You are on page 1of 16

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/239984438

Exploiting Rank Ordered Choice Set Data Within the Stochastic Utility Model

Article  in  Journal of Marketing Research · August 1982


DOI: 10.2307/3151563

CITATIONS READS
397 666

2 authors, including:

Richard Staelin
Duke University
143 PUBLICATIONS   17,825 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

The Role of Paid, Earned and Owned Media in Building Entertainment Brands: Reminding Informing and Enhancing Enjoyment View project

A “Meta-Analysis” of Multibrand, Multioutlet Channel Systems View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Richard Staelin on 20 March 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Exploiting Rank Ordered Choice Set Data within the Stochastic Utility Model
Author(s): Randall G. Chapman and Richard Staelin
Source: Journal of Marketing Research, Vol. 19, No. 3 (Aug., 1982), pp. 288-301
Published by: American Marketing Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3151563
Accessed: 20-03-2015 15:33 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/3151563?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Marketing Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Marketing
Research.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I I

RANDALL
G. CHAPMANand RICHARD
STAELIN*

Theauthorsreporton a procedurefor exploitingthe informationcontentof rank


ordered choice sets to estimateefficientlythe parametersof the multinomiallogit
modelformulationof the stochasticutilitymodelof choice behavior.The!availability
of rankorderedchoiceset data leads to an "explosion"or decompositionprocedure
for exploitingsuchextra information.This"explosion"process involvesthe decom-
positionof a rankedchoice set into a series of unrankedand statisticallyindepen-
dent choice sets. In relationto explosion strategies, several heuristicsand an an-
alytical procedurefor determiningthe "optimal"explosion depth are discussedin
detail. The resultsof a Monte Carlo study of the small sample propertiesof the
conditionallogit estimationprocedure(the maximumlikelihoodestimationprocedure
used to develop parameterestimatesof the multinomiallogit model formulationof
the stochasticutilitymodel)are reportedand interpreted.A college choice empirical
applicationillustratesthe proceduresdeveloped.

Exploiting Rank Ordered Choice Set Data


Within the Stochastic Utility Model

Accordingto a popularchoice behaviormodelingpar- associatedwith estimatingthe parametersof such choice


adigm, the consumer decision maker evaluates each models. Some illustrativeapplicationsof this choice be-
availablealternativein terms of its componentparts, havior modeling methodologyinclude the selection of
assessingthe relativeimportanceof the componentsand a college (Chapman1979; Kohn, Manski, and Mundel
ultimatelychoosing the alternativewith the greatest 1976; Punjand Staelin 1978), a mode of transportation
weighted aggregate score. Marketing scientists have (cf. Domencichand McFadden1975), a grocery store
positeda varietyof preferenceandchoice modelsof how (GenschandRecker1979), a shoppingcenter(Chapman
consumerdecisionmakerscombinethe componentscores 1980), a home (Li 1977), an occupation(Boskin 1974),
to producea weighted aggregate score. We are con- and an electricutility fuel (Joskowand Mishkin 1977).
cerned with one general class of consumer choice Although the assumptionsassociated with the sto-
models, the stochasticutility model. Withinthe choice chastic utility model do not restrictits applicabilityto
modelingliterature,this model is commonlycited as the situationsin which each consumer decision maker is
Luce (1959) choice model; in actualempiricalapplica- observedmakingjust a single choice from amonga set
tion, it is typically parameterizedas the multinomial of known alternatives,most marketingapplicationsof
logit model (cf. Gensch and Recker 1979). Econome- the stochasticutility model are limited to those cases.
tricians,most notablyMcFadden(cf. 1974, 1890), have In such situations,the analysisis cross-sectionalandthe
madesignificantstridesin refiningstatisticaltechniques econometricproblemis to assess the relativeimportance
of the quantifiableattributesthatdescribethe objectsof
choice, suchestimationbeingbasedon (theresearcher's)
knowledgeof each consumer's actual choice and the
*RandallG. Chapmanis VisitingAssistantProfessorof Marketing,
GraduateSchoolof Business,Universityof Chicago.RichardStaelin compositionof each consumer'schoice set.
is T. Austin Finch Professor of Business Administration,Fuqua We develop a procedureto enhancethe estimationof
School of Business,Duke University. the parametersof the stochasticutility model. This en-
The helpfulcommentsandadviceof CharlesF. Manski,J. Edward hancementis achievedby exploitingthe additionalin-
Russo, and an anonymousreviewer are most gratefullyacknowl- formationcontained in preference rank orderings of
edged. Responsibilityfor errorsof omission and commissionrests choice set alternatives,dataoften availableto marketing
with the authors.
researchers.In the next section, several key aspects of
288

Journal of Marketing Research


Vol. XIX (August 1982), 288-301

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STOCHASTIC
UTILITY
MODEL 289

the stochasticutilitymodelof choice behaviorarebriefly the systematic component of the model, and an er-
reviewed. The principleof decomposingrank ordered ror term e, which capturesthe measurementerrorsin
choice sets into a series of statisticallyindependentun- the modelng process. If one assumes these two com-
rankedchoice sets is explained. Strategies and tech- ponents are independentand additive, the model in
niquesfor coping with "noisy" and possibly unreliable equation1maybewrittenintheform
rankorderinformationare then considered.The results
of a Mont6Carlostudydesignedto investigatethe small (2) Ui.= Vy+ Eij
samplepropertiesof the parameterestimatesof the con- where V = V(xj,di,yi). The presenceof the stochastic
ditionallogit estimationprocedure(the maximumlike- errorterm in equation2 leads to this model being de-
lihood estimationprocedureused to develop parameter scribed as a stochastic utility model.
estimatesof the multinomiallogit model formulationof Supposethat individuali is observedto choose alter-
the stochasticutilitymodel)arereportedandinterpreted. nativej* fromCi. If rationalchoice behavioris assumed,
Particularattentionis focused on the incrementalcon- revealed pre erence implies that Ui,*2 U.i (for j =
tributionof using the additionalinformationcontained 1,2,...,Ji). Because the utility function is partly sto-
in the preferencerankorderingratherthanjust employ- chastic, the probabilityof this event occurringmay be
ing knowledgeof the chosen choice set alternative.We writtenas
concludewith an empiricalapplicationand a discussion
of the implicationsof these results for marketingre- (3) P,* = Prob(Ui, > U, j = 1,2,.. . ,J)
= Prob(Ei - ei* <
searcherswho use rankorderedchoice set data to esti- V,i - Vi, j = 1,2,...,i)
mate the parametersof the stochasticutility model to where Pi* is the probabilitythat decision maker i
drawinferencesaboutchoice behavior. chooses alternativej*. Furtherdevelopmentand simpli-
fication of equation3 requirethat a joint distribution
THESTOCHASTIC UTILITY MODEL functionbe specified for the errorterms. In principle,
The generalnatureof the choice behaviorbeing mod- any joint distributionfunction could be used and an
eled with the stochasticutilitymodel, and the natureof expressionfor the choice probabilitiescould be devel-
the data(assumed)availableto the empiricalmarketing oped. Unfortunately,the choice of most distributions,
researcher,may be describedas follows. Eachconsumer includingthe usual normaldistributionassumptionfor
decision maker i (i = 1,2,...,/) has a choice set Ci errortermsin statisticalmodels, necessitatesthe calcu-
consisting of Ji alternatives (1 < Ji < oo). The choice set lation of a formidableseries of numericalintegrations
alternativesare assumedto be characterizedby N quan- to determineexplicitly the choice probabilities.How-
tifiable attributes.Each decision makeris observedto ever, if the stochasticerrortermsareassumedto be iden-
choose an alternativefrom his or her choice set. The tically and independentlydistributed(IID) accordingto
decision makersare assumedto be utility maximizers the doubleexponentialdistribution,such that
(i.e., rational)whose choices representtheir most pre- Prob(Eij t) = exp [-exp (-t)],
ferredalternativesat the time of choice. Also, because (4)
the data used typically are cross-sectional,the sample one can show thatthe choice probabilitieshave the fol-
of decision makers is assumed to have homogeneous lowing form (cf. McFadden1974).
tastesandpreferencesin termsof the relativeimportance
of the attributescharacterizingthe alternatives. (5) PU*= exp(Vi,) forj* = 1,2,...,.
Let xj denote a vector of relevantattributesof alter- W ')*?- J, ,V
nativej, di denotea vectorof individualdecisionmaker I
exp(V,)
j=l
demographicattributes,and yijdenote a vectorof inter-
active variablesrelatingdecision makeri to alternative The value of the double exponentialdistributionas-
j. It is assumedthat a utility function U exists which sumptionis that a tractableclosed-formexpressionre-
measuresthe unobserveddesirabilityor attractivenessof sults for the choice probabilities.This particularpara-
an alternativewith attributevectorxj to a decisionmaker metricformof the stochasticutilitymodelis often called
with demographicvector di and associated decision the multinomiallogit model because it is the multiple
maker/alternative vector yij. choice generalizationof the binarylogit model.
To operationalizethe choice probabilityexpressionin
(1) U, = U(xi,d,,y,) equation5, the functionalformof the deterministiccom-
Measurementerroris typical in the modeling process ponentof the stochasticutilitymodel mustbe specified.
becausethe x, d, andy vectorsgenerallydo not capture A linear-in-parameters specificationassumptionwould
all of the factorsinfluencingthe choice process, the cor- lead to
rectfunctionalformfor the model may not be specified, N

and individualsoften exhibit aspects of idiosyncratic (6) j


n=n=l ln
behavior.Thus, Uijis assumedto be composedof two
parts-a deterministic component,V(xi,di,yY),
representing where Zijn is the measured value of attribute n for alter-

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
290 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,

native j to decision maker i and Zij = Zijn(xj,di,,y), and behavior,withinthe class of choice modelsof whichthe
0, is the relative importance of attributen to the sample stochasticutility model is a member,is providedby a
of decisionmakers.The 0 values in equation6 are the proof reportedby Luce and Suppes (1965, p. 354-6).
parametersof the stochasticutility model that must be Althoughthe Luce and Suppes proof is for constant
estimatedfrom the availablesamplechoice set data. utilitymodels (i.e., choice models in which each alter-
One particularfeatureof the stochasticutility model native has a fixed utility value and the probabilityof
with doubleexponentiallydistributederrortermsshould choosingone alternativeover anotheris a functionof the
be noted.Becausethe varianceof the doubleexponential distancebetween their utilities), both the constantand
distributionis a knownfixed constant,not dependenton stochastic(random)utility models have an econometric
the estimated0 values, the magnitudeof the estimated specificationsimilarto that of equation5 (cf. Luce and
Ovaluesdirectlyinfluencesthe "percentof varianceex- Suppes 1965, p. 332-9). Consequently,the Luce and
plained" by the systematic component of the utility Suppesproofrelatingrankingbehaviorto choice behav-
function. As shown in the Appendix, the quantity ior can be extendedto the lattermodel.
N
The Luce andSuppesRankingChoiceTheoremstates
o2 = 02 is a measureof the "size" of the systematic thatfor any rankorderedpreferenceset which has been
n=i
n=l derivedfrom a constantutility model,
component. As (2 -? oo,the systematic component dom-
inatesthe errorcomponentand the choice probabilities (7) Pr(a,b,c,...)= Pr(alC)-Pr(b,c,...)
approachunityfor the alternativesin the choice sets with
greatestutility, with all other choice probabilitiesap- where Pr(a,b,c,...) is the probabilityof observingthe
proaching zero. Conversely, as -)2-) 0, the error com- rankorderof alternativea being preferredto alternative
ponentin the stochasticutilitymodel dominatesthe sys- b being preferredto alternativec, and so on, and Pr(al
tematiccomponentand each choice set alternativehas C) is the probabilityof alternativea being chosen from
the set of alternatives C = {a,b,c,...}. This Ranking
approximatelyequal probabilityof being chosen. Other
detailsof these scale effects are given in the Appendix Choice Theoremenables the probabilityof a ranking
and in subsequentdiscussion. event, Pr(a,b,c,...), to be decomposedinto the product
Values of the parametersof the multinomiallogit of two probabilities-the probabilityof a choice event,
model may be estimatedby maximizingthe likelihood Pr(aIC), and the probabilityof a subrankingevent,
functionassociatedwith the probabilisticchoice model Pr(b,c,...). By successively applying this Ranking Choice
in equation5. Standardsoftwarepackages(cf. Manski Theoremto the subrankingevents, one can derive a
1974) are availableto calculatethe maximumlikelihood probabilityexpressionfor the rankingevent which is the
estimates.Because maximumlikelihood estimatesare, productof the probabilitiesof J - 1 choice events, i.e.,
in general,consistentand asymptoticallynormallydis-
(8) Pr(a,b,c, ...) = Pr(alC)'Pr(blC
- {a})
tributed,approximatelarge sample confidence bounds
on parameterestimates may be constructedand hy- *Pr(clC- {a,b}) ...
pothesesmay be tested in standardways.
whereC - {a} is the set of alternativesexcludingalter-
EXTENDING THE MODEL FOR native a. Equation8 is equivalentto saying that the
RANK ORDERED DATA probabilityof the joint rankingevent of J alternativesis
composed of J - 1 statistically independentchoice
The estimationof the parametersof the stochastic events.
utility model requiresthe availabilityof the following If one appliesthe RankingChoiceTheoremto the sto-
data from a representativesample of decision makers chasticutilitymodel, assumingthatthe alternativeindex
from the populationof interest:(1) the alternativesin j is now interpretedas a serial preferenceindex, it fol-
each decision maker's choice set; (2) the actual alter- lows that:
nativechosen (i.e., preferred)by each decision maker; J,
and(3) the numericalvalueof each quantifiableattribute
associated with the choice set alternatives (i.e., the Zij (9) Prob (Ui, 2 Ui2 > ... UJ) = [I Prob (U, > Uij,
j*=l
values).The modeloperateson the principleof revealed for j= *,...,J).
preference:the alternativeactuallychosen by a decision
makeris assumedto be preferredto all otheralternatives The left side of equation9 is the joint probabilitythat
in the decisionmaker'schoice set. The basic parameter alternative1 is preferredto alternative2 which is pre-
estimation methodology can be extended if the re- ferredto alternative3, and so on to alternativeJi - 1
searcherhas available (or could conveniently gather which is preferredto alternativeJ, for decision maker
along with the otherrequireddata) a completerankor- i. The rightside of equation9 may be interpretedas the
deringof all of the alternativesin the decision makers' statisticaldefinitionof the independenceof the events
choice sets. To exploitthe informationcontentof a pref- (UilI
= = 2,3,...Ji),
Uij, 1,2,...Ji), (Ui2 Uij, j
erencerankorderingof choice set alternatives,one must ..., (UiJ, Uij,).
relaterankingbehaviorto choice behavior.The theoret- The statistical independencecondition implied by
ical justificationfor relatingrankingbehaviorto choice equation9 leadsto the notionof an "explosion" process

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
UTILITY
STOCHASTIC MODEL 291

for exploitingthe informationcontentin preferencerank thoughtof as equivalentlybeing obtainedfrom Ji - 1


orderedchoice sets. More formally: independentdecision makers.(No statementapparently
is madeaboutthe errortermdistributionassociatedwith
Rankorder "explosionrule" definition:Given rankor- the exploded choice sets.) Because the elicitation of
deredchoice set data, the originalrank orderedobser-
vationthatdecisionmakeri prefersthe alternativesin the preferencerank orderedalternativesmay involve the
decision maker in forecastinghypotheticalchoice be-
order1,2,...,Ji-i.e., that U,1> U,a ... > U--can
be "exploded"(decomposed)intoJi - 1 statisticallyin- havior(whichmay not be identicalto actualchoice be-
dependentchoice observationsof the form (Uil > Uij,j havior),some "noise" may be introducedinto the data
= 1,2,...,Ji), (U 2 i, j = 2,3,...,Ji), ..., (Ui,i-l collectionprocess. This is equivalentto observingerror
' U,i). (Notethatthe trivialcase (Ui, - Uj,) is ignored.) terms with larger variancesfor lower ranked alterna-
tives. Sucha phenomenonmightoccurbecausethe con-
To illustratethe use of the explosionrule, considerthe sumerdecision makersgive less thoughtto "choices"
automobilechoice processin which a decision makeris associated with lower ranked alternatives.However,
observedto rankorderhis or her choice set in the fol- such a premiseis not consistentwith the underlyingas-
lowing manner:Pinto is preferredto Chevettepreferred sumptionsthatlead to the developmentof the explosion
to Omnipreferredto Pacer.Invokingthe explosionrule, rule, as the derivationof equation5 is based on the as-
one can formthreechoice sets {Pintopreferredto Chev- sumptionthatthe errortermsare IID. Consequently,if
ette, Omni,andPacer},{Chevettepreferredto Omniand one suspects that the lower ranked alternativesare
Pacer}, and {Omni preferredto Pacer}. Because these "noisier" and have greater error variance than the
threeexploded (decomposed)rank orderedchoice sets higherrankedalternatives,one must explicitly test for
are statisticallyindependent,they can be thoughtof as such a conditionpriorto use of the explosion rule.
equivalentlybeing obtainedfrom independentdecision A secondimplicationof note is the Luce and Suppes
makers.Thus, the explosion process appliedto prefer- RankingChoiceTheoremassumptionthatdecisionmak-
ence rankorderedchoice set data results in additional ers ranktheirchoice set alternativesfromtop to bottom.
choice observationsfor analysisat the estimationstage. Thoughthis behavioralmodel of the rankingprocess is
As the accuracyof the parameterestimatesof the sto- certainlyplausible,choice set alternativesmightbe rank
chasticutility model dependson, among other factors, orderedin otherways. Interestingly,if one assumesthat
the numberof independentchoice sets availablefor anal- the decision makersreversethis procedure(by succes-
ysis, the explosion(decomposition)processexploitsthe sively deletinginferiorchoice set alternativesfromcon-
informationcontent in a preferencerank orderingby sideration),the choice probabilitiesgeneratedfrom such
generatingmultiplestatisticallyindependentchoice ob- a bottom-to-topprocedurewill be equal to the top-to-
servationsfromeachdecisionmaker'srankorderedpref- bottom choice probabilitiesonly if the alternativesin
erences. These additionalchoice observationswill, in each choice set are equallylikely to be chosen, a rather
general,lead to "better"estimatesof the parametersof restrictivesituation(Luce and Suppes 1965, p. 356-8).
the stochasticutility model, "better" being interpreted Therefore,it mattersin a theoreticalsense whetherde-
in the sense of reducedsamplingvariance.The explo- cision makersranktheirchoice sets fromtop to bottom,
sion processis also importantin termsof samplingcost. becausethe explosionprocessholds only if this is true.
Obtainingadditionalchoice sets from independentde- Consequently,if the informationcontentof rankordered
cision makersis generallymore expensive than asking choice sets is to be exploited, the marketingresearcher
a smallerset of decision makersto supplythe complete musttry to ensurethatthe decisionmakers'behaviorin
preferencerankorderingof all elementsin theirchoice rankingchoice set alternativesapproximatesthe top-to-
sets (in additionto the chosen alternative).Hence, the bottombehavioralmodel. Any violation of the top-to-
rankorderexplosionprocesscan be viewed in eitherof bottomrankingmodel will lead to "noisy" choice sets
two complementaryways: (1) for a given numberof beinggeneratedby the explosionprocess. (Two obvious
rankorderedchoice sets, the explosionprocessleads to unresolvedresearchquestionsflow fromthis discussion:
incremental independentchoice observationsand, hence, "How do consumerdecision makersactuallygo about
to decreasedsamplingvarianceof the parameteresti- the process of rankorderinga given choice set?" and
mates, or (2) to reduce samplingcosts, rank ordered "How well are alternativerankingparadigmsapproxi-
choice sets can be obtainedfrom independentdecision matedby the top-to-bottombehavioralrankingassump-
makers(for a relativelysmall incrementalcost overjust tion?" The latter question is of particularnote in the
collectingdataon the chosen alternative)and, by use of contextof generatinga rankingof choice set alternatives
the explosionprocess, sufficientindependentunranked from ratingsdata suppliedby consumerdecision mak-
choice sets can be generatedfrom the rank ordered ers.)
choice set to yield a desireddegree of precisionin the
resultingparameterestimates. EXPLOSION STRATEGIES
Two other implicationsof the explosion rule should The ideal environmentfor gathering rank ordered
be noted.First,the rulestatesonly thatthe Ji - 1 choice choice set data would be a laboratorysetting. The de-
eventsderivedfrom a decisionmaker'spreferencerank cision makerscould be presentedwith a finite set of al-
orderingare statisticallyindependentand, thus, can be ternativesand asked to choose the most preferredele-

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
292 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,

ment. This most preferredelement would be assigned availablerankorderinformation(andtreatall of the rank


rankone and then removedfrom each choice set. Each orderedalternativesas being equallyreliable),the max-
decision makerwould then be asked to select the best imumnumberof explodedchoice observationswouldbe
alternativefrom amongthe remainingones. These sec- I
ond choice alternativeswould be assigned rank two. (11)
Thisprocesswouldbe iterateduntilthe choice sets were i=1

completelyrankedfrom top to bottom. Givena distributionof ri andJi values acrossthe sam-


Complicationsarise, however, in gatheringsuch rank
orderedpreferencedata with a survey researchdesign. ple of decision makers, I(E) will be a monotonically
One usually cannotcontrolhow the respondentunder- nondecreasingfunctionof E, andI(E) will typicallyin-
takesa rankorderingtask. Some respondentsmight in- crease at a decreasingrate. The definition of I(E) in
dicateonly the alternativeactuallychosen, whereasoth- equation 10 implies that I(E) - I(E + 1), where the
ers might provide rank order informationfor the first equalityholds when E is greaterthan or equal to the
maximum of ri or Ji - 1 for all i.
coupleof alternativesbut not for the rest of the elements In statisticalterms,the importantstrategicquestionis
in the choice set. Therefore,the questionarises of how
to cope with partial and/or "noisy" preferencerank how E shouldbe chosen. Largervalues of E will gen-
orderedchoice sets. eratemore independentchoice observations,leading to
reducedsamplingvarianceof the parameterestimatesof
Partiallyrankorderedchoice sets can be treatedin a the stochasticutility model, at least in principle.How-
straightforward manner.Denote ri as the depthof avail-
able rankorderinformationfor decision makeri on the ever, largervalues of E result in explosion of observa-
alternatives in choice set Ci (where 1 - ri - Ji - 1). tions that are fartherdown in the rank orderssupplied
Then, the maximumnumberof explodedchoice obser- by the sampleof decision makers.Becausethese order-
vationsthatcould be made availablefor analysiswould ings are more likely to be characterizedas randomor
be equalto I= min(ri,Ji- 1). Thepracticalsignificance "noisy" (or at least less systematicwith respectto the
of partiallycompleterankorderinformationis that the rulesused by the decisionmakersto choose the first few
unrankedalternativescannotbe exploded,butthe ranked alternativesin the preferencerankordering),the effect
alternatives can still be decomposed into unranked of addingsuch "noisy" orderingswould be to bias the
choice events in the usual fashion. parameterestimatestowardzero. Thus, the tradeoffin-
The conceptualproblem associated with using rank volves reducingsamplingvarianceof the parameteres-
ordereddatawherethe errortermsmightnot be IID and/ timates versus the possibility of less reliability (and
or the rankingmighthave been performedin some man- greater"noise") for the incrementalchoice observations
ner otherthantop down is more complicated.One so- generatedby explosions. Hence, an importantfactor in
lutionis to ignore the availablerankorderinformation the choice of E is the responsivenessof samplingvari-
and analyzethe choice set data accordingto the basic ance to increasesin the numberof choice sets available
stochasticutility model framework.A second, more for analysis.
constructiveapproachmight be to ask respondentsto An heuristicapproachto choosingE involves plotting
provideratingsof the choice set alternatives.Suchrating valuesof a likelihoodratioindex versusdifferentvalues
data could then be used to derive choice set rankings. of E. McFadden(1974) has proposedthe followinglike-
This approachwould allow respondentsto provideiden- lihoodratioindex as an overallgoodness-of-fitmeasure
tical ratingsof alternativesthey feel less sure about in (analogousto the multiplecorrelationcoefficient in lin-
the preferencerank ordering(as well as allowing the ear statisticalmodels).
respondentnot to rate some alternativesbecauseof lack L(O=
of relevantinformationor unfamiliarity).A third ap- (12)
2 - L( = 0)
L(O= 0)
proachmightbe to elicit confidencejudgmentsdirectly
fromrespondentson the degreeof confidenceassociated whereL is the log likelihoodfunction.To the extentthat
with the ranking(or rating)of each choice set alterna- the maximumlikelihoodparameterestimatesexplainthe
tive. A fourthapproachis to explode only partiallythe choiceprocesscompletely,R2will approachone in value
availablerankorderedchoice sets. DefineE as the depth becauseL(0 = 0) will approachzero in value. If 0, the
of the explosion(decomposition)processas specifiedby vectorof MLEparameterestimates,is essentiallyequal
the marketingresearcher.Then I(E), the numberof in- to 0 (implyingrandomchoice among the choice set al-
dependentchoice observationsavailableafterexploding ternatives), L(O = 0) will approach L(0 = 0) in value,
the rankorderedchoice sets to a depthof E, is defined implyingthat R2 will approachzero in value. Hence,
as R2 will vary between zero and one dependingon the
"explanatorypower" of 0. Now, becauseR2 does not
dependon the numberof availablechoice observations,
(10) I(E) = E min(E,r,Ji1 - 1). the calculatedR2 values should remain approximately
i=l
constantas E increases.If R2startsto decreasesubstan-
If the marketingresearcherdecides to use all of the tiallyat some value of E, this would implythat "noisy"

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STOCHASTIC
UTILITY
MODEL 293

exploded choice observationshad been added to the sive values of E until either the hypothesis that the
availablepool of choice sets, and the explosionprocess subgroupparametervectors are equal is rejectedor the
should be terminatedjust prior to the "elbow in the quantityI(E + 1) - I(E) yields too few explodedchoice
curve." observationsto providemeaningfulparameterestimates.
A secondconsiderationin choosingE is relatedto the The explosionprocess would terminatewhen either of
researcher's prior beliefs and knowledge about the these conditionsis encountered.
choice process being studied. Such beliefs and knowl-
SMALLSAMPLE PROPERTIES OF THE
edge mightlead the researcherto not considervalues of
E beyondsome practicalupperbound. CONDITIONAL LOGITESTIMATION PROCEDURE
Anotherfactorto consideris the distributionsof ri and The known propertiesof maximumlikelihood esti-
Ji values which serve to restrictthe possible range of matorshave been derived only under asymptoticcon-
explosion depths. For example, if the mean depth of ditions.To assess the value of generatingadditionalsta-
available rank order information is small-say tistically independentobservationsby exploding rank
r = 2.5-I(5) probablywill not be much larger than orderedchoice sets, one mustinvestigatethe small sam-
I(4). Thus, the researchermight decide not to explode ple propertiesof the multinomiallogit model parameter
beyonda depthof 4 because few additionalchoice ob- estimates.Of particularinterestto marketingresearchers
servationswill be generated and the extra exploded is the situationdescribedby McFadden(1974) as "con-
choice observationsbeyondE = 4 might be of a priori ditionallogit estimation,"in which thereis one choice
questionablequality. set per decision makerand no replications.As well as
The strengthof these heuristicapproachesis thatthey examininghow the precisionof the estimatesis affected
arerelativelysimpleto use. However,an obviousques- by the number of choice sets available for analysis
tion is whetheran analyticalapproachexists for deter- (among other factors), we investigatedseveral related
mining the extent to which rank orderedchoice sets issues such as unbiasednessof the estimatesand com-
shouldbe exploded(decomposed).One formalapproach putationalcosts.
involves groupingchoice observationsby depth of ex-
plosion and sequentialhypothesis testing. Define the Design of the Monte'Carlo Experiments
first subgroupof choice observationsto consist of the The generalprocedureused to investigatethe small
I(E) choice sets generatedby an explosionto a depthof samplepropertiesof the conditionallogit estimateswas
E. The secondsubgroupthenconsistsof the incremental Monte Carlo experimentationon artificiallygenerated
I(E + 1) - I(E) choice sets generatedby exploding to data. Choice sets with controllablecharacteristicswere
a depthof E + 1. If I(E + 1) - I(E) is large enough generatedandthe choice processwas simulatedwith the
to allowreasonableparameterestimatesto be developed, probabilisticchoice model in equation5. The simulated
the hypothesis that 0(E) = 0E+ can be tested by a sta- rank orderedchoice sets were then exploded and the
tisticaltestingproceduresuggestedby WatsonandWes- conditionallogit estimationprocedurewas appliedto the
tin (1975). This test affords an assessmentof whether resultingunrankedchoice observations.Becausethe true
two datasubgroupsshouldbe pooled for estimationpur- modelparameters wereknown,we were ableto examine
poses. To test the hypothesis that 0(1)= 0(2), the appro- the extentto which the estimationtechniquerecaptured
priatetest statisticis the trueparametervector-i.e., the extent to which O
-2{L( = @P))- [L(O = ()) + L(O = o(2)]}
approximates0.
The experimentalfactors hypothesizedto affect the
where O(P)is the MLE of 0 obtained by pooling the data ability of the conditionallogit estimationprocedureto
subgroups, and 0(1)and 0(2) are the MLEs for the separate recapturethe true parametervalues included (1) the
datasubgroups.This test statisticwill be asymptotically numberof parametersto be estimated(N), (2) the num-
distributedchi squarewith N degreesof freedom(Wald ber of choice sets availablefor analysisafterexplosion
1943). In applicationof the Watsonand Westinpooling (NOBS),(3) the averagenumberof alternativesin the
test, the failureto rejectthe null hypothesisimplies that choice sets afterexplosion (SIZE), (4) the relative size
the two datasubgroupscome fromthe same underlying of the deterministicportionof the choice model in com-
choiceprocess,with the sameerrortermstructure.Con- parisonwith the error componentas discussed in the
sequently,these two data subgroupscan be pooled for Appendix(SCALE),and (5) the collinearityamong the
the purposesof estimation.Thus, this is an exact test of variablesin the model (COLL).SIZEandNOBS are in-
whetherthe assumptionsunderlyingthe explosion pro- verselyrelatedbecauseboth dependon the depthof the
cess hold with real data: if the null hypothesis that explosionchosen by the analyst.1
0(E)= (E+1)cannot be rejected, the available choice set
dataare consistentwith the requisiteassumptionsof the
constantutilitymodel. If this null hypothesisis rejected, 'Becauseeachsuccessiveexplosiongeneratesadditionalchoice sets
no informationis providedas to which assumption(or with one less alternative(becausethe most preferredalternativeis
removedfromconsiderationin formingan explodedchoice set), SIZE
assumptions)is violatedby the data. This groupingand decreasesas E increases.Furthermore,as NOBS increaseswith in-
sequentialtesting procedurecan be iteratedfor succes- creasesin E, the indirecteffect is thatSIZEandNOBSare inversely

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
294 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,

The scale of the model parameters is defined as COLL were chosen stochastically, but in such a way as
N 1/2
to reflect the usual kinds of conditions an empirical mar-
(13) SCALE =E o2 keting researcher might encounter in real choice behav-
n=l
ior process data. With regard to choice set size prior to
explosion, each choice set was drawn from a normal
Because the size of the error component was known and distribution (whose mean was determined by a draw
the variance of the Z vectors could be determined, we from a uniform distribution with a range of 2 to 10 and
were able to select SCALE values to represent different a standarddeviation drawn from a uniform distribution
levels of "explained variance" ranging from about 10% with a range of 1 to 2). The actual size of any choice
(SCALE = 0.45) to about 85% (SCALE = 3.50).2 set (prior to explosion) was truncated so that 2 - Ji - 10
The collinearity among the individual components of for each choice set i. (The lower limit on choice set size
Z is capturedby an index value designed to measure the is the absolute minimum number of alternatives that can
overall average correlation among the variables describ- constitute a choice set; the upper limit of 10 was chosen
ing the choice set alternatives. The collinearity index to reflect the empirical reality of bounded choice set
used in this study is sizes.) Collinearity was induced into the variables char-
N
acterizing the choice set alternatives by a transformation
E2 --N procedure described by Chapman (1981).
The artificial choice set data in each cell of the ex-
(14) COLL= perimental design were generated in the following man-
N(N - 1) ner. A total of I choice sets were generated, each choice
where X, is the nt eigenvalue associated with the gen- set containing Ji alternatives (where the Ji values were
erated data (where the usual convention of ordering the determined as described above). Each of the N attributes
of each alternative were generated by drawing indepen-
eigenvalues from largest to smallest is followed). COLL
is bounded between zero and one. If the variables are dently distributed normal random variables with mean
zero and variance one. Collinearity was induced into
orthogonal (i.e., completely uncorrelated), Xh = 2 = these data. The transformed collinear data were stan-
...= = 1 and COLL = 0; if the data are completely
correlated and have rank 1, Xh= N and the other eigen- dardized so that each attribute had mean zero and vari-
values will be equal to zero and COLL = 1. ance one. COLL was then calculated.
The experimental design was factorial with one rep- The next series of steps involved simulating the rank
lication per cell. The factorial design set four factors at order choice process. A true parameter vector was gen-
each of the following levels. erated by drawing N independent values from a uniform
distribution with a range of zero to one. Positive and
N = 2, 4, 7, and 10, negative signs were attached to each of the parameters
I = 40, 100, 200, and 400, (the signs being determined with a probability of 0.5)
E = 1, 2, 3, 5, and 10, and the resulting true parameter values were rescaled so
SCALE= 0.45, 0.85, 1.375, and 3.50. that relation 13 was satisfied. Next, the probabilistic
Hence, a total of 320 (= 4 x 4 x 5 x 4) experiments choice model in equation 5 was used to assign the choice
were conducted. Within this Monte Carlo study, NOBS probabilities to each alternative. The "chosen" alter-
is defined as native was assigned rank one.3 The choice probabilities
I
of the "nonchosen" alternatives were then rescaled to
sum to 1.0, and the "choice" process was repeated to
(15) NOBS = E min(E,Ji - 1).
i=I
determine the rank two alternative. This procedure was
iterated to rank all of the alternatives in each simulated
Within each cell in the experimental design, SIZE and choice set. Finally, choice sets were exploded to a depth
of E, resulting in NOBS choice sets. These exploded
choice sets were input to a conditional logit estimation
related.This follows becauseboth SIZEandNOBS are functionsof program (Manski 1974) to obtain the parameter esti-
E. Note thatSIZEandNOBS are only correlatedwithin the context mates.
of an explosion,becausewhenE increasesso does NOBS,but at the Several additional points should be noted. First, this
expenseof slightlydecreasingthe averagechoice set size (SIZE).Ex type of experimental design involves an implicit as-
ante (beforeexplosion)measuresof SIZEandNOBSareuncorrelated
withinthe factorialexperimentaldesign used in this study. sumption that each simulated decision maker employs
2Thesevalues of SCALEwere chosen by noting that if the com- the same underlying choice model. Thus, there is no
ponentsof Z are standardizedto have unit variance,it follows that heterogeneity problem to confound the estimation pro-
Var(U)= SCALE2+ Var(e).BecauseVar e = 1.645 for the double cess. Second, reliability is not an issue in these experi-
exponentialdistribution,the usual partitioningof total variationinto
explainedvariationand unexplainedvariationimpliesthat:
3Byuse of a randomnumbergenerator,an alternativewas "cho-
"proportion of _ SCALE2 sen" with probabilityequal to the choice probabilityassignedto the
explainedvariation" SCALE2+ 1.645 alternative.

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
UTILITY
STOCHASTIC MODEL 295

ments because the same underlying probabilistic choice


process was employed to rank all of the choice set al-
(17)
161 1 NI
= Nn=l le .
ternatives. Third, only the non-extreme values of
COLL - 0.75 were considered, reflecting the usual pres- Thus, RELRSV is a measure of relative variation anal-
ence of modest degrees of interrelationships among the ogous to a coefficient of variation.
attributesof the choice set alternatives. Because of these Theoretically, RELRSV = f(NOBS, SIZE, COLL,
points, the results reported in the rest of this section SCALE, N) with prior beliefs that, ceteris paribus,
probably represent an upper bound on the degree to RELRSVshould decrease with increases in NOBS, SIZE,
which the conditional logit model estimates recapturethe and SCALE and decrease with decreases in COLL and
"true" underlying choice model. These results are "bet- N. The theoretical arguments associated with the signs
ter" than might be obtained with real choice data be- on NOBS, SIZE, and N all reflect "degrees of freedom"
cause potential problem sources such as respondent het- concerns. The expected positive sign on COLL is due
erogeneity, measurement and specification errors, and to collinearity being posited to lead to less precise esti-
unreliable rank order information are not present. mates of the model's parameters. SCALE reflects the
In each cell of the experimental design, several per- relative magnitude of the systematic component in the
formance measures were calculated. These measures model and, thus, should be negatively related to
were designed to represent the extent to which the con- RELRSV-a priori, a greater magnitude for the "ex-
ditional logit estimation procedure recaptured the true plained variance" component of the model should be
parameter vector values associated with the underlying associated with an improvement in the precision of the
multinomial logit model. The performance measures in- estimates (a decrease in RELRSV). An interactive func-
cluded the following. tional relationship was postulated and the model was
estimated after appropriate logarithmic transformation.
1. RMSE(root mean squarederror),where The OLS results were
I N \1/2
2
RMSE = I E(O - On) (18)
2. MAE(meanabsoluteerror),where log RELRSV= 0.1812 - 0.5753 logNOBS
(0.4270) (0.0487)
1N
MAE = - 1
In - Onl - 0.2164 log(SIZE-1) + 0.1849
Nn=1
3. BIAS(bias), where
(0.1260) (0.1138) 1-COLL
N - 0.6863 log SCALE+ 1.6146 log N
1
BIAS =-- (On- n) (0.0670) (0.0919)
n=l
4. TIME(CPU executiontime in seconds, includingonly R2 = 0.65 No. of obs. = 320
the time used for estimationand excludingdatagenera- where the standarderrors of the coefficient estimates are
tion time requirements)
in parentheses and log is the naturallogarithm. The form
In performancemeasures 1-3, Onis the known true value of the regression model in equation 18 reflects the the-
of the nh parameter in the multinomial logit model and oretical relationship between COLL and RELRSV. As
COLLapproaches one in value, RELRSVincreases with-
n,is the maximum likelihood estimate obtained from the
conditional logit estimation procedure. out bound regardless of the values of the other factors.
Also, note that SIZE - 1 is used to describe the choice
Results of the Monte Carlo Experiments set sizes because the conditional logit estimation pro-
cedure is based on the number of within-choice-set com-
The results of these experiments were analyzed by re-
parisons available for analysis (i.e., the chosen alter-
gressing variants of the performance measures on theo- native versus the other J - 1 inferior alternatives).
retically plausible causal experimental factors. Given the interactive functional form, the coefficients
Sampling variance. One component of the accuracy on NOBS, SIZE - 1, SCALE, and N can be interpreted
of the conditional logit estimation procedure is sampling as elasticities.
variance. To reflect relative sampling variation (and to
The estimated coefficients in equation 18 all have the
avoid the problem associated with, ceteris paribus, large
theoretically posited signs. The main conclusion to be
parameterestimates having associated large standarder- drawn from these results is that the explosion process
rors), the performance measure chosen was the relative leads to important sampling variance efficiencies. The
root squared variation (RELRSV), defined as
coefficient estimate of -0.5753 for log NOBS implies
RMSE that RELRSV decreases approximately with the square
(16) RELRSV = root of the number of choice sets available for analysis
|9| after explosion, ceteris paribus. A comparison of the
where: coefficients on log NOBS and log (SIZE - 1) is useful

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
296 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,

for assessing the marginal tradeoffs between the number sion results reported in equation 18, the explanatory
of available choice observations after explosion and the power of the model is rather low. The reason is partly
average choice set size after explosion. For example, a the experimental design used in this Monte Carlo study.
researcherwho has 100 choice sets each with five ranked Because only a single replication was performed in each
alternativescould use E = 1 (and NOBS = 100 and SIZE of the 320 cells in the factorial design, we could not
= 5) or the data could be exploded to E = 4 (where account for the within-cell variation of the performance
NOBS = 400 and SIZE correspondingly declines to 3.5). measures (the dependent variables). The source of this
Using equation 18, we can easily show that RELRSVfor within-cell variation is the probabilistic choice process
the former strategy (E = 1) is about twice that for the itself: the "chosen" alternative in each exploded choice
latter strategy (E = 4). Further, to obtain the same level observation is determined by a probabilistic model and
of RELRSVas that when E = 4 by retaining E = 1 and a single replication of the choice process reflects but a
increasing the average choice set sizes, we would have single point estimate of the parameter values. To mea-
to increase SIZE from five to about 100. (In this ex- sure the approximate magnitude of this replication error,
perimental design, there was much more variation in five replications of the simulated choice process were
NOBS than in SIZE; NOBS had a range of 40 to about conducted in each of the 16 cells characterized by the
2600 whereas SIZE ranged from about 2.6 to 9.2. If factorial design with N = 4 and 7, I = 100 and 250,
SIZE had been varied much more, say to 100, it might E = 1 and 4, and SCALE = 0.50 and 2.00. The average
have exerted a stronger influence on RELRSV. Still, as standarddeviation of the log RELRSVvalues over these
most empirical applications of the multinomial logit 16 cells is 0.499. Because the standard error of the es-
model would probably involve mean choice set sizes of timate in equation 18 is 0.894, the replication error rep-
fewer than 10 alternatives, this experimental framework resents about 56% of the total unexplained variance in
seems realistic. Note also that, in many applications, the the regression model in equation 18. If means of repli-
size of the choice sets is determined by the consumer cated choice processes had been used as the dependent
decision makers, and is not at the control of the mar- variable in equation 18, we could reasonably expect that
keting researcher. The number of sample decision mak- the total unexplained variance would have been reduced
ers, however, is often at the choice modeler's control.) by about 56%. The corresponding R2 value would have
Collinearity among the attributes seems to have only been increased to about 0.85. Such resulting unex-
a negligible impact on sampling variance. This result is plained variance (about 15%) is much more in line with
very encouraging because real choice data should be ex- a priori expectations.
pected to exhibit patterns of collinearity. Biasedness. Because the conditional logit estimates
As was expected, the precision of the conditional logit are obtained by means of maximum likelihood estima-
estimates is directly related to SCALE, a surrogate for tion techniques, the property of unbiasedness is guar-
the degree of systematic behavior exhibited by the sam- anteed only for large samples (asymptotically). Conse-
ple of decision makers. The coefficient estimate on log quently, it would be useful to know the degree and
SCALE implies that a doubling of SCALE would lead to direction of any small sample bias.
about a 68% decrease in RELRSV. For the 320 cells in the experimental design, the mean
A doubling of N, the number of model parameters, BIAS is -0.025 with an associated standard deviation
leads to about a 160% increase in RELRSV, ceteris par- of 0.311. A two-tailed test of the hypothesis that the
ibus. Because theoretical considerations guide the de- mean BIAS of the conditional logit estimates is zero
terminationof the number of parametersin the stochastic leads to the conclusion that the unbiasedness hypothesis
utility model, these results are useful to a choice modeler cannot be rejected at the conventional 5% level of sig-
in assessing the appropriate sample size to obtain a de- nificance (p = 0.15).
sired level of precision in the resulting parameter esti- To test for the possible presence of conditional
mates. For example, to obtain equivalent precision for bias-bias depending on the external factors-BIAS was
parameterestimates in a four-parametermodel estimated regressed against several theoretically plausible combi-
with 100 choice sets, the choice modeler would require nations of the external factors (NOBS, SIZE, COLL,
about 260 choice sets for a more theoretically complex SCALE, and N). None of the resulting F-statistics for the
model with eight parameters. regression models tested yielded significant values.
The model reported in equation 18 was also estimated Though it is not possible to prove unbiasedness via
with relative absolute variation as the dependent vari- simulation, these Monte Carlo results may be viewed as
able. The OLS results were virtually identical to those support for an hypothesis of unbiasedness. The possi-
reported in equation 18. Apparently, the relationship bility that subsets of the parameter estimates could be
between the external factors (i.e., NOBS, SIZE, and so biased is not precluded. That is, offsetting biases in in-
on) and the sampling variance of the conditional logit dividual parameter estimates could be present.
estimates does not depend on whether accuracy is mea- Computational considerations. The final performance
sured in terms of a quadratic or a linear loss function. measure of interest was computational cost. Because the
Although the small sample properties of the condi- explosion process yields additional choice sets for anal-
tional logit estimates are described clearly by the regres- ysis, the decision of how much to explode the available

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STOCHASTIC
UTILITY
MODEL 297

rankorderedchoice set datamightbe influencedby the Table 1


extra associatedcomputationalcosts. The performance CALCULATIONSOF RELRSVAND TIME
(CPUEXECUTION
measure for computationalcosts is execution time, TIME,IN SECONDS)IN THEEXAMPLEILLUSTRATING
TIME,which refers to the CPU executiontime for the PRECISION
AND COSTTRADEOFFS
Newton-Raphsonalgorithm(in seconds) used in Man-
ski's (1974) program. N=5 N=10
Theoretically,TIME= f(NOBS,SIZE,N) with TIME E NOBS SIZE RELRSV TIME RELRSV TIME
increasingwith increasesin each of the externalfactors. 1 100 8 0.96 7.7 2.93 23.4
Momentmatricesmustbe assembledat each iterationof 2 200 7.5 0.65 13.6 2.00 35.4
the algorithmand the numberof elementsprocessedat 3 300 7 0.53 18.6 1.61 45.3
each iterationequalsNOBS(SIZE- 1)N. Also, the mo- 4 400 6.5 0.45 22.6 1.39 53.3
ment matrixmust be invertedat each iterationand the
timefor suchan operationdependsapproximatelyon N2.
RegressingTIMEon these factorsyielded the following
OLS results. terizingthe choice set alternativesare expectedto have
some correlationamong them (COLL = 0.25) and a
(19) TIME= -2.2548 + 0.001991 NOBS(SIZE-1)N
SCALEvalue in the area of about 1.00 is anticipated.
(0.9866) (0.000040)
Table 1 lists the predictedvalues of RELRSVand TIME
+ 0.1175 N2 undervariousexplosiondepthsfor five- and 10-variable
(0.0185) multinomiallogit models. The values in Table 1 were
R2 = 0.91 No. of obs. = 320
calculatedby using the resultsin equations18 and 19.
Severalfeaturesof these data may be noted. First, as
wherethe standarderrorsof the parameterestimatesare NOBSincreasesbecauseof explosions, SIZEdecreases
in parentheses.These resultsimply thatTIMEincreases becausechoice sets of smallersize are being added to
linearlywith increasesin NOBSandSIZE,andincreases the availablepool of choice observations.Second, the
approximatelyquadraticallywith increasesin N. These decreasein RELRSVis approximately proportionalto the
resultscan also be used as a guide to the magnitudeof squareroot of the increasein NOBS. Hence, to halve
the computationalcosts associatedwith estimatingthe RELRSV,the choice modelerrequiresabout four times
parametersof the multinomiallogit model. Naturally, as manychoice observations.Third,even for the largest
the absoluteamountof executiontime dependson the model situationin this example (in terms of computa-
specific algorithmused and the particularcomputerin- tional cost), when E = 5 and N = 10, computational
stallationon which the analysisis performed.(All con- costs arenot prohibitive,amountingto slightlyless than
ditionallogit estimationsin the studywere performedon a minutein CPU time.
an IBM/360.) However,relativetimes for variouscom- Fora researcherdecidingon the size of a choice sam-
binationsof NOBS, SIZE, and N should be approxi- ple studyand on subsequentexplosion strategy,the re-
matelyequivalentacross differentalgorithmsand com- sults in Table 1 offer some insightinto the precisionof
puters. the multinomiallogit model parameterestimates. Sup-
For many, if not most, marketingresearchapplica- pose a marketingresearcherwouldlike each of the coef-
tions of the multinomiallogit model, computational ficient estimatesin a five-parametermultinomiallogit
costs apparentlywill not be an inhibitingforce. Com- model to be statisticallysignificant(i.e., have an esti-
putationalcosts tend to be in the orderof secondsrather matedstandarderrorno largerthan about one-half the
thanminutes.For example, with 250 choice sets of av- size of the coefficientestimate).Given the conditionsin
eragesize fourwith fourparametersto be estimated,the this illustrativeexample, explosion to a depth of four
applicationof the regressionresultsreportedin equation wouldbe required.Of course, the choice modelermight
19 yields a predictedexecutiontime value of about5.6 choose to gathermorethan 100 choice sets to startwith
seconds. An eight-parameter model of the same choice so that a lesser explosion depth would be possible. By
set configurationwould requireabout 17.2 seconds of using the resultsin equation18, the thoughtfulmarket-
executiontime. ing researchercan anticipatethe impactof choice study
Precisionand Cost Tradeoffs sample sizes and possible explosion strategieson the
precisionof the parameterestimates before collecting
To illustratethe natureof the tradeoffsbetween re- data.
duced samplingvarianceand additionalcomputational
costs associatedwith analyzing exploded choice sets, AN ILLUSTRATIVE EMPIRICAL APPLICATION OF
and to indicatehow a choice modelermight use the re- THEEXPLOSION PROCEDURE
sults reportedin equations18 and 19, considerthe fol- To illustratethe applicationof the explosionprocedure
lowing example. Supposea researcheris workingwith for exploitingthe informationcontent of rank ordered
completelyrankedchoice sets of size eight for 100 con- choice set data, we use a college choice behaviormod-
sumer decision makers. Further,the variablescharac- eling study. Chapman(1977) has given the full details

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
298 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,

of this study and a summary of the empirical results Table 2


(1979). COEFFICIENTS
OF THECOLLEGE CHOICEMODEL
The data base for the study consisted of admitted FOR"LOW"INCOMEENGINEERING AND
freshmen applicants to Carnegie-Mellon University, a SCIENCESTUDENTS (ASYMPTOTIC STANDARD
private independent coeducational university in Pitts- ERRORSIN PARENTHESES) FOREXPLOSIONDEPTHS
burgh, Pennsylvania. A survey research questionnaire OF 1, 2, AND 3
to admitted applicants was used to obtain the required
preference rank order and choice set composition infor-
Explosionstrategies
mation, as well as information on financial aid offered
E= 1 E=2 E=3
by schools to each high school student. These data were
combined with other information contained in Carnegie- FS, (quality/ 0.69555 0.6894 0.6100
Mellon's applicant information system (derived from affluence) (0.13553) (0.1123) (0.1037)
FS2(size/graduate 0.461[1 0.4104 0.3221
each applicant's application forms) and other publicly (0.0974)
orientation) (0.134t8) (0.1057)
available information (college alternative characteristics FS3 (technical 0.21556 0.2351 0.2428
and costs) to yield the required study data. Self-reported orientation) (0.12337) (0.0984) (0.0914)
preference rank order and financial aid information was FS4(ruralness) -0.069 }0 0.0281 0.0359
(0.12337) (0.0952) (0.0902)
subjected to consistency and reliability checks. Across FS5(fine arts 0.02C)5 -0.1208 -0.1503
the various academic areas in this data base, average orientation) (0.144t6) (0.1137) (0.1057)
choice set sizes ranged from 2.9 to 3.5 college alter- FS6(liberalness) 0.14223 0.1044 0.0811
natives, and less than 10% of the students in the sample (0.134t6) (0.1105) (0.1020)
had more than five college alternatives in their choice GRANTS 0.18319 0.2115 0.3608
sets. 1000 (0.19351) (0.1620) (0.1526)
The variables in the college choice model were of DRAIN -1.652 29 -2.0704 -1.3354
three categories: college characteristics variables; price, (0.87237) (0.7459) (0.6707)
INCOME
cost, and financial aid variables; and a miscellaneous
GRANTS 0.35228 0.3701 0.0442
group. To describe the attributes and characteristics of
colleges, 46 different variables were obtained from pub- TOTALAID (0.45C)9) (0.3750) (0.3501)
licly available sources, such as college guidebooks. Fac- (MILES/10)/2 -0.343 39 -0.1397 -0.0822
tor analysis procedures were used to reduce these 46 (0.185)5) (0.1403) (0.1271)
variables to a set of composite indices that would serve COMMUTE -0.09, 78 0.0524 0.1474
as suitable proxies for the college attributes. The six fac- (0.35337) (0.2763) (0.2546)
{SATi - SAT,2 -0.38( 53 -0.4081 -0.3188
tors extracted accounted for about 58% of the variance
in the original 46 raw variables. The results of a varimax 100 J (0.17110) (0.1425) (0.1331)
rotation led to the six factors (FS1, ..., FS6) being in- NOBS(after 303 452 505
terpretedas quality/affluence, size/graduate orientation, explosion)
L(O = 0) -309.18 -448.23 496.53
technical orientation, ruralness, fine arts orientation, and L(O= 0) -240.80 -353.16 399.60
liberalness, respectively. In the financial area, the fol- k2 0.221 0.212 0.195
lowing variables were used in the choice model:
DRAIN GRANTS
GRANTS, , and model with explosion depths of 1, 2, and 3 are reported
INCOME' TOTALAID
in Table 2. These results are for "low" income engi-
(GRANTSis total scholarship aid, DRAIN is total out-of- neering and science students, where "low" is defined
pocket costs, INCOME is parental income, and TOTAL- to be the bottom half of the applicants in terms of pa-
AID is total financial aid.) Collectively, these variables rental income (for those students who had applied for
account for amount and kind of financial aid (mix of financial aid and, hence, had supplied parental income
financial aid), and for costs in relation to income. Within information).
the miscellaneous group of choice model variables are The main result to be noted in Table 2 is that the stan-
MILES (distance from college campus to place of resi- dard errors of the parameter estimates decrease as more
dence), COMMUTE (a dummy variable which equals choice sets become available for analysis due to the ex-
one if the student could commute to a college campus plosion process for exploiting preference rank ordered
and equals zero otherwise), and (SATi - SATj)2(where choice set data. This result illustrates the main value of
SAT refers to mean scholastic aptitude test score, the the explosion procedure: explosion of rank ordered
subscript i refers to the student, and the subscriptj refers choice sets leads to more choice observations being
to a college), which attempts to measure the impact of available for analysis which leads to improved precision
"quality zoning"-the desire to attend a college that is (reduced sampling variance) in the stochastic utility
neither too much above nor below the student in average model parameterestimates.
student quality. The key strategic issue faced by the choice modeler
Statistical results of estimating this college choice is the choice of an explosion strategy. In the college

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
MODEL
UTILITY
STOCHASTIC 299

choice resultsreportedin Table 2, the heuristicof ex- CONCLUDING


REMARKS
amining R2 as E increases would probably lead the
choice modelerto concludethat an explosion depth of Withinthe context of the stochasticutility model of
2 is reasonablysafe (as R2only declinesslightlyin shift- choicebehavior,the informationcontentof rankordered
ing fromE = 1 to E = 2, namelyfrom0.221 to 0.212), choice sets can be exploitedto estimateefficiently the
buttheremightbe some uncertaintyin resolvingwhether parametersof the model. The availabilityof rank or-
E = 3 should be preferred to E = 2.4 deredchoice set data leads to an explosion (decompo-
In using the groupingand sequentialhypothesistest- sition)procedurefor exploitingsuch extra information.
ing procedurefor statisticallytesting for an "optimal" This explosionprocessinvolves the decompositionof a
explosiondepth, it is useful to begin by notingthat the preferencerankorderedchoice set into a series of un-
criticalchi squarevalue for a 5% level of significance rankedandstatisticallyindependentchoice observations.
is 21.03, whereasthe correspondingvaluefor a 1%level Becausethe ability to estimatethe model's parameters
of significanceis 27.69 (for 12 degreesof freedom,the dependson the numberof choice sets availablefor anal-
numberof parametersin this choice model). Recall also ysis, the explosionprocessrepresentsan intuitivelysim-
that the null hypothesisbeing tested is whether0(E = ple mechanismfor exploiting rank orderedchoice set
0(E+1). In assessing whether a change from E = 1 to E data.
= 2 is appropriate,the relevantlog likelihoodvalues are The choice modelermustresolvethe key issue of how
L(O = 6(+2) = -353.16, L(O = ()) = -240.80, and much to explode the availablerankorderedchoice set
L(O = (2) = -105.67. (In notational form, 6(1+20is the data. Several considerationsbear on this issue. First,
MLE for the pooled explodedrankorderedchoice sets because the computationalcosts are ratherminor, the
obtained by exploding to a depth of 2, @(l)is the MLE differencein computationaltime from exploding to a
for the choice sets basedonly on the firstmost preferred depthof E + 1 ratherthan a depth of E can probably
alternative, and 0(2) is the MLE for the choice sets based be ignored. Second, the problemof reliabilityof the
only on the second preferredalternative.)The relevant preferencerank order informationobtainedthrougha
chi square test statistic value is therefore equal to surveyresearchdesign may not be a majorproblem,as
-2(-353.16 - {[-240.80] + [-105.67]}) = 13.38. the precisionof the conditionallogit parameterestimates
Comparingthis calculatedtest statistic value with the is relatedto the squareroot of the numberof available
relevantcriticalvalues leads to the conclusionthat the choice set observationsafter explosion. Thus, because
nullhypothesisshouldnot be rejectedon the basis of the each successive explosion from E to E + 1 results in
availablesample evidence. Therefore,pooling the ob- incrementallysmallerimprovementsin the precisionof
servationsis feasible, and an explosiondepthof at least the parameterestimates,explodingbeyonda depthof 3
2 is warranted.In iteratingthis test to determinewhether or 4 will usually not increaseaccuracygreatly. This is
an explosiondepthof 3 is appropriate,the relevantlog true partlybecause the precision of the estimates de-
likelihood values are L( = (1+2+3)) = -399.60, creases by the squareroot of the numberof exploded
L(O = o+2)) = -353.16, and L(O = (3) = -32.50. choice sets and partlybecause not all decision makers
The relevantchi squaretest statisticvalue is equal to in mostchoice situationswill have choice set sizes large
27.88, which is above the 1% significancecritical chi enoughto allow for furtherexplosion. Also, as larger
squarevalue. Thus, one could conclude that the null explosionsare more likely to increasethe possibilityof
hypothesisshould be rejectedin this situation.As the including"noisy" choice sets, an explosion depth of
availablesample evidence seems inconsistentwith the morethanabout3 would not normallybe appropriatein
pooling hypothesis,an explosion depth of 3 seems in- a surveyresearchapplication.
appropriate.The grouping and sequential hypothesis In summary,an explosionstrategywill dependon the
testingprocedurefor choosing an "optimal" explosion choicemodeler'sknowledgeof the choice processbeing
strategyleads to the conclusionthat an explosiondepth studiedand the likely reliabilityof the complete pref-
of 2 is most appropriatewith these choice set data. erencerankorderinformation,the use of the grouping
andsequentialhypothesistestingprocedureandthe heu-
ristic tools we describe, and the Mont6 Carlo results
which suggest that large explosions (say, E largerthan
4R2does not depend on the number of available choice set obser- 3) are normallynot required.
vations, so the value of R2 should remain approximately constant as These resultsalso have implicationsfor surveyques-
E increases, if the extra choice sets generated by the explosion process
are characterized by the same 0 vector. If "noisy" choice sets are tionnairedesignsto elicit rankorderedchoice set infor-
added by the explosion process (either due to unreliable rank order mationfrom decision makers.Attemptingto guarantee
information or because the lower ranked choice sets are characterized completelyrankorderedchoice set data probablycosts
by some 0 vector other than that which described the higher ranked morethanthe dataare worth. A betterresearchstrategy
choice sets), one may observe that the value of R2 will decline with
increases in E. Sampling variation may explain successive values of
would be to ask for the first few rank orderedalterna-
R2 that are not identical, so an appropriate statistical test is required tives (say, up to three), and then ask for all otheralter-
to assess whether the explosion is feasible in the context of any spe- nativesconsideredby the decision makerin the choice
cific empirical application. behaviortask. As the statisticalworthof more than the

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
300 JOURNALOF MARKETING AUGUST1982
RESEARCH,
first couple of rank ordered choice set alternatives is estimated vector of parameters affects the error terms
marginal at best (because of reliability and "noisy" data and, hence, their variance.
problems), survey questionnaire respondents need not be Fixing the variance of the disturbance terms implies
confused and antagonized by having to supply more de- that the proportion of the variance of U represented by
tailed information than can be used profitably in the sub- the systematic component of the stochastic utility model
sequent statistical analysis. will depend directly on the "size" of the 0 values. In
this way, "large" 0 values will be associated with high
explanatory power of the stochastic utility model be-
APPENDIX cause the variance of the systematic component will be
SCALE CONSIDERATIONSAND THE STOCHASTIC large in relation to the error component. The following
UTILITYMODEL theorem clarifies these relationships.
The rank order of a set of alternatives in a choice set Scale theorem. In the stochastic utility model Uu =
will be invariant under monotone transformationsof the OZy + E., where the error terms follow the double ex-
form W = axU+ {3, for ot > 0. Hence, the most general ponentiai distribution in equation 4, let On = coO,where
form of the stochastic utility model would be N=i 02 = 1. This scaling implies that o2 = N=i 0n. The
scaling factor o may be interpreted as the "size" of the
(Al.1) U,i = a(O Zi + Ei) + 3. 0 values. It follows that
The model in equations 5 and 6 follows from the nor- (a) as w --> o, Pio -> 1 for j? alternativesuch that OZio=
malizations ao = 1 and P = 0. Because we are concerned max(OZi), and Pij- 0 for all otheralternatives
only with differences in the utilities of various choice set 1
alternatives, P will be identical for each alternative. (b) as o -> 0, Pi - forj = 1,2,...,J
i
Hence, no generality is lost by assuming that P = 0.
Setting a = 1 causes no difficulties with the ca0 Z.. term Proof. One version of the probabilistic choice model in
because ac is just a scalar, and in essence just indicates equations 5 and 6, which can be derived with some sim-
the size (or scale) of the 0 values. We estimate the vector ple manipulations of equation 5, is
a 0, the relative population taste parameters. To obtain
absolute 0 values, an estimate of a somehow determined Pij*= J,
independently from the estimate of 0 would be required. 1+ E exp {0(Z - Zi.)}
We only need the relative 0 values to draw inferences j=!

about utilities, which are only relative quantities them-


selves. Setting a = 1 in the term acxEdoes, however, with j* being some alternative in the choice set.
have important ramifications for the variances of the
disturbance terms. Part(a): For alternativej?, O(Z,i- Zio) < 0 because alter-
The most general form of the double exponential dis- nativej? has been defined as the most preferredal-
tribution is ternative.Hence, o -> ooimplies that exp{wO(Z,-
-- -- 1.
Zi)} 0. Therefore, o -> ooimplies thatPij
For Pj* such thatj* jo, O(Zio- Z.*) > 0, and o
(A1.2) Prob(E< t) = exp -exp( -- 1) - ooimpliesthat -
exp{co(Zijo Zi*)}-- ooso thatPi*
--> 0.
where m1and Tq2are location and scale parameters, re- Part(b): as -->0, exp{(x(Zi - Z.*)}- 1 forj* = 1,2,...,Ji.
spectively (Johnson and Kotz 1970, p. 276-9). If m1
= 0 and q2 = 1, then equation A1.2 is identical to equa- Therefore,co -> 0 implies that Pj*--> , for j* =
tion 4. Assuming 1 = 0 implies that P = 0 in A1.1; 1,2,...,Ji.
similarly, setting 12 = 1 implies that ca = 1 in A1.1.
Because the variance of the double exponential distri- In summary, as the estimated parameters become
1 larger, the systematic component of the stochastic utility
bution is Var(E) = - 72 r12,setting ql2 = 1 implies that model dominates the stochastic component and the re-
6
sulting utilities of the alternatives show greater disper-
Var(e) = ,r2 = 1.645. Hence, fixing ax in the general sion. This follows through to the probabilistic choice
6 model, with the probabilities of choosing the alternatives
model in A1.1 implies that the variance of the distur- approaching one for the alternative with greatest utility
bances is also fixed. and approaching zero for all other alternatives. In con-
The preceding discussion reveals an interesting facet trast, "small" 0 values would be associated with choice
of the stochastic utility model with double exponentially probabilities approximately equal to 1/Ji for each alter-
distributed error terms-the variance of the disturbance native. The latter empirical result implies that the choice
terms is a fixed number, not dependent on the estimated process is essentially random with each alternative in a
0 values. In contrast, in "regression-like" models the choice set having an equivalent chance of being chosen.

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STOCHASTIC
UTILITY
MODEL 301

REFERENCES (1976), "An EmpiricalInvestigationof FactorsWhich In-


fluenceCollege-GoingBehavior,"Annalsof Economicand
Social Measurement,5 (Fall), 391-419.
Boskin, MichaelJ. (1974), "A ConditionalLogit Model of Li, Mingche M. (1977), "A Logit Model of Homeowner-
OccupationalChoice," Journal of Political Economy, 82 ship," Econometrica,45 (July), 1081-97.
(April), 389-98. Luce, R. Duncan(1959), IndividualChoiceBehavior:A The-
Chapman,RandallG. (1977), BuyerBehaviorin Higher Ed- oreticalAnalysis. New York:JohnWiley & Sons, Inc.
ucation:An Analysis of College Choice Decision Making andP. Suppes(1965), "Preference,Utility, and Sub-
Behavior,unpublished doctoraldissertation,GraduateSchool jective Probability,"in Handbookof MathematicalPsy-
of IndustrialAdministration,Carnegie-MellonUniversity. chology-Volume3, R. DuncanLuce, RobertR. Bush, and
(1979), "PricingPolicy and the College Choice Pro- EugeneGalanter,eds. New York:JohnWiley & Sons, Inc.,
cess," Researchin HigherEducation,10(1), 37-57. 249-410.
(1980), "Retail TradeArea Analysis: Analytics and Manski, Charles F. (1974), "The Conditional/Polytomous
Statistics,"in Proceedings:MarketMeasurementandAnal- LogitProgram:Instructionsfor Use," School of Urbanand
ysis, RobertA. Leone, ed. Providence,RI: TIMS College PublicAffairs, Carnegie-MellonUniversity.
on Marketingand The Instituteof ManagementSciences, McFadden,Daniel (1974), "ConditionalLogit Analysis of
40-9. QualitativeChoice Behavior," in Frontiers in Economet-
(1981), "A Note on GeneratingCorrelatedData," rics, Paul Zarembka,ed. New York: Academic Press,
GraduateSchool of Business, Universityof Chicago. 105-42.
Domencich,T. and Daniel McFadden(1975), Urban Travel (1980), "EconometricModelsfor ProbabilisticChoice
Demand:A BehavioralAnalysis. Amsterdam:North-Hol- Among Products,"Journal of Business, 53, No. 3, Pt. 2
landPublishingCompany. (July), S13-29.
Gensch, Dennis H. and Wilfred W. Recker (1979), "The Punj,GirishN. andRichardStaelin(1978), "The ChoicePro-
Multinomial,Multiattribute Logit Choice Model," Journal cess for GraduateBusinessSchools," Journalof Marketing
of MarketingResearch, 16 (February),124-32. Research, 15 (November),588-98.
Johnson,NormanL. and Samuel Kotz (1970), Continuous Wald,A. (1943), "Tests of StatisticalHypothesesConcerning
UnivariateDistributions--1.New York:HoughtonMifflin Several ParametersWhen the Numberof Observationsis
Company. Large," Transactionsof the AmericanMathematicalSoci-
Joskow, Paul L. and FredericS. Mishkin(1977), "Electric ety, 54, 426-82.
Utility Fuel Choice Behaviorin the United States," Inter- Watson,PeterL. and RichardB. Westin (1975), "Transfer-
nationalEconomicReview, 18 (October),719-36. abilityof DisaggregatedMode Choice Models," Regional
Kohn, Meir G., CharlesF. Manski, and David S. Mundel Scienceand UrbanEconomics,5 (May), 227-49.
F--

FACE)th
Fr
with Ferber
Readings In The Analysis Of Readings In Survey Research
Survey Data Robert Ferber, editor
Robert Ferber, editor 604 pp. 1978
249 pp. 1980 $10/member $13/nonmember
$16/member $24/nonmember
A collection of readings which form
Key pieces of the published literature an extension of the special issue on
concerning applications of multi- survey research of the August 1977
variate and related techniques to sur- issue of Journal of Marketing Re-
vey data, and new, innovative ap- search. The articles focus on three
proaches to the analysis of survey aspects of survey research: sampling,
data are brought together in this book questionnaire preparation and data
of previously published articles. collection. An extensive bibliography
Emphasis is given to recent material is included.
although some of the classics in the
field have also been included. Biblio-
graphies follow each piece, to stimu- TO ORDER call or write Order
late the researcher to go further in Department, American Market-
ing Association, 250 S. Wacker
examining the various techniques. AMERICAN
MARKETING
ASOCIATION
Drive, Chicago, IL 60606, (312)
648-0536.

This content downloaded from 152.3.153.137 on Fri, 20 Mar 2015 15:33:01 UTC
View publication stats
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like