You are on page 1of 2

To be is to be: Jean-Paul Sartre on against capitalism and were establishing a

existentialism and freedom communist state in their respective countries.

"Being is. Being is in-itself. Being is what it “We do not know what we want and yet we
is." are responsible for what we are — that is the
fact.”

Jean-Paul Charles Aymard Sartre is one of the


most important philosophers of all time. Ultimately, Sartre was a humanist who wanted
Despite his work garnering considerable flak us to break free of our self-fastened shackles
over the years, his theories on existentialism and attain our massive potential. He wanted
and freedom cement his place among the most us to acknowledge our freedom, to not be
influential Western philosophers of the 20th- restricted by the popular definition of reality,
century and beyond. and live life as we wished to live it. And
despite people uncovering several flaws in the
way he presented his ideals, his ideals
The anguish of freedom themselves are certainly worth considering.
"Man is condemned to be free; because once
thrown into the world, he is responsible for
everything he does." ________________________________

Jean-Paul Sartre believed that human beings Freedom


live in constant anguish, not solely because
life is miserable, but because we are
'condemned to be free'. While the The concept of freedom, central to Sartre’s
circumstances of our birth and upbringing are system as a whole, is a dominant theme in his
beyond our control, he reasons that once we political works. Sartre’s view of freedom
become self-aware (and we all do eventually), changed substantially throughout his lifetime.
we have to make choices — choices that Scholars disagree whether there is a
define our very 'essence'. Sartre's theory fundamental continuity or a radical break
of existentialism states that “existence between Sartre’s early view of freedom and
precedes essence”, that is only by existing and his late view of freedom. There is a strong
acting a certain way do we give meaning to consensus, though, that after World War II
our lives. According to him, there is no fixed Sartre shifted to a material view of freedom,
design for how a human being should be and in contrast to the ontological view of his early
no God to give us a purpose. Therefore, the period. According to the arguments of Being
onus for defining ourselves, and by extension and Nothingness human freedom consists in
humanity, falls squarely on our shoulders. the ability of consciousness to transcend its
This lack of pre-defined purpose along with material situation (p. 563). Later, especially
an 'absurd' existence that presents to us in Critique of Dialectical Reason, Sartre shifts
infinite choices is what Sartre attributes to the to the view that humans are only free if their
“anguish of freedom”. With nothing to restrict basic needs as practical organisms are met (p.
us, we have the choice to take actions to 327). Let us look at these two different
become who we want to be and lead the life notions of freedom in more depth.
we want to live. According to Sartre, each
choice we make defines us while at the same
time revealing to us what we think a human Early Sartre views freedom as synonymous
being should be. And this incredible burden of with human consciousness. Consciousness
responsibility that the free man has to bear is (“being-for-itself”) is marked by its non-
what relegates him to constant anguish. coincidence with itself. In simple terms,
consciousness escapes itself both because it is
intentional (consciousness always targets an
Living in bad faith object other than itself) and temporal
"Everything has been figured out, except (consciousness is necessarily future oriented)
how to live." (Being and Nothingness, pp. 573-4 and 568).
Sartre’s view that human freedom consists in
consciousness’ ability to escape the present is
Jean-Paul Sartre decried the idea of living “ontological” in the sense that no normal
without pursuing freedom. The phenomenon human being can fail to be free. The subtitle
of people accepting that things have to be a of Being and Nothingness, “An Essay in
certain way, and subsequently refusing to Phenomenological Ontology,” reveals Sartre’s
acknowledge or pursue alternate options, was aim of describing the fundamental structures
what he termed as "living in bad faith". of human existence and answering the
According to Sartre, people who convince question “What does it mean to be human?”
themselves that they have to do one particular His answer is that humans, unlike inert
kind of work or live in one particular city are matter, are conscious and therefore free.
living in bad faith. In Being and Nothingness,
Sartre's renown discourse on
phenomenological ontology, he explains the The notion of ontological freedom is
concept of bad faith through the example of a controversial and has often been rejected
waiter who is so immersed in his job that he because it implies that humans are free in all
considers himself to be first a waiter rather situations. In his early work Sartre embraced
than a free human being. This waiter is so this implication unflinchingly. Famously,
convinced that his present job is all that he Sartre claimed the French public was as free
can do, that it's all that he's meant to do, that as ever during the Nazi occupation. In Being
he never considers the option of doing and Nothingness, he passionately argued that
anything else in life. Sartre believed that we even prisoners are free because they have the
alone are responsible for everything that we power of consciousness (p. 622). A prisoner,
really are, and by not exploring the myriad though coerced, can choose how to react to
possibilities life presents to us we alone are his imprisonment. The prisoner is free
responsible for restricting our freedom. "We because he controls his reaction to
are left alone without an excuse, " he said. imprisonment: he may resist or acquiesce.
Since there are no objective barriers to the
will, the prison bars restrain me only if I form
Rage against the machine the will to escape. In a similar example, Sartre
notes that a mountain is only a barrier if the
individual wants to get on the other side but
An ardent believer in the Marxist school of cannot (Being and Nothingness, p. 628).
thought, Jean-Paul Sartre touted money as the
one factor that restricts a person's freedom.
The need of money, he reasoned, is the excuse Sartre’s ontological notion of freedom has
people give themselves when the y shut down been widely criticized, from both political and
the idea of exploring unconventional life ontological standpoints. An important
choices. Society's acquiescence of money contemporary critic of Sartre’s work was his
infuriated Sartre and capitalism was the colleague Maurice Merleau-Ponty, whose
political system he blamed for the essay “Sartre and Ultrabolshevism” directly
phenomenon. He likened capitalism to a attacked Sartre’s Cartesianism and his
machine that traps people in a cycle of ontological conception of freedom (Merleau-
working in jobs they don't like so that they Ponty, Adventures of the Dialectic, 1955).
can buy things they don't need. This necessity
of material things, he argued, did not exist in
reality but rather was a man-made construct While Sartre never renounced the ontological
that led people to deny their freedom and view of freedom, in later works he became
consider living in other ways as foolhardy. critical of what he then called the “stoical”
Sartre was a vocal opponent of capitalism and and “Cartesian” view that freedom consists in
took part in several Parisian protests in the ability to change one’s attitude no matter
1968 against the system. As a Marxist, he what the situation (Notebooks, pp. 331 and
greatly admired Fidel Castro and Che 387; Critique, pp. 332 and 578 fn). It is an
Guevara, both of whom were vehemently open question whether and how to reconcile
the early, ontological conception of freedom
with the late, material conception of freedom. because he is dominated by a master
However, it is undeniable that in his political (Notebooks pp. 325-411). Material freedom
phase Sartre adopted a new, material view of requires, therefore, non-domination, or
freedom. Several points stand out in freedom from coercion. He adds that in
particular. In later works he never again used master/slave relations, t he self-conception of
the notion of consciousness to characterize the victim and perpetrator are intertwined and
human existence, preferring instead the distorted; both parties are in “bad faith”; both
Marxist notion of praxis. Further, he came to fail to fully understand their own freedom.
emphasize the “situation” (i.e. structural Though both perpetrator and victim are in bad
influences) in explaining individual choice faith, only the slave is coerced physically
and psychology (Anti-Semite and Jew, pp. 59- (Notebooks, p. 331).
60). Finally, he criticized all “inward” notions
of freedom, claiming that a change of attitude
is insufficient for real freedom. Sartre’s view of material freedom is
independent of any notion of human nature.
He consistently rejects the existence of a pre-
Sartre’s shift to a material conception of social human essence or a set of natural
freedom was motivated directly by the human desires (“Existentialism is a
holocaust and World War II. Anti-Semite and Humanism”; Anti-Semite and Jew, p.
Jew (Réflexions sur la question juive, 1946), 49; Search for a Method, pp. 167-181). The
published just after the war, was the first of material view of freedom assumes a thin set
many works analyzing moral responsibility of universal human goods, including positive
for oppression. The fact that Sartre’s view human goods (food, water, shelter and
in Being and Nothingness seemed to leave education) and negative goods (freedom from
little room for diagnosing oppression did not all of the following: slavery, poverty,
stop him from articulating a forceful discrimination, domination and persecution).
normative critique of Anti-Semitism. His While Critique elaborates an economic
analysis of oppression would, in fact, use the understanding of human goods (the essential
same dialectical tools as those in the section needs are those of the physical organism),
on “concrete relations with others” in Being elsewhere Sartre defends a wider spectrum of
and Nothingness. Anti-Semite and Jew argues human needs including cultural goods and
that oppression is a master/slave relationship, access to shared values ( Notebooks pp. 329-
where the master denies the freedom of the 331). In sum, we can say that a person is
slave and yet becomes dependent on the slave materially free in Sartre’s sense if (a) she
(pp. 27, 39 and 135). Sartre modified his enjoys basic material security; (b) she is un-
notion of “the look” by arguing that only coerced; and (c) she has access to cultural and
some, not all, interpersonal relations result in social goods necessary for pursuing her
alienation and loss of freedom. chosen projects.

Sartre’s new appreciation of oppression as a The foregoing definition casts Sartre as an


concrete loss of human freedom forced him to ally of political liberalism, and suggests that
alter his view that humans are free in any material freedom is a version of liberal
situation. He did not explicitly discuss such autonomy. Liberals who defend the primacy
alterations, though clearly abandoning the of autonomy typically claim that positive
view that humans are free in all situations. notions of freedom assume substantive,
“[I]t is important not to conclude that one can controversial conceptions of the good life.
be free in chains,” and “It would be quite Indeed, Sartre’s rejection of human nature and
wrong to interpret me as saying that man is his thin conception of universal human goods
free in all situations as the Stoics claimed” are consistent with liberalism. However,
(Critique, pp. 578 and 332). Sartre’s basic Sartre criticizes classical liberalism,
assumption in his political writings is that especially in Critique, arguing against asocial,
oppression is a loss of freedom ( Critique, p. atomistic notions of selfhood (p. 311).
332). Since humans can never lose their Further, like civic republican philosophers
ontological freedom, the loss of freedom in (such as Aristotle and Rousseau), Sartre
question must be of a different sort: contends that controlling the social forces to
oppression must which one is subject is a valuable type of
compromise material freedom. human freedom. Republican philosophers
variously call such freedom “self-
government” or “non-domination.” Whether
Take the case of the prisoner. The prisoner is Sartre’s view of freedom is a better fit with
ontologically free because she controls contemporary liberalism or civic
whether to attempt escape. On this view, republicanism is a matter of speculation.
freedom is synonymous with choice. But there Sartre’s discussion of freedom in Critique is
is no qualitative distinction between types of highly abstract and does not translate simply
choices. If freedom is the existence of choice, into one public policy or another. However,
then even a bad choice is freedom promoting. his preference for mass movements and
As he will put it later, an attacker who gives bottom-up social organization suggest that he
me the choice of “what sauce to be eaten in” would favor radical participatory democracy.
could hardly be said to meaningfully promote After the student re volts of May 1968 Sartre
my freedom (Notebooks, p. 331). The early told an interviewer: “For me the movement in
view is subject to the charge that if there are May was the first large-scale social movement
no qualitative distinctions between types of which temporarily brought about something
choices, then the phenomena of oppression akin to freedom and which then tried to
and coercion cannot be recognized. conceive of what freedom in action is”
(Life/Situations, p. 52).

In Anti-Semite and Jew and Notebooks Sartre


implicitly addresses the abo ve criticism,
arguing that oppression consists not in the
absence of choice, but in being forced to
choose between bad, inhumane options
(Notebooks, pp. 334-5). Jews in anti-Semitic
societies, for example, are forced to choose
between self-effacement or caricatured self-
identities (Anti-Semite and Jew, pp. 135 and
148). In Critique Sartre uses the example of a
labor contract to illustrate the claim that
choice is not synonymous with freedom
(Critique, pp. 721-2). An impoverished person
who accepts a degrading, low wage job for the
sake of meeting her basic needs has a
choice—she may starve or accept a degrading
job—but her choice is inhumane. He does not
claim that diffuse social structures like
poverty have the literal agency of individual
human beings, but that class structure is a
“destiny” and we can speak cogently of social
forces which exert causality and turn us into
“slaves” (Critique, p. 332).

In the political period as a whole Sartre


developed his material view of freedom by
contrasting the free person with the slave.
Though his notion of slavery is derived from
Hegel, Sartre, unlike Hegel, diagnosed literal
cases like American chattel slavery. Sartre
follows Hegel in portraying slavery as a form
of “non-mutual recognition” where one person
dominates the other psychologically and
physically. A slave, he argues, is un-free

You might also like