You are on page 1of 10

Conceptual change

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Conceptual change is the process whereby concepts and relationships between them change
over the course of an individual person’s lifetime or over the course of history. Research in three
different fields – cognitive developmental psychology, science education, and history and
philosophy of science - has sought to understand this process. Indeed, the convergence of these
three fields, in their effort to understand how concepts change in content and organization, has
led to the emergence of an interdisciplinary sub-field in its own right. This sub-field is referred to
as “conceptual change” research.

Contents
 1 Origins
 2 Emerging theoretical perspectives and recent developments
 3 How does conceptual change happen and how can it be supported?
 4 The scope of conceptual change research
 5 See also
 6 References
 7 Other references
 8 External links

Origins
Within cognitive developmental psychology, the interest in conceptual change was motivated by
problems identified in the stage theory of cognitive development proposed by Jean Piaget.[1][2]
Piaget claimed that the developing child passed through a series of four distinct stages of thought
and that concept development reflected these broad transitions between stages. However, it
increasingly became apparent that children’s conceptual development was best described in
terms of distinct developmental trajectories for each conceptual domain considered (e.g.
knowledge about number, knowledge about the motion and interaction of inanimate objects, and
knowledge about goal-directed intentional entities). The term “conceptual change” was
increasingly used as work on these distinct developmental trajectories led to the discovery that a
variety of types of changes occur in the content and organization of concepts.

In parallel, researchers in science education were learning that one of the main reasons students
often found scientific concepts like force and energy difficult to understand was the intuitive
concepts about the natural world that students brought with them to the classroom.[3][4] It became
clear that students were assimilating the scientific ideas presented to them in the classroom into
their existing concepts, resulting in what came to be referred to as “misconceptions”.
Researchers in science education turned to the task of identifying these pre-instruction ideas and
sought instructional strategies that would succeed in helping student transform their intuitive
concepts into more scientific alternatives.

These developments in cognitive developmental psychology and science education occurred


against a background of (and were influenced by) developments within the history and
philosophy of science. Arguably, most important, was the novel approach to how scientific
concepts and theories change over the course of history put forward by Thomas Kuhn in 1962 in
his landmark book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions[5] In this book, Kuhn argued that
changes in the scientific understanding of the natural world should not be seen as a gradual,
incremental progress toward ever better understanding. He pointed out that it is sometimes very
difficult to characterize how a more recent concept is better than a predecessor. The reason for
the difficulty is that the successive concepts are embedded in a distinct set of relationships with
other concepts and investigative techniques. Thus, the content of the two concepts and
relationships to others can be so different that it is inappropriate to compare the two successor
concepts directly with one another. An important concept to emerge from this reasoning was the
idea of a “paradigm.” Commentators have noted that Kuhn used the term in a number of
different senses. However, one sense seems to have had the most influence on what came to be
referred to as “conceptual change research.” That is, the idea of a “paradigm” understood as an
integrative set of theoretical concepts and methods taken for granted by a particular research
community. According to Kuhn, most of scientists’ work is conducted within a paradigm (what
Kuhn called “normal science”). Occasionally, however, insurmountable problems lead scientists
to question the paradigm’s assumptions, and a new paradigm emerges (what Kuhn called “a
paradigm shift”).

Kuhn’s work, and that of other philosophers and historians of science, had a substantial influence
on cognitive developmental[6] and science education research.[7] Increasingly, children and
students’ concepts were seen as embedded within their own set of relationships with other
concepts and the developmental or learning task came to be seen as a kind of paradigm shift.

Emerging theoretical perspectives and recent developments


The claims about concept and theory change made by philosophers and historians of science
served as a source of hypotheses about conceptual change occurring during child development
and student learning. These initial hypotheses served as the driving force for much theoretical
and empirical research. A number of perspectives on conceptual change have emerged, and
proponents have been engaging in a lively debate since the early 1980s.

One perspective views the process of conceptual change as “theory change”.[8][9][10][11][12][13][14] The
concepts of the child or learner are seen as themselves embedded within intuitive theories that
require substantial restructuring if they are to resemble those of the adult or scientist. This
perspective was the most directly inspired by Kuhn’s work. Indeed, some specific pre-instruction
concepts were seen as resembling some early concepts in the history of science.
A closely related perspective to this theory change view makes a particular claim about the
differences between naïve and scientific concepts. This “ontological shift” view[15][16][17][18]
emphasizes that many naïve concepts are incorrectly assigned to the broad (ontological) category
of material substance rather than to the ontological category of (constraint-based) processes.
Conceptual change, on this view, involves constructing the new ontological category of
constraint-based processes and reassigning the concept to this correct category.

A third view, draws from some of the basic commitments of these first two views but provides a
more dynamic account of the formation of naïve conceptions. This “framework theory” view[19]
[20][21][22]
suggests that when new ideas are encountered basic ontological commitments influence
how new ideas are assimilated. The result is often a model consistent with both the ontological
commitments and aspects of the new ideas presented. However, there is often a distortion of the
new idea in the process. Successful conceptual change on this view requires strategic changes in
the interfering ontological commitments.

Finally, a fourth view adopts a more systemic approach to concepts and how they change. This
“knowledge-in-pieces” or “resources” perspective[23][24][25][26][27] views both naïve and scientific
conceptual understanding as grounded in multiple, small knowledge resources that can be
considered “sub-conceptual.” These are sub-conceptual in that they are of a smaller “grain size”
than meanings associated with words and often can be seen to originate from abstractions from
sensori-motor schemas. Since both naïve and scientific conceptions are grounded in the same
broad pool of sub-conceptual resources, conceptual change is seen as the reorganization of these
resources. The reorganization is seen as involving the gradual increase in the degree of
coherence and consistency in the application of knowledge systems composed of a
heterogeneous collection of resources.

Most conceptual change researchers can be seen as adhering to one or the other of the above four
perspectives. In addition, theoretical accounts of conceptual change have varied on another
dimension – the extent to which the process of change should be seen as a “rational” or purely
“cognitive” process, as opposed to one involving emotional, motivational and socio-cultural
elements. Recently, there has been greater interest in clarifying this distinction and increasingly
greater attempts to create links across this divide.[28][29][30][31][32] Despite the various points of
disagreement, there has been a great deal of consensus around the idea that successful conceptual
change often requires meta-conceptual awareness and sophistication on the part of the learner.

How does conceptual change happen and how can it be


supported?
The way in which conceptual change research has addressed these two related questions
highlights the synergy that has emerged between cognitive developmental psychology, science
education and the history and philosophy of science.

The attempt to understand the psychological processes that lead to conceptual change in the
individual has predominantly been the purview of cognitive developmental psychology.
However, many of the psychological insights have been motivated by proposals in the history
and philosophy of science since Kuhn.[33][34][35][36][37][38] Kuhn’s work emphasized the role of
anomalous data as a drive for change. Moreover, what has come to be called cognitive-historical
analysis, developed by Nancy J. Nersessian, has been very influential. This type of analysis
involves conducting historical cases-studies of important episodes of theoretical change in the
history of science and making use of the analytical tools of cognitive science to provide accounts
of the cognitive processes involved. Such analyses have documented the importance of such
process as analogical reasoning, the use of visual representations, and thought experiment,
collectively referred to as model-based reasoning processes. Thus, the drive to make sense of
anomalous observations that are inconsistent with existing concepts and the various model-based
reasoning processes have been proposed as sources of conceptual change in the developing
individual and learner. Recent cognitive developmental work has also added language to this list.
[39][40]

Most researchers accept the above list of sources of conceptual change (with the exception of
language, which is the most recent addition to this list and perhaps the most controversial). They
differ, however, in their accounts of relative importance of the different sources and the details of
their role in the process of change.

The identification of sources of conceptual change has inspired the design of pedagogical
interventions that aim to promote the development of deep conceptual understanding of
challenging concepts.[41][42][43][44][45][46][47][48][49] Science education research has been able to provide
some documentation about the effectiveness of these interventions. However, more experimental
studies are needed that incorporate careful controls. Moreover, while some extended classroom
based studies exist, more research documenting the applicability and generalizability of
conceptual change based instruction is needed.

The scope of conceptual change research


While much of conceptual research has been geared to scientific concepts, recent work is
increasingly emerging in other domains. Conceptual change is now being examined in
mathematics[50] and history.[51] More research in more domains is needed. This will provide a
basis for insights about similarities and differences in how conceptual change occurs in different
domains.

See also
 Educational psychology
 Pedagogical constructivism
 Learning theory

References
1. Carey, S. (1985). Are children fundamentally different kinds of thinkers and
learners than adults? In S. F. Chipman, J. W. Segal, and R. Glaser (Eds.), Thinking and
learning skills, vol. 2. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
2. Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
3. Driver, R. & Easley, J. (1978). Pupils and paradigms: a review of literature related
to concept development in adolescent science students. Studies in Science Education, 5,
61-84.
4. Novick, S. & Nussbaum, J (1981) Pupils' understanding of the particulate nature
of matter: a cross age study. Science Education, 65, 187-196.
5. Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
6. Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
7. Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A. , Hewson, P. W. , Gertzog, W. A. (1982).
Accommodation of a scientific conception: Toward a theory of conceptual change.
Science Education 66(2), 211-227.
8. Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
9. Carey, S. (1999). Sources of conceptual change. In E. K. Schlonick, K. Nelson, S.
A. Gelman & P. H. Miller (Eds.), Conceptual development: Piaget’s legacy, (pp.293-
326). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
10. McCloskey, M. (1983). Naive theories of motion. In D. Gentner & A. Stevens
(Eds.), Mental models (pp. 75-98). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
11. Smith, C. (2007). Bootstrapping processes in the development of students’
commonsense matter theories: Using analogical mappings, thought experiments, and
learning to measure to promote conceptual restructuring. Cognition and Instruction,
25(4), 337-398.
12. Smith, C., Maclin, D., Grosslight, L., & Davis, H. (1997). Teaching for
understanding: A study of students' preinstruction theories of matter and comparison of
the effectiveness of two approaches to teaching about matter and density. Cognition and
Instruction, 15(3), 317-393.
13. Smith, C., Snir, J., & & Grosslight, L. (1992). Using conceptual models to
facilitate conceptual change: The case of weight-density differentiation. Cognition and
Instruction, 9(3), 221-283.
14. Wiser, M. (1995). Use of history of science to understand and remedy students'
misconceptions about heat and temperature. In D. N. Perkins, J. L. Schwartz, M. M. West
& M. S. Wiske (Eds.), Software goes to school (pp. 23-38). New York: Oxford
University Press.
15. Chi, M. T. H. (2005). Common sense conceptions of emergent processes: Why
some misconceptions are robust. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 14, 161-199.
16. Chi, M. T. H. (1992). Conceptual change within and across ontological
categories: Examples from learning and discovery in science. In R. N. Giere (Ed.),
Cognitive models of science: Vol. 15. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp.
129-186) Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
17. Chi, M. T. H., & Slotta, J. D. (1993). The ontological coherence of intuitive
physics. Cognition and Instruction, 10(2 & 3), 249-260.
18. Slotta, J. D., Chi, M. T., & & Joram, E. (1995). Assessing students’
misclassifications of physics concepts: An ontological basis for conceptual change.
Cognition and Instruction, 13(3), 373-400.
19. Vosniadou, S. (2002). On the nature of naïve physics. In M. Limon & L. Mason
(Eds.), Reconsidering conceptual change: Issues in theory and practice, (pp. 61-76)
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
20. Vosniadou, S., & Brewer, W. F. (1992). Mental models of the earth: A study of
conceptual change in childhood. Cognitive Psychology, 24, 535-585.
21. Vosniadou, S., Vamvakoussi, X. & Skopeliti, I. (2008). The framework theory
approach to the problem of conceptual change. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International
handbook of research on conceptual change. New York, NY: Routledge.
22. Ioannides, C. & Vosniadou, C. (2002). The changing meanings of force.
Cognitive Science Quarterly, 2, 5-61.
23. diSessa, A. A. (1983). Phenomenology and the evolution of intuition. In D.
Gentner & A. L. Stevens (Eds.), Mental models (pp. 15-33). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
24. diSessa, A. A. (1993). Toward an epistemology of physics. Cognition and
Instruction, 10(2 & 3), 105-225.
25. diSessa, A. A., Gillespie, N. M. & Esterly, J. B. (2004). Coherence versus
fragmentation in the development of the concept of force. Cognitive Science, 28, 843-
900.
26. diSessa, A. A. & Wagner, J. E. (2005). What coordination has to say about
transfer. In J. P. Mestre (Ed.), Transfer of learning from a modern multidisciplinary
perspective, (pp. 121-154). Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing.
27. Smith, J. P., diSessa, A. A., & Roschelle, J. (1993). Misconceptions reconceived:
A constructivist analysis of knowledge in transition. The Journal of Learning and
Sciences, 3(2), 115-163.
28. Limόn, M. & Mason, L. (Eds.) (2002). Reconsidering conceptual change: Issues
in theory and practice. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
29. Mason, L. (2007). Introduction: Bridging the cognitive and sociocultural
approaches to research on conceptual change: Is it Feasible? [Special Issue] Educational
Psychologist, 42(1), 1-7.
30. Schnotz, W., Vosniadou, S., & Carretero, M. (Eds.) (1999). New perspectives on
conceptual change. New York, NY: Pergamon.
31. Sinatra, G. & Pintrich, P. R. (Eds.) (2003). Intentional conceptual change.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
32. Vosniadou, S. (2007). The cognitive-situative divide and the problem of
conceptual change. Educational Psychologist, 42(1), 55-66.
33. Giere, Ronald N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
34. Giere, R. N (Ed.) (1992), Cognitive models of science: Vol. 15. Minnesota studies
in the philosophy of science. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
35. Nersessian, N. J. (1992). How do scientists think? Capturing the dynamics of
conceptual change in science. In R. Giere (Ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science (pp. 3-45). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
36. Nersessian, N. J. (1993). In the theoretician’s laboratory: Thought experimenting
as mental modeling. In D. Hull, M. Forbes & K. Okruhlik (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1992
Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2, (pp. 291-301). East
Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.
37. Nersessian, N. J. (2006). The cognitive-cultural systems of the research
laboratory. Organization Studies, 27(1), 125-145.
38. Nersessian, N. J. (2008a). Creating scientific concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
39. Carey, S. (2004). Bootstrapping and the origin of concepts. Daedalus, 133, 59-68.
40. Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
41. Brown, D. H., & Clement, J. (1989). Overcoming misconceptions via analogical
reasoning: Abstract transfer versus explanatory model construction. Instructional Science,
18(4), 237-261.
42. Clement, J. (1993). Using bridging analogies and anchoring intuitions to deal with
students’ preconceptions in physics. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 30(10),
1241-1257.
43. Smith, C. (2007). Bootstrapping processes in the development of students’
commonsense matter theories: Using analogical mappings, thought experiments, and
learning to measure to promote conceptual restructuring. Cognition and Instruction,
25(4), 337-398.
44. Smith, C., Maclin, D., Grosslight, L., & Davis, H. (1997). Teaching for
understanding: A study of students' preinstruction theories of matter and comparison of
the effectiveness of two approaches to teaching about matter and density. Cognition and
Instruction, 15(3), 317-393.
45. Smith, C., Snir, J., & & Grosslight, L. (1992). Using conceptual models to
facilitate conceptual change: The case of weight-density differentiation. Cognition and
Instruction, 9(3), 221-283.
46. White, B. (1995). The Thinkertools project: Computer microworlds as conceptual
tools for facilitating scientific inquiry. In S. M. Glynn, & R. & Duit (Eds.), Learning
science in the schools: Research reforming practice (pp. 201-225). Mahwah, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
47. Wiser, M. (1995). Use of history of science to understand and remedy students'
misconceptions about heat and temperature. In D. N. Perkins, J. L. Schwartz, M. M. West
& M. S. Wiske (Eds.), Software goes to school (pp. 23-38). New York: Oxford
University Press.
48. Wiser, M. & Smith, C. L. (2008). Learning and teaching about matter in grades
K-8: When should the atomic-molecular theory be introduced? In S. Vosniadou (Ed.),
The international handbook of research on conceptual change. New York: Routledge.
49. Zietsman, A., & & Clement, J. (1997). The role of extreme case reasoning in
instruction for conceptual change. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 6(1), 61-89.
50. Vosniadou, S. & Verschaffel, L. (2004). Extending the conceptual change
approach to mathematics learning and teaching. Learning and Instruction, 14, 445-451.
51. Limon, M. (2002). Conceptual change in history. In M. Limon & L. Mason
(Eds.), Reconsidering conceptual change: Issues in theory and practice (pp. 259-289).
Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Other references
 Vosniadou, Stella (2008). International handbook of research on conceptual change.
New York: Routledge. ISBN 0-8058-6044-4.

External links
 Special interest group "Conceptual Change" of the European Association for Research on
Learning and Instruction (EARLI)

Categories:
 Educational psychology
 Learning theory (education)
Navigation menu
 Create account
 Log in

 Article
 Talk

 Read
 Edit
 View history

 Main page
 Contents
 Featured content
 Current events
 Random article
 Donate to Wikipedia
 Wikimedia Shop

Interaction

 Help
 About Wikipedia
 Community portal
 Recent changes
 Contact page

Tools

Print/export

Languages

 Català
 Suomi
 Edit links
 This page was last modified on 18 September 2013 at 02:17.
 Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License;
additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy
Policy.
Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit
organization.

You might also like