You are on page 1of 14

CHAPTER 1

The Philosophy of Emotions


ROBERT C. SOLOMON

“What is an emotion?” That question was sophical view of emotion today. First there is
asked in precisely that form by William James, the inferior role of emotion—the idea that
as the title of an essay he wrote for Mind well emotion is as such more primitive, less intelli-
over 100 years ago (James, 1884). But philoso- gent, more bestial, less dependable, and more
phers have been concerned about the nature of dangerous than reason, and thus needs to be
emotion since Socrates and the “pre-Socratics” controlled by reason (an argument that Aris-
who preceded him, and although the discipline totle and other enlightened Athenians used to
has grown up (largely because of Socrates justify the political institution of slavery, as
and his student Plato) as the pursuit of rea- well). Second, and more profoundly, there is
son, the emotions have always lurked in the the reason–emotion distinction itself—as if we
background—often as a threat to reason and a were dealing with two different natural kinds,
danger to philosophy and philosophers. One of two conflicting and antagonistic aspects of the
the most enduring metaphors of reason and soul. Even those philosophers who sought to
emotion has been the metaphor of master and integrate them and reduce one to the other
slave, with the wisdom of reason firmly in con- (typically reducing emotion to an inferior ge-
trol and the dangerous impulses of emotion nus of reason, a “confused perception” or “dis-
safely suppressed, channeled, or (ideally) in torted judgment”) maintained the distinction
harmony with reason. But the question “What and continued to insist on the superiority of
is an emotion?” has proved to be as difficult to reason. It was thus a mark of his considerable
resolve as the emotions have been to master. iconoclasm that the Scottish skeptic David
Just when it seems that an adequate definition Hume (1739/1888), in the 18th century, fa-
is in place, some new theory rears its unwel- mously declared that “reason is, and ought to
come head and challenges our understanding. be, the slave of the passions.” But even Hume,
The master–slave metaphor displays two despite an ingenious analysis of the structure of
features that still determine much of the philo- emotions, ultimately fell back on the old mod-

3
4 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

els and metaphors. His work remains an exem- repertoire of emotions to fund and support a
plary celebration of reason, even while chal- dozen theories of emotion. As Descartes (1649/
lenging its limits. 1989) said in his introduction to the subject,
Philosophy is a historical discipline. It is con- “everyone has experience of the passions with-
strained and defined as much by its past as by in himself, and there is no necessity to borrow
any particular field of phenomena. Philosophi- one’s observations from elsewhere in order to
cal theories and debates today cannot be un- discover their nature.” Ultimately, there is no
derstood or appreciated without some under- justification for the century-old feud between
standing of philosophy’s rich and convoluted philosophy and psychology. Their history is in
past. Even when a philosopher pretends to un- fact the same, and the phenomenon of emotion
derstand the phenomenon of emotion “in it- lies equally open to both of them.
self,” or to analyze the language of emotion
without reference to history or to any earlier
attempts at analysis, both the wisdom and the THE HISTORY OF THE PHILOSOPHY
folly of generations of accumulated reflection OF EMOTION
and argument are nevertheless inescapable. Al-
though one might impatiently demand from Although the history of philosophy has often
the outset that one “define the terms” before been described as the history of the develop-
the current discussion commences, the truth is ment of reason—for example, by the great
that a definition emerges only at the end of a 19th-century German philosopher G. W. F.
long discussion, and even then it is always ten- Hegel—philosophers have never entirely ne-
tative and appropriate only within a limited glected emotion, even if they have almost al-
context and certain models of culture and per- ways denied it center stage. It would be a mis-
sonal character. take, however, to put too much emphasis on
In what follows, I have tried to sketch a the term “emotion,” for its range and meaning
somewhat selective history of philosophical at- have altered significantly over the years, due in
tempts to understand emotion, followed by a part to changes in theories about emotion. So
brief summary of questions still central to too, the word “passion” has a long and varied
philosophical debate. Given the nature of phi- history, and we should beware of the mislead-
losophy and its emphasis on reason, however, ing assumption that there is a single, orderly,
we would expect that the focus of most philo- natural class of phenomena that is simply des-
sophical analysis has been and remains the ignated by different labels in different lan-
more cognitive aspects of emotion, with the guages at different times. The language of
physiological and to a certain extent the social “passion” and “emotion” has a history into
and behavioral dimensions of emotion dimin- which various feelings, desires, sentiments,
ished or even denied. The dialectic in philoso- moods, attitudes, and more explosive re-
phy, accordingly, tends to go back and forth in sponses enter and from which they exit, de-
its rediscovery of these often neglected dimen- pending not on arbitrary philosophical stipula-
sions. Sometimes emotions are dismissed as tion but on an extensive network of social,
mere feelings and physiology, utterly unintelli- moral, cultural, and psychological factors.
gent, even subhuman. In reaction, emotions are Thus we will often find that the focus is not
then ascribed the virtues of true wisdom; they emotion as such, but rather some particular
are defended as the proper masters of reason class of emotions or particular emotion and its
and even the very foundation of our being-in- role in the manners or morals of the time.
the-world. Most philosophers, however, try to The emotions as such, accordingly, do not
find some more moderate, multidimensional form one of the three aspects of Plato’s (ca.
position. 428–347 B.C.) tripartite soul as defined in The
One might object that philosophical theories Republic (1974). There are reason, spirit, and
of emotion tend to be “armchair” speculation, appetite; not only does what we call emotion
devoid of the empirical support supplied by so- seem divided between spirit and appetite, but,
cial scientists. However, this objection ignores considering Plato’s discussion of eros as the
the fact that philosophers, contrary to their love of the Good in his dialogue The Sympo-
own self-styled reputations as men and women sium (1989), there are emotions involved in
of pure reason, have emotions themselves, and reason as well. Aristotle (384–322 B.C.), by
in most (but not all) cases a sufficiently rich contrast, did seem to have a view of emotion as
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 5

such, but although he had a mania for taxono- oric. (Thus its inclusion in a book on that
mies, he spent relatively little time listing or an- topic.) Anger (and several other emotions, no-
alyzing the emotions—as he did, for example, tably pride) is also prominent in Aristotle’s
the virtues and the various kinds of birds. In his classical list of virtues in his Nicomachean Eth-
Rhetoric (1941), however, he defined emotion ics (1941), where he discussed in some detail
“as that which leads one’s condition to become those circumstances in which it is appropriate
so transformed that his judgment is affected, to get angry, those in which it is not, and what
and which is accompanied by pleasure and amount or intensity of anger is justified. He
pain. Examples of emotion include anger, fear, suggested that forgiveness may be a virtue, but
pity, and the like, as well as the opposites of only sometimes. He also insisted that only fools
these.”1 (He did not tell us what these “oppo- don’t get angry, and that although overly angry
sites” might be.) Aristotle discussed certain people may be “unbearable,” the absence of
emotions at length, notably anger, which he de- anger (aimed at the right offenses) is a vice
scribed in remarkably modern terms. In the rather than a virtue. In this as in all else, Aris-
Rhetoric he defined anger as “a distressed de- totle defended moderation, the “mean between
sire for conspicuous vengeance in return for a the extremes.” So too, he discussed fear at
conspicuous and unjustifiable contempt of length in the Ethics with regard to courage,
one’s person or friends.” He added that “anger which is not fearlessness or “overcoming” fear
is always directed toward someone in particu- so much as it is having just the right amount of
lar, for example, Cleon, and not toward all of fear—not being either foolhardy or cowardly.
humanity,” and mentioned (if only in passing) The emotions, in other words, are central and
the physical distress that virtually always ac- essential to the good life, and the analysis of
companies such emotion. their nature is part and parcel of an ethical
The key to Aristotle’s analysis, however, is analysis.
the notion of a “slight.” This is the cause of an- So too, in Roman times, we find the conjunc-
ger, and it may be an instance of “scorn, spite, tion of ethics and emotion in the philosophy of
or insolence.” Aristotle made allowances for the Stoics (see Sorabji, 2003, and Nussbaum,
only imagined slights (in other words, unwar- 1994). But whereas Aristotle took emotion to
ranted anger is nevertheless anger), and he gave be essential to the good life, the Stoics analyzed
a central place to the desire for revenge, thus emotions as conceptual errors, conducive to
introducing a behavioral component at the misery. In modern terms, the Stoics Seneca and
heart of the emotion. We might note that Aris- Chrysippus developed a full-blooded cognitive
totle, who was so precocious in so many disci- theory of the emotions two millennia ago (see
plines, seems to have anticipated most of the especially Seneca, 1963). Emotions, in a word,
main contemporary theories. His analysis of are judgments—judgments about the world
anger includes a distinctive cognitive compo- and one’s place in it. But the world of Roman
nent, a specified social context, a behavioral society was not a happy or a particularly ratio-
tendency, and a recognition of physical arousal. nal place. (Seneca served under the Emperor
He even noted that physical or psychological Nero, and ultimately committed suicide at his
discomfort—sickness, poverty, love, war, behest.) And as the Stoics saw the world they
breached expectations, or ingratitude—yields a lived in as out of control and beyond any rea-
predisposition for anger. It is worth noting that sonable expectations, they saw the emotions,
Aristotle had little to say of “feeling,” presum- which impose such expectations on the world,
ably not because the Greeks were anesthetic, as misguided judgments about life and our
but rather because what we (inconsistently) call place in the world. The emotions consequently
“affect” and inner sensation generally held lit- make us miserable and frustrated. Accordingly,
tle interest for them and played no significant the Stoics made a careful study of the compo-
role in their language or their psychology. nent judgments that compose the emotions—
Perhaps the most important single point to the presumptuousness of moral judgment
make about Aristotle’s view of emotion is the in anger, the vulnerability of love, the self-
fact that his analyses make sense only in the absorption of security in fear. The alternative
context of a broader ethical concern. Anger was seen as “psychic indifference,” or apatheia
was of interest to him because it is a natural re- (apathy). The Stoics believed in a “higher” rea-
action to offense and a moral force, which can son, one transcending the vanities of the social
be cultivated and provoked by reason and rhet- world. But they felt that the best life in that
6 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

world could be achieved only by getting Thoughts about mathematics may be clearly
straight about the ultimate pointlessness of “in” the mind, as stomach contractions are in
emotional attachments and involvement. the body, but an emotion seems to require the
Throughout the Middle Ages, the study of interaction of mind and body in an undeniable
emotion was again typically attached to ethics, way. Accordingly, Descartes defended a theory
and it was central to Christian psychology and in his treatise On the Passions of the Soul
the theories of human nature in terms of which (1649/1989), in which the mind and body
the medievals understood themselves (see “meet” in a small gland at the base of the brain
Hyman & Walsh, 1973). There were elaborate, (now known as the pineal gland), and the latter
quasi-medical studies of the effects of the vari- affects the former by means of the agitation of
ous “humours” (gall, spleen, choler, and blood “animal spirits” (minute particles of blood),
itself) on emotional temperament, but there which bring about the emotions and their phys-
were (as there were among the Stoics) espe- ical effects in various parts of the body. But the
cially rich studies of the cognitive and “cona- emotions also involve not only sensations
tive” aspects of the emotions. Emotions were caused by this physical agitation, but percep-
essentially linked with desires, particularly self- tions, desires, and beliefs as well. Thus over
interested, self-absorbed desires. And so the and above the physical agitation and familiar
Christian preoccupation with sin led to elabo- sensations, the emotion of hatred ultimately
rate analyses of those emotions, passions, and arises from the perception of an object’s poten-
desires designated as sins (notably greed, glut- tial harmfulness and involves a desire to avoid
tony, lust, anger, envy, and pride; sloth, per- it. Accordingly, it is not as if an emotion is
haps, is a special case). The tight linkage be- merely a perception of the body; it may also be,
tween the study of emotion and ethics is as Descartes put it, a perception of the soul
particularly evident in the curious observation (e.g., a perception of desire), and some percep-
that the highest virtues, such as love, hope, and tions (as in dreams) may in fact be of things
faith, were not classified as emotions as such, that do not exist at all.
but were rather elevated to a higher status and An emotion is one type of “passion,” for
often (e.g., by Thomas Aquinas) equated with Descartes defined the passions in general as
reason. The old master–slave metaphor re- “the perceptions, feelings or emotions of the
mained alive and well, and as some emotions soul which we relate specifically to it, and
were seen as sins, the highest virtues could which are caused, maintained, and fortified by
hardly be counted among the mere emotions. some movement of the [animal] spirits.” The
Reviewing the ancient and medieval litera- passions in general are distinguished from
ture on emotion, René Descartes (1596–1650) “clear cognition,” and render judgment “con-
was provoked to write that what they taught fused and obscure.” Emotions are particularly
was “so slight, and for the most part so far disturbing passions. And yet emotions can be
from credible, that I am unable to entertain any influenced by reason. For example, writing of
hope of approximating the truth excepting by courage, Descartes stated:
shunning the paths they followed” (1649/
1989). Descartes is typically recognized as the To excite courage in oneself and remove fear, it is
not sufficient to have the will to do so, but we
“father” of modern philosophy, and, in a more
must also apply ourselves to consider the reasons,
scholarly vein, as the bridge between the scho- the objects or examples which persuade us that
lastic world of the Middle Ages and our own. the peril is not great; that there is always more se-
But Descartes was fundamentally a scientist curity in defense than in flight, that we should
and a mathematician, awed by “the natural have the glory and joy of having vanquished,
light of reason” and fascinated by the unique while we should expect nothing but regret and
autonomy of the human mind. Accordingly, he shame for having fled, and so on.
disdained the bodily and the bestial, insisting
that the mind is a separate “substance” from And so the physiological account gives way
the body (and that beasts therefore do not have to a cognitive account, and the emotions move
minds). The separation of mind and body from being merely bodily to becoming an es-
proved to be a famously difficult problem for sential ingredient in wisdom: “The utility of the
Descartes and his successors, however, and no- passions consists alone in their fortifying and
where was that problem more evident than in perpetuating in the soul thoughts which it is
his attempt to deal with the emotions. good that it should preserve, and which with-
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 7

out that might easily be effaced from it.” How mium on the virtues of reason. But Hume, in
then can there be “bad” emotions? “The harm carrying out the directives of reason to chal-
is that they fortify these thoughts more than lenge, debate, and question, came to question
necessary, or they conserve others on which it is the role and capacities of reason itself, and in
not good to dwell.” Somewhat bewildered by particular the power of reason to motivate even
the physiology (though he was at the cutting the most basic minimum of moral behavior. “It
edge of the science of his times), Descartes ulti- is not against reason,” he declared in one of his
mately tended to a value-oriented analysis of most outrageous proclamations, “to prefer the
emotion. His six “primitive” passions— destruction of half the world to the scratching
wonder, love, hatred, desire, joy, and sadness— of my finger” (1739/1888). What motivates us
are not meaningless agitations of the animal to right (and wrong) behavior, Hume insisted,
spirits, but ingredients in the good life. were our passions, and rather than being rele-
Baruch (Benedict) Spinoza (1632–1677) gated to the margins of ethics and philosophy,
might well be considered to be a latter-day the passions deserve central respect and consid-
Stoic, like Chrysippus and Seneca in ancient eration.
Rome. Just as the Stoics saw the emotions as Accordingly, he gave the passions the large
misguided judgments about life and our place middle portion of his great first book, A Trea-
in the world, Spinoza too saw the emotions as a tise of Human Nature (1739/1888). Unfortu-
form of “thoughts” that, for the most part, nately, however, most philosophers then and
misunderstand the world and consequently since have preferred to read the first and third
make us miserable and frustrated. But unlike parts, on knowledge and ethics, and to ignore
the Stoics, Spinoza did not aspire to that “psy- the central position of the passions.
chic indifference” known as apatheia; rather, in Hume’s theory is especially important not
his Ethics (1677/1982), he urged the attain- only because he challenged the inferior place of
ment of a certain sort of “bliss,” which can be passion in philosophy and questioned the role
achieved only once we get straight our thinking of reason. He also advanced a theory of the
about the world. In particular, we have to give passions that, although limited and encum-
up the idea that we are or can be in control of bered by his general theory of mind, displayed
our own lives, and adopt instead the all- dazzling insight and a precocious attempt to
embracing idea of ourselves and our minds as grapple with problems that would only be for-
part of God. Most of the emotions, which are mulated generations later. Hume, like many of
passive reactions to our unwarranted expecta- his contemporaries and predecessors, defined
tions of the world, will leave us hurt, frus- an emotion as a certain kind of sensation, or
trated, and enervated. what he called an “impression,” which (as in
The active emotions, by contrast, emanate Descartes) is physically stimulated by the
from our own true natures and heighten our movement of the “animal spirits” in the blood.
sense of activity and awareness. Spinoza, like Such impressions are either pleasant or un-
the Stoics, developed an early version of the pleasant, but the differentiation of the many
cognitive theory of emotion. But Spinoza also emotions is not to be found in the nature of
defended a grand and complex metaphysics, in these impressions as such. Rather, the impres-
which all substance is one, and mind and body sions that constitute our emotions are always
are but dual “aspects” of one and the same be- to be located within a causal network of other
ing. Accordingly, he did not face Descartes’s impressions and, importantly, ideas. Ideas
formidable “mind–body” problem; although cause our emotional impressions, and ideas are
he himself would not have predicted this, he caused in turn by them. The pleasant impres-
anticipated some of the subtle emotion–brain sion of pride, for example, is caused by the idea
research that is being carried out today. that one has achieved or accomplished some-
David Hume (1711–1776) was one of the thing significant, and the impression in turn
most outspoken defenders of the Enlighten- causes another idea, which Hume described as
ment, that very vocal and often rebellious intel- an idea of the self, simpliciter.
lectual movement that challenged old ortho- The emotion, in other words, cannot be
doxies, elevated science and put religion on the identified with the impression or sensation
defensive, attacked superstition and irrational- alone, but can only be identified by the whole
ity in all quarters, practiced and encouraged complex of impressions and ideas. What Hume
vigorous debate and discussion, and put a pre- acknowledged with his emphasis on the essen-
8 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

tial place of ideas in emotion is what we now sal and necessary dictates of reason. Thus Kant
call the cognitive dimension of emotion, in ad- reinforced the crucial distinction between rea-
dition to the physiological (“animal spirits”) son and what he called “the inclinations”
and merely sensational (“impression”) aspects (emotions, moods, and desires) and dismissed
of emotion. Moreover, his inclusion of the sec- the latter (including the moral sentiments) as
ond idea of the self in his analysis of pride inessential to morals at best and intrusive and
indicates his grappling with the notion of disruptive at worst. And yet, although Kant felt
intentionality (the “aboutness” of emotions)— no need to develop a theory of emotion to ac-
an effort further reinforced by his somewhat company his elaborate and brilliant “critiques”
obscure insistence that the connection between of reason, his position on the “inclinations” is
an emotion (the impression) and this conse- more ambiguous than is usually supposed, and
quent idea is “original” or “natural,” or some- his respect for “feeling” more significant. It
thing more than the merely causal associations was Kant, a quarter-century before Hegel (who
that form the usual bonds between ideas and is credited with it), who insisted that “nothing
impressions. great is ever done without passion,” and it was
The emotions, for Hume, form an essential Kant, in his Critique of Judgment (1793/1953,
part of ethics. There are good emotions and bad concerned in part with art and aesthetics), who
emotions. Pride, he declared, is a good emotion. celebrated the importance of shared (“inter-
Humility, its opposite (an unpleasant feeling subjective”) feeling in the appreciation of
brought about by the idea that we are inade- beauty and the awe with which we try to com-
quate or deeply flawed beings), is a bad emotion, prehend the wonder of God’s creation. Indeed,
a “monkish” emotion. Here we can see again the even Kant’s central notions of respect and hu-
extent to which, as so often, a theory of emotion man dignity—the very heart of his rationalist
serves to grind some larger philosophical ax—in ethics—are sometimes suggested to be matters
this case, Hume’s Enlightenment attack on reli- of feeling as well as reason, thus calling into
gion. In this regard too, we might mention an- question the harshness of his ruthlessly divided
other aspect of Hume’s moral philosophy, fol- self. When his successor Hegel took over the
lowed in kind by his illustrious Edinburgh friend reins of German philosophy in the early 19th
and colleague Adam Smith (1723–1790, also the century, the overstated distinction between rea-
author of The Wealth of Nations [1776/1976], son and passion was again called into question,
the bible of modern capitalism). and Hegel’s own odyssey of reason (in an
Hume and Smith both defended the impor- epochal book called The Phenomenology of
tance of what they called “the moral senti- Spirit [1807/1977]) has rightly been called a
ments” (see Smith, 1759/1976), the foremost “logic of passion” as well.
of which is sympathy, our ability to “feel with” Friederich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was a phi-
other people and appreciate (if not suffer with) losopher for whom passion was the watchword
their misfortunes. Sympathy, they argued, is a and reason a source of suspicion. He was the
universal feature of human nature (countering culmination of a long line of “Romantics,” be-
and mitigating the self-interest that Smith in ginning with the Sturm und Drang poets of the
particular famously championed in The Wealth previous century and continuing through the
of Nations), and it is the bedrock foundation of philosophy of Nietzsche’s own favorite in-
society and morality. Emotion, in other words, fluence, the neo-Kantian pessimist Arthur
is not an embarrassment or part of the refuse of Schopenhauer. Nietzsche anticipated the global
the human psyche, but rather the very essence skepticism and conceptual chaos of the 20th
of human social existence and morality. It is century; like Freud, who admired him, he de-
not to be unfavorably contrasted and opposed scribed (and celebrated) the darker, more in-
to reason, but, on the contrary, is to be cele- stinctual, and less rational motives of the hu-
brated and defended along with it. man mind. Accordingly, in his On the
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was also a Genealogy of Morals (1887/1967), he praised
champion of the Enlightenment, but although the passions and, in an ironic twist, described
he too questioned the capacities and lim- the passions as themselves having more reason
its of reason, he was uncompromising in its than Reason. But this was not to say that all
defense—against Hume’s skepticism, against passions are wise; some, he declares, “drag us
any attempt to replace reason by irrational down with their stupidity,” and others, notably
faith, and against any attempt to ground ethics the “slave morality” emotion of resentment,
in fleeting human feeling instead of the univer- are devious and clever but to a disastrous
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 9

end—the “leveling” of the virtuous passions (Sigmund Freud was one of his students.) Fol-
and the defense of mediocrity. Nietzsche never lowing the “phenomenology” of Edmund
developed a “theory” of emotions, but his dis- Husserl (1838/1960), Max Scheler (1916/
tinctions were remarkable in their insight and 1970), Martin Heidegger (1927/1962), and
subtlety. His celebration of passion scared the more recently, Paul Ricoeur (1950/1966) devel-
wits out of a great many philosophers in Eu- oped ambitious philosophies in which emo-
rope, however, who saw more than enough tions were given a central place in human exis-
passion and irrationality in World War I and tence and accorded with considerable respect.
then the rise of National Socialism in Germany. Heidegger, in particular, defended what he gen-
Accordingly, the ancient celebration of reason erally called “moods” as our way of “being
would once more rule philosophy, and emotion tuned” to the world. In the shadow of World
was again relegated to the sidelines. War II, Jean-Paul Sartre offered the slim but
In the 20th century, one can trace the fate of important The Emotions: Sketch of a Theory
emotion in Western philosophy through two (1939/1948), followed by his magnificent tome
very different tracks. In North America and in Being and Nothingness (1943/1956), which in-
England, the emotions were given short shrift, cludes embedded within its many pages a num-
in large part because of the newly exaggerated ber of detailed “phenomenological” analyses
emphasis on logic and science. The great Brit- of emotion. Sartre’s conception of emotions
ish philosopher Bertrand Russell gave elabo- as “magical transformations of the world”—
rate praise to love and passion in the opening willful strategems for coping with a difficult
pages of his autobiography (1967), but in his world—added a new “existential” dimension
philosophy he said virtually nothing about to the investigation of emotion. But, predict-
them. Of course, the nature of emotion was a ably, philosophy in both France and Germany
major concern of William James and the young turned again to other interests, although the
John Dewey in the early years of the century, study of emotion continued despite the peren-
but with James’s emphasis on the physiological nial shift in fashions.
nature of emotion (he argued [1884] that an In Anglo-American philosophy, however, the
emotion is a sensation or set of sensations fortunes of emotion were also to change. In an
caused by a physiological disturbance, which in article simply entitled “Emotion” (indicating
turn is prompted by some “perception” or how rarely the topic had even been broached),
other), coupled with the subsequent and quite Errol Bedford (1956/1964) addressed the
unfortunate split between philosophy and psy- Aristotelean Society in London on the nature of
chology as academic disciplines, questions emotion and the errors of thinking of emotions
about emotion were relegated to the realm of as “feelings.” The essay might have sat on the
psychology (where they were also treated with shelves gathering dust except for the fact that
less than the full respect due them). Indeed, the the then dean of Oxford philosophers, J. L.
first major attention to emotion in Anglo- Austin (1956–1957/1964), took it upon him-
American philosophy came in midcentury, self to remark on one of Bedford’s claims. (Aus-
when an ethical theory named “emotivism” tin’s own essay was not about emotions at all.)
came to dominate both the English and the Austin’s attention kept the article alive and oc-
North American scene. But emotivism, which casionally anthologized until the 1960s, when
was part and parcel of an across-the-board the subject seemed to come to life again.
philosophical purgative known as “logical pos- Today, one finds a rich variety of arguments
itivism,” was essentially a dismissal of ethical about emotions on both sides of the Atlantic
(and many other) questions in philosophy as Ocean and the English Channel. Given the na-
“meaningless” (i.e., unscientific and without ture of philosophy and its current concern with
verifiable solutions). Emotion came back onto epistemological matters, it is again not surpris-
the stage of philosophy, but only as the butt of ing that the focus is on the conceptual struc-
the argument: Ethical statements were viewed tures of emotion, rather than the sensory, so-
as meaningless because they were seen as noth- cial, or physiological aspects of emotion. But
ing but expressions of emotion. there has been a reaction even within philoso-
During the same period in Europe, however, phy to the “hypercognizing” of emotion; con-
the emotions enjoyed more attention. Franz sequently, there has been a serious effort to join
Brentano (1874/1971) succeeded the British forces with psychologists, neurologists, anthro-
“moral sentiment” theorists in attempting to pologists, and moral philosophers to obtain a
found an ethics on a foundation of emotions. more holistic theory of emotion.
10 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

SOME PHILOSOPHICAL QUESTIONS stance, to the stimulation of the autonomic ner-


ABOUT EMOTION vous system. The great virtue of the Jamesian
theory is that it ties down the nature of emo-
What is an emotion? Because philosophy is a tional “feelings” to quite particular and there-
discipline concerned with the essential nature fore verifiable bodily responses. Unfortunately,
and the “definition” of things, the basic ques- the Jamesian theory has often been shown to be
tion facing theories of emotion in philosophy is wrong, at least in its details (e.g., Cannon,
still the question posed by James and answered, 1929/2003; Dewey, 1894/2003; Schachter &
in a fashion, by Aristotle. It is, on the face of it, Singer, 1962). How specifically are emotional
a quest for a definition, a conceptual analysis. feelings tied to physiological processes? To be
But it is also a much larger quest for an orienta- sure, whatever goes on in the mind must now
tion: How should we think about emotion—as be supposed to have some correlate and cause
intrusive, as essential to our rationality, as con- in the brain, but can we not and should we not
stitutive of meaning, as dangerous, as dispens- describe the “phenomenology” of those feel-
able, as an excuse for irresponsibility, or as a ings quite apart from their brain correlations
mode of responsibility? Which of the evident and causes? Some theorists have tried to save
aspects of emotion—that is, the various sen- feeling theory by employing the vague, general
sory, physiological, behavioral, cognitive, and (and technical) notion of “affect” and its cog-
social phenomena that typically correspond nates (“affective tone”) (Stocker, 1996). But do
with an emotion—should we take to be essen- such terms do anything more than cover up the
tial? Many philosophers hold onto the old problem with another word, whose meaning
“Cartesian” view that an emotion cannot lack can only be explained by “the kind of feeling
its “subjective” or “introspective” aspect, al- you get when you have emotion X”? It is a heu-
though what this means (and how accessible or ristic mistake to suppose that such feelings are
articulate an emotion must be on inspection) is indescribable or “ineffable,” whether out of
itself a subject of considerable dispute, for in- excessive romanticism (as if understanding un-
stance, in Freud (1915/1935), Sartre (1943/ dermines passion) or dismissive scientism (why
1956), Lyons (1980), and de Sousa (1987). talk about feelings if we can’t experimentally
But many philosophers have become skeptical test them?)
about such subjective essentialism and, like Most feelings have at least an “as if” famil-
their associates in the sciences, have pushed iarity (“It feels as if I’d known her for years” or
the analysis of emotion toward more public, “It felt as if he had shot me through the heart, it
observable criteria. Accordingly, philosophers was so sudden and so traumatizing”). Many
have formulated their own versions of behav- feelings have a distinctive structure, which (not
iorism, physiologism, and social construction surprisingly) emerges in the thoughts (and then
theory, for example, although they have not al- in the verbal expressions) of the emotions.
ways been mutually aware of their counter- Thus we should identify the experience of hav-
parts in the social sciences, especially. ing an emotion (as opposed to just a simple
The seemingly self-evident Cartesian de- “feeling”) as embodying thoughts, judgments,
mand that first-person experience is inelim- and other cognitive elements. In general, one
inable is evident, nevertheless, even among the should ask how much cognition and learning
most radical philosophical behaviorists. For in- are presupposed in the feelings that we identify
stance, Gilbert Ryle (1951) chastised philoso- as emotions. It may well be that at least some
phers for their “myth of the ghost in the ma- “basic” emotions are largely to be explained by
chine” and suggested that many emotions are reference to one or another neurophysiological
mere “agitations” (much as Descartes had in- “affect programs,” but even the most basic
sisted) and dispositions to behave in certain emotions involve or come to involve
ways. But Ryle did not give up the idea that “intentionality”—an engagement with the
some of the symptoms of emotion consist of world. And this involves perception and some
“tingles and itches” or some such “feeling.” knowledge, as well as the abilities to act in the
Can one have an emotion without feeling? world. Thus an emotional experience is not just
What is a “feeling”? According to William a Jamesian sensation, but a complex awareness
James (1884), it is a specifiable sort of sensa- of one’s engagements in the world and one’s
tion, the sensation of one or more “visceral dis- tendencies to act in it. (There may be, however,
turbances”—changes in the body due, for in- a kind of “borrowed intentionality” peculiar to
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 11

emotional sensations; Goldie, 2000.) Whether Recent advances in neurology have disclosed
or not there are Jamesian sensations that ac- illuminating structural and functional patterns
company such engagements and action tenden- in the central nervous system that are corre-
cies (and no doubt usually there are), the emo- lated with, and that under experimental condi-
tion is first of all a mode of engagement. But it tions bring about, certain emotional reactions.
should be said that we are not always fully Do these patterns dictate the structure of an ad-
aware of our engagements in the world, nor are equate theory of emotion, or are those findings
we usually fully cognizant of our feelings. but one more set of (contingent) consider-
Thus there is room for “unconscious” ations for inclusion in an all-embracing theory?
emotions—a grab-bag concept that embraces Whatever the case, it is now clear that philoso-
everything from the Freudian “Unconscious,” phers cannot ignore or neglect the rich neuro-
to the fact that we misidentify and fail to recog- physiological literature on emotions. Indeed,
nize our own emotions, to the more bracing there is now a interdisciplinary subfield in
claims of some neuroscientists that an emotion philosophy called “neurophilosophy,” which
is essentially not conscious and that awareness makes the new neurology central to any ade-
(if it happens at all) comes late in the neurologi- quate analysis of emotion and “the mind”
cal game. As for the feelings (the sensations) (Churchland, 1986). Philosophers may con-
themselves, Freud was right in wondering tinue to argue that Aristotle knew all about
whether it makes any sense to claim that they emotions even though he did not know any-
can be unconscious, given that their whole ex- thing about the brain, but they do so at their
istence seems to be to be experienced. But this peril—and in the face of the obvious fact that
embodies just the confusion that one would ex- among the factors that have altered the history
pect with such a grab-bag concept of the un- of philosophy and its concepts most radically
conscious: On the one hand, an unfelt feeling have been new advances in previously un-
or sensation makes no sense, but the observa- known or undeveloped sciences.
tion that we are not always aware that we have Virtually all emotions get expressed (how-
a certain feeling or sensation is quite evident. ever minimally) in behavior. Should behavioral
And because the experience of an emotion is tendencies or sequences of actions or certain
so complex (engaging one’s beliefs about the basic gestures be taken as essential? A great
world, oneself, and other people, as well as any deal of detailed work in psychology has shown
number of preferred scenarios and outcomes), the enormous subtlety and the seemingly
it is obvious how and why we may not recog- “hard-wired” nature of basic patterns of facial
nize an emotion when we have it. But what expression. And yet philosophers remain skep-
does seem essential to all emotions, including tical about the implied shift in conception from
those that are most “basic,” is some sense of the emotion to a symptom of emotion. The
what is going on in the world, some “cogni- emotion would seem to be the experience, the
tion,” whether or not one is or even can be (re- perception, the awareness—what is expressed,
flectively) aware of it. Thus no neurological not the expression itself. On the other hand,
syndrome or “affect program” can be an emo- many philosophers of a somewhat behaviorist
tion if it does not engage the world in some bent (following Wittgenstein’s later Philosophi-
way, perhaps by virtue of a more or less auto- cal Investigations [1953] and Gilbert Ryle’s
matic “appraisal” or some possibly subliminal The Concept of Mind [1951]) have suggested
stimulus. The affect programs typical of, say, that an emotion is nothing but its behavioral
fear and anger do not actually constitute fear expression, though certainly not a single ges-
and anger if there are no appropriate apprais- ture but an open-ended sequence of actions. An
als, beliefs, or judgments accompanying them. emotion is not a “ghostly inner event,” accord-
A person may well feel flushed, uncomfortable, ing to Ryle, but a “multitrack disposition” to
and “as if ” he or she wants to flee or start a behave in any number of recognizable ways. So
fight with someone—but if there is no fearful too, philosophers have tried to understand
object (more precisely, if the person has no emotion not as an inner feeling but as a value-
sense of a fearful object), or if there is nothing laden description of a social situation. Thus
objectionable, frustrating, or offensive (to the Errol Bedford (1956/1964) suggested in his pi-
person), then those feelings do not count as oneering article that the difference between
fear and anger (or even as “feeling afraid” or shame and embarrassment, for example, is not
“feeling angry”). some shade of difference between internal
12 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

qualia, but the difference between two con- (intentionality). There is some corollary debate
trasting descriptions of the situation. concerning the status of moods and mood-like
What remains at the core of all such theories, emotions (e.g., joy), which do not have a deter-
however, is an awareness that all emotions pre- minate object, but it can be argued that moods
suppose or have as their preconditions certain do have an object—namely, the world as a
sorts of cognitions—an awareness of danger in whole. “A depressed man lives in a depressed
fear, recognition of an offense in anger, appreci- world,” wrote Wittgenstein (1953).
ation of someone or something lovable in love. There is also considerable debate over the
Even the most hard-headed neurological or nature of cognition itself. Beliefs seem to be es-
behavioral theory must take account of the fact tablished states and therefore lack the sponta-
that no matter what the neurology or the neity that characterizes many emotions. Beliefs
behavior, if a person is totally unaware (and also seem to be too fully articulate for the unre-
not just “consciously unaware”) of a certain flective reaction that characterizes most emo-
state of affairs or facts, he or she cannot have tions. For that reason, some theorists prefer the
certain emotions. If neurologically induced concept of “judgment” or “evaluative judg-
rage does not include some object of anger, that ment” (e.g., the ancient Stoics; Solomon, 1976,
reaction (whatever else it may be) cannot be 2003; Nussbaum, 2003), while others prefer
anger. So too, Freud’s “free-floating anxiety” the term “thought” (e.g., Spinoza, 1677/1982;
would count as an emotion only insofar as it Neu, 1977, 1999). Psychologists seem to prefer
does indeed (as Freud [1915/1935] argued) “appraisal,” although it should be said that the
have an object, albeit “unconscious.” Philoso- social sciences have been much more keen to
phers (following Aristotle and the scholastics understand “appraisal” in a multilevel fashion
of the Middle Ages) have come to call this the than philosophers, at least until recently (Prinz,
“formal object” of emotion, and one might 2004). Others have preferred the less cog-
well think of this as the minimum essential set nitively committal notion of a way of seeing
of “beliefs” defining an emotion type and a (“seeing as”)—sometimes as a rejection of the
more or less specific kind of emotional experi- cognitive view, but more appropriately, per-
ence. The formal object of fear, to take an obvi- haps, as a refinement of it (Calhoun, 1984,
ous case, is a fearful object, together with the at Roberts, 2003). The nature of an emotional
least minimal beliefs constituting the awareness cognition, and whether it must be fully con-
of the presence or threat of such an object. scious or capable of articulation, remain mat-
Other emotions are more complicated and, ters for considerable debate. Indeed, if certain
accordingly, are more often topics of philo- holistic suggestions can be worked out, it may
sophical debate and disagreement. Anger be that the very distinctions that philosophers
would seem to require a formal object involv- have so long presupposed among cognition,
ing an offense, but some authors would allow behavior, physiology, and feeling are them-
frustration alone to count as anger (Gordon, selves inadequate and ought to be integrated
1987). Still others would argue that anger is to into a single picture (Damasio, 1994).
a large extent “socially constructed,” and its One point of general agreement among phi-
manifestation in any given culture will there- losophers is that emotions have intentionality.
fore be more or less specific (though probably “Intentionality” is a technical notion, but its
not unique) to that culture (Averill, 1985). Jeal- common-sense meaning can be captured by the
ousy is more difficult still, for its object seems idea that emotions are always “about” some-
to involve not only a threatened loss but a per- thing or other. One is always angry about
petrator as well (perhaps the threatened object something; one is always in love with someone
as a perpetrator too), and possibly the larger or something (even if one is also “in love with
social situation in which jealousy involves not love”); one is always afraid of something (even
only loss but humiliation as well (Neu, 1980). if one doesn’t know what it is). Thus we can
But although the exact natures of the formal understand the “formal object” of an emotion
objects and requisite beliefs of various emo- as its essential intentionality—the kind of ob-
tions are matters of lively debate (and there is ject (event, person, state of affairs) to which it
even more doubt and debate over the very idea must be directed if it is to be that emotion. But
of a generalized formal object for emotions as intentionality has also been the object of philo-
such), the presumption is that every emotion sophical consternation for over a century now,
must have a cognitive basis and an object because despite its appeal as a way of under-
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 13

standing the nature of perception and other Gibbard, 1990). Particular instances of emo-
mental “acts” (which gets us away from the tion seem to be subject to two different sorts
image of images or representations “in” the of explanations. On the one hand, because
mind), intentionality has its own peculiar com- they are intentional and essentially involve
plications (Kenny, 1963; Searle, 1983). Some beliefs (as well as desires, needs, attitudes,
philosophers have argued for a more dynamic and values), emotions seem to require an ex-
and action-laden concept than “aboutness,” planation that invokes a person’s belief and
perhaps “motility” or “engagement” (as attitudes toward the world. A person is angry
above) (Merleau-Ponty, 1962/1994; Solomon, because he believes that so-and-so wronged
2003). Many philosophers accept the idea of him, or someone is saddened because she has
intentionality, but try to integrate it into a neo- found out that she has just lost a loved one,
Jamesian analysis of emotions as physiology and so on. But this cannot be a complete ac-
plus sensation, by way of an intricate causal count of emotional explanation. We also ex-
theory of perception (Prinz, 2004). It could be plain emotions by citing the fact that a per-
argued that in so doing, they are denying son has been sleepless all week, or is ill, or
intentionality with the right hand while endors- has been given some medication. In other
ing it with the left. words, explanation of emotion may cite an
Most troubling for philosophers is the obvi- underlying cause that may or may not make
ous fact that an emotion may be “about” some mention of the object of emotion. The cause
nonexistent, merely imagined object. The ob- may be physiological—for example, an un-
ject of fear may be nowhere around. The imag- derlying state of irritability, an ingested drug,
ined threat in jealousy may not exist. The per- or a direct surgical stimulation of the brain.
son one still loves may be dead. (Indeed, the The cause may be some state of affairs or in-
problem seems to remain whether the lover cident that “triggered” the person’s emotion,
knows of the death or not. In either case, the but this may not be the object of the person’s
emotion is directed at a person who is in no po- emotion, nor need he or she have any mem-
sition to receive it.) Moreover, the object of an ory or awareness of it. (Again, “subliminal”
emotion would seem to be one and the same messages presumably work this way.)
object, whether it exists or not. (It is one and How is causal explanation to be reconciled
the same devil that is the object of a child’s fear, with an explanation in terms of beliefs and
whether the devil exists or not.) Thus the onto- attitudes? Many philosophers have tended to
logical status of the intentional object of emo- emphasize the importance of one form of
tion causes considerable commotion, particu- explanation over the other, or to reduce all ex-
larly in the area of aesthetics and “make- planations to either causal explanations or
believe” (Walton, 1990). In recent decades, belief-and-desire, “reason”-type explanations.
many Anglo-American language-oriented or The latter sort of explanation provides a fuller
“analytic” philosophers have reduced the account of the intentionality of an emotion by
seemingly mysterious notion of intentionality describing not only its formal object (“He’s an-
to the supposedly more manageable notion of gry because he’s been offended”) but the spe-
“intensionality,” a precisely defined feature of cific details of the situation, as well as the per-
certain sorts of sentences (Dennett, 1978, son’s beliefs and various attitudes. The former
1991). But whether intensionality does in fact sort of explanation invokes an underlying
capture the necessary features of intentionality cause that may or may not make mention of
is itself a topic of considerable debate; at least it the object of emotion. Very often, however, the
seems to confuse the language in which we de- citation of a cause of emotion (its initiating
scribe emotions with the nature of the emo- stimulus or “trigger”) and the account of the
tions themselves (Searle, 1983). object of the emotion will be nominally the
Philosophers have also become concerned same (“He got mad because she stepped on his
with the “why?” of emotions—their function toe”). The problem that has been addressed by
and their explanation. Most of the work here many philosophers and in recent years has be-
has been done on the explanation of particu- come the subject of intense debate between
lar instances of emotion, although a few in- those who prefer some version of the in-
vestigators have recently tackled the much tentionality model of emotion and those who
larger question of the evolution and function demonstrate a strong preference for a more
of emotions as such (de Sousa, 1987; biological model of emotion (Rorty, 1980;
14 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

Nissenbaum, 1985; Griffiths, 1997; Prinz, ture to provide a firm basis for ethics; in other
2004). words, they are “relative.” But though philoso-
The cognitive basis of emotions also raises phers alone cannot answer the empirical ques-
another question, one that was often a matter tion of the universality or relativity of emo-
of deep concern for earlier philosophers: the tions, they can and should clear away the
question of the rationality of emotions. Many dogmatic assumptions and mistaken concep-
thinkers have written as if the emotions were tions that have often occupied philosophy in
not only irrational but also nonrational—not the past. There is nothing in the nature of
even candidates for cognition. Accounts of emotion (including the human brain, which
emotions as mere feelings or physiological pro- changes significantly with experience and var-
cesses would make them nonrational (one can- ies considerably from person to person) that as-
not have a “stupid” headache, except by way sures universality, but neither is it so obvious
of a roundabout complaint about its inconve- that emotions differ so much from place to
nience). Aristotle, on the other hand, simply as- place either. (This is indicated not only by stud-
sumed that an emotion can be appropriate or ies of facial expression, but by the logic of the
inappropriate, foolish or prudent, not just on “human condition” and its more general fea-
the basis of whether or not it is acceptable in tures.) Indeed, the whole question of “human
the circumstance in question (though that so- nature” is once again up for grabs.
cial dimension is certainly essential), but on the One of the most critical questions about hu-
basis of the perceptions, beliefs, desires, and man nature is the extent to which we can
situation of the individual. The fact that emo- transcend our own biology. In one sense, of
tions consist at least in part of cognitions course, this is absurd, but in another it is per-
means that they can be evaluated in terms of fectly plausible. Human beings did not evolve
the same epistemic, social, and even ethical cri- to fly, but through technology we now have
teria that we use to evaluate beliefs and inten- “frequent flyer” programs. Human beings did
tions: Are they appropriate to the context? Do evolve with anger and jealousy as putatively
they consider the facts of the matter? Are their universal emotions, but the question remains
perceptions fair and their evaluations reason- whether we can overcome our anger and jeal-
able? Indeed, the argument is now prevalent ousy, or perhaps even eliminate them from our
and persuasive that emotions cannot be under- emotional repertoires. This raises the question
stood without grasping their reasons, and these of emotions and choice, and challenges the sup-
reasons in turn give us a basis for evaluation position that we are passive regarding our
(de Sousa, 1987; Greenspan, 1988). The cur- emotions. Sartre (1939/1948, 1943/1956) sug-
rent debate, however, concerns how these rea- gested that the emotions are both choices and
sons are to be understood, and whether the ra- strategies, but many philosophers who do not
tionality of emotions can indeed be fairly share Sartre’s extreme voluntarism would agree
compared to the evaluation of more fully delib- that emotions are indeed ways of coping,
erative, articulate activities. whether inherited through natural selection or
The rationality of emotions also moves to cultivated in the less articulate practices of a so-
center stage the question of emotions and eth- ciety. But are we at the mercy of our emotions?
ics that we have been following through the Do we simply “have” them, or do we perhaps
history of philosophy. How does emotion enter to some extent cultivate them and “do” them
into ethical understanding, and how do our ourselves? Obviously, a good deal of ethics and
ethics affect our emotions? One thing is clear: our attitudes toward ourselves depend on this.
The commingling of emotions and ethics is not The study of emotion in philosophy is, accord-
grounds for dismissing either ethics or emo- ingly, not a detached and marginal discipline,
tion, as the midcentury “emotivists” suggested. but the very core of our inquiry into ourselves
But it is worth noting that a new conception of and our own natures. It was Socrates, the great
the emotional foundations of ethics has taken champion of reason, who took as his mottos
root in the Anglo-American tradition and, in the slogan at Delphi (“Know thyself ”) and the
an appropriate irony, has taken the name rather extreme injunction that “The unexam-
“emotivism” (Gibbard, 1990). Of course, one ined life is not worth living.” But part of that
of the questions that remains, left over from the knowledge, surely, is our understanding and
charge that emotions are “subjective,” is that appreciation of our emotions, which are, after
emotions vary too much from culture to cul- all, much of what makes life worth living.
1. The Philosophy of Emotions 15

NOTE Ekman, P. (2003). Emotions revealed. New York: Times


Books.
1. This and other quotations from Aristotle in this Ekman, P., & Davidson, R. J. (Eds.). (1994). The nature
chapter have been translated by Jon Solomon. of emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ellsworth, P. (1994). William James and emotion: Is a
century of fame worth a century of misunderstand-
REFERENCES AND FURTHER READING ing? Psychological Review, 101, 222–229.
Elster, J. (2000). Alchemies of the mind. Cambridge,
Aristotle. (1941). The basic works of Aristotle (R. UK: Cambridge University Press.
McKeon, Ed.). New York: Random House. See also Freud, S. (1935). The unconscious (C. M. Baines,
W. Fortenbaugh (1975). Aristotle on emotion. Lon- Trans.). In Essays in metapsychology. London:
don: Duckworth. Liveright. (Original work published 1915)
Austin, J. L. (1964). Pretending. In D. Gustafson (Ed.), Frijda, N. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge, UK: Cam-
Essays in philosophical psychology. Garden City, bridge University Press.
NY: Doubleday/Anchor. (Original work published Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory
1956–1957) of normative judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Averill, J. R. (1985). The social construction of emotion, University Press.
with special reference to love. In K. Gergen & K. Da- Goldie, P. (2000). The emotions: A philosophical explo-
vis (Eds.), The social construction of the person ration. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
(pp. 89–109). New York: Springer-Verlag. Gordon, R. M. (1987). The structure of emotion. Cam-
Barbalet, J. (1999). William James’ theory of emotions. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 29, 251– Greenspan, P. (1988). Emotions and reasons. New
256. York: Routledge.
Bedford, E. (1964). Emotion. In D. Gustafson (Ed.), Es- Griffiths, P. (1997). What emotions really are. Chicago:
says in philosophical psychology. Garden City, NY: University of Chicago Press.
Doubleday/Anchor. (Original work published 1956) Hamlyn, D. W. (1978). The phenomenon of love and
Ben-Zeev, A. (2000). The subtlety of emotions. Cam- hate. Philosophy, 53, 5–20. Includes a discussion of
bridge, MA: MIT Press. Brentano’s theory.
Brentano, F. (1971). Psychology from the empirical Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). The phenomenology of spirit (A.
standpoint. London: Routledge. (Original work pub- N. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
lished 1874) (Original work published 1807)
Calhoun, C. (1984). Cognitive emotions? In C. Calhoun Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time. New York:
& R. C. Solomon (Eds.), What is an emotion? New Harper & Row. (Original work published 1927) See
York: Oxford University Press. also the following explications of Heidegger: C.
Cannon, W. B. (2003). Bodily changes in pain, hunger, Guignon (1984). Moods in Heidegger’s Being and
fear and rage [Excerpt]. In R. Solomon (Ed.), What is time; H. Dreyfus, (1991). Being-in-the-world: A
an emotion? (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University commentary on Heidegger’s Being and time. Cam-
Press. (Original work published 1929) bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Charland, L. (2002). The natural kind status of emo- Hobbes, T. (1994). Leviathan. Indianapolis, IN:
tion. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Hackett. (Original work published 1651)
53, 511–537. Hume, D. (1888). A treatise of human nature (L. A.
Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, Selby-Bigge, Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
MA: MIT Press. (Original work published 1739) See also A. Baier
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. New York: (1991). A progress of sentiments: Reflections on
Putnam. Hume’s treatise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT sity Press. And see also D. Davidson (1976). Hume’s
Press. cognitive theory of pride. Journal of Philosophy, 73,
Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: 733–757.
Little, Brown. Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations (D. Cairns,
Descartes, R. (1989). On the passions of the soul (S. Trans.). The Hague: Nijhoff. (Original work pub-
Voss, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Original lished 1938)
work published 1649) Hyman, A., & Walsh, J. (1973). Philosophy in the Mid-
de Sousa, R. (1987). The rationality of emotion. Cam- dle Ages. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9, 188–
Dewey, J. (2003). The theory of emotion [Excerpt]. In 205.
R. Solomon (Ed.), What is an emotion? (2nd ed.). James, W. (1950). Principles of psychology. New York:
New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work Dover. (Original work published 1890)
published 1894) Kant, I. (1953). Critique of judgment (J. H. Bernard,
Ekman, P. (1973). Darwin and facial expression. New Trans.). New York: Hafner. (Original work published
York: Academic Press. 1793)
16 I. INTERDISCIPLINARY FOUNDATIONS

Kenny, A. (1963). Action, emotion and will. London: mentary in R. C. Solomon (1988). From Hegel to ex-
Routledge & Kegan Paul. istentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lane, R. (1999). The cognitive neuroscience of emotion. Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness (H. Barnes,
New York: Oxford University Press. Trans.). New York: Washington Square Press. (Origi-
Lazarus, R. S. (1994). Emotion and adaptation. New nal work published 1943) See also J. Fell (1965).
York: Oxford University Press. Sartre’s theory of the passions. New York: Columbia
LeDoux J. (1996). The emotional brain. New York: Si- University Press.
mon & Schuster. Schachter, S., & Singer, J. (1962). Cognitive, social and
Lyons, D. (1980). Emotion. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge physiological determinants of emotional state. Psy-
University Press. chological Review, 69(5), 379–399. For a good
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1994). The phenomenology of per- philosophical rejoinder, see R. M. Gordon (above),
ception. (C. Smith, Trans.). New York: Routledge. Ch. 5.
(Original work published 1962) Scheler, M. (1970). The nature of sympathy. New York:
Neu, J. (1977). Emotion, thought and therapy. Berkeley: Archon. (Original work published 1916)
University of California Press. Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philoso-
Neu, J. (1980). Jealous thoughts. In A. Rorty (Ed.), Ex- phy of mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
plaining emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Press. Seneca. (1963). De ira. Oxford: Loeb Classical Library,
Neu, J. (1999). A tear is an intellectual thing. New York: Oxford University Press.
Oxford University Press. Smith, A. (1976). Theory of the moral sentiments. Ox-
Nietzsche, F. (1967). On the genealogy of morals (W. ford: Oxford University Press. (Original work pub-
Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Random House. lished 1759)
(Original work published 1887) Smith, A. (1976). An inquiry into the nature and
Nissenbaum, H. (1985). Emotions and focus. Stanford, causes of the wealth of nations. Indianapolis, IN:
CA: CSLI. Liberty Classics. (Original work published 1776)
Nussbaum, M. (1994). The therapy of desire. Princeton, For a good study of the relation between Smith’s
NJ: Princeton University Press. A sympathetic and ethics and his economic theory, see P. Werhane
detailed discussion of the Stoics on the place of emo- (1991). Ethics and economics: The legacy of Adam
tion in life. Smith for contemporary capitalism. Oxford: Ox-
Nussbaum, M. (2003). Upheavals of thought. Cam- ford University Press.
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Solomon, R. (1976). The passions. Notre Dame, IN:
Ortony, A., Clore, G., & Collins, A. (1988). The cogni- University of Notre Dame Press. See also R. Solomon
tive structure of emotions. New York: Cambridge (1988). About love. New York: Simon & Schuster;
University Press. R. C. Solomon & K. Higgins (Eds.). (1991). The phi-
Plato. (1974). The republic (E. M. A. Grube, Trans.). In- losophy of (erotic) love. Lawrence: University of
dianapolis, IN: Hackett. Kansas Press.
Plato. (1989). The symposium (A. Nehamas & P. Wood- Solomon, R. (Ed.). (2003). What is an emotion? (2nd
ruff, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions. New York: Oxford Uni- Solomon, R. (2004). Not passion’s slave. New York:
versity Press. Oxford University Press.
Ricoeur, P. (1966). The voluntary and the involuntary Sorabji, R. (2003). Emotion and peace of mind. New
(E. Kohak, Trans.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern Uni- York: Oxford University Press.
versity Press. (Original work published 1950) Spinoza, B. (1982). Ethics. (S. Shirley, Trans.). Indianap-
Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions. New York: Cambridge olis, IN: Hackett. (Original work published 1677)
University Press. See also A. Rorty (1991). Spinoza on the pathos of
Robinson, J. (1995). Startle. Journal of Philosophy, love. In R. C. Solomon & K. Higgins (Eds.), The phi-
92(2), 53–74. losophy of (erotic) love. Lawrence: University of
Robinson, J. (2005). Deeper than reason. New York: Kansas Press.
Oxford University Press. Stocker, M. (1996). Valuing emotions. Cambridge, UK:
Rorty, A. (1980). Explaining emotions. In A. Rorty Cambridge University Press.
(Ed.), Explaining emotions. Berkeley: University of Thalberg, I. (1977). Perception, emotion and action.
California Press. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Russell, B. (1967). The autobiography of Bertrand Rus- Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Cam-
sell (Vol. 1). Boston: Little, Brown. bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ryle, G. (1951). The concept of mind. New York: Williams, B. (1973). Morality and the emotions. In
Barnes & Noble. Problems of the self. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
Sartre, J.-P. (1948). The emotions: Sketch of a theory (B. University Press.
Frechtman, Trans.). New York: Philosophical Li- Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations.
brary. (Original work published 1939) See the com- London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

You might also like