You are on page 1of 14

HEALTH ECONOMICS OUTCOME VALUATION

Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)


Published online 3 December 2002 in Wiley InterScience (www.interscience.wiley.com). DOI:10.1002/hec.768

The TTO method and procedural invariance


Anne Spencer*
Department of Economics, Queen Mary, University of London, UK

Summary
In a pilot study we investigate whether the inferences we draw about people’s preferences towards health care
treatments are altered if we vary the procedure that is used to elicit these preferences. In a conventional time trade-
off (TTO) question, respondents express their preferences towards treatment by comparing a period of ill-health with
a shorter period in a higher quality of life. In our less conventional TTO question, we vary the procedure by asking
respondents their preferences towards treatment by comparing a period of ill-health with a longer period in a lower
quality of life. The quantitative data are equivocal about whether preferences for treatment differ between the
conventional and unconventional questions. The qualitative data support the notion of contrasting issues in the
questions that involve prolonging time in a lower quality of life and appear to account for a failure to find
quantitative differences in all of the questions. Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

JEL classification: 131

Keywords time trade-off; procedural invariance

[2,3]. This set of assumptions allows for a unified


Introduction concept of utility to represent preferences in both
riskless and risky health care decisions [4,5]. A key
In health economics, survey methods have been feature of this utility is that procedural invariance
developed over the last thirty years to elicit holds and that preferences will be equivalent if the
people’s preferences for undergoing different method used to elicit them is changed slightly, for
health care treatments. One of these methods is instance, to one of prolonging life in a lower
the time trade-off (TTO) method [1]. The TTO quality of life [6].
method applies the principle of opportunity cost to Concern over whether procedural invariance
different types of treatment by asking respondents holds in practice has already been expressed for
to consider a trade-off between time and quality of preference elicitation methods that involve a trade-
life. In the conventional TTO method, respondents off between quality or longevity of life on the one
express their preferences towards treatment by hand and either risk or money on the other [7]. In
comparing a period of ill-health with a shorter the standard gamble (SG) method that involves
period in a higher quality of life. risk, it has been shown that procedural invariance
The assumptions required for the TTO method systematically breaks down if the question is asked
to be a valid measure of preferences under in terms of a treatment’s risk or longevity of life
expected utility theory, a theory of decision [8]. In the contingent valuation (CV) method that
making under risk, are outlined by Pliskin et al. involves money, the difference between asking the

*Correspondence to: Department of Economics, Queen Mary, University of London, Mile End Road, London, E1 4NS. UK.
E-mail: a.e.spencer@qmul.ac.uk

Received 3 July 2001


Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Accepted 23 July 2002
656 A. Spencer

question in terms of a person’s willingness-to-pay analysis describes the qualitative and quantitative
or willingness-to-accept money is well documented data and Results overviews our findings. Finally,
[9,10]. In the SG and CV methods this has led to Discussion considers the implications of our test
the development and application of alternatives to for the TTO method.
expected utility theory to explain the systematic
failures of procedural invariance. We add to this
debate by exploring whether procedural invariance
holds in the TTO method. Methods
The aim of this paper is to test the equivalence
of preferences elicited under the TTO method. A The questionnaire
secondary aim of the paper is to consider the issues
that respondents may be using to make their The study used the EuroQol classification system,
decisions. We ask a conventional TTO question which describes states of health along five dimen-
and a less conventional TTO question. In our less sions: mobility, self-care, usual activities, pain and
conventional TTO question, respondents express anxiety. Each dimension had three levels of
these preferences by comparing a period of ill- severity: no problems, some problems and severe
health with a longer period in a lower quality of problems, denoted by 1, 2 and 3, respectively, and
life. Procedural invariance states that if errors are colour-coded black, blue and red in the study.
small, preferences elicited from TTO questions Level 3 pain was described as moderate pain or
that offer a longer period in a lower quality of life discomfort with periods of severe pain or dis-
should be equivalent to preferences elicited from comfort rather than extreme pain or discomfort
TTO questions that offer a shorter period in a used in the EuroQol work. The description of level
higher quality of life. This is interesting for two 3 pain was changed to ensure that worse than
reasons. Firstly, the possibility of prolonging time death states were not included in the study.
in a lower quality of life already occurs in the Respondents were asked to tick one statement
treatment for certain cancers. Jansen et al. [11] are from each dimension that best described their
interested in using such questions in applied work current state of health. This helped to familiarise
but as far as we are aware such questions have not respondents with the EuroQol dimensions. Re-
been used. Secondly, if this method elicits quite spondents were then presented with six cards: five
different preferences, it raises concerns over the EuroQol states (11111, 12221, 21211, 21222 and
assumptions typically made in the conventional 22232) and immediate death [16,17]. Each state
TTO method. was colour-coded: 11111 was given the colour
The paper uses a combined qualitative and white, 12221 the colour grey, 21211 the colour
quantitative approach to reveal the issues con- yellow, 21222 the colour green, 22232 the colour
sidered by respondents in their answers. There pink and death the colour black (following the
appears to be renewed interest in linking qualita- example of Carthy et al. [18]). These are referred to
tive and quantitative approaches in the field of here by letters: 11111 is referred to as N, 12221 as
value elicitation to help understand the issues W , 21211 as X , 21222 as Y , 22232 as Z and death
driving respondents’ answers. However, there have as D. The state 12221 was used in a practice
been relatively few joint qualitative and quantita- question to allow respondents to become familiar
tive studies of value elicitation procedures [12–15]. with the methods but the actual values were not
A qualitative and quantitative approach is parti- used in the study.
cularly applicable in this paper given the pilot The respondents were asked to imagine that
nature of this work. each state lasted for ten years without change, to
Throughout, conventional values refer to values be followed immediately by death. They were
implied by the conventional TTO question and asked to rank the cards from the best state to the
unconventional values, refer to values implied by worst and then to place the cards on a visual
our question. The remainder of the paper is set out analogue scale, putting the best state at 100 and
as follows. The Methods section overviews the the worst state at 0. This was followed by twelve
questionnaire used in our paper and our test. In TTO questions, then seven SG questions. The
Theoretical predictions, we consider other recent research question posed in this paper involves the
explanations that have been offered to explain TTO questions only and the SG questions are
differences in the TTO values. Data collection and reported elsewhere [19]. To elicit the preferences

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance 657

we used the TTO boards and interview protocol If the value for V ðNÞ ¼ 1 and V ðDÞ ¼ 0 this
developed by the measurement and valuation of expression can be rearranged to give
health (MVH) study [14]. These boards and
V ðZÞ ¼ t4 =10 ð2Þ
interview protocols were modified slightly to
include the colours depicting each health state Question 4 is summarised in row 4 of Table 1,
and to allow for the new types of TTO questions where ten years in health state Z (column 1) is
presented here. The respondents were asked four compared against normal health and death (col-
conventional TTO questions that valued health umn 2), and is used to derive a conventional value
states against normal health and death (questions for Z (column 3).
1 to 4). They were then asked eight more TTO We considered two different types of unconven-
questions. We concentrate here on the two TTO tional question for this study. The first type
questions that involved prolonging time in a lower involved asking a respondent to imagine living in
quality of life (questions 9 to 10). The remainder of normal health for t4 years or undergoing a
the TTO questions tested whether the TTO value treatment that involved prolonging time in health
would be affected by comparing the health state state Z. Procedural invariance holds if the value
against normal health and a more-severe state (but derived from this unconventional question equal-
not death) and are reported elsewhere [19]. led the value derived from the conventional
question in question 4. Early piloting of the
questionnaire suggested that respondents found
TTO questions this type of unconventional question unrealistic.
Respondents argued that if they were in normal
The conventional TTO questions are illustrated health, they would not want to consider an
using question 4 in Figure 1. A respondent was alternative that offered a lower quality of life.
asked to imagine living in health state Z for ten Hence, it was very hard to get respondents to
years or undergoing a combination of t4 years in engage in the notion of a trade-off of time, an
normal health (N) but dying (D) 10  t4 , years essential feature of the TTO method. The second
earlier (where the subscript on the time, t, indicates type of unconventional question that was used in
the question number). In effect, they were asked to our study overcame this problem by asking a
consider a shorter period in a higher quality of life. respondent to imagine living in health state X or
The time in normal health t4 was varied until the Y , rather than normal health.
respondent was indifferent between the two alter- The two unconventional TTO questions used in
natives. At this point the two alternatives should our study are questions 9 and 10. In these
be equivalent. The majority of applied work using questions, respondents were asked to imagine
the TTO method then assumes that respondents living in a given health state for two years followed
do not have preferences towards the timing of ill- by death, or prolonging life in a lower quality of
health (or a zero rate of time preference) [5]. It is life. The time in the initial health state was set at
therefore possible to express this equivalence by two years, since it was anticipated that the
the following equality where V ð:Þ represents the responses to these questions would lie within the
TTO value assigned to the health state: ten year period based on conventional TTO
questions. Setting time at two years required us
10  V ðZÞ ¼ t4  V ðNÞ þ ð10  t4 Þ  V ðDÞ ð1Þ to impose an additional assumption, commonly
applied to the TTO method, that utility is linear in
duration. If utility is linear, the value of a health
state is not affected by the duration in that health
state [5]. Together with procedural invariance, this
assumption suggests that if errors are small,
the conventional value equals the unconven-
tional value. Questions 9 and 10 are illustrated
in Figure 2.
For example, in question 9, the question begins
by comparing two years in health state Y and two
Figure 1. An example of a conventional TTO question, years in health state Z and respondents are asked
question 4 which they prefer. When the time is the same, all

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
658 A. Spencer

Table 1. Questions used to test procedural invariance


(1) (2) (3)
Question Health state Comparison health states Abbreviation
1 10 W N þD Conventional V ðW Þ
2 10 X N þD Conventional V ðX Þ
3 10 Y N þD Conventional V ðY Þ
4 10 Z N þD Conventional V ðZÞ
9 2Y þ 8D ZþD Unconventional V ðZÞ
10 2X þ 8D Y þD Unconventional VðY Þ

Table 2. Summary of predicted impacts


Predicted impacts
Maximal endurable time +
Strong preference for longevity of life +
Loss aversion 
Time preference 

Figure 2. Questions 9 and 10


Theoretical predictions
respondents prefer to spend time in the higher Recent research has suggested that a respondent’s
quality of life, Y . The time in the lower quality of preferences are influenced by issues that are not
life, t9 is then increased until the respondent is typically reflected in the assumptions made in the
indifferent between the two alternatives (the TTO method. These issues are of interest to the
questionnaire and protocol are available upon study since they have the potential to create
request from the author). At this point of differences between the conventional and uncon-
indifference between the two alternatives the ventional TTO values. In this section, we review
following equality holds, assuming that respon- the impact these issues have on the conventional
dents have a zero rate of time preference: and unconventional values.
Table 2 summarises four issues that are pre-
dicted to create differences between the conven-
2  V ðY Þ ¼ t9  V ðZÞ ð3Þ tional and unconventional TTO responses: (1)
maximal endurable time, (2) strong preference for
longevity of life, (3) loss aversion and (4) time
If V ðY Þ is say, V ðY Þ ¼ t3 =10 (from question 3) this preference. In the following discussion we outline
leads to: the links between these four issues and the
conventional and unconventional values. We find
2  t3 that the first two issues would serve to increase the
V ðZÞ ¼ ð4Þ unconventional value whilst the last two would
10  t9
serve to decrease the unconventional value. Table 2
summarises the extent to which these issues result
Question 9 is summarised in row 5 in Table 1, in an unconventional value that is: ‘+’ higher
where two years in health state Y (column 1) is than, ‘=’ equal to or ‘’ lower than the conven-
compared against a longer period in Z (column 2), tional value. If the four issues in Table 2 cancel one
and is used to derive an unconventional value for another out in our study, then the conventional
Z (column 3). The null hypotheses to be tested in value will equal the unconventional value.
our paper is that the conventional value equals the A respondent may learn to cope and adapt to
unconventional value, and so in Table 1 the a new health state [20], termed positive adaptation
conventional V(Z)=unconventional V ðZÞ and by Ross and Simonson [21], or they may be-
conventional V(Y)=unconventional V ðY Þ. come increasingly disgruntled, termed negative

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance 659

adaptation. Dolan [22] speculated that healthy time. Let tl4 and tl9 denote the responses under scale
members of the public dwell more on the negative compatibility in questions 4 and 9, respectively. If
adaptation, whilst patients dwell more on the a respondent prefers any treatment which extends
positive adaptation. As respondents were recruited life then tl9 5te9 . However, the same respondent
from the general public and mature students it is may be unwilling to give up time in the elicitation
likely, therefore, that negative adaptation will be of the conventional value, tl4 4te4 . The conventional
more pronounced in the present study. If the and unconventional values in this case, therefore,
health state is particularly severe a respondent may will both increase. It is likely that this effect will be
doubt their ability to cope with continuing ill- greater for the unconventional value, given that
health, termed maximal endurable time by Suther- the unconventional value has two instances where
land et al. [23]. Sutherland et al. suggested that time has been set by a respondent (in Equation (4),
concerns over endurance might be particularly t3 and t9 ) and so this could amplify the scale
important if the health state is followed by death compatibility effect. A strong preference for the
rather than normal health. Question 9 involved longevity of life can be linked to the Robinson et al.
prolonging time in a more severe state Z, whilst [15] idea that there exists a threshold of tolerance
question 10 involved prolonging time in a less below which health must decline before a respon-
severe state Y . We would, therefore, expect the dent considers sacrificing time. If a respondent is
maximal endurance to arise more in question 9 unwilling to sacrifice time, the conventional and
than question 10. To illustrate the impact this has unconventional values both equal 1. Overall then,
upon the conventional and unconventional values, a strong preference towards the longevity of life,
consider the conventional and unconventional arising from scale compatibility or a threshold of
values in questions 4 and 9, respectively. Let te4 tolerance, leads to an unconventional value that is
and te9 denote the responses unaffected by the equal to or higher than the conventional value.
issues in Table 2 and tme 9 and tme
9 denote the Bleichrodt [25] and Spencer [19,26] consider the
responses under maximal endurance. For the impact on the conventional TTO value if a
unconventional value, a respondent’s fear that respondent evaluates the question as gains and
they cannot endure a severe health state may losses relative to a reference point. Central to these
discourage them from increasing time in the worse explanations is the assumption that a respondent is
state and then tme e
9 5t9 and the unconventional more sensitive to losses than to gains, termed loss
value will increase. However for the conventional aversion [27]. In addition, both Bleichrodt and
value, the same respondent’s concern for the severe Spencer assume that the reference point is the
health state will encourage them to sacrifice more initial health state that is considered in each
time to return to normal health and then tme e
4 5t4 , question. In the conventional value derived in
and the conventional value will decrease. Overall question 4, the reference point is Z, and in the
then, maximal endurable time leads to an un- unconventional value derived in 9, is Y . Let tloss 4
conventional value that is higher than the conven- and tloss
9 denote the responses under loss aversion
tional value. in questions 4 and 9, respectively. In the conven-
Anomalies between the conventional and un- tional value, the gains in health status are valued
conventional values may arise if respondents give less than the loss in longevity of life and so a
strong weight to quality or longevity of life. A respondent compensates by demanding a longer
respondent’s concerns over the quality or long- time in normal health, tloss4 > te4 . The conventional
evity of life can become more important if the value will increase. Whilst in the unconventional
treatment is assessed against a scale that includes value, the loss in health state is valued more than
quality or longevity of life, termed scale compat- the gain in health, and so they demand a longer
ibility [24]. Bleichrodt [25] used scale compatibility time in Z to compensate, tloss 9 > te9 , and the
to argue that respondents may give strong weight unconventional value will decrease. As a result of
to the longevity of life in the TTO method, since these two issues, the unconventional value is lower
the method varies time to elicit preferences. For than the conventional value.
instance, in questions that involve prolonging life, Finally, the TTO responses may be affected by a
they may seek to increase the longevity of life even respondent’s attitude towards time. Like the
if this puts them in a more severe health state. majority of TTO applications, the present study
They would, therefore, be willing to take any assumes that a respondent does not have prefer-
treatment which offered a marginal increase in ences towards the timing of ill-health [5]. It is as

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
660 A. Spencer

though a respondent gives equal weight to all time Table 3. The sample
periods. If a respondent instead prefers to con-
(1) (2) (3)
sume health in the short-term rather than in the
21–39 40–59 Total
long-term they will assign a higher weight to the
short-term. A value that correctly adjusts for a Male 9 3 12
respondent’s time preference hereafter is termed a Female 8 10 18
discounted value. The paper by Dolan and Jones- Total 17 13 30
Lee [28] can be used to show that the unconven-
tional value is lower than the conventional value,
given that the unconventional value includes two In the qualitative data the respondent was
instances where the values underestimate the encouraged to think aloud using a verbal protocol
impact of discounting (see appendix). analysis approach developed by Ericsson and
In the conventional TTO value, Bleichrodt [25] Simons [30].
noted that the assumption that there is no Early piloting of the questionnaire suggested
preference towards the timing of ill-health might that the questions might not have been well suited
cancel out the impacts of scale compatibility and to such concurrent data collection. In particular,
loss aversion. Maximal endurable time also has the the questions were broken down into a number of
same ability to cancel out the impacts of scale repetitive stages before the final answer was
compatibility and loss aversion in the conventional reached and the natural reaction of respondents
TTO value. This issue is predicted to gain was to give a conventional answer without
importance in our study for questions that involve elaboration.
severe states or cases where there is prolonged To overcome the problem, it was felt necessary
exposure to ill-health. to ask respondents an additional question at the
end of the task:
What types of things were you thinking about when
you answered this question?
Data collection and analysis
We avoided ‘why’ questions because Patton [31]
Respondents were recruited from members of the argues these can be answered on many different
general public and from mature students begin- levels. Patton classifies four broad types of probes:
ning a course in the Department of Health detail orientated, elaboration, clarification and
Sciences at the University of York. Respondents contrast probes. The study used elaboration
were invited to take part in a 90-min interview in probes, which encourage the respondent to con-
the Department of Economics at York University tinue talking using body language by a gentle
for a payment of £15. All interviews were tape- nodding of the head or verbal ‘uh-huh’ as well as
recorded. In total, 30 respondents were inter- questions which asked a respondent to say a little
viewed, 12 males and 18 females (see Table 3). more about a particular issue. The study also made
In the quantitative data, the Wilcoxon signed use of clarification probes to check that the
ranks test was used [29]. The test calculates the interviewer had understood the respondent [31].
extent to which the conventional and unconven- The interviewer verbalised a respondent’s non-
tional values differ for each respondent. It then verbal cues, such as eye or hand movements which
ranks the absolute value of these differences for all were used to emphasise a point. The interviews
respondents (i.e. considering only the size and not were transcribed and analysed using the software
direction of difference) from smallest to largest and package HyperResearch# that aids the manage-
calculates the sum of the ranks for all positive ment and analysis of non-numerical data. This
differences and all negative differences. The null analysis began by summarising excerpts using the
hypothesis is that the median of these differences is respondents own terminology and key phrases.
zero and that the conventional and unconven- These were categorised as specific codes. This was
tional values are the same. The alternative followed by an attempt to link the specific codes to
hypothesis is that there is a systematic difference form general codes which help to characterise
between the responses. If the alternative hypoth- particular themes. Finally, themes that seemed to
esis was to hold, there would be a clustering of the contradict the TTO assumptions were identified.
positive and negative differences in the ranking. The qualitative analysis seemed best applied to

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance 661

hypothesis generation rather than hypothesis Y and Z the estimated mean values in the MVH
testing as it challenged existing concepts and study were 0.81, 0.62 and 0.02 and the estimated
helped to understand the material more fully. At median values were 0.94, 0.65 and 0.028. These
the beginning of the analysis, there was no pre- values are very similar to those derived in this
defined coding schedule but only a series of study and that are shown in Table 4 except for
questions that the researcher intended to address. Health state Z. Health state Z is valued higher in
In the process of transcribing a coding system was the present study since level 3 pain was described
developed. Specific codes recorded the question as moderate pain or discomfort with periods of
number and any additional interview probes. severe pain or discomfort rather than extreme pain
Some respondents wanted to engage in debate or discomfort used in the EuroQol work. For
with the interviewer and it was felt necessary to equivalent health state descriptions, therefore, the
challenge a respondent’s answer if they were not conventional TTO method used in our study is
interating towards their point of indifference. This consistent with earlier TTO studies.
occurred particularly in the TTO question that The median unconventional value for health
involved prolonging time in the lower quality of state Z is 0.4 and for health state Y is 0.425 (see
life as some respondents began to answer the Table 4). The Wilcoxon signed ranks test showed
question by stating their maximum endurance in the unconventional values for Y were significantly
that state, or suggested the point at which one lower than the conventional values (in question 10)
treatment would be strictly preferred. whilst the differences between the unconventional
and conventional values for Z were not statisti-
cally different, and responses were evenly spread
Results between higher and lower unconventional values
(in question 9, column 1 rows 1 and 2 in Table 5).
Quantitative results In summary, the quantitative results were mixed:
the unconventional values for Y were significantly
lower in question 10 than conventional values, but
The median conventional values for health states
the unconventional values for Z in question 9 were
X , Y and Z are 0.9, 0.65 and 0.45 (see Table 4) and
not statistically different to the conventional
the Wilcoxon signed ranks test showed that
values. The null hypotheses, that the conventional
respondents found the states statistically different
values equal the unconventional values, are there-
(P ¼ 0:0002 or less). We can compare the conven-
fore rejected in only one of the two tests.
tional TTO values derived here against those
estimated from a larger study to check the extent
to which our results are consistent with earlier
studies. The MVH study asked 3395 members of Qualitative results
the general public to value a subset of EuroQol
states using the TTO method and this subset of In the qualitative analysis responses appeared to
states were used to infer the values for the full fall into five themes listed in Table 6 for questions
range of EuroQol states [30]. For health states X , 9 and 10, respectively. The first column of Table 6

Table 4. The summary statistics


(1) (2) (3) (4) (5)
Question Abbreviation na Mean Median Standard deviation
1 Conventional V ðW Þ 30 0.802 0.950 0.248
2 Conventional V ðX Þ 30 0.856 0.900 0.163
3 Conventional V ðY Þ 29 0.635 0.650 0.217
4 Conventional V ðZÞ 28 0.457 0.450 0.207
9 Unconventional VðZÞ 28 0.479 0.400 0.228
10 Unconventional V ðY Þ 29 0.502 0.425 0.257
a
Respondents were excluded from the analysis it they felt that the health states were worse than death. Two respondents felt that
health state Z was worse than death and one respondent felt that health state Y was worse than death.

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
662 A. Spencer

Table 5. The Wilcoxon signed ranks test


(1) (2)
Question 9 Question 10
unconventional V ðZÞ unconventional V ðY Þ versus
versus conventional V ðZÞ conventional V ðY Þ
No. of cases where unconventional value5 14 20
conventional value
No. of cases where unconventional value> 13 7
conventional value
No. of cases where unconventional value= 1 2
conventional value
Total 28 29

Wilcoxon Z 0.745 2.499


2-tailed P 0.456 0.010
Accept Reject

refers to the number of respondents in questions 9 values for a health state were lower than the
and 10 who were willing to trade quality of life conventional values.
(based on specific codes Q9 trade-off and Q10 Of those respondents who were willing to
trade-off). For example, in question 9 that asked trade quality of life for longevity of life,
respondents to consider prolonging time in the some respondents felt that they would need more
more severe health state (health state Z), 13 of the time in Z to compensate (specific codes: Q9
28 respondents expressed a willingness to trade increase by a lot, Q9 need longer Z). This supports
quality for longevity of life. This willingness to the notion that respondents sought longer periods
trade rose to 21 respondents in question 10 that of time to compensate for the reduction in the
considered prolonging time in the more moderate quality of life and is consistent with loss aversion.
health state (health state Y ). An example of this In addition, they felt that they might accommo-
kind of response is as follows: date to the health state (specific code: Q10
accommodate) or could cope with the state (specific
Respondent: For several reasons, in pink (Z) you are code: Q10 cope) which is consistent with positive
in a greater degree of ill-health so you’re not able to adaptation to the health state. Other respondents
do the things as you would be able to do if you were felt that they wanted longer to live but disliked the
in a lesser degree of ill-health, i.e. in green (Y). So
therefore, you may need that small duration of time more severe health state Z (specific codes: Q9 try
to achieve the same things as you would be able to hold on, Q9 only just cope, Q9 hang on, Q9 knock
achieve in a lesser state of ill-health, i.e. being in deaths door, Q10 adding poor quality, Q10 not
green (Y). Are you with me? What you can actually stand depression, Q10 plod, Q10 max endurance Y ).
do here, you may be able to do in a lesser time than One respondent in question 9 and 10 demanded
you could do there. [Interview 22, Q9 trade-off.] more time in the lower quality of life, but it is not
clear that this was perceived as a form of
The main reasons for their willingness to trade compensation and so this is reported separately
quality of life for longevity of life related to the in column 5, Table 6.
impression that two years was too short (specific The second most popular response related to
codes: Q9 time is short, Q10 time is short, Q9 that an unwillingness to prolong time in a lower quality
or death, Q9 yes alive, Q10 want extra life, Q10 still of life (based on specific codes: Q9 not prolong
alive) and that they would need more time to and Q10 not prolong). In the case of ques-
achieve the same life goals (specific codes: Q9 tions that involved prolonging time in the more
something to achieve, Q10 a bit more). Respondents severe health state Z, 11 of the 28 respondents
that were willing to trade accounted for the were unwilling to prolong time in Z (column 2,
majority of the cases where the unconventional Table 6). An example of the unwillingness

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
Table 6. The conventional and unconventional values for health states
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5)
Loss aversion: Maximal endurable time: Strong preference
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance

for longevity

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.


of life:
Willing to Unwilling to Increase Health Demanding
trade-off quality prolong time in a longevity of life states perceived to be more time in
for longevity lower quality irrespective of quality the same lower quality of life
of life of life and of life
Question 9
Unconventional5conventional 13 0 0 n/a 1
Unconventional>conventional 0 10 3 n/a 0
Unconventional=conventional 0 1 0 n/a 0
n ¼ 28 13 11 3 n/a 1

Question 10
Unconventional5conventional 20 0 0 0 0
Unconventional>conventional 1 3 1 1 1
Unconventional=conventional 0 0 2 0 0
n ¼ 29 21 3 3 1 1
n/a=not applicable.

Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)


663
664 A. Spencer

to prolong in a lower quality in Z is given as willing to prolong time irrespective of the quality
follows: of life (column 3, Table 6). An example of this kind
of response is as follows:
Respondent: I wouldn’t really want it, it’s a . . .
because its only two years anyway, but my sort of Respondent: No, I would always go for choice A,
personal feeling looking at it right now is, that’s it length of life rather than quality of life. [Interview 8,
would be two years in pink (Z) or 20 years in pink (Z) Q9 prolong life because like life.]
there’s not a great deal that’s going to be accom-
plished, if I’m able to I’ll see the kids grow up and The main reasons for increasing longevity of life
that, so a definite choice that I would want to live, irrespective of quality of life seemed to relate to the
but I think that my own state of mind that I would go desire for longer lives (Q10 time is short, but can
crazy in the end, so I’ll stick with choice B. [Interview envisage this). It is possible that scale compatiblity
12, Q9 not prolong.] encouraged these responses to give more weight to
the longevity of life than quality of life. In question
The main reasons for respondents’ unwillingness
9, this led to an unconventional value that was
to prolong time in a lower quality of life centred
higher than the conventional value. There is also
around the impression that this state represented a
evidence of a threshold of tolerance, below which a
very severe state of health (specific codes: Q9
health state had to fall before they were willing to
absolute writhing, Q9 go crazy, Q9 suffer, Q9 seen
sacrifice longevity of life. Two respondents were
people suffer, Q10 two major categories, Q10 can
unwilling to trade longevity for improvements in
take so much, Q10 prolong pain). However, all
quality of life for health states X and Y and the
these respondents had considered health state Z to
conventional and unconventional values equalled l
be better than death in the conventional TTO
for these states.
questions. Some respondents saw immediate death
These two types of responses, an unwillingness
as an option to a lingering death in a lower quality
to prolong time in a lower quality of life (linked to
of life (specific codes: Q9 believe in euthanasia and
maximal endurable time) and a willingness to
Q9 go quickly) whilst others just stated that they
increase longevity irrespective of quality of life,
would receive no benefit from increasing time in a
account for the majority of cases where the
lower quality of life (specific codes: Q9 no point
unconventional values were higher than the con-
and Q9 not worth living). These explanations are
ventional values. For example, in question 9, 10 of
consistent with maximal endurable time.
the 11 respondents who were unwilling to prolong
There was an indication that more of the
time in the lower quality of life gave an unconven-
respondents would have been unwilling to prolong
tional value that was higher than the conventional.
the time in the lower quality of life if the
This effect is greater for health state Z in question
alternative with which they were initially presented
9 than health state Y in question 10 and is likely to
was for longer than two years (two respondents,
account for our failure to find statistical differences
specific codes: Q9 time is short and Q10 time is
between the conventional and unconventional
short). An example of this kind of response is as
values for Z. Finally, in question 10, one of the
follows:
respondents felt that the two states were very
Respondent: Two years isn’t long, but I’m not too similar (column 4, Table 6).
bad am I, I don’t know because it’s a hard
comparison to make because I don’t want to be in
pink (Z) at all, so the thought of being in pink (Z) for Discussion
any length of time, fills me with dread but the
thought of being in green (Y ) for two years is equally In this section, we consider the issues raised by the
as bad because it’s only two years, so the instinct is to
favour pink (Z) because it’s for longer. . .. [Interview qualitative results, and the extent to which they
14, Q9 time is short.] explain the quantitative results. We also outline
the weakness of our test design and suggest where
Some respondents were willing to increase the further research is needed. Finally we look at the
longevity of life irrespective of quality of life implications that this study has the for the TTO
(based on specific codes: Q9 prolong because like method.
life and Q10 prolong because like life). In the case We are unable to conclusively reject procedural
of questions that involved prolonging time in invariance, with only one of the two tests detecting
health state Z, three of the 28 respondents were a statistical difference. The qualitative data help to

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance 665

shed light on the issues that people consider in valued closer to 0.5 than those in question 10, and
their responses and suggest three main issues can so we would anticipate more of an impact in the
account for the quantitative results. former than the latter questions. The contrary
result is found in our study. It is of course possible
* Firstly, a willingness to trade-off quality for that in question 9 the concerns over the maximal
longevity of life led to an unconventional value endurance undermined the impact of time prefer-
that was lower than the conventional value. The ences. Secondly, there is a general conclusion that
driving force for such responses appeared to be although summary measures suggest people have
related to loss aversion, where respondents no preference over the timing of ill-health, there is
demanded a larger increase in the time spent larger variation in preferences between people
in the more severe state to compensate for the [33,34]. It is therefore, quite possible that incor-
porating people’s preferences towards time will
decrease in the quality of life. It is also possible
lead to both higher and lower unconventional
that people’s preferences for the timing of ill- values compared to the conventional values, and
health led to an unconventional value that was so may fail to explain our findings. Nevertheless, it
lower than the conventional. We are unable to is an important variable to consider in future
test for these effects separately here but in a studies to determine whether time preferences lead
later section of the discussion we argue that to differences between the conventional and
discounting is unlikely to be the main driving unconventional values.
force in this study. The study also allows us to consider the extent
* Secondly, an unwillingness to prolong time in a to which the different issues cancel one another
lower quality of life led to an unconventional out. Both a strong preference for longevity of
value that was higher than the conventional life and maximal endurable time have the
potential to cancel out the impact of loss aversion.
value. The main driving force for such re-
However, maximal endurable time appears to play
sponses appeared to be related to maximal a greater role in the one test that resulted
endurance and was stronger when respondents in equivalent conventional and unconventional
were asked to prolong time in the more severe values.
state Z. More than a third of the sample were A design weakness of the test is that a
unwilling to prolong time in a more severe respondent’s willingness to trade quality and
health state Z in question 9 compared to only a longevity of life may have been affected by the
tenth for prolonging time in health state Y in short duration of the states in the TTO questions
question 10. The concern over the severity of Z, involving two years followed by death. Short time
therefore, appears to have undermined our periods have been shown to affect people’s will-
ability to detect statistically significant differ- ingness to trade in conventional TTO questions.
McNeil [35] found that, for states lasting under
ences in one of the two tests. Hence, the
five years, patients with laryngeal cancer were
quantitative results found lower unconventional unwilling to trade longevity for quality of life.
values in only one of the two tests considered. However, unlike the questions here, the conven-
* Thirdly, a willingness to increase longevity of tional TTO questions used by McNeil involved a
life irrespective of quality of life led to an reduction in the longevity of life. The qualitative
unconventional value that was equal to or data allow us to reflect upon whether the short
higher than the conventional value. The main duration affected those questions that increase
driving force for such responses appeared to be longevity. Some respondents explicitly stated that
related to scale compatibility and threshold of they would be more unwilling to prolong the time
tolerance. in the lower quality of life if the alternative
treatment was for longer than two years. This
There are two reasons to question whether time unwillingness to trade is likely to be related to
preferences alone are able to explain our findings. concerns over the maximal endurable time and so
Firstly, Dolan and Jones-Lee [28] show that the this issue could begin to dominate in longer time
distortions related to time preferences are larger spans, leading to an unconventional value that
for health states that are valued around 0.5. The is higher than the conventional value. We recom-
health states that are involved in question 9 are mend further work to replicate the questions

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
666 A. Spencer

for different time periods and health states, to see conventional and unconventional values are af-
the extent to which concerns over maximal fected by discounting.
endurable time cancel out concerns over loss Question 9 compares 2 years in Y and death or
aversion. t9 years in Z and death. Question 9 therefore
What are the implications of this study for compares 2 years in Y and dying (t9  2) years
the TTO method? Firstly, the study brings into earlier or t9 years in health state Z. Let a
question the assumptions that are typically made. respondent’s rate of time preference be represented
To improve the method’s descriptive ability, by a discount weight, r, and let 05r51. The
we recommend that it is expanded to incorporate discounted value for Z is then calculated from
respondents’ loss of quality of life and concern question 9 by equation (1).
over maximal endurance or longevity of life.
X
1 X
t9 1
For example, the TTO method could apply rt  V ðY Þ ¼ rt  V ðZÞ ðA1Þ
non-expected utility theories that model the impact 0 0
of loss aversion. In addition, the impact of
maximal endurable time and preference for long- where t9 52. The geometric progression formula is
evity of life could be considered in the interpreta- given as
tion of results. Secondly, the study raises concerns X
n1
a  ð1  rn Þ
over how best to aggregate individual responses. a  rt ¼
The equivocal quantitative results appear to mask 0
1r
a variety of individual responses associated with using this in Equation (A1) gives:
loss aversion, maximal endurable time and a
strong preference for longevity of life. The fact 1  r2 1  rt 9
 V ðY Þ ¼  V ðZÞ
that these issues can cancel out at an aggregate 1r 1r
level suggests that, in some instances, the summary
statistics may fail to closely approximate indivi- Rearranging it follows that the discounted value
dual values [5]. There is a trend towards subgroup for Z is:
analyses of preferences within populations [36]. If 1  r2
policy makers want to reflect more broadly the V ðZÞ ¼  V ðY Þ ðA2Þ
1  r t9
preferences of individual members, future work
should consider more carefully the implications of The unconventional value for Z assumes no
subgroup analyses and how these views should be discounting and is given as
aggregated. 2
V ðZÞ ¼  V ðY Þ ðA3Þ
t9
Acknowledgements To compare the unconventional value in Equation
(A3) against the discounted value in Equation (A2)
The author would like to thank Graham Loomes, Karl it is important to note that since 05r51 it follows
Claxton, Judith Covey, Nick Pidgeon, Björn Lindgren, immediately that
Carl Hampus Lyttkens and two referees for their
valuable comments. In addition, the author is grateful
1  r2 2
> ðA4Þ
to the Swedish Medical Research Council and the 1  r t9 t 9
Swedish Social Research Council for funding a visiting
research fellowship to pilot the approach, via research
Therefore, the unconventional value for Z,
grants to Björn Lindgren, Lund University. The author V ðZÞ ¼ ð2=t9 Þ  V ðY Þ, is lower than the dis-
is also grateful to the ESRC award R00023 4987 for counted value for Z, V ðZÞ ¼ ½ð1  r2 Þ=ð1  rt9 Þ 
financial support for the UK study. Any errors are the V ðY Þ
responsibility of the author alone. The extent to which the unconventional value is
lower than the discounted value is reinforced by
any underestimation of the conventional value Y
Appendix A which forms part of the unconventional formula
for Z in Equation (A3) [28]. Overall then, this
Dolan and Jones-Lee [28] showed that the reinforcement results in an unconventional value
conventional value is lower than the discounted for Z that is lower than the conventional value
value. We use their approach to compare how the for Z.

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
The TTO Method and Procedural Invariance 667

References 16. Gudex C, Dolan P, Kind P, Williams A. Valuing


health states: Interviews with the general public. Eur
1. Torrance GW, Thomas WH, Sackett DL. A J Public Health 1997; 7: 441–448.
utility maximization model for evaluation of 17. Dolan P, Gudex C, Kind P, Williams A. The time
health care programmes. Health Serv Res 1972; 7: trade-off method: Results from a general population
118–133. study. Health Econ 1996; 5: 141–154.
2. Pliskin JS, Shepard DS, Weinstein MC. Utility 18. Carthy T, Chilton S, Covey J et al. On the
functions of life years and health status. Operational contingent valuation of safety and the safety of
Res 1980; 28: 206–224. contingent valuation: Part 2 – The CV/SG
3. von Neumann J, Morgenstern O. Theory of Games ‘‘Chained’’ approach. J Risk Uncertainty 1999; 17:
and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press: 187–213.
Princeton, NJ, 1944. 19. Spencer A. The implications of linking questions
4. Wakker PP. Separating marginal utility and prob- within the SG and TTO methods. Department of
abilistic risk aversion. Theory Decision 1994; 36: Economics, Queen Mary University of London,
1–44. 2001; working paper 438.
5. Dolan, P. The measurement of health-related 20. Mooney G, Olsen J. QALYs: where next? In
quality of life. In Handbook of Health Economics, Providing Health Care, McGuire A, Fenn P,
Culyer A, Newhouse JP (eds). Elsevier: Amsterdam, Mayhew K (eds). Oxford University Press: Oxford,
2000; 1723–1759. 1991; 120–140.
6. Tversky A, Sattath S, Slovic P. Contingent weight- 21. Ross WT, Simonson I. Evaluating pairs of experi-
ing in judgement and choice. Psychol Rev 1988; 95: ence: a preference for happy endings. J Behav
371–384. Decision Making 1991; 4: 273–282.
7. Beattie J, Chilton S, Cookson R et al. Valuing health 22. Dolan P. Modelling valuations for health states:
and safety controls: a literature review, Contract the effect of duration. Health Pol 1996; 38:
Research Report. Health and Safety Executive 189–203.
books: London, 1998. 23. Sutherland HJ, Llewellyn-Thomas H, Boyd NF, Till
8. Wakker P, Deneffe D. Eliciting von Neumann- JE, Attitude toward quality of survival: the concept
Morgenstern utilities when probabilities are of maximal endurable time. Med Decision Making
distorted or unknown. Manage Sci 1996; 42: 1982; 2: 299–309.
1131–1150. 24. Slovic P, Griffen D, Tversky A. Compatibility
9. Beattie J, Covey J, Dolan P et al. On the contingent effects in judgment and choice. In Insights in
valuation of safety and the safety of contingent Decision Making. Einhorn J, Hogarth RM (eds).
valuation: Part 1 – Caveat investigator. J Risk The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, 1990;
Uncertainty 1998; 17: 5–25. 5–27.
10. Diener A, O’Brien B, Gafni A. Health care 25. Bleichrodt H. A new explanation for the difference
contingent valuation studies: A review and classifi- between time trade-off utilities and standard gamble
cation of the literature. Health Econ 1998; 7: utilities. Health Econ 2002; 11: 447–456.
313–326. 26. Spencer A, Value elicitation techniques: metho-
11. Jansen SJT, Stiggelbout AM, Wakker PP, et al. dological issues involved in two-stage pro-
Patients’ utilities for cancer treatments: a study cedures. D.Phil thesis, University of York: York,
of the chained procedure for the standard gamble 1998.
time tradeoff. Med Decision Making 1998; 18: 27. Tversky A, Kahneman D. Advances in Prospect
391–399. Theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty. J
12. Dolan P, Cookson R. A qualitative study of the Risk Uncertainty 1992; 5: 297–323.
extent to which health gain matters when choosing 28. Dolan P, Jones-Lee M. The time trade-off: a note on
between groups of patients. Health Pol 2000; 51: the effect of lifetime reallocation of consumption
19–30. and discounting. J Health Econ 1997; 16: 731–739.
13. Dolan P, Cookson R, Ferguson B. Effect of 29. Howell DC. Statistical Methods for Psychology,
discussion and deliberation on public’s views about (2nd edn), Duxbury Press: Boston, 1982.
priority setting in health care: focus group study. 30. Ericsson KA, Simon HA. Verbal reports as data.
Brit Med J 1999; 318: 916–919. Psychol Rev 1980; 87: 215–251.
14. Dolan P, Green C. Using the person trade- 31. Patton MQ. Qualitative evaluation and research
off approach to examine differences between methods. Sage Publications: London, 1990.
individual and social values. Health Econ 1998; 7: 32. EQ-5D information pack, Centre for Health Eco-
307–312. nomics, York.
15. Robinson A, Dolan P, Williams A. Valuing health 33. Dolan P, Gudex C. Time preference, duration
states using VAS and TTO: what lies behind the and health state valuations. Health Econ 1995; 4:
numbers? Social Sci Med 1997; 45: 1289–1297. 289–299.

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)
668 A. Spencer

34. Redelmeier DA, Heller DN. Time preference 36. Sculpher M, Gafni A. Can we reflect variation in
in medical decision-making and cost-effectiveness societal health state preferences in cost-effectiveness
analysis. Med Decision Making 1993; 13: 212–217. analysis? International Health Economics Associa-
35. McNeil BJ, Weichselbaum R, Pauker SG. Fallacy of tion, Third International Conference, York,
the five-year survival in lung cancer. N Engl J Med 2001.
1978; 25: 1299–1397.

Copyright # 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Health Econ. 12: 655–668 (2003)

You might also like