts a and u., I can conclude that this motion, being caused by the impact alone, lies in a
and now it is realised that at a given time a touches M and u. touches N, plane. Through my eye I can also comprehend the line which is described
at a later time a touches N and u. touches 0, then, later, a touches 0, and by A. And if I now find that a similar line is described no matter where
u. touches P, etc. I conclude that the distances between things M and N, the motion begins and what direction it takes, it follows that the surface
N and 0, 0 and P, etc., are approximately equal to the distance between of body B, upon which all of these motions take place, can only be one 155
parts a and u.. The body A which I use for this purpose can, for example, of two things, either the surface of a sphere, or a plane; and the lines can
be my own hand and parts a and u. can be two specially chosen parts of it either be segments of circles or straight lines. But my eye gives me a
(as for example the thumb and the little finger). simple means to distinguish a straight line from any other line (actually,
25) If a body A moves from the vicinity of M into the vicinity of N in this context, a line is a series of small bodies which are distinguished
and from there into the vicinity of 0, etc., and the distances MN and NO by their colour; and the eye can distinguish straight series of this kind
are equal to each other and the times which pass are also equal, then I from curved ones). The former has the property that, no matter from
know that bodies A and M,N, 0, move uniformly relative to each other. what vantage point it is observed, it generates upon the retina a picture
26) Assume that a body B has so far not changed its relation to cer- which coincides with a piece of that line generated at a different distance.
tain other bodies M,N,O,P, ... (among which there is my own body). Thus the ideas which are produced by a whole line, and the ideas which
Assume furthermore that another body A changed this relation and even- are produced by a piece of it (after the distance has been changed), must
tually came into contact with B: when this happened, the relation between be equal to each other. Every line in which I ascertain this property, I
Band those other bodies M,N, 0, ... also changed. I then conclude with recognise as straight. But if I have once seen several straight lines, I
154 probability that the contact between the moving body A and B (i.e., the become familiar with the peculiarity of this phenomenon so that I can tell
impact) was the cause of the ensuing motion of B. In this way I discover by sight whether a line should be reckoned among the straight ones or
that the members of my own body, for example my hands, can produce the curved ones. In this way I find in the above case that the lines are
motion by impact. straight and that the smi'ace of body B is a plane. Soon I learn from the

102 103
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

mere illumination of a surface whether it is plane or curved. But once I 30) Once we have become acquainted with several solids that have a
can distinguish straight and curved things, I acquire the ability to measure fairly permanent shape and size, it will become easier every day to gauge
distances; for if lines nm, no are straight, and are juxtaposed in such a way the shape, magnitude, and distance of other bodies, especially if we can
that mo is also straight, then the distance mo is the sum of the distances mn ernploy the sense of sight; in doing so we should particularly employ the
and no. Finally, since all spatial relations can be determined by distances, following rules: (a) every body that is kept out of sight by another body
it follows that if I can estimate distances, there are no relations in space rnust be farther away than the covering body; (b) every body that does
which I cannot determine. not change its magnitude must be the farther away from us the smaller
29) But it should not be imagined that the just-indicated method of the angle of sight under which it appears (the angle of sight is measured
estimating distances is the only possible one, and that the sense of sight by comparing the body in question with another body that changes neither
156 is indispensable for this matter. Even if we lack sight, we can determine distance nor size); (c) every body that does not change either its size or
these relations, albeit with more effort. We have shown in no. 21 how shape must be the farther away the more obscure it appears to us and the
the sense of touch alone can tell us whether or not a given body is solid. less we are able to distinguish its parts, all other things remaining equal,
Through the sense of touch we also find that there are bodies whose con- etc.
nected parts resist complete separation and destruction, though the parts 31) It could be asked how a child or even animals aITive at a knowl-
change their spatial relations to each other in many ways and, in particu- edge of all these relations in space, since it is quite obvious that they do
lar, can be brought closer together. Such a body we tend to call flexible. not perform the inferences which I have here described. My reply is that
We now grasp parts of this body that ai·e not in immediate connection the grasp of spatial relations which we find in children and animals can
with each other (perhaps with both hands) and try to move one of them be explained with no more than the well known law of the association
in a direction which it resists; we now know that the distance between of ideas, or the expectation of similar cases under similar circumstances
these two parts is the largest there can be, unless the connection between which issues from it, especially if we assume that instinct has certain ef-
them is severed. Now if the individual parts of this body are small, so that fects. We say that an animal has a grasp of relations in space if we notice
they can be easily grasped, while the whole body is much lai·ger (longer), that it avoids a stone lying in its path, or if it wants to acquire a food
then the position in which we have now brought it represents a straight object and turns either to the left or to the right depending whether the
line (actually a thread), and by touching it we can learn how such a line is object actually is at the left or the right. But all this can be explained
represented by the sense of touch. Consider some other body which of- satisfactorily from the mere association of ideas; it avoids the stone be- 158
fers the same sensations, no matter where we touch it; we must conclude cause several times when it had an intuition of the kind that it now has
that its surface is either plane or cylindrical or spherical. Which of the of this stone, its running was impeded; it turns right in order to snatch its
three is the case can be decided in various ways. For example, if we also prey since earlier on, when it had these kinds of intuitions, it also had to
have a body that can be moulded into different shapes and retains them, turn right in order to grasp it, etc. A child, when it is old enough to clarify
then we can make an imprint of the surface in question upon this material, some of its concepts, can go a step further and use successful associations
and if the surface which is generated by the impression is like the given of ideas to make rules for future cases, and thus to act consciously.
surface (i.e., if it produces the same sensations when touched), then it is Notes. So far I have considered only the most general points that had
flat, in the other case it is either cylindrical or spherical, the former if we to be stated by way of introduction. However, some readers may welcome
encounter different tactile sensations in different parts, the latter if this the discussion, in the following notes, of some points that arise only after
is not the case. If two plane surfaces of a body meet (an example is the a more detailed investigation of this subject.
edge of a prism), then the parts of the solid where this occurs (where a l) In no. 15 ff. it was shown, roughly, how we a!Tived at a knowl-
157 new sensation starts) form a straight line, and by a frequent and attentive edge of our body and its sensory organs. In a similar way we distinguish
touching of such a solid, we can learn how the peculiar properties of such whether a certain change in our perceptions derives from a change in our
straight lines are manifested to touch, etc. body or in one of the other external objects. If it is a change in one of our

104 105
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judge1nents

sensory organs, then it must uniformly extend to all perceptions deriving body. It is for this reason that we place the sensations which are given
from this organ. Thus, for example, I realise that the red spots which us by the sense of touch, taste, or smell in special organs of the body,
I have had before my eye for a few seconds (since I have cast a glance since the change which takes place in them whenever they give us these
into the bright sun) stem from a change in the eye, not from a change in sensations is also noticeable by other senses. If we touch something with
another external object; the reason is that I see the spots superimposed the tips of our fingers, the impression which this body makes upon the
upon every object upon which I fix my eye. One could object that this fingers can be seen, etc. On the other hand, the ideas which we derive
rule would also attribute the darkening of all objects after sundown to a from the sense of hearing or sight are referred to bodies outside of our
change in our eye or an extinction of vision, which would be absurd. But own body, since the changes suffered by these organs when they are ex-
there are two matters to be considered: first, the same blackout can be ternally influenced are not usually noticeable by any of the other senses.
achieved during the daytime as often as we want, so long we bring about Only in rare cases, where a strong impression causes a sensation of pain
a certain external change, e.g., close the shutters; second, we can see at (when our ears ring or our eyes bum, etc.), are we reminded of the organ
159 night as soon as we make certain external changes, e.g., light a fire. These which produced those ideas.
circumstances demonstrate that the cause for this darkening does not lie 4) Given these assumptions, several questions which were raised with
in our eyes, but is to be found in some external object. respect to judgements derived from the sense of sight can be easily an-
2) Even simple people often ask the question whether and how they swered. For example, how we can make such quick and automatic de-
can assure themselves that things present themselves to their senses in cisions concerning the magnitude, distance, and position (left, right, up)
the same way as they present themselves to the senses of other persons. of every visible object and why do such judgements appear to us to be
However, we can conclude that another being observes things in about immediate perceptions, so that we cannot disregard them even if other
the same way we do if we notice that it reacts to them in the same way circumstances show them clearly to be mistaken, whence we say that the
we do, i.e., that it, too, has a desire for impressions which we find pleas- thing, though it is not really this way, at least appears to be this way? The
ant, that it makes a distinction between objects between which we, too, origin of such judgements is all the more puzzling since (a) the pictures
differentiate, etc. On the other hand, if we notice that somebody differen- in the retina of the eye which (as was thought) are immediately seen by
tiates things which we confuse, we justly ascribe to him sharper, or more the mind, appear twice (once in each eye), while actually there is only
perfect, senses than ours. one object; since (b) these pictures are usually much smaller than the ex-
3) There is another very interesting question, namely, why we con- ternal object which causes them, while we do not perceive this object to
sider the location of some of our ideas and sensations to be in the mind, be diminished in size, but in its normal size; since (c) a small body at
while in other cases their actual place is considered to be in some part of a close distance produces a larger picture than a large body at a greater 161
the body, and in still other cases we think neither of the mind, nor of the distance, while the distances are very nearly alike in all these pictures,
body, but only of certain external objects. My opinion is that we consider and especially since (cl) their position is reversed so that what is to the
an idea or sensation as present only in ourselves if we do not notice any left in the picture is to the right in actuality, and what in actuality is on
external object as its immediate cause. Thus we say of a concept which top is at the bottom of the picture, etc. In order to overcome these diffi-
we form by mere thought, e.g., the concept of a perpetuum mobile, that it culties, some philosophers have assumed that the mind has an immediate
is to be found only within ourselves (in our mind). On the other hand, if sensation of the direction in which a light ray meets our eye; but aside
an idea is caused by a noticeable change in our body, e.g., a wound on our from the fact that this assumption still does not explain everything, it is
finger, then we locate this phenomenon in that specifically changed part very hard even to understand. Rather, the correct explanation rests upon
of our body. I have already discussed in no. 20 why we assume that a cer- different grounds. We have to make no decision whatsoever whether it
tain change in the body is the cause of that mental phenomenon. Finally, is the retina of the eye or some other part of our bodily machine which
if we do not notice the change itself which an external object produces in receives the light impressions in the first place: the only definite thing is
160 the organs of our body, then we seek the cause of this idea outside of our that there is such a part and that the mind must perceive immediately the

106 107
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

changes which take place in it, and must infer, merely from its attributes, tor is that from childhood on we found out nothing about these objects,
the figure, magnitude, distance, and position of the visible objects in the except what we learned by sight. Hence we find it natural to explain the
following way: whenever the organ is changed in the same way, the mind changes in their appearance from changes that take place in these bodies
infers a similar cause (unless some other circumstance inhibits this con- themselves, while we do not usually assume that a body with which we
clusion). Hence, if our eye (and indirectly also the actual mental organ) are more familiar, and of which we know that it does not quickly change
is stimulated, and we reach for the stimulating object, and find it above, its size (e.g., a man), becomes smaller whenever we see it from a larger
then we expect an object in an upward position as often as the light ray distance. We are so used to giving it the same size, even though it takes up
meets that place, i.e., we see it above, and so in other cases. If we ob- much less space on our retina, that we take this judgement to be an imme- 163
serve the change in our perceptions when a body, which changes neither diate perception and claim that it always appears to have the same size.
size nor shape, approaches or recedes, if we notice what aspect it offers Heavenly bodies exhibit various degrees of brightness, depending upon
when we have measured its distance with our hands or in some other way, how far they are above the horizon, and this explains why we assume that
then we are in a position, the next time, to judge, merely from the way in the skies have the form of a depressed sphere. But these considerations
which it is represented to our organs, whether it has the same, a larger, or do not explain the specific height that this sphere seems to have, and the
a smaller distance. The fewer parts we can distinguish in it, the farther distance at which the stars appear to be. The experience that even the
away we take it to be. Every object whose size we have learned by touch highest towers, mountains, clouds, and other objects sometimes obscure
becomes a means for estimating either the distance or the size of other a star, shows only that the distance of the stars is still larger; but we do
162 objects: the distance if we know its size, and the size if we know its dis- not know how large it is, nor have we found a limit within which they lie.
tance. Assume that you see, at a certain distance, a person with a staff in Rather, it seems that people assume the heavenly sphere to be at various
his hand. Because he holds the staff in his hand, you know that they are distances, depending on rather accidental circumstances. Those who have
at the same distance. If you find that one end of the staff coincides with never lived in the open or are nearsighted tend to think of the sky as being
the feet, the other with the head of the person, then you can conclude that lower, and the stars as being smaller, than those who have often climbed
the staff is about as long as the person. If we see a bird of known size high mountains and have keen eyesight. Perhaps when we were children
pass in front of the sun or the moon, in such a way that these bodies are we looked after a bird that was flying away, and it seemed to us that it got
not altogether covered by the bird, we conclude that they are larger than lost in a cloud, and we thought that the cloud or, what comes to the same
the bird. Through practice we learn to draw such conclusions with great thing, that the stars are as high as the bird; but the height of this bird we
rapidity, so that we no longer observe them, and are no longer conscious estimated from the time it took for its flight, etc. Even astronomers do not
of them. This explains why we mistake these judgements for immediate see the stars as larger, and this is clue to the fact that a judgement to which
perceptions, and why we cannot discount them even in cases when they we became accustomed in childhood can be corrected in later years but
are incorrect and we are convinced of their falsity through inferences of cannot be replaced in such a way that it does not come to mind at all.*
a different sort. Thus, sun and moon appear larger on the horizon than And it is this coming to mind which we call seeming [Scheinen]. If these
when they are overhead, because they emit a dimmer light when they are explanations are correct, then the difficulties mentioned above are over-
on the horizon, and are therefore taken to be farther away. That this is come. For example, we assume that there is only one object, even though 164
the correct cause can be seen from the fact that the same bodies appear to there are two parts of our body (both eyes) which are changed so as to in-
be of various size even on the horizon, if they appear under different cir- dicate the presence of an object; this is a consequence of the fact that we
cumstances; they seem especially large if we see a considerable number know from experience that if such and such corresponding parts of our
of objects of known size, e.g., villages, rivers, valleys, etc., between our- visual organ are simultaneously affected, there must be a single object
selves and them, especially if objects of considerable size are seen next to which is the cause of this affection. Consequently, we see double only
them on the horizon, for example, trees or buildings, though they appear
to us under the same or even a smaller visual angle. An additional fac- *Thus COMBE (Phreno/ogie, Braunschw., 1833) is incorrect in claiming that our in-
ability to suppress such illusions proves the immediacy of visual judgements.

108 109
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 303. Of Judgements

if our eyes change position in a non-uniform manner, for example, when §.304.
we look up with one and down with the other. For now we do not just
grasp those parts which we took in when there was only one object, but Other opinions on this subject
others: one eye sees parts which make the object appear in one position,
and the other as if it stood in another. Hence we see it double. The retinal
The topic of the origin of our judgements is so important, that we can-
images are very small, but we do not attribute the same small size to ex-
not forego a brief mention and examination of differing opinions on the
ternal objects; the reason is, simply, that we do not gauge the magnitude
rnatter put forward by others.
of external objects from these pictures at all (we do not even know that
1) The distinction between mediate and immediate judgements sug-
they are there), but mainly, we estimate size by touching. Similar points
gests itself so readily in this discussion that almost no one overlooked
can be made about distances and position. Finally, it should be remarked
it, even though (§300, note 1) not everyone grasped it with sufficient dis-
that the question whether we see objects in their true magnitude, distance
tinctness. The distinction between conceptual and intuitional judgements,
and position, has a reasonable sense only if it is applied to individual
which I look upon as indispensable, has, however, been rejected as of-
objects. If we wanted to ask whether or not perhaps all objects appear
ten as it has been proposed. The opposition which XENOPHANES, and
smaller or closer than they are in actuality, or upside down, we should be
still more his students PARMENIDES and the ELEATICS set up between
asking something entirely absurd. For an object can be smaller, or closer,
pure rational knmvledge and sensory experience was based upon a dis- J 66
or reversed, only with respect to others, but we cannot claim this of all
tinction between conceptual and intuitional judgements, even if this was
objects at the same time.
not recognised completely distinctly. What they called rational knowl-
5) Vision is indisputably the most perfect of the senses given to man.
edge were judgements composed merely of pure concepts, and what they
Almost all objects which are revealed to our other senses are also per-
called experience were judgements which either contain an intuition or
ceptible by sight, and for the most part at distances where they are un-
else were derived from one which does. And when PLATO (most likely
detectable by the other senses. In addition, the ideas of this sense have
not the first) went so far as to claim that certain concepts and truths were
the greatest variety, and can be distinguished with the greatest precision.
innate in the soul, while others are only learned through experience, this
After sight comes hearing, and much lower than these stand touch, smell,
clearly referred to the above distinction. DESCARTES, LEIBNIZ, CUD-
165 a~d taste. The first of the lower senses ranks higher than the others in my
WORTH, and many others agreed. Today, in Germany at least (thanks
view because any body which is of sufficient extent, and which comes
principally to KANT), there is a general conviction that, with respect to
close enough to us, can be perceived and judged by this sense, at least
their origin, there are two essentially different kinds of judgement, one of
in a certain measure. This ranking of the senses is also the basis for the
which may indeed begin with experience (the perceptions of intuitions we
fact that when asking about bodies, we generally inquire about the colour
have), but is not grounded in experience, and the other consisting merely
and shape, as well as certain properties detectable by the combined use
of intuitions or perceptions. Opposed to this view are the EPICUREANS,
of touch and sight.* Furthermore, the images discussed in §284 which
the STOICS, CAMPANELLA, GASSENDI, HOBBES, LOCKE, and almost
a~company our ideas are almost exclusively images of colour and shape.
all English and French scholars to the present day, who maintain that all
Fmally, we are inclined to deny the actuality of any object we cannot see
of our knowledge has an empirical origin. To refute this view, it is only
or feel. The advantages I have enumerated also explain why when we use
necessary to give a precise explanation of what is meant by empirical
signs for the changes occurring within us they are almost always either
origin. Nobody disputes that we begin to judge only when certain exter-
audible or visible.
nal objects have acted upon us, and have produced intuitions in us. The
only question is which of the following two cases actually takes place:
(a) All judgements which we form are either immediate judgements of
*Hence the use of the expression: "What does it look like?" in place of "What is its perception (cf. §300, no. 12), or can be deduced from a number of such
nature'l" judgements without the help of judgements of a different sort, namely,

110 111
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 304. Of Judgements

judgements which follow from pure concepts. (b) We also form some our derivative conceptual judgements, but rather how we arrive at the
167 conceptual judgements without deducing them from others. various judgements of experience, and in particular those we make with
Those who claim that all our judgements have empirical origin want such great fluency that we take them to be immediate. Principal among
to opt for the first alternative; but I believe that this is refuted by the mere these are judgements about temporal relations, e.g., between phenomena
fact that we form thousands of judgements whose origin cannot be ex- occurring within us. These have received little by way of explanation,
plained in this way. For example, how could we explain in this manner and often no attempt is made to explain them at all. Most seem to have
the simple judgement that fire burns? No matter how often we had simul- believed that our soul immediately recognises the temporal order of its
taneously a perception of fire and an impression of pain, we could never 0
wn ideas. LEIBNIZ (Nouv. Ess., II, xxvii, § 1) merely provided the hint
have formed the judgement that the same object is the cause of both, un- that we recognise differences of time and place from differences between
less we had first formed the judgement that a pair of phenomena which things, rather than the other way around (as LOCKE had claimed). Such
always happen at the same time have a common cause. I do not wish to judgements would accordingly be mediate, though LEIBNIZ provided no
claim that we must put this judgement in words, but at least we must have further explanation.
recognised it obscurely. Yet this judgement is purely conceptual. Indeed 3) One of the most remarkable attempts was, without doubt, that of
the ways in which the defenders of empiricism tried to explain the ori- BERKELEY (in his Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowl-
gin of these judgements are not satisfactory in the least. LOCKE, REID, edge and other writings). The fact that this philosopher denied the exis-
BEATTIE, OSWALD, and others found it necessary to have recourse to tence of the external material world need not have any detrimental effect
certain instincts, i.e., they all confessed that the matter is inexplicable. upon his explanation concerning the origin of mediated judgements of-
HUME could explain the origin of the concepts of cause and effect only by experience, since this mediation remains the same whether the intuitions 169
reference to observations of the repeated succession of certain phenom- which we take to be caused by external objects are really caused by them
ena. But it seems obvious to me that such observation could only induce or (as BERKELEY thought) directly by God. He noted quite correctly that
us to apply these concepts; we must already have been convinced that the reason why we unite into one whole intuitions which come through
everything that happens has a cause if the observation that phenomenon several senses, and take them to be the effect of one and the same object,
A always follows upon phenomenon B is to lead us to the conclusion that merely derives from the simultaneous presence of such intuitions. He
there is a causal connection between the two. also noted correctly that we infer a causal connection when certain phe-
2) When I say, however, that empiricism has never managed to pro- nomena always follow each other. He was not quite as successful in his
vide a satisfactory explanation of the origin of even the most common explanation concerning the origin of our knowledge of spatial relations.
of our judgements, I by no means intend to convey that those who sup- He was quite correct in saying that the eye does not immediately give us
168 pose that there are two different sources of cognition (sensibility and rea- any other ideas but those of colours, hence that we never recognise im-
son) have been fortunate enough to explain everything. On the contrary, mediately the shape of a surface which is in front of us (as others had
the greatest philosophers have admitted that much remains unexplained. thought) but he went too far when he claimed that through sight alone
Even KANT (Critique of Pure Reason, A 141/B 180-81) recognised this, we can never arrive at ideas of relations in space; that the theorem of the
speaking of "hidden abysses in the human soul, whose true operations three dimensions of space and other geometrical doctrines cannot be un-
nature hardly ever divulges, or lays open to our gaze." TIEFTRUNK also derstood unless we have a sense of touch, and that for this very reason a
writes (G1: d. L., §73 note) "that the production of the principles of expe- man born blind who is suddenly made to see cannot, by sight alone, tell
rience remains shrouded in darkness; for since every man's reason proves a cube from a sphere when they are put before him, and that he could not
to be creative in this respect, he is only very rarely aware of this act of even notice whether or not a body suspended before his eyes is in mo-
generation, and much remains for the student of reason to do in order to tion. The last remark seems to be the one that is most obviously false.
raise the acts of reason in this respect to full clarity." It seems to me, It is certain that the mind must notice immediately, and not only through
however, that the most difficult thing is not to explain how we arrive at the mediation of the sense of touch, whether, during a period of time, its

112 113
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 304. Of Judgements

visual organ is affected in just one way, or in different ways (whether it that is quite similar to mine, and makes a number of acute and noteworthy
receives one or several intuitions at that time); hence we must be justified remarks. Only a little of what he says seems incorrect to me. For exam-
'
t 70 in the latter case, in concluding that a certain motion (in whatever body) ple, the formation of a judgement of the form "This (actual) object has
is the cause of the changing ideas which are coming in from the exter- this attribute" is explained as follows (p. 390): first, the soul considers as
nal world. Concerning MOLYNEUX' s problem about the possibility of a whole A a number of sensations (intuitions), which the object conveys to
distinguishing a cube from a sphere, LEIBNIZ gave what I take to be the it; it then directs its attention to one part (one of these intuitions) a, recog-
correct answer (in Nouv. Ess. II, ix, §8), namely, that this discrimination nises this individual idea a as a part of the whole A, and thus forms the
could be made after some thought. In fact, it can be seen from the pre- judgement "The object A has the attribute a." In this way, only analytic
ceding section that the sense of touch is not absolutely necessary in order judgements would come about, for if the attribute a already lies within the
to give an estimate of the spatial relations between external objects. For idea A, the judgement "A is a" is obviously analytic. On p. 399 one reads
example, we are justified in surmising that a given body recedes from us, that the concept of a substance requires a sensation "which can be present
if the intuitions which it causes in the senses of sight, hearing, and smell by itself, separately, without being present as a part or trait in something
(i.e., senses other than touch), become weaker and weaker, or disappear else; such is the feeling I have of myself or of an individual body. Such
altogether. And if we are very attentive and notice how the sensory in- a separate, complete feeling, from which the abstraction of a substance
tuitions, e.g., of sight or hearing, change gradually, we are later on put arises, must possess a certain inner pe1fection. It must be possible for it to
in a position to infer from the nature of these intuitions the relative dis- be present alone and for itself, and thus able to fill the sensing soul during
tance between the object and ourselves. The only difference is that now perception so completely that no other greater and more widespread feel- 172
the scale of distance is no longer determined by the sense of touch, but ing which contains it can be noticed at the same time." According to this
will be distance as estimated by sight or hearing. We will no longer say explanation, whether we should look upon something as a substance or
"the body is at arm's length" (i.e., we can barely touch it when we stretch an accident would depend upon a quite fortuitous and uncertain circum-
out our hand), but we will say "the body is as far away as a fly that we stance. For even if an object has completely saturated our senses once or
can barely make out" or "the body is as far away as a man whom we several times, does it follow that it will always do so? And is the body
can barely hear talking" or "as far away as a rose we can just smell", etc. whose existence we infer from the intuitions just now formed in us only
But even if it were very difficult or even impossible, without the sense one single substance? On the contrary: we declare every body which is
of touch, to estimate the mutual spatial relations of bodies that act upon large enough to be perceived to be a collection of many, indeed infinitely
us, we must never say that we would then be unable to grasp the truths many, substances. In my view, things stand quite otherwise. From mere
171 of geometry. It is true enough that the ordinary expositions of this sci- concepts (or, as one says, from mere grounds of reason), we can gather
ence take many properties of space as given, for example that it has three two things: first, that our own ego must be a substance, and indeed a sin-
dimensions, and we should perhaps avoid this. It is also true that most gle substance; second, that every so-called external intuition (§286) must
of our proofs are carried out in a way that they convince only those per- be caused by an outer object, which is composed of an infinite multitude
sons who already have some acquaintance with most spatial relations by of substances (by a so-called body). I cannot go into the reasons for the
a mixture of touch and sight. But should it not be possible to proceed in first truth here; the reasons for the second are, briefly, as follows: there
an entirely different way? Should it be altogether impossible to demon- are infinitely many finite substances in every finite space, all in mutual in-
strate the truths of geometry from pure concepts, in such a way that even teraction, so that those which lie within a finite distance from us together
those who connect no pictorial ideas with the words "line", "surface", only produce an effect of finite magnitude. Thus in order to bring forth
etc., must admit them? a change in our inner self such as a new intuition requires the activity of
4) TETENS (in his Vers. iih. d. mensch!. Nat., Vol. I, essay v) explains a body, which, as a finite part of a finite sphere, must itself be composed
the origin of our cognitions of the objective existence of things in a way of infinitely many parts. Thus it requires no special observation to judge
whether an object we have perceived is a substance or not; for we know in

114 115
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 304. Of Judgements

advance that every outer intuition is brought about through the collective cases where we know through other inferences of which we are distinctly
activity of an infinite multitude of substances. aware that the judgement is false.
173 From what has been said, one will readily gather that I would rather 5) The attempts of CONDILLAC and BONNET can be passed over
express TETENS' rule ("We place every sensation in the thing, the simul- once we have considered the way in which Count DE TRACY (Elemens
taneous sensation of which contains it as a part in its whole", p. 415) d'fdeologie, II, p. 215 seq.) undertook to solve the above-mentioned
as follows: We always place the cause of an idea, sensation, etc., which problem. He imagined how things would be if he had just begun his
occurs in us in the only object we are aware of as changing at the same life, though with a fully formed body. He supposed that he would attempt
time. This rule is used on p. 417 to explain why we place joy and sadness to move at that very instant, and believed that this movement would pro-
within ourselves, namely, because we are aware of such states as parts duce a pure and simple idea. Car je ne puis y en joindre aucune autre
of the self. I would prefer to say that we locate joy and sadness within (idee), puisque je n 'en ai point encore perr;u. 1 This reason is, it seems
ourselves because we know of no outer object (e.g., part of our body) to me, insufficient, for ideas might also be produced in us which do not
which changes in certain ways every time we have these feelings. For come from the external world. Now where there is no judgement (je n 'en
this very reason, we do locate certain stronger feelings (e.g., anger) in porte aucun jugement) there can certainly be no error. But how do things
parts of the body, since we do perceive particular physical changes along stand with the claim that this sensation or idea (idee) is certain? Cer-
with such feelings. But TETENS himself hits upon this explanation (p. tainty is an attribute which belongs only to judgements, and in fact I am
418). I would also largely subscribe to what he says about ideas of hear- justified in the case of the sensation I have in judging that I have it. le
ing and sight (p. 419 ff.). From Essay VI (p. 429 ff.), one may gather cesse (he continues) de m 'agiter; cette sensation cesse. Dans cet etat
that TETENS did not properly grasp the distinction between immediate de repos, cette sensation qui n 'existe plus, affecte de nouveau ma sen-
judgements of perception (which he calls pure judgements of sensation) sibi!ite (may one ask how it is that something that no longer exists can
on the one hand and derived judgements or judgements of experience on have effects?); j'y repense, je me la rapelle, comme on dit; c' est-(1-dire, 175
the other. For he claims that the judgement "The moon is as large as en termes plus exactes, )'en sens le souvenir. Comment cela se fait-il?
the sun" is a pure sensation, and wants us to distinguish what belongs je n 'en sais rien; mais il est fa it, que c 'est un don, dont nous sommes
to pure sensation from what is derived or added in thought by using the doues; et c'est ce don, que je nomme memoire. 2 (Now how a memory
following principle: "That of which I am distinctly and intensely [but in the proper sense-i.e., the judgement that we have previously had a
how distinctly and how intensely?] aware in my present feelings is gen- given idea-comes about can indeed be explained to a certain extent.) I
uinely contained in them." Not so-rather, in order to distinguish pure find this sensation pleasant (he continues), and desire that it be repeated.
judgements of perception from others we must attend to their form. On p. There follows a second movement and a second sensation. Cette seconde
433, he rejects what I think is the correct explanation of why one sees a sensation cessera bientot comme la premiere; mais quand le souvenir
man as having the same size even at different distances, which is that one m 'en reviendra, il ne sera plus une idee aussi simple que le premia Ce
knows from other experiences that his size cannot change that quickly. premier souvenir ne pouvait etre compose que de l'idee de la sensation
His reason for our doing so is that "in this example the awareness that I meme, et du jugement que cette idee en etait la representation; mais la
174 feel and sense is too intense and vivid for me to have merely imagined seconde peut deja et doit, pour etre complet, etre compose de l'idee que
that I sensed it." I counter that it is not a matter of the degree of vividness cette sensation a ere eprouvee une premiere fois, de celle qu 'elle a cesse,
or confidence with which we form the judgement, since a mediate judge- de celle qu 'on se I' est rappellee, de celle qu 'elle a ete jugee bonne a
ment may also be formed with great vividness and confidence. Our belief
that we recognise the size immediately (i.e., that we believe we see it, as 1For I cannot connect another idea with it, since I haven't yet perceived any.
TETENS expresses things) rather than by inference is only clue to the fact 2I cease to agitate myself; this sensation ceases. In this state of rest, this sensation,
that we are not conscious of the inference upon which the judgement is which no longer exists, affects my sensibility anew. I think of it again, I recall it as one
based, and thus have formed the habit of making it involuntarily, even in says, more precisely, I sense the memory of it. How does this happen'J I have no idea; but
it is a fact that it is a gift with which we are endowed, a gift which I call memory.

116 117
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 304. Of Judgements

eprouve1; de celle qu 'elle a ete desiree en consequence-de ce jugemem, waY in which all of this happens in vain-not only here but also on p.
de celle qu 'el le a ete renouvelee en suite de ce desi1; et meme peut-etre de 3g7, where the author speaks further on the subject). On p. 397 the Count
celle qu'elle a cesse de nouveau malgre la continuation de ce desil; et de seems to want to explain how the concept of extension comes to be. fl
celle de plusieurs autres circonstances. l It is not obvious to me why au faudrait commencer par montre1; comment, apres avoir appris, qu 'un
of these ideas, or rather judgements, would have to occur. Indeed, I can- etre est lei, qui resiste a notre desir de sentir du mouvement, nous ap-
not even comprehend how some of them could have been formed at all, prenons, que cet etre resistant est etendu, parce qu 'en continuant asentir
e.g., that the sensation reappeared afterwards (ensuite), i.e., through the du mouvement, nous continuons a sentir la resistance de cet etre; ce qui
action of the desire. Only if we have already experienced several times nous prouve, qu 'il est compose de parties, qui se presentent successive-
that a change occurs after we have wished that it would do we gather that ment en opposition au mouvement, que nous faisons, cest-c't-dire comme
our wish or will (the two are not then separate) has the power to bring on dit ordinairement, compose de parties, qui existent hors et a cote !es
1
about certain results. According to DE TRACY we infer the existence 1111 es des mitres. (Here it remains to be explained how we know that we
of other beings merely from the resistance we feel to our desires. This move ourselves, i.e., our body.) fl faudrait faire voir ensuite, que cette
seems incorrect (even though I know that most scholars agree with this inertie, cette impenetrabilite, ayant acquis anotre egard la qualite d'etre
view). I believe that there are also intuitions which in and of themselves erendue, parce qu'elle continue a s'opposer a differens mouvemens suc-
176 point towards certain objects, distinct from us, as their cause. L'idee de cessifl', a cependant des limites qui determinent laforme du corps, auquel
vouloir et l'idee de resister (we read on p. 237) sont done !es deux noy- elle appartient, et qui composent sa swface. Par ce moyen on aurait la
aux, !es deux germes, autour des quels viendront se grouper toutes les generation exacte des idees solidite et swface physiques et reelles. 2 (I do
idees, que par la suite je reconnaitrai appartenil; soit cl mon moi, soit not find this explanation clear either. What we sense are not boundaries, 177
aux etres, qui ne sont pas lui, et qui cornposent l'idee totale, que j'aurai but bodies, and that bodies must be bounded is something which must be
de chacun de ces etres. L'idee de mon moi deviendra, outre l'idee de recognised a priori. For this reason, I cannot agree with DE TRACY when
vouloil; celle d'avoir un cmps, des membres, des organes, par les-quels he claims on p. 422 that nothing-i.e., empty space-is also perceptible.)
il sent, qui obeissent a ses volontes, et celle de posseder !es facultes, !es 6) Prof. HERBART (Lehrb. d. Psych., § 18 l) notes quite correctly that
puissances, !es faiblesses, !es jouissances et !es miseres, qui en resultent. judgements are more than mere combinations (complications or amalga-
L'idee des aittres etres, au nombre desquels sont mon cmps et mes mem- mations) of ideas. He may well have gone too far, however, when he
bres, sera Olttre celle de resiste1; eel/es de reunir toutes !es circonstances seems to claim (ibid., also Einl. z. Phil., §52) that every judgement must
et !es proprietes, par lesquelles ils affectent ma sensibilite, et qui carac- be preceded by a question, because the subject, as such, must always first
terisent chacun d' eux. 2 (One seeks a more detailed explanation of the waver between many determinations so that the determinable can con-
front the predicate. In particular, he seems not to have noticed that every
1This second sensation will soon cease; but when the memory recurs, it will no longer
be as simple an idea as the first. This first memory could only be composed of the idea beings, which include my body and limbs, will be, in addition to that of resisting, that
of the sensation itself, and of the judgement that this idea was the representation of that of uniting all the circumstances and properties by which they affect my sensibility and
sensation; but the second can be and, if it is to be complete, must be composed of the which characterise each of them.
1One would have to begin by showing how, after having learned that a being is present
ideas that this sensation had been felt a first time, that the sensation had ceased, that one
had recalled it, that it had been judged good to feel, that it had consequently been desired, which resists our desire to feel movement, we learn that this resisting being is extended,
that it had been renewed following this desire, and perhaps even that it had ceased once because in continuing to feel movement we also continue to feel the resistance of this
again despite the continuation of this desire, and of several other circumstances. being. This proves that it is composed of parts which successively oppose our motion,
2 The ideas of willing and resisting are thus the two cores, the two seeds, around which i.e .. as one ordinarily says, composed of parts which are outside and beside one another.
2
come to be grouped all the ideas I afterwards recognise to belong either to myself or to Afterwards, one would have to show that this inertia, this impenetrability, having
other beings, and which make up the entire idea I shall have of each of these beings. The acquired the quality of extension from our point of view, because it continues to oppose
idea of myself will become, in addition to the idea of willing, that of having a body, limbs, different, successive movements, nevertheless has limits that determine the shape of the
and organs, by means of which it senses, which obey its will, and that of possessing the body it belongs to and which make up its surface. In this way, one would obtain the exact
faculties, powers, weaknesses, joys, and miseries that result from them. The idea of other generation of ideas of solidity and real, physical surfaces.

118 119
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgements

question is already a judgement, namely, the judgement that one demands former presents no problems, because the pred.ica~e, although. ~t is ~ot
to know what is asked. I would not even claim that the hesitation between here part of the subject-concept, is to be met with m the (empmcal) 111-
several determinations makes an object more suitable to be a subject of 'ti·on connected with it. Thus the judgement "All bodies are heavy," is
tlll . . . . .
our judgement. For why should we not judge more readily and confi- supposed to arise because we find the charactenstlc of he.avmes~, w.h~ch 179
dently in cases where we do not hesitate at all? The way that HERBART admittedly does not form part of the concept of a body, 111 the 111tmt10n
attempts to explain the origin of the concepts of space and time (Lehrb. we have of a body. This explanation is no more satisfactory than the
d. Psych., § 163-178) is especially clever. He is certainly right to remark receding one. For a single intuition which I have connected with the
that we are only able to make judgements about space and time by means ~oncept of a body, i.e., in a single judgement of the form "This (which
of certain sequences of ideas appearing in our minds. What he says seems is presently acting on me) is a body" can in no way bring me to make
to fall short, however, in that: (a) he nowhere explains on what basis we the judgement that all bodies are heavy; at most I could form the judge-
infer whether given ideas in us are simultaneous or follow one another·, ment that this body (the one I am presently intuiting) is heavy. Thus it
(b) that he presents things as if the ideas of the spatial and the tempo- should have been shown how we come to make the comparatively (if not
ral were independent, whereas (I believe) spatial relations can only be strictly) universal judgement that all bodies are heavy. But what has been
grasped by means of temporal relations; (c) I cannot see why movement said here doesn't even explain the origin of the singular judgement: this
of the eye is an unavoidable necessity for spatial judgements; for experi- body is heavy. For if it were true (as is said here) that we encounter the
178 ence teaches us that in order to see distinctly, our eye must be motionless. characteristic of heaviness as a constituent in the intuition we have of this
body, i.e., in the idea which forms the subject-idea in our judgement, then
§.305. this judgement would also be analytic, which it shouldn't be according
to the explanation and isn't in fact. In my view, things stand like this:
The doctrine of the Critical Philosophy concerning this point
in the judgement "This body is heavy", the subject-idea "this body" does
not contain the idea of heaviness, but rather certain other completely dif-
The way that the origin of our judgements is explained in Critical Philos-
ferent intuitions, e.g., of colours, odours and the like. It has the form:
ophy has so many peculiarities and such important consequences, and is
"The object which is the cause of the colour I see, the odour I smell, etc";
still held in such high esteem in some places that it seems appropriate to
evaluate it separately. and the judgement itself states that this object is also heavy, i.e., is also
the cause of certain intuitions that I have, namely, of a pressure which I
1) To begin with, KANT distinguished analytic and synthetic judge-
feel, etc. We can see from this that the formation even of this singular
ments, and claimed that the origin of the former could be easily explained
judgement requires several repeated perceptions. There must have been
by the fact that in them a predicate which was a constituent of the idea
a repeated co-occurrence of the intuitions that stand under the concepts
of the subject was ascribed to that subject. I do not find this explanation
"colour", "odour", etc. with the intuition that stands under the concept
completely satisfactory. For even if I assume that by analytic proposi-
of that pressure, if I am to be justified in the conclusion (even the proba- 180
tions, KANT only meant those of the forms "A, which is B, is A" and "A,
ble conclusion) that the same object which is the cause of one is also the
which is B, is B", we still cannot be certain of such a judgement until we
cause of the other.
have convinced ourselves that the idea of an A which is B has an object.
3) It is supposed to be difficult (according to KANT) to explain the
Thus we cannot form the judgement "A triangle, which is equiangular, is
origin of synthetic judgements that are also a priori. Here it is asked:
equiangular" until we are convinced that there are equiangular triangles.
what is the unknown X that the understanding makes use of when it con-
The question thus arises of how we know that the idea of an A which
siders the concept A to be connected with a predicate B which is foreign
is B has an object, or, what amounts to the same, how we come by the
synthetic judgement "Some A are B''. to it? Here, precisely where K. encountered a difficulty, it seems to me
that there is nothing incomprehensible. What justifies the understanding
2) With respect to synthetic judgements, KANT distinguishes the em-
in attributing to a subject A a predicate B which does not lie in the con-
pirical from the a priori. He claims that explaining the origin of the

120 121
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgements

cept A? Nothing, I say, but that the understanding has and knows the the basis of this particular kind of intuition. In all of KANT' s writings
two concepts A and B. I think that we must be in a position to judge on this topic, however, there is no passage which speaks of this with the
about certain concepts merely because we have them. For, to say that desired precision. The most important passages are in the Critique of
somebody has certain concepts A, B, C, ... surely means that he knows pure Reason, A 140/B 179 ff., A 713/B74 l ff. From these, one gathers that
them and can distinguish them. But to say that he knows them and can K. thought he had noticed a very important distinction between the in- 182
distinguish them means that he can claim something about one of them tuitions corresponding to a certain concept, e.g., that of a triangle which
which he would not want to claim about the others, hence it means that was produced by the actual construction of an object standing under the
he judges about them. Since this holds generally, it also holds in the case concept (actually drawing a triangle) and intuitions produced purely by
when these concepts are simple. But in this case, the judgements which the imagination. He calls the former empirical, and admits that they can
we make about them are certainly synthetic. Without doubt, these syn- produce no universality or necessity. The latter, however, which he calls
thetic judgements, whose subjects are the simple concepts A, B, C, D, ... , pure, are claimed to do so. I must confess that this distinction seems com-
put us in a position to form further synthetic judgements about compound pletely unimportant to me. For whether we merely imagine a triangle or
concepts which result from the combination of A, B, C, D, ... , either by actually draw one, it changes little in our idea; at most it might become
themselves, or together with still other concepts. Thus it seems certain to more vivid or easier to retain or reproduce in the latter case. (b) KANT
me that we must be in a position to form some synthetic judgement about seems to have sensed this himself; accordingly, he sometimes required
any object, so long as we have a concept of it. that these constructions occur not in imagination in general, but instead
4) KANT thought that the origin of such synthetic judgements a priori in pure imagination. But this, it seems to me, is just hiding behind ob-
181 had to be explained in a completely different way. Here too (he claimed) scure words. For what is pure imagination and how do its operations and
because the predicate is not contained in the subject-concept, we must results differ from those of empirical imagination? (c) KANT says that
find it in an intuition connected with the concept (the construction of con- the empirical imagination only produces images, while the pure imagina-
cepts by means of intuitions). I have just shown how poorly the origin of tion produces schemata, where a schema is not so much an image as the
empirical judgements is explained by appealing to a connection between idea of a method or rule for providing a concept with its image. I must
the subject-idea and an intuition. Things are even worse in the case of a confess that I cannot understand how an idea of a method can be called
priori judgements. For while the subject-concept in such judgements al- an intuition, nor how this idea of a method for providing a concept with
ways comprehends an infinite number of objects, the intuition we connect its image differs from a so-called genetic definition (which no one will
with it can only present one single object; and the inference from what is want to count among the intuitions). If the schema of a circle is nothing
the case with this one to what is the case with all is not only invalid but but the idea of a method of providing an object can be provided for the
also cannot deliver the certainty and the insight into the impossibility of concept of a circle, then a schema is nothing but an idea of the way in
the contrary that such judgements are boasted to have. which a circle is generated, i.e., nothing but the well-known definition 183
5) Yet KANT countered that the intuitions which mediate synthetic of a circle, which is called a genetic definition, namely, the concept of a
judgements a priori are of a special kind: not empirical, but rather pure or line which is described by a point that moves in a plane in such a way
a priori. This is why our judgements are not merely probable, but rather that it always maintains the same distance from a given point. Thus if
certain and necessary. These pure intuitions are either spatial or temporal one recognises the truth of a synthetic proposition through the consider-
ideas. The reader already knows from §79 that and why I do not recog- ation of the schema of its subject-concept, one recognises this truth from
nise any intuitions in these ideas. In general, I cannot perceive any such the consideration of mere concepts. (d) How excessive, moreover, is the
difference as KANT describes among the intuitions of which humans are claim made in many places (e.g., Critique of Pure Reason, B 154) that "we
capable. But even if there were some such difference, it is obvious that cannot think any relation in space without constructing it, that we cannot
it is not enough simply to point it out. Rather, one would have to show think any line, any circle, without first describing them, that we cannot
how the origin of synthetic judgements a priori becomes explicable on think the three dimensions of space without putting three lines at right

122 123
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgen1ents

angles to each other in the same point. And even time cannot be thought istic construction presents the concepts of algebra, principally those of
unless, in drawing a straight line (which is supposed to be the external he relations of quantities, in intuition; but I don't see how the symbols
figurative idea of time) we attend merely to the activity of the synthesis ~ or_ can be claimed to present the concept of addition or subtraction in
of the manifold through which we successively determine inner sense, intuition, unless one is willing to say the same for other symbols used by
and thereby attend to the succession of this determination." I admit that hilosophers to present concepts of logic or metaphysics. EULER'S use 185
such constructions often serve to increase the distinctness and vividness ~f circles, one contained within the other, to depict the relation between
of our ideas and that we are for this reason quite accustomed to perform- a higher and a lower concept certainly has more intuitiveness than the
ing them, to the point where they are almost involuntary. But it can be designation of a sum by a+ h and a difference by a - b. (f) I find the
shown by many examples that such constructions are not indispensable. distinction between the schemata of sensible concepts and those of pure
Thus nobody will deny that even a beginner can understand me when I concepts still more obscure. The latter, moreover, are supposed to be intu-
define a dodecahedron as a body which is bounded by twelve similar and itions, without themselves being images, nor even being capable of being
equal plane faces. From that moment on he will connect a concept with brought to an image. (g) How odd, finally, is the claim that "images must
that word; he will think something by it, something that is correct. On always be connected with the concept only by means of a schema, but
the other hand, will he be able to construct such a dodecahedron? Does themselves are never completely congruent with the concept." What does
he already know whether the bounding faces are triangles or pentagons, "congruent" mean here? To be identical? By no means, for the image is
etc.? The dispensability of such a construction is even more obvious in never the same as the concept. To be subsumable under the concept? This
the following concept: "a finite spatial object which is fully determined can happen with or without a schema.
by two of its points, and each point of which stands in the same relation 6) Perhaps the way that KANT conceived of the origin of synthetic
184 to the whole". Perhaps several readers will not even know, for a moment judgements a priori through the mediation of pure intuitions can be bet-
or two, whether this spatial thing falls into the class of lines, surfaces, or ter gathered from the examples he gives than from his general explana-
bodies. How could they be in a position to produce a construction of it? tions. In the Critique of Pure Reason (B 15), he declares the proposition
Or are we supposed to believe that such an indistinct and obscure picture 7 + 5 = 12 to be a synthetic judgement, since it is in no way thought in
as our imagination can produce in this case can actually contribute some- the concept of the sum of 7 and 5 what the number is that they make
thing to the recognition of the properties of this object? But we certainly up together. "One must," he says accordingly, "go beyond these con-
think this object, and we are even in a position, by taking some thought, to cepts, and draw upon an intuition corresponding to one of them, perhaps
determine what kind of thing it is, namely, the surface of a sphere, where one's five fingers; and one after the other acid the units of the five given
those two points form the poles. in intuition to the concept of seven." At A716/B744 he provides another
But even with the concepts with which we are able to connect im- example, the proposition that the angles of a triangle, taken together, acid
ages, e.g., those of a circle or ellipse, etc., it may well be quite wrong to up to two right angles. "The geometer begins immediately by construct-
suppose that we obtain an idea of the image only by drawing it. Rather ing a triangle. He knows that the adjacent angles which can be drawn
it is the other way around: we can only make the drawing (whether it from a point on a straight line add up to two right angles. So he produces
take place in actuality or in the imagination) because we already have the one side of his triangle, and obtains two adjacent angles, which together 186
idea. (e) What a sad makeshift, furthermore, is the distinction between equal two right angles. He now divides the outer one by drawing a line
these two kinds of construction! If mathematicians choose so many sym- parallel to the opposite side of the triangle, and sees that in this way an
bols for the general concept of a quantity and the various combinations adjacent angle is created which is equal to the inner angle, etc." From
thereof in algebra, e.g., a, b, +, -, etc., this is by no means a matter of these and similar examples I conclude that assumptions that are based
necessity. They can prove their theorems without using such symbols, upon certain obscure reasons, usually merely upon the testimony of the
although this would require more words, and such verbosity would make senses, especially the eye, were taken by KANT to be effects of a special
it harder to grasp the proofs. It is said that this symbolic or character- pure intuition. Although mathematicians have succeeded in defining their

124 125
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgements

concepts more precisely, and giving stricter proofs than is the case in any formed without a clear consciousness of their ground, to a special source
other science, they still have not succeeded in defining their fundamental of knowledge under the name of pure intuitions.
and most general concepts, and they introduce their initial propositions ei- 7) I found it necessary in §79, in addition to consulting KANT, to
ther without proof or with proof that is not truly scientific. Thus the usual turn to SCHUUZ, the commentator he praised so highly. So too here.
textbooks of arithmetic do not give an exact definition of the concept of In the second part of his Priijimg one finds two long passages (p. 62 ff.
a sum. If this had been done, and had they said that a sum is a collection and p. 157 ff.) bearing on these matters. (a) The first states that from
where the order of parts is not taken into account, and where the parts of the moment we are aware of intuiting a piece of gold, the predicate "yel-
the parts should be looked upon as parts of the whole (§84) they would low" is given simultaneously along with it through this (merely empir-
have found that the following analytic proposition follows immediately ical) intuition, in such a way that we would have to overrule our entire 188
from this definition: a+ (b + c) =(a+ b) + c. By an application of this consciousness if we were not to accept the judgement: "This piece of
theorem together with the definitions that 7 + 1 = 8, 8 + 1 = 9, etc., the gold is yellow." How excessive! A judgement of this kind is by no means
proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is produced as a purely analytic truth for which no ;n immediate judgement of perception, but rather must be inferred from
intuition whatsoever is required. Even KANT must have been somewhat such, and this via the well-known premise: if certain intuitions A,B, C, ...
hard put to find the kind of intuition which allegedly occurs in this case. always occur together, they probably have the same cause. The conclu-
He concluded that, since the units of 5 are added to 7 one after another, sion: "This piece of gold is yellow" is thus only probable, and does not
it is an intuition of time which underlies these inferences. What a conclu- exclude the possibility of error. Why then would we have to overrule our
sion! One could say, for the very same reason, that every sorites depends entire consciousness if we didn't admit it? (b) Of a priori intuitions it
upon an intuition of time, since we arrive at its conclusion only in time. is said that these bring with them the consciousness of inner necessity.
The other example is more difficult, since the concepts which are But what can this mean when necessity in the sense used here can belong
187 present in the proposition are much more complex than in the preceding to propositions or judgements, but not to ideas? (c) The well-known ax-
case. I should have to write an entire treatise of geometry if I wanted to iom that two straight lines can meet in at most one point is considered
show how this proof can be produced from pure concepts. I will there- for the sake of elucidation. One is not justified in saying that the only
fore be satisfied with the following remarks. When a geometer (according way to convince oneself of the truth of this proposition is by constructing
to KANT' s description) begins his proof by drawing a triangle, either in its subject-concept merely because so far no other means is known. Did
imagination or on a piece of paper, we must ascribe these activities to the not SCHULTZ himself tell us that in the short time between the publica-
present impetfection of his science. We can think of a proof procedure tion of parts one and two of his book he had discovered how to prove
which does not require an imaginary triangle, or in any case one which propositions which he had listed among the axioms in Part I? Further-
requires it only to facilitate the argument, in the same way that we need more, if we consider the way he demonstrates that we see the truth of the
to write down the propositions when we go through a sorites, so that we above proposition only through intuition, we find nothing more than the
don't forget what we began with and how far we have proceeded. It is repeated assurance that we are aware through inner self-consciousness
said, quite properly, that the geometer sees how the extension of one side that it is so. This is admittedly a succinct proof, but it will only be ac-
produces an external angle, and how it is divided into two parts by a line cepted by those who are already convinced of the truth of the proposition
parallel to the base, and how these two angles are equal to two angles to be proved. Only SCHULTZ promised to show not only that, but also
in the triangle, etc. But it is not necessary, I say, that we must see these how, pure intuition grounds this axiom. Concerning the how not a word is
things; the testimony of the eyes is not required; the geometer could con- said; instead, we are told that all of this is immediate, so that no how can
clude all of this from his concepts. If we consider that this kind of seeing be indicated. (d) Given that SCHULTZ infers so much from conscious- 189
is not an immediate conception, but is inferred from our immediate per- ness, we desire to learn what he means by this. For my part, I maintain
ception through the unconscious application of many geometrical truths, that consciousness is the knowledge or cognition of a truth, and the ex-
then we will hardly be inclined to elevate these judgements, which are pressions "I am aware of the truth A, I know it, recognise it, I now form

126 127
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE §. 305. Of Judgements

the judgement A or have formed it previously, and am in a position to re- known not to be the case. SCHULTZ indeed says that if we did not possess
new it" are equivalent. With regard to self-consciousness, I think I agree a faculty like self-consciousness as he describes it, we could know none
with ordinary usage when I declare it to be immediate knowledge con- of these truths. But how does this follow? Why, if we do not know imme-
cerning ourselves, thus limiting it to knowledge of our own existence and diately that something is unthinkable (i.e., false), should we not be able
that which occurs within us. For no one considers other knowledge which to do so mediately, by inference? Since I take self-consciousness to be a
also concerns only ourself, e.g., of the simplicity of the soul, its immortal- kind of knowledge, hence a judgement, and since judgements are neither
ity, etc., to be part of self-consciousness. This is obviously because these intuitions nor the ability to form intuitions, I agree that self-consciousness
judgements are inferred.* When I read (p. 157) that all our know ledge is should not be confused with the faculty of intuition. But when SCHULTZ
ultimately based upon self-consciousness, and interpret this to mean that (as is almost certainly the case) intends to indicate with this claim that 191
without being aware of what occurs within ourselves we could not know self-consciousness does not spring from intuitions, not even inner intu-
anything else, this does not seem completely correct. For I do not think itions, I cannot agree. For the judgement "I have this idea" requires an
that it is absolutely necessary for us to think of ourselves in order to know intuition of this idea, thus an intuition of what occurs in our soul. And
any given truth, nor for us to be in a position to form the judgement that insofar as the ability to form such intuitions is called inner sense, I say
we recognise this truth. Thus I believe that a young child forms many that our self-consciousness, if it is not inner sense itself, at least requires
judgements, including correct ones, before it attains self-consciousness. it. For the same reasons I admit that self-consciousness is not an idea.
When I read, further, that SCHULTZ declares self-consciousness to be the But when it is added that it is only through self-consciousness that ideas
"I think, I represent something", I cannot reconcile this with my own con- become mine, I think that this is expressed poorly. For an idea can also be
cept. And when immediately afterwards the consciousness "that certain mine when I am not aware of it. One should say instead that we recognise
190 ideas are either impossible for us under certain conditions, or absolutely" ideas as our own via self-consciousness. It should be noted that when
is reckoned to be part of self-consciousness, I find this an overly wide SCHULTZ distinguished self-consciousness from an idea he has some-
extension of this concept, and indeed a serious error, especially since it is thing altogether different in mind. For he uses the word idea (as many
claimed afterwards that self-consciousness teaches us immediately, with- others do) in such a wide sense that it covers judgements as well. Thus
out any inference. For the impossibility of a certain idea (that something when he says that self-consciousness is not an idea, he also denies that it
cannot be) is by no means an object of immediate cognition, but rather is a judgement. Although I know that many share this view, I candidly ad-
must be inferred; for it simply means (according to § 182) that this as- mit that I can form no concept of such an ability in our soul, which refers
sumption contradicts a purely conceptual truth. Nor will SCHULTZ allow to the processes of thought, but is neither an idea (in the strict sense) nor
self-consciousness to be called a sense (namely, an inner sense). We need a judgement. (e) "I am aware," he continues, "empirically, through inner
not hold this against him, especially since he declares self-consciousness sensation, that I can represent outer things as either not existing or being
to be an ability "which must teach us immediately and non-inferentially different; for whenever I seek this idea, I actually have it." Against this,
what is determined through our cognitive faculties (i.e., sensibility, un- I will point out first that what is here called sensation I call intuition; for
derstanding, and reason), and which consequently is grounded in a nec- sensation is a word we require to designate another kind of inner phe-
essary and invariable way in them alone." There neither is nor can be nomenon. I also find the expression "I can represent outer things as either
any such ability. For it can be said of all purely conceptual truths we not existing or being different" ambiguous; for it can be taken to mean 192
recognise that we recognise them by means of our cognitive faculties (if either "I can form an idea of external things not existing or being differ-
reason is counted among these), and that consequently all this knowledge ent" or "I know that outer things might not exist or might be different." I
is grounded in a necessary and invariable way in our cognitive faculties can only agree with the statement on the first interpretation. We certainly
alone; all of these, then, would have to be known immediately, which is know from our own sensation (better, from intuiting an idea which is now
present within us) that we are able to form an idea of the non-existence of
*The expression "immediate self-consciousness", which one sometimes hears, is thus things, or of their being different. But I cannot agree with the claim under
somewhat redundant.

128 129
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgements

the second interpretation. For in no case are we able to know from mere indeed without knowing whether they designated something real or not."
intuition (or sensation) that things outside of us might or might not be dif- No one will want to deny that it is impossible to prove that a proposition
ferent; moreover, I doubt whether any kind of consideration can put us in is true, or to see that it is true by itself, as long as one does not know
a position to know this. The proof that SCHULTZ provides for his claim which concepts are designated by the words used to express it. But it
suggests that he had the first interpretation in mind. "Whenever 1 seek is incorrect, in the first place, to say that apart from analysing a concept
this idea, I actually have it," he says. This cannot prove that things might into its constituents, i.e., defining it, or presenting in (pure) intuition an
in fact be different, but rather only that I can imagine them being differ- object which stands under it, there is no other way of communicating a 194
ent. Yet he adds: "By contrast, I am immediately aware, independently concept connected with a certain word to someone else. For there are
of all sensation, which can never teach us of the absolute impossibility words which designate a simple concept, e.g., "something", "actuality".
of things, that it is absolutely unthinkable that space might not exist or We have also learned the meanings of these words, something which did
might be different, as unthinkable as an A which isn't A." Here SCHULTZ not occur either through definition or by means of a pure intuition of an
obviously passes from one meaning to the other, for no one can dispute object standing under the concept. In general, the requirement of secur-
the possibility of merely having the idea that there is no space, or that ing an understanding about the meaning of words only arises when we
space is constituted quite differently. Simply by speaking of this idea, seek to communicate them to others, not in solitary reflection. Thus what
one produces it in one's mind. And when we prove the impossibility of a is said here would at most point out a difficulty in explaining the origin
193 solid bounded by twenty-four equal faces, must we not first form an idea of such mathematical knowledge as one obtains through instruction by
of such a solid? And is not this idea an idea of a space which would be others. It would not show the impossibility of producing such knowledge
different from what it really is? Certainly SCHULTZ does not claim that by means of one's own reflection. The other points have already been
the mere idea of another space is impossible, but only that the space itself answered elsewhere.
is impossible. But if this is the case, one may fairly ask, first, what con- 8) It remains to consider how the origin of our judgements of experi-
nection there is between the first proposition and the second; and second, ence is explained in the Critical Philosophy. Concerning first the judge-
with what right may one claim that insight into this impossibility belongs ments in which we express temporal relations between our own ideas,
to one's immediate awareness? That a body such as I have just described I cannot see that they have attempted to explain how they are formed.
is impossible is not something we recognise immediately; rather, it re- The assurance that time cannot be perceived in and of itself is indeed
quires many inferences to see this. We may recognise other attributes of repeated ad nauseam, and it is explained in great detail on what basis
space, e.g., that two straight lines can only have one point in common, we gather that certain phenomena or changes in the external world fol-
more quickly, and without being aware of the grounds which support this low one another, or are simultaneous; yet not a word is said about how
knowledge. But no one has shown that they are groundless, i.e., immedi- we recognise that two ideas or phenomena within us occur at the same
ate cognitions. (f) On p. 131 one reads: "Geometrical objects in general or different times. It seems, instead, that KANT took these judgements
are lines, sutfaces, and solids. Thus one or more of these must occur to be immediate. Thus in the Critique of Pure Reason, Al 89/B233, we
in every geometrical definition. But what lines, surfaces, and solids are read: "I am only aware that my imagination places one thing before the
cannot be understood by means of any definition, but only through intu- other"* -which sounds as if the former judgement is taken to be imme- 195
ition, since (?) space is an individual, and hence comprehensible through diate. Now, concerning external objects: we are supposed to gather the
the immediate representation of the singular. It follows that no geometri- temporal sequence, e.g., that Bis later than A from our presentation of A
cal definition is comprehensible unless the defined object is individually as the cause of the effect B; and the latter is supposed to be recognised
produced in pure intuition by the productive imagination. If geometrical from our inability to perceive B earlier than A, while we are able to per-
demonstrations were possible without construction of concepts, it would
have to be possible to produce a demonstrative system of geometry with- 'It is admittedly difficult to reconcile this with what is said at B 156, namely, "that we
out knowing what the words in the definitions and propositions mean, always gather determinations of duration or temporal location of our inner perceptions
based upon changes in external things."

130 131
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 305. Of Judgements

ceive A before B. Simultaneity, i.e., that A and B are at the same time, we ment. "Just as someone blind from birth experiences that bodies and their
are supposed to recognise based upon our finding the objects A and B to parts are ou~sicl~ of one another, in that he touches ~hem in sequence,
stand in a relation of interaction; while we gather the latter from the fact and in so domg 1s aware of the actual movement of hrs hand, so too we
that A is perceived sometimes before and sometimes after B. Against this come by the idea that what is seen is outside of and different from us only
I recall that actual causes and effects do not follow one another in time, through touch, in that we move toward the things we see one after the
but rather are simultaneous. KANT himself seems to have sensed this, other. But as the awareness that we have moved presupposes the ideas
when he wrote (A203/B248): "For the most part, active causes in nature of space and difference of place, it is clear that the perception of external
are simultaneous with their effects." This passage is extremely obscure, things is only made possible, for the. blind as well as for those endowed
and I openly admit that I cannot understand how it is connected to the with sight, by the idea of space, and that the idea of space is consequently I 97
distinction made here between the order of time and the lapse of time; a priori." A very odd explanation! The idea of space may be as a pri-
just as little do I understand how two things can be simultaneous, i.e., ori as you like, it still remains incomprehensible how one is supposed to
at the same time, and yet temporally determinable, i.e., distinguishable. be immediately aware that one has moved oneself (i.e., one's body). For
Towards the encl, we find a completely different indicator: A is the cause movement is change of place, and thus can only be inferred if one recog-
of B if I never perceive A without B, but sometimes perceive B without A. nises that a body was earlier in this place and now in another. But one
9) SCHULTZ has explained at great length how we come to recog- cannot know a priori where a body is; rather, this must be gathered from
nise the diverse spatial relations (Priifung, Part I, p. 182 ff.). Against experience. I would also like to ask whether anyone has a sensation of
PLATNER' s claim that space is merely an idea of sight, he quite correctly the earth moving, and indeed at the speed astronomy tells us it is? On
remarks that what we immediately sense with the eyes is nothing other p. 184, we read: "With respect to our visual perception, it is not merely
than light. But he goes too far when he says immediately afterwards: sensation, but rather something based upon many comparisons and judge-
"To someone seeing for the first time, all objects must appear to be mere ments of the understanding." Should one gather from this that SCHULTZ
196 masses of coloured light, which are located immediately in his eyes." For believed that the estimation of distance by means of touch is not based
someone seeing for the first time will know nothing of the location of the upon any comparisons and judgements of the understanding, and is thus
objects which cause these ideas of light. The following, too, seems ex- immediate? His admission (p. 185) shows how incomplete his explana-
cessive to me: "Indeed, since the ideas of sight are not accompanied by tion of judgements of this kind is: "Little by little, our soul completely
any feeling of resistance, by means of them alone he cannot even know (?) abandons the measure of the angle of sight, and not only sketches for
that there exists something other than himself." Why not? From a so- itself, by means of an art unknown to us, a determinate image of the size
called outer intuition I rightly infer that there is an external object which of distances and things close to us, but also allows the size of this image
produced it. Feelings of resistance are in no way required for this. And to decrease in inverse (but difficult to discern) proportion to distance." In
if they were, would ideas of sight be utterly free from them? Does it my opinion, the soul not only uses the angle of sight to judge the distance
really depend only upon our will whether we become aware of a light of objects, but also light and shadow, and especially the comparison of
when someone enters the dark room we are in with a lit candle? Still the visual angle taken up by an object of known size with that of another
more incorrect and in obvious contradiction with the principles of the object which is connected with it (i.e., presently acting on it) in a way
critical philosophy seem to me the claims that sight and (according top. which gives us reason to ascribe the same distance to both.
191) hearing "in and of themselves are incapable of procuring us ideas Note. Recently BENEKE (Psycho!. Skizzen and elsewhere) and REIN-
of things outside of us." If this were so, if it depended upon such a con- HOLD have undertaken investigations which would deserve to be spoken
tingent condition, namely, the number of senses Goel saw fit to endow us of here, were it not for constraints of space. I will also only say a few 198
with whether or not we would have ideas of things outside of us and of words about the view of TROXLER (in his Naturl. d. mensch!. Erk., Aa-
space, how could these ideas be said at the same time to be necessary? rau 1828): "In man as well as in animals there is a knowledge which
According to SCHULTZ, we procure these ideas through touch and move- precedes sensible knowledge, which reveals itself through the actions we

132 133
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 306. Of Judgements

attribute to instinct." T. claims this knowledge to be immediate. It is sup- absent from our mind. This by no means requires that M has never been
posed to be extracted from the so-called "subsensible or pre-senSOJ)' soul, found in our mind as a mere idea. We might have an idea of a proposi-
before the distinction between receptivity and spontaneity obtains." The tion, e.g., that there are creatures capable to travelling from one planet to
phenomena of somnambulism are supposed to be based upon this knowl- another, without deciding anything about its truth or falsity. A judgement
edge. In my view the cognitions which must be presupposed to account can thus be absent even though the ideas required to form it are not. But
for instinctive acts or sleep-walking are far too complex to allow one to a judgement may also be absent if we have never represented or thought
assume that they arise without being derived from other judgements. By about it. (2) It can also happen that we do not presently form a judgement
instinct, I believe, one means not a cognitive ability, but rather the drive M, though we did at an earlier time: This is called a previously formed
and skill to carry out a certain kind of action. Thus one speaks of an in- judgement. In many cases, the trace left by the judgement after it dis-
stinct whenever one is aware that a living being possesses both the drive appears is so constituted that it makes recalling the judgement easy, or
and the skill for a certain activity which is optimally calculated to reach possible only with some effort, or possible only when an idea of it is pro- 200
a goal consistent with the moral order of things, e.g., self-preservation or ducecl by an external object, where these expressions are to be understood
reproduction; where it is obvious that the living being has no idea that its like the corresponding ones for ideas explained in §289, nos. 2, 3. (3) We
activity is well suited to meet the goal in question, and may not even have do not always have to form a judgement again every time we remember
an idea of this goal, and in any case the activity does not stern from such that we have formed it previously. If, however, we form the judgement
ideas. What then is the proximal cause of an instinctive action? I would "S is P" whenever the ideas S and P are awakened in us, or whenever
say that it lies only in the fate the being experienced in the infinite earlier the question arises in the mind whether the subject S has the attribute
period of its existence, which must have left certain traces and obscure p, we are said to be constantly committed to that judgement, namely, as
memories in the soul, but principally in the wise arrangements the creator long as this relation between us and the judgement obtains. Since there
conferred upon the organism. In these may lie the hidden ground of the is no word that designates propositions of this sort, and that imputes nei-
fact that on certain occasions exactly those ideas, sensations, and desires ther truth nor falsity to them nor implies that they are held with a certain
are awakened in the soul which are required to make it act as it does. confidence, I usually use the words "opinion" or "view". Hence by the
199 Finally, concerning the phenomena of somnambulism: in my view not opinions of a being I understand propositions which this being takes to
everything that his been said on this score has been sufficiently proved. be true, irrespective of whether they really are true, and whether this ac-
The little I have been able to confirm through my own observation, how- ceptance has a high or low degree of confidence. (4) A judgement is said
ever, seems to be sufficiently explained by a heightened sensitivity of the to be more familiar to the extent that the mere stimulation of the ideas S
so-called ganglia! system. A state in which no division (no difference?) and P, or the question whether p belongs to S, prompts us more quickly
yet obtains between receptivity and spontaneity explains nothing for me, to form the judgement that S is P. (5) If we raise the question whether
since I don't know what to think by this. proposition M is true, and wish to form one of the two judgements, M or
Neg.M, but form neither of them, even though we have concentrated our
§.306.* attention upon S and P, then the state of our mind with respect to M is
called doubt. (6) It often occurs that, depending upon where we focus our
Survey of the most important activities and states attention, we form a certain judgement M and then its negation Neg .M
of mind which concern the business ofjudging with the same degree of confidence, even if this be small. The mind's be- 201
haviour towards M in such cases is called vacillation. (7) Occasionally it
The encl of this chapter may well be the best place to set out as briefly as happens that we are committed to a judgement M for a span of time, even
possible the most noteworthy activities and states of our mind having to though it conflicts with several other judgements R, S, ... to which we are
do with the business of judging. (1) A proposition M, first of all, may not constantly committed. When we notice this conflict, we abandon M. This
be claimed by us now, nor have been claimed by us at any earlier point may be called a passing fancy, a quickly abandoned thought. (8) When
of our existence. In this case, we say that the judgement M is lacking or

134 135
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 306. Of Judgements

we direct our attention to everything that we deem pertinent to determin- a different opinion, regardless of whether these reasons are correct, I say 203
ing whether or not a proposition M is true, one says that we examine M. that we have been persuaded to form this judgement. And if we ourselves
Clearly, we can resolve to examine a proposition even if we already hold applied this means, I say that we have persuaded ourselves. ( 15) Just as it
either M or Neg .M to be trne with a certain degree of confidence. If we is often sufficient simply to recall that we previously formed a judgement
do so, we say that the judgement M or N eg.M is provisional with respect in order to form it anew (no. 13) so too it is often enough to discover that
to the examination. (9) A judgement formed without the required exami- someone else judges or has judged thus. A judgement formed for this
nation is called hasty, and when such a judgement is used to deduce many reason alone may be said to be based upon the authority of another. We
others, it is called a prejudice. (l 0) When we form a judgement which we make such a judgement, for instance, ·when we deem that a patient is in
have derived from others, but are not able to indicate these other judge- danger because we see that his doctor is troubled. A special case of this
ments (since we have not represented any of these clearly), we may call occurs when we form a judgement M because we deduce from percep-
it ajudgementfrom obscure premises. (11) When the ground which de- tion that it is the will of a thinking being that we accept the proposition M
termines us to form a certain judgement is so constituted that we could because he himself holds it to be true. An act which someone performs
hinder the formation of this judgement merely by choosing to direct our with precisely the intention that we, if we follow our best insight, will
attention to other objects, I call it voluntaty or freestanding; otherwise, I conclude from perceiving it that it is his will that we accept the proposi-
say that it is forced. Thus the judgement that I now feel a certain warmth tion M, because he himself holds it to be true, is usually called testifying
202 is forced, while the judgement that the square on the hypotenuse, etc., in favour of this proposition. A judgement M which we form because
like most mathematical and scientific cognitions, is voluntary. (12) If of such (actual or merely imagined) testimony, may be said to be based
the propositions from which a judgement M is deduced, as well as those upon testimony.
from which the former follow, down to the immediate judgements, are all Note. It may be necessary to say a few words by way of justification
purely conceptual propositions, then judgement M can be called a judge- of the definitions given here. KANT, KIESEWETTER and others use the
ment from pure concepts, or pure, or a priori. In all other cases it could term provisional judgement for the concept of a judgement formed with
be said to be drawn from experience or a posteriori. (13) When we form a small degree of confidence. But we already have enough words for this
a judgement merely because we recall having formed it before, I will concept, while the one I described in no. 8 would remain unnamed if we
call it a judgement of memory. In calculation and any deduction of a chose not to reserve this quite suitable term for it. It is indeed true that the
judgement from a long series of inferences, where the first inference is word prejudice is sometimes taken in a similar sense; but it is also true
lost to consciousness before the last is reached, such judgements from that this word has its own particular meaning-and it can be reserved for
memory are inevitable. But as every proposition expressing a memory this (no. 9). Others have defined the concepts of a hasty judgement and 204
is by its very nature empirical, all judgements drawn from memory, and a prejudice in roughly the same way I have-e.g., ULRICH (L., §270)
hence all those derived from them, must strictly speaking be said to be and REIMARUS (§329). Ordinary usage also seems to require that correct
judgements of experience. In a nan-ower sense, however, judgements are as well as incorrect judgements be called prejudices, if they are formed
only said to be acquired from experience if we must have perceptions not without appropriate reasons. I also believe I have defined the concepts
of things in our own mind, but rather of external objects in order to de- of persuasion and self-persuasion (no. 14) as ordinary usage demands.
rive them. By contrast, judgements which require no experience other The degree of confidence with which we form a judgement is not rele-
than memory may be reckoned among judgements from pure concepts. vant here, for judgements we express with a high degree of confidence
( 14) When the cause for our having accepted a certain judgement lies in can also arise through persuasion by others or oneself. For this reason I
part in the fact that someone, in order that we might accept M, gave him- did not retain the definition of KANT (L., Ak., 9.73) and others of per-
self the trouble of drawing our attention to all the reasons which might suasion as an opinion held on insufficient grounds, of which one knows
make the proposition M either probable or certain in our eyes, and of not whether they are subjective or objective. Here it is a question of the
averting our attention from all the reasons which might lead us to form attitude which one takes towards the grounds, rather than the grounds

136 137
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 306.

themselves. According to MAAl3 (§519) persuasion is an awareness of PART III


the truth of a proposition based upon grounds which either do not ob-
tain or from which the judgement in question does not follow. But this Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth
is the concept of a correct judgement based upon incorrect reasons. In
FRIES' Gt: d. L., § 105, persuasion is described as the determination of a §.307.*
claim according to a procedure that is formally incorrect. The mistake in
cases of persuasion certainly lies in the procedure, only this must be more More precise determination (~f' the concepts:
precisely indicated; for in a hasty judgement the mistake also lies in the knowledge, ignorance, and error
procedure. This difference, however, is that in the former case one errs
because one has the intention of discovering something true, while in the In this chapter the relation between our judgements and truth shall be
latter case one is simply careless. By contrast, I will gladly to admit that considered more closely. We know from §34 that among our judgements
the distinction made in nos. 15 and 16 between authority and testimony both true and false ones are to be found. Thus it is necessary to inquire
is not observed in common usage. For scientific purposes, however, th.e more precisely into the origin of true as well as false judgements. The
distinction may not be so insignificant, as its adoption by others suggests. latter inquiry is especially important in that it may show us the means
Thus FRIES uses the word "authority" exactly as I do (Sy st. d. L., p. 516, which must be applied in order to avoid error as much as possible. We
563). I take testifying in exactly the same sense it is usually taken when shall have to say something about the objects covered by true judgements,
understood broadly, i.e., to cover not only narratives but propositions in and also about the limits of our knowledge. Clearly we could never form
general. It seems to me, though, that the definitions that have been given a false judgement if we knew every truth, i.e., unless we were ignorant of
for this concept are either incorrect or not sufficiently detailed. Thus many things. Thus before entering into the question of how error arises,
205 in KIESEWETTER' s Logik (II, § 169), we read: "Testimony is another's we must explain how ignorance is possible. First of all, however, we must
statement that he believes something to be true." But if the word "state" determine the three concepts of knowledge, ignorance and error.
here simply means "express", or "present through signs", etc., then this 1) The first of these was determined in §36 only to the extent which
definition is too broad. For not every case where we give someone to was then feasible and necessary. There it was said that any judgement
understand (whether this be intentional or not) through our action that which accords with truth may be called a cognition [knowledge]. Taken
we hold something to be true is a case of testimony. If this flaw is to as a definition, this would result in too narrow a concept; for we would 207
be avoided, the word "statement" must be taken in such a peculiar sense have to deny a person knowledge of this truth at a given time if he did not
that it contains the entire concept of testifying. Other definitions, e.g., just then judge it to be a truth. This is not only contrary to accepted usage,
testimony is another's report of his experience, or the communication or but also useless for scientific purposes. According to customary usage,
206 expression of what one has experienced, etc., are still less adequate. we ascribe knowledge, and indeed continual knowledge of a truth A to
someone, if he has formed the judgement A at some point in the past, and
if under circumstances which suffice for him to remember other judge-
ments he hasn't forgotten, he not only would be in a position to recall A,
but would still be committed to it. Thus we say that a boy already knows
100 Latin words not when he has all 100 meanings in his consciousness
simultaneously, but rather when we find that when we name any of these
words, he gives its meaning correctly. I wish to adhere to this usage:
the words recognition [KenntnijJ] and knowledge [ErkenntnijJ], however,
I consider equivalent, since whatever difference there might be between
these words is of no importance for our purposes. Thus by both of these
words we shall mean a state of mind where we have once formed a true

138 139
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 307. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

judgement (whose content is called the content of our knowledge) and that matters in deciding whether someone knows something, is ignorant
where we can still remember this judgement and are still committed to it of it, or holds the opposite error, is whether he forms a certain judgement
(§306, nos. 2. 3). at the present moment. There is also no shortage of definitions which are
2) Turning now to the concepts of ignorance and error: I believe that incorrect in other respects. Among these I reckon all those which apply
these apply not to mere ideas, but only to complete judgements. This knowledge only to the existing (see, e.g., GENGLER' s Idea le d. Wiss.,
will be readily granted in the case of the word error. For although we P· I). For I believe that there are also truths about objects that do not ex-
frequently speak of error in connection to ideas and concepts, it is imme- ist, e.g., truths about the attributes of other truths. RITTER (AbrijJ d. phi!.
diately apparent that we really have false judgements in mind. We say Log., p. 145 ff.) claims that there are four possible kinds of conscious-
that someone has incorrect concepts of certain objects when we mean to ness with reference to knowledge: (1) ignorance of ignorance (error);
indicate that he makes erroneous judgements about them. But does this (2) ignorance of knowledge (correct opinion); (3) knowledge of igno-
208 also hold of the word ignorance? Must it always be a question of truths rance (doubt); and (4) knowledge of knowledge (the highest level). It
when we say that someone doesn't know certain concepts, or is ignorant strikes me as odd to think of error, correct opinion, and doubt as kinds
of them? Could we not call the lack of certain concepts ignorance of or indeed levels of consciousness. Someone who errs with respect to an
them? I admit that this can and may occur in cases where rigorous pre- object does not know it; and one who doubts a truth has no knowledge
cision is not required. But given that we already have the convenient and of it. According to RITTER, if someone has not yet heard that there are
sufficiently distinct expressions "lack or absence of a certain concept" planets between Mars and Jupiter, and thus not only does not know the
for the condition in which certain concepts have never yet been formed, details of their orbits but does not even know that he doesn't know them,
I believe that the word ignorance [ Unwissenheit, Unkunde ]-which as a we must say he is in error concerning them. Hence a stone must be full
derivative of the verb to know [wissen, kennen] clearly recalls the cogni- of errors-for it neither knows, nor knows that it doesn't know. KANT
tive faculties and thus the power of judgement-must be applied, if we and several others who divide truth into formal and material, also wish
are speaking precisely, not to mere ideas but rather to entire propositions, ignorance and error to be similarly classified. If, as KANT does [in his
to genuine judgements. It seems to me that we will be justified in calling Logik (Ak., 9.44)], we now define formal ignorance as ignorance with
somebody ignorant of a certain truth A, if he does not have knowledge respect to purely conceptual truths and material ignorance as ignorance
of it; hence, according to no. 1, if he has never formed the judgement A, with respect to intuitional truths, I have no objection. But if this division
or does not remember it, or, in any case, if, when we pose the question were understood in the same way as the distinction between formal and
whether A is true, he does not at once, and on the basis of memory alone, material truth, the objections made to the latter should also be applied 2 lo
agree with A. The concept of error can be defined similarly. For an error here. And indeed KANT seems to have understood the classification of
is any false proposition to which someone is committed in the sense of error in this way, in that he defines error in the formal sense of the word
§306, no. 3, i.e., he must not only have formed the false judgement, but (Ak., 9.53) to be a form of thought in conflict with the understanding.
also be prepared to form it again if now asked.
3) According to these definitions, in order to ascribe the knowledge §.308.
of a truth A to someone, it does not suffice to show that he holds certain
Grounds for the possibility of ignorance in man
propositions from which A is deducible to be true, unless it can be taken
for certain that he will actually have performed the deduction. Still less It is very easy to see how humans can be ignorant of many, indeed in-
is it permissible to say that someone is saddled with an error A simply finitely many, truths. For in order not to know a given truth A, it suffices
209 because one has shown that he is burdened by other errors from which A that we have either never formed it, or else not retained it in memory.
follows. It follows directly that there must be an infinite number of truths which
Note. The definitions given here differ from the usual ones only in we humans do not know. For otherwise our cognitive powers 1 would
that the latter are expressed in a way which suggests that the only thing 1Reading Erkenntniskraji for Einbildungskrqft (ed.).

140 141
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 308. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

have to be infinite. It may not be superfluous to go into particulars here §.309.*


and consider the various kinds of ignorance. Truths we do not know ar~
sometimes such that even the ideas they are composed of are lacking in Grounds for the possibility of err01; and circumstances promoting error
our minds; sometimes this is not the case. Thus the truth that there are
1) It is much more difficult to explain how error arises. We can consider
five regular solids is unknown to someone who has never looked into
the difficulty we encounter in this undertaking to be another proof of the
geometry in the first way, since he has never even formed the subject-
magnitude of our ignorance. We make so many errors, and still, in many
concept, that of a regular solid. By contrast, the truth that every fixed
cases, we cannot explain how the error came about; worse than that, we
star is much larger than the moon may well be unknown to many who
can hardly explain how error is possible at all. All our judgements are ei-
do possess the concepts of which it is composed. It is obvious why a
ther immediate, or derived from others. Hence the question is in which of
truth must remain unknown to us as long as we lack the ideas of which
these two cases error can occur. None of the judgements formed without
it is composed. It is more difficult to understand how a truth can remain
the mediation of others can reasonably be suspected of being mistaken;
unknown to us when its subject- and predicate-ideas are in our mind, per-
for if we wanted to doubt one of them, we should have to doubt them all,
211 haps even active at the same time, and compared with one another with
since they all come about in the same way. But if we wanted to doubt
the intention of discovering whether they can be united in a judgement.
all immediate judgements, we should also have to doubt all derived ones;
In order to find this comprehensible, one must consider the following. All
hence we should have to doubt all our judgements, which is absurd. Thus
of our judgements come about in one of two ways: either we form them
we can reasonably look for error only in those judgements that are de-
immediately, i.e., we are not moved to form them through others from
rived from others. But how can it occur even here? According to §300,
which they are deducible; or else we derive them from other judgements.
we should not assume that the mode of inference by which we derive
It cannot be claimed that we are in a position to recognise immediately
some of our judgements from others is erroneous, unless it is a rule we
whether a proposition is true or false every time the ideas of which it is
have formulated, i.e., a judgement. But if all our immediate judgements
composed enter our consciousness. For though it is definitely true that
are correct, and if the modes of inference by which we derive mediated
we could not be aware that we possess certain ideas a, b, c, d, ... if we had
judgements from them are all valid, how do erroneous judgements occur?
not distinguished them, and thus formed a judgement concerning them,
2) I can only think of one way in which this might happen. According
yet it is not necessary that we recognise the truth or falsity of every com-
to what was said in §§300 and 301 there are inferences of probability, i.e.,
bination of them. It is still more comprehensible why the truth of all
inferences where the conclusion merely states that a certain proposition
propositions we have to deduce from others is not obvious as soon as
M has a greater or lesser degree of probability. Moreover, our soul, on 213
the ideas of which they are composed appear in our mind. For this, two
account of its finitude, is obliged to hold this proposition to be true, i.e.,
things are required: the propositions from which they are deducible must
to form the judgement M, with a degree of confidence proportionate to
all be before the mind at the same time, and our soul must have the ability
the probability. But as a proposition which is probable need not always
to derive the conclusion from these premises. Either of these conditions
be true, it is clear how the soul, in elevating all the propositions with
could be absent. Even if all of these premises are known to us, we might
a high degree of probability to judgements, can sometimes err. Enw
not be thinking of some of them at present; or, though we think of them, a
arises whenever it happens that something which we have recognised as
lack of attention or inferential ability may prevent us from recognising the
probable, following perfectly correct rules of inference, and which we
conclusion that follows from them. We cannot notice all the conclusions
expect and take to be true, turns out to be false.
that follow from given premises, for our powers of inference are finite,
3) I hope no one will object that according to this definition it is not an
and the number of consequences infinite. And depending upon how well
error when, following correct rules, we expect with mere probability that
developed the power of inference, one person may be aware of more of
something will happen which in the end doesn't. What error would there
212 these consequences than another.
be in a mathematician saying that the probability of randomly drawing a
black ball from an urn containing one white and 99 black balls ?to? The

142 143
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 309. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

error does not lie in the proposition which states the degree of probability causes are, I believe, the following: (a) ignorance is d~u~tless_ the_most
of such a judgement, but only in the judgement itself. We do not eIT when fecund mother of error. For regardless of the fact that it 1s an mev1table
we estimate that the degree of probability that a black ball will appear is condition of all error (because we cannot err with respect to something
~ .
= 100 , but only when we e.tpect the appearance of a black ball (on the which is already known to us), it contains the reason why a false propo-
basis of this estimate or for some other reason). We do not err here by .tion often has a very high degree of probability in our eyes, and why
s1
choice, but rather are obliged to, in that it is necessary for us to expect the we claim it with great confidence. From ignorance we do not know all
far more probable appearance of a black rather than a white ball under the cases which have an equal relative probability under given circum-
these circumstances. stances, and consequently estimate the probability of one of them to be
4) Since, as I have said, I cannot find any other comprehensible way much higher than it really is. Thus, for instance, before the discovery of
in which errors could creep into our judgements, it seems to me that the Saturn's rings, people must have thought quite confidently that all planets
only source of errors lies in the just-mentioned peculiarity of our fac- were spherical. (b) Another cause for error lies in the inappropriate di-
214 ulty of judgement, namely, that it raises merely probable propositions rection of our attention. For according to whether we direct our attention
to judgements. If this explanation is correct, it follows: (a) that all and to these or those ideas arising in us, different sequences of ideas become
only beings which must maintain judgements of probability are exposed active in us. And because this circumstance has the greatest influence on
to the clanger of error; (b) that only in the part of our judgements which the character of the new judgements we form, it is quite comprehensible
we derive by probable inferences, and thus form not with certainty, but that we can be prompted by this to claim many things when, under differ-
only with a greater or lesser degree of confidence, are errors to be found; ent circumstances, we would have claimed the opposite. A truth we do
(c) that every error is a proposition standing in a certain relation of prob- not recall at the moment (because our attention is directed elsewhere) has
ability to the remaining propositions which are taken to be true by the be- such a small effect that it may as well have been completely unknown.
ing who is in error. The appearance of truth [Wahrscheinlichkeit] which Thus one who doesn't recall that two straight lines need not lie in the
every error possesses is usually called illusion [Schein] or illusoriness same plane might well claim that two lines which do not meet must be
[Scheinbarkeit]. This illusoriness may stem from propositions which are parallel. (c) Similarly, the accidental association of our ideas clue to the
all true, but also from other incoITect ones. In the former case, one speaks law of simultaneity can lead to thousands of errors. For this association 216
of original, in the latter of derivative error. is the cause why one or another idea or previously formed judgement
5) It is well known that the first judgements for which we inevitably comes to mind, and why our attention is directed to this or that object,
make use of judgements of probability are the so-called judgements of etc. (cl) From this it is obvious that many errors are clue to an unfaith-
experience. The realm of experience is accordingly the domain where ful memory as well as to an imagination that is either too feeble or else
error first and inevitably dwells. But etrnrs may also creep into purely overactive. For a memory which is unreliable leads us to forget truths we
conceptual judgements, when we are somehow forced or prompted to should bear in mind, and a feeble imagination does not lend the strength
make use of probability judgements in their derivation. This is the case to recalled ideas which is necessary for them to be combined in a judge-
in particular for all judgements which draw on memory (§306, no. 13); ment. An overactive imagination, finally, lends such vividness to some of
consequently, the danger of error extends to all judgements based upon our ideas that others, which do not accord with the former, cannot even
long series of inferences, no matter of what kind. For we arrive at these enter our consciousness. (e) Our own will plays a great role in the origin
by means of premises, some of which are merely drawn from memory. of, perhaps, most of the errors we humans make, in that, either with or
6) The above makes the origin of error comprehensible in general without the determinate intention to deceive ourselves, we pay heed only
terms. But for the purpose of formulating rules for the avoidance of er- to the reasons that speak for a given proposition and ignore those speak-
215 ror, it is all but useless. For this we must try to acquaint ourselves with ing against it. Thus the well-known phenomenon that we mostly believe
the most important circumstances favouring the origin of errors, for it exactly what appeals to our passions, and reject what would prevent their
is often though not always in our power to avoid these. The principal satisfaction. This is the reason why the opinions of one and the same man

144 145
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 309. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

change as often as his inclinations and needs. (t) Once we have made senses in these sentences; first in the sense according to which not all,
an incorrect judgement, we are in peril of repeating it in the future. For but only means of a certain kind may be applied, and then in the strict
if in the past something appeared to be thus and so, we presume it will sense which excludes any and all mediation. (i) As beneficial as it is for
appear so on another occasion if we again consider the reasons which led the development of our understanding that we grow up not alone but in
us to form the judgement in the first place. For this reason, we usually the company of other rational beings who communicate their views to us
do not even consider these reasons again. But even if we do weigh the from the start, it cannot be denied that we are also led by this to commit
proposition again, it is to be feared that the same unnoticed associations many errors. For in our youth we accept almost everything that others
217 of ideas which led us to err in the first place will again give rise to the say to us without examining it ourselves, and indeed without even being
same faulty conclusion. And the more often this occurs, the longer we capable of examining it, including a great many things they are mistaken
have adhered to a certain opinion, the stronger is our trust in it, and the about or concerning which they deceive us. When in later years we be-
harder it is to for us to change our mind. (g) Errors not only get repeated, come able to correct many of these opinions, we often still fail to do so,
but also usually lead us to commit other errors. For it is well known that on account of our laziness, because these opinions are pleasing to us, or
many, indeed infinitely many propositions are deducible from every false because we have grown so accustomed to them that we cannot easily be
proposition; so it is not surprising that holding one incorrect opinion soon convinced that they are incorrect. Thus students often adhere to the errors
leads us to hold many others. How many errors would we fall into if, for of their teachers, and the same error may be spread among entire peoples
instance, we made the fundamental mistake of thinking that the highest and ages.
moral law was to increase our own happiness! (h) The association of our
§.310.
ideas with signs, be these either imagined or actual (e.g., written) cer-
tainly does a great deal to facilitate thought. In certain cases, however, it Other treatments of the same subject
can also be the cause of errors. This may occur because every sign, which
The way that I explained the origin of error in the previous § is not so new
is itself an idea and as such is associated with various other ideas, can also
and different from previous accounts, and many others have said quite 219
produce the latter and can therefore produce a sequence of ideas which
similar things. Indeed, the common remark that all error is based upon
influence our thinking; but also because we confuse similar signs which
appearance [Schein] points to propositions which are merely probable
designate utterly different ideas, with the result that, instead of simply
[Wahrscheinlich] as the essential source of e1rnr. The account of FRIES
repeating a previously formed judgement, we replace it with something
(Syst. d. L., p. 480ff.) comes especially close to the account presented
essentially different; and finally because a given sign is often ambiguous
above: "Every error," he says expressly, "is based upon the premises of
and we pass from one of its meanings to another without noticing. An
a probable inference." The factors which I have indicated as conducive
example of the influence a name of a thing may have on the sequence
to errors are also enumerated more or less completely in every Logic;
of ideas which are activated in us, and thus on the judgements we form,
only it seems that people have not recognised clearly enough that these
may be found in every name which gives rise to an associated meaning.
factors in and of themselves do not constitute a complete explanation of
An example of an error arising from the confusion of similar signs may
the way that errors may occur. Let us then present and examine the most
218 be found in every error of calculation arising from the confusion of two
important previous accounts.
similar numerals. An example, finally, of an error caused by ambiguity
1) The dispute of the ancient Greek philosophers on this subject is
is given by the claim that divine revelation is impossible, where one at-
famous: while some of them, namely, those of the ELEATIC school and
tempts to demonstrate this impossibility by claiming on the one hand that
the PLATONISTS, claimed that all error stemmed from the senses, others,
such a revelation would have to be instruction given to us immediately by
especially the EPICUREANS, claimed that all errors came from the under-
God and on the other hand that we have no criterion which would allow
standing. To a certain extent, this dispute hasn't been cleared up even in
us to distinguish the immediate from the mediate effects of God. Here
our days. Nothing is resolved with the remark that the senses cannot de-
one overlooks that fact that the word immediate is taken in two different
ceive, because they do not judge, for here the words "senses" is obviously

146 147
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 310. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

taken in a different meaning than it is when used by XENOPHANES, PAR- by saying that the soul will be led by the altered nature of the renewed
MENIDES, et al., when they claim the senses to be the source of all error. idea to conclude, by means of a correct, but only probable and hence oc-
In a certain interpretation, one might claim that neither party was wrong. casionally misleading, rule, that the original idea was constituted exactly
For it is correct to say that only the senses deceive, if this is taken to mean as the imagination now portrays it to be.
that only know ledge based upon the testimony of the senses, either essen- 4) KANT (L., Ak, 9.53 ff.; cf. K. d. 1: V., A293/B349 ff.) and his
tially or accidentally (the latter case covering memories) is exposed to the followers encounter great difficulty in explaining the possibility of what
danger of error. It is no less correct to say that only the understanding errs, they call formal errors (see above, §307, note), "for it is incomprehensi-
220 while the senses do not lie, if by the judgements based upon the senses ble how a given power may depart from its own essential laws." Here I
one only means immediate judgements of perception, and counts all other would like to ask if simultaneously holding two contrary propositions to
judgements (as is fair) among the judgements of the understanding. be true should always be called a formal error. If this is the case, then
2) Several philosophers of ancient as well as modern times saw no I would say that the origin of formal errors is no more unusual than the
other way to explain the origin of error than as a mere misuse of free tvil!. formation of any material error. For it holds of any false proposition that
This, as is well known, was the view of DESCARTES, MALEBRANCHE, it conflicts with certain others which are true. But if we do not notice this
BERKELEY, and in our times is maintained by TIEFTRUNK and others. conflict, it cannot in any way prevent us from accepting this false propo-
KLEIN (Ansch. u. Denki., §272) says expressly: "The ultimate ground sition. And for this conflict to remain unnoticed, it is in no way necessary
of all errors lies in the free will, since the mere limitations of the mind, that the proposition conflicting with the false one remain unknown to us.
though they may be the cause of ignorance, cannot be the cause of er- Rather, it can also happen that we recognise it, and indeed think both
ror. Our innate striving towards knowledge of things, and our inability to propositions at the same time, and hold both to be true, as thousands of
know everything we desire, determine the soul, which is free, to expand examples show. But even if by a formal error one only meant taking an
the bounds by means of invented ideas, and to take these imaginings for incorrect rule of inference to be valid, a formal error would still be no 222
true pictures of objects." I do not find this account satisfactory, for it does more difficult to understand than any other. It is true that the incorrect-
not explain how it happens that our soul takes these invented ideas for ness of a false rule of inference is usually easily detected by applying it
true pictures of objects. That it does so merely because it wills to does to various examples. But when someone does not undertake this exami-
not follow, at least not directly. For it is certainly false to say that the nation, or if he is unlucky in his choice of examples, only picking such as
power of judgement depends upon the will in the sense that it is in a po- do not reveal the flaw, it is quite possible for a false rule to appear correct
sition to form any judgement the will desires-as is shown most clearly to him for a time; and have not many logicians themselves encountered
by the reproaches of one's conscience. this? But if (as KANT seems actually to have understood things) a formal
3) LOCKE (Ess., IV, 2, § 17 and 20, § 1) already found occasion to error is only supposed to be one we commit because we proceed accord-
remark that most errors are based on faulty memories; and Count DE ing to a false rule of inference which we have not ourselves constructed,
TRACY (ldeol., III, 3 and 4) goes so far as to claim that the only source then no one has ever shown that there are such errors; and I believe that
of our errors is the imperfection of our memories (l'impe1jection de nos there cannot be any such. According to KANT, this difficulty arises be-
souvenirs). It is quite right in my opinion to claim that a great many of cause the understanding does not work alone to produce our judgements,
our errors, even in fields based not on experience but on mere concepts, but another power, namely, sensibility, also plays a role; accordingly, "the
are actually due to memory; but it is not obvious to me why errors should incorrect judgement should be considered as the diagonal, so to speak, of
221 arise only in this way, nor how merely pointing to the imperfection of two forces. The influence of sensibility causes us to take merely subjec-
memory is supposed to provide a complete explanation of the origin of tive grounds for objective ones, and consequently to confuse truth with
even a single error. The question still persists of how the imperfection of the mere semblance of truth." 1 To my mind, this account leaves unex-
memory, i.e., the difference between a renewed and the original idea, pro- plained how it comes about that merely subjective grounds are taken for
duces an erroneous judgement. And this question can only be answered 1
Kant says something similar at KrV, A294-295/B350-35 I (ed.).

148 149
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 310. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

objective, and how the mere semblance of truth and truth itself (or the sub- our satellite by a few dozen miles? His judgement was false, but for all
jective and the objective) are confused. For to take one thing for another his attentiveness it could not have been otherwise; even if the possibility
is already a judgement, and indeed a false one, an error. Thus the possi- of such a perturbation by a comet had occurred to him, he would have
bility of error cannot be explained in this way. It is also noteworthy that to have found it so improbable that he could not have prevented himself
accordinab to KANT' s views our entire cognitive faculties are constituted [rom forming his judgement (albeit with a degree of confidence which is
precisely so as to lead us to err. The pure concepts of the understand- not the highest of all).
ing (categories) and the a priori principles of the understanding founded 6) RITTER has his own account of the origin of en-or (L., p. 146 ff.)
upon them lead us into error as soon as we apply them to supersensible According to him every error is based upon invention and hypothesis. I
things. The concepts of reflection of the faculty of judgement give rise cannot agree-for where is the invention when we expect, in accordance
223 to errors, as soon as we apply them to intuitions in the way we apply with all the rules of probability, that a ball drawn at random from an urn
them to concepts. The Ideas grounded in reason, finally, produce errors containing 99 black and one white will be black? Yet as is well known,
whenever we use them constitutively rather than regulatively. Of the last, we can be mistaken in this expectation, and the white one can appear.
we read in the Critique of Pure Reason (A297/B353): "In our reason According to RITTER, furthermore, all error is caused by a voluntary
there are fundamental rules and maxims governing their use, which com- withdrawal of attention, so that there are no innocent mistakes. But this
pletely resemble objective principles, and through which it happens that is already refuted by the example just cited. Although I too believe that
the subjective necessity of a certain combination of our concepts, for the every error is a mere judgement of probability, and thus is never formed
benefit of reason, is taken to be an objective necessity of the determina- with the complete confidence which, e.g., immediate judgements enjoy,
tion of things in themselves. This illusion cannot be avoided, no more I nevertheless would not claim along with R. that conviction in cases of
so than, e.g., an astronomer can avoid the moon appearing larger when error never equals that of cases of knowledge, if this is supposed to mean
rising, even though he is not deceived by this appearance." It seems to that the confidence with which we form an incorrect judgement is always
me that it is already sufficiently clear from what has been said previously less than that with which we form a true one. If, for instance, we had
(§§ 119, 279, note) that the distinction between the so-called categories, placed 51 black and 49 white balls in that urn, we would still judge that a
concepts of reflection, and Ideas, as well as the claims limiting the use of black one would be drawn. This judgement would be formed with much
these concepts, are entirely based upon incorrect assumptions; more will less confidence than the previous one. Yet chance might make the latter
be said on the subject later. The origin of so-called sense illusions has true and the former false. 225
already been explained (§303). But if it were true that the Ideas of God,
of a universe, and the like necessarily led to errors as soon as we suppose §.311.*
that certain objects correspond to them, then this would be a truly inex-
Origin of true judgements. Understanding and reason
plicable phenomenon, unless we assumed that contradictions were to be
met with within our reason itself. Before we assume this, let us sooner
1) From the preceding theory of the origin of error it follows by mere
believe that these contradictions lie within our systems!
opposition how our true judgements, which also bear the name of cog-
5) Several logicians, e.g., CROUSAZ, ULRICH (Inst., §271), JAKOB
nitions, arise. First of all, those of our judgements which are formed
(L., §433), METZ (L., 237), GERLACH (L., §238), CALKER (L., 232)
without mediation must be true, as must those which are deduced from
teach that error is based upon a kind of haste. I would not venture to
such immediate judgements by inferences that are not inferences of prob-
claim this myself. For how could one accuse an astronomer of haste
ability. By the very way in which they are produced, these judgements
when, after the most careful calculations, he forms the judgement that in a
are secure from the danger of error. Secondly, many judgements formed
hundred years there will be a lunar eclipse on such and such a day, and the
in other ways may also be true, in particular, judgements deduced from
224 eclipse does not occur only because in the meantime (something which
those of the first kind by mere probabilistic inferences, or judgements
could not have been foreseen) a comet appears and changes the path of
obtained by perfect inferences from other false judgements. For merely

150 151
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 3 l l. Of the Relation betiveen our Judgements and Truth

probable judgements can be true sometimes, and true conclusions may of astronomy are mere products of the understanding. Rather, we usually
be derived from false premises. These two sorts of origin of true judge- describe their discovery as a work by which human reason has most en-
ments are essentially different. The first produces only true judgements, nobled itself. Should we then only ascribe to the understanding the em- 227
while the second only produces many true judgements. The former may pirical cognitions obtainable without the mediation of purely conceptual
be called the necessmy sort of origin of true judgements, the latter contin- truths? But then only the so-called immediate judgements of perception
gent. For it follows from the concept of the first sort that all judgements would count as products of the understanding; and that sugar is sweet
arising in this way are true, while this is not the case for the second sort. and gall bitter would have to be counted as truths of reason, since they
The necessary sort of origin may be further divided into an immediate are derived from immediate perception only through the mediation of the
origin, responsible for the occurrence of immediate cognitions, and a me- principle of sufficient reason. I do not think that we are too far removed
diate sort, which gives rise to mediated cognitions. The contingent sort is from common usage if we define understanding as the capacity for em-
always mediate. pirical cognitions, which may require the mediation of purely conceptual
2) This seems the most appropriate place to define the concepts that truths, but where we do not have to be conscious of these truths. On the
226 ordinary usage connects with the words understanding and reason; for other hand, any truth which requires for its derivation the clear recogni-
there is no dispute that these words do not mean an ability to produce tion of a purely conceptual truth is justly attributed to reason, even if it
judgements in general, whether they be true or false, but rather only a also requires a perceptual premise. This also allows us to explain (in a
faculty for producing true or probable judgements. For if we hear that manner similar to that described above for reason) how the understand-
someone has formed a judgement which is neither true nor probable, we ing came by its Latin name (intellectus). For the first phenomenon which
do not ascribe it either to his reason or to his understanding, but rather to points to a greater measure of this Goel-given power in the growing child
the want or non-use of these powers, i.e., to his lack of understanding or than in the most developed animals is that he begins to understand (hu-
unreasonableness. It is equally certain that we rank reason higher than man) speech.
understanding, as may be gauged by the fact that we attribute reason to Note. The explanation of E. REINHOLD (Psycho!., p. 142) is very
the most perfect being, God, without hesitation, while we have misgiv- similar. By contrast if, as so often happens, people call the faculty of
ings about attributing understanding to Him, and do so only on pain of concepts the unclerstancling, I remind them that the understanding also
contradiction. In addition, we find the true superiority of humans over forms judgements, and that constructing appropriate concepts may re-
animals not in the possession of understanding, which we are inclined to quire knowledge of a great many purely conceptual truths. Nor do I
accord to the more developed animals as well, but rather in reason. If now understand how, on these accounts, one could ascribe Ideas [ldeen] to
we recall the important division of truths into conceptual and intuitional reason, when these are only a particular kind of concept. If one defines
propositions, we can hardly refrain from counting all purely conceptual reason as the highest cognitive activity, it will first be necessary, it seems
truths among the cognitions of reason. For even such an easy and sim- to me, to explain what a higher cognitive operation is, and which activi-
ple conceptual truth as the well-known principle of sufficient reason [Satz ties should be counted among the highest, which among the lower. Every 228
vom Grunde] we ascribe not to the understanding, but to reason, and do truth deduced from another is in a certain sense produced by a higher ac-
so with such firmness that in many languages we take the name for reason tivity than that which produced the latter. Accordingly, the highest activ-
(ratio) from this proposition; to all appearance because the first expres- ity would only be exercised on a truth from which nothing further may be
sion of awakening reason is to inquire everywhere into grounds. But if cleclucecl-but are there any such things? Others (e.g., FR. SCHLEGEL),
we call the power of arriving at the knowledge of purely conceptual truths as is well known, see the relation between understanding and reason in
reason, the understanding is left with the responsibility for the production exactly the opposite way. This also applies in a certain measure to all
of our sensible cognitions. Yet we do not give the name of truths of the those who look upon the understanding as the faculty of reflection or of
understanding to all truths which contain a sensible constituent, i.e., an voluntmy control, and of mediate repetition of immediate cognitions (of
intuition. Thus, for example, we usually do not say that the sublime truths reason); e.g., FRIES, SCHMID, et al. The derivation of this word from

152 153
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 312. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

understand indeed speaks strongly in favour of this definition; against truth stating the presence of these ideas and sensations in me must have
it, however, speaks the fact that we ascribe a great deal of understand- a ground. It is no less obvious that all the cognitions we gain through
ing even to people who do not know how to make the grounds of their mere probabilistic inferences (and thus contingently) do not spring from
judgements distinct, provided that they make many correct judgements the previous knowledge of their ground. For when we form a judgement
(concerning objects of experience). According to TROXLER's Logik (I, M by means of a probabilistic inference, we take M to be true merely
p. 104) reason is "the higher unity of understanding and feeling, the inter- because we recognise that it has a determinate degree of probability with
mediary between the senses and the mind, very much like experience, dif- respect to assumptions A,B,C,D, ... which we hold to be true. But the
fering from it only in that experience is directed towards the outer world around of a truth can never lie in such mere probabilities. Given that 230
Cl

and reason towards the inner." Understanding, for its part, stands "be- judgements of experience are as such always recognised through proba-
tween reason and experience as the purely logical and dialectical power bilistic judgements, it holds in general of this part of our cognitions that
which mediates between the mind and the senses, etc." I confess my in- we obtain them without first having learned their grounds. The question
ability to grasp such definitions. may also be raised with respect to conceptual truths. Here we are not
concerned with purely conceptual truths which we discover through mere
§.312. probabilistic inferences, but rather with those we discover without any
probabilistic inferences, or at most only those which are used in recalling
Whether we can recognise a truth without recognising its grounds previously recognised conclusions so that we may use them as premises.
If it were the case that all purely conceptual truths which we recognised
If what was said above (§203) about the concept of a ground is correct,
in this way, i.e., purely by means of perfect inferences, were recognised
then the ground of a truth is always either another truth or a collection
through their grounds, then all the conceptual truths which we recognised
of several truths, and thus an object of our cognitive faculties. It will be immediately would have to be basic truths. We may leave it undecided
readily understood that recognition and consideration of the ground quite whether all the purely conceptual truths which we recognise immediately
naturally gives rise to the recognition of the consequence; indeed, one are basic truths. But in order to say that all truths which recognise through
might surmise that we never know a consequence except from its ground. inference (even perfect inferences) are recognised through their grounds,
229 It is therefore worth the trouble to look into this, i.e., to raise the question
it would have to be the case that in every perfect inference the premises
of whether it is possible for us to recognise a truth without having pre- are related to the conclusion as grounds to consequence. This is, I be-
viously recognised the ground upon which it rests, i.e., the one or more lieve, not so. Only the tiniest portion of our inferences are constituted
truths of which it is a consequence. If (as is often imagined) every truth in a way which would justify our looking upon their premises, whenever
had its own ground, then the mere fact that we form immediate judge- they become true, as the genuine ground of the truth of their conclusion.
ments, which all belong to the class of true judgements, would already tell How else could it be that we arrive at one and the same conclusion in
us that we are in a position to recognise truths without having previously
such diverse ways, given that there is only one objective ground of any
recognised their ground. For the truths we recognise immediately would individual truth (as seems to be the case according to §206)? Certainly,
also have a ground, and yet not be recognised by means of this ground. then, it is not always the case that when we recognise a conceptual truth,
But according to §215 there are truths which have no ground, so that the even by means of perfect inferences, we do so with the aid of a previous 231
above argument fails, unless I also show that some of the truths we recog- recognition of its ground. Rather, it most often occurs that we know the
nise immediately are not of the sort which do not have grounds. Now this consequence, yet do not know the truths that constitute its ground, or at
can be shown quite easily for the part of our immediate judgements which
least do not know that they are its ground.
belong to the class of perceptual judgements. For a truth of the form "I
have the idea or sensation A" cannot be among the truths which have no
further ground; rather, just as my own existence and the fact that I now
have precisely these ideas, sensations, etc., must have a cause, so too the

154 155
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 313. 314. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

§.313. when we speak of indicating the limits of a power we simply mean cer-
tain propositions that truly state what this power is capable and incapable
Grounds for the recognition of truth of accomplishing.
Such indications may be called complete if they permit the determi-
If we do not form a judgement M immediately, but rather deduce it from nation of everything that this power can and cannot accomplish, and in-
other (true or false) judgements A,B,C,D, ... , then the latter are the complete or partial if they only determine some things the power either
cause of the former. Now if the judgement M is true, and thus merits to can or cannot do. According to this, we mean by an indication of cer-
be called a cognition, the judgements A, B, C, D, ... , in which lie the tain limits of our cognitive faculty nothing other than certain propositions
cause of the origin of this cognition, may properly be called the cause of which truly state what we are able or unable to know. A little reflection
the recognition of the truth M. From this it follows immediately that not shows, however, that this concept requires further refinement. For since
every truth has such a ground. Our immediate judgements are true, and every judgement that accords with truth is called a cognition, even if this 233
thus deserve to be called cognitions, but there is no ground of their recog- accord is accidental or was the effect of previous errors, it is clear that
nition, i.e., no collection of judgements from which they are deduced. the limits of our cognitive faculty would be vacillating if one adhered to
It also follows from this definition that the ground for the recognition the broad definition given above. For mere chance or even an error might
of a truth does not always have to be a collection consisting entirely of extend these limits. Thus we would not be able to deny, for example,
truths. False judgements may also sometimes lead to true conclusions, that even the most ignorant man has the ability to know the nature of the
and thus provide the occasion for the origin of a cognition. Finally, it inhabitants of Mars or Venus, etc. For could it not happen that for some
is clear that the ground of recognition of a truth should by no means be reason or other (e.g., like Ennemoser's clairvoyant wife) he labours un-
confused with the ground of the truth in the sense of § 198. For even in der the delusion that he can make judgements on such matters, and one
the case where the ground for recognition of a truth consists entirely of of them just chances to be true? Truths such as these, recognised through
truths, it is not necessary (as pointed out in the previous section) that these error, should certainly not be counted when we intend to determine the
truths must be precisely the ones which constitute the genuine ground of limits of our cognitive faculty. Here we require propositions which state
232 the truth that one has deduced. Sometimes, however, this can occur, so what kinds of truths we can or cannot arrive at, not by chance, but rather
it will be permissible to distinguish two kinds of grounds of recognition: in a rule-governed way. But such limits can be quite diverse. They would
those which consist in the truths that are the genuine (or objective) ground be complete if they completely determined the collection of truths we can
of the recognised truth, and those where this is not the case. Allow me recognise, as well as the collection of those which we cannot, and other-
to call the former objective, and the latter merely subjective grounds of wise incomplete. They might specify these collections by indicating one
knowledge. characteristic or another, something which can affect their usefulness for
certain ends. It is also obvious that the determination of these limits will
§.314. be different depending upon whether we consider the cognitive faculties
of single individuals or those of mankind in general; and upon whether
Whether there are definite limits to our cognitive faculty we speak of factors which hold only in the present, during our entire life
on earth, for all humanity in all future centuries, or for all finite beings in
the universe. 234
1) The thought that there are infinitely many truths, but that we as finite
2) When we attempt to determine the limits of our own cognitive fac-
beings are only in a position to know finitely many of them, leads quite
ulties or those of humanity as a whole, it becomes clear that this cannot
naturally to the question of whether there are definite limits to our cogni-
be accomplished by explicitly enumerating all the truths which a single
tive faculty and, if so, whether we might be able to indicate them. Before
individual or mankind as a whole cannot attain. For in order to do so, they
answering this question, we must first say more precisely what we mean
would have to be known to us rather than unknown. Generally, when we
by such limits of our ability to know and their determination. Usually

156 157
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 314. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

attempt to distinctly specify the goal for the sake of which we wish to wants to say that an object is unknown if we are incapable of indicating
present the determination of the limits of our cognitive faculty in a trea- any of the attributes which are proper to it, I reply that even on this defini-
tise of logic, we find (it seems to me) that this only happens because we tion there are no completely unknown objects. For already the idea A un-
wish to provide a means which can be used by someone embarking on an der which we comprehend the object, expresses a proper attribute, in that
inquiry of some sort or another to decide beforehand whether answering the attribute a is certainly one which belongs only to the objects standing
his questions would be beyond his cognitive abilities-in which case we under A. Thus we must interpret the given definition more narrowly; one 236
not only save him from the futile effort the inquiry would involve, but would have to say, perhaps, that an object is said to be unknown if we are
also free him from the danger of going wrong in his inquiries. unable to indicate any of its proper attributes which do not already lie in
3) Given this specific goal, one gathers that many determinations, its idea. In order to fix limits to our cognitive faculty in this way, one
which may be quite correct and useful for other ends, are useless here. would have to set out one or more propositions of the following form:
Thus, for example, it would be a true determination of the limits of our "None of the objects standing under the idea A has an attribute which be-
knowledge, well worth taking to heart, to say that we are able to know longs exclusively to these objects, is knowable by us humans, and does
only as much as is beneficial for us. But how useless this determination not lie in the idea A itself." But as there is nothing impossible in an object
would be for the present purpose! having attributes which do not lie in its idea (§64), and it cannot be denied
4) From the indicated goal it also follows that a determination of the that humans have the ability to recognise such attributes, i.e., to form true
limits of our cognitive faculty which was only valid for the present or the synthetic judgements ( § 197), it is obvious that the truth of such a propo-
past, i.e., if it only taught us what we could not know at present, would sition could only be proven by appealing to the particular constitution of
be of no use. For from the fact that we have been so far unable to know the idea A. For my part, I confess that I know of no such peculiarity of
a cetiain truth, it by no means follows that it will be impossible to do so certain ideas. Indeed, it seems to me that a proposition of this form would
in the future. A determination which can be used for our goal must also be self-refuting. For if the idea A is not such that what is stated of it in
be valid for the future: it must mark out a class of truths as being beyond this proposition is already contained in it (in which case the proposition
235 our capacity to know not only at present, but for the entire future of our would be a measly tautology), then the judgement set out here is already
existence, at least while we are still human. of the kind it denies we can have.
5) Given that these truths cannot be explicitly enumerated, the first 6) The second thing that might occur to us is expressly to indicate
thing that might occur to us is to indicate that there are objects of which the propositions which are so constituted that our cognitive faculties will
we can know nothing. Determinations of limits of this kind would then be forever incapable of deciding whether or not they are true. But how
consist of propositions of the following kind: "Every object which falls hard it would be to prove claims of this sort! The fact that we have so far
under idea A is beyond our know ledge" or (what comes to the same thing) not been able to decide whether attribute b belongs to the objects which
"We can recognise no truth of the form 'A is X' ." But who can fail to see stand under the idea A does not entitle us to conclude that we will never
that such a claim is absurd? We know something of every object, at least find grounds for such a decision. In order to see the difficulty which arises 237
what it has in common, qua object, with all other objects. Moreover, the here more clearly, let us consider the two cases which may occur, depend-
statement that we cannot know anything about this object is itself a judge- ing upon whether A and b are pure concepts or mixed ideas. Suppose the
ment about it; hence it is actually a contradiction to say of an object that former, i.e., a case of recognising a purely conceptual truth. Here, admit-
we cannot know it at all, i.e., that we cannot form a single true judgement tedly, no experiment of any kind that we might petform will help to decide
about it. One might reply that in saying that we do not know this object, the question, at least if the kind of knowledge which does not allow the
we do not mean that we are ignorant of absolutely all its properties and possibility of error is required. But who could want to claim that even a
that we cannot even form a single judgement about it. I accept this, but I very lengthy consideration of the two concepts A and b, more and more
should like to ask now for a more definite identification of the attributes precise and many-sided comparisons between these and related concepts,
that must be unrecognisable if the object is to be called unknown. If one etc., could not lead to the recognition that the two concepts can or can-

158 159
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 314. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

not be combined into a judgement? How many questions in the realm of §.315.
purely conceptual truths have remained undecided for centuries, and yet
a way was found in the end. Think, for example, of the question whether The doctrine of Critical Philosophy on this subject
or not the ratio of the diameter to the circumference of a circle is rational.
What I have just said about the limits of our cognitive faculties agrees
On the other hand, the ideas A and b, of which it is asked whether they
more or less with what most philosophers, aside from the sceptics, have 239
can be combined to form a true proposition, might be mixed concepts. In
always thought. Yet the founder of the Critical Philosophy prided him-
this case, mere contemplation cannot decide anything, rather, experience
self on having measured the power of the human understanding more
is necessary. Suppose further that no one has yet had these experiences,
precisely and having established most definite limits of our knowledge.
or indeed that we cannot even conceive of how they might be possible.
In the discovery (examined above in §305) that synthetic judgements can
Nevertheless, they might still occur in the future, and decide the ques-
only be mediated by intuitions, and that apart from empirical intuitions
tion for us. Thus to the present day no one knows how to decide what
there were also two pure intuitions, namely, space and time, he thought
form the inhabitants of the moon have. But who would wish to conclude
he had found the right way to fix these limits. We are only in a po-
from this that we will never be able to do so? This would be to make the
sition to form true synthetic judgements concerning objects which we
same mistake that someone made centuries ago when he claimed that no
either intuit empirically, or which stand under one of the two pure in-
one would ever be able to calculate the weight of the moon because no
tuitions, space and time. The incoITectness of this claim is clear from
238 one had so far clone so. The flaw of this inference from the past to the
what has already been said, since it has been shown that there are no pure
future becomes all the more palpable when we demand that one indicate
intuitions such as KANT supposed; that synthetic judgements arise not
more precisely what is meant by the future. Is it the near future, which
through intuitions, but rather in a completely different way, partly imme-
all of us hope to live through? Or the duration of the existence of our
dia~ely. through the concepts of which they are composed, partly through
entire species on earth (who knows how long this will be)? Or the future
denvat10n from other judgements; and finally that even analytic judge-
which begins with the withdrawal from this earthly life? Or eternity it-
ments can only come about if certain synthetic judgements have preceded
self? Hardly anyone will venture to opt for the last, i.e., to claim that for
them. Still, it behooves me to consider more closely these consistently
all eternity we will be unable to decide whether a given proposition is true
acute thoughts and the reasons with which KANT supported them.
or false, because we cannot do so now. But if we cannot go so far without
l) K. thought that the above principle could sufficiently explain what
the greatest temerity, it seems to me that we already run some risk even
knowledge we are capable of obtaining, and which sciences we may pur-
in making this prophecy for a much shorter time.
sue. Yet only the so-called theoretical sciences of logic, mathematics,
Note. Hence I confess myself to be of the opinion that it is hardly
physics, and metaphysics were covered by this explanation. I would point
possible to make a determination of the limit of our cognitive faculty, at
out that we also make practical judgements. And as indubitable (as K.
least not the kind that is generally desired. It might be argued that this
himself admits) as the truth of many of these judgements is, so too is
claim contains a contradiction, similar to the one pointed out above in
it obvious that they must be counted not among the analytic, but rather 240
no. 5; for this impossibility itself seems to form a limit for our faculty
among the synthetic judgements. One may fairly ask for an explanation
of knowledge. I reply, in the first place, that I do not claim that such a
of the origin of these, i.e., the pure intuition upon which they are based.
limit can never be given, but only that I clo not know of one; furthermore
Besides this, there are more theoretical sciences than those named above,
that the claim of this impossibility can be considered an indication of
whose existence also requires explanation. I will mention only aesthetics,
an eternally unknowable truth only if it is presupposed that such a limit
of which it can hardly be said that all of its propositions are empirical, or
actually exists even though we cannot indicate it. But I do not say this; I
that all of them are analytic.
rather think that we are unable to indicate this limit because there is none,
. 2) Concerning logic, K. claimed that it (i.e., pure, general logic) con-
so that the sum of human knowledge is capable of increasing ad infinitum.
sisted of nothing but analytic judgements, so that no intuitions were re-
quired to recognise them. I cannot agree with this finding; rather, it seems

160 161
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

to me that logic contains a considerable number of synthetic propositions not in the least follow that the science of numbers requires an intuition
which are also purely conceptual. Who could claim that the propositions of time, as was already pointed out above (§306, no. 6). If this were the
that there are ideas, simple and complex ideas, intuitions and concepts, case, then, since all thought takes place in time, the science of thought
that every proposition may be analysed into three or more parts, that a (or logic) would also be based upon the intuition of time. In general,
relation of ground to consequence obtains among truths, and hundreds of the fact that the ideas of time and space do not occur in the theorems of 242
other similar propositions are analytic? Who would want to claim that arithmetic seems to me to show that neither of these ideas are necessary
they do not belong in logic? Even the well-known rules of syllogistic are for the recognition of arithmetical truths. The concepts of quantity and
incorrectly looked upon as analytic. The proposition "If all men are mor- number (§87) certainly contain neither the idea of time, nor that of space;
tal, and Caius is a man, then Caius is mortal" might reasonably be called just as little are they contained in the concepts of a sum, a product, a dif-
analytic in the wider sense of§ 148, but the rule itself, namely, that from ference, a quotient, etc. No mathematician would deny that arithmetical
two propositions of the forms "A is B" and "B is C" a third proposition of theorems are valid for all objects without exception; nor that the laws of
the form "A is C" follows, is a synthetic truth. his science are valid not just for those which are in space or time, but
3) Our philosopher seems to have found himself in a difficult situa- for all the others as well, namely, also for mere concepts. And do not
tion when it came to mathematics, and in particular its general parts, i.e., logicians also calculate? Still more odd is the inference that the theory
the theories of numbers and quantities. For given their intimate connec- of quantities requires the intuition of space or of time because the sym-
tion with geometry, he did not wish to claim that these sciences contained bols that mathematicians use are in space and time. Is this not also true
241 only analytic propositions. But if he allowed that they contained synthetic of the signs metaphysicians use? Do they not construct their claims by
propositions, he would have to point to a pure intuition that they are based means of words, and in time? SCHULTZ (Priif., I, p. 226 ff.) found it
upon. To claim that it was the intuition of space would be utterly implau- necessary to offer a different explanation on this point. He claimed that it
sible. Thus he felt compelled to say that the basis here was the intuition was absolutely impossible to think a plurality without the aid of an intu-
of time. By way of justification, he pointed out that all enumeration oc- ition, for things which are identical in their inner characteristics can only
curs only in time, i.e., successively (K. d. 1: V., Bl5, Al42-3/182, and be distinguished by representing them in different times and places. In
elsewhere). It is clear that he wavered in this decision, however, from the my opinion it is in no way necessary for the things which we unite in a
fact that he occasionally calls upon space to help, claiming that one could number to be perfectly identical in their inner characteristics; rather we
only recognise arithmetical truths by making the numerical concepts that can also unite things that are quite diverse, and represented as such, in a
occurred in them sensible by means of points or some other sort of spa- number, provided only that they have something in common. Thus we
tial objects; while in other passages (e.g., K1:, A717/B745) he says that might ask about the number of concepts or theorems found in this or that
the concepts of the general theory of quantities are made sensible through development of a science; and here it is plain as clay that we think of these
signs, and that here there is no geometrical or ostensive construction, but concepts and theorems as different from each other. What of the claim, 243
rather a symbolic or characteristic construction takes its place. I hope it then, that we cannot distinguish the units we are supposed to enumerate
will not be thought that I do so for the pleasure of contradiction when unless we place them in different times and places? And why should it be
I say that the theory of quantities has a greater right to the name of a necessary for both to occur together? "Because time flows," we read, "the
purely analytic science than any other, including logic. For if not all at imagination cannot embrace and retain the units unless they are attached
least many of its theorems seem to me to be analytic. The proposition to something permanent." I ask anyone who has clone any counting: is it
already mentioned in §305: a+ (b+c) = (a+b) +c, seems to me to be really like this and indeed necessarily so? Does he really represent every-
obviously analytic. And many other propositions, e.g., the famous bino- thing that he counts in different places? What about the chimes a clock
mial theorem may be held to be analytic, at least if it is understood in makes? or the ideas of which a given judgement is composed? In my
a certain way. But as I cannot go into this here, please consider it un- view, locating things in different places in order to distinguish and count
said. Now from the fact that all enumeration takes place in time it does them is so far from necessary that, on the contrary, it is by recognising

162 163
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

another difference between them (in the way they affect us) that we con- in the inverse relation of their distances from the fulcrum, etc. But that
clude that they occupy different places. And if we could not count things /2 = l .4142 ... , that the volume of a sphere is exactly two-thirds of that
that aren't in space, we could never count things that are. Finally, when of the circumscribed cylinder, that in each solid there are three free axes 245
it is said that the concept of a number is only possible though an intuition of revolution, etc., we claim mainly because they follow from proposi-
in time, while on the other hand it is admitted that even the most per- tions of the first kind by arguments that others have conducted hundreds
fect understanding recognises numbers, we have a contradiction. For one of times and have found valid; an additional factor is that in all these
cannot recognise a concept without having it. But according to the above, matters we do not have the slightest advantage if the thing turns out to
one would have to have intuitions, and thus sensibility, in order to have be otherwise. That the reason for our confidence really lies in these cir-
the concept of number. The addition that God recognises numbers only cumstances can be seen most clearly from the fact that our confidence
as predicates of our understanding alters nothing-it is enough that He rises and falls as these circumstances dictate. If we have not tested the
recognise them. It is also quite incorrect to say that a concept is a predi- truth of a proposition either by experiment, or by repeated checking of its
cate of the understanding. This can be said at most of the appearance or derivation, we do not give it unqualified assent, if we are at all sensible,
grasping of the concept by the mind, not of the concept itself. no matter what Critical Philosophy may say about the infallibility of pure
4) KANT thought that he could sufficiently explain, from his theo- intuition which is supposed to ground these judgements. Does not experi-
ries, why the four sciences logic, arithmetic, geometry and pure physics ence in fact teach us that we make mistakes in mathematical judgements,
244 are in the undisputed possession of generally acknowledged truths, the and that we make these mistakes more easily the more we trust what that
reason for this being that in the case of merely analytic propositions, as philosophy calls by the pompous name of pure intuition? The geometri-
they are found in logic, as well as with propositions which can be tested cian responsible for the claims in Euclid's Elements that the two halves
by intuition, e1rnrs cannot easily creep in or maintain themselves. - I into which a parallelepiped is divided by a diagonal plane are congruent,
do not wish to deny that the indicated sciences have a marked advan- or that a pair of solids have the same volume if they are bounded by sim-
tage over others in the reliability of their doctrines. But nobody who ilar and equal sides made such a gross mistake certainly only because he
has accepted even the larger part of the foregoing arguments can hold trusted his intuition, i.e., mere appearance, too much. And why is it that
that the reasons for this are to be found in the circumstances cited by in mathematics one also finds long disputes over certain subjects, e.g., the
KANT. Indeed, I see no reason why we should forsake the explanation measure of vis viva, the ratio of force to resistance with wedges, the dis-
which was given long before him. It has always been maintained that tribution of pressure over several points, etc., which are still unresolved?
these sciences enjoy such a high degree of certainty only because they Certainly only because these are theses which cannot be tested by any
have the advantage that their most important doctrines can be easily and appropriate experiment, or at least for which no experiment has yet been
variously tested by experience, and have been so tested, and that those performed. And what happens when passions become involved? When
doctrines which cannot be immediately tested are deducible by means someone undertakes to solve a problem that has occupied the greatest 246
of inferences which have been tested many times and have always been thinkers for centuries, when he imagines that he has found the solution?
found valid, and finally, that the results obtained in these sciences do not How blind he then becomes despite all his intuition, as the history of
infringe upon human passions; hence most of these investigations were mathematics bears witness with the theory of parallels, the quadrature of
begun and finished without bias, and with suitable leisure and peace. The the circle, etc.
only reason why we are so certain that the rules Barbara, Celarent, etc., 5) KANT' s most objectionable teaching is doubtless that we cannot
are valid is because they have been confirmed in thousands of arguments make any synthetic judgement about objects that we cannot perceive, so
in which we have applied them. This also is the true reason why we are so that we can make synthetic judgements neither about God, nor about our
confident, in mathematics, that factors in a different order give the same own soul, its immortality, about freedom or other super-sensible objects.
product, or that the sum of the angles in a triangle is equal to two right But it is clear from the foregoing that this bleak conclusion is anything but
angles, or that the forces on a lever are in equilibrium when they stand proven. For if the claims examined in the previous subsections are as un-

164 165
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

proven and false as I believe to have shown, then the premises supporting tion that no synthetic judgement may be made about supersensible object 248
it disappear. I will add here that it seems to me that the Critical Philos- is itself a synthetic judgement about them.
ophy has incorrectly described the distinction which is supposed to hold 6) Since it is precisely of the existence and attributes of these super-
between sensible and supersensible objects. If we do not wish to depart sensible things that metaphysics is supposed to instruct us, the Critical
from customary usage unless necessary, then by sensible or perceptible Philosophy declares that a science worthy of this name neither exists nor
objects we must understand all those which are so constituted that un- can exist. The fate of this science so far is repeatedly called upon to con-
der certain circumstances they can through their action on the organs of firm this claim; for not a single thesis can be found upon which all agree.
our body produce perceptions (outer intuitions) in us. On this definition, I admit that metaphysics up to the present day cannot come close to re-
some objects we never perceive still count as perceptible; it suffices that joicing in the brilliant progress seen in other sciences, in particular, math-
they be constituted as they must be in order to be perceived. It can be ematics. Yet it is too much to say that it does not even contain a single
shown that such objects are always bodies, i.e., collections of an infi- settled thesis. Consider the propositions that there is a Goel, that this Goel
nite number of simple, finite substances which are capable of change, in is inalterable, omniscient, omnipotent, holy, etc., that all substances in
such a way that their collection at any moment fills a certain finite three- the universe are in continual interaction, that no simple substance ceases
dimensional space (§304.4). If one now calls any actual object that is not to be, that ideas may only be present in simple substances: should not
247 sensible a supersensible object, then the individual substances of which these be looked upon as settled theses? It is admittedly true that each of
these bodies or sensible objects are composed must be counted among these propositions is contested by some individual philosophers. But this
the supersensible objects. But then we cannot say of them that they are does not justify calling them doubtful; for in just the same way there is
neither in space nor in time; on the contrary, they are in both, although no truth of mathematics that has not been contested by individual philoso-
it is true that a single one of them occupies only a single point in space. phers, e.g., the sceptics. And here it is relevant that metaphysical truths by
In particular, we would have to also look upon the thinking substance their nature provide a much stronger temptation to contradict them; that
within us, the soul, as supersensible, even though we must place it both their truth cannot be confirmed by experiences and experiment as many
in time and in space-the former because it changes and causes changes, mathematical truths can; and because the various consequences which
the latter because there must be a reason why at a given time it alters or stem from them conflict with the sensuous appetites of men. But perhaps
is altered by this or that neighbouring substance. Further reflection also it is not so much that people have disputed the truth of these theses as
makes it probable that not only some, but all simple substances are en- that they have been unable to agree on their correct grounds. Whatever 249
dowed with the power of representation, though in differing degrees, so one adduces as the ground, the other rejects as untenable, which led K.
that the differences between so-called lifeless matter, plants, and animals to remark that no sure step had been taken in metaphysics. Here it must
are differences of degree. Only one single substance, that which contains be noted that it is a special indicator of the truth of a judgement when,
the ground of the existence of all finite substances, i.e., the unconditioned despite the lack of unity concerning its ground, the proposition itself is
substance of the divinity, is distinguished from all others not only by de- not doubted. For does this not show that its truth must be almost undeni-
gree but by its complete perfection. We may say of this divine substance ably obvious to us, if despite all the trouble we have indicating its ground,
that it is neither in space nor time insofar as it undergoes no change; but we are not led astray concerning the proposition itself? Our inability to
insofar as it is the cause of everything in every place and at every time, indicate the grounds of these propositions admittedly stems from a great
we may say just as correctly that it is in all times and places. From these imperfection in our scientific presentations of metaphysical truths, and
views, which I can only point to here, it follows even more obviously how insofar as some of these theses belong among the first propositions in
incorrect the procedure of the Critical Philosophy is, when it denies us the system, one may even say that we still lack the first grounds of this
knowledge of every supersensible thing, including our soul. Many, by the science. But it does not follow that our reason lacks the ability to form
way, most recently GESSNER (Spec. u. Traum, I, Vorr., xxi), have recog- secure judgements about the objects of metaphysics. Indeed, closer con-
nised that this Kantian doctrine is self-contradictory, in that the proposi- sideration shows that the case is the same with all sciences. We may say

166 167
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

of all of them, even those whose perfection we usually pride ourselves general, then there must also be infinite sequences in time, indeed in both
on, that they are still defective in their first grounds. Does not a precise temporal directions, into the future as well as into the past. And KANT
definition of the object of a science belong to its first grounds? But how himself did not find anything objectionable in the possibility of an infinite
few treatises of geometry have even attempted to define the concept of sequence into the future; he should therefore also have admitted the pos-
space. And do things stand any better with the concepts of a line, surface sibility of such a sequence into the past, i.e., the possibility of an already
or solid, etc.? The notorious axiom of parallels, finally, is at least as great past infinite sequence, since both directions in time are completely simi-
a problem for geometry as the existence of God is for metaphysics, if the lar to each other. (b) The proof of the proposition that the world must also
latter were simply presented as an axiom requiring no proof. In general, it be limited in space is supported by the preceding proof. KANT says "in
seems to me that we proceed in these sciences according to quite different order to think a world that fills all spaces as a single whole the successive
logical strictures, which are in both cases faulty. One of these sciences, synthesis of parts of an infinite world must be considered as completed,
mathematics (perhaps out of gratitude for the magnificent things it has i.e., an infinite time must be thought to have passed in counting all exist-
250 taught us), we hold to be above any violation of the rules of logic, so ing things, which is impossible." We have already seen that this impossi-
much so that we don't even strive to improve it. In metaphysics, by con- bility is a sheer invention. An additional error is that a world consisting
trast, we not only demand (as is proper) that it seek the genuine ground of infinitely many parts can only be thought by means of a successive
of the truth of each of its theses, we also forbid any use of a proposition, synthesis of parts, while we already think such a world when we simply
no matter how certain, so long as it has not been properly grounded. How speak about it. (c) In the second antinomy I take the thesis "every com-
far would we have got in mathematics even today if we had demanded pound substance in the world consists of simple parts, and nothing exists
the same of it? except the simple or what is compounded from the simple" to be true,
7) The most remarkable fact is that KANT, not satisfied with denying only with the proviso that there must be infinitely many simple parts of
the ability of human reason to judge super-sensible objects, went on to which compound objects consist. I find the proof of the antithesis, or the
say that in the domain of metaphysics there are four pairs of contradic- proposition that no compound thing in the world consists of simple parts
tory propositions (antinomies), each of which can be proved with reasons to be completely untenable. This proof proceeds from the claim that space
that do not violate any of the rules of logic. In the Critique of Pure Rea- does not consist of simple parts, but of spaces, i.e., of manifolds which are
son (A426/B454 ff.) these eight propositions are given with their alleged external to each other. This has frequently been said by mathematicians
proofs. I believe that I have found several mistakes in these proofs, but and is indeed true if taken in a certain sense, but if it is taken in another
to avoid prolixity will merely indicate some of them: (a) The proof of sense, the one required for KANT' s proof, it is false. In compound things 252
the proposition that the world has a beginning in time is based upon the we can often distinguish two kinds of parts, namely, homogeneous parts,
claim that an infinite past sequence is a contradiction; the reason for this i.e., parts which stand under the same concept as the whole, and hetero-
is that the infinity of a sequence is said to consist in the fact that it can geneous parts for which this is not the case. Thus we show that a piece
never be completed through a successive synthesis. This I believe to be of saltpetre has homogeneous parts, if we break it into pieces which are
quite false, for the infinity of a sequence does not consist in the fact that themselves pieces of saltpetre; heterogeneous parts appear when we show
it cannot be completed through a successive synthesis (i.e., through a that saltpetre consists of hydrochloric acid and potash. And if we want
synthesis which is carried out gradually in time). The concept of time to speak merely of homogeneous parts, then it is quite correct to say that
does not belong to the concept of an infinite sequence at all, since there every extended space consists only of other extended spaces, every line
are sequences of things, finite as well as infinite, which are not in time only of lines, etc. But if we want to speak of parts in general, so that het-
at all. One is the infinite sequence of natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5,. .. , erogeneous parts are also included, then we should not hesitate to admit
or the following: ... , -5, -4, -3, -2, -1,0, + 1, +2, +3, +4, +5, ... , the that every extended space, whether line, surface, or solid, also consists of
first of which goes to infinity only in one direction, the second in both di- simple parts, namely, points; it is nothing but a certain collection of such
251 rections. But if there are infinite sequences of numbers, and quantities in points. To make this clear I note, firstly, that it is a generally accepted

168 169
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

doctrine that in every line, surface, or solid there are, or as they say, there der the same circumstances it could have refrained from doing so. In
lie points. But what can this being or lying of points in a spatial object this sense of the word it can indeed be said that every free resolution of
be, if not that they arc parts of these objects? It will be objected that these the will absolutely starts a sequence of consequences; one cannot claim
parts are not integral parts, since it is impossible to produce a solid out of the converse, however, i.e., that freedom is present whenever a sequence
a number of points, no matter how large. I freely admit this if this num- of consequences absolutely begins. A sequence of consequences begins
ber is finite; I also admit that not every infinite number of points forms an absolutely whenever an uncaused cause acts. God is such a cause, yet
extended object. But as soon as we think of a collection of points of such we certainly cannot attribute freedom in the sense of indeterminacy to
a nature that for every one of them, and for every distance, no matter how Him. (e) In the proof of the thesis it is said that when everything occurs
small, there are one or several points in the collection which lie at this merely according to laws of nature (i.e., that everything which happens
distance from the given point, then we have a true continuum (which will has a cause, which is itself something that happens), there can be no com-
253 be either a line, a surface, or a solid). Thus we think a surface of a sphere pleteness of the sequence on the side of the causes. But it only follows
if we think the collection of all points which are equidistant from a given from this assumption that the sequence of things which have happened
point. That there is nothing in this spherical smface but this infinite set of must be infinite; it by no means follows that it cannot be complete, and
points, which is represented by the concept of the totality of points which hence cannot actually exist. For infinite sequences can exist, and even
have the same distance from a given point, follows from the fact that it already have passed by, as I noted in (a) above. Moreover, if an infinite
is quite impossible to indicate anything that belongs to the surface of this sequence is actually a mere sequence of causes in the strictest sense, it is
sphere which is not such a point or a collection of such points. Thus if simultaneous with its effect. When, however, its terms are looked upon
one has parts in general in mind, and not just parts of a certain kind (ho- not as causes but rather as conditions, each of the next, then it is not even
mogeneous parts), it is false to claim that space does not consist of (an necessary that an infinite time is required to run through them all. Every
infinite multitude of) simple parts. (cl) In the third antinomy the expres- motion a body makes over even the smallest path, provides an example of
sion of the propositions which are supposed to contradict one another is a sequence of infinitely many terms, each of which is a condition for the
already obscure. "Causality according to laws of nature," the thesis reads, next one, and which must be passed through before it, even though the
"is not the only one from which all the phenomena of the world can be duration required to run through them all may be very short (§87). (f) In
derived. In order to explain all of these, one must also suppose that there the fourth antinomy, the thesis reads: "Something belongs to the world,
is a causality through freedom." And the antithesis: "There is no free- either as one of its parts or as its cause, which is an absolutely necessary
dom, rather everything in the world occurs entirely according to laws of being." Only from the proof does one gather how "to belong to the world"
nature." In the proof of the latter, freedom is defined as "a capacity of must be understood, namely, that this necessary being is supposed "either 255
absolutely starting a state, and hence a sequence of consequences, i.e., to be the entire series of the world's changes, or else a part of it." How
where nothing happens which would determine this action according to odd this is! And the proof is: "For the beginning of a time-sequence can
enduring laws." Here it is striking in the first place that such an ability only be determined by something preceding it in time. Thus the highest
is called a causality, given that this word means a causal relation which condition of the beginning of a sequence of changes in time must exist
does not obtain in this case. It is also assumed that every cause must pre- when these did not yet exist. Thus this cause belongs to a time, and thus
cede its effect in time, which is incorrect, in that the cause must instead be to appearance; and hence it cannot be thought in isolation from the sen-
simultaneous with its true effect. Even more important is the fact that this sible world as the collection of all appearances." Here, it seems to me,
definition describes something quite different from what common usage it is assumed without warrant that the sequence of the world's changes
means by freedom. For this is always taken to mean a certain attribute of must have had a beginning in time if it is grounded in something. Can
the will, and if we adopt the concept which comes closest to the above we not equally well, indeed must we not, assume that the substances of
254 definition (that of indeterminacy), freedom would be the possibility of a the world exist at all times, yet do so only through the activity of the
will forming a resolution which has no determining ground, so that un- substance whose existence is unconditioned? It also seems to me hasty

170 171
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 315. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

to conclude that a substance which acts in time must itself belong to ap- the highest good if the existence of God, freedom and immortality are
pearance and hence to the sensible world. We only count objects which already proved. Hence these three truths cannot be deduced from that 257
can bring about perception in us as belonging to the sensible world (no. postulate; on the contrary, the postulate can be proved only if these three
5), and these are never the simple substances themselves, but rather only truths are presupposed.
infinite collections of them. Thus we cannot even call individual finite Note. It was to be foreseen that a doctrine which so forcefully limited
substances appearances or sensible objects; still less the simple substance the natural human drive to have knowledge of supersensible things would
which is their cause. And although these simple substances, e.g., our not last long. Even the truest adherents KANT has today, KRUG and
soul, are supersensible objects, they nevertheless act in time; and hence FRIES, have tempered his views somewhat. The latter not only admits, as
God may also act in time without thereby becoming a sensible object. KANT wanted, a practical belief, but also a speculative one, a presenti-
8) It stands to the credit of this philosopher's moral character that he ment, and if not theory then at least knowledge through Icleas, knowledge
attempted to compensate for the damage caused by setting limits to our which has the peculiarity of being deduced from ine.ffable premises (and
cognitive faculties (in denying us any knowledge of supersensible ob- hence cannot be demonstrated). Almost all of the philosophers in Ger-
jects) in claiming that in the concept of obligation which we find in our many go still further; only-and this is the sad thing in this affair-not
256 consciousness there lies a completely sufficient ground for holding the a one of them who makes use of our common right to make judgements
existence of Goel, our freedom and immortality to be practically true, and about supersensible things goes to work in this difficult area with the
this with a certainty capable of withstanding any knowledge based upon greatest possible care, taking care not to set out anything as true until
theoretical grounds. Practical reason (he says) unconditionally requires the most precise examination has shown that and why one must accept it
the realisation of the highest good in us, which consists in holiness and as such. Instead, they either expressly say or else their behaviour shows
the happiness which corresponds to it; thus this must be possible. But clearly enough that if they do not incline towards Kantianism in anything
if we were not free and immortal, and if there were no God, this highest else, they at least agree with KANT in the claim which would liberate
good could not come to be. As certainly, then, as we are conscious of every philosopher from the obligation of providing rigorous proofs as
these requirements of our reason, just as certainly must we believe that well as precise definitions in his science. They do this with a quite tran-
we are free and immortal, and that there is a Goel. I must admit that I do quil conscience, since almost all of them are convinced that they possess
not find the method of "practical postulation" very satisfactory. I think their own special faculty for immediately recognising the entirety of the
we can speak of a duty, or a necessity, of believing something only where truths which they set out, each in his own system. Reason, testimony,
there are decisive grounds for the truth of the respective proposition. If presentiment, feeling, faith, revelation, inner experience, consciousness,
there are no such grounds for our freedom and immortality, or for the the deepest and most inner unconscious, intuition (rational, intellectual,
existence of Goel, then nobody has the duty, nor is it even possible, to transcendental, and ideal), absolute intuition, knowledge, unconditioned
believe in these objects. It seems to me a perverse procedure to deduce, knowledge are just some of the many names given to this faculty or the
as KANT did, from a postulate of reason the possibility of its satisfac- knowledge grounded in it. Now not much, I admit, is riding on names. 258
tion. Strictly speaking, reason never demands anything unconditionally, Nor, as you know, do I deny that we know certain purely conceptual truths
but only if a being exists which has the power to do a good thing, then immediately. But I cannot admit that truths as complex as those stating
reason demands of this being that it should bring about this good. For ex- the existence of Goel, or that we are free, or that our soul is immortal, can
ample, reason does not demand unconditionally that a sick person should be known immediately. And it is inexcusable to claim that a judgement is
be healed; it only demands from a physician, and from nobody else that, immediate without having first shown that it can in no way be mediated.
if he is present, and if he can heal the sick person, then he should do so.
Hence if, as K. claimed, the realisation of the highest good is possible
only if there is a God and if we are free and immortal, then it follows
that we are justified in claiming that reason demands the realisation of

172 173
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 316. Of the Relation between our Judgements and Truth

§.316.* knowledge [Wissen] or scientific cognitions; the latter may be called or-
dinary cognitions. Instead of using the word "knowledge" in this sense,
Sun'ey of the most important distinctions between ·t miaht be more correct to speak of comprehension or insight; one could 260
1 b .
judgements, based on their relation to truth say of cognitions of this sort that one comprehends them, and the cogm-
tions themselves could be called insights or distinct insights. .
1) If we consider only the relation a given judgement bears to truth,
Note I. The concept I designated in no. 3 by the word sense 1s so
we obtain the known classification of judgements into true and false, the
important for logic and many other sciences as to be indispen~able. Al-
former also counting as cognitions (§307).
though the word I have chosen is multiply ambiguous, I know of no better.
2) Given that most, though not all, of our judgements are mediated
For not only has it often been used with this meaning, it is also fortunately
by others, one may also ask about the relation that the mediating judge-
the case that its other meanings are either easily distinguished from the
ments bear to truth. If these are true, one may call the judgement derived
context, or else it is fair to ask that one refrain from using them. Thus
from them a judgement based upon true or correct grounds, where the
the meaning the word has when it designates ideas conveyed to us by ~er-
word ground is taken in the sense of §313, i.e., we refer not to the objec-
tain sensory organs, is so easily distinguished from the above meanmg
tive ground of a truth, but rather to an individual truth or a collect~on of
that there is no worry of the two being confused. The same holds for the
truths the consideration of which mediates a judgement. If not all of these
meaning in which one speaks of sensing pleasure or pain, etc. My defi-
judgements are true, we speak of a judgement based on false or incorrect
nition has the peculiarity that only cognitions which we gain mediately,
grounds. According to §309, not all judgements based on true grounds
by means of inferences (though we are not conscious of them) are said to
need be true. For if in the derivation of a given judgement we have not
be sensed. Moreover, I think that a great many judgements which others
only used perfect inferences, but have called upon the aid of probabilistic
consider to be immediate are really mediated; and in general I consider it
259 inferences as well, it is not completely certain, but only probable, and
to be incorrect and harmful to the aims of science to declare a judgement
hence may be mistaken. But just as a judgement based on true grounds
to be immediate without having shown that it can in no case be mediated.
need not be true, so too a judgement based on false grounds need not be
The problem with using the word knowledge [Wissen] in the sense of no.
false. For false premises sometimes lead to true conclusions, in cases of
4 is not only that I wish to retain it for another concept (§321), but also
both probabilistic and strict inferences.
that knowledge [Wissen] reminds one too much of certainty [Gew@heit],
3) Understandably, the distinction between judgements already men-
i.e., of a very high degree of confidence. In no. 4, however, it is a matter
tioned in §306 no. 10, based upon whether we are aware of the grounds
of a different kind of cognition, whose peculiarity lies not in the degree
we have for forming a judgement, also applies to true judgements. But
of its certainty, but in something else altogether. For even though it usu-
here it is very noteworthy. And one usually calls the ability to form a cor-
ally happens that the recognition of the grounds of a truth makes us more
rect judgement or (what amounts to the same) to recognise truth without
certain of the truth itself, yet the degree of certainty with such truths is
recognising the grounds from which one recognises it, a sense [Gefiihl]
not always as high as one imagines when one hears us say We knmv that!
for the truth; and one says of truth recognised in this way that one senses
Incidentally, this sense of the word (Scire, sn:kn:cxavw) has earned pride 261
it. If, on the contrary, one is also aware of the grounds from which one
of place in the older treatises. The Greeks, e.g., ARISTOTLE (An. Post., I,
has formed a true judgement, one says that he has a distinct cognition.
2) only wanted us to say that someone knew something if he recognised
4) Another important difference obtains between our true judgements
its ground. And the same definition is given by WOLFF (L., §594), the
or cognitions depending upon whether its genuine, i.e., objective, ground
Ars cogit., REUSCH, and others. From this stemmed the difficulty that we
is known to us or not. Cognitions for which we also know whether the
could never say that someone knew a truth which had no further ground
truth that constitutes their content rests upon a further ground, and what
of its truth. This difficulty can be addressed with the small alteration
this ground is, differ essentially from those for which this is not the case,
of this definition I suggested above. Less consistently than ARISTOTLE,
i.e., those such that we do not know whether they have a further ground
KANT (L., Ak., 9.70; K. d. 1: V., A822/B850) defined knowledge as hold-
of their truth, or what this is. Cognitions of the first sort are usually called

174 175
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 316.

ing something to be true based on grounds which are both objectively PART IV
and subjectively sufficient, and then went on to classify knowledge as
either mediate or immediate. Others, by contrast, either for the reason
Of Certainty, Probability, and
already adduced by ARISTOTLE, or for some other (e.g., BOUTERWECK
Confidence in Judgements
Leh rb. d. ph. W, I, p. 50), believe that there is a contradiction in the con~
§.317.
cept of immediate knowledge. For my part, the only things I disapprove
of in this use of the word are those mentioned above. But given that the Definition ()f the concepts of certainty and probability
word science [Wissenschcift] often (it seems to me) no longer suggests the with respect to thinking beings
misleading associated concept of certainty [Gewissheit], I prefer to use
1) The relation between our judgements and truth has been sufficiently
the expression scient(fic cognition rather than "knowledge" in the above
discussed, and it is now necessary to consider their certainty or probabil-
sense.
ity and the degree of confidence which depends upon them. If the theory
Note 2. Although it is incumbent upon synonymies rather than logic
concerning the origin of error maintained in §309 is correct, then we can
to point out the differences which the German language makes between
the various words kennen [to be acquainted with], erkennen [to recog- say of every fallible thinking being that it commits errors only for the
following reason: it takes propositions to be true which stand in a real
nise], anerkennen [to recognise the character of], begreifen [to compre-
or fancied relation of probability (cf. § 161) to certain other propositions,
hend], einsehen [to realise], verstehen [to understand], and the like, I will
which this being, rightly or wrongly, assumes to be true. In the case of
nevertheless give a brief account of them. It seems to me that we say
judgements that are not mediated, likewise with judgements that follow
we are acquainted with an object when we are in a position to make as
from immediate judgements by non-probabilistic arguments in the sense
many true judgements concerning it as generally seem humanly possible
of §253, no error can occur; all such judgements are true.
and useful with objects of this sort. To recognise an object means to form
2) Consequently, judgements generated in a way that makes error im-
the true judgement that it is the same as the object we elsewhere thought
possible are, for this reason, called certain, or secure. Thus, certainty
under certain other ideas. To recognise the character of an object as an
in this sense must be distinguished from the concept defined in § 161, 264
A means to form a true judgement that it stands under the idea A. In
no. 3. The latter is merely a relation which holds between propositions,
262 my opinion we only say that we comprehend or realise something when
where one of them is deducible from the others, and where it is a matter
we wish to point out that we have some knowledge of the reason (the
of indifference whether these propositions are in themselves true or false
genuine, objective ground) why it is so. We usually say we realise some-
or whether there is a thinking being who takes them to be true or even
thing when this knowledge of the ground involves a good deal of our own
thinks them. Certainty in the present sense is a property which belongs
mental activity, while comprehending something can also be used when it
only to judgements, and belongs to them only in relation to a thinkinab be-
was principally the efforts of others which brought us knowledge of this .
mg who presently forms them, provided that they are generated in a way
ground. To understand, finally, is almost always used for the recognition
that makes error impossible. The context will make clear in which sense
263 of the intentions, especially the meanings, we connect with signs.
the word "certainty" is taken in a given case; if it does not, I will add the
phrase, "for a certain thinking being". It follows from this explication
that a proposition which has certainty for a being must be considered true
by that being, or (what comes to the same thing) is one of its judgements.
This is also in conformity with common usage; it would be strange if
we wanted to call a proposition certain for a person even if he does not
:ake it to be true, perhaps only because he could be easily convinced of
it. Furthermore only propositions which are true in themselves can be
called certain with respect to a thinking being; for the judgement which

176 177
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 317. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

contains this proposition must come about in a way that makes error im- certain thinking being, and only if that being accepts as true the propo-
possible, hence it must be true. Since true judgements are also called cog- sitions relative to which that proposition has probability. Hence, if we
nitions, propositions which are certain can all be called cognitions. One say that a proposition M has probability for a certain being with respect
and the same proposition will have to be considered sometimes certain, to assumptions A, B, C, D, ... and ideas i, j, ... , then propositions A,
sometimes not, depending on the being to which it is related. Thus, for B. C, D, ... must be considered true by that being, and proposition M
God everything which is true is certain, since He recognises all truth and must stand to A, B, C, D, ... in the relation of probability (cf. § 161) with
recognises it without possibility of error. With men, the class of certain respect to ideas i, j, .... But this definition does not require that the being
265 propositions is restricted to truths that are recognised without mediation should also take proposition M itself for true, nor does this seem to be
(no. l), or that follow from immediate judgements by a non-probabilistic required by common usage. Could it not be the case, for example, that
deduction. there is a proposition which follows with probability from certain other
3) On the other hand, propositions about which we may be mistaken propositions accepted by somebody, although he does not know this be-
are, according to no. 1, only those that stand in a real or fancied relation cause he is not paying attention to the matter? It would seem reasonable,
of probability (cf. § 161) to other propositions that have already been ac- in this case, to call this proposition probable for him (though he is not
cepted as true by the being in question. Hence only the following cases conscious of this fact). The composition of the word "Wahrscheinlich"
can arise: (a) the premises A, B, C, D, ... , which are taken to be true by [probable], especially the suffix, does not indicate an actual holding to
the being are indeed true and, proposition M stands to them in the relation be true or appearance, but rather the possibility of these. It follows from
of probability (cf. § 161 ); or (b) the propositions A, B, C, D, ... are true, this that probability in this sense can be divided into recognised and un-
but the proposition M does not really stand in the relation of probabil- recognised. Concerning proposition M itself, it is not necessary that a
ity with respect to them, but the being mistakenly thinks that it does; or thinking being must accept M even if it is aware of the relation of prob- 267
(c) the premises A, B, C, D, ... are not all true but a real relation of prob- ability which holds between M and the accepted propositions A, B, C,
ability obtains between M and them; or, finally, (cl) the propositions A, B, D, ... ; this, indeed, never happens if the recognised probability of the
C, D, ... are not all true nor is there a real relation of probability between 1,
proposition is < since in this case it will incline toward the judgement
Mand them. A moment's thought shows that cases (b) and (d) can be re- Neg.M. Hence we must distinguish probable propositions which are held
duced to (c ). Since reason never ens in the judgement that a proposition to be true and others which are not. The assumptions A, B, C, D, ...
is deducible from certain other propositions, except by introducing a rule which are accepted by the thinking being, and to which M stands in a
R according to which this deduction is to proceed, we can always add this real relation of probability are either all true or some of them are false.
erroneous rule R to the propositions A, B, C, D, ... which are accepted as In the first case the probability of M can be called actual or objective,
premises by the being. But then the premises A, B, C, D, ... and R stand in the second a merely apparent or subjective probability. In the case
not only in an imagined, but in a real, relation of probability. Hence we where the probability of M with respect to A, B, C, D, ... is objective
can say that enor arises only if a being accepts as true propositions stand- for a certain being, i.e., if the propositions A, B, C, D, ... are all truths,
ing in the relation of probability to certain other propositions that it has they are occasionally called grounds of that probability, sometimes even
already accepted as true. It is very important to draw attention to these the grounds (though not sufficient grounds) of proposition M itself. Ac-
266 propositions, and to give them a name; let us call them propositions which cording to the sense of the word ground given in § 198, we could only
have probability for this being. Hence we must distinguish probability in say of these propositions that, taken together, they are not the ground of
this sense of the word from probability as it was defined in § 161. There M itself, but the ground of the proposition which states its probability
we meant by probability a relation which holds between propositions as for that being. If we call them grounds in the plural, then these must be
such, no matter whether they are in themselves true or false or whether looked upon as partial grounds; while if they are said to be grounds of
somebody takes them to be true or false. Here, on the other hand, prob- the proposition M itself, this must mean the mere cause of holding M
ability is an attribute which a proposition can have only in relation to a to be true or grounds of recognition in the sense of §313. Consider all

178 179
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 317. Of Certainty, Probubility and Confidence in Judgements

propositions which are accepted by a thinking being and which stand in this harm and the degree of probability of Neg.Mis the magnitude of the
the relation of probability (§161) to a given proposition M; the probabil- risk to which we are subject when we do not prepare for N eg.M. What
ity which accrues to M only on the basis of part of this collection is called makes it foolish or illicit then, to prepare for or consider the opposite of
a relative probability of M for that being; while that which accrues to M a given proposition M is that the clanger in neglecting Neg .M is smaller
268 on the basis of all of these propositions is called the complete or abso- than the danger in neglecting M. Hence, whether or not a proposition is
lute probability of M for this being. Thus, for example, the probability morally certain depends on the magnitude of harm that would result if
of the proposition that the earth turns around its axis merely on the basis its opposite came about and we were unprepared for it, and on other cir-
that such revolutions are found in several other heavenly bodies is only a cumstances as well. Thus, the probability that somebody who is in good
relative probability of this proposition; on the other hand, the probability health will not live to see the next clay is small enough to be neglected
which accrues to it from the consideration of all circumstances known to in connection with business that would not greatly suffer from his death; 270
me which speak for or against such revolutions, is the absolute proba- hence his survival for one clay is credible; but where great disadvantages
bility which this proposition has for me. We can see from § 161, no. 18 accrue, it is certainly one's duty to think of the possibility of sudden death,
that the absolute probability of a proposition does not always have to be and make appropriate preparations; hence in this respect it is not certain
larger than every relative probability. For, among the totality of proposi- enough that he will live to see the following clay, etc.
tions which are accepted by somebody as true, there may be some which, Note 1. In defining the concept of certainty I wanted to follow com-
taken in themselves, give a probability < ~ to it; such propositions will mon usage exactly. This is why I limited it to propositions which some-
diminish the degree of probability that accrue to it from other consider- one in fact holds to be true, though the similarity between the certain and
ations. Thus the probability with which a doctor expects the death of a the probable might have permitted a generalisation. WOLFF (L., §564)
patient based upon the symptoms he observed in him a few days ago will gave the definition: Si cognoscimus, propositionem esse veram vel fal-
lessen considerably when he considers the other circumstances, e.g., that sam, propositio nob is dicitur esse certa; 1 and MAAB writes (L., §328):
he has not yet received word of his death. If the absolute probability of a "A judgement is certain insofar as one is aware of its truth." It seems to
proposition for a certain being is very large and if there are circumstances me that in these definitions the entire concept of certainty occurs unanal-
which make it foolish or illicit to consider the possibility of the opposite ysed in the words "cognoscere", "to be aware of", etc. Others, like FRIES
and to act on it, then I call these propositions trustworthy, secure, reliable (L., §95), say that a judgement is certain if it has sufficient grounds. By
for that being. In ordinary life these propositions are often called certain, these, obviously, mere grounds ofrecognition (§313) are meant; but there
but in science they are merely called morally or sufficiently certain in con- are also immediate judgements, which are completely certain because of
trast to proper certainty (no. 2). Hence I call it a trustworthy proposition their immediacy, and one cannot say that they are recognised from suffi-
269 that the ceiling of this room will not collapse. This calamity, though I do cient grounds. KANT (L., p. 90) and several others defined certainty as
not find it impossible, has such a low degree of absolute probability that a belief [Fiirwahrhalten] which is connected with a consciousness of ne-
it would be foolish to consider it in my actions and, for example, leave cessity. Presumably the necessity under discussion consists in a certain
the room, since the clanger of an accident if I remain here is not larger relation to the judging person, i.e., a judgement is certain whenever the
than the clangers encountered when I leave it and spend the night outside. judging person feels that his judgement could not be otherwise and that he
Hence trustworthiness has several degrees; and one and the same degree is compelled to judge in this way; against this I should like to call to mind
of absolute probability, which makes one proposition trustworthy for a that all judging is in a certain sense necessary: it is not our arbitrary de-
given being, may be too low for another proposition. For it is not the low cision to form a judgement in this or in some other way; on the contrary,
degree of probability alone which makes it foolish or illicit to think of the after we have directed our attention to certain objects, we feel compelled
possible opposite of proposition M and to prepare for it, but certain other in each of our judgements. If I am told that out of a hundred balls most
circumstances also play a role. Consider the harm which would arise if
1
the opposite of M were true and we did not prepare for it. The product of If we know that a proposition is true or false, then the proposition is said to be certain
for us.

180 181
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 317. Of Certainty, Probabi{i(Y and Confidence in Judgements

are black and only a few are white, and I see somebody choosing one relation to a subject. I wish to reply that my distinction between these
at random, I cannot decide to expect that a black ball will be drawn; I two kinds of probability depends upon the kind of premises this thinking
271 am compelled to expect this although I know that it could be mistaken being accepts as true. If they are objectively true, then the probability can
and that a white ball could be drawn. On the other hand, if the notion also be called objective; if they are in themselves false, but are taken to
of necessity is related to the proposition itself which is the content of the be true by the subject, then we ought to call the probability subjective.
judgement, I must reply that necessity in the proper sense of the word is In HOFFBAUER'S Logik, (§419), we read: "When the lack of certainty
an attribute which belongs only to actual things, but not to objects that do presupposed by a determinate probability is necessary on account of the
not have actuality, for example propositions. In an improper sense one limitations of human knowledge, and the grounds upon which the prob-
may attribute necessity to a certain kind of proposition, namely, those ability rests can be recognised by everyone, the probability is objective;
that express purely conceptual truths; but the class of certain propositions otherwise it is subjective." The definition of CRUSIUS is almost exactly
comprises more than these; it also includes so-called empirical truths, and the same (W z.. G., §369). It seems to me that these definitions are some-
KANT himself accordingly distinguishes rational and empirical certainty. what unsteady, and not very useful. For who will deny that the limits of
Note 2. Everyone will see for himself that the concept of probability human knowledge expand from time to time and that consequently much
for a given thinking being as set out in no. 3 is far closer to the sense in that now seems probable to us may cease to be at another time, or that the
which this word is most often taken in ordinary life than that described in degree of its probability may change? But when HOFFBAUER (note 2)
§161; yet I intentionally departed from common usage in the following adduces games of chance as examples of objective probability, with the
respect. According to my definition, a proposition M is said to be proba- remark that "the possibility of all cases can be determined a priori, but
ble for a given thinking being if it stands in a relation of probability with nobody can give reasons why one outcome rather than another should be
respect to propositions A, B, C, D, ... which this being holds to be true, the case," I must confess that I cannot understand him. For the claim that
regardless of the degree of this probability. According to ordinary usage, the possibility of all cases can be determined a priori can only mean that
a proposition M is only called probable for this being when the probabil- we can determine a priori that each of several enumerated cases has the 273
ity that accrues to it with respect to the propositions A, B, C, D, ... turns same probability. But we can attribute this equal probability to several
out greater than ~. One will readily understand why I did not retain this cases only if we ignore all dissimilarities (e.g., that one ball is heavier
restriction. I also did not require that the thinking being with respect to than the others, etc.). If we assume that these cases are in actual fact
which we ascribe probability to a proposition hold this proposition to be equal, then not only is it impossible for any person, but even for God to
true. The reason for this is not simply that ordinary usage and syntax per- give a reason why "this rather than that outcome will be the case." Ac-
mit this, but rather because of the fact, mentioned in no. 3, that there are tually, nothing would happen, since the exact equality of circumstances
propositions which stand in a relation of probability in the sense of § 161 would give no preference to one case over all others. But this is not
to certain propositions held to be true by a thinking being, without it be- the case; rather, in each of several cases which have an equal probabil-
ing possible for this being to accept them as true (and thus to judge that ity there are certain peculiar circumstances which make it happen that
M) even if it notices this relation. Namely, when the degree of probability only one of them comes about, and which makes the occurrence of all
272 is < ~, not the proposition itself but rather the opposite will be reckoned the others impossible. Even we are capable of ascertaining, under certain
to be true, i.e., the being will judge that M is false. circumstances, some of these dissimilarities, for example that some balls
Note 3. I also found myself obliged to depart at a few points from are heavier or smoother, etc., and can then make estimates of which case
the usual concepts in my definitions of the various kinds of probability. is more likely to occur. When, as is usually the case, the difference
Some will take exception to the fact that on the one hand I connect the between relative and absolute probability is said to lie in the fact that the
concept of probability with certain thinking beings, and on the other hand former consists in the relation to another probability and the latter in the
I distinguish an objective from a subjective probability; they probably relation to certainty, it strikes me that such a distinction is not important
object because we call something objective if it can be thought without enough to merit its own designation. By contrast, I note that we often

182 183
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 318. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

need a word for the kind of probability a proposition has, not in relation it is appropriate to go into greater detail on this subject. I shall first look 275
to all circumstances, but rather in relation to those known to us, and for into the conditions upon which the nature of our confidence depends, then
this the word relative seems quite serviceable. - The concept I defined the most noteworthy levels of confidence, and finally the way degrees of
under the names of trustworthiness or moral certitude has been described confidence may be determined through calculation.
by LEIBNIZ (Nouv. Ess., IV, xi), SCHULZE (L., 107), CRUSIUS (W z. G., The question arises as to the ground of our attaching this or that de-
§361 and 410) and others in almost the same words. - The distinction gree of confidence to a given judgement. Could it be that, before forming
between sirnple and complex probability one finds, e.g., in HOFFBAUER any judgement, we weigh its precise degree of probability or full cer-
(L., §418) seems to me to be of no importance. Often mathematical prob- tainty? This could be the first thought that comes to mind here. It cannot
ability on the one hand and dynamic or philosophical probability on the be denied that this occurs sometimes, and that often before pronouncing
other are distinguished; the former is said to occur where all so-called judgement M, we first note either that M belongs to the propositions that
grounds are homogeneous and need only to be counted; the latter, where are certain for us, or else that it has such and such degree of probability,
274 this is not the case. I, too, believe that there are probabilities we can cal- which then governs the degree of confidence with which we judge. But it
culate, and others we cannot calculate, but I think that this distinction is is another thing to claim that this occurs with every judgement, i.e., that
very subjective and vacillating. What seems more important to me is the we never form a judgement M without first having noted the degree of
distinction, already touched upon in § 161, no. 8, between probabilities probability or the full certainty M has for us. This would be absurd, for
which are determined by their premises and those that are not. Perhaps it the observation that the proposition M is either fully certain or else has
was only this distinction they had in mind without being aware of it. - a determinate degree of probability is itself a judgement, whether or not
Some logicians, for example KIESEWETTER (L., I, §297) distinguish be- it is formulated in words. In order to form this second judgement with a
tween real and logical probability. The former is said to be the probability certain degree of confidence, then, we would have to have formed a third
of a thing, the latter of a judgement; the former is said to be calculable judgement fixing its degree of confidence, and so on without end. Thus
"since the reasons are envisaged as similar, the latter not, since the rea- there must be judgements for which the degree of confidence with which
sons for and against an opinion are dissimilar" (ibid., p. 468). I should we form them is in no way produced by the previous observation of their
like to reply that, strictly speaking, probability is an attribute which be- degree of probability or complete certainty. It is obvious that all imme-
longs only to propositions, hence to judgements only in so far as they are diate judgements must be counted among these. But even in the class
propositions, but which does not belong to any other object. Hence, if we of mediate judgements there must be a great many which we form with- 276
frequently use expressions such as "this event is probable", etc., all we out having previously judged the degree of probability or the complete
want to say is that the proposition stating that this event occurs is proba- certainty of a proposition. For even a judgement that fixes the degree of
ble. Just as it is improper to call an event true (at most this could mean probability or the complete certainty of a proposition is obviously me-
that the prvposition which states it is true) so too is it improper to call diated. If we wanted to claim the contrary, we would fall back into the
it probable. If this is cotTect, then the above distinction and the remarks just noted absurdity. But although it is certain that the determinate degree
made about it require no further refutation. of confidence with which we form a judgement M does not always arise
from the observed degree of probability or complete certainty the propo-
§.318.
sition M has for us, we must nevertheless admit that this degree of prob-
Factors which determine the confidence of our judgements ability or full certainty, even when it is not noticed, has an influence on
the degree of our confidence. Indeed, a little reflection shows that nothing
Although I have already defined the concept I connect with the word con-
can immediately determine the degree of our confidence in a judgement
fidence in §293, and also noted on that occasion that this confidence is
M except the following two things: (a) the degree of absolute probability
an attribute which belongs to all of our judgements (if not always in the
or complete certainty which accrues to proposition M with respect to the
same measure), it is only now, after having spoken of the difference be-
totality of judgements A, B, C, D, ... that are currently in our mind, and
tween true and false judgements and the probability of propositions, that

184 185
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 318. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

provide evidence for or against M; and (b) the degrees of confidence of ability. Their force is larger the larger the degree of their own confidence,
the ju~gements A, B, C, D, ... themselves. What besides these two things and judgement M, which is generated by them, will become stronger, i.e.,
could it be that determines the confidence of our judgement? Judgements will enjoy greater confidence the greater the force of its generators. It is
which we have formed earlier, but have forgotten, or which are not now in not surprising that all this should happen without our knowing the mag-
our mind, either clearly or obscurely, cannot act, simply because they are nitude of the forces of A, B, C, D, ... or of the strength which judgement
not there. The greater or smaller degree of attention with which we test M receives from them. This is no more surprising than the fact that we
proposition M, the strength of our wish that it should turn out true or false: bring forth thousands of other effects without being aware of the laws
such matters certainly have an influence. They determine to some extent according to which they are produced.
how our judgement turns out (whether it will be affirmative or negative)
and in particular they will also determine the degree of our confidence §.319.
in it. But it seems to me that all these circumstances act only indirectly,
277 not immediately, namely, only in so far as they stimulate judgements that
The most notevvorthy levels of our confidence
we have formed earlier, and on whose presence in the mind the degree of
No one will deny that the degree of confidence with which we form judge-
probability of proposition M depends. It is also obvious that the degree
ments is not the same in all cases. Everyone will also admit, I hope, that
of our confidence does not depend upon the relative degree of probability
judgements we form without the mediation of others never have a lower
which proposition M has in relation to a part of our judgements, but it
degree of confidence than those we deduce from them. I would like to
depends upon the degree of absolute probability of this proposition, pro-
go still further and say that the degree of confidence with which we form
vided that we mean by absolute probability the probability which accrues
immediate judgements is the same in all cases. The judgement that I just
to it with respect to all judgements currently in our mind. It is similarly
now feel a certain pain may perhaps be more vivid than the judgement that
obvious that these judgements can influence the degree of confidence of
I have the idea of a green colour, but the degree of confidence with which
judgement M only in proportion to the confidence that they themselves
we form them seems to be completely equal. Indeed we must maintain
have. But there is a twofold difficulty connected with this view. (a) Since
that they are equal if (as was claimed in the previous section) the degree
the degree of confidence with which we judge is always actual and finite,
of confidence is determined by the degree of probability alone. For the
it must in each case be completely determined. However, according to
probability of all immediate judgements is the same, namely, = 1. Since
§ 161, no. 8, it is reasonable to suppose that there are premises which
according to this there is only one sort of confidence with which we at
leave the degree of probability of a certain proposition completely unde-
least form all immediate judgements, and given that there is certainly no 279
termined. How then can the confidence with which we judge have a deter-
higher degree, permit me to call this sort of confidence the highest, or
minate degree, if it depends upon something that is itself undetermined?
pe1fect or complete confidence. People often use the words certaintv. or
(b) Is it not incomprehensible how a degree of probability which we do
pe1ject, complete certainty to designate this level of confidence. Thus
not actually notice can have effects in our mind such that it determines
the same word is used to designate an attribute of propositions and an
the degree of confidence with which we form a judgement? I should like
attribute of the confidence with which we pronounce these propositions
to make the following reply. Concerning (a): if the judgements which are
in judgements.
currently in the mind, A, B, C, D, ... , and which function as premises
It is no less obvious that judgements we form through the mediation
to the proposition M, do not produce a determinate degree of probability
of probabilistic inferences enjoy a lower degree of confidence than im-
for M, we will neither form judgement M nor judgement Neg.M, just as
mediate judgements. It remains to be decided how things stand with the
we do not form this judgement when the premises bestow a probability of
kind of judgements that are indeed mediated, but only by so-called perfect
1 upon proposition M. Concerning (b): we must envisage judgements A,
inferences. According to what was said in §301 about the actual origin
278 B, C, D, ... from which a certain probability accrues to proposition M as
of our judgements, the number of judgements of this kind is never very
forces which generate judgement M with its determinate degree of prob-
great, since not only every judgement of experience, but also any purely

186 187
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 319. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

conceptual judgement based upon a long sequence of inferences, requires any mediation, such as immediate judgements of perception, we do not
mediation by probabilistic inferences. Given, then, that the number of usually say that they are pronounced with conviction, even though they
judgements we obtain without any probabilistic inference is very small, are fully certain. The definitions given by KANT in his Logic [Ak., 9.73]
we might well leave open the question of the degree of confidence with and the Critique of Pure Reason (A820/B848ff) of the concept of persua-
which they are formed. But when everything pertinent is considered, we sion and the opposed concept of conviction are not only difficult to justify,
will scarcely object to the claim that they are formed with the same degree but also incompatible. In KIESEWETTER' s W. A. d. L. (I, p. 463) we read:
of confidence as the immediate judgements from which they are derived. "Conviction is holding something to be true, when the subjective grounds
Indeed, this must be so if the degree of confidence is determined by the are also the objective ones." He acids "A ground is subjective if it is based
degree of probability. For the latter is also = 1 for this kind of proposi- upon the individual constitution of the person in which it is found, and
tion. Now given that the immediate judgements as well as the conclusions thus is valid for him alone. It is objective when it is drawn from the thing
280 derived from them through perfect inferences are the only ones where er- itself, i.e., is universally valid." Here it is incomprehensible how a subjec-
ror cannot occur, it can also be said that these and only these judgements tive ground could be objective as well; furthermore, it is a mystery how
are formed with complete confidence. By contrast, all judgements that "drawn from the thing itself" and "universally valid" could be equivalent
are merely probable propositions for us are formed with a lower degree expressions. KANT delineates the meaning of the latter in the follow-
of confidence. The confidence with which we form a judgement that is ing terms (ibid.): "if holding something to be true is valid for everyone
not completely, but only morally certain (in the sense of §317), e.g., the insofar as he is rational." Here I ask whether by "everyone who is ratio-
confidence we have when we believe it to be foolish and impermissible nal" means absolutely every rational being, e.g., including God, or only
to worry about the possibility of the contrary and prepare for it, may be human beings? If the former, then grounds which are merely probable
called moral confidence or conviction. This degree of confidence is usu- could never produce conviction, since a being like God could never make
ally called certainty too, i.e., complete or moral or reassuring certainty. use of such grounds in its judgements. In this case, we would have to ex-
If, however, the degree of confidence is less than this, so that it is in no clude all truths of experience from the domain of conviction, something
way foolish or impermissible to consider the possibility that we are mis- which neither KANT himself nor accepted usage would allow. But if one
taken, we call this activity of our mind mere opining or surmising. only speaks of humans, then it is plain as clay that it depends very much
Note. It would be futile as well as unreasonable to want to forbid the upon the particular circumstances in which someone finds himself-his
use of the word certainty in both of the senses mentioned above. The previous knowledge, his attentiveness, etc.-whether certain grounds are
twofold usage of this word is so widespread that it would be difficult to sufficient for him or not. Hence I ask: in what state should we think peo-
decide which sense occurs more often. Who could hope to effect a change ple to be? If it is replied "in the state they are actually in," I would reply
in this usage? And why would one want to, given that these meanings can that innumerable truths that these scholars pride themselves on knowing 282
scarcely cause misunderstandings provided that one is careful in applying with conviction would have to be struck from the roll of those which hu-
them? In most cases, the context shows whether one speaks of the cer- mans can know with conviction, since they are beyond the reach of many.
tainty of a proposition or the certainty with which one forms a judgement. And if one says "one must imagine that every man has procured the per-
The meaning of the word conviction is also quite variable, yet it seems to tinent previous knowledge, and is appropriately attentive, etc.," I remark
me that the sense in which I have taken it here accords best with accepted that the concept of conviction could then have been defined much more
usage. For one usually only speaks of conviction when there is no worry briefly and properly as holding something to be true clue to following the
of the contrary occurring, i.e., when the proposition one accepts is either rules of correct thought. Some have indeed actually given this definition,
281 completely or morally certain. Admittedly, another, related concept is as- e.g., FRIES (Syst. d. L., p. 491): "Conviction is holding something to be
sociated with this one, namely, that the confidence with which one has true in accordance with formal laws. I am convinced when I follow the
pronounced a judgement has been produced by a preceding examination correct rules for the formation of a cognition." It seems to me, however,
or special proof. For in the case of judgements which arise in us without that this concept is completely different from the one that accepted us-

188 189
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 320. Of Certain(v, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

age connects with [the word] conviction; for I can follow correct rules of of confidence with which we form this judgement will be proportionate
thought even when this only gains me a small probability, so that I have to the surplus of the probability of proposition M over the probability of
only surmised; but a surmise is quite different from conviction. MAAB its negation Neg.M, since it is nothing but this surplus which determines
(Gt: d. L., §519) gave the definition: "Conviction is the consciousness of us to judge. Let us use 11 to designate the probability of proposition M;
the truth of a judgement from grounds that actually hold, and from which then the probability of Neg.M 1 - µ. Hence the degree of confidence
this truth follows." Accordingly, every judgement pronounced with con- with which M is formed will be proportional to the quantity µ - ( 1 284
viction would have to be true, one would have to be aware of its grounds, µ) = 2µ 1, and can be expressed by (2µ - 1)C, where C is a constant.
and these grounds would have to be objective. None of these conditions Now since the degree of confidence that has no higher degree above it
is required by accepted usage. KRUG (Fund., §89) defines conviction in is finite, we can take it as a measure for the rest and use it as the unit.
the broad sense as "an enduring consciousness of the validity of a judge- Hence the expression (2µ - 1)C should equal unity when µ = 1. For if
ment, or that mental state which stems from a durable approval." In my the probability of a proposition turns into certainty, then the confidence
view it is indeed true that conviction is in the main durable. This does of our judgement is pe1fect, and there can be no higher degree. Hence the
not form part of its concept, however; rather, it follows from its partic- value of the constant C = 1, and the degree of confidence with which we
ular attributes. Under certain circumstances the strongest conviction can form a judgement which has probability µ is simply 2µ - 1.
quickly disappear. For if we suppose that conviction may also occur with Recall ( § 161) that the probability µ is a fraction, the denominator
respect to objects of experience, then, because with judgements of this of which is the number of mutually exclusive, equally probable cases
sort the utter impossibility of the contrary never obtains, it is possible for in which the assumptions A, B, C, D, ... all become true, and whose
the strongest conviction which we have at one moment to be annihilated numerator is the number of these cases in which M as well as A, B, C,
283 in the next. D, ... come out true. Thus if we designate the number of cases in which
M is true by m and the total number of cases by m + n, we have 11\ = lll1fl
'~ ,
§.320.
and the probability of Neg.Mis = 111 : 11 • Thus the difference between
How the various degrees of confidence can be represented numerically the two, designated above as 2µ - 1, is = ;;:~;:. Hence we can say that
the degree of confidence with which we form a judgement can be found
It will rarely be very important to represent numerically the degree of
by calculating the differences between the number of mutually exclusive
confidence with which we judge. Still, it might be a useful intellectual
cases in which the judgement becomes true and the number of cases in
exercise to consider the question how these degrees should be calculated;
which it becomes false, divided by their sum.
this motivates the present discussion.
3) This mode of calculation gives a value of zero for the confidence
1) If the degree of probability of a proposition M with respect to the
premises A, B, C, D, ... (which are certain for us) is = !,
i.e., if this
of a proposition whose probability equals one-half. This indicates that
we do not judge at all, which is as things should be according to no. 1.
proposition is just as probable as its negation Neg .M, and if we notice
If the degree of probability µ of a proposition M is smaller than one-half,
this, then it is obvious that we will not form judgement M. For if we form
211 - 1 or ;;:~;: will be negative, and its size will vary directly with the 285
that judgement, then for the same reason we should also have to form
difference between n and m. If we calculate the degree of confidence
judgement Neg .M, and it is certain that we cannot do both at the same
we would attach to Neg.Min this case, we find that it is;;;;_;:. But since
time. Hence we do neither, i.e., we do not judge at all. In this case the
;;,~;: = - ;;:~;:, we see that a negative value for the degree of confidence
degree of confidence is called doubtfulness, possibly because we do not
judge but doubt, whenever the probability of a proposition is = !. simply indicates that we no longer form the judgement M, but instead
form Neg .M with the same, but positive, degree of confidence.
2) On the other hand, if the degree of probability that proposition M
4) If a proposition Mis deducible from premises A,B, C, D, ... and if
has for us with respect to the (certain) premises A,B,C,D, ... is larger
we have these premises currently in mind, and consider them true, then,
than one-half, then it is understandable that we form judgement M, if
according to § 161, the degree of probability M for us should never be
premises A, B, C, D, ... are then present in our mind. Likewise, the degree

190 191
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 320. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

smaller but somewhat larger than the product ax ~ x y x 5 x · · · . If we somebody who picks a ball at random will draw a black one. Similarly,
are afraid that we might be mistaken in the judgement that M is deducible we will not want to judge that he will pick a white one or a red one. What-
from A,B,C,D, ... , then the degree of probability will be somewhat ever reason we might have for forming one judgement, we have the same
lower. Hence on balance the probability of a conclusion will rarely be reason for forming another; nonetheless, it is obvious that we cannot ac- 287
much larger; rather, it will usually be somewhat smaller than the product cept all three of them, since they are contrary propositions. Hence we
of the probabilities of all its premises. Only if this product is larger than form none of them. Calculation shows that the degree of probability for
one-half will the judgement M actually be formed. If this product is equal each of them is one-third. Now if we did not distinguish between the
to one-half, we will not judge at all, and if it is smaller than one-half we degree of probability of a proposition and the degree of confidence with
will form the judgement Neg.M. which we form the corresponding judgement, we would have to form all
5) If everything is as above, but M is not deducible from A, B, C, D, ... three judgements, each of them with a confidence of one-third, which
but only receives the degree of probability µ from them, then we will form is quite absurd. Given the concept of confidence that I have introduced
judgement M with a degree of confidence proportionate to the degree of here and its mode of calculation, everything is explained properly. The
probability ofµ x a x ~ x y x 5 x · · · . degree of confidence for each of the three judgements is 2 ·1- 1= 1,
6) Consider a number of partial reasons, each of which bestows acer- which shows that we form none of these judgements, but only the three
286 tain probability upon proposition M. No matter how large the number of negations (which are compatible with each other, each with a degree of
these partial reasons is, no perfect confidence for judgement M can result confidence which equals + 1). But it could be objected that nonetheless
from them, though a moral confidence can arise, which can approximate the drawing of a black (likewise of a white or a red) ball is not impossi-
perfect confidence as closely as desired. For, the degree of confidence ble, but expected; consequently, if somebody were to claim the opposite,
with which we form judgement M depends upon the degree of absolute namely, that no black ball will be drawn, if he wanted to wager more than
probability which this proposition has for us. But, according to § 161, this two to one on it, we would contradict him and perhaps accept his offer of
will never attain perfect certainty, i.e., unity, though it can come as close a wager in the hope of a gain, all of which might be said to prove that the
to it as desired. But ifµ cannot equal 1, though it can approximate 1 as judgement that a black ball will be drawn has not been completely given
closely as desired, 2µ - 1, i.e., the degree of confidence, can also never be up. I reply that to contradict somebody who does not want to admit that
equal to 1, although it can approximate this value as closely as desired. a black ball will be drawn, and to engage in a wager with him, does not
Note. What has been said will suffice to make clear the difference require that we should believe that such a ball will be drawn; rather, it
between the concepts of probability, including the sense defined in §318, will suffice for this that we form the judgement that the indicated propo-
and the concept of confidence. Probability is always an attribute belong- sition (namely, that a black ball will be drawn) has a degree of probability
ing to propositions as such, whether or not they are taken for true or even of one-third. But this judgement is quite different from the judgement
mentally represented; hence it can be divided into known and unknown that a black ball will be drawn. The former not merely has probability,
probability. On the other hand, confidence is always an attribute of judge- but it is deducible from the premises by means of a perfect deduction,
ments that have been formed. Hence, with respect to one and the same and therefore has as much certainty as they have. As I become more and
proposition M and to one and the same thinking being, we can distinguish more clear about this distinction between probability and confidence, I
several kinds and degrees of probability, but not several kinds and degrees find it more and more surprising that all previous writers on the subject 288
of confidence. The necessity of distinguishing the confidence with which have never clearly made this distinction.
we form a judgement, and the probability of the proposition itself, and
§.321.*
of assigning different values to their respective degrees is particularly ap-
parent in cases where the probability is less than or equal to one-half. Knowledge and belief
Assume that we are told that in an urn there are ten black, ten white, and
There are two important states of our mind with respect to our own judge-
ten red balls. It will certainly not occur to us to form the judgement that
ments, states which (if I understand them correctly) have to do with a

192 193
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 321. Of Certainty, Probability and Confidence in Judgements

consideration of the confidence with which we are attached to a given also adequate to the meaning which common usage connects with these
judgement; they do not depend upon the degree of this confidence, but words. KANT' s definition is of course quite different, since it describes
rather on whether or not we are able to destroy this confidence. Suppose opining, believing, and knowing as three essentially different modes of
that a truth M, either immediately or after we pay attention to its grounds, taking something to be true. He says that the ground of an opinion is nei-
has become so evident to us that we assume we could not persuade our- ther objectively nor subjectively adequate, that of a belief subjectively,
selves of the opposite even if we wanted to. In other words, we think but not objectively, and that of an item of knowledge both objectively and
that it is not in our power to destroy the confidence with which we are at- subjectively adequate (Log. and K. d. r: V). I should like to call grounds
tached to judgement M. In this case I should like to call truth Man item of merely subjective if they appear to be grounds to the person forming the
knowledge [Wissen]. For example, we obtain such knowledge of the truth judgement, irrespective of whether or not he followed correct rules of
of the Pythagorean theorem once we have been exposed to its proofs. For thought, but objective if they still appear to be grounds in cases where 290

now we know the truth of this proposition in a way that assures us that we the rules employed were correct (see above, §319, note). But then it is
could not persuade ourselves of its falsity even if we tried. On the other strange to say that "what I believe I do not hold to be objectively, but only
hand, consider a proposition M which we take to be true, but of which subjectively necessary (for me)." It seems to me that if I become aware
we do not have knowledge. In this case it does not seem impossible that that I accepted something on the basis of incorrect rules of thought, then
we could come to form the opposite judgement, Neg .M, by concentrating I can no longer believe it. Other passages (e.g., Log., Ak., 9.72) lead us
our attention on true or apparent reasons against M. In such a case I call to believe that grounds are called subjective if they are "derived from the
the relation between our mind and proposition M a belief in this propo- nature and interest of the subject." But then it would have to be permissi-
sition, provided we intend to continue to pay attention to the grounds for ble to claim that we do not know, but merely opine or believe, that we are
the truth of M. For example, I believe that the heavenly bodies are pop- hungry and thirsty; for is it not obvious that the grounds upon which we
289 ulated, since I have decisive reasons to form this judgement, although I base such judgements are derived from the nature and the interest of the
do not doubt that, if I wanted, it would be possible for me to persuade person judging? But since no one will accept this, we must understand
myself of the contrary. Hence knowledge is a relation of our faculty of by subjective grounds not merely judgements but rather certain other at-
judgement to a given proposition which is initially, but not permanently, tributes of the judging being that lead it to form the judgement. Others
dependent upon our decisions; belief, on the other hand, depends upon seem indeed to have taken this view. Thus in KIESEWETTER' s W A. d. L
our will not only at its inception, but permanently; hence it also desig- (I, p. 473), we read: "subjective grounds are intentions, aims, interests."
nates a relation of our attitude to the proposition in question. Usually, the KRUG (Fund., §93) acids inclinations, needs and testimony to this list.
degree of confidence is higher in the case of knowledge than in the case But here I recall KANT'S remark (L., Ak., 9.73-74) that our wish or will
of belief, but there are also cases where the confidence of a belief does in and of itself cannot produce belief. Rather, only when certain (genuine
not fall behind that of knowledge. This is usually the case with our belief or apparent) grounds are present and we willingly direct our attention to-
in God. A belief which has a lower degree of confidence is usually called wards them does belief occur; and in the end it is the grounds which give
an opinion, or taking something to be true. Moreover, with respect to rise to the belief. Accordingly, every opinion produced through subjective
the firmness of our resolution to keep the grounds for our proposition in grounds would be nothing other than what I have called a judgement gen-
mind, we can distinguish a solid and a wavering belief, with respect to the erated by self-persuasion (§306, no. 14). And in fact, we read in the Cri-
ground which produced this resolution, we can distinguish a reasonable, tique of Pure Reason (A8820/B848): "If opinion has its ground merely
moral, as well as a foolish or immoral belief and, finally, with respect to in the peculiar constitution of the subject, it is called persuasion." But
its object (i.e., whether it is a conceptual or an empirical proposition) a now I ask: how can one speak of such subjective grounds as sufficient'? 291

theoretical or an historical belief. It seems to me that a ground can only be called sufficient if it alone suf-
Note. The concepts which I have here assigned to knowledge and be- fices to produce belief. Yet this can never be said of a mere wish. Nor
lief seem to me not only important and worthy of a special name, but do I understand, finally, how under this definition the three well-known

194 195
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE§. 321.

. 1 po.stulates, (see
prac t1ca , above ' §315
. - ' no · 8) could be presented
. as matters Book Four:
of belief. In essence, one makes the inference: "The highest good must
, ··bl e. It is, only possible if God exists. . Thus God exists." ..Now
b e possi
THE ART OF DISCOVERY
where in the premises of this argument (supposmg them all to be couect)
§.322.*
is there something which is merely subjective? .
FRIES (S. d. L., p. 451) says that "Belief in the logical sense is the
Purpose, contents, and divisions of this book
acceptance of an opinion only because I am mo:e? by interest to for~1 a
judaement with respect to it, e.g., when the physician must treat a patier~t
Given that I declared right from the start that for me logic is nothing other
eve~ though the outcome is doubtful." I deny that we are ever necessi- than a theory of science, i.e., instruction on how one should go about di-
tated to de~ide for or against a doubtful proposition M merely i~ or~er to
viding the entire domain of human knowledge into individual sciences
be able to act. I say that in order to act, and act rationally, nothmg is re-
and composing suitable treatises of these, it will be readily understood
quired but a deliberation whether the probabil~ty of M is large en?u.gh to that I only consider parts of the theory of the way in which one should
take certain measures appropriate under the circumstances. If this is the
proceed in order to discover truth to belong to logic. The rules of the lat-
case, and if we take these measures, then it is said, improperly, ~hat we
ter belong to logic, namely, only if they either stand in close connection to
have decided in favour of M, whereas a rational person takes special care
rules which must be observed in the pursuit of the two goals mentioned
before he makes such a decision. The example of the physician shows this
above, or else are necessary to understand them. Thus not all the rules
clearly: though he takes steps for one possible outcome, he also prepares
which must be observed if one wishes to be successful in the search for
for others. truth will be considered here, but rather only those that relate to the way
In the metaphysical sense FRIES distinguishes knowlec'.ge, belief m~d
we conduct our thinking, and are in addition generally applicable. I say
sentiment [Ahnung] as three modes of conviction of ~h1ch the first. 1s
that a rule applies to our conduct in thinking if it only deals with how
said to derive from intuition, the second without intuition, and the third
our thought, but not the rest of our behaviour, must be guided in order
from feelings without definite concepts. It is obvious why I cannot a~ree
to progress in the search for new truths. And because the truths in a sci- 294
with these definitions. It is generally acknowledged that mathematical
ence should be presented in a way that is both readily comprehensible and
cognitions can become an object of knowledge, y~t in my view they are
convincing, it is understandable that many such rules are either applied or
not based upon intuition. Fmthermore, I do not thmk (the m:~der ~!ready
must be presupposed when giving instruction on scientific presentation.
knows why) that there are cognitions which proceed from feelmgs 111 such
For the train of thought through which we become convinced of a pre-
292 a way that it is altogether impossible to reduce them to clear c.oncepts (as
viously unknown truth is often, if not always, the most suitable way of
FRIES teaches). One will gather how to evaluate a number of other defi-
bringing others to recognise this truth. It is not the same with the other
nitions based on what has been said here, e.g., those of the late HERMES
rules governing our conduct that belong in a complete instruction on how
(Einl. z. Theo!., p. 257 ff.) or MARHEINEKE (Dogm.). !ROXL.ER (Log:, to discover new truths, e.g., the development of our heart, the employ-
II, . 351-409) makes a big fuss (as he alone can) of his special undet-
sta~ding of the concept of belief. I will admit that I haven~t und~rstood ment of our senses, recourse to the instruction of others, and so on. In the
present book, one will find hardly any applications of such rules, which
him. Belief is supposed to be "a holding to be true and certam, which h<:~S
are in any case only serviceable as a kind of preparation for it. Thus if
much similarity with immediate cognition but also with mediate cog~1-
I do mention some such rules, it is only on account of the context and
tion; it is, so to speak, an idea which has become intertwined (sic!) with
their importance. Furthermore, I say that the rules I shall discuss have a
293 its object." Understand that if you can! general application if it can be useful to observe them not only for finding
a single truth, but rather many truths belonging to diverse fields of human
knowledge. It is plain as clay that in a treatise oflogic one can only ask for
such rules. For a precept which is useful only for finding either a single

196 197
THE ART OF D£SCOVERY §. 323. THE ART OF DISCOVERY

truth, or several truths belonging to one and the same science, can pre- we do not continually reflect. No one can say that our soul is enaaaedb b

cisely for this reason be applied only in the elaboration of that particular in reflection if the ideas or judgements which appear in our soul follow
science, and thus belongs at most to the logic of that science. Among the each other without the participation of our will, occasioned simply by the
rules which are suitable for the discovery of many truths in diverse fields impressions of outer objects, or as prompted by the associations prevail-
of human knowledge, only a very few are so widely useful that they can ing in our soul; nor if our will has an influence on the sequence of ideas
295 be applied in every kind of inquiry. Hence the present instruction may be and judgements, but does not aim at the production of a certain kind of
divided into two parts: the general, containing the rules to be observed judgement, e.g., if we pay more attention to ideas which we find pleasant
in every inquiry, and the particular, which teaches one how to proceed in than to others, without intending to form certain judgements. For all of
the most common special kinds of inquiry. this occurs when we dream. In all cases of reflection it is required that
Concerning the benefit the reader may expect from this book, the we awaken ideas and judgements in ourselves with the determinate and
above should suffice. I in no way believe myself able to point out pro- conscious intention of arriving at a judgement which is constituted in a
cedures to be followed in reflection which have not been long observed certain way. One may, for example, say that someone reflects when he
by every competent thinker, nor do I promise anything novel. Rather, I strives to convince himself that such and such is true. For he produces
have striven to set out in clear terms the various rules and procedures that ideas and judgements in himself with the determinate intention of being
talented thinkers have followed, for the most part without being aware of able in the end to form the judgement that such and such is true. We also
doing so. And although I do not flatter myself with the hope that I have say that someone reflects when he calculates. For he allows ideas and
been completely successful in this, I nevertheless believe that the little one judgements to arise within him in order to know a certain truth, namely,
finds here will not be unwelcome to many, and shall find its application that which determines the quantity to be calculated. From these and other 297
in the sequel. I recognise that the title of this book promises rather too examples, one sees that in all reflection we have an intention to produce a
much. But what other choice did I have? Heuristic says the same thing, judgement that we cannot always completely determine in advance, but of
only in Greek. Topic is not only less appropriate on account of its orig- which we nevertheless have fixed certain attributes-e.g., the object the
inal meaning, but also suggests a foreign associated concept-for Topic judgement concerns or that it should be a true judgement, etc. But it also
seems to be only a special kind of art of discovery, perhaps arranged in depends upon the means we use to produce these ideas and judgements.
tabular form. For if the ideas we use for our purposes are produced by the impressions
of certain external objects, it may well be that although we reflect, we
§.323. also do something else, which ordinary usage distinguishes from reflec-
tion: we perceive. Thus the question arises of the nature of the influence
The concept of reflection, in particular of reflection of the will on our ideas in all cases of reflection, even cases of pure reflec-
aimed at the discovery of new truths tion. Should we say that it is only pure reflection if the influence that our
will exercises on our ideas is not mediated by any external object (i.e.,
We must begin by determining the concept of reflection somewhat more one distinct from our soul); or, what amounts to the same, when we make
precisely. If we ask what is commonly understood by this word, nothing no use of objects distinct from the soul in order to produce the ideas, and
is more obvious than that in all reflection a certain orderly sequence of through these the judgements, we aim at? Yet this would be an excessive
296 ideas and judgements must occur. A soul wherein several ideas are not
restriction of the concept; for is not almost all the influence that our will
present at the same time, or where ideas follow each other in such a way has on the nature of our ideas mediated by our body, and thus by some-
that one has disappeared before the next begins; a soul which does not thing distinct from the soul? Could it not be the case that whether or not
form judgements with these ideas, or develop further judgements from We are conscious of it, every time we direct our attention to one of our
the former, will be said by no one to reflect. But it would be quite incor-
~<leas with the intention of keeping it longer before the mind or raising
rect to believe that this suffices to fix the concept of reflection. For ideas It to a higher degree of vividness an effect is produced in our body, a
and indeed judgements are constantly formed in our souls even though

198 199
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 323. THE ART OF DISCOVERY

change in our mental organ? Thus if the only cases of pure reflection that be noted, however, that even on the definition given above the concept of
we recognised were those in which our will does not act through any outer reflection is still so broad that it leaves the nature of the judgement we
298 objects distinct from our soul in order to procure the ideas we require, we wish to bring about completely indeterminate. Thus there can even be
could in fact never speak of pure reflection. We must therefore consider a kinds of reflection where it is not required that the judgement at which
measured broadening of this definition; and the observation we just made one finally arrives be true. Reflection which does aim at a true judgement
can easily lead to the thought that in pure reflection it is at most permis- I shall call reflection directed towards or in search of truth. It is evident
sible to act upon our own body, though not upon any other object distinct that the rules which must be followed in such reflection must be quite dif-
from it. Yet it soon appears that this determination would be incorrect; for ferent from those where truth is not our goal. Yet even reflection directed
according to it all observations and experiments which a man can perform towards truth must be completely different depending upon whether the
with and on his own body would have to be reckoned as pure reflection, truth in question is already known to us, but not present to the mind,
something which would certainly contradict accepted usage. After some or else new and unknown. In the former case, where we wish to recall
consideration, it should be clear to everyone that it is not a matter of the a judgement we made previously, our reflection may more precisely be
object upon which our will acts, but rather the way this action occurs, called recollection or recall. It is governed by rules I do not intend to go 300
namely, whether we are conscious of this action or not. Actions which into here, since they have no application to the ultimate goal of this book,
we perform either on our body or else through it on other bodies, pro- namely, to develop the rules which must be followed in elaborating sci-
vided that we are unaware of them, in no way prevent one from calling ences. Thus there remains the case of reflection aimed at the discovery*
the state of our soul one of pure, calm reflection. If, e.g., someone in his of new truths. Now it is clear that the circumstance whether the truth we
reflection audibly pronounces a few words without being aware of doing seek is unknown only to us, or to all other people as well, alters nothing in
so, or raises his hand to his brow, he certainly brought about changes in the way we must go about our own reflection-that is, unless we wanted
his own body; but we would hardly say he was doing anything other than and were able to turn to others for instruction. In this case, however, the
thinking. Only when such actions are perfotmed with the determinate rules to be observed would no longer have anything to do with pure reflec-
intention of producing or sustaining ideas of a certain sort, would ordi- tion, and since they are so far removed from our goal, we may pass over
nary usage say that his activity was something more than mere reflection. them. According to what has been said, then, all reflection of which we
Mere reflection is that activity of our mind through which we-without shall henceforth speak will have the aim of producing a cognition in our
making conscious and intentional use of the mediation of outer things- consciousness which was not previously present there. I shall say that we
produce ideas and judgements in ourselves that we consider necessary in find this cognition, and discover the truth which is its matter. So long as
order finally to arrive at a judgement we seek. it remains unknown, I shall call it the object or aim of our reflection, the
If this definition is correct, the question arises whether we should re- problem set for our reflection, and the question before us. The discovery
299 tain the received concept, or else allow ourselves to modify it somewhat. shall be called the solution to this problem or the answer to our question.
I in fact find no reason to define it more broadly or more narrowly. To If the truth we seek in our reflection is not sought with the definite inten-
narrow it, perhaps by excluding even the unconscious activity of our will tion of applying it in some foreseeable way, but rather only because the
on outer objects, would obviously not bring the slightest advantage, yet truth will produce some benefit, be this only that of providing exercise
would create the difficulty that we would be unable to say that such pure in thinking or the pleasure of discovery; and if, moreover, the truth we 301
reflection ever occurs in human beings. To broaden it by counting cases of
*I point out here once and for all that I-despite the difference observed in common
conscious and deliberate action on the external world as reflection would
usage between the words discover [Entdecken] and create [Elfinden]-consider these
entail that we would have to deal with all the laws governing this kind of terms equivalent when applied to truths. I call someone who first recognises a previously
action. Our instruction would certainly be more complete, but it would unknown truth both its discoverer and its creator. The former is appropriate because the
also be much more voluminous, and this multiplication of rules would truth is there even if no one recognises it, while the latter is appropriate insofar as the
do little to serve the end which is our principal concern here. It should recognition of this truth among men began with him, which is why we may call him the
creator.

200 201
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 324. THE ART OF DISCOVERY

seek as well as the propositions we seek to derive it from are all purely without awareness of rules is called a mere way of doing something (and
conceptual propositions, we call the reflection spernlation. Truths found when this is highly peculiar, a :,11ecial style or manner of doing some-
through speculation are called speculative truths and people who enjoy thing), one can also say that the knowledge of the sort of rules we shall
and are good at speculation are called speculative thinkers. deal with here is what makes methodical reflection possible. Without
§.324. such knowledge, all reflection would follow a mere style or manner.
Note. There is perhaps no reason to fear that the above definition of
The concept of instructions for thinking the concept of a methodical procedure will be contested; that my concept
of a manner includes the notion of a peculiarity may also be accepted,
All reflection, as we have just seen, is a complex mental activity com-
since common usage obviously requires this. But from this derives the
posed of several individual actions as its parts, undertaken with a deter-
necessity of a concept which is higher than that of a manner, namely, that 303
minate and conscious aim. With every activity, however, and indeed in
of a procedure which does not follow rules, regardless of whether it is
every change which is not completely uniform, one may ask for a more
highly peculiar or not. Since I know of no word which is used uniquely
precise indication of its nature and the way it is performed. Propositions
to designate this concept, I permitted myself to use the word style for this
that determine (truthfully or otherwise) this nature are usually called the
purpose. For at least in certain cases, e.g., the expression style of life, we
(correct or incorrect) laws of such changes. Thus the proposition that any
actually use the word in this sense. 304
freely falling body traverses spaces which increase as the square of the
times is called a law of this kind of motion. If the change can occur in dif-
ferent ways, and need not always have the same result, one may ask how it
must occur if a pat1icular outcome is to occur. Propositions determining
this (either truthfully or otherwise) may be called (correct or incorrect)
laws for this outcome. Thus in medicine one sets out laws which describe
the course of an illness for the case where it is not fatal; these may be
called the laws of development of this illness in cases of recovery. If the
302 change belongs to the class of those which depend in whole or in part on
the choice of a rational being, one may ask about the individual volitions
this being must form in order to produce the given outcome. Propositions
that answer this question, i.e., those which determine the course of action
required to bring about a certain outcome, when the former depends upon
someone's choice, bear the name of precepts or rules for the attainment
of this outcome. A collection of several precepts or rules of this kind is
called a set of instructions or a method; and if these are correct and suf-
ficiently numerous to determine the required behaviour completely, the
instructions are called correct and complete. From this one may gather
what I mean by instructions for reflection aimed at the discovery of new
truths, and the individual rules which make up this instruction. Attributes
of reflection independent of the thinker's choice I need not for that very
reason discuss, but I do have to mention all those we can give to our re-
flection, at least in pa11, merely by earnestly intending to do so. Since
every procedure a rational being establishes according to rules he consid-
ers correct is called a methodical procedure, while a procedure followed

202 203
THE ART OF DISCOVERY

PART I for example, the widest determination we could reasonably specify if we


demanded nothing other than the discovery of some previously unknown
General Rules truth which is either worth learning or useful. A determination of the
narrowest sort, one which covers only a single truth, would be if we set
0 ut to decide whether or not a given proposition M was true. Another case
§.325.* where the sought truth is not so precisely determined occurs when we
consider two ideas A and B and demand that a truth be inclicatecl in which
I. Exact determination qf' the tntth we actually seek, without
these two ideas are united into a single proposition through the mediation
rejecting truths ivhich present themselves unbidden
of a purely logical concept, e.g., "Every A is B", or "No A is B" or "The 306
idea [A]b has objectuality", etc. Often we only specify the object that the
1) Since the number of truths is infinite, we may neither demand nor hope
sought truth is supposed to concern, i.e., the subject-idea of the truth, and
to learn them all. Rather, we must be satisfied with the knowledge of a
demand of the predicate only that it represent an attribute of this subject
part of these which is always finite and rather small. Obviously it is not a
which was previously unknown to us and noteworthy. More often, not
matter of indifference to us which of these infinitely many truths fill the
even the object the truth is supposed to concern is fully specified; instead,
limited measure of our cognitive faculties. For even if it should happen
we merely indicate a concept it stands under, i.e., we indicate the kind of
that there is no completely useless and still less a genuinely harmful truth
thing it is supposed to be.
(and there is still much dispute about this), it is nevertheless certain that
2) Some might object to this first rule that experience teaches us that
there are degrees of usefulness and needfulness in knowledge; and if the
we make the most fortunate discoveries by chance, i.e., on occasions
apprehension of one truth prevents us from learning another which would
where we were occupied with something else entirely. I admit this, but
have been more beneficial, it can at least be said to be relatively harmful.
I point out that such experiences do not show that our rule is useless.
Although it is not certain that we will discover a certain kind of truth
For although experience teaches us that we often find most useful truths
merely because we undertake to look for it, it is understandable that we
without seeking them, it also teaches that we often find through seek-
are m~re likely to find it if we search assiduously for it than if we simply
ing. Actually, it is generally only the first, crude thought that chance
leave it to chance to determine which truth we are or are not led to. For, as
delivers. For this to be useful, we must pursue it further, and connect a
305 ~as already been noted several times, our will has a great, though indirect,
number of other truths with it, all of which can only happen through de-
mfluence on the origin, duration and vividness of our ideas, and hence on
liberate reflection. Thus the necessity of such reflection remains beyond
our judgements. From these considerations comes the first rule which
a doubt. Thus the above objection does not refute the given rule, but it
should always be observed in reflection aimed at the discovery of truth:
does require us to acid the following precision: one should never reject
First of all, establish in detail the nature of the truth we wish to discovet:
a previously unknown truth which simply presents itself merely because
What is required here is a judgement of the form which I called questions
one set out to make discoveries of a completely different kind; i.e., one
in § 145; and the truth we seek is the answer belonging to this question
should never utterly ignore it if it is noteworthy or has the appearance qf'
(§ 163). Accordingly, we can also express the above rule as follows: In
something which might lead to the discovery of other noteworthy truths.
all reflection, one must begin by establishing the question which is to be
The observation of this last rule may be the main reason why i1;clividual 307
answered. If the determination of the object of our reflection is quite vivid
men sometimes make the most beautiful discoveries in the most diverse
(and it is obvious that it will be more effective, the more vivid it is) we
fields of knowledge. We find that they are generally people who are ac-
must be clearly conscious of it: we must represent to ourselves our desire
customed to ignoring nothing, to asking themselves at every opportunity
to discover a truth of such and such a kind and, if need be, we must be in a
what is to be learned, to taking up every hint they receive, no matter what
position to express this desire in words. The ways in which we determine
its source, and using it as a basis for reflection. Before ARCHIMEDES
the truth we seek may be quite varied, in that we may specify an attribute
bathers must have perceived that their arms were easier to lift in wate;.
that belongs either to many, a few, or only to a single truth. It would be,

204 205
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 326. General Rules

than out; but since they reflected no further on the matter, he was the first uestion whether or not it could be answered. But I at least know of
to discover the law of the equilibrium of floating bodies. ~o means that could be generally applied to this encl: On the contrary, I
believe that there are questions which we only recogmse as unanswerable
§.326.*
on the basis of results, i.e., only because, despite all our striving, we 309
II. Preliminary consideration (~f whether an.s·tvering the question have never found a satisfactory answer do we realise that such an_ answ~r
before us is impossible either as such orfor us is beyond the grasp of our powers. It lies within the nature of certam
kinds of questions that we can only discover that they are unanswerable
1) It not seldom occurs that we hit upon questions, or others ask us ques-
by vainly attempting to answer them. Most ~istorical que~tions when
tions, which either cannot be answered in and of themselves, or else can-
first raised are of this sort if they concern a subject about which we have
not be answered given the limited powers and means at our disposal for
various historical data which, if compared, might furnish the information
the recognition of truth. Now if the question we seek to answer through
we seek, e.g., the year of Jesus' birth.
reflection is of this sort, we will not only fail to reach the goal of our
3) The examples cited in no. 1 show that there are also cases for which
reflection, we will also run the risk of falling into many errors. For if
a preliminary investigation easily establishes that a question c~nnot be
we incorrectly assume that the question before us can be answered, and
answered either in itself or by us. Prudence thus counsels that tvzth eve1y
indeed answered by us, it is to be feared that we will sooner or later
question we set ourselves, provided it is not a preliminary questi~n, we
persuade ourselves that we have truly found it, something which cannot
should first investigate whether we can notice any feature from whzch the
happen unless we are deceived. The proposition we take to be an answer
impossibility of an answer (either generally or for us) follows. .
to our question may be false, it may be not an answer to our question or,
4) Prudence counsels us to make this inquiry, but does not reqmre us
308 in the most favourable case, where the proposition is true and contains the
to persist in it until it succeeds, i.e., not to proceed to the examination ~f
correct answer to our question, there is still an elTor, in that we imagine
the question we originally set ourselves until we have fully answered this
that we have grasped the truth of the proposition as well as the fact that
preliminary question. No, if consideration of this preliminary question
it correctly answers our question on the basis of reasons. If one were to
reveals that it would be harder to answer than the question we originally
ask oneself, for example, how old the world is (i.e., how many years have
set ourselves, or that it can only be answered by successful or unsuccess-
passed since the creation), and to answer that it is six thousand years old,
ful attempts to answer the original question, it would be foolish to waste
then the proposition would be false, provided that by the word "world"
more time on it.
one meant not just the human race or the earth, but the collection of all fi-
5) In certain cases it may be expedient to switch our attention back
nite beings. If one asked what organic feature of bees was responsible for
and forth between the given question and the question about whether it 310
the fact that bees build hexagonal cells, and responded that they do this
can be answered. The problem of the trisection of the angle, for example,
instinctively, this proposition would indeed be true, but it would not be an
is of this kind. Here the discovery of the impossibility of a solution would
answer to the given question, which asked for something quite different.
be just as noteworthy as a solution, and both must be sought along the
Finally, if one asked in what season Adam was created, and replied that
same path.
this happened in Spring (in the Northern hemisphere); this might just hap-
6) Sometimes we also have the benefit of discovering that our present
pen to be true, and if so, would be an appropriate answer to this question.
knowledge does not suffice to answer the question before us through re-
Yet one would err in thinking that he had proved the truth of this claim.
flection alone, but that instead new experiences and experiments are nec-
All of these errors could have been avoided if one had considered that
essary. A chemist, for example, can know in advance that, given the
these questions cannot be answered: the first in and of itself, the second
present state of his science, a question about the effects of combining
given the present level of our knowledge of bees, and the third given the
two kinds of matter cannot be answered by reflection unless some new
complete lack of historical reports on the matter in question.
experiments are performed.
2) One gathers from this that it would be very desirable to have a
means which would permit us to know before we begin to look into a

206 207
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 327. General Rules

§.327.* 3) Thus it is a matter of providing instrnctions on how this reduction


of a given question to others which are easier to answer can be accom-
Ill. Taking up suitable preliminary questions plished. By my reckoning there are only t~o ways of doing thi:. (a) ~he 312
first is that we take a close look at the attnbutes a, b, c, d, ... of the tn~th
1) Only in the rarest cases are we in a position immediately to discover
to be discovered which are explicitly mentioned in the problem, and m-
the truth our problem requires. What we cannot accomplish immedi-
uire whether these might be derived from others v., p, y, ... which taken
ately, however, we can often accomplish by first seeking several other
truths which are so constituted that their possession, and indeed some-
~aether have the same extension as the former. If we succeed in this, it is
o:Vious that we have reduced the question about a truth which possesses
times merely the search for them, promises to facilitate the discovery of
attributes a,b,c,d, ... to one about a truth with attributes v., p, y ... .
the truth we really seek. Problems which we set ourselves with this aim
If it happens that the attributes v., p, y, ... are more easily recognised
in mind, i.e., in order to pave the way towards the solution of another
characteristics of the sought truth than the originally given a, b, c, d, ... ,
problem, I call preliminary questions or problems. By contrast, I call
then we have gained something by this reduction. Suppose, for example,
the problem for whose sake we occupy ourselves with these preliminary
we had set ourselves the problem of discovering the highest moral law.
questions the original or main question or problem. Thus in the case of
The question itself contains (by dint of the definition of the concept of the
every problem we are not able to solve immediately it will be appropriate
highest moral law) the determination that the sought truth must be a prac-
to inquire whether we might not succeed in devising one or several de-
tic:11 proposition from which all other practical truths follow objectively,
cidedly easier problems, which are so constituted that if we solve them,
aiven a purely theoretical minor premise. It might well be quite hard to
311 the solution of the original problem will follow of itself. When we have b .
find this truth immediately by means of this attribute. Some reflection,
shown that a problem can be solved once one or several others have been,
however, allows us to derive several other attributes from this one. If the
I shall say that the former has been reduced to the latter. Thus I say that
highest moral law is to be a practical truth, it must require some action
mathematicians have reduced the question "How heavy is the earth?" to
or other; and if all other practical truths can be derived from this one as
that of how heavy this or that mountain is, since they have shown how an
consequences from their ground, the highest moral law must require this
answer to the first yields an answer to the second.
action without exception, i.e., not merely under a condition (whether this
2) If the question to which a given question is reduced is no easier
be explicitly stated or tacit), as in the proposition "You should do M, pro-
to answer, then we have indeed gained nothing for our attempt to answer
vided that this does not prevent X ." This circumstance suggests a more
the latter. Yet the connections we learn of in this way between many
easily recognisable characteristic through which we may find the highest
still unknown truths sometimes furnish quite remarkable truths. Thus
moral law. For if we now make an appropriate survey of all the possi-
the question of whether the heavenly bodies move in trajectories that are
ble ways of acting, and consider these in order, we soon find that with a
constantly moving closer together might be reduced to the question of
single exception all are either required only conditionally or else not at 313
whether the space in which they move is filled with matter; and even
all. Even in the case where the attributes v., p, y, ... , which we derive
if the latter question is no easier to answer than the first, the truth one
from the given a, b, c, d, ... , have a wider extension, and hence do
expresses here (namely, that the former would be a consequence of the
not alone suffice for the determination of the sought truth, it may still be
latter) is already noteworthy in itself. Now if we first attempt many such
useful to consider them. We may find ourselves in a position to greatly
reductions, it is to be hoped that among them we will find one through
reduce the number of propositions among which the required truth is to
which the solution of the original question can be made to depend upon
be sought, and hence to make this search easier. Suppose, for example,
the solution of several other, easier ones. The reduction mentioned in
we were given the problem of finding common divisors for the two num-
no. l provides one example of this. For it would not be impossible to
bers 2n + 1 and 2m. From the circumstance that one is odd and the other
determine approximately the weight of an individual mountain, perhaps
even, we may immediately gather that no even number will provide a so-
by measuring its volume and the density of the material one finds by
lution, and accordingly search for factors of 2m, or indeed m, which also
digging in its interior.

208 209
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 327. General Rules

divide 2n + 1. (b) The second means is to think about the various ways in reduced to them. The consideration of some preliminary questions is
which a proposition like the sought truth X may be derived from others useful merely because they introduce the subject of our main question, 315
Y, Z, .... For if we find that a proposition of the form X can be deduced j.e .. renew and stimulate in our consciousness the ideas and knowledge
from propositions of the known forms Y,Z, ... , then it is easy to find X required to answer it, or else acquaint us with the principal factors which
as soon as we have truths of the forms Y,Z, .... The problem of finding 111 ust be considered in finding an answer. Dealing with a preliminary
X is thereby reduced to that of indicating truths standing under the forms question can do great service for us in these respects, even if it does not
Y,Z, ... ; and clearly the latter is often easier to solve than the former. lead us to a solution, simply because we gave it our attention for a while.
Suppose, for example, we were assigned the problem of discovering the Admittedly, it is not always possible to tell whether it will be useful in
distance between two places, when no straight path leads from one to the this way. It is to be expected, however, that dealing with a preliminary
other. We begin by considering the various ways there are of determin- question will be of benefit if it stands in one of the following relations
ing distance. It then occurs to us that the third side of a triangle (and to the main question: if it bears on a question which is either superordi-
thus a distance) may be calculated when we are given the other two sides nate, subordinate, or coordinate to the main question; or if it requires the
and the angle they include. The problem of finding AB is thus reduced more precise determination of certain concepts which occur in the sought
to those of finding the distances AC and BC and the angle ACB, where C truth, or concerns a subject which is either very similar or else opposed
is an arbitrary third location. If now there is a location C connected to to the subject of the main question, etc. Thus, for example, if we had to
314 A and B by straight paths, and we know how to measure the angle ACB, discover the theorem of the parallelogram of forces, we would do well to
then we know how to solve the latter three problems and, through them, ask what result two equal forces acting in either the same or else opposite
the main problem. Concerning the various ways in which a truth of the directions would have; then what must be the effect of two equal forces
form of the sought X can be deduced from others, the first we should look acting at an arbitrary angle, or two unequal forces acting at right angles
for among all the truths already known to us is a hypothetical one with X to each other, etc. For these cases are subordinate to the general truth we
as its consequent. Every truth of this form, e.g., "If A, B, C, ... , then seek. If we have to specify the duties which issue from a contract, we will
X" indicates a way for us to transform the problem of finding the truth do well to begin with the concept of a contract; if we have to enumerate
X into one of finding the truths A, B, C, .... Suppose we had to answer the benefits of the virtue of moderation, it will be appropriate to begin by
the question whether the planets are attracted by the sun, and we had the considering the harmful consequences of immoderation, etc.
theorem "If one body moves around another in such a way that the line
connecting them describes equal areas in equal times, then it moves as it §.328.*
would if so attracted." This theorem would give us the means of deciding
whether this attraction occurred or not. If we know of no such hypotheti- IV Deductions from already known truths or direct method
cal proposition, we ask whether one can be found. Thus we reflect about
1) It is well known that at any given time only the smallest part of our
whether we know a truth that bears great similarity to the sought truth X.
knowledge is actually present in our mind; the rest is absent, but in such 316
If we find several of these, we try to remember how we came to know
a way that through the use of certain means within our power-for ex-
them. We may well be able to find X in a similar fashion. In order, for
ample, what we call rumination-it is possible to renew it. Among the
example, to answer the question of whether the moon has an atmosphere
things known to us but not immediately present there are often some that
and how far this extends, it will occur to us that we already know a similar
would serve to answer a question which is before us, i.e., from which we
truth, namely, how far the atmosphere of the earth extends. We may then
could deduce the sought truth if they were present. If, in addition, the
see whether any of the means used to learn the latter may be applied to
subject upon which we are to reflect is not of the kind where it is obvious
determine the former.
in advance that there will be nothing in our previous knowledge which
4) It should not be forgotten, however, that dealing with prelimi-
might serve to illuminate it (and this will seldom be the case), we will be
nary questions can also be useful even if the main question cannot be
wise to begin by asking ourselves what knowledge related to this subject

210 211
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 328. General Rules

we already possess. We must, I say, try to bring everything to mind which rnind all the truths known to us which have the soul as their topic, as well
we know of our subject, so that we may select therefrom the items that as those dealing with another topic yet containing ideas occurring in the
might serve to facilitate our answering the question about it. former. A truth of the first sort would be, for instance, that our soul is
2) Now it is customary to call every truth we may presuppose as a simple substance, while a truth of the second sort would be that every
known in our search for another a given truth or a datwn, if one thinks simple substance is imperishable. When we combine these two truths
it may be helpful in the search. By contrast, the truth we seek is called with each other we immediately notice that the new truth that the soul
the qwesitum. Thus we may express the above rule as follows: in every is imperishable follows from them-a proposition which does not indeed
problem one must attempt to bring to mind not only the qucesitum but also answer the question of immortality, yet does bring us closer to a solution.
all available data. 6) Since in the method just described we pass from a consideration of
3) It is admittedly difficult in many cases to find precisely the truths already known truths to the recognition of a new one, and from the latter
which might help us to discover the sought truth by surveying all the to yet another one, etc., it has been called the progressive method. And
truths we know. The most likely ones are those which have constituents since the new truth is usually deduced from the combination of several
in common with the sought truth (provided that some of these constituents previously known truths, it is also called the combinat01y or synthetic
317 are already known). Thus if the topic of the sought truth is known, it will method. In comparison to the methods we shall consider in the following
be worthwhile to consider any truth we know having to do with this topic. sections, it can also be called the natural or direct method.
Yet truths with completely different constituents can often be useful, es-
pecially when they have a considerable number of parts in common with §.329.*
truths we have recognised to be useful on independent grounds. It is ob-
vious that among the large number of truths we recall we must direct our V. Tentative acceptance or indirect method
attention to those which seem to us most likely to help us solve our prob-
1) If we have pursued the method just described for a long time with-
lem. Only if we are unable to accomplish anything with these should we
out reaching our goal, i.e., without having found the truth we seek, it is
take up others. The only truths we should overlook entirely are those we
advisable to take a different route, one which is sometimes worth taking
can know in advance to be of no use for our purpose.
even before trying our luck with the direct method. The method I have
4) If we have collected certain propositions A, B, C, D, ... which we
in mind is that in which we randomly form propositions with the form of
hold to be true, and if we are not convinced in advance that they will be
the sought truth, though we do not know in the moment we form them 319
useless for solving our problem, the next thing to do is actually to attempt
whether or not they are true, something which we can only find out by
to use them to solve it. We do this by closely considering them both
reflecting on them. Such reflection, which aims at discovering whether
individually and in every possible combination in order to see whether a
or not a given proposition is true, may be called an inquily or, more pre-
new proposition M can be deduced from some individual proposition or
cisely, an examination of the proposition M (cf. §306). If this inquiry
combination of propositions, where even if M is not the sought truth, we
shows that M is false, then the problem we had set ourselves is admittedly
at least have reason to hope it will bring us closer to a solution. That is,
not solved. But if it shows that it is true, then in the randomly selected
it will be easier to discover the truth we seek if we consult the truth M
M we have the very truth we sought. Propositions which we form with
along with A, B, C, D, ....
this intention, namely, in order to determine through further reflection
5) We have shown in the chapter on inferences how one should at-
whether or not they are true, may quite appropriately be called tentative
tempt to deduce M from the truths A, B, C, D, .... From this chapter
assumptions or hypotheses, and the procedure of looking for the truth we
we will gather which combinations of the propositions A, B, C, D, ...
seek by this means may be called the method of tentative assumptions.
are most promising, namely, those related to each other like the premises
If we compare this procedure with the one described in the previous sec-
of an argument. If, for example, we wanted to decide the question of
tion, it is apparent that even if it sometimes brings us quickly to our goal,
318 whether our soul is immortal, we would do well to begin by recalling to
it can still be called artificial, backwards or indirect, since it attempts to

212 213
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 329. General Rules

find truth by means of something that is not yet recognised as truth, while with the former before the latter. Sometimes the mere consideration of the
the most natural thing is to derive truths from truths. A considerable attributes of one or several assumptions we have already discovered to be
number of truths in all sciences will indeed only be discovered through false makes it possible to recognise other attributes which the sought truth
this procedure, i.e., by at first merely representing the propositions which must possess, and thus either to determine the latter completely, or else to
express these truths, and then becoming convinced of their truth by ex- make it easier to do so. Examples are the well-known reguli falsi of the
amining them. Someone who cannot use this procedure, someone who masters of calculation, as well as the diverse methods of approximation
does not even want to form ideas of propositions saying one thing or an- used in astronomy and elsewhere.
other about the matter at hand before he can pronounce a well-grounded 4) The first thing we can do with regard to the examination of ten-
judgement on it, cuts himself off from the opportunity to investigate this tative assumptions is to think of the proposition under examination as
proposition and hence from the knowledge of many a truth. In fact, the distinctly as possible. To this end, we should also present it in words or
complaint one often hears from people who are by no means dim-witted other kinds of signs and, if called for, even to express it in different (mutu-
320 that for all their reflection they are not able to get anywhere seems to stem ally equivalent) ways. Such efforts sometimes make the truth or falsity of
entirely from a stubborn refusal to use this procedure. They don't want to the proposition obvious to us, without recourse to any other means. They
form an idea of a proposition until they know they may accept it as true, may also remind us that we had previously judged its truth or falsity and,
so they cannot even examine it, and hence discover nothing. depending on the circumstances, this previous judgement may still seem
2) Now two things are required when this method is employed, namely: reliable enough. What we have to guard against is holding a proposi-
(a) the propositions in question must be suitably chosen, and (b) they must tion to be true simply because it presents itself to us quite unbidden, or
be tested in every feasible way. comes to mind with great vividness. For these phenomena provide at best
3) Pure reflection knows no other means for producing a suitable stock a very weak presumption of the truth of the proposition. They can never
of propositions than to make use of the combinations of ideas already be looked upon as a sufficient indicator of its truth, since they can merely
present in our soul. For no idea is utterly isolated in the soul; rather, each be the effect of quite accidental connections produced by the well-known 322
is connected with others, and the latter in turn with others still. Thus laws of the association of ideas.
merely considering the matter we wish to reflect on cannot fail to intro- 5) If the mere distinct representation of a proposition M does not lead
duce many other ideas, and reflecting on the latter will develop an ever to a judgement about it, or if this judgement does not appear reliable
greater number of ideas in us. If, as often occurs, we then combine these enough, the next stage in its testing is that we attempt to deduce, either
ideas into entire propositions, we can produce in short order a consider- from M alone, or from M together with other already known premises,
able number of propositions which have the form of the truth we seek. several consequences and from these further consequences, etc. If we
Here it is obvious that those which we can see at first glance to be false recognise any one of these consequences as a false proposition, then
may be discarded without examination. When we turn to actual reflec- we are entitled to the conclusion that our tentative hypothesis M is it-
tion, however, we often become aware that the large and perhaps infinite self false. Conversely, if all consequences drawn from the proposition
multitude of propositions that have the form of the truth we seek may M are true, we ought to do the same thing we just did with M now also
be reduced to a moderate number which need to be examined; and even with its negation, the proposition Neg.M, i.e., we should collect all conse-
among the latter some usually show themselves to be far more probable quences which follow from Neg.M either immediately or in conjunction
than the rest. If, for example, we had to solve an equation with integral with known truths. If we can find one which is decidedly false, then it is
321 coefficients, and we knew that the roots were rational, we simply need to shown that N eg.M is false and hence that the initial hypothesis M itself
recall that these roots must all be whole numbers and also factors of the is true. This procedure of showing the truth of proposition M, and thus
last term, in order to reduce the number of values for tentative investi- of solving the indicated problem, is generally called reduction to absur-
gation to a quite reasonable size. If among equally probable assumptions dity, or the apagogic method. Examples are common in the mathematical
some are easier to investigate than others, it is obviously advisable to deal sciences so that I need not mention any at this time.

214 215
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 329. General Rules

6) If neither the assumption of M nor that of Neg.M leads to an ab- cause we had previously noted that M is deducible from the propositions
surdity then almost nothing can be decided in this way. At most, in cases J,K,L, ... , which are deducible from D,E,F, ... which are deducible
where the falsity of one of these propositions could be expected to lead from A,B,C, ... , and had learned that A,B,C, . .. were true. Our con-
more readily to absurdity than that of the other given the context, we viction in M is thus a consequence which is grounded in our conviction
323 might claim it to be probable-but only if the probability the other propo- that the propositions/, K, L, ... , which were formed later, are true; while
sition has in other respects is not greater. our conviction in the latter results from our conviction with respect to
7) Another means of coming to a decision about the proposition M, D, E, F, ... , which were considered after them. Thus one may say that
which is to be highly recommended if M already has a considerable prob- the consequences are considered before their grounds, or that one pro-
ability, is the following procedure. We select from the multitude of all ceeds from the former to the latter. Given that the most natural movement
propositions from which, if they were true, M would be derivable those, of thought is in the opposite direction, one may call the present procedure
I, K, L, ... , which seem most probable to us. We then introduce them as regressive. If in addition, which is often if not always the case, the propo-
new assumptions, and attempt to prove their truth using all the means at sitions I,K,L, ... are simpler than the proposition M, and D,E,F, .. .
our disposal. If we do not succeed, but instead prove that some of them simpler than I, K, L, ... , etc., one may also say that this procedure is
are false, we discard these and try others. If we fail to prove either the a resolving or analytic one. The requirement that the assumption to be
truth or the falsity of I, K, L, ... , we look for several new assumptions examined, M, already have a considerable degree of probability, as well
D, E, F, ... , from which, if they were true, I, K, L, ... and thence M could as the requirement that one always select the most probable among the
be deduced; as before, we select from the propositions D, E, F, ... those new assumptions I,K,L, ... from which M can be deduced, and similarly 325
which seem most probable. We then do with them what was just pre- for D, E, F, ... , were only stipulated so that in the end we should arrive
scribed for I,K,L, ... or M, and continue in this way until we finally suc- all the more surely at assumptions A, B, C, ... which reveal themselves to
ceed in discovering assumptions A,B,C, ... which can be proved without be true. The procedure would also be correct if we did not observe these
drawing on others. If this occurs, it is clear that we have shown the truth restrictions. And if we do not shrink from the danger of a futile search, or
of M, and thus solved our problem. Suppose, for example, we wanted if among the many assumptions which we might have used in such a pro-
to decide in this way whether or not a perpetuum mobile was possible. cedure none is more probable than the others, we may follow whatever
Since all previous attempts to show that one is possible have failed, we order we like in our inquiry.
assume to begin with that none is possible. Then, considering several 8) Another quite useful means of testing a proposition M suggests
propositions from which this would follow, we hit upon the proposition itself in the special case where the subject-idea is a general concept A and
that no single substance in nature continually remains at the same level of we are able to survey either all or many of the objects standing under it
existence. If this could be proved, then so would the former. But as this in order to figure out whether the attribute b, which the proposition to
proposition only seems probable to us, we reflect about whether we are be tested ascribes to all A, in fact belongs to all of them. If, in a case
able to prove it. It is clear to us that we could prove it if we were permit- like this, we find even one A which lacks attribute b (which is often quite
324 ted to assume that every (finite) substance has powers of representation. easy to do), then the falsity of M is decided. Many philosophers, for
Given that this is also probable, we assume it, and look for a proof. It example, accept the proposition that if the relation between two things
appears that this would be proved if we assumed every finite substance along with one of the things is completely determined, then so is the other.
which acts externally also experiences reaction internally. And as this This can be shown to be false in the way just described, by applying
last proposition is clear in and of itself after a little reflection, we may it to the case where both things are spatial objects, e.g., a point and a
consider the problem we had set ourself solved. If we look at the path we line. But in order to recognise the truth of M in this way, and this with
took in this procedure in order to arrive at the recognition of the truth of certainty, then we can obviously not restrict our investigation simply to a
M, it is clear that we represent first M, then I, K, L, ... , then D, E, F, ... , great number of the objects standing under A, but we must extend it to all
and finally A,B,C, ... only tentatively; we finally saw the truth of M be- of them. Now if A comprises many, perhaps even infinitely many, objects,

216 217
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 329. General Rules

then this becomes possible only by finding certain concepts A' ,A", ... , tests, which is perhaps vanishingly small in comparison with the number
which stand under the concept A in such a way that their domains together of cases for which the formula is supposed to be valid, but rather because
exhaust the domain of A; moreover, they must be such that the truth of it is improbable that if we had committed errors of calculation in deriving
the propositions "Every A' has b", "Every A" has b", ... can be more the formula, these would be precisely of the sort which produced c01Tect
326 easily established than the universal proposition "Every A in general has results in the cases we tested. So too, if we go into a small section of a
b". This procedure is also well-known from the mathematical sciences. It large library and take a few books from the top shelf, and a few books
is clearly not necessary for the ideas A' ,A", ... to be exclusive, but only from the bottom shelf, and we find them to be theology books, we can
that they together exhaust the domain of A (§95). If we cannot establish conclude that all the books in this section are on theology, since it is
a sufficiently large number of propositions of the form "A' has b", "A" reasonable to suppose that the books in the library are ordered according
has b", ... to conclude decisively that all A in general have b, since the to subject. As the kind of inference by means of which we recognise
ideas A',A", ... taken together do not completely exhaust the domain the truth of M in such cases is usually called a (complete or incomplete)
of A, then the propositions already established still entitle us to conclude induction (§§236, 253), we may call this way of solving a problem an
with a certain degree of probability that the attribute b, which belongs inductive procedure.
to all the A already investigated, also belongs to the remaining ones and 9) In the procedure just described we undertook a kind of division
hence to all A. In particular, assume that the number of all A is m + n, with respect to the subject of the proposition. One may also sometimes be
and the number of those already investigated and found to have attribute equally successful by attempting a division with respect to the predicate,
b is m; also assume that besides our observation we have no other reason namely, in the case where the attribute b which the proposition ascribes 328
whatever to suppose that property b should belong only to the A which is a collection of several attributes b, b', b", .... Here it must be decided
we have investigated rather than to the others; assume furthermore that whether or not the attribute b belongs to all A; to do this, it suffices to
concept A itself does not furnish any reason why it is more likely than decide whether or not the individual attributes b, b', b", ... belong to all
not that the attribute b should belong to the objects falling under A; and, A, something which is clearly often easier to accomplish. I need only call
lastly, assume that we have no reasons other than those produced by our upon examples from mathematics which everyone knows. Even in the
observations to suppose that the A should be all alike with respect to an case where we are unable to prove the existence of all of b', b", ... which
attribute of the kind of b: if all these conditions are fulfilled, then the together make up b, it will sometimes be permissible to infer the existence
degree of probability with which we can assume that the remaining A, of all of them from the presence of some of them with a greater or lesser
and hence all A, have attribute bis = 11 ;~~! 1 . (The calculations leading to degree of probability. For if the number of attributes b', b", ... is = m + n,
this expression can be found in the literature.) Since 11;~~! 1 either equals and the number of those we have perceived to exist= m; and if apart from
or is smaller than one-half, whenever m < n, and since we cannot accept the reasons provided by these observations we have no reason to accept
propositions whose probability is smaller than one-half, it follows that the rather than reject any of the attributes b', b", ... ; when, furthermore, we
327 truth of a proposition M cannot be assumed unless we have tested at least have no reason to expect that the existence of one of these will make the
half of all A and have found them to have property b. It is, of course, a existence or absence of another more likely; if all these conditions are
different matter if we have independent reasons that make the existence met, then the degree of probability with which we may assume that all of
of the attribute b in all A more or less probable, or if we have reason to the b'.. b", ... are found together is (exactly as in no. 8) = m+n+m+ 1 . This
1
surmise that these objects are all equal with respect to their possessing procedure may most appropriately be called one of analogy (cf. §253).
b. In such cases, when we have indubitably perceived the existence of b Note. It is usually said that in all reflection aimed at the discov-
only in a few A, we may infer that all of the A have b with a higher degree ery of new truths there are only two ways of proceeding, respectively
of probability than is indicated by the previous rule. For example, when called the progressive and the regressive method. Although there is lit-
we have a formula we have derived through calculation, a few tests may tle unity in the definitions of these concepts, the most common describe
suffice to convince us that it is correct-not on account of the number of the former as a progression from grounds to the grounded, and the latter

218 219
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 330. General Rules

as a progression from the grounded to the grounds. The first definition method, but rather may choose them with constant attention to the form
329 seems clear enough, supposing that it has been noted somewhere that of the truth we seek, which is supposed to play the role of conclusion;
the words "ground" and "grounded" (or consequence) are taken in their and when we do this we may certainly expect that the truths we produce
widest sense, according to which any proposition which is deducible from will bring us closer to the one we want to discover. Yet it remains un-
another may be said to be grounded in it (or is its consequence). Thus I certain whether we will actually reach it, even in cases where it is really
also maintained this definition of the progressive method. With respect deducible from the chosen premises, since there are so many ways these
to the definition of the regressive method, however, it seemed necessary premises may be combined without leading to the desired goal. The in-
to indicate more precisely how one might proceed from the grounded to direct methods all have the flaw that we must randomly assume how the
its grounds. It doesn't seem correct to me to call the progressive method truth we seek runs; and if this form is quite indeterminate, if luck does not
synthetic and the regressive analytic in every case. When, for instance, favour us, we tire of the many unsuccessful assumptions before finding
one seeks the highest moral law in the way described in §327, no. 3, one something noteworthy. Each of the indirect methods also has its own spe-
proceeds progressively, since one proceeds from known truths to other cial problems as well. With the apagogic method we may proceed from
known truths; yet the truth one finally arrives at is simpler than those a false assumption (M or Neg.M), and deduce a considerable number
form which one started. Thus one cannot say that one has synthesised; of consequences from it, without hitting upon any noticeable absurdity.
one should instead say that he has resolved. A historian, by contrast, With the regressive method, we may pile assumption upon assumption,
who in order to determine the true course of an event tentatively as- only finding out after a long inquiry that they are all false or indemon-
sumes that it occurred in such and such a way and then, in order to justify strable. The inductive method, finally, only furnishes certainty when the
these suppositions, assumes certain other events, etc., certainly proceeds induction is complete, but inductions are usually difficult and tiring, and 331
regressively-but can one say that he proceeds analytically when the later often incomplete. Thus we must all wish that adepts of Heuristic would
assumptions are always more complex than their predecessors? Yet not discover other, more perfect methods. But before looking for these, we
much is riding on terminology, especially given that a different justifica- should first see if it would help to use the already known methods not
tion of these terms can be devised. But when some (e.g., TWESTEN, L., individually but-to the extent that this is possible-in combination. No
§ 175) say that the regressive procedure cannot be used for the discovery instruction seems to be required for how to combine the indirect methods,
of truths, but only in order to find a proof for an already known truth, they since this can only happen by applying one after the other, using one and
are correct up to a point, insofar as this procedure is especially suitable the same assumption-and here it goes without saying that one should
for discovering such proofs. But to say that it can only be used for this begin with the most promising assumption. But a few useful things may
and cannot be applied in cases where one merely surmises the truth, or be said about how to combine these indirect methods with the direct.
does not recognise it at all, is going too far. At one point, for instance, 1) In order to combine the direct and the apagogic methods in the
people did not know which law governed the refraction of light. Yet they most advantageous way, we must aim the former at propositions that
tentatively assumed various laws and thereby found that the sines of the stand in the relation of incompatibility with the consequences derived
330 angles of incidence and refraction stand in a constant ratio. from the hypothetical assumption Mor Neg.M, and the latter at proposi-
§.330. tions which stand in the relation of incompatibility with the propositions
obtained by the former method. If we have discovered a consequence Z
VI. Combination of several methods that follows from M which conflicts with a truth E discovered by the di-
No matter how many means we already know for the discovery of truth, rect method, then the falsity of M is proven; and if we have discovered a
we learn all too well how defective they are when we come to apply them. consequence of Neg .M that conflicts with a consequence of E, then the
truth of M is proven. But propositions usually only stand in relations of
The direct method indeed always leads us to truths, but not always to new
incompatibility if they have several constituents in common. Thus in or-
or noteworthy ones, or at least not to the truths we wish to discover. Ad-
der to get propositions like Z and E we must, in looking for a suitable Z
mittedly, we need not combine premises haphazardly when using this

220 221
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 330. General Rules

(i.e., consequences of M or N eg.M), pay attention to the constituents of gating indeterminism, i.e., the proposition that the human will sometimes
which the truths D,E, ... are composed and, when deriving D,E, ... , makes resolutions without any determining ground, and we assume this
pay attention to the constituents of Z, and strive to obtain propositions proposition provisionally in order to try the regressive method, we find
with common constituents. We will succeed all the better at this if we oc- ourselves moving on to the further provisional assumption that our will
332 cupy ourselves in turns with the derivation of Zand the derivation of E. forms resolutions without any determining ground, at least in cases where
Many examples of this procedure will come to mind for mathematicians. reason demands a certain course of action and our faculty of desire wishes
In order to give an example from another science, let us suppose that we another. In order to establish this, we make the further assumption that
had to prove the existence of God, i.e., the existence of a being that has no it would be incorrect to claim that we only do and can follow the dic-
ground of its existence. Following the apagogic method, we assume the tates of reason when they are stronger than our wishes, and that we must
opposite, i.e., that there is no being which does not have the ground of its follow our wishes whenever they are stronger than the dictates of reason.
existence in another being, and attempt to derive some absurdity or other. This assumption now becomes a target we must strive to attain though the
Since no noteworthy consequence which follows from this proposition direct method. We would, e.g., proceed from the truth that only homo-
alone occurs to us, we look for a known truth which, combined with it, geneous things may be compared with respect to magnitude (e.g., spaces
would yield consequences. The truth to us that there are beings comes with spaces, but not spaces with times or masses), and see whether the
to mind. From the combination of this proposition and our assumption assumption we just made can be proven from this.
it follows that there are also beings (at least one) that have the power to 3) If, finally, we think to combine the direct method with the method
create, i.e., the power to be the (at least partial) cause of the existence of of induction, it is obvious that in looking for the different ideas A' ,A", ...
another being, and also that these beings must also be created. Now, in standing under the idea A, we must seek those for which we may hope to 334
order to reveal the contradiction which this claim contains in itself, we prove either the truth or falsity of the propositions "A' has b", "A" has b",
seek truths concerning the nature of created or creating beings by the di- etc., by the direct method. If, for example, we were supposed to prove the
rect method. With respect to the former, it is obvious that the nature of a well-known theorem that the measure of an angle inscribed in a circle is
created being must lie (at least partly) in another being, since the ground half of that of the arc it cuts off, we would take up the three cases usually
of its existence lies in another being. Thus a created being must be acted distinguished in this case, since we can expect in advance that it will be
upon by the other being and hence be changeable, becoming gradually easier to prove these cases separately.
more perfect, while having been less perfect earlier. Accordingly, there is
no degree of force which is so small that this being was not at a lower de- §.331.*
gree at some point. If we now consider the nature of a creating being, we VII. Consultation of others' judgements and of experience
find that the act of creation does not occur in time, and hence presupposes
a power which does not attain a certain magnitude in time, but rather has Although the accumulation of new experiences is foreign to the kind of
it from all eternity. Thus it now appears that the claim that a created be- reflection for which I have undertaken to give instruction, namely, pure
333 ing could also create leads to a contradiction; namely, that there can be no reflection (§323), permit me nevertheless to mention a few things on this
power, however small, in a created being which has persisted for all eter- topic, at least for the reason that reflection is often required to decide
nity, yet a creating being must have exercised some power which it has whether this means is appropriate.
had for all eternity. Thus we recognise that there must be an uncreated 1) We have recourse to experience, strictly speaking, even when we
being. listen to the views of others on a topic, and indeed even when we seek to
2) In order to combine the direct method with the regressive method recall our own, previously formed judgements on the subject, for instance,
to good effect, we must look upon the assumptions to which the latter when we look through papers where we noted them. Yet the way that
gives rise as so many targets we must strive to reach by the inferences the consideration of such judgements (whether they be ours or those of
of the direct method. If, for example, we have the problem of investi- others) influences our reflection is so peculiar that we rightly distinguish
it from all the other ways that experience may enlarge our knowledge,

222 223
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 331. General Rules

and only call the latter the way of experience in the narrow sense. It is complicated inquiry with no guide whatsoever, may it be better to begin
335 reasonable to see what other thinking beings, or ourselves at an earlier by consulting previous judgements.
time, have judged whenever one of the following cases occurs: (a) when 4) Whenever the subject of our reflection belongs to the kind of things
a truth is sought which we could not discover without employing this that can be judged using nothing but reason and experiences which all
means, either because it exceeds the limits of all human knowledge or else people can have, all men are in a position to form a valid judgement on
the limits of our own knowledge, or can only be known in circumstances the matter. We will thus do well to ask how the general opinion runs in
that it does not lie in our power to bring about. Much information that such cases. If we discover that all, or almost all people have judged the
we can only obtain through higher revelation is of this kind, as are most matter in the same way, and when on top of this it appears that the judge-
of the truths belonging to history and other empirical sciences. (b) Also, ment that almost everyone acknowledges with one voice is not one that
when it is a matter of a truth which we are indeed able to discover without flatters our human inclinations, but rather places limits on them then, I
recourse to this means, but not without a considerable loss of time and say, we may assume with a high degree of confidence that this judgement
the use of energies that could be more beneficially applied to other tasks. (which I shall call a pronouncement of common sense) must accord with
Here belong a multitude of purely conceptual truths which others have truth. For because this judgement does not flatter human inclinations, the 337
already discovered through reflection and which we may safely accept general consent cannot be explained in the way so many erroneous opin-
on the basis of their testimony, and which are in addition so constituted ions that arise and spread can be, namely, because reason is com1ptecl by
that if we were to seek to discover them again on our own, this would our sensible nature, or because thousands have repeated without exami-
involve a loss of time and energy better spent elsewhere. Who would be nation what one has claimed without proper consideration. Instead, we
so foolish, for instance, to refuse to use any logarithms except those he must recognise that only the power of truth and the power of a quite ob-
had calculated himself? (c) Whenever what we have discovered about vious truth must have compelled everyone to avow something they would
a given subject is not so reliable that it would be impossible by seeking rather not have. - But even in inquiries which do not immediately con-
the opinions of others, or one's own earlier views, either to correct it or cern matters already decided by the judgements of common sense, such
usefully elevate the degree of its certainty. pronouncements may sometimes be used to good purpose, namely, if we
2) If this inquiry into the judgements of others is to provide the ex- are able to reduce our problem to one that can be decided in that way.
pected benefits, we must know how to determine whether and to what This is the case in almost all religious inquiries, for even if the questions
degree these judgements are credible. Here we should set ourselves the that arise here are not answered by the pronouncements of common sense,
law never to assume that someone is wrong unless we know how to ex- more reflection almost always reveals such a pronouncement from which
336 plain (or at least have tried to explain) how the error might have arisen, the sought answer follows by a brief and evident series of inferences.
or unless we have found that it would be far more improbable to say that 5) We now turn to the consultation of experience in the naITower
it is not he who is in error but those opposed to him. For more on this see sense. It goes without saying that we cannot hope to find instruction in
§388-390. this way on every question; and even where the nature of a question allows
3) Concerning the time at which we seek to learn of the judgements of it to be resolved through perception, everything depends upon the char-
others, we shall do well in most cases not to call to mind our own earlier acter of the latter. There may be perceptions which allow our question
judgements, nor to consult the views of others right from the start, but to be easily and decisively answered with the most satisfactory certainty,
rather to attempt to solve the problem with the concepts currently at our and others from which we can only infer something once we have aclclecl a
disposal. In this way we shall judge the matter all the more impartially, number of intermediate propositions, and even then only with probability.
and be all the more likely to avoid errors that we ourselves or others have Thus if it is in our power to choose among diverse perceptions, we shall
made earlier. Only where there is no fear that the authority of others or be worthy of censure if we take the circuitous path in seeking something
our own earlier opinions will lead us to consider the matter one-sidedly, which could have been reached more directly. It is well known that it is 338
and where we would be in clanger of error if we were to launch into a not always up to us whether certain perceptions which promise to pro-

224 225
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 33 l. General Rules

vide information are made now or at some other time. Rather, we must the sun around the earth; that created beings must have a beginning; that
make use of opportunities as they present themselves. If circumstances everything on earth is there for our sake alone, etc.: yet these opinions
are such that certain perceptions may be made whenever we please, then can all be incorrect, since none of them meet all the conditions enumer-
it will almost always be appropriate to postpone making them until we ated above. If, on the contrary, we find that all peoples at all times have
inquire into what can be extracted from the perceptions we have already held charity, fidelity in fulfilling promises, and the like to be praiseworthy
made. This may have the useful result of teaching us towards which cir- and dutiful, while adultery, immoderate use of food and drink, ungrateful-
cumstances we must direct our attention if the new truths thus acquired ness, etc., have been considered shameful and impermissible, we rightly
are to yield a good deal of information. Now in different cases, differ- say that these are pronouncements of common sense that impart certainty
ent methods are required to perform the desired perceptions. Sometimes beyond a doubt to the truths they concern.
it suffices to pay heed to the intuitions stimulated in us from outside, in Note 2. Observation and experiment are a pair of ambiguous words.
which case we are peaceful observers. Sometimes we must go to a par- In its widest sense, observation just means to direct one's attention to a 340
ticular place or await a specific time. Sometimes we must make a number determinate object. And taken in this sense, the object of observation
of preparations in advance, e.g., strengthening the powers of our senses need not be sensible, for all kinds of objects of which we have ideas may
with machines. Sometimes, finally, it is necessary to produce through be observed in this sense, e.g., God. In the sense of no. 5, however, the
our own activity the object or change in the external world that promises object one observes is always sensible, and observation is understood not
information for our question. Undertakings of this kind are called experi- as simply directing one's attention but also, if necessary, directing one's
ments. Depending upon whether the goal of performing such experiments sense organs towards it, and in general means the totality of actions which
is to confirm a truth already known on other grounds, to decide whether a are necessary to have informative perceptions. Experiment 1 in the widest
given proposition is true or false, or to lead us to some hitherto unknown sense means to do something because we do not know for certain, but
truths, they are called confirmatory, exploratory or random. only expect that a given result we desire will probably be produced. In
Note 1. What was said in no. 4 concerning the so-called pronounce- this sense we already conduct experiments when we direct our attention
ments of common sense may itself be looked upon as a pronouncement to certain truths in the expectation that a new truth may be deduced from
339 of common sense; it is frequently acknowledged even by the greatest them. But in the sense of no. 5 the result one aims at must be a perception
philosophers, i.e., precisely those who feel the greatest temptation to deny which will provide us with useful information, and the action we perform
it. Already HERACLITUS was compelled to admit the kind of infallibility in order to attain this result must consist in certain impacts on our envi-
of the pronouncements not of individuals but of human reason in general. ronment which we create in order to bring about the change we wish to
And it is well known how much this has been emphasised in recent times, observe. This is the way I believe we understand these words in the em-
especially by many English and after them French philosophers. It is true pirical sciences. Observation is looked upon as the generally applicable
that there are and have been many scholars who declared the appeal to means for expanding our knowledge; experiments, however, are seen as
common understanding to be a mistake. But closer consideration reveals a means that can only sometimes be applied, and always in combination
that it was almost always the case that they only inveighed against ap- with observation. Many seem to have overlooked this last circumstance,
peals to common sense in cases where it does not in fact have the claimed claiming that when experiments are performed, there is no observation.
infallibility-cases where quite special observations or experiments are
required, which the great majority of people never have and never could §.332.*
have made; or on questions where the decision has no impact on other
Vlll. Examination of one's own previously formed judgements
matters, or when it does have an impact, but one which appeals to human
passions. In such cases one may not trust the judgement of the crowd, In any reflection aimed at the discovery of new truths we must form judge-
even if it is unanimous. Thus it might be believed all around the world ments if our purpose is to be fulfilled. For that we have discovered the
that giants once existed; that day and night are caused by the movement of
Versuch; this may also have the sense of "attempt" (ed.).

226 227
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 332. General Rules

341 sought truth, and that it runs thus and so, is already a judgement. But 2) If it appears in this way that the judgement under examination
in order to arrive at this judgement, we must in most cases first form a does not have a sufficient degree of reliability, it will be necessary to
number of other judgements, which serve as premises of the former. But Jook around for other grounds for or against it; in the opposite case, this
if we wish, we may pose the question of whether we have erred with re- will still be both permissible and appropriate. Here it is obvious that
spect to any judgement we have formed with clear awareness. What one we may have a greater expectation of discovering the truth if we impar-
undertakes in order to answer such questions may be called an examina- tially consider every reason that speaks infavour as well as all those that
tion of one's own judgement in light of the similarity between it and the speak against the judgement. If we direct our attention only to that which
procedure described in §329 for the examination of a given proposition in speaks in.favour of our judgement while disregarding any reasons against
general. It is easy to see that such an examination of our own judgements, it, then we will never be able to recognise its incorrectness if it is false,
if properly concluctecl, may be quite useful. For in this way we often come and simply reinforce our error. If, on the contrary, we attend only to that
to see the incorrectness of a judgement we have formed, and are moved which seems to conflict with our judgement, then it is to be feared that 343
to revoke it; in other cases, when the examination confirms the judge- we will gradually be led to abandon it, even if it is true.
ment anew, we will adhere to it with a higher degree of confidence. Not 3) Let us now ask how long this business of seeking grounds for and
to mention that such examinations provide exercise in thinking, and may against should continue. Since for every judgement there is an infinite
just happen to lead to many new truths which we had not formerly no- number of more or less probable assumptions from which it may be de-
ticed, and so on. Doubtless, then, we can recommend that the judgements duced with more or less probability, it might well happen that continued
we form in reflection aimed at the discovery of new truths be assiduously reflection, especially when combined with other means, will from time to
examined. For this reason it is appropriate to give brief instruction on this time reveal new, previously unconsidered and at least somewhat probable
business. propositions that speakjor, and others that speak against the proposition
If someone, confronted with the question of whether a judgement he under examination. It would obviously be asking too much if someone
formed previously is correct, answers in the affirmative without further were to demand that we continue our search for such grounds as long
reflection simply because he is aware that he just formed it, then a pro- as we may still hope to discover them. Yet I know of no other rule that
cedure of this kind would not be of the slightest use to him. If it is to is both general and instructive which would govern the time and effort
be possible for us to become aware of errors we may have committee!, that should be devoted to this task. It seems easy, however, to point to
or if in the case of a correct judgement our confidence is to be increased many cases where we may justifiably break off our examination. Such a
342 with good reason, then the answer we give to the question "Is this judge- case occurs when we already possess so many grounds speaking either in
ment true?" must be grounded in a separate consideration. Now since favour or against the judgement under examination, and these have been
there must be a ground that determined us to form the judgement we are mustered in such a way that the affirmation or denial of the judgement
to examine, provided that it was not immediate, it will be appropriate to has attained such a degree of probability that we can see that further con-
become distinctly aware of this ground if we are not so already. Thus tinuation of our inquiry would never make the opposite more probable,
we must ask ourselves whether we formed the judgement immediately provided that no events outside of our control occur. In order to illus-
or, if we deduced it from others, which others? If it turns out that it was trate this, consider the following example. Suppose that we have just
formed immediately, then we may suppose that it is a true judgement with calculated that the ratio of the diameter of a circle to its circumference
the same degree of confidence that we form the former judgement, since is l : 3.141 .... We then learn from a variety of books that others have
no error may enter into immediate judgements (§309). But if we find that sought this ratio in the most diverse ways, and attained the same result, 344
the judgement was deduced from others, and are distinctly aware of these but that the few who have sought it and claimed to find a different an-
other judgements, then we will also be able to judge the degree of relia- swer do not agree with each other. Moreover, the former all claim to be
bility of these earlier judgements and whether the sort of inference used able to indicate the place where the latter have erred, and even some of
to derive the former from the latter is a perfect one or only probable. the latter have come to agree with them. In this case, I claim, we may

228 229
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 332. General Rules

justifiably break off our examination without first having learned of the a rule which would specify which propositions merit examination more
grounds that the opponents have put forth in support of their differing than others.
answer. For we may know in advance that at best (i.e., if we cannot see 5) Should we choose based on the degree of confidence, that is, should
their incorrectness) these grounds would not have as high a degree of we only examine the premises which we hold with a considerably lower
probability as those which we have already mustered for the correctness degree of confidence? It might not be completely wrong to proceed in
of our calculation. We could not reject this unless events completely out this way, but I cannot agree that it would be completely suitable. For it is 346
of our control were to occur, namely, until people tell us with the same well known that confidence may be deceiving, as erroneous judgements
or nearly the same degree of unanimity that the previous calculation was may possess, if not our complete confidence, at least a very high degree
false, and explain at the same time how it could have come about that so of it. And if we were to exempt from examination every judgement we
many made the same mistake. In the case I just discussed we may break form with a high degree of confidence, how could we ever become aware
off our inquiry, since it is no longer necessary for the immediate goal of of such mistakes?
our examination, i.e., to become more certain of the truth or falsity of the 6) Should we say that our examination should cover all the premises
judgement in question. But it does not follow from this that we may not which could not by their very nature be mistaken? But if we did this,
continue for some other reason, e.g., for the sake of exercise in thinking we would have to examine all judgements which are not immediate, i.e.,
or the discovery of other truths. Thus we might still find it worthwhile those which are deduced from others. If so, we would always have to con-
to acquaint ourselves with a few of the unsuccessful attempts to square tinue right up to the immediate judgements. How difficult this is! How
the circle, so that it may become more obvious to us how far one may err seldom (perhaps never) are we likely to succeed! We would always be
even in a science which boasts the highest degree of evidence once one starting over again, never able to look upon something we had already
makes room for some passion or other (e.g., the desire to say something examined as decided, and hence never able to assume it without further
novel). Clearly, there will also be a great many cases where further in- examination-how would we ever get anywhere? Indeed, carefully con-
345 quiry is forbidden for other reasons, e.g., because we are already too tired sidered, it is clear that we would thus get lost in an infinite process. For
to succeed if we continue, or if it intem1pts our leisure, etc. the truth that a certain judgement was formed immediately cannot itself
4) We must now ask which judgements should be subjected to this be recognised immediately. Hence if we wanted to examine every medi-
sort of examination. It is obviously impossible to examine eve1y one of ate judgement, the judgements whereby we declare other judgements to
our judgements. For since a resolution to examine a judgement already be immediate would themselves be subject to examination which, as it is
presupposes a judgement, since in every examination we must declare easy to see, would continue ad infinitum.
the judgement under consideration to be either reliable or unreliable, and 7) From what has been said thus far concerning the way the process
finally since this declaration must itself be preceded by many other judge- of examination should be conducted, it is clear that it is only possible to
ments, it is obvious that someone who wanted to examine every one of his examine a given proposition that is based upon one or more other propo-
judgements would never come to an end, since every examination would sitions taken to be true. If we suppose that the one or several propo-
force him to undertake further examinations. It would also be asking too sitions that must be assumed to be true in order to examine another M
much to require that we examine all the judgements used as premises in have a lower degree of reliability than M itself, then it is obvious that al-
order to arrive at the judgement which we consider to be the genuine an- though it might be corroborated through this examination, it could never
swer to the question before us. For here too the number of judgements to be overturned. For since the degree of reliability of a judgement is never
be examined would grow to infinity, since the propositions upon which we considerably greater than that of the premises from which it is deduced, 347
ground a judgement while examining it also appear as a kind of premise but usually smaller (because of the possibility of an error in the deriva-
of this judgement and hence of the judgement we intend to deduce from tion), the degree of probability that the proposition N eg.M would acquire
them as well. Since we cannot examine everything, then, it all comes should the examination speak against M would still remain smaller than
down to whether the choice we make is appropriate. Thus we must seek that possessed by M, because the assumptions from which Neg .M follows

230 231
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 332. General Rules

have a lower degree of probability than M. Thus even in this case we may But there is no way to avoid this risk, and it is clearly not as great as the
not switch to Neg .M, but must remain with the already pronounced judge- risk we would be exposed to were we to determine by some other rule or
ment M. From this it follows, however, that we may confidently refrain by mere chance which of our judgements should be examined. It is worth 349
from examining a proposition M in all cases where we can only do so by noting that according to this rule one and the same judgement made by
assuming propositions with a lower degree of reliability than M itself. For the same man may merit examination at one time but not at another. For
although one cannot say that such an examination would be totally use- the degree of reliability with which we form one and the same judgement
less since we would have to remain with M even if the examination spoke may be different at different times-perhaps because we may have ex-
against it-for it might at least provide some exercise in thinking-one amined it or because other circumstances have changed in the meantime.
may claim that it is not necessary for the present purpose, in which the It may also happen that at one time we know of no way to examine the
judgement M will be applied as a premise. If, on the contrary, we intend judgement without presupposing a less reliable judgement, while later a
to apply a judgement M in our reflection and we know a way to examine better way occurs to us. Finally, circumstances may change: at one time
it without assuming any propositions with a lower degree of reliability, we may be pressed for time and granted leisure at another, etc.
then we will do well always to petform this examination, provided that Note. It is not surprising that the rule set out by DESCARTES to doubt
the prolongation of our examination does not threaten to cause more harm everything at least once in one's life has frequently been challenged. For
than error would. If there is no such fear, the examination is reasonable, although one may gather from everything this philosopher said of his
since it may turn out that we are moved to correct the judgement M. For method that he himself was anything but a sceptic, still less a fervent
example, I would not subject to examination the judgement that I am one, his rule is nevertheless both incorrect and dangerous. Doubting is no
thinking right now, or that I have an intuition of something red, merely more immediately and unconditionally dependent upon our will than ac-
348 because I know of no other judgement upon which I could base my ex- ceptance or rejection. Thus one cannot claim it to be a duty or an offence
amination that would be more reliable than the former judgements. So to doubt unless one first indicates the means of bringing it about or pre-
too I shall not examine the judgement that a calculation yields the result venting it. Someone who wants to tell us that we must doubt everything
I have found if this examination would take so long that the advantages (at least once in our life) must first show how this can be accomplished.
to be gained by the correct answer (e.g., from a wager) would disappear. Some truths are so evident that we can never bring ourselves to doubt
But if there is time enough and the subject merits it, I would undertake them, no matter what we try. Of this sort, for instance, are the truths that
the examination, and continue it as long as it takes to confer such a high we are thinking or that we have ideas, etc. But even supposing we could
degree of certainty on the correctness of my calculation that every other doubt everything, why should we? Why should we raise doubts concern-
calculation to which I would have to have recourse in order to overturn it ing truths we know with great assurance, the certain knowledge of which
would have a lower degree of probability. is of such great importance to us that we cannot doubt them for even the 350
8) Judgements that we form without being aware of it cannot for that shortest of times without feeling unhappy or placing our virtue in danger?
very reason be examined, no matter how much they might merit this by Such truths are, e.g., the existence of God, the immortality of our soul,
dint of their unreliability. Thus a rule telling us how to undertake such ex- the binding nature of the moral law, etc. Who would counsel people in
aminations would be absurd, since it would require something impossible earnest to raise doubts in themselves against these important truths? It
ofus. But the rule I just set out (no. 7) is not subject to this objection, for it seems to be that DESCARTES simply failed to express himself properly
only tells us to examine judgements when we can see that this is possible here, speaking of doubt when he actually thought of examination. The
without recourse to less reliable judgements; thus judgements we are not examination of a given proposition, if this is simply an inquiry with the
even aware of are already excluded. It is indeed true that the judgement aim of becoming aware of the grounds upon which we may or may not
that it will be possible for us to examine the judgement in question with- rely upon it, is a process we may undertake without in the least doubting
out recourse to other less reliable judgements can in no way be formed its truth. The fact that we confuse examination with doubting occurs in
immediately, and hence in forming it we run the risk of falling into error. part because it is most necessary to examine propositions we doubt, and

232 233
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 332. General Rules

in part because in the process of examining a proposition we presuppose sition if we doubt the correctness of its proof. But are there not proofs
neither that it is true nor that we may infer things from it, exactly as we for some truths which are so evidently correct that doubting them would
would do if we did not hold the proposition to be true, but rather doubted constitute an absurdity, an incongruwn? But when R. defines this doubt-
it. But this happens not because we do not in fact hold the proposition to ing as a kind of meditatio analytica, it is clear that he had in mind not
be true, but rather because we cannot become aware of the ground upon doubt, but rather examination. HOLLMAN (Log., §233-240), who dealt
which it rests if we already presupposed it, since this ground obviously with this topic more thoroughly than most logicians, also failed to remove
lies in other propositions. Indeed, we must do this whenever we intend to this difficulty. De omnibus, he wrote (§233) dubitandum aliquando est.
prove the truth of a proposition we recognise as true to someone else who Du bitare vero (§234) nobis initio nihil aliud est, quam judicium suum de
does not; there too we may not presuppose the proposition to be proved, veritate vel falsitate alicujus proposition is cohibere; quo ipszmz magnum
but rather must proceed from other propositions. One may no more ob- omnino inter dubitationem et negationem alicujus rei discrimen interesse,
ject that we must doubt a proposition in order to examine it than one may satis statim apparet. 1 This is certainly correct. But is not the suspension 352
claim that we must doubt it in order to prove it to someone else. But the of judgement already a bad thing if it concerns a truth we should never
Cartesian rule would still be defective even if we replaced the doubting it for a moment remain undecided on? He explains the de omnibus (§233
requires with examination. For what does it mean to say that this exam- and 236) by saying that even claims recommended since the most ancient
ination must cover "everything"? By this, clearly, nothing else could be times should not be considered settled; this is fair enough, provided that
meant but all of our judgements. But it was already shown in no. 4 that doubting is understood to mean examining. In §238 we read that doubt
351 this is too much to ask. We can only ever examine a few of our judge- is merely a means for arriving at truth (from this it is clear that it must
ments, and must leave others unexamined. Thus we need a rule to govern really be examination). In §239 we read tamdiu dubitandum, donec de rei
our choice, and DESCARTES' rule, far from providing this, forbids such vel veritate vel falsitate distincte constet. 2 But it is not always possible
a choice. MALEBRANCHE (De la recherche de la verite, I, l) sought to to attain a distinct knowledge, i.e., knowledge coupled with recognition
remedy this defect and said "one must not assent to any propositions save of the grounds. CRUSIUS (W z. G., §538) says that "in his reflection, a
those which are so evidently true that one could not renounce them with- scholar is bound by law to retrace every proof up to the ultimate ground
out suffering inner pain and one's own reproaches." 1 We certainly do well of all knowledge, for otherwise he runs the risk of assuming unproven
if we follow the voice of conscience when doubting or rather examining propositions as proven." But would this clanger be avoided if we were
our opinions. But this voice is sometimes mute; and when it speaks there to follow this rule? What one finds in some recent treatises is no more
is one (not distinctly recognised) ground which determines the judge- precise. Thus in JAKOB' s Log., §492, we read: "One must carefully run
ment of our conscience, and it is this which we need to know about, at through one's entire system of thought, all of one's judgements and opin-
least in general terms, i.e., one must indicate the rule our conscience fol- ions, all one's powers of inquiry at least once, and doubt of the truth of
lows when allowing us to examine some judgements but not others. Nor everything one has hitherto believed long enough to discover through rig-
did RUDIGER (De Sensu V. et F, IV, 1, §3) improve upon this by stating orous, rational examination grounds which justify the opinions of reason.
that we should not doubt the proposition, but rather the proofs of it. Non This is the so-called Cartesian scepticism, which commands us to hold
de re ipsa, sed de probationibus dubitemus. Nihil hinc unquam emerg- nothing to be true without rational grounds." FRIES (Syst. d. L., p. 593)
ere incongrui potest; cum talis dubitatio sit species meditationis, nempe speaks of a "genuinely philosophical postponement of judgement, which
analyticae. 2 It is admittedly not necessary to doubt the truth of a propo- is not doubt, but rather a preparation for critical inquiry." I only know two
1Translated in the WL: The original reads: "On ne doit jamais donner de consente- actions that might be called "postponing judgement": either we do not ac-
ment entier qu'aux propositions qui paroissent si evidemment vraies, qu'on ne 1misse le 1All things ought sometimes to be doubtful. Indeed. at the start doubting is for us
leur reji1ser sans sentir une peine interieure & des reproclzes secrets de la raison." nothing other than restraining our judgement concerning the truth or falsity of any propo-
2
We should not have doubts about the thing itself, but the proofs. Nothing incongruous sition, because it is immediately quite obvious that there is an important distinction be-
could possibly emerge from this since such doubting is a species of meditation, indeed of tween doubting and negating something.
the analytic sort. 2 0ne should doubt until the truth or falsity of the thing is distinctly established.

234 235
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 333. General Rules

tually form a judgement we were just about to, because we consider how Premises supporting it, to clarity-this in order to exa·1111·ne eac h o f' th ese
~
easily we might be mistaken, or else we do not even think about a certain P ropositions which (according to §332) merits 1·t so tl1at w
. · . · ' e may assure
353 judgement, but rather turn to other things. In the first sense, postponing ourselves that no fallacy has been comnutted in deduci'ng th e cone us10n
1 ·
judgement seems to me to be nothing other than momentary doubt of the from these premises. Thus we will do well to run throuoh th " .
. . b e same se-
truth of a proposition. In the second, admittedly, it is anything but doubt- c1uence of ideas and judgements that led to this conclus · t'
~ · . 1011 severa1 1mes
ing, but I do not see how simply setting aside a judgement, not thinking from the beginning, stopping ourselves now sooner, now later and at-
about it, could be called a preparation for examining it. tending to the ideas and judgements present in our 1111·nd <at tl1e t:une. B ut
in order to be able to repeat the sequence of inferences ii1 th .
§.333. . . . e sdme way
they first occurred 111 our soul, it helps to dll'ect our attention to the same
objects that we thought of at first. It may also be useful to place ourselves
IX. Directing one's attention preferentially towards
in the same external surroundings, e_ither: in fact or at least in thought. In
individual judgements and ideas
order to break off the sequence before 1t has fully r·tin 1·ts course et'ther
sooner or later, sometimes our will suffices, but sometimes it b
It is well known that for the most part we can choose towards which . . . . may e use- 355
ful to have a1.1 external object remmd us. Fmally, it is obvious that the
judgements currently in our souls we may direct our attention and that this
more uncertam one of these premises is in our eyes·, the n1ore att en t'ion
may strongly influence the good or bad results of our reflection, by raising
must be devoted to it, provided, that is, that we know of no other way to
now this, now that judgement or idea to a higher degree of vividness, per-
reach the conclusion without using it.
haps even to the level of clarity, or at least by bringing to consciousness
sometimes more, sometimes fewer associated ideas and judgements, and §.334.
thus generating judgements we had not previously formed (§286). Thus
it is reasonable to ask for a rule governing the use of our attention in the X. Associating our ideas with suitable signs.
process of reflection. It would be incorrect to say that we should simply Advantages of this association.
strive to attend to the largest possible number of judgements and ideas.
For since this mental power is of such a nature that it can only encompass In o~der to c~rry out the elevation of ideas to clarity as required by the
a finite number of phenomena in our soul at one time, is less efficacious prev10us section all the better, and for other reasons as well, it cannot be
the more things it is occupied with, and tires more quickly the more ar- recommended strongly enough that we also represent these 1·d I I
. . · · eas t uvug 1
duous its task, it is clear that the progress of our thought is slowed, and signs. Although the use of this means does not belong to pti re re·ft ec t'10n
we tire sooner, the greater the number of judgements and ideas we con- if the chosen signs are not mere ideas or the kind of obiect
• • . J we can pro-
354 sider, and also that by directing our attention towards one thing we may duce without. bemg clearly aware of domg so, it is nevertheless .
. .. necessary
perhaps withdraw it from another which merits it more. Thus we must to speak of it here, 111 part because some of these signs can be counted
make a rational choice of the ideas as well as the judgements we turn our among the objects of pure thought, and in part because the rules we must
attention to; and it is obvious (as has already been said in §325) that the follow in designating our ideas for the purposes of our own reflection
idea of the object which is the aim of our reflection has first call on our must be presupposed as known in the theory of scientific presentation.
attention. Above all, we must make this clear. Concerning the judge- Let us begin by making a survey of the advantages a suitable notation for
ments we form concerning this object, it will be appropriate to see first our ideas can bring to our reflection. (1) Merely seeking suitable signs
where reflection leads when we do not slow its natural progress by linger- ~or our ideas often results in ideas which were formerly obscure becom-
ing on each judgement until it becomes completely clear. Thinking with mg clear. (2) ~~en if th~s does not happe.n, perhaps because the sign is
partly obscure ideas proceeds much more briskly and does not tire us so already ~o fa~mha~· that It occurs t~ us wtt~out us having to first repre-
soon. Only when this sort of reflection leads to a conclusion that we find sent the idea 1t designates, an attentive cons1cleration of the s 1·on ., ·t'll
. . . . . . • b may S I 356
noteworthy need we attempt to elevate this conclusion, along with all the help us form an 111tmt10n of the designated idea, i.e., raise it to clarity.

236 237
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 334. General Rules

(3) Only by associating our ideas with certain signs may we hope gradu- Note. It should not be overlooked that here I only wanted to point out
ally to attain the power of calling forth these ideas whenever we wish. For the benefits that signs have when used by oneself, and then only for the
the idea of the sign, as an idea of a sensible object, may be much more eas- purpose of discovering new truths. If I had spoken of the benefits of signs
ily raised to the necessary level of fluency, or else there are external means in general, or even only of the advantages they have for the discovery
for producing the ideas of this sign in us whenever we wish. But once it of new truths when they are in general use, I would have had to mention
is stimulated, the designated idea will also occur to us. (4) If we are used many other things, principally that by communicating what we have gath-
not simply to forming vivid ideas of the chosen signs (sounds, figures, ered from observation and reflection to our fellow men and transmitting 358
etc.) but rather of really producing them, then we soon acquire such fa- this to the remotest posterity, the expansion of knowledge may continue
cility in performing the necessary bodily movements that we may repeat ad infinitum.
them whenever we like. And whenever we do this, or indeed simply at-
tempt to do it, the idea belonging to the sign will be renewed in our mind. §.335.
(5) The use of suitable signs greatly facilitates the retention of ideas which
are composed of many parts. For if such an idea has been before our mind The nature of signs ·which are supposed to aid us in our
in its completeness a few times at the same time as the sign for it, such an own reflection: 1) They must be sensible objects
intimate connection is formed between all the constituents of this idea and
the idea of this sign that all recur whenever it does. But without such a It is obvious that we could not realise the just enumerated advantages
means of combination, some characteristic or other of the idea may easily of designating our ideas if the signs chosen were not suitable for this end.
be omitted. (6) If the chosen signs are persistent external objects such as Thus it is necessary to make brief mention of the attributes signs must
figures or characters, and we do not content ourselves with mere ideas of have if we are to use them in our own reflection with hope of success.
them but actually produce them, i.e., we write down our thoughts, then we First of all, it is certain that only sensible objects make for truly useful
put ourselves in a position to recall these thoughts whenever we wish, to signs. For there is no doubt that the ideas which such objects produce
357 examine them anew and, if they are found to be correct, deduce new con- in us, i.e., the so-called sensible ideas (of colours, sounds, shapes, etc.)
sequences from them. In this way we make our judgements more reliable, are among the most familiar of our ideas; nor that, although they are (as
we can impress them upon ourselves all the more firmly, and discover I believe) complex, they nevertheless arise in us with the same rapidity
truths which would otherwise remain unknown, since the sequences of as simple ideas. From this it is understandable how they can serve as
inferences involved are so long that not even the strongest memory could a means for uniting all the individual parts of which a complex idea is
retain them unaided. Just think of the truths we discover through written composed, and thus serve to bring it to mind.
calculations! (7) When we use written signs, it is possible to collect and
survey all the truths already known to us on our topic, and by frequently §.336.
and attentively running through this list discover how to further our in-
quiry. (8) Even a purely arbitrary combination of our signs guided by 2) Which can be easily displayed anywhere
blind chance can give rise to a number of new ideas and propositions, the
consideration of which may lead to new truths. (9) Next to such impor- But it is not enough that the objects which are to serve as signs in the
tant benefits, we may pass over others, e.g., that the mere coincidental process of reflection be sensible. They must also be such that it is in our
similarity and relations between signs may lead to useful thoughts. Only power to display them easily at any place. In §334 it was said that one
one more thing deserves to be mentioned here, namely, that the repre- of the advantages of using suitable signs was that the effort required to
sentation of our thoughts through signs which others can understand puts produce them can slow down the overly rapid flow of our thoughts. From 359
us in a position to submit our claims, along with the reasons supporting this it may be seen that the ease with which we are are able to produce
them, to the judgement of others. signs may be too great, as is the case with many words which suggest
themselves to us purely through habit, and are merely represented rather

238 239
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 337, 338. General Rules

than actually spoken. But if too much effort and attention is required to one we have specifically chosen it to stimulate. But if these secondary
produce a sign, it is obvious that the process of thinking is unduly im- ideas are of a kind which do not exercise any detrimental influence on
peded by its use, that the attention we must devote to the sign may lead us our judgements, if they do not lead us to ascribe attributes to the object
to lose sight of the designated idea, and that in every case our reflection that sign refers to which do not really belong to it simply because the idea
will proceed more slowly, and be more tiring. It is just as bad if we cannot of the sign is accompanied by ideas of these attributes and if, furthermore,
produce the sign wherever and whenever we wish, but only under special the secondary ideas do not attract too much of our attention or stimulate
conditions and at particular times and places. For then our thought, inso- dangerous sensations or desires, then we may nevertheless consider the
far as it has become accustomed to the assistance of these signs, will be signs serviceable. To this attribute of a sign, which I shall call its purity, 361
limited to specific times and places as well. Should someone say that we there belongs the fact that the object of which it consists is not itself
can at least imagine an object which is difficult or impossible to produce, attractive. For if this were the case, there would be the risk that upon
and that this suffices, something which, as just noted, often occurs with perceiving the sign our mind would attend to it alone, and the idea it was
the words of our spoken language, I would counter that the mere imagin- supposed to introduce would either not be called forth at all or else would
ing of a sign does not produce exactly the same effects as an externally not attain the requisite clarity. The case would be similar even if the sign
stimulated intuition, and also that even this mere imagining is not possi- itself was not attractive, but was associated with other, very attractive
ble in all the cases where we might need the sign and, provided this is ideas, perhaps because it once served as a sign of these. What may be
easy enough, actually produce it as well. said of attractive things holds equally well for repulsive things. If the
object which is to serve as a sign is either itself repugnant, or associated
§.337. with repulsive secondary ideas, it will not be able to call forth the idea it
3) An inner connection between the idea of the sign and the is supposed to designate with the requisite clarity and vividness, and will
designated idea must either exist or else be easily produced have a detrimental effect on the entire course of our thoughts. There are,
alas! all too many examples where a single detested word has hindered
A given object does not become a sign of an idea merely because we want the recognition of the most beneficial truths.
360 it to, and even if it had all the other qualities of a suitable sign, it would
not be capable of awakening this idea in our mind if it lacked one, namely, §.339.
if the idea of the object was not associated with the idea it is supposed to Special attributes of signs that are supposed to preserve our thoughts:
designate. As long as this association has not been established, the sign I) They must be sufficiently long-lasting
does not recall the idea of which it is supposed to be a sign. Thus one
of the following two things must be the case with any object we choose The attributes indicated so far must belong so generally to signs used
as a sign: either its idea must already be connected in our mind with in our reflection that they are already necessary if we use them merely
the idea we wish to designate, or else this connection must be easy to for the purpose of making our ideas more distinct. But as we have seen
establish. With a truly good sign, there is not simply a loose and indirect above, one of the greatest benefits of using signs is only realised when
connection, but rather an inner and immediate one, so that the idea of the signs are employed to give a kind of lasting existence outside of us to
the sign always brings forth that of the object without delay, and with the the thoughts that rush by within our consciousness, whereby it becomes 362
requisite vividness. possible to reawaken years later the same thoughts we had, say, today in
much the same order, and to communicate them to others. In order to do
§.338. this, however, we must not choose as signs objects which are just as fleet-
4) A suitable sign should not call forth any detrimental secondmy ideas ing as our thoughts themselves, as is the case, for example, with sounds
and words. Rather, these must be persistent objects which, once pro-
As already remarked in §285, no. 9, it is well-nigh inevitable that an duced, will continue to exist on their own for a time without undergoing
object used as a sign will call forth many secondary ideas along with the any change that would result in their no longer being the same signs.

240 241
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 340-342. General Rules

§.340. For if such confusions occur, i.e., when we fail to notice the difference
2) They should be easily recognised everywhere between certain signs because it is not striking enough, then we are in
just as bad and perhaps a worse state than if there were no difference
If we wish to use certain signs for the purpose of preserving our thoughts, at all, i.e., as if we had allowed one and the same sign to have several
if the signs are to make it possible for us at any later time to recall the meanings.
same series of ideas we had earlier as soon as we consider these signs
again, it is obviously not enough that the sensible objects of which the §.343.
signs consist merely remain unaltered in the interim; rather, it is also nec-
essary that when we look at them we recognise them as precisely what Some other recommended attributes of signs
they should be, namely, signs of these ideas. Thus what is essential in
them, i.e., what makes them signs and indeed signs of precisely these We may look upon the four attributes of signs discussed in §335-§338
and no other ideas, must be easily recognisable under all circumstances. as ones which should always be present if the signs are to be of use to 364
For if this were not the case, when confronted with such a sign we could us in our reflection, while the next four, discussed in §339-§342, should
only sometimes and after strenuous concentration of our attention recog- never be lacking if the signs are used for the special purpose of preserv-
nise that it is a sign and what it is a sign of. We would have to fear that ing our thoughts. But there are other attributes of signs which, although
this recognition would often fail to take place, that we would often guess not necessary, can nevertheless increase their utility. I call these recom-
incorrectly, and that even when we guessed correctly the difficulties in- mended attributes. (1) One of these is that the chosen signs bear a certain
sit~itm:ity to the objects standing under the designated idea, a similarity
363 volved in their interpretation would soon prove tiring.
which is not only so great that no other sensible object could be chosen
§.341. as a sign that would be more similar, but also great enough that we can
3) Identical signs should never have several easily confused meanings perceive some of the properties of the objects in the signs as well. It is
already obvious from the fact that there are objectless ideas that this at-
From what has just been said it also follows that no sign is truly useful tribute cannot be required of all signs. But even if the idea for which we
for the purpose of preserving our thoughts if it has several meanings, are seeking a sign is objectual, this object may be so peculiar, and dif-
especially meanings that are easily confused with one another. Otherwise, fer so greatly from any sensible object that we might choose as a sign
when we wish to recall a sequence of thoughts that we wrote down a long (§335~'. that. we cannot find a single object with the required similarity.
time ago and have since forgotten, such signs must give rise to doubts, Even if the idea to be designated represents sensible objects, and even if
and sometimes we will either be completely unable, or else only able signs with the required similarity could be found for each of these ob-
after laborious reflection, to determine in which of its several senses it jects, these objects may be so numerous and diverse that no sign may be
was taken. And even when this does not occur, the associated ideas which found which bears the required similarity towards all of them. We have
such a sign stimulates in our mind due to its other meanings may exercise examples in the ideas "animal", "colour", and others. Finally, the idea
a detrimental influence on the course of our thoughts. to be designated may have an object for which a quite similar sign may
be found, but the latter is so elaborately complex that it would not really
§.342. make a suitable sign. In all such cases we must relinquish the require- 365
4) Different ideas should never be expressed by ment of similarity. But when this attribute is genuinely present, there is
means of signs which are too similar no doubt that it is advantageous. For the greater the similarity between a
~ign and. the objects the idea of which is supposed to bring forth the sign
For the same reason, however, it is also wrong when the signs we use to m our mmd, the more easily we will be able to recognise its meaning, i.e.,
designate different ideas are too similar to one another, that is, when it to establish an appropriate connection between the idea of these objects
is not possible to avoid confusing them unless one is especially attentive. with the idea specified to awaken the former. The greater the similarity,

242 243
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 343. General Rules

the more it is to be expected that the mere sight of the sign will bring to idea of the sign is moderately agreeable, and if the associated ideas help
mind many of the particular attributes of the object of our reflection. Not to call forth the idea that is supposed to be designated by the sign. Thus
to mention the pleasure of being able to say why precisely this sign was a sign which looks pleasant for an idea we do not find repulsive will, all 367
chosen ahead of so many other possible ones. (2) But if a sign cannot be other things being equal, be more beneficial than one that we find ugly;
similar to the object it is supposed to designate, it may nevertheless stand while a sign that is repulsive in and of itself may be quite suitable for an
in relations to signs used to designate other objects which bear a cer- object that we should find repulsive and detestable, since it promotes the
tain similarity to the relations between the designated objects themselves, formation of the idea that is supposed to come forth, etc.
and this too is an advantage. For since the relations obtaining between Note. When LAMBERT (N. 0., II. Sem., §23) indicates as the highest
signs as sensible objects can be perceived by sight, noticing these can perfection of a sign that one might exchange the theory of the signs with
help to bring to mind the similar relations between the designated objects. the theory of the things, he seems to have had in mind nothing other than
(3) Since every sign which is an external, perceptible object must be com- the property mentioned in no. 2, i.e., that the signs should be related as the
plex, they may sometimes be constructed in such as way that one or more things themselves. But this, as may be seen from what L. acids afterwards,
of their parts already possesses a meaning. It is to be expected that the is not always entirely possible, for omnis similitudo claudicat. 1
idea that such an individual part designates will come to mind when the
whole sign is perceived. This is not a matter of indifference, since sec- §.344.
ondary ideas may be introduced in this way which may lead us astray in
366 our assessments of the designated objects. If this really happens, then it Rules for the invention and use of signs for the purposes
is an offence against the purity of signs required according to §338. But of one's own reflection
it is also possible, at least in some cases, for a sign to be composed of
parts in such a way that the peculiarities of the meanings of these parts What I have just said about the attributes of appropriate signs puts me in
facilitate the formation of the idea the whole sign is supposed to stimu- a position to indicate rules that should be observed in their invention and
late. This is a case which must occur, notably, when the individual parts use. But here I shall only speak of the rules to be followed if the signs are
of which the sign is composed designate the individual ideas of which to be used for our own reflection.
the idea designated by the whole sign is composed. It is easy to see that l) Before we invent a new sign for an idea we wish to designate, let us
we would not be justified in requiring this attribute in every case, since first see whether we already possess one, or others have already devised
the advantages it b1ings will frequently be outweighed by disadvantages one, and, if this is the case, let us retain that sign unless there are weighty
of other kinds-e.g., with highly complex ideas, the signs would have reasons why it is unsuitable. It quite often occurs in our reflection that we
to be overly intricate and thus difficult to produce. But where no such hit upon an idea that at first glance seems to be something we have never
disadvantages are present, this property is doubtless a highly valuable thought before, but when we consider it a little longer, and from different
one. (4) From this it follows immediately that it is advantageous for signs sides, and search our memory, we recall that we have already thought it, 368
belonging to simple ideas to have no meaningful parts themselves. All and indeed designated it. It happens even more often that an idea which
other things being equal, signs of this kind will be all the more com- is new to us has already long been considered by others, and provided
mendable the simpler they are or the more homogeneous their parts. For with a quite appropriate sign. If, without having first looked into this, we
this simplicity or homogeneity already points to the simplicity of the idea. wish to devise our own designation for the idea, do we not run the risk of
(5) When I demanded (§338) for the sake of the purity of a sign that the replacing the better with the worse? Moreover, if we haven't completely
object of which it consists have nothing, either in itself or in combination forgotten the previous sign, when it occurs to us at some point, how will
with others, which is either attractive or repulsive, this was not meant to we be able to avoid the error of thinking that two things which are at
require that its particular constitution or the ideas associated with it must bottom the same are in fact different? And if we want to communicate
be indifferent to the soul. On the contrary, it will be advantageous if the 1All comparisons limp.

244 245
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 344. General Rules

our thoughts to others so that they may examine them, how inconvenient means we have used from our childhood to express our thoughts, so that
it will be to have to acquaint them with the ways of speaking we have we are so accustomed to connect a specific word, or at least the idea of a
so needlessly introduced! On account of the difficulties caused by this, word, with every idea of which we are clearly aware that when we cannot 370
would it not be reasonable to retain signs that are already in general use, do this, something seems to be lacking. But if we can only imagine a word
even when they do not seem the most suitable to us? In order to force that has been chosen as a sign for an idea, but are unable easily to produce
us to reject a sign, it must have essential shortcomings, shortcomings that it, the sign will not have the attribute required in §336. Since in addition
outweigh the bother of learning something new. most sounds that we can easily produce with our mouths, or at any rate a
2) If no serviceable sign is available, we see whether among the al- great number of them, can also be represented in alphabetic script, i.e.,
ready existing signs there is one that might be used to designate our new the kind of writing where complex sounds are designated by representing
idea in the future, without creating the possibility of misunderstandings. the individual sounds of which they are composed, the requirement that
If the new meaning which the sign is to have in addition to those it already only such audible signs be chosen is in no way an improper restriction.
possesses is so different that the circumstances in which we use the sign But following this rule has the advantage that we do not need special new
will always make it obvious enough which sense is intended, we need fear signs when we want to write down these audible signs for some reason
no misunderstanding. It is all the better if the differences in one respect or other-for instance, so that we may recall them later when we have
are complemented by similarities in another, since the new meaning can forgotten them.
be retrieved all the more easily from memory-and this is a satisfactory 5) Yet only in rare cases will it suffice to have only an audible sym-
reason for our choice of this sign over others that might in other respects bol; most often we will also need a second, written sign as well-if for
369 have been just as serviceable. Thus the word "grasp", which originally no other reason than that we may write clown our thoughts so that they
designated an action of the hands, can quite appropriately be used to des- may be recalled in the future. If the audible signs are formed according
ignate the somewhat similar action of our understanding. For the two to the rule indicated above, then this written sign must simply be an ex-
meanings are different enough that we can know in each case which was pression of the audible sign in the alphabetic script. But in certain cases,
meant, yet they are similar enough that we can see why we chose pre- especially when we desire a brief overview, or where expressing things in
cisely this word to designate this mental activity. the usual vocal language would be too drawn out, we must seek simpler
3) If we find that the meaning of a sign already in use bears consider- written signs. Abbreviations obtained, e.g., by omitting most vowels or
able similarity to our new idea, so that the sign might easily be used for other easily guessed letters or syllables is perhaps the first thing that will 371
the latter as well, but that the similarity is so great that there is a risk of occur to us here. But if this does not suffice, we must devise individual,
confusing the two meanings, we consider whether some small alteration, easily drawn signs for frequently occurring concepts and propositions,
some addition or deletion, might result in a sign that would be more wel- as mathematicians have clone and continue to do in their science to such
come than a completely new sign. Thus, for example, the easily confused great benefit.
concepts which are designated by the word "Verdienst" in the following 6) When attempting to devise an audible or written sign, we should
sentences are sufficiently distinguished by the gender: "Der Anne hat keep three things especially in mind: they should be easy to produce, free
keinen Verdienst," "Der Reiche hat kein Verdienst." 1 from association with ideas that may lead us astray, and clearly different
4) If a suitable sign for our idea cannot be found in the way described, from any other signs that designate other ideas. The reasons for this may
there is nothing for it but to devise a new one. If the idea we seek to des- be found in what was said above. If on top of this we are able to make our
ignate is one which is going to be used frequently, then even if we already sign somewhat similar to the designated object, or the relations between
possess a suitable enduring, written sign for it, it is advisable to go fur- this sign and others similar to those between the objects they variously
ther and devise an audible sign for it, indeed one we can produce with our designate, so much the better.
mouth and write clown in our existing system of writing. Sounds are the 7) If the idea to be designated is simple, then the sign must be as
1'The
simple as possible, compatible with its being perceptible and readily dis-
poor man has no income," "The rich man has no merit."

246 247
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 344. General Rules

tinguished from other signs. Signs for complex ideas, however, should be or fatigue or for the sake of some other benefit, such alternation will al-
combinations of signs of the simple parts of the idea, provided this does ways be blameworthy, especially if our goal is simply to write clown our
not result in a sign which is overly complicated. If the latter would be the thoughts so that we may communicate them to others or examine them
case, the sign should be composed of signs for the most important parts later. Apart from the fact that it is bothersome when we or others are
of the entire idea. And if even this would be asking too much, as would not familiar enough with the different signs, when we read at a later time
be the case with a sequence of ideas, each of which was composed of its what we have written, the sight of clifferent signs for one and the same
predecessors, then on occasion a new, simple sign must take the place of idea will make also us feel compelled to seek the reason which led us
a complex one. With the Roman numerals, for instance, the numbers 1, to use now one, now another of these signs. If it is not obvious enough
2, 3, 4, are represented as I, II, III, IIII, but the number 5 as V, and 6, 7, 8, what reason there might have been for the alternation, this will cause the
9, accordingly as VI, VII, VIII, VIIII, while the number 10 is represented unpleasant sensation that we do not know how to answer this question,
as X (i.e., V and V). or else we will guess based on reasons which are not in fact valid, sus-
8) Once we have decided that we want to use a sign for our idea, pecting an indication of a distinction when none was intended, and in any
372 we must take care that this sign is so intimately connected with the idea case dividing our attention and tiring us. It is another matter when we
that every time we represent the sign, we also become conscious of the ourselves are caught up in reflection and already know and are familiar
designated idea. Otherwise, it might happen that we use the sign without with the several signs we intend to use to express the same idea. Here it
thinking the idea it is supposed to designate. This is a flaw that not only can in fact be useful to express the thoughts which are to be considered
destroys the entire aim of our employing signs, but also can give rise to the more closely not only in one way but in all the various ways we are used
grossest errors, if the obscure idea that a glance at the sign produces leads to expressing them. For since each of these signs is associated with its
us to ascribe attributes to the designated object that really only belong to own series of secondary ideas, things which can help us solve our prob-
the sign or else to the object the obscure idea represents. Even with the lem may occur to us, and thus lead us more rapidly to our goal. People
highly developed signs of mathematics, people commit e1rnrs when they will scarcely believe how beneficial this is. Yet who has not had the ex-
forget the wider sense that these signs have in certain cases, manipulating perience of the same proposition which has been represented repeatedly 374
them in ways that are only justified when the signs are taken in their in the same words appearing new if expressed differently?
narrower senses. Thus it would be hasty to conclude from the equation 10) If it is a mistake to use now this now that sign for the same con-
ax= bx that a = b, if x represents a quantity in the broadest sense of this cept for no reason, then it is an even bigger one to have fewer signs than
word, which includes zero. In order to avoid this danger, we must not we have ideas, i.e., to use the same sign now in this, now in that sense,
only repeatedly think of the sign at the same time as we think the idea it when the context does not always make it clear that we are speaking of
is supposed to designate at the start, but also recall this idea from time to different things in different places. If this is not obvious enough then not
time when looking at the sign. only others, but we too may forget these differences of meaning and think
9) Sometimes we need to have more than just one audible and one that something we have shown to be true of objects comprehended by one
written sign, since the constant repetition of the same sign whenever the sense of our ambiguous sign is also true of objects covered by the other
same idea recurs would not only prove revolting and fatiguing, but also sense. But if this can happen by forgetting even in cases where at the
cause a certain confusion, meaning that we would not be able properly beginning we were fully aware at the start that the same sign was being
to grasp the thought that is represented. How awful it would be if the taken in different senses, it is easy to see that the clanger of error is all the
concept of speaking or that belonging to the word "that" had to be ex- greater when we do not even know at the time of using a sign in a differ-
pressed by the same word every time it occurs in the following propo- ent sense that we are doing so. This happens to us quite often when we
sition: "Someone told me how someone else had communicated to him either frequently take a sign in several similar senses (even if fully aware
373 that people had already said I had claimed etc." But where it is not nec- of doing so at the start), or else hear others do this. From this comes the
essary to use different signs for the same idea in order to avoid disgust rule that when expressing our ideas through signs we must be constantly

248 249
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 344. General Rules

attentive to ensure that we always take the same sign in the same sense in the art of representing it and in bringing about the changes in the exter-
or, if this is not feasible, to check whether we have assumed that some- nal world required to produce it, that we can sometimes do either without
thing demonstrated for the one sense also holds for the second. It is the being clearly aware of it. Usually the idea of the sign arises, sometimes
violation of this rule that is responsible for most of the errors committed even accompanied by some of the actions required to produce it, when the
in the purely conceptual sciences. When it is claimed, for example, that idea it designates is only dimly present to our consciousness. And if we
375 no extended thing can be composed of unextended parts, that every effect wanted to prevent this, if we did not want to allow ourselves to represent
must be later than its cause, that man has no duties towards Goel, that this sign or pe1form any of the actions required to produce it, we would
miracles are no proof of divine revelation, and so on, these are all errors have to forcibly constrain ourselves, and disrupt our train of thought. But
based upon ambiguities that have not been appropriately noticed. what benefit would come of this restraint, especially since the signs we
11) If we may not allow ourselves to use the same sign now in this, are accustomed to are easy and appropriate enough, and in addition are
now in that meaning, then the metaphorical use of a sign (§285, no. 8) usually merely imagined rather than actually produced? Rather, precisely
must also be looked upon as an error. That is, it is an error to take a sign because thinking with signs, and representing these signs outside of us (in
in a sense that is only similar to its proper sense, one which we specify a kind of writing) comes naturally to us, the signs may sometimes bring
only to the extent of demanding that the expression as it occurs in a given us the great benefit of getting to know and being able to examine more 377
context be interpreted in a way that would not have us say something carefully a thought that was only briefly before our mind. Thus it should
absurd, but where the context does not fully determine the meaning of not be held against us if we sometimes speak or write in the process of
the sign. When we do this, we expose ourselves along with others to reflection without being able to distinctly indicate what we have said or
whom we communicate our thoughts to the risk of altering the meaning written. We may do this, I say, if our goal is to become aware of what
of the sign as it recurs, and thus falling into error. For since the meaning we have accomplished along the path of mere obscure ideas, and thus
in which the sign is supposed to be taken is left indeterminate, there is do not intend to look upon the results as established truths, but rather as
no wonder that we connect now this, now that meaning with it without something to be rigorously examined.
being clearly aware of doing so, and are all the more easily deceived. Note. Given the many flaws of all existing languages and systems of
Thus it does not seem too severe, at least in the case of reflection aimed at signs, even the most perfected, and the indisputable fact that they may all
determining concepts more precisely, to lay clown the rule that one must be improved in certain ways, it must be exceedingly difficult to devise a
forego any metaphorical use of signs. completely new universal language, answering perfectly to all the wishes
12) Given that I said (§333) that it was neither useful nor even possi- of logic, a language which would render all others superfluous, at least
ble to employ only clear ideas in reflection, it is obvious that one cannot for scholarly use. Of that which RAYMONDUS LULLUS, AGRICOLA,
376 demand that every thought be represented in signs. On the contrary, it BRUNO, BECHER, ATHAN. KIRCHER, the great LEIBNIZ, KUI-ILMANN,
is enough if we attempt to do this for the part of our thoughts where WILKINS, SOLBRIG, HARTLEY, BILFINGER, MEIER, PLOUCQUET,
this already happens through force of habit, or where one of the bene- KALMAR, BERGER, LAMBERT and others have either proposed or con-
fits enumerated in §334 may be expected if we do so-e.g., if this makes sidered as already accomplished in spirit, nothing has survived the test
it easier for us to become clearly aware of an idea, if writing clown our of time. Without a doubt, the most important was LEIBNIZ' s claim that
thoughts would allow us to preserve them more faithfully than mere mem- he could indicate a number for every concept in such a way that merely
ory would, or if we intend to communicate them to others so that they may by combining these signs according to certain universally valid rules one
examine them. could bring forth the most important truths. What should we say to this?
13) But if we are permitted occasionally to reflect with obscure ideas, Was the great man overhasty? Did he flatter himself with the thought that
then it must also be permissible to apply signs without being clearly aware he had made a discovery that he only later discovered to be illusory, and
of the ideas we connect with them and, indeed, even if we are not clearly was he later unwilling to admit his error? Might not the thing he sought,
aware of the signs. For if we have often used a sign, we acquire such skill and which he thought he had found, be a bare impossibility? 378

250 251
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 345, 346. General Rules

§.345. only does the recognition of such attributes and relations provide an ex-
cellent exercise in thinking, it also gives us the opportunity to notice a
XI. The use qf images connected with our ideas great many errors we would otherwise have missed, it leads us to a num-
ber of consequences that otherwise would not have occurred to us, and
If what I have said in §284 about the images connected with our ideas is makes us rightly more confident in the correctness of the judgements we
not false, then in our reflection many such images of the objects we want make. Thus in all reflection involved with a difficult inquiry, where there
to judge will present themselves unbidden, and we will be able to intro- is clanger of getting tangled up in the web of our own concepts, we will
duce others that may be raised to a high degree of vividness if we dwell do well to take a closer look at the logical attributes and relations of our
on the idea to which they belong. The question arises of whether and in own judgements and ideas, and often to make a separate problem of their
what cases we do this, and of how we should allow ourselves to use such determination. It is obvious, however, that we only do this for ideas and
images. Ordinary people, when they set out to make a judgement about judgements when it promises to be beneficial.
an object, begin by calling forth an image accompanying the concept of
this object, and try to make it as vivid as possible. They then ascribe the §.347.
attributes they find in this image to the objects themselves. This proce- XIII. Estimating the reliability of the answer we have discovered
dure should be rejected in part, but not completely. For we must doubtless
first consider the idea which englobes the object or objects about which All of our judgements, with the exception of the few that we form either
we intend to make a judgement (as was already said in §333); from this directly or without the mediation of a probable inference, enjoy only a 380
it naturally results that the image connected with this idea (if we should limited degree of confidence (§319). Thus in a complete solution we must
happen to have one) also appears, and we are right to make it more vivid only claim the proposition to be true with the degree of confidence that
rather than suppressing it. For given the way that this image was pro- accords with its actual probability, and only declare it to be the required
duced in us, it may well lead us to many useful thoughts. Many of the answer with the degree of confidence that accords with the probability
attributes that belong to this image actually belong to all of the objects of the second claim. It is also obvious that, generally speaking, it is less
as well, while others belong to at least some of them; finally, the truth harmful to err on the low side in this double question of confidence. Thus
that one of these attributes belongs to none of the objects may well be it is reasonable at the encl of an inquiry, provided that circumstances and
a truth worth taking to heart. In any case, we may look upon the image time allow for it, to undertake a new consideration aimed at determining
as well as the propositions it suggests to us as worthy of our attention. the degree of confidence with which we may assume that the proposition
379 We would only do wrong in immediately taking these propositions to be
we have discovered is true, and an answer to the question we had before
truths, since we should first examine them, and allow the results of this us. But since this degree can only be determined in a very few cases, we
examination to determine whether we should accept or reject them. must content ourselves with an approximation, remembering to err on the
low rather than on the high side. Thus we must consider not only the rea-
§.346.* sons that speak in favour of our decision, but also those that speak against
it. We must also bring to mind how often others have erred before us when
XII. Consideration of the logical attributes and they imagined they had found the answer to this problem, and how often
relations of our judgements and ideas we ourselves have been deceived by the mere appearance of truth with
other problems, if not this one. But if the following conditions are met,
The logical attributes and relations of our judgements and ideas are those the result of our inquiry will attain a degree of reliability that can and
with which the concepts of logic acquaint us, e.g., what is the subject (provided we are not afflicted by a general scepticism) will set our mind
and what the predicate in a given judgement, of what parts a given idea at rest; for this reason they are called indicators (or criteria) of certainty:
is composed, etc. Becoming distinctly aware of these attributes and re- (1) if our judgement (as it is usually said) forces itself irresistibly upon
lations in our reflection will only rarely fail to yield benefits. For not us, i.e., when all attempts to think of things being otherwise simply bring

252 253
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 347. General Rules

forth the judgement that they are not (see §43); (2) when we recognise fe vrai/ 1 but not II me paraft, je pense/ 2 But are we not sometimes de-
381 with a high degree of confidence that our judgement belongs to the class ceived by first impressions? And must not what is true stand up to long
of those which we form without any mediation (§311). For the reliability reflection, and prove itself? The important criterion of common sense (no.
of these judgements is at least as great as the reliability of our recogni- 5) has been misrepresented by some, who go too far in claiming it to be
tion that they are immediate; (3) when we discover that our judgement the only one, and thus neglect to indicate more precisely the cases where
may be deduced from other, highly reliable judgements by an easy and it is applicable. The late HERMES (Einl. in die kathol. Theo!., 2nd ed.,
secure inference. (4) Even a judgement that has been deduced through a I, p. 217 ff.) laid great stress on the following criterion that he himself
long and intricate sequence of inferences can have a high degree of relia- had devised. Having remarked that with practical reason there may also
bility if this sequence of inferences has been run through many times, if arise a necessity to take something as true which is theoretically doubtful,
the same result has been obtained in different ways or, finally, if many he expresses the indicators of such cases as follows: "We are obliged to
other people have examined our reasons and found them convincing. accept as true a theoretically dubitable cognition when the fulfilment of
(5) Our judgement acquires an almost infallible certainty if it is con- a certain unconditional, universal duty depends upon our making this as-
firmed by the pronouncement of common sense in the sense explained sumption (namely, the present fulfilment of the duty) in all and only those
in §331. (6) All propositions of experience, strictly speaking, are based cases where there is no reason to doubt of its truth which can be inferred
upon merely probable inferences from propositions of the form: "If cer- from some special case of the universal duty in question." The objections
tain intuitions a, b, c, d are often found together at the same time, then I have to this view, which resembles the Kantian method of postulation,
they are (probably) produced by the same cause." But if the number of have already been stated in §315. I also believe that in order to know that
such cases is large enough, propositions of this kind may attain a degree a case of duty exists (e.g., to bury a corpse) it is by no means necessary to
of reliability that is equivalent to that of complete certainty as regards its hold something to be certain which is theoretically dubitable (here, that
effects (§161, §317-319). the man is actually dead); rather, it suffices that there is an overwhelming 383
Note. The theory of the criteria of truth and certainty has been so probability that the performance of this action will promote the general
much discussed that I can only mention a few of the most recent views well being more than its omission (§321 note). Indeed, I believe that the
on the subject here. GEBNER (Specitl. u. Traum., II, p. 10) would have condition that HERMES requires for the assumption that a case of duty
it that the only criterion of truth is an inner compulsion, the coercion of exists can never occur in actuality. He would have it that we can only
thought. But although I myself (§291, no. 5) claimed that our judging is assume that a case of duty exists if no grounds for doubt are opposed
anything but arbitrary, it seems to me that the words compulsion or co- to this assumption which would not apply to all other cases. Obviously,
ercion are not suitable here. For is any coercion present, anything which however, such an assumption is an experiential proposition, which has a
goes against our will, when we judge, e.g., that we are now having a degree of probability that always falls short of certainty, and it is precisely
382 pleasant sensation? And is not this judgement both true and certain when this shortfall that provides the full measure of the grounds for doubt. No
we form it? But perhaps these words are simply meant to convey that matter how small this may be in some cases, it is always possible to think
with truth we have a feeling that it would be impossible to judge other- of other circumstances under which it would be smaller; thus there is no
wise? We do in fact often speak of such a feeling of impossibility, and case where this reason for doubt is so small that none could be smaller.
I myself used a similar expression in no. 1, though I took care to define
§.348.*
it. For we can never actually feel that something is impossible. Rather,
we can only learn that all our previous attempts to bring it about (in the XIV. Additional rules concerning the conditions of thought
present case, all our attempts to convince ourselves of the contrary of What I have said so far is just about everything I have been able to no-
what we hold to be true) were in vain. According to COUSIN and DAM- tice concerning the correct method of rational reflection. The only thing
IRON (Psycho!., I, p. 148 seq.) the only things that are true are those that
1It is so, it is true.
present themselves to us without any reflection, where we say II est, voila 2 It seems to me, I think.

254 255
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 348. General Rules

remaining is to touch upon several rules that concern not thought as such with another that is merely similar to it, and so on. (4) Let us also stop
but rather the circumstances in which thinking is done. (1) Experience our reflections as soon as we feel fatigued. For not only will we work
teaches us that we are not always able and disposed to undertake the busi- without success and simply waste time, indeed run the risk of mistaking
ness of reflection. It is easy to see why this is so. All reflection, as mental error for truth, if our forces are spent, but also our health may suffer se-
activity, requires a certain mental strength and, due to the intimate con- rious and hard to repair damage. (5) Nothing is more dangerous for the
nection between mind and body, bodily strength as well. Even if it can recognition of truth in reflection than a decided inclination for or against
never be said of a simple being like our soul that long exertion or other a proposition, i.e., a wish that we might be brought through our reflection
384 activity will tire or weaken it, there is no doubt that our bodily forces vary to find the proposition either true or false. There is no disputing that such
considerably. Thus merely because we lack the necessary bodily strength wishes are quite often present: we wish for various reasons that we might
and conditioning, it can occur that we are unfit for reflection. This is the be persuaded that a certain claim is true, e.g., because the proposition in
case, in particular, when we have previously engaged in long, strenuous question would license us to satisfy our sensual desires, or would justify
reflection. We must also have control of our attention and be able to di- our previous actions, or sometimes even for moral reasons. Naturally,
rect it towards a particular subject for a long time if we are to reflect on such wishes are not always without effect; rather, they often lead us to
it. This can be quite difficult, however, when our mind is occupied with direct our attention to the genuine or merely apparent reasons in favour
other matters, and even more difficult if the object we are supposed to of the claim we favour and to ignore those that speak against it. Indeed, 386
reflect on recalls these other matters. Thus, insofar as possible, we must we should not forget that we can do this without being distinctly aware of
choose a time when we are disposed to reflect. We must either be healthy it ourselves. But whether we do this intentionally or not, it is understand-
or at least free of the illnesses that hinder thought or our ability to pay able that we often succeed in our endeavours, i.e., we take the proposition
attention to a determinate subject. Our mind must be at peace, there must to be genuinely true, no matter how false it may be in and of itself. Thus
be no other object present that we find so attractive that we cannot tear if we wish to avoid the danger of such errors of self-persuasion (§306),
ourselves away from it. (2) Just as the condition we are in is anything we must watch out for such wishes and, if we cannot prevent ourselves
but indifferent to the business of reflection, so too is this the case for from having them, must set ourselves the rule of always paying most at-
the things surrounding us. If these make too strong, varied, and unusual tention to the reasons which speak against what we so eagerly wish to
impressions on us, then they draw too much of our attention, and it be- find true. (6) Our reflection is disturbed in another manner when fear and
comes impossible to follow through to the end the sequence of ideas we hope colour our expectation of the conclusion we shall reach. For either
hope will lead to the discovery of the truth we desire to know. If, on the we are too hasty or, even if we proceed slowly, we may miss altogether
contrary, the impressions the external world makes on us are too weak something that is right under our noses because the peace of mind re-
and uniform (as is the case, say, when we intentionally close off some quired for observation is lacking due to the confusion of our senses. We
of our senses), our awareness of the external world will gradually dwin- must strive to keep ourselves free of such overwhelming fears and hopes,
385 dle, making us incapable of properly retaining the ideas or judgements and to this end must either (if this is possible) try to forget the importance
we have just formed, etc. Our thought would thus become as defective the conclusion will have for us, or (if that is impossible) try to reduce
and unreliable as it does when we dream. One who wishes to reflect suc- the question before us to several others which, considered individually,
cessfully must therefore choose an environment that does not draw too do not have the same importance, but together provide an answer to the
much of his attention, and also not shut off his senses to the degree that former. Thus, for example, an accountant who is supposed to sum a large
his consciousness of the external world becomes like a dream. (3) It can- number of entries and who hopefully expects that this sum will equal a
not be recommended strongly enough that we do not proceed too quickly certain number, can help himself in this respect by breaking up the en-
in reflection. For mere haste is often enough responsible for our not ade- tries into two or more groups. If none of the above means is possible or
quately considering the reasons supporting an opinion we have adopted, helpful, then we are incapable of undertaking the inquiry properly, and
or for our confusing a judgement we wanted to retrieve from memory must ask others to look into things for us. Thus, for example, even the 387

256 257
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 348. General Rules

most competent doctor is not capable of properly judging the condition name for it. To my knowledge, there is no word that fully expresses the
of a patient whose life is too dear to him. (7) With inquiries where errors concept of this mistake, and we have only loan words for the two most
can easily creep in, no matter how collected our thought, it is necessm·y to noteworthy species of this genus. The care taken to observe certain rules,
repeat the inquiry many times and, where possible, to reach the answer to even if not excessive, can be detrimental if the rules are incorrect. This
the question before us in different ways. If we have tried this, and found case is not noteworthy enough to merit designation. But even when the 389
the same answer in every case, it is obvious that we may have even more rules are correct, an exaggerated observance of them can lead to clum-
confidence in its correctness. For even if we have always taken the same siness that might otherwise have been avoided. Our activity will be too
path and never thought of changing the course of our thoughts, accidental slow and clumsy, we will misapply a correct rule, exceed the just measure
differences in the circumstances under which we repeat one and the same in its application or, paying too much attention to one rule, forget others.
inquiry will introduce diversity into the sequence of our ideas; thus it is The case where this occurs for moral reasons-e.g., from fear of evil,
possible that in repeating these reflections we shall either avoid an error of doing wrong-is especially worthy of attention. It is usually called
we committed when reflecting the first time, or else become aware of it scrupulousness or having an anxious conscience. If it does not occur for
thanks to the light shed by the newly introduced ideas. If we have gone so this reason, but instead merely for the sake of the (sensible) pleasure of
far as to try different ways, using now these, now some other premises, it following rules, and is accompanied by a greater or lesser want of judge-
would be still more odd if we did not perceive any errors. For the error to ment, it is roughly the same thing that is called pedantry. Prof. KRUG
remain undetected it would either have to be the case that its source was (L., § 184, note; Aesth., §62, note 2) describes a pedant as one who "es-
in one of the premises we did not change and which was overlooked on timates the value and importance of things according to a conventional
every occasion, or (far more improbably) that we made different e1rnrs in standard, in itself quite arbitrary, to which he has become accustomed."
every case, but such errors as led to the same conclusion. (8) From the But in his Dictionary he defines pedantry as the flaw of "setting a high
above explanations it is clear that we will do well to repeat our attempts importance on trivialities when communicating with others (?)." It seems
to answer a question not in immediate sequence, but rather at appropri- to me that this first definition sounds roughly like a definition of the con-
388 ate intervals, and to alter our environs or other things within our con- cept of a mistaken adherence to tradition, while the second sounds like
trol in order to ensure that the course of our thoughts is always different. a definition of persnicketiness. In my view, a pedant does not have in-
(9) In cases where the sought answer does not suggest itself even after correct ideas about the value and importance of things; rather, he merely
long inquiry, we must guard against impatience. For if we are annoyed overestimates the importance of certain rules of procedure. That these
we are all the less in a state to discover the truth we seek. And does not rules must be conventional does not seem to me to belong to the essence
reflection whose conduct is disagreeable affect our health? We should of pedantry. Would we not call someone a pedant who gets caught up
rather set the matter aside as soon as we begin to lose patience and return in rules of his own devising, impeding his own activity and rendering
to it later, when we are more fresh. (10) It should also be noted that every- himself incompetent? 390
one has his own peculiarities that he must get to know in order to direct
his reflection. Some, for instance, will think better when their bodies m·e
at rest, while others will think better when they are engaged in some light
physical activity. (11) In conclusion, it may not be superfluous to warn
against an overly scrupulous observance of the rules that are supposed
to govern reflection. For one may be too careful in following rules, and
worrying about whether one has followed all the rules may make one less
likely to succeed.
Note. The last mistake I mentioned is encountered not only in reflec-
tion but in so many other activities as well, that it is desirable to have a

258 259
Particular Rules

PART II a divine revelation of which we have learned. Other truths aim at the
improvement of our earthly condition, teaching us of means to free the
Particular Rules human race from this or that affliction, and making our stay on earth
more pleasant. Still other truths promise no immediate use, but lead us
§.349." to hope that they might be applied in the future, or else are valuable for
providing us with exercise in thinking. Certain truths are useful for our-
I. Discovering suitable problems selves alone, others for thousands of people; some are unknown only to
us, others generally unknown, etc. It should not be thought that the order 392
When, in §325, I claimed that it is always advantageous to have a specific in which these different kinds of truths are here enumerated is the order in
problem in mind when reflecting, I tacitly assumed that the problem was which we should make them the object of our reflection. It is not the kind
a suitable one. Now the question of what sorts of problems we should set of usefulness, but rather the magnitude that matters, and even work that
for our reflection is itself a useful problem for our reflection. And since it is quite necessary in itself can be set aside with good conscience if this
is anything but easy to answer this question, this seems the right place for postponement does not create any disadvantage and there is in the mean-
a little instruction on how to look for problems. It is obvious, however, time something for us to do that could not be done as profitably later, or
that a problem is all the more suitable, the more we (a) may expect in which would make us better able to carry out the former. This much is
advance that we will really find the truth we seek and (b) the greater the beyond doubt: we must occupy ourselves most often with the question
promised benefit of recognising this as yet unknown truth. For though of what our duties are. Everything we do should be accompanied by a
it cannot be denied that we sometimes make important discoveries by distinct or obscure consciousness that it is right. And special reflection is
chance when occupied with questions that seem utterly futile, this occurs often, though not always, required to produce this awareness. Someone
very infrequently and rational people must guide themselves by what is who is unaccustomed to daily thinking about his duties, asking himself
most probable. Supposing that the degree of probability that we will ac- whether he has any erroneous beliefs concerning his duties, whether any
tually discover the truth we set out to find in our problem is = p and the of the changes in his circumstances has brought about changes in his obli-
expected utility of the recognition of this truth is U, the motive that gations, will not remain free from error in an area where mistakes have
391 could lead us to attempt to solve this problem would have a magnitude of
the most harmful and shameful consequences, no matter how much other
p. U. This quantity vanishes if either U or p does. Thus we should set knowledge he may have. Sometimes it is a matter of considering a ques-
aside problems when we can see that the truth in question, no matter how tion which, regardless of how important it may be, need not be decided
sure we might be that it would not escape us, would be almost useless, on the spot, since nothing need change in our present behaviour no mat-
and also when it is extremely improbable that we shall discover a truth, ter how the decision turns out. Sometimes the nature of the question is
no matter how important knowledge of it might be. But given that the such that we could not possibly deal with it in one go, perhaps because
expected usefulness of knowledge as well as the conjectured probability years of inquiry would be required. Sometimes it cannot be decided until
of succeeding in an inquiry can change from one moment to the next, it is we are older, or have acquired skill in thinking, previous knowledge and
obvious that one and the same problem may be rightly dismissed at one experience we now lack. In all these cases, no one will blame us if we 393
time and just as rightly taken up at another. Recognising a truth may be turn to other, less important matters from time to time, even though we
useful in several different ways. Some truths are principally necessary aren't yet completely clear on the answer to our question. One gathers
for us because they lead us to a recognition of our duties. Among the from this, in particular, how people who have an exceptional talent, or
truths that belong here are the general moral truths as well as the truths are young, or find themselves in circumstances where they can do little
concerning our present circumstances, from which we gather what our that is useful, may be justified in devoting a considerable part of their
duties are at the present moment. Other truths serve to provide us with time to inquiries that promise little immediate benefit apart from that of
the desire and power to fulfil our duties. Of this kind are teachings con- providing exercise in thinking. But no matter how unpracticed someone's
cerning God, the immortality of our souls, the existence and content of

260 261
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 349. Particular Rules

judgement may be, and no matter how little previous knowledge he may other ideas. (d) We may ask about an idea that englobes more objects
posses~, there are still an infinite number of useful truths which he may than these; (e) one which englobes fewer objects; or (f) one which en- 395
learn either through pure reflection, or else reflection combined with eas- alobes /'Jrecisely these objects. One may ask (g) for an idea that enalobes
b b

ily performed perceptions, provided only that he sets himself the problem 1110 re objects than these ideas but fewer than some other given multitude
of discovering them and directs his attention towards them. Thus in order of objects; or (h) for an idea that englobes both more and less than the
to put ourselves in a position to choose suitable problems, nothing is more given multitude of objects; or (i) for several ideas which together englobe
necessary than to ensure that many questions and problems can occur to the given multitude of objects, etc. Finally, (k) we may combine the
us. In order to accomplish this, that is, to direct our attention towards all given ideas in complete propositions and undertake similar inquiries with
sorts of useful questions when we set out to reflect, and merely to recall respect to the latter.
useful problems, specially made books might be of good service. If no 5) If we have several mutually exclusive ideas A,B,C, ... , i.e., if we
such external aids to recollection are available, nothing remains but to consider several distinct individual things or kinds of things, we may ask:
consult the ideas and knowledge we already have in order to arrive at all (a) in what respects do these things agree; (b) in what respects do they
sorts of concepts and knowledge we still lack. differ; (c) is there a thing or kind of things that is intermediate between
1) In the first place, every individual idea we consider may provide them, i.e., one that is closer to A than B and closer to B than A, etc.?
the occasion for a variety of quite useful discoveries when we ask the 6) If we consider an individual proposition, we may: (a) ask about
following questions and attempt to answer those which promise to be its constituents; (b) determine the logical species to which it belongs,
394 of greatest benefit: (a) whether the idea is simple or complex, and if whether, e.g., it is analytic or synthetic; (c) investigate its truth or falsity;
complex, what its parts are; (b) whether it belongs to the class of redun- (d) alter some of its parts and then undertake the above investigations with
dant ideas, and thus might be simplified without alterinab its extension·' respect to the new propositions.
(c) whether an object does or indeed can correspond to it; (cl) whether 7) If we have several propositions before us, we may ask about their
it has only one object or several; (e) which ideas have a wider, which a relations, e.g., whether they are compatible, whether there are relations
narrower extension; (f) which ideas are equivalent to it; (g) which ideas of deducibility or exclusion between them, etc.
stand to it in a relation of exclusion, either as contrary or contradictory, 8) If a proposition under consideration appears to be true, we may
or in a relation of overlapping, or coordination, etc. ask: (a) for a proof of its truth; (b) for the degree of confidence with
2) If the idea we consider appears to be one that applies to an actual which we may accept it; (c) about reasons that appear to speak against it 396
object, we may ask: (a) whether a thing of this kind is even possible; and how they may be refuted; (cl) whether it has a ground of its truth, and
(b) whether there is one in actuality; (c) whether it exists necessarily; if so, what that ground is; (e) what consequences flow from this truth;
(d) which attributes belong to it necessarily; (e) which contingently; and whether its discovery brings about changes in our duties, or could be
(f) which attributes it might have. used to improve the condition of ourselves or others; (f) we may also
3) If our idea concerns a way of acting, we may investigate: (a) the ask whether the attribute p that the proposition S ascribes also belongs to
circumstances under which the action is possible or impossible; (b) the objects not comprehended under the proposition S, i.e., whether Smay be
circumstances under which it is morally good or evil; (c) the motives that generalised; similarly, (g) if there are objects that lack this attribute, and
might determine us to perform it, etc. if so, which ones?
4) If we have several ideas before us: (a) we can ask about their 9) If the truth we have before us states that some actual object or
relations to one another, both with respect to content and to extension; alteration exists, we may ask: (a) about its cause; (b) whether this cause
(b) provided that the ideas are objectual, we may ask about an idea that consists in the activity of a rational being, and in this case, what aim the
englobes them all, i.e., a similarity between all the objects falling under being's action might have had. We can also ask (c) about the effects of
these ideas. (c) We can ask about an attribute which distinguishes the this object, and (cl) the ends towards which it might be applied as a means.
objects comprehended under these ideas from certain other ideas, or all

262 263
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 350. Particular Rules

10) If we have several truths of the forms "A has p", "B has p", "C has even when we do intuit the whole. But if we do not individually intuit the
p", etc., and thus know of several individual objects or entire genera of parts of a given idea, it is understandable why we are unable to form the
objects that all have the attribute p, we may ask: (a) whether these objects judgement that these parts occur in that idea. Thus, from the mere fact
have other common attributes and (b) how they differ in other respects. that we are unable to indicate on the spot the parts of which a given idea is
11) If we have a couple of truths of the forms "A has p" and "B does composed, we are in no way justified in inferring that it has no parts and
not have p", and thus know of two individual objects or genera which is thus simple. In order to judge even somewhat reliably in such cases,
differ in a certain attribute, we may ask: (a) about any further differences we must repeatedly attempt to intuit the idea whose content we wish to
between them; (b) about other respects in which they agree. determine, and to prolong this intuition as long as possible. For the longer
Note. I must leave the question of whether the thought of a book the intuition lasts, the more we may hope to perceive the individual parts
as mentioned above is worth pursuing for others to decide. Supposing, which are combined to form the idea, especially if our attention is focused
however, that people do not find it suitable to have all fields of human precisely on discovering these parts, i.e., we consider the idea with the
397 knowledge covered in one and the same book, since in that case each intention of noticing its parts. Only if it should happen that, despite all
would have to search for the questions that are useful for him within a our efforts in repeated trials of this procedure, we are unable to perceive
multitude of others, it would in no way follow that catalogues of ques- anything that may be considered a part of the idea would we be permitted
tions drawn from a single science or questions that might be answered to surmise, with a very small degree of probability, that the idea actually
by a given class of people in certain circumstances would be worthless. has no parts and instead belongs to the class of simple ideas. It can also
Indeed, people have already hit upon this idea, writing questions, e.g., happen that while intuiting an idea for a long time we see other ideas that
for travellers and the like. BACON' s well-known desiderata, however, are not actually its parts, but occur at the same time, belonging perhaps to
were supposed to encompass all the sciences, and would thus represent a the associated image, which may lead us to mistakenly take them for parts
catalogue of the first sort. of the idea. In order to avoid such errors, we must investigate whether the
ideas which appear to be parts of a given idea can really be combined
§.350.* in the way they must in order to form a single idea, namely, the one in 399
question. Obviously, there must be several such ideas, and among them
II. Analysing an idea given to our consciousness certain connecting concepts, e.g., the idea of having, the idea "which" and
the like. If this is not the case, then it is obvious that these ideas cannot be
It is my hope that the goal of this part (namely, to provide instruction on
said to be parts of the given idea, which cannot yet be declared complex.
the various kinds of reflection) will best be reached by working through
Thus, for example, after intuiting the idea "red" for a long time, the ideas
the catalogue of problems with which reflection aimed at the discovery
"rose" or "blood" may also occur to us. But since we find that these ideas
of truth may deal, emphasising those that require special instruction and
are not and cannot (without the help of other ideas) be combined in the
arise in more than one science. Now one problem that arises in almost
way required to produce a single idea, we may not claim them to be parts
every science is that of analysing an idea given to our consciousness, i.e.,
of the idea "red'', but only ideas associated with it. If, on the contrary,
the demand that we correctly determine whether an idea of which we are
we are in a position to combine these ideas, or certain others m,n,o, ...
cmTently conscious is simple or complex and, in the latter case, what parts
regardless of how we may have come by them, into a single idea M where
it has and how these are combined. At first glance it might be thought an
it is not immediately obvious that M is different from the idea A we seek
easy matter to answer a question of this sort, since it seems that everyone
to define, further examination will be aimed principally at determining
who possesses an idea must know whether or not it is simple and, if not,
whether M and A can be interchanged in every case where one of them
what parts it has and how they are combined. We know from experience,
is combined with other ideas to form new ideas and entire propositions
however, that this is one of the hardest problems of all. For because most
without any difference coming to light. If we notice no such difference,
398 of our ideas are not raised to clarity or, what amounts to the same, are not
we may conclude that the idea M, i.e., the idea we form by combining
intuited by us, it often occurs that the patis of a given idea are not intuited,

264 265
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 350. Particular Rules

m,n.o, ... is nothing other than the idea A resolved into its parts, and dation, omitting certain parts of M and incorporating some new ones. If
we will have succeeded in indicating the pa1is of A and the way they are we finally succeed in producing an idea M that stands up to the above
combined. Thus we may believe that the idea of the word "nothing" is kind of scrutiny, it admittedly does not follow that A and M are identical,
exactly the same as that expressed by the words "not something", since since two ideas that are merely interchangeable would also have this at-
the latter may be substituted for the former in any proposition without tribute. But if we have formed M by combining the ideas m,n,o,p, ...
400 altering the sense. which seemed to us to be contained in A, then it is not likely that Mand A
If the idea A that we are supposed to define belongs to the class of will be different if they have the same extension-provided, that is, that
those that have objects, then clearly the idea M which we form by com- the idea A is not redundant ( §69), in which case it could certainly occur
bining m, n, o, ... could not be the same as A if there were even one object that we have put M together using fewer parts than are actually thought
which stood under one of the two without standing under the other. Thus in A even though the two have the same extension. Only a frequent and
if it is possible for us to procure other ideas X ,X' ,X", ... of some of the attentive consideration of the idea A can protect against this.
objects standing either under A or M, then one way of testing the correct- In my opinion, we may only hold ourselves to be justified in claim-
ness of our definition would be to investigate whether each of the objects ing that a concept M is simple if we have failed in repeated attempts to
mentioned stands under both A and M, i.e., whether all of the proposi- form a concept [A, B, C, ... J from other concepts A,B,C, . .. (which
tions "X is A" and "X is M", "X' is A" and "X' is M", "X" is A" and obviously may not include M itself) that is equivalent to M, i.e., repre-
"X" is M", ... , and among them the propositions "X is A" and "A is sents exactly the same objects. For it seems to me that all simple ideas
X", are acceptable. Thus I test whether the ideas stimulated in me by the have this in common: for none of them is there an equivalent idea which 402
expressions "polygon" and "a plane figure bounded by straight lines" be- does not contain the idea as one of its parts. This seems to follow from
long to the same objective idea by investigating whether every polygon is the following considerations. If the concept M is simple, then there must
a plane figure bounded by straight lines, and whether every plane figure be, I believe, one or several truths of the form "M has p" which may be
bounded by straight lines is a polygon. If we discover that every object considered independent basic truths. But if Mand [A,B,C, ... ] are
standing under A also stands under M, but that the converse does not hold, interchangeable ideas, then for every truth of the form "M has p" there
the idea M is not the same as A, but rather is a wider idea. It may thus will be an equivalent one of the form "[A,B,C, . .. ] hasp''. Thus if the
be surmised that we have not discovered all of the parts m, n, o, p, ... of former is a basic truth, the latter must be as well. But propositions of the
which A is composed, or at least that we have not combined them in the latter sort do not look like independent truths; rather, whether they are
appropriate way. Thus we must focus our attention again on A, and look true or false seems to depend on the nature of the individual constituents
to see whether we may perceive some parts q, r, s, ... we did not notice A,B,C, ... , and thus on certain truths of the form "A has a", "B has~",
before, parts which may be combined with the aforementioned ideas to "Chas y", etc. Thus we obtain a contradiction if we assume that a simple
produce an idea that stands up under examination. If we do not notice idea is equivalent to another idea. Be that as it may, this much at least
any, we must try to see whether a different way of combining the parts may be claimed: the claim that an idea M is simple, even though there is
m,n,o,p, ... might produce an idea of natTower extension. If, on the a concept [A,B,C, ... ] equivalent to it, will be viewed with the greatest
401 contrary, it turns out that while every M is A, not every A is an M, then suspicion. For, provided that we are reasonably sure that M is not a part
Mis too narrow, and we may conclude either that we have mistakenly of A,B,C, ... , how would we make sure that Mand [A,B,C, ... ] are
taken some of m,n,o,p, ... for parts of A, or at least have not combined really different ideas? For given all that has been said on this topic, the
these correctly. Thus we must see whether permuting the parts or omit- mere fact that we are not aware of any constituents such as A, B, C, ...
ting some of them can produce an idea with the the same extension as when we think M is a reason with little or no weight. Thus, for example,
A. From this it is obvious what we must do if it turns out that neither even though many scholars hold the concept of possibility (or of what
all M stand under A nor all A under M. As both of the aforementioned can be) to be simple, if it can be shown that the definition given in § 182
flaws are combined in this case, we must combine two methods of emen- produces a concept with the same extension, then no one can dispute that

266 267
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 351. Particular Rules

possibility is a complex concept and my definition is correct. For hope- with a given curve is of this sort, for this definition would cover many
403 fully no one will deny that none of the concepts used in that definition lines that we do not call tangents, and would also not cover many lines
(namely, actuality, negation, purely conceptual truth, etc.) as defined in we do call tangents. (f) The idea M may well have the same extension as
earlier sections, contains the concept of possibility. A, but not the same content, and thus be only equivalent to A. This occurs
with the definition of a point as the limit of a line, since the concept of a
§.351.
limit is not contained in that of a point. (g) If we consider the way that we
Mistakes in carrying out this task may come to misunderstand the idea to be defined A, the following case
is noteworthy: we misunderstand A merely because we contemplated not
Given that the definition of an idea is a difficult problem which is some-
A alone, but rather one or more other ideas A',A", ... as well, without
times very important, it will not be superfluous to warn against the most
recognising that these differed from A, and then mistakenly took parts of
common mistakes that can be made in carrying out this task. It happens
A',A", ... for parts of A itself. We may quite appropriately say that such
all too often that (a) we declare concepts to be simple when they are in
definitions miss the mark. Of this sort, it seems to me, is the definition
fact complex merely because we learned them in our earliest childhood or
of Goel as a being that has the ground of its being not in something exter- 405
else in circumstances which did not permit us to notice their constituents.
nal but rather in itself. For that God has no ground of his being is quite
Thus great philosophers have declared concepts such as those of exten-
correct, and drawn from the consideration of the concept of God. But it
sion, temporal sequence, movement, and unity as well as the ideas red,
seems incorrect to say that Goel has the ground of his own being within
blue, sweet, etc., to be simple, even though it is probable (at least to me)
himself. This thought seems to have arisen because people consider an-
that they are all complex. (b) But it can also happen that we claim an
other concept, namely, that of a finite being, and it lies in the concept of
idea to be complex when it is in fact simple. This occurs most often be-
a finite being that it must have a ground.
cause the idea to be defined belongs to the class of object-ideas and we
notice that it stands under many other higher ideas, which makes it look §.352.
like the idea contains all these higher ideas as parts. Thus many have
thought that the concept of actuality must be compounded from the idea III. Whether a given idea is real or imaginary,
of possibility, since everything actual is possible. (c) Often the idea M and whether it has an object
that we form by combining the ideas m,n,o, ... is wider than the idea
to be defined A, especially when we think of other constituents without Not only in scientific inquiries but also in everyday life, when we use an
being distinctly aware of them, and thus do not explicitly cite them. Thus idea, we desire to know first of all whether an object can correspond to
404 the geometers who defined a circle as a line, all the points of which are it, and whether an object in fact corresponds to it. It is obvious that in
equidistant from a given point, must have tacitly and unwittingly thought order to decide the matter, we must have formed the idea in question and
that all these points lay in one and the same plane. (d) Again, it often hap- raised it to clarity. For if this were not the case, how could we make a
pens that the idea M which is produced from the given parts is narrower judgement concerning it? To this end it is, though not indispensable, at
than the idea A which is to be defined, a mistake to which we are espe- least to be recommended that we first inform ourselves whether the idea
cially prone if we think only of some of the cases in which A can be used. in question is simple or, if complex, what parts it has, i.e., to raise it to
We have an example in the well-known definition of a straight line as one distinctness. For knowledge of the parts of the idea can make it much
which is determined by the situation of its two end points, where the case easier to determine whether an object can correspond to it or not. If we
of lines that are infinite in one or both directions has been overlooked. discover that it has no parts and belongs to the class of simple ideas, it
(e) Sometimes the ideas M and A stand in the relation of overlapping, would already be decided that it is a real idea (§70); and whether or not
each applying to some objects that the other does not. One usually says it is objectual will result directly from its nature. If, however, the idea in
in this case that our definition is both too wide and too narmw. The def- question is complex, and of the form [Something]( a + b + c + d + ·· ·),
inition of a tangent as a straight line that has only one point in common then we first try to see whether the attributes a,b,c,d, ... that are united 406

268 269
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 353. Particular Rules

here conflict with one another, i.e., whether any of the propositions No A be only one sum of all the B. But even if the idea A is not of this form,
is B, No A is C, No B is C, etc., can be proven from purely conceptual it can usually be decided easily enough whether it has only one or more
truths. If this is the case, it is decided that the idea is imagincuy (§70). If than one object, provided that A's objects do not have actual existence.
not, then it is real. But this does not yet decide the question of whether Here it is a question of whether closer consideration reveals that the de-
the idea is objectual, even in cases where the idea has the form of an terminations contained in the idea suffice to determine every attribute of
idea that applies to objects, e.g., the form of a concrete idea (§60). In its object. If so, then there is only one object; if not, several. Thus with
order to determine this, we must also decide whether the attributes that the concept "an even number which lies between 4 and 8'', it is obvious
the idea would ascribe to its object presuppose actual existence or not. that no other object than the number 6 meets this condition, and hence
If not, the idea is to be declared objectual. For if its object need not that the idea is singular. It is far more difficult to determine whether the 408
be something existing, it is obvious that such an object could only be idea has an object when the given idea is a pure concept whose objects (if
lacking if the assumption that there were such an object contradicted a it had any) would have to be actual. Apart from the concepts mentioned
purely conceptual truth. But if the idea in question is of the sort that above, where it lies in their form that they cannot have several objects,
requires the actual existence of its object, nothing remains but to attempt I can only claim with confidence that the concept of God and concepts
to see whether the existence of such an object can be proved from purely equivalent to it have only one object. With ideas of this kind, only ex-
conceptual truths or, this failing, from experience. perience can tell us whether or not an object corresponds to them. But
merely from the fact that experience has so far shown us no such objects,
§.353. or only one, we are in no way justified in concluding that there are none
or only one; rather, it is probable that if we have found one, there are in
IV. Whether a given object-idea has only one or several objects fact several of this kind.

If it is often difficult to determine whether or not an idea A has an ob- §.354.


ject, it is often even more difficult to say whether there is only one such
object or several, i.e., whether the idea before us is a singular idea or a V. Whether an idea is redundant; purification of redundant ideas
general concept (§68). If we manage to find a pair of ideas of the forms
[A]b and [A]non b, and have assured ourselves (following the instruction One of the virtues of a rigorously scientific presentation, as shall be shown
of the previous section) that they are both objectual, then we would ad- later, is that it avoids all redundancy (§69) in the concepts and ideas it em-
407 mittedly have shown that the given idea A encompasses several objects. ploys. Thus the problem of determining whether a given idea is redundant
For whatever stands under [A] b certainly does not stand under [A]non b, arises quite frequently, as does that of finding an idea equivalent to a re-
yet both stand under A. In order to find ideas such as [A]b and [A]non b dundant one. It is obvious that if we are to solve such problems we must
we must try to bring to mind and examine all the attributes that we do not first know the idea and all of its parts, and have made all of these distinct.
know in advance to belong either to all A or to no A (i.e., attributes b such For how could we judge whether an idea has more parts than it needs if
that we do not know in advance that "All A have b" or "No A has b" is we do not know what these parts are? But when we do know the parts
true). We easily convince ourselves, for example, that the idea "triangle" of which an idea is composed, the next thing to determine is whether the
is a general concept, since we discover that the idea of a triangle that is idea belongs to the class of objectual or to the class of objectless ideas.
equilateral as well as the idea of a triangle that is not are objectual. If, 1) In the former case, if the idea is to avoid the flaw of redundancy,
on the contrary, we can discover no attribute of this sort, then we may one may not omit even a single one of its constituents without it ceasing 409
conclude with more or less probability, though not with certainty, that A to have the same extension it did before. Thus we must inquire whether
is a singular idea. Sometimes, however, for instance when the idea is of it survives this test, that is, we must investigate (for the parts where the
the form "The sum of all B", it already lies within the form of the idea answer is not obvious in advance) whether any part can be removed and
that it can only have one object provided it has any at all, since there can still leave an idea with the same extension. If none can, then the idea

270 271
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 355. Particular Rules

is free from redundancy as it stands. Otherwise, it is redundant, and we to their extensions is whether these ideas have any objects in common,
must remove constituents from its content until we obtain an idea that sur- i.e., whether they are concordant (§94). If the idea A is to have an ob-
vives the test we just described. Now there are two ways of investigating ject in common with another idea M, the idea [Something] (a+ m) must
whether an idea Y which we obtained from a given idea X by omitting have objectuality, and conversely. Thus if we only wish to compare two 41 l
some of its parts has the same extension. First, we may decide as we do ideas, A and M, we need only, following the instructions of §352, inves-
in general whether a pair of ideas X and Y are equivalent, namely, by ask- tigate whether the idea [Something] (a + m) is objectual. It is obvious
ing whether the propositions "Every X is Y" and "Every Y is X" obtain. how one must proceed if we are comparing several ideas A, M, R, ... and
In the special case where Y is composed of parts of X, however, there asking whether there is an object comprehended by all of them. Here
is a quicker way to decide the matter. For if we suppose that the given we must investigate whether [Something](a + m + r + · ··) is an objec-
idea X is of the form [Something]( a+ b + c + d + · ··) and the idea Y is tual idea. But if we ask whether there is a relation of concordance be-
obtained from X simply by omitting the parts c + d, then the equivalence tween the several ideas A, B, C, . . . on the one hand and M, N, 0, . . .
of the ideas X and Y depends merely on whether or not a proposition of on the other, this amounts to asking whether there is an object standing
the form "Every [Something](a + b + · ··) has (c + d)" is demonstrable. under one of A, B, C, ... and under one of M, N, 0, .... We will answer
Thus, for example, it can be shown that the concept of "a being, that has in the affirmative or negative depending upon whether among the many
powers" is redundant, since it can be shown that the proposition "every ideas [Something] (a + m), [Something]( b + m), ... that can be formed
being has powers" holds. by combining each of A,B,C, ... with each of M,N, 0, ... there is an
2) If, finally, the given idea is objectless, it is called redundant if every objectual idea. If, finally, we ask whether several groups of ideas A, B,
objectual idea we can form by altering some of its parts is redundant. C, . . . ; M, N, 0, . . . ; R, S, T, ... are concordant, this amounts to
Thus we must first attempt to form such object-ideas from the given idea, asking whether there is an object that stands under one of A, B, C, ... ,
4 IO and then see whether these are redundant, and if so, which constituents under one of M,N,O, ... and under one of R,S,T, .... Thus we must
are the ground of the redundancy of the new ideas we obtain. investigate whether there is an object-idea among the multitude of ideas
[Something](a +m + r+ · · · ), [Something](b + m + r+ ···), ... that may
§.355.
be formed by combining each one of A, B, C, ... with each of M, N, 0, ...
VI. Investigating the relation between the extensions of given ideas and each of R,S, T, ....
2) If we know that a relation of concordance holds between given
The problems mentioned so far are the most imp01tant ones concerning ideas, i.e., they have at least one object in common, the further ques-
individual ideas. If we have several ideas, however, one may also ask tion arises whether they stand in the relation of equivalence (§96), i.e.,
about the relations between them. The knowledge of the relations be- whether they have all their objects in common. Now if we are investi- 412
tween ideas with respect to their content (e.g., whether they have any gating whether an individual idea A is equivalent to another M, it comes
parts in common) is immediately obtained once one has specified the na- clown to whether either of the ideas [A]non m or [M]non a has objectual-
ture of the ideas following the instructions given for the first problem. ity, or (what amounts to the same) whether the two propositions "Every
Thus here we shall deal only with the consideration of relations between A is M" and "Every M is A" hold. From this one can see what must
ideas with respect to their extensions, supposing that they are objectual. be done if more than two ideas are involved. But if we are speaking of
When it comes to comparing of the extensions of ideas that have no ob- entire groups of ideas, the claim that these groups are equivalent means
jects in common, we are only rarely able to say whether their widths are that every object comprehended by one of these groups (i.e., represented
the same or which of the two is greater. In cases where the number of by one of the ideas belonging to this group) is comprehended under the
objects represented by each individual idea is finite and known to us, the other groups as well. This will occur when none of the following ideas
answer follows of itself. is objectual: [A](non m +non n + · ·· ), [B](non m +non n + · · · ), ... ,
1) Thus the first question that arises when we compare one or sev-
[M](non a+ non b + ··· ), [N](non a+ non b + ···), .... Thus we must
eral ideas A, B, C, ... with one or several others M, N, 0, ... with regard

272 273
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 355. Partirnlar Rules

see whether in fact all these ideas are objectless; or, what amounts to the (§ 103). We recognise the presence of this case by discovering that the
same, whether the following propositions hold: No A is a [Something] idea [Something] (a+ m) is objectless, or, what amounts to the same, that
(non m +non fl+···), No Bis a [Something]( non m +non fl+···), ... , one of the two propositions "No A is M" or "No M is A" holds. But if
No Mis a [Something] (non a+ non b + · · · ) , No N is a [Something] (non a+ several ideas A, M, R, ... are to stand in a relation of exclusion, we must
non b+ · · · ), .... show that all of the following ideas are objectless: [Something] (a + m),
3) Another relation between concordant ideas is that of subordination [Something]( a+ r), [Something](m + r), ... ; or we must show that the
(§97). Whether one individual idea A is subordinate to another Mis eas- following propositions are true: No A is M, No A is R, No Mis R, ....
ily decided if we investigate whether the two following propositions are If entire groups of ideas A, B, C, ... ; M, N, 0, ... ; R, S, T, ... stand
true: Every A is an M and not every M is an A-or, instead of the latter, in a relation of exclusion, then it must be the case that no object standing
that the idea of an [M]non a has objectuality. But if it is asked whether under one of these groups stands under any of the others, i.e., that there
the collection of ideas A,B,C, . .. is subordinate to the collection M,N, is a relation of exclusion between the groups of ideas A, M, R, ... ; A, M,
0, ... , we wish to know whether every object that stands under one S, ... ; A, N, R, ... ; A, N, S, ... ; B, M, R, ... ; B, M, S, ... ; B, N, R, ... ;
of A,B,C,D, ... also stands under one of M,N, 0, ... , and in ad- B, N, S, ... , etc.
413 dition that there are objects that stand under one of M,N, 0, ... but 6) In order to determine that a pair of ideas A, M or two groups of
do not stand under any of A, B, C, . . . . This will be the case if each ideas A,B,C, ... and M,N,O, ... stand in a relation of contradiction
of the ideas [A](non m +non n + · · · ), [B](non m +non n + · · · ), ... is (§ 103), we need to investigate whether the idea " non A" is equivalent
objectless and also at least one of the ideas [M](non a+ non b + · · · ), to M or whether [Something] (na + nb + nc + · · ·) is equivalent to M, N,
[NJ (non a+ non b + · · ·) has objectuality. Thus we must direct our in- 0, ....
quiry towards these ideas. 7) If, finally, the collection of ideas A,B,C, ... is supposed to ex-
4) Finally, concordant ideas may stand in a relation of overlapping haust the extension of another idea M, then A,B,C, ... must be mutu-
(§98). We say that individual ideas A and M stand in this relation if ally exclusive and also collectively equivalent to M. To investigate this
there are objects standing under both A and M, but also some that stand question, the methods of nos. 2 and 5 must be applied simultaneously,
under A but not M, and others that stand under M but not A. Thus we i.e., we must show that the idea [M] (non a +non b + · · ·) as well as the
must investigate whether each of the three ideas [Something]( a + m), ideas [Something]( a+ b ), [Something](a + c ), [Something](b + c ), etc.,
[Something]( a+ non m), [Something]( non a+ m) has objectuality. If one are objectless. 415
group of ideas A, B, C, ... is to be compared to another M, N, 0, ... to see
whether they are overlapping, then there must be, in addition to the ob- §.356.
jects standing under A,B,C, ... and simultaneously under M,N,O, ... ,
VII. Discovering an idea that contains a similarity between given objects
also some that stand under one of A, B, C, ... but not under any of M, N,
0, ... as well as some that stand under one of M,N, 0, ... but not
A problem that recurs frequently in all reflection is that of discovering
under any of A,B,C, ... Thus among the ideas [Something](a + m),
the respects in which certain objects X,Y,Z, ... are similar to one an-
[Something]( a+ n), ... , [Something]( b + m), [Something]( b + n), ... ,
other. But since every similarity is simply an attribute that the objects
as among the ideas [Something](a+non m+ non n + · · · ), [Something](b+
X, Y, Z, ... have in common, one soon realises that in order to discover
non m +non n + · · · ), etc., and also among the ideas [Something](m +
a similarity between these objects we must already be acquainted with
non a+ non b + · · · ), [Something](n +non a+ non b + · · · ), there must
them to some extent and thus have some ideas that apply to them more
be at least one that is objectual. Other cases of overlapping, which occur
specifically. For if we had no knowledge at all of these objects except,
less often, are dealt with similarly.
say, knowing that they are things, it is obvious that we could indicate
5) If a pair of ideas A, M does not stand in a relation of concordance,
no other similarity than that they are things, and this is hardly ever of
414 then, provided that they are objectual, they stand in a relation of exclusion
any use. Yet it is not strictly necessary for us to have ideas that apply

274 275
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 356. Particular Rules

exclusively to these objects, even though this can be useful. For if the it will be easiest to decide whether they have the attribute. If the degree of
ideas A, B, C, ... through which the objects X, Y, Z, ... are given to us similarity between the objects X, Y, Z, ... that may be claimed by virtue
have such a wide extension that together they encompass other objects of the ideas A, B, C, ... is quite unequal, and if it is known that some of
R. S . ... as well, the similarities that we may discover by means of these them, e.g., those represented by A and C, are the least similar, we will do
ideas will obviously be those holding between X, Y, Z, ... and R, S, .... well to compare these first before turning to others. For since these have
But if the ideas through which we know X, Y, Z, ... are so narrow that the smallest number of common attributes, we spare ourselves many in-
together they encompass only these objects, then it is possible that we quiries if we only see whether the attributes that they have in common are
will discover similarities that hold between X, Y,Z, ... alone. No matter shared by the other objects.
what kinds of ideas we may have of X, Y, Z, ... , the search for similar-
ities will essentially consist in trying to learn as many attributes of these §.357.
objects as we can by means of the ideas A, B, C, ... , and then seeing how
VIII. Discovering an idea that furnishes a difference
416 many and which of these attributes are common to X, Y,Z, . ... Every at-
between given objects
tribute a for which we can demonstrate the propositions "Every A has a",
"Every B has a", "Every C has a", etc., will be a similarity we have dis-
The problem of discovering differences occurs just as frequently as that of
covered between the objects X, Y, Z, .... Sometimes it will happen that
discovering similarities. Now a difference between objects U, V,
the given ideas already point to some common attributes, when they are
W, ... on the one hand and X, Y, Z, ... on the other is simply an at-
of the forms: [Something](a+b+c+ · · · ), [Something](a+b+d + · · · ),
tribute that belongs to one of these classes but not to the other. From this
[Something](a + g + h + ... ), etc., where the mere comparison of their
it is clear that in order to discover a difference between given objects we
constituents makes it clear that their objects have the attribute a in com-
must first have certain ideas of them. But these need not be ideas that
mon. But even where this is not the case, and the ideas of the objects to
apply exclusively to these objects. For even if we suppose that the ideas 418
be compared do not have a single constituent in common, it cannot be im-
A,B,C, ... , through which the objects U, V, W, ... are known to us, or
mediately concluded that the objects themselves bear no similarity to one
the ideas M,N, 0, ... , through which we know X, Y,Z, ... , encom-
another. For, according to §64, every object has infinitely many attributes
pass other objects in addition to these, any difference that we can gather
that an idea which applies to it, even exclusively, need not mention.
through the consideration of these ideas, i.e., every attribute that belongs
Since, according to the law mentioned in §284, ideas of objects that
to all of A, B, C, ... but to none of M, N, 0, ... will nevertheless represent
are quite similar are easily associated with one another, it can happen that
a genuine difference between the objects U, V, W, ... and X. Y, Z, ....
certain particularly obvious similarities between objects we are compar-
For an attribute that belongs to all of A, B, C, ... also belongs to all of
ing occur to us without any reflection. The less obvious ones may be
U. V, W, ... , while an attribute that belongs to none of M,N, 0, ... also
discovered in the way described above. Our task will be rendered eas-
b~longs to none of X, Y, Z, .... Thus an attribute that belongs to all of
ier if we do not direct our attention exclusively for too long to only one
A,B,C, ... and to none of M,N, 0, ... also belongs to all of U, V, W, ...
class of the objects we are comparing, but instead switch from the objects
and to none of X, Y, Z, ... , and is thus an actual difference between
contained under A to those contained under B, and if we do not linger
them. What is necessary is that the ideas A, B, C, ... and M, N, 0, ... ,
on attributes when it can be known in advance that they are not common
through which, respectively, we know the objects U, V, W, ... and X, Y,
to all the objects. Nor is the sequence in which we consider the objects
Z, ... , be mutually exclusive, i.e., that there be no object that stands both
417 a matter of indifference. It is best to begin with the class of objects we
under A,B,C, ... and under M, N, 0, .... Otherwise, as long as we
know best, i.e., those of which we may hope to learn the greatest number
know of no other ideas than these, it would be impossible to discover any
of attributes with little effort. As soon as we discover an attribute belong-
difference between these objects. For, in order to indicate a difference be-
ing to this class, we immediately see whether it can be shown to belong to
tween given objects that are known to us only under the ideas A,B,C, ...
the others. And here it is best to begin with the classes where we suspect
on the one hand and M, N, 0, ... on the other, we would have to find

276 277
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 357. Particular Rules

an attribute that belongs to all of A, B, C, ... but not to M, N, 0, .... follow that we must always be in a position to perceive this difference.
But if there is even one object that stands under A, B, C, ... as well as This will often be difficult or indeed impossible for us, especially if we
419 M,N, O, ... , then it is obvious that no such attribute could be indicated, are required to express the difference in terms of pure concepts, while
since it would have to both belong and not belong to the given object. It the ideas A, B, C, ... , M. N, 0, ... consist of mere intuitions or differ
is also the case here that we will be able to discover more differences the only in the intuitions they contain. In order to make this work quicker
narrower the extensions of the ideas are, and that it is most advantageous and easier, the techniques described in the previous section may be used;
in this respect if the ideas A, B, C, ... represent the objects U, V, W, ... only it should be noted that simply because certain attributes a, a, ... ,
exclusively and M,N, 0 . ... represent X, Y,Z, ... exclusively. For if taken individually, do not reveal any difference between U, V, W, ... and
the ideas in question are wider, then we will only be able to discover X, Y, Z, ... one may not conclude that they never do so together. For if
differences between the objects U,V,W, ... and X,Y,Z, ... that they all of these attributes belong to all of U, V, W, ... , it may still be the case
have in common with many other objects; and the wider the ideas, the that although none of them is absent from all of M, N, 0, ... , they are
greater the number of these other objects. But if they have the narrowest never all found together in any one of X, Y, Z, .... In this case neither a 42 l
extension possible if they are to represent U, V, W, ... and X, Y, Z, ... , nor a, ... would by itself represent a difference between U, V, W, ... and
we may become acquainted with differences that obtain only between X, Y, Z, ... , yet their sum (a+ a+ · · · ) would. Thus after we have run
these objects. One way of discovering differences between the objects through the attributes a, e1.., ••• that are common to the things U, V, W, .. .
U, V, W, ... and X, Y, Z, ... through mere reflection, when these are given and found that none is a difference between U, V, W, ... and X, Y, Z, ... ,
through the ideas A,B,C, ... and M,N,O, ... respectively, is to attempt we must still investigate whether a combination of two or more of these
to bring to light as many attributes of the objects as we can through the attributes would represent such a difference. To this encl, it is a good idea
given ideas, noting whether some of the attributes which belong to one when examining the individual attributes that belong to all of U, V, W, ...
of the classes of things, e.g., to U, V, W, ... are the exact opposite of to single out those that are only found in some of X, Y, Z, ... , noting at
others that belong to the things of the other class X, Y,Z, .... If we find the same time which of these objects have or lack the attributes. If this
o
an attribute that can be affirmed of all of U, V, W, ... but must be de- is recorded appropriately, one may in the encl see at a glance whether it
nied of all of X, Y, Z, ... , i.e., with respect to which the propositions is possible to combine some of these attributes to indicate a difference
"Every A has o", "Every B has o", "Every Chas o", ... as well as "No between U,V,W, ... andX,Y,Z, ....
M has o", "No N has o", "No 0 has o" are demonstrable, then o is the Note. Clearly, the problem of discovering similarities or differences
kind of difference we seek. Instead of proving the negative propositions between the objects represented by the ideas A,B,C, ... and M,N, 0, ...
"No M has o", "No N has o", ... , we may also manage to prove that is completely different from the problem of discovering similarities or
420 the ideas [M]o, [N]o, ... are objectless. It can happen that in the ideas we differences between the ideas themselves. The latter problem also arises
are comparing an attribute IT appears as a constituent in all of A, B, C, ... frequently, and may be looked upon as a special case of the former, the
while the denial of this attribute occurs in M, N, 0, .... In this case, a objects under comparison here being ideas. But the comparison is under-
mere glance at the given ideas shows that the attribute IT is a difference taken in the way that has just been described. But since an idea is quite
between the objects U, V, W, ... and X, Y, Z, .... But it by no means different from its object, it should come as no surprise if the compari-
follows from the absence of differences lying within the ideas that no son of ideas reveals completely different similarities and differences than
differences can be established, if the ideas genuinely stand in a relation those obtaining between their objects. Thus the ideas "equilateral trian-
of exclusion. On the contrary, if the ideas do stand in this relation, we gle" and "equiangular triangle" differ, but the objects they represent are
may infer that a real difference obtains between the objects U, V, W, .. . the same. So too the ideas "equilateral triangle" and "scalene [unequal-
and X ,Y,Z, .... For if there were no such difference, and U, V, W, .. . sided] triangle" are similar in that both contain the idea of equilaterality, 422
were constituted just as X, Y, Z, ... are, then an idea which represented while the objects they represent differ in that the attribute of equilaterality
one of them would have to fit the other as well. Admittedly, it does not belongs to the former but not to the latter.

278 279
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 358. Particular Rules

§.358. example. Suppose U is an equilateral triangle, V is a square, W a quadri-


lateral with unequal sides, the opposite angles of which acid up to two
IX. Discovering an attribute that belongs exclusively to given objects right angles, X a rhombus, and Y a quadrangle with an inward pointing
either with respect to a given multitude of objects or in general angle. The ideas through which these things are represented are: the con-
cept of a triangle (H), which includes the thing U, and the concept of a
In science as in daily life one often needs to find an attribute that belongs quadrangle (I) which englobes the remaining things V, W, X, Y. Finally,
exclusively to given objects-exclusively either with respect to a given the ideas through which the things U, V, W are known are: the concept
multitude of objects that includes them, or with respect to all objects in of a triangle (A), covering U, and the concept of a quadrangle whose op-
general. The former is necessary when we wish to use the att~·ibute a.s an posite angles add up to two right angles (representing V and W). Since
indicator that allows us to distinguish the objects from others 111 the given these two concepts do not englobe X or Y, our method can be applied.
multitude, the latter when we wish to recognise them in general. Now The concept [H] (non a+ non b) is here the concept of a triangle which is 424
an attribute that belongs exclusively to the objects U, V, W, ... of a given neither a triangle, nor a quadrangle whose opposite angles add up to two
multitude U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... must belong to all of U, V, W, .. . right angles. Since this concept is imaginary, we may simply omit it. The
and to none of X, Y, Z, ... , and thus be a difference between U, V, W, .. . concept [I] (non a + non b) will be the concept of a quadrangle which is
and X,Y,Z, .... And in order to discover such a difference, we must neither a triangle nor the kind of quadrangle whose opposite angles add
(according to the previous §)first have found certain ideas A,B,C, ... up to two right angles. If we remove the redundancy in this concept, we
and M, N, O, ... that respectively encompass the things U, V, W, ... and obtain that of a quadrangle whose opposite angles do not add up to two
X, Y, z, ... and also stand in the relation of exclusion. If we already know right angles, an idea which in fact covers the things X and Y. If we now
of such ideas, the present problem can be dealt with as described in the compare this concept with the given concepts A and B, we soon discover
previous section. But it is not necessary for such ideas to be given to the difference that the things standing under A and B are polygons that
us directly. Rather, it suffices if we only have some ideas H ,I, K, ... may be inscribed in a circle, which is not the case for the things standing
which encompass all of U, V, W, ... X, Y, Z, ... and several others under [I] (non a+ non b). It is easy to see, however, that in the contrary
A,B,C, ... that represent U, V, W, ... if not exclusively, at least in such
case, when the given ideas H, I, ... , A, B, C, ... do not meet the stated
423 a way that they represent none of X, Y, Z, ..... For if this is the case, the
condition (i.e., when A, B, C, ... also cover some of the things X, Y, Z, ... )
ideas [H](non a+ non b +non c + · ·· ), [!](non a+ non b+ non c+ · · · ), it is impossible to solve the problem at hand, that of finding an attribute
[K] (non a+ non b +non c + · ··) will certainly not all be objectless, and that belongs only to U, V, W, ... but not to any of X, Y, Z, .... For since I
yet together will encompass all of X, Y, Z, .... For it follows from the only know the objects U, V, W, ... and U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... through
mere form of these ideas that the first contains all the H that are neither the ideas A, B, C, ... and H, I, ... , I can at most recognise that a certain
A nor B nor C, ... , the second all the I that are neither A nor B nor attribute belongs to all the things standing under A, B, C, ... , but not to
C, ... , and so on; but all of X, Y, Z, ... must certainly be found among any of the things belonging to either the H or I which are also neither A
these H ,I, .... Obviously, these ideas stand in the relation of exclusion nor B nor C. Since I may not presuppose that none of X, Y, Z, ... stands
to the given ideas A, B, C, ... ; thus they meet the stated requirement, under one of the ideas A, B, C, ... , an attribute may indeed belong ex-
and we can use them instead of M, N, 0, .... If 8 is to be an attribute clusively to A, B, C, ... among all of H, I, ... but not to U, V, W, ...
that belongs exclusively to U, V, W, ... among all of U, V, W, ... , X, exclusively among all the U, V, W, X, Y, Z, ... , as it may still belong to X,
Y, z, ... , then the following propositions must hold: "Every A has 8", Y, Z. It is no less obvious that for this business of seeking an attribute that
"Every B has 8'', "Every C has 8'', etc., and also "No [H] (na + nb + ·· ·) belongs exclusively to U, V, W, ... among the U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... ,
has 8", "No [I](na + nb + .. ·) has 8", etc. Instead of the latter negative it is highly advantageous if the given ideas A, B, C, ... and H, I, ... are 425
propositions, it suffices to show that none of the ideas [H] (na + nb + ·· · ), as narrow as possible, i.e., if the former represent only U, V, W, ... , the
[I](na + nb + ... ), etc., has objectuality. Let us illustrate with a simple latter only X, Y, Z, ..... In this case the ideas [H] (non a+ non b + · ·· ),

280 281
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 359. Particular Rules

[I] (non a+ non b + · · · ), etc., will cover X, Y, Z, ... exclusively, so that also subsume X, Y,Z, . .. and thus be constituted in the way required by
the best case, as described in the previous section, occurs. our problem. But the circumstance of whether the objects X, Y, Z, ... are
If, finally, the problem is to discover an attribute that belongs to the known to us through a single idea A or through several A, B, C, ... makes
given objects U, V, W, ... exclusively among all conceivable objects, then a difference in the way we must proceed.
this amounts to discovering a difference between the objects U, V, W, ... 1) The first case occurs both when the problem is to find an idea M
on the one hand and all other objects on the other. According to what that subsumes a single object X and when we are supposed to hit upon an
was just said, this will require that the ideas A, B, C, ... through which idea that represents several objects X, Y, Z, ... , where we do not know 427
these objects are given fit no other objects, and thus represent U, V, W, ... any difference between them since X, Y,Z, ... are only represented by
exclusively. But in this case the objects other than U, V, W, ... will be rep- one and the same idea A. In the former case, our problem is at bottom
resented by [Something](non a+non b+non c+ ···),and our problem is that of finding an idea that has either the same extension as a given idea
one of discovering a difference between the objects comprehended under A or a wider one, i.e., is either equivalent or superordinate to A. One
the ideas A,B,C, ... on the one hand and [Somethingl(non a+non b+ obvious way to accomplish this is to attempt to recall an attribute that all
non c + · · · ) on the other. If 6 is to be such a difference, the following of the objects standing under A possess or, what amounts to the same, to
propositions must hold: Every A has 6, Every B has 6, ... and, finally, No recall a truth of the form "Every A has b". If we have an attribute b that
[Something](non a+ non b +non c +···)has 6. belongs to all A, then the concretum B will be an idea of the required kind,
since the idea B will have either the same or a wider extension than A. If
§.359. we already know a truth of the form "A has b" or, what amounts to the
same, if we have an attribute b that belongs to all A, it is to be expected
X. Discovering an idea that subsumes a given multitude of objects that it will occur to us merely because we direct our attention towards the
idea A for a while, since A and Bare associated through simultaneity. But
Nothing is required as often as the discovery of an idea that subsumes a
if we do not know any attribute that belongs to all A, we must first try
given multitude of objects, though it is often left unspecified whether it
to find one; this will be dealt with below. If the idea A is complex, and
426 should represent these objects exclusively. It is obvious that without even
of the form [Something](a + u. + · · · ), then merely omitting some of the
knowing the objects X, Y, Z, ... in the slightest we may claim that the
parts a, u., ... will give rise to an idea that has, if not a wider, at least not
concept of "something in general" subsumes all of them, and thus is one
a narrower extension than A, and thus solves our problem.
of the ideas that solves our problem. But if one demands an idea that does
2) In the second case, when there are several ideas A, B, C, ... which
not have such a wide extension, it is clearly necessary that we be given
represent the objects X, Y, Z, ... , the problem is to discover an idea M
one or more ideas that apply to these objects, in such a way that none of
whose extension contains all those of A, B, C, .... Obviously, we will
them is not represented by any of the ideas. For if among the given objects
have such an idea as soon as we know of an attribute that belongs to all the
X,Y,Z, ... there were even one which none of the ideas A,B,C, ...
objects standing under A, B, C, .... For if m were such an attribute, the 428
represented, it would remain completely unknown to us, and hence we
concretum M would be an idea under which all of A,B,C, ... stand, and
could never be sure that an idea M we had come up with subsumed all
hence under which all of X,Y,Z, ... stand. Our problem is accordingly
of X, Y, Z, . . . , no matter how wide its extension, unless M had the
reduced to that of §356, that of finding an attribute common to given ob-
widest extension of all, that of the idea "something in general". But it is
jects or, in other words, that of finding a similarity between these objects.
not necessary for the one or several ideas A, B, C, ... through which the
If A,B,C, ... are complex ideas of the forms [Something]( a+ u. + · · · ),
objects X, Y, Z, ... are presented and made known to us to represent these
[Somethingl(b + ~ + · · · ), [Somethingl(c + y + · · · ), ... , then one in-
objects exclusively, i.e., represent no objects besides X,Y,Z, .... For if
vestigates whether among the parts a,u., ... , b,~, ... c, y, ... , etc.,
the extensions of these ideas, taken together, do not exhaust the extension
there are any common ones. If u. is one such, then the idea [Something]u.
of something in general, then it will always be possible to discover an idea
would have, if not a wider, at least no narrower an extension than the ideas
M that subsumes all of them, and indeed more, and this idea will certainly

282 283
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 360. Particular Rules

A,B,C, ... , and hence would be a solution to our problem. It should be we may seek an idea that subsumes the objects standing under either A or
noted that the instructions just given will not lead us to every idea that B as described in the previous section. This idea will obviously be wider 430
would solve our problem. For the required idea need not be of the form than A and hence as required. But this procedure, in which the objects
of a concrete idea, and if the objects X, Y, Z, ... that are supposed to be U. V, ... that are to be subsumed by the new idea along with all the A are
subsumed by an idea are existing things, one can in many cases combine arbitrarily chosen, will not always lead us to an idea of the sort we need.
intuitions from these objects with certain general concepts to produce an Another procedure that can be useful consists in bringing to mind all the
idea that subsumes them all. Such techniques cannot be spoken of here, attributes of the objects standing under A that we are able to discover (i.e.,
however, in part because such a procedure cannot be generally applied, in all truths of the form "A has b") and then inquiring whether any of these
part because it requires more than mere reflection. is such that it is found in more objects than the A or (what amounts to
Note. Concerning the present problem (in his terms, that of find- the same) for which the truth "Not every Bis an A" can be demonstrated.
ing a generic concept for given kinds A, B, C, ... ) LAMBERT (N. 0., Obviously, every such B is a higher idea of the required sort. Thus, for
Dian., §42) says that we need only compare the most different of these example, if someone had set me the problem of discovering an idea that
kinds, and single out their common characteristics. This was a mistake, is higher than the idea "human", I would run through all the known at-
as MAAB (Gr: d. L., §468 note 3) pointed out. Attributes which belong to tributes of humans, asking whether any gives rise to a concretum that, put
the most different kinds or individuals of a genus need not belong to all in the place of B in "Every B is a human" states something demonstrably
429 the kinds or individuals of the genus. false. The idea "mortality" is one such, and hence the concept of a mortal
is higher than that of a human. If the given idea is complex, one may
§.360. above all inquire whether the simple omission of some of its parts will
produce a higher idea. Thus, given the concept of a living being that has
XI. Discovering an idea that subsumes more only one heart, one may, by omitting the idea "one", derive the higher
than a given multitude of objects concept of a being with (one or more) hearts. If the objects X, Y, Z, ...
are known through several ideas A, B, C, ... , one may first seek an idea
In the previous section we learned how to find an idea that subsumes
M that subsumes all of A, B, C, ... , following the instructions of the
given objects, where it does not matter whether the idea subsumes other
previous section, and then seek a wider idea in the way just described. 431
objects as well. The problem becomes somewhat more specific if we are
required to discover an idea that subsumes more objects than the given §.361.
ones. It goes without saying that this is only possible if the given objects
X, Y, Z, ... are not the collection of all objects, and also that the objects XII. Discovering an idea that subsumes fewer
must be known to us through one or more ideas A, B, C, ... that collec- than a given multitude of objects
tively subsume all of X,Y,Z, ... without being so wide as to encompass
all objects whatsoever. If the ideas A,B,C, ... are so wide that they sub- We have the exact opposite of the previous problem when we are asked
sume other objects in addition to X, Y, Z, ... and we are aware of this to discover an idea that represents not all of a given multitude of objects
relation, our problem may be solved simply by following the instructions X, Y, Z, ... , but only a part of them, without specifying which part this
of the previous section for finding an idea subsuming A, B, C, .... If, how- should be. For this to be possible, there must actually be several objects
ever, the extension of the given ideas A, B, C, ... subsumes X, Y, Z, ... X, Y, Z, ... , at least two. It is also obvious that these objects must be
but no other object, then the idea we are to discover must have a greater known to us through ideas which, we are assured, subsume no other ob-
extension than A,B,C, ... together. If X,Y,Z, ... are known to us only jects apart form X, Y, Z, .... For if the given ideas A, B, C, ... subsumed
through a single idea A, then our problem is to find an idea that is super- more objects than X, Y, Z, ... , we could never be sure that a certain idea
ordinate to A. We can accomplish this in many ways. First, if we know of M, no matter how much we were to narrow its extension, did not repre-
objects U, V, ... that do not stand under A but do stand under the idea B, sent one of these other objects. Thus the given ideas must either subsume

284 285
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 361. Particular Rules

all of X,Y,Z, ... and nothing else besides, or else have a narrower ex- attribute a, we may hope that the ideas of many objects that possess this
tension, and thus not even subsume all of X,Y,Z, .... But here we must attribute will spring to mind, provided that we know of any such. Now if
distinguish two cases, depending upon whether there is one idea or more it is true that all the objects standing under the idea C have the attribute
than one. If we only know the objects X, Y, Z, ... through a single idea a, it is clear that the idea C, provided that it is not equivalent to A, will
A, and A does not subsume all of these objects, it is obvious that A is the have a smaller extension than A. And since it is far more common that the
idea our problem requires. If, however, A subsumes all of X,Y,Z, ... , subject-idea has a smaller extension than the concretum corresponding to
the problem is actually that of finding an idea that is subordinate to A. the predicate-idea, we may expect that when we recall several such ideas
Now if several objects that A represents are of the sort that we can pro- C, of which the predicate a may be ascribed, some of them will have a
cure ideas of each individually, e.g., through intuitions, it is obvious that narrower extension than A. But the only ideas we discover in this way
432 any such idea solves our problem. But if we cannot assume that we al- will be those we could already have known to be subordinate to A. In
ready possess several singular ideas of this sort, there is no other way that order to find others, including completely new ones, we may try the fol-
leads to our goal than for us to bring to mind as many attributes of things lowing path. First, we seek several attributes m, n, o, ... that belong to A
as we can and, by comparing them with A, try to find one, b, that belongs or, what amounts to the same thing, ideas M,N, 0, ... which we know
to some, but not all, A; or, what amounts to the same, concerning which to have the same or wider extensions than A. We now undertake with
we may show that both of the ideas [A]b and [A]non b have objectuality. each of these, one after the other, what we had previously clone with A,
It soon becomes clear that in this case we obtain a pair of solutions to i.e., we recall all sorts of objects R,S, T, ... that stand under these ideas
our problem, since if both [A]b and [A]non bare objectual, then both are (one object under one idea, another under another). Naturally, we can ar- 434
certainly lower than A. It should be noted, however, that the new idea rive at a greater number of objects, or rather of ideas R, S, T, ... through
we seek need not be a compound containing A. Thus we must inquire which we think of these objects, in this way than we could before. For
whether among the many attributes of things, we recall that there is one previously, when we only had the idea a to call forth associated ideas,
b that already furnishes a concretum B that is a lower idea than A. This we now have many such (m, n, o, ... ) for this purpose. But since some
will be the case when the two propositions "Every B is an A" and "Not of the ideas R,S, T, ... that we discover in this way will stand under M,
every A is a B" (or "The idea [A ]non b has objectuality") hold. It goes others under N, and still others under 0, etc., and hence under ideas that
without saying that if none of the attributes b, b', b", ... meets this condi- are themselves subordinate to A, it is likely that some of R, S, T, ... will
tion, we have no assurance that combining them will produce an attribute also stand under A, or at least that combining them to produce ideas of the
that does. For if none of the ideas B,B',B", ... is itself lower than A, form [Something](r+s+ ···)will yield an idea subordinate to A. By way
the idea [Something] (b + b' + b" +···)can also fail to be lower than A. of illustration, suppose that we were given the problem of finding ideas
Thus if we haven't tested certain attributes b, b', b", ... individually, we that are subordinate to the concept of a triangle with unequal sides (sca-
need not test combinations of two, three, or more of them. The procedure lene) =A. We begin by inquiring about attributes m, n, o, ... that belong
described so far, even with any shortcuts we might introduce, remains not generally to the objects of the given concept, and are led to the concept of
only time-consuming but also leaves it to mere chance whether among a triangle in general as well as that of a figure with unequal sides. If now,
the infinite number of attributes that there are in general we hit hit upon conversely, we ask about objects R, S, T, U, ... that have these attributes
433 exactly the ones that are met with in the A. Thus it would be good if (triangularity and of not having any equal sides), it may occur to us with
the kind of attributes that might usefully be considered could be speci- reference to the former that triangles come with different sorts of angles,
fied more precisely. According to the law of association of simultaneous and may be acute-angled, right-angled, or obtuse-angled; and, with ref-
ideas, we may expect not only that the idea of a thing will bring to mind erence to the latter, that there are figures whose sides are in arithmetical,
the attributes we know it to have, but also that the idea of an attribute will geometrical or harmonic proportion. If we now inquire whether any of
bring to mind many objects that possess it. Thus if instead of keeping the these concepts stands under that of a scalene triangle, it turns out that this
given idea A in mind, we think the corresponding abstractum, i.e., of the is not the case for the concepts of an acute-, right- or obtuse-angled trian-

286 287
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 361. Particular Rules

gle, since these may have two equal sides. The concepts of figures whose §.362.
sides are in arithmetical, geometrical, or harmonic proportion stand in the
435 relation of overlapping with the concept of a scalene triangle; combined XIII. Discovering an idea that exactly
with the latter, then, they will yield concepts narrower than the given one, subsumes a given multitude of objects
namely, that of a triangle whose sides are in arithmetical, geometrical, or
A more difficult problem than the previous two is that of finding an idea
harmonic proportion. If we have succeeded in finding ideas R, S, T, U, ...
that exclusively or exactly (adequately) subsumes a given multitude of
that stand under the given idea A, combining these with each other will
objects X, Y, Z, .... Now one usually says that such ideas determine the
easily yield more such. For if even one of R, S, T, U, ... is lower than A,
given objects. Thus the problem may also be expressed as that of discov-
then so too is [Something](r + s + · · · ), provided that it is objectual. We
ering an idea that determines given objects. One soon sees that in order
need only observe which of the ideas formed through combination in this
to solve this problem the objects X, Y, Z, ... must not only be known to
way are objectual. Thus, since the concept of a triangle whose sides are
us, but known to us by means of ideas that apply exclusively to them.
in arithmetical proportion is already lower than that of a scalene triangle,
For if the ideas through which we know the objects X, Y, Z, ... do not
we immediately obtain other lower concepts when we investigate whether
subsume all of these objects, we would not be able to say that an idea
it may be united with the concept of a right-, or acute- or obtuse-angled
we have thought up subsumes all of them, while if the ideas subsume 437
triangle. This proves its worth, and leads to the concept of a triangle
other objects in addition to X, Y, Z, ... , we would not be able to say
whose sides are in arithmetic proportion and which is right-angled (or
that the idea we have thought up does not subsume any additional ob-
acute-angled, or obtuse-angled).* But ideas R,S, T, U, . .. , which are not
jects. The two cases discussed in the previous problems are also present
themselves lower than A, may also be combined to produce ideas of the
here: the objects X, Y, Z, ... may be known to us through one idea or
form [Something](r+s+ ···)which are lower than A; thus if it is a matter
through several. In the first case, i.e., when we either seek an idea that
of finding the greatest possible number of subordinate ideas, we should
fits the one or several objects known through the idea A exclusively, the
not fail to examine combinations of such ideas. The only difference is
ideas we seek must be equivalent to A. Thus the problem is that of find-
that in addition to checking whether the ideas produced are objectual we
ing ideas equivalent to a given object-idea. One way this may be done
436 must also see whether they are in fact lower than A. Finally, we must also
through pure reflection is to follow the instructions given in §358 and
consider the case where the objects X,Y,Z, ... are known to us through
seek attributes that belong exclusively to the things represented by A. If
several ideas. Since these ideas are not applicable to any other objects,
m is such an attribute, then M yields an idea equivalent to A. Thus we
only one of the following cases may occur. Either we know of one or
must see what attributes b, b', b" the objects standing under A possess,
more of the ideas A, B, C, ... that it subsumes only some of X, Y, Z, ... or
i.e., we must try to become acquainted with all truths of the form "A
else we know this of none of them. In the first case, when we know that
has b", set these out, and investigate whether one of these attributes, or
one of the given ideas A, B, C, ... does not subsume all of X, Y, Z, ... ,
some combination of them, belongs exclusively to the A; that is, we must
it is itself an idea of the kind our problem requires. In the second case,
see whether by combining these attributes in order to produce ideas of
when we do not know of any of A,B,C, ... that it subsumes only some
the form [Something] (b + b' + b" + · · · ) we produce one for which the
of X,Y,Z, ... , we need only, following the rules already given, seek an
proposition that every [Something] (b + b' + b" + · · ·) is an A holds. If
idea that is lower than one of these and hence will certainly not subsume
this proposition is found to be true, then [Something] (b + b' + b" + ... ) is
all of X, Y,Z, ....
an idea of the sort we require. If not, then it is still too wide, and we must
attempt to add other attributes that are not mere consequences of these
ones, until we anive at an idea that makes the proposition true. In the
second case, where the objects X,Y,Z, ... are known to us not through a
*Further investigation reveals that the first case only occurs when the sides are in the
ratio 3:4:5, the second when the sides increase at a smaller rate, and the third when they single idea but through severalA,B,C, ... , the problem is to find an idea
increase at a greater rate. M that is equivalent to A,B,C, ... taken together. An idea that immedi- 438

288 289
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 363. Particular Rules

ately suggests itself here is that of "something, that is either an A or a B or 1) The first case obtains when the objects U, V, W, ... , X, Y,Z, .. .
a C etc."; yet we may be asked for other ideas, and in particular ideas that are known to us through a single idea H, and the objects X, Y, Z, .. .
solve our problem by virtue of their peculiar content rather than simply through a single idea A. Our problem is then to interpolate an intermedi-
by virtue of their form. In order to find such ideas we must, following the ate idea between two ideas standing in the relation of subordination. One
instructions of §358, seek attributes that belong exclusively to the objects may proceed as follows to find such an idea. Since the extension of the
represented by A, B, C, ... If m is such an attribute, then M is the idea idea H surpasses that of A by more than one object, it is certain that the
we require. Incidentally, the reminder of §359 to the effect that the rules idea [H]non a is not only objectual, but subsumes more than one object.
aiven there will not lead us to the discovery of every idea that solves our
b
Thus, following the instructions of §361, it will be possible to find an idea
problem, may be repeated here and in the following sections as well. For with a narrower extension than [H]non a. According to §362, however,
all these rules only tell us how to find concreta. it should not be impossible to think of an idea I that subsumes the ideas
comprehended under A and I and no others. If we have found such an
§.363. idea, say E, then E will be higher than A and lower than H, as required 440
by our problem. But since it is often quite difficult to find a serviceable
XIV. Discovering an idea that represents less than a given multitude idea that represents the objects of two given ideas A and I exclusively, it
of objects but more than a given part of this multitude will be desirable in most cases to have another way of reaching our goal.
One way is to bring to mind all the attributes that belong to all A, i.e., all
Sometimes we are asked to find an idea that subsumes less than the col-
of the truths of the form "A has m", and then see whether there is one of
lection of objects U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... yet more than a given part
these attributes m for which all of the following propositions hold: All M
of this collection X, Y, Z, .... But in order for it to be possible for us to
are H, not all Hare M, and not all Mare A. If we have discovered such
discover an intermediate idea M ( § 100), the ideas H ,I, K, ... , through
an attribute m, then M is the sort of idea we seek. Suppose, for example,
which the multitude of the U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... are known to us,
we were asked to find a concept that was intermediate between those of
must not represent more than these objects, while the ideas A,B,C, ... ,
a sun-dial and a clock in general. Among the many attributes that belong
through which the multitude of the X, Y, Z, ... are known to us, must not
to a sun-dial is that the hours it indicates are not of equal duration. Fur-
represent less than these objects. The first condition follows from §361,
ther inquiry reveals that the concept of an object that indicates hours of
since Mis supposed to cover fewer objects than all of U, V, W, ... , X, Y,
unequal length meets the above three conditions; that is, the propositions
Z, ... , and the second condition follows from §360, as M is supposed to
that all objects of this sort are clocks, that not all clocks are things of
represent more than just X, Y,Z, .... No less obvious is the necessity of
this sort, nor are all things of this sort sun-dials. Thus the concept of an
the condition that the extension of the ideas H ,I, K, ... , through which
object that does not indicate hours of equal length is the sort of interme-
the objects U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... are known to us, and the extension
diate concept we seek. In the special case where the idea A is composed
439 of the ideas A,B,C, ... , through which X,Y,Z, ... are known to us,
of H and some other ideas, perhaps like [H] (a+ a'+···), one may first
must differ by at least two objects. For since we only know the objects
investigate whether merely omitting some of the parts that A contains in
U,V,W, ... , X,Y,Z, ... through the ideas H,I,K, ... , we will only
addition to H will give rise to an idea such as [H]a or [H]a', which has the
be justified in believing that an idea M we have thought up does not rep-
intermediate extension we seek. Suppose, for example, we are given the
resent all of U, V, W, ... , X, Y, Z, ... if we find that it subsumes more
two concepts of a punishment and an evil, and are asked to find an inter-
than A,B,C, .... But if the idea Mis supposed to represent less than
mediate concept. Since a punishment is nothing other than an evil that is
H ,I, K, ... and more than A, B, C, ... , it is obvious that the sum of the
visited upon a moral person on account of his ethical transgressions, the
objects of H ,I, K, ... must be at least two more than the sum of objects
comparison of the components of the two concepts immediately leads to 441
of A,B,C, .... Now the multitude of objects U, V, W, ... , X,Y,Z, ...
the concept of an evil suffered by a moral person; and closer examination
as well as X, Y, Z, ... may each be known to us through a single idea or
reveals that this concept is, as we require, in fact intermediate.
through several. Thus there are four cases to consider.

290 291
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 364. Particular Rules

2) The second case we intend to consider is that where the sum of the that here there cannot be so many objects U, V, W, ... that there are no
U, V, W, ... , X, Y,Z, ... as well as the sum of the X, Y,Z, ... are known others. It is no less obvious that it would be impossible to find such an
to us through several ideas (H,l,K, ... and A,B,C, ... respectively). If idea if we did not already know the objects U, V, W, ... to some extent;
it is possible to think of a pair of ideas H' and A' which are respectively indeed, we see that we are only in a position to solve this problem if the
equivalent to H,l,K, ... and A,B,C, ... taken together, then we once ideas A, B, C, ... we have of the given objects comprehend all of these
again have the first case, and proceed with H' and A' as we did before with objects and no others, and thus, as we say, fit them exclusively. Then it
Hand A. But since it is often difficult to find such ideas, we may proceed will depend upon whether there is only one such idea, or several.
in the following way. Following the instructions of §356, we recall as 1) If the objects U, V, W, ... are given through a single idea that ap-
many of the attributes common toX,Y,Z, ... (i.e., oftheA,B,C, ... ) plies exclusively to them, the problem becomes that of thinking up an
as we can, and then inquire which of them meet the following threefold idea that stands in the relation of overlapping (§98) to a given idea A.
requirement: first, that they belong to more objects than those standing We could do this by first finding an idea B that is subordinate to A and
under A,B,C, ... , i.e., that the idea [M](non a+ non b +non c + · .. ) an idea C that is subordinate to the idea Non-A according to the instruc- 443
has objectuality; second, that all M are contained within the sum of the tions of §361, and then finding an idea M which subsumes the objects of
U, V, W, ... , X, Y,Z, ... , i.e., the idea [M](non h +non i +non k + ·.. ) B and C, or of B and Non-A, and none others, following the instructions
is objectless; and finally that some objects among U, V, W, ... are not of §362. Then M and A would certainly overlap. Another, usually far
M, i.e., that among the ideas [H]non m, [!]non m, [K]non m, ... there is at easier way to solve the problem is by first seeking an idea B that is sub-
least one objectual one. Then, clearly, Mis an idea of the sort we require. ordinate to A, and bringing to mind all the attributes that belong to all B
If, for example, we were asked for a concept intermediate between the that we can, then investigating whether among these there is an attribute
three concepts of a regular pentagon, a regular hexagon, and a circle on m that meets the following two conditions: first, that it does not belong
the one hand and the two concepts of a polygon and a second-degree to all A, or that the idea [A]non m has objectuality; and second, that m
curve on the other, we would begin by acquainting ourselves with the also belongs to some things that do not belong under A, or that the idea
attributes that are common to the first three things. Among these is the [M]non a has objectuality. If both conditions are met, M and A overlap.
attribute of being figures that can be constructed geometrically. Further If A were the idea of a musical instrumental, for example, we would first
442 investigation reveals that the concept of such figures in fact encompasses seek an idea subordinate to it, e.g., that of an organ, and then consider
more than the first three concepts, and less than the two last ones, and the various attributes of organs. One of these is that it can imitate various
hence is intermediate. voices, including the human voice. Examining this attribute according
3) The way we must proceed in the third and fourth cases, i.e., when to the previous instructions, we find that the concept of an object that
only one of the two sums U,V,W, ... , X,Y,Z, ... and X,Y,Z, ... imitates the human voice actually stands in the required relation of over-
is known to us through several ideas, will be readily gathered from the lapping with the given concept. If we review the rules given in §361 for
foregoing. finding ideas subordinate to a given one, we see that they would serve
equally well for finding an idea that overlaps with a given one. Among
§.364. the collections of attributes that we know a thing to have, we seek those
for which the following three ideas are objectual: [Something]( a+ m),
XV. Discovering an idea which subsumes both [Something]( a+ non m), and [Something](non a+ m). Then Mand A
more and less than a given multitude certainly stand in a relation of overlapping. If the idea B that is subor-
dinate to the idea A is composed of A and other parts, say as [A]p, it is
A final problem related to the ones considered so far is that of discovering
natural to ask first whether the idea P would itself yield an idea that stands 444
an idea that subsumes both more and less than a given multitude, i.e.,
in the required relation of overlapping. And if the idea A is composite,
which covers only some of the given objects U, V, W, ... and at the same
with the form [Something](a +ex+···), we may also hope to come by an
time covers objects not contained in this collection. It goes without saying

292 293
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 365. Particular Rules

overlapping idea by omitting some of the parts of this idea and combining that the ideas we seek must be mutually exclusive. It goes without saying
the rest with p, i.e., producing an idea of the form [Something]( rx + p ). that the number of ideas M,N, 0, ... , which together are supposed to
For example, let the given idea A be the concept of a morally good action, subsume all of X,Y,Z, ... , may in no case be greater than the number
and the subordinate idea that of a morally good action that is physically of these objects themselves; and also that these objects must be known
enforceable. If we omit the concept of moral goodness from this sub- through one or more ideas A,B,C, ... that apply to them exclusively.
ordinate idea, we obtain the concept of a physically enforceable action 1) If they are given to us through a single idea A, then the problem we
in general, which stands in the required relation of overlapping with the have to solve is actually this: to discover a collection of several ideas that
concept of a morally good action. exhaust the extension of a given idea A, or to divide this extension into a
2) It remains to consider the case where we know the objects U, V, given number of parts (§104). According to §140, no. 10, this problem 446
W, ... through several ideas A, B, C, .... It is obvious that this case can also be called that of establishing an exact classification. Since the
can be reduced to the first, if we are able, following §362, to indicate an ideas we must find all stand under A, it is natural to look for them among
idea A' which is equivalent to A,B,C, ... taken together. But since this the ideas standing under A, which we know how to find from §361. And
procedure rarely leads to a serviceable idea, we must mention another. in fact each of these ideas can be used for our purposes. For if M is sub-
We begin by seeking an idea L that stands under one of A,B,C, ... , ordinate to A, then it follows that every Mis an A, but not every A is an
or only includes a part of the objects standing under A,B,C, .... We M. Thus the idea [A]non m is also objectual, and stands in the relation
then enumerate the attributes that belong to all L, and see whether among of exclusion to M. The two ideas M and [A]non m together, however,
them there is one m which meets the following two conditions: first, that certainly exhaust the extension of A. Thus if we are asked for only two
it does not belong to all A,B,C, ... or, what amounts to the same, that ideas that together exhaust the extension of A, our problem is solved by
at least one of the ideas [A]non m, [B]non m, [C]non m, ... is objectual; Mand [A]non m. But if we are required to divide the extension of A into
and second, that there are objects that stand under M but not under any of more than two parts, we need only undertake with one or both of the
A, B, C, ... , i.e., that [M] (non a+ non b +non c + ··· ) is objectual. If we ideas Mand [A]non m what we did before with A, repeating this as often
445 find such an attribute m, then M will be an idea of the required sort. Given as needed to obtain the required number of parts. For example, suppose
the similarity of this procedure with that of no. 1, it is clear that similar the idea A is that of a triangle, and the subordinate idea M that first oc-
shortcuts may sometimes be used here as well. Suppose, for example, curs to us is that of an isosceles triangle. The idea [A]non mis then that
that the given objects are exhaustively and exclusively represented by the of a triangle that does not have two equal sides, i.e., a scalene triangle.
concepts of a right-angled triangle, a square, a right-angled sector of a Here it is obvious that these two ideas together exhaust the extension of
circle, and an ellipse. We seek an attribute that belongs to one or several the idea of a triangle in general. But if we want to divide this extension
of these things, and may hit upon the concept of a figure that contains in more than two parts, a further division that suggests itself is based on
right angles. When we examine this, we find that it is what we require. the idea of an equilateral triangle (one in which more than one pair of
sides are equal), which is subordinate to M. If we call this idea M', then
§.365. the idea [M]non m' is that of a triangle with only one pair of equal sides,
which is an isosceles triangle in the narrower sense. If we replace M with 447
XVI. Discovering several ideas which only collectively these two ideas, which exhaust its extension, we obtain the three follow-
subsume a given multitude of objects ing ideas, which together exhaust the extension of the idea of a triangle
in general: that of an equilateral triangle, that of an isosceles triangle in
One of the most important and common problems requires us to find a
the narrower sense, and that of a scalene triangle. It is obvious that the
collection of ideas M, N, 0, ... that exactly subsume a given multitude of
instructions just given permit us to discover a great many collections of
things X, Y, Z, ... and, in addition, stand in the relation of exclusion to
ideas M,N, 0, ... that all have the attribute of exhausting the extension
one another. If we know how to do this, it will be even easier to solve the
of a given idea A. For depending on whether we choose these or those
other problems that might be raised here, e.g., if we omit the condition

294 295
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 365. Particular Rules

ideas from among the subordinate ideas we have found following §361 subsume all of X, Y, Z, .... If, for example, A is of this sort, then among 449
to go along with M, and depending upon whether we take further parts the ideas [B]non a, [C]non a, ... at least one will be objectual; and the
within Mor [A]non m, different collections of ideas will result. We can one or more ideas that are like this, taken together, furnish the required
also proceed in many other ways, e.g., as follows. If, following §361, we collection.
have first found a considerable number of ideas M,N, 0, ... that stand
under A, we can, following §355, investigate which of these happen to be §.366.
so constituted that they stand in the relation of exclusion to one another.
If we have found some of these, say M,N, 0, ... , then we may inquire, XVII. Defining a proposition that is given to our consciousness
further, whether these already exhaust the extension of A, i.e., whether the
idea [A] (non m +non n +non o + · ··) is objectless. If this is not the case, If orderly reflection requires us to elevate a considerable number of the
we need simply add the idea [A] (non m +non n +non o + ·· ·) to our col- mere ideas we have to distinct consciousness and to determine their con-
lection in order to obtain the sort we require. Thus the books in a certain tent, it requires this all the more for our judgements. Thus the following
library might be quite appropriately classified as theological, philosoph- question arises frequently in all reflection: how does the judgement you
ical, mathematical, physical, etc., and, finally, those that belong to none just formed run, and what are its parts? The way to answer this ques-
of these fields (miscellaneous). tion has a good deal in common with the procedure we follow in defining
2) If the objects X, Y, Z, ... are known to us not through a single an idea given to our consciousness (§350). Here too we must repeatedly
448 idea, but rather through several ideas A,B,C, ... applying exclusively
attempt to attain an intuition of the judgement that is as vivid and long-
to them, how to proceed depends upon whether or not these ideas stand lasting as possible, and then direct our attention towards the constituents
in the relation of mutual exclusion. If they do, then these very ideas are of the judgement. In order to pick out the ideas that really are parts of
a collection of the required sort. But if we are asked to find other such our judgement from among all those that come to mind in such attempts,
collections, it may happen that we replace one or more of A, B, C, ... with i.e., to distinguish them from others that appear merely through associ-
ideas equivalent to them. The various collections of complementary ideas ation via simultaneity, we must inquire whether the ideas that appear to
that result will have the peculiarity of dividing the multitude X,Y,Z, ... be such parts may really be combined to form a judgement, and indeed
in exactly the same way (into the same parts). But if we are asked to find the very judgement we have just formed. Ideas that do not allow of being
collections of ideas M, N, 0, ... that divide the multitude X, Y, Z, ... into so combined may be cast aside. If we have formed a proposition M with
different parts than A, B, C, ... do, we may proceed as follows. First, ideas ex,~, y, ... that seems to be completely identical to the judgement
A we are supposed to define, the correctness of this surmise will be con- 450
following §§361 and 363, we seek an idea M that either subsumes more
than the given ideas A,B,C, ... or else subsumes more than one of these firmed mainly by our ability to deduce the same consequences from M
ideas but less than all of them collectively. Under these conditions, the as we can from A. Admittedly, this really only shows, strictly speaking,
ideas [A]non m, [B]non m, [C]non m, ... will certainly not all be objectless. that the two are equivalent (§ 156). But if the constituents of which M
If we choose those that have an object, say [B]non m and [C]non m, then is composed are all found in A as well, and our most carefully scrutiny
it is obvious that they, along with M, exhaust the extension of all A B reveals no parts in A that are not also in M, nor any parts combined in
' ' different manners in the two, we may be allowed to surmise that we have
C, .... We need not mention that here we may, as in no. 1, further divide
the ideas M, [B]non m, and [C]non m, provided that they are not singular correctly indicated the way A is composed in our definition. Obviously,
ideas, and thus increase the number of ideas that collectively exhaust the the given instructions for defining a proposition may also be applied in
extension of the given ideas A,B,C, .... If the given ideas A,B,C, ... cases where it does not actually appear in our minds as a judgement, but
are not mutually exclusive, then in order to attain our goal we need not rather is merely represented.
first look for an idea M that is wider or narrower than one of them, but
can instead choose one of these ideas, provided that it does not already

296 297
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 367, 368. Particular Rules

§.367. what degree of probability is involved-often require a good deal of other


knowledge to decide. Thus we shall only say a few words here about the
XVIII. Investigating whether a given proposition is analytic or synthetic manner in which these relations may be judged. It is easiest to see that
certain propositions A, B, C, D, ... stand in the relation of compatibility
Once we know all the parts of which a proposition is composed, the de- with respect to the variable ideas i, j, ... (§ 154) by finding certain ideas
termination of most of its inner attributes follows almost of itself-for which, when put in the places of i,j, ... , make all of A,B,C,D, ... true.
example, whether it is simple or complex, affirmative or negative, a con- But if we must demonstrate that the propositions M,N,O, . .. are de-
ceptual or an intuitional proposition, etc. It is not so easy to answer the ducible fromA,B,C, ... with respect to the variable ideas i,j, ... (§155) 452
question whether a given proposition belongs to the class of the analytic we can by no means do so by showing that all of the infinitely many ideas
or to that of the synthetic. According to § 148, a proposition is called an- which, when put in the places of i,j, ... , make all of A,B,C, ... true, also
alytic if a part in it can be indicated which could be exchanged for any make all of M, N, 0, ... true. Rather, we must gather this from a consid-
other idea without losing the truth, or falsity, it originally had, provided eration of the form of these propositions-either directly, or else through
that it remains objectual. Admittedly, we cannot figure out by means of the consideration of other truths. The most important forms where a re-
an immediate inquiry whether this is the case with respect to the given lation of deducibility can be recognised, either immediately or with the
proposition and if so with respect to which ideas; rather, we must gather help of knowledge belonging to logic, have been discussed in the chap-
this from the form of the proposition. We must look upon now this now ter dealing with inferences. Others, those where mathematical, historical,
that of its components as variable, and then judge from the peculiar at- etc., knowledge is required to judge are not treated here. We can only see
451 tributes of its remaining parts and their combination whether the propo- that a relation of equivalence obtains between the propositions A, B, C, ...
sition might remain true or false regardless of what one puts in the place and M,N,O, ... with respect to the ideas i,j, ... (§156) by showing
of that variable part. Occasionally, this is obvious-for instance, when a that A,B,C, ... and M,N, 0, ... are mutually deducible with respect to
predicate is ascribed to this subject which is already thought in the sub- these ideas. If the deducibility is not mutual, we learn that the proposi-
ject, or more generally for analytic propositions of the sort adduced in tions stand in a relation of subordination (§ 157); and if we find that the
§ 148 no. 2. For other propositions, however, much knowledge may be re- propositions A, B, C, ... and M, N, 0, ... are compatible, but there is no
quired in order to judge. Thus, for example, only a mathematician knows relation of deducibility between them (which reveals itself as soon as we
that the proposition "the sum of the angles in a regular quadrangle equals find ideas i,j, ... that make one part true without making the other true),
four right angles" is analytic with respect to the concept "regular". When we learn that they stand in a relation of overlapping (§ 158). Finally, it
we are unable to discover that a proposition is analytic but find, on the is easy to see from the definitions of § 159 how to judge whether given
contrary, that for each of its parts there is a variation which changes its propositions stand in the relations of incompatibility, exclusion, mutual
truth or falsity, then we are justified in declaring it synthetic. exclusion (or contradiction), or mere contrariety. 453

§.368. §.369.*

XIX. Investigating the relations between given propositions XX. Testing the truth of a given proposition

If we have been presented with several propositions A, B, C, ... , we Testing the truth of a given proposition is the most frequently encoun-
may be asked about the relations between them. Some of these, e.g., tered problem in human reflection, since, as remarked in §352, problems
if the propositions deal with the same object, are subordinate to one an- of other kinds may almost always be reduced to one or more of this sort.
other, etc., are obvious once we know the constituents of the propositions. This is the reason why I have already mentioned some of the rules that
Others, by contrast-e.g., whether the given propositions stand in the re- must be observed here. But earlier I spoke only of rules that are com-
lation of ground to consequence or the relation of probability and, if so, pletely general, no matter what sort of problem was involved. Thus some

298 299
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 369. Particular Rules

things that apply only in certain cases were not mentioned, and may be object-idea(§ 196). Thus, for example, we could not be sure that the com-
taken up here. If we must answer the question whether or not a given bination of ideas that lie in the words "The soul of Socrates is something
proposition M is true, much depends upon whether it belongs to the class simple" represents a truth until we know that the intuition "Socrates" ap- 455
of purely conceptual truths or to that of empirical truths. If we find that it plies to a being that has a soul. But a proposition that says this, and thus
consists entirely of concepts, it will be appropriate to begin by analysing determines more precisely the object of a given intuition, is an empirical
these concepts. Then, from the propositions we seek, following the pre- proposition, and so it is obvious that the truth of an empirical proposition
cepts of §§328-330, in order to decide mediately the truth or falsity of M, can never be established without presupposing other empirical proposi-
we begin by choosing those which contain these very concepts. For if M tions, thus through experience. The analysis of constituents described in
is a truth, then the ground of this truth (if it is not a basic truth, in which no. l can also be used with empirical propositions, provided that all the
case it will be self-evident to us) lies in other conceptual truths which (as intuitions the proposition contains are included; but success is far less
we know from §221) are no more complex than M itself. Thus if we form certain, since we are seldom in a position to learn the objective grounds
all, or almost all, the propositions which can be formed by combining the of such truths. Thus, for example, the analysis of the constituents of the
concepts occurring in M, it may be surmised that these will contain the proposition that Alexander defeated King Darius on the river Hydaspes
propositions which contain the ground of M. We may also expect these will not tell us whether it is true; we require testimony from historians for
propositions to be for the most part simpler and more evident than M, that. But if it is supposed to be proved through experience that a given
454 and thus more readily recognised to be true, if not at first glance, then proposition (whether it be purely conceptual or empirical) is true, this can
at least after some reflection. But if we have first recognised the truth only happen, generally speaking, if (a) we do not find a single perception
of the propositions that are the grounds of M, it is to be hoped that we that conflicts with this proposition, i.e., allows us to deduce a proposition
will also be able to see the truth of M itself. But if M is false, Neg.M contrary to the given one, and (b) we have had many perceptions that ac-
will be a truth, and indeed one which, setting aside the few concepts in- cord with the given proposition, i.e., which could be deduced from it if
volved in negation, contains no more concepts than M. Thus if we have we accepted it as true. Both of these things can occur in many different
formed all or almost all of the propositions which can be formed with ways, with results that are more or less reliable according to the degree
the concepts occurring in M along with those of negation, we may expect of probability of the inferences by means of which we deduce the per-
through a consideration of these propositions to recognise that and why ceptions we have made from the proposition under examination (or its
M is false. But if we are unsuccessful in our attempts to prove or refute opposite), as well as on the number of such perceptions. Clearly, when it
our proposition through purely conceptual truths, the only thing that re- stands within our power to choose, we should prefer the perceptions that
mains is to see whether experience yields grounds capable of deciding give the most certain decision on the truth or falsity of the proposition.
the question. If the proposition is empirical, i.e., contains intuitions, then We say that such perceptions immediately decide the question, especially
we may know in advance that through mere concepts we could at most when they can be deduced from the proposition under examination by
show its falsity, but never its truth. The former case occurs when closer a sequence of inferences that are so familiar to us that we are scarcely 456
consideration reveals that the proposition belongs to the special sort of aware of making them.
analytic propositions that remain false no matter what ideas we substitute It should be noted, however, that there are some propositions, and not
for the intuitions they contain. Of this sort would be, for example, the only those consisting merely of concepts but even among the so-called
proposition that the soul of Socrates has been annihilated; for a purely empirical propositions, which we can know in advance to be undecidable
conceptual truth teaches us that no soul is annihilated, so that the above by experience in the strict sense (i.e., not including testimony). Of this
proposition is false no matter what object the intuition "Socrates" refers sort is the proposition that no substance ceases to be in time. For if we re-
to. But in order to say with confidence that such a proposition is true, we flect on this matter a little, it becomes clear that no experience, no matter
must first be assured that the intuitions occurring in it all apply to objects how constituted (provided it is not the statement of a witness) would be
of the kinds required to make the subject-idea of the proposition a genuine able to prove either the truth or the falsity of this proposition. How might

300 301
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 370. Particular Rules

we infer the truth of this proposition? Perhaps because we experience rience. Understandably, some proofs may be appropriate for their end,
that every substance that we have once perceived continues to act and an- i.e., have everything required to bring about the intended judgement (the
nounce its existence? But from this the most that would follow would be judgement to be proved) in the mind of the being that considers the proof,
that this substance has persisted thus far, not that it shall continue to do while others are more or less ill-suited to this end. The degree of appro-
so for all eternity. Or perhaps we might want to infer the falsity of the priateness of a proof should not be confused with the actual attainment
proposition from the fact that we no longer perceive a substance we once of its goal; for even a proof that is suitable in itself may not reach its
did? But from the fact that a substance no longer acts on us, at least not goal on account of the hindrance of external circumstances, e.g., lack of
in a way that we can perceive, it in no way follows that it has ceased to attention on the part of the person to whom we present the proof. So too
be. The proposition that some of the resolutions of our will take place a proof that is in itself quite unsuitable may still attain its end. Thus the
without a determining ground is similar. Propositions that have this pecu- appropriateness of a proof should be distinguished from its efficacy. If
liarity merit a special designation. One may call them transcendent or, as the consideration of the propositions A, B, ... is supposed to lead us to the
some prefer transcendental, since these words have already been used in judgement C, and the consideration of D, E, ... to the judgement F, etc.,
a similar sense. Prudence counsels us to ask whether a given proposition and then the consideration of C, G, ... to the judgement H, the consid-
457 is transcendental before we set out to test it; if it is, any efforts to decide eration of F,l, ... to the judgement K etc., and finally the consideration
its truth based on experience would not only be in vain, but would also of H, K, L, ... to the judgement M, as the goal for the sake of which
expose us to the danger of gross eITors, in that we might take many phe- all the others were presented, then we may not only call the collection
nomena which at bottom decide nothing to be proofs either of its truth or of all the propositions A, B, C, D, E, ... , K, L, ... a proof of M, but
of its falsity. This occurs all too often to those who seek to determine the we may also call the propositions A,B, ... a proof of C, and D,E, ...
question of determinism mentioned above through experience. a proof of F, etc. It is clear from this how one proof may include many
others within itself. Such proofs may be called complex, and the oth-
§.370.* ers simple. The propositions A, B, D, E, G, ... in a proof that are not
themselves furnished with proofs (at least not in the course of the proof
XX!. Testing the force of conviction of a given proof in question) are called the starting point (principia, &pxw), presupposi-
tions, premises, or assumptions of our proof; the other propositions, such
In general, we give the name of a proof of a proposition M to anything
as C, F, ... can be called intermediate propositions; while M is called 459
that we think someone may, by directing his attention to it, use in or-
the conclusion. Finally, the degree of confidence that a proof is capable
der either to form a judgement M that he had not previously formed, or
of confeITing on its conclusion if the requisite attention is given to it I
else to form it with a higher degree of confidence. In the second case
call the power of conviction of the proof. A proof that has such power
one speaks of confirmation. All sorts of sensible objects and changes
is called convincing, true, correct, tenable, binding, etc., while one that
can furnish proofs, e.g., blushing or turning pale may in certain circum-
has no such force is called untenable, false, incorrect, etc. It is easy to
stances be proof of guilt. Since most of our judgements, as we saw in
see that one and the same proof may be convincing for one of us and not
§300, arise through the mediation of others, and thus through the con-
for another. Here I shall only deal with how we must direct our inquiries
sideration of other propositions, the presentation of a specific collection
in order to determine whether a given proof has a force of conviction for
of propositions is quite often a means of bringing about a judgement of
ourselves. In order to discover truth, that is, to aITive at the goal at which
a certain kind in the minds of others. It is only this sort of proof that
the present instruction aims, it suffices if we know whether and to what
I mean, the sort consisting in a given collection of propositions, when I
degree we may rely on a given proof; and the attributes a proof must have
speak of a proof in the strict sense, as is almost always the case in this
for other reasons if it is to be included in a treatise will not be dealt with
book. According to whether the propositions of which a proof consists
here. In order to decide whether a proof before us justifies our trust in
are all purely conceptual or else contain some intuitional propositions,
a proposition M which is its conclusion, we must investigate two things:
458 I call it, respectively, a proof jl'mn pure concepts or a proof from expe-

302 303
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 370. Particular Rules

first, whether we may accept with an appropriate degree of confidence premises and inferences employed, since each of these runs the risk of
all the propositions A,B,D,E, ... that are used without proof (i.e., as an error, which can be lessened to some degree through testing, but never
mere presuppositions), and then whether the proposition M stands in ei- completely removed. If some of the inferences are merely probable, then
ther a relation of deducibility or ground-consequence to A, B, D, E, ... or we must take the risk of error all the more seriously. Supposing that the
some part of them, or at least whether these confer a degree of probability degrees of probability that the individual assumptions A, B, C, ... have are
upon M that surpasses doubtfulness. Understandably, we cannot under- =a.,~' y, ... and the degree of probability with which the conclusion Mis
take either of these investigations unless we have a clear awareness not deducible from them is = µ, then the degree of probability that the given
only of the individual propositions of which the proof consists, but also proof confers on M may never be assumed to be boTeater than a.. G · '( .... \u
I
of all the kinds of inferences that are used. This, then, is the first thing (§161). The degree of confidence can be increased, however, if we find
we must do if we are to examine a proof. We must raise to a quite clear that in the proof several mutually independent grounds speak in favour of
460 consciousness all of the propositions of which the proof consists, even the truth of the proposition. For if the degrees of probability that the indi-
those that may perhaps be tacitly passed over in the verbal presentation, vidual grounds would confer upon the proposition are x,y, z, ... , then
and to this end express them in precise words, afterwards doing the same the probability they confer together is roughly = . . ( x'Y"z.... .
. . . . . . x·_"Z .... + l-x)(I-y)(l-z)· ..
for the inferences. In order to improve the chances of our investigation, Fmally, It IS worth recallmg that the exammatlon of proofs is one of those
we must also be aware of the most common errors that are committed in problems for our reflection that often results (according to the rule of
producing proofs, sometimes deliberately and with foreknowledge, and §325) in our learning of truths that we did not seek, and not only when a
comparing the proof with these, check to see whether it commits any of proof is correct, but also when it is not. For even in a flawed proof many
them. Since, in addition, there are indicators the presence of which allows new truths, or new combinations of known truths, or new, useful forms of
us to detect the incoITectness either of a premise or an inference without inference may occur, and even the faults that one encounters may teach 462
knowing exactly where the flaw lies, it will also be advantageous to learn us something; and if the proof does not prove what it is supposed to, it
and apply these indicators. For it is certainly an advantage to learn that a may still serve to prove something else.
given proof is untenable, even when we do not know where the fault lies. Note. The words proof and confirmation, in the senses that common
Closer examination will in most cases reveal just where that is. Indeed, usage gives them, are only applied in cases where something is actually
it may be useful to undertake the last-mentioned investigation before the accomplished, either someone is brought to accept a proposition as true
others. For if we have discovered that the proof has one of the indicators, after appropriate consideration, or else his confidence in its truth is ac-
we already know that it is faulty, and thus will work with even greater tually raised. If neither of these things is accomplished, one often says
assurance and diligence to discover where the flaw lies. In this case, we that nothing has been proved. As unobjectionable as this way of speaking
will not be annoyed when we consider the propositions and inferences may be, it is more in line with the aims of science to connect a somewhat
both individually and in combination, nor when we check the whole pro- wider concept with these words, as we do when we speak of unsuccess-
cedure for the various flaws that may be committed in proofs until we ful proofs, or even of proofs that make the conclusion more rather than
have discovered the problem. But since there are no indicators that allow less doubtful. Some thought they had defined this concept merely by say-
us easily to detect the presence of an eITor in evet:Y case, it still remains ing that to prove a proposition merely means to demonstrate or deduce it
possible that a proof is flawed even when we cannot detect this by apply- from others (see, e.g., KIESEWETTER, p. 489; SCHULZE, § 110; FRIES,
461 ing these indicators. Thus if we want to proceed with assurance, we will p. 311; TWESTEN, § 128); but clearly the entire concept to be defined is
have to undertake the examination we just described. Finally, concerning contained in the words "demonstrate" and "deduce". In KRUG's Worter-
the degree of confidence with which we may accept a conclusion on ac- buch, a proof is defined as the presentation of the grounds of a judgement.
count of a proof, provided that all our examination has revealed no flaws If this were correct, the grounds spoken of could not be objective, and the
that would destroy its power of conviction, we may say that this degree judgement would have to be not something already formed, but some-
becomes smaller, all other things being equal, the greater the number of thing to be formed in the future.

304 305
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 371. Particular Rules

§.371.* one wanted to prove to us that it is permissible to hate one's neighbour


by saying that permission to do this had been granted through a special
The most commonflmvs ofproofs; a) with respect to matter divine revelation. For in order to prove the latter, we would have to prove
the former, that hating one's neighbour is permissible, and indeed morally
As the instruction that I just gave for the examination of a given proof
aood. (c) A special kind of backwardness occurs when the proposition to
only covered the force of conviction that it had for us ourselves, so too
be proved itself occurs in the proof, i.e., figures as one of its assumptions.
I shall now deal with the flaws of a proof that can destroy or weaken its
This offence is so flagrant that we need to do some explaining in order to
power of conviction for us. Such flaws may either lie in the nature of the
understand how anyone could be guilty of it. The first circumstance that
463 propositions used as assumptions in the proof, or in other features, e.g.,
makes this understandable is the use of signs, which often permit us to
in the order of these propositions. It is customary to consider the assump-
express one and the same proposition in quite different ways. In this way,
tions used in a proof as its matter, and everything else as its form. But
we get the deceptive appearance of having several truths before us, when
according to §309, if certain kinds of inference that are used in a proof are
really there is just one truth said in different words. But if we believe that
faulty, they must have been tacitly assumed by the inventor of the proof,
two different expressions of the same proposition are different proposi-
if they do not appear explicitly. Thus if we count all the tacitly thought
tions, it is no wonder if we use one of them, perhaps the one that is more
propositions among the presuppositions of a proof, we must also count
common and hence appears to be a better-known truth, to prove the other.
the kinds of inference used in a proof, at least when these are faulty, as
A second circumstance is that many proofs consist of long sequences of
belonging to its matter. But since there is an essential difference between
inferences, and most of us have the bad habit of putting off the proof of
an incorrect rnle of inference and other incorrect propositions, the former
propositions we need right now to a later time. When, finally, we come
being far more dangerous, I will permit myself to distinguish two kinds
to carry out the promised proof of a proposition we applied earlier, we
of proposition belonging to the matter of a proof: those that treat of a kind
may well find that we-looking around in our stock of already proved
of inference used in the proof, and the others. After these preliminaries,
propositions in order to find out which of these can serve to prove t.he 465
we may say:
proposition before us-hit upon a proposition that was only proved with
1) The first material fault of a proof consists in its employing as pre-
the help of that very proposition, and yet do not notice this, since we do
suppositions propositions that either cannot be accepted at all, or else not
not keep in mind the grounds supporting every one of our claims. Since
accepted with a sufficient degree of confidence. This may be called the
the demonstration of one proposition from another is called moving from
flaw of untenable presuppositions or assumptions (petitio principii). If
one to the other, and thus likened to a movement, a proof that somewhere
such an assumption is true while its truth is not evident to us, and if it
assumes the very proposition to be proved can be looked upon as mov-
is possible to convince ourselves of its truth by directing our attention
inab throuah
b
a number of places before coming back to where one started.
to other propositions, then the proof should not be discarded; rather, one
Thus one describes a kind of circle here, which is why the above flaw
may remove the flaw simply by adding a few propositions that demon-
is called that of circular proof Such a circle occurs, for example, when
strate the assumption in question. Such an emendation cannot be ex-
we attempt to prove that our eyes do not show us things upside do~n (as
pected, however, if (a) the assumption is obviously false. For nothing can
some believe), but rather as they actually are, by calling on the expenence
be concluded from false presuppositions. We might call this the flaw of
we have when we find that what our eyes show to be higher, we touch by
false assumptions. (b) A second case occurs when we know of no way to
reaching higher. For we only infer that we are reaching higher because
464 demonstrate the proposition that is assumed in the proof other than deriv-
we see this, and accordingly only based on the assumption that if our eyes
ing it from the proposition to be proved. In this case, we would already
show us something to be higher, it actually is.
have to hold the proposition to be proved to be true in order to find the
2) It happens all too often that starting from assumptions a conclusion
proof convincing, and thus the proof would be entirely dispensable. We
is deduced that in fact is neither strictly deducible from these assumptions
shall say of a proof with this flaw (which the ancients called uoL"t:pov
nor stands to them in a relation of consequence to ground, but rather is
np6L"t:pov) that it has things backwards. This fault would occur if some-

306 307
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 371. Particular Rules

deducible only through probable inferences. This mistake, which on the Thus in EUCLID'S Elements (I, 23) the possibility of an angle equal to a
above view only occurs when a faulty rule of inference is thought, if only given angle is proven only under the condition that it occupies the same
tacitly, is usually called a non sequitur. The following are a few notewor- plane as the given angle; but later, e.g., XI, 20, he assumes the possibil-
thy kinds of non sequiturs: (a) If the assumptions someone starts from ity of such an angle in any other plane. (d) A non sequitur also occurs
466 in order to prove the desired conclusion are not suitable for that purpose, in proofs which commit the error of incomplete enumeration or induc-
then there must have been some reason that led him to begin with these tion, i.e., those in which a certain attribute b is stated of all A, while the
propositions. This reason often lies in the fact that a proposition that is premises only show that this is the case for some of them, either because
similar to the proposition to be proved and easily confused with it does in one doesn't know that there are other A, or knows this but, having found
fact follow from these assumptions. If we seek to prove a given proposi- the attribute bin so many A, he wishes to deduce not with mere probabil-
tion, and to this end combine all kinds of propositions in order to see if ity but with complete certainty that it is found in all. This mistake may
it follows from any of them, it may easily happen that we first hit upon a be called that of concluding all from many. It is committed by those who,
conclusion that is very similar to the proposition to be proved, and then starting from the perception that all the larger organic bodies we observe
immediately mistake the former for the latter. We are all the less likely to come to be do so through procreation from similar bodies, draw the
to notice our mistake if our attention is flagging due to the investiga- conclusion that all do. (e) Just as people often take propositions to be
tions we have been conducting, or if we eagerly desire to have finally equivalent when in fact they stand in a relation of subordination, so too
found a proof for our proposition. It can also be the case that someone people often mistakenly think that compatible propositions are incompat-
who discovers a proof knows full well that the indicated premises do not ible, and incorrectly infer the falsity of one of them from the truth of the
demonstrate the proposition to be proved, but only a similar one, and yet other. Thus when it is shown that various teachings of a religion arose
presents his proof anyway, in the hope that we will not notice the con- through error, some people conclude that this religion cannot be a di-
fusion. This mistake can quite appropriately be called that of confusion. vine revelation. (f) Propositions that are merely contrary are occasionally 468
Prof. KRUG gives the quite suitable name of a displacement of the point taken to be contradictory, and thus people permit themselves to infer the
at issue; and, depending upon whether it is done wittingly or not, either truth of one from the falsity of the other, which is not admissible. Thus
a mere misjudgement or a distortion of the point. We have an example in people often conclude that someone denies something merely because he
the well known proof through which the friends of materialism attempt to does not affirm it. (g) When someone undertakes to prove a proposition
prove that our thoughts and sensations take place in the body, since these stating that something is greater or smaller than it should be for a given
are changed by movements in the body. For this only shows that these purpose, it often happens that assumptions are used from which it only
changes are dependent upon the body; it is another thing altogether to say follows that the object is quite large or small with respect to some other
that they take place in the body. (b) In the special case where the proposi- measure. This might be called a confusion of measures. This occurs, for
tion that really does follow from the given assumptions is only similar to instance, when people try to prove that there is more evil in the world
the proposition to be proved because it is subordinate to it, i.e., deducible than is consistent with God's perfection merely by reckoning how much
from it, though the latter is not deducible from the former (§ 157), one evil is found on earth. For the most that follows from this is that this evil
usually says that the proof demonstrates less or too little, because we say represents a considerable quantity in relation to our sensory capacities; it
467 that a proposition subordinate to another states less than it does. Thus in no way shows that this quantity is incompatible with God's perfection.
one proves too little if, in attempting to prove the well-known geomet- The same mistake is committed when people try to prove that Christian-
rical theorem of the equality of vertical angles, one merely shows that ity is not divinely revealed by pointing to the small amount of good it
these angles have the same magnitude. (c) Every proof wherein a univer- has been able to produce so far. (h) Often many grounds are adduced in
sal conclusion is demonstrated by grounds that hold only under special a proof of a proposition, which are all so constituted that none can deny
conditions also belongs here. This mistake is called inferring from the that individually they do not suffice to convince, yet it is expected that
particular to the universal, or from the conditioned to the unconditioned. all of them together will produce complete certainty. Now if the degree

308 309
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 371. Particular Rules

of probability that a partial ground has by itself is < ~, ~


then by addino-b erthal (Reutlingen, 2nd. ed., 1801, p. 54). For his objection to what he
more such grounds, the probability of the proposition to be proved will calls relative inferences, by means of which opposed propositions can be
be lowered rather than raised; while if it is > ~, the probability indeed proved with apparently equal right, applies to this kind of inference. "Our
increases, but it can never attain complete certainty in this way. Many oratorical fantasy," he says here, "takes the difference between more and
theologians commit this error when they attempt to give their opinion the less to be that between something and nothing." And so it is; for in these
authority of a teaching authenticated by the word of God by producing a proofs one concludes from propositions that are only relative, and only
469 pile of citations from Scripture, when they must admit that each of these hold with respect to a given measure, to propositions stating something
texts could be interpreted differently. (i) In proofs which are drawn from utterly absolute.
experience it often happens that people conclude from the fact that they
perceive two phenomena A and B either at the same time, or one shortly §.372.*
after the other, that they stand in a causal relation. Yet in order to jus-
tify such an inference, we would have to have observed these phenomena b) With respect to form
many times in the same temporal relation, and also observed that when
~ften, the propositions which form the basis of a proof as its assump-
the phenomenon that is claimed to be the effect is absent, we must have
tions may all be true, and recognised as such by us, and in addition stand
observed circumstances in most if not all cases that sufficiently explain
to the proposition to be proved in a genuine relation of deducibility, and
the absence of this effect. One may call this an unwarranted inference
nevertheless the proof fails to produce the required conviction simply be-
from experience or the surreptitious eJ.perience; in the language of the
cause its form is deficient. In a proof presented in language, this flaw may
Scholastics it was called the Sophisma non causae ut causae or post hoc,
occur (1) because the expressions chosen are obscure, so that we cannot
ergo propter hoc. Physicians frequently make this error when, perceiving
clearly gather from them what the author actually claimed, what reasons
that the patient improves following treatment, they describe the treatment
he had for his conclusions, etc. (2) The flaw may also lie in the fact that
as the cause of the improvement. (k) Just as people, in setting out to prove
the appropriate order is not observed, e.g., when the conclusions are too
one proposition, only succeed in proving a similar one, so too, in setting
far removed from their premises. Or again (3) it may lie in the fact that
out to refute a proposition, i.e., show its falsity (or the truth of its denial),
the conclusion that the author claims to follow from given premises only
people often only manage to refute a similar proposition. This flaw is
follows by a form of inference that is not evident for us, since only af-
called the ignoratio elenchi; if committed wittingly, it is called a mutatio
ter reflection and the mediation of several simpler forms of inference are
controversiae. (1) Another flaw that occurs with refutations is that instead
we able to recognise this relation of deducibility. Since this flaw arises
of showing the falsity of a given proposition, people are content to make
through the omission of propositions that should have been included, one 47 l
it ridiculous or improbable. (m) Often people think they have refuted a
may call it a gap or a leap in demonstration. (4) The opposite problem,
proposition when in fact they have only discovered the untenability of its
that of mixing in propositions (be they assumptions or conclusions) that
customary proof.
are completely dispensable for the derivation of the conclusion, can also
Note. Generally speaking, faulty inferences are counted as belonging
hinder conviction. Such proofs might be criticised as redundant or over-
to the form rather than the matter. Thus in KIESEWETTER'S L., §319,
loaded.
we read: the form of the proof lies in the consequence. I would have
Note. The way I have understood the concept of a leap (no. 3) is
nothing against this, only it would then be necessary to give different
the same as that adopted by others, e.g., REUSCH, BAUMGARTEN, REI-
470 definitions, and not count all the propositions occurring (expressly or tac-
MARUS, KANT. Some, e.g., KRUG (§ 133, note 4), however, only want
itly) in a proof as belonging to its matter, but rather only those that are not
to recognise a leap in cases where one passes from one proposition to
rules of inference. The flaw discussed in no. 2, g has not, to my knowl-
another that does not follow. Accordingly, a leap would be the same
edge, been mentioned in previous treatises of logic, but another author,
thing as an invalid inference. It seems to me, however, that my way of
the much-loved JEAN PAUL RICHTER, pointed it out in his Campan-
drawing the distinction is favoured by common usage, since by a leap we

310 311
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 373, 374. Particular Rules

understand a kind of movement in which certain intermediate places are were true, and all the forms of inference correct, a proposition deduced
not touched. The aims of science also require this meaning, since logic from such assumptions using such forms of inference (either immediately, 473
must certainly warn us against the mistake of leaving out intermediate or else with the addition of other decidedly true assumptions and correct
propositions when these are necessary for a proof's power of conviction. forms of inference) could not possibly be false. Now since any proof
from which we may deduce something false in the way described must
§.373.* be untenable, we may also say, conversely, that any proof that is unten-
able must allow us to deduce something false. For if a false assumption
Various indicators of the incorrectness of a proof is made, then-since it is well-known that from any false proposition in-
a) if the conclusion is false numerably many others are deducible, and that anything deducible from
a part of the given assumptions must be considered deducible from them
Since we only call a proof convincing if all the assumptions it makes are all, since one may not assume that they conflict-it is beyond doubt that
true and in addition the proposition adduced as the conclusion stands to something false may be deduced from such a proof. But if an incorrect
the former in a relation of consequence to ground or of deducibility, it form of inference is used, i.e., if the proposition Mis represented as stand-
is obvious that the conclusion of a correct proof must itself always be ing in the relation of deducibility to certain other propositions A, B, C, ...
true. Thus if we discover that the conclusion a proof attempts to bring when in fact it does not, then it must be permissible to count the rule of
472 us to is false, we may certainly infer that the proof is untenable. Here the inference, expressed in words, as one of the premises of the proof. If
it is obvious that we may not claim that the conclusion is false unless the rule is false, then it is possible to deduce something false from it as
the grounds for its falsity are, taken together, obviously more probable well, namely, by specifying the variable ideas i,j, ... so as to transform
than the grounds in favour of it, including those which occur in the proof the propositions A,B,C, ... and Minto others A',B',C', ... and M' such
under examination. Accordingly, one way of examining a proof is to see that A',B',C', ... are all true and and M' false. Admittedly, it does not
whether we can see the falsity of its conclusion. It is well known that it is follow from this that we will always be able to deduce an obviously false
often easier to convince oneself of the falsity of a (universal) proposition proposition from an untenable proof in the way described (i.e., from its
than it is to convince oneself of its truth, since a single case where the own premises and its own forms of inference). Nonetheless, we may ex-
proposition does not hold suffices to prove the former. Thus one should pect to succeed in this in many cases, especially if we take the trouble to
look for such examples, that is, for clearly false things that would follow make several attempts. We may thus recommend as a particularly useful
from the proposition. Thus the proof of the proposition that no synthetic means of detecting untenable proofs that one see whether from the very 474
judgement may be formed concerning things in themselves must be quite propositions and kinds of inference used in a proof it is possible to de-
defective, since the proposition itself is false; indeed, it is itself a synthetic duce a decidedly false proposition (either immediately, or else with the
judgement concerning things in themselves. aid of other decidedly true propositions and decidedly correct forms of
inference). An example where this indicator of untenability is easily per-
§.374.* ceived is the well-known proof whereby the opponents of Christian reve-
lation wish to show that mankind has no need of this revelation, because
b) {f the proof proves too much
if we did, it would already have to be universally known. In order to show
that this inference is incorrect, we need only inquire whether there is any
Often the proposition to which we are led in a proof is true, or at least
know ledge that no one would deny to be necessary for the human race,
we are not able to show its falsity beforehand, yet we can show that from
and yet which is, like Christianity, not universally acknowledged. The ex-
the assumptions and forms of inference something obviously false is de-
ample of natural religion occurs to us immediately, since its necessity for
ducible. In this case, too, we are justified in declaring the given proof un-
mankind is acknowledged in precisely the same sense that the necessity
tenable, i.e., that either among the assumptions or among the forms of in-
of revelation is claimed, even though natural religion is only found in the
ference employed, there is something incorrect. For if all the assumptions

312 313
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 375. Particular Rules

appropriate purity and completeness in a few people. Thus we see that be considered variable in them, i.e., if a does not occur in the general
the above proof for the dispensability of revelation must be flawed, since, form of this kind of inference, then we may certainly conclude that the 476
if it were correct, we could claim the dispensability of natural religion on proof is incorrect. For if it were correct, i.e., all the assumptions were
equal grounds. A proof that has this indicator of incorrectness, i.e., one true and the forms of inference valid, then if we omitted the idea a or else
from whose premises and forms of inference something decidedly false replaced it everywhere with a, then all the assumptions would remain true
can be deduced, is usually said to prove too much. In this expression, and the inference forms valid. The first follows because the idea a either
prove does not mean to convince someone of the truth of a proposition, does not occur in the assumptions at all, or else only in propositions that
but rather that a proposition is deducible from the assumptions follow- remain true if a is replaced by a. The second does as well, because a is
ing the kinds of inference used; by too much, we mean something false. considered variable in the inferences that are used. But if the idea a is
Yet people go further, and say "that a proof that proves too much, proves omitted or replaced by a in all propositions (including the conclusion),
nothing at all." Here "prove" is used in its proper sense, so that the en- the conclusion becomes false and hence there must be an error either in
tire saying means that a proof from whose premises, using the very forms the proof (namely, in the propositions we altered) or in the kinds of infer-
475 of inference employed, one may deduce something false procures no con- ence used. Since in the case considered here the truth of the proposition
viction for the proposition it is supposed to prove. From this paraphrase it to be proved depends upon the condition that one may not omit the idea
is obvious that one is not justified in saying that a proof proves too much a, or replace it with a, one may say that the flaw of the proof is that it
simply because it proves more than intended. For to prove more sim- does not make use of all the conditions of the truth of the proposition.
ply means to begin from assumptions and make inferences from which a That is, the fact that the idea a either does not occur at all in the assump-
proposition follows that says more than the proposition proved, i.e., from tions, or else only in propositions where it can be replaced by a without
which the latter is deducible without the former being deducible from affecting truth may be looked upon as a failure to observe this condition.
the latter. Thus one who proves more by the same token also proves the Thus a special means for discovering the incorrectness of a given proof
lesser conclusion than he set out to prove. One can only say that he has is to investigate in the way described whether all the conditions of the
proved too much, and hence has proved nothing, if a false proposition fol- truth of the proposition to be proved are used. For this purpose we must
lows from his premises according to his inferences. Proofs that are said consider each idea a contained in the proposition to be proved that cannot
to prove too little are another thing altogether. By this one means (§371, be omitted from the proposition or exchanged with a certain other idea a
no. 2, b) proofs from whose assumptions there only follows a proposition without affecting its truth, and investigate whether it appears in the given
stating less than the proposition to be proved. Thus if one claims this as assumptions in such a way that these would no longer remain true if a 477
the conclusion, one must make use of an incorrect rule of inference, and were omitted or replaced with a. If we find even a single idea a for which
hence might also have derived many other false propositions following this is not the case, i.e., which either does not appear at all in the premises
the same rule. It may be claimed, accordingly, that all proofs that prove or else only in propositions that would remain true if it were omitted or
too little also prove too much in a certain respect. replaced by a, and if the inferences used in the proof are also such that
a may be considered variable, if there is perhaps no kind of inference in
§.375.* whose form the idea a occurs as a constituent, then we have discovered
that the proof is incorrect. The most common case where the error of
c) If it doesn't use all the conditions which I have spoken occurs is when the subject-idea of the proposition
to be proved is of the form [Something] (a + b + c + d + ···), and one of
If a certain idea a that occurs in the conclusion of a given proof cannot
the ideas a, b, c, d, ... , which cannot be omitted if this proposition is to
be omitted or even exchanged with another idea a if the proposition is to
remain true, either does not occur at all in the premises or else not in the
remain true, but a either does not occur at all in the premises or else only
right way. In this special case, one may say that the given proof is too
occurs in places where it can be replaced by a without affecting the truth
wide, since it may be extended from [Something]( a+ b + c + d + ···) to
of the premises, and if the kinds of inference are such that the idea a may

314 315
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 376, 377. Particular Rules

the wider idea [Something] (b + c + d + ·· ·). Even the writings of mathe- that such inquiries hold nothing worth knowing for him, he may skip this
maticians contain proofs that betray their incorrectness in this way. Thus section. In order to avoid misunderstanding, I must point out that my 479
EUCLID (Elem., I, 22) states in the form of a problem the proposition that purpose in presenting and analysing these examples is not to protect the
from any three straight lines, any two of which are together greater than reader from the danger of believing what is proved in these fallacious ar-
the third, a triangle may be constructed. The condition that any two of guments. Rather, they were invented precisely in order to make it obvious
these lines are together greater than the third is a well-known condition at the first glance that the conclusion is false, and hence the proof incor-
for the truth of this proposition. But as it is not even touched upon in rect. It is merely a matter of teaching beginners how these mistakes may
the proof, we see that the latter must be flawed. We have another exam- be pointed out; and such examples are all the better the more undeniable
ple with the well-known theorem concerning the sum of the peripheral it is that there is an error, even though it may not be obvious where the
angles in any convex polygon. For even though the condition of convex- error lies. ARISTOTLE, who wrote a special book on this subject (rrspl
ity, which is essential to the truth of the proposition, is mentioned in the oocpta"Ltxwv E:Myxwv 1) classifies all false proofs or (on the assumption
proof, this does not occur in a place where something is inferred which that the proofs were produced with bad intentions) sophisms under two
478 could not have been said had the condition not been mentioned at all. genera: those in which the deception arises from the verbal expressions
chosen (E:1'syxot mxpa "L~v At~tv 2 ) and others, where this is not the case
§.376.* (s1'syxot s~w "L~c; M~sc0c; 3 ). This classification is quite correct; only one
should not forget, as ARISTOTLE himself remarks, that one and the same
d) If it calls upon the experience at the wrong place, or scorns it
sophism may belong in both genera. He mentions six kinds of sophisms
I have already noted in §369 that there are truths which cannot be proved that are based on language, three of which (namely, the 6µc.wuµ(cx, the&µ-
by experience, unless this were to take the form of an appeal to authority cpt~o1'(cx, and the rrpoo06(cx4 ) I need not take the time to explain. For who
or testimony; and that there are also other truths which cannot be inferred would be unable to solve a sophism like the following: Mus syllaba est,
from conceptual truths alone. If we nevertheless find that someone refers Mus autem caseum rodit; Syllaba ergo ca.sewn rodit? 5 SENECA' s well-
to experience in the proof of a proposition of the first kind, or scorns all justified rebuke (Ep., XLVIII) was only meant to apply to such vulgar
reference to experience in the proof of a proposition of the second kind, sophisms. The other three kinds (the auvr:lsmc;, 6tcx(psmc; and the ox~µcx
wishing to decide the matter from concepts alone, or at least not provid- /,€~t:u)c; 6 ) are more artful.
ing a basis of the kind of experiences which alone could lead to a decision 1) For A., a a6vHsmc; is present when an expression, which must be
here, then we know in advance that the proof must be faulty. If, for ex- taken in a divided sense if the proposition is to be true, is taken in another
ample, we read that someone intends to prove the principle of sufficient sense, the so-called composite sense, as in the following argument: "If an 480
reason by experience, or the absurdity of the homeopathic principle by a eye were necessary for seeing, then it would have to be either the left or
priori reasons, we may know in advance that both proofs are faulty. the right, for we have no other. But neither the left nor the right eye is
necessary for seeing, since we can see without the former and we can see
§.377. without the latter, as anyone can easily establish through an experiment.
Thus it is not necessary to have an eye in order to see." The deception
Examination of some famous sophisms from the writings of logicians in this inference stems in my opinion merely from the fact that a pair of

From the very beginning of logic among the Greeks, it has been consid-
1On sophistical rejittations.
ered important to teach the c01Tect method of examining proofs to dis-
2 deception through the expression
cover their flaws not merely by presenting dry rules, but also by provid- 3 deception independent of the expression
ing a considerable number of examples invented for the sake of practise. 4 equivocation, amphiboly, and accent
Perhaps it will not be unwelcome to the reader to find the most notewor- 5 Rat is a syllable. A rat eats cheese. Therefore a syllable eats cheese.

thy of these examples presented and examined here. If someone thinks 6 composition, division, and form of expression

316 317
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 377. Particular Rules

different thoughts, one of which occurs in the major premise, the other in 2) According to A., a 6tdpwtc; is present when an expression that
the minor, are stated using the same expression "either or". This creates must be understood in the composite sense if the proposition is to be true
the illusion that the three propositions have the following form: If A were is taken in the divided sense, as in the following argument: "Whoever has
the case, B would have to be the case. But B isn't the case. Hence, A one, two, and three Thaler, has six Thaler altogether; thus anyone who
isn't the case. And this would be correctly inferred. But if we express has only three Thaler has six." Neither premise is expressed precisely
the meaning in which the major and minor premise must be taken more enough. If the major premise is to be true, it must be taken in a sense
distinctly, it appears that these propositions do not correspond to the in- which is more distinctly expressed as follows: "Whoever has a single
dicated form. In the major premise the "either or" merely indicates that Thaler, and in addition to this a sum of two Thaler, and in addition to
some eye or other, the right or the left, no matter which, must be present these yet another sum of three Thaler, and beyond this no other single
if one is to see. But in the minor premise the denial of the either-or, or Thaler nor any sum of several Thaler, has in total a sum of six Thaler." 482
the neither-nor, has the sense that the right eye is not necessary for sight, The minor, for its part, if it is to remain true, must be interpreted to mean:
and neither is the left, a claim that is entirely compatible with the former. "Whoever has three Thaler, has in this sum a part which contains two,
I will not devote much time to the question of whether the sense in which as well as a single Thaler." It is now obvious that the above conclusion
the either-or occurs in the major premise might be called composite, and does not follow from the combination of these two propositions. Another
the sense in which it occurs in the minor might be called divided. In- example is: "Two and three are even and odd. But two and three are five;
stead, I shall show how the incorrectness of the inference may be seen hence five is even and odd." If the major premise is to remain true, it
even more clearly if the propositions are expressed in a way which makes must be understood to mean "The sum of the numbers two and three is
their logical constituents more evident. The major premise would have a sum of an even and an odd number," while the minor must be taken to
to be expressed roughly as follows: "If an eye were necessary for sight, mean "The sum of the numbers two and three is equivalent to the number
then the idea of a man who has no right eye and no left eye, and yet sees, five." The most that follows from this is the conclusion that the number
481 would be objectless." The minor, however, would run as follows: "Each five is equivalent to a certain sum of an even and an odd number, which
of the following two ideas is objectual: that of a man who has no right eye is certainly true.
and yet sees, and that of a man who has no left eye and yet sees." Now it 3) A. defines a sophism m:xpi:X LO ax~µcx L~c; MC:E:(0c; 1 as one that one
is obvious that the two propositions are not connected in such a way that obtains OLCXV LO fl~ WULO (0CTWJL(0c; E:pf1YJVE:UYJLCXL, 2 as in the argument:
the conclusion can be deduced from them. The minor claims something "You are not what I am; I am a man. Hence you are not a man." The ma-
completely different from what the consequent of the major denies. The jor premise "You are not who I am" does not mean "Every attribute that
former concerns one idea, the latter two; and the idea that is claimed to belongs to me must be denied of you," but rather "Not every attribute that
be objectless in the consequent of the major is of a completely different belongs to me also belongs to you." If the first interpretation were admis-
sort than the two said to be objectual in the minor. The latter two ideas sible, then the minor "I am a man" would certainly justify our drawing the
may well have objectuality even if the former, which is far more com- conclusion. But if the major is taken in the second sense, the whole argu-
plex, is objectless. The consequent of the major and the minor are thus ment falls apart. From this, one will know how to resolve the sophism of
compatible, and hence one may not infer here in modo tollente. A. also MENEDEMUS (in Diogen. Laert., II, 18, no. 2): "Generally beneficial is
counts the following inference as belonging to this kind: "Many a very not the same as good; thus the generally beneficial is not good." Another
good man is a bad poet; thus many a good man is a bad man." The error sophism that ARISTOTLE reckons to be of this sort is: "What someone
in this inference consists merely in the fact that the attribute of badness, had before but no longer has, he has lost. If someone has ten marks at
which is ascribed to the poetic ability in the premise, is applied in the the beginning of a game and loses one, then he formerly had ten marks
conclusion to his humanness, and indeed, following the customary usage and no longer has ten marks. Thus someone who has ten marks at the 483
of this expression, to his moral character.
1which depends on the form of expression
2 when what is not the same is expressed in the same form

318 319
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 377. Particular Rules

beginning of a game and loses one, has lost ten marks." Here only the so does the whole argument. The sophism of DIODORUS (from SEXTUS
major premise is incorrect. For we do not always say of someone who EMPIRICUS, Hypotop., II, 22) is similar: "If a body moves, it must do so
previously had something and now no longer has it that he has lost it; either in the place where it is, or in a place where it is not. But a body
rather, when speaking of objects that have a quantity, it is customary to cannot move in a place where it is; for if it does so, it remains in the same
understand by loss only the difference between the quantity previously place, and thus is at rest. Still less can it move in a place where it is not;
possessed and the quantity that remains, just as by profit we mean only for wherever it is to have motion, there it must first be located. Thus it
the difference between the quantity presently possessed and the quantity is impossible for a body to move." In this argument, too, only the major
one previously had. Thus someone who previously had ten marks but no premise is incorrect. For movement is nothing but a change of place that
longer does, but rather (having lost one) only has nine left would not be lasts a certain time, and so it is absurd to suppose that movement can take 485
said to have lost ten, but only one mark. Perhaps the sophism reported by place in a single place; rather, one must suppose that there are several
SEXTUS EMPIRICUS also belongs here: "If Socrates died, he must have places in which the movement occurs. Thus instead of saying that if a
done so either while living or when dead. But while he was still living, he body moves it moves either in the place where it is or in the place where
did not die, for someone who is living is not dead. Nor did he die after he it is not, we should say: if a body moves, it moves from one place to an-
had already finished living; for if he were no longer living, he was already other. Another sophism I would include here is the following: "Someone
dead, and a dead man cannot die a second time. Hence Socrates is not yet who says that a man is a living being speaks truly. Someone who says that
dead." Here we should notice that the noun "death" is taken in two senses. a man is a bird thereby says that a man is a living being. Thus someone
In the first, it means the single, indivisible moment which constitutes the who says that a man is a bird speaks truly." The major premise may only
final limit of life. In this sense, one cannot say that death has a certain be admitted insofar as it is understood to mean "Someone who says that
duration, since no moment has a duration. In this sense of death, one can- man is a living being, and adds nothing to this, says something true." Or,
not even say that death is a change, since every change consists of parts, more succinctly: "The proposition that man is a living being has truth."
and has a duration. Thus one must say of this moment that as long as a If the indicated conclusion were to follow from this, the minor premise
being still lives, it lies in the future, and if it has ceased to live, it lies in would have to be expressed as follows: "Whoever says that a man is a
484 the past. It does not follow from this that this moment cannot also be the bird says that a man is a living being, and adds nothing to this" or "The
present moment. For this occurs when the being is neither still living nor two propositions 'a man is a bird' and 'a man is a living being' are equiv-
has yet ceased to live, but instead ceases to live at this moment. But far alent." But this is obviously false, so it is no wonder the conclusion is
more commonly the word "death" is taken to mean a ce1tain change that also false.
begins at a not completely determinate moment, roughly that at which 4) A. enumerates seven kinds of sophisms belonging to the second
the body can no longer perform the most important functions required to genus of sophism, those that are based on something other than the ver-
sustain life, and ends with the last moment of life. This meaning is the bal expression. The first of these, 11:cxpa -ro ouµ~c:~rixos 1 is supposed to
basis of the verb "to die", since verbs always designate something that has consist in a confusion of an object with its attributes. The following ar-
a duration. In this sense of the word, when we speak of death we must gument is of this sort: "Socrates is a man. Koriskos is a man. Hence
ascribe it a duration that begins while the man is still living and ends at Socrates and Koriskos are the same." But this conclusion does not follow
the end-point of his life. Thus we may say that a man begins to die while from the premises. For it does not follow from the fact that two objects
he is still living, but stops dying as soon as he ceases to live. Hence in the have one attribute in common that they share all their attributes, still less
above argument the major premise,"If Socrates were already dead, then that they are one and the same object, only represented twice. If, on the 486
either he must have died while he was still living or when he had already contrary, someone wanted to argue: "Socrates and Koriskos are differ-
ceased to live," cannot be admitted; for he was not already dead when he ent; but Socrates is a man. So Koriskos is not a man," we would have
was still living, but instead began to die then; nor did he die when he was to counter that here the major premise simply means that not every at-
already dead-rather, he had already died. But if the major premise fails, 1fal!acies connected with accident

320 321
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 377. Particular Rules

tribute belonging to Socrates also belongs to Koriskos. But it in no way attribute that belongs to certain beings found in M. cannot belong to any
follows from this that the property of humanity that belongs to Socrates being in A." But this would be quite false, and indeed a self-contradictory
must be denied of Koriskos. A. also includes the following argument proposition, for the beings in M. and A. would have at least the common
here: "A painting that I have bought is my property; but every painting attribute of being beings.
is a work of art. So a painting I have bought is my work of art." From 5) A. mentions as a second kind of sophism not dependent on the
the given premises, only this conclusion follows: "A painting that I have mere form of expression the rco:pa -ri.J &rc/,&)c; fi µYj &rcl\Dic; Myc:m~o:t. 1
bought is mine and is a work of art" while to say that the painting is my The tj;c:u56µc:voc; 2 of EUBULIDES, for which PHILETAS OF Kos sought a
work means something completely different in common usage. A. also solution until he died, is of this sort: "It is possible for a liar to admit that
seems to count the argument usually called Electra or E:yxsxo:/,uµµsvoc; 1 he is a liar; but if a liar admits that he is a liar, he speaks the truth; but 488
as belonging here too. "You do not know who appears before you with someone who speaks the truth is no liar. Thus it is possible that a liar is
a veiled face. But it is possible that a man you know quite well appears also not a liar." This sophism seems to arise from a false concept of what
before you now with a veiled face. Thus it is possible that you do not a liar is. One presupposes that only someone who either always denies
know a man whom you know quite well." It seems to me that the prob- the truth or at least does so now, deserves to be called a liar. For only on
lem in this sophism arises from the ambiguity of the word know, which this understanding would the major premise of the second syllogism be
is admittedly taken in several senses in ordinary life. Thus we are often true: "Someone who speaks the truth" (in some particular case, i.e., in
required to add more specifically whether we mean knowing his name, or admitting that he denied the truth in many other cases) "is no liar." But
the person himself, or something else. In the above argument, the context on this concept the major premise of the first syllogism, "It is possible for
indicates that by knowing a man as spoken of in the minor premise, we a liar to admit that he is a liar" is no longer tenable. For if only someone
simply mean the mere ability to determine under certain circumstances who either always denies the truth or denies the truth right now is to be
(which may not yet obtain)-principally, seeing his face or hearing his called a liar, then it can never happen that a liar admits that he is one. But
voice-that he is the same person we saw or heard on another occasion. if this is to be possible, we must suppose that someone who speaks the
487 But in the major premise, to know someone means to gather from the truth sometimes may still deserve to be called a liar (on account of other
signs currently available to us that he is the same person we saw on some statements), and then the second major premise no longer holds. I would
other occasion; while not to know him means not to be in a position to ex- also include here the famous sophism 6 &v-rtcnpscp(0v. 3 Protagoras took
press this judgement. But if one inserts these two meanings that the word on the student Euathlus on the condition that he would pay Protagoras
"know" has in the premises into the appropriate places in the conclusion, a certain sum of money as soon as he won his first case. Since Euath-
all the apparent absurdity disappears, and it comes to mean: "A man that lus did not take on any cases after his schooling was over, and did not
you are able to say under certain circumstances is the same one you saw pay his teacher, Protagoras brought a suit against him and brought forth
or heard on certain other occasions, e.g., when you see his face or the like, the following argument: "Regardless of whether the judges decide that
can appear before you in circumstances where you are unable to say this." Euathlus must pay me, he will be obligated to do so. For if it is decided
The sophism of CHRYSIPPUS more rightly belongs here: "Whoever is in he must pay, then he will be obligated to on account of this judgement.
Megara is not in Athens. Now there are men in Megara. Hence there are But if the judgement is that he need not pay, he will be obligated to pay
no men in Athens." The major premise "Whoever is in M. is not in A." is me, because he will have won his first case." Then Euathlus mounted
at most true if interpreted to mean that one and the same finite substance the stage and claimed that he would in no case be obligated to pay. "For
that is in M. at a certain time is not in A. at the same time. But nothing if the judges free me from the obligation to pay, I will not be obligated 489
follows from this that would justify the conclusion that if there are beings
in M. that have the attribute of humanity there cannot be any such beings 1
the case where one expression is used absolutely or in a certain respect [and not in
in A. To justify this conclusion, we would require the major premises "An its proper sense
2 1iar
1the veiled one 3 retort or reversal; also known as the boomerang or the lawyer

322 323
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 377. Particular Rules

to do so on account of the judgement. But if they decide I must pay, I is called Koriskos; thus you know him. But you don't know that he is
will not be obligated to because of the contract with Protagoras, since I a musician; thus you don't know him. Hence you both know and don't
have lost my first case." The judges are said to have found the dispute know the same man." This is easily dealt with. If to know a man means
so complicated that they made no decision.* The astonishing thing here to know his name, then the first, but not the second premise holds; but if
is the phenomenon that from the same presupposition (E.'s promise that more is required, the second may hold, but the first will not.
he would pay as soon as he won his first case) two contradictory conse- 7) No examples worth considering here are given of either the fourth
quences (he is both obligated and not obligated to pay) may be deduced kind (reap& -ro i!:v &pxfj ),aµ~&vc:tv 1 ), where the proposition to be proved
with apparently equal right. But this appearance arises only because the is assumed in the proof, or of the fifth kind (reap& -rb tre6µc:vov 2 ), where
assumption is taken in a sense according to which it is not only false, but one infers the existence of the ground from the existence of the conse-
self-contradictory. When Euathlus declares "I shall consider myself obli- quence. The so-called Achilles, however, namely, the proof that ZENO
gated to pay you as soon as I have won my first case" and the expression OF ELEA and his followers used to dispute the possibility of motion, is
"my first case" is understood literally to cover any case, no matter what sometimes considered the strongest instance of the latter kind of sophism.
its content, provided that it really is his first, then he stated something It runs roughly as follows: "If motion were not impossible, then more and 491
self-contradictory. For it is quite possible that his first case will concern less rapid motions must be possible. And if two bodies move in the same
precisely the question of whether he should pay, in which case his dec- direction, it must be possible for one to overtake the other if its speed is
laration would amount to saying "I will consider myself obligated to pay greater. But the following proof shows that this is impossible. Suppose
you at a time when I do not consider myself obligated to pay you, when I that Achilles, the fleet of foot, is one thousand times more rapid than a
have been released by the court from my obligation to pay you." It is no snail, and he attempts to overtake this snail, who is 1000 feet ahead of
wonder that from such a self-contradictory proposition self-contradictory him. While he runs these 1000 feet, the snail is no longer in the place
conclusions can apparently be deduced; for it is only from true premises he was before (because Achilles' movement requires some time), but
that no false conclusions can be deduced, and hence no self-contradictory 6
has instead crawled 10 0 of the distance Achilles did, i.e., 1 foot. Thus
ones. But since every pronouncement of a rational being, and still more Achilles has not overtaken him, since he is still one pace ahead. Now
490 every declaration that is to serve as the basis of a contract, must at the while Achilles runs this foot in order to overtake the snail, the latter has
very least be required to be not self-contradictory, the judge should have again moved 101 0 of a foot. Thus Achilles has again failed to ove1iake the
interpreted the expression "my first case" in E.'s declaration so that it did snail, who is idoo
of a foot ahead. But since this inference can be con-
not include the question of whether or not he is obligated to pay, in which tinually repeated, one sees that Achilles can never overtake the snail, no
case the argumentation of both E. and P. would be overturned, since both matter how long he tries." In this proof, it is correctly demonstrated that
wished the contract extended to cover this case. The decision of the ques- there is an infinite sequence of durations of which it may be claimed that
tion of when and how much the student must pay would then have to be Achilles has not yet overtaken the snail in any of them, since at the end of
determined in another way altogether. The famous syllogismus crocodil- each one he finds himself at the place where the snail was at its beginning.
inus (Quinctil. Inst., I, 10) should be judged similarly. But the claim that Achilles never (i.e., not after any time, no matter how
6) The third kind of sophism, E~(J -r~c; M~t:(uc;, 1 is said to be that in long) overtakes the snail does not follow from this. This would follow if
which something other than what was supposed to be proved is actually the above infinite sequence of durations was collectively greater than any
demonstrated. A. calls this -ro m:xpa -r~v wu ?:)J:.yxou &yvotav; 2 others given, finite duration. But this need not be the case. For if, e.g., these du-
call it E-rt:po(YJ-r~onc;. 3 He cites as an example: "You know that this man rations decreased in geometrical progression, so that each successive one
was half the length of its predecessor, then their sum would never surpass
*I have been unable to look at A LEFELD' S article on this sophism. a certain finite quantity, in the above example, 2, since the sum of the 492
1independent of the expression
2 fallacy connected with an ignorance of the nature of refutation 1begging the question
3 partiality 2 fallacies connected with the consequent

324 325
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 377. Particular Rules

1
quantities l + + ~ + k+ 1 ~ + ··· never becomes greater than 2. Now in 9) The seventh and last kind of sophism -r:b reap& -r:b -r:& rcAd(,) sp0YC·fi-
order to determine whether or not this case occurs here, we must consider t1cxw sv rcmdv, or the oocptoµcxw rcoAU(Y)c~osoc: 1 owes its origin to the
something that was passed over in silence in the above proof. This is the customary way of asking questions. This sophism consists in posing a
question of whether or not the speeds with which Achilles and the snail question that contains a hidden ambiguity, e.g., when someone asks: is
move are to be considered constant, or whether only the ratio between the this one and that one a man? If the answer is yes, then one infers "So if
two speeds is to remain constant, while the motions themselves change, someone kills this one and that one, he has only killed a man, not sev-
i.e., become ever slower, so that Achilles always takes the same time to eral." Here the answer yes is incorrect, since this one and that one are
cover the ground between him and where the snail was, while the snail al- not one man, but several. Some also include here the so-called Cornutus
ways moves one thousandth of this distance in the same time. In the first (6 xspcx-r:[vric: 2) which arises from the following question: If you haven't
case, Achilles will soon catch the snail. For if it takes Achilles a second, lost something, must you not still have it? If someone answers yes, he
say, to cover a foot, then in 1002 seconds he will already have overtaken is asked: have you lost your horns? And when this is denied, the con-
the snail. This would not be the case if one assumed that Achilles and clusion is: so you still have horns. But if he responds no to the second
the snail always move more slowly, e.g., so that the same time elapses question, saying that he has lost his horns, one concludes that he formerly
every time, even though ever smaller distances are covered. For then the had them. It is obvious that one should not answer yes to the first ques- 494
infinite number of times required for Achilles to catch the snail would all tion (If you haven't lost something, must you not still have it?). For in
be of equal length, and their sum would accordingly surpass any given, order to say that one still has something one need not only not have lost
finite time. On this assumption, one would be justified in claiming that it, but must also previously have possessed it. One of the most difficult
Achilles would never catch the snail, even though he moves a thousand sophisms is the Sorites inexplicabilis or acervus 3 (Cicero A cad. quaest.,
times faster. But this claim is unobjectionable, and contradicts none of II, 16). One raises the question of whether a heap of grains remains a
the theorems of kinematics. Indeed, it is quite comprehensible that one heap of grains if one removes one grain from it. If we respond yes, then
body can never catch another if their motions are reduced in the measure the following conclusion is drawn: "Insofar as that which remains when
of the distance separating them. one grain is removed from a heap of grains is still a heap of grain, one
8) Among the sophisms of the sixth kind mxpa -r:o µ~ cxfoov (;)C: d(- may remove another grain (the second grain removed from the original
493 -r:Lov -r:v0svw, 1 we may count the so-called sophisma pigrum or 6 &pyoc: heap) and there will still remain a heap. Thus one may also remove an-
Myoc:: 2 "Whatever I may strive to accomplish through my activity must other grain from this heap (the third taken from the original heap), and a
fall under one of two cases. It must either be a result that will in fact come heap will still remain. But since this can be repeated endlessly, it follows
to be, or else one that will not. But if it is a result that will in fact come that one may remove any number of grains you like from the heap and
to be, my activity is dispensable, since the result will come to be even if still have a heap, which is absurd, provided that the original number of
I do not act. But if it is a result that will not come to be, my action is grains is not infinite." But if we respond no to the above question, we
in vain, since the result would not come to be even if I did act. Thus in claim: "There is a heap which ceases to be a heap as soon as one removes
either case my activity has no effect, and I am wiser to remain inactive." a single grain from it; thus we claim that some number of grains, which
In this inference the only incorrect proposition is the one stating that my does not constitute a heap, will constitute one if a single grain is added
activity is dispensable if the result that I strive to attain will in fact come to it, so that a single grain can produce a heap." And this is also absurd.
to be. For it can indeed be the case that my activity is one of the causes The deceptive part of this sophism arises from the indeterminacy of the
through which it happens that this result is produced. But if this premise concept of a heap, since we are often in doubt as to whether or not a given
is false, then the conclusion that our activity has no effect in any case is multitude of objects should be said to be a heap. With this concept it is
unproven.
1the fallacy of making several questions into one
1 2 thehomed one
the fallacy of taking as the cause what is not the cause
2 1azy mind 3 argumentation by accumulation

326 327
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 378. Particular Rules

not just a matter of the number of things, but also of other factors: the Next, we must construct from the parts we have discovered in the propo-
things must be spatial objects, lying close to one another, not assembled sition M propositions that are simpler or at least not more complex than
according to any rule we can discern, and their number must be so great M, and also constituted so that Mis deducible from them. If in doing this
495 that we cannot perceive and specify it at a single glance. Thus the same we find it necessary to have recourse to concepts not contained in M, we
number of things, even if they are not mrnnged in an orderly way, may or must seek to reduce their number as far as possible. Only when we have
may not be called a heap depending upon how they lie before us, whether succeeded in this way in assuring ourselves that the truths A, B, C, D, ...
we are skilled in counting, and a number of other factors. Thus it is in from which M is deducible, are each simpler or at least no more complex
any case incorrect to say that a heap must remain a heap if one removes than M, and taken together constitute a simpler collection than any other
a single grain. It is certainly the case that removing a single grain from a from which M may be deduced may we permit ourselves to look upon
heap that is very small may result in something we no longer recognise as the former as the ground of the latter. Concerning the indication of the
a heap. There is in fact nothing absurd in the claim that a single grain can grounds of empirical truths, i.e., discovering the causes of a given effect,
produce a heap-namely, not on its own, but when added to certain oth- more will be said in the next section.
ers. In the same way, one may claim that an inch taken by itself does not
make an ell, and neither do two or three together, yet an ell results when §.379.
a single inch is added to 23 inches. Calvus (Menag. ad Diog., II, 8) and
crescens ratio (Cicero A cad., quaest., II, 28 and 29) are mere variations XXIII. The discove1y of causes for given effects
of the above argument.
One of the most common and important tasks for human inquiry is the
§.378. discovery of causes which produce given effects. According to § 168, I 497
call an object A the cause (either the complete or partial cause) of another
XXII. Discovering the ground of a given truth object B if the proposition that A exists forms the (complete or partial)
ground of the proposition that B exists. It follows that, in this sense, ev-
Once we have convinced ourselves that a given proposition is true, the ery cause is an actual thing; properly speaking, a cause is not a substance,
question of whether this proposition belongs to the class of truths that but an attribute or force which resides in a single substance or a collec-
have a ground, and hence are consequences, or instead to the class of tion of them. But in an extended sense, we give the name of a cause to
truths that, while being grounds of others, themselves rest on no grounds, an individual or a substance or a collection of them if they possess a cer-
and hence are basic truths, may become one of great scientific impor- tain force. It is my view that two kinds of cause must be distinguished,
tance. In the first case, one will want to know what the one or several namely, those which do not require any time in order to produce an effect
truths are that form the ground of the given truth. But since I admitted in of finite magnitude, and those which can produce such an effect only in
§ 198 ff. that the theory of the indicators which allow us to detect a rela- a finite period of time. An example of the first kind is the creative force
tion of ground to consequence has not been much elaborated to this point, of Goel; for Goel needs no time, no matter how small, in order to produce
496 and indeed that the very concept of this relation remains obscure, it is to a substance; rather, such a substance will exist from eternity if Goel wills
be expected that no satisfying instructions on how to solve this problem that it should so exist. An example of the second kind is every motive
will be forthcoming. Everything I believe myself capable of advancing as force which can produce a finite speed only if it has acted through a fi-
somewhat probable has already been said in §221. From what was said nite time. The existence, as well as the attributes of causes of the first
there it is clear that in order to judge whether a given truth is a basic or kind, can be demonstrated from concepts alone; hence they are discussed
a consequential truth we must know the constituents not only of the truth in a special science, namely, metaphysics. It is not necessary that logic
in question but also of those truths that are advanced as its grounds. An should give special instructions on how such causes can be discovered,
analysis of the given proposition that extends to its simple parts, insofar since the rules are the same as for the discovery of purely conceptual
as we are able to perform it, must be our first business in this problem. truths in general. But the same does not hold with respect to causes of

328 329
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Partirn!ar Rules

the second kind, which act in time, and merely produce changes. One that the cause of a certain change is a rational being, we can determine
of the reasons is that these causes have a definite magnitude and charac- from pure concepts that this cause is a simple being, that it had a rational
ter only at a certain time; hence they cannot be recognised a priori, but purpose in its activity, and so on. But whether this purpose is good or evil
only through perception. We know the nature of the mutual influence of cannot be decided from the indicated attribute alone; this would require
heavenly bodies only from perception; this influence depends upon their further perceptions. But I need not give any instructions as to how one
498 mass and spatial relations, which can and must be different at different can find attributes which are deducible from those already found, or from
times. The identification of causes which can be recognised only through pure concepts, or both. Hence I have to consider only those attributes
perception is of extreme importance. Hence it is reasonable to indicate, whose presence is found through perception. But all attributes of an ob-
in broad outline, how we must proceed in this matter. But if we are to ject whose presence is deduced from mere perceptions consist in nothing
investigate the cause of a given change, we must never doubt that there is but certain jbrces, namely, those in whose presence we make the asser-
such a cause. Common sense itself insists that for each change there must tion that the object in question is capable of causing certain perceptible
be a cause which has brought it about, and only very few scholars have changes in us and in others. Now in order to infer a given attribute from
dared to assume the possibility of certain changes without the existence perception, we must either have ourselves made this perception or some-
of a cause which determines them completely; they have done this only in one we find credible enough must report to us that he has made it. And in
the single case where those changes are the acts of will of a sentient and order to arrive at an object from this perception, one of two things must
rational being. Hence these philosophers allow us to assume that every be the case: either we must think of the object as the immediate cause of 500
perception has a cause, but we cannot simply suppose that this cause has this perception, or else we must assume that the object had some influ-
another cause and that the second cause has a third and so to infinity. For ence or other on the changes of the thing that was the immediate cause of
if we are forced to explain a certain phenomenon by claiming that a free our perception. In the first case, we must ascribe to the object the power
act of will of a sentient and rational being was a near or remote cause, to produce the perception that we (or others) had. In the second case, we
the sequence of causes finds its end at this point since we have arrived at must assume that it has the power to bring about certain changes in cer-
a cause which itself has no (fully determining) further cause. But in all tain other objects, and in this way to bring about a perception mediately.
other cases, especially where we do not encounter acts of will, we must Hence it follows that a closer determination of a cause always consists in
assume that every perception has a cause, and that the latter has again a showing that one and the same object, which we assume to be the cause of
cause, etc., even if we subscribe to this system of indeterminism. But be- a certain change, has also produced other changes of such and such a kind
fore we consider how to discover these causes, we must clearly determine under certain circumstances. But even though it is true that every effect
what is asked for when the discovery of such a cause is desired. Obvi- that occurs in time is a mere alteration, and every cause that brings forth
ously, nothing can be meant but that we should determine this cause, i.e., an effect may be looked upon as aforce, we would be needlessly depart-
that we should enumerate its various attributes, especially those which be- ing from customary ways of speaking and fettering ourselves if we were
long exclusively to it, or at least which it does not have in common with always to insist on using the words "alteration" and "force". Usually, we
499 every other cause. Thus, for example, when someone asks us to indicate only call an effect an alteration if it occurs quite quickly before our eyes,
the cause of light, we are supposed to indicate whether the cause lies in a and only call an attribute aforce when we consider it the cause of some
fluid medium that is situated between the illuminated body and our eye, quite obvious alteration. Finally, concerning the effects themselves for
which through vibratory motion begins to oscillate, or whether this cause which we want to find a cause, two essentially different cases must be
lies in certain very small bodies that the illuminated body emits in all di- distinguished. The effect can be a single determinate object, and it is de-
rections, etc. When we consider how we recognise these attributes, we sired that we should indicate the determinate forces which have brought
can again make the following distinction: some of them we can deduce it about; or it is a certain kind of phenomenon and it is desired that we
with the aid of pure concepts from others, already found, while we are led should indicate the kind of force which can bring about such phenomena.
to the discovery of others merely through perception. Thus, if we know An example of the first kind is the task of finding the cause of the eclipse

330 331
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

501 of the sun described in Matthew 27, 45. An example of the second kind best we can to learn of all the circumstances that accompany E, i.e., all
is the task of finding the causes of eclipses of the sun in general. phenomena that occur either simultaneously with or shortly before E. If
1) In the first case, when the object whose cause we wish to find is this has been done, and the comparison of all the cases has brought to light
a single fully determinate actual object, it follows from the well known the fact that a certain collection of phenomena a, a', a", ... always occurs
truth that God is the Creator and Governor of the whole world, and from shortly before an effect E does, or if we have discovered that one of the
the law of the universal reciprocal influence of created objects, that the collections a. a', a", ... , b, b', b", ... or c, c', c", ... always precedes E,
complete cause of the existence and the attributes of our object can only then we shall be permitted to surmise in the former case that the object A
be the totality of all existing objects. For each of them has some influ- which produces all the phenomena a, a', a", ... is necessary for the occur-
ence upon it, no matter how small, so if that other thing did not exist, our rence or E; and in the latter that one of the several objects-perhaps A, as
object would be different. It follows from this that the task of finding the the object that produces a, a', a", ... or B as the object that produces b, b',
complete cause of something is impossible for us. But that is not usu- b", ... , or C, which produces c, c', c", ... -must be present if the effect 503
ally what is wanted when we are asked to find the cause of an object or E is to be produced. We will even think ourselves justified in adhering
effect. Normally, only an indication of objects which have a humanly dis- to this conjecture if, along with the many cases where we have perceived
cernible influence upon the fact that the object has such and such observed tl1e co11 cc't'10n of phenomena a, a"I , a II , ... , 01• b , l7I , b" , . . . 01· c, c' , cJ' , ... ,
>

attributes is desired. Moreover, we usually allow ourselves to neglect all there is one where we did not in fact perceive all these phenomena-it
those circumstances whose presence is understood, as well as those which suffices that the circumstances be such that our not perceiving them does
are not important for the purpose of the investigation in question. The lat- not permit us to infer that they are absent. Thus we rightly surmise that
ter explains why one and the same event, depending on the point of view none of the more highly developed plants are produced on earth today
from which it is considered, and depending on the reason why we want except through reproduction from plants like them, even though we have
to know its cause, can truly be said to have very different causes. Thus not observed this in every case. For in a case where we have not per-
the death of Clitus can be attributed by a doctor to bleeding, by a moralist ceived the existence of a parent plant, the circumstances are never such as
to rage, by a judge to a murder, and by others to other objects. Hence would compel us to deny the existence of one. The degree of confidence
the various designations causa principalis, concomitativa, effectiva, in- our conjecture possesses increases with the number of cases in which we
strwnentalis, physica, moralis, etc. If it were already known that effects have observed E to follow the phenomena a,a',a", ... , or b,b',b", .. .
502 of kind E could be brought about only by the particular kind of object or c,c',c", .... But saying that E never occurs without a,a',a", .. .
C, then no further investigation would be required to show that C was or b, b', b", . . . or c, c', c", . . . does not mean that we are entitled to
present in this case. On the other hand (by far the most common case), if say that the objects A,B,C, ... are the cause of effect E. For what has
there are several objects C, C', C", ... , each of which is suitable for pro- been observed so far, namely, that E never occurs without a, a', a", ...
ducing an effect of kind E, then, if we already know this, we only have orb, b', b", ... or c, c', c", ... occurring either simultaneously or shortly
to investigate which of these various causes, C, C', C", ... was present in before, can also happen if one of the objects A, B, C, ... is not the com-
this particular case. We will find this by investigating the phenomena si- plete, but only a partial cause, a mere condition of E, or indeed an effect
multaneous with E or slightly before E and by considering whether they of E. Which of these relations obtains between E on the one hand and
indicate the presence of C or C' or C", .... From this we can see that the A, B, C, ... on the other must be decided based on other considerations.
first of the indicated problems can be solved if only the second is solved, If we could only observe a, a', a", ... in some cases where E occurred, 504
i.e., that we can find the cause of the given effect easily enough if we only and only b, b', b", ... in others, then there can be no doubt that neither
know which kind of cause produces what kind of effect. But how do we a, a', a", ... nor b, b', b", ... can be considered an effect of E alone. For
arrive at this knowledge? if the complete cause of even one of these phenomena were contained in
2) In the case of perception, this can only happen, I believe, if we E, then we would have to perceive it every time we perceive E, since a
observe many cases where an effect such as E takes place, and attempt as complete cause always produces its effect. Admittedly, it does not follow

332 333
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

from this alone that E cannot be a partial cause of these phenomena. But occur as often as those we first noticed (a, a', a", ... or b, b', b", ... or
we have a simple indicator that this is not the case when we notice that c, c', c", ... ), are nevertheless encountered often enough, or else seem
some or all of the phenomena a, a', a", ... occur a certain time before E. important to us on other grounds, or even come to light by pure chance. 506
For it is obvious that an effect can never be present earlier than its cause, We must then test to see whether the presence of the factors a, a', a", ...
though it may occur later, if by ejj'ect one means that which persists after along with a"' (or b, b', b", ... along with b"' or c, c', c", ... along with
a cause has been active for a certain length of time. Thus if we notice that c111 ) produces E. If we succeed in this way in assembling a collection of
the phenomena a,a',a", ... always occur a certain time earlier than E, phenomena a,a',a 11 ,a111 , ••• or b,b1 ,b11 ,b111 , ••• , etc., of which it may be
we will be justified in surmising that A is only a partial or complete cause said that whenever it occurs, E occurs as well, and indeed never before
of the effect E to be explained. If A or A, B, C, ... are supposed to be not but rather somewhat later, then we will be well justified in our conjecture
just a partial but the complete cause of the phenomenon E, then not only that the complete cause of the effect E is contained in the one or several
must A or A, B, C, ... be present everywhere that E is, but also conversely, objects that are necessary to produce these phenomena (we may call these
whenever A or A,B,C, ... are present, E must be as well. Thus we must A,A', ... or B,B', ... or C,C', ... ). But in the case where these objects
inquire whether this occurs, i.e., whether everywhere we may perceive are complex, we may ask whether all of their parts are required to bring
a,a',a", ... or b,b1 ,b11 , • • • or c,c',c", ... , E may also be perceived. about E, i.e., whether there is a simpler object than the one that brings
The larger the number of cases in which this occurs, and the greater the about a,a',a",a'", . .. or b,b 1 ,b11 ,b111 , • •• , etc. We have no other rea-
505 differences in all other respects, the greater the confidence with which we son for this conjecture than that E never occurred unless the phenomena
may assume that the object A or one of the several objects A, B, C, ... is a a, a', a", a'", ... orb, b', b", b'", ... , etc., also occurred together. Hence if
complete cause of E. For, the greater the differences between the remain- it is within our power to bring about these phenomena singly or partially,
ing circumstances under which E took place while A or one of A, B, C, ... then it would be reasonable to see whether an object which produces only
was present, the smaller the danger that some other, hidden, object A' or a, am, or only b and b111 , is sufficient to produce E. For example, people
B' was a partial cause in the production of E. Thus somebody can be would have thought that the propagation of sound requires air, if they had
all the more confident that he gets a headache from drinking coffee, the not made experiments which showed that one can propagate sound with-
more often he realises that he gets this headache when he drinks coffee out air, for example in water; from this it followed that the true cause of
and the greater the differences in the rest of his activities on those days. sound lies only in those properties of air which it shares with other elastic
If the number of cases that present themselves should tum out to be too bodies.
small to allow us to infer anything with sufficient assurance, and the na- 3) The difficulties which stand in the way of the just-indicated pro-
ture of the case allows it, we must perform more experiments, i.e., we cedure are greater than might be thought. The reason is that the number
must produce the objects A,B,C, ... and observe whether E occurs. of circumstances which accompany every event, including the event E 507
What was said above about not perceiving a, a', a", . . . or b, b1 , which is to be explained, is infinite. Hence it happens only too frequently
b", ... or c, c', c", ... , also holds for not perceiving the effect E, at that in spite of careful attention we fail to see just those circumstances
least in cases where not perceiving E does not compel us to conclude that which are required to find the true cause. Among the large number of
E is not present. If, by contrast, there is even a single case in which the perceptions it is difficult enough to find those which occurred in all or
factors a,a',a", . .. or b,b',b", ... or c,c',c", ... , are all present yet most cases where E took place. It is even more difficult to remember pre-
the effect E does not follow, we would have to conclude that the objects cisely whether these perceptions have been found together on other occa-
A,B,C, . .. do not contain the complete cause of E. We must then strive sions although E did not follow. Moreover, testing by experiment whether
to find other objects A', B', C', ... which, in conjunction with those we whenever we produce all the phenomena a, a', a", ... or b, b', b11 , • • • E
have already discovered, do produce the effect E. For this it is necessary also occurs, and whether E does not occur when we produce only some
to observe the circumstances in which E occurs still more carefully, and of these phenomena, is not only almost always difficult, costly, and time-
to take note of circumstances a'", b"', c111 , ••• which, though they may not consuming, but also may be impossible. The patience of even the most

334 335
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

assiduous researcher is tried when after long inquiry he discovers that an cl) Let E be an object which has a mathematical opposite, and let C be
object that he had looked upon as the cause of a given phenomenon does its cause; then we may assume that the opposite of C is the cause of the
not belong at all to this cause, so that he must start again from the begin- opposite of E. Hence we investigate whether among the circumstances 509
ning. Given these difficulties, it is desirable to know some rules which accompanying E there are some that are the opposite of those accompa-
would shorten and facilitate this work somewhat. nying the opposite of E. If we find any, then we may assume that they
a) One of these rules is the following: if there are a great number are, if not the complete, then at least a partial, cause of E. For exam-
of cases when E occurred, where E is the event to be explained, then ple, if we notice that the volume of a body becomes larger if it becomes
we should first concentrate on those cases which differ most widely from warmer, and becomes smaller if we remove heat from it, we conclude that
each other, i.e., which have very few common features outside of the the cause of its expansion lies in the increased heat.
presence of effect E. In these cases it would be permissible to assume e) If we wish to find the cause of a phenomenon which is found to
only one of two things, namely, either that the cause of the effect to be accompany many objects only occasionally, then it is reasonable, above
explained was different in these two cases, hence that there are several all, to see if there are not some of them that display this phenomenon all
causes which can bring about E, or that this cause lies in one of the few the time and others that never display it. In the former case, there must be
508 circumstances which the two cases have in common. Now since it is something which causes this phenomenon, in the latter, something which
not very probable that so many utterly different causes have one and the prevents it. If we therefore consider the attributes belonging exclusively
same effect, it is reasonable to begin with an examination of the second to the former class, or at least to the former class in contrast with the
assumption, especially given that we can expect that this examination will latter, then we may hope to find at least a partial ground of the event.
not take a lot of time, since there are only very few circumstances which For example, transparency is an attribute which is found in all bodies
need to be examined. that have a high degree of fluidity and in all expansible fluids, but not
b) It often happens that whenever a certain event E took place a con- in solids that have a non-homogeneous structure. Therefore, we surmise
siderable number of similar circumstances occurred which are not all that the similarity of parts of a body is one of the main conditions for its
necessary for the occurrence of E. In order to find out whether this is transparency.
the case, the quickest method is to look for cases where most of these 4) If the object A that we perceive to be the cause of a given phe-
circumstances were present without the occurrence of E. From this we nomenon E is composite, for instance, a body, then we may also ask
find out at once that none of these circumstances contains the complete whether all of the parts of A take part in bringing about E. And if this
cause of E; hence we do not have to make a lot of guesses which we must is the case, and the phenomenon E consists of several individual parts
eventually discard. e, e', e", ... , one may also ask whether each part of A plays a role in
c) If the effect E is of a kind which admits of more or less, or (as bringing about all of these individual phenomena e, e', e", ... , or whether,
we say) which admits of degrees, then the discovery of its cause may be e.g., only some parts of A bring about e, and other parts bring about e',
greatly facilitated if we first concentrate upon phenomena which increase etc. Thus we say that a rosebush that stands before us is the cause of
and decrease concomitantly. For, wherever the effect has a degree, the the pleasant fragrance we smell, yet it may not be the entire rosebush, 510
cause also must have a degree, and the larger the latter the larger must be but rather only some of the small parts developed from its petals that are
the former. Hence it is reasonable to suppose that the phenomena which the proximal cause which, along with the air, produces this scent. The
increase and decrease concomitantly with the effect belong to its cause, pressure we feel from a stone held in our hand, by contrast, is an effect
unless, incleecl, we discover that they are its effect; the latter case could be to which each individual part of the stone contributes equally. Now what
discovered if we found that these phenomena occur somewhat later than characteristics allow us to know which of these two cases obtains? If a
the event we wish to explain. Thus we conclude that the light of the sun phenomenon E remains unchanged when certain parts of the object A are
causes warmth on earth because we notice that a spot becomes warmer changed in diverse ways, we gather that these parts do not belong to the
the larger the number of sun rays which fall upon it. cause of the phenomenon, at least not to its proximal cause. Thus we

336 337
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

find that the scent of the rose remains when the petals remain close to our unknown to us, capable of producing such a phenomenon, and which
nose, no matter how far away the other parts may be. We conclude that did produce it in this case, provided that each of the assumptions that the
the petals contain the proximal cause of the scent. When, by contrast, we object A (or B or C) was present though we did not observe it has a smaller
observe that the effect E becomes smaller the more we alter the relations probability than the assumption that there is another object that possesses
of the parts of A, and that it does not matter which parts are involved, the capacity to produce E, even though we have not yet observed it. If
we may conclude that all the parts of A contribute equally to the produc- the circumstances of the phenomenon we seek to explain confer an equal
tion of the effect E. If, by contrast, we succeed in reducing A to parts relative probability on the presence of each of the objects A, B, C, ... , it is
in such a way that one of them produces e on its own, another produces obvious that we will find the one to be most probable which we have so far
e', etc., then there is no doubt that the phenomena e, e', e", ... of which found most often to be the cause of such phenomena. But if the number of
E is composed are produced only by the individual parts of which A is cases in which one of the causes, e.g., A, was found to be operating is not
511 composed. larger than half of the total number of observations, then the probability
5) If we indicate several objects A,A' ,A", ... as the cause of E or, of the assumption that E was caused by A is not large enough to warrant
what amounts to the same thing, if we claim that A is composite and only the claim that it really was that way. For, given that we have observed n
some parts of A bring about one part of the phenomenon E while others cases, and A was found to have occurred a times, then the probability of
bring about other parts, it is still necessary to determine in what spatial the proposition that A was present in this case equals ~!: and this figure
and temporal relations these several objects or parts must be in order to becomes > 4only if a > ~. Unless the circumstances of the present case
to produce E. For example, if we wish to explain a multiple echo, it speak for each of A, B, C, ... with equal strength, we must also include in
will not suffice to state that there were several elastic surfaces capable our calculation of probability the relevant conditions of the present case 513
of reflecting the sound, for the unequal distances between these surfaces in addition to the considerations of former cases. Finally, we must favour
must also be indicated. Some information on how we begin to gather the that assumption which has the highest degree of probability over all the
nature of such relations in space and time through experience has already others.
been given in §303. 7) It often occurs that a phenomenon E we seek to explain can be
6) If we have come to know through experience one or several objects analysed into several parts e, e', e", ... in such a way that we know one
A,B,C, ... capable of producing an effect E, and we are asked to explain or several objects capable of producing these parts. Understandably, we
how an effect like E was produced in a new case, it is natural to conjecture should not proceed to assume that there is an object hitherto unknown to
that it was produced by one of the the objects A, B, C, .... But this is not us that has the power to produce E until we have seen that every attempt
necessary, for there might be many other unknown objects that produce to explain the phenomenon in question through a combination of forces
effects like E, and one of them might have been responsible in this case. already known to us has either proved untenable, or else depends upon as-
In order to decide this question, we must (a) inquire whether among the sumptions that are less probable than the former assumption. In order to
circumstances that accompany E there are any indications of the presence decide such cases, we must consider in addition to what was mentioned in
of one of A,B,C, ... , i.e., whether there is any phenomenon that belongs no. 6, (a) whether the several objects, whose combined operation would
specifically to one of these objects. If this is the case, then we have no explain E, are indeed compatible; or whether one of them might not have
reason to suppose that there is another ground (here, another cause) of E a force which cancels the presence or efficacy of another. If the mode
than the presence of the given object. (b) But if there is no such indication, of operation of these objects is unknown to us, if we have no experi-
we must look to see whether there is some factor that makes the absence ence showing that they can act together, then it is far from certain that
512 of one or several of these objects probable. This would be the case, for they can together produce the sum of what they can produce individually.
instance, if these objects produce phenomena that we could not overlook (b) Secondly, we must consider whether it is probable that the number of
had they occurred. If this occurs for all of the objects we know so far to be objects required can actually be found in the necessary spatial and tem-
capable of causing E, we must conjecture that there is some other object, poral relations. The larger we assume the number of these objects to be,

338 339
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

the smaller the probability that they will be found together in exactly the En-2 that it has the attribute c and so on, until we are finally justified
way required, unless there is some particular cause that can bring about to assume of the given phenomenon E, that its cause C, no matter how
this disposition of objects. different from Ci, still has the attribute c, which was possessed by all
8) The most difficult case arises when a phenomenon is to be ex- the other causes as well. This conjecture, which is quite weak at first,
514 plained that has been observed only once, i.e., a phenomenon which can may be strengthened if the attribute c of the causes C11 _ 1, C11 _2, ... lying
be brought under a concept E which does not fit any past observation. In between Ci and C, which is inferred merely through similarity, is also
my view, there are only two methods with which we can determine more found through experience. Thus if we had never seen any living beings
precisely the cause of such a phenomenon. (a) One of them is to find out apart from humans, it would hardly occur to us to seek a living cause of
whether there were not some unique circumstances accompanying or im- the movements of the tiny bodies we see through a microscope in every
mediately preceding the phenomenon. We would then assume that they drop of a fermenting liquid. But since we have sufficient experience of
belong to the cause of E, since it is certain that an unusual effect can our own life being expressed through movement, and know of a number
only be brought about by an unusual cause. (b) No matter how peculiar of other beings that move in similar ways in similar circumstances, since
the given phenomenon is, it will still have certain similarities with other these beings are similar to us in so many ways (e.g., in their limbs, etc.) 516
phenomena which we have often seen and whose cause we know. Now that we could not doubt that they too are alive, since these beings again
since similar causes bring about similar effects, we can conversely argue, bear so much similarity to other, smaller ones that we must suppose life
at least tentatively, from the similarities of effects to a certain similarity as the cause of the latter's movements, and since the sequence of similar
of causes. In this way we can estimate not only several characteristics beings actually extends to the infusoria, the thought that these last beings
of the unknown cause of E, but if we find an object with these charac- are alive occurs to us irresistibly as soon as we observe them.
teristics in the vicinity of E we can often strengthen our assumption by 9) From all of this it becomes obvious that in looking for the cause of
a closer investigation of this object, provided only that we find several a given effect we almost always have the choice among several assump-
further properties of the cause which is to be determined. It is understood tions, where the task is to decide which of them is the most probable. Now
that this latter method can also be used when we have to explain a phe- in order to calculate or even estimate the degree of probability of each of
nomenon which we have seen several times, provided it is done carefully these assumptions, we must, first of all, know of which and how many
enough. Thus from the similarity between the phenomena of light and simple (i.e., not further decomposable) and independent premises each of
of sound, we can argue for a similarity of causes for both of them and, them is composed. Next we must determine the degree of probability of
by suitable experiments based upon this assumption, we can arrive at a each of these individual premises, if not by precise calculation, then at
more detailed knowledge of the nature of light. A repeated application least by a rough estimation, if only based on an obscure feeling, and fi-
515 of this argument from similarity will often lead to at least a partial, if not nally we must form the product of these degrees. Lastly, the assumption
complete, knowledge of the cause of the phenomenon which was quite which shows the greatest value for the product of the degrees of probabil-
inexplicable in the beginning. It can happen that repeated comparisons of ity of its individual premises is the most probable of all. But it can also be
many objects lead to a whole series of phenomena E, E 1 , E2 , E3 , ... , En, the case that the individual premises into which two assumptions A and B
which are such that each of them has great similarities to the next one, can be decomposed, or at least those premises in which they differ, have
although members that are farther apart, especially E and E,z, have al- the same degree of probability-when, that is, there is no reason to main-
most no similarity at all to each other. Finally, it may well be the case tain that the individual assumptions a, a', a", ... of which A consists hold,
that we have a reasonably close knowledge of cause C,1 of phenomenon rather than the assumptions p, P', p", ... of which B consists. It is fairly
En. Now the great similarity of En-I and E11 allows us to assume that obvious that we should, in this case, declare the assumption which con-
phenomenon En- I has a cause C,1_ 1 which is not exactly like C,z. but has sists of the smallest number of presuppositions to be the most probable of 517
a certain attribute c in common with it. In the same way, the similarity the two, even if we do not know the degree of their probability. Hence,
of En-I and E11 _2 can be of a kind which justifies us to assume also for it is generally maintained that, other things being equal, a hypothesis is

340 341
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 379. Particular Rules

the more acceptable, the smaller the number of the independent premises truths; it would be false to assume that the latter are found in a different
of which it consists. Thus, if the phenomenon E can be explained in two way than the former while in fact their greater reliability rests only on the
ways, namely, by the accidental conjunction of three objects a, b, c, and greater number of observations.
also by the accidental conjunction of four objects d,e,f,g, and if these Sometimes, the reason why a simpler hypothesis is to be preferred to
premises are of equal probability, then the first explanation must be pre- a more complex one (cf. no. 9) is sought in the circumstance that we may
ferred to the second. presuppose that nature always follows the simplest rules. In my opinion,
Note. Many philosophers have claimed that the true causes of phe- no special presuppositions are needed for this, rather, it follows from the
nomena, or the powers of things, are forever hidden; the reason is that rules of the probability calculus itself; cf. §253, note.
we can know only their effects, since what we perceive are always ef-
fects, never causes. These claims are occasioned by the discovery that §.380.
the cause of a given effect can never be determined through experience in
any other way than by showing that this cause also produces certain other The most common mistakes in pe1fonning this task
phenomena. Now this provides a splendid opportunity for loud lamenta-
Since the discovery of the causes of given effects is such a difficult prob-
tions about the limitations of human knowledge. I gladly agree that hu-
lem, it is not surprising that people often fail to solve it, and that there are
man knowledge is limited, but it seems to me that this sort of complaint
several kinds of mistakes committed in performing this task. It will be
is improper. We cannot properly say that we do not know the powers
useful to provide even a very brief survey of these mistakes. It may hap-
of things since we perceive only their effects; for to know the powers of
pen ( 1) that we indicate something as the cause of a given effect when in
things means to know their effects. There cannot be any way of knowing
fact it does not belong to that cause. Or (2), that we look upon something
the power of a thing, either for men or for anybody else, except through a
as the complete cause when it is only partial cause. (3) We may seek 519
recognition of its effects, since a power cannot be anything but a cause, or
the cause in a whole when one of its parts suffices to produce the effect.
a ground for the generation of certain effects. What I would acknowledoe b
(4) We may believe that the cause of all the phenomena of a given kind E
as a limitation of our knowledge and the knowledge of all other created
lies in one of the objects A, B, C, ... when in fact there are other objects
beings, is that we can perceive the powers of things only in so far as they
M,N, 0, ... which can equally well produce this effect. (5) We indicate
act upon us, either mediately or immediately, that we know so very few of
the cause correctly, but do not specify it more precisely, or at least not
518 their powers and that of these we only have probable and quite unreliable
as precisely as might be asked. This would be the case, for example, if
knowledge.
we sought to explain the cohesiveness of a body by saying simply that
It is usually maintained that the discovery of the cause of a given phe-
there is a special force of cohesion between the parts of the body which
nomenon does not always, but only sometimes, require the introduction
produces this phenomenon. For such a force is admittedly the true cause
of certain hypotheses. But if a hypothesis is nothing but a proposition
of the phenomenon of cohesiveness, but we would like to know also the
which we introduce in order to give an explanation, of which we are not
properties of this force and its causes, provided that it has them. The ex-
fully certain but maintain only with probability, then every determination
planation of so many of the productions of animals, e.g., of bees, as the
of a cause to a given effect which is taken from experience requires hy-
effects of instinct is just as worthless. (6) We may indicate the correct
potheses. The reason is that such determinations can only be arrived at
cause, but ascribe properties to it that it does not have. This is the case,
by means of probabilistic inferences. The only difference is that these
e.g., when we falsely represent the way that a cause produces its effect.
hypotheses may have a larger or smaller degree of probability; hence it
Thus many people, who rightly indicate the eye as the organ of sight, are
is a mere difference of quantity and should be described as such. I think
mistaken in thinking that it accomplishes this with the help of the tiny im-
that we should issue a specific warning to novices not to overlook this
ages which appear on its surface. (7) Finally, we may err in ascribing too
fact, i.e., not to assume an opposition between hypotheses on one hand
high a degree of probability to our claim indicating a cause, one which is
and propositions which are in ordinary life called established experiential
not justified by the perceptions we have had so far.

342 343
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 381. Particular Rules

Note. Some, e.g., JAKOB (§380), go too far when they reject a hy- which upon analysis turn out to be merely identical propositions, as with
pothesis simply because its possibility is not certain, or requires other the ancient explanations by means of so-called qualitates occultas. (3) If
hypotheses. It suffices that its impossibility has not been shown, and that the explanation is neither obviously absurd nor of the kind that is pate.ntly
the sum of the assumptions which are made to support it is smaller than obvious, we inquire whether the grounds it adduces (via the percept10ns
520 it would be in any other case. it is inferred from) have received sufficient proof; especially whether the
degree of their probability has not been overstated. T.his .inquiry pr~­
§.38 l. ceeds entirely according to the rules governing the exammatlon of proofs
in general, and more particularly on those concerning proofs inv~lving
XXIV. Examination ofpwported causes probable inferences. (4) If it should turn out that the. ground~ are .mcor-
rect or at least insufficient to render the given explanat10n credible, it does
It often happens, either through error or evil intent, that someone claims not follow that the explanation is incorrect, but only that it is unproven.
something to be the cause of a given effect when in fact it is not. In such Thus we must see whether it is possible to give a stronger proof of the ex-
cases, we say that a cause has been falsely ascribed to the given effect, planation by making better use of the observations we have already m.ade
which is called a .spurious production. By contrast, effects that actually or by making new ones. We must inquire in particular whether every time
owe their existence to the indicated causes are called authentic produc- the indicated cause A is posited, the result E follows, whether a mere part
tions. In particular, writings are called authentic or spurious depending of A suffices to produce E, whether E sometimes occurs without any part
upon whether they were actually written by the person claimed to be the of A preceding it, etc. (5) If none of the inquiries discussed so far proves
author, either in the work itself or by general consent. If a work does the incorrectness of the explanation under examination, we must finally
stem from the person it is said to, but contains many changes due to an- inquire whether it would be possible to devise an explanation which. has
other hand, i.e., if some of its parts are spurious, one says that it has been a higher degree of probability, either because it has fewer assumptlo1:s
adulterated, otherwise, one says that it is unadulterated. We now turn to than the given one, or for some other reason. If we do not succeed m 522
the most general rules to be employed in testing the genuineness of an these attempts, if instead every explanation we try is less probable, then,
effect, or the correctness of declarations concerning its cause. (1) The though it will not be permissible to deem the given explanation correct on
first thing is to inquire whether any of the propositions contained in these the spot, it will be permissible to accept it before any other on account of
declarations either completely contradicts truths already known to us, or
its greater probability.
else is so improbable in light of these truths that all possible grounds of Note. When I extend the concepts of authenticity and unadulterated-
proof for them would be far too weak to render them credible. Such a ness so that they apply to objects other than writings, one should not, I
case occurs when the given explanation contradicts a definitively settled believe, object, since common usage already takes these words in rou~hly
conceptual truth, and thus (as one says) supposes something completely these senses. One speaks for instance of authentic and adulterated wmes,
impossible. Of this sort is any explanation of an effect through a force, and everyone calls a painting that has been falsely claimed to be the work
the presence of which presupposes the effect, for example, the explana- of Raphael spurious. Admittedly, for effects of special kinds ther~ .are
tion of cohesion through the assumption that the parts of all cohesive many other rules besides the general ones indicated above for determm.mg
521 bodies have the form of little hooks. Similarly contradictory is the expla- their authenticity. With written works, for instance, it is quite appropriate
nation of evil in the world through the supposition of a fundamentally evil to divide the grounds for authenticity into the internal and the external,
being, among others. (2) If the given explanation does not contradict any where by inner grounds one means those that arise from the nature of .the
truths known to us, we may proceed to investigate how much it accom- work itself (whether in the work there occurs something that contradicts
plishes, i.e., whether the cause of the effect we seek to explain is more what is known about the nature of the supposed author; and whether it
precisely determined by it, or whether we simply learn what we already would have been easy or difficult for an impostor to impart the character-
knew, or else only learn something that requires no experiences, but only istics of authenticity to a forgery), and by outer we mean all other factors,
a few inferences from pure concepts. Of this kind are all explanations

344 345
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 382. Partirnlar Rules

especially the authority of those who have either taken the writino-b to be which logicians have accordingly given a name: Sophisma: post hoc vel
.
genume or else rejected it, etc. cum hoc, ergo propter hoc (§371.2i). 1 (5) No less care should be taken to
assure that one does not proceed too hastily in inferring that because one
§.382. does not perceive something that it is not there; because, for example, one
did not see any other phenomena besides a, a', a", ... , hastily inferring
Further rules to be observed when seeking causes that the object A contains the complete, and indeed the unique cause ca-
pable of bringing about E. One may call this fallacy non vis um, ergo non
In order to be even more certain to avoid the errors enumerated in the last praesens. 2 (6) Finally, one should take care to assure that the desire to
sectio.n whe~1 .seeking causes, it is advantageous to adhere to the following find an explanation does not lead us to make assumptions that, while they
rules m add1t10n to those set out in §§379 and 381: (1) One should take may explain the case before us, are nevertheless inconsistent with earlier
care not to confuse propositions that are mere consequences of our imme- experiences. This occurs especially easily in cases where we want to sup-
523 diate perceptions and indeed consequences drawn through merely prob- pose the existence of new, hitherto unnoticed forces; for in this case we
able inferences, with the immediate perceptions themselves, and thereby must always show why it was that the existence of such forces was never
take the former to have the complete certainly that only belongs to the noticed before.
latter. As one usually says, we should not ascribe to perception itself
what is merely inferred from it. This can occur as soon as the inferences §.383.
we use to deduce these propositions from our immediate perceptions be-
come so familiar that we perform them without being distinctly aware of XXV Discovering suitable means for given ends
doing so. (2) Even with propositions one knows to be merely probable,
No problem for our reflection arises more often than that of discovering
one should be careful not to overestimate the degree of probability. This
means that lead to a given end. By an end I mean any effect we may
happens all too often when we do not make a complete survey of all the
represent a thinking being as intending to bring about, or an end that such
various cases that may occur, and also when we have used a proposition
a being could will to bring about. Something that is in fact willed is
many times without hitting upon an example that shows its incorrectness.
called an actual end, and something that merely might be willed a possi-
(3) We should never forget to pay heed to the influence that the consti-
ble end. Whatever the infinite being, i.e., God, wills is actual at the same
tution of our body has on the origin and nature of our perceptions, and
time God wills it; but not everything that finite beings will manages to 525
indeed the effects our body has on the soul on account of the soul's own
become actual. Indeed, they may even will things that cannot be. God's
influence on the body, e.g., its imaginings, wishes, expectations, etc. Ifwe
ends are always morally good, while ends of finite beings may also be
are not attentive to this influence, which often escapes our notice, it will
evil. Every object which, through the action of the will (more precisely,
occur only too often that we attribute the changes in our perceptions only
the outwardly-directed force) of a being, becomes the (complete or par-
to the external objects surrounding us while in fact a change in ourselves
either in our body or our soul, plays a significant role. Thus we will mak~
tial) cause of something the being intends is called a means to this end.
An object that the being holds to be a means though actually it is not, is
quite false judgements about what befalls us, and hence incorrectly de-
called an alleged means, as opposed to the so-called actual or suitable
termine its causes. For instance, we quite frequently see people whose
means. Finite beings all too often choose only alleged means. Since a
organs of taste are altered through illness incorrectly judging the taste of
means, even if it is suitable for bringing about a given end, may have
food, when they are either unaware of the changes or else fail to think
other effects as well, it is not always the case that when the end is for the
of them. (4) One should be constantly aware that it is risky, and in cer-
best the means is too. Hence even if an end is morally good, the means
524 tain cases impermissible, to infer from the mere fact that the phenomena
may not be praiseworthy. It may often be useful to know morally bad
a, aI , aII , ... occurre d e1t. her bf .
e ore or smmltaneously with E one or more
times that the object A which produces a, a', a", ... contains the complete 1Sophism: this occurred either after or with that, therefore this was caused by that.
2 It is not seen, therefore it is not present.
cause of E. Most errors in the search for causes stem from this fallacy, to

346 347
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 383. Particular Rules

means, for instance in order to hinder those who would use them. Thus latter can clearly happen in the same way we learn of causes in general.
one should not hold it against logic if it deals with the most general pro- for example, if we experience repeatedly that our resolutions or those
cedures for finding suitable means (whether good or bad) for given ends of others are followed by a certain change, e.g., changing an object a
(whether good or bad). (1) The first thing is to consider whether it is pos- into A, we may conclude that the resolution is the g.rouncl o~ this change.
sible to see in advance that because of some circumstance there simply (5) But even if the proximal cause of the effect e 1s not of the so:t that
is no means of the sort demanded. This would be the case if we were a mere act of will could produce, we should not be deterred by this, but
able to see through some reflection either that the required effect has its rather we must (through repeated applications of §379) see~ the :emoter
sufficient ground in the will or, more precisely, in the outwardly directed causes of e and see whether we in the encl come across a thmg oi the re-
force of a being and hence, as one says, follows immediately, or that the quired sort, i.e., one that depends only on a being's will. If, no mat~er how
required effect is something impossible or, finally, that it is something far we continue our investigation, we are not fortunate enough to discover
over which the will and its outwardly-directed force have no influence. a proximal or remote cause for each of the effects e, e', e", ... , which is
526 (2) If we do not discover anything that would demonstrate the impossi- so constituted that we may expect it to be produced by a mere act of the
bility of the sought means in advance, we proceed to inquire whether we being's will, then we are in no position to indicate a means that would
or others have previously encountered a phenomenon of the required sort serve to bring about the end in its entirety. But if we have discovered one
' or indeed several causes for each of the pl1enomena e, eI , e II , ... , wh"1c j1
either complete in itself or else, if it is complex, if we have encountered
its parts. (3) If (as far as we know) neither we nor others have perceived the being might expect to produce, it is easy to point out a means that
an effect of the required sort, either as a whole or in its individual parts, will lead to the given encl, for every combination of any one of the causes
it will hardly be possible for us to indicate a means capable of producing capable of bringing about e with one capable of bringing about e', etc.,
it, unless we could see from concepts alone not only the sort of cause will be such a means. Thus if there are several causes that can produce
that might produce such an effect, but also that the being in question has one of the phenomena e, e', e", ... , there will also be several means for
within its power the forces necessary to bring about this cause. Thus, for us to recommend. (6) If, among the means discovered in this way, we
example, with respect to God we may know from concepts alone that He are supposed to single out the one that is easiest and simplest, we must
must have the intention of producing the greatest possible sum of happi- clearly first know how much effort is required, and how complex a coor- 528
ness, and also that as a means to this end He must have created an infinite dination of forces is required to bring about each of the individual causes
number of sensate beings, that he must reward goodness and punish evil, A,A' ,A", .... Here we must investigate in particular whether any of the
and allow us to persist after death, etc. (4) If, however, we discover that causes that produce e also produce e' at the same time, and so on.
the individual phenomena e, e', e", ... , for which we are supposed to
find means to bring about together, have already occurred somewhere, we §.384.
must investigate, following the instructions of §379, the causes whereby
each of these phenomena might be produced. If we find in this way that XXVI. Discovering the effects of given causes
the phenomenon e may be brought about through the causes A,B,C, ... ,
Frequently, our problem is not to discover the causes of given effects, as
and e' brought about by A', B', C', ... , etc., then the question arises of
in §379, but rather to discover the effects of given causes. Here too one
whether any of these causes are constituted in such a way that the mere
may immediately distinguish two cases, namely, whether the given cause
will of the being for whom we seek to specify means to the given end is
is a single, fully determinate object, or the entire kind of objects standing
capable of producing them. But in order to be in a position to claim that
under a concept C, and whether one accordingly asks us to indicate a sin-
the mere will of a being is capable of bringing about a certain cause A,
gle, completely determinate effect that will occur in this case, or only the
one of two things must be the case: either we see from concepts alone that
kind of effect E that is to be expected in all cases standing under the con-
527 the will of this being can affect an object a in such a way that it becomes
cept C. Now since the (complete) cause already completely determines
the desired cause A, or else we must know this through experience. The
its effect we will know how to determine the effect that is to be expected
'

348 349
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 384. Particular Rules

in a given individual case when we know the nature of the effects that ca ccurred only once or even never. Here only two means may be applied,
be produced by the kind of cause to which the given one belongs. Thu~ ~ntirely similar to those indicated in §379, no. 8 for the case where we are
the first sort of problem is solved as soon as we know how to solve th sked to discover the cause of a phenomenon that has occurred only once.
second sort. But in order to learn, and indeed through experience, Wha~ ~a) If the object has occurred at least once, and if we have precisely ob-
sort of effect each object standing under the concept e has, we will clearI served all the circumstances accompanying its occurrence, then we may
first have to look for such objects everywhere we can, and ?bserve in~ see whether among the observed circumstances there are some that we
many cases as we can find what sorts of phenomena occur either simulta- do not observe anywhere else (i.e., not along with any non-e). It will
neously with e or shortly thereafter. By comparing these phenomena We be permissible to assume at least tentatively that these are effects of e.
529 must determine whether there are any that uniformly occur whenever C (b) For all its peculiarities, e must bear certain similarities to other objects
does. If we discover that whenever e occurs, the phenomena e,e'.e" we have already observed, and whose effects we know. Based on these
do as well, it will be permissible to conjecture that e, e', e", ... be I~~~ similarities, we may make a conjectural inference that the effects will be
to the sought effects of e, provided that they are not parts of its cause. similar. If, for example, e is a combination of c, c', c", ... and if these
Whether the last is the case may be decided following the instructions of individually have the effects e, e', e", ... , we may conjecture that that the
§379. If it turns out that the phenomena e, e', e", ... do not belong to effect of e will be some sort of combination of the known effects e, e',
the cause of e, since, e.g., they occur later than e, then our conjecture e", .... Following this rule, for example, doctors hope that a medicine
that they should be counted among the effects of e receives confirma- consisting of two ingredients will have the effects of both of them. Clearly,
tion. And this conjecture may even continue to stand if we sometimes however, we may also use this means in cases where we have observed
find e without finding that all of e, e', e", ... follow, provided that cir- c many times, and even in cases where we can produce e ourselves. For
cumstances are such that our failure to perceive these phenomena does even though such inferences based on analogy are not secure, they are
not oblige us to conclude that they were absent. The more often it hap- useful in that they lead to conjectures that will help us to reach our goal
pens that e is followed by e, e1 , e", ... , the more probable it becomes more quickly, when we examine them according to the rules given above.
that e, e', e", ... are in fact results of e. Finally, we will be permitted to Indeed, repeated application of this kind of inference will sometimes put 531
infer that the object e is not merely a partial cause of e, e', e", ... , but us in a position to indicate the effects of an object which at first glance
rather their complete cause if we have observed that e, e', e", ... follow does not bear enough similarity to any object known to us for us to make
e in the most varied circumstances. Thus if it lies within our power to any such inference. We do this in a way similar to that described in §379,
produce the object e as often as we please, it is obvious that we can con- no. 8-namely, by comparing the object e with all objects that bear a
fer a much higher degree of reliability on the probable inferences through certain similarity to e, and the latter with others similar to themselves,
suitable experiments than through mere observation. Thus we must also en'
etc., we might arrive at a sequence of objects e, el' e 2 ' e 3 ' ... , where
make use of this means, i.e., we must produce the object e in the most the extreme terms e and e 11 are quite different, even though each term of
varied circumstances, and see whether e, e', e", ... occur in every case the sequence bears the greatest similarity to the following term. It may
that e does. If some of e, e', e", ... do not occur in quite varied circum- also turn out that the effect E" of the object C'1 is known well enough to
stances, we then see that these cannot be reckoned among the effects of C, us, and the similarity that obtains between C'1 and cn- 1 is great enough

since they only arise through a combination of e and other factors. The to justify the surmise that the effect of en- I, though not completely equal
methods just recommended are useful when the object whose effects we to that of C'1 , will nevertheless have a certain property e in common with
530 are investigating according to the concept C has already occurred many it. In the same way, it may happen that en-I and cn- 2 are similar in such
times, i.e., when we are only asked to indicate the kind of effects that this a way that we may infer the presence of the property e in cn- 2 from its
object has in common with several others we have already observed. The presence incn- 1
• If this continues all the way toe, one sees that we may
problem is far more difficult when we are asked to indicate the effect of surmise that the property we noticed in £ 11 (the effect of the object C") is
an object which, according to the concept under which we subsume it, has also present in the effect of e, i.e., in E, especially if we do not merely

350 351
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 385. Particular Rules

infer the presence of the given property in all of En- i, E' 1-- 2 •... , E 1 by instituted in order to communicate our thoughts in detail to others-but
analogy, but actually confirm its presence in some of them through expe- also everything that we wittingly and willingly undertake; for from every
rience. The most beautiful examples of the utility of this procedure are action we may infer something about the concepts and judgements of the
provided by comparative anatomy, which led us to discover, for exam- agent, namely, his opinions concerning what is permissible and what is
ple, the auditory organs of fishes in the swim bladder. If we are required forbidden, what is beneficial and what harmful, and so on. One should
to enumerate not just some but all of the effects of an object, this only also count here the things a man refrains from doing, for example, his re-
ever means that we are supposed to enumerate effects from which all the maining silent when accused. Finally, many things belong here that hap-
others follow. In doing this, no one should object if we include some pen to a man involuntarily, such as his sudden confusion, blushing, fear,
532 remote effects in this enumeration; indeed, people would be satisfied if and many other sensations which often reveal themselves against his will.
all these effects were mediate. What is required of us is that there be no (2) But because the circumstances under which the views of a man may
important effect that is not either one of those enumerated or a result of become observable are so diverse, it is scarcely possible to say some-
one of them. We will be permitted to suppose that we have reached this thing general yet more precise about how we should infer his thoughts
degree of completeness in our enumeration of the effects of C when apart from what we have perceived, except perhaps that we would only be jus-
from the phenomena e, e', e", ... , there are no others, or at least no other tified in concluding that someone held a certain opinion if this assumption
important ones, that occur every time C does, either simultaneously or were the only way to explain why he said, acted, or appeared precisely
shortly afterwards. the way he did in a given situation, when only this assumption made it
comprehensible how he could have looked upon what he did as his duty
§.385. or to his advantage, or necessary. We would be justified, for example, in
supposing that a man believed confidently in the immortality of his soul
XXVII. Investigation of the judgements of other beings when we observe that on his death-bed he is consoled and refreshed by
the thought of that other life. So too we may conclude that someone con-
Everyone knows that the knowledge of the opinions and judgements of siders wealth to be a highly desirable good when the unexpected news
other beings is of the greatest importance not only for scientific aims but that he has suddenly become a rich man fills him with immoderate joy.
for others as well. There is only one being, namely, the infinite being, (3) In such inquiries we must beware especially of the following: (a) We
of which we know independently of all experience, from concepts alone, must not attribute a change or phenomenon to someone when it is not his 534
that its judgements are constituted so that it recognises every truth. With doing. Thus we might easily think someone slightly vain on account of
respect to all the other beings, however, we must first learn of some of certain embellishments of his clothes which we take to be there accord-
their judgements by experience before being able to reach a conclusion ing to his wish, while in truth they were put there by his tailor without
(and only a probable one at that) about the nature of their other judge- his knowledge. (b) We must not be overly hasty in concluding that an
ments. But the experiences from which we are able to gather the opinions observed change could not have occurred had it not been produced by
of a being are never anything other than certain phenomena which can be someone's opinions. We would be hasty to conclude, for example, that
shown to be caused, at least mediately and partially, by certain judgements someone must be conscious of his guilt because he blushes when we ask
that this being must have formed. The problem we must now attempt to him if he is guilty. (c) We must never forget to inquire whether someone
solve is thus actually a special case of the general problem of §379, which has intentionally undertaken a certain action in order to deceive us with
concerns the discovery of the causes from their effects. Yet it should be respect to his true views, i.e., to make us think that he holds an opinion
noted that here the effects are not usually looked upon as given, but rather when he does not. Someone might, e.g., pretend that he can find no flaws
must first be sought. ( 1) First of all, we note the various circumstances in our work, while thinking something completely different in his heart.
533 under which the views of a being may become evident, and then watch
carefully for their occurrence. Among us humans, such circumstances
include not only what we say-the best means we have discovered and

352 353
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 386. Particular Rules

§.386. needs, that is, of increasing its happiness. But here we seek guidance on
how to determine the intentions of God or of created beings much more
XXVIII. Investigation of the intentions behind given actions precisely than these quite general attributes allow us to, and in particular
through observation.
T~e intentions ~ehind the undertakings of rational beings are also a kind
1) First, concerning divine intentions, we already know from what
of cause, of which these undertakings are the effects. Thus the problem
has been said that, with respect to every object, they consist in the collec-
of discovering the intentions behind given actions is again a special case
tion of all the good that has been or will be brought about by it. But as
o~ the problem of §379, which demands the discovery of the causes of
we are never in a position to completely survey this good-which is of
given effects. By the intention which a being has in its action, or the
infinite extent-it is clear that we may never have exhaustive knowledae b
aim of its action_( or the object brought about by this action-cf. §383),
of God's intentions. But in order to specify something of these intentions,
I understand a (nghtly or wrongly) expected effect of its activity, which
and indeed before the results themselves teach us what they are, we con-
determined the will of this being to perform this action, or which (as
sider the given object from all sides, note its constitution, and inquire in
one says) provided the motive for this action. But since every intention
the way indicated in §384 about the effects it might have, especially if
is a kind of judgement, we see that the present problem is subordinate
certain possible circumstances, among them our own activity, were to oc-
535 not only to that of §379, but also to that of §385, which concerned the
cur as well. If we have thought of several such effects E, E', E", E"', ... ,
investigation of others' judgements. Now since it is not specified in this
which we can see are either certain or likely to occur, or which might be
definition that the expectation which the acting being has with respect to
produced by us, we investigate which of these effects would be conducive
the successful peiformance of the act must be conscious, any being which
to the well-being of the whole, and indeed more so than any other. Of this
has the power of representation, e.g., animals, may act intentionally in
we may claim with the same degree of probability that we expect that it
this sense. In a nairower sense, however, one only speaks of intentions
will occur and at the same time be something good, that it belongs to the
in beings which represent their own ideas and judgements, and thus may
aim which God had in producing this object. If in the future these effects
become conscious of them. Understandably, we cannot infer from the
actually occur, we have proof that our conjecture was correct. In the op-
mere fact that the individual beings which contributed to the production of
posite case, when an effect we claimed to be God's aim is not produced,
some phenomenon acted intentionally that there was also an intention to
we have proof of our error. When, for example, we wish to indicate the 537
produce the combined effect of their action; this would only be justified if
purpose of an organic part of some animal, we must first seek to learn
there were one being among them which had represented the entire effect,
all the details of its structure, and then consider what effects, beneficial
willed it, and had somehow brought the other beings to act together in
either for the animal or for other beings, might be brought about by this
the way necessary. The question now arises of when we are justified in
part under favourable circumstances. If we discover one effect which ev-
claiming that the case described above occurs with a given phenomenon,
erything is so suitably arranged to produce that the same effect could not
so that it may be said to have an aim; and also to what extent it is possible
be brought about as well were anything at all different, we may conclude
for us to discover this aim. From concepts alone, we already know that
that the production of this effect is (in general) the genuine purpose of
there is one being, namely, God, that may be considered the ground of
this part, even before we have assured ourselves through experience that
everything which exists and happens in the world; that this being through
the animal uses this part to bring about the effect in question. If we also
its omniscience recognises every effect, and through its holiness wills
observe that this is the case, then our conjecture becomes fully certain
only the good. Thus we may claim of every airnngement or change which
(not, indeed, with respect to all individuals, but only with respect to those
we perceive that it has its aim with respect to God, which consists in
we have perceived to use the part in this way). If the given object has a
all the good brought about through it. We also know at least this much
considerable number of attributes and structures which we do not know
through concepts alone about the intentions of all created beings: that
to be merely results of the remaining ones, and if at the same time these
each of these beings is capable only of willing things that it represents as
must be present in order to bring about the effect we intend to point to as
536 either commanded by reason, or else capable of satisfying its desires and

354 355
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 386. Particular Rules

the purpose of the object, and if, finally, we can think of no other useful that these certainly do not belong to the intention of the agent we are try-
effect that could be the purpose of this object, then the greater the number ing to discover. If, after the elimination of all these, only one or several
of such independent attributes, the greater the probability with which we consequences remain with the peculiarity that the agent either considers
infer the correct purpose of the object. For since structures or attributes the act which will produce them a moral obligation, or else something
which do not result necessarily (i.e., by means of concepts alone) the one that will satisfy his desires and needs, we rightly surmise that it was one
from the other must be together through God's will, it is clear that the ex- or several of these consequences which brought about the resolution. In
istence of such an object is due not just to one but to several (though not these (true or merely imagined) consequences, then, lie the genuine in-
occurring one after the other in time) divine resolutions, each of which tention we sought. And our supposition will become all the more solid
would have to have a purpose which we could not indicate if the main the less we are able to think of any other consequence apart from these
538 purpose were not operative. that the agent could have thought of and desired. If we know how the
2) I now turn to the way that the intentions of finite beings must be resolutions, or what amounts to the same, the intentions of the being are
determined through experience. We must begin by distinguishing cases usually constituted, it is obvious that the credibility of our explanation
where we already know that a given phenomenon was produced by the will increase if the intention we now ascribe to the being is of the same
resolution of a being, and hence has a purpose, from those where we do sort as the others. In the opposite case, our explanation will be examined
not know, and must still decide, whether this is the case. (a) The for- all the more rigorously, and can be accepted only if the improbability of
mer case is undoubtedly easier, especially if we also know which being its negation is decidedly greater than the improbability of the assump-
is responsible for the phenomenon to be explained, and if many of its pe- tion that our being has on this occasion departed from his usual way of
culiarities are known to us, notably, the constitution of its cognitive and acting. Occasionally, the given action is composed of several individual
appetitive faculties. It is obvious that here we must begin by minutely resolutions which are so constituted that we would be unable to find a
examining the action we seek to explain. Next, we consider the diverse purpose for any of them, unless we presupposed the goal for the entire
effects or consequences this action might have, not so much in actual- action we had surmised according to the rules given so far. It requires no 540
ity as in the thoughts of the agent, and indeed according to the concepts proof that this circumstance increases the probability of our conjecture.
which he had at the very moment of forming the resolution (rather than (b) The foregoing shows the difficulties connected with the discovery of
ideas he acquired after the fact). It is clear that this is usually a very diffi- intentions, even when we know that an intention must be present, and also
cult inquiry. With God, we know that everything that will actually result know the nature of the agent and his intentions to some extent. How much
is foreseen. With men, and indeed all finite beings, however, we cannot more tricky this business must be when we do not even know whether a
infer from the fact that an action has a certain result that this result was given phenomenon had a purpose! When we notice phenomena that bear
foreseen and still less that it was intended. Here we must take account the greatest similarity to those our own body brings about, we rightly in-
of the agent's intelligence, how observant and deliberate he is in forming fer that these stem from the presence of similar bodies, and surmise at the
resolutions, the false ideas he may have of the causal connections between same time that entities similar to our soul reside in these bodies. If we see
certain things, and many other circumstances besides, in order to be able changes in these bodies like those which occur in our own when we have
to say with some assurance which consequences he had thought of, or certain ideas and sensations, we surmise that these beings have similar
even could have thought of. But if the thought of a consequence is to ideas and sensations. If, finally, we see that they act through their bodies
induce a rational being to act, it must not only be represented, but also be on other objects, in roughly the same way we ourselves usually do, we
539 such as could be willed. In this circumstance lies a further characteristic surmise that they have roughly the same intentions that we do when we
which may often be sufficient to determine intentions. For if we suppose act similarly. In continually applying this inference from the similarity of
that among the many consequences we believe that the agent might have the effects to the similarity of the causes, we generally arrive at the con-
thought of, some are such that their expectation could not have made the viction that apart from the human race there are innumerably many other
act seem either obligatory or beneficial to the agent, then it is decided kinds of sensate beings. But as we almost always only see the kinds of

356 357
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 386. Particular Rules

actions performed that humans can ped(mn without being distinctly con- are behind an action, we generally content ourselves with indicating a
scious of our own ideas or using reason, and see them do so many things single one or, if indicating several, do not appropriately subordinate one
they would have to avoid if they had reason, we conclude that all of these to the other. It is obvious that in order to avoid this mistake we must
are beings of a lower kind than us, lacking reason. Continued observation pay close attention to all, even the smallest circumstances accompanying
54 l teaches us more about the powers and nature of other objects, which puts the action, as well as the attitudes, needs and circumstances of the agent.
us in a position to decide in many, though not all, cases whether a given (e) Finally, in the special case when we must discover the intentions of
phenomenon was produced intentionally, and if so what the intention was. our own actions, it occurs all too often that we convince ourselves that
In particular, we surmise that a phenomenon before us was intentionally something resulted unintentionally, or that some quite innocent intention
brought about by a being with cognitive powers when we already know lay behind an action when a completely different, secret, intention was
kinds of beings that are able to produce such phenomena, while the ori- responsible. One must have the firm intention to learn the truth about
gin of the phenomenon could only be explained otherwise as the result of oneself, to note not only isolated acts but their circumstances as well, and
numerous circumstances, which are not usually found together, occurring finally consult the judgements of others if one is not to deceive oneself on
at the same time. Such judgements often require weighing the probabil- this point.
ities of many contrary events. Suppose, for example, that a sailor finds
himself on an island where there is no trace of humans ever having been. §.387.
He sees some lines in the sand which are roughly like those in the well-
XXIX. The interpretation of given signs
known figure used to prove the Pythagorean Theorem. At any other place,
we could infer without further ado that these lines had been drawn by a
The problem of interpreting given signs may be considered a special case
human being, but on that island this can still remain doubtful.
of the problem of discovering intentions. By interpretation I mean noth- 543
3) Among the errors that may be committed in attempting to solve
ing other than an indication of the ideas which someone intended to stim-
this problem, let us caution against the following: (a) We are all too used
ulate by producing certain signs (§285); and the word "indicate" means
to inferring from ourselves to others-that is, perceiving a phenomenon
either the production of these ideas in one's own consciousness, or the
which is similar to those we can bring about, we immediately suppose
production of certain other signs which are better known than the given
that the being which produced it had the same intention we would have
ones or belong to a different system of signs, and at the same time serve
had under such circumstances when acting in that way. In order to avoid
to stimulate the same ideas which the original producer of the former
this error as much as possible, we must become acquainted with the dif-
signs had intended. Thus the business of interpretation is not a matter of
ferences between men with respect to their ideas, sensations, wishes, etc.
learning which ideas occurred to the original producer of given signs, but
(b) We often assume that Goel has intentions which He does not in fact
rather of saying which ideas he intended to produce in the minds of oth-
542 have, sometimes because we only consider the (admittedly good) proxi-
ers through these signs. Thus, for example, a liar often has a completely
mal results, and overlook the more remote effects, and sometimes because
different opinion than the one he seeks to produce in us through the signs
our inclinations lead us to claim that something is the will of Gocl-e.g.,
he uses. But we interpret his speech quite correctly as soon as we indicate
if this would allow us to justify our actions. (c) It often happens that we
the ideas he intended to bring about in us. To determine whether he him-
judge that a human or another finite being brought about something inten-
self has these ideas is another problem entirely. It should not be forgotten
tionally when it was accidental, occurring without the knowledge or will
that writer, reader and interpreter can often be one and the same person,
of the being. We are especially in danger of committing this mistake when
as is the case when we want to interpret signs we used earlier to record
the result brings advantages to the being, and it is not sufficiently obvious
our own thoughts.
that these advantages were not foreseen. So too when it brings us joy to be
1) In order to justify the claim that certain signs were produced by
able to ascribe such intentions to others, e.g., when we hate someone, and
someone with the intention of producing such and such ideas in us, we
the intention we ascribe to him is an evil one. (d) When several purposes
must (a) show that there is nothing impossible about a being of this kind

358 359
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 387. Particular Rules

in these circumstances intending to stimulate such ideas in us. Part of must be the same as the sense the speaker intends it to have in the other
this is to show that it could look upon this task as something which was cases. For the same sign may have several, though there are always only
either its duty or else would bring it certain benefits. Thus it would have a small number of such meanings, and in most cases they are similar and
to believe that the stimulation of such ideas would bring us to recognise derivative. If we succeed in discovering one or more meanings of the kind
544 some useful truth, or at least bring us pleasure, or else bring honour or described above for each of the individual signs of which a discourse is
some other actual or merely imagined pleasure or benefit to itself. (b) We composed, which are so constituted that one or the other of them yields
must also show that the being could have considered the signs it used as a sense one might expect the speaker to have intended, it becomes quite
the best means of stimulating these ideas among those at its disposal- probable that he actually intended this sense. It goes without saying that
showing, e.g., that these signs are either natural or else introduced into this business of guessing will be extremely difficult if we do not already
common usage, or were already previously declared by the speaker to be know the meanings of some of the signs, or if we do not know the topic
signs of the given ideas, or resemble these, etc. (c) Our interpretation will of the discourse to some extent.
become all the more probable if we show that no other purpose could be Once we have determined some of the signs, the remaining ones be-
devised for these signs-showing, for example, that these signs consist come increasingly easier to determine, since the number of meanings 546
of phenomena which have no use apart from stimulating ideas that the which might be conjectured if an acceptable sense is to be produced be-
producer could have foreseen and intended. comes ever smaller.
2) From what has been said it is clear that the interpretation of given 4) But if we may suppose (and until the opposite is shown, this must
signs is facilitated by first learning who produced them, the circumstances be supposed to be the case, since it is most common) that the speaker
in which he found himself, his ideas, needs, etc., as well as possible. The intended to be understood by the people he spoke to, then we may also
more reasonable someone is, the less we can allow ourselves to interpret suppose that he chose his signs in accordance with this purpose. And
his words in ways which suppose him to commit gross errors. The more this supposition becomes all the more certain the greater his acquain-
ethical someone is, the less we may ascribe meanings to him which betray tance with his interlocutors. In such cases we may thus suppose that the
immoral aims, and so on. We must especially strive to learn the nearest speaker uses signs which are already known to his interlocutors unless
motive the speaker or writer had, and attempt to bring out as much of his obliged to do otherwise, and uses these signs only with the meanings al-
purposes as we may by other means. ready known to them; he does not use new signs, or old signs with new
3) Even when the sign before us is a single and completely simple one meanings without having previously defined their senses; he does not use
(§285), and its meaning is conventional but not yet known to us, it may the same sign now in one sense, now in another, without making sure
sometimes be possible to divine the idea the speaker intended to stimulate that the context will make apparent the meaning in which the sign was
545 with it. For if the circumstances in which he finds himself are such that we taken; he must have expected that when he uses a sign in one sense, he
may suppose with near certainty that he must have wished to stimulate the takes it in the same sense when it is used immediately afterwards, so
idea a in us, perhaps in order to move us to perform a certain action A, and long as this interpretation gives rise to a sense we might have expected
we observe that he brings about a change a which we cannot think to have of him, and he himself gives no hint that he means to depart from this
any purpose other than to stimulate the idea a in us, we may conclude that meaning. Understandably, many rules for the business of interpretation
he brings about this change with precisely this aim, no matter how little flow from these assumptions, especially for the case where we have not
connection we perceive between the sign a and the idea a. Be the word a merely a fragment of a discourse but a self-standing (and hence in itself
man who suddenly finds himself in mortal danger calls out to us ever so comprehensible) whole. As an example of one of these rules, if we must
unknown, we may still conclude quite confidently that he intends to tell us determine the meaning of a hithe1to unknown sign, we must assemble as
that we should help him. But if there are many signs occurring together, many passages from the given composition as we can, and attempt to dis-
occmTing repeatedly in various combinations, it is not necessary that the cover a meaning which would yield a sense in all these passages that we
meaning we ascribed to an individual sign when it occurs in one case could expect from the speaker; and if we convince ourselves that we can- 547

360 361
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 387. Partirnlar Rules

not manage this with a single meaning, we must attempt this with two, we already know, what ideas are combined to form the idea designated by
three or more. In such circumstances, i.e., when we may not suppose the unknown sign. But even this means may fail, if the author has made a
more meanings than necessary in order to produce a reasonable sense in mistake in his definition (as happens even with practised authors).
each passage, passages which are highly indeterminate when considered 5) If the signs that someone uses already have a meaning firmly fixed
alone may nevertheless be very useful in discovering the meaning we by common usage, it is to be surmised that he takes them in this sense
seek. For even if infinitely many concepts would produce an acceptable unless there is an explicit indication of the contrary; yet this rule has ex-
sense in one passage, there may be only one which works for the second ceptions. For people sometimes depart from the usual meaning of a sign
passage. Generally speaking, sentences in which the sign stands for either through ignorance, having misunderstood it, and not even being aware
the subject- or the predicate-idea, while the remaining signs are already that they understand and use it differently; sometimes people are moved
known, prove to be especially useful for the determination of a meaning. to take words in new and unusual senses, because they believe that the 549
For if we have several sentences of the form "Every X is A" or "No X is new concept they have in mind would be best designated in this way;
B" or else several of the form "Every Mis X" or "No N is X", where we sometimes, finally, it is merely the desire of novelty, which finds plea-
already know A,B,M,N, then we may (provided we do not suspect the sure in every departure from the ordinary. Thus if we find that the usual
speaker to have been mistaken in these propositions) immediately infer meaning does not yield a sense we might expect from the speaker, it is
that X designates an idea which is not higher than the ideas A, not-B, and necessary to seek another sense that fits, all the more so if any of the rea-
not-N, and not lower than the idea M. If the extension of one of the ideas sons just mentioned lead us to think that the speaker has not retained the
here represented by A, not-B, and not-N comes quite close to that of the usual meaning.
idea designated by M, or if these extensions coincide, then the extension 6) If someone comes to speak of the same object several times, it
of the idea Xis either nearly or completely determined. Yet we might still may be surmised that he will make, if not the same, at least compatible
err concerning the content of this idea. But if we consider the sentences claims about it, especially if this occurs in a brief interval of time and in
in which X occurs more closely, and assume that the speaker has not pro- similar circumstances (e.g., when speaking to the same people). If what
duced useless tautologies, merely analytic or identical propositions, we he says in one passage is distinct, i.e., its sense may be determined with
may infer that none of the ideas A, not-B, and not-N is a constituent of sufficient certainty, we may make use of it in the interpretation of other,
548 X, and also that X itself is not a constituent of M. In this way, we learn more obscure passages. Given several possible interpretations, some of
more and more parts of which X does not consist, and hence the number them compatible with the distinct passage and others not, we may only
of those which we still seek becomes ever smaller, especially since the declare one of the former to be correct.
ideas people find worthwhile to designate with their own signs are never 7) If we have somehow discovered one sense that someone intended
composed of a great many parts, and are not redundant. On account of to express through his signs, we may not immediately suppose that his
this last circumstance, the infinite multitude of ideas equivalent to a given intention was directed at this sense and no other besides. For it is also
one is reduced to a moderate number, and it is usually easy enough using possible that someone intended to stimulate more than one proposition in
the method just described to discover which of these the speaker intended the minds of his interlocutors (or readers) though the same signs. It may
to connect with X. If we are aware that the discourse we are to explain occur to anyone with some skill of expression to speak in such a way, and
has the purpose of instruction, or of demonstration, we may also assume even such a person cannot always be sure that people will understand the
that X designates an idea such that the propositions containing it which several senses of his discourse, rather than only one of them. We have
are not proven are already obvious, but the propositions which are proved plenty of examples of cases where lively-minded people make use of the
are not, and only become known through the former. This circumstance occasions provided by life in society to make statements which not only 550
furnishes a means which, in combination with others, may serve to deter- fit the present topic of conversation, but also can, and are intended to be,
mine the meaning of a sign. But the easiest and most secure means (when looked upon as pointing to completely different truths. Thus if we want
this is possible) is when the speaker himself indicates to us, using signs to have a complete and exhaustive interpretation, we must never be sat-

362 363
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 387. Particular Rules

isfied with having found one sense for the signs before us. Rather, we speaks to us. And the content of what he says to us here, or the inter-
must see whether there is also a second sense that we may also attribute pretation of his speech, consists precisely in those beneficial ideas which
to the speaker's intention. We may do this if (a) we show that the speaker we may produce in ourselves through an appropriate consideration of the
neither lacked the necessary knowledge, nor the attentiveness required in phenomenon. This much, in my opinion, follows from a correct con-
the present case, in order to perceive that his words could also be taken ception of God's providence and the definition of a sign set out in §285.
in this second sense; and further (b) that the production of this second From God's providence, it follows that Goel intends everything good in 552
meaning was something that he might have aimed at, either for moral the world which either happens or can happen. If it is certain enough that
reasons or from some other natural motivation; and that finally (c) there ideas which are or can be produced in us through the consideration of a
were many signs he might have used had he intended to express only phenomenon are good and beneficial, then it is also certain that among
one sense, while only the signs he chose to use, which are either unusual the reasons which determined God to produce this phenomenon was that
or awkwardly combined, make the second sense possible. But there is of stimulating these ideas in us. Thus if we call any phenomenon which
another case where we may claim that someone intended his discourse a thinking being produces with the intention (either complete or merely
to have several senses, namely, when he speaks to several people, and partial) of stimulating certain ideas in others a sign of these ideas, we
would like to prompt certain ideas in some of these people and different must also recognise in the case just mentioned signs through which God
ones in others. Since different ideas need not be incompatible, it is under- speaks to us. And it is obvious that these signs can only be interpreted
standable that this can occur without intending to deceive either of these according to the given principles.
groups, still less to lie to them. Now if we really do attribute such a dou- 10) If, finally, we are required to present the (already discovered)
ble meaning to a given discourse, we must, if our interpretation is to be meaning of signs through other signs (perhaps better known, or belong-
complete, indicate both of these senses, and also point out which of these ing to a different system), we need only follow the rules governing the ex-
551 was intended for whom. It is obvious that in this case we proceed roughly pression of one's own thoughts, some of which were mentioned in §344
in the same way as in the previous case, only we judge based upon the and others of which will be mentioned in the sequel.
nature of the persons to whom the discourse was aclclressecl which of them Note. Along with me, others have distinguished between the inter-
the speaker intended to understand in one way and which in the other. pretation of a given discourse and the search for the opinion the author
8) Finally, it is not seldom the case that someone does not wish us to really had, yet many of them have not held firmly to this distinction. Thus
be able to know precisely which ideas he intended to stimulate through KRUG (L., § 179) says quite correctly that "the interpretation is supposed
his speech, i.e., when the speaker is deliberately obscure. In this case we to show what thoughts the author intended to connect with the expres-
have clone our duty as interpreters as soon as we have proved that this was sions he actually used"; but immediately afterwards, in a note, one reads:
his intention. For this, we must show (a) that the speaker found himself "the interpreter of a writing is nothing other than the historical transmitter
in circumstances where he could have been led to form such an intention, of another's thought." Not so: as interpreters, we do not have to divine the
as would be the case, for instance, if he was forced to say something on thoughts of another, at least not his thoughts on the topic he speaks of, but
a given subject, but feared that a specific declaration would cause harm rather we must divine the thoughts the author intended to produce in the 553
to himself or others; and also (b) if he had not intended to be obscure, he minds of his readers. The claim has made its way into most recent trea-
could easily have expressed himself clearly and definitely. tises of logic and hermeneutics that one may only suppose a single sense
9) The infinite being, i.e., God himself may figure among the beings for any given passage. If by the sense of a passage one means the collec-
which can have the intention of awakening ideas in us through signs. The tion of all ideas that the speaker intended to stimulate in the minds of his
question thus arises of determining more precisely the rules for this spe- interlocutors or readers, then each passage would admittedly have only
cial case. Whenever we perceive a phenomenon which either turns out one sense by definition. But this was not what they meant, as is shown
to produce very beneficial ideas in us, or else can be foreseen to do so, by the fact that people have already disputed this claim. The proponents
we may always say that this phenomenon is a sign through which God of this claim are of the opinion that every passage (every combination

364 365
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 387. Particular Rules

of signs) which expresses a certain proposition could not according to gathered from one passage in determining the senses of another, where it
the speaker's intention express another proposition. I admit that multiple cannot." But if we took the rule as literally expressed, we would have to
senses are rare, and form a kind of exception; but that multiple senses declare it incorrect. For one call~ a pass~ge clear or obscure only insofar
would be something contradictory and hence should never be supposed, as one may or may not gather with certamty what is expressed in it. But
I cannot accept. When we complain frequently about the intentional am- in this sense a passage may be exceedingly obscure, and yet still be used
in the interpretation of another passage which is less obscure. As obscure
biguity someone permits himself; when we object that he has studiously
as the former may be, it may nevertheless make clear enough the meaning
used expressions that can be and are interpreted now one way, now an-
of a certain doubtful expression in another passage. - Against the uni- 555
other, does this not simply say that such a man meant his words to have
versality of the canon that anyone who speaks intends to be understood I
a double sense? Here, indeed, this occurs not with one interlocutor, but
have brought the case (no. 8), already mentioned by others, of someone
with several. Yet just as it is possible to bring it about that our words are
who intentionally expresses himself in a way that people cannot gather
understood differently by different interlocutors, so too is it possible to
his meaning. In such cases, by the way, one might as.k whether som~~ne
bring it about that the double meaning of our words occurs to one and the
is indeed speaking, i.e., producing signs. For accord~ng to the de~mtion
same interlocutor and, in addition, that he may observe that both senses
of a sign, someone who produces signs effects certam changes with the
were intended. How often do witty people answer questions in a way
purpose of stimulating definite ideas in us. ~ut sot~eone wh_o .do~s not
which not only provides the demanded reply but also point to something
intend to be understood does not aim at the st1mulat10n of defimte ideas.
else altogether-paying a compliment to one of those present, or rebuk-
One is almost justified in saying that he only intends to appear to speak,
ing someone, or revealing a long-fostered wish, etc. This kind of double
but does not actually do so. But in a wider sense one .may sa~ that he
meaning is not to be confused with the so-called allegory, nor with what
. and one (as I did above) may take the interpretation of his speech
theologians usually mean by the higher or secret meaning of a passage. speak s, · f h
to consist in the indication of his intention to leave us uncertam o w at
One who presents an allegory, e.g., that of the wolf and the lamb, does
554 not really intend us to believe the literal sense of his words, i.e., that a he is actually saying.
lamb was really taken to task by a wolf. Rather, the entire story is only a §.388.
means to convey knowledge of another kind to us. Thus one can say that,
at bottom, his discourse has only one sense. What theologians call the XXX. Discovery of available testimony
higher or secret sense of a passage is not generally and demonstrably a
sense that the author intended along with the other literal sense, but rather The reader will recall from §306 that by testimony I mean any change
an interpretation of something God intended (using the speaker as an in- which someone brings about with the determinate intention that someone
strument). What was said above in no. 9 about God speaking to us and else, if he proceeds according to his best insig.ht: will ?raw t?~ c?nclu-
how his discourse is to be interpreted is so briefly sketched that I cannot sion from the consideration of the change that 1t 1s the former s will that
hope for it to pass without dispute. I merely recall that this sort of divine i:
he accept a certain opinion, because he hims~lf ~olds to be t~·u~. Most
speech to us should not be confused with the kind that is called a divine of the knowledge we obtain through commumcatlon with others 1s based
revelation or testimony in the strictest sense. If we only conclude that upon testimony in this sense of the word. Now if we are not to o~er­
God intended such and such phenomena to produce such and such ideas look much of the testimony that is presented to us, nor to take so~ethmg
in us because these ideas are beneficial for us, we may not say that these for testimony when in fact it is not, some instruction on the discovery
ideas were revealed to us by God. The next section deals with what must of available testimony is necessary. I will indicate the most ge~eral c~n­
also be added if this is to be the case. - The well known canon that one cepts upon which such instruction is. based. In my vie:", the. bemg which
556
must explain obscure passages with the help of clearer ones but not the testifies may be either the infinite bemg or another, fimte bem~.
other way around is quite correct in the sense in which it is actually taken; 1) If God himself wishes to testify, he must produ~e a certam chm:ge-
for it is usually understood to mean "one should use what may be safely either immediately or mediately-which is so constituted that we, if we

367
366
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 388. Particular Rules

follow our best insight, must draw the conclusion that it is His will that believing certain teachings; yet we must hold to the most probable, and in
we accept a certain teaching as true because He himself recognises its so doing assume not just hypothetically but with complete certainty that
truth. The first thing, then, is to discover an individual proposition or col- God would not allow us to fall into such a harmful error. Accordingly, we
lection of propositions which are so constituted that when we associate may look upon a given teaching as authenticated (revealed) by God with
certain other circumstances with them we must look upon them as truths full confidence if we find that: (a) the proposition of which the teaching
that God wishes us to believe. If we find that these propositions con- consists is such that we hope to become better and happier by accepting
tain something demonstrably false, or that belief in them would harm our it; and in addition (b) there are certain extraordinary events which draw 558
virtue, then we certainly may not give any room for the thought that God our attention to these teachings, to which the teachings owe their origin,
wants us to believe such teachings. When, on the contrary, we recognise preservation or spread, which are so constituted that we can perceive no
not that the truth of these teachings, but that belief in them (if this should purpose their existence might have if we did not admit that they are a sign
somehow be possible) would be beneficial for our virtue and happiness, of God's will that we believe the teaching.
then there is no doubt that God wants us to look for reasons which would 2) If the witness is not God, but a finite being, in particular a hu-
establish their truth. If this reason is to be testimony from God himself, man being, then (a) the first thing we must do is to inquire whether the
then we must perceive an event which presents a sign of this divine tes- phenomenon which is supposed to constitute the testimony was indeed
tifying. Such an event obviously cannot be an everyday occurrence. For produced by this being, and indeed wittingly and willingly. It must be
not only would there be nothing to draw our attention, there would also be possible (b) to indicate a being the witness acted upon, or hoped to act
no reason to surmise that a phenomenon that is so ordinary has, in addi- upon, through the change, and indeed in such a way that the idea of the
tion to its ordinary purpose, also that of authenticating divine testimony. proposition to which he testified, as well as the will to accept it, are either
Thus the event must be unusual, i.e., must somehow or other conflict with actually or presumably produced in the mind of the second being. It must
the rules according to which events usually follow one another. Events be (c) comprehensible how the will to give such testimony could have
like these involuntarily draw our attention and make us wish to know the arisen in the being; for this, it is necessary either that he looked upon this
557 purpose for which God, as the ultimate cause of all events and hence of as a duty or else as something which was to his advantage. Finally, (d)
these as well, brought it about either immediately or mediately. But since there may be no other purpose which we may discover his action to have
the purposes of God can only consist in the promotion of the virtue and had were it not that of giving testimony.
happiness of his creatures, the question of what purpose He had in pro- Note. The theory of indicators of revelation sketched in no. 1 does not
ducing this event is the same as the question of what use it can be for really belong in general logic. It is mentioned here only to draw attention
us. Now if the unusual occutTence is connected with the previously men- to a view which I believe not only to agree perfectly with the common
tioned propositions, if it is the proximate or remote cause of our having judgement of mankind, but also to resolve many difficulties which can
learned of them, then insofar as we may suppose that it has the purpose of scarcely be avoided with the ideas usually encountered in treatises of the-
serving as a sign of God's will that we believe these propositions, we have ology. But although it may have been acceptable to mention this theory
discovered a good that God might reasonably have aimed at in bringing here, this is no place for a detailed exposition or defence of it. 559
it about. And if we find that in the absence of recognising such a sign
§.389.
in the event we could find no good that it might have aimed at, then we
may conclude, in accordance with the rules of §385, that this collection XXXI. Investigating the credibility of given witnesses
of propositions is a genuine divine revelation. It is certainly true that this
Once we know that a certain phenomenon is testimony, we may inves-
event might also have a use we do not perceive, and hence that we would
tigate whether we should believe the testimony, i.e., accept as true the
not be justified in saying that it would be purposeless if it was not in-
proposition which is its content, even in case we have no other ground
tended to testify in favour of these propositions; it is also true that we may
for its truth apart from the authority of the witness. The degree of prob-
sometimes be mistaken in our expectation of the good that will come of
ability with which we may do so is called the credibility of the witness.

368 369
THE ART OF DISCOVERY §. 389. Partirnlar Rules

Understandably, in most if not all cases, two things are involved in es- him. We must (g) see whether he might belong to the sort of men who
timating this credibility: first, the degree to which we are able to assure find pleasure in deceiving others, or who have become so accustomed
ourselves that our witness himself is of the opinion he puts forth; and the to lying that they do so even when it promises no advantage, and even
confidence with which we may infer the truth of an opinion from the fact without being distinctly aware of doing so; (h) whether the desire to say
that he holds it. If we suppose the probability of the former to be = x, something striking, or the spirit of contradiction might have led him in
and that of the second to be = y, then the probability that the proposition the absence of any bias to depart from the truth; (i) whether the very way
acquires merely through the testimony is = x. y. that he conducts himself in giving his testimony gives us good grounds 56 l
1) The first matter involves the question of whether the witness had to doubt his veracity, as would be the case if he speaks to us in a highly
the intention of making known to us what he himself holds to be true. We emotional state or when visibly confused, or if he takes a long time to
must therefore investigate whether and to what degree we may convince think before responding to questions that are easily answered by those
ourselves that such an intention was present. With finite beings, and in who only wish to tell the truth, etc.; (k) whether any of his actions lead us
particular humans, we must here look into the following: (a) whether the to suspect him to hold another opinion.
nature of the subject the witness pronounced on and the circumstances in 2) If we have discovered whether and with what degree of probability
which he found himself were of the sort that would make a lie (a mis- we may assume that a witness actually believes what he tells us, the next
representation of what appears to him to be true) impossible for him, in thing is to investigate whether and with what probability we may suppose
that his duty as well as his own advantage required him to say what he that he has not erred in his opinion, i.e., that he has knowledge of the mat-
himself held to be true. To this inquiry belongs, in particular, the ques- ter at hand. Here, when dealing with a finite being, namely, a man, we
tion of whether our witness might have worried about whether a lie, had must be attentive to the following things: (a) whether his previous knowl-
560 he chosen to tell one, would have been immediately detected and thus edge and his intelligence might be too limited to permit him to grasp a
bring shame and punishment upon himself. (b) If this is not the case truth of the kind he testifies in favour of; (b) whether, insofar as percep-
we must inquire further whether the witness is known to be a man of ~ tions are necessarily involved in grasping the truth, he has the necessary
righteous disposition, who may be expected to tell the truth. We must sensory organs, which are in a healthy condition; (c) whether he found
ask, in particular, if (c) he has given proof of a particular love of truth. himself in the appropriate place, at the appropriate time, to make the per-
We may suppose this to be the case if he has already said many things in ceptions required to lead him to such a truth; (d) whether other objects
cases where some natural inclination or other of the heart might have led mioht
b
have distracted him at this time. Thus someone who is in mortal
him to remain silent, if he did not have the principle and ruling disposi- danger may think only of how to survive, and hence be in no position
tion to bear witness to the truth. If we find nothing of this kind, we must to notice much else. So too scholars may be so absorbed in their reflec-
(d) investigate whether, on the contrary, he has betrayed his opinion that tions that they are unaware of significant events occuning around them.
it is sometimes permissible to lie, namely, for the sake of pious ends; and (e) Whether the witness' imagination was overly vivid, or was overstim-
whether this delusion might have led him in the present case to give false ulated in this case, whereby it might happen that he imagined that he saw
testimony with a peaceful conscience in this case. We must (e) investi- things which did not in fact occur; (f) whether he had preconceived opin-
gate whether he might obtain or hope to obtain certain advantages from ions that exercised a detrimental influence on his judgement; (g) whether
his statement or whether, on the contrary, it is disadvantageous to him, in he was too hasty in forming his judgement; (h) whether it is credible that 562
such a way that he can foresee the disadvantages. We must (f) consider he retained what he told us in memory from the moment he learned it
whether the circumstances under which the testimony was delivered con- until the time he told us or wrote it down in his notebook. Here one must
tained an increased obligation to report the unadulterated truth, as is the ask whether it made a deep or only a shallow impression on his mind;
case in court, where testimony is given under oath, etc., or whether, on the whether there were many other similar ideas in his mind that might have
contrary, the circumstances provide at least an apparent excuse for lying, led to confusion; whether one may surmise that he recalled the matter
as when he is interrogated by people who have no authority to investigate frequently or infrequently in the interim, etc.; (i) whether he has changed

370 371
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 389. Particular Rules

his mind often on the subject, and for what reasons; (k) whether we may the grounds that made his other statements unreliable are absent-e.g.,
assume the presence of various things required to know about the matter if in the other cases he lacked the requisite knowledge or was in a posi-
in question based merely on the witness' word (as is the case, for exam- tion where he would be tempted to distort the truth. Thus the statement
ple, when someone assures us that he was present, had the appropriate of a witness concerning the sensible phenomena that could be observed
instruments, etc.), or whether we have reason to distrust what he says on a certain occasion might be quite credible, even if his judgements on
about this. their cause should be rejected. (c) Finally, there is a third case, one which
3) If the witness whose knowledge we must judge provides mediate occurs quite infrequently, where the statement of a witness becomes cred-
testimony, i.e., if his testimony is based upon the testimony of another, ible even though we find that he has neither knowledge of the matter at
then his knowledge of the matter at hand depends on whether he correctly hand nor the intention of speaking truly. This occurs in cases where cir- 564
understood the witness upon whose testimony he based his belief, and cumstances are such that we may conclude with great probability that the
whether the latter was trustworthy. We must also consider whether our witness is mistaken, but also that he had the intention to deceive us, and
witness has the knowledge required to assess the credibility of a given accordingly tells us something he thinks to be false while in fact it is true.
witness. Note. Usually people require that a witness be competent and sincere
4) It is also worth mentioning that there are a couple of cases in in order to be credible, and that, in addition to what I called knowledge
which the credibility of a witness may be directly inferred, that is, without of the matter at hand in no. 2, he must also have the ability to express
first showing that he had the intention and the ability to report the truth. what he intends to communicate to us in a comprehensible way; one calls
(a) The first is when we have several statements from the witness which a witness sincere, however (or honest or veracious) if he has the intention
are all demonstrably correct, and when it is completely impossible to see to communicate what appears to him to be true. In my view, a witness'
what peculiarity the present statement (the truth of which we must test) ability to express himself in a comprehensible way does not belong so
might have which would lead him to be deceived or to want to deceive much to the requirements of being a credible witness as to those required
563 us. Such a case occurs, for instance, when the knowledge the witness has for the apprehension of testimony. For insofar as we do not understand
shown through other statements is such that we may infer from it that he what a witness intends to communicate to us, he has in fact not commu-
must also have knowledge concerning the statement under examination nicated anything, and thus we have not apprehended any testimony at all.
and, in addition, there is no conceivable ground which might have deter- But I do think that the above terms are poorly chosen to designate the
mined him to produce an untruth here rather than elsewhere, as occurs property according to which a witness intends to communicate to us what
when he has no advance knowledge of which statements of his we are to he takes to be true in a given case. Sincerity, honesty, veracity are words
put to the test. (b) The other case occurs when the witness gives such a which in common usage designate virtues that a witness must possess in
complete account of something that we cannot suspect that he would be some, though not all, cases where we find him credible. We may even
able to conceive all this if it were not true. Thus when an uneducated trust a statement of a person who often lies if the circumstances are such
man reports an eloquent saying he claims to have heard from someone as to make it impossible for him to lie in a particular case. The word
else, we may confidently conclude that he speaks truly. Yet it should truthfulness might be more appropriate in this case, though we have seen
not be forgotten that the inference drawn in (a) above from the truth of in no. 4 that it is incorrect to think that knowledge of the matter at hand
other statements to the truth of the one under examination is only valid and the intention to communicate the truth are indispensable conditions
when the specified conditions are met. For if other circumstances obtain for the credibility of a witness, since we may sometimes be able to credit
with the statement under examination, it may admittedly be the case that a witness' statement even though we know that the witness neither knows
the witness lacks the requisite knowledge of the matter at hand or the the truth nor has the will to communicate to us what he takes to be true. 565
will to communicate the truth. For similar reasons, the demonstrated in-
correctness of many statements a witness has made need not cast doubt
on the veracity of what he says in a certain other case, if it appears that

372 373
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 390. Particular Rules

( -l)(p-1)
§.390. often as not, then the credibility of the event would be (n~t)ip-ll+t' which
XXXll. Determining the credibili(y of a proposition based on may be brought as close to unity as one wishes, either by increasing n
the opinions of all those who either accept or reject it while keeping p constant or, keeping n constant (provided that n > 2) and
increasing p. (3) It is clear that the case we just considered would not
In §331, I recommended consulting the opinions of all who either ac- occur if, among the many witnesses we find to be in agreement, there
cept or reject a given proposition as a means that is quite useful in many are some who formed their opinions later, based upon the opinions of the
cases for discovering the truth, or at least for attaining a high degree of others who had formed theirs earlier. Even so, when we become aware
confidence in one's judgements. Here I shall simply describe in greater that this has occurred it may still increase our trust in the earlier witnesses
detail how one should proceed. ( 1) First, it is obvious that we should considerably, provided that closer examination shows that the later wit-
count ourselves among the number of those who either accept or reject nesses know how to test the credibility of those they are asked to believe.
the proposition in question if we have grounds either for or against its (4) It is more complicated when we meet not only with people who speak
truth that are not merely drawn from the consideration of which other in favour of a proposition M, but also those who speak against it. Above 567
people accept or reject it. The essentials of reckoning the degree of cred- all, one must beware here of not being too hasty in such cases, i.e., not to
ibility conferred on a proposition through a combination of several in- falsely believe that one statement conflicts with another simply because it
ternal or external grounds have already been presented in § 161, no. 17. sounds different. A genuine conflict may only be supposed if one person's
(2) If we want to estimate the increase in the credibility of a proposi- statement either explicitly denies the other's proposition (explicit contra-
tion due to the appearance of testimony or in general through someone diction); or if the former claims something that stands in the relation of
else's opinion, it is necessary to distinguish two cases, the first where incompatibility with the other's proposition (contrariety in the narrower
the other person must either affirm or deny our proposition if he is not sense); or, finally, if he says nothing when he would have had every rea-
to leave it completely undecided, and the second where we ask in such son to confirm the other's statement had he not taken it to be false (tacit
a way that many other answers are possible. An example of the former contradiction). I need not add that in the case of such conflicts, the num-
is when we ask someone whether the ball no. 1 was drawn from an urn; ber of people who stand on the two sides should not merely be counted,
an example of the latter is when the witness of his own free will tells us, but also their importance should be estimated. We should, however, avoid
without having consulted others, that the ball no. 1 was drawn. It is easy overestimating the weight of the party to which we ourselves belong. If
to see that in the latter case people who, individually, are only capable others are more practised thinkers than we are, or (if the matter involves
566 of conferring a small probability on the proposition may, through their perception) if they are better observers than we are, we must in fairness
agreement, produce a satisfactory guarantee when there are many ways trust their judgements more than our own. If the assumption of veracity
that their statements might have differed from each other. If the number (the will to speak the truth in a particular case) has the same probability
of answers that might have been expected with equal probability was = n, for several witnesses, then understandably the most credible among them
and if we receive the same answer from the p witnesses whose respective will be the one for whom the assumption that he has knowledge of the
I II
degrees of credibility are represented by the fractions r~s, r':s', /~s", ... matter at hand is the most probable. Now when there are no other dif-
-if, for example there were n balls in an urn and the p witnesses all ferences, for instance, of intelligence or attentiveness, the truth is more
reported that the only ball drawn from the urn was ball no. 1-I reckon easily and securely known the more immediately it is inferred from the
the degree of probability that this event gains through the combined testi- perceptions that have been made. Hence it is rightly said that, all other
. (11-l)(p-l).,-././'.... .
mony of all the witness to be (n--J)(p-J).,-.,-'.,-" .... +s·s'·s" ..... If this formula things being equal, an immediate witness is to be preferred to a mediate
is correct, then it is apparent that r may be quite small compared to s, and one, an eyewitness to an earwitness, the nearer witness to the farther, etc.
1
1 quite small compared to s', etc., but if n becomes larger, the value of (5) The statement of a witness who lacks either the necessary knowledge
the fraction may come quite close to unity. If, for example, all of the r of the matter at hand or veracity can at most be counted among those
were equal to s, i.e., if all the witnesses were dubitable, speaking truth as speaking in favour of a proposition in the case where, uniting these flaws, 568

374 375
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 390. Particular Rules

he hits upon the truth. Otherwise we must look upon his testimony as a extinct, where we are in no way asked to say something that applies to all
ground against the truth of the proposition. But every ground against the of these creatures, but only to say something previously unknown about
truth of a claim that has credibility m may be considered a ground for it one of them, e.g., about Megatherion.
with credibility I - m. (6) The circumstance that given witnesses contra- l) If some truths about the given object are already known to us, it
dict one another in certain respects weakens our confidence in the points will be appropriate to recall many, if not all, of them since it is quite
where they agree in some cases, but strengthens it in others. The former possible that from these, either on their own or else in combination with
happens if the only thing that may be gathered from the disagreement is truths belonging to some other domain entirely, we shall be able to de-
that they (either some or all of them) lack either knowledge of the matter duce new propositions (as was recommended in §328). If, for example,
at hand or else the necessary veracity. The latter occurs when we gather we were required to discover a previously unobserved prope1iy of a (loga-
that the witnesses did not consult one another, and that where one of them rithmic) spiral, and we begin by thinking of the known properties of such
lacked either knowledge or veracity, the other had either better knowledge curves, e.g., about the method of determination, which involves only a
or a firmer intention to tell the truth. Our trust will be greater especially given point, a given straight line, and a given angle, it occurs to us im-
in cases where we are convinced that it was not the intention to misrep- mediately that every point in this line has a situation that is similar to 570
resent the truth, but rather the attempt to bring it to light that caused the every other, and that in particular the curvature is uniform in all points,
divergences between the witnesses. (7) Mere hearsay and rumours whose from which it follows that this spiral (and not, as NEWTON supposed,
source is unknown, even legends elating from remote times may be worthy a parabola) should be used to represent the way in which a given line
of belief if there is no good explanation for how they might have arisen changes its curvature in a point.
and spread if what they recount (if not in every detail, at least on the main 2) But it is not only by seeking consequences of truths already known
points) had not actually happened. (8) Finally, if we consult the opinion to us that we may atTive at previously unknown truths, for this may also
of someone who is himself not certain of what he advances, it is obvious happen when we inquire into the grounds from which they are deducible.
that the credibility of his statement is reduced by this circumstance. But And the latter may be all the more useful since an appropriate combi-
if he admits his uncertainty of his own free will, our trust in his veracity nation of them would to all appearance allow us to deduce even more
as well as in his insight can increase, in that we are able to gather that truths than the ones we began with. If, for example, we inquire about the
he is not hasty in his judgements, and feels no shame in admitting his ground of the fact that reason makes it our duty not to torment animals
569 uncertainty. aimlessly, it becomes obvious that this happens because we should act
in general in such a way that the happiness of the whole increases. But
§.391. from this truth we may deduce a considerable number of other, previously
unknown truths.
XXXIII. Discovering new truths about a given object 3) A third procedure consists in forming propositions at random ac-
cording to §329, and then inquiring whether any are true. Understandably,
There remains, finally, the consideration of a problem to which most sci-
this procedure will only be advantageous if the probability that there is a
ences owe the expansion of their domains. It is the problem that asks no
true proposition among those we have formed is not too small, and if the
more of us than to discover new truths that are specified only by indicat-
investigation of whether the propositions are true does not surpass our
ing the object they are supposed to concern. This object in its turn may
powers. Depending on the varied natures of the objects the truths we
either be completely determined, in that one indicates an idea A applying
seek are supposed to concern and the nature of the truths already known
exclusively to it, or else only partly determined, in that one indicates that
to us, the way to proceed in this may vary considerably. If among the
the object is one of those standing under a given idea A. An example
already known truths there is one whose subject-idea is not as wide as
of the first sort would be the problem of discovering new, previously un-
A (as the domain concerning which the sought truths must not surpass),
known reports about Alexander the Great; an example of the latter would
nothing is more suitable than to inquire whether this proposition can be 571
be the request to hear something about prehistoric creatures that are now

376 377
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 391. Particular Rules

generalised without affecting its truth. i.e., whether it would still remain both subject- and predicate-ideas is a quite useful means of discovering
true if we replaced its subject-idea with a wider one; or whether in partic- new truths, whether we do this by omitting certain constituents of p or by
ular we might be able to delete one of the constituents of the subject-idea. replacing it with another idea altogether. If, for instance, we have found
If it turns out that the proposition in question remains true even when we that a circle may be circumscribed around every quadrangle whose oppo-
remove the constituent a from the subject-idea [S]a, or when some other site angles sum to two right angles, we may immediately conjecture that
higher idea T is put in the place of [S]a, this discovery is always a most every quadrangle may be circumscribed by some smt of curve of which
welcome one. For if the extension of the proposition is not in fact broad- the circle is a special case; we then find that this curve is an ellipse. Just
ened by simplifying its subject-idea, we learn that this idea, as it was first as we can arrive at new truths by attempting to broaden the subject-idea
constituted, was redundant, and that the truth "All S are I,'' holds. But if of a given truth by omitting some of its constituents, it is also useful to 573
the idea S is higher than [S]a, or if the higher idea T that replaces [S]a alter certain constituents in this idea, i.e., to replace them with others,
is not a mere constituent of [S]a, then the truth that we have just learned especially if we make a corresponding change in the predicate-idea at the
has a wider extension than the one we started with, and is thus doubtless
important. This even holds if the ideas Sor Tare wider than A, for in that
case the truth we discover, although it is not of the sort we set out to find,
curve for which the equation y2 = *(
same time. If, for example, we know that in every ellipse, i.e., every
a 2 - x 2 ) holds, there are two points
for which the sums of the vectors are equal to a constant quantity, we in-
is nevertheless noteworthy, and may be useful for other purposes. If, for vestigate what sort of alteration must be performed on the predicate-idea
example, we investigate whether the truth that triangles are similar when of this proposition if we change the subject-idea from tha\ of an ellipse

*(
to that of a hyperbola, i.e., instead of the expression y2 = ~ (a - x ) we
2 2
two sides and the angle they include are similar can be generalised, we
hit upon the discovery of the far more general proposition that things in have y2 = a2 + x2 ). Here it turns out that instead of the sum of the
general are similar if their determining elements are similar. Even though vectors, we must have their difference.
the latter proposition may be far more general than the truths we set out 4) When the given idea A does not determine one object we are sup-
to discover, as when, e.g., if we had only set out to discover geometrical posed to discover truths about, but rather a domain of objects, we. do
truths, it is nonetheless worth bearing in mind, since it can be a fruitful well even if we merely discover previously unknown truths concernmg
source of new discoveries, even in geometry. If every generalisation we only part of the objects standing under this idea. To do this, however,
572 undertake with the subject-idea of a given proposition destroys the truth we must first form ideas of such parts, i.e., of species subordinate to the
of the proposition, we surmise that it cannot be generalised, so that the genus A, or even of a single thing standing under the idea A. §361 ~ro­
subject-idea S and the concretum P corresponding to its predicate are a vides instructions on how to do this. If, for example, we were reqmred
pair of equivalent concepts. Thus it would be appropriate to investigate to discover truths belonging to the theory of curved lines, we begin by
the correctness of this conjecture or, what amounts to the same, whether attempting to form a concept of curves that have not yet been considered,
the proposition that every P is an S is true. Since this proposition is called e.g., by assuming an arbitrary equation or method of construction fo~ su~h
the converse of the former, one may also say that we intend to investigate curves. Then, when we investigate the attributes of these curves, 1t will
whether this proposition may be converted. A considerable number of appear either that we have discovered a new curve or else a new i:iethod
very beautiful truths, especially in the mathematical sciences, are discov- of construction for an already known curve. If we know several kmds of
ered precisely through such attempts to convert propositions. If the at- objects subordinate to A, or several individual things standing under~'
tempted generalisation of the proposition "Sis P" does not succeed, i.e., and wish to consider their attributes more precisely, it is natural to begm 574
if every time we replace S by a higher idea we obtain a false proposition, with the consideration of those that are simpler, or those whose attributes
then it may be possible to obtain a true proposition by suitably broaden- may be more easily discovered. For example, after we have formed the
ing the idea Pat the same time, i.e., if we replace P with a certain higher concepts "triangle", "quadrangle", etc., which are subordinate to the con-
idea Q. For even if the property p does not belong to all T, the property q, cept "polygon", we will begin with the consideration of triangles rather.
which has a wider extension than p, may belong to all T. Thus broadening than that of quadrangles, as the former are simpler, etc. In the process of

378 379
THE ART OF DISCOVERY§. 391.

seeking new ideas subordinate to the given concept A we ascend, when Bibliography
the nature of the matter permits it, to genuine singular concepts or else
to species that are so low than no further subdivision promises any note-
worthy differences. Thus mathematicians, when considering triangles, ABEL, JAKOB FRIEDRICH
proceed to the equilateral, the right-angled isosceles, when considering
1. Einleitung in die Seelenlehre. Stuttgart 1786.
quadrangles to the square, when considering hyperbolas to the equilat-
eral, in the theory of numbers to individual numbers (e.g., the numbers e 2. Ueber die Quellen der menschlichen Vorstel!unoen St tt
'~ · · u gart 1786.
and n). If, however, we have discovered certain attributes of such indi-
ALEFELD, JOHANN LUDWIG
vidual things or of such lowest species that are common to several, then
it is time to raise these to a higher genus, and thus to pose the question 1. Mutua Protagorce et Evathli sophismata. GieBen 1730.
of what is the most general concept of things which have this attribute.
It is well known that FERMAT and others discovered many attributes of ARISTOTLE
prime numbers in this way. If there are sensible objects that stand un-
der the idea A, we may in many cases become aware of the the attributes 1. Organon, including: Categories, On Interpretation Prioi· A l t'
. · . . ' nay zcs,
belonging either to all A or to all of some special kind of A by investigat- Posterwr. Analytzcs,
. Topzcs and On Sophistical Rejiaations · E ng l'ISl1
ing more carefully the sensible objects of the kind A that we are able to translations 111 J. Barnes ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle, revised
Oxford translation. 2 Vols. Princeton 1984.
observe. If we find the attribute bin all A or at least in all [A]m that we
are able to observe, then we may conclude with greater or lesser prob- 2. On the Soul. English translation in Barnes ed.
ability that all [A ]m, indeed even all A have the attribute b; and through
continued reflection we may succeed in deducing this proposition from ARNAULD, ANTOINE AND PIERRE NICOLE
575 pure concepts. Many laws of physics, e.g., the laws of collision, the law
1. La logique ou ! 'Art de penser: Paris 1662; Latin translation: Logica
of capillary attraction, the law of refraction, which may be counted as
sive ars cogitandi. Basel 1749 (both published anonymously).
purely conceptual truths, were originally discovered in this way. It was
pointed out in §331 that we should not fail to perform appropriate ex- BACHMANN, CARL FRIEDRICH
periments if circumstances permit. One of the important factors here is
that the objects sunounding us not undergo many changes at the same 1. System der Logik. Ein Handbuch zum Selbststudium. Leipzig 1828
time, since otherwise we will have a difficult time judging which of these (Logik).
changes is the true cause of the new phenomena we obtain. Thus we must
BAUMGARTEN, ALEXANDER GOTTLIEB
alter one part at a time, though ensuring that in the encl all are altered. For
instance, a chemist who wants to perform truly instructive experiments 1. Acroasis Logica. Halle 1773 (Logica).
on the behaviour of two substances will not vary the quantity and the
temperature simultaneously, but rather separately. BEATTIE, JAMES

1. Versuch iiber die Natur und Unveranderlichkeit der Wahrheit. Copen-


hagen and Leipzig 1772; a translation of An Essay on the Nature and
Immutability of Truth. Edinburgh 1770.

BECK, JAKOB SIGMUND

1. Lehrbuch der Logik. Rostock und Schwerin 1820 (Logik).

380 381
BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY

BENEKE, FRIEDRICH EDUARD CRUSIUS, CHRISTIAN AUGUST

1. Psychologischen Skizzen. 2 Vols. Gottingen 1825, 1827. 1. Weg. zur


. Gewij3heit und Zuverliissigkeit
. . der menschlichen E 1·kenntnzs.
.
Le1pz1g 1747, 2nd ed. Le1pz1g 1762.
BERKELEY, GEORGE
DAMIRON, JEAN PHILIBERT
1. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. Dublin
1710. 1. Cours de philosophie. 3 Vols. Paris 1831-1836. (Vol. 1 contains his
Psychologie.)
BONNET, CHARLES
DEGERANDO, JOSEPH MARIE BARON DE
1. Es.mi analytique sur !es facultes de l 'ame. Copenhagen 1760.
l. Des signes et de l 'art de penser consideres dans leurs rapports mutuels.
BORN, FRIEDRICH GOTTLOB
4 Vols. Paris 1799-1800.
1. Versuch iiber die urspriinglichen Grundlagen des menschlichen Denkem
DESCARTES, RENE
Leipzig 1791. ..
1. Discours de la methode. Vol. 6 of (4).
BOUTERWEK, FRIEDRICH
2. Meditationes de prima philosophia. Vol. 7 of (4).
1. Lehrbuch der philosophischen Wissenschaften. Gottingen 1813, 2nd
ed. 1820. 3. Principia philosophice. Vol. 8 of (4).

CALKER, FRIEDRICH 4. CEuvres de Descartes, ed. Ch. Adam et P. Tannery. 13 Vols. Paris 1897-
1913.
1. Denklehre oder Logik. Bonn 1822 (Logik).
DIOGENES LAERTIUS
CICERO, MARCUS TULLIUS
1. Lives and opinions of eminent philosophers. Loeb Classical Library.
1. Academica. In De Natura Deorum and Academica. Loeb Classical English translation by R. D. Hicks. 2 Vols. London 1925.
Library. English translation by H. Rackham. London 1933.
ENNEMOSER, JOSEPH
COMBE, GEORGE
1. Der Magnetismus nach der allseitigen Beziehung seines Wesens. Leipzig
1. System der Phrenologie. Braunschweig 1833. A translation of A Sys-
1819.
tem of Phrenology, 3rd ed. London 1830.
ESSER, WILHELM
CREUZ, FRIEDRICH CARL CASIMIR FREIHERR VON
1. System der Logik. Elberfeld 1823 (Logik).
1. Versuch iiber die Seele, Part 1. Frankfurt and Leipzig 1754.
EUCLID OF ALEXANDRIA
CROUSAZ, JEAN PIERRE DE
l. Elements. English translation by T. L. Heath. 2nd ed. 3 Vols. Cam-
1. La Logique. 3rd ed. Amsterdam 1725.
bridge 1925.

382 383
BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY

EULER, LEONARD HILLEBRAND, JOSEPH

1. Lettres a une princesse d'Allemagne. 3 Vols. St. Petersburg 1768- 1. Grundrifi der Logik. Heidelberg 1820 (Logik).
1772.
HOBBES, THOMAS
FRIES, JAKOB FRIEDRICH
1. De Co17;ore. London 1665. The first part is on logic (Log.) English
1. Wissen, Glaube und Ahnung. Jena 1805. translation by A. P. Martinich in Computatio, sive, Logica =Logic [Part
I of De Cmpore]. New York 1981.
2. Grundrifi der Logik. Heidelberg 1811
HOFFBAUER, JOHANN CHRISTOPH
3. System der Logik. 1st ed. Heidelberg 1811, 2nd ed. 1819 (Logik).
1. Anfangsgriinde der Logik. Halle 1794 (Logik).
4. Neue oder anthropologische Kritik der Vernunft. 3 Vols. Heidelberg
1828-31 (Kritik). 2. Grundrifi der Erfahrungs-Seelenlehre. 2nd ed. Halle 1810 (Psych.).

GENGLER, ADAM HOLLMANN, SAMUEL CHRISTIAN

1. Die Ideate der Wissenschaft, oder: die Encyclopadie der Theologie. 1. Philosophia rationalis, qua? Logica vulgo dicitw: Gottingen 1746 (Log-
Bamberg 1834. ica).
GERLACH, GOTTLOB WILHELM HUME, DAVID

1. Grundrifi der Logik, zwn Gebrauch bei Vorlesungen. Halle 1817 (Logik). 1. A Treatise of Human Nature. London 1739.
GESSNER, JOHANN ANTON WILHELM JAKOB, LUDWIG HEINRICH

1. Spekluation und Traum. Leipzig 1830. 1. Grundrifi der allgemeinen Logik. Halle 1791, 2nd ed. Frankfurt and
HEGEL, GEORG WILHELM FRIEDRICH Leipzig 1794 (Log.).

1. Wissenschaft der Logik. 2 Vols. Nuremberg 1812-16 (Logik). 2. Grundrifi der Eifahrungs-Seelenlehre. 3rd ed. Halle 1800 (Psych.).

HERBART, JOHANN FRIEDRICH KANT, IMMANUEL

1. Lehrbuch zur Einleitung in die Philosophie. Konigsberg 1813, 2nd ed. 1. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. 2nd ed. Riga 1787.
1821.
2. Logik, edited by Gottlob Benjamin Jasche, Konigsberg 1~~0. For the_
2. Lehrbuch zur Psychologie. Konigsberg and Leipzig 1816. Logik we indicate the pages not of the original Jasche ed1t1~n, but of
Vol. IX of the Akademieausgabe, Berlin 1923. The best Enghsh trans-
3. Psychologie als Wissenschaft neu gegriindet auf Eifahrung, Metaphysik lation (Lectures on Logic, pp. 517-640, tr. by J. Michael Young, Cam-
und Mathematik, 2 Parts. Konigsberg 1824-1825. bridge 1992) gives this pagination in the margins.
HERMES, GEORG

1. Einleitung in die christkatholische Theologie. Erster Theil: Philosophis-


che Einleitung. 2nd ed. Mtinster 1831.

384 385
BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY

KIESEWETTER, JOHANN GOTTFRIED CARL CHRISTIAN LEIBNIZ, GOTTFRIED WILHELM

1. Grundrij3 einer allgemeinen Logik nach Kantischen Grundsdtzen. This 4. Nouveaiu: essais sur l 'entendement humain. First published long after
work consists of two volumes. Vol. 1 (Berlin 1802) is "Pure General Leibniz's death in (3), pp. 1-496. (Nouv. Ess.) English edition New
Logic", Vol. 2 (Berlin 1806) is "Applied General Logic". Bolzano cites Essays on Human Understanding ed. and tr. by Peter Remnant and
only the first which consists of two parts, with separate pagination, but Jonathan Bennett. Cambridge 1982.
bound together: pp. 1-164 contains the theory itself (Logik) and the
next 520 pages an analysis of each of the paragraphs in the first half of LOCKE, JOHN
the book (Weitere Auseinandersetzung der Logik). 1. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London 1775 (lst ed.
KLEIN, GEORG MICHAEL 1690).

1. Anschauungs- und Denklehre. Bamberg 1818 (Denki.). MAAB, JOHANN GEBHARD EHRENREICH

KRUG, WILHELM TRAUGOTT l. Versuch iiber die Einbildungskrcift. Halle 1792.

1. Fundamentalphilosophie. Ztillichau and Freystadt 1803. B. sometimes 2. Grundrij3 der Logik. Halle 1793, 3rd ed. 1806, 4th ed. 1823 (Logik).
cites it as Fundamentallehre.
MALEBRANCHE, NICOLE
2. System der theoretischen Philosophie. Er:ster Teil: Denklehre oder
1. De la recherche de la verite. 2 Vols. Paris 1772.
Logik. Konigsberg 1806, 2nd ed. 1819 (Logik).
MARHEINEKE, PHILIPP KONRAD
3. System der theoretischen Philosophie. Drifter Theil. Geschmackslehre
oder Asthetik. Vienna 1818. 1. Die Grundlehren der christlichen Dogmatik als Wissenschaft. 2nd ed.
4. Allgemeines Handworterbuch der philosophischen Wissenschaften. 5 Berlin 1827.
Vols. Leipzig 1827-1829. MAYER, JOSEPH ERNST
LAMBERT, JOHANN HEINRICH 1. Ueber den VernunftschlujJ, 2 vols. Vienna 1777, 1779. (A Vermm-
1. Neues Organon. Leipzig 1764 (Bolzano sometimes cites sections of ftschluss is a categorical syllogism.)
this by their section names: Dianoiologie [of thought], Aletheiology
MEHMEL, GOTTLIEB ERNST AUGUST
[of truth], but usually as Organon or N. 0.).
1. Versuch einer vollstiindigen analytischen Denklehre als Vorphilosophie
LEIBNIZ, GOTTFRIED WILHELM
und im Geiste der Philosophie. Erlangen 1803 (Denklehre).
1. "Meditationes De Cognitione, Veritate, & Ideis (1684)." Published in
METZ, ANDREAS
Duten's edition: Gothofredi Guillelmi Leibnitii Opera Omnia. Geneva
1768, Vol. 2, pp. 14-18. English translation by Leroy E. Loemker pp. 1. Handbuch der Logik. 2nd ed. Bamberg und Wtirzburg 1816.
291-295 in Philosophical Papers and Letters. 2nd ed. Dordrecht 1969.
NDSSLEIN, FRANZ ANTON
2. Otium Hanoveranum sive Miscellanea. Leipzig 1718.
l. Grundlinien der Logik. Bamberg 1824.
3. CEuvres philosophiques, ed. Rudolph Erich Raspe, Amsterdam and Leipzig
1765. Reprint Hildesheim 2006. (Bolzano owned the edition of 1785).

386 387
BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY

PLATNER, ERNST SCHMID, CARL CHRISTIAN ERHARD

1. Philosophische Aphorismen. Leipzig 1793, 2nd ed. 1800. 1. Empirische Pscyhologie. 2nd ed. Jena 1796.

REIMARUS, HERMANN SAMUEL SCHMID, HEINRICH

1. Die Vemunftlehre. 3rd ed. Hamburg 1766. l. Versuch einer Metaphysik der inneren Natw: Leipzig 1834.

REINHOLD, CARL LEONHARD SCHULTZ, JOHANN

1. Das menschliche ErkenntnijJvermogen. Kiel 1816. l. Priifung der Kantischen Critik der reinen Vernunft. 2 Vols. Konigsberg
1789, 1792.
REINHOLD, ERNST
SCHULZE, GOTTLOB ERNST
1. Grundziige eines Systems der Erkenntnisslehre und Denklehre. Schleswig
1822. 1. Grundsiitze der allgemeinen Logik. Helmstadt 1802. 2nd ed. 1810, 4th
ed. Gottingen 1822.
2. Lehrbuch der philosophisch propiideutischen Psychologie nebst den
Grundziigen derformalen Logik. Jena 1835. SENECA

3. Theorie des menschlichen Erkenntnisvermogens und Metaphysik. Gotha 1. Epistolce morales. Loeb Classical Library. English translation by R.
and Erfurt 1835. (Metaphysik) M. Gummere. 3 Vols. London 1917, 1920, 1925.
REUSCH, JOHANN PETER SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

1. Systema Logicum antiquorum atque recentiorum item propria prce- 1. Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Hypotyposes Pyrrhoneion). Loeb Classical
cepta exhibens. Jena 1760. Library. English translation by R. G. Bury. London 1955.
RICHTER, JEAN PAUL 2. Against the Professors. Loeb Classical Library. English translation by
R. G. Bury. London 1949.
1. Das Kampaner Thal oder iiber die Unsterblichkeit der Seele. Reutlin-
gen 1801. STIEDENROTH, ERNST

RITTER, HEINRICH 1. Theorie des Wissens. Gottingen 1819.

I. Abriss der philosophischen Logik. Berlin 1824. TETENS, JOHANN NICOLAS

RUDIGER, JOHANN ANDREAS 1. Philosophische Versuche iiber die menschliche Natw: Leipzig 1777.
1. De sensu veri et falsi. Leipzig 1722, 2nd ed. Leipzig 17 41. TIEFTRUNK, JOHANN HEINRICH

SCHAUMANN, lOHANN CHRISTIAN GOTTLIEB 1. GrundrijJ der Logik. Halle 1801.


1. Elemente der allgemeinen Logik. GieBen 1795 TRACY, ANTOINE LOUIS CLAUDE DESTUTT DE

1. Elemens de ideologie. 5 Vols. Paris 1805-1817.

388 389
BIBLIOGRAPHY

TROXLER, IGNAZ PAUL VITAL INDEX OF NAMES

1. Naturlehre des menschlichen Erkennens, oder Metaphysik. Aarau 1828.


The numbers refer to the pages of Volume 3 of the 1837 edition of the Wis-
2. Logik. 3 Vols. Stuttgart und Ttibingen 1829-1830. senschaftslehre, indicated in the margins of the present edition.
TWESTEN, AUGUST DETLEV CHRISTIAN
Abel, Jakob Friedrich 53, 63 Cousin, Victor 382
1. Die Logik. Schleswig 1825. Alefeld, Johann Ludwig 489n Creuz, Friedrich Carl Casimir
Achilles 490-492 Freiherr von 37
UEBERWASSER, FERDINAND Agricola 377 Crousaz, Jean Pierre de 36, 38,
Alexander the Great 455, 569 223
1. Anweisungen zum regelmiifiigen Studium der Empirischen Psycholo-
Archimedes 307 Crusius, Christian August 53, 63,
gie. Munster 1787.
Aristotle 94, 261, 479, 481-482, 110-111, 272-273, 352
ULRICH, JOHANN AUGUST HEINRICH 485-486 Cudworth, Ralph 166

1. Institutiones logicre et metaphysicre. Jena 1792. Bachmann, Carl Friedrich 31 Damiron, Jean Philibert 79n, 382
Bacon, Francis 397 Darius, King of Persia 455
WEISS, CHRISTIAN Degerando, Joseph Marie Baron
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb
37,43,471 de 84
1. Untersuchungen iiber das Wesen der menschlichen See le. Leipzig 1811.
Beattie, James 63, 167 Descartes, Rene 30, 37, 98, 166,
WOLFF, CHRISTIAN Becher, Johann Joachim 377 220, 349-351
Beck, Jakob Sigismund 43 Diodoros Kronos of Megara 484
1. Psychologia empirica. Frankfurt and Leipzig 1738.
Beneke, Friedrich Eduard 53, 63,
Empedocles 93
2. Philosophia rationalis sive Logica. 3rd ed. Frankfurt and Leipzig 17 40. 197
Ennemoser, Joseph 233
Berger, Christian Gottlieb 377
WYTTENBACH, DANIEL
Esser, Wilhelm 31
Berkeley, George 168-169, 220
Eubulides of Miletus 487
Bonnet, Charles de 54, 174
1. Prrecepta philosophire logicre. Halle and Berlin 1820. Euclid 245, 467, 477
Born, Friedrich Gottlob 33
Euler, Leonhard 77, 185
Bouterwek, Friedrich 261
Evathlus 488-490
Bruno, Giordano 377
Btilffinger, Georg Bernhard 377 Fermat, Pierre de 574
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 15n, 111
Caesar, Gains Julius 94 Fries, Jakob Friedrich 34-35, 53,
Calker, Friedrich 77, 223 65, 111, 117, 204, 219, 228,
Campanella, Tommaso 166 257,270,282,291-292,352,
Chrysippus 487 462
Cicero, Marcus Tullius 71, 94,
494-495 Gassendi, Pierre 100, 166
Combe, George 163n Gengler, Adam 209
Condillac, Etienne Bonnot de 174 Gerard, Alexander 63

390 391
INDEX OF NAMES INDEX OF NAMES

Gerlach, Gottlob Wilhelm 33, 43, Klein, Georg Michael 220 Raphael522 Solbrig, David 377
223 Koriskos 485-486, 490 Reid, Thomas 167 Stiedenroth, Ernst 134
GeBner, Johann Anton Wilhelm Krug, Wilhelm Traugott 34, 43- Reimarus, Hermann Samuel 43,
100, 247, 381 45, 66, 94, 110, 257, 282, 204,471 Tetens, Johann Nicolas 37, 133,
290, 389,462,466,471,552 Reinhold, Carl Leonhard 79 171, 173-174
Hartley, David 377 Kuhlmann, Quirinus 377 Reinhold, Ernst Christian Gottlieb Tieftrunk, Johann Heinrich 168,
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 6, 35, 79,97, 197,227 220
36, 75n Lambett, Johann Heinrich 31, 367, Reusch, Johann Peter 31, 63, 261, Tracy, Antoine Louis Claude
Heraclitus 339 377,428 471 Destutt de 174, 175, 177,
Herbart, Johann Friedrich 6, 8, 53, Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 31, 37, Richter, Johann Paul Friedrich 470 220
97, 101-103, 135, 177 43, 53, 64, 97, 99, 166, 168, Ritter, Heinrich 34, 209, 224 Troxler, Ignaz Paul Vital 198, 228,
Hermes, Georg 292, 382-383 170, 273, 377 Rtidiger, Johann Andreas 351 292
Herod 72 Locke, John 31, 37, 99-100, 166- Twesten, August Detlev Christian
Hillebrand, Joseph 33 168, 220 Schaumann, Johann Christian 329,462
Hobbes, Thomas 77, 100, 166 Lull, Raymond 377 Gottlieb 34, 43
Schlegel, Friedrich 228 Ueberwasser, Ferdinand 62-63
Hoffbauer, Johann Christoph 63,
MaaB, Johann Gebhard Ehrenreich Schmid, Carl Christian Erhard 38, Ulrich, Johann August Heinrich
78, 80, 272-273
43, 63, 77, 100, 204, 270, 18, 100,204,223
Hollmann, Samuel Christian 31, 43
282,428 Schmid, Heinrich Johann Theodor
351 WeiB, Christian 15n
Malebranche, Nicolas 62, 220, 63,228
Horace 94 Wilkins, John 377
351 Schultz, Johann 187-193, 195-
Hume, David 63, 167 Wolff, Christian 15n, 31, 37, 63,
Marheineke, Philipp Konrad 292 197, 242
Mayer, Joseph Ernst 18 261, 270
Jakob, Ludwig Heinrich 34, 38, Schulze, Gottlob Ernst 31, 110,
Mehmel, Gottlieb Ernst August 35 Wyttenbach, Daniel 31
62-63, 76-77, 223,352, 519 273,462
Jesus of Nazareth 25, 309 Meier, Georg Friedrich 377 Seneca, Lucius Annaeus 479 Xenophanes 165, 219
Menedemus 482 Sextus Empiricus 483-484
Kant, Immanuel 24-25, 25n, 34- Metz, Andreas 31, 43, 77, 223 Socrates 89, 454, 483-486 Zeno of Elea 490
35, 37, 64-65, 134-135, 166, Molyneux, William 170
168, 178, 180-182, 185-187,
Newton, Isaac 570
194-195, 203-204, 209-210,
Ntisslein, Franz Anton 35
221-222, 239-240, 243-244,
246, 249-252, 256-257, 261, Oswald, James 167
270-271, 281, 289-290, 382,
471 Parmenides 165, 219
Kalmar, Georg 377 Philetas of Cos 487
Kiesewetter, Johann Gottfried Carl Platner, Ernst 18, 34, 37, 43, 53,
Christian 34, 36, 62-63, 76- 62-63, 100, 195
77, 94-96, 203, 205, 274, Plato 24, 94, 166
281, 290,462,469 Ploucquet, Gottfried 377
Kircher, Athanasius 377 Protagoras 488-489

392 393
INDEX OF SUBJECTS

INDEX OF SUBJECTS authenticity (cont.) binomial theorem 241


grounds for blindness 169
external 522 bodies 46, 50, 54, 148, 150, 152-
The numbers refer to the pages of Volume 3 of the 1837 edition of the Wis- internal 522 154, 157-160, 172, 176,
senschaftslehre, indicated in the margins of the present edition. authority 204, 336 246,247, 297, 298,466
appeal to 478 colour of 165
awakening law of 59 elastic 506
abbreviations 370 antinomies 250, 251, 253, 254 axiom 134, 188, 249 flexible 156
abstraction 87, 103 of pure reason 135 of parallels 249 mutual attraction of 154
abstractum 7, 433 appearance 219 mutual repulsion of 154
acceptance, degree of 113 apperceptions 37 basic truth 133 shape of 165
accident 172 approval 114 bees, hexagonal cells of 308 solid 156
Achilles paradox 490, 491 degree of 113 being brain fibres 54
acid, hydrochloric 252 approximation, methods of 321 absolutely necessary 254
acoustics 97 aptitudes 53 created 333 calculation 202, 296, 327
act arithmetic 242, 243 creating 332 Calvus 495
intentional 535 Art of Discovery 293-575 finite 405, 525, 538, 559 categories 222, 223
rational 291 assent 114 intentions of 538 causal connection 169
action 312, 394, 533 association of ideas 150, 157, 158, infinite 137, 532 causality 253
motive for 534 215,216 omniscient 136 law of 63, 64
activity 7 law of 59, 62, 63, 433 rational 396, 499, 534 through freedom 253
actuality, concept of 403 assumptions sensate 540 causes 167, 229, 526, 527
adherence l 0, 109 false 463 sentient and rational 498 and effects 56, 57, 195, 253,
adulteration 522 hypothetical 331 simple 49, 499 375, 396, 469, 496, 497,
aesthetics 240 tentative 319 thinking 335 529,534
agent, intentions of 539 examination of 321 uncreated 333 complete 124, 149, 497, 505,
aim, of reflection 300 untenable 463 belief 17, 256, 270, 288-292 528,529
algebra 184 astronomy, methods of approxi- and will 290 concomitant 501
allegory 553 mation in 321 foolish 289 determination of 498
alteration 47, 49, 101, 396, 500 attention 353, 354, 384, 385 historical 289 discovery of 497-518, 532
ambiguity, intentional 553 attributes 7, 10, 43, 57, 394, 428, immoral 289 instrumental 501
anatomy, comparative 531 497 in God 289 moral 501
anger 173 common 415-417, 421, 428, moral 289 partial 497, 503, 504, 529
angle 485 practical 257 physical 501
of sight 197 conflicting 406 reasonable 289 principal 501
trisection of 310 exclusive 422, 424 solid 289 proximal 510, 527
animals 157, 247 inner 11, 13, 18, 30, 33, 44 speculative 257 remote 527
whether they have concepts 92 outer 11 theoretical 289 similar 514
answer 300 authenticity 522 wavering 289 uncaused 254

394 395
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

certainty 114, 174, 260, 261, 263, cognitive faculties 6, 41, 136, 190, concepts (cont.) confusion of measures 468
264, 270, 272, 275, 280, 208, 228 logical 379 congruency 185
281,383,467,468 limits of 3, 232, 234, 238 lower 185 conscience 351
complete 279 cohesion 519, 520 mixed 101, 237 consciousness 26, 32, 34, 37, 38,
criteria of 381 colours, general concepts of 91 obscure 35, 36 48, 54, 96, 189, 209, 257,
degree of 113 common sense 339, 382 of reflection 222, 223 361
empirical 271 judgements of 337 produced analytically 97 distinct 449
indicators of 380 pronouncements of 336, 338, produced synthetically 97 indirect 35
moral 273 339, 381 pure 88, 90, 91, 99-101, 166, subject of 38
perfect 279, 286 common understanding 339 171, 185, 237, 408, 420, consequence 469, 570
rational 271 common usage 462, 544, 548 499,521,574 construction 182-184
change 7, 8 communication 194, 357, 362, of understanding 222 characteristic 184, 241
concept of 6 368, 373, 376, 555 redundant 408 geometrical 241
external 141 compatibility 451 sensible 185 of concepts 64, 181
inner 53 completeness 37 simple 20, 88, 91, 194, 401, 402 ostensive 241
characteristics 77 comprehension 260-262 origin of 85 symbolic 184, 241
common 94 concepts 6, 21, 22, 24, 66, 88, 159, singular 408 contemplation 237
charity 339 172, 180, 187,227,453,454 subjective 21 content 10
choice, of a rational being 302 a posteriori 101 vivid 61 contingency 111
Christianity 468, 474 a priori 101 concordance 411 continuum 252
circle, squaring the 344 absence of 208 concretum 7, 114, 427, 428, 433, contract 315
clarity 18, 34, 35, 37, 43-45, 353- analysis of 43, 94, 193 572 contradiction 223
356, 361 and images 184 conditions 148, 149, 254, 312, 503 explicit 567
degrees of 36 clear 34-36, 292 conduct tacit 567
logical 35 complex 91, 403 rules governing 294 contrariety 567
psychological 35 construction of 181, 193 confidence 114, 200, 201, 203, contrast, law of 63
classification, exact 446 distinct 43, 110 204, 215, 224, 245, 260, conviction 114, 280-282
clock 440 distinctly thought 110 263, 274, 275, 277, 278, moral 280
cognitions 3, 31, 38, 117, 189, equivalent 572 281, 286, 288, 289, 341, Cornutus 493
207, 230, 231, 233, 258- extensions of 34, 402 342,345,346, 395,459,463 counterexample 472
260, 264, 300 formation of 94 and probability 115, 287 counting 243
empirical 227 general39, 104,406,407 complete 279, 280 court 560
immediate 190, 193, 228 origin of 103 degree of 113, 213, 278, 283- creation 308, 332
mediate 260 higher 185 285, 461 creatures, prehistoric 569
ordinary 259 imaginary 24, 61, 424 ground of 27 5 credibility 568
origin of 171, 225 incorrect 207 levels of 275 crescens ratio 495
scientific 259, 261 innate 99, 100, 166 moral 280, 286 Critical Philosophy 95, 96, 178,
sensible 226 intermediate 441 perfect 279, 286 239, 245-248
cognitive ability 136 lack of 208 confirmation 457, 462 curvature, uniform 570

396 397
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

datum 316 doubt200, 212, 351, 352 errors (cont.) experience (cont.)
death 483, 484 Cartesian 349, 350 causes of 215 inner 257
deception 534, 550, 560, 564 grounds for 383 derivative 214 judgements of 115, 131, 134,
decision 291 momentary 353 explanation of 335 140, 279
deducibility 126, 127, 129, 130, doubtfulness 283, 459 formal 210, 221, 222 principles of 168
134, 136, 208, 211, 285, drawings 82 in purely conceptual sciences propositions of 381
287, 329, 342, 451, 452, dreams 296, 385 374 sensory 165
459, 461, 465, 466, 470, durations 483, 484 material 221 experiments 310, 338-340, 505,
471,474,496 infinite sequence of 491 origin of 212, 214, 215, 218, 506,529,575
deduction duty 256, 382, 391, 392, 396 224,263 confirmatory 338
perfect 287 original 214 exploratory 338
rule of 265 effects source of 213 random 338
definitions 36, 75, 97, 186, 193, discovery of 528-533 essence 7 explanation 518
194, 257,548 similar 514 eternity 238 expression 68, 69
geometrical 193 Electra 486 Euler circles 185 pure 72
too wide and too narrow 404 ellipse 572, 573 events 56, 58 extension 403
desiderata 397 empiricism 167 extraordinary 558 concept of 176
desire 137, 175, 198, 536 ends probability of 274 eye 160, 161, 519
determination of objects by ideas and means 524, 525 probable 274
436 God's 525 unusual 556 faculty 8
determinations 177, 407 morally bad 525 evidence 99 of desire 333
determining elements 571 morally good 525 evil 468, 521 of imagination 96
determinism 457 possible 524 examination 201, 319, 344, 346- of intuition 190
5to:(pwtc; 481 real 524 348, 350,352, 379 ofjudgement86, 137,222, 289
difference 242, 417-422, 425 Ennemoser's clairvoyant wife 233 of a given proposition 341 of reflection 23
discovery enumeration 241 of judgements 349, 350 faith 257
and invention 300n Epicureans 219 of one's own judgements 341 fancy, passing 201
chance 306 equality 14 of opinions 351 fantasy 121
disposition 53, 54, 99 equilibrium of floating bodies 307 exclusion 422, 446, 447 fear 386
distance 155, 157, 160, 164, 170, errors 3, 115, 134, 174, 188, 206- exercise in thinking 300, 341, 344, feeling 228, 257, 291
197 210, 213, 214, 216, 217, 347, 379,391, 393 fictions 66
distinctness 18, 37, 43-45 223, 225, 233, 264, 307, existence 10, 497 fidelity 339
aesthetic 45 336, 341,342,347,387,461 actual 406, 407 finitude 213
analytic 45 and attention 215 experience 99, 100, 115, 134, 166, fish, auditory organs of 531
degrees of 42 and haste 223 228, 237, 310, 334, 336, force 48, 142, 278, 332, 497, 499,
intensive and extensive 44 and the senses 219 406, 454-457, 511, 517, 500,513,519,520,524,526
synthetic 45 and the understanding 219 518, 524, 527, 528, 531, God's creative 497
disturbance 101 and will 216, 220 532, 538 forms of inference 472, 474, 476
double vision 164 caused by ambiguity 218 in narrow sense 334, 337 incorrect 473

398 399
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

freedom 246, 253, 256, 258 grounds (cont.) ideas 4, 174, 175, 188, 191, 198, ideas (cont.)
as indeterminacy 253, 254 mutually independent 461 207, 229, 248, 320, 353, contradictory 394
future 238 objective 126, 222, 230, 232, 393, 399,400,449,540 contrary 394
258, 259, 262, 281, 282, absence of I 05 coordinated 394
games of chance 272 abstract 19
455,462 derivative 90
ganglial system 199 abstracted 87, 96
of reason 172 differences between 421
general well-being 383
of recognition 232, 267, 270 acquired 91, 98, 99 distinct 34, 40-42, 106, 117,
genus 428
objective 232 analysis of 42, 97 361
geometer
subjective 232 and images 64, 378, 398 distinctness of 71
blind 64
partial 267, 497 and objects 60 duration of 48
paralytic 64
recognition of 229, 261, 352 and signs 217 effects of 51
geometry 170, 171, 187, 240, 243,
subjective 222, 281, 289, 290 and words 60 empirical 96
249
sufficient 149, 290, 291 appearance of 8 equal 12, 13, 15, 59
axioms of 134
trne 258 application of in judgements 31 equivalent 394, 40 I, 402, 404,
God 13, 23, 25, 44, 45, 63,
associated 77, 80, 86, 360, 363, 411, 412, 414, 427, 437,
79, 98, 100, 169, 218, 223,
399,416,427,434,449 448,548
226, 243, 246, 248, 254-
happiness 526, 536 association of 150, 157, 158, exclusive 326, 394, 414, 420,
256, 258, 264, 273, 281,
haste 385 215,216, 322 423,445
291, 340, 375, 391, 404,
heap 494, 495 cessation of 104 exhaustive and mutually exclu-
405, 501, 524, 526, 535,
536,538,551,552,554,557 hearing 164, 196 clarity of 30, 33, 405 sive 414
belief in 289 hearsay 568 clear 25-27, 29, 31, 32, 34, 35, extensions of 33, 394, 401, 404,
hermeneutics 553 37, 39-41, 46, 55, 61, 106, 409,410,419,426,428
concept of 61, 99, 408
existence of 332, 350 Heuristic 295, 331 116, 117, 375, 398 factitious 90
perfection of 468 highest moral law 217, 312, 329 coextensive 427 familiar I 07
grasping 369 history 335 collections of forgotten 53, 106
gravity, law of 154 homeopathy 478 contradictory 414 formation of 90
ground and consequence 56, 57, homogeneity 366 exclusive 414 general 88
127, 130, 230, 231, 240, human beings 13, 281 complementary 448 generic sensory 88
312, 329, 451, 459, 465, human race 540 complete 107 given 90
471,490,495 human understanding 239 complex 19, 20, 22, 28, 39-42, God's 11
recognition of 228 hydrochloric acid 252 44, 85, 87,371, 393,405 grasping of 6
grounds 226, 228-231, 248, 249, hyperbola 573 production of 87, 102 higher 571
254, 267, 290, 328, 332, hypothesis 224, 319, 322, 517- components of 43 human 45
333,405,454, 570 519 compound 90 ideas of 28, 38, 55
complete 497 simpler 518 concordant 410, 413 imaginary 406
correct 258 concrete 19, 406 immediate parts of 41
false 258 ideals 24, 25 confused 41, 44, 106 impossibility of 190
incorrect 258 Ideas 24, 25, 223, 227, 257 content of 33, 34, 41, 117, 394, impossible 189
inner 522 transcendental 25 404, 410 in themselves 5, 8

400 401
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

ideas (cont.) ideas (cont.) ideas (cont.) images (cont.)


indistinct 40, 41, 44 of sounds 88 spatial 181 general 66
infinitely complex 94 origin of 90, 96, 101 stimulated 59 poetic 66, 67
innate 91, 98, 99 original 90 stimulating 59 retinal 164
interchangeable 401 overlapping 394, 404, 413, 442, strength of 52 vivid 378
444 subjective 3, 5-107, 110 imagination 54, 65, 66, 121, 182,
intermediate 438, 439, 441
parts of 398 defining 449 187, 194, 561
intuited 398
perfectly distinct 42, 43 definition of 397 empirical 182
intuitions of 29-31, 40, 46, 55,
356,449 predicative 31 equal 14 feeble 216
invented 220 previous presence of 106 matter of 9, 14, 16-18, 31, overactive 216
lack of 105 real 405 108 productive 193
lacking 210 reawakening of 54 objects of 9 pure 182
law of association of 59, 62 recalling 50, 51 simple 39 imagining 54, 62
location of 159 recollection of 53, 55, 106 strength of 17, 18 imitation 82
vividness of 17, 18 immortality 189, 246, 256
logical attributes of 379 redundant 394, 401, 408, 409,
matter of 13, 39, 52, 54, 57, 59, 571 subordinate 412, 435, 442, 446, impact 153, 154
62 renewal of 54, 86 447 impatience 388
renewed 59, 62 superordinate 427, 429, 431 impenetrability 176
mixed 237
mutually exclusive 395, 418, repetition of 54 supersensible 24 impossibility 192, 193
temporal 181 impressions 53, 54, 131, 139, 296,
445,448 retention of 356
narrower 404, 410 revival of 54, 55 thought 5 297
objective 9, 12-14, 16-19, 31, secondary 60, 72, 360, 361, traces of 50, 52-54, 62, 106, inclination 54
39, 67, 96, 108, 400 365,373 119 incompatibility 331, 567
ultimate parts of 42 indeterminism 333, 498
simple 39 harmful 72
objectless 31, 93, 364, 409 seeking out 86 unconscious 34, 37-39 indication 543
objects of 5, 31, 32 unequal 12, 13 indicators 76, 80, 422
sensible 24
objectual 32, 66, 394, 403, 405- sensible general 93 vivid 51, 59, 86, 107, 356 induction 327
407, 409, 41l,437 vividness of 52, 99, 112, 216 method of 333
sequence of 56, 58
obscure 25, 26, 29, 32, 33, 35, signified 67 wider400,403,410 inertia 176
37, 46, 53, 55, 106, 116, similarities between 421 identity 14 force of 102
117, 354, 376, 377 simple 19-21, 41, 42, 44, 84, ignorance 206-210, 212, 215, 220 infallibility 245
obscurity of 30, 33 formal 209 inference, faculty of 123
90, 104, 371, 393, 398, 402,
material 209 inferences 123, 140, 190, 260,
of colours 88 405
ignoratio elenchi 469 317,342,452,459,460,469
of equal width 410 origin of 84
illusion 214, 223 based on analogy 530, 531
of hearing 173 simultaneity of 143
images 61, 65, 66, 107, 165, 185, forms of 461, 472, 474, 476
of light 196 simultaneous 15, 57, 60, 177,
197 incorrect 473
of odours 88 433
single 12, 14 accompanying 61 immediate 135
of propositions 69, 71, 108
singular 406, 407, 432 and concepts 184 invalid 471
of sight 173, 195

402 403
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

inferences (cont.) intuition (cont.) judgements 4, 17, 28, 29, 33, 38, judgements (cont.)
modes of 141, 212 pure 188 39, 45, 48, 51, 55, 57, 80, formation of 110
of probability 212, 225 rational 257 85, 87, 108-205, 214, 270, freestanding 201
perfect225, 230,231,258, 279 transcendental 257 274, 278-280, 283, 340- from experience 202
probabilistic 229, 230, 258, intuitions 6, 21-23, 28, 29, 37, 39, 343, 353, 360, 378,449 from obscure premises 201
279,518 40,42,46,47,54,64,66, 77, a posteriori 202 from pure concepts 202
probability of 455 84, 88, 91-96, 98-101, 104- a priori 181, 202 grounds of 123, 462
probable 381, 461, 521, 523, 106, 116, 131, 132, 139, abandonment of 119 hasty 201, 204
529 147-152, 158, 166, 169, about temporal relations 168 immediate 123, 125, 126, 130-
relative 470 171, 172, 175, 179, 181, absent 199 134, 140, 165, 212, 224,
rules of 127-130, 135, 212, 221, 185, 188, 190, 191, 193, analytic 115, 171, 178, 179, 225, 229, 231, 263, 265,
222,470,475 226, 240, 244, 246, 338, 239,240 270, 275, 278, 279, 281,
incorrect 463 359, 398, 420, 428, 431, based on authority 203 342,346,381
sequences of 354, 357, 381, 464 454,455 based on testimony 203 of perception 166, 173, 188,
variable ideas in 476 a priori 181, 188
certain 263, 270 220,227,281
infusoria 516 causes of 179, 180
clear 116, 119 origin of 13 8
inquiries, religious 337 empirical 178, 182, 187, 239 common of mankind 558 probability of 278
inquiry 319, 380, 387 external 85, 88, 104, 146, 172
complex 115 immediate parts of 117
critical 352 human, objects of 89
conceptual 115, 138, 165, 166 indistinct 117
insight 260 internal 85, 146
derivative 168 inferred 123
distinct 260 of colours 150
concluded 123 influence of will on 110
instinct 157, 167, 198, 519 of judgements 119
confidence in 4, 112, 113, 174, intuitional 115, 138, 165, 166
instructions 302 outer 196, 246
380,457 immediate 139
complete 302 pure 22, 90, 181, 182, 185-187,
confused 117 intuitions of 119, 121
correct 302 193, 194, 239-241, 245
constant adherence to 200 lacking 199
intentions 77, 80, 534, 541 sensory 170
constituents of 5 logical attributes of 379
discovery of 540 similar 146
content of 271 matter of 108, 109, 114
God's 536, 541 subjective 21
credible 335 mediated 131, 140, 165, 174,
investigation of 534 temporal reference in 89
deduced 231, 381 258, 275,276, 279, 346
of finite beings 538 traces of 120
intuitive faculty 22 degree of confidence in 113 origin of 168
recognition of 262
intuitiveness 99 degrees of distinctness of 117 mediation of 123-126, 136, 457
interaction 195
invention 224 derived 123, 212 morally certain 280
interpretation 543
distinct 117, 118 obscure 116
verbal 68 joy 173 duration of 112, 118 of common sense 337
intuition 18, 38, 184, 291
judgement 3, 15, 16, 21, 26, 27 empirical origin of 181 of experience 115, 131, 134,
absolute 257 and will 220, 305 equal 112 140, 168,214,230,279
ideal 257
philosophical postponement of examination of 345, 349, 350 origin of 194
in time 243 352 familiar 200 of memory 202
intellectual 257 suspension of 352 forced 201 of other beings 532-534

404 405
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

judgements (cont.) judgements (cont.) language, word- 83 m1thematics, mistakes in 245


of perception 131, 134 true 226, 232 law 301 matter 10, 49
immediate 131, 133, 134 origin of 225 formal 282 lifeless 247
pure 173 truth of 4, 258 of action and reaction 29 meaning 67
of probability 214, 224 unequal 112 of association of ideas 433 derivative 74
of sensation universal 179 of nature 253, 254 double 550, 553
pure 173 unmediated 123 of physics 575 higher 553
of temporal relations 141, 144, vivid 278 of simultaneity 216 original 75
194 vividness of 112, 113, 174 legend 568 secret 553
of the crowd 339 voluntary 201 Lewis Carroll's Paradox 128 means
of understanding 220 with sufficient grounds 270 liar 487, 488, 543 actual and alleged 525
origin of 123, 167, 211 judging 79 lie 559 and ends 524, 525
perceptual 229 light suitable 525
kinematics 492 and shadow 197
perfectly distinct 117 measures, confusion of 468
know 486, 487 cause of 499
practical 239 medicine 301
knowledge 27, 38, 115, 189, refraction of 329
previously formed 145, 199 Megatherion 569
190, 206-209, 257, 259- limit, concept of 404
probable 226 memory 50, 51, 53-56, 121, 122,
261, 288-291, 304 line 154
provisional 203 175, 198, 210, 214, 357,
distinct 259, 352 concept of 249
pure 202 376, 385
human 3, 293 curved 155
purely conceptual 132, 140, as source of errors 221
limits of 272, 335 straight 155-157
167,214, 279 faulty 220
immediate 261 locations 142
reawakening of 121 unfaithful 216
limits of 206, 239 logarithms 335
recalling 121, 122 mental organ 148, 161
mathematical 194 logic 3, 5, 36, 115, 239-241, 243,
relation of 25 mental phenomena 101, 143
mediate 261 294,377,452,478,553,558
reliability of 3, 342, 349 metaphysics 239, 248, 250, 497
origin of 166 pure general 240
renewal of 121 method 302
rational 165, 166
repeating 122 rules of 249
usefulness of 391 apagogical 322, 330-332
revival of 121 synthetic propositions in 240
artificial 319
secure 263 language 68, 79, 81, 90 loss 483
backwards 319
simple 115 conventional 83 lying 560, 564
combinatory 318
singular 179 flaws of 377 direct 318, 330-333
spatial 177 metaphorical use of 78 magnitude 157, 160
manner 303 indirect 319, 330
strength of 112, 278 metonymical use of 78
of doing something 302 inductive 330
synthetic 115, 178, 185, 236, of gestures 81, 82
Mars, inhabitants of 233 natural 318
239,240,247, 248,472 of imitation 82
materialism 466 progressive 318, 328, 329
a priori 178, 180, 181, 185 origin of 80, 84
mathematics 239, 240, 244, 248, regressive 328-330, 333
empirical 178 spoken 359
250 synthetic 318
origin of 180, 185 tropical use of 78, 79
universal 377 history of 246 microscope 515
traces of 119-121, 199

406 407
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
INDEX OF SUBJEC1's

mind 10, 12, 13, 15, 29, 31, 35, objects (cont.) opinions (cont.) phantasm 61
159, 161, 297 extended 252
miracles 375 general 336 phenomena
external 31, 62, 85, 94, 101, others' 335 internal 144
misunderstanding 68
104, 131, 133, 146, 148, opposite, mathematical 508 mental 10, 101, 143
mode of inference 141, 212
151, 158, 159, 166, 169, order simultaneous 144
moderation 315
170, 172, 195, 196, 200, law of 63 series of 145, 146
Molyneux 's problem 170
202, 297, 365, 523 simultaneous 194
moment 483 temporal 141
size of 164
Moon recognition of 142 philosophy, mechanical 49
non-existent 209 physics 239
inhabitants of 237
of reflection 300 law of 575
weight of 237 parabola 570
opposed 56, 58 pure 243
moral law 350 paradox, Lewis Cairnll's 128
outer47, 140, 173, 296 place 56, 58, 196
moral order 198 parallelogram of forces 3 15
intuitions of 50 change of 197
motion
perceptible 246, 365 parallels, axiom of 249
possibility of 490, 491 plane 155
powers of 147 part and whole 55, 186
relative 153 plants 247
purpose of 537 parts Platonists 219
uniform 153
recognition of 261 heterogeneous 252 points 247
motive 394
recognition of character of 261 homogeneous 252, 253 position 160, 164
movement 176, 196, 197, 403,
sensible 23, 24, 246, 247, 255, integral 252 possibility, concept of 402, 403
484,485
358,362,364 simple 253 post hoc ergo propter hoc 469, 524
multitude, infinite 7
signified 67 passing fancy 201 postulate
mutatio controversiae 469
similarities between 421, 428 passions 216, 244, 245, 339 of reason 256
nature 518 supersensible 24, 246, 250, 255, passivity 7 practical 291
law of 253, 254 257 pedantry 389 postulation
necessity 256, 271 unknown 236 perception 31, 37, 134, 166, 246, Kantian method of 382
consciousness of 188, 270 visible 160-161 297, 337, 338, 340, 455, practical 256
non sequitur 465, 467 obligation 497-499, 507,517,523,567 potash 252
non visum ergo non praesens 524 concept of 255 immediate 133, 187, 227, 522, power 8
nothing 399 moral 539 523 limits of a 232
novelty 549 obscurity 34, 46 immediate cause of 499, 500 of objects 147
number 240, 242, 243 degrees of 36 immediate judgements of 131 of judgement 108
numerals, Roman 371 deliberate 551 judgements of 131, 134 practical reason 256, 382
observation 339, 340, 529 visual 197 precepts 302
objective grounds 126, 136 observers 338 perceptual faculty 22 prejudice 201, 203, 204
objects 57 occurrence, unusual 557 pe1petuum mobile 323 premises, ineffable 257
acquaintance with 261 odours, general concepts of 91 persnicketiness 389 presentation, scientific 249, 294
actual 394, 396, 408 opinions 200, 204, 280, 289, 290 persuasion 114, 202, 204, 290 theory of 355
complex 40 erroneous 337 persuasion, self- 203, 204 presentiment 257
differences between 421 examination of 351 petitio principi 463 presuppositions, untenable 463

408 409
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
INDEX OF SUBJECTS

principle problems 300 proofs (cont.) propositions (cont.)


a priori 222 discovery of suitable 390, 393 geometrical 193 equivalent 450, 452, 467, 485
objective 223 main 310
incorrect 459 exclusive 395
of sufficient reason 226, 227, original 310
indicators of incorrectness of experiential 383
478 preliminary 310 460,471-478 extensions of 571
priority 144 reduction of 311, 314 intermediate propositions in forms of 450, 452
probability 114, 126, 128, 130, procedure 458 generalisation of 571, 572
137, 138, 146, 147, 153, analogical 328 leaps in 4 71 hypothetical 314
213, 215, 224, 263, 265, analytic 324 ideas of 108, 199
matter of 463, 469
266, 270, 271, 274, 275, inductive 327 identical 521, 547
power of conviction of 459, 471
282, 286, 323, 324, 326- methodical 302 premises of 458 inclination for or against 385
328, 337, 343, 347, 348, regressive 324 presuppositions of 458, 459 incompatible 452, 467
380, 383, 390, 391, 451, resolving 324 redundant 4 71 intuitional 115, 226, 457
459, 461, 467, 468, 512, product 242 simple 458 morally certain 268
513, 516-519, 521, 523, production, authentic 520 tenable 459 mutually exclusive 452
541,559,561, 566,567 progression, geometrical 491 that prove too much 474, 475 objective 109, 112
absolute 268, 269, 273, 276, promise-keeping 339 too wide 477 overlapping 452
277, 286 proofs 186, 257, 329, 351, 460- true 459 practical 3 12
and confidence 115, 287 462, 464, 467, 471 unsuccessful 462 probability of 114, 27 6, 277,
complete 268 appropriate 458 untenable 459, 473 283
complex 273 assumptions of 458, 470 properties 11 probable 115, 214, 219, 267
degree of 278, 285 backwards 464 proportion 434-435 proof of 395, 457
dynamic 273 binding 459 propositions 188, 199, 271, 274, purely conceptual 456, 457
grounds of 267 by experience 478 279 reliable 268
kinds of 272 by incomplete induction 467 analysis of 496 self-contradictory 489
known 286 circular 465 analytic 115, 178, 186, 395, simple 115
logical 274 complex 458 450,451,454, 547 subordinate 451, 452, 466, 467
mathematical 273 conclusions of 458 in logic 244 synthetic 115, 183, 241, 395,
objective 267, 272 convincing 459 certain 268 450,451
conect 459 certainty of 276 purely conceptual 240
philosophical 273
efficacious 458 compatible 395, 467 theoretical 312
real 274
examination of 521 complex 115 transcendent 456
recognised 266, 267
false 459 conceptual 115, 226, 289 transcendental 456
relative 268, 273, 277
flaws of 462 contradictory 452, 468 trustworthy 268, 269
simple 273
force of conviction of 462 contrary 452, 468 ~suooµsvoc; 487
subjective 267, 272
form of 463, 469, 470 converses of 572 psychology 62
unknown 286
from experience 458, 469 credibility of 565 purposes 499
unrecognised 266 from pure concepts 458 degree of approval of 113 purposes, God's 557
probability calculus 518 gaps in 471 empirical 202, 289, 454-456 Pythagorean theorem 541

410 411
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

qmesitum 316 reflection, speculative 301 scepticism, Cartesian 352 senses (cont.)
qualities, occult 521 refraction of light 329 sceptics 239, 248, 349 inner 191
quantity 240, 242 reguli falsi 321 schemata 61, 64, 66, 182, 183, 185 literal 554
general theory of 241 relations 11, 33, 44 and images 65 multiple 553
questions 177, 300, 305, 307 spatial 142, 148, 151, 152, 154- science 70, 261, 268, 293-294, secret 554
catalogues of 397 157, 170, 177, 511, 513 300 sensibility 22, 168, 176, 190, 222
main 310 knowledge of 169 analytic 241 sensory organs 158
original 310 recognition of 195 empirical 335, 340 sentiment 291
preliminary 310, 314, 315 temporal 142, 177, 511, 513 purely conceptual separation 87
unanswerable 309 judgements of 144 e1rnrs in 374 sequence
quotient 242 reliability 114, 346, 34 7 theoretical 239, 240 infinite 7, 250, 251, 254
religion 467 theory of 293 in time 251
reading 68
natural 474 written presentation of 3 of conditions 254
realisation 261, 262
renewal, law of 59 scientific exposition 4 infinite past 250
reason 111, 168, 190, 223, 226-
representation 37, 47, 175, 247 script, alphabetic 370 temporal 195, 403
228, 257, 333, 336, 337,
exclusive 425 scrupulousness 389 beginning of 255
535, 540
powers of 323 seeming 163 shape 157
human 250
reproduction 198 self 38, 173 sight 155-157, 160, 162, 196
infallibility of 339
resistance 17 5, 17 6, 196 idea of 176 angle of 197
postulate of 256
resolution 254, 333, 527, 538, 539 self-consciousness 188-191 signification 67
practical 256, 382
result, accidental 542 pure 37 derivative and original 70
pure, antinomies of 135
retina 160-162 self-deception 216 signs 67, 74-77, 81, 82, 84, 165,
receptivity 198, 199
revelation 257, 335 self-persuasion 203, 204, 290, 386 355, 356, 358-365, 367,
recognition 207
Christian 474 self-preservation 101, 198 368, 373-375,464
grounds of 267, 270
recollection 299 divine 218, 375, 391, 464, 468, acts of 102 ambiguous 70, 217, 374
power of 122 554, 557 sensation 173-17 5 and ideas 372
reduction to absurdity 322 indicators of 558 generic ideas of 88 and mathematics 372
reflection 3, 98, 228, 295-297, risk, magnitude of 269 sensations 150, 152, 156, J60, and thinking 79, 80
306, 307, 310, 334-336, Roman numerals 371 171, 191, 197, 198, 229, as cause of error 217
347, 352-354, 358, 375, round square, idea of 9 466, 540 audible 69, 369-372
378, 383-386, 388, 390, rules 302 location of 159 benefits of 357
392, 397,428,449,453 governing conduct 294 tactile 156 complex 70, 78
aim of 300 of inference 127-130, 135, 212, sense illusions 223 contingent 68, 77
concepts of 222, 223 221,222,463,470,475 senses 67, 260 conventional 68, 77, 78
in search of truth 299, 302, 305, ofthought282,289,290 borrowed 71 direct 73
340 rumour 568 common 339 distinctness of 71
object of 300 extended 71 n figurative use of 72
pure 297-300, 320, 334, 355, sadness 173 higher 554 for our own reflection 367
437 saltpetre 252 improper 71 for simple ideas 366, 371

412 413
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

signs (cont.) solid 157 speaking 67 surmise 280, 282


imagining 359 concept of 249 to oneself 7 4 s_vllogismus crocodilinus 490
impure 72 solidity 152, 176 speech syllogistic, rules of 240
in metaphysics 242 solution 300 God's 552 symbols 75
incomprehensible 71 something 32, 426 interpretation of 551, 554 in mathematics 242
indeterminate 70 somnambulism 198 sphere 155, 252 used in logic 185
indirect 73 sophisma non causae ut causae spiral, logarithmic 569, 570 used in metaphysics 185
interpretation of 68, 362, 542- 469 spontaneity 198, 199 synthesis 85, 183
555 sophisma pig rum 492 squaring the circle 344 successive 250, 251
invention of 367 sophisms 479 state lOn o0v0rnv:;, fallacy 479
meanings of 262, 369 sorites 186, 187 subordination 439
metaphorical use of 72, 375 sorites inexplicabilis 494 substances 10, 11, 23, 45, 47, 49, tabula rasa 99
metonymic use of 72 soul 6, 17, 20-23, 25, 30, 35, 37, 172,251,255,456,497 taste 164
natural 68, 77, 78, 544 39, 47-54, 57-60, 64, 80, collections of 23, 46, 172 tautology 236, 547
proper signification of 71 86, 87, 93, 95, 98-101, 104, infinite 255 telescope, achromatic 77
purity of 360, 366 105, 109, 110, 118, 119, concept of 171 temporal relations 177
similar 217 122, 139, 140, 171, 189, finite 7, 46, 48, 172, 324, 487 temporal sequences, internal 142
simple 544 191, 197, 198, 213, 220, collections of 246 testimony 203-205, 257, 335, 456,
single 69, 78 246, 247, 255, 297, 320, inner changes in 49 555,558,559, 565,568
symbolic use of 72 353, 354, 383, 454, 455, levels of existence of 323 appeal to 478
systems of 543 523, 540 material 93 credibility of 559
flaws of 377 immortality of 258, 317, 350, neighbouring 247 divine 554
thinking with 376 391 qualities of 7 God's 556
universally accepted 68 pre-sensory 198 simple 6, 247, 248, 255, 318 mediate 562
use of 367 simplicity of 93, 102, 103 subsumption theology 558
vacillating 70 sound, propagation of 506 adequate 436 theory of science 293
visible 69 sounds 83, 84, 362 exact 436, 445 things
written 357, 370-372 general concepts of 91 succession, law of 63, 64 actual 10, 100
similarity 56, 415, 417, 421, 428, space 95, 172, 192, 193, 195, 196, sufficient reason, principle of 226, existing 428
531,571 239,242, 243, 247, 251 227,478 homogeneous 333
between sign and object 365 concept of 249 sum 242, 421 in themselves 472
law of 63 origin of 177 concept of 186 things, supersensible 222
simplicity 366 empty 177 sun, eclipses of 501 thinking and signs 79, 80
simultaneity 195, 427 idea of 197 surface 176 this 22
law of 61-63, 92, 216 intuition of 241, 242 concept of 249 thought, rules of 282, 289, 290
relations of 142 properties of 171 curved 155 thoughts 79, 466
sleep 37 spatial relations 148, 151, 152, cylindrical 156 and symbols 74
smell 164 154-157, 170, 177 plane 155, 156 communication of 368
social intercourse 90 recognition of 195 spherical 156, 253 preservation of 361, 362, 364

414 415
INDEX OF SUBJECTS INDEX OF SUBJECTS

time 95, 239, 242, 247 truth (cont.) vision 160-164 witnesses 560, 562
concept of 250 objective 135 double 164 credibility of 559-569
origin of 177 of experience 281 vividness 37, 44, 45, 49, 50, 321, honest 564
directions in 251 of reason 227 353, 360,361 sincere 564
intuition of 241, 242 power of 337 volition 302 veracious 564
measurement of 142 practical 312 words20,70,77, 362, 370
Topic 295 purely conceptual 99, 190, 209, way 303 proper signification of 79
touch 152, 154, 156, 157, 161, 230, 237, 258, 271, 335, of doing something 302 single 70
164, 169, 196, 197 403, 406, 453, 454, 478, of life 303 work
sense of 170 520,575 which 333 spurious 520, 522
traces 198 discovery of 497 whole and part 55, 186 adulterated 520
of judgements 199 recognition of 229, 230, 294, will 137, 147, 148, 150, 175, 176, world 25, 254, 255
tradition, adherence to 389 300, 300n, 307, 385, 391 253, 254, 296, 297, 525- age of 308
transparency 509 utility of 390 527, 534 concept of 111
treatise 293 recognition of grounds of 260 free act of 498 external 174, 194
trisection of the angle 310 semblance of 222 God's 537, 542, 558 consciousness of 385
tropical mode of speech 72 sense for 259 human 333 material 168
trustworthiness 273 similar 314 wish 137, 144, 175, 291, 385 sensible 255
degrees of 269 speculative 301
truth 3, 206, 209, 222, 304 synthetic 240
basic 133, 230, 402, 495
cause of recognition of 231
criteria of 381
u &vna-cpscp6Jv 488
unconscious 257
discovery of 293, 300, 329, 330,
understanding 22, 68, 190, 222,
341, 344, 357,397,569
226-228, 262, 369
empirical 271, 453
common 339
established 518
pure concepts of 64
ground of 496
units 243
formal 209
unity 403
given 316
universe 223
grounds of 228, 231, 288, 396,
453
in itself 9 vacillation 201
independent 402 vector 573
innate 166 Venus, inhabitants of 233
intuitional 209 veracity 567
material 209 verb 484
metaphysical 249 virtue 350
moral 391 vis viva 245

416 417

You might also like