You are on page 1of 8

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature

Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie


©

Environmental ethics
Konrad Ott

This article outlines the seven essential types of argument that can be put forward for protecting natural
phenomena or natural resources. This is done against the background of certain ontological assumptions
about nature and wilderness, about the concept of protection itself and with reference to different
theoretical approaches (“paradigms”) in environmental ethics. The seven forms of argumentation outlined
here involve different perspectives on the value of nature: dependence on natural resources, forms of
experience of the good life, future responsibility in respect of nature, the intrinsic moral value of certain
natural phenomena, virtuous attitudes, so-called ecosophical world views and religious approaches. In the
medium of these arguments, a relationship to nature based one-sidedly on control and usage can be
broadened and corrected. This reconstruction of arguments enables all persons interested in environmental
ethics to independently develop a justifiable and well-grounded conception of environmental ethics.

Citation Information and License Notice


Ott, Konrad (2020): Environmental ethics. In: Kirchhoff, Thomas (ed.): Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of
Nature / Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie. ISSN 2629-8821. https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420
This work is published under the Creative Commons Attribution License 4.0 (CC BY-ND 4.0).

1. Introduction Field of study


Environmental or natural ethics is an established field Protection is a value-concept. Protection is to be given
of interdisciplinary-oriented practical philosophy which to what is worthy of protection because of its value or
reconstructs the essential types of argumentation that because, due to specific circumstances, it requires protec-
can be made for protecting natural entities and the tion (Rolston 1988). Protection can be institutionalised
sustainable use of natural resources (Krebs 1999; Bren- in a normative way (e.g. by designating conservation
ner 2008; Ott 2010). The term “environmental ethics” areas). In its argumentation, environmental ethics
has become established, although “ethics of nature” is makes an ontological assumption that natural entities
more factually precise. The term “bioethics” should be (“natural beings”) exist in reality and that the talk of
reserved for the moral topics of the medical life naturalness remains meaningful (Lie 2016), although in
sciences, although there are some overlaps between today’s world many natural beings are mediated with
bioethics and the ethics of nature (e.g. in the field of human forms of practice, i.e. are increasingly humanly
environmental health). The term “ecological ethics”, shaped. The subject area of environmental ethics
which is sometimes used, has the disadvantage of concerns those entities whose origin, existence and life
implying that ethics could be established on the basis processes are not exclusively or primarily owed to
of scientific ecology (Eser/Potthast 1999). This is ruled human action. We call these entities “natural beings”.
out, however, by the so-called naturalistic fallacy For this reason, animal ethics, whose subject area
(Potthast/Ott 2016), which states that normative includes both domesticated and wild animals,
statements cannot be derived from factual claims or especially vertebrates, is an essential part of environ-
laws of nature. Biology and ecology are natural sciences mental ethics. If living creatures are heavily modified
that cannot, for example, justify why species should biotechnologically (e.g. laboratory mice), one can
be protected. Thus in the following the established speak of “biofacts” (Karafyllis 2003). The boundaries
term “environmental ethics” will be retained. between natural beings and biofacts are fluid. The term
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

“environment”, in turn, refers, strictly speaking, to those 7) religious traditions. These categories are not mutu-
environments in which humans or non-human creatures ally exclusive and can therefore appear in different
factually exist. Many people live in artificial environ- variations. It follows that there can be more than one,
ments (libraries, offices, factories, sports halls, under- but not an infinite number of justifiable variations and
ground car parks, etc.). The design of such environments concepts of environmental ethics. As a reflexive disci-
does not fall within the core area of environmental ethics. pline, environmental ethics intends not to prescribe a
specific and binding morality, but rather to enable
“Nature”
persons to adopt these categories critically and
“Nature” is the conceptual title for all natural beings,
discursively, i.e. in exchange with other persons. An
whether living or inanimate. Nature is not the same as
ultimately binding environmental ethics is impossible,
wilderness. Thus talk of an “end of nature” (in the sense
if only for reasons of justification and argumentation,
of McKibben 1989), which rests on an elision of nature
since central problems such as that of inclusion have so
and wilderness, is wrong. The planet still contains many
far been fundamentally disputed and different types
natural beings. In this respect, nature is a scaled con-
of theory of environmental ethics exist alongside one
cept that ranges between the poles of “wilderness” and
another.
“artefact”. Within the concept of wilderness we need
to differentiate between the ideal pole of an absolute Types of environmental ethics
wilderness without any human influence and a relative One can distinguish three types of theory. The “classi-
wilderness in which human influence is demonstrable cal” theory type focuses on the problem of inclusion
but irrelevant to natural events. Absolute wilderness and thus on the question of intrinsic moral values of
may (perhaps) still exist in Antarctica and the deep sea. natural beings, defends a certain solution (see below)
Furthermore, primary wilderness can be distinguished and derives from this a concept of nature conservation
from secondary wilderness, the former being histori- that includes principles, virtues and rules of prece-
cally original, while the latter applies to areas that have dence. A prime example of this type of theory is Paul
historically been used but where human use has ceased Taylor’s Respect for Nature (1986). A second type of
(such as the protected zones of national parks). Relative theory is environmental pragmatism, which takes as
and secondary wildernesses as well as modified natural its starting point human practices in dealing with nature
formations (such as the Lüneburg Heath in Germany) (agriculture and forestry, fishing, hunting, sailing, hiking,
may also be worthy of protection. In the field of gardening, care and maintenance, etc.) and explicates
conservation, frequently used criteria for worthiness of and orders the values involved. This includes the prac-
protection are closeness to nature, rarity, relevance of tice of nature conservation with its various guidelines
location and vulnerability. The classificatory concepts as well as renaturation (Ott 2015b). A prime example of
of conservation (Usher/Erz 1994; Romahn 2003) environmental pragmatism is Bryan Norton’s Sustain-
presuppose the arguments of environmental ethics, ability (2005). A third type of theory is represented by
to which they are linked in terms of justification. the so-called postmodern environmental ethics, which
Kirchhoff et al. (2017) provide discussion of the natural- eludes (or tries to elude) simple characterization. In
philosophical foundations of environmental ethics. these approaches, narratives, literature, pictorial
representations, alternative media approaches to
Views on value (axiology)
nature and a playful treatment of the possibilities
One can assign the various views concerning the value
of staging human-environmental relations all have
of natural beings to seven categories or patterns of
an important role. Prime examples of postmodern
argumentation: 1) arguments from dependence and
environmental ethics are Donna Haraway’s Staying
instrumental values, 2) cultural and eudaimonistic values,
With The Trouble (2016) and Timothy Morton’s Dark
3) responsibility for the future and sustainability,
Ecology (2016). Suggested readings from these various
4) (existential) virtues, 5) intrinsic moral values of certain
theories can be found at the end of this article.
natural beings, 6) new “ecosophical” world views and

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 2


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

2. Arguments from reliance and dependence These values are subdivided into the value of recuperation
in nature, the experience of natural beauty, the familiarity
Arguments from dependence claim that human beings,
of native landscapes, and the value of unifying experi-
as bodily and precarious beings, are dependent on a
ences. Bryan Norton (1987) has argued that experiences
continuous metabolism with an external nature, the
maintenance of which entails a careful use of natural of nature never leave people unchanged but rather have
resources and environmental media. Due to the value a transformative effect on their attitudes and behaviour
of physical health, this metabolism should take place (“transformative values”). These transformative values
with as few pollutants as possible, which is why the input point to the questions of an environmental virtue ethics
of toxins and harmful substances should be minimized (see below). The same applies to the view that nature
is an indispensable “sphere of resonance” for human
(Schäfer 1993). This gives rise to ideas for environmen-
experiences (Rosa 2014).
tally compatible and low-pollution economies. In the
field of pollutants, environmental policy depends on
the setting of limits, which are based on normative 4. Responsibility for the future and sustainability
assumptions such as precaution and the protection of The values of the first two categories (dependence/
people who have suffered damage. Strict precautionary health, enjoyment of nature/transformation values) can
limits (such as for fine particulates) then compete with be translated into an intergenerational perspective. It is
well-established practices (such as private transport). then a matter of the art of thinking long-term in terms
The presupposed value of human health then also leads of nature (Klauer et al. 2013) and of the question of
to the question whether and to what extent visits to what natural resources future generations might have
certain natural settings (forests, coasts, mountains) are legitimate claims on (responsibility for the future). This
beneficial to physical health. The healing effects of question leads to theories and concepts of sustainability
forests and coasts and the health-promoting activities (see Ott/Döring 2011) and thus also to the issues of
of hiking and bathing are no longer questioned, even climate change, agriculture and forestry, renaturation
from a medical point of view. Health-related and ecology and also marine protection, including fisheries.
cultural causes intertwine in social movements as in In one fundamental concept of sustainability that
earlier times, for example in the lifestyle reform attaches great importance to the protection and promo-
movement or the German “Wandervogel” movement tion of natural capital (so-called “strong” sustainability),
(Wolschke-Buhlman 1990; Wedemeyer-Kolwe 2017). nature conservation represents an essential dimension
of sustainability policy (Ott 2015b). Survey articles on
3. Eudaimonistic values specialist areas such as climate protection, restoration,
moorland protection, oceans and fisheries can be found
Arguments from cultural or eudaimonistic values
in Ott et al. 2016.
(“eudaimonia” = good life) claim that experiences of
nature are an essential part of a rich, successful and
meaningful life (Ott 2016). These values are divided into 5. Environmental virtue ethics
different ways of enjoying nature, such as experiences The values and commitments of these first three
of natural aesthetics (Seel 1991), a sense of home in the categories (dependence, eudaimonistic values, sustain-
midst of familiar landscapes (Scruton 2012) and recuper- ability) lead almost inevitably to the question of what
ation in nature. These values are conveyed via nature- kind of person one wants to be in the era of the Anthro-
based practices such as gardening, hiking, sailing, pocene, when one now understands oneself to be a
diving, etc. The phenomenology of nature offers a transient member of a series of generations bound to
philosophical method to articulate the ways and means nature. This question concerns different attitudes to-
of experiencing and enjoying nature (Böhme/Schiemann wards nature, including one’s own biological-embodied
1997). Eudaimonistic values explain why many people nature. Such a line of questioning leads us to the realm
are unwilling to forego contact with nature in their lives. of Environmental Virtue Ethics (Sandler/Cafaro 2005).

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 3


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

Preservation and care, protection, consideration, mod- that combine (strong) biophilia with (weak) biocentrism
eration, but also joyful devotion, affirmation of life to form an existential attitude of protecting and
and gratitude are some of the relevant attitudes. Every promoting living structures (Wetlesen 1999). Thus,
virtue ethic has a pedagogical dimension; environmen- there can be different authentic “environmental
tal virtue ethics is conveyed through the practices of virtues” which are based on religious traditions such
environmental and nature education. Of course, as shamanism, Buddhism, Daoism and paganism.
environmental virtue ethics explores not only virtues
but also vices, which brings with it the danger of
7. Physiocentrism
hectoring today’s lifestyles as “immoral”. Thus, in envi-
The category of intrinsic moral values leads beyond
ronmental virtue ethics, there is sometimes a peculiar
anthropocentrism, if and in so far as it leads to the
craze for ever more extremes of renunciation and for
protection of certain natural beings for their own sake
emulating those who have renounced the most. On the
(so-called physiocentrism). Natural beings are to be
contrary, environmental virtue ethics should also take
protected for their own sake precisely when they are
into account human shortcomings, habits, misguided
accorded a morally relevant quality. Probably the
incentive systems, sophistry and weakness of will,
surest morally relevant characteristic is the ability to
and should not try to force the environmental-ethical
orient one’s own actions to moral standards. In this
perfectionism of humankind with a crowbar, as it
spirit, for Immanuel Kant, only beings that are able
were. Ascetics are themselves the lived paradox of a
to test their maxims for universalizability by means of
deterrent role model.
the Categorical Imperative have dignity (Kant 1785).
These beings are always to be respected for their own
6. Anthropocentrism: sake. Dignity means being able to orientate oneself
protected resources and biophilia with reasons towards rational grounds. It is also possi-
The categories discussed so far are anthropocentric, i.e. ble to ascribe dignity to people who either do not yet
although they are based on a wide-ranging practical- or no longer possess this human-specific ability, as a
rational interest in establishing harmonious relation- derivative of generic solidarity among human beings. In
ships with nature, they only recognize human dignity principle it is ethically wrong to detach Kant’s formula
and rights. In the anthropocentric view, natural beings of humans as ends in themselves from its context of
are stocks of natural capital that are to be managed justification and simply extend it to all living beings
sustainably, or natural assets that are to be protected or anything that exists. The category of dignity cannot
because of their beauty, rarity, recreational value, etc. be applied to natural beings, although this terminology
An understanding of these categories reveals that is often used, for example when talking about
humans need not be imagined as beings greedily and “plant dignity”.
short-sightedly plundering nature. Insofar as they Now there can be more than just one morally relevant
appropriate nature in various cultural and historical property and status category, including those that belong
contexts according to the values mentioned above, to natural beings. Certain characteristics lead not to the
humans ipso facto become nature-bound personalities. status “dignity” but to the status of direct consideration,
As a legacy of co-evolution, human beings may possibly i.e. they function as a criterion for granting or withdrawing
even possess a biophilic inclination structure (Wilson intrinsic moral value (! problem of inclusion) (Ott 2008;
1984), which in modernity has been suppressed or Warren 2000). In physiocentrism, different criteria of
ridiculed (as “romanticism”). It can be a fascinating direct moral consideration are discussed. For example,
experiment with one’s own corporeality and sensuality sentience (sentientism), perceptive awareness (zoo-
to uncover biophilic tendencies in oneself within a centrism), being alive (biocentrism), biocenotic self-
phenomenological setting, for example in the recon- organisation (ecocentrism) or existence (holism) are
struction of archaic embodied experiences (in the claimed as morally relevant characteristics or criteria.
sense of Rappe 1995). Concepts are also available

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 4


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

The concept of interest is also used as a criterion, of interpretation of the modern scientific world view in
whereby a distinction is made between weak and strong a way that does not directly contradict this world view.
interests. A strong interest exists when a natural being To physics, nature shows itself to be objective under laws.
takes an interest in something or “has” this interest. A To a technical world view (Heidegger 1962: “framing”
weak interest exists when something is “in” the interest (Gestell)) it shows itself as a resource. Nature is thus
of a natural being. A lion has an interest, while water is “determined” physically and technologically. In this way
in the interest of a potted plant. other approaches to nature are blocked off. Deep ecol-
An appropriate solution to the inclusion problem ogy wants to remove these blockages. In deep ecology,
could be to combine the characteristics of sentience religious, spiritual and “ecosophical” interpretations
and the ability to communicate into a gradable concept and approaches to nature are regarded as conditions
of openness to a species-specific world (Weltoffenheit) for finding ways out of the environmental crisis of
(Ott 2015a), followed by a complex casuistry that modernity. Ethically, deep ecology, as Næss understood
ranges from chimpanzees and whales to dragonflies it, is closest to virtue ethics. Since Næss (due to his phil-
and spiders, for some even to plants. The decisive osophical education in the empirico-logically oriented
factor in this characteristic of world-openness is that a “Viennese Circle”) believed that moral demands and
natural being, due to its organic endowment (brain, imperatives are ultimately commands, he developed
nerve cells), perceives something of its environment, his environmental ethics by setting a limit to the Kantian
feels its own joy and pain and can communicate with doctrine of duty, namely the “beautiful soul” which
others through sounds or physical signals (such as bees does what duty demands of it out of inclination. Followers
through their “dances”). This solution excludes every- of deep ecology need duties and imperatives only as
thing inorganic, genes, viruses and – depending on provisional guidelines; they act “correctly” out of joy
empirical findings – also large groups of organisms and generosity. Nothing is “more beautiful” for them
(phyto- and zooplankton, bacteria, fungi and plants) than to live in harmony with nature and to identify
from the moral community. However, within the newer themselves with natural beings (Næss: “widening iden-
plant physiology and ecology it is controversial which tification”). In deep ecology, the problem of inclusion is
terms should be used to describe the complex behav- solved by means of physiocentrism, without the need
iour of plants (for example biochemical information for rational justification, so it is believed. The intrinsic
transfer is sometimes viewed as “communication”). value of nature is self-evident for deep ecologists, and
On plant ethics see Kallhoff (2002). requires no rational justification.

8. Ecological world views 9. Religious traditions


Finally, in ecological world views such as Arne Næss’ The religions are also traditions that deal with nature and
deep ecology (Næss 1989), environmental ethics is not have been questioned as to their positions on secular
axiologically or morally, but ontologically founded environmental ethics (see contributions in Jenkins et al.
(Hendlin 2016). Among these approaches is Klaus 2017). As far as the Judeo-Christian tradition is concerned
Michael Meyer-Abich’s metaphysical holism, which is (see Link 1991; Neumann-Gorsolke 2004), the allegedly
based on the philosophy of Nicholas of Cusa (Meyer- “hard” mandate of subjugation in the clerical creation
Abich 1997). It is usually assumed that nature (“physis”) story has been contrasted with the allegedly “soft”
can reveal itself to different people in different places mandate to “cultivate and take care of” the Garden of
in different ways. What Heidegger (1976) terms “clear- Eden (Gen 2:15). However, this reading misinterprets
ing” (lichten) and the modern interpretations of nature both creation narratives. A re-reading of the six-day
as value-free objectivity (physicalism) and usable creation, which culminates in the Sabbath, provides a
resources (economics) are only two of many possible condensed reminder that the human being, in receiving
interpretations. Deep ecology thus denies the monopoly God’s blessing to procreate, is given a symbolic mandate

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 5


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

to act responsibly “coram Deo” (“living in the presence the diagnoses of a global crisis of nature can no longer
of God”) in the midst of a magnificent creation (see be ignored. As a diagnostic title for our epoch, the
Hardmeier/Ott 2015). A climax of this creation narra- geo-logical expression “Anthropocene” is apt (cf. Ehlers/
tive is the exclamatory “hinne”: “Yes, just look”, with Krafft 2006). Many people, including the younger
which the eyes of the mandated are directed to the generation, experience the present time as the inter-
splendour of nature (as creation). In the context of a twining of life- and world-time, in which much is at
post-secular translation, as Jürgen Habermas (2005) stake. Will humanity be able to rapidly halt or at
has proposed, religious persons can explain to their least limit climate change, the loss of biodiversity, the
secular and agnostic fellow citizens why it makes good loss of fertile soil and the clearing of primary forests,
sense for them to live “coram Deo” “etsi Deus non dare- the acidification and littering of the oceans, the expan-
tur” (“even/as if God did not exist”). These explanations sion of urban structures and also the growth of the
cannot, of course, serve as rational proofs. human population? Will concepts of sustainability
gain acceptance, or will authoritarian or free-market
political styles, for which environmental issues are
10. Conclusion
secondary, prevail?
All in all, thanks to its various strands of argumentation,
environmental ethics is able to correct or expand an In this light it is not decisive whether the Anthropo-
understanding of nature that is primarily interested in cene has its origins in 1950, 1750, 1550 or already in
mastering and exploiting. An in-depth understanding of the Neolithic (according to Scott 2017). What is
the various arguments makes it possible for any reason- decisive is whether environmental ethics can take the
able person to acquire his or her own conception of key step from mere morality (Kant) to actual ethical
environmental ethics by orienting himself or herself with life (Hegel) in the fully-fledged Anthropocene. Ethical
reasons towards rational grounds. These conceptions life encompasses culture, law, economy and politics,
can then be classified into overarching philosophical so that environmental ethics cannot take this
currents and theories. Through this classification, a step alone. By itself, it is condemned to remain in the
content-related conception gets a philosophical profile. medium of reflection and analysis of the lines of
A conception strongly oriented towards the practice of argumentation and categories presented. It has no
argumentation is assigned to a discourse theory of power except the unforced force of good reasons.
practical reason (“discourse ethics”). Environmental Although environmental ethics has the transcendental
pragmatism (Norton 2005) exists within the wider will to become the shape of objective spirit (in Hegel’s
tradition of pragmatism (cf. Schneider 1963, Chapters sense) in the Anthropocene, this transcendental will
VIII and IX), in so far as it takes its starting point in must become socio-political reality. In this sense the
human forms of practice in dealing with nature and aims, future of environmental ethics does not lie with it
in a reforming way, to make these forms of practice alone.
more compatible with nature. A coalition of discourse
ethics and pragmatism could prove to be a philosophi- Basic literature
cally robust and sustainable basis for environmental
Elliot, Robert (ed.) 1995: Environmental Ethics. Oxford,
ethics. Oxford University Press.
Environmental ethics is not bound to a specific Krebs, Angelika (ed.) 1999: Ethics of Nature. A Map.
Berlin/New York, de Gruyter.
historical epoch, since the question of successful and
Ott, Konrad 2010: Umweltethik zur Einführung.
good human-nature relationships is at least as old as Hamburg, Junius.
philosophy itself. A comprehensive overview can Ott, Konrad/Dierks, Jan/Voget-Kleschin, Lieske (eds)
be found in Clarence J. Glacken (1967). Nevertheless, it 2016: Handbuch Umweltethik. Stuttgart, Metzler.
is not surprising that environmental ethics as an Vogt, Markus/Ostheimer, Jochen/Uekötter, Frank (eds)
2013: Wo steht die Umweltethik? Argumentations-
academic discipline has emerged in an epoch in which muster im Wandel. Marburg, Metropolis.

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 6


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

Literature
Böhme, Gernot/Schiemann, Gregor (eds) 1997: Phäno- Naturphilosophie. Ein Lehr- und Studienbuch.
menologie der Natur. Frankfurt/M., Suhrkamp. Tübingen, UTB/Mohr Siebeck.
Brenner, Andreas 2008: UmweltEthik. Ein Lehr- und Klauer, Bernd/Manstetten, Reiner/Petersen, Thomas/Schil-
Lesebuch. Fribourg, Paulus. ler, Johannes 2013: Die Kunst langfristig zu denken.
Ehlers, Eckardt/Krafft, Thomas (eds) 2006: Earth System Wege zur Nachhaltigkeit. Baden-Baden, Nomos.
Science in the Anthropocene. Berlin/Heidelberg, Krebs, Angelika (ed.) 1999: Ethics of Nature. A Map.
Springer. Berlin/New York, deGruyter.
Elliot, Robert (ed.) 1995: Environmental Ethics. Oxford, Link, Christian 1991: Schöpfung. Schöpfungstheologie
Oxford University Press. angesichts der Herausforderungen des 20. Jahrhun-
Eser, Uta/Potthast, Thomas 1999: Naturschutzethik. derts. Gütersloh, Mohn.
Eine Einführung für die Praxis. Baden-Baden, Nomos. Lie, Svein Anders Noer 2016: Philosophy of Nature.
Glacken, Clarence 1967: Traces on the Rhodian Shore. Rethinking Naturalness. New York, Routledge.
Nature and Culture in Western Thought from McKibben, Bill 1989: The End of Nature. New York, Anchor.
Ancient Times to the End of the Eighteenth Century. Meyer-Abich, Klaus Michael 1997: Praktische Natur-
Berkeley, University of California Press. philosophie. Erinnerung an einen vergessenen Traum.
Habermas, Jürgen 2005: Religion in der Öffentlichkeit. München, Hanser.
In: Habermas, Jürgen: Zwischen Naturalismus und Morton, Timothy 2016: Dark Ecology. For a Logic of Future
Religion. Frankfurt/M., Suhrkamp: 119–154. Coexistence. New York, Columbia University Press.
Haraway, Donna 2016: Staying with the Trouble. Næss, Arne 1989: Ecology, Community and Lifestyle.
Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Durham, Duke Outline of an Ecosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press. University Press.
Hardmeier, Christof/Ott, Konrad 2015: Naturethik und Neumann-Gorsolke, Ute 2004: Herrschen in den Grenzen
biblische Schöpfungserzählung. Ein diskurs-theoreti- der Schöpfung. Ein Beitrag zur alttestamentlichen
scher und narrativ-hermeneutischer Brückenschlag. Anthropologie am Beispiel von Psalm 8, Genesis 1 und
Stuttgart, Kohlhammer. verwandten Texten. Neukirchen-Vluyn, Neukirchener.
Heidegger, Martin 1962: Die Technik und die Kehre. Norton, Bryan G. 1987: Why Preserve Natural Variety?
Neske, Pfullingen. Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Heidegger, Martin 1976: Vom Wesen der Wahrheit. Norton, Bryan G. 2005: Sustainability. A Philosophy of
Frankfurt/M., Klostermann. Adaptive Ecosystem Management. Chicago, Chicago
Hendlin, Yogi H. 2016: Tiefenökologie. In: Ott, Konrad/ University Press.
Dierks, Jan/Voget-Kleschin, Lieske (eds): Handbuch Ott, Konrad 2008: A modest proposal about how to
Umweltethik. Stuttgart, Metzler: 195–202. proceed in order to solve the problem of inherent
Jenkins, Willis/Tucker, Mary E./Grim, John (eds) 2017: moral value in nature. In: Westra, Laura/Bosselmann,
Routledge Handbook of Religion and Ecology. New Klaus/Westra, Richard (eds): Reconciling Human
York, Routledge. Existence with Ecological Integrity. London/Sterling,
Kallhoff, Angela 2002: Prinzipien der Pflanzenethik. Earthscan: 39–60.
Die Bewertung pflanzlichen Lebens in Biologie und Ott, Konrad 2010: Umweltethik zur Einführung. Ham-
Philosophie. Frankfurt/M., Campus. burg, Junius.
Kant, Immanuel [1785] 2000: Grundlegung zur Meta- Ott, Konrad 2015a: Kommunikation, Sprache und das
physik der Sitten. In: Immanuel Kant. Werkausgabe Inklusionsproblem der Umweltethik. Zeitschrift für
in 12 Bänden, Band VII: Kritik der praktischen Semiotik 37 (3–4): 151–169.
Vernunft. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. Ott, Konrad 2015b: Zur Dimension des Naturschutzes
Herausgegeben von Wilhelm Weischedel. Frank- in einer Theorie starker Nachhaltigkeit. Marburg:
furt/M., Suhrkamp: 7–102. Metropolis.
Karafyllis, Nicole C. (ed.) 2003: Biofakte. Versuch über Ott, Konrad 2016: On the meaning of eudemonic argu-
den Menschen zwischen Artefakt und Lebewesen. ments for a deep anthropocentric environmental
Paderborn, Mentis. ethics. New German Critique 43 (2): 105–126.
Kirchhoff, Thomas/Karafyllis, Nicole C./Evers, Dirk/Falken- https://doi.org/10.1215/0094033X-3511895.
burg, Brigitte/Gerhard, Myriam/Hartung, Gerald/Hüb- Ott, Konrad/Döring, Ralf 32011: Theorie und Praxis
ner, Jürgen/Köchy, Kristian/Krohs, Ulrich/Potthast, starker Nachhaltigkeit. Marburg, Metropolis.
Thomas/Schäfer, Otto/Schiemann, Gregor/Schlette, Ott, Konrad/Dierks, Jan/Voget-Kleschin, Lieske (eds)
Magnus/Schulz, Reinhard/Vogelsang, Frank (eds) 2017: 2016: Handbuch Umweltethik. Stuttgart, Metzler.

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 7


Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie
Konrad Ott | Environmental ethics | 2020 | https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.71420

Potthast, Thomas/Ott, Konrad 2016: Naturalistischer Scruton, Roger 2012: Green Philosophy. How to Think
Fehlschluss. In: Ott, Konrad, Dierks, Jan, Voget- Seriously About the Planet. London, Atlantic.
Kleschin, Lieske (eds): Handbuch Umweltethik. Seel, Martin 1991: Eine Ästhetik der Natur. Frankfurt/M.,
Stuttgart, Metzler: 55–60. Suhrkamp.
Rappe, Guido 1995: Archaische Leiberfahrung. Der Leib Taylor, Paul W. 1986: Respect for Nature. A Theory of
in der frühgriechischen Philosophie und in außer- Environmental Ethics. Princeton, Princeton Univer-
europäischen Kulturen. Berlin, Akademie. sity Press.
Rolston, Holmes, III 1988: Environmental Ethics. Duties Usher, Michael/Erz, Wolfgang (eds) 1994: Erfassen und
to and Values in The Natural World. Philadelphia, Bewerten im Naturschutz. Heidelberg, Quelle &
Temple University Press. Meyer.
Romahn, Katrin S. 2003: Rationalität von Werturteilen Vogt, Markus/Ostheimer, Jochen/Uekötter, Frank (eds)
im Naturschutz. Frankfurt/M., Lang. 2013: Wo steht die Umweltethik? Argumentations-
Rosa, Hartmut 2014: Die Natur als Resonanzraum und muster im Wandel. Marburg, Metropolis.
als Quelle starker Wertungen. In: Hartung, Gerald/ Warren, Mary Anne 2000: Moral Status. Obligations to
Kirchhoff, Thomas (eds): Welche Natur brauchen wir? Persons and Other Living Things. Oxford, Clarendon
Analyse einer anthropologischen Grundproblematik Press.
des 21. Jahrhunderts. Freiburg, Alber: 123–141. Wedemeyer-Kolwe, Bernd 2017: Aufbruch. Die Lebens-
Sandler, Ronald/Cafaro, Philip (eds) 2005: Environmental reform in Deutschland. Darmstadt, WBG/von Zabern.
Virtue Ethics. Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield. Wetlesen, Jon 1999: The moral status of beings who are
Schäfer, Lothar 1993: Das Bacon-Projekt. Von der not persons. A casuistic argument. Environmental
Erkenntnis, Nutzung und Schonung der Natur. Values 8 (3): 287–323.
Frankfurt/M., Suhrkamp. Wilson, Edward O. 1984: Biophilia. The Human Bond
Schneider, Herbert W. 1963: A History of American with Other Species. Cambridge, Cambridge Univer-
Philosophy. 2. Edition. New York/London, Columbia sity Press.
University Press. Wolschke-Bulmahn, Joachim 1990: Auf der Suche nach
Scott, James C. 2017: Against the Grain. A Deep History Arkadien. Zu Landschaftsidealen und Formen der
of the Earliest States. New Haven/London, Yale Uni- Naturaneignung in der Jugendbewegung und ihrer
versity Press. Bedeutung für die Landespflege. München, Minerva.

Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 8

You might also like