You are on page 1of 6

Books Forum

Stengers on emergence Lagrange, Carnot, Hamilton, Duhem, Poincaré, and


de Donder among them. Second, Stengers writes
as someone personally invested in this history, since
Isabelle Stengers she worked as a close associate of Ilya Prigogine, the
Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota celebrated Russian-born Belgian chemist. Despite
Press, 299 pp., US$25, £18.50, receiving a Nobel Prize in 1977, Prigogine ended his
ISBN: 9780816656868; 9780816656875 career as a somewhat marginalized figure, accused of
‘delusions of grandeur’ for reasons described in
Reviewed by Graham Harman haunting fashion by Stengers herself.1
American University, Cairo, Egypt. What will become of Stengers’ detailed history of
E-mail: gharman@aucegypt.edu dynamics among her philosophically minded readers?
Gilles Deleuze launched an unexpected fashion for the
Stoics and Duns Scotus, to name just two of his
BioSocieties (2014) 9, 99–104.
‘minor’ favorites. Alain Badiou has spurred a genera-
doi:10.1057/biosoc.2013.43 tion of young readers to learn set theory and idolize
the madman-genius Cantor. Will Stengers’ Cosmopo-
litics provoke a comparable wave of enthusiasm for
Cosmopolitics, the major work of Belgian philosopher the history of dynamics? Or will it remain an intri-
Isabelle Stengers, has been available in English since guing dark horse of a book, left by the wayside as
2011 in a lucid two-volume translation by Robert different paths are followed? As Stengers demon-
Bononno. In the Anglophone world Stengers is strates in her approach to the history of physics, there
already known as a formidable interpreter of Alfred is no way to predict which human works will become
North Whitehead, a thinker she has done so much to events that produce a tangible line of heirs. Just as
disseminate in the French-speaking world (Stengers, Prigogine’s scientific breakthrough in 1972 could
2011). But in the present work we encounter Stengers’ have rewritten the history of physics,2 Stengers’
own philosophical voice even more directly. Origin- lengthy treatise could lead to a new style of continen-
ally published in the 1990’s in seven slim French tal philosophy: steeped in Deleuze and Whitehead,
volumes, Cosmopolitics should be regarded as one of while closely tracking the shift from Lagrangians to
the most unique works of continental philosophy in Hamiltonians to Niels Bohr’s model of the atom.
the past several decades. While this may sound unlikely in view of the meager
For many years, continental philosophy was past relations between science and continental philo-
attacked for its focus on purely literary and social sophy, who would have expected Cantor to become a
science texts, far from the stunningly successful labors favorite of young French philosophers? It is at least
of the natural sciences. Cosmopolitics is one of several conceivable that Stengers has opened a door that
prominent recent works that have begun to reverse other talented thinkers will enter, and this gives
this trend. Karen Barad’s Meeting the Universe Cosmopolitics the refreshing air of a possible future,
Halfway also comes to mind (Barad, 2007), as does no matter what eventually becomes of the book.
Manuel DeLanda’s Intensive Science and Virtual What must now be asked is whether the elegance
Philosophy (DeLanda, 2002), along with several and historical thoroughness of Cosmopolitics go
books on neuroplasticity by Cathérine Malabou hand-in-hand with a compelling philosophical posi-
(2008). All of these works have had considerable tion. In her remarkably calm and even-tempered
influence, and they may look in retrospect like a book, Stengers nonetheless shows considerable impa-
collective turning point. Yet Cosmopolitics differs tience with philosophers of the old style, who brand-
from the others in at least two respects. First, Stengers ish their arrogant certainties about how the world
gives us a long historical narrative filled with a roster really is. She argues instead for what she calls an
of heroes barely familiar to her philosophy readership: “ecology of practices.” Yet this ecological program

Graham Harman is Distinguished University Professor at the American University in Cairo. He is the author of numerous books,
most recently Bells and Whistles: More Speculative Realism (2013).

1 For Stengers’ treatment of Prigogine see Cosmopolitics II, Chapter V, Life and Artifice, pp. 105–204. For a
more detailed earlier collaboration between the two, (see Prigogine and Stengers, 1984).
2 Stengers makes this claim about Prigogine in Cosmopolitics II, p. 151.

© 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109 99


Books Forum

turns out to be an ontology in its own right, as open to posits discrete individuals hiding behind their tangible
counter-argument as any other. To zero in on Sten- manifestations. Or we might play the double game of
gers’ ontology, I will focus on her concept of emer- doing both at once, duomining the world by appealing
gence. This is both a central philosophical theme of sometimes to ultimate particles or indeterminate flux as
Cosmpolitics and a topic where she differentiates her the bedrock of reality, and other times to an uppermost
views equally from the ‘reductionists’ and the ‘holists,’ layer of the visible, the evental, or the determinate that
who are presented as sharing the same basic flaw. float without a bedrock.6 What is lost through this two-
Though it may seem difficult to extract isolated faced process is the middle kingdom: the robust reality
themes from such a densely interwoven work, the of specific things that are more than the inner relations
brief format of the present review requires that we of their parts, but less than their outer relations with
make the attempt. Ignoring for now her critique of the their environment. Object-oriented philosophy insists
notion of physical ‘states,’ and her important passing on the rights of the middle kingdom, with objects
salute to Gilbert Simondon’s dismissal of fully protected from reduction in two directions rather than
formed individuals, we can find the core of Stengers’ just one. From an object-oriented standpoint, how does
concept of emergence in Chapters 13 and 14 of Stengers look when it comes to the question of emer-
Cosmopolitics II. These chapters are entitled “The gence? Is she an underminer, an overminer, a duominer,
Question of Emergence” and “The Practices of Emer- or an ally? Or does she somehow escape all of these
gence,”3 and together total just under thirty pages. categories, which through her act of escape would be
Before considering Stengers’ own views, we should exposed as artificial or at least non-exhaustive? What-
place the question of emergence in philosophical con- ever the answer, this will not be an exercise in name-
text. How does something new emerge irreversibly calling or empty labelling. Each of the terms just
from the old? This was a central concern of Henri mentioned (undermining, overmining, duomining,
Bergson a century ago, and Francophone thought since object-oriented) has a precise meaning and definite
the 1960’s has often been nearly obsessed with the philosophical consequences.
question of the new.4 Beyond this theme of the new Stengers is aware that the problem of emergence has
arising from the old, emergence can also be framed as ancient metaphysical roots: “Aristotle’s disciples were
the question of how the large emerges from the small or already arguing about composite bodies endowed
the more composite from the more simple. If this never with new qualities that arose from the elements that
happens, if mid-sized entities are always mere aggre- composed them. How could these new qualitative
gates of tinier authentic things, then we are left with properties be explained?” (p. 208) The standard
a reductionist or even eliminativist approach to the reductive approach is exemplified by today’s most
world in which a privileged ultimate layer is treated as zealous materialists, who “signal a future in which,
the sole authentic reality. Thinking would thereby from psychology to the social sciences and therapeutic
become a permanent exercise is undermining: debunk- practices, all forms of knowledge concerning human
ing illusory macroscopic beings in favor of underlying behavior will be understood in terms of neuronal
subcomponents or perhaps even a barely articulate, interactions.” (p. 209) Such materialists, of course,
gelatinous mass (See Harman, 2011). Particle physics do not even treat neurons as the fundamental basis
would become the chosen discipline of the gods; all of the world, since they too can be explained through
others would have to accept a subordinate local status, the workings of even tinier constituents. Neurons
ruled by the ultimate primacy of physics.5 for them are simply a convenient, provisional, local
Yet we must also beware of a kind of reduction that supply base for reductive explanations of the human
moves upwards rather than downwards – namely, the realm. Undermining is treated as the very business of
kind that I have called overmining. Instead of dissol- thought, the sole legitimate method for assaulting all
ving a thing into its constituents, we might dissolve that is supposedly mysterious.
it upward into appearances, effects, manifestations, All resistance to such undermining must hold that
or events, while mocking the ‘naïve realism’ that something new emerges at levels higher than the

3 Stengers, Cosmopolitics II, pp. 207–233.


4 For an intriguing account of this phenomenon, see the treatment of Badiou and structuralism in Bryant
(2011), p. 243 ff.
5 I have criticized this tendency in the work of James Ladyman and Ross, among others. See Harman (2010).
6 I borrow the term ‘duomining’ from the credit card industry, where it refers to the simultaneous use of data
and text mining. See Harman (2013).

100 © 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109


Books Forum

physically ultimate. This approach need not come appeal to finality proves to be a bad move for the anti-
from outside the sciences. Stengers notes that the mechanists, since Darwinian natural selection allows
anti-mechanistic chemists of the eighteenth century Richard Dawkins to replace the purposeful time-
“claimed there was a difference between composition, keeper with the “blind watchmaker” whose living
which was their problem, and the simple aggregation creatures have no internal finality, but simply survive
of physicists” (p. 209). The quarrel between reduction or fail to survive in the environment they happen to
and anti-reduction thus became a disciplinary dispute confront. (p. 210) By the same token, it allows Jacques
between physicists and chemists. Here the chemists Monod to dismiss final causes and say that living
are joined by Leibniz, one of Aristotle’s greatest creatures are merely “teleonomic,” meaning that we
heirs, who “pointed out the foolishness of those who can describe them on the basis of their aim of self-
dreamed of explaining sensation, perception, and reproduction, but without metaphysical commitment
consciousness in terms of inert matter,” and in doing to an actual finality inherent in these beings them-
so “he seems to have been taking part in a quarrel that selves. (p. 210)
continues today with the unfortunately celebrated And here we encounter Stengers’ impatience with
mind-body problem.” (p. 208) Of course, there are both the reductionist and vitalist sides of the dispute.
several different intellectual camps that might view Locked in mutual polemic, each adopts self-defeating
the celebration of the mind-body problem as ‘unfor- strategies that open up vulnerable paths to their
tunate.’ One of these camps is that of the hardcore mortal enemy. “What I want to emphasize here is
materialists mentioned in the previous paragraph. For that understanding the challenge to which the living
them there is no mind-body problem simply because being exposes the biologist is barred to the vitalist
body is destined to win; mind will eventually cave in biologist just as it is to the believer in neo-Darwinism.
to advancing physical explanations of the brain. For In both cases, the polemical position is expressed by
a hardcore idealist such as Berkeley, by contrast, the production of an identity that is substituted for
there can be no mind-body problem because mind practical requirements and obligations the way a
has already won; to be is to be perceived, and there is solution is substituted for a problem.” (p. 211) In
no autonomous ‘body’ outside the configurations it other words, the neo-Darwinist defends inert mechan-
displays for some human or divine mind. Against ical matter and the vitalist defends non-mechanistic
these two options, seekers in the realm of the mind- purposes, but these are both ‘identities’ that ought to
body problem at least mark a place of uncertainty, give way to ‘practical requirements and obligations.’
a temporary bastion against quick reductions in either This is the pragmatist gist of Stengers’ call for an
direction. Given that Stengers views this bastion as “ecology of practices”: disputes over the nature of
‘unfortunate’ (as I do, but for very different reasons) reality are pointless polemics that ought to be
we will need to see how she hopes to outflank all three re-inscribed in the practical soil that enables the two
positions simultaneously. opposite positions in the first place. We are led not to
A point of especial interest in Stengers’ story is the an ambiguous real world in which everything is both
changing status of clocks, one of the most useful and mechanistic and purposive, but to an ultimate human
earliest-perfected machines of the modern era. “The practical context in which things are neither mechan-
clock is a weapon against Aristotelian thought, for istic nor purposive, apart from the ‘requirements and
which matter is unintelligible as such but requires a obligations’ following from how the problem is posed
form, with which are associated both the existence of at any given time.
individual beings, each of which is endowed with its Stengers cites the cases of Pasteur demonstrating the
own end, and the possibility of knowing them.” autonomy of the microorganism, Körner displaying
(p. 210) However, “in the case of the clock, matter the hexagonal structure of benzene, and Nirenberg
and finality can be understood separately: consisting using an artificial DNA molecule to synthesize a
of inert parts, and as such subject to the laws of protein. (p. 213) Stengers’ ontological conclusions
mechanics, it owes its clocklike existence to the genius about these events might be called ‘deflationary,’ since
of the maker, who has subjected those parts to their they neither add real autonomous microorganisms,
own ends, who has incorporated them into a coherent benzene molecules, and proteins to the world, nor do
mechanism defined by a finality – telling time.” they shatter these things reductively into tinier com-
(p. 210) The question of emergence is thereby con- ponents. As she puts it, “events of this kind mark the
flated with the question of purpose or final causation: creation of new laboratory beings and the new
“The question of finality designates the stronghold laboratories that correspond to them. But they do not
that must be defended or conquered.” (p. 210) This pose the problem of emergence and do not allow any

© 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109 101


Books Forum

reduction to occur. They mark the success of an from the point of view of something else.” (p. 219)
operation of delegation.” (p. 213) The understated This gives ammunition to her claim that the identities
tone of the passage cannot mask its radical philoso- of whole and part must be determined in terms of “the
phical claim. For it is not just that Pasteur, Körner, and practices that allowed those identities to be defined.”
Nirnberg happened not to brush against the philoso- (p. 220) In the case of water, for instance, we can
phical question of reduction and emergence. Instead, actually speak of two waters: “one of its identities
for Stengers, reduction and emergence are not legit- corresponds to the chemist’s purpose in understanding
imate philosophical problems at all. They are pseudo- it as a molecule that will interact with other molecules;
problems that ought to be replaced by the true the other corresponds to the purpose of understanding
problem of how successful and unsuccessful ‘delega- it as a solvent that is a liquid.” (p. 220; emphasis
tions’ are made. Instead of disputing over the criteria added) The purposes of the understanding are always
for what would or would not count as an ‘emergent’ what is central, hence my added italics in the passage.
being immune to mechanistic reduction, “it is much But even more surprising is Stengers’ brazen rewriting
more interesting to point out how the operations of of “emergence” so that it dwells within the under-
experimental delegation that have treated bacteria standing itself. As she puts it, “ ‘water’ had to emerge
as targets or actors have been possible.” (p. 213) Is twice: as a molecule composed of ‘parts’ and as a liquid
Stengers’ theory of delegation simply ‘much more with specific properties, composed of molecules.”
interesting’ than ontological disputes over emergence, (p. 220) The scare-quotes around ‘water’ and ‘parts’
or are there more convincing grounds for dissolving in this passage should not distract us from what is
those disputes into her own pragmatic theory? I for happening to the non-scare-quoted “emergence.” For
one do not share her lack of ‘interest’ in emergence, Stengers, the term “emergence” no longer pertains
nor can I accept the concluding lesson of her Section to levels of reality where something new happens
13: “all the confrontations that serve as ecology in the independently of our understanding; instead, it is
modern sciences converge around the question of produced by that very understanding.
emergence. Therefore, it is from this field of battle It certainly looks as though Stengers is simply
that we must escape… a practical, constructivist sense replacing the part/whole dualism of classical disputes
must be given to the issues covered by [the term over emergence with a new and unimproved twofold
‘emergence’].” (p. 218; emphasis added) in which a non-articulate or semi-articulate world
We can now move to Stengers’ attempted coup de is confronted by human scientists whose practical
grâce in Section 14. “It is not often,” she reports, purposes serve to cut the world into neatly defined
“that I have the opportunity to speak well of the work sections for the first time.8 Here, Stengers might
of philosophers of science.” (p. 219) Yet she now sees answer that she does not advocate a two-leveled
opportunity for praise when referring to the three- theory of emergence, but something more like
tiered model of emergence proclaimed by J.K. Feible- Feibleman’s three-leveled model. Let’s consider how
man. Though he starts with “a conventional definition such a model might operate in the framework of
of emergence, which associates the relation between Comsopolitics.
a whole and its parts to the relation between ends Stengers briefly develops her own three-level
and means,” (p. 219) he seems to add an extra layer approach with the example of chemical elements.
to the problem. In Feibleman’s own words: “For an “Ever since Mendeleev,” she recounts, “the element
organization at any given level, its mechanism lies at has been a part of the chemical definition of molecules
the level below, and its purpose at the level above. and reactions, but it presents no problem for emer-
This law states that for the analysis of any organiza- gence.” (p. 220) From there, Stengers goes on to
tion three levels are required: its own, the one below, describe an asymmetry between elements/molecules
and the one above.”7 For Stengers, the value of this on the one hand and atoms on the other; I will treat
model lies in its implication that “the purpose of an ‘elements/molecules’ as a pair only because Stengers
organization is not found in itself but is always seen does not distinguish between them in this passage. As

7 Stengers is quoting here from page 61 of Feibleman (1954).


8 The ‘human scientists’ part is slightly unfair, of course, since Stengers like Latour tries to reinterpret words such
as ‘negotiate’ in non-anthropocentric terms (see her remarks on the body’s twofold treatment of water in
Cosmopolitics II, p. 221). But the same ontological problems occur even if we allow non-humans to join
humans in using their own purposes to carve a largely inarticulate world into pieces. See my remarks about how
a global ‘relationism’ is only marginally better than a human-centered ‘correlationism’ in Harman (2009).

102 © 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109


Books Forum

concerns elements/ molecules: “The chemical element, knows even better than the chemical layman) can
like matter in the Aristotelian sense, has no properties be analyzed downward into quarks and electrons
that could be used to define it ‘in itself.’ Its defini- just as easily as molecules can be analyzed into
tion entails the definitions of simple and compound atoms. What she evidently means is that, given
bodies and their reactions.” (p. 220) We will discuss our momentary interest in the element/molecule
this again shortly. But the case of the atom is appar- as a chemical agent, and given the sub-chemical
ently quite different: “On the other hand, the atom status of atoms, we can treat atoms for the
claims to explain the molecule the way the part moment as explanatory agents or ‘black boxes’
explains the whole. It owes its scientific existence to lacking internal articulations of their own. Cer-
practices of a very different kind, which do not tainly, we could always change our question and
address it as a chemical actor; therefore it can, focus on the composition of atoms instead. But
unlike the element, claim a separable identity.” the ‘practices’ relevant to our current question
(p. 220) Along with elements/molecules and atoms, allows us to treat the atom (for now) as an
we also find the anticipated third level: “element and explainer that does not need to be explained in
atom came to designate the same being only after turn.
a series of complicated negotiations in which data 3. Finally, we must consider the element/molecule
from various practices had been articulated and at the level above it. For Stengers (there is no
coadapted. And in this process of negotiation, evidence that Feibleman would see it this way) this
the ‘purpose’ is found ‘above,’ on the level of the third level is the most important, since it is not just
practice of negotiation itself.” (p. 220) one among equals, but governs the very production
Though Stengers does not do all the work for us of of the difference between the other two. For as we
mapping her threefold schema onto Feibleman’s triad, saw, “element and atom came to designate the same
it is not difficult to see how she proposes to do so. being only after a series of complicated negotiations
Stengers’ Feiblemanian analysis runs as follows: in which data from various practices had been
articulated and coadapted. And in this process of
1. We must consider the element/molecule on its own negotiation, the ‘purpose’ is found ‘above,’ on the
level. According to Stengers, this level is reminiscent level of the practice of negotiation itself.” (p. 220)
of Aristotelian matter, having no properties in its There may be three layers, but practice is the layer
own right but serving as a kind of amorphous that rules them all.
receptacle that gains its qualities only from the levels
below and above it. We should note in passing that In short, Stengers does not argue for a three-leveled
this first level is both dubious and surprisingly theory at all, but for precisely the sort of twofold theory
innovative. It is dubious because it is by no means of which we were complaining a few pages ago. First,
clear that the properties of a chemical element can given that Stengers shows no traces of frank Berkeleyan
be reduced either to the properties of its atoms or idealism, she seems to concede that there is a world out
the uses one makes of the element. Indeed, this is there that resists our conceptions and allows for some
one of the chief recurrent arguments of partisans of negotiations to succeed and others to fail. That’s the
real emergence. Yet Stengers simply declares their first level: a world that is not just an image in our
argument irrelevant by her fiat of comparing chemi- minds. And second, there is the dominant layer of
cal elements to ‘Aristotelian matter’ lacking intrinsic praxis and negotiation that allows for the very articu-
properties of their own. Yet in another sense her lation between parts and wholes in the first place.
model is also quite innovative, since normally the And what of the additional level that Feibleman
defenders of matter-without-qualities place it at the requires – the consideration of the element/molecule
very bottom of the cosmos, rather than at an (or anything else) ‘on its own level’? We recall Stengers’
intermediate level as Stengers does. rather noncommittal description of this level: “The
2. Following Feibleman’s threefold method (which chemical element, like matter in the Aristotelian sense,
Stengers endorses), we must now consider the has no properties that could be used to define it
element/molecule at the level below it. In the present ‘in itself.’ Its definition entails the definitions of simple
example, atoms are the level just below molecules. and compound bodies and their reactions.” (p. 220)
“Unlike the element,” Stengers already told us, The upshot is that nothing has any qualities in its own
atoms ‘[can] claim a separable identity.’ Obviously right (here we are speaking of elements/molecules,
Stengers does not take this to be a permanent special but the same would hold for atoms, horses, balloons,
feature of atoms, which (as the scientist Stengers persons, nations – for anything at all). A thing gains its

© 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109 103


Books Forum

properties either from the explanations provided by its Bryant, L.R. (2011) The Democracy of Objects. Ann
own parts, or the ‘purposes’ that articulate it in one Arbor, MI: Open Humanities Press.
way rather than another. DeLanda, M. (2002) Intensive Science and Virtual
In a word, from the standpoint of object-oriented Philosophy. London: Continuum.
philosophy, Stengers is a classic duominer who reduces Feibleman, J.K. (1954) Theory of integrative levels.
entities simultaneously both to lower-level atoms and British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17:
59–66.
higher-level scientific purposes, while reserving for
Harman, G. (2009) Prince of Networks: Bruno
entities themselves nothing but the amorphous status Latour and Metaphysics. Melbourne: re.press.
of inarticulate Arisotelian matter, fit only to be shaped Harman, G. (2010) I am also of the opinion
by our ‘ecology of practices.’ Reality becomes a hot that materialism must be destroyed. Environment
potato, passed either downward to tiny pieces or and Planning D: Society and Space 28(5):
upward to all-encompassing practices, but is never 772–790.
stationed wherever we happen to be searching for it. Harman, G. (2011) On the undermining of objects:
Grant, Bruno, and radical philosophy. In: L.R.
This is the philosophical pitfall of duomining, and
Bryant, N. Srnicek and G. Harman (eds.) The
I hope that the unfamiliarity of the term does not Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and
overshadow the seriousness with which I use it. For all Realism. Melbourne: re.press.
her claims to surpass all the stale old dualistic polemics, Harman, G. (2013) Undermining, overmining, and
Stengers simply shows us the most classic reflex of duomining: A critique. In: J. Sutela (ed.) ADD
Western philosophy: a simultaneous reduction of the Metaphysics. Aalto Finland: Aalto University
Design Research Laboratory, pp. 40–51.
world in two separate directions rather than one, with
Malabou, C. (2008) What Should We Do With Our
each reduction providing an alibi for the other. Brain? Trans. S. Rand. New York: Fordham Univ.
Press.
Prigogine, I. and Stengers, I. (1984) Order Out of
References Chaos. New York: Bantam.
Barad, K. (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway: Stengers, I. (2011) Thinking with Whitehead: A Free
Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Wild Creation of Concepts. Trans. M. Chase.
and Meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.

To speak for human nature: E-mails: suparna.choudhury@mcgill.ca;


Cosmopolitics, critique and the alberto.sanchez2@mcgill.ca
neurosciences
BioSocieties (2014) 9, 104–109.
doi:10.1057/biosoc.2013.44
Isabelle Stengers
Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota
Science has been used, in some cases for over a
Press, 299 pp., US$25, £18.50,
century, as the pre-eminent framework under which
ISBN: 9780816656868; 9780816656875
truth is arbitrated. It is now a well-told story: before
the world was enchanted and revealed itself in the
Reviewed by Suparna Choudhury and Alberto
terms of religion and magic, today it reveals itself
Sanchez-Allred in the terms of science. The fact that many people
Division of Social & Transcultural Psychiatry, continue to use religion, magic and other extra-
McGill University, Montréal, Quebec, Canada. scientific frameworks to inform their conception of

Suparna Choudhury is an assistant professor at the Division of Social & Transcultural Psychiatry, McGill University and an
investigator at the Lady Davis Institute for Medical Research in Montreal. Her research is on the social studies of neuroscience,
focusing in particular on the context of the adolescent brain. She is an editor of Critical Neuroscience: A Handbook of the Social &
Cultural Contexts of Neuroscience.
Alberto Sánchez-Allred, anthropologist, lecturer in the Anthropology Department at McGill University and faculty at John
Abbott College, researches in the area of social and transcultural psychiatry, looking in particular at mental health and emerging
modes of existence.

104 © 2014 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1745-8552 BioSocieties Vol. 9, 1, 94–109

You might also like