You are on page 1of 3

Peter D. Fenves. The Messianic Reduction: Walter Benjamin and the Shape of Time.

Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2011. 336 pp. $65.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-8047-5787-4; $24.95 (paper),
ISBN 978-0-8047-5788-1.

Reviewed by Paula Schwebel (Universiteit Antwerpen)


Published on H-Judaic (August, 2012)
Commissioned by Jason Kalman

Walter Benjamin’s Reduction of Mythology and the Messianic as “Total Neutrality”

Peter Fenves’s recent book is a welcome addition Husserl’s notion of eidetic intuition lacks a “historical in-
to Benjamin scholarship for several reasons: First, it dex.”[3] Yet, Fenves’s discussion of “temporal plasticity”
is an expert work of historical excavation, unearthing and the “shape of time” (chapters 1 and 4) anticipates
a wealth of detail about Benjamin’s intellectual forma- some aspects of Benjamin’s late philosophy of history,
tion during his student years (1913-25). Second, Fenves as Fenves suggests in the conclusion (pp. 242-244).
presents a nuanced history of ideas, situating Benjamin’s
Fenves’s argument does not intend to provide an ex-
early work at a crossroads between two major schools
haustive account of Benjamin’s references to Husserl,
of German philosophy in the interwar period–namely,
Husserlian phenomenology and Marburg School neo- or his relationship to phenomenology more generally.
Kantianism (i.e., Hermann Cohen and Ernst Cassirer). Rather, under the titular designation of the “messianic
Third, Fenves offers a “systematic” interpretation of Ben- reduction,” Fenves explores a specific point where Ben-
jamin diverges from Husserl. According to Fenves, Ben-
jamin’s early, mostly fragmentary, work, demonstrating
jamin does not reject the task of reducing the “natu-
how Benjamin navigated between Husserl and the Mar-
ral attitude”–an attitude that Fenves describes as the
burg School to develop his own philosophical position (p.
16). “mythological” belief that experience results from the
causal interaction between substantial things and a con-
Benjamin’s relationship to neo-Kantianism has else- scious subject (p. 165). What Benjamin does dispute, in
where been more fully explored, but Fenves’s sugges- Fenves’s view, is the intentional character of Husserl’s
tion that Benjamin was critically engaged with Husserl reduction: it is not within a subject’s power to “turn off”
breaks new ground.[1] In light of the evidence gathered the natural attitude. If such a reduction can be accom-
by Fenves, Benjamin’s engagement with phenomenology plished, it is referred to a “higher power”–an idea that
can no longer be ignored. In the preface to the Origin of Fenves interprets in the mathematical terms of transfi-
the German Mourning Play (a text written in 1925 that nite set theory, rather than in theological terms.
represents the culmination of the period under discus-
sion in Fenves’s book), Benjamin challenges two pillars Fenves argues that Benjamin fashioned various per-
of Husserl’s philosophy, arguing against the intentional spectives from which the methodological priority of tran-
scendental consciousness could be “turned off,” such as “a
character of consciousness, and rejecting the method of
child’s view of color,” the “coloration of shame,” and “the
eidetic intuition.[2] Because Fenves restricts his analy-
sis to Benjamin’s early work, he does not address Ben- colors of fantasy” (chapters 2 and 3). Notably, these per-
jamin’s contention, in the Arcades Project (1927-40), that spectives cannot be willfully adopted by a subject. Col-

1
H-Net Reviews

ors, as seen by a child, are not defined by an interest in This unity corresponds to a “sphere of total neutrality,” in
the existence of things, or the judgment of inherence in which both the subjective and the objective poles of the
an underlying substance (p. 63). Hence, Fenves argues natural attitude have been reduced (p. 172).
that the child’s view of color guarantees the existence of
a fully reduced world, or an attitude of pure receptivity Presumably, such a “sphere of total neutrality” would
to the phenomena (p. 3). But a guarantee of existence correspond neither to an attitude of pure receptivity to
phenomena, nor to their pure “functional” generation,
is not a method; the child’s view of color, like childhood
raising the question of how this sphere enters into re-
itself, is “evanescent,” and therefore cannot be intended
or universalized (pp. 64-65). lation with the phenomenal world of possible experi-
ence. The answer to this question has high stakes, since
Fenves maintains that Benjamin shares Husserl’s Fenves suggests that the relationship is, at least struc-
ideal of a fully reduced world, and that Benjamin can thus turally, equivalent to the relationship between the pro-
be regarded as a phenomenological thinker. The goal of fane world and the “messianic.” Fenves’s answer is pri-
the reduction, in Fenves’s account, is to attain an attitude marily negative, indicating that this sphere of total neu-
of “pure receptivity” to the phenomena, “without distor- trality cannot be anticipated or foreseen. But Fenves also
tions that result from theoretical presuppositions” (p. 3). employs certain mathematical models to think about the
But Fenves’s claim that Benjamin sought an attitude of “shape” that the messianic reduction might take. While
“pure receptivity” sits uneasily with his characterization it is not inconceivable that a mathematical model could
of Benjamin as an adherent to certain tenets of the Mar- leave “open-ended” what cannot be anticipated or fore-
burg School, since the explicit goal of the latter was to seen (p. 3)–and Fenves provides the example of a curve
eliminate any residue of receptivity to a given “thing in that has no tangents (pp. 239-244)–it seems that his neg-
itself,” instead generating objective knowledge from the ative argument is threatened to the extent that he suc-
spontaneous activity of pure thinking. ceeds in mathematically representing what, according to
his own argument, is unrepresentable.
Fenves finds the link between Husserl and the Mar-
burg School in their common anti-psychologism (p. 227). Although Fenves does not explicitly state as much,
But the tension between pure receptivity and the pure the unity of his argument seems to revolve around an at-
generation of knowledge runs throughout Fenves’s book tempt to think through the meaning of Hölderlin’s no-
without being fully resolved. In contrast to chapters 2 tion of “holy sobriety,” which was also a key idea for
and 3, where Fenves reads Benjamin’s 1915-16 studies on Benjamin (pp. 38; 45; 77). Sobriety receives various for-
color as aiming towards an ideal of pure receptivity, in mulations in Fenves’s argument, from a pure receptiv-
chapter 1, Fenves shows the influence of Cassirer’s “func- ity that is “untouched” by objects (p. 49), to the afore-
tional” generation of reality on Benjamin’s 1915 essay, mentioned “sphere of total neutrality,” corresponding to
“Two poems by Friedrich Hölderlin.” Fenves notes that a fully reduced world. Such sobriety is “holy,” accord-
this tension between Husserlian phenomenology and the ing to Fenves, because it coincides with the elimination
Marburg School shaped not only Benjamin’s early philos- of mythology (p. 175). With this notion of sobriety, we
ophy, but also much of German philosophy during the also find the underlying link to Fenves’s argument about
first part of the twentieth century (p. 6). It is to Fenves’s the “shape of time.” Fenves amplifies the idea of a curve
credit that he traces these dizzying oscillations in Ben- without tangents to include a broader interpretation of
jamin’s work, without imposing a simplifying schema. the “untouched”: tangentless, the temporal curve is also
“inviolable,” and thus “innocent” (p. 241).
Ultimately (in chapter 6), Fenves argues that Ben-
jamin “declines” to follow either Husserl or Cohen (p. Fenves’s “messianic reduction” runs the risk of re-
167). Whereas Husserl replaces the subject-object model ducing not only the natural attitude, but also anything
of experience with a primordial “stream of conscious- resembling the critical capacity of a subject. In the first
ness,” and Cohen replaces transcendental subjectivity place, Fenves suggests that Benjamin upholds an ideal of
with the “fact of science,” Benjamin seeks to ground pure receptivity, but if the goal is simply to receive what
a new concept of experience in a “ ‘pure epistemo- is given, then any attempt to change the world is deemed
theoretical (transcendental) consciousness,’ which no impure. Pure givenness is regarded as untouchable, and
one can claim as his or her own” (p. 167). Fenves parses this untouchability is sanctified as an “innocent” world.
this complicated idea by describing it as a unity that is As a consequence, the political charge of Benjamin’s
“higher” than the transcendental unity of apperception. messianism is neutralized. Moreover, Fenves’s appeal

2
H-Net Reviews

to a mathematical “higher power” yields to an author- etition of the same few passages, Fenves’s introduction
ity that is untouchable in yet another sense. As Ben- and analysis of this new material makes an exciting con-
jamin argues in the preface to the Origin of the German tribution to Benjamin scholarship, while preparing the
Mourning Play, the inevitability and necessity of math- ground for further study of Benjamin’s relationship to
ematical proof is “coercive.”[4] Fenves’s invocation of a phenomenology.
mathematical “higher power”–in the name of reducing
Notes
the “myth” of the psychological consciousness–may yield
to the mystification of mathematical truth. [1]. See, for example, Astrid Deuber-Mankowsky,
Der frühe Walter Benjamin und Hermann Cohen. Jüdis-
Notwithstanding the density and difficulties of
Fenves’s argument, this book performs a great service to che Werte. Kritische Philosophie, vergängliche Erfahrung
scholars of Benjamin, interwar German philosophy, and (Berlin: Verlag Vorwerk 8, 2000).
German-Jewish thought. One of the book’s greatest as- [2]. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften, ed.
sets is its inclusion, in an appendix, of Fenves’s original Rolf Tiedemann and Hermann Schweppenhäuser, 7 vols.
translations of two short texts of Benjamin’s from 1915 (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1972-91), v. 1: 215-16.
or 1916 (“The Rainbow: Dialogue on Fantasy” and “The
Rainbow; or, The Art of Paradise”), as well as a remark- [3]. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften, v. 5:
able document, attributed to Benjamin and recorded in 577.
Gershom Scholem’s diary of 1916 (“Notes toward a work [4]. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften, v. 1:
on the category of justice”), which Fenves interprets in 208.
chapter 7. In a field that is often moribund due to the rep-

If there is additional discussion of this review, you may access it through the network, at:
https://networks.h-net.org/h-judaic

Citation: Paula Schwebel. Review of Fenves, Peter D., The Messianic Reduction: Walter Benjamin and the Shape of
Time. H-Judaic, H-Net Reviews. August, 2012.
URL: http://www.h-net.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=34907

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-


No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License.

You might also like