You are on page 1of 138

E D M U N D H U S S E R L

Critical A s s e s s m e n t s of L e a d i n g Philosophers

E d i t e d b y R u d o l f B e r n e t ,

D o n n W e l t o n a n d G i n a Z a v o t a

Volume V

Horizons: Life-world, Ethics, History, and Metaphysics

Routledge
R Taylor & Francis Group
LONDON AND NEW YORK
C O N T E N T S

First published 2005 VOLUME V HORIZONS: LIFE-WORLD, ETHICS,


by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN HISTORY, AND METAPHYSICS
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge Acknowledgements vii
270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
Editorial matter and selection © 2005 Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton PART 10
and Gina Zavota; individual owners retain copyright in their own The Concept of the Life-world 1
material
Typeset in Times by Wearset Ltd, Boldon, Tyne and Wear
Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books Ltd, Bodmin 70 The lifeworld revisited: Husserl and some recent interpreters 3
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or DAVID CARR
reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical,
or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including
photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or 71 Husserl's concept of the world 19
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. RUDOLF BERNET
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
72 Heimwelt, Fremdwelt, die eine Welt 39
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data KLAUS HELD
A catalog record for this book has been requested
ISBN (M15-28956-4 (Set)
ISBN 0-415-34536-7 (Volume V)
PART 11
Publisher's Note
References within each chapter are as they appeared in the original Ethics and Community 59
complete work
73 Husserl's phenomenology of willing 61
ULLRICH MELLE

74 Moral objectivity: Husserl's sentiments of the understanding 80


JOHN J. DRUMMOND

75 Phenomenology, value theory, and nihilism 99


STEVEN CROWELL
CONTENTS

76 Edmund Husserl: from reason to love 119


ULLRICH MELLE

77 Freedom, responsibility, and self-awareness in Husserl 140


TOM NENON A C K N O W L E D G E M E N T S

PART 12
Culture and the Problem of History 163

78 Die Phanomenologie als transzendentale Theorie der


Geschichte 165
Volume V
LUDWIG LANDGREBE
The publishers would like to thank the following for permission to reprint
79 Husserl's Crisis and the problem of history 184 their material:
DAVID CARR Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint David Carr, "The
lifeworld revisited: Husserl and some recent interpreters", in William R.
80 "Faktum Geschichte" und die Grenzen phanomenologischer McKenna and J. N. Mohanty (eds), Husserl's Phenomenology: A
Geschichtsphilosophie 204 Textbook, Washington, DC: Center for Advanced Research in Phenom-
KARL-HEINZ LEMBECK enology and University Press of America, 1989, pp. 291-308.
State University of New York Press for permission to reprint Rudolf
PART 13 Bernet, "Husserl's Concept of the World", in Arleen B. Dallery, Charles
Rationality and Metaphysics 217 E. Scott and P. Holley Roberts (eds), Crises in Continental Philosophy,
Albany: The State University of New York Press, 1990, pp. 3-21. © 1990
State University of New York. All rights reserved.
81 Husserl's concept of the "absolute" 219
RUDOLF BOEHM Karl Alber Verlag for permission to reprint Klaus Held, "Heimwelt,
Fremdwelt, die eine Welt", in Ernst Wolfgang Orth (ed.), Perspektiven
82 Entelechy in transcendental phenomenology: a sketch of the und Probleme der Husserlschen Phanomenologie, Phanomenologische
foundations of Husserlian metaphysics 246 Forschungen 24 (1991): 305-337.
JAMES G. HART Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint Ullrich Melle,
"Husserl's phenomenology of willing", in James G. Hart and Lester
Embree (eds), Phenomenology of Values and Valuing, Dordrecht: Kluwer,
1997, pp. 169-192. With kind permission of Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint John J. Drum-
mond, "Moral objectivity: Husserl's sentiments of the understanding",
Husserl Studies 12 (1995): 165-183. With kind permission of Kluwer Acad-
emic Publishers.
Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint Steven Crowell,
"Phenomenology, value theory, and nihilism" (Kluwer, forthcoming).
Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint Ullrich Melle,

VI vn

L
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

"Edmund Husserl: from reason to love", in John J. Drummond and Lester


I Embree (eds), Phenomenological Approaches to Moral Philosophy, Dor-
drecht: Kluwer, 2002, pp. 229-248.
Noesis Press Ltd for permission to reprint Tom Nenon, "Freedom,
Part 10
responsibility, and self-awareness in Husserl", in Burt Hopkins and Steven
Crowell (eds), The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomeno-
logical Philosophy 2 (2002): 1-21.
T H E C O N C E P T O F T H E L I F E
Karl Alber Verlag for permission to reprint Ludwig Landgrebe, "Die
Phanomenologie als transzendentale Theorie der Geschichte", in Ernst
W O R L D
Wolfgang Orth (ed.), Phanomenologie und Praxis, Phdnomenologische
Forschungen 3 (1976): 17-47.
Southwestern Journal of Philosophy for permission to reprint David Carr,
"Husserl's Crisis and the Problem of History", Southwestern lournal of
Philosophy 5(3) (1974): 127-148.
Kluwer Academic Publishers for permission to reprint Karl-Heinz
Lembeck, "'Faktum Geschichte' und die Grenzen phanomenologischer
Geschichtsphilosophie", Husserl Studies 4 (1987): 209-224. With kind per-
mission of Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Noesis Press Ltd for permission to reprint Rudolf Boehm, "Husserl's
concept of the 'absolute'", trans. R. O. Elveton, in R. O. Elveton (ed.),
The Phenomenology of Husserl: Selected Critical Readings, Chicago:
Quadrangle Books, 1970, pp. 174-203.
Philosophy Documentation Center for permission to reprint James G.
Hart, "Entelechy in transcendental phenomenology: a sketch of the
foundations of Husserlian metaphysics", American Catholic Philosophical
Quarterly 66(2) (1992): 189-212.

Disclaimer
The publishers have made every effort to contact authors/copyright
holders of works reprinted in Edmund Husserl: Critical Assessments of
Leading Philosophers. This has not been possible in every case, however,
and we would welcome correspondence from those individuals/companies
whom we have been unable to trace.

vm
70

T H E L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

Husserl and some recent interpreters

David Carr

Source: David Carr "The lifeworld revisited: Husserl and some recent interpreters' in David
Carr, Interpreting Husserl: Critical and Comparative Studies, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers, 1987, pp. 227-44.

The concept of the lifeworld was of central importance to the revived


interest in Husserl's thought during the 1950's and 1960's. In Europe this
revival was influenced jointly by the French existentialists and by the post-
war publication of Husserl's collected works. Maurice Merleau-Ponty had
referred at several points in his 1945 Phenomenology of Perception to the
unpublished portions of Husserl's last work, The Crisis of European Sci-
ences, in which the Lebenswelt figures prominentley, and those portions
were then published in 1954 in vol. VI of Husserliana. As existential
phenomenology attracted interest in North America in the 1960's,
Husserl's late work was seen as part of a trend that included Merleau's
concept of the monde vecu and Heidegger's emphasis in Being and Time
on being-in-the-world.
Inevitably the philosophical landscape has changed since then, and the
lifeworld has been somewhat lost from view. This shift is not without its
historical ironies. Continental European philosophy was contrasted in the
post-war period with a strong Anglo-American preoccupation with lan-
guage. But German and French philosophy has itself taken up language
since then, either literally or as a powerful metaphor for human thought
and experience. Hermeneutics sees human reality as a text to be inter-
preted, and structuralism and post-structuralism analyse everything in
terms of realms of discourse closed in upon themselves. Meanwhile Anglo-
American philosophers have for some time felt the constraints imposed by
taking language as the paradigm for thought, and in some quarters
Husserl's concept of intentionality is being proposed as a mentalistic solu-
tion to the problem of linguistic meaning.
In my view something important has been lost in these developments,
something valuable that Husserl contributed precisely in his concept of the
lifeworld. And by overlooking this contribution some of those who now
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S . THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

focus their attention on Husserl are not fully understanding this thought. and perhaps since the birth of philosophy in Greece, we have lived in what
By returning to the concept of the lifeworld in this essay I hope to rectify Husserl thought of as a scientific culture, that is, a culture which places in
in some measure this oversight. our free, rational, theorizing activity its hopes for our ultimate understand-
What has been overlooked can be characterized in a preliminary and ing of ourselves and our place in the universe. But instead of faciliting our
very general way as follows: Those who focus on language as discourse self-understanding science seems to have contributed to our estrangement
tend to dissolve the world into language or equate it with a series of con- from our world and ourselves.
ceptual projections, forgetting or denying that language refers beyond There is a social side to this development of which we are all aware.
itself. Those who concentrate narrowly on Husserl's theory of meaning, The scientist's universe is not only removed from us but also incompre-
and in particular on the noema as the meaning of an expression or its cor- hensible to most of us. To those who do comprehend it, the professional
responding mental act, rightly complain that the above view overlooks the scientists, we cede our right to understanding; they become intermediaries,
distinction between sense and reference; but in their interest in the rela- like high priests, between us and the true nature of things, even the true
tion between act, meaning and object meant they forget that the world as a nature of ourselves. And like high priests, with access to the powers of the
whole is co-intended (Husserl's term is mitgemeint) along with particular universe, they can also direct those powers for our good or ill. The
objects of reference. In the absence of an exploration of how this co- abstractness of scientific theory can suddenly become very concrete when
reference works, the world is sometimes simply posited in an uncritically its applications can both improve life and threaten our survival.
realist way, and indeed in a scientifically realist way, as if its status as a Husserl has no quarrel with scientists as such. We are all well advised to
whole were not at issue in phenomenology. Those who focus on language as follow them if we seek a sophisticated physical theory and if we desire the
discourse at least recognize that language not only permits us to speak of technological advantages that result from it. Husserl's criticisms are
this and that, but commits us to a whole system of interconnected meanings. directed at philosophers. In the face of the growing discrepancy between
* The conceptual picture we have presented here is not, by the way, the scientific view and our ordinary sense of ourselves and our world, most
altogether unlike the one which Husserl faced when he wrote the Crisis, philosophers have simply followed the lead of science. But philosophers
and to which his notion of the lifeworld was meant to respond. Scientific ought not merely to follow but to understand and even evaluate what sci-
realism (Husserl calls it 'physicalistic objectivism') was the long legacy of entists do, especially when it comes to attributing reality to their objects.
the modern period, and this is the primary object of Husserl's criticism in Husserl said that philosophers should be functionaries for mankind, 2 and
the Crisis; but conceptual relativism and other forms of skepticism were, ' part of what he meant is that they should mediate between the scientists
his long-standing adversaries as well, and I shall try to show that the and the rest of us. But for many philosophers, what counts as real is what
concept of the lifeworld is no less addressed to them. Let us first place is determined to exist by the latest criteria of physical theory. Reduced to
Husserl's idea in the context of its own time before coming back to the a mere hand-maiden or cheer-leader for science, philosophy has left the
question of how it is relevant to ours. articulation of man's concrete sense of his world to the novellist and poet.
This is how the novelist Milan Kundera views Husserl's notion of the
crisis.3 And the literary critic Harold Bloom seems to agree that literature
I has taken over philosophy's function.4
The modern idea of a scientific realism has always contained elements of But Husserl believes philosophy can exercise its proper reflective and
paradox, and the paradoxes were growing more and more acute in the critical function in relation to science in its own way. He reminds us that
early decades of this century. As physical theory penetrated ever further scientific theory is after all a human activity within a cultural space, and
into the inner workings of nature, its idea of what is real seemed to differ that this cultural space itself presupposes an everyday world of perceived
more and more markedly from the world in which we find ourselves. The things and other people. The scientist lives in the same world as the rest of
directly felt and sensed qualities of the world around us were declared us. As laymen we may think that his achievement is to devise instruments
mere appearances, while the reality which supposedly underlay them was like the microscope so that he can see this world better than we do. But his
deemed inaccessible to our experience. As this all-encompassing view of real achievements are techniques not of seeing but of thought: the major
nature includes human beings as well, it seems to present us with a view of accomplishments of modern science are really very specialized ways of
our own nature that we can no longer recognize as ourselves. What thinking about and conceiving the physical world.
Husserl called the crisis of European science was not an internal crisis hut In putting the emphasis on the active and constructive character of the
an external one: the loss of its meaning for life.1 Since the Renaissance, scientific view of reality, Husserl so far follows the lead of Kant. But Kant
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

still regarded the scientifically constructed world as the best candidate for presuppose the lifeworld. What had seemed a specialized problem for the
knowable reality and thus concurred in the ontological devaluation of the philosophy of science is now seen as a 'universal problem for the philo-
everyday or prescientific world. What Kant overlooked, according to sophy' as such.10 This universal problem can be characterized generally as
Husserl, is the actual context in which scientific thinking takes its point of that of the relation between thought and intuition, but the 'empty and
departure. vague notion of intuition' 11 - the implied reference is again to Kant - is
This context is not one of fleeting and subjective sense-data or impres- now grasped as the problem of the life-world and its role in our
sions buzzing about in the scientists's head prior to being fixed and objecti- experience.
fied by the categories of scientific thought. The world of perception has a It may be thought that the concept of the lifeworld really represents
nature of its own which, far from being confused and chaotic, is in fact nothing new in Husserl's thought, even though the term assumes new
coherently structured in an intentional way. It is indeed a sense-world, and significance in this late work. And indeed we have seen that Husserl's real-
its appearance to the perceiver is correlated structurally with the human istic view of perception, and even the ideas of passive synthesis and of
body which not only passively receives impressions but actively engages bodily subjectivity, which are at the heart of his presentation of the life-
itself in its surroundings.5 The perceived world as we experience it is corre- world in the Crisis, had been developed before. But as Husserl's
lated with a flowing and synthetic 'bodily subjectivity'6 which remains exposition unfolds it begins to take on features that distinguish it in more
'anonymous' 7 in the sense that for the most part we do not notice it. than just emphasis from what has gone before.
Husserl builds here on earlier investigations into what he calls 'passive One such feature is the prominence of the notion of Vorgegebenheit or
synthesis'. H e also proposes the title 'transcendental aesthetic', almost as a pregivenness. The section's title refers to the vorgegebene Lebenswelt, and
reproach to Kant for so severely restricting his analysis of sensibility. the lifeworld is almost always referred to in this way, sometimes as immer
But far more important than this subjective analysis of perception is its schon vorgegeben - always already pregiven. It is likewise frequently said
objective side. Husserl had always been a 'direct realist' in his treatment of to be 'presupposed' and 'taken for granted'.
perception, and in the Crisis too he stresses that here we have direct 'Pregiven', of course, means 'given before'. Before what? In keeping
contact with a real world. Only by contrast to the rigorously mathematized- with the focus on scientific realism with which the section begins Husserl
and idealized scientific world is the perceived world 'subjectively relative' obviously means 'prior to science', and that in the sense we have already
and changeable.8 In their own domain the objects of perception are stable, outlined: people live in the real world of perception before they develop
independent, and coherently distributed in the oriented space around our sophisticated theories about it or the 'reality' which lies behind it and
bodies. Above all they are real, and are directly given (intuited) as such. causes its appearances, etc. Even after the development of such theories,
By contrast, what is posited as 'real' in the context of a sophisticated phys- the real life of any individual is still played out in the perceptual world.
ical theory is what Husserl calls a 'logical constrution'. The entities so con- There is also historical sense to this 'before': 'as history teaches us, there
structed are 'in principle not perceivable'. 9 The view which declares the was not always in the world a civilization that lived habitually with long
perceived world 'mere appearance' is itself a psychological variant of a established scientific interests. The life-world was always there before
physical theory, in this case about how our experiences are caused. But the science, then, just as it continues its manner of being in the epoch of
proponent of this theory, like everyone else, lives in the full certainty of science'.12
the directly given reality of the world about him. The physical and neuro- But a stronger sense of pregivenness begins to emerges as Husserl dis-
logical entities and events of his theory are objects of his thought; but he cusses the 'most general structures of the lifeworld'.13 The latter is taken
does his thinking in the perceptually 'pregiven', full-bloodely real world of for granted or presupposed in theoretical conscious activity, but it is also
things and persons. presupposed in perception itself. In perception we are aware of particular
As we have seen, Husserl is led to these considerations by the growing things and events, and we take them to be real. But this means merely that
discrepancy between the scientific concept of the real and our prescientific we count them as belonging to a world to whose reality we are committed
sense of reality, and by the failure of philosophy to come to terms with beforehand. Particular real things are like so many aspects of the real
that discrepancy. Having introduced the concept of the lifeworld as a way world that present themselves to us in turn, and yet the world is not itself a
of reassessing the significance of science, Husserl now recognizes that the large-scale thing or even the sum-total of all real things, considered as an
lifeworld has much broader significance as a philosophical theme. Not only object. It is the horizon against which all things stand out and without
the sciences but any and all conceptual thought and all human cultural which they could not appear to us. As horizon, the lifeworld is unique and
endeavor including philosophy itself arise within and in a certain sense unitary, it is not singular as opposed to plural, for 'the plural makes no
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

sense when applied to it'.14 Furthermore, full-blooded as it is, the 'reality' Now he not only stresses the enveloping, pregiven character of the per-
of particular things is always to some degree provisional: the course of ceived world and the pervasive and deep-lying character of our commit-
future experience may place in question even our clearest perceptions. But ment to it; he is also convinced that in a certain sense we never leave this
such revisions change only the details and in no way alter the 'ontic cer- commitment behind, however sophisticated our thought about reality may
tainty of the world' as such.15 Our comittment to its reality is always linked become. Furthermore, he recognizes that an adequate description of con-
to our ongoing perceptual experience, to be sure, but does npt require any sciousness in all its forms must not give exaggerated importance to one
particular inventory of objects. form - the quest for theoretical comprehension of the real - over all
Those familiar with Husserl's works will recognize that even this theme others.
is not new. In one of the best known passages of the Ideas, in which the A second feature which distinguishes the account of the perceived
epoche is first introduced,16 it plays an important role. There too Husserl world in the Crisis from earlier accounts is that this world is repeatedly
stresses that in perception we are not merely confronted with this or that described as public or intersubjective: it is 'pre-given as existing for all in
but through them have a direct experience of the world. Just as objects common', 20 as ' 'the' world common to us all'21 'even what is straightfor-
stand out from their background, so the particular perceptual acts in which wardly perceptual is communalized'. 22 There is considerable ambiguity on
they are given repose upon an underlying 'attitude' or 'standpoint' (Ein- this point in Husserl's earlier writings about perception. His direct realism
stellung) which Husserl calls the 'natural' attitude. This is 'not a particular world seem to suggest that the object I perceive is given as the same object
act' but a fundamental belief in or committment to the world as such.17 It you perceive. But this presupposes the availability to me of the concept
is our conviction that in and through each and all of our particular percep- and the actual experience of others within my world. Yet in the Cartesian
tions we have direct experience not only of particular things but of the Meditations, when Husserl finally gets around to a pubUshed discussion of
world as their ultimate horizon. intersubjectivity, he introduces it only after the subject of perception and
But, as I have tried to show in detail elsewhere,18 this conception, after its world have been introduced, and seems at times to suggest that we
its brief appearance, is eclipsed by another description of the world, which acquire or develop the concept and the experience of others on the basis
is also developed in Ideas and which gains in importance in works like of a fuU-fledged perceptual world given beforehand. Husserl speaks of the
Cartesian Meditations. Husserl is so preoccupied with the move from per- 'sphere of ownness' with its 'transcendent objects'23 as if these made up a
ception to theoretical thought that he treats the objects of experience as if concrete and self-sufficient world which we then surpass toward the other.
their sole function in our experience is to be integrated into a scientific Though it is possible to read the text in another way, such that the 'sphere
theory. Not only does he suppose that the natural purpose of our con- of owness' is a mere abstraction from the concrete (as Husserl indeed calls
sciousness is to know them in the full theoretical sense; he even proposes it at one point),24 this difficult text is ambiguous to say the least. For
an idealized full theoretical knowledge of the totaUty of real objects and example, Husserl says that the ownness sphere stands in a relation of
then identifies this latter as the world. The provisional or presumptive Fundierung to the intersubjective world, which is to say that I cannot have
character of perceived objects is extended to the world as a whole, and the latter without the former, but I can have the former without the
world is now described as 'an idea correlative to a perfect experiental evid- latter. 25 This directly contradicts the view that the ownness sphere is an
ence'.19 Naturally, such perfect evidence is never forthcoming in our abstraction.
experience and remains infinitely distant. The world in this sense is the While it is not possible to say that the question of what is abstract and
object of a concept that can never be fulfilled. This contrasts sharply with what is concrete here is entirely cleared up in the Crisis, the order of
the description of the world of the natural attitude in the Ideas. The dif- presentation, at least, is very different from that of the Cartesian Medita-
ference is between the direct experience of the world, which we actually tions. The lifeworld is dealt with explicity as an intersubjective world and
have at every moment, and the idea of an experience, which in principle described as being pre-supposed, with precisely this sense, in any and all
we can never have. Instead of being given in experience the world is an particular- experience. This is then found to include the problem, to be
object of thought. It is to the former conception that Husserl returns in the sure, of how I as an individual experience the others and 'constitute' the
Crisis. It is not merely that he places emphasis on modes of experience sense of their existence in my own consciousness. But the sense of the
which are prior to scientific and other forms of theoretical interest. Husserl whole section leaves no doubt that the full concreteness of the lifeworld,
had always acknowledged that such forms exist. But he had treated them including its public and intersubjective character, is pregiven in relation to
as in some way deficient and provisional for a consciousness whose this particular type of experience just as much as it is for any other.
primary aim is to surpass them toward a full theoretical comprehension. A third prominent feature of the Ufeworld can be seen as related to the
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

second. In addition to stressing its pregiven character and its common or This is Husserl's new version of the 'natural standpoint' of conscious-
intersubjective status, Husserl attributes certain cultural objects and prop- ness, of the world which is the inalienable correlate of that standpoint, and
erties to the Ufeworld as well. We already know that the concreteness of of the nature of the relation between the two. And the development of this
the lifeworld extends farther than the mere things given in bodily percep- new version has certain consequences for the exercise of the phenomeno-
tion, since it also includes other persons. But persons come equipped with logical method. If phenomenology is to understand consciousness in its
their own experiences, and presumably their thoughts too. Husserl is from various theoretical and practical activities, and if it is to comprehend the
the start concerned with the relation between science and the lifeworld, sense of the objects to which consciousness stands related in all its possible
and has made the point that scientists too live in and experience the world modes, it must trace both to their origins in this original matrix, the
as do the rest of us, whatever they may think about it in their theory. But 'natural state' of consciousness and the world. It is in this sense that
he goes on to include in the lifeworld not only the scientists but also 'the Husserl calls the analysis of the lifeworld a universal problem for philo-
sciences as cultural facts in this world with their . . . theories'.26 He is obvi- sophy: it becomes the central theme of phenomenology itself.
ously impressing on us the difference between conceiving the world
through the scientists' theoretical concepts and encountering those con-
cepts themselves as ideas put forward by persons in the everyday world and II
passed along to us in the classroom, in books, or by hearsay. We encounter I said earlier that Husserl's concept of the lifeworld had something valu-
them as 'human formations, essentiaUy related to human actualities and able to contribute to today's philosophical climate, and I shall turn to that
potentialities'27 and as such they have a reaUty which is integrated with the now. It can be seen first of all as an antidote to some of the excesses of
reality of concrete things around us. Naturally, the first things we think of continental philosophy as it has developed since Husserl's time. As indi-
when we hear of 'human formations' are artifacts, which are quite concrete cated before, I am thinking of the predominance of a certain conception
and particular objects of perception. And we encounter them not merely as language as the exclusive key to understanding human existence and its
things with their spatio-temporal properties and relations to their surround 1 relation to the world. Gadamer's concept of Sprachlichkeif8 is very differ-
ings, but precisely as the artifacts they are. Their cultural meaning is given ent indeed from Foucault's notion of the episteme29 but they have this
along with their bodily status; we see them as houses and streets, tools and much in common, that human existence and activity are conceived almost
ornaments, cars and other machines. As for the products of theoretical exclusively as the use of and understanding of language. Indeed, this use
activity, though they are accessible not through the senses but through the and understanding is in turn conceived largely on the model not of speak-
medium of language, Husserl seems to be saying, these products have a ing and hearing but of writing and reading texts. Perception is either
similar status within our world. Scientific theories are of course not the only neglected altogether or viewed metaphorically as itself being a special
cultural products that have this status; there are also other and sometimes^ version of the deployment of the concepts of our language.
conflicting 'views' of the world we encounter as weU, such as religion and
philosophy. There are other products which have the status of ideas, such Against this view, Husserl reminds us of the conceretely and sensuously
as stories and poems, without being 'theories' or 'views'. Husserl doubtless given, indeed pregiven reality of the world around us. Merleau-Ponty, of
puts so much stress on scientific and other theories because he wants to course, followed him in this, drawing on and enhancing Husserl's notion of
make clear the distinction between subscribing to such theories and Uving the living body as the anonymous subject of perception. One wonders if
in a world in which they count among its constituents. the overemphasis on language is not merely the self-centeredness and
even elitism of philosophers and literary critics who spend their time
In these three ways, then, the lifeworld of the Crisis is both deeper and reading and writing, and project their bookish world onto everyone else.
wilder than the perceptual world of earlier writings: deeper because of its Husserl was the first to conceive of perception as neither a weak version of
pregiven character, that is, because of the strength and pervasiveness of conceptual thought nor a blind causal process but as embodying a
our committment to its reality, whatever theoretical view we may take up meaning-structure of its own and deploying itself in a world which is pre-
about 'reality' as defined by some theory; wider, because the world to supposed by rather than created by thought.
which we are thus committed is so much richer than the previous discus- But there is a second and more important sense in which the lifeworld is
sions of perception would allow. It includes, as we have seen, not just relevant to the over-intellectualized views of recent continental thought.
things but also persons; and persons not just as minds but as bearers of The emphasis on language has brought with it a conceptual relativism so
experiences and thoughts; and it also contains the products of their activity extreme that it no longer makes sense to speak of language, as we did
and even the content or sense of their experiences and thoughts. above, as mediating between human beings and the world. Thought and

10 11
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

experience are viewed as enmeshed through language in radically different appealed to in this context to help solve certain problems which have
conceptual schemes, whether discontinuous and self-contained or slowly arisen in .the philosophy of language. In particular, he is seen as providing
developing in a continuous tradition. And these constitute our only access a supplement to Frege's theory of linguistic meaning. One advantage seen
to what is. Different conceptual schemes make up so many different in Husserl's noema is that it derives Unguistic meaning from a source
worlds or universes of discourse. Reality is fragmented or splintered into outside language itself. This in turn makes it possible for Husserl to extend
these different* domains and the idea of a unity among them is no longer the notion of meaning to perception, where it is not necessarily linked with
thought to make sense. linguistic expression.32
I am convinced that Husserl's concept of the lifeworld was meant to In moving from Unguistic meaning to a broader conception of meaning
counter a conception like this, as well as the scientific realism Husserl these philosophers are, of course, following the path Husserl himself took,
actually attacks in the Crisis. In fact, these two are not as far apart as they beginning with the First Logical Investigation. But in a sense they are not
may seem. We have already remarked the irony that the scientifically 'real' moving far enough with Husserl. They could be said to move from the
has retreated farther and farther from our actual experience of the world. Logical Investigations to the Ideas, where the noema is introduced, and to
This makes a view like Husserl's, which emphasizes the constructed and get stuck there. But the focus on the noema, which even in that work is not
idealized character of the scientifically real, all the easier to accept. And as central as some make it out, was a relatively brief episode in Husserl's
indeed, whether due to Husserl's influence or not, this view of scientific development. This is not to say that he dropped the idea; nor did he by
'reaUty' has gained ground among philosophers of science. But this, any means solve aU the problems surrounding it. But as he moved beyond
coupled with a strong historical sense of the changing character of scien- the Ideas his main purpose was to integrate the noema (and the noesis)
tific-theory, recommends the view that modern science is merely one into a larger context. Objects with their meanings belong to regions of
among many equally valid conceptions of the world, and we are left while being, according to Husserl, and in works like Ideas II and III he sought to
a tolerant and open-ended pluralism of world-views. The difference distinguish these regions and relate them to the sciences. Acts of con-
between science, religion, superstition and magic becomes just a matter of sciousness are related not only to their objects but also to each other in a
opinion. These would be just so many languages or conceptual schemes temporal flow; and Husserl also devoted himself to the study of the
which are in the end equivalent to worlds, just so many realities. dynamics of consciousness in its active and passive forms. In a sense the
Such views are not unlike those of the skeptical relativism, especiaUy of Crisis, and in particular some aspects of the theory of the Ufeworld, can be
the 'historicist' sort, which Husserl attacked along with naturalism in his seen as the culmination of this search for the ultimate or full context of the
early essay 'Philosophy as Rigorous Science'. The concept of the lifeworld noesis-noema relation.
would count against such conceptual relativisms by urging that different Its relevance for those who focus on the noema is this: because they
ways of conceptualizing reality are still different ways of thinking about take their point of departure from'Unguistic meaning, they may view per-
the world, the very same world that we all encounter in our everyday ceptual meaning on the model of linguistic meaning even if they hold that
experience. Husserl insists at one point that for all the differences that non-linguistic meaning is somehow prior.33 This is especially true of those
may exist between cultures and world-views, the Ufeworld has an invariant who hold that perception has a propositional content: but it is no less true
structure in which aU share.30 This is precisely the basic relations of things, of those who describe the perceptual noema as a 'singular meaning'.34
thing-experience, world horizon and intersubjectivity we have already dis- Such meanings are treated in relation to their object and the act of percep-
cussed. Different persons and different peoples Uve amongst different tion itself, but what may be overlooked is the perceptual horizon of the
ideas and views, just as their surroundings are composed of different world which belongs precisely to the meaning of any perceptual object. H.
objects and populated by different groups of people. But it is possible to Dreyfus speaks of 'Husserl's insistance on the philosophical priority of the
reach beyond our particular enclaves and understand and communicate analysis of the representational content of individual intentional states',35
with representatives of different cultures, precisely in virtue of the but offers no textual evidence for this purported insistance. It is not
common structure of the lifeworld. Husserl but those who more recently focus all their attention on the
A second contemporary strain to which the concept of the lifeworld is noema to the exclusion of aU else, who make this mistake. Smith and Mac-
relevant concerns Husserl himself. Some philosophers take Husserl's lntyre describe the phenomenological reduction, for example, as Husserl's
concept of the noema, as developed in the Ideas, to be his most important answer to 'how to become acquainted with noemata and noematic
contribution, and have recently written about it in connection with other Sinne'?6 as if these were individual items, to be discovered one by one. In
theories of meaning.31 I made the point earlier that Husserl is being fact, from the analysis of the natural standpoint and its world, in the Ideas,

12 13
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

to the treatment of the lifeworld in the Crisis, Husserl always insisted on undercuts and finally renders inoperable his phenomenological program.
treating perceptual meaning - and indeed any other sort of meaning - in For what he has done is to make the intentionality of consciousness
the broad context to which it actually belongs in the Ufe of consciousness. depend upon certain non-intentional capacities and practices.40 To be sure,
Husserl in the Crisis warned expUcitly against a piecemeal approach to Husserl in the Ideas tried to express the natural standpoint in a 'thesis',
meaning, as if the reduction were a matter merely of abstaining from and and in the Crisis he speaks of beliefs that have become 'sedimented' and
analysing 'individual validities' one by one, and leaving aU the others can be reactivated and analysed intentionally. But these would make up at
intact. This is the sort of reflection which occurs in the natural attitude most a complex of particular beliefs, and even if these were somehow
when we ask 'what did she mean?' or 'what did I actuaUy see just then?' summarized in an overall 'thesis' of the natural attitude this would again
But this 'only creates for each instance a new mode of validity on the be the particular expression of a belief. But is our perceptual or bodily
natural ground of the world'.37 That is, it leaves intact and unreflected the engagement in the world just a belief that can be expressed? The argu-
overall realistic commitment of the natural attitude. Husserl insisted that ment here is that to treat it as such is to falsify precisely what Husserl was
the reduction be extended to include the whole world. But it is very the first to discover.
important to see that this insistance derives not from a commitment on his It is to be recalled as well that in the Ideas it was as a thesis that the
part to ideaUsm. Rather, its motivation is purely phenomenological. We natural standpoint could be 'bracketed' and the phenomenological reduc-
need to include the whole world in the reduction because the whole world tion initiated. 41 It has been argued that 'only what is posited as an object
belongs to the sense of each and every perceptual act, and if we do not can be bracketed .. ,'42 But the lifeworld, by Husserl's own account, is not
include it we have not understood that sense. When those who focus an object but the prior condition for anything's being posited as an object.
narrowly on the noema claim that their version of phenomenology can be Our commitment to it is so deep we cannot detach ourselves from this
reconciled with a physicalistic ontology,38 they are missing the point made commitment by an act of thought. Thus by penetrating to the level of the
in the Crisis. life-world Husserl seems not only to have tacitly questioned the pervasive-
So far I have spoken of Husserl's concept of the lifeworld as a ness and self-sufficiency of intentionality in mental Ufe, but also to have
response to certain philosophical problems of his day and ours. But the deprived himself of the means for investigating it phenomenologically.
lifeworld raises certain questions in its turn which Husserl either did not This is often taken to be the meaning of Merleau-Ponty's famous dictum
see or left inadequately treated. These are questions both about how to that 'the most important lesson which the reduction teaches us is the
understand the lifeworld itself and about how to reconcile it with impossibility of a complete reduction'. 43
Husserl's overall conception of phenomenology. I shall conclude this One way to counter this objection is to ask its proponents to tell us
essay with a brief sketch of the most important of these questions as I more about the nature of these capacities and practices that are presup-
see them. posed by intentional acts. If they are not-intentional, what sorts of relation
The first concerns the pregivenness of the lifeworld, the notion of its do they involve? Are they simply objective causal relations? It can be
being presupposed and taken for granted by every particular act, whether counter-argued that while Husserl's concept of the life-world does indeed
of perception or of thought. We made the point that this can be seen as an require going beyond a too narrow, noesis-noema concept of intentional-
expansion of the notion already included in the Ideas of the natural 'stand- ity, it calls not for a rejection but an expanded and revised treatment of
point' or 'attitude'. This basic stance of consciousness is neither an 'act intentionaUty. And this is what Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty have in fact
proper' nor is it the temporal multiplicity of acts and experiences: it given us. The latter, for example, roots consciousness in the body not as an
somehow underUes them all. As we have seen, in the Crisis Husserl objective automaton but as the subject of a type of intentionality all its
stresses more than before that this stance is literally embodied in the cor- own. Whatever Merleau may say about the phenomenological reduction,
poreal and 'anonymous' functioning of sense-perception, in the body as an he still treats the perceived world not as a collection of objects but as a
'I move' or capacity for engagement in its surroundings.39 These surround- meaning-structure, and the bodily subject as what understands and grasps
ings, as they are geared to our bodily capacities, constitute the deepest- this meaning. To be sure, it does this not by observing, thinking and utter-
lying reality in our experience Here is lodged our most fundamental prior ing sentences, but by moving and acting.
commitment to the reaUty of the world as the horizon for whatever we do The second critical question raised by Husserl's concept of the life-
or think. world is not, I fear, so easily answered as the first. It concerns the fact
Now some argue - and this is one view of Heidegger's and Merleau- that Husserl includes in the lifeworld, as we saw, not only perceived
Ponty's revision of their predecessor's phenomenology - that Husserl here things and persons but also cultural properties and even ideas. Husserl is

14 15
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S THE L I F E W O R L D R E V I S I T E D

undoubtedly right that we tacitly and unquestioningly presuppose these 3 Milan Kundera, 'The Novel and Europe' New York Review of Books vol. 31 no
too in our active mental life, that they too form the background for the 12 (July 19,1984) p. 15.
development of scientific theories and the like. But this makes it harder 4 Harold Bloom, A Map of Misreading (New York: 1975) p. 39. Quoted by
Richard Rorty in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton
for him to claim that the life-world has a universal and invariant struc- University Press, 1979), p. 168.
ture, common to all, underlying whatever theoretical 'garb of ideas' we 5 The Crisis, p. 106.
may cast over it.44 For some of the ideas that populate our world are not 6 Ibid.,p. 108.
merely encountered as items of its furniture but constitute, as in the case 7 Ibid., p. 11.
of science, religion and philosophy, interpretations of reality as a whole. 8 Ibid., p. 125.
9 Ibid., p. 121.
Such ideas can become sedimented in such a way that they affect our 10 Ibid., p. 132.
'view', our whole 'sense' of reality. Husserl seems to recognize this when 11 Ibid.,p. 134.
he says that the results of theoretical accomplishments 'flow into' the 12 Ibid, p. 123.
very subsoil out of which they grow.45 It becomes harder and harder to 13 Ibid., p. 142.
distinguish between the world as experienced and the world as inter- 14 Ibid., p. 143.
preted by this or' that theory. The theory has become part of our way of 15 Ibid.
16 Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philo-
experiencing. Theory in this sedimented and appropriated form may sophy. First Book, trans. F. Kersten (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983), Part
affect the very structure, and not merely the content, of the life-world. two, Chapter one.
If this is so, the life-world may differ fundamentally from one cultural 17 Ibid, p. 51.
18 See my Phenomenology and the Problem of History (Evanston: Northwestern
group or historical epoch to another, depending on the nature of the sedi- University Press, 1974) Chapter 6.
mented interpretations that have taken hold. And while it remains true 19 Cartesian Meditations trans. D. Cairns (The Hague: Mart Nijhoff, 1960), p. 61.
that some world-structure is pregiven or taken for granted and serves as 20 The Crisis, p. 121.
the background for any new theoretical accomplishment, it will not always 21 Ibid, p. 122.
be the same structure that is thus taken for granted. For example, Husserl 22 Ibid.,p. 163.
repeatedly speaks as if the notion of 'things' and the distinction between 23 Cartesian Meditations, p. 104.
24 Ibid., p. 93.
things and persons were a universal feature of the world. But do such dis- 25 Ibid., p. 96.
tinctions exist for those who think of every being and aspect of the world 26 The Crisis, p. 104.
as ensouled, or those whose world is organized in terms of the elaborate 27 Ibid., p. 130.
totemic systems the anthropologists have called to our attention? Could 28 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (New York: Continuum, 1975) pp.
the thing-person distinction be the sedimentation of a system of thought 345 ff.
29 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things (New York: Random House, 1970) p.
we have inherited in the modern, western world, in part precisely thanks XXII.
to the advent of objective science? 30 The Crisis, p. 139.
These considerations make it hard to consider Husserl's concept of the 31 See Husserl, Intentionality and Cognitive Science ed. H. Dreyfus (Cambridge,
lifeworld, as Husserl considered it, a response to conceptual and historical Mass: the MIT Press, 1982) especially the reprinted articles by D. Follesdal;
and Husserl and Intentionality by Ronald Mclntyre and David Woodruff Smith
relativism. Indeed many see Husserl as having contributed, along with (Boston: Reidel, 1982).
other phenomenologists, to the widespread acceptance of such views. It is 32 A similar strategy is followed by John Searle in his Intentionality (Cambridge
certain that he would not have approved of them. But it is also true that he University Press, 1983), though no debt to Husserl is acknowledged.
does not provide us with arguments which would prevent his thought from 33 Searle (op. cit. p. 5) explicitly follows such a model.
being taken in this direction. 34 The propositional view is held by Searle (op. cit. pp. 40 ff). The 'singular
meaning' view is advanced by I. Miller in his Husserl, Perception and Temporal
Awareness (Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press, 1984) p. 55.
Notes 35 Dreyfus (op. cit.) Introduction pp. 2f.
36 'Husserl's Identification of Meaning and Noema' in Dreyfus (op. cit.) p. 91.
1 Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental 37 The Crisis, p. 106.
Phenomenology, trans. D. Carr (Evanston: Nortwestern University Press, 1970) 38 E.g. Smith and Mclntyre in Husserl and Intentionality (op. cit) p. XV.
p. 5. 39 The Crisis, p. 106.
2 Ibid. p. 17. 40 Dreyfus (op. cit.) introduction, p. 23.

16 17
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

41 See Ideas I sections 30 and 31.


42 See Ernst Tugendhat Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl und Heidegger (2nd.ed. 71
Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970) pp. 263 f.
43 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. C. Smith (New
York: Humanities Press, 1962), p. XIV. H U S S E R L ' S C O N C E P T O F T H E
44 The Crisis, p. 51.
45 /tod., p. 113. W O R L D

Rudolf Bernet

Source: Arleen B. Dallery, Charles E. Scott and P. Holley Roberts (eds), Crises in Contin-
ental Philosophy, Albany: The State University of New York Press, 1990, pp. 3-21.

The clarification of the meaning of the world was a constant endeavor on the
part of Edmund Husserl. This is seen immediately in the great number of
newly coined "world"-composites, such as "spiritual world" (geistige Welt),
"life-world" (Lebenswelt), "environing-world" (Umwelt), "home-world"
(Heimwelt), "world of interests" (Interessenwelt), "universal world" (Allweit),
"horizon of the world" (Welthorizont), "annihilation of the world" (Weltver-
nichtung), "enworlding" (Verweltlichung), etc. Although much used by phe-
nomenologists, and used with many different connotations, the concept of
"the world" as such, however, has worn out and covers many, often incom-
patible enterprises. Basic questions, such as what it means for the world to
appear and how the subject is involved in the disclosure of the world, are
often taken for granted. The result is that some phenomenologists turn
toward the world, others rather turn away from it, and many remain shut up
in their own worlds. Life-world phenomenologies flourish without their
authors giving much thought to the fact that their descriptions of the life in
the world presuppose a stance at the limit of or beyond this world. There is
also a need to look more closely into the different forms under which "the
world" reveals itself to a subject. In particular, the question how manifold
local and self-contained worlds refer to a common and unique "open" world
deserves more attention than Ufe-world relativists are usuaUy wilUng to
concede.

The phenomenological reduction


The appearing of the world cannot be understood apart from the phenom-
enological reduction. This can seem disconcerting, in that it involves a step
that leads the subject, at one and the same time, to turn away from the
world and to turn toward it. This is the price of a better comprehension of
the appearing of the world, and the phenomenology that is consecrated to

18 19
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS .HUSSERL'S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

this task cannot economize on the phenomenological reduction. In tran- compares the phenomenological reduction to the attitude of a poet. 1
scending the things of the world, the reduction reveals at once the world as Nevertheless, the strongest motive for exiling oneself from the world of
world and the subject as subject. Treating the question of the world and things remains for Husserl of a theoretical nature. More precisely, the
the question of the reduction together offers the possibility of rethinking point is to understand how the subject is related to the world. This can be
the sense of the "reconduction" of the phenomenon to the subject and conceived only if the subject is not itself a thing of the world and if the
grasping better how the subject contributes to the appearance of a multi- order of things is not foreign to the life of the subject. For Husserl, what
plicity of worlds. distinguishes most radically the subject from a thing is the intentionality of
If the aim of phenomenological reduction is to reveal the link between the subject. This is, however, nothing other than the relationship of the
the diversity of worlds and the modes of life of the subject, as well as the subject to things. Thus, intentionality shows at the same time the dif-
enduring difference between the subject and its "world," then the reduc- ference and the connection between the subject and things. It also reveals
tion should be something else and, indeed, much more than an outmoded the world as an order of things, because this order can appear only for a
methodological exercise. To transgress the closed world of our habits, to subject who relates itself to things without being overwhelmed by Jhem.
assist at the collapse of a cultural world, to be excluded from a particular For Husserl, this means that the order of things appears to the subject as
world that presents itself as universal, these are daily existential situations an instituted order, an order shaped by the subject. This shift from a
that nonetheless offer an access to the phenomenon of the world and that world for the subject toward a world by the subject is made through the
therefore must be considered as carrying out a phenomenological reduc- phenomenological reduction, understood as retreat from things and as
tion. This then opens up as well the essential philosophical task concerning openness to their appearing. If it is perhaps possible to think the being of
the safeguarding of the idea of an indefinitely open common world, which things independently of the subject, the same does not hold for their
is inseparable from the idea of human rationaUty. being-given. As phenomena, things are the concern of the subject; their
For Husserl, the analysis of the phenomenon of the world and the doc- logos is disclosed only to a subject; and the phenomenologist is inclined to
trine of phenomenological reduction are closely related. The increasing make this subject the owner, instigator, and even founder of the logos of
attention Husserl gave to the phenomenon of the world in his later-work the phenomena. In this way of thinking, the world appears as a significant
made it necessary for him to clarify and also modify the meaning of the order of things in the manner it has been instituted by the transcendental
phenomenological reduction. It is true that Husserl never surrendered the subject or posited as its correlate. Rather than showing the belonging-
conviction that a phenomenological philosophy can be estabUshed only together of the being of the world and the being of the subject, phenom-
through a Une of thought that in some manner turns away from the world. enological reduction then displays a subjugated world, a world colonized
It is no less true that this withdrawal from the world will reveal itself more by the constituting subject.
and more clearly as a necessary detour on the way to the discovery of the
world. This discovery of the world is no sign of abandonment; it is rather
the necessary fulfiUment of the program of phenomenological reduction. It Subjugation and annihilation of the world
is not a question of ceasing to think in order to live; it is, on the contrary, a This logic of subjugation dominates the first reflections of Husserl on the
question of thinking the world as "phenomenon." The phenomenological world, notably the notions of world view (Weltanschauung) and annihila-
view of the life-world already participates in another mode of life. The tion of the world (Weltvernichtung). If "world view" witnesses to the sub-
phenomenologist is awakened from the dogmatic slumber of a life that is jugation of the subject to the world, "annihilation of-the world" on the
as entangled with the world as a sleeping dog in his basket. This life in the contrary deals.with the subjugation of the world to the subject. In "world
world forgets the world because our attention is absorbed in the objects of view." the subject in fact remains riveted to the world and to practical
the world; objects that appeal to our interests so strongly that they leave us interests, to urgent problems, to vital preoccupations which make up the
without reprieve. Something must break this bondage to the things of the world.2 In the actual functioning of "world view" the world is not grasped
world, this constant entertainment, or "divertissement," as Pascal calls it. in itself but appears as a coUection of things that are urgent to do, reason-
The world can appear only when, somehow, our view wanders among the able to hope, necessary to believe. The world of "world view" only
things of the world without having anything particular "in view." It is one appears as such in a second moment, in a theoretical reflection which is
and the same movement that takes us away from the world of our pre- often animated by a project of comparing different world views and
occupations and reveals to us the order of the world. looking for their possible common ground. For Husserl, this viewed world
In a letter to Hugo von Hofmannsthal of January 12, 1908, Husserl is in no way superior to the naively believed-in world of the natural

20 21
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

attitude, since a subject is lost when engaging itself, body and soul, in a ance enters into conflict with the preceding appearances. On the other
particular world view, which is provisional and closed in upon itself. hand, the subject manifests itself in a deficient and indeterminate form, as
On the contrary, in the "annihilation of the world" of the first book of an immanent "residue" of the annihilation of the transcendent world, that
Ideas the subject disengages itself radically from the world and sets it up as is, still as a "small piece of the world" (Endchen der Welt).
an objective correlate. 3 The world of things becomes a pure object of con- The hypothesis of the annihilation of the world thus does not meet the
templation for the subject, but under such conditions that this perfect visi- aims of the program of phenomenological reduction: it allows to appear
biUty of the world implies as well the possible disappearance of the viewed neither the world as phenomenon, nor the transcendental being of the
world. Husserl's argumentation is well known: if the phenomenological subject, nor the correlation or belonging-together of subject and world.
reduction consists in making every esse a percipi, one must conclude that The annihilation of the world does not even merit its own name, since the
the being-seen of the world depends on the seeing of the subject, whereas world (insofar as it exceeds the real existence of things) is not even taken
the subject is able to see itself without recourse to the world and thus into consideration.
depends only on itself. The result is that the being of the subject is of a
higher dignity than the being of the world, as it could survive the abolition
of the world, whereas the world could not subsist independently of the life Horizon and world
of the subject. At the same time, this Ufe of the constituting subject is not If the.world, understood as the surplus of the perception of things, is
sufficient to guarantee the existence of the world in an absolute manner. already present in the first book of Ideas, it is rather in the term halo
The being of the world is dependent on harmony among the experiences [Hof] or, more frequently, horizon. This notion of horizon owes its sense
of the subject, and this harmony is threatened by a rupture that remains to what Husserl calls horizontal intentionality (Horizontintentionalitdt),
always possible. Thus, the subject, which has gone to great lengths to dis- and this, at least at the outset, remains marked by the preoccupations of a
tance itself from the world in order to acquire a good view of it, eventually psychology of attention. Everything that I already or still perceive
views helplessly the collapse of the world it so much had wanted to see. without giving it my whole attention belongs to the horizon of actual per-
Husserl's criticism, twenty years later, of the hypothesis of the annihila- ception. This horizontal intentionality has many diverse modes: reten-
tion of the world has the immediate consequence of elevating "world tional and protentional horizon, which envelops the present grasping of
view" to the dignity of an original project within transcendental phenom- an object; active or passive forms of motivation that prompt one to a
enology - the latter having "the capability . . . of actualizing the correlation series of (other) acts, that make the realization of one possibility of
between the possibility of experience and the possibiUty of the world experience preferable to another, that lead to an enlargement or rather a
under the form of a world view."4 The error of the annihilation of the retraction of one's field of vision, and so on. Horizontal intentionality
world was precisely the severing of this correlation between the seeing of thus establishes a continuity and a unity in one's conscious life. It antici-
the world and the world seen. The annihilation of the world goes against pates future possibilities; it conserves the memory of past acts; it assures
the sense of intentionality, which always carries the subject to an interest in the passage from potentiaUty to realization; it is the principle that inte-
the entities of the world and their appearing. The hypothesis of an annihi- grates all acts in a continuous unity of one life, of one subjective flux of
lation of the world rests upon an ontological dualism (of a Cartesian type) consciousness. Though a principle that is essentially subjective, this hori-
whose two poles are the (self-evident) being of immanent consciousness zontal intentionality has nevertheless its objective or noematic correlate -
and the (doubtful) being of the transcendent world; this dualism is totally for instance, a field of vision, where certain things are closer to me than
foreign to the sense of the transcendental constitution of the world by the others, where certain things hitherto simply coperceived appeal to me
subject. The constituted world is neither purely within nor purely exterior more vividly than others, and where the possibility of the future course of
to the constituting subject. If the sense of its being is said to depend on its my vision is mapped out.
being-given-for-the-subject, this does not mean that the appearing of the Still one might be hesitant to foUow Husserl when he calls this noematic
world is nothing other than an immanent experience of the subject. There horizon a world (Umwelt; Idl sect. 45). The horizon is more a dynamic
is therefore a paradox in the annihilation of the world in that it finally principle of constituting life than an order of constituted objects. Rather
levels the difference between the subject and the world which it was sup- than being an indefinitely open framework within which things are
posed to put in relief. The existence of the world is treated as if the world inserted to receive sense and come to meet us, the horizon is the shape of
were a singular thing that confirms its existence in a harmonious course of the present, future, and past data of my actual experience, a particular
intuitive appearances or, on the contrary, "explodes" when a new appear- changing gestalt. With the realization of each potentiality, the entire

22 23

1
r

L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

horizon is modified. Besides lacking the objectivity and permanence which specificaUy reunites them. The things are not in themselves part of
proper to the world, the horizon also lacks the possibility of being truly the spiritual world but become so in virtue of the way in which the subject
shared. Any world, even the solipsistic world that Husserl introduces for approaches them, a way that Husserl calls the personalistic attitude. The
methodological reasons, must lend itself to being shared with other sub- spiritual world exists only as the world constituted by a community of
jects. A horizon cannot be shared since it is nothing else than what leads a persons; it is the communal "environing-world" (Umwelt) of then-
particular constituting subject from one experiencing process to the next exchanges and interactions. In this world, things are related to each other
and, correlatively, from one object to another. not by causal links but in virtue of the place that they occupy within the
The richest approach to the phenomenon of the world can be found motivational fabric of the Ufe of a person.
in those sections of the first book of Ideas where one discovers, opposed
to the objective reahty of the natural sciences, a "world of appearance"
The environing-world
(Erscheinungswelt; Idl sect. 41) or a "world of experience" (Erfahrungs-
weltr, sect. 47-48). This proto-Lebenswelt is the correlate of the open total- The characterization of this environing-world in Ideas II remains
ity of possible experiences (sect. 45, 47) of an intersubjective community unchanged in the later writings of the 1920s and 1930s. The environing-
(sect. 48). In one and the same movement phenomenological reduction world (Umwelt) is a limited world cut off from the more general world.
reveals the a priori conditions of possible experience and the a priori con- This cutting-off is a function of theoretical, axiological, and practical inter-
ditions of a possible world, for the reduction reveals their correlation. ests of a person or a community of persons. The environing-world is the
Nevertheless, the possible world of experience still depends on the possi- familiar world where everything I encounter already has a sense for me
biUty of experience. It is this possibiUty of experience that gives the world and for others. It is a "meaningful" (bedeutsam) world because "it carries
its meaning and its reaUty; it is the experience of the subject that consti- a spiritual meaning in itself," but it is a meaningful world that remains
tutes the world. This possible reaUty of the constituted world should not open, in that it is "always susceptible to receiving a new sense of this type"
be confused with the possible being of a "res," that is, with a particular (Idll sect. 51, p. 197). This environing-world owes its meaningfulness to
thing; the being of the world is the being of any possible thing. If the being the activity of a community of persons whose interest in things is aimed
of the possible world thus transcends the possibiUty of particular things, not only at knowledge but also at the appreciation of their ethical or aes-
then one must conclude that the being of the world has a transcendental thetic value or at their capacity to serve as means in a process of practical
value. The world therefore prepares and welcomes the coming into being production (Idll sect. 50).
and manifestation of things, but this gift and mission of the world is con- The meaningfulness of things of the world is thus tightly connected with
ferred upon it by the transcendental ego. the diverse ways with which the subject approaches them: In knowing and
This means that the logos that orders this possible world is essentiaUy particularly in perception, the things are given as "present-at-hand"
subjective. The lines of force that cut across and order the world are (vorhanden). "In acts of evaluation . . . the object is given . . . as having a
understood by Husserl as being motivational in nature. The world under- value, as agreeable, beautiful, etc." In "practical acts," the objects
stood as an order of possible things is still governed by the anticipation of
the experiencing subject. This is verified in reading the analyses, found in are able . . . to be apprehended as useful [dienlich] for serving the
the second book of Ideas, devoted to the constitution of the "spiritual satisfaction of this or that need, in virtue of this or that property,
world." 5 It is well known that this description of the spiritual world is pre- and they are then the object of an apprehension as means of sub-
ceded in Ideas II by an analysis of the constitution of nature, consisting of sistence, as useful objects of whatever type: materials for heating,
physical objects and also mental states insofar as those remain conditioned axes, or hammers, etc. For example, I view coal as material for
by physical causaUty. This presentation of the spiritual world as a higher heating, I recognize it and recognize it as useful [dienlich] and
stratum of reality poorly serves Husserl's design, for it suggests that next usable [dienend] for heating, as suitable [geeignet] and determined
to the world of spiritual and ideal objects is a world of real or physical to produce heat.
objects. This is not the case, however, because for Husserl the collection of
objects of nature does not deserve the name world and because natural Husserl does not hesitate to emphasize that in this relation of persons to
objects are in no way excluded from the spiritual world. ActuaUy, the their environing-world, the practical dimension has priority: "In its broad-
determination of this spiritual world owes less to the metaphysical division est meaning, we are able to describe the personal attitude . . . as a practical
between nature and spirit than it does to the phenomenon of expression attitude" (Idll sect. 50). These passages deserve to be cited for their

24 25
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD
profound resemblance to Heidegger's analyses in Being and Time dedic-
something far away, or how to behave in order to collaborate with a col-
ated to the Vorhandenheit and Zuhandenheit of things of the world.
league in view of a common project. Every important occurrence within
The analysis of environing-world in Ideas II resembles Being and Time
this familiar world relates itself intentionally to things and persons and yet
in another characteristic, namely, that the environing-world envelops both
transcends them in understanding them on the basis of what is already
familiar things and the persons occupied with these things. My environing-
understood in advance (i.e., understood a priori), that is, the world to
world contains not only "the real objects that we actually experience" and
which they belong. Inner-worldly comportments are thus constitutive in a
"all the things that are found [in the world] without my already knowing
twofold sense: first, their intentionaUty brings them to things and persons;
them but which I will be able to experience," but also "other humans
second, these comportments' transcendence reveals and shapes the world.
[Nebenmenschen], animals, and . . . the human I denote as . . . being me,
bearing such and such a name, constituted in such and such a way. As a As far as the constituting intentionality of inner-worldly comportment
human, I am part of the real environing-world of the pure ego . . . " (Idll is concerned, a distinction should be made between relations to things and
sect. 27, p. 109). If the environing-world as a world of the significance of relations to persons. Similar to the difference between the intentional rela-
things is constituted by a pure ego, we should add that this constitution of tions to inner-worldly entities and the transcending relation to the world
the world goes together with a "mundanizing" or "enworlding" (Ver- itself, this distinction is de jure and not de facto. In fact, a person under-
weltlichung) of the constituting subject. Or to put it in the rigorous standing the things of the world and producing works thus enriches the
formulation of the Cartesian Meditations: world, which in turn will affect the sense of its being-with-other-persons. If
our relations to worldly things are primarily practical (as Husserl emphas-
izes from Ideas II onward), it follows that being-with-others assumes pri-
In that I, as this ego, have constituted and am continually further marily the form of interaction. In the facticity of communal life within the
constituting as a phenomenon (as a correlate) the world that exists world, this interaction and the feeling of being-with-others (Miteinander-
for me, I have carried out an apperception of myself as belonging sein) precedes empathy (Einfuhlung). Empathy is thus not at the origin of
to the world [verweltlichende Selbstapperzeption]. This appercep- community but is rather a symptom of decay, the sign of an incomprehen-
tion makes of myself an ego in the ordinary sense, that is, a human sion among inner-worldly subjects and the mark of confrontation with
person [situated] within the totality of the constituted world.6 strangeness.
In a text from January 10, 1931, which clearly shows traces of his
In its ordinary or, as Husserl prefers to caU it, "anonymous" life the consti-
tuting subject exists-in-the-world. It discovers its power to constitute the reading of Being and Time, Husserl describes this "being-in-connection-
world long after having already been constituted as a worldly subject, that with-others" (In-Konnex-mit-Anderen-Sein) in the following way: it is a
is, a "human person." The "enworlding" of itself accomplished by the manner of "living in the same world [Hineinleben], of being concerned in
transcendental ego has always already (anonymously) taken place, and the the "same world [Hineinsorgen]," "while being constantly with one another
world the transcendental subject constitutes has always already been there [miteinander]" in the same world
as pregiven.
The description in Ideas II of the personalistic approach to the environ- which becomes the world of our interests [Interessenwelt], the
ing-world thus opens for phenomenology the rich domain that Husserl will environing-world of our practical life [praktische Lebensumwelt].
later call intentional anthropology, a domain to which numerous texts in In this manner of being, we ourselves (that is, I and the others)
the Husserliana volumes 14 and 15 are devoted. Phenomenological belong to the constituted world of objects, and this in a permanent
anthropology studies human life in the world and can be called intentional way, whereas at the same time this "we" is subject of the world, a
because it is through intentional experience and related tendencies and we that experiences the world ..., knows the world and acts within
motivations that human beings occupy themselves with things and one the world, all of which leads to an enriching of the objective
another, and also relate themselves to the framework of Ufe common to content of the world.
them all, a framework that can properly be called life-world (Lebenswelt). (ZPh 138)
This framework is neither independent of the intentional experiences that
take place in it, nor can it be reduced to those experiences. All intentional Husserl continues his analysis by pointing out that due to "the historicity
relations to things and to other persons are mediated by consciousness of of human Dasein" this "we" is "a historical community," living in an
this familiar world. In this world, I know how to move in order to reach environing-world which is itself historical (139). This historical environing-
world has a sense extending above and below the actual community of

26
27
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF T H E WORLD

"we": the historical environing-world is a part of the historical world which world of humanity. The environing-world, which transcends everything
is the world of all human beings, the world of "humanity." Humanity and everyone within it, can reveal itself only to a subject who is itself
(Menschheit) is "a persistent [verharrend] reality of a higher order," main- capable of transcending its occupation with inner-worldly objects belong-
taining itself "throughout the coming and going of persons, throughout the ing to this environing-world. That is, the environing-world appears only to
fact that people come into the world at birth [Hineingeborenwerden] and a subject for whom the inner-worldly things have lost their tranquil cer-
leave the world at death [Heraussterben]" (139). tainty, their completely self-evident sense (Selbstverstdndlichkeit). One
could say that the environing-world reveals itself to a subject who is on the
border of this world - not completely in it but also not totally out of it. We
The givenness of the world
have seen that Husserl gives an existential meaning to this limit-situation
The world maintains itself and is maintained through the constitution of of the subject when speaking of the entrance into the world at birth
inner-worldly objects; and to these objects belong the communal "we" and (Hineingeborenwerden) and the departure from the world at death (Her-
the poUtical and social institutions that are the incarnations of this "we." aussterben). In birth, the world welcomes the person, the world is given to
Our contribution to the maintaining of the world consists as weU in the the person in the form of a gift, which Husserl calls pregivenness
present enrichment of the world and its transmission to future generations: (Vorgegebenheit). Throughout one's life, one is generaUy so avid to take
We shape the world we have received with a view to the future of human- possession of the riches of the world and so desirous of imposing oneself
ity. If preserving the human world is a task and even a duty (ZPh 143-44), upon those with whom one should share these riches, that in fact one fails
and if the world is a willed ethos for which we are responsible, then it to pay attention to this gift of the world. Only in crisis situations, in which
should be added that this responsibility'concerns the future of a world that the ground seems to be slipping away, does one experience everything that
has already been handed over or, as Husserl says, pregiven (vorgegeben). is owed to the world. Nevertheless, one inevitably faces the world at the
If we transcend ourselves in our concern for the world, we do so toward moment of departure in death, whether this consists in a desperate clinging
that which, however, gives meaning to our existence. In • self- to the world or in handing over this gift of the world to future generations.
transcendence, we open ourselves to the world, receive it as a legacy and
become the temporal guardians of it. Our existence in the world in no way
resembles the way in which things are present (vorhanden) in the world, Transcending the limits of a familiar world
nor should the world itself be confounded with a thing that is to be known Birth and death are events in which the secure distance between the famil-
or possessed. In this way, this openness to the world changes radically our iar and the unknown collapses. This holds, too, for the confrontation with
relations to others and to humanity as such. The human community foreign cultures. During a journey in a foreign land, we not only see things
receives a new sense from this common concern for a world which tran- of which we are unable to grasp the meaning, we also recognize things that
scends particular interests. This community inscribes itself in are familiar to us but that clearly have another sense. Here, too, the famil-
iar environing-world - or, as Husserl says, the "home-world" (Heimwelt) -
an endless chain that runs through the generations of human reveals itself to a subject who has reached a limit, a point of intersection
beings. . . . Human life, the unity of which is limited by birth and between a home-world that is one's own and a home-world that is foreign.
death, is thus traversed by the extension of the life of humanity, The home-world is a symboUc system that lets the environing-world
the unity of which is . . . the experience of all people [allmen- appear in its contingency - but also in its necessity; in its singular facticity
schliche Erfahrung] and the tradition built upon it. Thus, I under- which nevertheless is not unique; in its arbitrary and yet unavoidable
stand humanity as historical, I grasp how the time of the world transcendence. In the home-world, relativity has a certain absoluteness:
[Weltzeit] ... surpasses the time of my life [meine Lebenszeit] and the arbitrary nature of a symbolic order imposes itself in the form of an
that of my fellow human beings living at the same present time unconditional law. Husserl also asserts that we can "translate" a foreign
[mitgegenwdrtig]. environing-world into the idiom of our environing-world, and even that we
(ZPh 169) can come to an understanding of a total and unique world that embraces
all particular environing-worlds (ZPh 162). Nevertheless, such a transla-
The familiar environing-world that is shared by contemporaries is still tion will never make the foreign environing-world into a home-world for
not the historical world of all humanity. Nevertheless, the environing- me; and I will never completely "Uve" in this universal "aU-world"
world can stiU only appear as already pointing to the revelation of the (Allwelt) (ZPh 624-25). If it is true that this confrontation with a foreign

28 29

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

environing-world does not cause one to leave completely one's home- as a work in progress, as the risky and adventurous quest for meaning.
world, it is equally true that this confrontation is an invitation to take an Rather than being the residue of the order of the world, the disorder of
interest in the more general world, that is, the world of humanity as a abnormality evokes, on the contrary, the active quest and constitution of
whole. The intercultural shock has in common with death the fact that it the ordered world. This constituted world is above aU the intelligible world
reveals at the same time both the familiar world (Umwelt) of a person (or that governs the rational exchanges among human beings.
a community of persons) and the universal world (Allwelt) of humanity. It is in view of this common rational world that the deviation of abnor-
For Husserl, the environing-world and the "all-world" (Allwelt) reveal mal comportments reveals itself. The comportment of a child is said to be
themselves as transcending one's being-in-the-world and yet also as yield- abnormal because a child does not yet contribute to the constitution of the
ing meaning for an understanding of one's own existence-in-the-world. rational meaning of the human world. Maturation is precisely the process
Thus, it can be readily said that for Husserl the transcendent relation to of appropriation or reconstitution of the meaning of the world, which wiU
the world is the most profound determinant of the meaning of the being of make the child into "my equal" (meinesgleichen). The case of animals is
the individual person. Husserl understands the life of this human being as different. They are excluded from our rational world, but they constitute
a constitutive activity. If the world appears as such, and if the sense of the their own world according to the species to which they belong. Nonethe-
world is to be constituted by human beings, then the world must appear to less, as the world of certain pets fits advantageously into the human envi-
them as being constituted by them. The phenomenologist is thus con- roning-world, Husserl seems to suggest a partial contribution to the
fronted with the task of describing how and in what type of human com- constitution of the human world on the part of the animals: "One might
portment the world reveals itself as being constituted. I believe that the object that in the case where animals are considered as relating themselves
numerous analyses that Husserl devoted to normality and abnormality in to the world, to the same as ours, they might sometimes contribute to the
the apperception of the world are responses to this preoccupation regard- constitution [mitkonstituierend] of the world as world. When one under-
ing the letting-appear of the world as being constituted. 7 It is surely no stands a dog sensing the hunt, the dog as it were teaches us something we
mere coincidence that, once again, it is in our relation to the unfamiliar did not already know. The dog enlarges the world of our experience"
and foreign that the sense of the being of the world reveals itself. (ZPh 167). This possible comprehension of the animals' contribution to
The "abnormals" who interest Husserl are above all the mentally ill, the constitution of my environing-world (which is, to be sure, not yet the
children, and animals. These abnormal subjects belong to the same world rational "aU-world" [Allwelt] of humanity) depends on a sort of sinularity
as the normal subjects, and they comport themselves as having a certain between the animal and the normal human subject. Just as in the case of
apperception of this common world. They are thus not merely inner- apperception of a foreign human subject, this similarity primarily concerns
worldly entities; nevertheless, they appear as abnormal because normal the corporeaUty (Leiblichkeit) of the animal (ZPh 625-26).
subjects do not comprehend them. Indeed, normal subjects understand As far as the "crazy" or "insane" are concerned (that is, Irrsinnige,
neither the way in which the common world reveals itself to these abnor- Wahnsinnige, Verritckte), Husserl does not deal with these at any great
mals, nor how these abnormals contribute to the shaping of this common length. Nevertheless, these cases, as with all cases of behavior related to
world. Their place in the world is obscure, because, on the one hand, they the unconscious, are particularly interesting. My parapraxes surely con-
are recognized as subjects having an apperception of and even participat- tribute to the constitution of my life-world (Lebenswelt), even if I do not
ing in the constitution of the common world, yet, on the other hand, the recognize myself in them. The psychotic delirium, the logic of which
meaning of their participation remains enigmatic. They are not subjects remains foreign to me, is however of the same material as my rational
"like me" (meinesgleichen) with whom I can agree on the meaning and apperception of the world and thus contributes to a clarification of the
destiny of the historical world in which we live together. Their incompre- meaning of my world. So we must concede that there are human com-
hensible contribution to my world has the result that a part of the meaning portments, the meaning of which I cannot grasp even though they appear
of this world remains undetermined and unknown to me (ZPh 627). This to me as participating in the constitution of the human world. The
stretch of strangeness within my famiUar world reveals by contrast the unconscious and delirium thus constitute an improper world, which is
world of which I understand the meaning as being my world, that is, as a nevertheless neither behind, below, nor beside the proper world of
world the sense of which I am able to appropriate in constitution. The rational subjects. This improper world bursts into and blooms in the
experience of the lack of meaning functions as an appeal to meaning. The midst of the proper world. This proper world does not thereby become
world of the abnormals, limited and closed in upon itself and thus inacces- an improper world but appears as a world shot through with strangeness,
sible, reveals by contrast the normal world as a world of infinite openness, as a haunted house, as a mine field. The proper world of rationality is

30 31
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

never an established fact. It is precisely this fragility that lends the world the existential 'mode' of the 'not-at-home' [Un-zuhause]. Nothing else is
its value. meant by our talk of 'uncanniness' [Unheimlichkeit]" (SZ 189; BT 233).
The appearing of the human world, whether it be the familiar home- This analysis of anxiety shows us in an exemplary manner the ambiguity
world of a social group, or the "all-world" of humanity, or the disquieting of this "leaving the world" through which the world manifests itself as
world of madness, is certainly a phenomenon unlike others. It is hos- world. First, we see that the world we leave and the world manifested by this
pitable, but its hospitality reveals itself most clearly when we "miss" the leaving are different. This difference is even indicated by the terminology:
world, for example in anxiety or in facing death. The same can be said for we leave the environing-world (Umwelt) and face the "world" (Welt).
the rationality of this world, which reveals itself only when it is threatened. Second, the world revealing itself in anxiety concerns only the being of
Should we conclude that the appearance of the world is always a dramatic Dasein itself. The exchanges with inner-worldly things or persons are sus-
event? Does it unavoidably reveal the profound isolation of a human pended. Dasein's understanding of the environing-world and of the being of
subject that has been expelled from the secure ground of its famiUar sur- entities that Dasein is not, does not count anymore: the world and the
roundings? This seems to be what Heidegger is saying in the period of being-in-the-world of Dasein itself are "nothing ready to hand [Nichts von
Being and Time when he opposes the phenomenon of the environing- Zuhandenheit]" (SZ 187; BT 231-32). The world of Dasein owes its phe-
world (Umwelt) to the phenomenon of the "world" (Welt). nomenalization to an "annihilation of the world," understood as aboUtion of
the environing-world. Third, the world of Dasein that manifests itself in
anxiety isolates Dasein from everything that is different from itself, even
The world of Dasein other Daseins. The strangeness of this world is a proper form of strangeness
The environing-world is for Heidegger the everyday world, which Husserl and not a foreign strangeness. It is true that Heidegger insists on the gift of
calls life-world (Lebenswelt). In ordinary life, Dasein is submerged in the the world, on the fact that the world imposes itself upon Dasein in affecting
things of the world, and Dasein's constant preoccupation with these things Dasein, that is to say, in the form of "state-of-mind" (Befindlichkeit) or the
leaves no occasion for questioning the meaning of this world. Even rela- remarkable "mood" (Stimmung) that is called anxiety. Nevertheless, in the
tions with other human Daseins are inscribed within the framework of isolation by which Dasein gains access to a proper understanding of its own
these preoccupations and thus amount to mere associations of collabora- being, anxiety becomes a type of self-affection. If, rather than constituting
tion. If Dasein were to take notice of the environing-world in the midst of the world, Dasein receives the revelation of the world as world, it is still true
such occupations, it is still only to be assured of the arrangement of things that it receives this gift of a given world from itself.
and persons in view of the efficacy of its own future actions. The environ- This description of the disclosure of the world in Being and Time is
ing-world is viewed in circumspection (Umsicht). This circumspection is remarkably similar to the one provided by Husserl. The world reveals
actually an "inspection" by the owner, who assures himself or herself of itself when its obvious and familiar presence is disrupted and it reveals
the presence of everything contained in the familiar world. Among the itself to a subject that has turned away or has been expelled from the
things of the world is Dasein itself, and other human Daseins. Without world. Heidegger's "anxiety" accomplishes some sort of phenomenologi-
confounding things and persons, this concernful circumspection neverthe- cal reduction or even an "annihilation of the world."9 The disclosure of the
less embraces them in one single view as beings in the world. Seeing the world is thus dependent upon the self-transcending comportment of the
world and not merely the things of the world, Dasein still remains too tied subject, on a theoretical or existential "project." No wonder, then, that for
to inner-worldly preoccupations to consider the world as such. To have the both Husserl and Heidegger the world shows itself as having been "consti-
world appear as such, one must leave the environing-world or at least tuted" or at least "shaped" by the subject.10 Not only does it take a special
transport oneself to its limit. sort of subjective comportment to let the world reveal itself, but in this
Being and Time analyzes the leaving of the world that allows the world revelation it becomes clear also that the meaning of the world depends on
to appear - or, rather, the worldliness of the world - by means of a phe- the subject. Nevertheless, and despite aU these analogies, Husserl and Hei-
nomenological description of anxiety: "The state of anxiety discloses, pri- degger fundamentally differ both in the way they understand the world-
mordially and directly, the world as world." 8 In anxiety, the familiar revealing and the world-shaping comportment of the subject, and in the
environing-world collapses, and the world imposes itself upon Dasein in way they characterize the belonging-together of the subject and the world.
all its strangeness: "Anxiety . . . brings Dasein back from its fallen absorp- These differences made themselves felt as soon as Husserl and Heidegger
tion in the 'world'. Everyday familiarity collapses. Dasein has been indi- tried, in 1927, to put in common their conception of phenomenology for
vidualized, but individualized as Being-in-the-world. Being-in enters into the Encyclopaedia Britannica?1

32 33
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E W O R L D

The constitution and gift of the world its pregivenness the world reveals a meaning that was bestowed on it by
other subjects, known or unknown, explicitly or anonymously.
For Husserl the possibility of the revelation of the world depends on a
Husserl's concept of constitution does not quite allow for a satisfactory
particular attitude, on a specific sort of action, on a will and sense of
phenomenological account of the transcendence of the world. Despite the
responsibility on the part of the subject. For Heidegger, too, at least in
important amendments this concept underwent when Husserl discovered
Being and Time, the world discloses itself only for an authentically existing
the constitutive function of noematic phenomena, when he investigated
subject, but this authentic existence is not a matter of voluntary decision the constitution not only of singular objects but also of the world, when he
or ethical responsibility. In anxiety, Dasein undergoes the manifestation of took into account passive and anonymous forms of constitution, Husserl
the world; it is unexpectedly overwhelmed by it. The appearance of the continued to consider "constituting" a subjective achievement and the
world stops the busy life of human activities. Emmanuel Levinas's descrip- "constituted" its objective result. It is true that in his "intentional anthro-
tion of insomnia - when, in the darkness of the night and while absolutely pology" Husserl gave much attention to the being-in-the-world of the
nothing happens, one is realizing with fright that "there is" (ity a) unceas- human person and thus to forms of comportments where the subject and
ingly being - is a good illustration for such a passive experience of the its world are intimately intertwined. Nevertheless, as we have seen, the
world.12 constitution of the world belongs to a pure Ego that, while constituting the
But there are certainly other, less dramatic ways in which the world world, "enworlds" itself to become a human person. The entanglement
gives itself and in which we receive its gift. Jan Patocka, in his early text between the person and its world is a constituted form of entanglement.
entitled Le monde naturel comme probleme philosophique, has emphas- The constituted world is a world posited by the transcendental subject "in
ized with particular force that if the revelation of the world requires front of" itself. The world thus opposed to the transcendental subject as its
"movements tending . . . towards the Umits," this does not necessarily correlate is a pregiven world with a meaning the subject can fully appro-
mean they take the form of anxiety or of an isolation of the subject: The priate since it is a meaning it has already bestowed on it, anonymously or
step they accomplish leads, one could say, historically. The subject gives everything to the world and the world gives
the subject only what it has received from the subject; the disclosure of the
behind everything that exists, in order to find there the possibUity constituted world celebrates and brings into full light the constitutive
of being human in ways other than everyday life; there is thus a achievements of the subject. Husserl's notion of constitution thus does not
change of the world, not of its content. These movements are suffice to provide a full understanding of the different forms in which the
characterized by the fact that it is impossible [possible?] to estab- subject contributes to the manifestation of the world, and it is unable to
lish oneself in them; there is in them a time of rest or rather account for the gift of the world to the subject.
dwelling, . . . the philosophers in awe, the artist in admiration, In my opinion, Husserl is most convincing in what he says about the
others in hatred, some in love.13 human way to enrich the historical world, to take care of it in view of
future generations, to make it more rational. I also think that Husserl is
In love, for example, "it is possible to become for another thrown exist- right to say that pointing to the universal world (Allwelt) of humanity is a
ence a warm hearth transforming the anxiety of the uninhabitable into a matter of philosophical responsibility. In doing so he successfully resisted
possibiUty of acceptance. Without acceptance, there is no human exist- the temptation either to sacrifice the plurality of home-worlds (Heimwel-
ence, for we are not only thrown into reality, but also accepted " ten) to the unity of the "all-world" or to abandon the rational quest for
The human being that is "accepted" by the world receives this world as human equality in favor of a celebration of cultural relativism. Husserl's
a gift. It is true that there is no gift without a donation and a donator, no "all-world" should, of course, be understood as the philosophical telos of
given world without encountering other human persons and their works. humanity and not as the realization of a world market indistinctly gov-
But it is also true that works of art, for example, that disclose the world erned by one-dimensional technological rationality in all the countries of
give more than an artist could ever give; the given world has a meaning the world. Making everyone a "citizen of the world" in no way implies
that goes beyond what was given to it by a person or even by the infinite making uniform the different styles and contexts of human Ufe. For
community of all human beings. As we have seen, Husserl did not remain Husserl, the most valuable contribution philosophy can make to the
blind to the phenomenon of a pregiven world. However, this world, which common work of the constitution of the world is to guide the march of
is given to us as having already been there, as receiving or accepting us, is history toward its telos of a world that would be fully rational. Still, there
a world with a meaning that other, former subjects have "constituted." 14 In exist other ways of participating in the constitution of the world by

34 35
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS HUSS.ERL'S CONCEPT OF THE WORLD

modifying, enriching, preserving, enlarging, and improving its meaning. Notes


These various modes of the constitution of the world might all go together 1 Letter quoted in R. Hirsch, "Edmund Husserl und Hugo von Hofmannsthal.
with a feeling of satisfaction or gratitude for what humanity in its historical Eine Begegnung und ein Brief," in Sprache und Politik: Festgabe fur Dolf
development has achieved. Should we then conclude that whatever is Sternberger, ed. C. J. Friedrich (Heidelberg: Lambert Schneider Press, 1968),
revealed in the disclosure of the world reveals itself in the form of a pp. 108-15.
meaning constituted by us? In the event that the world effectively dis- 2 For this early conception of world view see E. Husserl, "Philosophie als strenge
Wissenschaft," first published in Logos 1 (1911): 289-341, esp. pp. 323-41; pub-
closes itself in such a manner, is that enough to affirm that we then can lished in the collection, Aufsatze und Vortrage (1911-1921), ed. T. Nenon and
totally appropriate its meaning to ourselves? Is every meaning of the H.-R. Sepp, Husserliana no. 25 (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987), pp. 1-62,
world a meaning constituted by us, and is every constituted meaning the esp. pp. 41-62; English translation: "Philosophy as Rigorous Science," in
result of a deliberate action that lends itself to being "reactivated" with Husserl, Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy, trans. Q. Lauer (New
perfect fidelity? Is the meaning of the world always a human meaning, and York: Harper & Row, 1965), pp. 71-147, esp. pp. 122^17.
is the human meaning of the world open to a totally comprehensive 3 E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen
Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allegemeine Einfiihrung in die reine Phdnomeno-
"reprise"? logie, ed. K. Schuhmann, Husserliana no. 3/1 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
1976), sect. 49. Subsequent references to this volume will be indicated in the
text by "Idl," followed by section and page number. Compare the English
The world and the subject translation: Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenolog-
ical Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology,
The world that reveals itself in birth and death, in anxiety, insomnia, reli- trans. F. Kersten (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983).
gious devotion, artistic admiration, in hatred and love is much more than a 4 E. Husserl, Zur Phdnomenologie der Intersubjektivitdt. Texte aus dem Nachlass.
"human-made" world. It can, and often does, appear as both inhuman and Drifter Teil: 1929-1935, ed. I. Kern, Husserliana no. 15 (The Hague: Martinus
unmade. Not that this world would not concern us as human beings or that Nijhoff, 1973), p. 621. This text comes from 1933. Subsequent references to this
we could not do anything about it, but it is more than we can achieve and it volume will be indicated in the text by "ZPh," followed by the page number;
translations are my own.
is less familiar than what we know. The human shaping of the world is pre- 5 E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenologischen
ceded and guided by a disclosure of the world that reveals the essential Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phdnomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitu-
limits of aU human endeavor. Rather than revealing itself as a human tion, ed. M. Biemel, Husserliana no. 4 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1952),
achievement, the world reveals that human existence is interwoven with the sect. 48-64. Subsequent references to this volume will be indicated in the text
blank pages of what is inhuman. Human beings receive the revelation of by "Idll," followed by section and page number; translations are my own.
their transcendence from the world rather than - through the effectuation of 6 E. Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vortrage, ed. S. Strasser,
Husserliana no. 1 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1950), sect. 45, p. 130; my
a phenomenological reduction - actively bringing the world to show itself. translation. See as well ZPh 492.
The disclosure of the world interrupts the identification of human 7 Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen, sect. 55; see also ZPh 133-70, 613-27.
beings with their familiar surroundings. The world reveals that, considered 8 M. Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tubingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1977), p. 187;
as subjects, human beings do not belong (in-)to the world. This is, of my translation. Compare English translation: Being and Time, trans. J. Mac-
quarrie and E. Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), pp. 231-32. Sub-
course, not to say that the subjects, to which the world is disclosing itself, sequent references to Sein und Zeit will be indicated by "SZ" followed by page
exist outside or independently of the world. The appearing of the world number; translations are my own. References to Being and Time, indicated by
rather shows both: the essential belonging-together of the subject and the "BT," that follow a reference to SZ, are for comparison.
world and their essential difference. The belonging-together of the subject 9 See the excellent article of J.F. Courtine, "L'idee de la phenomenologie et la
and the world is a form of entanglement that reveals a difference, a form probl^matique de la reduction," in Phanomenologie et mitaphysique (Paris:
Presses Universitaires de France, 1984), pp. 211-45; see esp. pp. 232-33.
of interdependence that excludes reciprocity. The appearing world shows
10 For Heidegger's account of such a "shaping" of the world see especially M.
itself as being strange and inhuman and at the same time as being in need Heidegger, Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt - Endlichkeit - Einsamkeit,
of humanization and appropriation by the subject. The subject, in its turn, vols. 29-30 of Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio
discovers that although its entire life takes place in the world, it is itself not Klostermann, 1983), pp. 397-532; "der Mensch ist weltbildend."
a worldly being, and that although it is different from the world, it is also 11 E. Husserl, Phdnomenologische Psychologie, ed. W. Biemel, Husserliana no. 9
in charge of the world. Its shaping of the world contributes to the revela* (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962), pp. 274-75, 601. Heidegger summarizes
their different approaches when he asks Husserl: "Does not a world in general
tion of the otherness of the world, and caring about this foreign world is belong to the essence of the pure ego?" (p. 274, n. 1.).
the proper meaning of the life of a human subject. 12 E. Levinas, De l'existence d I'existant (Paris: Vrin, 1978), pp. 109-10. Compare

36 37
T
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

English translation: Existence and Existents, trans. A. Lingis (The Hague: Mart-
inus Nijhoff, 1978), pp. 65-66.
13 J. Patocka, Le monde naturel comme problime philosophique (The Hague: 72
Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), p. 175. The next quote is from p. 176.
14 The pregivenness of the world therefore should not be confused with the pre-
givenness of the sensuous "hyl6"; unlike the hyl6 which precedes constitution, H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , D I E
the world is for Husserl always a constituted world.
E I N E W E L T

Klaus Held

Source: Ernst Wolfgang Orth (ed.), Perspektiven und Probleme der Husserlschen Phanom-
enologie, Phdnomenologische Forschungen 24 (1991): 305-337.

Im Zeitalter des planetarischen Zusammenwachsens der Menschheit


gewinnt eine Reihe von Texten in Band XV der Husserliana1 besondere
Aktualitat, die alle um die Problematik der Konstitution der einen Welt in
der Begegnung von Heimwelt mit Fremdwelt kreisen. Die Problematik ist
einerseits noch im Umkreis der 5. Cartesianischen Meditation angesiedelt,
andererseits weist sie aber auch schon voraus auf einen charakteristischen
Aspekt der Krisis. In der 5. Meditation geht es um die Konstitution der
intersubjektiven Welt als objektiver Welt. Die objektive Welt ist eine fiir
alle Menschen uberhaupt. Tragender Gedanke der Krisis ist die teleologis-
1
che Perspektive auf die eine Welt einer verniinftig kommunizierenden
Menschheit. So bildet die Frage nach der Konstitution der einen Welt sys-
tematisch die Briicke zwischen den Analysen der 5. Meditation und der
Krisis. FreiUch springt zunachst ein Unterschied zwischen diesen Analysen
ins Auge. Nach der Konzeption der Krisis vollzieht sich die Konstitution
der einen Welt genetisch, d.h. als Entwicklungsschritt der inneren
Geschichte, in der sich das BewuBtsein mit neuen Horizonten anreichert:
Die historische Urstiftung von Philosophie und Wissenschaft bei den
Griechen stellt der Menschheit die Aufgabe, die wahre, objektive Welt zu
erforschen. Diese eine Welt ist nichts Fertigkonstituiertes, sondern im
Unendlichen liegendes Telos fiir die in der Zeit verlaufende Entwicklung
der sich verwissenschaftUchenden Menschheit. Im Unterschied dazu
setzen die Analysen der 5. Meditation, wie Husserl in § 58 hervorhebt, sta-
tisch an. Sie nehmen den eidetischen Gehalt von fertigkonstituierten
Gegebenheiten - und so auch der Gegebenheit „objektive Welt" - zum
Leitfaden und fragen zuriick nach den gleichsam zeitlosen Motivations-
zusammenhangen, durch die sie dem BewuBtsein begegnen konnen. Die
innere Geschichte des BewuBtseins ist fiir diese FragesteUung irrelevant.
Die Konstitutionsanalyse in der 5. Meditation bleibt aber nicht statisch.
Zwar hat die erste der Konstitutionsstufen intersubjektiver Lebenswelt

38 39
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE EINE WELT

(215, 437ff.), auf die sich die erwahnte Feststellung in § 58 bezieht, statis-
chen Charakter, nicht aber die darauf aufbauenden hoheren Stufen. Jene
erste Stufe bildet die analogisierende Apperzeption, mit der ich ausgehend Die StrukturparaUeUtat beginnt damit, daB die heimische Kulturwelt tat-
von meiner Primordialitat den Andern als das an sich erste Fremde konsti- sachlich als eine Art Primordialsphare zweiter Stufe angesehen werden
tuiere; ich transzendiere meine primordiale Welt, indem ich sie als kann: So wie ich in der abstraktiv vorausgesetzten reinen Primordialitat
Erscheinungsweise einer Welt auffasse, die dem Andern und mir gemein- nur von mir selbst und meiner Welt weiB und „noch" nichts von der Exis-
sam ist. Meine primordiale Welt ist dadurch gekennzeichnet, daB sie ihre tenz eines anderen Ich und seiner Weltauffassung, ebenso ist den Ange-
Bestimmtheit ausschUeBlich meinen eigenen Apperzeptionsleistungen ver- horigen einer vollig abgeschlossenen kulturellen Heimwelt noch nichts
dankt. Methodisch ist der Riickgang auf diese Welt eine Abstraktion: Ich von anderen Kulturen bekannt. Solange Menschen innerhalb einer
sehe kunstlich davon ab, daB meine Lebenswelt „immer schon" eine isolierten Kulturwelt leben, miissen sie das BewuBtsein haben, sie seien
gemeinsame, d.h. von den Apperzeptionsleistungen der Mitsubjekte „alle Menschen" (217), die Menschheit uberhaupt (140f., 165,176,431). Es
durchtrankte Welt ist. Deshalb bildet die Konstitutionsleistung, durch die ist ja charakteristisch, daB die Selbstbezeichnung der Angehorigen vieler
mein Ich die primordiale Welt transzendiert, keinen Entwicklungsschritt Volker einfach „Mensch" lautet. Die geschlossene Totalitat einer solchen
in der Genesis der BewuBtseinshorizonte;2 die Erweiterung des primor- Welt kann nicht einmal als heimische oder heimatliche Welt empfunden
dialen Horizonts ist keine „Urstiftung", wenn man unter „Urstiftung" die werden; das Heimische hebt sich als solches erst durch den Kontrast zum
Erzeugung einer Apperzeptionsmdglichkeit versteht, die es in der „Fremden" ab (176). Erst nach der Bekanntschaft mit einer „Fremdwelt"
Geschichte des BewuBtseins vorher noch nicht gegeben hatte. kann die eigene Welt, die bis dahin die einzige Welt war, als das „uns
GrundsatzUch anders steht es bei der zweiten Hauptstufe intersubjek- Eigene", d.h. als „Heimwelt" erfahren werden; erst vor dem Hintergrund
tiver Konstitution, wie Husserl sie in § 58 der 5. Meditation im UmriB der Begegnung mit dem Fremden erlebt man das Heimische auch als das
skizziert hat. Hier geht es um die Uberschreitung der ersten bereits konsti- HeimatUche, als Zuhause.
tuierten gemeinsamen Welt, namlich der Kulturwelt, in der eine Men- Das „Fremde" sowohl bei der urspriingUchen Transzendierung der Pri-
schengemeinsch&ft heimisch ist, durch die Begegnung mit einer fremden mordialitat als auch bei der ersten Begegnung mit einer bis dahin fremden
Kultur. DaB Menschen nur ihre heimische Kulturwelt kannten, war Kultur ist ein umfassender Verweisungszusammenhang von apperzeptiven
geschichtlich durchaus mogUch und ist insofern kein bloBes Abstraktions- Gehalten, d.h. eine „Welt" als Horizont. Konkret erfahrbar wird das
produkt des Philosophen. Entsprechend beruht die Offnung der heimis- umfassend Fremde an einer „Fremdwelt" allerdings immer nur in einzel-
chen fiir eine fremde Kulturwelt auf einer Urstiftung, die den Horizont nen Vorkommnissen innerhalb dieser Welt; jedes solche Vorkommnis ist
gemeinsamer Welterfahrung geschichtUch erweitert. Husserl benutzt gleichsam welthaltig und indiziert die Fremdheit der Fremdwelt. So
deshalb in § 58 auch ausdriickUch den Begriff Genesis (vgl. 437). Obwohl kommt die Fremdheit einer bis dahin unbekannten Kultur in alien Ber-
es sich bei der ursprunglichen Uberschreitung der Primordialsphare nicht eichen von Vorkommnissen zum Vorschein, die sich innerhalb dieser
um eine Genesis handelt, kann Husserl die geschichtliche Uberschreitung Kultur beobachten lassen: in erster Linie in den fremden Menschen, den
r einer heimischen Kulturwelt doch damit vergleichen. Betrachtet man „Fremden", mit ihren Handlungsweisen, Gewohnheiten und Institutionen,
diese Uberschreitung namUch im Stil statischer Konstitutionsanalyse auf dann in den fremdartigen Gegenstanden, die sie herstellen, aber auch in
ihre Motivationsstruktur hin, so zeigt sie einen parallelen Aufbau zur anal- all dem, was sie zwar nicht hergestellt haben, was ihnen aber doch auf eine
ogisierenden Apperzeption des Anderen. An diese Strukturver- uns fremde Weise, als uns fremde Natur begegnet.
wandtschaft, die. § 58 als Leitlinie vorgibt, mochte ich mich im folgenden Was eine bis dahin unbekannte Welt fiir „uns" in „unserer" Heimwelt
halten. Ich versuche auf dieser Grundlage zunSchst die Systematik zu zur fremden Welt macht, ist der fremde Apperzeptionszusammenhang,
„rekonstruieren", die in den schwierigen einschlSgigen Texten von Band durch den die Fremden sich selbst, ihre Verhaltensart, ihre Produkte, ihre
XV durchscheint (I.). Die Analyse wird aber zu einem Punkt fiihren, an Natur und was es sonst an „Bestandteilen" ihrer Welt geben mag, anders
dem der genetische Charakter der Problematik nicht langer ausgeklam- auffassen, als „wir" es tun. Die Weise, wie ihnen die Vorkommnisse in
mert bleiben kann. Das genetische Problem wird sich auf die Frage zu- ihrer Welt erscheinen - und damit unthematisch das Ganze ihrer Welt
spitzen, in welchem Sinne die griechische Urstiftung, die der Menschheit selbst - , stimmt mit der unsrigen nicht iiberein. Ihre Welterfahrung ver-
als Entwicklungsziel die eine gemeinsame Welt vorzeichnet, heute ihre lauft in diesem Sinne, wie Husserl sagen wurde, nicht „einstimmig" mit
ErfuUung finden kann (II.).
der unsrigen. Dieses Fehlen der Einstimmigkeit laBt uns ihre Welter-
fahrung als „anomal" erscheinen.

40 41

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE E I N E WELT

Nun kennen wir auch innerhalb unserer Heimwelt Verhaltens- (198). Der Einzelne erfahrt die Endlichkeit seiner Heimwelt in Stufen der
moglichkeiten und Vorkommnisse, die aus der Einstimmigkeit der „ver- Umweltlichkeit, also als Kind vielleicht zunachst darin, daB sich sein
trauten Typik" (221) des normalen Apperzeptionssystems herausfallen. Leben im Umkreis seiner StraBe, seines Dorfes oder StadtteUs abspielt,
MaBstab ist dabei das durchschnittUche Auffassen des reifen Erwachsenen dann aber erweitert sich seine Lebensumwelt. Immer bleibt diese Umwelt
(178, 231) zwischen Kindheit und Jugend auf der einen und Alter auf der endlich, aber sie ist stets nur „relativ geschlossen" (219); sie enthalt in sich
anderen Seite. Was diesem MaBstab geniigt, gilt fur Jedermann" (142, ein Potential der Erweiterung (429), der Uberschreitung (205) des jeweili-
165); es ist das Normale. Entscheidend ist, daB das heimische „System" gen endlichen Umfeldes. So ist die Heimwelt im offenen ProzeB einer fort-
der Normalitat so umfassend ist, daB es die Anomalie mit einbegreift dauernden „Aneignung" bewuBt. Das Eigene, das lebensweltliche Heim,
(142f., 154ff., 211 ff., 230f., 438). Das Anomale mag zwar im Einzelfalle der oikos als Eigenes, als oikeion, bewahrt sich als dieses Eigene durch die
unerwartbar sein, aber ihrem Typ nach sind die Abweichungen von der fortschreitende Erweiterung seines Umfangs - eine Konzeption, die struk-
Normalitat im heimweltlichen Erwartungshorizont gleichsam vorgesehen. turell - nicht inhaltlich - an die stoische Lehre von der oikeiosis erinnert.
Die NormaUtat behauptet sich gegenuber der Anomalie, indem sie ihr ihre Die Heimwelt bleibt uns immerfort unaufhdrUch zur Explikation (202)
Typik vorgibt. aufgegeben. Sie ist ein „Erwerb, der immerzu im Erwerben ist" (201), „ein
Eine bisher unbekannte Kultur erweckt den Eindruck umfassender Seinssinn, der fiir mich wird" (201). Sie ist etwas, was uns jederzeit aufs neue
Fremdheit, weil ihr gegenuber die heimische Typik der Anomalie versagt. bevorsteht und was deshalb „immerzu Antizipation" (202) ist. So ist uns der
Das heimische Anomale mochte uns „befremden", aber es war in letzter heimweltliche Horizont im Modus der Zukunftigkeit bewuBt. Aber zugleich
Instanz nichts Fremdes, es hob die Einstimmigkeit der Wertapperzeption besitzt er den Charakter der Vergangenheit; denn alle Explikationen lagen
im ganzen nicht auf. Eben dies tritt nun ein, ein Bruch im gesamten Stil als MogUchkeiten schon in der bisherigen Erfahrung der Heimwelt
(198, 431 f.) der lebensweltUchen Erfahrung, der uns die bislang unbekan- beschlossen. Die Heimwelt ist, um diesen Sachverhalt auf eine Formel zu
nte Kultur als unverstandlich (233), als etwas „unverstandlich Fremdes" bringen, ein explicandum, dessen Zukunfts- und Vergangenheitscharakter
(432) erscheinen laBt, weil sie auf einem eigenen System der NormaUtat eins sind: Nur indem wir den Horizont unserer heimatUchen Umwelt in die
unter EinschluB einer entsprechenden Typik der Anomalie beruht. offene Zukunft hinein explizieren, bewahrt er sich als das immer schon
Damit ist der eigentUche Grund dieser Verstandnislosigkeit aber noch „Vorgegebene" (171), und nur indem wir uns an dieses Vorgegebene,
nicht aufgedeckt. Auch innerhalb unserer Heimwelt konnen uns heim Ein- unvordenkUch Alte halten, bringen wir das Zukunftige, Neue zum
tritt in ungewohnte Lebensverhaltnisse in gewissem Umfange neue Systeme Vorschein.
der NormaUtat begegnen, etwa bei der Aufnahme in einen Verein oder bei Als unabschUeBbar immer weiter explizierbare Vorgegebenheit gibt die
der EheschlieBung. Vieles mag uns dann unverstandUch erscheinen, und Heimwelt unserem Leben Sicherheit. Denn wenn alles Neue nur als Exp-
auch die Typik der AnomaUe ist partieU eine andere. Trotzdem ist die likation des vorgegebenen Gesamtsystems normaler Auffassungstypik
UmsteUung auf die neuen Verhaltnisse mogUch, weil es sich nur um par- begegnen kann, darf ich mich darauf verlassen, daB dieses System als Ver-
tieUe Modifikationen (136) innerhalb eines in Geltung bleibenden standigungsgrundlage mit den Andern nie ins Wanken gerat. Aber die
vorgegebenen Gesamtsystems normaler Auffassungstypik handelt. Frage ist: Was gibt mir eigentlich von vornherein diese Sicherheit, und wie
Die normale Typik enthalt in sich bereits die Moglichkeit von Korrek- ist es vor diesem Hintergrund moglich, daB das heimweltUche BewuBtsein
turen usw., ohne daB sie im ganzen gefahrdet ware; sie ist eine „flieBende dann doch auf die Fremdheit der Fremdwelt stoBen kann, deren Unver-
Typik", wie Husserl sagt (431). Deshalb erscheint keinerlei Neues, d.h. standUchkeit in der Kontinuitat des unabschlieBbaren ExpUzierens einen
nichts zunachst als anomal Erscheinendes, fur dessen Aneignung wir Bruch hervorruft?
unseren heimweltlichen Horizont erweitern mtissen, in ganz strengem Sinne Das Gesamtsystem der Normalitat erscheint jedermann als etwas,
als uberraschend. Es begegnet nie als vollig unbekannt, sondern als „vor- worauf man sich verlassen kann, weil es den Charakter der jeweils schon
bekannt". So wird jede Erweiterung als Explikation von Moglichkeiten eingespielten Gewohnheit (144) hat. Es stammt aus einer Vergangenheit,
erfahren, die schon in dem vorangegangenen engeren HorizontbewuBtsein die unserer eigenen Erfahrung mit der Normalitat, innerhalb derer wir sie
beschlossen lagen. partieU modifizieren oder erweitern konnen, voraufgeht. Es verweist als
Der Horizont der Heimwelt ist offen und geschlossen zugleich. „Hori- Althergebrachtes unmittelbar auf die Generation derer, die vor uns Heuti-
zont" bedeutet „begrenzender Umkreis", aber bildlich gesprochen liegt gen gelebt haben. Aber weil auch die Generation unserer Eltern schon ein
der Radius des Kreises nicht fest. Der Horizont als Grenze macht die solches - von ihnen eventuell modifiziertes oder erweitertes - System
Heimwelt endlich, aber die Endlichkeit ist eine „relative Endlichkeit" als Verstandigungsgrundlage voraussetzen muBte, reicht der Verweis

42 43
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE EINE WELT

mittelbar in die vorvergangene Generation zurtick und von da weiter in Das tiberraschende ist das, worauf man nicht gefaBt war. Nicht gefaBt
eine Generationenkette, die „endlos offen" in die Vergangenheit zurtick1- ist man auf das, was einem nicht bloB als unmoglich erschien, sondern was
geht (138,168 f., 199 f.). man wegen seiner UnmogUchkeit fiir die Interessen des Lebens gar nicht
Der gegenwartige Bestand der Normalitat und ihrer Typik ist also erst in Rechnung gestellt und als irrelevant auBer Betracht gelassen hatte
Resultat der Auffassungsarbeit ins Unendliche zuriickreichender Genera- (232). Das Uberraschende tiberfaUt uns so aus einer Gegend, einer
tionen. Normalitat beruht in diesem Sinne auf der „Generativitat" (431), Dimension, die wir von vornherein lebenspraktisch abgeblendet hatten.
sie hat als generativ gewachsene Gewohnheit wesenhaft eine historische Eine solche Gegend oder Dimension gibt es nun in der Tat fiir das
Dimension (139, 205). Die Menschen haben in diesem Sinne im Unter- heimweltUche BewuBtsein. Es weiB - wenngleich nur unthematisch -, daB
schied zu den Tieren durch ihre Heimwelt eine generative, historische es zur in sich unendlich explizierbaren Umwelt der NormaUtat ein AuBer-
Welt" (160 Anm.). halb gibt. Wenn namlich alles Erwartbare nur Explikation sein kann, dann
Nun ist aber die Geschichte der Generationen, denen wir die Normal- besitzt die Heimwelt den Charakter eines umfassenden Innenhorizonts.
itat unserer Heimwelt verdanken (168f.), „unsere" Tradition. Es waren Als das „immer schon", aus unvordenkUcher Vergangenheit Vorgegebene
nicht beliebige Menschen, die die Normalitat iiber das Absterben der ist die Heimwelt ein Drinnen, das Geborgenheit bietet. An dieses ver-
alten Generationen hinweg (168 f.) weitergetragen und weiterentwikkelt traute Drinnen halt sich die Lebenspraxis; „das praktische Interesse ist iiji
haben, sondern es waren „unsere" Eltern, deren Voreltern usw. Diesen Drinnen" (431). Aber dem Drinnen korrespondiert ein DrauBen (431),
Aspekt der Generativitat hat Husserl in den Forschungsmanuskripten von der heimweltUche Innenhorizont hat einen AuBenhorizont zur Kehrseite
Band XV nicht eigens hervorgehoben, obwohl gerade er es ist, der dem (219).
heimweltlichen System der Auffassungsnormalitat eigentlich seine Zuver- Weil der Innenhorizont das Drinnen umschUeBt und gegen das
lassigkeit und Vertrauenswiirdigkeit verleiht. Der springende Punkt ist die DrauBen abgrenzt, kann Husserl die Heimwelt mit einer Kugel ver-
Herkunft dieses Systems aus einer exklusiv gerade „unserer" Heimwelt gleichen (430,438). Der Umfang dieser Kugel liegt allerdings - darin hinkt
zugehorigen Generativitat; „unsere" Vorfahren sind nicht gegen die einer der Vergleich - wegeri der Relativitat der EndUchkeit nicht fest. Mit ihrer
Fremdwelt austauschbar. Mit dieser Feststellung hat sich zugleich geklart, Selbstexplikation in der heimweltlichen oikeiosis setzt die Kugel wie eine
worin die unverstandliche Fremdheit der fremdweltlichen Auffassungs- wachsende Zwiebel immer neue Schalen (430) an, aber sie bleibt endlich,
normaUtat ihre letzte Wurzel hat. Das Fremde ist das Nicht-Eigene; das weil sie einen AuBenhorizont als ihr Anderes hat. Der AuBenhorizont
nicht austauschbar Eigene jeder Heimwelt sind die Vorfahren, auf deren aber ist deshalb ein Anderes, sein Inhalt also kein Explikat der Heimwelt,
Auffassungsarbeit das geltende System der Normalitat beruht. Dieses weil jedes Explikat in den Umkreis des Erwartbaren gehort. Der AuBen-
Eigene laBt sich nur generativ „erben", aber nicht von auBen „aneignen". horizont konstituiert sich demgegenuber gerade als die Dimension oder
Wir haben damit den Punkt erreicht, an dem wir den eigentlichen Grund Gegend fiir das Nichterwartbare, und der Grundcharakter der Konstitu-
der EndUchkeit der Heimwelt aufdekken konnen. Husserl betont zwar in tion dieser Gegend ist ihre praktische A.bblendung.
den Texten von Band XV mehrfach, daB die Welt als Lebenswelt notwendig Damit hat sich folgender Zusammenhang herausgestellt: Letzter Grund
endlich ist (171, 205, 431, 625), und diese EndUchkeit charakterisiert die ftir die Endlichkeit der Heimwelt ist ihre Vorgegebenheit aus einer unvor-
Lebenswelt als Heimwelt. Aber weil Husserl immer ebensosehr hervorhebt, denklichen generativen Vergangenheit; denn deswegen erscheint alles
daB es sich um eine relative d.h. unabscblieBbar explizierbare EndUchkeit Neue als Explikat von „schon" Vorbekanntem. Eben dies aber macht die
handelt, entsteht der Schein, als sei die Heimwelt entgegen Husserls Ver- Heimwelt zu einem Innenhorizont, einem vertrauten Drinnen, und das
sicherung unendlich. Man muB kritisch fragen: Bedeutet die unbeschrankte heimweltUche BewuBtsein vom Drinnen impliziert als praktisch inter-
Offenheit fiir kontinuierUche Erweiterung des Horizonts durch vorbekannt essiertes BewuBtsein die Abblendung eines irrelevanten DrauBen. Durch
Neues nicht doch UnendUchkeit? So wie Husserl die heimweltUche Kapaz- diese praktische Abblendung des AuBenhorizonts konstituiert sich das
itat fiir die unbegrenzte „Aneignung" von vorbekannt Neuem in Band XV explicandum „Heimwelt" als notwendig endlich.
fiber weite Passagen beschreibt, konnte es so kUngen, als sei eine eigene Das DrauBen, das AuBerhalb ist der Bereich fiir das Auftreten des
Konstitution von Einstimmigkeit mit der Fremdwelt gar nicht erforderUch, Unerwartbaren. Als Bereich ftir . . . muB es den Charakter einer Dimen-
weil auch das Neue der Fremdwelt nur Explikat des unvordenklich Alten sion oder Gegend haben, die durch das Auftreten des Unerwartbaren mit
der Heimwelt sein kann - und damit nichts wirkUch Uberraschendes. Was Vorkommnissen „besetzt" werden kann. Weil das AuBerhalb aber abge-
die Heimwelt eigentUch endlich macht, muB dasjenige sein, wodurch das blendet wird, bleibt es volUg unbesetzt, es wird ganz leergelassen. Der
Neue an der Fremdwelt fiir uns unverstandlich ist und uns iiberrascht. AuBenhorizont der Heimwelt ist deshalb ein Leerhorizont (216, 429) im

44 45
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S • H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE E I N E WELT

strengsten Sinne von „Leere". Trotzdem besitzt er eine rudimentSre Bes- ungeeignet - erscheinen, um sie uns im Zuge einer weiteren Explikation
timmtheit dadurch, daB er eine Dimension fiir Besetzbarkeit ist. Die jeder des heimweltUchen Innenhorizonts durch Kultivierung anzueignen. Um in
inhaltlichen Besetzung bare Dimension von Besetzbarkeit ist die leere ihnen Territorien fur eine mogliche Fremdwelt zu erblicken, muB das
Raumzeitlichkeit (139, 209, 216). Das praktisch abgeblendete AuBerhalb heimweltUche BewuBtsein die bereits beschriebene Erfahrung der
ist deshalb, wie Husserl einmal formuliert, die „Au8enraumzeitUchkeit" Unbrauchbarkeit seines ganzen normalen Apperzeptionssystems machen.
(429). Erst in dieser Erfahrung wird das „eigene", die zweite Primordialitat
Die erste Begegnung mit einer Fremdwelt vollzieht sich, indem in der „Heimwelt", mit dem eigentlich „Fremden" zweiter Stufe konfrontiert.
bislang abgeblendeten und leergelassenen AuBenraumzeitlichkeit eine Wie gelingt es nun dem heimweltUchen BewuBtsein, mit diesem neuar-
„Besetzung" (216, 232) stattfindet. Das aber setzt eine VerMnderung dieser tig Fremden zu einer ebenso neuartigen Einstimmigkeit zu kommen? Als
leeren Dimension selbst voraus. Wie mehrfach gesagt wurde, ist jede Wurzel der Fremdheit hatte sich der Abgrund zwischen den jeweils unaus-
Fremdwelt eine „Kultur". Damit ist gemeint, daB sie als Apperzeptions- tauschbar eigenen Generativitaten herausgestellt. Auch in der Motivations-
system einen Gesamtbereich von Vorgegebenheit iiberlagert, der dem struktur der Intersubjektivitatskonstitution erster Stufe gab es ein
apperzeptiven Auffassen-als unterUegt. Das Apperzipieren „besetzt", d.h. unerreichbar Fremdes: das absolute Hier des Leibes, worin der Andere
iiberzieht oder durchsetzt diesen Vorgegebenheitsbereich mit einem flexi- „waltet". Das Hier des Leibes des Anderen bleibt fiir mich unaufhebbar
blen Geflecht von Auffassungscharakteren, einer flieBenden Normaltypik, das Dort jenes Korpers, welcher fiir den Anderen sein Hier, das „NuU-
ahnlich wie die erste cultura den rohen Boden der Natur bearbeitet. Die glied" seiner Weltorientierung bildet. Jenes Dort kann ich nur in der
leere AuBenraumzeitlichkeit bildet fur die potentiellen apperzeptiven Phantasie, im BewuBtsein „als ob ich dort ware", nicht aber in positionaler
Kultivierungen durch Fremdwelten die „Natur", aber „Natur" aUein als ReaUtat zu meinem leiblichen Hier machen. Das Walten des Anderen im
dasjenige Bestimmbare, das sich in der Dimension der Raumzeitlichkeit absoluten Hier seines eigenen Leibes ist das ftir mich schlechthin
erstreckt, also die reine res extensa. Wtirde diese Natur eine dariiber hin- UnzugangUche. Ebenso gibt es bei der Intersubjektivitatskonstitution zweiter
ausgehende Bestimmtheit aufweisen, so ware sie bereits ein Stuck weit Stufe ein prinzipieU Unzugangliches: die eigenen Vorfahren der Angehori-
durch heimweltUche Auffassungscharaktere kultiviert. Damit aber ware gen der Fremdwelt.
sie kein vollig leerer AuBenhorizont mehr. Die kulturelle Besetzung Die Uberschreitung der Primordialsphare war trotz der UnzugangUchkeit
verandert die reine raumzeitliche Natur. des fremdleibUchen Hier mogUch, weil der Leib des Anderen nicht bloB
Solange diese Natur als AuBenhorizont ganzUch abgeblendet war, bUeb Leib-fur-ihn, sondern ineins damit Korper-fur-mich und damit Bestandteil
sie fiir unbeschrankt viele Besetzungen offen, d.h. sie hatte den Charakter meiner primordialen Korperwelt ist. Auch zu dieser Struktur der Intersub-
der UnendUchkeit. Die Kultivierung schrankt diese UnendUchkeit ein. Dies jektivitatskonstitution erster Stufe gibt es eine Entsprechung in der
kann nur so geschehen, daB aus der puren res extensa konkrete Natur wird, zweiten Stufe. Die fremde Generativitat verleiblicht sich gleichsam, indem
wie wir sie lebensweltUch als „Lebensfeld" (177) erfahren: „Erdboden, das aus ihr erwachsende Apperzeptionssystem ein bestimmtes Territorium
Himmel, Pflanzen, Tiere", wie Husserl einmal formuliert (177). Um sich kultiviert. Sofern wir die MogUchkeit haben, dieses Territorium in
eine kultureUe Fremdwelt begegnen lassen zu konnen, muB das Abstraktion von seiner kuturellen Besetzung als unkultivierte Natur auf-
i-r heimweltUche BewuBtsein die unendUch leere Dimension des AuBerhalb zufassen, konnen wir es als einen Bestandteil unserer Heimwelt behan-
einschranken (206) auf eine endUche Gegend konkreter Natur. Erst damit deln, so wie der Leibkorper des Anderen rein als Korper zu meiner
wird das DrauBen durch eine bestimmte Fremdwelt mit ihrer EndUchkeit Primordialsphare gehort. Jeder Tourist, der die Natur einer Fremdwelt
kulturell besetzbar. Die durch Beschrankung der raumzeitUchen bereist, ohne sich um die Kultur derer, die sie bewohnen, zu kummern, ist
UnendUchkeit gewonnene Gegend konkreter Natur als Spielraum fiir eine fiir diese Moglichkeit ein (freiUch trauriger) Beleg.
bestimmte kultureUe Besetzung nennt Husserl Territorium (177, 206 u. 6.). Fiir die analogisierende Apperzeption des Anderen geniigt es nicht,
Das Territorium ist also mehr als ein auf der Landkarte abgegrenzter daB sich das Dort des Korpers in meiner Primordialsphare fiktiv, im
Bezirk; es besteht aus der ganzen konkreten Natur in einem solchen Bezirk, Modus des „als ob ich dort ware", in mein Hier verwandelt. Damit die
wie Husserl sie in der gerade angefuhrten Formulierung umschreibt. Konstitution des Anderen wirklich stattfindet, brauche ich einen Anhalt-
Nun konnen uns auch innerhalb unserer Heimwelt Sttikke unkul- spunkt dafiir, jenes Dort nicht bloB in der Phantasie als absolutes Hier zu
tivierter konkreter Natur begegnen, ohne daB wir sie als Territorien fiir betrachten. Diesen Anhaltspunkt bietet das bei dem Korper dort zu
die mogliche Besetzung durch eine fremde Kulturwelt auffassen. Sie sind beobachtende „Gebaren". Es bestatigt in der ReaUtat kontinuierlich die
fiir uns Leerstellen, die uns geeignet - order auch im Grenzfalle MogUchkeiten erwartbaren Verhaltens, die mein fiktives „Walten" in

46 47
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE EINE WELT

jenem absoluten Hier vorzeichnet. Die kontinuierUche Deckung des realen des Lebens. In alien Mangelzustanden, die wir in unseren Bedurfnissen
Gebarens mit dem fiktiv erwartbaren Verhalten laBt jenen Korper alsXeib spuren, droht am Ende der Tod, und in jeder Befriedigung solcher
eines anderen Ich erscheinen und bildet zugleich die Grundlage der Ein- Bediirfnisse erleben wir ein Wiedergeborenwerden. Das eigentUch - d.h.
stimmigkeit zwischen ihm und mir.3 als Mythos erzahlbare - Generative ist in seiner Grundform der periodis-
Entsprechend braucht nun das heimweltUche BewuBtsein einen Anhalt- che Wechsel der Generationen. Das „Urgenerative" ist der naturhafte
spunkt, einen „Kern der Bekanntheit" (432), um ein Stuck Natur real als periodische Wechsel von Bediirfnis und Bedurfnisbefriedigung (432), die
fremdes Territorium, d.h., als besetzt durch eine fremde Kultur zu regelmaBige Regeneration der instinktiven Lebensbedurfnisse (413). In
erfahren. Das „Gebaren" jenes Korpers dort gab auf der ersten Stufe seiner einformigen Periodizitat braucht dieser urgenerative Wechsel nicht
meiner Phantasie den AnstoB, in ihm als einem absoluten Hier zu walten. erzahlt zu werden, und wegen seines naturhaften Charakters ist er die
Ebenso muB auf der zweiten Stufe das heimweltUche BewuBtsein im Weise, wie das fremde Apperzeptionssystem anhebt, sich in der
moghcherweise fremden Territorium ein „Gebaren" antreffen, das ihm naturhaften Umwelt des Territoriums zu verleibUchen; vom Urgenera-
den AnstoB gibt, darin das Walten einer aus fremder Generativitat tiven her „breitet sich Verstandlichkeit fiber die [im Territorium
erwachsenen NormaUtat zu erblicken. Dabei spielt es fiir den prinzipiellen konkretisierte] raumzeitliche Natur" (432). So bietet das indirekt oder
Gang dieser Analyse keine Rolle, ob jenes Gebaren unmittelbar als Ver- direkt erfahrene urgenerative Gebaren im fremden Territorium den
halten von Fremden oder mittelbar in Zeugnissen von Kultur in Erschein- Anhaltspunkt fiir die Entdeckung einer Fremdwelt als Fremdwelt. Dieses
ung tritt. WesentUch ist nur, daB in dem direkt order indirekt erfahrenen Gebaren ist dem heimweltlichen BewuBtsein einerseits wegen seiner
Gebaren ein Hinweis auf Generativitat Uegt; denn die unaufhebbare Naturhaftigkeit in einem „schlichten apprasentativen Verstehen" (436)
Fremdheit der Generativitat macht die andere Kultur zur Fremdwelt. zuganglich und bildet so die Briicke zur Apperzeption der Fremden „als
Die Generativitat tragt als anonymer geschichtlicher Hintergrund die meinesgleichen" (135) und zum Verstandnis ihrer zunachst vollig unver-
NormaUtat des geltenden Apperzeptiofissystems. Sie bleibt in der gegen- standUchen fremden Kultur. Andererseits enthalt es als Vorform des
wartigen Geltung dieses Systems als etwas GeschichtUches verborgen. Als eigentlich Generativen den Verweis auf eben dieses als das niemals
Geschichte der Generationenfolge mit den ftir das Normalitatsbewufilsein „anzueignende" Fremde.
entscheidenden Ereignissen tritt die Generativitat erst hervor, indem diese In dieses eigentlich Fremde. kann sich das heimweltUche BewuBtsein
Ereignisse von Generation zu Generation durch Erzahlen (145) iiber- nur im Modus des „als ob" hineinversetzen; das „anschauliche Nachverste-
Uefert werden. Dieses den Generationswechsel uberbrukkende Erzahlen hen" der Fremde ist nur so moglich, „als ob sie Heimat ware" (625). So
ist fiir Husserl der Mythos (436 f., dazu die Anmerkungen 432 ff.). Er wie das leibliche Hier des Andern nur fiktiv mein Hier sein kann, so
gehort zu einer geschlossenen Heimwelt, weil er ihren Fortbestand als konnen wir uns an der Erzahlung der Mythen der fremden Generativitat,
endlicher Innenhorizont durch Bewahrung des uralten Eigenen fiber wenn es uns gelingt, vermittels des Urgenerativen in sie einzudringen, nur
Geburt und Tod hinweg sichert. so beteiUgen, „als ob" die fremden Vorfahren auch die unsrigen waren. So
Nun ist der fremde Mythos aber - zumeist schon wegen der Sprachbar- wie das primordial dortige absolute Hier nie mein absolutes Hier werden
riere - dem heimweltUchen BewuBtsein zunachst ganz und gar unzugangUch. kann, so konnen wir die generative Vergangenheit der „dortigen"
Wenn es also im potentiell fremden Territorium direkt oder indirekt auf Lebenswelt und ihrer NormaUtat nie als unsere Vergangenheit haben. So
ein Gebaren stoBen soil, das auf fremde Generativitat verweist, so kann wie meine Primordialsphare sich nie die PrimordiaUtat des Anderen von
diese Generativitat zunachst nicht die in ihrem geschichtUchen Charakter seinem Orientierungsnullpunkt aus aneignen kann, so bleibt der genera-
hervortretende mythisch erzahlte Generativitat sein. Es muB sich um eine tive Orientierungsnullpunkt der fremden Kultur der Aneignung durch
Vorform der Generativitat handeln, die zwei Bedingungen erfiiUt: Ihr unsere heimweltUche Primordialitat entzogen.
Geschichtscharakter bleibt noch verborgen, aber sie ist schon der Beginn Trotzdem kann die Fremdwelt annaherungsweise, in unendlicher
der Verleiblichung des fremden Apperzeptionssystems in der konkreten Approximation, verstandlich werden; zunachst im Verstandnis der Urgen-
Natur des fremden Territoriums. erativitat mit ihrem Territorium, dann durch „historische Einfuhlung"
Diese Vorform von Generativitat nennt Husserl das „Urgenerative" (233 Anm.) im Nachverstehen des Mythos und der Geschichte der
(432), und dieses Urgenerative gibt es: Der Wechsel der Generationen fremden Kultur, schlieBlich im Sicheinleben in das fremde Normalitats-
vollzieht sich mit Geburt und Tod, die kein „zufalUges Weltfaktum" sind system auf der Grundlage dieser Verstandnishorizonte. In der Wechsel-
(171). Geborenwerden und Sterben sind nun aber nicht nur Grenzstatio- seitigkeit dieser Verstandigung - denn aus der Perspektive der fremden
nen am Rande des Lebens, sondern melden sich auch naturhaft innerhalb Heimwelt ist „unsere" Heimwelt die Fremdwelt - entstecht eine neue

48 49

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE E I N E WELT

Einstimmigkeit und damit eine gemeinsame Heimwelt hoherer Stufe mit Faktisch geschichtlich ist das planetarische Zusammenwachsen der
einer neuen gemeinsamen Geschichte. Menschheit unmittelbar oder mittelbar ein Resultat des Ausgreifens der
Es kann sein, daB es innerhalb dieser umfassenderen Heimwelt um die Europaer auf alle Lander und Kontinente. Die grundlegende ideelle
Verstandigung schlecht besteUt ist. Vielleicht besteht die gemeinsame Vorbedingung der realen Vergemeinschaftung der Menschheit, die sich
Geschichte lange Zeit aus kaum mehr als einer einzigen Abfolge von damit anbahnte, war die Urstiftung von Philosophie und Wissenschaft bei
Kriegen. Und doch konstituiert sich auch in diesem Grenzfall dann eine den Griechen. In dieser Urstiftung war namlich der Gedanke einer
Heimwelt hoherer Stufe, wenn die beiden Grundbedingungen von Offnung aller vorgegebenen Heimwelten in Richtung auf die eine Welt
HeimweltUchkeit erftillt sind. Erstens muB es wiederum eine Peripherie der einen Menschheit schon angelegt, weil sie dem menschUchen Denken
geben, an der der AuBenhorizont praktisch abgeblendet wird. Zweitens die Aufgabe stellte, die eine „wahre Welt", die „Welt an sich" (215, 627)
muB ein System iibergreifender Auffassungsnormalitat entstehen, das die zu erkennen.
Systeme der alten Heimwelten so als Bestandteile enthalt, wie schon jede Das vorwissenschaftlich-vorphilosophische BewuBtsein interessiert sich
dieser Heimwelten ihre apperzeptiven Teilsysteme - etwa die von Dorfern zwar auch schon dafur, was die Gegenstande „an sich" sind, d.h. was
oder Famihengeschlechtern - in sich einbegreifen konnte. Im Grenzfall jeweils das Identische ist, das sich in seinen Erscheinungsweisen nur auf
mogen diese Teilsysteme lange Zeit nur so koexistieren, daB sie sich wech- partikulare, endliche Weise zeigt (175, 437). Aber es begniigt sich damit,
selseitig unversohnlich als Anomalie denunzieren, und die. iibergreifende die Identitat der Genenstande ausschlieBUch im Durchgang durch ihre
Auffassungsnormalitat mag dann nur darin bestehen, daB ftir den ..Nor-1 endlichen Erscheinungsweisen zu besitzen. Nach Husserls Interpretation
malfall" geregelt ist, in welchen Formen man miteinander Krieg fuhrt. vergegenstandlicht das beginnende philosophisch-wissenschaftliche
Doch selbst dann entsteht jenes Eigene, das eine Heimwelt als Innenhori- BewuBtsein bei den Griechen die bis dahin immer nur antizipierte Iden-
zont zusammenschlieBt: eine gemeinsame Generativitat, deren Mythos in titat der Gegenstande, indem es diese Identitat als PoUdee, als Flucht-
diesem FaUe hauptsachlich von den eigenen und den feindlichen Helden punkt einer UnendUchkeit von Erscheinungsweisen auffaBt. Das
jener unaufhorlichen Abfolge von Kriegen handeln mag. philosophisch-wissenschaftUche BewuBtsein tut damit so, als hatte es die
unendUche Menge aller moglichen Erscheinungsweisen durchlaufen und
konnte nun vom Zielpunkt dieses .Durchlaufs her, dem Identitatspol
n. selbst, gleichsam auf die unendUche Mannigfaltigkeit zurtick- und herabb-
Da jede - ob friedliche order feindUche - Offnung von ursprUnglich einan- likken. Diesen Schritt, mit dem das BewuBtsein die AnschauUchkeit der
der fremden Heimwelten ftireinander den Beginn der gemeinsamen endlichen Erscheinungsweisen radikal transzendiert, bezeichnet Husserl
Geschichte einer Heimwelt hoherer Stufe markiert, ergibt sich an dieser als Idealisierung (236). Da alle Gegenstande durch den horizonthaften
Stelle eine Signatur unseres Zeitalters. Heute ist absehbar, daB auch der Verweisungszusammenhang ihrer Erscheinungsweisen ihren jeweiligen
letzte Winkel abgeschiedener Heimwelt auf dieser Erde seine Geschlossen- apperzeptiven Welthintergrund unthematisch miterscheinen lassen, kann
heit verUert. So ist die „Weltgeschichte", einst eine bloBe geschichts- der identische Pol, auf den die Idealisierungsaktivitat ihre Aufmerk-
philosophische Idee, zur Realitat geworden. Eine neue, umfassende samkeit richtet, letztUch nur einer sein: die eine und einzige Welt. In der
Heimwelt ist im Entstehen begriffen: die der einen „totalen ,irdischen' Men- Idee der einen identischen Welt kommt dasjenige zum Vorschein, was die
schheit" (139), der „irdischen Total-menschheit" (440), mit dem ErdbaU Einstimmigkeit aller Erscheinungsweisen uberhaupt verbiirgt. In diesem
als Territorium und einem alle heimweltUchen Normalitaten iiber- Sinne ist sie die „an sich wahre Welt" (215). Zu erforschen, was diese Idee
greifenden Rahmen von Normalitat fiir „jedermann" auf Erden (233). impliziert, ist nach Husserl die Aufgabe, die sich das philosophisch-
wissenschaftUche Denken mit seiner Urstiftung gestellt hat.
Spatestens mit der unvermeidlichen Reflexion auf diese geschichtUche
Situation verliert die phanomenologische Analyse der inter subjektiven Die Grundlage der moglichen Einstimmigkeit von divergierenden
Weltkonstitution ihren gleichsam zeitlosen, statischen Charakter. Im Blick Gegenstandsauffassungen ist die vorgangige Identitat des Gegenstandes,
auf die faktische Konstitution einer planetarischen Heimwelt der die wir durch Idealisierung als Idee vergegenstandlichen konnen. Indem
gesamten Menschheit muB sie die genetische Frage stellen, durch welche wir die Idee der einen Welt als Grundlage moglicher Einstimmigkeit uber-
Urstiftung es bewuBtseinsgeschichtlich zur Erweiterung der alten haupt auffassen, vergegenstandUchen wir sie auf die gleiche Weise. Das
heimweltUchen Horizonte in Richtung auf das Ganze der Menschheit und bedeutet aber: Die eine Welt als Idee erscheint als ein Gegenstand, als ein
damit zu einer „einzigen Geschichte der Menschheit" (236) kommen „Selbiges" (210), das sich in einer UnendUchkeit von endlichen Erschein-
konnte und ob oder wie sich diese Urstiftung heute erftillt. ungsweisen, Auffassungen, Apperzeptionen gleichsam perspektivisch

50 51

i
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , D I E E I N E WELT

abschattet (217, 437). Zu beachten ist aber: In diesen Erscheinungsweisen mit der „unendUchen Natur als Territorium" (140; vgl. 181 Anm.) die fak-
zeigt sich nun keiner der uns vorwissenschaftlich vertrauten Einzelgegen- tische ..Synthesis der endUchen Umwelten" (209) nicht ersparen, und diese
stande, sondern die Welt, der Horizont ftir diese Gegenstande. Demnach faktische Synthesis darf man mit jener unendUchen Synthesis nicht ver-
mussen es Horizonte, Welten sein, in denen die Idee der einen Welt in wechseln (207). Die faktische Synthesis.»aber bilden die endlichen Ver-
Erscheinung tritt - „Sonderwelten", wie Husserl in der bekannten Krisis- standigungsprozesse zwischen endUch wenigen Heimwelten, und das
Beilage XVII formuUert. GeUngen dieser Prozesse wird von der ganzen Faktizitat-des „Irdischen",
Zu diesen Sonderwelten gehoren auch die Heimwelten. Vor der Urs- von „Schicksal" und „Zufall" beeinfluBt (181 f. Anm.).
tiftung von Philosophie und Wissenschaft war die Einstimmigkeit zwis- Weil die Idee der einzigen Welt impliziert, daB sie sich in einer
chen ihnen nur auf eine Weise denkbar: als der im I. Teil beschriebene UnendUchkeit von heimweltlichen Abschattungen zeigen kann, weist sie
VerstandigungsprozeB, durch den sich zwei - oder jedenfalls eine tiber- fiber das gegenwartig zu beobachtende faktische Zusammenwachsen der
schaubare Anzahl - bis dahin geschlossene Heimwelten wechselseitig Menschheit auf dieser Erde noch hinaus. Denn denkbar sind auch noch
fureinander offnen. Mit der Urstiftung entsteht im Prinzip die Idee einer Menschheiten jenseits unseres Planeten. Deshalb erfiiUt die umfassendste
neuartigen Einstimmigkeit, die solche partieUe Verstandigung trans- Vergemeinschaftung auf dieser Erde, die „irdische Totalmenschheit"
zendiert. Sie beruht auf der Einsicht, daB alle Heimwelten uberhaupt (440), „noch nicht die Idee der Menschheit im universalsten Sinne" (163).
vorab zu alien partiellen Verstandigungs-prozessen bereits darin aufeinan- Diese Idee verschafft uns, so schreibt Husserl pathetisch, „die offene
der bezogen sind, daB sie „Erscheinungsweisen der einzigen Welt" (177) Moglichkeit weiteren Fortschreitens vermoge der UnendUchkeit der
Ii II als Idee sind. Damit aber ist in der Urstiftung die Vergemein-schaftung Natur" (440). Und doch darf man fiber diesem Unendlichkeitspathos nicht
aUer erdenklichen Heimwelten vorgezeichnet, namUch auf der Grundlage aus dem Blick verlieren, daB die Idee einer unsere Erde transzendieren-
ihrer Zusammengehorigkeit als „Abschattungen" der einen Welt. Das den Allmenschheit mit der unendlichen Natur als Reservoir aUer erden-
reale Zusammenwachsen der kulturellen Sonderwelten aller vormals klichen Territorien nicht mehr ist als eine gedankUche Extrapolation. Hier
getrennten „Sondermenschheiten" (217) dieser Erde enthiiUt sich so als wird nur das ideale Telos formuliert, in dessen Licht der historische Weg,
die faktische Einlosung einer ideellen Vorgabe aus der griechischen Urs- der faktisch zum Zusammenwachsen der irdischen Menschheit gefuhrt
tiftung. In jenem Zusammenwachsen hat „die Idee der identischen Welt hat, von uns geschichtsmetaphysisch als ein Fortschreiten auf ein im
sich bewahrt" (438) und sich damit als die „Wahrheit" (438) bestatigt, auf Unendlichen liegendes Ziel hin interpretiert werden kann - als ein
die die Urstiftung abzielte. Fortschreiten, das sich durch „eine fortschreitende Synthesis historischer
Endlichkeiten" (233 Anm.) vollzieht. Die VorsteUung von diesem Telos
In dieser Konzeption Husserls steckt eine Problematik, die er selbst
ist, wie Husserl selbst gelegentlich betont, nur ein „Denkgebilde" (227)
wohl gespiirt hat, ohne sie deutlich zu entwickeln. Die Deutung der kul-
und deshalb nicht in konkreten interkulturellen Einstimmigkeitserfahrun-
turellen Heimwelten als Abschattungen der einen Welt impliziert die
gen anschaulich erlebbar. Wegen ihrer UnanschauUchkeit bietet sie auch
Vergegenstandlichung dieser einen Welt; denn es ist das Wesen des
keine „wahre universale Weltanschauung" (240). AnschauUch erlebbar
Gegenstandes, daB er sich als Identisches in Erscheinungsweisen zeigt.
sind nur die faktischen endlichen Verstandigungsprozesse, von denen die
Jene Deutung ist verfuhrerisch, weil sie sich offenbar auf identische
Rede war. Trotzdem besitzt die Weltidee der unendlichen Synthesis eine
Gegenstande, die gleichermaBen in verschiedenen Heimwelten auftreten
Faszination, die Husserl so in ihren Bann schlagt, daB er die Endlichkeit
konnen, leicht anwenden laBt: Dieser weiBe Klumpen beispielsweise
der Verstandigungsprozesse gegenuber der Unendlichkeitsidee beden-
erscheint dem Europaer als Kase und eBbar, dem Chinesen hingegen als
kUch vernachlassigt.
verfaulte Milch und ungenieBbar. Aber die Welt ist kein Gegenstand,
sondern Horizont fiir die Erfahrung von Gegenstanden. Der Grund fiir diese Faszination liegt darin, daB die Vergegen-
FreiUch kann die Welt vergegenstandUcht werden. Geschieht dies, so standlichung der unendUchen Welt als Idee fiir Husserl die Grundlage der
erscheint sie als der niemals anschaulich gegebene Pol, auf den wir uns modernen Naturwissenschaft bildet, und diese verdankt ihren uberwalti-
beziehen, indem wir jede erdenkliche Heimwelt, ob bekannt oder genden Erfolg dem Umstand, daB sie eben jene VergegenstandUchung ins
unbekannt, als Abschattung der einzigen unendlichen Welt deuten. Als Extrem treibt. Wenn wir die eine und einzige Welt denken, die in den
das im Unendlichen liegende Telos dieser unendlichen „Synthesis" aller unendlich vielen Heimwelten erscheint, dann geht das nicht ohne eine
erdenklichen Heimwelten ist die Welt eine bloBe Idee (181 ff., 207, 227, korrespondierende Idee: die Idee dessen, was sich in den Territorien all
236). Deshalb kann uns die teleologische Vorzeichnung einer unendlichen dieser Heimwelten abschattet; denn zu jeder Heimwelt gehort ein Territo-
„Synthesis aller Menschheiten" (140) zu einer „AUmenschheit" (140, 668) rium. Die gesuchte Idee kann nur die Natur als res extensa in unendUcher

52 53
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE E I N E WELT

RaumzeitUchkeit sein; denn, wie im I. Teil erlautert, ist sie es, die in den ist, als eine unmittelbare Konsequenz aus der griechischen Urstiftung
territorialen Einschrankungen erscheint, indem sie uns als konkrete aufgefaBt werden dtirfte. Die Entwicklung in der Neuzeit wurde vielmehr
lebensweltliche Natur begegnet. Da jene Natur als Idee nichts anderes ist faktisch erst dadurch moglich, daB Europa die moderne Technik, also eine
als der Gegenstand der modernen Naturwissenschaft, kann man sagen: ganz ungriechische Errungenschaft, mit ihren sozialen Begleiterscheinun-
Diese Naturwissenschaft beschreibt den idealen Identitatspol aller erden- gen in alle Welt exportierte. Diese Technik ihreseits konnte - um nun
kUchen heimweltlichen Territorien - womit u.a. gesagt ist: auch derjenigen wieder Husserl zu folgen - gerade dadurch entstehen, daB die neuzeitliche
Territorien, die moglicherweise auBerhalb unseres Planeten liegen (163, Naturwissenschaft die eine Welt als Feld fiir einen unendUchen
219, 226,239, 440, 668). ForschungsprozeB idealisierte. Der uberwaltigende Erfolg der so ent-
Aber an eben dieser Stelle verftihrt die Naturwissenschaft dazu, die standenen Forschung aber wurde mit einer Einstellung zur Welt erkauft,
Endlichkeit nicht ernst zu nehmen. Die seriosen Naturwissenschaftler die Husserl Objektivismus nennt. Der Objektivismus treibt die Vergegen-
hfiten sich, dieser Verfuhrung nachzugeben. Doch die Science-fiction- standlichung der Welt ins Extrem, indem er von ihrem Horizontcharakter
Medien plaudern es aus. Sie schwelgen in der VorsteUung, daB es auBer- radikal absieht. Diese NeutraUsierung des Horizontcharakters der einen
terrestrische Heimwelten auf unbekannten Territorien im Universum Welt in der modernen Wissenschaft beruht aber auf einer Vergessenheit
geben konnte und daB die Menschheit die Moglichkeit hatte, auf solche derjenigen Einstellung zur einen Welt, durch die sie bei den Griechen
Territorien auszuwandern. Das Spiel mit solchen Auswanderuhgsphan- ursprunglich tiberhaupt erst zum Thema werden konnte, und damit auch
tasien ist der unernste Widerschein der ernst zu nehmenden Leichtfer- der Endlichkeit als griechischer Grundbestimmung der Welt. Wenn
tigkeit, mit der die wissenschaftsglaubige Moderne die Erde, das endliche Husserl die objektivistische IdeaUsierung der einen Welt, ihre Auffassung
Territorium der vergemeinschafteten Menschheit, behandelt hat. Was als unendUche Polidee, bereits in der griechischen Urstiftung beginnen
man in dem BewuBtsein bewohnt, man sei wegen der UnendUchkeit der laBt, dann steht er selbst noch im Bann des Objektivismus.4
Natur nicht definitiv daran gebunden, braucht man nicht mit auBerster Das planetarische Zusammenwachsen der Menschheit im technischen
h Sorge und Sorgfalt zu pflegen. Zeitalter ist mit der Hypothek belaster, daB es faktisch erst durch die
Gegen die Verfuhrung, die im Unendlichkeitscharakter der Welt als Herrschaft einer EinsteUung zustande kommen konnte, worin die fiir die
Idee liegt, gilt es, sich entschiedener als Husserl auf die Endlichkeit der griechische Urstiftung konstitutive EndUchkeit der Welt in Vergessenheit
Heimwelt zu besinnen. Mit dieser Besinnung springen wir keineswegs aus geraten war. Wegen dieser Vergessenheit droht bei der heutigen Verge-
der durch die griechische Urstiftung begrundeten Tradition heraus. Im meinschaftung der Menschheit die Endlichkeit als traditionsbestimmte
Gegenteil: Husserl unterschiebt der griechischen Urstiftung bereits einen Eigenart der Heimwelten in einer weltweiten Uniformitat technikbes-
Gedanken der neuzeitlichen Wissenschaft, wenn er untersteUt, die timmter Lebensorganisation unterzugehen. 5 Dieser Gefahr kann eine
ursprungUche Thematisierung der Welt im griechischen Denken habe den philosophische Besinnung entgegenwirken, die daran erinnert, daB
Charakter einer Idealisierung gehabt, also einer VergegenstandUchung der die grundlegende ideeUe Vorbedingung jener Vergemeinschaftung, die
Welt als einer im Unendlichen liegenden Polidee. Im Rahmen der griechische Urstiftung, gerade auf einer Einstellung beruhte, in der die
griechischen Urstiftung wird die Welt, der kosmos, ftir ein vom Staunen Welt als endlich erschien. Die Phanomenologie bedeutet keine restaura-
getragenes Anschauen Thema, und als „Gegenstand" solcher Anschauung tive Ruckkehr zu dieser EinsteUung, wohl aber ihre Erneuerung unter den
kann die Welt nur endlich sein. Diese Korrektur steUt Husserls Interpreta- Bedingungen der Moderne. Den Ansatz daffir bietet der Husserlsche
tion des Anfangs von Philosophie und Wissenschaft nicht grundsatzlich in Gedanke, daB die Idee einer unendlich sich abschattenden einen Welt, das
Frage: Indem das frtihe Denken sich in einer menschheitsgeschichtUch Telos des modernen Forschungsprozesses, von sich her eine komplemen-
neuartigen Weise fur die eine Welt offnet, stiftet es damit im Prinzip die tare Einsicht fordert. Diese Einsicht besagt, daB die „Abschattungen", die
MogUchkeit, alle „Sonderwelten" und darunter auch alle bekannten oder Erscheinungsweisen der einen Welt als Welt, nur endliche Sonderwelten
unbekannten Heimwelten durch den Ruckbezug auf die eine Welt, von sein konnen. Deshalb muB die eine Welt der vergemeinschafteten Men-
der alle Sonderwelten nur Erscheinungsweisen sind, zu „synthetisieren". schheit konkret jeweils als eine kultureUe Heimwelt neben anderen
Damit ist - auch ohne die Bestimmung dieser einen Welt als unendlicher erscheinen.
Idee - in der Tat eine Vergemeinschaftung aller bisher isolierten Men- Wie im I. Teil gezeigt, liegt es an der praktischen Abblendung des
schheitskulturen vorgezeichnet. AuBenhorizonts, daB eine Heimwelt endlich ist. Der AuBenhorizont ist
Diese Vorzeichnung bedeutet nun freilich nicht, daB das planetarische die offene Dimension fiir mogliche fremde Territorien. Mit der praktis-
Zusammenwachsen der Menschheit, zu dem es in der Neuzeit gekommen chen Abblendung dieses Horizonts verzichtet das geschlossene

54 55
'•' H E I M W E L T , F R E M D W E L T , DIE EINE WELT
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

heimweltUche BewuBtsein von vornherein darauf, jene Territorien in den andere Territorien auf irgendeine Weise kultureU zu „besetzen". Das ware
Gesichtskreis seiner praktischen Interessen einzubeziehen. Es handelt sich die eigentUche Grundlage des Friedens, nach dem sich die Menschen
hier um einen Verzicht, der aUen bewuBten Verzichtleistungen voraufliegt, heute so sehnen wie eh und je.
ein seiner selbst nicht bewuBtes Absehen-von, das nicht weiB, wovon es Der geforderte neue praktische Verzicht hat aber noch einen weiteren
konkret absieht, und sich nur dessen sicher ist, daB es sich auf das genera- Aspekt. Das Territorium der zusammenwachsenden Menschheit ist die
tiv gewachsene Eigene beschranken will und nicht bereit ist, sich auf das, Erde. Im - zwar nicht mehr ungebrochenen, aber doch weiterbestehenden
was jenseits seiner liegen konnte, das fur alle lebensweltUchen Interessen - Vertrauen auf die ErschlieBungskraft der modernen Naturwissenschaft
unbestimmt Irrelevante, einzulassen. richtet die planetarische Menschheit ihren BUck fiber die Grenzen des Ter-
Inzwischen treten auch die letzten Residuen geschlossener Heimwelt ritoriums Erde hinaus. In dieser Beziehung ist eine Variante der genannten
auf dieser Erde in Bekanntschaft mit den auBerhalb ihrer gelegenen Terri- Selbstbeschrankung mogUch: Sie besteht d^rin, mit Entschlossenheit zu
torien und ihren kulturellen Besetzungen. Der Verzicht, durch den sich akzeptieren, daB es gilt, sich ohne auBerterrestrischen Auswanderungsvor-
die ursprunglich geschlossenen Heimwelten als endUch konstituiert hatten, behalt auf dem Territorium Erde einzurichten und das territoriale Interesse
ist damit unwiederbringlich auBer Kraft gesetzt, die Introvertiertheit der der Gesamtmenschheit auf den pfleglichen Umgang mit der konkreten
heimweltlichen Innenhorizonte ist definitiv aufgehoben. Das andert nichts Natur dieses Territoriums zu konzentrieren. Es ist anzumerken, daB dieser
daran, daB ftir die Endlichkeit der Heimwelt ein lebenspraktisches Verzicht eine praktische Selbstbeschrankung ist. Er impliziert also nicht
Absehen-von und in diesem Sinne eine Selbstbeschrankung konstitutiv ist. den Verzicht auf die theoretische Erforschung des „Weltalls" mit den
Eine solche Selbstbeschrankung kann heute im Unterschied zur friiheren, Mitteln der Astrophysik; ein solcher Verzicht kame einer Aufhebung der
naiven Abblendung des kulturellen AuBenhorizonts nur ein bewuBter Urstiftung-von-Wissenschaft selbst gleich.
Verzicht sein, ein Verzicht, der nach der Aufhebung der ursprungUchen In den Texten seiner Spatzeit hat Husserl mehrfach betont vom Primat
heimweltUchen Introvertiertheit weiB, worauf er verzichtet. Der naive • der Erde gesprochen (vgl. etwa 667f.). In einem Manuskript vom Mai
Verzicht war eine Ausblendung der „drau6en" antreffbaren Territorien 1934 beschreibt er die Erde mit dem biblischen Bild der Arche. 6 Der
aus dem eigenen praktischen Interessenhorizont. Das praktische Interesse Aufenthalt in der Arche gibt uns Menschen den festen Halt, den wir als
in bezug auf ein Territorium als Territorium kann nur darin liegen, es das Ruhen des Erdbodens erleben, der uns lebens-weltlich tragt. Die bib-
durch Kultivierung mit der heimweltlichen NormaUtat zu besetzen. Usche Arche ist ein Hausboot. Als Haus, als oikos kann es Sinnbild fiir das
DemgemaB kann ein neuer, in der Bekanntschaft mit'fremdweltlichen lebensweltliche Heim sein. Aber das Haus ist zugleich Boot. Es schwimmt
Territorien bewuBt vollzogener Verzicht nur darin bestehen, jedes Inter- in der unendUchen Raumzeitlichkeit des Universums. Die unabsehbare
esse an der eigenkulturellen Besetzung fremden Territoriums fallenzu- Flut, welche die biblische Arche umgibt, ist das Unheimische, aber auch
lassen. Unheimliche, vor dem man sich htiten muB. Die unbestimmte Angst vor
Ein fremdes Territorium laBt sich auf gewaltsame oder sanfte Weise diesem Unheimlichen ist eine Weise archaisch introvertierter Abblendung
mit dem eigenen System apperzeptiver Normalitat besetzen: Man kann die des AuBenhorizonts. Mit dem Okular der modernen Naturwissenschaft
dort lebende Bevolkerung vernichten oder ihr mit physischer Gewalt die spaht der moderne Mensch vielmehr wie Noah in die unheimische
Gewohnheiten aus ihrer Generativitat austreiben .und sie so der eigenen UnendUchkeit hinaus und versucht so, ihr Lebenspendendes abzugewin-
Kultur unterwerfen. Man kann die fremde Kultur aber auch geistig so nen oder sich gegen ihr Bedrohliches zu wappnen. Noah allerdings hielt
lange unterwandern, bis sie ihr Eigenes zugunsten der dominierenden Ausschau nach Inseln in der Flut, um die Arche wieder verlassen zu
Kultur vergessen hat. Alle diese Varianten sind aus der Geschichte konnen. An dieser Stelle kann die Besinnung auf die endUche Lebenswelt
sattsam bekannt. Ein neuer praktischer Verzicht in bezug auf fremde Ter- dem biblischen Mythos nicht mehr folgen.
ritorien kann nur in dem habitualisierten EntschluB bestehen, keine der
genannten MogUchkeiten wahrzunehmen. Ein solcher Verzicht ist um der
Endlichkeit der Heimwelt wiUen gefordert; denn fiir sie ist die besagte Notes
praktische Abblendung konstitutiv. So hat die phanomenologische Besin- 1 Einfache Seitenzahlen im Text beziehen sich auf diesen Band der Hua.
nung auf die EndUchkeit der einen Welt eine politische Konsequenz. Sie 2 DaB es sich bei der ursprunglichen Erfahrung des Andern aber im Grunde doch
verlangt, daB alle Heimwelten niederer oder hoherer Stufe der zusam- um ein genetisches Problem handelt, habe ich zu begrUnden versucht: vgl. Held
1972.
menwachsenden Menschheit, seien dies einzelne Volker oder Volkergrup- 3 DaB Husserl sich die ursprungliche Konstitution des Andern so denkt, habe ich
pen wie „Europa" oder „die islamische Welt", dem Interesse abschworen, andernorts nachzuweisen versucht: vgl. Held 1972.

56 57
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

4 Diese Kritik an Husserls Griechendeutung und die im folgenden daraus gezo-


gene Konsequenz einer Besinnung auf die Endlichkeit der Welt habe ich
genauer begrUndet und ausgefiihrt: vgl. Held 1989 a.
5 Warum eine planetarisch durch die objektivistische Wissenschaft und ihre
Ableger uniformierte Welt nur eine pervertierte Gestalt von Heimwelt sein
konnte, habe ich eingehender dargestellt: Held 1989 b. Part 11
6 Es handelt sich um das Manuskript mit der Archiv-Signatur D 17, das zuerst in
Philosophical Essays. In memory of Edmund Husserl, hrsg. von M. Farber 1940,
veroffentiicht wurde (Reprint New York: Greenwood Press Publishers 1968).
E T H I C S A N D C O M M U N I T Y

Literaturverzeichnis
11 *
Held, Klaus: Das Problem der Intersubjektivitat und die Idee einer phanomenolo-
gischen Transzendentalphilosophie, in: U. Claesges und K. Held (Hrsg.): Per-
spektiven Transzendentalphanomenologischer Forschung. Ludwig Landgrebe
zum 70. Geburtstag (Phaenomenologica 49), Den Haag 1972,3-60.
: Husserl und die Griechen, in: Phanomenologische Forschungen 22,
Freiburg/Miinchen 1989 a, 137-176.
: Husserls These von der Europaisierung der Menschheit, in: Phanomenologie
im Widerstreit, hrsg. von Chr. Jamme und O. Poggeler, Frankfurt a. M. 1989 b,
13-39.

58

m
I

73

H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y
1
O F W I L L I N G

Ullrich Melle

Source: James G. Hart and Lester Embree (eds), Phenomenology of Values and Valuing,
Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997, pp. 169-192.

I. Historical introduction
A large part of Husserl's philosophical work bears on the investigation,
description and analysis of the Ufe of consciousness, of its various forms
and contexts. Hence, it is a non-experimental, reflective investigation of
consciousness. As Husserl says, consciousness is an autonomous field of
being, a field of investigation and work; he even speaks of it metaphoric-
ally as a land, and because of the immense complexity of the structures of
consciousness, he speaks of it as a jungle. One is in need of great effort
and thousands of points of reference in order to clearly distinguish the
phenomena in this jungle and to grasp them in their essential determina-
tions and their manifold and tangled connections. Husserl sees this with a
truly impressive acuity. He recorded the results of his investigative journey
into the innermost reaches of consciousness in thousands of manuscript
pages.
The emphasis of Husserl's analyses of consciousness without doubt is
on the forms and structures of intellective consciousness. On the other
hand his descriptive analyses of emotive and volitional consciousness are
much less comprehensive and developed. Between 1909 and 1914 he
worked on the phenomenology of emotive and volitional consciousness,
investigations, found in not-yet published and rather fragmentary manu-
scripts. These analyses of affective consciousness and volition are a part of
the comprehensive investigation of consciousness in those years during
which Husserl sought to systematically describe the whole of conscious-
ness in aU its act-forms, founding relations, modes of accomplishment, etc.
Even in its fragmentary state, the scope of this investigation of conscious-
ness is extremely impressive. It coyers more than 1,000 manuscript pages.
As Husserl's assistant in 1926-27, Ludwig Landgrebe produced, on the
basis of these collected materials, a very extensive typed manuscript with
I

61

P
Ii»
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

the appropriate title "Studies on the Structure of Consciousness."2 The gardens,* houses, tables, clothing, tools, and so forth. AU these are various
second of its three studies, which, carries the title "Value Constitution, types of objects of value, objects of use, practical objects. They are not
Affective Consciousness (Gemiit), WiU," is devoted to the structures of natural scientific objects."5 In everyday life we only rarely attend to
emotive and volitional consciousness. As Langrebe admits in his Preface objects in a purely observational, purely theoretical way. Our quotidian
to Experience and Judgment? he drew upon the above mentioned manu- worldly behavior has, in the first place, an emotive-practical orientation.
scripts in the preparation of Experience and Judgment. But for Husserl, even our valuing and willing admit of the question of
Husserl's often minute analyses in his investigation serve the philosoph- reason, the question of truth and validity.
ical project of working out a phenomenological theory of reason and of In connection to his Logical Investigations, which appeared in 1900-01,
rational vaUdity, as well as its correlative doctrine of categories and a Husserl first worked on the groundwork of a phenomenological theory of
theory of true being. A phenomenological theory of reason is constructed theoretical-logical, which means, cognizing and judging-speaking reason.
in two-steps. The dicta of reason in the pertinent spheres of acts do not In his axiological-ethical lectures of 1908-9, 1911 and 1914,6 he then turns
happen arbitrarily, rather are carried out according to principles. The cor- to the theory of axiological and practical reason. In these lectures what he
responding doctrines of principles make up the superstructure of the is trying to show is that there are formal-axiological and formal-practical
theory of reason. These doctrines of principles are then to be rationaUy principles analogous to the formal-logical principles, such that alongside
and critically grounded through a phenomenological description of the the formal logical discipUnes stand the parallel disciplines of formal axiol-
forms and networks of acts that fall, along with the noematic correlates, ogy and practice. The lectures on ethics do not contain any systematically
within the jurisdiction of these principles and, above all, through a descrip- carried out phenomenological description of emotive-valuing and voli-
tion of the teleological relations of fulfillment that exist in these networks tional-acting consciousness. As Husserl said in his lecture of 1911, here
of acts. one winds up in a "true jungle of difficulties," a jungle with "lurking behe-
The number of the forms of reason depends upon the classification of moths." 7 However, the lecture course of 1914 contains a short section on
the forms of acts. However many basic forms of acts there are, so will the phenomenology of willing.8
there be as many basic forms of reason; for, according to Husserl, a spe- The descriptive analyses of emotive and volitional consciousness during
cific form of justification and rational validity belongs to every basic act-1 the time of the lectures on ethics have an exploratory and extremely frag-
form. Husserl abides by the Kantian classification of types of acts into mentary character. The terminology is still not fixed. The following expli-
intellective acts, valuing acts, and acts of will. Accordingly there are for cation restricts itself to the main themes of Husserl's analysis of
Husserl three types of reason: logico-cognitive, axiological and practical wiUing-acting consciousness.9
reason.
The insight into the phenomenological apriori of correlation is bound
up with the accomplishment of the phenomenological reduction. Accord- II. Historical background to the nachlass texts on the
ing to this apriori of correlation, rational vaUdity and objective being are phenomenology of willing
inseparable correlates, so that one can say that there are just as many basic Extensive analyses of volitional consciousness were performed in January
types of rational consciousness as there are basic types of objects. of 1910. There are about twenty manuscripts of various lengths. Husserl
Axiological and practical characteristics and objects like value, goods, put these texts together with a smaller number of analyses of emotive con-
behavior and goals are the objective correlates of the acts of feeling and sciousness into a collection with the title "Phenomenology of Feeling,
wiUing. As Husserl often puts it, one can see in valuing-feeling acts and Desiring, WUling."10 One cannot tell whether this collection was to form
willing-behaving acts that new predicative levels are constituted in the the basis of a publication. A few suggestive presentations of a phenom-
mere natural object, levels which are those of cultural determination. In enology of willing can be found in an extensive manuscript with the title
his lecture course of 1919-1920, entitled "Introduction to Philosophy," "Valuing and Value," a manuscript generated during this same period and
: Husserl says "Everything we in one way or another include under the title devoted above aU to the analysis of feeling-valuing consciousness.11
'culture' is related to a sphere of creation that is understandable only as In 1911 the short essay on the psychology of willing, "Motive and
the correlate of the valuing and practically formative consciousness."4 Our Motivation" by Alexander Pfander, appeared. Pfander was the leading
quotidian life-world is a cultural world and not a world of mere natural representative of the so-caUed Munich Phenomenology.12 Husserl accorded
objects. So, in Ideas II Husserl says "In ordinary life we never deal with great significance to this work. He not only prepared a very thorough
natural objects. What we call 'things' are actuaUy paintings, statues, excerpt of it, but was also inspired by it to carry out a series of analyses of

62 63
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

voUtional consciousness. Later Ludwig Langrebe compfled the resultant are founded in .objectifying acts.17 For Husserl, these objectifying acts are
manuscripts as the so-caUed Pfander-coUection.13 One of the texts in this representations and judgments; non-objectifying acts are emotive and voli-
collection has the character of a beginning of an introduction, which would tional acts as weU as intellectual acts like questioning.18 Accordingly, for
suggest that Husserl composed these manuscripts with the view to publish- Husserl non-objectifying acts are secondary intentions. As valuing, willing,
ing them. In this introductory text Husserl writes of Pfander's work that and suggesting, these acts relate to objects and states of affairs that are
through deep and careful analyses, it leaves all that the previous literature given to them through the founding acts of representing and judging. In
offered in terms of a description of the sphere of wflling in its wake. Yet it his later investigations of consciousness, Husserl does not rest content with
does not completely overcome the extraordinary difficulties of the material the determinations of the Logical Investigations. Rather the later analyses
and constitutes the beginning of a fundamental investigation of the sphere are developed and carried out as a substantive critical discussion with the
of willing rather than its end.14 basic descriptive determinations of the Logical Investigations. The distinc-
A further series of manuscripts were produced at the beginning of 1914, tion between objectifying and non-objectifying acts remains, for Husserl, a
manuscripts which, like the texts in the Pfander-CoUection, are occupied basic problem of the description of consciousness.
with the problem of the relation of willing and inclination and which, once In his descriptive investigations of emotive and volitional consciousness,
more, were put together into a collection and given the title of "Tend- Husserl is guided by the idea of an analogy between the structures of the
ency" (Tendenz) by Landgrebe. 15 An edition of these manuscripts on the basic types of consciousness. In his lectures on ethics Husserl speaks of a
phenomenology of wiUing would yield a volume of the Husserliana with "method of analogy."19 Taking as the point of departure the already inves-
about 170 printed pages. Shorter presentations of the phenomenology of tigated structures of the inteUect, the parallel and analogical structures of
willing can also be found in many other manuscripts that are related to the affective and volitional consciousness are to be discovered and described.
general analysis of intellectual and emotive consciousness. The presenta- However, the parallel and analogy between the basic types of conscious-
tion I offer here of Husserl's analysis of voUtional consciousness will draw ness is tied to manifold interlacing of types of consciousness, and it is this
principally on the three collections mentioned and the section of the interlacing that poses great difficulties for description. This is particularly
phenomenology of wilUng from the 1914 lecture course on ethics. But first true of voUtional consciousness, not only because it is in many ways
a few more remarks about other philosophers with whom Husserl was in founded in other acts, but also because the exact demarcation of the
conversation. sphere of wiUing already proves to be a difficult problem.
Husserl's investigation of consciousness develops through an engage- From all of this it should be clear already that Husserl had no doubt
ment with Brentano's descriptive psychology. In his psychology Brentano that willing could not be reduced to inteUectual and emotive phenomena
distinguishes three basic classes of psychic phenomena. Representations of consciousness. At the very least, Husserl was quite famiUar with two
belong to the first class, judgments to the second, and feelings and acts of reductive psychologies of willing: that of William James in the Principles
willing belong to the third. Brentano does not deny the differences that of Psychology,20 and that of Christian von Ehrenfels. Husserl took from
obtain between feeling and wflling, but between the phenomena of feeling James the concept of fiat, a concept that plays an important role in
and wiUing there are, according to him, continuous transitions, and these Husserl's own analyses. James' analyses have a clearly reductive tendency:
phenomena possess a common basic characteristic: They relate to their The will is reduced to prevailing representations and attention. "The
objects either lovingly or hatefuUy. According to Brentano, important impelling idea is simply the one which possesses the attention." 21 "Will is
analogies obtain between the second basic class of judgments and the third the relation between the mind and its ideas."22 "The wflUng terminates
basic class of phenomena of affective consciousness and willing. A judg- with the prevalence of the idea." 23 "We thus find that we reach the heart of
ment is a recognition or rejection of the object of representation with our inquiry into violition when we ask by what process it is that the
regard to its being, the motive and voUtional acts being a loving or hating thought of any given object comes to prevail stably in the mind."24 Husserl
of the object of representation. In the acts of loving and hating, an analogi- underlined the following passage and alongside it in the margin placed a
cal characteristic of insight corresponds to the judgmental evidence.16 nota bene: "The essential achievement of the will, in short, when it is more
m 'voluntary,' is to attend to.a difficult object and hold it fast before the
In the Fifth of the Logical Investigations Husserl embarked upon a
penetrating critique and revision of Brentano's doctrine of representation mind, the so-doing is the fiat; and it is a mere physiological coincidence
as the foundation for all other acts of consciousness. Husserl's new that when the object is thus attended to, immediate motor consequences
formulation of Brentano's psychic fundamental law stands at the end of a should ensue." 25 And again on the following page he says: "Effort of atten-
complex argument. This new formulation goes: AU non-objectifying acts tion is thus the essential phenomenon of will."26 And two pages later

64 65

JU
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

James gives a new formulation: "This strain of the attention is the funda- 3 The objectivities of wiUing.
mental act of will."27 Yet James' volitional-psychological discussions are 4 The relation of will and inclination; in connection with this I will touch
not free of contradictions. Thus James also defines "fiat" as "consent," as upon the problem of the demarcation of the sphere of wiUing.
the following passage, which Husserl also underlined, shows: "There is
indeed the fiat, the element of consent, or resolve that the act shaU ensue. Obviously these themes are connected to each other; therefore they
This doubtless, to the reader's mind, as to my own, constitutes the essence cannot be treated as completely separate from each other.
of the voluntariness of the act."28 According to James, this "act of mental
consent," occurs when the antagonistic alternatives of behavior that are
represented mutually neutralize themselves. We will see that this defini- a. The founding of willing
tion of the fiat as the "act of mental consent" is the one to which Husserl In the ordinary sense, willing is directed toward something in the future
orients his own definition of the fiat. that is to be actualized through a creative act. Willing can only be directed
A second reductive volitional psychology that Husserl studied inten- towards something in the future that is, ontologicaUy speaking, real. It is
sively is that of Christian von Ehrenfels who, above all, is known as one of necessarily founded in the consciousness of what is practically possible, in
the original proponents of Gestalt Psychology. As innumerable underUn- the consciousness of the "I can." The realm of the ideal as well as the past
ings, citations, and annotation show, Husserl read closely von Ehrenfels' are closed off to wiUing.31 WiUing presupposes a consciousness of what is
1887 Habilitationschrift, which had the title "On Feeling and Willing."29 willed, and thus is founded in the representation of a future event, a
Von Ehrenfels denies the existence of a basic psychic phenomenon of representation that is bound up with the consciousness of the "I can."
desire, whereby desire is von his general concept for volitional phenom- Indeed willing excludes a beUef in the actuaUty of what is wiUed, but it
ena. For von Ehrenfels, desire is nothing but a special sort of process of implies the belief in its actual becoming. Whoever wants something to
representation. For von Ehrenfels, as for James, desire consists in the happen thereby also believes that it wiU happen, namely, that it will
strength and power with which representations impose themselves on con- happen through the creative, actualizing act.32
sciousness. According to von Ehrenfels, representations struggle for room What is willed must not only be represented, but it must also be given a
in consciousness. Thus, pleasant representations get a boost. Von Ehren- positive value. WilUng is always directed toward an intended value. Value
fels calls this the law of the relative increase of happiness and defines is the motive of wilUng. According to Husserl, values are given to us in
desire with the help of this law: emotive acts. Therefore, wilUng always implies the emotive act of valuing
of a future event that is represented as practically possible. Thus wilUng is
Desire is a representation which is accompanied by a relative itself the practical positing, the volitional positing of a creative "So be it!"
demand of happiness and thereby is an accentuated representa- Husserl devoted special attention to the relation between wishing and
tion of the causal connection of an object with or separation of an wilUng. The question is whether wishing is a necessary constituent of
object from the present subjective reality.30 wilUng. In the 1914 lectures on ethics Husserl thus writes: "Mere wishing
contains nothing of a wiUing; it contains nothing of the practical modalities
and is not itself a practical act, an act of the will in the broadest sense."33 As
is the case with wiUing, so wishing is also necessarUy founded in inteUectual
III. Husserl's analysis of willing
and emotive acts. But in contradistinction to willing, wishing does not
For Husserl, practical acts, acts of willing, are indeed necessarily founded include the consciousness of practical realizability. Thus it can even direct
in intellectual and emotive acts; they are in need of representing and itself towards something that is known to be completely unrealizable.
valuing acts as a basis; but these alone will never produce willing. For If what is wished for has the property of being practicaUy possible,
Husserl, practical intentionality indeed is a dependent, yet irreducible wishing can become a willing - it can, but it need not. According to
basic type of intentionality. Husserl, wishing must be distinguished from volitional urge, volitional
In what follows I would like to take up four main themes in Husserl's inclination. When what is wished for is represented as practically possible,
analysis of the wiU: often all that emerges is a tendency, a propensity toward willing. But this
may eventually be blocked by an opposing inclination, or the ethical con-
1 The founding of wilUng. science exhorts that I ought not follow this inclination. Husserl sees here
2 The types of wiUing. important analogies between willing and judging. In judgment too an

66 67
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING
inclination to judge, a tendency to reach a judgment, often precedes the The fiat is an empty intention of the 'will that immediately passes over
concluding of a judgment. into constant fulfillment by the acting wiU.39 But this willing is itself a con-
Now, it seems certain that I cannot wiU something that I do not wish for stant relation of fulfillment.40 In every phase of action we have a creative
or desire. (Wishing and desiring are, for Husserl, often synonymous moment that gives to its correlative phase of an action the character of a
I i expressions.)34 But according to Husserl this need not mean that an act of creatively realized present. Every such creative moment is always sur-
wishing is contained in every willing as a founding component. It would rounded by continual perspectival profiles, profiles of the past creative
be, as Husserl says in the 1914 lecture, "irrational to will something that is moment and of the volitional moments that are directed toward the mater-
not desirable, whether in itself or for the sake of something else. Thus an ial of the action that lies in the future.
implication of reason is present." 35 But that something is wished for need The deed is in each moment (in each phase of the deed) in a certain
not mean that it is presently wished. It can also mean that it is desirable*. manner directed to the corresponding phase of the action. In the creative
Yet, in his earlier manuscript of 1910 on "Valuing and Values," Husserl moment, in the practical positing, this moment is posited. But the wilUng
had still put it this way: "Thus the will is founded in wishing and through goes through this positing and, in so far as it penetrates it, it is directed to
wishing it is directed to something [held to be] good, and it is directed the subsequent positings and through these to the further ones until the
toward this in the manner of a making or doing."36 And in an addendum to end of the action.41
the 1914 lectures on ethics Husserl again seems to assume such a founding
Thus the practical positing that occurs at every moment also traverses
of willing in wishing and desiring: "The will does not belong to the series
the adumbrations of the future volitional moments and is directed, until
of desiring acts (joy, wish), acts of reaching for . . . But here ^something is
the activity ceases, toward the future phases of the action. Living in the
missing. The wfll is also a reaching for ..., but it introduces something new
consciousness of action, the prospect of the will traverses the phase of
that presumes a reaching f o r . . . but is not itself a reaching for . . . (desiring,
action, which has the character of the creatively actualized present, toward
wishing): the fiat, the practical "it ought to be!"37 Moreover, an interesting
the to-be-realized future of the process. Thus during an action we have an
question not posed by Husserl is that of the type of act to which the acts of
intention of the wiU that constantly maintains itself as an empty intention
wishing and desiring belong. If they are not acts of will, then in the rubrics
that simultaneously constantly acquires the fullness of satisfaction through
of classification they could only be feelings or emotions.
a constantly creative positing.42
Yet we now confront the question of that towards which the intention
b. The forms of volitional positing of the will and the positing of the will are directed. On the noetic side, the
fiat is immediately followed by the willing that carries along the action and
Husserl distinguishes three essentiaUy different types or forms of voli- by the perception of the action as an objective process. This process
tional positing: the resolution or resolve, the fiat, and will-activity or will- appears and constitutes itself in perception. But then, does not the willing
action (Handlungswille). We wfll first look at the last two forms in the case primarily produce the perception of the process, and is not the intention of
of simple action, of the simple "I will and I do." As with every action, we the will thus directed toward a future perception, or even toward the
have an original impulse of the will, the fiat which is supported during its future willing of the future perception?
entire course by a willing, a willing activity. So, we may ask, does the fiat In a manuscript from the coUection titled "Tendency," Husserl takes up
precede the action, and must it be distinguished from the beginning of the this problem with a dramatic example.
action? The fiat would then be founded in a mere representation of action.
"It just so happens that in real action, the fiat imparts practical agreement If I want to give someone a slap in the face, then the actualization
to this representation." 38 According to Husserl it is difficult to decide this of the will calls as an end-point for the perception of the accom-
question descriptively. He finally comes to the conclusion that willing as plished slap in the face. But the wfll is not directed toward a per-
fiat immediately and constantly passes over into wilUng as action, and that
ception as its goal (perception founds the fulfillment of the will
both are only able to be abstractly separated from one another. There is
with which the goal is reached, but is not itself the goal). The goal
no further inaugural moment lying between the fiat, on the one hand, and
is the slapping someone in the face.43
the unity of will-action and the perception of the process that proceeds
from it, on the other hand. Thus there is no presentation of action at the
Of course, instead of being directed to a process that is to be creatively
basis of the fiat, but only a presentation of a process, which does not yet
actualized, the will can be directed to a perception and cognition of some
have the character of an action.
objective thing.

68 69
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING
There is also a form of the positing of the wiU that can be directed to a c Objectivities of the will
future willing and acting. It is the third essential form of the positing of the
wfll along with the fiat and volitional activity: the plan or resolve or One of the most difficult problems in the phenomenological analysis of
making of a resolution (Vorsatz). Planning and making a resolution are constitution is the problem of non-natural, or, as Husserl says, extra-
not actually creative positings of the will; they are directed to a future essential determinations of objects, their various types, and how these are
event that is to be creatively actualized. With plans and resolutions it is a constituted in consciousness. These include doxic qualities, temporal
matter of completely unfulfilled intentions of the will that are fulfiUed in a modes, axiological determinations, emotional colorings, the sign and
future action.44 But in foUowing Husserl we must now "sharply distinguish image character of an object, and even wish and volitional characteristics.
the relation of the will to the future event and the 'Become!' which is According to Husserl all these are determinations of what is objectively
directed to the future event, from the relation of the will to future willing given and can be validly or invalidly predicated of it. Thus, e.g., an object
or future acting."45 A plan would thus be based only upon the representa- may be phenomenally-objectively characterized as a tool or a process as
tion of the future process toward which the practical positing of the "So be an action. Apparently they are immediately perceived as so characterized,
it!" would then be directed. But, as Husserl must admit, things here are just as the colors of an object are. Nevertheless these characteristics are
not so simple. The "So be it!" of the plan can only mediately bring about radically different from the natural qualities of the object. They originate
the future process, namely by means of the future fiat and volitional from different constitutive sources than such qualities. An object is origin-
action. Yet, according to Husserl, it nevertheless remains that the voli- ally constituted as having natural qualities in receptive, sensuous percep-
tional positing of the process is directed toward the desired process and tion. How are the non-natural determinations of an object constituted?
not toward the willing of the process. "It is only through reflection that we "What is that new noetic element that belongs to the consciousness of
learn that the creative aspect in willing which is directed toward a future appearing, to the consciousness of the perception? What is woven together
stretch of time necessarily goes beyond the proper theme of wilUng."46 As with it when a process becomes action?" 49
Husserl correctly remarks, here we find "very difficult relations that one
In his general analysis of intentional acts in the Fifth Logical Investiga-
must ever again think through." 47
tion, Husserl distinguishes between the matter and the quality of an act.
When it is a matter of an action that fulfills a plan or resolution, a recol- The matter is the part of the act that gives the act its objective reference,
lection of the plan preceeds the fiat. "The recollected will (as resolve) and indeed in its complete material definiteness. The matter not only
undergoes a 'fulfiUing' identification through a newly posited creative will establishes that the act grasps the object "but also as what it grasps it, the
that is posited as having the identical meaning." 48 properties, relations, categorial forms, that it itself attributes to it."50 The
According to Husserl, the relation between simple action and action as qualitative part of the act determines then in which manner the act relates
I the fulfilling of an intuitive plan has its analogy in inteUectual conscious- to what is objectivity given through the matter in the 'how' of its determi-
ness: simple intuitive judgment just says "It is!" But on the other hand, if nations. "QuaUty determines . . . whether what is already 'made pre-
the intuitive judgment steps forward as the confirmation of an originaUy sentable' in definite fashion is intentionally present as wished, asked,
empty intention, it says affirmatively "It really is thus." However, as posited in judgment etc."51
opposed to simple judgment, simple action is already the constant fulfill-
Later, instead of material and quality, Husserl most often speaks of
ment of volitional intentions that inhabit action itself. The analogue is here
apperception or apprehension on the one side, and positing, thesis, and
rather the self-developing perception in which the object constantly shows
taking a position on the other side. In the Sixth Logical Investigation he
itself from aU sides.
introduces a concept of representation in which material in the sense of
The distinction between simple action and action as the carrying out of apprehension is only a part. At the same time there belongs to representa-
a plan is an initial, important distinction in the typology of action. In his tion the apprehended content of sensation and the form of the apprehen-
manuscripts, Husserl took up still other distinctions, like that between sion which determines "whether the object is merely signitive or intuitive
simple and composite, mediate and immediate actions. A very important or represented in some sort of mixture. The differences between percep-
distinction is between the arbitrary and non-arbitrary. I will come upon tual representation and fantasy representation also belong here."52
this distinction later when I will speak about the relationship between wiU
The apprehensional sense, the form of apprehension, and position-
and tendency. According to Husserl, the distinctions among the various
taking are three different forms of intentionality and constitutive activity
types of actions are based upon the distinctions in volitional orientation
that have correlatively different sorts of object-determinations. So, accord-
and not just different gradations of attentiveness.
ing to Husserl's analyses in the Logical Investigations, the characterization

70
71
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

of an object as a sign or image is the objective correlate of a specific form of tions, but are not themselves objectivation. The character of action is ulti-
apprehension of a perceptual act; the qualification of a represented object as mately a determination .of reflexion. First we have the empirical appercep-
being probable is the objective correlate of a doxic position-taking. tion of the process, then the wiUing that produces the process, and finally a
Still another basic form of constitution must be mentioned, namely that new apperception directed to the wiU and the process, an apperception
of the creative production of a state of affairs in judging. As is well-known, that grasps the process as proceeding from the wfll. The alternative under-
in the Logical Investigations Husserl did not make a very convincing standing to which Husserl feels drawn, even when, as he says, it goes very
attempt to subsume the categorial acts under the schema of content and much against the grain, is as follows:
apprehension. But it already becomes clear there that involve categorial
acts an essentiaUy different form of intentionaUty and constitution than The consciousness of a creative effecting is built upon a sensible,
perception. In an explicitly accompUshed predicative judgment a new empirical apperception through which the process is constituted, a
object is produced in the form of a ramified state of affairs. Judging is a consciousness that voluntarily animates the process. And this con-
creative constituting which, however, is, in the last instance, referred to the sciousness is a consciousness of action, of deeds. I have no need of
receptive constitution of perception. a further objectivization. Here is the element in which intending
Husserl found no definitive answer to the question of the constitution of lives, and it suffices in order to say then, in a logical apperception,
axiological or volitional determinations. Do these determinations stand on 'This is an action.'55
the same level with sensible-perceptual qualities, or are they new, non-
doxic thetic characters; or are they related to the creative production of It is not clear here whether Husserl is speaking from the point of view
thinking? On the one hand, Husserl sought to grasp what concerns the of the person acting or of the person externally observing the action. In his
constitution of axiological determinations by means of analogies to sensi- analyses, Husserl, by the way, does not go into this difference any further.
ble qualities. Correspondingly, there is supposed to be an evaluating per- For Husserl, action is originally constituted in acting. That means it is con-
ception (Wertnehmung), a value-taking, which is analogous to the stituted in the fiat, in the action-wilUng, and in the perception of the
t 'E perception (Wahrnehmung) upon which it is founded. On the other side, action-process. According to the new understanding, when I will and act,
he also understands emotive valuing as a new form of position-taking over the process is immediately given to me as an action without any reflection
against the doxic position-taking, a new form of position-taking whereby on the willing. For the external observer, this means that in order to see a
the axiological determinations would be thetic characters.53 process as action, he does not need to feel his way into some aUen willing
The constitutive analysis of volitonal-practical determinations and or to perform a reflection in empathy. Nevertheless, there remains the
objectivities is particularly difficult. In the first place, there are obviously question of how the observer comes to the consciousness of a creative
different sorts of practical objects: tools, goods, means and ends, actions. effecting and how he is aware of what kind of consciousness this is: Is it an
•fM
For the most part, in his manuscripts, Husserl limits himself to the analysis apperception, or an apprehensional form of the founding perceptual
of the constitution of action. Can one put the character of action on the apprehension, or is it a position-taking, a positing?
same level with axiological determinations? Husserl asks, "But is it not
clear that the character of action is of a completely different sort in the
way it depends 'on' the object than the character of beauty, pleasantness, IV. Will and tendency
etc.?"54 It seems to be quite impossible to understand willing in analogy At the middle of the analysis of the wiU found in the "Tendency"-
with perception and valuing as the apperception of specific volitional sen- Collection and the Pfander-Collection is the question of the relation of
sations whereby a process would then be given and characterized as an wiU and incUnation. In the two manuscript pages that perhaps represent a
action. Therefore, Husserl always understands willing as a specific sort of beginning of an introduction to the Pfander-CoUection, Husserl observes
'•*: positing and position-taking. Willing takes a position vis-d-vis a represen- that the difference between spontaneity and receptivity permeating, in a
ted process; it posits a process as an imperative and a creatively evolving parallel manner, all types of acts is the difference that "ever anew gives
process. But is the character of action thereby constituted? rise to confusions and especiaUy makes more difficult our penetrating into
In the manuscript on "Valuing and Value" Husserl contrasts his older the essence of the specificaUy rational will."56 As Husserl writes later on, in
understanding in the Logical Investigations with a new understanding. In every type of act there are "possible different mixtures of spontaneity, and
the Logical Investigations the acts of will belong to the non-objectivating everywhere spontaneity can pass over into receptivity, and vice versa."57
acts, to secondary intentions. As such, they convey materials for objectiva- Receptivity then leads still further back into "the hinterlands

72 73
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

(Hintergrunde) where we really can no longer speak of either spontaneity The will must affirm itself over against the drives, tendencies, and
or receptivity."58 Along with the opposition between receptivity and spon- stimuU. So Husserl says that the will itself can be carried out in various
taneity, Husserl also speaks of an opposition between sensibility and degrees of strength and depth. A weak will does not maintain itself against
understanding, between passivity and activity, between latent and patent drives: It is subjected to them; they drag it along and it lets itself be
consciousness, between unthematic and thematic consciousness. These dragged along. Husserl called the passive following of a drive a passive
oppositions, which are by no means identical, serve Husserl as the funda- willing. Husserl makes the terminological distinction between mere deed
mental principles for his analysis of consciousness. Discovered, developed, as following from drives and activity as the carrying out of an intention.
and contentually concretized, Husserl first used these oppositional "Drives are directed, but they have no intentions." 62
schemata in the description of intellectual consciousness. According to the The question is whether the understanding of drives as a passive willing
method of analogy, he then used these schemata as the guiding thread in makes sense. Elsewhere Husserl even speaks of drives as blind desire. But
the analysis of axiological and voUtional consciousness. Until now we have as we learned above, desire is not a wiUing, but it rather at most is tied up
only occupied ourselves with the wholly conscious, the spontaneous, active with a willing.
and patent will and its forms. But are there also forms of the unconscious According to Husserl, there are still other forms of inattention that lie
or preconscious, passive wiU? between the so-called complete voUtional passivity of drives and the active
Husserl opposes drive and activity of a drive as the passivity of the will will. When I am occupied with a theoretical task, I can, in the background
to genuine and free willing. of my consciousness address my fiat or non-fiat to an impulse, as for
When it is a question of the activity of "drive," one can speak of a mere example, the impulse to smoke a cigarette. In contradistinction to the
drive, and of a being driven toward an end if the end is represented along drive, the will is here already present, albeit latently, in the background.
with it . . . In voluntary activity, in action, the very same doing is made The transition from a latent act of the will into a patient act of the wiU is
present in the resolve; but it functions as "resolution"; an "I will" proceed- therefore also of a completely different sort than the introduction of voli-
ing from the I achieves an active thesis .. .59 tional impulses into an instinctually occurring event.
The instinctive deed occurs unintentionally; the I does not accompany As the description of consciousness now shows, the mode of tendency,
it. Husserl often mentions breathing as an example of such an instinctive of tendential striving,63 belongs to consciousness in all its basic types such
deed. Breathing is a non-voluntary, yet subjective happening. "It is not a that according to Husserl we must distinghish a double concept of inten-
mere process, rather in playing itself out it is a relaxation of tendencies tionality: There is intentionality in the sense of consciousness-of and there
and a new exertion, a bUnd drive that works itself out and does so without is intentionality in the sense of striving, of tendency.64 This double concept
involving my wiU."60 An act of the I can then direct itself towards breath- of intentionality corresponds to a double concept of fulfillment: fulfillment
ing in a twofold manner: The I can attentively take note of breathing, or through the satisfaction of a striving, and fulfillment by passing over to
the I can arbitrarily and consciously breathe; it can also intentionally inter- evident givenness. Tendency is not only a phenomenon of the non-
vene in breathing: It can slow or accelerate breathing. egological, passive life of consciousness. In every accomplished act qua
The difference between passively-foflowing-a-drive without really accomplishment, an inclination is set in motion, an inclination lives itself
willing and willful resolution is of great significance for the question of out and is fulfilled in a further accomplishment. As Husserl notes in a
voUtional reason. Thus, the genuine will is a purporting or "meaning to do manuscript from the Pfander-CoUection, "The central question is now the
. . . " that can be demonstrated as rational, as correct. question of the relationship of the will and tendency." 65 Is every tendency
As a purporting or 'meaning to do ...,' willing indeed is directed toward a volitional mode? "If so, then willing would Ue in every act. Willing would
the deed, and it implies that it is esteemed as good and that it exists. As a have no content peculiar to it, it would be a general mode of conscious-
willing it itself aims at a being in the mode of realization. But it has its ness."66 This would obviously have far-reaching consequences for
motives. The motivating evaluing can be incorrect. And the fundamental Husserl's concept of consciousness, his classification of types of acts and
judgment of the circumstances itself can be incorrect. In that case the will his analysis of founding relations.
taken purely in itself would not be called into question but rather the total Yet here one must, as did Husserl, distinguish drive as bUnd impulse
phenomenon, the wilUng with its founding stratum. But the willing, in that from the tendency towards accomplishment found in an act. The tendency
it directs itself, itself thereby assumes something. The directing-itself con- that lives in an attentive orientation and is strivingly directed toward a
cerns the willing in its "interior." WiUing fulfills itself in the action, but it deepening of the orientation is still not a desire toward the deepened ori-
corrects itself through the evaluation of its motives.61 entation. Likewise, the tendency that, in the achievement of a judgment, is

74 75
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

strivingly directed toward completing this achievement, is not an impulse Instead of being rendered in the geographic or geological images of a
toward the completion of this achievement. But is this not tendency also terrain or as strata lying on top of one another, consciousness would be
an unconscious striving? And is not the relation of willing to tendency the better viewed through the biological image of life. In the fragmentary
same as that to drive? Elsewhere Husserl himself often uses the expres- analyses of the manuscripts here in question, one does not find such a vol-
sions "drive" and "tendency" as synonyms. Indeed, the will can dispatch untaristic concept of consciousness formulated and worked out. Instead
its volitional impulses into events stemming from drives as well as tend- Husserl tries, in accordance with the above citation from Ideas I, to
encies and thereby transform these events into willful actions, or it can prevent the infiltration and occupation of intellectual and emotive con-
address its wiUful negation in order to inhibit the course of the corre- sciousness by wilUng. But it is perhaps in these analyses that one finds the
sponding activities and accomplishments. first seeds of Husserl's later ethical-metaphysical voluntarism.
Now, even if tendency is an unconscious striving, the achievements in
which tendency works itself out need not be an unconscious striving. The
explicit orientation and/or articulate achievement of a judgment are free, Notes
spontaneous and active deeds of the I. How does this spontaneity fit in 1 This text was originally given in English in 1990 as part of the program for the
with an unconscious striving, and how does this spontaneity fit in with "Touring Scholar in Continental Thought" sponsored by the Center for
genuine willing? Is all reason, as is said in Experience and Judgment, also Advanced Research in Phenomenology. For this I would like to thank Profes-
practical reason? In §48 of Experience and Judgment Husserl draws a par- sor William McKenna who organized the tour.
2 Landgrebe's typescript is to be found in the Husserl-Archives in Leuven under
allel betwen cognitive activity and practical action. He thereby establishes the signature M III 31—III.
that cognitive striving has, "structurally, a precise analogy with an action 3 See Edmund Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil, Untersuchungen zuer Genealogie der
that is externally realized."67 Even in Ideas I, §121, Husserl finds it neces- Logik, edited and published by Ludwig Landgrebe (Hamburg: Claassen Verlag,
sary to recognize that every thesis has the character of a free spontaneity 1964); Experience and Judgment, ed. Ludwig Landgrebe, trans., by James
and activity, and that its point of initiation is thus something like the fiat, Churchill and Karl Ameriks (Evanston: Northwestern, University Press, 1973).
the point of initiation of willing and activity. But then again Husserl says: 4 Ms F 140,113a. Here I would like to express my thanks to the Director of the
Husserl Archives in Louvain, Professor Samuel IJsseling for permission to
One must not mix up the universal and the specific. Spontaneous resolv- quote from the unpublished manuscripts.
ing, the voluntary deed that is carried out is just one act among other acts; 5 Edmund Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenologis-
its syntheses are specific as compared to others. But every act, whatever chen Philosophie, Zweites Buch, ed. Marly Biemel, Hua IV (Tlie Hague: Marti-
sort it may be, can arise in the mode of spontaneity of the so-called cre- nus Nijhoff, 1952), p. 27.
ative beginning in which the pure I has its commencement as a subject of 6 See Edmund Husserl, Vorlesungen iiber Ethik und Wertlehre (1908-1914), ed.
spontaneity.68 Husserl tries to stick to his classification of acts of conscious- Ullrich Melle, Hua XXVIII (Dordrecht, 1988).
7 Hua XXVIII, p. 205.
ness, but it in fact becomes evident, as Husserl writes in the introduction 8 Hua XXVIII, pp. 102-125.
to the Pfander-CoUection, that "the general investigation of the possible 9 Needless to say with regard to my presentation of Husserl's analyses of emo-
structures of wiUing is in need of the difficult investigations of the general tional consciousness I have not been in any way exhaustive. For more detail cf.
structures of consciousness, since the correct demarcation of the shapes of my "Objektivierende und nicht-objektivierende Akte," in Husserl-Ausgabe
consciousness that the word 'will' is supposed to characterize is hardly an und Husserl-Forschung, ed. Samuel IJsseling, Phaenomenologica 115 (Dor-
drecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 25^19.
obvious matter." 69
10 At the top of the margin of the title sheet (Ms. A VI7,2a) there is to be found in
blue pencil the Husserlian signature "Ph." The Ph-sheets were later paginated
The problem of the relationship between will and tendency and the consecutively by Landgrebe. At the present time we have been able to retrieve
about about one-hundred Ph-sheets. Nevertheless the proper place of several
problem of the demarcation of the sphere of will are of great significance sheets is not clear. Originally there may have been well over one-hundred manu-
for Husserl's concept of consciousness. The description of consciousness script sheets. Most of the Ph-sheets are to be found in Mss. A VI7 and A VI12II.
found in the Logical Investigations suggests a static-geological image of 11 This research manuscript bears the Husserl signature Q II. It encompasses
three mutually founded levels of consciousness: at the depest level is exclusively appendix sheets and one sheet with a partial table of contents for
representation and judgment. Upon this is built the level of valuative feel- thirty-six sheets. With the exception of the last and of the appended sheets all
ings and then upon this level is the level of willing. But if all consciousness the sheets are to be found in Mss. A VI7 and A VI30.
12 Alexander Pfander, "Motive und Motivation," in Miinchener Philosophische
has the character of a striving-willing intentionality, then this obviously Abhandlung: Theodor Lipps zu seinem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet
signifies a basic modification of this static concept of consciousness. (Leipzig: 1911); for the English, see Alexander Pfander, Phenomenology of

76 11
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y OF WILLING

Willing and Motivation, trans, by Herbert Spiegelberg (Evanston: Northwest- 39 "Mit dem fiat setzt die Handlung ein und in seinem Sinn lauft sie ab, immerfort von
ern University Press, 1967), pp. 3^40. dem sich forterstreckenden und erfullenden Willen getragen." (A VI12II, 159a)
13 Of this Pfander-Folder, which encompassed probably about sixty sheets, only 40 For an analysis of the will-action (Handlungswillens) see Hua XXVIII, p.
forty sheets could be retrieved. As a result, of course, the proper ordering of 109-112.
some pages is questionable. The pages are to be found in the three Mss. A VI 41 See A VI12II, 199b. See also Hua XXVIII, p. 110.
3, A VI 30 and A VI12 I. With regard to the Pfander Folder, see Karl Schuh- 42 "Das Wollen ist in jedem Moment des Tuns Willensintention: Dasselbe sagt
mann, Die Dialektik der Phdnomenologie I: Husserl iiber Pfander, Phaenom- das Wort Streben. Das Streben ist die leere Willensintention; das kreative
enologica 56 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 94ff. Wollen, das praktisch-schopferisch setzende, ist das voile (Wollen), der blossen
14 A VI3,5. Intention im stetig vorangeneden Moment and der stetig vorangehenden vol-
15 Of the estimated fifty sheets of this collection (Konvoluts) at the present only unturen Form uberhaupt. Die Willensintention erhalt sich stetig (sofern sie
about half of them have been retrieved in Ms. A VI121. unrealisiert bleibt) als Intention und erhalt zugleich stetig Ftille der Befriedi-
16 For the classification of psychic phenomena see the rich explications in Franz gung im stetig kreativen Setzen." A VI12II, 200a)
Brentano, Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis, ed. Osknr Kraus (Hamburg: 43 See the Folder "Tendency," A VI 12 I, 168b. The proper place of this page
Meiner, 1969), pp. 17-19. within this folder is not fully certain.
17 See Edmund Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. IL, Part I, ed. Ursula 44 "Der fiat ist willentlich der Anfang der Handlung, leitel sie notwendig ein,
Panzer, Hua XIX/1 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. 513 ff. gehort zu ihrem willentlichen Wesen. Es ist der 'Springpunkt' der Handlung
18 This last point is often overlooked. See for this Edmund Husserl, Logische und ohne Springpunkt keine Handlung. Der blosse Vorsatz ist das Gegenbild
Untersuchungen, Vol. II, Part II, ed. Ursula Panzer, Hua XIX/2 (The Hague: der Handlung, es ist der 'leere' Entschluss, der in der wirklichen Handlung
Martinus Nijhoff, 1984), p. 737 and 781. seine Erfullung findet, und somit vor allem in dem einleitenden fiat, dem nun
19 Hua XXVIII, p. 347. die Handlung zu folgen hat." (A VI12II, 202b)
20 William James, Principles of Psychology in two volumes (London, 1890). In 45 Hua XXVIII, p. 108.
Husserl's library there can be found also the German translation of Principles 46 Ibid., p. 109.
of Psychology: William James, Psychologie, trans. Marie Dtirr (Leipzig, 1909). 47 Idem.
The translation has no traces of having been read. Husserl had read carefully 48 A VI12II, 206a.
the comprehensive review of Anton Marty in Zeitschrift fiir Psychologie und 49 A VI3,23a.
Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, Vol. Ill, No. 4, 1892, pp. 297-333. In Husserl's 50 Hua XIX/1, p. 430.
library there is an annotated offprint of this review. In Husserl's copy of Prin- 51 Ibid, p. 429.
ciples of Psychology one minds numerous references to the review by Marty. 52 Hua XIX/2, p. 624.
21 Principles of Psychology, Vol. II, p. 559. 53 For this see Ullrich Melle, "Objektivierende und nicht-objektivierende Akte,"
22 Idem. op. cit., pp. 41-47.
23 Ibid., p. 560. 54 A VI, 30, p. 25b.
24 Ibid., p. 561. 55 A VI30, p. 235b.
25 Ibid.,p. 561. 56 A VI3, p. 5b.
26 Ibid., p. 562. 57 Idem.
27 Ibid, p. 564. 58 Idem.
28 Ibid., p. 564. 59 Pfander Folder, A VI121, p. 129a.
29 Christian von Ehrenfels, Uber Fiihlen und Wollen: Eine psychologische Studie 60 Ibid., A VI121, p. 130b.
(Vienna, 1887). 61 Ibid. A VI3,42b.
30 Ibid., p. 15. 62 From the Folder, "Tendenz," A VI121, p. 230a.
31 For a discussion of the impossibility of willing the ideal, see the nuanced analy- 63 "In each act-achievement there lies an achievement, a tendency is released."
ses in Hua XXVIII, p. 106. ("Tendenz" Folder, A VI12 I, p. 208a)
32 "The will is the will's certainty of the creating of the future." See the Pfander 64 "We have therefore intention as position-t.aking and intention as tendency, a
Folder, A VI, 3,19a. tension to be released [Spannung zu scheiden]. ("Tendenz"-Folder, A VI12 I,
33 Hua XXVIII, p. 103. p. 29b.)
34 In the Pfander folder we find in one place the following determination of 65 Pfander-Folder, A VI121,152b.
desire: "Desiring is a longing, a yearning, for something futural, indeed a wish 66 "Tendenz" Folder, A VI121,206b.
that I have something, that something pleasant or good might occur for me." 67 Edmund Husserl, Erfahrung und Urtiel, p. 235; trans., Experience and Judg-
(A VI3,31a) ment, 200-201.
35 Hua XXVIII, p. 105. 68 Edmund Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenolo-
36 A VI7,8a. gischen Philosophie, Erstes Buch, new ed. Karl Schuhman, Hua III. 1 (The
37 Hua XXVIII, pp. 156 ff. Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976), 281 ff.
38 See A VI3,21a. 69 A VI3,5a.

78 79
H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

I have chosen the epigraph of this paper to indicate that the thrust of
74 Husserl's thought, in a manner I think typical of him, (a) transcends the
modern disputes between inteUectuaUsts and emotivists and between intel-
lectuaUsts and voluntarists and (b) points toward a position in which prac-
M O R A L O B J E C T I V I T Y tical cognition has an emotive content or, conversely, the emotions have a
cognitive content. My concern in this paper is to develop that thrust. I aim to
Husserl's sentiments of the understanding show that a phenomenology of moral experience grounded in Husserl's
reflections discloses a view of practical reason reminiscent in certain ways of
the substantive practical reason of those pre-moderns for whom reason and
John J. Drummond sentiment are co-constitutive of moral judgments. Butler's expressions "sen-
timents of the understanding" and "perceptions of the heart" also highUght
this' relation between reason and sentiment in our moral judging. But
Source: Husserl Studies 12 (1995): 165-183. whereas Butler seems to have been concerned only with what is empirically
true about our moral discernments and not with providing a theoretical
It is manifest great part of common language, and of account of the relation between reason and sentiment, Husserl was con-
common behaviour over the world, is formed upon supposi- cerned to discover the essential necessities embedded in our actual
tion of such a [approving and disapproving] moral faculty, experience, including the essential relation between reason and emotion. I
whether called conscience, moral reason, moral sense, or have borrowed Butler's expression "sentiments of the understanding" for
divine reason; whether considered as a sentiment of the my subtitle to underscore the particular emphasis on understanding evident
understanding, or as a perception of the heart, or, which in Husserl's formal axiology and his account of moral intentionality.3
seems the truth, as including both. Nor is at all doubtful in
the general what course of action this faculty or practical dis-
cerning power within us approves, and what it disapproves. 1.
For, as much as it has been disputed wherein virtue consists,
or whatever ground for doubt there may be about particulars Husserl's axiological perspective intimates a view of ethics as a thoroughly
- yet, in general, there is in reality an universally acknow- rational and objective discipline comparable in its rigor and universality to
ledged standard of it..., namely, justice, veracity, and regard logic. His intentions are to defend ethics as a pure discipline and to pre-
to common good. serve the absolute, a priori validity of moral laws. The rival here is ethical
Joseph Butler empiricism, which he understands as a form of psychologism that grounds
Bishop of Durham1 ethics in the psychology of emotion (Hua XXVIII, 12). Husserl extends his
well-known criticism of logical psychologism to moral psychologism. He
claims that moral psychologism has anti-ethical consequences insofar as it
Edmund Husserl's recently published writings in ethics and axiology2 undercuts the universal validity of moral norms and makes ethical cogni-
approach ethical issues from a variety of perspectives. Two stand out. The tion and argumentation impossible. Just as logical psychologism cannot
first is the axiological, from which Husserl develops an analogy between yield suitable notions of truth or logical vaUdity, so moral psychologism
formal logic and formal axiology (Hua XXVUI, 3-101). The second is the cannot yield suitable notions of the moral good and of what we might call
"conflict between a moraUty of the understanding (Verstandesmoral) and a "moral validity" (Hua XXVIII, 12). To ground ethics in psychology (or,
moraUty of sentiment (Gefuhlsmorat)" (Hua XXVIII, 251), i.e, between the similarly, in biology) would reduce moral laws to those empirical laws gov-
"inteUectuaUsts" (Verstandesmoralisten) and the "emotivists" (Gefuhlsmoral- erning the activities of evaluating and acting rather than the universal and
isten). From this perspective, Husserl develops a phenomenological descrip- ideal laws governing the relations among the contents, i.e., the meanings,
tion of evaluative intentionaUty, a description which clarifies how intentionally inherent in evaluative acts. To ground ethics in psychology
understanding and emotion jointly function in the axiological sphere. This would thereby undercut the possibility of any unconditional demand, of
paper wfll explore these two perspectives in order to sketch anew a phenom- any adequate notion of obligation. Evaluative terms such as "good" and
enological account of practical reason and of the objectivity of moral under- "bad" would refer exclusively to historicaUy and culturally conditioned
standing. usages generally applicable only in particular times and cultures. They

80 81
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

would have a merely factual validity, they would refer only to the gener- The second consideration mitigating Husserl's "ethical absolutism" is
ally true fact that in a certain historical culture people feel obligated on his characterization of the formal laws governing our moral life. The
psychological or biological grounds to act in certain ways (Hua XXVIII, analogy with formal logic is instructive. Just as pure logic concerns itself
13). Indeed, the claim that ethical norms reflect only the actualities of a with the formal possibilities for the combination of meanings, pure ethics
particular human development allows at the extreme-^for a thoroughly concerns itself with the formal possibilities for the combination of axiolog-
skeptical, perhaps even cynical, behavior which rejects the need to attend ical meanings. These combinations of meanings occur on a variety of
to these norms at all (Hua XXVIII, 16). Such claims and behavior, levels. In the case of pure logic, for example, Husserl speaks of rules which
although not blocked in fact, have their justification withdrawn by an a govern the combinations of meanings in the formation of judgments; these
priori ethics. rules constitute what he calls the "pure theory of forms of meanings (or
There are, according to Husserl, norms for correct behavior that are pure logical grammer)." 5 At this level of logic, there is still no concern with
grounded in a theoretical science whose claims about the rules governing the consistency of judgment? or the truth of conclusions. These latter con-
the contents of moral thinking are absolute and universal. Husserl does cerns define the second and third levels of logic. The second level Husserl
not thereby deny the empirical dimension of ethics. He does not deny, that calls the "logic of consistency" (Konsequenzlogik) or the "logic of non-
religious and political authorities play a role in our moral life, although contradiction," and its concern is the possible combinatory forms of judg-
blind and unthinking obedience to such authorities leads to an inauthentic ments (Hua XVII, 58/53, 327-30/330-33). This level constitutes formal
life in which agents do not think and decide for themselves, in which they logic as traditionally conceived. It is concerned primarily with the validity
exercise neither a "rational" nor "practical" autonomy. 4 Nor does he deny of arguments, and establishes rules which guarantee that the conclusion is
the differences between the customs, mores, and moral institutions of dif- not contradictory of the premises. In the case of deductive systems, which
ferent peoples and different times, nor that our moral capacities are condi- are Husserl's primary concern, these rules guarantee that the conclusion is
tioned by our psychophysical constitution and its position within the causal an analytic consequence of the premises. In its exclusive focus on validity
nexus of the physical world. But the fact of these empirical factors in our apart from soundness, the logic of consistency is not yet concerned with
ethical life is not sufficient to justify the claim that ethics is an empirical the truth of premises and conclusions. But insofar as logic is an art for the
science, for these factors affect only how ethical principles are particular- theoretical sciences and insofar as these sciences have a teleological
ized in different circumstances and the ethical practices in which they are concern with truth, the logic of consistency is incomplete. Hence, the third
realized. For Husserl the theoretical part of ethics must be an a priori level of logic is the "logic of truth" (Wahrheitslogik) (Hua XVII, 60/55).
science. While* the first two levels of logic deal with the combinatory forms of
The "ethical absolutism" suggested by Husserl's notion of formal axiol- meanings, the third connects the notion of meaning to that of truth. It is
ogy is mitigated by three considerations. Consider first the very notion of Husserl's notion of intentionality and, more specifically, his notion of evid-
formal axiology. The formal dimension of any judgment does not exhaust ence - notions to which we shall return - that provide the connection.
the judgment; every judgment also has a material content. In response to If we are to take Husserl's analogy between formal logic and formal
questions about how rationally to order one's life, i.e, how rationally to axiology seriously, we can expect corresponding levels in formal axiology.
shape one's entire life as a good life and to attain happiness (Eudaimonia), The first "grammatical" level would have to do, then, with the possible
Husserl speaks of the need "to define a system of absolute and pure prin- forms of axiological judgments wherein value-attributes are predicated of
ciples of practical reason which, free from all reference to the empirical objects and wherein axiological meanings are brought into conjunctive,
human and its empirical relations, ought to take over the function of pro- disjunctive and hypothetical relationships. These individual axiological
viding an absolutely normative standard for aU human behavior, whether judgments are ordered into consistent unities. Husserl believes "there
these standards are only formal or also material" (Hua XXVIII, 11, my must also be in the ethical sphere, in the sphere of rational practice, some-
emphasis). But the standards provided by formal axiology can only be thing like an analytic, something like a formal theory of practice (formale
formal. The material content of our evaluations is not and cannot be pro- Praktik), a complex of principles and laws which in an analogous sense
vided by a formal axiology. So, in addition to formal axiology, there is for abstract from the "matter" of the practice and express conformities to laws
Husserl what might be called a "material a priori" of the moral life "free of pure form, just as formal-logical laws do with respect to cognition and
of all reference to the [merely] empirical human," and this is what gives to just as they abstract from the so-called matter of cognition" (Hua XXVIII,
practical reason its substantive content. We shall return below to the 37). Here we would find Husserl's version of a deontic logic. Adherence to
material a priori. its laws yields consistency in our moral beliefs and practice; the laws of

82 83
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

consistency are laws of rational motivation. When a law claims that we material and contextual dimensions, however, point toward the need for
must do something, say, in order to achieve some good, the necessity here an analysis of our concrete intendings of goods and bads.
is not logical or physical. The law asserts that a rational person, given a
desire for that particular good, ought to do that thing. The law asserts that 2.
not to do that thing, given the desire for that good, would be irrational.
However, just as in pure logic the truth of a judgment is not the same The valuable properties of things, according to Husserl, are disclosed by
as its consistency with other judgments, the correctness of an evaluative the emotions or feelings. But the experience of objects qua good, qua
judgment and of the actions executed on its basis do not lie exclusively in likable and desirable, is a founded one, and the term "founded" here has a
the consistency of a practical conclusion with its premises. The premises double sense. To say that one experience is founded upon another means
and thereby the conclusion must also be correct in the sense of true or (1) that it presupposes something as necessary and (2) that it builds itself
evident or "insightful" (einsichtig). We must go beyond mere formal con- upon it so as to form a unity with it. The experience of objects as good is
sistency to evident and .rationally insightful judgment. An evident judg- founded on the purely cognitive experience of objects simply qua objects
ment, for Husserl, is not merely one for which reasons can be given. An without value-properties. Husserl claims that objects can be presented in
evident judgment involves the intuitive presentation in what Husserl such purely cognitive experiences, e.g., perceptions, memories, judgments,
calls "categorial intuitions" of the state of affairs as judged, as intended suppositions, or theories (Hua XXVIII, 252). It is possible, he thinks, to
in the judgment. In this appeal to the need for evident, rational insight, conceive of cognitive experiences completely divorced from the emotions
we are again led back to the material content of our evaluative and and feelings; I might simply notice things in the visual field, attend to their
moral life. color, and register them as trees, grass, or stones. Indeed, at one extreme
Beyond the reference to the material content of our evaluative judg- the theoretical sciences pride themselves on their separation from the
ments and laws found in the first two considerations, there is a third factor domain of emotion and feeling and their pursuit of a "pure" cognitive
mitigating Husserl's "absolutism." It is a universal and formal feature of truth.
our acting that it always occurs in a situation. Consequently, our evalua- While such purely cognitive experiences are existential possibiUties, the
tive judging must always be ordered toward the situation, toward the great bulk of our everyday experience is not of this unmixed, purely cogni-
goods that are desirable and attainable therein. The material content of tive character. Even our everyday perception of objects is governed by
the judgment must be relativized to the situation. To will, Husserl says, is practical interests which lead us to explore the object in particular ways
impossible "without a certain conviction of attainabiUty" (Hua XXVIII, and to a determinate degree. 6 While hiking I need something to hammer
52). Husserl's first, formal law of moraUty - his categorical imperative - on a loose heel; I inspect nearby rocks until I find one that is long and
must therefore be formulated with a formal reference to the situation in relatively flat. Upon finding one, I am satisfied. This rock is good for ham-
which the wflled act is to occur: "Do what is best among what is attain- mering on the heel; it has an instrumental value for me. The length and the
able" or, stated objectively, "The best among what is attainable in the total flatness of the rock are perceptuaUy presented. But its being a good rock
practical sphere is not only comparatively the best, but the sole practical (i.e, good for hammering) is not perceptually presented; its presentation
good" (Hua XXVIII, 221). Hence, the universaUty of tire laws governing as a good rock arises in my satisfaction that this rock has the properties I
practice is itself relativized to the practical possibilities which exist for want (i.e, the properties that I need in order to do what I want done). It is
agents; the laws governing the combinations of axiological meanings and an essential feature of our evaluative experiences that the desires and
evaluative judgments do not vary from situation to situation, but the emotions combine with the senses and understanding in presenting objects
material content of the judgments might be relativized to the extent that qua good or valuable by virtue of having certain properties ordered to the
the goods identifiable and attainable in concrete historical and cultural satisfaction of our desires (Hua XXVIII, 252). The experience of the
situations might vary. object having value necessarily presupposes the cognitive apprehension of
the object .and necessarily involves a moment of feeling which builds itself
Both the material and contextual dimensions of our evaluative judg-
upon the cognitive experience of the object (Hua IV, 8-11/10-13). More
ments indicate that the absolute and universal character which belongs to
precisely, we should say that the value-properties belonging to the object
the laws of formal axiology might not belong to the concrete moral judg-
are founded on that object's "logical" properties (i.e, the sort predicated
ments we make. Those judgments have not only a formal dimension but a
in simple, unmodalized, categorical propositions), and the value-properties
material one (both a priori and empirical), and the material dimension is
are the correlates specifically of a moment,of feeling or emotion in the
relative to the context in which the concrete judgment is made. Both the

84 85
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

concrete valuing act. In our example, the value of the rock, its being good it; I am looking for it. But knowing the purpose for which I want the table,
for hammering, is grounded in its being long and flat and our awareness I know the properties for which I should look in the tables I consider.
that these properties in a rock are properties useful for hammering. When I find a table with suitable properties, I like it and want it; I value
In the language of Husserl's theory of intentionality, the valuing act is the table as good. The feeUng-moment in the experience (the "liking," my
the "noesis" and the rock as good is the valuing act's "noema," its inten- satisfaction that this table will do what I want done) is directed to the good
tional correlate. The noema is the intended object just as intended and the in the table. However, my experience can - and often does - move beyond
intended object itself is an identity presented in a manifold of noemata. 7 the feeling directed to the value-property. I can also explicitly judge the
Indeed, we can think of the object as an identity in a manifold of noematic table as good. I expUcitly express my valuing the table in the judgment
manifolds. So, for example, the rock is the identity in a manifold of per- "This table is good," and the logical properties which underlay my valuing
spectival presentations. I can look at the rock from above; from its various the table can be identified in the statement of reasons given in support of
sides; I can pick it up and look at its underside. All these views differ from my judgment: "It is sturdy, of good size, and the right height." My attitude
one another, but all are presentations of one and the same rock. In circling has now returned to a theoretical one; I make a value-judgment. I under-
the rock or in turning it in my hands, what is present at one margin of the stand the value of the table and can provide objectively compelUng
field in one view gradually moves across the visual field to the center and, reasons for thinking it valuable.
finally, disappears at the other margin. This phenomenal continuity reveals Even in the movement from my simple valuing of the table to the judg-
the identity of the rock in its various views. But the rock is not only the ment that the table is good and the identification of the reasons underlying
identity manifesting itself in the manifold of actual views we have of it, it is my judgment, there remains a certain emptiness to my value-intention. I
also the identity in the manifold of possible views we might have of it. The have affirmed that this table has the desired properties and is thereby
rock is also the identity in the manifold of its actual and possible proper- good. But the value of the table is a use-value, and my judgment of the
ties, in the manifold of its actual and possible relations (e.g., spatial and table's value, of the table as good, is fully confirmed only in its use. We still
causal) with other objects, and so forth. Equally important, the rock is the require, in other words, what Husserl caUs a "fulfilling" intention. We still
identity in the manifold of the experiences of different subjects. I can see require evidence for our judgment that this is a good table, but this evid-
the same perspectival view of the rock that you now see if I move myself ence is not to be found simply in the statement of reasons. We here move
to your position. You can describe the rock to me so that I can pick it out from the axiological equivalents of the logic of consistency to the logic of
from among the many rocks in front of us. The rock, in other words, and truth. The evidence that the table is good is found in the direct experience
its properties are "objective" in a double sense: (1) they are not really of the table as good. It cannot be gained merely by looking at the table or
inherent contents of the experiencing act itself and (2) they are intersub- by identifying its relevant logical properties and reciting the reasons why it
jectively experienceable and experienced. is a good table. Since the table is good for use, I must use it to gain the
appropriate evidence. So, should the table after three days collapse under
Another example will further illustrate the foundedness and objectivity
the weight of my computer equipment, I would think the table a bad table.
of value-properties. I want a table for my computer and its various periph-
It would disappoint my expectations. And it would not merely fail to
erals. But any table satisfying this want must be sturdy, with a certain
satisfy but would produce great dissatisfaction. It would now evidentiaUy
surface area, and of a certain height so that it wfll (i) safely hold aU my
present itself as a bad table. In such evidential insights, I gain objective
equipment, (ii) be large enough also to hold my papers, and (ni) not be too
evidence about the value-property I have attributed to the object. The
high for comfortable typing. Sturdiness, of course, would be a property
valued object is not merely the correlate of my desires and emotions; it is a
desired in any table. But the desirable area and height of the table are
complex of objective properties related both to my understanding and to
identified in relation to the specific purposes for which the table is to be
my desires and emotions. And my value-judgment is fulfiUed in an "axio-
used. In examining tables, consequently, I look for certain objective, per-
logical" intuition (Hua IV, 9/10) analogous to a categorical intuition. I
ceptible properties in order to find a good table, a table that wfll be good
direct myself intuitively toward the articulated state of affairs in which the
for holding my computer equipment and papers and for allowing me to
object as valued concretely appears to me with the value-property predic-
work in comfort. The "logical" properties grounding the value-property
ated in the judgment. I therein recognize the truth of the value-judgment
are objective. But the value-property, the goodness of the table, insofar as
(cf. Hua XXVII, 26).
it is grounded in objective, perceptible properties, is also objective.
The objectivity of the value-property can be made manifest in another Our two examples make clear the central role of the desires and emo-
way. I want a table to use as a computer table and desk. I do not yet have tions in the evaluative experience. But there need not be an actual desire

86 87
Ii
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND
METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G
or emotion operative in order to recognize the value of an object. Values
can be apprehended in an experience which includes an "as if" moment of one person toward another and take pleasure and delight in the goodness
desire. You who do not want a computer table can recognize that the table of such actions, both in themselves and in their consequences for the
I have picked out would be a good computer table. There are reasons for person aided by this generosity.
valuing this table. It presents itself as sturdy, as five feet long, two and one-
half feet deep, and three feet high, and thereby presents itself as good rela-
tive to the satisfaction of my desire for a work table for my computer.
You, indeed anyone who has wants of the sort identified in the example or Since the value-property itself is apprehended in a feeling-moment (or an
anyone who can consider the table in relation to such wants, can appre- "as if" feeling-moment) within the concrete experience of a valued object,
hend the perceptible properties of the table and recognize that the table and since feelings belong to our psychic dimension with its causal depen-
would be a good computer table. Understanding, in other words, knows dencies, one might still object that value-judgments are relative to particu-
the value as befitting the object relative to certain wants or desires a lar subjects or, at least, to the wants of those particular subjects. So, for
person might have. example, liking sweets, I find hot fudge sundaes desirable, but someone
who is aUergic to chocolate would not judge them valuable even while
Thus, while the complete experience of value contains an irreducible
allowing that I could find hot fudge sundaes desirable. Or, one might
moment of feeling or emotion in which the value-property is apprehended,
object, liking to help others, you are generous, but someone who likes
the complete experience of value, we can now see, contains even more
material goods and does not like to be separated from them might not find
important cognitive moments. The foundation of the value-predicates on
generosity a good, and each of these persons, recognizing what the other's
cognitively apprehended logical predicates, the act of judging the object
desires are, might agree that, relative to those desires, generosity is a good
valuable and identifying the reasons underlying the judgment, and the
or selfishness is a good. This possibility seems very far from Husserl's
rational insight into the value of an object all point to the central role of
desire for a universal ethics with a strong sense of obligation, and we must
the understanding in the complete and fulfilled experience or judgment of
consider how a phenomenology of moral experience grounded in
value. Moreover, the cognitive dimensions of the experience of value
Husserl's thought would respond.
ensure that the value-judgment is intersubjectively objective. The constel-
lation of logical properties is such as to arouse a feeling, a value-reception Our earlier examples were directed toward the utility of the rock and
(cf. Hua IV, 10/12), and the predication of the value-property to the object the table, and this utility is related to my particular needs and wants.
is subject to fulfilmerit or disappointment by any experiencing subject. The Husserl would certainly agree that universal ethical principles can be
valued object, then, is the identity presentable in a manifold of perceptual erected neither on the valuing of particular goods related to my particular
apprehension, of desire, of satisfaction, of judgment, and of evidential needs and wants nor on the value-judgments involved in the experience of
insight. In experiencing valued objects, we identify (a) the object as appre- such particular goods. Either path would allow that ethical principles are
hended with relevant logical properties, (b) the object as desired, and - in empirically grounded and constitute a return to ethical empiricism.
the complete evaluative experience - c) the object as the judged value- Husserl avoids ethical empiricism not only through his formal axiology but
object, and (d) the object as the evidentially understood value-object. In also through his notion of the material a priori, and we must now investi-
short, we identify the good desired and the good known. Both of our gate that notion. We must determine whether there are goods which are
examples have involved the use-value of objects, but the experience of recognizable as such independent of our particular empirical needs and
value is not limited to the experience of objects' utiUty. However, the wants. We must determine whether there are goods characteristic of
account of the experience of value is similar in other areas. In the aesthetic human nature as such. If there are, these goods would provide the content
domain, for example, upon seeing the bright red of the sunset, we pass for the universal laws identified in Husserl's formal axiology and together
over from the simple perceptual experience, the sensory having of the red the formal laws and a priori goods would constitute a universal ethics.
sky, to an aesthetic experience, a taking delight in the brilliance of the red. Two points must be noted. First, Husserl's notion of the material a
We value the pleasurable object, and we judge the sunset beautiful on the priori should not be understood in such a way that the a priori is discover-
ground of the brilliance of its colors. Similarly in the moral domain, in able through the operations of reason alone apart from all experience. The
watching someone pick up another's dropped package, we appreciate an material a priori is discovered through the exercise of what Husserl calls
act of kindness. In knowing how someone has shared wealth with another eidetic or imaginative variation, a method reminiscent in many ways of a
even at some cost to himself or herself, we experience the generosity of Platonic or Aristotelian dialectic culminating in an essential insight into a
form. Eidetic variation begins with particulars, with an experienced

89
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

instance or instances of the type under investigation. Then particular qual- for the kind of object under question. There are, in other words, theo-
ities, aspects, or parts are considered in their relation to the whole. If the retical and practical limits to our philosophical grasp of essential struc-
varied component can be eliminated without a change in the type of the tures, but this does not mean that we cannot legitimately make essentialist
object, a non-essential feature of the object - Husserl calls it a "piece" or claims.
"independent part" - has been isolated. However, if the varied component The second point to be noted is that the materially a priori essence is
cannot be eliminated without a change in the type of the object, then what not completely determinative of any particular. The eidetic reflection on
Husserl calls a "moment" or "non-independent part" of the object, an the nature of the human and the human experience of goods and bads
essential characteristic, has been isolated.8 This method of eidetic variation yields a material a priori of the human which is reminiscent of what
moves beyond empirical generalization to an a priori consideration, Martha Nussbaum caUs a "thick vague conception of the human being"
however, because in systematically varying the parts of the whole it con- and a "thick vague conception of the good." 9 Human goods and practices
siders possible cases as weU as actual ones. The analysis considers not only
must conform to the material a priori of the human to be good, but differ-
empirical instances of the type, but imaginatively posits possible instances
ent possibilities for specifying the same good can accord with the material
in order to move toward a set of variations in which each part belonging to
a priori. The discovery of the human a priori and the subsequent determi-
the object is systematicaUy varied so as to determine its necessity for an
nation of a priori goods for all humans is not completely determinative of
object of that type. This imaginative and systematic variation isolates
the particular character those goods might take for different historical cul-
necessary conditions for an object to be of a certain type. The analysis con-
tures or different human individuals. This does not imply that one form
tinues by identifying what other conditions are necessary for an object to
cannot be found better than another. But it will not be found better by an
be of that type, what other conditions are required to complete the whole.
exclusive appeal to the material a priori. Other reasons which appeal to
This set of conditions is a set of a priori conditions insofar as its identifica-
tion no longer rests merely on a generalization from actual examples, and the evidence provided by our concrete experience of things and of the
the set of conditions governs not merely actual cases but any past, present, world - an experience which is not only philosophical but also, for
or future instance - indeed, any possible instance - of an object of that example, scientific, practical, productive, artistic, aesthetic, and reUgious -
type. would have to be identified. Nor is the materially a priori essence com-
pletely determinative of the practices which might be adopted to realize
The goal of the method of eidetic variation is the identification of a set those principles. In different circumstances, the same good might be real-
of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for an object of a ized in different specifications and through different practices, but not in
certain type. Such an identification would constitute a fuU and adequate any specifications and practices for not aU accord with the material a
insight into an eidos or essence. However, because of the limitations of our priori, and among those that do accord some are for complex reasons
knowledge we can never be certain that we have identified a set of fully better than others.
sufficient conditions. The eidetic insights we can attain are, according to Given our reflection on evaluative acts we can already recognize
Husserl, indubitable, i.e, we have no reason to doubt that the conditions humans, at least, as thinking and desiring agents. Our reflection has also
we have identified as necessary for an object to be of a certain type are in revealed a teleological dimension in evaluative acts. In valuing things as
fact necessary, because we find it impossible to imagine or conceive of an good, we tend toward the judgment and evident comprehension of them as
object of that type without those conditions. We have no reason to think good. This teleological dimension is present, Husserl's analyses reveal,
that our identification will ever be negated by subsequent discoveries. But throughout our intentional Ufe. It is this a priori fact which provides the
the indubitability of our insights does not mean they are incorrigible or moral urgency at the center of Husserl's philosophy. In addition to any
infallible. Again because of the limitations of our capacities for under- vocational callings to a central, material good around which we order the
standing, our insights might very weU be subject to correction, not so much pursuit of goods in our daily lives, we are all as humans caUed to the full
by negation but in the form of refinements and quaUfications. Even our exercise of reason with its teleological direction toward evidential under-
confidence in our identification of individually necessary conditions must standing (cf. Hua XXVII, pp. 28-34). We are called to the authentic
be tempered by the shortcomings of our cognitive powers. Each identifica- human life, the life of rational, free, insightful agency. This life is the chief,
tion of a necessary condition might be grounded in variations which are but not the only, good for humans. Moreover, certain conditions are
insufficient because they either fail to distinguish relevant factors or necessary for the exercise of rational, free, insightful agency in the fuUest
mistake irrelevant factors for essential ones, or because the complex of degree. Some of these conditions are primarily bodily, e.g., life itself,
individual insights might fail to take into account all the novel possibilities health, and the sustenance and shelter necessary for maintaining them.

90 91
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

These caU forth the virtues of temperance, generosity, justice in the distri- only a schema for strongly valued goods and since these goods are under-
bution of material goods, and so on. Others are not primarily bodily, e.g., stood and specified in varying ways in different historical and cultural cir-
education with its concern for both theoretical and practical truth, and the cumstances, we must remember that our valuations are always directed to
poUtical freedoms of association and speech. These call forth the virtues of these a priori goods as concretely specified in particular historical and cul-
honesty, sociabihty, forbearance, good judgment, prudence, fortitude, tural circumstances. Insofar as these goods have a truth grounded both in
wisdom, and the like. All these - the conditions themselves, the virtues the a priori and in the facts of our particular circumstances, our valuings
called forth by those conditions, and the exercise of thought and agency in and judgings.are always open to disappointment and subject to question.
the fuUest degree - are human goods as such. The social and political The life of rational, free, insightful being, consequently, calls us to regular
issues of how these might be best instantiated given our particular, present reflection on the truth of our concrete judgments about human goods and
circumstances is a concern which would lead beyond the scope of this bads. And this investigation, given that our particular understandings and
paper, but the identification of the best political institutions to ensure valuings are affected by the historical and cultural horizons in which we
these goods would yield another set of goods, viz. those political institu- frame our judgments of value, proceeds best through a reflection not only
tions themselves. upon our own historical and cultural understandings of these goods but
The material a priori of the human good recalls Charles Taylor's notion also upon other historical and cultural understandings. We are called
of "strongly valued goods." Strong evaluations, Taylor teUs us, "involve upon, in other words, to undertake an eidetic variation regarding these
discriminations of right or wrong, better or worse, higher or lower, which substantive goods, a variation which takes actually present historical speci-
are not rendered valid by our own desires, inclinations, or choices, but fications of the material a priori of the human good as its starting points
rather stand independent of these and offer standards by which they can but which also considers other possibilities (historical and imaginative). By
be judged." 10 Goods which are the objects of strong evaluations make a means of this variation we clarify and, when appropriate, revise our under-
claim upon us. They are not goods simply by virtue of being the object of standing of the material a priori of the human good itself and of our con-
my desire as, for example, the hot fudge sundae is a good. They make their crete instantiations thereof.
claim upon us independent of our particular desires because they are a If all this is correct, a Husserlian-based phenomenology of moral
priori goods. Beyond our particular desires and goods, those goods con- experience would respond to the problem raised at the beginning of this
tained in the material a priori of the human make a claim on us precisely section by arguing that value-judgments are relative only when they are
because we must recognize the desirability of those capacities, material exclusively related to the empirical, sensuous dimensions of our existence.
conditions, social circumstances, habits, and institutions without which we Thus, it is perfectly acceptable that I like and value hot fudge sundaes
would no longer be truly rational, free agents at aU. Moreover, since they while someone aUergic to chocolate does not. But it is equaUy important
are human goods as such, they impose an obUgation upon me to seek their to note that my valuing hot fudge sundaes occurs in a context and against a
realization both for myself and for others as part of my good. Such goods standard defined by a material a priori of the human good, Le., by strongly
are substantive goods and, insofar as they make claims upon us, the ques- valued goods. Ill do value hot-fudge sundaes, I must value them only in
tion of true goods - as opposed to merely apparent goods - arises, and we moderation. I would not simply choose to eat hot fudge sundaes without
are called upon to achieve an understanding of and rational insight into restraint, for too many hot fudge sundaes are undoubtedly bad insofar as
the true goods. Insofar as I recognize these goods as true goods, I desire they do not in numbers conduce to the materiaUy a priori good of health.
them for their own sake - both for myself and for others - in addition to or This last point leads us to a consideration of the unity of the two perspec-
apart from whatever pleasures or pains, beneficial or detrimental con- tives in Husserl's moral philosophy.
sequences might arise for me from their pursuit.
The introduction of the a priori of human goods does not change our
account of evaluative intentionality with its fundamental identification 4.
between an objectivity as known and as desired. Just as certain features of In our concrete historical valuings we are faced with a multiplicity of
tables were recognized as practical necessities for the table to serve as a goods worthy of choice, some of which derive from or particularize the
computer table and were consequently desired, so certain a priori necessi- material a priori of the human good and some of which arise from our
ties for realizing our humanity in the full sense are apprehended in the individual capacities and desires. In many cases the choice among compet-
course of our experience, are desired as human goods, and judged as such. ing goods is relatively easy. I do not choose to eat hot fudge sundaes in
Since even a fully developed conception of the material a priori provides excess because health is better than iUness and because health better

92 93
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

enables the pursuit of other goods I seek. But in other cases, e.g., between a single historical culture order their lives. But all these vocational choices
the goods of parenting and those of career (including simply keeping one's ought to be responses to goods which specify the material a priori of the
job in order to be able to provide for family) or between the good of com- human in a concrete historical circumstance; aU these vocational choices
passion for employees and that of responsibility to the institution for ought to realize those goods which belong to our nature as human beings,
which one works, the choice can be very difficult. The easy choices, goods from which our fulfilment as individual humans is inseparable.
however, already provide a guide toward understanding how we rationally Moreover, among the different material, vocational goods, we find a non-
order our Uves in the face of competing and sometimes incommensurable manifest identity. There is a good identical to each of these manifest
goods. Goods are subordinated one to another, and the agent whose Ufe material goods, a non-manifest good embedded in each manifest material
and striving are rationaUy well ordered to the attainment of happiness good. We find the key to identifying this non-manifest or formal good in
must choose a life-goal or, as Husserl puts it, a vocation (Hua XXVII, p. Husserl's formal axiology.
28). What we know about the nature of goods and the material a priori of Husserl speaks of laws of rational consistency governing our valuing,
the human good reveals that among the goods which are available for wishing, and willing experiences (Hua XXVIII, 237). But rejecting the
choice some are particularizations of the material a priori and these goods Kantian notion of the categorical imperative; Husserl thinks it insufficient
make a claim upon us, they call to us as goods and our weU ordered voca- to say that these laws constitute a procedure for determining the good
tional choices are dutiful responses to such caUs. We must choose for our- toward which a rational agent orders his or her Ufe. It is insufficient to say
selves an overarching, material good, what Taylor caUs a "hypergood." 11 only that there is a rational criterion according to which goods and maxims
Since there is a multiplicity of historical, cultural, and individual particu- for action are tested. In Husserl's ethical system there must also be both a
larizations of the material a priori, our choice of one particular good over material content for the good drawn from the material a priori of the
another, even one strongly valued good over another strongly valued human and a relation to circumstances. There must also be a material
good, involves a response to our individual interests and capacities and our good which makes its claim upon us, whose goodness we have understood
cultural and historical circumstances. We again here see the interplay of and insightfully grasped, and to which we have afforded an emotional
the understanding which is capable of recognizing goods derivable from legitimation in recognizing it as a vocational good. And this good must be
the material a priori and the desires and emotions in bringing something to attainable under the circumstances. Once one emotionaUy, comprehend-
presence as an overarching good and in judging it valuable enough to give ingly, and insightfuUy gives a material content to the notion of the "best"
moral order to a life. in our lives, one has an overarching good which orders all those goods
It is at this point of our discussion that we can see how Husserl's belonging to the practical domain under it as more or less conducive to the
accounts of moral intentionaUty and of formal axiology can be united in a best, mediately or immediately conducive to the best, and so forth (cf. Hua
universal ethical theory. To identify a vocational good - whether making XXVII, 31-32).
money or attaining salvation - is to identify a material good which, as the Insofar as this non-manifest dimension of rationally and freely valuing
highest good, orders all other goods under it according to what Husserl what is best belongs to all manifest material goods, it follows that it is itself
caUs "the law of absorption" (Hua XXVIII, 145). This law, along with a goal sought in any willing of the good for humans or for a particular
Husserl's version of the categorial imperative, belongs to his formal axiol- human being. Regardless of the differences which might exist between dif-
ogy. We are called upon by the categorial imperative to do what is best ferent material conceptions of the good, our moral activity aims at the
among what is attainable. What is best is knowable by reflection on both ends mandated by the categorical imperative: rational (consistent), free
the nature of the human and upon the circumstances which affect what is (actively achieved rather than passively received), insightful (true) think-
attainable, circumstances which include our interests, our capacities, and ing and willing. This non-manifest good presents itself as one which
our resources. Both laws operate not only at the level of our vocational encompasses all other goods - insofar as it is reaUzed in the very choosing
choice but at the level of individual choices which arise in the course of of those goods - but which is nevertheless consistent with the identifica-
Ufe. All goods - even incommensurable goods, the conflicts of which can tion of different material goods as the highest good in terms of which we
impart a tragic dimension to human life - take their place within a hier- order other material goods. Husserl speaks of this good as "authenticity"
archy of goods as more or less conducive to the overreaching good. (Eigentlichkeit). But this is not authenticity in the fuUy voluntaristic sense
There can, therefore, be material differences among the goods towards that we find, say, in Nietzsche or Sartre. It is not merely a matter of choos-
which different individuals within different historical cultures order their ing or willing well; it is also a matter of knowing weU, of being able to give
lives and among the goods towards which different individuals even within reasons for our identification of certain goods, and of evidently knowing

94 95

»
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S HU S S E R L ' S SENTIMENTS OF THE U N D E R S T A N D I N G

the good. We here return to the moral urgency at the heart of Husserl's Brief Dissertations: I. On Personal Identity; and II. On the Nature of Virtue,
philosophy: to decide for oneself. But for Husserl, as we have seen, to together with a Charge Delivered to the Clergy of the Diocese of Durham, at the
Primary Visitation, in the Year 1751 (Hartford: Samuel G. Goodrich, 1819), pp.
decide is both to decide about what is truly good in the light of evidence
(rather than passively accept what others claim as the true good) and to 216-217.
2 Edmund Husserl, Vorlesungen uber Ethik und Wertslehre 1908-1914, ed.
decide what to do among the alternatives so as best to attain that good. Ullrich Melle, Husserliana XXVIII (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
This gives force to Husserl's claim that the Greeks in their discovery of a 1988). Subsequently, references to Husserliana volumes after the first reference
theoretical approach to the world moved beyond appeals to reUgious and will be abbreviated as "Hua" followed by the volume and page numbers. When
civic authorities and discovered a theoretical autonomy. And, Husserl an English translation is available, references to it after the first reference will
says, "theoretical autonomy is followed by practical autonomy" (Hua VI, be included with the interlinear reference to the critical edition; the page
6/8). To be truly autonomous is first to gain evidence regarding what is number of the German edition will be followed by a "/" and the page number
of the English edition.
true about the human and the world and about what goods make claims 3 There are, of course, other aspects of Husserl's thought that lend themselves to
upon us independently of our desires and inclinations. The autonomous a reflection on ethics. Robert Sokolowski's Moral Action: A Phenomenological
agent wills from among these goods that one which gives a vocational Study (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985) develops Husserl's notion
direction and order to that agent's individual Ufe. That agent also orders of categoriality in the moral sphere. James Hart's The Person and the Common
his or her life - or attempts to, for this is very difficult - so that everything Life: Studies in a Husserlian Social Ethics (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub-
lishers, 1992) explores Husserl's ethical views and develops especially his con-
done and every good sought conduces mediately or immediately to that ceptions of social and theological ethics. R. Philip Buckley and Karl
fundamental, vocational good. To be autonomous in this way is to attain Schuhmann have also examined Husserl's social and political thought; cf.
the non-manifest good of authenticity, or - to state it in terms reminiscent Buckley, Husserl, Heidegger and the Crisis of Philosophical Responsibility
of Aristotle and terms which make the point more clearly than the term (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992); Buckley, "Husserl's Notion
"authenticity" - of thinking well (for oneself), both theoretically and of Authentic Community," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 66
practically. (1992): 213-227; and Schuhmann, Husserls Staatsphilosophie (Freiburg: Karl
Alber Verlag, 1988).
Whatever our vocation, then, we are aU called, not necessarily to be 4 For a discussion of authentic life in both the individual and the community, cf.
philosophers, but to be philosophical. We are called to reflect upon our the third and fourth of the Kaizo-articles ("Fiinf Aufsatze iiber Erneuerung") in
choices so that in thinking and willing we realize ourselves as rational, free Edmund Husserl, Aufsatze und Vortrage (1992-1937), eds. Thomas Nenon and
beings who think, decide and act with evidential insight whatever the Hans Rainer Sepp, Husserliana XXVII (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publish-
ers, 1989), pp. 20-59; cf. also Buckley, "Husserl's Notion of Authentic
material or vocational goods to which we direct ourselves. We are caUed Community," pp. 217-223, and Hart, The Person and the Common Life,
to reflect upon human activities and capacities and to discover the essen- passim.
tial norms which govern them so that in our pursuit of those material 5 Cf. Edmund Husserl, Formale und transzendentale Logik: Versuch einer Kritik
goods and vocational goods which govern our individual lives we can der logischen Vernunft, ed. Paul Janssen, Husserliana XVII (The Hague: Marti-
recognize that we are Uving the life of the rational, free being. Many ques- nus Nijhoff, 1974), p. 55. English translation by Dorion Cairns, Formal and
tions are, of course, left unresolved: which goods to choose, how to recon- Transcendental Logic (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969), p. 50. Husserl
develops the idea of a pure logical grammar at greater length in Logische
cile competing goods even when non-compossible or incommensurable, Untersuchungen, Zweiter Band, Erster Teil: Untersuchungen zur Phdnomenolo-
how to arrange political institutions to achieve shared, human goods while gie und Theorie der Erkenntnis, ed. U. Panzer, Husserliana XIX/1 (The Hague:
preserving the authentic autonomy and political freedom of the individual. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1984), pp. 301-351. English translation by J.N.
But the answers to these questions must always be cognizant of the urgent Findlay, Logical Investigations, 2 vols. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
caU central to moral life, the same urgent caU which was at the center of 1970), II: 493-529.
Husserl's life and philosophizing - a call to thinking and deciding truth- 6 Cf. Edmund Husserl, Ding und Raum: Vorlesungen 1907, ed. U. Claesges,
Husserliana XVI (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 128-138; cf. also
fully, to an ethics which is both objective and universal, but neither
John J. Drummond, "Object's Optimal Appearances and the Immediate
absolute nor dogmatic. Awareness of Space in Vision," Man and World 16 (1983): 182-183.
7 Cf. John J. Drummond, Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational
Realism: Noema and Object (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990),
Notes §§29-32; and Drummond, "De-Ontologizing the Noema: An Abstract
1 Joseph Butler, Bishop of Durham, The Analogy of Religion, Natural and Consideration" in John J. Drummond and Lester Embree, eds. Phenom-
Revealed, to the Constitution and Course of Nature, to which are added Two enology of the Noema (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992), pp.
89-109.

96 97

L
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S

8 Husserl discusses eidetic or imaginative variation in several places. See espe-


cially Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenologischen Philoso-
phie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einfiihrung in die reine Phanomenologie, ed. K. 75
Schuhmann, Husserliana III (rev. ed. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976)
[English translation by F. Kersten, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology
and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Book I: General Introduction to a Pure P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , V A L U E
Phenomenology (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983)], §§69-70; and Erfahrung
und Urteil: Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik, ed. L. Landgrebe with T H E O R Y , A N D N I H I L I S M
f * Afterword by L. Eley (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1972), [English transla-
tion by J.S. Churchill and K. Ameriks, Experience and Judgment: Investigations
in a Genealogy of Logic (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973)], §87. Steven Crow ell
For an account of the theory of wholes and parts underlying his discussion of
imaginative variation, see Hua XIX/1, inv. 3, and for a related discussion of the
different types of abstraction, see Hua XIX/1, inv. 2. Robert Sokolowski has
written clearly on Husserl's theory of wholes and parts; cf. his Husserlian Medi- Source: Kluwer, forthcoming.
tations: How Words Present Things (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1974), ch. 1; "The Logic of Parts and Wholes in Husserl's Investigations,"
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 28 (1967-68): 537-553; and "The §1. Human pathos
Structure and Content of Husserl's Logical Investigations," Inquiry 14 (1971):
esp. pp. 333-337. Pathos. In EngUsh this term does not normally call to mind the project of
9 Cf. Martha Nussbaum, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," Liberalism and the the human sciences, scholarly inquiry, or phenomenology. Yet it names
Good, eds. R. Bruce Douglass, Gerald M. Mara, and Henry S. Richardson (New something that lies very much at the intersection of technology, nature,
York and London: Routledge, 1990), p. 205. Both this article and her "Non-Rela-
tive Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume and life.1 For pathos, as Hegel might say, is that point where nature passes
XIII. Ethical Theory: Character and Virtue, eds. Peter A. French, Theodore E. over into life, and it is my aim to show that the significance of this passing
Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre remains deeply contested precisely in those inquiries - the human sciences
Dame Press, 1988), pp. 32-53 detail a universal account of the human good which and philosophy - that reflect on our destiny in the age of technology. To
nevertheless allows for historical, cultural, and individual differences. Cf. also speak of human pathos is to speak of that which touches us, of our capacity
Drummond, Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational Realism, ch. 9; and
Drummond, "Modernism and Postmodernism: Bernstein or Husserl," The for passivity, of what we undergo. And should not the project of science
Review of Metaphysics 42 (1988): 275-300. and technology, born of the human instinct for autonomy and expressing
10 Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cam- the power of freedom, be concerned with what may limit its Promethean
bridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), p. 4. striving? Those sciences for whom "human" is simply a natural-kind term
11 The Sources of the Self, pp. 62 ff. may see no special importance in the dimension of pathos: to be affeqted
by what is other, to be "determined," is, for such sciences, simply the fate
of every entity in causal interaction, obeying laws to which it can only be
indifferent, toward which it can take no stand.2 But those sciences for
whom the term "human" retains something of its normative character, the
human sciences, cannot ignore the complications for their own scientific
practice that flow from the fact that the human being is neither simply an
inert variable in causal explanations nor the supremely rational creator of
all he surveys, but rather a being who undergoes its world - a creature who
is affected by things, moved by them, afflicted; who suffers, endures, and
remains exposed. Because of this exposure, the problem of method is
incomparably more troublesome in the human sciences than it is else-
where, a fact to which phenomenology has always tried to do justice. It
has, however, not yet met with great success.
Before looking at the problems phenomenology encounters when it
tries to provide a "logic" of the human sciences that does justice to human

98 99
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

pathos, let me call upon it to help us see why this theme - the kind of pas- human pathos as the ontological dimension that includes them aU, a
sivity inscribed in the passions, in what we undergo - is not simply a topic dimension inseparable from the constitution of meaning as that which dis-
for the human sciences, but their root soil. For phenomenology insists on tinguishes the specifically "human" as being-in-and-of-the-world. Because
the difference between this sort of passivity and that in which something is dwelling within a space of meaning, rather than merely inhabiting an
acted upon causaUy to produce an effect. Whereas the latter, as Kant environment, is the exclusive prerogative of a pathetic being, we may not
pointed out, makes sense only in a space of reciprocal casual interaction neglect that dimension in favor of reason when we try to understand our-
(Wechselwirkung), and so in such a way that what is passive is in turn, and selves as standing, in Aristotle's phrase, between beast and god. But why is
simultaneously, active, the passivity of the passions is not reciprocal. To it so difficult to think this dimension in its own terms? Why do the custom-
undergo, to be moved, touched, affected; to suffer: these are not forms of ary, mostly cognitivist, approaches conceal as much as they reveal? Why
interaction with the other but of exposure to the other, modes of being do we continually faU back on such models of human meaning, no matter
that take place not in a space of causes but in a space of reasons, 3 a norm- how often phenomenology reminds us of their limits? Here Nietzsche can
ative space in which I am not constrained merely to react but am open to help us toward an answer, since he reminds us that human pathos is itself
learning. Just this distinction is voiced in the ancient Greek saying, pathei exposed to a malady; Befindlichkeit can itself undergo a pathological con-
mathos - learning through suffering - and in a certain sense it is because dition, a disease; can suffer a collapse of meaning: nihilism.
undergoing can be learning that human beings can become selves. If That nihilism belongs to the dimension of pathos is evident in Niet-
undergoing is a way of being addressed, of being caUed upon to take a zsche's description of it as "the feeling of valuelessness."6 By terming it a
stand, then to be an I is to be capable of exposure to the world in this way, feeling of valuelessness, Nietzsche indicates, further, that nihflism is a
such that what is undergone is not lost in a causal nexus but is registered deformity of this dimension: in it things lose their meaning, they no longer
and inscribed, however dimly, in a character. Phenomenologically, it is claim us, nothing matters any longer. Is there anything to be learned from
impossible to say whether the freedom to take a stand on what one under- the suffering nihilism? Consider Nietzsche's diagnosis: Nietzsche under-
goes (to learn) makes exposure in this human sense possible, or whether stands nihflism, the pathology of meaning, to be an affliction of values; we
this being exposed is the condition of freedom itself. They belong insepa- undergo nihilism because "the highest values de-value themselves." Nor-
rably together. As Heidegger puts it, Dasein is constituted "equiprimor- mally, meaning arises because things take on value in light of goals and
dially" by Befindlichkeit and Verstehen? purposes that I posit from my point of view. These goals and purposes
Heidegger's account of Befindlichkeit - of the kind of pathos he calls themselves take on the character of values that ultimately come to
"thrownness" - contains what is phenomenologically crucial in this theme: measure the worth of my existence itself. When they fail, as in nihilism,
to be a creature of passion is not merely to allow a "mood" to provide meaning coUapses. From this, says Nietzsche, we should learn a "revalua-
some "subjective coloring" to things already simply there in the world; it is tion of aU values." The sick man of today, with the life-denying values
rather that whereby the world and all that appears in it can matter to us at ("ascetic ideals") that have hitherto perversely measured his existence,
all.5 To suffer or undergo is not a momentary event but the very modaUty must undergo this revaluation by going under, must learn, through suffer-
in which things as a whole and in particular make a claim upon us, concern ing, the meaning of the earth, which speaks in the life-affirming values of
us in some way, take on significance. While a purely rational being, lacking wfll-to-power.7
pathos, might be able to register things (as a computer or a photographic Nietzsche's prescription for dealing with the nihiUsm afflicting the body
plate might), it could not respond to them since it would lack motivation to of Western culture draws upon the passions rather than reason. With his
do so. Things could not move such a being since nothing could matter to it; "pathos of distance" the strong human being is to posit a new "order of
such a being could not inhabit a meaningful world. RationaUty, surely a rank" among values by enacting it, by "giving style to one's existence"
necessary condition, is nevertheless not a sufficient condition for meaning. according to a "great mood," an aesthetic "taste" that shapes one's drives,
An account of the "affects" - love and hate, rage, joy, boredom, fear, feelings, and instincts into an individual whole.8 This gaya scienza is
longing and so on - is thus not an appendix to the real work of explaining poetry; there is no "science" of value in which reason poUces the validity
the "mind" in "cognitive science"; it is the window onto a human mind's claims made by competing values, since, as Nietzsche puts it, "faith in the
most fundamental condition. As yet, however, it has been hard to look categories of reason is the cause of nihflism."9 And yet Nietzsche's heirs -
through that window. or at least those, like Husserl, who occupied chairs of philosophy in
If the modaUties of the pathetic - of undergoing, exposure, passivity - Germany at the end of the nineteenth century - had a very different pre-
are ways in which things variously matter to us, we may speak generally of scription. For them, it is precisely by restoring to reason her rights over the

I?
100 101
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

dimension of human pathos that a theory of meaning, a scientific antidote theoretical psychologism so as to motivate similar arguments against
to nihilism, is to be achieved.10 AU agree that, as Husserl would write, value-theoretical empiricism and naturalism. However, gathered under the
baldly, in 1935, "the European nations are sick."11 Already in 1911 Husserl generic term Werten ("valuing"), the text also contains elements of a
had noted that "the spiritual need of our time has, in fact, become unbear- phenomenology of the Gemutssphare, reflections on experiences ("acts")
able."12 Like Nietzsche, Husserl sees this sickness as a crisis of values, and, of feeling, desiring, wishing, hoping, taking joy in, fearing, and so on.
like Nietzsche, Husserl sees values as deeply connected with human Despite Husserl's hope, these two aspects of his text are not in harmony;
pathos - what he calls the Gemutssphare in which we are affected, moved, indeed, his thinking is marked by an aporia between the analogical projec-
touched by things, in which things matter to us. But Husserl's diagnosis tion of axiological reason and a phenomenological reflection on affective
does not follow Nietzsche's. experience that in fact undermines the analogy at crucial points. This
According to Husserl, the impasse in Western culture has resulted not aporia is, I shall argue, inseparable from the concept of value itself, and to
from reason exercising its hegemony over passion and value but from a untie it we must abandon the chimaera of a rational theory of value.
failure to exercise the kind of reason - "axiological reason" - appropriate Why does Husserl believe that affective life is governed by a peculiar
to passion and value. Husserl's prescription caUs for something like a form of rationality? For one thing, it seems to be entailed by the way we
• i
i critique of axiological reason, a reflection on its nature and possibiUty.13 express ourselves in "common Ufe" (Hua XXVIII:169): We say, "That is a
Husserl therefore turns to a phenomenology of affective life not for its beautiful sunset," or "He is a fine fellow," or "This Mont Blanc is an excel-
own sake but because he hopes to construct a rational theory of value lent pen." On the one hand, Husserl suggests that such expressions point
(Wertlehre). For this reason, our understanding of the role that the back to acts of feeling in which the values expressed are experienced: "The
Gemutssphare plays in human Ufe, its contribution to the disclosure of a fact of valuing, of being pleased or displeased, of wishing, and so on, signi-
meaningful world, is from the start filtered through a distorting cognitivist fies at first nothing more than that we are struck [angemutet] in this or that
lens. In an effort to begin to remove this lens I shall argue, in what foUows, way by objects, that we feel ourselves so moved by them, and the like." On
that the lectures on ethics and theory of value that Husserl delivered peri- the other hand, the fact that such feelings get expressed as predicates, that
odically between 1908 and 1914 are marked by an irresolvable tension "we ascribe a predicate to the evaluated matters that pertains to them irre-
between phenomenological analysis and analogical reasoning, a tension spective of the contingent act of valuing," signals, for Husserl, "something
that undermines the very notion of a Wertlehre. I suggest that if we hope new" (Hua XXVIII:86). Thus the ordinary language in which we express
to profit from what a phenomenology of human pathos has to teach us, we our feelings about things already poses the "problem," for Husserl, of how
must reject the analogy in favor of the phenomenology. 14 we can legitimately move from the mere "fact" of a feeUng in which some-
thing is valued to a "predicate which raises the claim to objectivity," from
"This is valued" to "This is worthy of value, good" (Hua XXVIII:254).
§2. The analogical approach to affective life This is the problem that axiological reason - "valuing reason with its law-
Husserl approaches the Gemutssphare by way of an analogy between fulnesses" (Hua XXVIII:86) - is supposed to address.
"logical" or "theoretical" reason (which embraces the laws of cognitive Let us note two things about Husserl's point of departure. First, his
experience, governed by the norm of truth) and what he calls "axiological" phenomenology of value affirms the fact that feelings present themselves
reason (which, by analogy, would embrace the laws of appetitive and not as mute but as meaningful: undergoing is not simply a causal-psycho-
affective experience, governed by the norm of the good). Why does logical occurrence but a kind of intentionaUty, which Husserl calls
Husserl proceed analogically here? His motivation is itself introduced by "deeming" (Vermeinung). As intentional, it necessarily involves a norm of
il an analogy: just as logical reason emerged in the ancient world as a means intelligibility. But, second, he immediately construes this normativity as a
for confronting theoretical scepticism, so "in the modern period" nihflism kind of rationality - that is, as a "claim to objectivity" and hence, in the
It
so threatens practical life that there is an "ever more urgent striving" after last analysis, as a kind of cognition?6 By construing our linguistic penchant
a "system of absolute and pure principles of practical reason" (Hua for assigning predicates to objects as a clue to the normativity of the
XXVIILll). By analogy, then, just as logical reason secured the claims of Gemutssphare, the latter becomes amenable to the analogy with theo-
cognitive experience against scepticism in the ancient world, so axiological retical reason. At the same time, however, the peculiar character of the
reason should secure the claims of affective/evaluative experience against normativity embedded in the intentionality of the affects gets covered
nihilism in the modern world.15 Much of Husserl's text is given over to over. To support this claim I shaU first examine how Husserl's phenom-
developing this analogy - for instance, to rehearsing the arguments against enology discloses, in the affective sphere, a normative dimension that is

102 103
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

descriptively distinct from cognitive normativity (truth). I will then argue blue sensations" (Hua XXVHL63). To explain this, Husserl argues that
that Husserl's own examples of the supposed analogy between theoretical though our passions do not judge in the logical sense, they do "judge" in
and axiological reason fail to convince. We will then be in a position to an analogical sense (Hua XXVIIL64) and thus seem to predicate some-
understand why value theory is, phenomenologically, wooden iron (holzes thing about what they are about: this landscape is sublime, this person is
Eisen). lovable, this desired state of affairs is desirable and should become reality.
What norm governs such attributions; according to what measure are they
justified?
§3. Affective intentionality
Husserl notes that it is not, strictly speaking, the norm of truth. Truth is
Husserl's phenomenology of the affective dimension has two goals: to a matter of the logic of judgment, while the affects are not judgments. As
establish the intentionality of the affects, and to distinguish them from Husserl puts it, if we "think away" all value predicates "nature remains
cognitive experiences - or what he calls "objectifying acts." The first dis- nature. Theoretical science" - governed by the norm of truth - "remains
closes pathos as an element in the constitution of meaning, while the what it is: in itself it never leads to values." Nevertheless, he is convinced
second, because it is shackled to the concept of act, becomes a tangled that "the value predicates do truly [in Wahrheit] pertain to [the object]; to
confusion that cannot, in principle, be unraveled. disavow them would be perverse. They belong," Husserl continues, "in
Husserl begins by taking seriously the phenomenological fact that in the another dimension" - a dimension other than the one accessible through
experiences I undergo at the hands of the world my feelings, such as being theoretical reason and assessable in terms of truth (Hua XXVIII:262).
pleased or displeased (Gefallen, Misfallen), have intentional content; they Just this sort of suggestion, however, has led some philosophers to con-
are, in a distinctive way, about something (Hua XXVIII:57). When I take clude that the phenomenology of valuing life is systematically misleading.
delight in leafing through my copy of Heidegger's Sein und Zeit, I am not Agreeing with Husserl that science neither encounters value properties
merely directed toward the book. Rather the delight deUghts in the book's nor need appeal to any in its explanations, J. L. Mackie, for instance, held
feel, the fineness of its binding, the clarity of its typography. These things this to show that all phenomenological attributions of such properties are
move my delight and are inseparable from it; that is, a "fineness" of the in fact in error. How can Husserl's appeal to "another dimension" avoid
binding or a "clarity" of the typography that would be accessible to mere this "argument from queerness"? 18
sight would not be the sort of thing that we express by these terms when One response, surely, would seize upon the naturalistic assumptions
describing the affective experience.17 They belong to its kind of intention- governing Mackie's argument (and many others of this sort) - the idea
aUty. If I am moved by the sublime landscape, then against psychologism that the set of legitimate explanations is exhausted by the sort of explana-
phenomenology insists that this sublimity is no more something merely tion found in natural science. Husserl, for example, argued that this idea
subjective, an inner "representation," than is the landscape itself. The undercuts itself since it leaves no room for any sort of normativity, includ-
affects, no less than simple perception, open out onto the world. Yet this ing the logico-cognitive normativity upon which naturalistic explanations
distinction between psychological and intentional content requires that themselves depend. This opens the door to a strategy once championed by
intentional experiences are, while psychological experiences are not, nor- John McDoweU, who, likening value predicates to secondary qualities,
matively oriented; that is, their content is a claim that might or might not offered a defense of non-reductive explanations couched in terms of such
be satisfied by the world. For instance, in the case of cognitive acts (which qualities.19 Once we no longer imagine that all "real" properties must be
for Husserl includes perception) the norm is truth: to say that I perceive a like primary qualities ("just there"), we can accept the fact that physical
red ball before me (that is, that "red ball" is the intentional content of my explanation need not encounter or appeal to secondary qualities, and still
perceiving) is to say that there is in fact a red ball before me if my percep- maintain that this is no good reason to deny such qualities to objects.
tion is true. Something similar must hold for the Gemutssphare if one is to Though one cannot account for what such a property is - being-red, say -
attribute genuine intentional content to it. Thus Husserl insists both that without reference to how the object shows itself in a certain kind of
affective life is distinct from judgment - that it is "as such not belief, not experience (otherwise it would not be an account of being-red), this does
cognition; it does not perceive or predicate, it carries out no deductions or not at all tell against the object's actually being red. "Being red" just is
inductions" (Hua XXVIII:64) - and that it is nevertheless normatively ori- "being such as to look red in appropriate circumstances" and is independ-
ented, e.g. toward a "valuing that values as it should value" (Hua ent of its "actually looking red to anyone on any particular occasion."20 If
XXVIIL57). Were this not the case it would have no intentional content this is so for secondary qualities, then perhaps something similar is true of
but would be "blind experience like, for example, experiences of red or values: to account for what it is for something to be a beautiful piece of

104 105
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

music is to say that it is "felt to be beautiful under appropriate conditions" affective normativity in light of logical reason without actually using it as a
- conditions which, as in the case of looking red, will include features of "torch." 22 That is, though he admits that undergoing "does not see, does
the environment as well as of the perceiver. This seems to be close to what not conceive, does not explicate, does not predicate" (Hua XXVIIL69), he
Husserl means by saying that value predicates belong to the object, but "in nevertheless describes it, analogically, as a sphere of valuing reason. What
another dimension" (Hua XXVIII: 259-60,261-2). authorizes this analogy is simply that Husserl equates the normative with
Yet we may still feel that there is a salient difference between sec- the rational: "reason" stands for "the essentially closed class of acts and
ondary qualities and values here. For one thing, speUing out what "appro- their appurtenant correlates which stand under the ideas of legitimacy and
priate" conditions amount to in the latter case leads us back to the initial illegitimacy, correlatively of truth and falsity, of obtaining and not obtain-
problem: whereas in the case of perception of secondary qualities (an ing, etc. There are just so many fundamental types of reason as there are
objectifying act), the cognitive norm of truth is in play, in the case of affec- acts that we can distinguish of which this holds" (Hua XXVIII:68). Well
tive or evaluative Ufe the very character of the axiological norm itself is in then, is the Gemutssphare made up of such acts? A rigorous phenom-
question. Thus in trying to specify what "appropriate conditions" mean in enology of this sphere would be required in order to answer this question,
evaluative life there is nothing obviously analogous to Husserl's account of but one looks in vain in these texts for such a phenomenology. Instead, the
appropriate perceptual conditions in terms of normality and optimality, procedure Husserl adopts in the 1911 "Introduction" to his "Lecture on
i« centered in the "orthoaesthetic" lived body.21 If there is nevertheless an Fundamental Problems of Ethics and Value Theory" is fairly typical.
analogy, as Husserl believes, we have no choice but to look phenom- Assuming the sphere of "theoretical-objectifying reason" as "analogical
enologically at affective Ufe itself to see the norm at work. clue" to the affective sphere, Husserl stipulates that though the affects are
But here the real difficulties begin. For in a certain sense it is impossible not judgments or cognitions they "in turn do support rational questioning"
to see the distinctive norm that governs the other dimension in which (Hua XXVIII:204). For instance, "desire has the character of a deeming;23
affective life plays itself out, because the light of theoretical reason shines one can ask about the legitimacy or illegitimacy of the desire . . . and in the
too brightly, obscuring the very different intentionality that belongs to our objectivations that are built upon acts of this group something stands there
undergoings. On the one hand, Husserl understands that affects are not in an objective manner as something that ought to be, as a good; and we
cognitions: "If we ascribe to a joy [Freude] a relation to an object, if we say that it is actually good if the question of its [sc. the desire's] legitimacy
designate it an intentional experience relating to the enjoyable [das receives a positive and well-grounded answer" (Hua XXVIIL205). It is
Erfreuende], then this sort of 'relation-to' is totally different from the one obvious that the main claims in this passage - that desire can be ques-
we ascribe to a perception, for example, or a memory or a judgment" tioned about its legitimacy and that the good is that correlate of desire
(Hua XXVIIL336). On the other hand, the norm governing this sort of which survives such questioning - are not derived from a phenomenology
intentionality - the norm belonging to "valuing reason" - is available only of the "other dimension" of the passions itself but from the analogy with
as bound up with cognitive acts: "it must interweave [verflechten] with acts theoretical reason. Indeed, Husserl admits that these "preliminary distinc-
of the logical, doxic sphere" since "only by carrying out such acts can acts tions" call for "penetrating clarifications" in order to see "in what sense
in general, and what they deem, come to objective givenness" such that and with what actual justification essential demarcations are really to be
"we can see that valuing acts are 'deemings' . . . and further, that they made here, or in which sense we may really speak here of reason and
stand under ideal predicates of legitimacy and illegitimacy [Recht und objective validity" - clarifications that "lead into phenomenology and the
Unrecht], etc" (Hua XXVIIL69). Without this interweaving of theoretical theory of reason." Yet because that is a "veritable primeval forest of dif-
and valuing acts we cannot see affective intentionality for what it is. And ficulties," Husserl chooses to "avoid this primeval forest and all the mon-
yet Husserl concludes that if "the forms and norms concealed in the sters lurking within it" by taking it for granted that reason is operative
spheres of affect and wiU are to come forth into the bright Ught, the. torch here, that the normative is eo ipso a matter of reason (Hua XXVIIL205).
of logical reason must be abandoned" (Hua XXVIIL69). How then are we Thus if one were to doubt that the claims we experience in the dimension
to see the norms of the "other dimension" at all? of human pathos are properly analogized to theoretical reason, one would
have to show that the results obtained by applying this analogy actually
distort the character of the Gemutssphare. And in fact, if we turn to
§4. Analogy and its discontents Husserl's proposal for what he caUs "formal axiology" - the analogue of
formal ontology - evidence for the failure of the analogy is not hard to
At this point Husserl supplements phenomenological analysis with an ana-
find.
logical approach that is supposed to enable us to see the phenomena of

h 106 107
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

Central to the normativity of the cognitive sphere is the relation of image and reaUty, a view in which I wiU thank God - and not the automo-
ground to consequent. Hence, if there is to be a formal axiology something bile - for the existence of beautiful sunsets, or in which only those paint-
like this relation must obtain in the affective sphere as well: "wherever it is ings are beautiful that depict things, the existence of which would be good.
possible to speak of valuing and value, there also is a distinction between A further supposed example of a law of rational motivation is this: "If
value grounds and value consequents, between presupposed values and one is happy \freut sich] about some actual W, and if one knows that
the values posited on or derived from them" (Hua XXVIII:71). However, because A is, W also is, then, rationally speaking, the happiness is trans-
the passage from one to the other is not governed by truth-functionality, ferred to A " (Hua XXVIIL75).24 But this too seems contingent. It would
as in the case of formal logic; rather, it is a function of "contexts of motiva- make it irrational to be unhappy about any regrettable circumstances upon
tion" - "the ground-valuing motivates the valuing of the derived values" - which some good and pleasing thing depended. (Perhaps the contraposi-
and it is this motivation that is assessed as to its reasonableness. If formal tive might be a law: if I am happy that something exists - say, a big luxury
axiology is supposed to be a theory of "laws of consequence" that are car - and then find out that it only exists because something else that I am
"laws of rational "motivation" (Hua XXVIIL71), the success of the analogy unhappy about exists - say, exploitation of workers - then I should be
will depend on whether contexts of motivation behave sufficiently sim- rationally motivated to change my valuing of the car). Or again, consider
ilarly to truth-functional contexts to justify applying to them the term the law, "if a property is valuable, so is every object that possesses such a
"reason." And though Husserl does not apply the analogy mechanically - property to that extent valuable" (Hua XXVIII:77). Either this is the unin-
there are, for instance, interesting discussions of the adiaphoron and the teresting tautology that a valuable property is a valuable property, or else
failure of excluded middle - the violence done to the phenomenology of it is false, since a very despicable person might possess a valuable property
motivation quickly becomes apparent. (cleverness, for example), though the mere possession of that property
Let us begin with Husserl's distinction between "existential" and "non- would not, for all that, make him more valuable. I would not be irrational
existential" pleasure. Non-existential pleasure is the sort taken, for to esteem him no whit more for having it.
example, in the beautiful, which, according to Husserl, is valued in its mere Finally, following the analogy with formal logic Husserl believes that
appearance and not in its existence. Existential pleasure, in contrast, is the the law of transitivity holds in formal axiology (Hua XXVIII:91): if A is
sort that depends on the existence of the thing enjoyed. Now Husserl better than B and B is better than C, then A is better than C. But as a law
believes that the following is a law of rational motivation, that is, an of rational motivation this does not in fact hold: I might be right to prefer
apriori law of formal axiology: "Whoever takes a non-existential pleasure A over B, and right to prefer B over C, but not right to prefer A over C.
(valuing-something-as-beautiful) in A, must, rationally speaking [vernunf- Because the argument for this counter-intuitive fact is compUcated,
tigerweise], be glad [freuen] in case it is certain that this 'beautiful' [thing] however, I will not try to reproduce it here but will refer to the account by
is, and must be sad [trauen] in case it is certain that it is not" (Hua Larry Temkin. 25
XVIII:73). But this hardly seems to hold at aU, let alone be an apriori law. Now these few counterexamples would not be enough to undermine
Considering only its appearance, I take pleasure in a beautiful sunset with Husserl's idea of a formal axiology if there were other good reasons to
burning reds, oranges, and yellows spectacularly laid out across the sky. think that an axiology is entailed by the phenomenology of the
Now I consider that this thing really exists; perhaps I recall that it is actu- Gemutssphare. But Husserl provides us with no such reasons, relying
ally produced by intense air pollution. Must I be glad of this existence, just instead on analogy to do the work. Systematically committed to the idea of
because it is beautiful? Is it irrational of me to be depressed that such a value-theory, Husserl develops the necessary formal axiology in spite of
thing exists? Husserl would call that an "affective contradiction" the actual phenomenology of motivation. I say "in spite of" because, being
(Gefuhlswidersinn). Or perhaps I am looking at a painting of nymphs the honest thinker he is, Husserl does engage in phenomenological analy-
dancing in a ring in which I take aesthetic pleasure. I may be glad that the ses that tend at every turn to cut the ground out from under the analogy.
painting exists, but this is presumably not what Husserl means by "rational Beyond our critical arguments from consequences, then, let us turn to
motivation" here. Rather, it is the existence of what is depicted that I am some rather more phenomenological criticisms.
supposedly motivated to value. But it does not seem that I would be irra-
tional not to take pleasure in the existence of a world where nymphs were
dancing in a ring, just because I took pleasure in the depiction of such a §5. A crisis in the concept of act
world. Husserl's principle seems not to be an apriori law but rather to
What finally undermines the analogy between formal logic and formal
reflect a limited view of the relation between the beautiful and the good,
axiology is that the phenomenological difference between cognitive

108 109

i
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

experiences and affective experiences involves a significant difference in (Hua XXVIII:332; my italics). Now despite the fact that acts in the
the movement from the implicitly normative to the explicitly normative in Gemiitssphdre, as non-objectifying, do not exhibit this definitional connec-
these realms. Normativity in the cognitive sphere can be traced to a dis- tion with the "contexts of judgment," Husserl nevertheless insists that
tinct telos belonging to acts in this sphere: they are "objectifying" or there is a continuity between pre-predicative and predicative experience
"object constituting." Such acts can be said to succeed or fail in Ught of the here too: "So it is also in the sphere of affective acts with its novel affective
constitution of a consistent, identical object, whether on the pre- theses [Gemutsthesen]: we transpose 'what' we value or wiU into predica-
predicative level of perception or the predicative level of everyday life and tive form, as when we say: May A be B, A should become B, etc. Every-
science. The normativity of theoretical reason is nothing but a reflection of thing that we have just expounded in the sphere of belief holds as well for
this phenomenological structure of object-constitution. In affective the sphere of affective acts" (Hua XXVIIL212).
!• experience, however, things are quite otherwise.26 As Husserl notes, it is The legitimacy of this last claim, however, depends entirely on the legit-
characteristic of such experiences that they do not constitute objects, and imacy of talk of affective theses (Gemutsthesen) in analogy to belief theses
therefore the reason that is supposedly implicit in them is a form of "non- (Glaubensthesen). There must be theses at the pre-predicative affective
objectifying reason" (Hua XXVHI:208f). This means that its normativity level if there is to be a continuity between it and the thetic form of evalua-
cannot be understood to derive from the telos of consistent, identical tive predication. Only then would there be something like a pre-
;; object-constitution. But since the analogy with truth-functional logic offers predicative quasi-object that would implicitly call for (and admit of)
no other way to grasp affective normativity, the tension between analogy critical justification; and only then would an explicit theory of value,
JI
and phenomenology becomes acute. grounded in axiological "reason," appear plausible. Yet this does not seem
Above aU, the analogy leads Husserl to distort the phenomenological to be the case. When I take pre-predicative joy in the beauty of a flower -
i. <
relation between predicative and pre-predicative experience in the am absorbed in it - the world is indeed disclosed to me in a certain way,
Gemutssphare. For while there is, in the cognitive sphere, a continuity matters to me in a certain way, but I do not find any kind of positing, any-
between the two, there is no such continuity in the sphere of what we thing that could be called a "thesis" that might implicitly call for "critical"
undergo. Since, however, axiological reason will be normative for pre- assessment as to its "validity." In contrast to cognitive acts, there is here a
predicative affectivity only if there is such continuity, continuity must be discontinuity between pre-predicative experiences and the predicative acts
manufactured. To do so, Husserl once again argues from analogy, this time that subsequently express evaluations - apparently objective and open to
operating with the phenomenological notion of These (thesis). Rec.aU that criticism - about things. It is true "that in loving someone I can wonder
object-constituting experience is characterized by a Glaubensthese: in con- whether I should love her, but the answer to that question will not come
trast to existentially neutral experiences such as imaginings, object- from a value theory, however much the form of the question suggests such
constituting experiences include a moment of commitment to, or beUef in, a thing.27
the object's "truly being" thus-and-so determined. At the pre-predicative Thus everything comes down to whether the dimension of human
level Husserl notes that "such theses emerge in the spheres of perception, pathos, of what we undergo in our exposure to the world, can be construed
of memory, of sensibility and the lower intellective forms of consciousness as something like an objectifying act and so as amenable to the norms of
that lie prior to specific thinking and conceiving" (Hua XXVHL212). correctness and incorrectness that derive from the identity of objects. Far
Because all and only "belief theses" are "object-constituting" (Hua from convincing us that it is, Husserl's attempt to construe affects in this
XXVIIL277) there is a normative continuity between these, proto- way leads to a crisis in the concept of act itself. A brief look at this crisis
intellective acts and "the domain of specifically _ thinking, cognizing will allow us to grasp the essence of the concept of value and see why,
reason" (Hua XXVIIL212); that is, the kind of objective validity that is rather than being an answer to nihflism, it is a symptom of it. What, after
claimed in explicit acts of cognitive reasoning, in expUcit predicative doxic all, is a "value"?
positing of "true being" as truly constituted identical object, is already at
In his writings on "The distinction and relation between theoretical and
stake at the lower level. The two levels belong together in a most intimate
axiological reason" of 1908, Husserl struggles for many pages with the
I way since the higher "takes up so to speak all of the legitimacy and illegiti-
relation between "understanding" - the objectifying faculty of judgment
macy of the lower consciousness and in the case of its justification it also
and representation - and "affectivity," which neither objectifies, judges,
co-justifies the lower consciousness" (Hua XXVIII:212). Indeed, Husserl
nor represents (Hua XXVIII:252). The problem is that even if we recog-
defines the "general class of objectifying acts" as those that have a "capac-
nize that all acts within the Gemiitssphdre are founded on objectifying
ity to enter into contexts of identity and so into contexts of judgment"
acts of some sort - say, acts of perception - this does not exhaust then-

110 Ill
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

intentionality. But how can a non-objectifying act be genuinely intentional §6. Nihilism, values, and meaning
at all - how, Husserl wonders, can they reaUy "constitute" a distinctive Husserl's attempt to counteract nihilism through a critique of axiological
"meaning" (Bedeutung) or "appearance" (Erscheinung) at aU (Hua reason and a theory of value must be judged a failure on phenomenologi-
XXVIII:324-25)? 28 It would appear that to include the distinctive inten-
cal grounds. The essence of the failure lies in the attempt to construe
tionality of the affects under the concept of act requires that there be a
human pathos, the sphere of what we undergo, in terms of the concept of
specific correlate for it, an affective meaning. However, this makes it seem
act. The "other dimension" in which the world speaks to us affectively, in
that "the title 'objectifying act' swaUows up everything" such that "it is
which we are exposed to things such that they matter to us, is not made up
hard to anticipate how one should be able to retain the concept of a non-
of acts, though in it meaning is indeed constituted. Husserl sees clearly
objectifying act" (Hua XXVIII:333). But then what would remain of the
that our passions are not inert effects but meaningful openings onto the
distinctiveness of the affective sphere?
world, and he holds, quite properly, that a phenomenology of human
This is no merely rhetorical problem for which Husserl has a ready pathos can provide a bulwark against nihilism. But he does not see that his
solution.29 Phenomenologically, the attempt to squeeze human pathos into own approach draws fataUy on the very source of the problem. As Heideg-
the schema of act intentionaUty leads to a crisis in the concept.of act itself. ger argues extensively in his Nietzsche lectures, thinking in terms of values
Husserl confesses that he has not been able to "get to the bottom of the
is nihilism.
affective acts and the whole essence of the founding among them and in
their relation to objectifying acts." Given that when we speak of affective Husserl takes objectifying acts to be the measure of meaning constitu-
"intentionaUty" what "intentionality means here is phenomenologically tion. For aU that this differs from modern representational thinking from
something other than what it means for objectifying acts, there remains an Descartes to Kant, it remains within the orbit of such thinking insofar as it
uncomfortable residue" that requires clarification if "the meaning and demands that Husserl construe our affective exposure to the world in
ill function of this intentionaUty" is to be made plain. The existence of this terms of the concept of act, lest it lose all contribution to meaning consti-
"uncomfortable residue" means that the concept of act itself is "seriously tution. The concept of value is a trace of this demand. As Heidegger wrote
threatened": "Does the concept of act still have unity? Is it not exploded in an appendix to "The age of the world picture,"
by the knowledge of this double sense of intentionaUty" (Hua
XXVIII:337)? Here we stand at the decisive point in the development of Where anything that is has become the object of a representing, it
value theory, for it is precisely in order to save the unity of the concept of first incurs in a certain manner a loss of Being. This loss is ade-
act that Husserl introduces the concept of "value" - that is, precisely not in quately perceived, if but vaguely and unclearly, and is compen-
response to demands stemming from the phenomenology of the affective sated for with corresponding swiftness through the fact that we
t
sphere itself.30 impart value to the object, and that we take the measure of what-
Let us recapitulate the argument. The concept of act requires a corre- ever is, solely in keeping with the criterion of value, and make of
late. Affective life is non-objectifying, so it is hard to see what its correlate values themselves the goal of all activity— From here it is only a
could be. To save the unity of the concept of act a correlate must be found, step to making values into objects themselves.31
but it cannot be an object lest all acts turn out to be objectifying. "Value"
names this correlate. "Valuing acts are not 'directed' toward objects, but Value, then, is what thinking posits to make up for the fact that it has
toward values. Value is nothing existing; value is something that refers to reduced being (meaning) to what it can reckon, calculate, and objectify.
being or non-being, but it belongs in another dimension" (Hua Such thinking is helpless in the face of what it knows, namely, that such
XXVIII:340). Values are the quasi-objects that populate the other dimen- objectification cannot do justice to the thing it grasps, that the density of
sion in which we undergo the world, suffer it, become exposed, and are things has escaped it. Positing values as "belonging" to these things but "in
acted upon as it were - because the concept of act requires a correlate. another dimension" is a mark of this helplessness.
And the concept of act is indispensable because without it (and the so- But how do we know that something is missing, that things have suf-
caUed Gemutsthesen) the .analogy with theoretical reason can gain no pur- fered a loss of being? We know it because we are exposed to things,
chase and loses all plausibility. Therefore values are theoretical postulates because in feeling we do not merely register the world but hearken to it
demanded by the analogical project of defining an axiological reason; they and respond, resonate with that which speaks to us, that which matters to
are not phenomenological data derived from the meaning of affective Ufe us. Nihflism - the feeling that things lack meaning - is a modern phenom-
itself. enon because modern thinking takes its self-posited representations to be

112 113
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND NIHILISM

the measure of being, and the only kind of being that can be constituted in and Lau Kwok-Ying. A shorter version of the present essay was read at a con-
this way (i.e. through objectifying acts) does not matter, of itself it presents ference on "Technology, Nature, and Life: Contemporary Social and Cultural
us only with "structures" or "identities" - or pictures - to which we are Problems in the Light of Phenomenology" at Seoul National University. I
would like to thank the hosts, Lee Nam-In and Jung-Sun Han Heuer, for pro-
perfectly indifferent. In nihilism we undergo this indifference. Any
viding a challenging context in which to further refine my ideas.
attempt to redress the loss of being in this malady besetting human pathos 2 No one believes that Dostoevsky's Underground Man, who tried to take a
by appeal to a theory of value - by insisting that affective meaning can stand against the laws of nature, is anything other than sick, his freedom
take the form of value properties that function, logically, Uke objective "pathetic" in the colloquial, pejorative sense. On the other hand, as Max
properties - is itself nihilistic. We love, suffer, hope, desire, ache as before, Horkheimer's analysis in "Traditional and critical theory" (Critical Theory:
but these modes of our being, of our Befindlichkeit, cannot be made to Selected Essays, trans. Matthew J. O'Connell et al, New York: Continuum,
1972), pp. 188-243, makes plain, the sorts of "law" proffered by the human sci-
look like acts with correlates, do not cluster under an identifiable "region" ences, broadly construed, are just such as call for those subject to them to take
of the "axiological," and cannot become the field for a general Wertlehre. a stand on them: the reality they reflect can be changed, and it is sheer ideology
Human pathos itself opens out onto a reform of phenomenology. to give them the status of laws of nature.
In registering the "sickness" besetting Europe, Husserl wondered: "why 3 This distinction derives from Wilfred Sellars. See Empiricism and the Philo-
sophy of Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997, p. 76.
is it that so luxuriantly developed humanistic sciences here fail to perform 4 Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward
the service that in their own sphere" - namely, sickness of the body - "the Robinson, New York: Harper & Row, 1962, p. 172 [H132].
natural sciences perform so competently?"32 Can the human sciences, phe- 5 In Being and Time 176 [H137] Heidegger writes: "Letting something be
nomenologically guided and grounded, provide "therapies" for the maladies encountered is primarily circumspective; it ... has the character of becoming
that beset cultures? Clearly Husserl hoped that a rigorous value theory affected in some way;... But to be affected ... becomes ontologically possible
only in so far as being-in as such has been determined existentially beforehand
would contribute to such therapies, that by bringing reason to this sphere we in such a manner that what it encounters within-the-world can 'matter' to it in
could put our priorities in order so that only that would matter to us that this way. The fact that this sort of thing can 'matter' to it is grounded in one's
really ought to matter. But our experience of exposure to the world, of the Befindlichkeit [attunement, state-of-mind]..."
claims things make upon us, of what we undergo such that things mean 6 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J.
something to us, does not support such a theory.33 What, then, may be Hollingdale, New York: Random House, 1967, p. 13.
hoped from a connection between phenomenology and the human sciences? 7 On sickness and "ascetic ideals" see Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of
Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House, 1969, pp. 97-163;
It seems to me that something indispensable opens up once we abandon the on "going under" and the "meaning of the earth" see Nietzsche, Thus Spoke
idea that these sciences can yield technologies of culture - namely, access to Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann, in The Portable Nietzsche, New York:
the full scope of that "other dimension" in which things speak to us, a Viking Press, 1968, pp. 125,127,137 etpass. "Umwertung aller Werte" ("reval-
foothold for an approach to meaning that respects the different ways in uation of all values") is the subtitle that Nietzsche considered for his projected
which the world gets "constituted" by human beings who can learn through (but never written) book to be entitled The Will to Power. See "Editor's Intro-
duction" in Kauffmann (ed.), The Will to Power, xvii; also Friedrich Nietzsche,
suffering, undergoing. A collaboration between phenomenology and the Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House,
human sciences can help us attend to what is reaUy being said in our "evalu- 1966, p. 117.
ative" sentences, lead us to Usten to ourselves with a sensibility unprejudiced 8 On the "pathos of distance" and a new "order of rank" see Nietzsche, Beyond
by the urge toward system, toward axiological hierarchies, divine teleolo- Good and Evil, pp. 117-18,201ff; on "giving style" see Friedrich Nietzsche, The
gies, metaphysical personalisms, and all such substitutions for the loss of Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House, 1974,
p. 232; on the "great mood incarnate" see Nietzsche, The Gay Science, p. 231;
being. In short, it can perhaps help us to forge a language for what we
on the "affect of command" see Nietzsche, The Gay Science, p. 289.
Iff undergo in which things would not incur a loss of being. In a certain sense, 9 Nietzsche, Will to Power, p. 13.
that would be the sort of therapy required, would it not? 10 See Steven Gait Crowell, "Nietzsche Among the Neo-Kantians; or, The Rela-
tion Between Science and Philosophy," in Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge,
and Critical Theory: Nietzsche and the Sciences I, Babette Babich and Rober S.
Notes Cohen (eds), Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999, pp. 77-86.
11 Edmund Husserl, "Philosophy and the Crisis of European Man," in Phenom-
1 An earlier version of this paper was read at the inaugural meeting of the enology and the Crisis of Philosophy, trans. Quentin Lauer, New York: Harper
Research Centre for Phenomenology and the Human Sciences, The Chinese & Row, 1965, p. 150.
University of Hong Kong. I would like to thank the conference participants for 12 Husserl, "Philosophy as Rigorous Science," in Phenomenology and the Crisis of
very helpful criticisms, especially Professors Cheung Chan-Fai, Kwan Tse-Wan, Philosophy, p. 140.

114 115
<•
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S P H E N O M E N O L O G Y , VALUE T H E O R Y , AND N I H I L I S M

13 See the discussion in Husserl's "Vorlesungen uber Grundfragen der Ethik und and acting reason" should proceed "in as presuppositionless way as possible"
Wertlehre" of 1914, in Edmund Husserl, Vorlesungen uber Ethik und Wertlehre while nevertheless being "guided by the analogy with theoretical, objectifying
1908-1914, Husserliana XXVIII, Ulrich Melle (ed.), Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988, reason" (Hua XXVIII:204). How presuppositionless can that be?
pp. 57-58. Subsequent references to the texts collected in this volume will be 23 Husserl means by this that, for example, desiring something posits it as desir-
given between parentheses in the body of this chapter. able - a claim that we will have reason to challenge below.
14 Husserl's approach to questions of value changed in important ways after 1914. 24 This law is formulated in specifically causal terms at Hua XXVIII:78.
For a fine account of this see Ulrich Melle, "Edmund Husserl: From Reason to 25 Larry Temkin, "Intransitivity and the Mere-Addition Paradox," Philosophy
Love" in Phenomenological Approaches to Moral Philosophy, John Drum- and Public Affairs 16 (1987), 138-187. See also Temkin, Inequality, New York:
mond and Lester Embree (eds), Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002, pp. 229-248.1 shall Oxford, 1993.
ignore these developments here. Though I believe my argument could be 26 Nor is the problem essentially altered if we admit, following Lee, Phanome-
extended to them, to do so would require another paper. nologie der Instinkte, p. 142f, that objectifying acts - both passive and active,
15 Husserl here operates with a general neo-Kantian scheme in which different predicative and pre-predicative - are themselves "wertend" since they are ori-
"validity spheres" (to use Habermas's term) are distinguished: theoretical, ented toward a kind of "satisfaction." For the question concerns whether we
practical, and axiological. I shall not speak further of practical reason in this can make sense of objective criteria for satisfaction as such, without which we
paper. Husserl believes that the practical sphere of "willing" is founded in the cannot speak of a special kind of "reason." And because of their orientation
axiological sphere of "valuing" (for instance, Hua XXVIII:47). At the conclu- toward object-constitution we can specify such criteria in the case of acts that
sion of this paper we shall find some reason to question this view. seek the satisfaction of truth, whereas we cannot in the case of other sorts of
16 Again, crucial parts of the text are devoted \o sorting out the peculiar priority affective valuing.
that belongs to logical reason - oriented toward objective cognition - among 27 This of course does not mean that pre-predicative affectivity is discontinuous
III 1 with all forms of linguistic expression, or predication. It may, for instance, call
the various spheres of validity. The issue is introduced at Hua XXVIII:57-8,
1'» and we shall follow it up in more detail below. Here we need only recall that forth the non-objectifying language of lyric poetry in much the way that per-
"cognitivism" is the term that names precisely the tension between acknowl- ception calls forth object-identifying judgments. If something like this is even
edging the phenomenological distinctiveness of an "axiological" sphere and conceivable, the general question must be asked: is the judgment-form, used to
trying to cash it in in terms of a kind of "reason." express these evaluative "acts," a reliable guide to the normativity that charac-
17 Just as the red that belongs to an object solely insofar as the object is con- terizes the realm of feeling? Is it, for example, true that when I take pleasure in
sidered as reflecting light of a certain frequency would not be the red that we the heft and flow of my pen this entails or tends toward, a claim that, "the pen
express when we say that the object "looks" red. This analogy is elaborated in a is good," that is, toward a norm of correct evaluation? It is certainly true that I
bit more detail below. can make an objective judgment about the quality of the pen - that it is objec-
18 See J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth: tively a good pen. But this is because I can note that it fulfills its function as a
Penguin, 1977, pp. 38-42; on the "error theory" see pp. 48-^49. pen in an exemplary way, and this sort of evaluation does not refer to the
19 John McDowell, "Values and secondary qualities," in Mind, Value, and Reality, sphere of feeling at all. A computer could make such a judgment. On the other
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998, pp. 130-150. hand, just because I express myself in predicate form about some delight I take
20 McDowell, "Values and secondary qualities," p. 134. in something does not mean that that delight is from the start oriented toward a
21 See Edmund Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a pure Phenomenology and to a Phe- norm of objective predication in which a property is attributed to an object.
nomenological Philosophy, Second Book, trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, But to question Husserl's assumption here is to question whether, at the level
Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989, pp. 61, 63-80. There have been several recent of affect itself, there is an analogy with theoretical reason, whether it is plausi-
attempts to develop an account of similar conditions for moral and evaluative ble to speak of "correct" or "incorrect" desiring, hoping, enjoying, and so on.
life - for instance, James Hart, The Person and the Common Life, Dordrecht: Even if we grant a normativity to the affective dimension, it may not be ration-
Kluwer, 1992; Robert Sokolowski, Moral Action: A Phenomenological Study, al - which does not thereby make it irrational either.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985; John Drummond, "Moral Objec- 28 It should be noted that this sort of language derives from the fact that in this
tivity: Husserl's Sentiments of the Understanding," Husserl Studies 12(2) text Husserl is pursuing his question in the framework of the Kantian schema
(1995): 165-183; and John Drummond, "Agency, Agents, and (Sometimes) of practical and theoretical philosophy.
Patients," The Truthful and the Good, John Drummond (ed), Dordrecht: 29 In "Complicating the emotions," a paper deliverd at the 2002 Husserl Circle
Kluwer, 1996, pp. 145-157. Nam-In Lee, Edmund Husserls Phanomenologie meeting in Lima, Peru, John Drummond argued that Husserl in fact possessed
der Instinkte, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1993, p. 134, suggests that the normativity of the means to do so already in the Logical Investigations. It remains to explain,
values and valuing has an instinctual basis: "die Instinktintention ist also der then, why he didn't avail himself of these means in the lectures on value theory.
Ausloser des Lustgeftihls und als solcher stiftet sie, indem sie sich auswirkt, das 30 In his "Value-theory and phenomenology," which introduces the volume
Phanomen des Wertens." I shall not stop to consider these proposals in detail, Phenomenology of Values and Valuing, James Hart and Lester Embree (eds),
however, since my main quarry in this paper is the concept of value itself. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997, p. 5, James Hart registers an anxiety here: Does "the
22 The awkwardness of this procedure, from a phenomenological point of view, topic of value strive to explicate and therefore enrich our appreciation of the
becomes apparent when Husserl remarks that his effort to "clear an open path concrete context of experience," or "is it a bogus notion?" Believing that an
l! to the pure disciplines which supposedly belong to the idea of valuing, striving, "exorcism of value" is not an option for phenomenology, Hart ingeniously
fi
116 117
I

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

assimilates values to "how we experience the world" rather than to "what we


experience" (6). Whether this leaves anything like a rational "theory" of values
intact is not something we can pursue here. 76
31 Martin Heidegger, "The age of the world picture," in The Question Concerning
Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt, New York: Harper &
Row, 1977, p. 142. E D M U N D H U S S E R L
32 Husserl, "The crisis of European man," pp. 150-51.
33 I should add that I am speaking here only of the affects; I am not extending this From reason to love
to the question of ethical obligation, which has a different structure and is
related to affectivity differently than the way Husserl conceived of this relation.
Ethical obligation is not a function of our Befindlichkeit.
Ullrich Melle
I.
Source: John J. Drummond and Lester Embree (eds), Phenomenological Approaches to
Moral Philosophy, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002, pp. 229-248.

1. Introduction
Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) is the founder of phenomenology and the
"phenomenological movement." A mathematician by training, he turned
to philosophy under the influence of Franz Brentano, who grounded philo-
sophy in descriptive introspective psychology. Husserl's first major pubU-
cation - Die Philosophie der Arithmetik (Philosophy of Arithmetic) from
1891 - can be regarded as an application of Brentano's philosophical
method to foundational problems in mathematics. Husserl pubUshed the
Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations) in two volume in 1900
and 1901. The first volume became renowned for its refutation of psy-
chologism, the view that formal sciences such as logic and arithmetic
have to be grounded in psychology as an empirical science. The second
volume contains contributions to what later came to be called a phenom-
enological foundation of the formal sciences and of epistemology. Such a
phenomenological foundation is a foundation in terms of intentional acts
of consciousness in which different kinds of objects, including ideal and
categorial objects, are intended and intuitively given. Phenomenology
was distinguished from descriptive empirical psychology by its eidetic
character. Young philosophers in Gottingen and Munich adopted the
new philosophical method of eidetic description and formed the first
phenomenological movement. They were disenchanted, however, by
Husserl's transcendental turn in his next major publication, Ideen zu
einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenologischen Philosophie,
Erstes Buch (Ideas to a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological
Philosophy, First Book) from 1913. Employing the method of tran-
scendental epoche and reduction, phenomenology now becomes the
analysis of the constitution of intentional objects in transcendental
consciousness.

118 119
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S FROM REASON TO LOVE

In 1928 Martin Heidegger edited Husserl's "Vorlesungen zur Phanom- which Husserl worked rather intensively on axiology and ethics. From
enologie des inneren Zeitbewusstsein" ("Lectures on the phenomenology 1908 until 1914 he gave three lecture courses on axiology and ethics and
of internal time-consciousness") from 1905. A year later, in 1929, Husserl wrote numerous research manuscripts devoted to the phenomenological
published Formale und transzendentale Logik (Formal and Transcendental analysis and description of emotional and volitional consciousness. From
Logic). This work was originaUy intended to be the introduction to an 1920 to 1925 he gave a new lecture course on ethics, published three art-
edition of his manuscripts on genetic logic that he had asked his assistant icles on ethics, and again wrote a great number of research manuscripts in
Ludwig Landgrebe to prepare. Landgrebe's edition, entitled Erfahrung which he addressed axiological and ethical issues. And from 1930-1935 he
und Urteil (Experience and Judgment), appeared only in 1939 after wrote a number of research manuscripts in which he dealt with ethical
Husserl's death. Inspired by lectures he gave at the Sorbonne in Paris in questions in connection with metaphysical considerations.
1929, Husserl pubUshed Meditations Cartesiennes (Cartesian Meditations) While Husserl's prewar axiology and ethics is strongly indebted to
in 1931. His last work was Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und Brentano, Fichte is a major influence on his later ethical thought. At the
die transzendentale Phdnomenologie (The Crisis of European Sciences and center of aU of Husserl's ethics stands the idea and ideal of reason, the
Transcendental Phenomenology). He himself pubUshed only the first two identification of the good with the rational. The human being has to
parts of the work in 1936. The third and final part, which was more than become what it is: animal rationale. The highest form of rationaUty is
half of the work, was held back by him for revision. scientific, i.e., philosophical rationaUty, so that the ethical Ufe as the fully
The number of writings pubUshed by Husserl during his lifetime is relat- rational life is a life guided by scientific insights. But in his later ethics
ively smaU compared to the enormous quantity of his unpublished manu- there is a new point of departure that diverges from the dominant rational-
scripts, which are mostly written in Gabelsberger stenography. While his ism. Possibly inspired by Scheler, Husserl now defines the human being as
published work is largely introductory and programmatic, it is in his animal amans rather than solely as animal rationale.
research manuscripts that again and again he reflected upon his methodol-
ogy and its philosophical impUcations. But above aU, it is there that he
tried to describe in minutest detail the constitution of the world, and of 2. Husserl's early ethics
real and ideal objects, in the passive and active Ufe of transcendental con- The earUest lecture course on ethics of which substantial fragments in
sciousness. manuscript are preserved is the course "Foundational problems of ethics"
Husserl himself published no major work on ethics or practical philo- from summer semester 1902. Husserl deals in this course with the historical
sophy. Only recently has a start been made with the publication of his opposition between ethics of feeling (Gefuhlsmoral) and rationaUst ethics
lecture courses and research manuscripts on axiology and ethics, as well as (Verstandesmoral). He sides with rationaUst ethics in denouncing the sub-
his descriptions of emotional and volitional consciousness. These manu- jectivism and relativism of the ethics of feeling, but he agrees with the
scripts show that Husserl devoted considerable time and effort to develop- ethics of feeling that axiology and ethics are ultimately grounded in acts of
ing the foundations of a phenomenological axiology and ethics. feeling and wiUing. The ultimate origin of our axiological and ethical con-
Already during his early years as lecturer at the University of Halle, cepts are acts of the heart and the wfll. "It is evident that there is absolutely
Husserl regularly gave courses on ethics. Unfortunately, only smaU frag- no talk of 'good* and 'evil' if we abstract from feelings" (Hua 28,394). Fun-
ments of these courses are preserved in manuscript, so that we do not damental to the whole of Husserl's ethics is the conviction that the founda-
know what he taught in these courses. The largest of these fragments is tion of ethics on the acts of the heart and the wfll does not compromise the
from a course on "Ethics and the philosophy of right" from the summer objectivity of values and the ideal validity of ethical principles.
semester of 1897. In these few pages of manuscript, the central concern in This points to a further basic tenet of Husserl's ethics: the idea of paral-
the whole of Husserl's ethical thought is expressed: the refutation of lel or analogous forms of rationality. Rationality, objectivity, ideality, truth
ethical skepticism through a scientific ethics that addresses and settles are not privileges of the inteUect, of logical thought; rather, there are par-
questions of principle. He defines ethics as "the scientific discipline, more allel or analogous forms pertaining to our emotional and volitional acts
precisely, the Kunstlehre, that investigates the highest aims of life, but on and their intentional objects. RationaUty, objectivity, and truth are circum-
the other hand equally strives to formulate rules that should facilitate for scribed by a priori, i.e., universal and ideal, laws. Regarding the intellect
the individual actor a rational order of Ufe and action in relation to these these are the laws of formal logic. If there are forms of emotional and voU-
aims" (Hua 28,384). tional rationality, objectivity, and truth analogous to those of acts of think-
Setting aside this early period, there are three different periods during ing, then there have to be formal laws pertaining to our acts of feeling and

120 121
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

willing analogous to those acts of thinking. This search for analogues to acts of thought. Husserl compares this with the way states of affairs are
the forms and laws of the inteUect in the sphere of the emotional and voli- constituted in acts of judging, but thematized and objectified only in sub-
tional acts - a search that is already announced in his lecture course of sequent acts of nominalization. In such acts a singular gaze is directed
1902 - dominates Husserl's early ethics, i.e., his lecture courses on axiol- toward the constituted state of affairs and it is posited as a categorial
ogy and ethics from the winter semester of 1908/09 and the summer semes- object that can serve as a subject for a further predication, in which case
ters of 1911 and 1914, as well as his many research manuscripts from this yet another state of affairs is constituted.
time analyzing the acts of the heart and of the will. Husserl's early ethics is To sum up, axiological and practical characters and objects are consti-
then an extension of the phenomenological theory of theoretical reason to tuted exclusively by emotional and volitional acts that are founded in pre-
axiological and practical reason, with the overaU aim of elaborating a com- sentations and acts of thought and that require intellectual acts for the
prehensive and unified phenomenological critique and theory of reason. objectification of these characters and objects.
There are three forms of reason and rationality corresponding to the Husserl later revised his conception of the foundational relationship
three fundamental classes of intentional acts: acts of presenting and of between the different classes of acts. He stressed first of aU that a rational
thinking, acts of feeling, and acts of wilUng. In acts of presenting and subjectivity cannot be a pure intellect, merely presenting and predicating a
thinking, objects are given and conceived of in their purely factual deter- pure factuaUty. It necessarily engages emotionally and practically in the
minations; in acts of feeling they are given with value-characters, in acts of given world, constituting values and practical objects, i.e., a cultural world.
wiUing with practical characters. Each of the three classes of acts com- More importantly, instead of a one-sided foundational relationship
prises a number of different kinds of acts with their corresponding inten- between the intellectual acts on the one side and the emotional and voli-
tional objects. The most fundamental act of presenting is perception, in tional acts on the other side, there is rather a mutual foundation. Intellec-
which an object is given in its bodily presence. Remembering and imagin- tual acts themselves are practical acts, doings that in their purest form
ing are modifications of perception. In these acts an object is intuitively strive for truth as their aim, which is chosen as an aim because of its value.
given - not, however, in its bodily presence, but as being past or being fic- Intellectual, emotional, and volitional acts interpenetrate each other.
titious. Acts of thought proper are categorial acts that articulate and expli- According to the "method of analogy," the phenomenology and
cate in categorial forms objects given in non-categorial intuitions. The critique of theoretical reason can serve as a paradigm for the phenom-
most fundamental value-giving act is the general feeling of pleasure enology and critique of axiological and practical reason. The phenom-
(Gefallen) and its opposite, displeasure (Misfallen), conceived in a very enology of reason is the phenomenology of the ways we acquire truth in
broad way as liking or disliking something. Joy and distress are other our intentional act-life. These ways are quite different depending on the
important feelings. In the class of the voUtional acts, there is the fundamen- kind of object the truth is about, whether it is a mathematical proposition,
tal distinction between the voUtional acts preceding the action (the wishing a thing, a past event, or a value. But truth is always acquired in particular
and desiring, the choosing and deciding); the fiat that initiates the action; kinds of evidencing, in processes of fulfillment of empty intentions by
and the volitional act that supports the action and Uves in the action. intentions that bring the intended object to intuitive presence.
The three classes of acts are not unrelated. There exists instead a neces- According to Husserl, it was the great discovery of Brentano that there
sary foundational relationship between acts of the three classes. Acts of were forms of evidence pertaining to non-objectifying acts (i.e., emotional
feeling are necessarily founded in acts of presenting and thinking; acts of and voUtional acts) that are the exact analogue to the forms of evidence
willing are necessarily founded in acts of feeling, and through these acts pertaining to the objectifying acts. We acquire truth not only in our intel-
of feeling in acts of presenting and thinking. Something has to be given in lectual acts of presenting and thinking, but also in our acts of feeling and
a presentation or thought that can then give rise to a feeUng giving the willing - a truth, however, that can only be expressed and articulated in
object a value; the object having a certain value can further motivate my subsequent acts of thought. A value, for example, can first be emptily
willing and acting. intended in a vague feeling. I can then enter into a process of further and
The emotional and volitional acts are dependent on acts of presenting further clarification of my feeling toward that particular object; I can try to
and thinking in yet another sense. In pleasure and displeasure, a value or feel the overall value of that object more clearly by running through the
disvalue is felt but not presented or predicted, i.e., it is not posited and different value-aspects, just as I get to know the object in its factual deter-
objectified as a value. It is similar with acts of wilUng: these acts constitute minations more clearly by looking at it from different sides. Similarly,
practical meanings and characters, such as means and ends, desirability, or there are peculiar kinds of emptiness, fulfillment, and evidencing in the
action, but to talk about them, we have to thematize and objectify them in domain of the volitional acts.

122 123
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

Making use of the "method of analogy," a comprehensive phenom- field of theoretical knowledge. If logic is the ideal science of the laws of
enology of axiological and practical reason has to analyze and describe thought, then ethics should be the ideal science of the laws of wilUng and
these different kinds of emptiness, fulfillment, and evidencing. As acting. This parallelism between logic and ethics is the main subject in
Husserl's numerous research manuscripts devoted to the analysis and Husserl's lecture courses on axiology and ethics from 1908/09, 1911, and
description of the acts of the wfll and of the heart show, this is a very 1914.
demanding task. He himself speaks of "a jungle of interlaced analyses." It A crucial distinction regarding the a priori conditions of possibility of
is a major question whether the method of analogy does not prejudge the truth is the distinction between purely formal and material conditions of
analyses, functioning as an unphenomenological straitjacket through possibility, in the case of theoretical knowledge between formal logic and
which the emotional and volitional act-life is pressed into a foreign mold. material logic. Formal logic abstracts from aU subject matter investigating
For example, Husserl's analyses of the experience in which a value is only the forms of meaning; the combination of these forms into meaning-
originally given in feeling leaves unresolved the problem oLto what intel- ful propositions; and the concatenation of these propositional forms into
lectual act this feeling is an analogue. There are three candidates: a per- valid inferences and complex chains of reasoning, and ultimately into
ception, a doxic position-taking, or a categorial act. Depending on the whole theory-forms. Validity is here purely formal and is grounded in the
candidates chosen, the value or value-object has a different ontological essence of the fundamental categories of meaning. Beyond these formal
status: in the first case it is a given quasisensuous object, in the second case conditions for the truth of propositions and inferences, there are a priori
a noematic character, and in the third case an actively constructed object material conditions grounded in the essence of the particular subject
of a higher order. Only rarely does Husserl compare the original value- matter of the proposition. A proposition about a material thing cannot
giving act with a full categorial act of thought. He does point out that there possibly be true if it fulfills the formal conditions of truth but offends
are emotional analogues to such categorial acts, e.g , a plural, many-rayed against the ontology of the material thing.
act of love as a coUective loving. But for the most part, he conceives of the The difference between matter and form belongs to the essence of
primordial value-giving act either as a value-perception (Wertnehmung as reason in general, and thus not only to theoretical but equally to axiologi-
the analog of Wahrnehmung) or as a position-taking. cal and practical reason. Just as logic in the broad sense has a formal and a
Like the perception of spatial and material objects, value-perceptiqn is material part, so axiology and ethics must have a formal and a material
supposed to come about through the apperception, the ensouling interpre- part. Ethics thus far lacks the formal disciplines, formal axiology and
tation, of sense data; the difference is only that the sense data here are formal praxis, that are the analogues of formal logic. Husserl regarded the
sensuous feelings founded in perceptual sense data. One of the main prob- development of these formal disciplines in his lecture courses on axiology
lems with this account is that just as perception is not yet theoretical and ethics as his most original and important contribution to the history of
reason in the full and proper sense, neither can value-perception be axio- ethics. He does'acknowledge his indebtedness to Brentano. Brentano's
logical reason in the full and proper sense. The question of rationaUty and seminal 1889 text Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis (The Origin of our
truth is reaUy addressed to the active and spontaneous position-takings of Knowledge of Right and Wrong), Husserl remarks, was the impulse to all
the ego as they occur in acts of judging. This leads Husserl to conceive of his attempts to develop a formal axiology. Brentano had already formu-
the value-giving acts as such as non-doxic position-takings. The axiological lated a number of formal axiological and practical laws, without, however,
and practical characteristics become analogues of doxic characters like conceiving of the possibiUty and necessity of a formal axiology and ethics.
"being doubtful," "being probable," etc. Husserl does not come to a final The first candidate for a formal-practical law is Kant's hypothetical
conclusion regarding how to conceive of the acts of feeling in which values imperative formulated as a general law: "The one who wants a particular
are given to us originaUy. aim equally wants the means that are necessary to reach that aim." This is
Truth and the acts of evidencing in which truth is acquired are governed neither a psychological nor a logical law. It does not claim that the wanting
by ideal laws. These laws are the subject matter of ideal sciences. Objectiv- of the means is a real part of the wanting of the aim, nor does it say that
ity and truth are thus inseparable from ideaUty, from the ideal validity of the wanting of the means is logically contained in the wanting of the aim.
principles that express the necessary conditions of objectivity and truth. In It is not a logical contradiction to want the aim but not the means; it is
his famous refutation of psychologism in the Prolegomena to the Logical unreasonable in a purely practical sense.
Investigations Husserl showed that the denial of the ideality of the logical Husserl goes on to formulate a number of formal-axiological laws of the
laws and their empirical grounding in psychological, anthropological, or transference and derivation of values, e.g., "If V is of value and if it holds
biological facts led to a self-contradictory skepticism and relativism in the that if A, then V, then with regard to this relationship A equaUy is of

124 125
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

value" or "If a property is valuable, then each object having this property best. For this we need a material axiology and praxis. "Were there no
is valuable because of it." There is a formal-axiological analogue of the material a priori, were there no types and famiUes of objects that carried a
formal-logical laws of contradiction and of the excluded middle. In the axi- priori predicates of values, then the concept of objective value would have
ological realm, however, we have a middle between positive and negative no support, and consequently there would be no support for the idea of an
values in the form of value-neutraUty, so that the formal-axiological ana- objectively preestablished prefer ability and for the idea of a 'best'" (Hua
logue to the formal-logical laws of contradiction and of the excluded 28,139). Formal axiology and praxis are "only a small, albeit the most fun-
middle takes the following form: "If M is in itself of value, then it is not in damental, part of the task of a scientific and first of aU a priori ethics"
itself of disvalue and it is not in itself value-neutral and vice versa accord- (Hua 28,140).
ing to all disjunctive combinations." Husserl did not develop this material part of axiology and ethics
Then there are formal-axiological laws that have no analogue in formal systematicaUy and in detail, neither in his early nor in his late ethics. His
logic. These deal with the ranking of values. Yet other formal-axiological material axiology consists of an elementary classification of values into
laws deal with axiological parts and wholes. existential values and values of appearance, i.e., aesthetic values, and dis-
From formal axiology we move into formal praxis if we consider the tinguishes between sensuous, hedonistic values and spiritual values.
formal laws of preference and choice. The most fundamental of these laws Regarding the spiritual values, he usually distinguishes three basic kinds:
is the law of absorption: "In every choice the better absorbs the good and aesthetic values, epistemic values, and the values of rational self-love and
the best absorbs everything else that is in itself to be valued as good." If of love of neighbor. The altruistic values of love of neighbor are the specif-
we relate this law of absorption to a Umited domain of practical pos- icaUy moral values. Occasionally he adds as a fourth category, religious
sibilities, Brentano's categorical imperative arises: "Do the best that is values. Regarding the ranking of the values, a clear order of rank only
attainable!" Husserl formulates it as follows in his lecture course from exists between the sensuous and the spiritual values: sensuous values have
1911: "Formal praxis leads to a highest formal principle, which in the first value only as means for making spiritual values possible. Among the spir-
place rests on the principle 'The better is the enemy of the good.' This itual values themselves no such definite and generaUy vaUd rank can be
principle says 'Do the best that is attainable!' That is, of course, a noetic established. "If one of the classes, e.g., the class of the moral goods, i.e.,
expression. Objectively, the expression would be: the best attainable the goods of the love of neighbor, were distinguished as the absolutely
within the entire practical sphere is not merely the best comparatively higher and highest one, then each scientist and artist at once would be an
speaking, but rather the sole practical good'" (Hua 28, 221). This highest ethically bUnd or bad person" (Ms. F I 40,140a). This does not mean that
formal principle of praxis is the fundamental law of practical truth. It is a scientist or artist is never ethicaUy obliged to help others; in some situ-
formal in the sense that it does not determine in advance what the best ations moral values outweigh the epistemic or aesthetic values he is pursu-
attainable is in a particular situation. But in contrast to the formal logical ing. But it is not that whenever there is a conflict between moral values on
laws, it does not determine only the necessary condition of practical truth. the one side and epistemic and aesthetic values on the other, the latter
A proposition that conforms to the formal logical laws can stiU be false, have to yield. The duty of a scientist to his work can and often does out-
whereas a willing and acting conforming to the highest formal principle of weigh the obUgation to help his needful neighbors.
praxis is necessarily true.
Noetically, the principle is formulated as a categorical, i.e., uncondi-
3. The transition to the later ethics
tional, imperative but the possibility of such a categorical imperative
depends on the existence of a closed practical field that comprises a finite The previous quotation is from the extensive section on axiology and
number of practical possibflities at each moment the subject deliberates ethics in Husserl's lecture course "Introduction to philosophy" from
upon what to do. Such a practical field will necessarily be different for dif- winter semester 1919/20, which documents the transition from his early to
ferent subjects; accordingly, the best attainble will be different for differ- his later ethics. In this section he takes over from his earUer lecture
ent subjects at each moment. But the best in each field is objectively the courses the derivation of a categorical imperative from the law of absorp-
best. The formal conditions of rational preference and choice can then be tion: the better is the enemy of the good. But he introduces two important
summarized as follows: wiUing must aim at its own practical possibilities; it revisions. First, the practical domain includes at each moment an open
must grasp the entire realm of its practical possibiUties; and it must find future horizon of practical possibflities that are or might be attainable and
and choose the highest value from all the values therein. that have to be taken into account at the moment of choice. The categori-
iii.
Formal praxis cannot tell us whether what we choose is actually the cal imperative demands then "to choose the positive good that is the best

126 127
FROM REASON TO LOVE
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

in the whole, of the practical sphere, this sphere at the moment of choice from 1919/20 point to a central theme of Husserl's later ethics: the
stretching into the endless open future" (Ms. F I 40, 132a). But Husserl absolute ought grounded in the personal love and calUng of the subject.
does not explain how in the moment of moral deliberation and decision I The two notes in the manuscript from 1919/20 can be compared with
can take account of an endless horizon of future practical possibflities. another note found in a research manuscript from a few years later in
Second, Husserl stresses that the ethical value of the will does not which Husserl refers again to Geiger's criticism and renounces his earlier
depend on objective attainabihty, but only on what the acting subject is axiological and utilitarian ethics, which he had adopted from Brentano.
convinced of as being attainable. Nor does it depend on the objective "Should the mother first deliberate and make such considerations of the
values or disvalues involved, but only on what the subject posits as values highest possible good? This whole ethics of the highest practical good such
or disvalues. "If we prefer according to our best knowledge and conscience as it was derived from Brentano and taken over by me in its essential traits
the best of what is attainable, we have acted ethically, then and only then cannot be the last word. Essential delimitations are needed! Vocation and
our will is absolutely right" (Ms. F140,132b). If it turns out, however, that inner calling cannot be done justice in this way. There exists an uncondi-
we have been wrong in our convictions about attainability and values, we tional 'you ought and must' that addresses itself to the person and that is
may be blamed for not having previously chosen to educate our abilities of not subject to a rational justification and does not depend for its legitimate
judging, evaluating, and preferring correctly, so that our "best knowledge obligation (rechtmassige Bindung) on such a justification for the one who
and conscience" would not be our actual knowledge and conscience, but experiences this absolute affection. This affection precedes all rational
the one we could have had if we had educated our intellectual and moral explanation even where such an explanation is possible" (Ms. B 121,65a).
abflities properly. After the exposition of the categorical imperative in the lecture course
Summing up his exposition of the categorical imperative, Husserl states from 1919/20, Husserl introduces two other important topics of his later
that it "expresses an evident, absolute validity, a law, how the motivation ethics. The categorical imperative reaUy only becomes properly categori-
of a will has to be so that the will is an ethically good one, so that what is cal if I decide from now on to act according to it, if I make it into a law of
wflled is something that absolutely ought to be - indeed not only this: it my wiUing. The moment I realize that this general lawful wilUng itself is a
expresses lawfully an unconditionally vaUd positive criterion of the ethi- practical possibiUty in my practical domain, it becomes the highest ethical
cally good and bad will" (Ms. F140,133a). obUgation for me. I can be ethicaUy good only if I decide always to act
In the middle of the exposition of the categorical imperative, the manu- according to the law. The truly ethical will is a general will that transforms
script contains a critical note that opens with the statement: "I shall have the whole life of a person into an ethical life.
to give up the whole teaching of the categorical imperative or else define it A particular form of such a general wiU is the choice of a vocation. The
anew" (Ms. F I 40, 131b). The reason for this radical revision is what categorical imperative can and usuaUy does demand that one devote
Husserl calls in the note "the problem of love." The question is whether oneself throughout his whole life to one particular class of values. Weigh-
the practical good that is acknowledged by me to be the objectively best is ing the practical possibflities of one's future life, one comes to the conclu-
actually for me that which absolutely ought to be. I can experience a per- sion that one can realize the greatest amount of practical good by
sonal and pure love of particular values that is different from the valuing specializing in the pursuit of one particular kind of good, e.g., as a scientist
as weU as from the enjoyment of the possession of the value. or an artist. This, of course, does not imply that we can neglect the goods
There is a second supplementary critical note later in the manuscript of the other classes completely. Since there does not exist an a priori order
that elaborates this point further. Again this second note opens with a of rank between the different classes of goods, the categorical imperative
clear renunciation of an ethics based on the categorical imperative. does not demand from anybody to realize goods of one class exclusively.
Already in 1907, Mortiz Geiger, Husserl remarks, had correctly pointed In his later ethics, the themes of the general will and of the call to a
out to him that it would be absurd to demand from a mother to first delib- particular vocation will no longer be linked to the categorical imperative,
erate whether the fulfillment of the need of her child is the best in her but to the absolute ought of love.
practical domain. One has to distinguish between the objective value and The lecture course from 1919/20 marks the transition to Husserl's late
the same value as an individual, subjective value of love. A pure and true ethics in yet another respect. In it Husserl moves from individual ethics to
love is not only a value-perception, but a loving embrace and choice of the social ethics, claiming that any fully developed individual ethics leads
value out of the most inward center of the subject. For practical reason necessarily into community-ethics. Each person is born into a community
these subjective values are of particular relevance. and forms a community with other persons in social acts. A true commun-
These critical notes enclosed in the manuscript of the lecture course ity itself functions Uke a person; it has the form of a personaUty of a higher

128 129
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

order. The categorical imperative demands that the community strive to makes at the end of this lecture course between the axiological and the
realize the best of the attainable common goods. Husserl stresses, ethical standpoint. A theory of values and goods is not yet an ethics. To do
however, that the community has no life and identity separate from the the best in axiological terms is not yet to do what ought to be done, even if
life and identity of its members. All its valuing, willing, and acting is the value of what has been done is not irrelevant. One can do the best but
executed through the valuing, willing, and acting of its individual without moral disposition. The question whether I am a moral person is
members. "The social-ethical aim that a community has to pursue has its therefore completely different from the question whether I am a valuable
reason only by being rooted in and being demanded by the individual aims person. With the ethical self-evaluation, the measure Ues in me - it is the
of the members of the community. The community only lives in the Ufe of absolute idea of my moral personaUty, and the question is how close I
the associated individuals in such a way that the individuals know them- have approached this idea.
selves through acts of consciousness of the type of the 'social act' as func- Husserl then refers to the ethical will that gives itself a norm for the
tionaries of the community, that is, that they know that they execute in whole of Ufe and that is directed toward the universal fulfillment of the
such acts acts of community" (Ms. F140,170a). norm just as the choice of a vocation is the choice of a certain normative
The ethically highest form of community, a form that is categorically rule and of the direction toward its fulfillment. The vocational will,
required, is the community of humankind. Humankind must not remain a however, does not, as the ethical will does, comprise all spheres of one's
mere collective unity, but has to transform itself into a unity of a social life.
personality, a universal community of ends (Zweckgemeinscha.fi) that sees An important theme in the lecture course from 1920 is the ontology of
its highest common end in the highest possible elevation of all individuals. the spirit and the argument against the naturaUstic reduction of spirit to
By the joint work of their members, communities create' a cultural mechanical nature. Spiritual life is personal life, be it in the form of an
world out of a pregiven nature. Possible forms of culture correspond to individual person or in the form of a social personality of a higher order.
possible forms of community. Communities are part of their own environ- Husserl's later ethics is grounded above all in such an ontology of the
ment; they can cultivate and educate themselves. Cultures themselves as spirit or of personal Ufe.
products of common choices and work can be ethically evaluated. The cat- Only a person can form an ethical will because orily a person has a con-
egorical demand for an ethicaUy highest form of a universal human ception of the wholeness and unity of his life, i.e., of its past and future
community has its correlate in the categorical demand for an ethically horizons. The ethical will is the will to change one's life as a whole and to
highest form of universal human culture. The best possible culture of an give it a new form and purpose. Husserl accordingly speaks of the
ethically best humankind is an ethical ideal in the form of an infinite task "amazing phenomenon of the self-direction and self-making of the I by the
that gives our world an a priori necessary ethical teleology. It is the task of I" and of "the most amazing self-renewal" (Ms. F128,134a).
ethics to work out the system of ideals and norms implied in this task.
The lecture course "Introduction to ethics" from the summer semester
4. Husserl's later ethics
1920 (repeated in the summer semester of 1924) resumes the topic of his
early course from 1902: the historidal opposition between an ethics of Husserl's later ethical thought is much broader in scope than his early
feeling and a rationalistic ethics. The lecture course contains historical ethics, and is often connected with theological and metaphysical consider-
expositions and critiques of hedonism, of the ethical rationalism of the ations. It consists of a number of recurrent themes, issues, and views, but it
Cambridge Platonists Cudworth and Clark, of Shaftesbury's ethical aes- is not shaped into a coherent and systematic unity. Most of it has not
theticism, of Hume's naturaUstic ethics of feeling, and of Kant's rationalis- moved beyond the research manuscript stage.
tic ethics. As to the allegiance of his own position, Husserl remarks at the The indebtedness of his later ethical thought to Fichte is perhaps not as
end of the manuscript: "not mentioned unfortunately the kinship with the strong as the indebtedness of his early ethics to Brentano, but as the lec-
Fichtean ethics" (Ms. F I 28, 200a). He reaffirms the paraUelism between tures, on Fichte that Husserl gave to wounded German soldiers in 1917
intellectual acts of knowing and evaluative acts, between epistemological show, and as Husserl himself acknowledged,. Fichte's ethico-reUgious
and evaluative reason, and correspondingly between logic and ethics; idealism influenced him greatly (cf. Hua 25, 267-93). In these lectures
between formal logic, formal axiology, and formal praxis. What is missing, Husserl speaks admiringly of Fichte's reconfiguration of the ideals of true
though, is the derivation of a formal categorical imperative. But neither humanity. He calls Fichte's activist conception of subjectivity, according to
does Husserl talk about love and the values of love. Pointing to this new which to be a subject means to be an actor through and through, a thought
ethical perspective in his late ethics is, however, the expUcit distinction he of enormous boldness. This conception of subjectivity implies that a

130 131
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

subject is historical, moving on from action to action in an unending chain community and through their association in a social movement for the
of ends and tasks. The whole creation of the world in the absolute inteUi- ethical renewal of their life in common.
gence is only for the sake of humans, to offer them opportunities for free True knowledge not only of facts but of values and aims is the precondi-
action and ethical self-perfection, the final end being a moral world-order. tion for a rational-ethical life. It is the task of science and of philosophy as
The world- and self-creation is determined by an ethical teleology. Husserl the universal and ultimately justified science to acquire such knowledge. It
points out that in Fichte's later metaphysics and philosophy of religion, is through philosophy that individuals as well as their communities and
God is no longer identified with the moral world-order, and religious life is cultures reach the highest stage of autonomy and reason so that the ethical
no longer identical with ethical life; the latter is only a step toward the ful- life is a philosophical life, a life guided by philosophical insight. The idea
fillment of the human destination, which consists in unity with God. All of philosophy as a science motivated by a purely theoretical interest and
life in its deepest ground is God's life. All life wants to be blissful Ufe and the ideal of a truly autonomous life guided by scientific reason we owe to
the truer a life, the more love and bUss. the ancient Greeks. But for Husserl this idea and ideal are valid for all
AU of these Fichtean themes will resurface in Husserl's later ethics and humans and for all cultures; it is a categorical imperative for each indi-
metaphysics. Fichte's popular ethical writings may even have been the vidual and for all humankind.
model for Husserl's important articles on "Renewal" that he published in The Kaizo articles, and the research manuscripts related to these art-
1923/24 in the Japanese journal The Kaizo. icles, however, give only an incomplete and one-sided picture of Husserl's
These articles express a radical ethical rationalism in which the Kantian later ethical thought. The theme of love and of the values of love is almost
ideas of rational self-rule and of the dualism between irrational impulses completely absent. At one place Husserl refers to the love for a particular
and rational self-determination are central. Husserl defines ethics here as class of values as motivating the choice of a vocation. But according to
"the science of the whole acting life of a rational subjectivity under the Husserl,' to follow such a professional caUing is only a pre-ethical form of
viewpoint of reason that regulates this whole life uniformly" (Hua 27,21). self-ruUng.
Ethics and the science of practical reason are identical. Ethical life is As already mentioned, the foundation of Husserl's later ethics is an
guided by the ideal of reason, which is an ideal of perfection. The perfect ontology of the person, both of the individual and of the collective person.
life is the fully rational life, a life that can be ultimately justified in all its There are three essential characteristics of a person. First, persons make
activities. themselves into what they are by their freely chosen acts. They are
Husserl introduces a new concept to characterize the ethical life. Such a responsible for their own being. The character, habits, and dispositions of
life begins with a decision for a radical renewal: "Renewal of the human a person are formed by the spontaneous acts of thinking, valuing, and
being - renewal of both the single person and the community— is the chief willing that do not simply evaporate after their actual performance,
theme of ethics. Ethical life is essentially and consciously inspired by the making room for new acts, but endure as lasting convictions, evaluations,
idea of renewal; it is a life intentionally led and formed by this idea" (Hua and decisions. New acts can reaffirm and strenghten these convictions,
27, 20). The idea of cultural renewal had great currency ^after the devasta- evaluations, and decisions or weaken and change them. The character,
tions of World War I. The decision for such a renewal is, according to habits, and dispositions of a person are formed by a process of sedimenta-
Husserl, a decision for a radical new beginning, for a new life of rational tion of spontaneous acts.
self-rule. It impUes a determined struggle with irrational impulses, bad A person, however, is not pure spontaneity and freedom. She has a
habits, and false ideals,.a rigorous pulling-oneself-together. Such a renewal twofold dimension of passivity, original and secondary passivity. Original
is not a singular event but a permanent task: the wiU to renewal must itself passivity precedes any activity and spontaneity, while secondary passivity
be renewed constantly. The ethical life is therefore a Ufe of methodical is the result of. the sedimentation of prior spontaneous acts. Original pas-
self-cultivation, self-discipline, and self-control. sivity comprises the primary constitution of temporal and associative
Since human personhood is related to a community, individual and unities in the stream of consciousness and of the temporal and associative
,1 social ethics are inseparable. The concern for my personal ethical life unity of the stream itself. It further consists of primal instincts and drives.
> includes the concern for the ethical life of the others and of the community The sphere of original passivity is the ground of the spontaneous and
as a whole. The community itself can and should become a personal rational activity of the ego; it affects the ego and elicits its responses. For
subjectivity and an ethical subject that stands under the categorical imper- Husserl, this is not always and only a sphere of irrationality that opposes,
ative of reason. A community becomes an ethical community only through resists, or undermines the autonomy and rationality of the ego; rather, it is
the ethical reflections of the individual subjects about themselves and their teleologically oriented toward autonomy and rationaUty. Already at its

132 133
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

deepest level of passivity, personal life is characterised by a tendency, a child has an instinctual ground that is absent in the professional calling. A
general wiU toward rational self- and world-creation. purely instinctual love can, however, be refined into a pure love.
The second essential characteristic of personal life is implied by the Husserl now distinguishes between two completely different kinds of
first: personal Ufe is historical; a person has a history. A person is con- values: objective values and values of love. The first are given in a value-
cerned about her history, i.e., about her Ufe as a whole. Therefore, the reception as objective characters of the object; the second are given to the
ethical question is always twofold: "What to do in this particular situ- object through the love of the subject. This love is something active; in one
ation?" and "How to transform my life as a whole into an ethical life?" place, Husserl calls it "a personal decision of the active heart," indicating
The concern about my life as a whole becomes an ethical concern that it can no longer be classified as a mere feeling, but involves an
through an ethical epoche, a bracketing of my whole previous Ufe and a element of choice.
universal critique of it oriented toward a radical renewal according to The values of love take absolute precedence over the objective values.
ethical ideals. A person can draw together the totality of her previous Ufe "Over and against a value that is absolutely rooted in the T itself and that
and can come to the insight that her first life was neither happy nor good has arisen from love (as absolute love), over and against such a value an
because it was a life of dispersion and drifting or a naive life guided by objective value counts for nothing . . . " (Ms. B I 21, 53b). All absolute
unquestioned traditional acceptances. She can then make a solemn values are equally absolute, so that the law of absorption cannot be
decision that encompasses her entire future life from then on, a decision to applied to values of love. In case of conflict between absolute values, there
Uve a life determined solely by her own critically tested and rational posi- is no rational preference of one value for the other; there is only the tragic
tion-takings, that is, a radically self-determined and self-responsible life. sacrifice of one absolute value for another equally absolute value. And
The ideal is a life wherein each "position-taking" is completely and defi- since I am who am I by loving such a value absolutely, I sacrifice myself in
nitely justified and accounted on the basis of one's own insight. Such sacrificing this value.
insight founds convictions, evaluations, and decisions that are no longer The categorical imperative and the law of absorption from his early ethics
threatened by falsification. The ideal is a life based on a completely good are now demoted to the status of the rational norm for our non-ethical Ufe.
theoretical, axiological, and practical conscience - a life with no regrets. All non-ethical values are hedonistic values, values of pleasure and enjoy-
As it is expressed in a manuscript from 1931: "The T must be able to look ment. Husserl fllustrates the difference between the two kinds of values by
.t at, survey, and appraise its entire active life in such a way that all the referring to the difference between the dedicated professional scientist and
decisions that it accomplishes and has accomplished can be continually the amateur of science. The first is not striving for enjoyment; science for him
affirmed in the will" (Ms. A V 22, 22a). This ideal of an absolutely rational is a holy cause and it is his destiny. But for the amateur, science or art are
Ufe is the ideal of a person who would be absolutely true to herself and objects of enjoyment and recreation. A rational preference in terms of higher
who would preserve herself in all her acts, the "herself" referring here not and lower values and of the best that is attainable is possible only regarding
to an empty pole of identity, but to the self-formed character of the these hedonistic values. Choosing differently here is not immoral but, foohsh.
person. Two questions arise now. First, what is the relationship between the
A person - and this is the third essential characteristic - is who she is non-ethical or hedonistic and the ethical values of love? Is there still room
most inwardly by her love and calling. To each person belongs her own for a non-ethical life, a kind of vacation from the arduous ethical task? Or
individual ethical ideal. Every person receives from the depths of her is the pursuit of hedonistic values ethically only legitimate insofar as it fur-
personaUty her own absolute values, her values of love. Such a value is an thers the realization of the ethical projects? Secondly, and more import-
absolute 'ought,' and "to go against this value is to be untrue, to lose antly, what does practical reason still mean regarding the values of love?
oneself, to betray one's true 'I,'" which amounts to an "absolute practical Are these personal values of love - is my individual calling - not an irra-
contradiction" (Ms. B I 21, 53a). We have to foUow the caU of our indi- tional facticity, something that I have not rationally chosen on the ground
vidual conscience; we have to realize and preserve our true genuine self, of evidential acts of knowing, valuing, and willing?
be true to our deepest self, to the absolute ought of our pure love. Husserl does not give a clear answer to the first question. But if the
The two rather different examples for such personal values .of love choice of hedonistic values had to be justified by their instrumental value
Husserl usually gives in his manuscripts are the love of the mother for her for the realization of ethical values, then the categorical imperative and
child and the professional calling to be a scientist, an artist, or a politician. the law of absorption would no longer have any practical role to play. The
It may be that Husserl thought of motherhood as being analogous to a best of the attainable hedonistic values might not be the best in instrumen-
professional calling. He does point out that the love of the mother for her tal terms for the realization of my values of love.

134 135
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS FROM REASON TO LOVE

As for the second question, Husserl acknowledged the irrationaUty of forms of community? What is the ethical ideal of a community beyond the
the absolute ought if it is looked at in isolation. The absolute ought of the individual ideals of its members? If the analogy with the individual ideals
individual person has its rational meaning only in a theological context. holds, it has to be something Uke a calUng to create a culture rich in certain
The absolute ought has "its highest, rational and therefore intelUgible values, other communities being called to create cultures rich in other
sense in a divine world" (Ms. A V 21,122a). values. The communities themselves then could form a yet higher
Basic to Husserl's conception of the divine world and of the ultimate community of communities. Ultimately there would be a universal
telos of the ethical life is a communitarian ideal. It is constitutive of the community of communities that would be a community of love where the
person to be in community with other persons. A subject becomes a member communities would mutuaUy help each other to realize their true
person only through communicative and social acts. The ethical life of a community-calUng. This universal community of communities would be a
person is therefore inextricably interwoven with the ethical life of other personaUty of a higher order only in the sense that a common will is
persons. directed to the reaUzation of each member's true community-self. But it
It is a task of formal ethics to distinguish the different forms and types would not itself have a true self and an ethical ideal that would transcend
of communities and to determine the form of the ethical community. In that of its individual member communities.
two important manuscripts from 1921 on the common life, Husserl distin- This possible reconstruction of Husserl's communitarian ideal appears,
guishes three forms of community (see Hua 14, 165-84, 192-204). The however, to be in conflict with the claim that one particular culture and
community of love is a community where the aims and strivings of each community - namely the European culture - has a universal calling, the
member are part of the aims and strivings Of every other member. The ethical ideal being a Ufe and culture of reason that for Husserl is identical
truly ethical community of love would be a community where aU with a scientific or philosophical Ufe and culture. What is missing in
the members mutually help each other to realize their true selves. The Husserl's manuscripts is an expUcit and systematic reflection on the rela-
community of accumulative production is a historical community where tionship between love and reason, between the community of love and the
the work of each member increases a common stock. Husserl's prime community of reason. It is interesting to note that the discourse of reason
example is the generational community of the scientists. The community is predominant in Husserl's published writings, whereas the discourse of
of the scientists is different from a mere community of language because love is to be found almost exclusively in research manuscripts.
the scientists form personal relations with each other by addressing each Reason and love, Husserl seems to think, are one only if placed into
other and reacting to each other regarding their work. What is lacking in their full context of a divine world-order. Only through faith in God can
this form of community, however, is a consciously formed common will. we overcome any apparent contradiction between the rule of reason and
This common wiU is constitutive of the third form of community, which the rule of love.
has the character of a personality of a higher order. These personaUties of A rational faith (Vernunftglaube) in God gives ultimate meaning to my
a higher order are more than the sum of the individual members of the absolute ought in yet another sense. Only through faith in God and in a
community. They have their own ethical ideal, their own true and ideal world led by God am I able to withstand the despair about what Husserl
self, and it is to the communal realization of the true self of the community once caUed "the fate- and death-structure of the world," irrational anom-
that its members are called. The true self, the absolute ought of the aUes such as blows of fate, natural catastrophes, and sudden and early
community, must be made communally conscious: it must be clarified and death, as well as all the suffering and unhappiness in the world. In the pur-
formed into a common will so that the true self of the community becomes suance of the ethical ideal we have to cope with regular setbacks. This
a moment of the true self of the individual. ideal is an infinite ideal of perfection that we can strive for and work
I' Husserl variously regards all three forms of community as the ethical toward and in some sense approximate, but without ever coming closer to
form of community. The second form clearly corresponds to a production its realization. In the face of the fate- and death-structure of the world the
paradigm that was characteristic of Husserl's early ethics. The rationale of desperate question arises whether aU my ethical strivings are not ulti-
ethics is the maximum production of objective values such as scientific mately in vain. I have to beUeve that my life and the world make sense,
truths or works of art. His later ethics can be seen as a critique of this pro- that my ethical will counts. "The world must be beautiful and good, it must
duction paradigm. The community of love seems to be the communitarian be a universally teleological world. Human activity must be led by God,
ideal belonging to Husserl's ethics of love and of the values of love. What and still be free and responsible. The free activity and its sinful errors and
is not clear is how the first and the third form of community are related to aU teleological irrationalities must be a medium of universal teleology, and
each other. Is the ultimate ethical ideal and telos a synthesis of these two everthing therein must bear a teleological function, so that a human life in

136 137
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S FROM REASON TO LOVE

the world is possible as an energetic life with final ends" (Ms. A V 21,20a). — . The Person and the Common Life: Studies in Husserlian Social Ethics. Dor-
I have to beUeve that acting in accordance with our ethical caUing has the drecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992.
power to overcome blind fate and evil because God is with us. "The Summum Bonum and Value-Wholes: Aspects of a Husserlian Axiology
The faith in God is the condition of possibiUty for genuine self- and Theology". In Phenomenology of Values and Valuing. Ed. James G. Hart
realization and self-preservation of a self. It is a faith necessitated by a and Lester E. Embree, 193-230. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997.
Melle, Ullrich. "Objektivierende und nicht-objektivierende Akte." In Husserl-
practical motive, "the motive of a possible Ufe of practical reason" (Ms. A
Ausgabe und Husserl-Forschung. Ed. Samuel IJsseling, 35^19. Dordrecht:
V 21, 21b). This faith is self-verifying. "In order to be able to believe in
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990.
myself and my true self and the development toward it, I have to beUeve
. "Husserl's Phenomenology of Willing". In Phenomenology of Values and
in God, and doing so, I see God's guidance, God's advice, God's opinion Valuing, 169-92.
in my life" (Ms. A V 21, 24b/25a). Only in seeing us as children of God Schuhmann, Karl. "Probleme der Husserlschen Wertlehre." Philosophisches
and the world as being guided by God can we reach the highest good Jahrbuch der Gorres-Gesellschaft 98 (1991): 106-13.
which is the blissful life, a life of pure and final fulfillment. Spahn, Christine. Phanomenologische Handlungstheorie. Edmund Husserls Unter-
suchungen zur Ethik. Wurzburg: Konigshausen & Neumann, 1996.
Selected bibliography

Primary sources
Husserl, Edmund. Vorlesungen uber Ethik und Wertlehre 1908-1914. Ed. Ullrich
Melle. Husserliana 28. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998 (Hua
28).
. "Fichtes Menschheitsideal" [1917]. In Aufsatze und Vortrage (1911-1921).
Ed. Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, 267-93. Husserliana 25. Dordrecht:
Martinus Nijhoff, 1987 (Hua 25).
. "Gemeingeist I. - Person, personale Ganze, personale Wirkungsgemein-
schaften. Gemeinschaft-Gesellschaft." [1921]; "Gemeingeist II. - Personale Ein-
heiten hoherer Ordnung und ihre Wirkungskorrelate" [1918 or 1921]. In Zur
Phanomenologie der Intersubjektivitdt. Zweiter Teil (1921-1928). Ed. Iso Kern,
165-84,192-204. Husserliana 14. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973 (Hua 14).
."Fiinf Aufsatze iiber Erneuerung" [1922-24]. In Aufsdtze und Vortrage
(1922-1937). Ed. Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, 3-124. Husserliana 27.
Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989 (Hua 27).
. "Wert des Lebens. Wert der Welt. Sittlichkeit (Tugend) und Gliickseligkeit"
[1923]. Ed. Ullrich Melle. Husserl Studies 13 (1997): 201-35.
. "Die Idee einer philosophischen Kultur. Ihr erstes Aufkeimen in der
griechischen Philosophie" [1922/23]. In Erste Philosophie (1923/24). Erster Teil.
Ed. Rudolf Boehm, 203-7. Husserliana 7. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1956.

Secondary sources
Drummond, John J. "Moral objectivity: Husserl's sentiments of the understand-
ing." Husserl Studies 12 (1995): 165-83.
Embree, Lester. "Advances regarding Evaluation and Action in Husserl's Ideas
II." In Issues in Husserl's "Ideas II." Ed. Thomas Nenon and Lester Embree,
173-98. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996.
Hart, James G. "Axiology as the form of purity of heart: A reading of Husserliana
XXVIII." Philosophy Today 34 (1990): 206-21.

138 139
F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

1. Freedom and responsibility apply to beings to which


77 motivational (as opposed to simply causal) categories
apply

F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , Freedom and responsibility are not directly observable phenomena. Nor


do they apply to all kinds of entities. They are part of a way of viewing
A N D S E L F - A W A R E N E S S I N some things in the world and apply only to those entities whose behavior
we explain in motivational rather than causal terms. In the first of the
H U S S E R L Kaizo articles from 1923,1 Husserl makes clear that there is an essential
connection between humans as beings who act on motives and as beings
who possess freedom:
Tom Nenon
Now there belong to the human mentality [Geistigkeit] a priori as
possibly predeUneated forms of consciousness or motivation also
Source: Burt Hopkins and Steven Crowell (eds), The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and
Phenomenological Philosophy 2 (2002): 1-21. the normative formations of "reason," and there also exists a
priori the possibility of thinking universally in freedom and of
determining oneself practically and universally according to self-
The following essay is organized around eighteen theses concerning the , recognized a priori normative laws.
relationship between freedom, responsibility, and self-awareness that I (Hua XXVII, 9/329)
beUeve are both correct and consistent with specific doctrines and the
overall positions advanced in Husserl's published writings. The eighteen The most extensive discussion in Husserl's pubUshed writings until now
theses are logicaUy interrelated but are not meant to represent a deductive of the difference between these two ways of explaining events may be
argument. Most of them are not unique to Husserl or phenomenological found in §§ 54-64 of his Ideas II? especially in § 56. The overall project of
philosophy, but I am not aware of any other thinker who has brought all of Ideas II is to show how different kinds or "regions" of entities are consti-
them together as does Husserl. tuted as correlates of specific epistemic attitudes (Einstellungen). Each
These eighteen claims are descriptive claims. They teU us how certain region of beings and its corresponding attitude are constituted around and
aspects of persons as free agents are dependent upon a fundamental self- on the basis of certain fundamental concepts or principles that essentially
awareness that is at least usually taken to be unique to human beings apply to them. In this essay these fundamental concepts wfll be referred to
(though this is an empirical issue that the following theses leave open). as categories since they fulfill for various regions of beings a function
After introducing and explaining the eighteen theses, I shall also list three similar to that of the twelve Kantian categories for the region of natural
further corollaries that are based on the positions described in the first objects. They set the parameters within which our experiences of certain
eighteen theses but go beyond them to advocate a mode of life that kinds of things are organized and within which they can appear for us as
Husserl considers most consistent with our status as rational agents. These the kinds of things they are.
positions are well known to most readers of Husserl, but they have often This general project of analyzing the basic concepts that guide and
been understood more as expressions of a merely personal conviction, as pertain to a specific epistemic attitude and thereby constitute a region of
historical residues of the classical Western philosophical project Husserl is beings as the kinds of things they are grew out o i Husserl's analyses in the
trying to revive, or as examples of the typical rhetorical pathos of his age, Logical Investigations of ideal objects as fundamentally different kinds of
than as viable systematic positions based upon serious and careful philo- entities from real objects or."things." In the lectures later published as The
sophical analyses. It would go beyond the limits of this paper to discuss the Idea of Phenomenology3 Husserl in fact describes the general project of
ultimate legitimacy of the project the three corollaries set out. However, I phenomenology as establishing the essential correlation between various
hope that the systematic philosophical justification for this project will ways of conceiving of objects oriented on fundamental concepts and prin-
become more easily understood when these corollaries are placed in direct ciples, on the one hand, and the way in which these objects present them-
connection with the preceding eighteen theses.
selves to us, on the other (Hua II, 23). This overall approach, explicitly
formulated as a variation of transcendental philosophy along Kantian

140 141

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND SELF- A W ARENES S

lines, is given a general formulation in Husserl's Ideas I4 as the project of part of what constitutes them, whereby the actual physical existence of
displaying the necessary correlation between noesis and noema for any that object is irrelevant for the purposes of motivation (for example, I run
given sort of object whatsoever and exhibiting how various kinds of just as fearfuUy from a falsely perceived tiger as from a genuine tiger, and
objects can only appear for subjects in light of various kinds of mental I can be just as indifferent to an actual tiger that I fail to perceive as to one
operations or "acts." Moreover, in later sections of the same work, he that is not at all present.) For the possessors of such intentional states, that
makes clear that to each of these regions of beings there corresponds a is, for entities whose behavior is most appropriately described in terms of
particular kind of "evidence" that serves to confirm or disconfirm specific such intentional states, Husserl adopts the traditional term of 'person'.
intentions about these kinds of objects, for example, performing the calcu-
lations for a mathematical equation, experiencing the appropriate sense
perception about the color or taste of a physical object, etc. (Id. 1,296-97). 3. Personhood is defined in terms of subjectivity
Husserl's technical term for such physical objects is Ding ('thing'). "As a person, I am what I am (and every other person is what he or she is)
At the beginning of § 56 of Ideas II in which the concept of motivation as a subject of a surrounding world [Umwelt]," Husserl states in § 50 of
is introduced as one of the fundamental principles guiding a different atti- Ideas II (185). Associated with subjectivity is the concept of "mineness"
tude towards some of the objects that surround us, Husserl states: "A for each of the appropriate activities (Akte) or states (Zustdnde) that make
change in attitude implies nothing other than a thematic transition from up the mental life of the subject.
one way of grasping things into another, to which correlatively different In addition to the various traits associated with the subjectivity of
objectivities correspond" (Id. II, 210). The assertion that freedom and persons described below, Husserl in other places also associates the notion
responsibility are terms that make sense only within a framework of moti- of a continuous unified style with personhood and sees persons as entities
vational versus causal explanation is then analogous to the assertion that that possess "personality," not just as the formal trait of being a subject
terms like 'odd' and 'even' apply to natural integers and not to tastes, or but as a specific or individual habitual way of thinking or acting.6 This is
that spatial location applies to physical objects but not to numbers. the notion of the personal ego introduced, for example, in the Cartesian
lit However, one should also note that Husserl does not assert that all Meditations in contradistinction to the ego-pole of subjectivity in the sense
motivations are "free" in the fullest sense. The level that he terms the of a merely formal principle of unity that persists throughout all of the
"most original and specifically subjective for the ego in the authentic specific moments of mental life.7 This latter point will be important for the
sense" is the I we consider free, he says (213). Yet' on the other side, three closing corollaries.
motivations can stiU be attributed to an ego whose mental states are char-
acterized by a kind of "passivity" that is actually, as a state of an ego, still
a kind of activity, but simply the "lowest level of activity." Husserl 4. Subjects are entities
describes this level as the ego of "tendencies to which it simply succumbs" a whose behavior is appropriately explained in terms of intentional
(213). We shall return to this issue further below in the discussion of states such as beUefs, values, and desires AND
Thesis Thirteen. b who are aware of (at least some of) their own mental states.

Just as a physical object or "thing" (Ding) is constituted as a unity of


2. Motivational categories apply to persons
various potentially perceivable physical traits, so too a subject is a unity -
The distinction between explanations in terms of motivation and explana- but a unity of mental states each of which is characterized as "mine" for
tions in terms of external causes is introduced in Section Three of Ideas II someone because it belongs to a "me," a subject that knows itself as the
as part of the description of the personalistic attitude. The principle of bearer of these states:
causality is identified in Section One as one of the fundamental concepts The ego is the identical subject of the function in all acts of the same
for the constitution of nature and natural objects. The principle of motiva- stream of consciousness; it is the center out of which everything radiates or
tion, by contrast, is unique to the personaUstic world and applies only to rather the center into which all conscious life streams, all affections and
those entities whose behavior is most appropriately explained in terms of actions, all attending, all grasping, relating, conjoining, all theoretical,
motives rather than simply causes.5 The states that are factors in motiva- valuing, practical position-takings, all being pleased or displeased, all
tional explanation are "intentional states" characterized by directedness hoping and fearing, aU doing and suffering, etc. In other words, all of the
towards some object. The way they are directed at objects is an essential manifold particularizations of intentional relatedness towards objects that

142 143
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND' S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

here are called 'acts' have a necessary terminus a quo from which they 5. Subjects are thus beings who have at least some
emanate (Id. II, 105). second-order mental states (i.e. states of being aware of
To say that persons are subjects is to say that the intentional states that at least some of their own mental states) directly
are theirs are always identifiable in terms of a 'for whom'-structure, the
answer to which is the "I" that is the possessor or bearer of that mental This does not necessarily mean that subjects are directly aware of all of
state.8 their mental states. Whether a subject can have a mental state and not be
By introducing the very notion of a "for whom" that is capable of iden- aware of it is a different question. Some of the statements quoted above
tifying itself as the "I" who has this mental state or mental trait, the I, as suggest that Husserl often leans towards the view that it is part of the
an ego-pole, as a subject who is aware of the mental trait or state that it nature of being a mental state for a subject that the subject is at least
ft'j identifies as its own, must be aware of that trait or state. To be a subject, implicitly aware of it and can turn its attention to the act and transform
ii! then, implies not only that the person must have mental states but also this awareness into an explicit and thematic awareness through a shift in
that it must have an awareness of them as his or her own. It involves self- attitude. However, Thesis Five does not involve this claim. It simply
awareness or self-consciousness. By itself, however, this thesis does not yet asserts that subjects are aware of at least some of their mental states.
address the issue of whether this awareness must be direct or immediate Moreover, in fact, Husserl's analyses of concrete personality suggest
self-awareness, although the latter feature also has been traditionally asso- that he recognized that we know about many of our mental states and dis-
ciated with subjectivity for good reason. I shaU return to this question in positions only by observing and analyzing our own behavior, and not
Thesis Eight. through pure reflection (see Theses Ten and Fifteen below).
It should be noted, incidentaUy, that when Husserl describes persons in
Ideas II as the subjects of an Umwelt, he is also stressing the fact that 6. Subjects (and hence persons) are not entities that exist
persons do not distinguish themselves simply through the fact that they behind or in addition to physical entities in the world
have mental states that passively represent the world around them. They (their bodies). Rather, subjectivity and personhood are
are not just theoretical in the original etymological sense of "seeing" or features of concrete unified entities, specific organisms,
perceiving the world around them. Rather, he contrasts the Umwelt or that possess some traits best described in simple physical
"surrounding world" as a context towards which we are constantly "taking terms (location and weight, for example) and other traits
a stance," "evaluating" in practical and valuational terms, towards the described most appropriately in personalistic, that is,
sphere of "nature" as the realm of objects viewed strictly in a theoretical
motivational terms, such as desires, values, and self-
sense. The distinction is similar to the Heideggerian distinction, intro-
understandings
duced a few years later in Being and Time, between Umwelt as the realm
of Zuhandenheit (being ready-to-hand or available) and Natur as the Husserl is very clear that even the more naturalistically conceived "soul"
realm of Vorhandenheit (being merely present-at-hand). Husserl maintains (Seele) - more naturalistically as opposed to the concept of 'person' - is
that all valuings and desirings are complex, higher-order acts that essen- not something that subsists on its own, but is what Husserl calls a 'stratum'
tially always also involve some representational element as a necessary (Schicht) of a physical organism: "The surplus of reaUty beyond the mere
component of that complex act, but his description of persons as the sub- physical thing is nothing separable, not something next to, but part of the
jects of a surrounding world also emphasizes that our immediate mode of latter, hence it moves 'with' it, it gains a spatial determinacy through its
access to the things that surround us as persons is not neutral and that our being as part of this spatial thing itself" (Id. II, 176). Subjectivity and per-
'i ordinary stance towards the world is not simply as observers but rather is sonhood are traits properly attributable to concrete entities that have
normaUy and from the outset a practically engaged stance. In Ideas II, bodies and mental states and are furthermore capable of becoming aware
then, Husserl describes persons not just as subjects but as practically of themselves, their bodily and mental states, and - in the case of human
engaged subjects. beings - of forming beliefs and desires about their own physical, mental,
In the Kaizo articles Husserl even tries to trace ethical responsibility and emotional states, and even of expressing them in terms of statements
and freedom back to these everyday and ordinary practical strivings that that start with the personal pronoun T (or its equivalent in some lan-
ii i arise within daily life itself (Hua XXVII, 23-43). We shaU xeturn to that guage). To use the terms Husserl coined in the Third Logical Investiga-
issue at the end of this essay. tion: they are "dependent objects" that are actually found only as
"moments" of "independent objects" such as human beings.

144 145
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

7. Based on one's own experience of subjectivity, one can sion" (Ausdruck) of a person's intentional states. This does not mean that
also attribute subjectivity to others under certain the latter way of viewing the event is necessarily less vaUd than the former.
circumstances Under the proper circumstances and for many expressions of intentional
states, it is possible to form consistently correct and reliable judgments
In the personalistic attitude that guides our daily lives, we are all well about those states, just as it is in theory possible for a subject to fail to
aware that there are other persons in the world. In fact, as we interact grasp one of his or her own mental states correctly for one reason or
within the surrounding world, we not only recognize other subjects whom another (for example, if one fails to focus clearly on it), and just as it is
we view as persons but even find ourselves as members of an "association possible for one to be mistaken about the perception of a physical object.
of persons" (Personenverband) who share the same surrounding world Both purported apperceptions about one's own mental states and pur-
with one another. 9 In the personalistic attitude, subjects immediately ported appresentations about the mental states of others can be correct or
encounter the other as "a person who is on the same level with us as incorrect, reliable or unreliable, depending on the circumstances. Husserl
persons who are members of an association of persons" (Id. II, 190). does believe that the directness of reflective apperception of one's own
This goes beyond the mere attribution of mental states to the other mental states gives them a reliability in principle that does not obtain for
person. Even in a naturalistic attitude, one can attribute mental states to the perception of any external events - be they simply of physical objects
something as part of the causal explanation of its behavior without recog- or of the mental states of others as manifested through the externally
nizing that thing as a subject or a person. Husserl terms the stratum of observable expressions of those states.10 Moreover, the terminological dis-
mental states used in causal (as opposed to truly motivational) explanation tinction makes clear that there remains an irreducible difference between
a 'soul' and recognizes that we attribute mental states such as perceptions the two modes of access to mental states and that direct first-person
and impulses to animals without necessarily attributing personhood or awareness of even some of one's own mental states is possible only for the
subjectivity in the full sense to them. bearers of those mental states.
Whether there could be organisms other than human beings whom we It should be noted that this is a separate issue from the issue of the
would or should recognize as persons is an empirical question. Empirical validity or reliabiUty of specific claims to know one's own mental states or
observations of the behavior of these organisms would have to justify the those of another person. For example, there is a very legitimate sense in
imputation of subjectivity to them, that is, not only that we are justified in which one can say that a mother can know with absolute certainty that her
attributing mental states to them as an essential part of a good explanation of child is in pain and that she might even feel her child's pain more intensely
their behavior, but also that we should recognize that they have second-order than her own. To say that this awareness and this feeling are forms of ap-
mental states exhibited through self-critical learning processes or the appro- presentation rather than original apperceptions is just to say that she must
priate use of words like T in whatever language we discover they employ. see, hear, or otherwise observe something about the child or the circum-
stances in which the child finds itself to know this, whereas at least some-
times she can feel pain in herself and thus know about it independently of
8. The imputation of subjectivity to another does not
any external observations of herself or her circumstances. This does not
imply that one has direct access to any ofhis or her necessarily diminish the validity of the knowledge about the child or the
mental states intensity or genuineness of the feelings for it at all.
The difference between the way in which one is directly aware of at least
some of one's own mental states in a kind of direct perception and the way
9. Successful comprehension of the mental states of
one is aware of the mental states of others is terminologicaUy fixed in the
someone else through the application of motivational
distinction between 'apperception' and 'appresentation' in the Fifth Car-
categories in a specific case is called 'understanding'. It
tesian Meditation (CM, 143-49). Part of the difference is the relative sim-
involves inferring the motives, the mental states of others,
plicity of the former act as opposed to the more complex, higher-order act
based not on direct acquaintance with their mental states
involved in appresentation. Appresentation is always based upon the per-
through direct self-awareness but through motivational
ception of some externaUy observable phenomenon, such as something the
explanations of their observed behaviors
other person does or says. At the lowest level, this externally observable
event could be described simply in physicalistic terms; however, in the per- In Ideas II Husserl coins the term 'comprehending experience' (kompre-
sonalistic attitude we comprehend this event in another way as an "expres- hensive Erfahrung) to capture the way we recognize others in our daily

146 147

L
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND SELF-A W ARENES S

lives. When we see them not merely as physical objects to be dealt with 10. It is therefore possible and often reasonable to
but as persons in their own right with whom we genuinely interact as attribute mental states such as valuings, beliefs, or desires
persons, we "understand" them: to oneself based on a self-understanding grounded not in
direct self-awareness but on a reasonable application of
Whenever I am able to put myself in the place of the other by motivational categories to oneself and based on an
means of empathy, I say "I understand why the other has decided understanding of one's own behavior
this way, I understand why he or she has come to this judgement
. . . and if I enter into the network of motivations within my cogito,
(the 'in view of what [woraufhin]')." - All of these "causaUties"
into the open and the concealed intentionalities of its motivation,
can be intuitively completely laid out precisely because they are
then I experience how I am motivated by them and usuaUy tend to
motivations. (Id. II, 230)
be motivated, which experienceable unique style I, as the motivat-
ing subject of these motivating circumstances, possess in general:
Moreover, in the personalistic attitude persons orient themselves in their
or what kind of personal subject I am. This aU takes place without
mental actions towards each other (the I towards the other and vice
any accompanying conceptual fixation and without thinking back
versa). They perform actions with the intention of being understood by
on it (without "reflecting" on it in a completely different sense, .
their counterparts and of influencing them in their understanding grasp of
namely in the sense of a thinking and stating) [that is, in the
these actions (as expressed with this intention) towards certain personal
propositional sense].
ways of behaving. This establishes relationships of mutual understanding
(Id. II, 248-49)
and agreement [Einverstdndnis]" (Id. II, 192). IdeaUy this common
surrounding world constituted by mutual interaction in light of the
persons' interaction with each other achieves the level of a "communica- To view oneself as a person means not only that one is a subject and
tive" world constituted by shared understandings between the persons that one's own behavior is comprehensible in motivational terms but also
who inhabit this common world (193). In fact Husserl notes in the same that one has a style of acting that reveals one's personal "character."
passage that the notion of an "egoistic world" inhabited by a single person Hence part of the way we discover who we are is not through introspec-
in isolation is actually an "abstraction" in which one moves back or tion upon our hidden mental states but by means that Husserl in this quote
abstracts from the social relationships in which one immediately and con- caUs "experienceable," that is, by observing how we tend to act and react
stantly finds oneself immersed in one's everyday Ufe. and by finding out about ourselves, our values, and our dispositions by
observing and making sense in motivational terms of what we see our-
The key to the move into a common surrounding world and the pos-
selves doing. In this sense, we very often understand ourselves (in the
sibiUty of a genuinely communicative interaction with others, however, is
the move beyond the categories of mere physical causality:11 technical sense described in Thesis Nine) in exactly the same way as we
understand other persons.
It is certainly true that the perception of an T move' includes the
perception of the physical movement in space and so the question 11. Since the attribution of first- or second-order mental
concerning physical causality can be raised. On the other hand, states to oneself and to others is originally and ultimately
however, it does not have to be raised and should not be raised in derived from one's direct acquaintance with mental states
the personalistic attitude in which solely the active and affected in one's own case (a second-order mental state), only
person is posited as the subject of motivations and the subject of subjects (entities with second-order mental states) can
its surrounding world. (Id. II, 260) attribute mental states (consciousness or even
subjectivity) to others
At its simplest level, this statement claims about subjects: "It takes one to
know one." However, it actually involves more than that. It allows that we
might conceivably attribute mental states or consciousness of some kind to
others, perhaps to members of other species, without necessarily having to
attribute fuU-blown subjectivity to them, that is, we might attribute some

148 149
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

mental states or consciousness to them as part of the causal explanation of fife to other human beings but that we must have an awareness of our own
their behaviour without necessarily attributing self-consciousness to them. mental life, that is, second-order mental states, if we are to attribute any
However, it also asserts that for an entity to attribute anything like mental kind of states as belonging to another organism as mental - perhaps even
states to any entity whatsoever - be it to oneself or another, to a thing of especially so in the case of those organisms whose behavior does not
one's own kind or of* another kind - one would have to have some direct exhibit the features - such as the habit of saying T believe' or T want' -
second-order awareness of one's own mental states that would provide the that would justify attributing subjectivity in the strong sense of self-
basis for the constitution of a region of beings with anything like a mental consciousness to them. For an entity to posit mental states to another,
life at all. Husserl seems to hold not only that "it takes one to know one" but also
It is part of what it means to be a subject in the fullest sense that it must that "it takes one that knows itself to know another one." Hence even
have some sort of at least prereflective awareness of its own mental states. before Husserl moves from the naturaUstic to the personalistic attitude in
Explicit reflective awareness of one's mental states seems to be conceiv- Section Three of Ideas II, he begins the analysis of animal nature in
able only for a being that has such a prereflective awareness of them.12 As Section Two with an analysis of the "pure ego." He does so in spite of the
Husserl puts it: "Self-perception is a reflection (self-reflection of the pure fact that we do not normally attribute anything Uke self-consciousness or
ego) and essentially presupposes an unreflected consciousness" (Id. II, personhood to animals.
248). The ability to focus on this prereflective awareness and make it I therefore take the organization of Section Two as an indication of
explicit is what makes a being what in the Cartesian Meditations Husserl Husserl's repudiation of what has come to be called "functionaUsm",
calls a "transcendental ego" (CM, 99-106) or, more often, simply an namely the view that although we need something like mental states as
example of "self-consciousness." Without at least this pre-reflective aware- causal factors in our explanation of the behavior of certain entities, these
ness, these mental states would not be experiences for us at all. Mental life are at bottom all really natural states whose complete description can ulti-
as an experience involves a direct, albeit often impUcit and unfocused mately be given in natural terms. Husserl, by contrast, is suggesting that
awareness of these mental states without having to infer them from an there is something about a first-person perspective, that is, something
observation of one's own behavior. The implicit awareness can become about the abiUty to be directly aware of at least some of our own mental
clearer and it can become the object of our immediate attention in an states, that makes it irreplaceable for us. Only by virtue of this difference
expUcit reflection upon it, but often we are directly and even explicitly do we have any reason at all for calling these states 'mental states' in our-
aware of a desire, of something as valuable or interesting for us, or even selves or in others. He also seems to be suggesting that this something is
just of a relevant fact as something we know, without any effort at reflec- something we must first be directly aware of in our own case in order to be
tion and without drawing any inferences at all from anything we say or do. able to attribute it to others.
This is not to say that our mental life takes place as a series of expUcit
reflections upon what is going on inside us or that our self-awareness nor-
mally takes the clear and well-defined propositional form "I want this" or 12. To attribute freedom to an entity involves not only
"I know that", or even that all of our mental states are "experiences" in the attribution of a mental state as an explanatory factor
the sense of things that we are ever even implicitly aware of. However, it in an action (causal responsibility) but also some other
does assert that without such experiences, the very category of mental life mental state in the broadest sense (a value, a decision, a
and subjectivity would never arise at all. desire) as part of the explanation of that mental state
itself (freedom as the source of responsibility for that
When we ascribe a "soul" to another human being or to a non-human
factor)
organism, part of what we are doing is describing their typical functions.
We are positing a causal element as part of the explanation of their In the Kaizo article entitled "Formal Types of Culture in the Develop-
behaviour that we do not ascribe to non-Uving organisms. But why do we ment of Humanity," Husserl declares that
take this element to be something like consciousness, why is it evidence
for some kind of mental Ufe? Why call it a 'soul' instead of just assuming Freedom is an expression for the abflity and above all for the
that it is some kind of complicated chemical process that has been dis- acquired habit of critical position-taking towards that which pre-
turbed when those organisms cease to be animated or aUve? I take it that sents itself to consciousness - at first without reflection - as true,
I! the organization of Ideas II is meant to convey not only that we have to as valuable, as what practically ought to be, and moreover as the
start with our own subjective mental life to attribute a subjective mental basis for a free decision that subsequently decides about it. Thus it

150 151
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

is better to relate freedom back to free decisions, to whose that would happen to be persons but also a normative claim. It does not
essence it belongs to follow "on the basis of" deUberations, the necessarily describe what happens in fact. In one sense, it describes some-
pure freedom of a position-taking, nothing to do with coercion. thing less than that, namely a shift in attitude that is not always a reality
(Hua XXVII, 63) but just a possibility. On the other hand, it describes something more than
a mere fact, since Husserl believes that this capacity is one that is espe-
He continues by noting that such critical consideration of one's own ciaUy important for persons to exercise. Husserl's description of this shift
beliefs and desires can serve to inhibit the efficacy of one's initial tend- as an adoption of a theoretical attitude refers to the fact that any second-
encies and lead to better beliefs, values, and willings. It makes no sense to order mental state - including, for example, second-order mental states of
attribute to an agent freedom as the ability to influence its own actions self-evaluation - necessarily involves a form of self-awareness since he
through the influence on one's beliefs, values, and willing unless one were holds that all intentional acts (whether first or second-order) involve a rep-
aware of one's actual (and potential) beliefs, values, and wilUngs. That is, resentational element that he calls 'theoretical'. In fact, however, as the
freedom only makes sense for beings with second-order mental states, and examples of the personal attitude in Ideas II and in the Kaizo articles
under the additional assumption that the second-order mental states, for make clear, one's stance towards oneself and one's own mental states and
example, one's beUefs about the appropriateness of one's initial beliefs or dispositions is not normally or primarily theoretical but most often prac-
desires, one's desires about the kinds of desires and beliefs one should or tical or evaluationally motivated. I find myself not just "confident that I
could have, might at least have some influence on the beliefs and desires know this" or "worried that I might not be justified in believing that" but
that one actually continues to adopt throughout the course of a lifetime. In also "happy to know this," "wondering why I feel this or that way," or
fact, at the very beginning of the essay "Renewal and Science" both as an "wishing that I did or did not want that." The possibility of the theoretical
individual ethical project and as a project of social improvement Husserl shift in attitude described above simply points to the possibility of making
states unequivocally that the basis for such a project lies in human beings' the act itself the object of my attention. The "theoretical aspect" of this
inherent capacity for self-consciousness: self-awareness is not normaUy (or perhaps ever) given first of all and
purely by itself but rather is usuaUy (or perhaps always) embedded in a
As our point of departure we take an ability that belongs to the more complex act of practical and evaluational self-awareness, part of our
essence of human beings, the ability for self-consciousness in the own self-monitoring process.
pregnant sense of self-observation (inspectio sui) and the therein Ethical responsibility for Husserl extends further than strictly moral
grounded ability to relate back to oneself and reflexively take a responsibility, which is a subspecies of ethical responsibility. The realm of
stance towards oneself and one's life in personal acts such as self- the ethical applies to any actions that are subject to norms of practical
knowledge, self-evaluation, and practical self-determination (self- rationaUty for Husserl, including but not limited to moral norms: "It is
willing and self-formation). obviously a restriction if we take ethics as morality. Ethics is related in
(Hua XXVII, 23)13 every sense towards action just as logic is related towards thinking. Just as
the latter is directed towards correct or rational thinking, ethics is directed
towards correct or rational action."14 Since it only makes sense to hold an
13. Responsibility (in an ethical sense) is a special form of agent responsible for an action under any norm if we can also impute
motivational attribution, one in which the agent is seen as freedom to that agent, then whatever is an essential condition for freedom
the source of the mental state, and this involves at the will also be an essential condition for ethical responsibility. Moreover,
least the possibility of the agent's possessing second-order since freedom also involves seeing the agent not only as the cause of the
mental states about the mental state that explains the action in the sense of the locus of the state that caused the action but also
action as having at least the capacity for influencing the mental state that is taken
Husserl explicitly claims that the subject is capable of a shift in attitude for to be a crucial explanatory factor in the motivational account of what hap-
any mental state such that the state itself becomes the direct object of our pened, ethical responsibility must also assume this capacity as a feature of
attention. "This unique shift in attitude belongs to all acts as an ideal pos- personhood.
sibility. That is, aU acts that are not from the outset theoretical acts can be
changed into theoretical acts through a shift in attitude" (Id. II, 8).
Responsibility is not just a fact about human beings and any other species

152 153
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

14. Only subjects - possessors of second-order mental and this proceeds hand in hand with the development of the
states - can understand someone (including oneself) as subject itself.
ethically responsible and, in order to do so, must also (Id. II, 252)
recognize that person as also being a subject
Husserl does not believe that human behavior normaUy issues from con-
The point is almost obvious but not at all trivial. The ethical responsibility
scious and explicit deliberation, or that all or even most human actions are
we attribute to human beings as persons derives from their subjectivity,
best explained in terms of second-order mental states (except perhaps in a
that is, their status as bearers of second-order mental states. It also
deficient mode). 15 Human lives are permeated by what he calls 'passivi-
requires the additional ability to have some of these second-order mental
ties', ways of being affected by things from sense perceptions to one's own
states influence first-order mental states; but without the second-order impulses: "Prior to the will with the active thesis of a 'fiat' lies behavior as
mental states, there could be no question of whether they can influence instinctive behavior, for example, the involuntary T am moving,' the invol-
them or not. Husserl's position provides a basis beyond mere species prej- untary 'I am reaching' for my cigar, I want it and do that 'without any
udice for extending the status of ethical (and more specifically moral) further ado,' which of course can hardly be distinguished from complete
responsibility to human beings and, based on the empirical evidence we arbitrariness in a narrow sense" (Id.II, 258). What makes us ethically
have thus far, to them alone. responsible is not that we normally do subject all of our actions to explicit
This does not necessarily mean that we do not have moral obligations or even implicit scrutiny through second-order mental acts but rather that
to anything other than to human beings. That is a different question. It we see ourselves as always in principle capable of doing so if we choose to
means only that it would be inappropriate to apply ethical or moral stand- reflect on them as our own and capable of evaluating them in terms of the
ards to the actions of anything else. If there are ethical or moral obliga- general norms for practical rationality.
tions towards members of other species or the environment in general,
then these obligations hold only for subjects since one has to be a subject
to be free or to be responsible - and thus far human beings seem to be the 16. Hence responsibility (even in one's own case) does
only species whose behavior warrants the attribution of subjectivity in the not necessarily involve explicit or even direct and implicit
strong sense. awareness of the mental states for which the agent is held
responsible. Responsibility involves only the assumption
of freedom along with the appropriate circumstances for
15. The attribution of subjectivity does not mean that the viewing the action in motivational rather than causal
subject must have direct awareness of all of its own terms
mental states
It follows from the previous theses that one need not consciously choose
This is particularly true of dispositions and habits. It is true not only for an act, much less consciously choose a tendency or a disposition to act in a
others but even for the person who is the bearer of these dispositions and certain way, in order to be ethically responsible for it. To be thus respons-
habits: ible for it, the agent must simply be able to become aware of it - either
through direct reflection or through a motivational analysis of one's own
The ego can be more than the ego as an apperceptive unity. It can behavior - and thereby at least in principle be able to exercise some influ-
have hidden capacities (dispositions) that have not yet emerged, ence on the behavior. Not all behavior, of course, will be subject to such
have not yet been apperceptively objectified, just as a thing [Ding] motivational analyses. One's heartbeat or one's nervous tics might be
can have properties that have not yet been included in the apper- explicable solely in causal terms and thereby inaccessible to influence
ception of that thing. We also make all of these distinctions in the through second-order mental states. Husserl does not try to define sharply
common personal observation of human beings and hence in the what the cases may be but simply spells out the Umits of this approach as
human sciences (such as history), as well as in our common the limits of the appropriateness of motivational categories as relevant
experience. Someone does not "know" what he is Uke, he learns explanatory factors. How far these extend is an empirical matter.16
about himself. One's self-experience, one's self-apperception is
continually expanding. "Coming to know oneself" is one with the
development of self-apperception, the constitution of the "self,"

154 155
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S
17. In Husserl's terms this means that responsibility is 18. In sum, then, it is our nature as transcendental egos,
attributed to the "personal ego" as the ego that is
as pure consciousness that is directly given to itself in
constituted over a lifetime through the habitualities of its
reflection, that makes it possible for us to constitute
position-takings (beliefs, valuings, and desires) that may
ourselves and anyone else as persons, that is, as free and
not all be directly accessible to reflection
responsible agents. Yet the limits of personal
In § 60b of Ideas II Husserl describes very graphically how our knowledge responsibility are not restricted to those actions explicitly
of ourselves as concrete and individual persons involves empirical el- chosen and consciously performed after careful
ements based on one's own experience with oneself as a concrete person deliberation of all of the factors involved, but extends to
interacting with other persons and objects in the surrounding world. It also all of those things that we can attribute to ourselves as
involves background empirical knowledge about human beings in general actions based on motives that are our own
- how people tend to act, how such things as age and general circum-
stances tend to influence behavior. Yet he does not believe that this We are human beings, freely willing subjects who are actively
absolves the agent as a person, that is, as one who is capable of identifying engaged in our surrounding world, who continuously have a part
oneself as the agent by reflecting on one's actions, from having to take in shaping it. Whether we want to or not, whether we do it well or
responsibility for them. It instead provides the starting point for the task poorly, we do it. Can we not also do so in a rational way; are not
of taking responsibility for those actions to the extent that they are seen as rationaUty and virtuousness in oiir power?
following from motivations that are one's own: (Hua XXVII, 4/326)

One can easily see how this thesis then leads to the three corollaries listed
The autonomy of reason, the "freedom" of the personal subject
therefore does not consist in my passively succumbing to aUen below. In closing, I shaU briefly elucidate each of these corollaries and
influences but rather in my deciding on my own. And furthermore attempt to show how it is a specific application and extension of the posi-
[it consists] in my not allowing myself to be "puUed along" by any tions laid out in the previous eighteen theses.17
other tendencies or drives but rather in my being freely active,
and doing so in accord with reason. Corollary 1. Subjectivity and personhood are not simply
We must therefore distinguish between the human person, the descriptive terms for essential features of human beings
apperceptive unity that we grasp in self-perception and the per- but rather are possibilities that can be realized more or '
ception of others, and the person as the subject of rational acts, less fully. Moreover, lives are more truly human that
whose motivations and motivational forces come to be given to us realize these possibilities more fully
in our own original experience and in the experiences in which we
understand others. There our view is focused on the specifically If it is true that not all or even most of human conduct is governed by acts
Geistige, the free Ufe of acts. (Id. II, 269) that are "free" in the fullest sense but are more often governed by
impulses and habits that may be hidden to the agent him- or herself and
Our charge is thus to become rational persons by taking responsibility for may or may not be justified in Ught of the overaU goals that the agent
those acts that all along have always been our own. would be able to justify or even accept upon further consideration, then
subjectivity and personhood as the possibility of freely and consciously
positing beliefs, values, and desires that govern action are not always real-
ized in the Uves that human beings lead. For Husserl 'reason' (Vernunft) is
the general formal heading for the sustainability of any sort of epistemic,
that is, theoretical, evaluational, or practical position-taking in light of the
demand for justification. Reason is thus not an external norm imposed on
persons from outside but the demand that they take advantage of their
capacity as subjects and as persons to become aware of the position-
takings that they are enacting throughout their lives, to reflect on them
and their justification, and to adjust them when appropriate:

156 157
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

Moral philosophy is just a fuUy subordinate part of ethics, which Corollary 3. The project of philosophy in general and
must necessarily be viewed as the science that concerns the entire phenomenology in particular is nothing other than a
active Uve of a rational subjectivity from the perspective of reason systematic and sustained effort to articulate and foster
that governs and unifies this entire life. And regardless of which these norms and contribute to their realization in
I particular spheres of possible action we view normatively from individual lives and in societies as a whole '
this perspective - including, for example, cognitive knowledge
characterized as a kind of action - there ethics has its thematic On Husserl's view it is no accident that philosophy and science emerged
domain. together in ancient Greece as the systematic attempt to reflect upon and
(Hua XXVII, 21)18 identify the ultimate norms for human knowing and acting.22 The crisis of
modern science is not in itself a crisis of reason itself but rather a crisis that
arises from a far too narrow definition of what can count as evidence or
Corollary 2. The norms that guide the striving towards reason, so that only what is observable and measurable in a narrow sense
more complete personhood are the norms implicit in modeled on the natural sciences counts as genuine science and as gen-
everyday knowing, valuing, and willing as such. uinely accessible to systematic rational inquiry. This modern development
Systematic and explicit reflection can help further and instead represents a turn away from the inherent possibilities of rational
realize these norms in a human life scientific inquiry in the broadest sense that can be restored if one returns
One of the more interesting insights provided by the Kaizo articles is the to the original project of philosophy in the proper way.23 A philosophy
clear light they shed on Husserl's view that the norms for knowing, grounded in systematic reflection upon the a priori norms inherent in cog-
valuing, and desiring grow out of what he calls "pre-ethical forms of self- nition, valuing, and willing itself, a philosophy that recognizes all of these
regulation" (Hua XXVII, 26). Each of these specific kinds of acts involves operations as the personal acts of free and responsible subjects would
a kind of essential and implicit teleology towards its own unique form of therefore fit into his overaU view of philosophy as a form of rational self-
fulfillment. Cognition essentially aims at truth and finds its fulfiUment or realization - not just for the individuals that practice it, but for any society
disappointment through the further course of experience. What is valued that dedicates itself to the inherent value of human self-realization. We
promises its own kind of value-fulfillment that the further course of a life can then see that, according to Husserl's own self-interpretation, his
can confirm or disconfirm, and thereby reveal as "genuine" (echt) or not.19 repeated and emotional calls to dedicate oneself again to the classic
The aforementioned studies by Zahavi20 and Welton 21 emphasize how all project of philosophy are not only part of a longer tradition that he con-
of these structures can ultimately be traced back to the temporal struc- sciously embraces. They are also consistent with and arise from many of
tures of protention and retention that underlie all of human consciousness. the detailed and careful analyses of human persons and human mental life
They aU strive for unity over a lifetime of experiences, ultimately at an that he developed as part of that overaU project.
ideal universality that would provide reliable and complete unity for aU Nothing described in the eighteen main theses normally or necessarily
rational beings and for all possible experiences. That is why Husserl involves phenomenology as a systematic philosophical enterprise. None of
defines reason as a formal structure inherent within each of these funda- the acts described in those theses or in the first two corollaries depends
mental forms of striving for unity, whether in the theoretical realm as upon phenomenological reduction. However, Husserl not only believes
genuine knowledge or in the practical realm as unconditional values or that philosophy - as a systematic and rigorous investigation of the proper
wilUng. That is also why each of them points to a possible form of evident- norms for knowing, valuing, and acting - grows out of and represents the
ness as its fulfillment and why in Ideas I Husserl addresses the issue of culmination of the everyday search for the right beliefs, values, and
Evidenz under the general heading of a "Phenomenology of Reason" (Id. actions, but also that it is an ethically demanded project precisely because
1,282-323). it can help identify what these are and how to find them. Phenomenology
is particularly suited to this task because it recognizes that knowing,
valuing, and acting are subjective activities and that systematic self-
reflection is the proper means for identifying the norms inherent in the
very nature of these activities. As such, it is particularly consistent with the
personalistic attitude and the overall project of a caU to responsibility for
the actions that every person constantly undertakes in various degrees of

158 159
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S F R E E D O M , R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , AND S E L F - A W A R E N E S S

self-awareness throughout a lifetime. On Husserl's view phenomenology is 5 A very thorough discussion of this distinction may be found in Bernhard Rang,
a particularly appropriate way, but certainly not the only way, for persons Kausalitdt und Motivation. Untersuchungen zum Verhaltnis von Perspektivitdt
to exercise the capacities for self-awareness and freedom that make them und Objektivitat in der Phdnomenologie Edmund Husserls (The Hague:
Nijhoff, 1979).
persons at all.
6 The distinction between the two notions of the ego and their interrelationship
is carefully analyzed in Eduard Marbach, Das Problem des Ich in der Phdnom-
enologie Husserls (The Hague: Nijhoff 1974), 298-339. Marbach's study is a
Notes very careful discussion of the development of Husserl's concept of the ego
1 In 1922 and 1923 Husserl composed several articles for publication in the throughout all of the major works published until now.
Japanese journal Kaizo. They were entitled "Erneuerung. Ihr Problem und 7 Edmund Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen in Cartesianische Meditationen
Ihre Methode" ("Renewal: Its Problem and Method"), "Die Methode der und Pariser Vortrage, ed. S. Strasser, Husserliana I (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1950),
Wesensforschung" ("The Method of Research into Essences"), "Erneuerung 41-183, here 101; English translation: Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to
als individualethisches Problem" ("Renewal as a Problem in Individual Phenomenology, trans. Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1960), 67. Hence-
Ethics"), "Erneuerung und Wissenschaft" ("Renewal and Science"), and forth cited as CM with German pagination, which is included in the margins of
"Formale Typen der Kultur in der Menschheitsentwicklung" ("Formal Types the translation.
of Culture in the Development of Humanity"). The first three were published 8 See also Id. II, 4: "the subject (understood here as the ego that is inseparably
in 1923 and 1924 in that journal. All of them have since been published or bound to each cogito, as pure subject)...." The word 'pure' here refers simply
republished, along with earlier versions and related drafts of essays, in Edmund to the possibility of becoming directly aware in a reflective act of this cogito as
Husserl, "Funf Aufsatze iiber Erneuerung," in Aufsatze und Vortrage "my own."
(1922-1937), ed. Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, Husserliana XXVII 9 See Id. II, 191: "We exist in relation to a common surrounding world - we exist
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989), 3-121. The first of them has been translated into in an association of persons: these belongs together."
English by Jeffner Allen and published in Edmund Husserl, Shorter Works, ed. 10 One of the best known formulations of the difference between the ideal reliabil-
Peter McCormick and Frederick A. Elliston (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of ity of direct reflective graspings of one's own mental states as opposed to the per-
Notre Dame, 1981), 326-31. (Henceforth, cited as 'Hua XXVII5 with .German ception of external events can be found in Husserl's Philosophy as Rigorous
page references. English page references follow the German only when the first Science ("Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," in Aufsdtze und Vortrage
article is cited.) See also Hua XXVII, 8/328: "every mental [geistige] reality has (1911-1921), ed. Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, Husserliana XXV [Dor-
an internality, a self-contained 'life of consciousness,' that is related to an 'ego,' drecht: Nijhoff, 1987], 3-62). Up through his last writings, he makes much of this
so to speak as a pole that centers all of the individual acts of consciousness, difference as a basis for phenomenology as a totally different kind of science
whereby these acts are located in contexts of 'motivation.'" "To these acts and from the empirical sciences. See, e.g., CM, 66-76. However, it is important to
their motivations belong differences of rationality and irrationality, of 'right' note that Husserl comes to see that even the so-called direct perception of one's
and 'wrong' thinking, valuing, and wilUng." own mental events in reflection contains elements of unreliability that must be
2 Edmund Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologis- bracketed out for the pure reflection he uses as the basis for phenomenology.
chen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phdnomenologische Untersuchungen zur Kon- 11 Husserl puts it very succinctly in a note published posthumously as part of the
stitution, ed. Marly Biemel, Husserliana IV (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1952); English text-critical apparatus to one of the Husserliana volumes on intersubjectivity:
translation: Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenolog- "Human beings as social beings [Geist, egoic subjects], as the bearers of social
ical Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution, and of egoic relations in general are not viewed as something real [Reales], as
trans. Richard Rojcewicz and Andr6 Schuwer (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989). the bearers of causal (real causal) relations, but rather as the egoic subjects of
Henceforth cited as Id. II with German page reference, which is included in the motivational relations." (Edmund Husserl, Zur Phanomenologie der Intersub-
margins of the translation. jektivitat, Erster Teil: 1905-1920, ed. Iso Kern, Husserliana XIII [The Hague:
3 Edmund Husserl, Die Idee der Phdnomenologie. Funf Vorlesungen, ed. -Walter Nijhoff, 1973], 504).
Biemel, Husserliana II (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1950); English translation: The 12 Dan Zahavi has made this point clearly in his study Self-Awareness and Alter-
Idea of Phenomenology, trans. William P. Alston and George Nakhnikian (The ity: A Phenomenological Investigation (Evanston, 111.: Northwestern University,
Hague: Nijhoff, 1964). Henceforth cited as 'Hua IP with German page refer- 1999), esp. 52-62.
ence, which is included in the margins of the translation. 13 See also the subsequent pages where he spells out the essentially free nature of
4 Edmund Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phdnomenologis- persons as the ability to inhibit, call into question, or revise the otherwise
chen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einfiihrung in die reine Phdnom- passive operations of mental Ufe through an analysis of them and the justifica-
enologie, ed. Karl Schuhmann, Husserliana III/l (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1976); tion or lack of justification for them.
English translation: Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phe- 14 See, e.g., Edmund Husserl, Vorlesungen uber Ethik und Wertlehre 1908-1914,
nomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to a Pure ed. Ullrich Melle, Husserliana XXVIII (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988), 33-
Phenomenology, trans. F. Kersten (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1983). Henceforth cited 15 This level of experience according to Husserl has been described in great detail
as Id. I with the original Jahrbuch-pagination, which is included in the margins by Nam-In Lee, Edmund Husserls Phdnomenologie der Instinkte (Dordrecht:
of the German and English editions. Kluwer, 1993).

160 161
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S

16 For examples of the difference and how Husserl applies this distinction, see Id.
II, 259-65.
17 The positions advanced in the first and third of these corollaries can be found
in almost all of Husserl's published works. Until recently, they have been asso-
ciated most closely with Husserl's final works on the crisis of European human-
ity, namely in the so-called Vienna lecture on "Phenomenology and the Crisis Part 12
of European Humanity" and in The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcen-
dental Phenomenology. (For the latter, see Edmund Husserl, Die Krisis der
europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phdnomenologie, ed.
Walter Biemel, Husserliana VI [The Hague: Nijhoff, 1954]; English translation: C U L T U R E A N D T H E
The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, trans.
David Carr [Evanston, III: Northwestern University, 1970]. The German text P R O B L E M O F H I S T O R Y
of the Vienna lecture may be found under the title of "Die Krisis des europais-
chen Menschentums und die Philosophie" in Hua VI, 314-48, and in English as
"Philosophy and the Crisis of European Humanity" in Carr's translation of the
Crisis, 269-99.) Both of these works stress and explain Husserl's views on the
third of these three corollaries. More recently, the publication of the Kaizo art-
icles in Hua XXVII connects that corollary more clearly with the positions
expressed in the first two corollaries and in the eighteen theses.
For a helpful and systematic discussion of the philosophical views Husserl
lays out in these essays, see Donn Welton, "Husserl and the Japanese," Review
of Metaphysics 44 (1991), 575-606. A detailed exposition of the positions listed
in these corollaries and their overall status within Husserl's philosophical work
has been provided by Hans Rainer Sepp, Praxis und Theoria. Husserls tran-
szendentalphilosophische Rekonstruktion des Lebens (Freiburg/Munich: Alber,
1997).
18 He describes the results of this process of ethical formation as follows: "This is
how the life-form of 'genuine humanity' arises, and for the human being who
evaluates himself, his life, and his possible actions how the idea of a 'genuine
and true human being,' that is, a rational human being, arises" (Hua XXVII,
33).
h 19 In The Person and the Common Life (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992) James Hart
11 has gathered together passages from Husserl's published and unpublished man-
uscripts and presented a convincing reconstruction of Husserl's normative
theory of a hierarchy of goods and a community of subjects dedicated to the
achievement of the good.
20 See Zahavi, Self-Awareness and Alterity, esp. 63-89. ...
21 See Welton, "Husserl and the Japanese," esp. 585-88.
22 See on this topic Hua XXVII, 79-89 and, even more clearly, Husserl's "Die
Idee einer philosophischen Kultur," in Erste Philosophie (1923/24). Erster Teil:
Kritische Ideengeschichte, ed. Rudolf Boehm, Husserliana VII (The Hague:
Nijhoff, 1956), 203-7,8-10, and 11-17, here 8-10.
23 A good account of this crisis and Husserl's attempt to offer phenomenology as
a response to it has been provided by R. Philip Buckley, Husserl, Heidegger
and the Crisis of Philosophical Responsibility (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992).

162
78

D I E P H A N O M E N O L O G I E A L S

T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E
1
D E R G E S C H I C H T E

Ludwig Landgrebe

Iii Source: Ernst Wolfgang Orth (ed.), Phanomenologie und Praxis. Phanomenologische
Forschungen 3 (1976): 17-47.
11
Mit dem Titel ist die These genannt, die in den folgenden Ausfuhrungen
begrUndet werden soil: „Wenn die Phdnomenologie Transzendental-
philosophie sein soil, dann ist sie, konsequent zu Ende gedacht, transzen-
dentale. Theorie der Geschichte." Mit dieser These soil die Frage
dahingestellt bleiben - man konnte sagen „eingeklammert" -, ob die
Phanomenologie transzendentale Phanomenologie sein soil oder sein muB.
Diese Frage war bekanntlich bei den Husserl-Schulern schon umstritten,
if seitdem er in seinen „Ideen", wie man so sagte, die „transzendentale
Wendung" vollzogen hatte. Aber die Schlichtung dieses Streits setzt
voraus, daB geklart ist, welche Bedeutung das Wort „transzendental" bei
Husserl hat, und diese Bedeutung ist nur aus dem Kontext seines Werkes
selbst zu eruieren. Dem Ausdruck darf nicht einfach die Bedeutung unter-
legt werden, die dieses Wort in der Philosophie vor Husserl hatte. So
werden die folgenden Ausfuhrungen selbstverstandlich an* Husserl
anknupfen, aber sie konnen nur mit Vorbehalt als ein Beitrag zur Husserl-
Interpretation verstanden werden. Interpretationen gibt es bald unuber-
i sehbar viele und im Streit miteinander liegende. Fast mag es so scheinen,
als ob ihre Verschiedenheit davon abhinge, welche Partien und Zitate
jeweils aus den vielschichtigen Texten Husserls herangezogen werden, um
sie zu stutzen. Dieser Streit bezieht sich fast auf samtliche der operativen
Grundbegriffe Husserls, die sich alle als nicht eindeutig erwiesen haben.
Aber gemeinsam ist den meisten der neueren Untersuchungen fiber
Husserls Phanomenologie, daB sie vom Spatwerk und den Manuskripten
der letzten Lebensepoche Husserls ausgehen, um die fruheren Arbeiten
als Schritte auf dem Wege zu seinen letzten Einsichten zu verstehen. Sie
gehorchen damit aber nicht der Anweisung einer Modestromung,
dergemaB erst das Spatwerk eines Denkers die letzten und entscheidenden

165
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

Gedanken bringt, von denen aus alles Fruhere nur als Vorbereitung ver- physik, die Kants Angriffsziel war, sondern* auch Kritik der versteckten
standen werden muB. Vielmehr hat dieses methodische Prinzip gerade metaphysischen Implikationen in modernen antimetaphysischen Positionen,
hier seine Fruchtbarkeit gezeigt, indem mit ihm nachgewiesen werden allgemein gesprochen also Kritik des ungepruften Gebrauchs aller
konnte, daB sich in der Entwicklung der Gedanken Husserls kein Bruch uberkommenen philosophischen Begriffe, mir denen Verstandigung fiber
finden laBt, sondern daB sie einer von Anfang an leitenden Intention unsere Welt und schUeBUch eine umfassende Welterklarung geleistet
entspricht, die freiUch in ihrer Entfaltung erst allmahlich zur Klarheit fiber werden soUte. In diesem Sinne ist Transzendentalphilosophie zugleich
das kommt, worauf sie von Anfang an hinaus war. DaB es so ist, entspricht Kritik des Sprachgebrauchs und als Auseinandersetzung mit metaphysis-
durchaus Husserls Konzeption der Intentionalitat und ihres Verhaltnisses chen und antimetaphysischen Theorien der Welterklarung selbst Theorie.
von Intention und Erfullung als eines Weges vom Dunklen zur Klarheit. Aber weil afle Versuche der Welterklarung in ihrem ursprungUchen Sinne
Das Verfahren, mit dem „spaten" Husserl gegen den fruheren zu argu- immer mer mehr waren als ..bloBe" Theorien, sondern vielmehr Versuche
mentieren, dessen sich alle neuern Untersuchungen bedienen, welche die der Verstandigung fiber die Welt, um in ihr den richtigen Weg des Lebens
Sache um ein Stuck weitergebracht haben, hat sich durch seinen Erfolg als zu finden, folgten aus solchen Theorien immer praktische Prinzipien des
legitim erwiesen. Daraus ergibt sich, daB eine Auseinandersetzung mit Handelns. Daher ist auch ihre transzendentale Kritik zugleich Kritik der
Husserls transzendentalphilosophischem Entwurf ihr Ziel verfehlen muB, Prinzipien des Handelns, die aus ihnen folgen. Diese Verklammerung UeBe
wenn sie ihn voreilig an Zielstellungen miBt, die von einem anderen sich schon in der ursprungUchen Pragung des Begriffs der Theoria durch
philosophischen Ausgangspunkt herstammen. Zuvor muB seine Position Aristoteles zeigen, und auch Husserl hat schUeBUch seine transzendentale
mit aUen in ihr enthaltenen Moglichkeiten zu Ende gedacht werden; erst Phanomenologie als „Kritik des Lebens" verstanden wissen wollen.
dann kann einsichtig werden, wo etwa die Grenzen der MogUchkeit einer Soviel zur vorlaufigen Verstandigung fiber den Begriff des ./Transzen-
transzendentalphilosophischen Reflexion liegen und wo mit einem dentalen" und fiber den Sinn, in dem Phanomenologie als transzendentale
anderen Verfahren fiber sie hinausgegangen werden muB. Theorie verstanden werden soU. Damit ist noch nichts fiber Geschichte als
SoUte sich dabei zeigen, daB Husserls spaten Reflexionen selbst die Hint das Thema dieser transzendentalen Theorie gesagt. Es ist bekannt, daB das
weise auf diese Grenzen zu entnehmen sind, dann wtirde seine Philosophie Wort Geschichte mindestens zwei Bedeutungen hat: Es konnen darunter
in berechtigter Weise Anspruch auf den Titel ..Transzendentalphilosophie" sowohl die res gestae wie die Historia rerum gestarum, die Geschichtswis-
machen konnen: ..Transzendental" in dem Sinne, daB darunter eine Erken- senschaft, verstanden werden. Mit der aufgesteUten These soU nun nicht
ntnisweise und ein Erkenntnisweg zu verstehen ist, der es ermoglicht, sich behauptet werden, daB die transzendentale Phanomenologie hier nur
t
selbst kritisch seine Grenzen zu setzen. Dieser Begriff von „transzendental" insoweit erortert werden soil, als sie Theorie der wissenschaftlichen Erken-
wtirde auch dem entsprechen, was Husserl in einem Manuskript ausfiihrt, ntnis der Geschichte ist, oder gar, daB sie uberhaupt auf eine solche, also auf
das offenbar nach AbschluB des „Krisis"-Textes und im RiickbUck darauf die Theorie der frfiher so genannten Geisteswissenschaften beschrankt
geschrieben ist und sich vor aUem auf den Galilei-Abschnitt dieses Werkes werden soU; denn wenn eine solche Theorie als eine philosophische
bezieht. Er spricht dort von empfindUchen Schwierigkeiten dieses Textes, Aufgabe verstanden wird, dann ist damit eine Reflexionsstufe genannt,
davon, daB „in solchem historischen Gang aUmShhch ein neuer Stil welche der transzendentalphilosophischen Reflexion nachgeordnet ist und
philosophischen Fragens und eine neue Methode philosophischer Arbeit sich erst auf sie griinden kann. Transzendentale Phanomenologie hat es
aufleuchtet". Zu seinem Gesamtsinn gehort, „das Ineinander von his- vorab mit der Frage zu tun „Was ist Geschichte?" bzw. was sind die tran-
torischer und durch sie motivierter systematischer Untersuchung, von vorn- szendentalen Bedingungen der Moglichkeit, daB es ftir uns so etwas wie
herein angelegt in der eigenen Reflexivitat, in der sich die Selbstbesinnung Geschichte gibt, die dann auch Gegenstand wissenschaftlicher Erforschung
des Philosophen aUein bewegen kann, der in der Situation ist, keine werden kann? In diesem Sinne hat Husserl nach dem „Apriori der
vorgegebene Philosophie, eigene wie fremde, voraussetzen zu konnen" Geschichte" gefragt. Es wird sich nun zeigen, daB dieses Apriori ganzUch
(Hua VI, 364). eigener Art ist.
Husserls Gebrauch des Wortes „transzendental" ist also formal gemein- Eine transzendentalphilosophische Besinnung kann daher auch nicht
sam mit dem Kantischen, daB er „Kritik" bedeutet: „Kritik des Umgangs die Gebietsabgrenzungen zwischen den einzelnen Wissenschaften einfach
mit Uberkommenen philosophischen Begriffen, die Frage nach dem quid als gegeben hinnehmen; denn diese Abgrenzungen sind zumeist aus den
juris?" ihres Gebrauchs zur Explikation unserer Erfahrung. In diesem Notwendigkeiten ihrer Erkenntnispraxis entstanden und heute in vielem
Sinne bedeutet ..transzendental" nichts anderes als den absoluten Gegen- fragUch geworden. Daher konnen wir auch nicht an Husserls Entwurf
satz zu jeder Art von Dogmatismus, nicht nur des Dogmatismus der Meta- regionaler Ontologien anknupfen, der im II. Band der „Ideen" vorliegt,

166 167

<•
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

und an dem sich auch Heidegger noch in „Sein und Zeit" orientiert hat; insbesondere als eidetisch denkendes und sehendes Ich mir faktisch
denn auch dieser Entwurf nahm die damals noch geltenden Abgrenzungen erworben habe. Die Phantasie-moglichkeiten als Varianten des Eidos
der Wissenschaftsgebiete einfach als gegebene hin. Er entstammt einer schweben nicht frei in derLuft, sondern sind konstitutiv bezogen auf mich
statischen Betrachtung. Die transzendentale Phanomenologie hat jedoch in meinem Faktum, mit meiner lebendigen Gegenwart, die ich faktisch
u erst als genetische Phanomenologie ihren voUen Begriff gewonnen - was ,lebe'"? Daher ist „die apodiktische Struktur der transzendentalen Wirk-
hier wohl keiner weiteren Begrundung bedarf (Aguirre, 153 ff.). Daher Uchkeit nicht vermoge jenes Umdenken-konnens eine solche, die kontin-
kann die Phanomenologie als transzendentale Theorie der Geschichte nur gent ware - ein zufaUiges Faktum, das einen Wesensrahmen von anderen
die genetische Phanomenologie sein. Es soil gezeigt werden, daB ihre Moglichkeiten hatte, die ebensogut hatten sein konnen. So muB dieses Ich,
Ergebnisse selbstverstandlich auch fiir die Theorie der wissenschaftlichen das ich selbst bin, absolutes Faktum genannt werden" (a.a. O.S. 148). „Ich
Erkenntnis von Bedeutung sind, daB aber unter Geschichte mehr zu ver- bin das Ur-faktum in diesem Gang der Ruckfrage . . . das Absolute, das in
stehen ist als der Inbegriff der res gestae. Daher muB der Sinn, in dem in sich selbst seinen Grund und in seinem grundlosen Sein seine absolute
der These von Geschichte gesprochen wird, zunachst noch in Schwebe Notwendigkeit hat als die eine .absolute Substanz'. Seine Notwendigkeit
bleiben. ist nicht Wesensnotwendigkeit, die ein Zufalliges offen lieBe. AUe Wesen-
Nun setzt aber eine transzendentale Theorie der Geschichte eine aus- snotwendigkeiten sind vielmehr Momente seines Faktums . . . sind Weisen,
reichende Theorie der Intersubjektivitat voraus. Auch sie kann nur als sich selbst zu verstehen oder verstehen zu k6nnen" (Hua XV, 386). „Das
f genetische entwickelt werden. Es ist nun nachgewiesen worden, daB Absolute, das wir enthUllen, ist absolute Tatsache" (Hua XV, 403).
I, Husserls Theorie der Intersubjektivitat in der 5. Cartesianischen Medita- Diese Thesen klingen im ersten AugenbUck befremdUch. Wird nicht mit
tion daran gescheitert ist, daB Husserl dort den Versuch machte, sie als ihnen die Grenze einer Transzendentalphilosophie Uberschritten in einem
statische zu entwickeln (Held, 1972, Iff.). Auch seine spateren Ansatze, Ubergang zu einer Metaphysik des Absoluten, die an ScheUings ..Positive
•I die jetzt in Band XV der Husserliana vorliegen, sind nicht ans Ziel gekom- Philosophie" erinnern konnte? Schon E. Fink hat seinerzeit eine solche
men, wohl aber kann einigen spaten Reflexionen Husserls der Hinweis Deutung zuruckgewiesen (Fink, 99 ff.). Er kannte diese Gedanken schon seit
darauf entnommen werden, wie diese LUcke zu schlieBen ist. Darauf soU der Zeit ihrer Entstehung (1931), in der Husserl an dem spater aufgegebenen
spater zuruckgekommen werden. Versuch arbeitete, den deutschen Text der ..Cartesianischen Meditationen"
Nach diesen einleitenden Bemerkungen sei zur Begrundung der These zu revidieren: Es handle sich hier keineswegs um einen tjbergang in eine
ubergegangen, die nun etwas erganzt lauten muB: Die transzendentale spekulative Metaphysik, sondern vielmehr um „Verlegenheitsbegriffe
genetische Phdnomenologie ist als solche transzendentale Theorie der philosophischer Grenzlagen", die aus dem unermudhchen Bestreben
Geschichte. Es sei hierzu an zwei Gedanken Husserls angeknupft, die auf stammen, durch reflektive Analyse den LebensvoUzug des transzendentalen
den ersten BUck miteinander unvertragUch zu sein scheinen. Der erste BewuBtseins sozusagen auf frischer Tat zu ertappen. SoUte dies so sein, dann
betrifft die Charakteristik des transzendentalen „Ego", dessen weltkonstitu- ware dies gerade eine Bekraftigung der Legitimitat des Anspruchs der
ierende Leistungen das Thema der Phanomenologie sind. Die phanomenol- Phanomenologie auf den Titel „transzendental". Sie hatte damit gezeigt, daB
ogische Reduktion fuhrt zuruck auf die apodiktische SelbstgewiBheit dieses sie in der Lage ist, sich kritisch ihre eigenen Grenzen evident zu machen.
Ich. Es ist in dieser Reflexion in einer unmittelbaren Weise fiir sich selbst Um hierin zur Klarheit zu kommen, sei diese These fiber die Abso-
gegenwartig. In dieser Selbstgegenwart seiner konstituierenden Funktionen lutheit des transzendentalen Ego mit einer These fiber die Geschichte
ist es fiir sich selbst apodiktisch gewiB und kann diese Funktionen in eidetis- konfrontiert, die sich im SchluBabsatz eines Forschungsmanuskripts Uber
cher Variation als zu jedem uberhaupt erdenkUchen Ich notwendig gehorig „Transzendentale Reduktion und absolute Rechtfertigung" findet. Diese
erkennen. Husserl hat freiUch von Anfang an immer wieder betont, daB These lautet „Die Geschichte ist das grofie Faktum des absoluten Seins"*.
eine solche Reflexion jeweils von einem faktisch existierenden Ich ausgeubt Dieser SchluBabsatz hat in Husserls Manuskript den Untertitel „Mon-
wird. Aber gemaB der schon in den „Ideen" entwickelten Wesenslehre ist adologie" erhalten. Hierzu ist zunachst zweierlei zu bemerken:
ein singulares Faktum seinem Wesen gegentiber zufallig. Erst seit 1931 wird 1. Dieses Manuskript stammt aus dem Anfang der zwanziger Jahre. Es
in zum Teil noch unveroffentUchten Manuskripten diese These umgekehrt: ist also nicht so, daB Husserl erst in der letzten Phase seines Denkens die
„Das Eidos transzendentales Ich ist undenkbar ohne transzendentales Ich Bedeutung der Geschichte fiir die Phanomenologie entdeckt hatte. Das
als faktisches" (Hua XV, 385), denn „,Ich' der Umdenkende, der mich gibt die Anweisung, diese Entdeckung nicht ads einen Bruch in seinem
durch Variation der faktischen WirkUchkeit Enthebende bin apodiktisch Denken, sondern als Konsequenz aus seinem fruheren transzendental-
das Ich der faktischen Wirklichkeit und bin das Ich der Vermogen, die ich philosophischen Ansatz zu verstehen.

168 169

m
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

2. Das Manuskript gibt einen Hinweis auf den Kontext, aus der Husserls tivismus fUhrt und damit den Weg zur Wahrheit der Geschichte verbaut.
These Uber die Geschichte stammt: Es ist die Monadologie. Die Interpreta- Dieser Hinweis mag genUgen, um zu zeigen, daB es sich bei der Erwah-
tion hat bisher diesem Titel zu wenig Aufmerksamkeit geschenkt und damit nung dieses Streites zwischen Ranke und Gervinus nicht um eine bloBe
das Problem nicht beachtet, das hinter der Rezeption eines Leibnizschen historische Reminiszenz handelt, sondern um ein Grundproblem der
!
! Terminus verborgen ist. Es ist eine Rezeption, in welcher die Bedeutung Erkenntnis der Geschichte, das bis heute noch umstritten ist. Im Anfang
dieses Terminus verandert wird. Die Leibnizschen Monaden haben keine der 50er Jahre berichtete die ..Historische Zeitschrift" Uber eine Diskus-
Fenster, wohl aber die „Monade" im Kontext der transzendentalen sion der amerikanischen Historiker um die methodischen Prinzipien,
Phanomenologie als Bezeichnung fiir das transzendentale Ego. In diesem denen gemaB der japanische Uberfall auf Pearl Harbour dargestellt
Sinne spricht Husserl von der transzendentalen Intersubjektivitat als dem werden soil. In dieser Diskussion standen genau die gleichen Positionen
„Monadenall". sich gegenuber, wie sie seinerzeit durch Ranke und Gervinus verkorpert
Hieran sind zwei Fragen zu knupfen: waren. Auch an den Umgang der Bolschewisten mit der Geschichte mag
1. Was gibt das Recht, fUr das „transzendentale Ego", das in seiner fUr dabei erinnert werden, die bekanntUch immer wieder nach den Interessen
sich selbst apodiktisch gewissen Gegenwartigkeit „absolutes Faktum" ist, der Partei umgeschrieben werden muB. Es handelt sich also um das
den Titel „Monade" zu verwenden? Problem, ob die Wahrheit dessen, was historisch Uberliefert ist, sich in
2. Wie sind die beiden Thesen fiber das ..Absolute" mit einander dem erschopft, was davon fUr die Interessen der jeweiUgen Gegenwart als
vertragUch, bzw. wie gehoren sie, sich gegenseitig erganzend, zueinander, bedeutsam gilt, oder ob es vor alien anderen Fragen in seiner Individual-
und was ergibt sich daraus fur das Verstandnis des Sinnes von Husserls itat, so „wie es eigentlich gewesen ist", gewUrdigt werden muB. Die
Rede Uber das Absolute und fUr den transzendental-phanomenologischen Geschichtstheorie der SUdwestdeutschen Schule des Neukantianismus
Begriff der Geschichte? hat um dieses Problem sehr wohl gewuBt, indem sie die geschichtUche
Es zeigt sich hier, daB beide Fragen nicht getrennt voneinander behan- Erkenntnis als „idiographische" von der „nomothetischen" der Naturwis-
delt werden konnen. Gerade ihre Zusammengehorigkeit ist das transzen- senschaften zu unterscheiden suchte. Von einer kritischen Diskussion des
dental-phdnomenologische Problem der Geschichte, das im folgenden in Weges, auf dem die neukantianische Theorie das Problem der Individual-
wenigen groben Grundztigen entfaltet werden soil. Zur Vorbereitung i s t mittels des Begriffs der Wertbeziehung zu losen suchte, muB hier
hierauf sei auf die Bedeutung hingewiesen, welche die Einfiihrung des abgesehen werden, obwohl eine solche auch heute noch von aktueller
Begriffs der Monadefur die Wissenschaftstheorie der Historie hat. Bedeutung ware; denn diese Theorie der Wertbeziehung hat in dem
Es ist hierfUr daran zu erinnern, daB auch der Grundgedanke von gegenwartigen Streit um die Wertfreiheit in der Gesellschaftstheorie noch
Herders Philosophie der Geschichte nachweisUch von Leibniz' Monadolo- immer ihre Nachwirkungen.
gie inspiriert ist. Es ist der Gedanke der schlechthinnigen IndividuaUtat Es soil damit nicht behauptet werden, daB Husserl bei seiner „Entdeck-
und EinmaUgkeit aUes dessen, was geschichtlich ist. Es hat seine absolute ung" der Geschichte irgendwie von der Entwicklung der Geschichtstheo-
Bedeutung in sich selbst und nicht erst in dem, was aus ihm hervorgeht. rie seit Herder beeinfluBt war. Nichts laBt darauf schlieBen, daB er sich
Herder hat damit den Fortschrittsgedanken der Aufklarung und insbeson- uberhaupt mit ihr und spezieU mit Herder beschaftigt hat. Er ist in der
dere Voltaires kritisiert und damit der modernen Geschichtswissenschaft Konsequenz seines eigenen Weges auf die Bedeutung des „ Urfaktums" der
den Boden bereitet. Sie ist geleitet von dem Interesse an dem individu- IndividuaUtat fiir die Geschichte gefuhrt worden, und es laBt sich zeigen,
eUen Sein. Leopold von Ranke hat Herders These in fast gleichlautenden daB in der Verfolgung dieses Weges zu einer besseren Begrundung der
Wendungen in seinen Vortragen vor Konig Maximilian von Bayern uber Wahrheit der Geschichte zu gelangen ist, als es die war, welche die
die Epochen der neueren Geschichte wiederholt. Sie ist das Credo der neukantianische Geschichtstheorie anbot. Zunachst soUte aus diesem
Geschichtswissenschaft, von dem her erst der Sinn der von ihr geforderten Hinweis nur ersichtlich werden, daB die Ubernahme des Leibnizschen
Objektivitat zu verstehen ist. Von der „PoUtischen Historie", insbesondere Titels „Monade" zur Bezeichnung des absoluten Faktums des transzen-
von Gervinus wurde diese Forderung Rankes bekampft: Die Historie habe dentalen Ego in seiner lebendigen Selbstgegenwart nicht die EinfUhrung
den Interessen des Tages zu dienen, dem Interesse an der Selbstbehaup- eines bloBen „Verlegenheitsausdrucks" bedeutet, sondern daB damit das
tung der Nation. Ranke trat dieser These nachdruckUch entgegen, weil er zentrale Problem der Begrundung der Wahrheit anvisiert ist, so wie es sich
ihre relativistischen Konsequenzen und darin das Ende der Historie als bis heute auch fur den Historiker stellt. Aber es ist nicht nur ein Problem
Wissenschaft sah. In dieser Auseinandersetzung zeigt sich, daB nicht der der Wissenschaftstheorie der Historie, sondern es betrifft darUber hinaus
Gedanke der IndividuaUtat, sondern vielmehr seine Mifiachtung zum Rela- das Verhaltnis der Menschen je einer Epoche oder Gruppe zu ihrer

170 171
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

Geschichte schon vor ihrer wissenschaftlichen Erkenntnis. Es hat seine Wahrheiten nie werden." Kann also der reflektive Rekurs auf das „Ich
besondere Aktualitat in einer Zeit, die vom Verlust der Geschichte und bin" in seiner geschichtiichen Bedingtheit uberhaupt den Anspruch
den Tendenzen zur Abkehr von ihr bedroht ist. machen, der Weg zur Einsicht in das zu sein, was wir aUe, ein jedes Glied
Damit sei tibergegangen zur zweiten Frage, die sich auf den Zusammen- der ..Menschheit" sind. Es ist dies im Grunde die Frage, die sich Husserl
hang zwischen den beiden Thesen fiber die Absolutheit des „Ego" und selbst im Krisis-Werk gestellt hat, die Frage nach der allgemeinen Bedeu-
Uber die Absolutheit der Geschichte bezieht sowie auf den daraus folgen- tung dieses seinem Ursprung nach europaischen Stiles der Reflexion.
den transzendental-phanomenologischen Begriff der Geschichte. Es Diese Frage kann nun in folgender Weise formuUert werden: Dieser
wurde darauf hingewiesen, daB sowohl Herders Geschichtsphilosophie wie Weg der Reflexion fuhrt Husserl auf den Gedanken der Absolutheit des
Husserls „Monadologie" auf den Leibnizschen Gedanken der Monade ..transzendentalen Ego" als Monade und, was deren Verhaltnis zur
zuruckgreifen. Der historische Hintergrund der Leibnizschen Monadolo- Geschichte betrifft, zu einer Bemerkung, die als die letzte Antwort auf
gie ist der reformatorische Gedanke der Unmittelbarkeit eines jeden seine Frage nach dem „Apriori" der Geschichte verstanden werden muB:
einzelnen Menschen zu Gott. Diese Unmittelbarkeit fordert, daB jede Die Welt ist eine geschichtliche nur „durch die innere GeschichtUchkeit
menschliche Monade von nichts abhangig ist als von Gott, der sie geschaf- jedes einzelnen und als einzelne in ihrer inneren GeschichtUchkeit mit der
fen hat. Sie muB also in sich abgeschlossen, „ohne Fenster" sein. DaB die anderer vergemeinschafteten Personen" (Hua VI, 381 Anm. I) 4 . ..Innere
Monaden untereinander in einem commercium stehen konnen, kann also GeschichtUchkeit" besagt im Sinne Husserls eine Charakteristik der
nur durch eine prastabiUerte Harmonie gewahrleistet sein. Fur die tran- monadischen Qualitat der Einzigkeit jedes einzelnen personalen Subjektes.
szendentale Phanomenologie verbietet sich jedoch eine solche metaphysis- Sie ist' danach das ..Apriori", das heiBt, die Struktur, auf Grund deren es ftir
che Begrundung des Gedankens der Monade und ihres commercium. Sie uns uberhaupt erst „die Geschichte" gibt. Inwiefern ist damit ein Verhaltnis
muB auf dem Wege der ihr eigentumUchen Reflexion auf die Subjektivitat genannt, das in apodiktischer AUgemeinheit fiir jedes personale Subjekt
die Einfiihrung des Monadenbegriffs in der Weise begrUnden, daB die Uberhaupt gilt, und uns dann schUeBUch von einer ..Geschichte der Men-
These der Absolutheit ihr Recht behalt, aber trotzdem ihr commercium schheit" sprechen laBt? Warum kann dieser Satz nicht umgekehrt werden,
bestehen kann. Hierfur dUrfen die Monaden nicht als fensterlos gedacht wenn andereseits das Wort gelten soU „Die Geschichte ist das groBe
werden. Es ist also die Aufgabe der phanomenologischen Analyse, den Faktum des absoluten Seins"? Er mtiBte in der Umkehrung lauten: Die
Punkt zu finden, an dem die „Fenster" zu suchen sind. Dazu bedarf es, wie Geschichte ist die apriorische Voraussetzung der inneren GeschichtUchkeit
schon gesagt, einer Intersubjektivitatstheorie, die imstande ist, diese Frage jedes einzelnen Ichsubjektes; dies ware nur dann mogUch, wenn sich die
nach den Fenstern zu beantworten.
..Monade" schon vorab im Zusammenhang der Geschichte findet. In einem
Um das Problem noch scharfer ins Auge zu fassen, ist zunachst einem modernen Jargon gesprochen hieBe dies: Die innere GeschichtUchkeit ist
Einwand Rechnung zu tragen, der sich gerade aus dem Hinweis auf die nichts anderes als die InternaUsierung der Geschichte. Nur unter ganz bes-
historische Herkunft des Monade-Gedankens als unabweislich ergibt: Ist timmten historischen Bedingungen ware eine solche InternaUsierung
nicht der Stil einer solchen Reflexion selbst erst Ergebnis der moghch und konnte ein Begriff von ..GeschichtUchkeit" gebildet werden.
neuzeitlichen Geschichte des Denkens mit ihren spezifischen, auf Ihm kame demgemaB uber den Bereich abendlandischer Kultur hinaus
Descartes zuruckgehenden Voraussetzungen, die ihrerseits in einer noch keinerlei VerbindUchkeit zu.
weiter zurUckreichenden Geschichte des abendlandischen Denkens ihre Nur wenn gezeigt werden kann, wie die transzendental-phanomenolo-
Wurzel haben? Andere Kulturen haben bekanntlich diesen Stil der gische Reflexion imstande ist, eine verbindliche Entscheidung Uber diese
Reflexion nicht entwickelt. Der Begriff der Einzigkeit und Einmaligkeit Alternative zu treffen, kann yerstandlich werden, wie die beiden Thesen
und in diesem Sinne Absolutheit eines jeden menschlichen, und das heiBt Husserls zusammengehoren, und kann die Behauptung begrUndet werden,
mit Denk- und Reflexionsvermogen ausgestatteten Wesens ist ihnen daB die transzendentale genetische Phanomenologie transzendentale
fremd. Ist also dies nicht nur das Resultat einer ganz bestimmten Theorie der Geschichte ist. Hierzu ist nun der Shin des Reflexionsweges in
abendlandischen Kulturentwicklung und Geschichte, ein Gedanke, der aller KUrze nachzuzeichnen, auf dem Husserl zu seinen beiden Thesen
nur unter ganz bestimmten geschichtlichen Bedingungen formuliert gefuhrt wurde. Es ist die eigentumUche Form der Reflexivitat naher ins
werden konnte? Kann also das, was nur geschichtsbedingte Tatsache ist, Auge zu fassen, fUr die nach dem schon genannten Zitat das Ineinander
zur apodiktischen Einsicht in unbedingt Allgemeines und Notwendiges von historischer und durch sie motivierter systematischer RUckfrage
fUhren - eine Frage, die schon Lessing gestellt und verneinend beant- charakteristisch ist.
wortet hat: „Geschichtliche Tatsachen konnen der Erweis ewiger Die transzendentale Phanomenologie in ihrer vollen Entwicklung zur

172 173
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

genetischen Phanomenologie wird von Husserl auch als Ursprungs- Konnens. Husserl ist diesem Sachverhalt sehr wohl auf der Spur gewesen,
forschung bezeichnet. Zuletzt nennt er sie auch „Archaologie" des wenn er in der Analyse des kinasthetischen Vermogens in „Ideen" II (Hua
BewuBtseins, weil sie genetisch die „Tiefenschicht" der passiven Vorkon- IV, 261) sagt „das ,ich bewege' geht dem ,ich kann' voraus". Das gilt auch
stitution zum Thema hat. Ursprung all unserer Vorstellungen von dem, schon dort, wo auf einer frtihen Stufe der vorsprachlichen Entwicklung
was wir erfahren und erkennen, sind die der Reflexion zuganglichen kon- des Kindes die zielgerichtete Bewegung der Leibesglieder eingeubt und
stituierenden Funktionen der Subjektivitat. Nun ist auch schon fiir Kant nachgeahmt wird. In solcher Betatigung, in ihrem Gelingen oder MiBUn-
die Transzendentalphilosophie geleitet von der Frage nach dem Ursprung. gen erfahrt sich das Kind schon frtih als Zentrum und Quelle spontaner
Er hat Vernunftursprung und Zeitursprung unterschieden (Kant 1793,39). Bewegung, mit der es in seiner Umwelt etwas bewirken, ergreifen,
Aber diese Unterscheidung wird von Husserl abgelehnt: „Das wegschieben etc. kann. Alle Vorstellungen von wirkenden Kraften haben
herrschende Dogma von der prinzipiellen Trennung von erkenntnistheo- in dieser Erfahrung ihren Ursprung. In ihr wird ein „weil - so" in
retischer Aufklarung und historischer Erklarung, von erkenntnistheoretis- ursprtingUcher Weise erfahren. DaB dieses Zentrum spontaner Bewegung
chem und genetischem Ursprung ist . . . grundverkehrt" (Hua VI, 379). und Wirkung sich als Ich dem Du gegentibersteUt, ist genetisch ein
Was ist nun die eigentumliche Form der Reflexivitat, im HinbUck auf Spateres. Es ist schon vorher diese individuelle Existenz und „kennt" sich
welche diese Behauptung begrUndet werden kann? Diese Form findet sich als solche aus der Erfahrung des Verftigenkonnens iiber seinen Leib in
nicht in der Tafel der gangigen Begriffe von Reflexion, wie sie H. Wagner der allmahlich erlernten Fahigkeit der Beherrschung seiner Motorik. Sie
in seinem Artikel „Reflexion" im Handbuch philosophischer Begriffe eroffnet ihm den ersten Zugang zu seiner Umwelt.
zusammengestellt hat. Es ist dort freiUch die Husserlsche Form der Reflex- Man konnte freiUch fragen, ob diese Art vorsprachlicher Bekanntschaft
ion als „Konstitutipns-reflexion" aufgefuhrt. Sie ist der reflektive RUckgang mit sich selbst als Zentrum spontanen Sichbewegenkonnens etwas spezi-
vom Noema als Produkt zu den es produzierenden und konstituierenden fisch Menschliches und nicht vielmehr auch dem Tier zuzusprechen ist.
Akten. Diese Charakteristik trifft ftir Husserls eigenes Verstandnis seines Gilt sie nicht ftir einen jeden biologischen Organismus als einer der Selbst-
Vorgehens freiUch zu. Es ist immer orientiert an dem Schema der Gegen- steuerung fahigen Einheit? Dazu kann hier nur gesagt werden, sie
standskonstitution, in der sich Gegenstand als synthetische Einheit seiner fungieren selbstverstandlich als Zentren der Bewegung, aber sie wissen
Erscheinungsweisen bildet, und er sucht die Selbstkonstitution des Ich als sich nicht als solche. Husserl spricht in diesem Sinne im AnschluB an
des indentischen in der Mannigfaltigkeit seiner konstituierenden Aktvol- Leibniz von schlafenden Monaden. Es wtirde zu weit fuhren, dieses
lztige nach diesem ModeU zu begreifen. In diesem Sinne ist die Reflexion Problem hier weiter zu erortern.
immer ein „Nachgewahren", ein nachtragliches Sichzurtickwenden auf die
Was mit dem Hinweis auf den Ursprung all unseres Wissens um ein
bereits voUzogenen Funktionen (Landgrebe 1963,192ff.). Es ist dies aber
Konnen gesagt sein soU, ist nur dies, daB ohne diese ursprungUche Ver-
ein statischer Begriff von Reflexivitat, der damit entwickelt wurde. Husserl
trautheit mit dem kinasthetischen Konnen es keine hohere Stufe der Reflex-
selbst hat freiUch die Grenzen des statischen Verfahrens in seinen genetis-
ivitat geben kann, die auch auf jeder hoheren Stufe immer den Sinn einer
chen Analysen de facto frtih Uberschritten, aber gerade diesen Ubergang in
Reflexion auf das Konnen, auf seinen Spielraum und seine Grenzen hat.
seiner systematischen Bedeutung nicht mehr zum Thema gemacht. Er sei
Dieses Sichbewegenkbnnen ist die elementarste Form der Spontaneitdt, und
hier in einer vereinfachten Weise skizziert.
eine Handlungstheorie, die nicht von ihr ausgeht, kann nur zu einem abstrak-
Statische Reflexion kann nicht auf den Ursprung der Bekanntschaft mit ten and globalen Begriff von Handlung gelangen. Auch das Sprechen, in
uns selbst und unseren konstituierenden Funktionen fuhren, welche aller dem das Denkvermogen erst artikuUert wird, hat die Struktur des kinas-
Reflexion auf schon vollzogene Akte voranliegt. Diese eigentUmliche thetischen BewegungsvoUzuges. So sind diese kinasthetischen Funktionen,
Weise der Reflexivitat als einer vorgangigen Bekanntschaft mit uns selbst ohne die es keine Zeitkonstitution gibt, die tiefstUegende Dimension der
kann durch einen Blick auf die Weise verstandlich werden, wie wir im transzendentalen Subjektivitat, die eigentiiche Ursprungssphare, so daB auch
alltagUchen Leben zum Anhalten unserer AktvollzUge in einer. Reflexion der Leib als fungierender Leib nicht ein bloB Konstituiertes, sondern selbst
auf ihr Gelingen oder MiBUngen motiviert werden. Das geschieht zumeist konstituierend ist als transzendentale Bedingung der MogUchkeit jeder
dann, wenn wir im Vollzug einer Handlung auf Schwierigkeiten stoBen. hoheren Stufe des BewuBtseins und seines reflexiven Charakters (Land-
Dann wird der naive Vollzug angehalten mit der Besinnung, die sprachlich grebe, Reflexionen 1974,466 ff.).
formuliert lauten wtirde „Warum hast Du das nicht gekonnt?" So ist Husserl hat diese Konsequenz nicht explizit vollzogen. Aber wenn er
Reflexion primar immer Ruckwendung auf das, was wir vermogen. Aber von der „Naturseite" der Subjektivitat spricht, und davon, daB die tran-
was wir vermogen, das erfahren wir erst in der Betatigung unseres szendentale Subjektivitat nur per aequivocationem ein Ich zu nennen ist,

174 175
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

so weist dies darauf hin, daB er die „Natur" nicht als das Andere Fungieren zum Gegenstand der Reflexion, die als solche immer ein
gegenuber der Subjektivitat verstanden wissen wiU, sondern als sie selbst Nachgewahren ist, dann wird es nicht mehr als das erfaBt, was es in seinem
in ihrem untersten Grunde. So verstanden ist sie nicht die zum Inbegriff lebendigen Vollzug ist. Nur in ihm ist es „selbst da". FreiUch dieses
des realen Daseins „au6er uns" objektivierte Natur, sondern die Natur, so apodiktisch gewisse Selbstda entspricht nicht den Forderungen, die
wie sie ftir uns unmittelbar erfahren ist in der Bekanntschaft mit unseren Husserl an den RUckgang auf letzte apodiktische GewiBheit gestellt hat.
leiblichen Funktionen. Wenn es diese Beherrschung unserer kinasthetis- Selbstdasein bedeuter ftir ihn, in phanomenologischer Reflexion
chen Funktionen ist, die uns den ersten Zugang zu unserer Welt eroffnet, anschaulich sein. Aber eine Funktion ab Konnen kann nicht angeschaut
so ware es doch falsch zu sagen, daB es der Leib ist, der individuiert. Er ist werden, sie kann in ihrem Selbst-da nur bewuBt sein in ihrer Betatigung.
es nur insofern, als ihn einer als seinen Leib weiB, iiber den er in gewissen Hier ist freiUch eine Grenze nachgewahrender, das Gewahrte thema-
Grenzen verftigen kann. Auch dies hat Husserl gesehen, wenn er (a. a. O. tisierender Reflexion erreicht, jenseits derer es gleichwohl ein unmittelbar
Hua IV) sagt „die Entdeckung des Mein geht der Entdeckung des Ich apodiktisch Gewisses gibt. Es ist freiUch vorsprachUch. Wird es ausge-
voran". Aber er hat nicht die Konsequenzen gezogen, die sich daraus ftir sprochen, so unterUegt das Aussprechen schon dem Ontifikationszwang,
das Verstandnis des Sinnes der Absolutheit des ..transzendentalen Ego" der mit der Rede unausweichlich verbunden ist, weil die Bedeutung ihrer
ergeben und ftir die Einsicht in den primar praktischen Sinn der Reflexion Worter immer schon bezogen ist auf bereits Konstituiertes und nicht auf
als Reflexion auf das Konnen. letztkonstituierende Funktionen. Gleichwohl ist dieses absolute Da nichts
Das Sichbewegenkonnen ist die tiefstiiegende transzendentale Funktion, bloB Erschlossenes, sondern eben in seinem Fungieren Bekanntes und
mit der sich ineins die Zeit konstituiert. Es hat also seinen Grund, daB die Gewisses, gewiB als die Unausweichlichkeit des Da, von dem wir schon
erste ausftihrliche Zeitanalyse - die des Aristoteles - im Kontext der Frage immer gestellt sind, und dem uns zu stellen wir gezwungen sind. In diesem
nach der Bewegung ihren Ort hat (Landgrebe 1969). In der Erfahrung Sinne ist es absolutes Faktum, das hinzunehmen, durch keine Reflexion
dieses betatigten Konnens erschUeBt sich je mein oder je des Anderen mehr zu hinterfragen ist. „Das letztfungierende Ich kann sich selbst als
unaufhebUches Da als apodiktische GewiBheit lebendiger Funktionsgegen- standiges nicht einholen. Das letztfungierende Ich ist seinem eigenen
wart. Von diesem Da gewinnt der Begriff des absoluten Faktums erst seinen reflexiven Gegenwartigen stetig vorweg" (Held 1966).
Sinn: „Einerseits ist das letztfungierende Ich vor aUer Betatigung freier Damit ist in kurzen und groben ZUgen der genetische Reflexionsweg
Variation und Ideation von JchUchkeit tiberhaupt' und vor der Setzung der transzendental meditierenden Jch-Monade nachgezeichnet. Dieser
eines allzeitiichen nunc stans schon da; das Ich stoBt gleichsam auf dieses Weg ftihrt auf ihr undurchstreichbares Da als den letzten Grund der
'Da', das es selbst ist. Andererseits muB gesagt werden, daB dieses Da nicht apodiktischen Gewifiheit ihrer selbst als lebendiger Funktionsgegenwart.
in der Weise ,vorgegeben' ist, wie Sinnesreize hoherstufigen Erfahrungen in Dieser Grund selbst kann nicht mehr reflektiv thematisiert werden. Er
der Konstitution voranUegen" (Held 1966,149, cf. Schtitz, XXXI). Das wfll wird vielmehr erfahren als die Grenze, auf die die transzendentale Reflex-
sagen: um Sinnesreize zu empfangen, bedarf es schon dieses Da. Das muB ion stoBt und an der sie sich bricht. Wenn nun Reflexion primar den Sinn
richtig verstanden werden: wenn wir von unserem Da sprechen, so ist mit einer Reflexion auf das Konnen hat, so besagt dies, daB sie hier an die
diesem Demonstrativum schon immer mitgemeint ein Da an seiner Zeit- Grenze ihres Kdnnens stoBt, der gegentiber aUes Konnen machtlos ist, und
stelle, dem andere Da vorangehen und folgen. Aber diese Rede stammt.aus die es einfach hinzunehmen hat. So findet sich jedes Ich-subjekt im
einer nachgewahrenden Reflexion, in der dieses Da schon vergegen- Vollzug seiner konstituierenden Funktionen in unmittelbarer Weise in
standUcht ist als eines unter anderen, denen das in aUen beharrende „ste- sein Da gestellt - in der Sprache von Heideggers „Sein und Zeit" ausge-
hende und bleibende Ich" korrespondiert. Es ist diejenige Reflexion, welche drtickt konnte man sagen „geworfen". Es wird dabei mit sich als dem
Hegels Dialektik der sinnUchen GewiBheit in Gang setzt; sie soU zeigen, daB Zentrum seiner Funktionen und mit ihrem Konnen unmittelbar durch
diese vermeintUche Unmittelbarkeit selbst eine vermittelte ist. Hier dagegen ihren Vollzug bekannt. Es erfahrt sich dabei, in dem, was es vermag, und
handelt es sich um den Nachweis, daB diese lebendige Funktionsgegenwart erfahrt von Anfang an sein Konnen als ein zu erlernendes und zu tibendes.
ein apodiktisch undurchstreichbar Gewisses ist, ein nicht mehr hinterfrag- In dieser Erfahrung ist aber bereits die Verweisung auf seine Lebens-
bares Faktum, und in diesem Sinne unmittelbar und absolut, als absolutes geschichte beschlossen: das Konnen, in dem es sich erfahrt, ist erfahren als
Faktum, das die tiefstiiegende transzendentale Bedingung der Moglichkeit ein gewordenes durch die Geschichte seiner Erfahrung, in der es dieses
aUer Funktionen und ihrer Leistungen ist. sein Konnen ausgebildet hat. Sie kann ihm in Reflexion primar als die
Die konstitutiven Funktionen sind immer Vermogenzu . . . aber Geschichte seines Lebens bekannt werden, die aber „anonym" schon
Vermogen sind ftir uns nur „da", indem sie betatigt werden. Wird dieses immer geschehen ist und gewirkt hat, bevor die Reflexion darauf beginnt.

176 177
L I F E - W O R L D , ETHICS, H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

Eine solche Reflexion kann z. B. sprachlich artikuliert lauten „Warum ist es Ich" ist, derart, daB eines nicht ohne das andere sein kann. Es ist also die
so gekommen, warum habe ich dies getan?". Daher kann Husserl sagen Frage zu beantworten „Wie kommen die Anderen in meine eigene Ur-
„Die Frage des Warum ist ursprtinglich Frage nach der .Geschichte'" (Hua Zeitigung?" (Hua XV, 353), so daB jede „Seele" „zwar in sich und ftir sich
XV, 420). Das wfll sagen, sie ist die Frage nach der „inneren ist, daB sie aber doch nur Sinn hat in einer in ihr selbst gegrtindeten, aus
GeschichtUchkeit", die aUem ausdrfickUchen Sich-erinnern und aller Auto- ihr selbst zu entfaltenden Pluralitat" (Hua XV, 341).
biographic vorangeht und der transzendentale Grund ihrer MogUchkeit ist. Husserl ist eine systematische Entfaltung und Beantwortung dieser
Diese „innere GeschichtUchkeit" ist auffindbar auf dem Wege einer Fragen nicht mehr gelungen, wohl aber geben einige spate Manuskripte
„egologischen" Reflexion und genetischen Ruckfrage. Sie wird gefunden als den Hinweis in die Richtung, in der sie gesucht werden kann. Dort wird
die GeschichtUchkeit des je-eigenen Lebens, das durch sein Da unaus- Husserls schon frtihere Charakteristik der Intentionalitat als „Urstreben in
tauschbar und unaufhebUch von dem jedes Anderen getrennt ist. Nun soil der Monade" ein Sttick weiter konkretisiert: ..Dtirfen oder mtissen wir
aber nach Husserl die innere GeschichtUchkeit das „Apriori" der nicht eine universale Trieb-Intentionalitat voraussetzen, die jede urttim-
Geschichte sein, sei diese nun verstanden als die Geschichte der eigenen liche Gegenwart als stehende Zeitigung einheitlich ausmacht und von
Famflie oder des eigenen Volkes, der eigenen Epoche oder ganz allgemein Gegenwart zu Gegenwart forttreibt, derart, daB aller Inhalt Inhalt von
als die Geschichte der „Menschheit", also immer der Geschichte, die ein Trieberftillung ist und vor dem Ziel intendiert ist" (Hua XV, 595). „Die
jeder mit den Anderen gemeinsam hat. Wie kommen nun die Anderen in Strukturanalyse der urttimUchen Gegenwart (das stehende lebendige
die je-eigene „innere GeschichtUchkeit" hinein, oder wie kann es evident Stromen) ftihrt uns auf die Ich-Struktur und die sie fundierende standige
gemacht werden, daB sie schon immer in ihr mit darin sind? Diese Frage ist Unterschicht des ichlosen Strdmens, das durch eine konsequente Rtick-
keine andere als die nach dem „Fenster" der Monade. Nur wenn ein solches frage auf das, was auch die sedimentierte Aktivitat moglich macht und
nachweisbar ist nicht bloB als erschlossenes und postuUertes, sondern als voraussetzt, auf das radikal Vor-Ichliche zuruckleitet" (Hua XV, 598). In
von vornherein erfahrenes, kann die jeweils eigene innere GeschichtUchkeit diesem Sinne sucht Husserl den Geschlechtstrieb „als instinktive Ur-
als Apriori der Geschichte in Anspruch genommen werden, und kann die intentionalitat der Vergemeinschaftung" zu verstehen (Ms. E III 10, 1:
Zusammengehorigkeit der beiden Thesen von der Absolutheit der Monade Waldenfels, 298). Als Urtrieb ist er von vornherein auf den Anderen
und von der Absolutheit der Geschichte verstandUch werden. bezogen und hat in ihm seine Erwiderung. „Im Trieb selbst liegt die Bezo-
Es ist die Aufgabe der transzendentalen genetischen Intersubjektivitat- genheit auf den Anderen als Anderen und auf seinen korrelativen Trieb".
stheorie, den Weg zur Beantwortung dieser Fragen freiztilegen. Wie schon In seiner „ur-modalen ErfUUung haben wir nicht zwei zu trennende Erftil-
einleitend bemerkt wurde, ist Husserl bei der ersten ausfuhrlichen lungen je in der einen und anderen Primordinalitat, sondern eine sich
Darstellung seiner Intersubjektivitatstheorie in der 5. Cartesianischen durch das Ineinander der Erftillungen herstellende Einheit der beiden Pri-
Meditation daran gescheitert, daB er diese statisch zu entwickeln suchte. mordinaUtaten" (Hua XV, 593f.).
Darauf ist nun wenigstens mit einigen Andeutungen zurtickzukommen. Es sei versucht, diesen Gedanken erganzend noch ein StUck weiter zu
Eine ausfuhrliche Untersuchung wtirde den Rahmen unserer Erorterung verfolgen.
vollig sprengen. Die nun vorUegenden drei Bande Uber Husserls Intersub- Die Folge der ErfUUung jenes „Urtriebes" kann die Geburt eines neuen
jektivitatsanalysen (Hua XIII-XV) 5 zeigen, daB Husserl bereits 1927 die Menschen mit seiner ihm dann eigenen Geschichte sein, die aber in ihren
Grenzen einer rein statischen Analyse tiberschritten hatte,-indem er die Moglichkeiten schon weitgehend durch das Erbe seiner Vorfahren bes-
Konstitution der Intersubjektivitat durch apprSsentierende analo- timmt ist6. So sind Zeugung und Geburt nicht bloB Themen der Biologie,
gisierende Apperzeption auf ihre passive Vorkonstitution in einer assozia- sondern von transzendentalphilosophischer Bedeutung als Bedingungen
tiv gestifteten Apprasentation zurtickzuftihren suchte. Aber auch dieser der MogUchkeit von Geschichte. Es grtindet darin der Unterschied der
Versuch laBt die Frage offen, ob nicht fur solche assoziative Analo- Generationen, durch den das, was sie gemeinsam haben, aufgrund der
gisierung die Selbstunterscheidung der Monade von dem Du, dem Wir unterschiedlichen Zeit ihres Lebens in unterschiedUchen Perspektiven
und uberhaupt von dem Anderen bereits vorausgesetzt ist, derart, daB ihr erscheint. So bildet sich gemeinsame Geschichte, einer Familie, eines
eigenes Da in Korrespondenz stehen kann mit dem D a des Anderen, so Volkes, einer Epoche etc. Jedes in sie durch seine Geburt und sein
daB ihre je-eigene Zeitlichkeit und innere GeschichtUchkeit apriori .in Erwachsenwerden eintretende Glied hat seine Zeit, die ihm zugeteilt ist.
einer Beziehung steht zu der der Anderen, so daB eine gemeinsame Zeit Erst durch solchen RUckgang auf die tiefstliegenden genetischen Struk-
mogUch wird und mit Recht von einer Ur-intersubjektivitat gesprochen turen, der hier nur stichwortartig angedeutet werden konnte, ist der Satz
werden kann, die gleichursprunglich mit dem jeweils vereinzelten „Ur- Husserls mit konkretem Inhalt erftillt: ..Geschichte ist von vornherein

178 179
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y ; AND METAPHYSICS T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

nichts anderes als die lebendige Bewegung des Miteinander und Ineinan- Grenze, in bezug auf die alle unsere Reden von „Natur" aUein einen
der von ursprtinglicher Sinnbildung und Sinnsedimentierung". anschaulich erfullbaren Sinn, ftir uns gewinnen. Es ist ein Grenzbegriff, der
Die „Fenster" der Ich-Monade sind also nicht erst oben in der Apperzep- zugleich die Moglichkeit jeder Spekulation iiber eine in sich und an sich
tion oder tieferUegend in der assoziativen Analogisierung zu suchen; waltende Natur abschneidet. Erdgeschichte und Naturgeschichte gibt es
sondern im „Urtrieb", der als solcher schon immer auf den Anderen nur, sofern wir durch unsere Individuation geschichtliche Wesen sind, auf
bezogen ist und in ihm seine Erwiderung und ErfUUung hat. In seiner Ur- deren jeweiliges Da alle Zeitbestimmungen des Naturgeschehens letzten
einigung in der Doppefheit grtindet die MogUchkeit der Analogie von Mit- Endes zuruckbezogen sind.
gegenwart und Selb.stgegenwart, die Held in seiner schon oben genannten In diesem universalen Sinne, auch das Naturgeschehen in sich
Auseinandersetzung mit Husserls Intersubjektivitatstheorie thematisiert befassend, ist also das Wort von der Geschichte als dem groBen Faktum
hat. Die GewiBheit um das Da des Anderen geht also allem Apperzipieren des absoluten Seins zu verstehen. Es ist das stehendstromende Geschehen,
und alien Assoziationen voran. Ihr letzter Grund ist auch nicht das das „transzendentale Leben", das sich nur dadurch als Geschehen erfahrt,
„Apriori" der Ich-Du-Beziehung, das Waldenfels untersuchte. Er hat darum daB es sich schon immer als Trennung und zugleich Einigung der zunachst
wohl gewuBt, indem er zuletzt nach dem „Untergrund" des Dialogs fragte. anonym sich bewegenden Zentren der Bewegung (der „Monaden") vol-
Diese vorgangige Einigkeit und gleichwohl absolute Getrenntheit ist lzieht (Hua XV, 373f.). In diesem Sinne ist es zu verstehen, daB „das Jch'
ursprUnglich passiv erfahren im Vollzung des Strebens zum Anderen, das in schon immer voraus ist, aber zugleich das Stromen immer voraus ist" (Ms
ihm seine Erwiderung findet. Diese Erfahrung ist „absolute Erfahrung" C VII, I, 18). Von daher ist es auch zu verstehen, in welchem Sinne der
(Landgrebe 1973, 13 ff.), und auf ihrem Grunde ist die Geschichte absolut. Satz gilt, daB „Natur" selbst ein Gebilde der transzendentalen Geschichte
Aber sie ist mehr als die Geschichte im Sinne der res gestae, sie schlieBt das ist (Hua XV, 391); denn nur weil die transzendentalen Subjekte, die
in sich ein, was alien res gestae voranliegt, das transzendentale Eins-sein in Monaden, schon „geschichtlich" sind, „gibt" es auch ftir uns so etwas wie
Entzweiung, das wieder zu neuem Eins-sein ftihrt, zu einer neuen absoluten eine Naturhistorie und dann eine Wissenschaft von der Natur, welche sich
Monade, die schon die generativ gemeinsamen Ztige in sich tragt. Sie sind im modernen Sinne erst dadurch konstituieren konnte, daB sie von diesem
gemeinsam, weil die Erfuflung der ursprtingUchen TriebintentionaUtat eine transzendentalen Bezug methodisch abstrahiert. In diesem Sinne ist also
„Einheit der beiden PrimordinaUtaten", des Einen und des Anderen, her- die Zusammengehorigkeit von Absolutheit der Monade und Absolutheit
stellt. Jede hat im strdmenden Vollzug ihr Da, das in der Erfullung zum der Geschichte zu verstehen. Inwiefern ist dann die Bestimmung des
gemeinsamen wird. Dieses Da ist das Da der leibUch sich bewegenden Sub- „Absoluten" als „Da" eine transzendentale und damit eine apriorische
jekte. In ihrem leiblichen Sich-bewegen ist ihnen von vornherein „Natur" Bestimmung, und daher die Phanomenologie, die zu diesem obersten
erschlossen, weil sie selbst als leibUche in sie „hineingehoren". Es ist ein Da Punkte ftihrt, Transzendentalphilosophie? Sie ist es, weil sie auf das ftihrt,
an seinem „Ort" in der Natur, und damit bezogen auf die „Erde". Sie „ftigt was allem anderen, von dem wir in irgendeinem Sinne sagen konnen „es
sich ein in eine universale .Naturhistorie', in die der Mensch als Lebewesen ist", schon immer zuvorgekommen ist. Die Faktizitat dieses Da ist ein
hineinreicht" (Ms C I u. B III, I: Waldenfels, 336; cf. Hua VI, 304). Strukturprinzip (Aguirre). Das Zuvorkommen ist in seinem „zuvor"
„anonym", und so sind „anonym" und „Da" transzendentale Bestim-
Aber die Geschichte ist deswegen keineswegs nur Naturgeschichte.
mungen, mit denen der aufierste Punkt transzendentaler Reflexion erreicht
Wohl aber ist „Naturgeschehen" ihr Boden, aber nicht im Sinne einer
ist. Es ist der Punkt, an dem sie die sich selbst gesetzte Grenze findet als
nicht weiter bestimmbaren „Materie", sondern uns bekannt als die
eine solche, die sie nicht tiberschreiten kann. Sie kann das Zuvorkommen
„Erde", und das heiBt, als der Inbegriff der Bedingungen, die allem Tdtig-
nicht hintergehen. Mit dieser Entdeckung ist das entdeckt, von woher
sein des Menschen und damit seiner Geschichte im Sinne der res gestae ihre
transzendentale Reflexion und Transzendentalphilosophie sich als Kritik
Grenzen setzen. Gerade dies ist die Situation, in der wir heute Geschichte
jedes Dogmatismus verstehen muB. Diese Kritik ist nicht nur Kritik der
erfahren, weil uns diese Begrenzung aller menschlichen Moglichkeiten
alten, vorkantischen Metaphysik, sondern auch zugleich Kritik der verbor-
desto ausdrtickUcher bewuBt geworden ist, je weiter der Vorgang der
genen metaphysischen Implikate in den modernen sich antimetaphysisch
Bemachtigung der Erde fortgeschritten ist. Zur Absolutheit unseres Da
dtinkenden Positionen. Sie verbietet auch das Uberschreiten der von ihr
gehort die Absolutheit der Erde als der Grenze jedes moglichen Da. Von
gefundenen Grenzen durch eine Postulatenlehre im Sinne Kants. Aber sie
der Raumfahrt soU hier nicht weiter gesprochen werden. Sie wird wohl
ftihrt deswegen keineswegs zu einem absoluten Skeptizismus. Gerade im
kaum jemals anders als „erdbezogen" geschehen konnen. „Erde" in
HinbUck auf die Bedingungen der Moglichkeit daftir, daB es ftir uns so
diesem Sinne ist also ein transzendentaler Grenzbegriff. Sie ist eine Grund-
etwas wie „die Geschichte" „gibt", ftihrt sie zur Einsicht in das, was von
struktur der menschlichen Lebenswelt und bezeichnet zugleich die

180 181
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S T R A N S Z E N D E N T A L E T H E O R I E DER G E S C H I C H T E

uns als oberstes Prinzip der Lebensftihrung angesichts dieser durch ihre cher Forschung (fiir Ludwig Landgrebe zum 70. Geburtstag), hrsg. von U. Claes-
Grenzen bestimmbaren condition humaine in unbedingter Allgemeinheit ges und K. Held (Phaenomenologica 49), Den Haag 1972, S. 3-60.
und Verbindlichkeit gefordert ist. Es wurde zu zeigen gesucht, daB die Kant, Immanuel: Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloBen Vernunft 1793, in:
Faktizitat der Geschichte an der Faktizitat des Da der jeweils vereinzelten Kants Werke - Akademie-Ausgabe Band VI.
Landgrebe, Ludwig: Der Weg der Phanomenologie, Gutersloh 1963.
individuellen Existenz hangt (Landgrebe, Faktizitat, 1974, 275 ff.). SoU es
—: Die Zeitanalyse in der Phanomenologie und in der klassischen Tradition, in:
also ftir diese in ihr Da auf der „Erde" gebannte Menschheit eine Zukunft Phanomenologie - lebendig oder tot? Hrsg. Eugen Fink u. a., Karlsruhe 1969.
geben und ihre Geschichte nicht am Ende sein, so ist die Bedingung daftir —: The phenomenological Concept of Experience, in: Philosophy and Phenom-
nicht nur die Anerkennung aller „unseresgleichen" eben als gleicher, enological Research, XXXIV/1 (1973), S. 13ff.
sondern zugleich als absolut individuell verschiedener. Die unbedingt-aUge- —: Meditation uber Husserls Wort ,Die Geschichte ist das groBe Faktum des
mein verbindliche Forderung ist also die der Anerkennung und der absoluten Seins', in: Tijdschrift voor Filosofie XXXVI/1 (1974), S. 107-126.
Achtung vor der jeweils eigenen individuellen Existenz eines jeden —: Reflexionen zu Husserls Konstitutionslehre, in: Tijdschrift voor pilosofie
„unseresgleichen" und der historisch gewordenen Gruppen, Volker, XXXVI/3 (1974), S. 466^82.
Stamme, Nationen in ihrer „kollektiven" IndividuaUtat. Erst in dieser —: Faktizitat und Individuation, in: Sein und GeschichtUchkeit. Festschrift fur K.
Anerkennung ist es begrUndet, daB die Hinnahme der eigenen Faktizitat H. Volkmann-Schluck, Frankfurt a. M. 1974, S. 275 ff.
Schutz, Alfred: Collected Papers I, ed. M. Natanson (Phaenomenologica 11), Den
nicht die Unterwerfung unter ein undurchschaubares Geschick bedeutet,
Haag 1962.
sondern die MogUchkeit einer menschlichen Welt.
Strasser, Stephan: Grundgedanken der Sozialontologie Edmund Husserls, in: Zs. f.
philos. Forschg. Bd. 29 (1975), S. 3-33.
Notes Waldenfels, Bernhard: Das Zwischenreich des Dialogs. Sozialphilosophische
Untersuchungen im AnschluB an Edmund Husserl (Phaenomenologica 41), Den
1 Eroffnungsvortrag fur die „Internationalen phanomenologischen Studientage", Haag 1971.
Berlin 23.-27. 5.1974.
2 Msk. K III, 12, S. 34 f. - Zitiert nach Held, 1966,147.
3 Zur ausfuhrlicheren Interpretation dieser These vgl. Landgrebe, Meditation
1974,107 ff. und in englischer Fassung: The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy,
vol. V/3, p. lllff. Norman/Oklahoma 1974. Die folgenden Ausfuhrungen
konnen als eine zum Teil erganzende, zum Teil verbessernde Variation dieses
Themas verstanden werden.
4 Das Zitat stammt aus der Abhandlung „Vom Ursprung der Geometrie" von
1936 (Hua VI, Beilage III S. 367-386).
5 Vgl. dazu die ausfuhrliche Analyse von S. Strasser zu Husserls Sozialontologie,
die bei Abfassung dieses Beitrags noch nicht vorlag.
6 Zum Problem der „Erbmasse" als Leerhorizont vgl. Hua XV, 604 ff.

Literaturverzeichnis
Aguirre, Antonio: Genetische Phanomenologie und Reduktion. Zur Letztbegrun-
dung der Wissenschaft aus der radikalen Skepsis im Denken E. Husserls
(Phaenomenologica 38), Den Haag 1970.
Fink, Eugen: Die Spatphilosophie E. Husserls in der Freiburger Zeit, in: Edmund
Husserl 1859-1959, Recueil Comm6moratif (Phaenomenologica 4), Den Haag
1959, S. 99-115.
Held, Klaus: Lebendige Gegenwart. Die Frage nach der Seinsweise des transzen-
dentalen Ich bei Edmund Husserl, entwickelt am Leitfaden der Zeitproblematik
(Phaenomenologica 23), Den Haag 1966.
—: Das Problem der Intersubjektivitat und die Idee einer phanomenologischen
Transzendentalphilosophie, in: Perspektiven transzendental-phanomenologis-

182 183
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY

for the historical considerations, it might be said, this is easily explained.


79 Husserl begins by stating that the sciences are in crisis because philosophy
has failed in its task of clarifying their ultimate unity and significance.
Even thus is nothing new - it was the theme of 'Philosophy as a Rigorous
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS A N D T H E Science' in 1910. Having thus pointed to the crisis, it is to be expected that
P R O B L E M O F H I S T O R Y Husserl should be interested in finding out how we got into it, going back,
as he does, to the origins of modern science in Galileo and tracing the
course of the flawed attempts at its philosophical interpretation from
David Carr Descartes to Kant. What is more normal, in fact, than that a philosopher
should rehearse the failures of his predecessors to solve philosophical
problems, before proceeding to solve them himself? Coming from Husserl,
such an elaborate treatment of the history of philosophy is perhaps
Source: Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 5(3) (1974): 127-148. unusual, but he had done something like this before, in the 1923-24 lec-
tures on 'First Philosophy', whose 'systematic part' had been preceded by
a 'critical history of ideas'. 1 Although he had not tried this before in print,
It has long been claimed that The Crisis of European Sciences, Husserl's external circumstances may have decided him in favor of it. The turbulent
last work, represents a significant new development in his thought. I events of the Nazi years, Husserl's feeling that he had been deserted by his
believe this is true, but I think this claim has consistently been made for most brifUant students and the reading public - all suggested the need for
the wrong reasons. Not the concept of the life-world, which is usually a new and more impressive mode of presentation for his phenomenology.
taken as the new departure, but the emergence of the problem of history, If this were truly the character of the historical framework of the Crisis,
is what is radically new in the Crisis. To be sure, the two notions are and these Husserl's motives for adopting it, one might remark its novelty
closely related. But there is a way of considering the life-world which, but not be inclined to ascribe to it any significance for the program of
although it greatly expands the scope of Husserl's earlier phenomenology, phenomenology. But such a reading would also be guilty of ignoring the
is entirely consistent with its program. It is otherwise with the problem of text, for Husserl's historical investigations exhibit features which distin-
history, as I shall try to show. For what this problem introduces into guish it sharply from anything he has done before. These features make it
phenomenology is neither a new theme for investigation nor even, as in impossible to dismiss them as embellishments chosen for external effect or
the case of the life-world, a new conception of the whole domain of inves- timely relevance, and they prove, as we shall see, to be of decisive signific-
tigation. Rather, it calls forth a new conception of the procedure of investi- ance for phenomenology itself.
gation itself, a new conception of phenomenological method.
In the first place, Husserl justifies his historical reflections in terms of
Of course there are also those who have argued that there is really urgent necessity. After expounding this notion of the crisis of science,.
nothing new in the Crisis. After aU, the work bears the subtitle 'Introduc- Husserl says: 'What is clearly necessary (what else could be of help here?)
tion to Phenomenological Transcendental Philosophy', presumably the is that we reflect back, in a thorough historical and critical fashion, in order
same transcendental phenomenology that had been introduced in the to provide, before all decisions, for a radical self-understanding'.2 We gain
Ideas and the Cartesian Meditations. The manner of introduction is new, to a notion of the 'task which is truly our own' as philosophers, he says later,
be sure, dispensing with and even criticizing the Cartesian approach of the 'only through a critical understanding of the total unity of history - our
two earlier works. But Husserl had experimented with other methods of history'. 3 The critical-historical reflections in which Husserl is engaged are
introduction before, notably the logical method of Formal and Transcen- described as 'the philosopher's genuine self-reflection on what he is truly
dental Logic and the psychological one of the Encyclopedia Britannica seeking [auf das, worauf er eigentlich hinauswilt]'? Such remarks suggest
article. There is certainly no evidence that Husserl himself regarded his much more than a mere resume and critique of past attempts to solve
phenomenology as being crucially, much less fatally, affected by the ideas philosophical problems before proceeding to their true solution. Such a
explored in his last work, that his remarks about the end of the dream of resume might be helpful, but would not be a material part of philosophy
philosophy as rigorous science should be taken as his own opinion. Those itself and could just as well be dispensed with. But here we find Husserl
who regard the Crisis as a kind of deathbed conversion to existentialism insisting on the necessity of historical reflections in order to discern the
and a renunciation of his earlier efforts have simply not read the text. As very business of philosophy itself. Being clear on the task of philosophy

184 185
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
cannot be dissociated from doing philosophy; it is an indispensable part of the Crisis is that reflection on the history of philosophy is now seen by
its establishment. And, as we know, it is the establishment or foundation Husserl as one of these ways. But this interpretation is not tenable.
of philosophy, its true beginning, that is Husserl's prime interest. Husserl is still explicitly conscious of the notion of alternative ways in the
But why does this require precisely historical reflections? Husserl first Crisis, and the two sections of Part III are presented as two parallel ones:
calls for them because his brief exposition of the contrast between the the way from the pre-given life-world and the way from psychology. But
present crisis and the optimism of the Renaissance has, as he says, history is not mentioned in these terms. In fact, as we have seen, Husserl's
'reminded us that as philosophers we are heirs to the past in respect to the language indicates something much stronger than this. The historical route
goals which the word 'philosophy' indicates, in terms of concepts, prob- is not a merely possible but a necessary one, and the idea seems to be that
lems and methods'. 5 Later, he says that historical reflections are needed to whichever of several parallel alternatives is chosen, it must be accompan-
reveal the 'task which is truly our own' because 'we not only have a spir- ied by historical reflections.
itual heritage, but have become what we are thoroughly and exclusively in
The idea that the way to philosophical truth passes through the history
a historical-spiritual manner'. 6 'A historical reflection of the sort under dis-
of philosophy is not new in itself, but for Husserl it is not only new but
cussion', he writes, 'is thus actually the deepest kind of self-reflection
almost startling in contrast to his earUer views. 'Zu den Sachen selbst!' was
aimed at a self-understanding in terms of what we are truly seeking as the
the motto of the early phenomenological school gathered about Husserl.
historical beings [historisches Wesen] we are'. 7 These remarks suggest that
What it meant primarily was best expressed by Husserl in 'Philosophy as
'being historical' is something like an essential trait of those who do philo-
Rigorous Science': 'The impulse of research must proceed not from philo-
sophy, and because of this they must begin philosophy in a historical way.
sophies but from the issues and problems [von den Sachen und Proble-
An indication of the importance he attached to his historical reflections men]'?1 To deal with the history of philosophy is to deal not with the
is Husserl's recurring preoccupations with the method, aims, and presup- Sachen but only with what others have said about the Sachen. Husserl
position of his procedure. Twice in the course of Part II of the Crisis objected not to the history of philosophy as a discipline, of course, but only
Husserl interrupts his historical expositions with remarks on the method to the tendency to confuse if with philosophy itself, either in the manner of
he is following.8 As if unsatisfied, he returns to the problem in a text Weltanschauungsphilosophie or as an attempt to conjure a doctrine of one's
designed as a preface to Part III but not included in the published text.9 own by ingeniously mixing and stirring the doctrines of others. In the Ideas,
Other unpublished manuscripts of the period exhibit the same preoccupa- to ward off from the start any such temptation, Husserl laid down what he
tion. The common point of departure in these methodological considera- called the 'philosophical epoche': 'Expressly formulated [it] consists in this,
tions is a negative one: what we are engaged in, although certainly that we completely abstain from judgment respecting the doctrinal content
historical in character, is not history in the usual sense. This shows us an of all pre-existing philosophy, and conduct aU our expositions within the
important difference between the Crisis and the first part of the Erste framework of this abstention'.12 Husserl does not, of course, rule out refer-
Philosophie. In the 1923 lectures, which are in many details similar to the ences to philosophy as 'historical fact' especially for purposes of criticizing
exposition of the Crisis, Husserl hardly seems conscious of methodological one or another of its representatives. And, indeed, criticisms of other philo-
problems. What he is engaged in is, after all, something easily classifiable sophers are found throughout his writings. But we find nothing Uke the
and famfliar: it is a 'history of ideas'.10 elaborate historical reflections of the Crisis and nothing like the insistence
But most important of all, the distinction between the 'historical intro- on the necessity and problematic character of such reflections.
duction' and the 'systematic part', found in the Erste Philosophie, is . If is the 'thoroughly and exclusively' historical character of those who
broken down in the Crisis. Historical expositions are, to be sure, found pri- do philosophy which makes it necessary, says Husserl, that they reflect
marily in Part II, while the two sections of Part III, on the life-world and critically on the history of philosophy in order to 'do' it properly. What
psychology respectively, are largely nonhistorical in character. But even does this mean - in what sense are potential philosophers 'historical
they are couched in historical references, and the historical and nonhistori- beings' - and why should it result in this requirement? After all, philo-
cal are constantly mixed. In any case, if historical reflection really belongs sophers could be, in some sense, historical beings without, for that reason,
essentiaUy and not just accidentally to the estabUshment of philosophy, as having to engage in historical reflections. What is Husserl's concept of the
we have seen, then it is just as 'systematic' as the nonhistorical. historicity of the potential philosopher? In this concept lies the only expla-
We have already spoken of the notion of alternative 'ways into' nation for Husserl's new approach, the key to its correct interpretation,
phenomenology, a notion Husserl first developed, in fact, in the Erste and the clarification of its ultimate significance for the phenomenological
Philosophie. One possible interpretation of Husserl's novel approach in program.

186 187
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
The answer to this question is to be found, I think, in Husserl's earlier nent subsides into the universal substratum - the socaUed 'unconscious'
philosophy, and goes back even to some of his earliest writings. It is in the which, far from being a phenomenological nothing, is itself a limit mode of
very pursuit of the project of transcendental philosophy that Husserl even- consciousness'.14 In passing beyond the limit of conscious retention,
tually arrives at the necessity for this seemingly untranscendental pro- Husserl says, the past cogitatio becomes sedimented as an acquisition or
cedure. But if the answer is to be found in Husserl's earlier writings, it is possession (Erwerb or Habe) which can be awakened in recollection. But
there only in concealment, for otherwise the necessity of historical reflec- even if is not actually reawakened, it remains a part of what the calls 'the
tions would have emerged much sooner. Or, to put it more precisely, substratum of sedimented prominences which, as a horizon, accompanies
certain lines of inquiry, pursued independently throughout Husserl's every living present': 15
career, finally intersect in the Crisis, and their intersection explains
Thus, while, from the transcendental point of view, every object is given
Husserl's novel approach. These lines of inquiry are pursued under the
as what it is in virtue of the character of the act in which it is given, this act
headings of genetic phenomenology and the theory of intersubjectivity. Let
in turn is what it is partly by virtue of the temporal background or horizon
us examine these separately before dealing with their convergence and its
against which it stands out. 'Every evidence', as Husserl says in the Car-
consequences for the problem of history.
tesian Meditations, 'sets up' or 'institutes' for me an abiding possession'?6
Genetic phenomenology derives directly from the demands of transcen- and it is with an ever growing stock of such abiding possessions that con-
dental philosophy. The latter gets its name, Husserl says, from the sciousness enters each new living present. Each act not only intends its
problem of transcendence. 13 The transcendence of the object - its objectiv- object but unifies itself with its past and intends its object in light of that
ity or validity (Geltung) as such - does not ground itself but must be past. Its sedimented evidences, although no longer actual, function as pre-
grounded in the consciousness in which it manifests itself. In the Logical suppositions and norms for the future until cancelled or modified by
Investigations, the givenness of the objective is sought in consciousness present evidence. Thus, consciousness, rather than a mere succession of
conceived as sense-bestowing, intentional experience or act. In the Ideas, experiences linked by memory, or tied to an unchanging ego, is a cumula-
this notion is broadened through the concept of attitude - pre-eminently tive process of reciprocal interrelations and influences. Again, it must be
the natural attitude - which is not itself an act but which underlies and emphasized that this characterization is called forth not only by the desire
expresses itself in all acts falling within it. Both of these concepts - act and to describe consciousness but by the needs of transcendental philosophy.
attitude - are static, in that they do not take into account the flowing char- In order to account for how objects are given or constituted, it is necessary
acter of consciousness. The natural attitude runs undifferentiated through to make reference to the self-constitution of consciousness. The givenness
the life of consciousness, and the act or cogito, at least as originally con- of the world requires the unity of consciousness, and this unity is not
ceived, is a sUce in time, likewise undifferentiated temporally. Such char- simply a brute fact but the result of a process of self-unification which is
acterizations are obviously abstract from the standpoint of a description of the very form of conscious life.
consciousness, but, more important, they are also abstract from the tran-
scendental point of view as weU. That is, the givenness of the objective Of interest to our topic is the fact that Husserl uses the terms 'history'
must be regarded as a temporal affair, for the object is given as a unity and 'historicity' to describe this form. 'Every single process of conscious-
through the temporal multipUcity of its appearances. Thus the concepts of ness', he says in Formal and Transcendental Logic, 'has its own 'history',
retention, protention, recoUection, and such, first developed in answer to that is, its temporal genesis'?7 And every such particular history finds its
the question of our experience of time, must be brought into play in the place within the temporal unity of a particular conscious life as a whole,
analysis of our experience of anything in time. The abstract, static treat- which has its own 'history' in such a unity. As he says in the Cartesian
ment of consciousness in the Ideas must be made concrete by taking into Meditations, 'the ego constitutes himself for himself in, so to speak, the
account the dynamic or temporal dimension. unity of a 'history' \ 18
This is a rather unusual, even metaphorical sense of 'history', as Husserl
With this, the character of transcendental grounding changes some- indicates by his use of quotation marks or expressions like 'so to speak'.
what. Each act passes into retention as it is replaced by a new act. As the What does it have to do with history in the usual sense? Since the term is
original act is pushed farther and farther back by successive retentional usually applied not to the Ufe of the individual but to that of groups or
modifications it approaches what Husserl calls, in Formal and Transcen- societies, the link between the two concepts must be found in Husserl's
dental Logic, an 'essentially necessary limit. That is to say: with this inten- philosophy of intersubjectivity.
tional modification there goes hand in hand a gradual diminuation of
Contrary to the usual interpretation, Husserl's Fifth Cartesian Medita-
prominence: and precisely this has its limit, at which the formerly promi-
tion is not concerned with the problem of solipsism in any standard or

188 189
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
traditional sense at all. His question is not whether other minds, in fact,
exist or whether we as philosophers can prove, inductively or deductively, persons, the experience of another is an act of communication and the
that they do. Rather, Husserl poses the same question here that he does formation of a rudimentary community - Husserl caUs it Vergemeinschaf-
with respect to any other object of our awareness, the question: how is it tung?1 Just as the object may be conceived as one by reference to the mul-
given? For Husserl this means, as in all other cases, that we must seek tiplicity of its appearances to me (through time), so the intersubjective
'insight into the explicit and impUcit intentionality wherein the alter ego object is one by reference to the (simultaneous) multiplicity of its appear-
becomes evinced [sich bekundet] and verified in the realm of our transcen- ances to me and to others.
dental ego; we must discover in what intentionalities, syntheses, motiva- What implications does this have for the phenomenological conception
tions, the sense 'other ego' becomes fashioned in me'.19 The special of individual consciousness? How do I constitute the intersubjective object
difficulty here is presented by the fact that the objects is in this case a and hence the objective world? Only by combining my own experiences
subject, a cogitatum cogitans. This is what Husserl calls the paradox of with those not my own, only by borrowing, as it were, what others
solipsism which he challenges himself to overcome. communicate to me in my encounters with them. The world I live in is
only partially given to me directly; it has the sense it does for me, which far
As is well known, this matter has significance beyond the problem of
outruns what is directly given, because I live in a community of other sub-
how other subjects are given. For only by understanding such givenness
jects whose experiences complement, but can never be, my own. It is com-
can we account for the givenness of the objective world in the sense of the
pounded of direct and indirect or quasi-evidences. Thus, again stressing
world which exists not just for me, but for others as well. Only if there are
the transcendental point of view: the sense of the world for the individual
others for me can there be a world for others as well as for me. The
subject is at least partially traceable to the community in which he lives,
worldly object is transcendent because it is not reducible to the act or acts
or, more precisely, to his appropriation of the experiences of others
in which it is given. This is because it is the reference point of other pos-
through his communicative encounters with them.
sible acts of consciousness. But up to the Fifth Meditation, aU actual and
possible acts of consciousness were considered acts of my consciousness. If we combine the intersubjective and genetic analyses, what emerges is
The problem of objectivity concerns the object which transcends not the full-fledged notion of the historicity of subjectivity from the transcen-
merely my actual experience, but all actual and possible experience of dental point of view. The object as given is mediated through the temporal
mine, because it is given to other experiences not my own. The task is to and social horizons of the act itself. The 'substratum of sedimented promi-
understand how I transcend this 'ownness sphere' of my actual and pos- nences which, as a horizon, accompanies every living present' 22 as we saw,
sible experiences and encounter a world which is not my private property forms a background of presuppositions which determine the character of
by encountering an experience which is not my own. Thus, the importance that present. But this substratum may in turn be socially mediated. Husserl
of the problem of intersubjectivity from the transcendental point of view: says that 'every evidence sets up in me an abiding possession',23 but we
not merely the givenness of a particular sort of entity, the alter ego, is at could also say that not every abiding possession may be traceable to direct
issue, but, through him, the sense of the world's transcendence as a whole. evidence. It may derive from the quasi-evidence of a communicative
We need not recount in detail Husserl's description of the experience in encounter. Every subjective process is an expression not only of its own
which the alter ego is given. Certainly it contains many problems. But its past but also of the past of the community in which it functions, a past
general sense is already prefigured in the very way the problem is set up. which it appropriates through its communal life with others.
Through what Husserl calls 'appresentation' and 'analogizing apprehen- As I have constantly stressed, the concept of history is developed
sion',20 I encounter another subject. But this means that what I encounter according to the procedures of transcendental phenomenology and in
is another flow of experience, actual and possible, with all its objects. What answer to the demands of that very procedure. But the phenomenological
could be called 'my world' is now confronted with 'his world'. But this is description of the historicity of consciousness is not itself a historical
only an abstract description, for there is only one world. What I actually reflection. What happens in the Crisis is that the results of this investiga-
encounter is another perspective on the world, a perspective which is not tion reflect back upon and caU into question the very procedure foUowed
my own. Because of my awareness of this alien perspective, the world that in order to reach them.
I experience is always more than what I directly experience of it or ever Husserl justifies his historical reflections there, we remember, by stating
could directly experience of it. Yet through my encounter with the other, that we as philosophers are 'historical beings', that 'we . . . not only have a
that alien perspective is at least indirectly given, given by analogy. This is spiritual heritage, but have become what we are thoroughly and exclus-
why, in even the simplest case of the wordless confrontation of two ively in a historical-spiritual manner'. 24 We are now in a position to under-
stand what Husserl means by this. We are historical beings first of all

190
191
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
because we are conscious beings; our conscious life consists in constituting awareness of this underlying presupposition which otherwise remains
itself 'in the unity of a history', personal and social. Again, it must be
hidden, and the whole effort of phenomenology is to sustain this epoche,
stressed that this is the character of consciousness considered transcenden-
to avoid the hidden, unrecognized commitment which is the natural atti-
tally. To say that we are historical beings is not merely to say that we are
tude, to struggle against the gravitational pull of consciousness to resume
in history, that we arrive on the scene and disappear at certain points in
objective historical time. Each of us is indeed aware of himself as such an its natural state.
empirical ego, but this is not what Husserl means by the historicity of con- If we now arrive at the generalized recognition that the philosopher is
sciousness. burdened by historical prejudices which, like the natural ones, are unac-
knowledged and hidden, what do we do? Does it suffice that we be warned
But how does this notion of historicity apply to the philosopher in
against them? But - and here is the rub - what do we mean by theml In
particular? As conscious beings we are heirs to the past, whatever our
the case of the natural attitude, as we have seen, overthrow must at the
beliefs, attitudes, and goals; and if we are philosophers, we are, as Husserl
same time be discovery. It is not enough simply to announce the principle
says, 'heirs to the past in respect to the goals which the word 'philosophy'
of emancipation from aU prejudices in order to make it so. Hence, the
indicates, in terms of concepts, problems, and methods'. 25 What signifi-
peculiar relationship between the natural attitude and its suspension: it
cances could this have? Obviously, becoming a philosopher involves not
must be reUved at the same time it is being overthrown-rediscovered. The
only accepting a certain notion or definition of an endeavor that exists and
has existed in society, but also studying the works of those who are com- result is what Husserl occasionally describes as a splitting of the ego
monly regarded as philosophers. But the procedure of the incipient philo- between the natural self and his phenomenological observer26 and a
sopher is generally not a matter of simply accepting and identifying pattern of inquiry involving a zigzag between the two. In the case of histor-
himself with the philosophers he reads. For most, taking up philosophy ical prejudices, something similar seems indicated. Like natural prejudices,
does not mean simply learning the 'truths' that others have written. This these are distinguished by being taken for granted, selbstverstandlich.
may be the attitude of the interested layman, but the potential philosopher What suggests itself here, by analogy to the phenomenological epoche, is a
is more often marked by his very dissatisfaction with traditional doctrines. reliving of our philosophical prejudices, a repetition of the philosophical
It is the task of philosophy that Husserl has in mind, and the assumption of Selbstverstandlichkeiten under which we turn to philosophy in the first
this task may even involve the conscious, total rejection of the entire place. Like the phenomenological epochs, such a repetition will not be a
philosophical tradition. But even such a philosopher, Husserl is saying, is mere repetition: what is relived is relived reflectively in order to be raised
an 'heir of the past' in taking up the problems which his predecessors, in from the level of something taken for granted to that of something explic-
his view, have failed to solve. Yet his awareness of his indebtedness to the itly recognized. Just as the phenomenological epoche is habitually prac-
past rarely penetrates to this level; his acknowledged relation to the past ticed in the form of a method caUed the phenomenological reduction, so
consists in his rejection, or even his eventual critical acceptance, of what the philosophical epoche must be systematized and universalized to
he finds there. It is clearly the notion of unacknowledged heritage which become a philosophical reduction, or what might better be called a histor-
interests Husserl at this point and which constitutes the pecuUar historicity ical reduction.
of the philosophically engaged consciousness. Although Husserl nowhere uses this term in the Crisis, this is, we main-
tain, precisely what he has in mind in that work and is the initial key to his
Once Husserl begins to take seriously the idea of the unacknowledged
heritage of the philosopher, his relation to the past becomes a much more historical procedure. 'This manner of clarifying history', Husserl says of
complex affair than it was originally thought to be. When he enunciated that procedure:
the principle of philosophical epoche in the Ideas, Husserl clearly had in
by inquiring back into the primal estabUshment of the goals,... is
mind one's conscious, explicit, acceptance of this or that philosophical doc-
to make vital again, in its concealed historical meaning, the sedi-
trine. This was to be put aside, bracketed. And this presents no special
mented conceptual system which, as taken for granted, serves as
problem, because what is explicitly acknowledged can just as easily be set
the ground for [the philosopher's] private and non-historical work
aside. The phenomenological epoche, by contrast, was a real effort,
. . . If he is to be one who thinks for himself [Selbstdenker], an
because the natural attitude, which it bracketed, has the character of an
autonomous philosopher with the wiU to liberate himself from all
unacknowledged prejudice, a Selbstverstandlichkeit. In order to be brack-
prejudices, he must have the insight that all the things he takes for
eted it must be dredged up and recognized as a thesis to which we sub-
scribe. In fact the process of bracketing is identical with coming to granted are prejudices, that all prejudices are obscurities arising
out of a sedimentation of tradition.27

192 193
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY

. . . There is no doubt [he writes elsewhere] that we must engross Modern Opposition Between Physicalistic Objectivism and Transcenden-
ourselves in historical considerations if we are to be able to under- tal Subjectivism'.32 His discussion of modern philosophy constitutes a
stand ourselves as philosophers and understand what philosophy 'historical reduction' because it is above all, as he says, an 'inquiry back
is to become through us. It is no longer sufficient to grasp . . . at [Ruckfrage] into the primal establishment of the goals'33 of modern philo-
certain working problems we have run up against in a naive devel- sophy, not simply a rehearsal of the 'doctrinal content' of certain theories.
opment, to treat of them with our working partners, with those It tries to show in detail how we are 'heirs of the past in respect to the
who, in the same course of a living tradition, have run up against goals which the word 'philosophy' indicates, in terms of concepts, prob-
the same problems.28 lems and methods'. It is an attempt to relive the tradition of which we are
a part in order to bring to recognition the prejudices that- are part of that
This is why even the 'theory of knowledge' has to become a 'peculiarly tradition.
historical task', as Husserl says in the 'Origin of Geometry', and why the Not surprisingly, Husserl traces the origin of modern philosophical
failure to see this is 'precisely what we object to in the past'.29 It is not problems to the rise of modern science, whose decisive feature is its math-
enough simply to proceed 'naively' to the Sachen and Probleme of philo- ematical character. It is primarily to GaUleo that we owe the trans-
sophy as we find them in our own present; or, as we have put it elsewhere,30 formation of the study of nature into a mathematical science, and as soon
the history of those Sachen and Probleme, their very Selbstverstdndlichkeit as this science 'begins to move toward successful realization, the idea of
as part of the tradition, is now seen to count pre-eminently among the very philosophy in general . . . is transformed'. 34 In order to understand the
Sachen to which philosophy must turn. origin of the modern idea of philosophy, we must turn first to what made it
And this is indeed remarkable: for it seems to demand of the philo- possible: Galileo's 'mathematization of nature'.
sopher, as an essential part of his method, a serious and systematic Husserl's inquiry is directed toward uncovering goals, and the question
consideration of his particular time and place, a consideration previously he asks about Galileo's mathematization is 'How do we reconstruct the
declared irrelevant to phenomenology but the eidetic reduction. Under train of thought that motivated it?'35 Galileo's basic goal is that of over-
that reduction facts and particular events, even and indeed especially coming the subjectively relative character of our everyday manner of
those revealed in transcendental reflection, serve only as examples of the describing the world around us and arriving at exact, intersubjectively
patterns which are ultimately sought. Now facts and events become agreed upon characterizations of it. Such exactness is already to be found
important in their own right. To be sure, it may be essentially true that in the mathematical disciplines, handed down from the Greeks, one of
consciousness, and thus philosophical consciousness, is historical, that is, which is geometry. Is it not the case that our natural surroundings contain,
that it is laden with prejudices derived from its social-historical milieu. But somehow embedded in them, examples of the shapes geometry is able to
this means precisely that the character of such prejudices will vary depend- determine with such exactness? Galileo's proposal is that we deal with
ing on the milieu. This is why, when explaining the need for historical nature only to the extent that we can describe it in geometrical terms. In
reflections in order to obtain clarity on the task of philosophy, Husserl this way, our description can partake of the exactness enjoyed by that
says that we can obtain such clarity 'not through the critique of some science. Initially, this seems to leave out a great deal of what presents itself
present or handed down system, of some scientific or prescientific 'Weltan- to our experience, notably the socaUed secondary qualities which do not
schauung' (which might as weU be Chinese, in the end)' - that is, not lend themselves to exact measurement. Changes in these qualities can,
through the study of just any history - 'but only through a critical under- however, be correlated with changes in primary qualities, and, in his
standing of the total unity of history - our history'.31 It is no longer the boldest move of all, Galileo proposes to treat all such secondary qualities
case that any example will serve as well as any other, as in the search for exclusively in terms of their measurable correlates with the idea that all
essences. The historical reduction, unlike the phenomenological reduction, will thereby be accounted for.36
is not and cannot be coupled with an eidetic reduction. In order to pen-
etrate to the previously unacknowledged historical prejudices which deter- Now Husserl is not as interested in the Galilean proposal itself as he is
mine the Sachen and Probleme of philosophy, we must turn not to the in its philosophical interpretation. In the hands of philosophers, Galileo's
essence of history, or to the essence of consciousness, but to the particular proposal is transformed into an ontological claim: to be is to be measurable
tradition of which we are a part. in ideal terms as a geometrical configuration. Thus it happens, as Husserl
says, 'that we take for true being what is actuaUy a method'?1 Math-
And this is exactly what Husserl proceeds to do in the Crisis. After his ematical science is a method which considers the world as if it were exclus-
brief introduction he embarks upon what the calls the 'Clarification of the ively a manifold of measurable shapes; the ontological interpretation

194 195
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
simply states that it is such a manifold. Now the scientific problem is differ- objects are not ideal geometrical shapes; instead, they faU into vague and
ent from the philosophical problem: the first seeks intersubjectively exact approximate types and exhibit not only primary and secondary qualities
knowledge about the world, the second hopes to determine the true nature but aesthetic and practical ones as weU. As long as knowledge is con-
of reality. But here the solution to the first problem is taken as the solution sidered the causal effect of the objective world upon the mind, the pre-
to the second and a hidden shift of meaning has occurred. AU subsequent scientific features of the life-world can be explained away as 'mere
problems connected with the world - its scope, its beginning and end, appearance'. But if the approach to knowledge is that of transcendental
man's place in it and, above all, his knowledge of it - henceforth operate grounding, the role of the lifeworld must be taken into account. The theo-
with this conception of reality as a presupposition. Rationalism treats the retical constructions of the scientist take the lifeworld for granted as built
scientific method as a kind of instrument, like the microscope, through upon it. We cannot adequately understand those constructions without
which we come to see reality; empiricism makes the point - correct, given understanding the intermediate and founding role of the lifeworld.
the rationaUst assumptions - that all we ever see are the causal effects of
Yet this is what Kant failed to do, says.Husserl. Thus, while he suc-
reality upon our minds, and then asks the legitimate question of whether
ceeded in one sense in overthrowing the naive objectivism ofhis predeces-
what we see accurately informs us of what is. The development ends in
sors, his philosophy contains a hidden presupposition inherited from them.
Hume's skepticism, which is only possible because the rationaUst concep-
The transcendental problem of the world, for Kant, is predetermined by a
tion of reaUty is taken for granted.
concept of the world borrowed from modern science. Hume, although he
But the real opposition in modern philosophy, for Husserl, is not had no explicit conception of the transcendental turn, had a much clearer
between rationaUsm and empiricism but between objectivism - which awareness, says Husserl, of 'the world enigma in the deepest and most ulti-
includes both of these - and transcendentaUsm. Hume demonstrated the mate sense' for he questioned 'the naive obviousness of the certainty of the
ultimate futiUty of the quest for an objective justification of our know- world . . . and, what is more, the certainty of the everyday world as weU as
ledge, but it was Kant who turned this apparent failure of philosophy to that of the sophisticated theoretical constructions built upon-this everyday
positive advantage. He did this by returning to that radical reflection world'.38 But Kant failed to see any enigma here, and began his transcen-
which Descartes had considered merely provisional and estabUshing it as dental critique in the wrong place.
the true method of rigorous philosophy. The objectivity of knowledge is We can see that Husserl's discussion of Galileo, in which the life-world
given not an objective but a subjective grounding through an examination emerges, takes on its ultimate significance not in his critique of objec-
of the forms of thought in which it announces and establishes itself. The tivism, but in his critique of the transcendental turn in which objectivism is
idea of such a subjective or transcendental grounding was Kant's contribu-1 overthrown. But whose transcendental philosophy is actuaUy being criti-
tion to the history of modern thought. cized? The strange fact about the Kant-critique in the Crisis is that while
But Kant's philosophy too must be interrogated in terms of its under- Husserl takes Kant to task for not recognizing the significance of the live-
lying problems and motives, and it is here that the true significance of world, this is the first time, in Husserl's own writings, that the lifeworld is
Husserl's historical reduction begins to merge. Husserl had always been accorded this significance. It is hard to avoid the conclusion that Husserl's
critical of many aspects of Kant's philosophy, but in the Crisis his criticism Kant-critique is really a Husserl-critique in disguise, that the inadequate
takes a new form. Kant envisaged the possibiUty and necessity of a tran- concept of transcendental philosophy that is criticized here is not Kant's
scendental grounding of the objective world; but what is the nature of that but that of the earUer Husserl. It is true that Husserl had not made the
objective world which is susceptible of and requires such a grounding? The mistake of identifying the world with the entities of natural science alone.
fact is that this world, although no longer naively taken for granted as self- He had always criticized Kant for doing this, insisting that other forms of
grounding, is still conceived in exactly the same terms as it was by the objectivity, those treated in the humanistic, social, psychological, and even
rationalists and empiricists. That is, it is the mathematized world of life sciences, should be treated in their own terms and according to their
the natural scientists that constitutes Kant's problem. For him, this is the own 'categories'. But this suggests a sort of additive concept of the world,
world. But we have seen, through our reflections on Galileo, that the as if it were composed of the various scientific domains side by side. Here
scientific conception must be regarded as an interpretation of the world, a Husserl's lengthy discussion of natural scientific idealization and construc-
certain way of looking at it and dealing with it which serves certain pur- tion is carried out not for the purpose of contrasting natural science to
poses. There remains the world of which this is an interpretation, the pre- other sciences, but rather in order to contrast the scientific endeavor - any
scientific lifeworld in which such interpretation begins and to which it must scientific endeavor - with a prescientific consciousness and its world. What
return for the direct verification of all its hypotheses. This is a world whose is being criticized is precisely the conception of world articulated in the

196 197
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF HISTORY
early pages of the Ideas, that of 'the totality of objects which, on the basis
many dimensions, and it is not just this or that science which abstracts
of actual experience, are knowable in correct theoretical thinking'.39 This
from its full concreteness, but science as a whole, or theoretical conscious-
conception was then pursued in the second volume of the Ideas, where the
ness generally.
theory of constitution takes its clue from the various material regions,
which correspond to the main divisions of science: the natural, the psychic Significant as this new development is, however, I do not think that, in
and the spiritual or Geistige. The implication is that these ontologies, itself, it involves a threat to the phenomenological program as a whole.
taken together, constitute an ontology of the world. But in the Crisis, Here I must side with those I was just attacking who minimize the novelty
Husserl suggests that the lifeworld as a whole requires its own ontology,40 of the theory of the lifeworld. Both consciousness and the world are con-
which is not equivalent to the totality of those ontologies which corres- ceived more broadly, but the phenomenological analysis of their relation is
pond to the various domains of science. The lifeworld is the realm of what the same. This is clearly what Husserl has in mind. From the new ontology
is pre-given to consciousness not only prior to natural science but also, as of the lifeworld we must proceed through a phenomenological reduction
he says, 'before anything that is established scientifically . . . in physiology, to the conscious intentionality in which this world is constituted. With is
psychology, or sociology'.41 Correlatively, the lifeworld calls forth its own base broadened, everything previously accomplished in phenomenology
theory of constitution, a theory of prescientific world-life whose intention- can be integrated into this new theory of consciousness and the world
ality is not that of subsuming its objects under theories of any kind, whose while maintaining the pattern of analysis.
interest is not determined by the demands of logical consistency or com- The really serious questions for phenomenology are raised not by the
pleteness of theoretical scope. Husserl has come to the realization that theory of the lifeworld itself but rather by Husserl's way of arriving at it,
consciousness is not theoretical all or even most of the time, that there was namely, not through the phenomenological reduction alone but through
consciousness before there was science, and, above aU, that there was a the historical reduction we spoke about. For what has emerged from our
world before science came along to interpret it. discussion is that Husserl's historical reflections are not a mere attack on
his predecessors and a historical justification post hoc of theories he
Now there can be no doubt that the concept of the life-world represents already held, but rather a questioning of his own assumptions and a recog-
a significant new development in Husserl's phenomenological theory. It is, nition of their rootedness in their own past. Husserl is above all criticizing
after all, nothing less than a new approach to the problem of the world, himself for taking over the Sachen und Probleme of philosophy from his
not merely the opening of a new domain within already established phe- predecessors. This helps explain Husserl's strange remark that it is not just
nomenological guidelines. Those who seek to minimize the novelty of the any history, but the totality of our history that must be subjected to inter-
Crisis often point out that many of Husserl's descriptions of the life-world rogation, as weU as the fact that the history he actually examines contains
coincide with those developed much earlier under the rubric of the only the philosophers he himself has studied intensively. Far from being a
phenomenology of perception or, as it was later called, that of a transcen- philosophy of history, in the sense of a description of the sense emerging
dental aesthetic,42 and that even the term 'lifeworld' seems to have been from the vast panorama of Western thought - hardly a world about Hegel,
used as early as 1917.43 All this is true, but none of these earlier investiga- none at all about Nietzsche or Marx, no mention of Christianity - the
tions are carried to the point of requiring such a thorough reconstruction Crisis offers us a historical critique above all of Edmund Husserl and the
of the world-concept. Even the borrowed term 'transcendental aesthetic' philosophical milieu from which phenomenology emerged. The Crisis is
suggests that, while Husserl wishes to enlarge on the Kantian conception essentially the construction of a history which reflects the philosopher's
he still sees it as oriented toward a theory of judgment and ultimately own philosophical prejudices for purposes of overcoming those very preju-
theoretical judgment. The investigations of Erfahrung und Urteil, for dices. Husserl even speaks of his historical reflections as the 'construction
example, and those of Formal and Transcendental Logic, exhibit this ori- of the novel of history for purposes of self-reflection [Selbstbesinnung]'?5
entation in their very titles. But in the Crisis, Husserl explicitly says that
the problem of the lifeworld must be separated from its connection with The emergence of the concept of the lifeworld in the Crisis confirms the
the theory of science and seen as a philosophical problem in its own necessity for historical reduction which is only prescribed in principle by
right.44 He conceives of the possibility of an Erfahrung which is not ori- Husserl's investigations in genetic and intersubjective phenomenology. His
ented toward Urteil at aU, at least not in the theoretical sense. Rather than aim had always been to describe the world just as it presents itself to us,
being essentiaUy an 'incipient science', in Merleau-Ponty's words, and to describe the forms of consciousness in which this presentation is
experience is a much broader field with many possible orientations, only actualized. But in the Crisis a discovery is made which changes radically
one of which is science. The world, correlatively, is characterized as having the character of phenomenological investigation. This discovery has been
particularly weU expressed by Aron Gurwitsch in a recent article: 'On

198
199
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND T H E ' P R O B L E M OF H I S T O R Y

account of our historical situation as heirs to the modern scientific tradi- matter is to criticize his view just as he criticized the modern scientific
tion, the world presents itself to us, including those of us who are not pro- world view in the Crisis: namely, by rooting out its hidden prejudices,
fessional scientists or are even ignorant of the details of scientific theories, showing its limitations, its one-sidedness, its abstractions. Such criticism
with reference to and in the light of its possible mathematical by its very nature makes impossible the relativist thesis, for prejudice is
idealization'.46 The implication is that any attempt to describe the world as recognized only by contrast to the unprejudiced, limitation only by an
it presents itself, if it is historically naive, will result in the description of a insight that goes beyond the limits, one-sidedness by our awareness of the
historical-cultural phenomenon which nevertheless takes itself to be a uni- other side, abstractness by a reference to the concrete. In short, criticism
versal characterization. My view is that Husserl is impUcitly accusing of this or that view of the world and of consciousness as historically rela-
himself of having made just such a mistake. The historical-cultural world is tive always has in view a nonrelative conception of the world of con-
another of the discoveries of the Crisis, by the way, to which Husserl also, sciousness, whether it succeeds in attaining that conception or not.
rather confusingly as I have argued elsewhere,47 gives the name 'lifeworld'. Insofar as such criticism is used to support the relativist thesis, as Husserl
There can be many lifeworlds in this sense, as in the Cartesian showed in the Prolegomena to Pure Logic, relativism contradicts itself by
Meditations?8 whereas the lifeworld in the sense described earlier is uni- presupposing the very thing it sets out to deny. But the self-contradictory
versal and is both prescientific and precultural. It is the condition of the character of relativism does not justify claiming absolute validity for any
possibility or the universal ground of any conceivable cultural or scientific particular philosopher's view; it merely suggests that there is a truth to be
interpretation. It is this world which must be laid bare and subjected to known and that we cannot assert the impossibility of knowing it. Much of
phenomenological-constitutional analysis if the phenomenology of science the pathos of Husserl's last work comes down to just this question: we
or culture or anything else is to be placed in its proper perspective. Yet, cannot exclude the possibiUty of a knowledge which lies beyond the limits
arriving at this world, laying it open to phenomenological description, is of our cultural-historical situation, but are we willing to take on the task
more complicated than the mere description of the world as it presents of actualizing it?
itself. It is rather a constant struggle against historical prejudices which
It must not be forgotten that there is a positive as well as a negative side
takes the form of careful attention to and analysis of those very prejudices.
to Husserl's historical reflections. He seeks to work his way through the
In this sense the constant danger is that of falling back into the attitude of
inadequate attempts at actualizing philosophy to a clear conception of its
historical naivete, which paraUels Husserl's earlier warnings against falUng
task. So the historical critique serves the purpose, as Husserl says, of clari-
into the natural attitude, of reasumming its prejudices rather than keeping
fying what 'the point of it'49 ultimately is, the telos of philosophy which is
a distance from them in order to analyze and understand them.
implicitly presupposed by our critique. Husserl is often accused of a sort of
Insofar as Husserl insists on such analysis as an essential part of the cultural chauvinism because he seems to speak of the task of philosophy as
phenomenological enterprise, his last work does lend support to several if it were a purely European affair. Yet if we look closely at Husserl's
post-Husserlian developments. Merleau-Ponty's notion of the relevance of characterization of the origin of that task in Greece, we see that it begins
historical and sociological evidence, precisely because it frees us from cul- with the very recognition of the difference between a cultural world and
tural naivete, seems to me to be compatible with Husserl's new concep- the world as such. Husserl obviously has the physis-nomos controversy in
tion. The idea of philosophy as Ideologiekritik, or as a hermeneutic of the mind. The paradoxical essence of the European spirit, for Husserl, lies in
tradition, becomes not only possible but necessary for phenomenology. At its very attempt to transcend the limits of any cultural world, including
the limit, even Heidegger's attempt to think the unthought in the whole that of Europe in the empirical historical sense. What was born with the
Western tradition is a legitimate task. But does it follow, once the possibil- European spirit was the ideal of a nonrelative truth, that is, a truth which
ity and necessity of such investigations is recognized, that this is all philo- is neither European truth, Chinese truth, nor any other.50 Neither Husserl
sophy can be? This seems to be suggested by the advocates of these nor any other philosopher, to my mind, can demonstrate that he has ful-
approaches, often expUcity in criticism of Husserl. After all, who is to say filled this ideal and attained such a truth. What Husserl does through his
that Husserl's attempt to describle the universal lifeworld is not itself critique of relativism is to show that the ideal is in a sense unavoidable,
merely the articulation of the presuppositions of a historico-cultural since to deny it is to subscribe to it secretly. This much was accomplished
mflieu? By admitting the importance of history, does Husserl ultimately in the Prolegomena and 'Philosophy as a Rigorous Science', and transcen-
fall prey to the very historicism he attacked in 1910? dental phenomenology was developed in the service of the ideal. But the
It seems to me that there is no guarantee that Husserl's description has Crisis, I have tried to show, adds a new dimension to phenomenology. For
attained the universality he hoped for; but the only way -to decide the here Husserl recognizes that it is not enough simply to turn our backs on

200 201
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S CRISIS AND THE PROBLEM OF H I S T O R Y

history - our history - in order to move toward a non-relative truth. We 37 Ibid., p. 51.
must work our way through it in order to escape it. 38 Ibid., p. 96.
39 Ideen, etc., p. 11.
40 Cr., p. 173ff.
Notes 41 Ibid., p. 105.
42 Cf. Formal and Transcendental Logic, p. 291 f., Cartesian Meditations, p. 146.
1 E. Husserl, Erste Philosophie, Erster Teil, Vol. VII of Husserliana, ed. by R.
Boehm (The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1956), p. 3. 43 E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phdnomenologische
2 E. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenom- Philosophie, Zweites Buch, Vol. IV of Husserliana, ed. by M. Biemel (The
enology, trans, by David Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1952), p. 375.
1970), p. 17 (hereafter abbreviated as 'Cr.'). 44 Cr.,p. 134f.
3 Cr.,p.71. 45 Die Krisis, etc., p. 556.
4 Ibid. 46 A. Gurwitsch, 'Problems of the Life-World', in Phenomenology and Social
5 Cr.,p.ll. Reality, ed. by M. Natanson (The Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1970), p. 48 (my
6 Cr.,p.ll. emphasis).
1 Cr., p. 72. 47 'Husserl's Problematic Concept of the Life-World', in American Philosophical
8 Cf. Cr., sections 9-1,15. Quarterly, October, 1970.
9 E. Husserl, Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale 48 Cartesian Meditations, p. 133.
Phanomenologie, Vol. VI of Husserliana, ed. by W. Biemel (The Hague: M. 49 Cr., p. 73.
Nijhoff, 1954), p. 435 ff. (This section was not included in its entirety in the 50 Cf.Cr., p. 286.
English translation, but cf. Cr., p. ICQ. for an excerpt).
10 Erste Philosophie, Erster Teil, p. 3.
H E . Husserl, Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft (Frankfurt: Vittorio Kloster-
mann, 1965), p. 71.
12 E. Husserl, ideen zu einer Phanomenologie und phanomenologische Philoso-
phie, Vol. Ill of Husserliana, ed. by W. Biemel (The Hague: M. Nijhoff. 1952),
p. 40f.
13 E. Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, trans, by Dorion Cairns (The Hague: M.
Nijhoff, 1960), p. 26.
14 E. Husserl, Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans, by Dorion Cairns (The
Hague: M. Nijhoff, 1969), p. 319.
15 Ibid.
16 Cartesian Meditations, p. 60.
17 Formal and Transcendential Logic, p. 316.
18 Cartesian Meditations, p. 75.
19 Ibid, p. 90.
20 Ibid, pp. 109, 111.
21 Cf. ibid., p. 120.
22 Formal and Transcendental Logic, p. 319.
23 Cf. Cartesian Meditations, p. 60.
24 Cr., p. 71.
25 Ibid, p. 17.
26 Cartesian Meditations, p. 35.
27 Cr., p. 72.
28 Ibid., p. 3911
29 Ibid., p. 370.
30 Ibid., p. xxxii (Translator's Introduction).
31 Ibid., p. 71.
32 Ibid., p. 20.
33 Ibid, p. 11.
34 Ibid, p. 23.
35 Ibid.
36 Ibid.,p.34&.

202 203
GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE

aUem, im Krisis-Werk ausdrticklich wird, in einem bestimmten Sinn als


80 aporetisch gekennzeichnet werden. Und zwar als aporetisch in der gut
sokratischen, sozusagen 'therapeutischen' Bedeutung: Sie ftihrt uns
phanomenologisch in Verlegenheit, in die Verlegenheit eines Wissens um
" F A K T U M G E S C H I C H T E " U N D ein Nicht-Wissen.1 Ich mochte dies in einem 1. Teil anhand einer Darstel-
D I E G R E N Z E N lung von Zusammenhang und Differenz der Begriffe 'Faktum Geschichte'
und 'Faktengeschichte' bei Husserl erlautern und daran orientiert in einem
P H A N O M E N O L O G I S C H E R 2. Teil zeigen, inwiefern ich meine, dass die geschichtsphilosophisch
motivierte Frage nach einem 'Sinn der Gesamteinheit der Geschichte'
G E S C H I C H T S P H I L O S O P H I E phanomenologisch keine befriedigende Antwort zulasst.

Karl-Heinz Lembeck 1. 'Faktum Geschichte' und Faktengeschichte


Zunachst werde ich Husserls bekannte Wendung von der Geschichte als
dem "grossen Faktum des absoluten Seins" (Hua VIII, 506) zum Leit-
Source: Husserl Studies 4 (1987): 209-224. faden nehmen und sie einer Interpretation unterziehen, in der sie -
moglicherweise entgegen dem natUrlichen Sprachgeftihl - bewusst als dop-
peldeutig verstanden werden soil. Dazu bieten sich m.E. zwei unter-
Der Sinn einer Wissenschaft, so schreibt Husserl in einer Beilage zum schiedliche Auslegungsmoglichkeiten des Genitivs in diesem Satze an. Die
Vorlesungstext der Ersten Philosophie, "steht in wesentlicher Beziehung erste und sprachlich gewiss naheliegendere Auffassung ist die des ein-
zum Sinn der Gegenstandlichkeit, auf die Wissenschaft sich bezieht" (Hua fachen Identitatsgenitivs: das "absolute Sein" ist das absolute "Faktum",
VIII, 321). Von der Idee dieser Gegenstandlichkeit her lasst sich ein seine Seinsweise ist geschichtlich. In dieser Form ist das Husserlsche Wort,
Masstab gewinnen, mit dessen Hilfe Moglichkeiten und Grenzen des soweit ich sehe, auch Gegenstand der bekannten Auslegungen Ludwig
Sinnes einer ihr entsprechenden Wissenschaft ergrtindet werden konnen Landgrebes. 2
(vgl. Hua V, 13). Trifft diese Einsicht prinzipiell zu, so muss sie auch auf Legt man den Genitiv in Husserls Satz nun aber possessiv aus, so ware
die nach Husserl tiefste und strengste aller Wissenschaften, die phanom- sein Sinn dieser: Die Geschichte ist ein Faktum fur das absolute Sein.
enologische Philosophie, anwendbar sein. Und ein Mittleres beider Auslegungsweisen konnte schUessUch zu der
Als 'Forschungsgegenstand' transzendentalphanomenologischer Wis- Auffassung fuhren, dass das absolute Sein eine geschichtliche Grosse
senschaft gilt nun, ganz aUgemein gesprochen, "das absolute oder transzen- gerade dadurch ist, dass das Faktische in und an ihm das transzendentale
dental reine Bewusstsein" (Hua III/l, 121), das "Residuum" der Korrelat des zugleich fiir es Faktischen ist. Beide Formen der Auslegung
transzendentalen Reduktion, das in dem Sinne "absolutes Sein" ist, als es wtirden sich dann auf derjenigen Ebene versohnen, die Husserl beschreibt,
"prinzipiell nulla 're' indiget ad existendum", wie es in den Ideen I (ebd. wenn er versucht zu zeigen, dass das "transzendentale Ich dasselbe (ist),
104) heisst. Die konstitutiven Leistungen dieser den Sinn alien Seins absolut das in der Weltlichkeit menschliches Ich ist" (Hua VI, 268), weil es
stiftenden transzendentalen Subjektivitat aus letzten Ursprtingen heraus "notwendig als Mensch in der Welt konstituiert sein muss" (ebd. 190).
"verstehen" zu woUen, ist das wissenschaftliche Ziel der Phanomenologie Mundanitat und Transzendentalitat erweisen sich dann als zwei (method-
(vgl. z.B. Hua XIX/1,27; Hua XVII, 282; Hua VI, 193). Lasst sich von dieser isch) unterscheidbare Fundierungsschichten ein und derselben Realitat.
Gegenstandsbestimmung her ein kritischer Masstab ftir Recht und Grenzen Doch bevor darauf einzugehen ist, muss zunachst geklart werden,
phanomenologischer Forschung selbst gewinnen? Im folgenden soil diese inwiefern der hier genannte Genitiv possessiv auslegbar ist. Argumente
Frage am Beispiel des Verhaltnisses von Phanomenologie und Geschichte ftir eine solche Deutung Uefert der Begriff des Faktums selbst. In der
untersucht werden. Es geht hierbei um eine kritische Grenzziehung ftir die Auslegung des absoluten Seins als Faktum tragt er eine wesentlich andere
mogUche Reichweite einer Phanomenologie der Geschichte anhand einer Bedeutung als im Fall einer possessiven Interpretation des Genitivs. Denn
Wesensbestimmung des transzendentalen Forschungsfeldes. Zu diesem Faktum fiir das absolute Sein des Bewusstseinslebens ist alles objektive
Zweck soU insbesondere jene spate Husserlsche FragesteUung nach einem konstituierte Sein der Erfahrungswelt. Dies ist das transzendente Faktis-
teleologischen Einheitssinn der europaischen Geistesgeschichte, wie sie vor che, also das Empirische. Als das Individuell-Tatsachliche in der Welt der

204 205
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE
Erfahrung ist es, so wissen wir seit den Ideen I, stets ein im weitesten Sinne und dem transzendentalen Faktum dieser Konstitution selbst zieht Husserl
Zufalliges, das faktisch immer auch anders wtirde sein, d.h. in anderen einen radikalen Trennungsstrich. 4 Ist jenes das im jeweiligen Wie der Kon-
Gegebenheitsweisen wtirde erscheinen konnen. Ein Absolutes dagegen ist stitution als transzendentes Faktum Gesetzte, so ist dieses das Faktum des
ein Notwendiges. Was soil es dann heissen, dass dieses Absolute als irre- Dass und Wie der Konstitution tiberhaupt. Die Pointe dieser Unterschei-
duzibel Notwendiges, das kein Zufalliges often lasst (Hua XV, 386), dung wird besonders deutlich, wenn man versteht, warum Husserl nun das
dennoch als ein "Faktum" zu bezeichnen ist, als eine "absolute Tatsache" transzendentale Faktum als eine "Irrationalitat" beschreibt.
(Hua XV, 403)? Ein empirisches Faktum kann es doch wohl nicht sein?
Jede als reale Wirklichkeit gesetzte empirische Tatsache ist stets als
Hier ist offenbar eine Unterscheidung zwischen zwei Begriffen von
konstitutive Einheit einer Sinngebung zu betrachten (Hua III/l, 120). Sie
"Faktum" zu treffen.
setzt daher sinngebendes Bewusstsein voraus. Sinnsetzendes Bewusstsein
Husserl hilft uns hier selbst weiter, wenn er beide Begriffe in einem ist idealiter Vernunftbewusstsein, d.h. es ist Setzungsbewusstsein, das in
einzigen Satz direkt aufeinander bezieht und mit diesem Bezug zugleich originarer Gegebenheit, also Selbstgegebenheit des intendierten, als
ihren Unterschied deutlich macht. Er schreibt: "Das faktische Bewusst- seiend gesetzten Objekts seinen ausgezeichneten Rechtsgrund hat (vgl.
seinsleben, das universale in seiner transzendentalen intersubjektiven ebd. 316ff.). Dementsprechend heisst 'wahrhaftes Sein' soviel wie 'aus
Immanenz, tragt als 'Phanomen' in sich das korrelative Faktum der in ihr verntinftiger Motivation heraus gesetztes Sein', wobei "verntinftig
vorstellungsmassig konstituierten Welt." (Hua VII, 256f.) Hier ist von motiviert' meint: durch originare Gegebenheit motiviert (vgl. ebd. 329,
"Faktum" als Korrelat des faktischen Bewusstseinslebens die Rede. 332).
Diesem transzendenten Faktum einer transzendental konstituierten Welt
Das sinngebende Bewusstsein ist in diesem Sinne keine ReaUtat,
gegeniiber, dem Faktum der empirischen WirkUchkeit gegeniiber, muss
sondern absolut, insofern alle Realitat als gesetztes Sein auf es relativ ist
nun jedoch mit Husserl das "transzendentale Faktum" des "Bewusst-
(vgl. ebd. 120f.). Dieses Absolute, von dem sich phanomenologisch zeigen
seinslebens" als sein Korrelat, und d.h. als etwas entschieden anderes
lasst, wie es ftir alles Sein transzendental grund-gebend ist, ist ftir sich
betrachtet werden. 3 Wie entschieden, das zeigt eine sehr wichtige
selbst in diesem Sinne "grundlose(s) Sein" (Hua XV, 386): Es ist, wie
Anmerkung zum historischen Teil der Ersten Philosophie. Da heisst es
Husserl sagt, transzendentales "Urfaktum" (ebd.) des Dass und Wie der
namlich, dass das in nattirlicher Einstellung und in der Einstellung der
Konstitution transzendenter Faktizitat. Selbst ist es daher nicht transzen-
Tatsachenwissenschaften als Faktum konstituierte objektive Sein, in
dental gesetztes Sein, weshalb sein Sein auch nicht 'verntinftig' (im genan-
Bezug auf die konstituierende transzendentale Subjektivitat betrachtet,
nten, spezifisch Husserlschen Sinne), d.h. nicht in einem originar gebenden
Gegenstand phanomenologischer Wesensanalysen werden kann und muss,
Bewusstsein ausweisbar sein kann. Das absolute Sein kann von sich selbst
worin ihm dann eine "letzte" oder auch " 'metaphysische' Interpretation"
daher niemals unmittelbar ein Vernunftbewusstsein erlangen. Und auch
zuwachsen soil, was ftir Husserl an dieser Stelle aber "nichts anderes
die letzte methodische Pointe Descartes', das Prinzip des cogito me cog-
heisst, als eine Interpretation, hinter der eine andere zu suchen keinen
itare, des sich-selbst-denkend-Denkens, bleibt transzendentalanalytisch
wissenschaftlichen Sinn gibt. Aber dahinter", so schreibt Husserl sogleich
stumpf, weil sich hier noch immer jenes beruhmte "Endchen der Welt"
weiter, "eroffnet sich auf phanomenologischem Boden eine weiter nicht
(Hua I, 63) in den BUck stellt, das die Methode in einen schlechten Zirkel
mehr zu interpretierende Problematik: die der Irrationalitat des transzen J
zwingt. Denn ist auch die Evidenz des ego cogito Motiv genug, das
dentalen Faktums, das sich in der Konstitution der faktischen Welt und
Faktum des absoluten Seins reflexiv zu bestimmen, so ist damit nichts
des faktischen Geisteslebens ausspricht: also Metaphysik in einem neuen
gewonnen, da eine solche Setzung ihrerseits das setzende Bewusstsein
Sinne." (Hua VII, 188 Anm.)
bereits wieder voraussetzt: Als gesetztes ware es relativ auf das setzende
Hier kommen drei wichtige Punkte zur Sprache, die einer Auslegung Sein und darum nicht mehr absolut - ware es doch widersinnig zu sagen,
bedtirfen: 1. Der angesprochene Unterschied zwischen dem konstituierten das Absolute sei gesetzt. Deshalb kann Husserl feststellen, dass das Sein
objektiven Sein als transzendentem Faktum und dem transzendentalen des Absoluten als das Faktum des Dass der Konstitution der faktischen
Faktum der Konstitution des faktischen Seins selbst; dartiber hinaus dann Welt phanomenologisch eine "IrrationaUtat" sei.
2. die mit dieser Unterscheidung sich herausstellende Begrenzung des 2. Mit dieser Unterscheidung zwischen dem (rational) konstituierten
Feldes eidetisch-phanomenologischer Zustandigkeit; und schliesslich 3. die Faktischen und dem (irrationalen) Faktum des Dass der Konstitution
damit einhergehende Differenzierung im Metaphysik-Begriff. werden nun auch der Reichweite eidetisch-phanomenologischer
1. Zwischen dem Faktum (resp. den empirischen Faktizitaten) einer im Forschung selbst Grenzen gezogen. Das als Faktizitat gesetzte objektive
konstitutiv fungierenden Bewusstsein vorsteUungsmassig gesetzten Welt Sein (zumal als Gegenstand positiv wissenschaftlichen Interesses) lasst

206 207
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE

sich phanomenologisch interpretieren, d.h. transzendentalanalytisch auf selbst - bleibt eben ein "Wunder" (Hua VII, 394), ihn hinterfragen zu
das Recht seines Geltungssinnes hin auslegen. Hier liegt die reflexive woUen Widersinn.
Aufgabe der transzendentalen Geltungsbegrtindung und der wesensana- Was hat es nun aber mit der These auf sich, dass die Geschichte
lytischen Rechtfertigung 'naiver' ontologischer Wissenschaftsstandards. Es dies grosse Faktum des absoluten Seins sei? Die Frage beantwortet
handelt sich dabei um die Auslegung des faktischen Wie konstitutiver sich mit Husserl folgendermassen: Ist das Dass-Sein des Bewusstseins-Ich
Bewusstseinsleistungen. notwendig ein "absolutes, undurchstreichbares Faktum", so ist demge-
Das 'irrationale' transzendentale Faktum des absoluten Seins aber ist genuber sein Wie-Sein "zufallig" (Hua XIV, 154f.). Dieses Wie-Sein des
unhinterfragbares "Urfaktum", weil es als das Dass des konstituierenden intentionalen Bewusstseinslebens ist nun aber bei afl seiner inhaltlichen
lebendigen Bewusstseins nicht selbst Ergebnis einer transzendentalen ZufalUgkeit gleichwohl gesetzmassig strukturiert. Sein Wesen ist, wie wir
Leistung sein kann, weil es, transzendental verstanden, grundlos ist. Das wissen, Horizontintentionalitat und als solche von genetisch-teleologis-
transzendentale Faktum steUt deshalb vor ein "auf phanomenologischem chem Charakter. Die intentionale Genesis ist die formalste Wesensbestim-
Boden . . . weiter nicht mehr zu interpretierende(s)" Problem (Hua VII mung des Bewusstseinslebens als absolutem Sein. Das absolute Sein ist
188 Anm.)! Genetisch-Sein. Das Dass-Sein dieser Genesis ist das schlechthin grand-
3. Interpretierbar ist es aUenfalls auf dem Boden einer Metaphysik, die iose und darum phanomenologisch unbegrtindbare Faktum des absoluten
nun jedoch nicht mehr ernstlich mit dem Pradikat 'phanomenologisch' Seins. Demnach konnte man sagen: Genesis ist das grosse Faktum des
versehen werden kann. Gewiss schreibt Husserl zu Recht, dass jede "Irra- absoluten Seins. - Aber Genesis, transzendentale Genesis zumal, ist nicht
tionalitat . . . als eine Moglichkeit (sc. des "Bruches" rationaler Erfahrungs- eo ipso Geschichte.
horizonte) selbst etwas" sei, "das unter rationaler Erwagung steht" (Hua Damit ist ein gewiss schwieriges und in jungerer Zeit haufiger disku-
XIV, 561) - doch wie sollte es auch anders sein? Was denn anderes als das tiertes 6 Problem angesprochen. Ich kann hier jedoch nicht zeigen, wie der
rational fungierende Bewusstsein sollte das Irrationale als Irrationales komplizierte Zusammenhang von transzendentaler Genesis und mun-
auch bestimmen konnen? Aber eben als Grenze und nicht mehr. Die Fak- daner Geschichte sich, wie ich meine, im einzelnen fiber einen Ausweis
tizitat, auch die empirische, insofern sie uberhaupt ist, weil das Bewusst- der Identitat des transzendentalen mit dem mundan-personlichen Ich her-
sein tiberhaupt ist, "ist das Feld nicht der Phanomenologie und Logik, leiten lasst. Husserl sucht diesen Ausweis zu erbringen, indem er das per-
sondern der Metaphysik" (Hua VII, 394). Die Phanomenologie aber ist sonliche Ich als das konstitutive Ergebnis einer "Selbstobjektivation" des
nur insofern metaphysisch zu nennen, als sie die Welt (als subjektives transzendentalen Ich beschreibt. 7 Seine in der systematischen Ausffihrung
Konstitutionskorrelat) einer Interpretation auf ihre letzten transzenden- leider fragmentarisch bleibenden Versuche konnen - soviel mag sich
talen Geltungsquellen hin unterziehen kann, einer Interpretation, hinter schon von dem bereits Gesagten her zeigen lassen - ein entscheidendes
der dann aus phanomenologischer Einsicht heraus "eine andere zu suchen Motiv fur ihre Angemessenheit den Bestimmungen zum transzendentalen
keinen wissenschaftlichen Sinn gibt" (ebd. 188 Anm.). Faktum selbst entnehmen. Denn das absolute Sein als unhinterfragbares
Das transzendentale Faktum des absoluten Seins, das Faktum des Dass- Faktum der Konstitution kann von sich selbst kein Vernunftbewusstsein
Seins der Konstitution dagegen konnte nurmehr Gegenstand einer Meta- erlangen, da es sich nicht als "Urfaktum" setzen und diese Setzung dann
physik im "neuen Sinn" werden (ebd.). Ihr "neuer" Sinn ware aber nur als verntinftig sich ausweisen lassen kann (was widersinnig ware oder aber
insoweit bestimmbar, als sich sagen lasst, dass sie, wie Ludwig Landgrebe einen infiniten Regress zur Folge hatte). Demnach kann das absolute Sein
mit Husserl betont hat,5 eine "Lehre vom Faktum", und zwar vom tran- nur dadurch von sich selbst ein vernunftmassig ausweisbares Bewusstsein
szendentalen Faktum, Uefern mtisste; aber es ist nun keineswegs mehr ver- erlangen, indem es sich objektivierend setzt, dann aber nattirlich nicht als
wunderlich, wenn Husserl nirgends eine Metaphysik entwickelt, die das absolute Dass-Sein, sondern als eine horizontintentional, also genetisch-
diesem Begriff entspricht - denn ein solches Unterfangen mtisste, wie wir zeitlich verumstandete Einheit: als Person. Es setzt sich objektivierend als
nun gesehen haben, die Grenzen phanomenologischer Moglichkeiten Inbegriff seines intentionalen Wie-Seins in und Verhaltens zur Welt seiner
entschieden tiberschreiten. Damit ist nicht gesagt, dass die Phanomenolo- intentionalen Objekte - also als ein intentionales Objekt in der intentional
gie Metaphysik tiberhaupt ausschliessen wollte: Innerhalb der faktischen konstituierten Welt der Erfahrung mit dem Geltungssinn: Mensch in der
Sphare der transzendentalen Monade treten alle nur mogUchen auch Welt.
"ethisch-religiosen Probleme" auf, "aber gesteUt auf den Boden, auf den Im Rahmen dieser objektivierenden Selbstauffassung als menschliche
aUes, was fur uns soil moglichen Sinn haben konnen, eben gestellt sein Person mtisste das .transzendentale Subjekt seine intentionale Genesis als
muss" (Hua I, 182)! Doch dieser Boden transzendentaler Rationalitat Entwicklungsgeschichte seines stets mehr oder minder verntinftig

208 209
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE
motivierten Verhaltens zur Erfahrungsumwelt auffassen. Und die person- Seiende sein historisches Gewordensein und Werden empfangt. So sind
liche Geschichte des personlichen Ich ware dann die Geschichte der Selb- unsere beiden Auslegungsweisen im Problem der transzendentalen
stmodifikation einer sich in diesem Entwicklungsgang stets kontinuierlich Fundierungsschichten vermittelt, dessen Bearbeitung in Husserls Versuch
naherbestimmenden wie auch wandelnden personalen Einheit, eines per- kulminiert, die Identitat von transzendentalem und mundanem Subjekt
sonalen Stils, eines "personalen Charakters", wie Husserl sagt (Hua 1,101; auszuweisen, weil die Wesensbestimmung des transzendentalen Ich
vgl. Hua IX, 214f.; Hua IV, 112f.). Diese Geschichte ist grossteils in der undenkbar ist "ohne transzendentales Ich als faktisches" (Hua XV, 385),
erinnernden Vergegenwartigung zuganglich. Und sofern nun die dieser und das heisst auch als manifestes, mundan lokalisiertes Ich.9
Person korreUerende Umwelt nicht nur einen sachlichen sondern vor Dass dieses Apriori nun aber als Quellpunkt ftir die Konstitution einer
allem auch einen sozialen Sinn trSgt, erscheint sie eo ipso als das Korrelat faktisch-geschichtUchen Welt fungiert - ist seinerseits ein Faktum. Es ist
einer vergemeinschafteten Interpersonalitat, d.h. mundan als das stets das Faktum des Dass-Seins des genetisch verfassten und konstitutiv
modifizierbare Ergebnis interpersonal-kommunikativer Bedeutuhgsverlei- fungierenden absoluten Seins (Bewusstseins). Hier tritt die andere Lesart
hung. Darin tibertragt sich der geschichtliche Charakter interpersonaler des Genitivs ins Recht: Das absolute Sein ist das unhinterfragbare Faktum
Auffassungsweisen auf den Sinn des Auffassungsgegenstandes: Die des Genetischresp. Geschichtlich-Seins. Wenn Husserl haufig statt von
Erfahrungsumwelt wird zur historischen Welt. Genesis gleich von 'Geschichte' spricht, so deshalb, weil transzendentale
Dieser Komplex kann freiUch in seiner ganzen Weite hier nicht thema- Sinngenesis eben niemals nur kontinuierliches 'Geschehen' sondern auch
tisch sein und sollte deshalb nur angedeutet und dann als vorlaufig akzept- 'Schichtung' und 'Geschichtetes', also 'Sinnsedimentierung' und Wieder-
abel ftir unsere jetztige Absicht vorausgesetzt werden.8 Allerdings kommt Identifizierbarkeit meint. Und dass auch die sog. 'Faktengeschichte' im
dieser Zusammenhang zwischen 'Geschichte' (in Anftihrungszeichen) und gewohnUchen Wortsinn ftir Husserl im Grunde nichts anderes als Sinn-
Geschichte (im gewohnUchen Wortsinn) nun m.E. auch, auf eine ktirzeste geschichte bedeuten muss, erhellt schon daher, dass Geschichte niemals
Formel gebracht, in der doppelten Auslegungsmoglichkeit des Genitivs in 'Geschehen an sich', sondern stets Auffassungs- und Auslegungsprodukt
Husserls Wort von der Geschichte als dem Faktum des absoluten Seins zum eines genetisch organisierten und von daher geschichtlich orientierten
Ausdruck. Subjekts ist, und dass alle geschichtliche Welt, transzendental betrachtet,
Denn je nachdem, wie man diesen Genitiv liest, so hatten wir gesehen, intentionales Korrelat eines sinngeschichtlich strukturierten geistigen
muss man auch den Begriff des Faktums im betreffenden Zusammenhang Lebens ist. Die Faktengeschichte als geschichtlicher Zusammenhang
entsprechend auslegen. Bedeutet der Genitiv, dass Geschichte ein Faktum intentional konstituierter Faktizitaten hat sonach ihren Ursprung im
fur das absolute Sein sei, so heisst Faktum hier 'vorsteUungsmassig konstitu- Faktum der geschichtlich-genetischen Organisiertheit des absoluten
iertes Faktum'. 'Geschichte' ware dann Inbegriff ftir den sinngeschichtUchen Bewusstseins. - Husserls Kritik an der blossen 'Tatsachengeschichte' ist
Zusammenhang der (empirischen) Faktizitaten einer konstituierten Welt daher als ein Moment seiner generellen Kritik am naiven Objektivismus
der Erfahrung und ihrer Menschen. In naturlicher und positiv- zu betrachten: Ebensowenig wie es blosse, objektive Tatsachen 'an sich'
wissenschaftUcher EinsteUung ware diese Geschichte als Faktizitat dann gibt, ebensowenig gibt es eine blosse 'Tatsachengeschichte'. Denn es gibt
etwa der Bereich eines als Tatsachengeschehen erforschbaren Seins. Ftir die ebensowenig eine bewusstseinsunabhangige Geschichte wie es eine
mundane Phanomenologie ware sie ein entscheidendes Moment im bewusstseinsunabhangige Welt gibt.
anschaulich beschreibbaren und eidologisch analysierbaren Aufbau der
geistigen Welt (vgl. die Beschreibungen in Ideen II und bes. auch in den
Intersubjektivitdtsbdnden). Transzendental reduziert aber ware sie 2. Grenzen der Sinnfrage
schliessUch Leitfaden ftir eine radikale Interpretation auf die transzenden-
Ftir Husserls Auseinandersetzung mit der Geschichte hat nun diese Dop-
talen Urquellen ihrer Konstitution.
pelauslegung des Worts vom geschichtlichen Faktum eine Konsequenz, die
Diese konstitutiven Urquellen liegen nun jedoch in dem, was Husserl insbesondere hinsichtlich der Grundfrage nach einem teleologischen Ein-
"innere Historie" nennt als der sinngenetisch-teleologischen Struktur der heitssin der Geschichte bemerkenswert ist. Ich mochte diese Sinnfrage hin-
transzendental fungierenden Subjektivitat (Hua VI, 386, vgl. 381. Anm.). sichtlich des Geschichtsprozesses in zwei mogliche Fragevarianten
Alle erfahrungsmassig konstituierten Fakten haben von daher ihre innere differenzieren: Sie fragt a) nach einem ursachlichen Grund oder b) nach
Sinnstruktur, die keine statische ist, sondern eine genetische. Es ist, wie seinem Zweck, wobei ein ausgezeichneter Fall noch derjenige ware, bei
Husserl sagt, das "gewaltige strukturelle Apriori" (Hua VI, 380) der tran- dem Grund und Zweck in Begriff der Finalursache zusammenfaUen. Dies
szendentalen Subjektivitat, das Apriori der Sinngenesis, von dem her aUes wtirde dann bedeuten, dass der ursachliche Grund des Geschichtsprozesses

210 211
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE

(sein 'Sinn') durch sein Woraufhin bestimmt ist. In Husserls teleologischer bewusstseinsmassig auf Welt bezogen. Die Bezogenheit liegt in seinen
Auslegung der Geschichte des europaischen Geistes erweist sich tatsach- Zielungen, er ist durch und durch 'teleologisch' und die Welt ist sein tele-
lich diese finalursachliche Deutung als ausschlaggebend. ologisches Gebilde und teleologische Weltbetrachtung und Welterklarung
Ftir Husserl Uegt der teleologische Anfang des Entwicklungsprozesses ist von vornherein vorgezeichnet durch reflektiven Riickgang auf die per-
des europaischen Geistes bei der griechischen "Urstiftung" des Sinnes sonale Subjektivitat . . . " (ebd.). Die Teleologie des faktisch-praktischen
einer letztwissenschaftUchen Philosophie (Hua VI, 72). Zu jeder "Urs- Weltlebens (der Zweck-Mittel-Rationalitat) ist reduzierbar auf die
tiftung" gehort eine dem historischen Prozess aufgegebene "Endstiftung" genetisch-teleologische Struktur intentionaler Weltbezuglichkeit, also letz-
(ebd. 73). Die Urstiftung kommt erst von der vollzogenen Endstiftung her tendlich auf das absolute Teleologischsein der transzendentalen Subjektiv-
zur Klarheit, d.h. in der historisch-kritischen Rtickbesinnung auf den tele- itat, auf das absolute Faktum seiner "Geschichte im pragnanten Sinn", wie
ologischen Sinn dessen hin, "worauf 'es' letztiich in der verborgenen Husserl sagt (Hua XV, 669). Diese Reduktion aber, so Husserl weiter,
Einheit intentionaler Innerlichkeit, welche aUein Einheit der Geschichte muss schUesslich "zu einer absoluten Teleologie ftihren, eine in den men-
ausmacht, . . . 'hinauswoUte'" (ebd. 74). Erst von der "Endstiftung" her schUchen ZweckUchkeiten selbst waltende, eine ubermenschliche" (Ms. K
zeigt sich die "sinnhaft-finale Harmonie" (ebd.) des sinngeschichtlich- III 1/VIII, S. 8).
geistesgeschichtlichen Prozesses. Die Frage nach dem Einheitssinn der Damit jedoch befinden wir uns an dem eingangs erwahnten aporetis-
Geschichte ist bei Husserl sonach identisch mit der Frage nach dem chen Punkt der Argumentation. Die relativ begrenzt fungierenden teleolo-
finalursachlichen Grund ihrer Teleologie, nach ihrem Woraufhin. gischen Strukturen intentionaler Weltbeztiglichkeiten, wie sie sich im
Der Begriff der Finalursache hat nun seinen eigentlichen Ort im praktischen Zweckleben bekunden, werden in der Reduktion auf das tran-
Rahmen der von der praktischen Philosophie gestellten Frage nach der szendentale Faktum zu Abschattungsformen einer absoluten Teleologie
Bedeutung der Vernunft ftir das menschUche Handeln. Demnach liegt hypostasiert. Mogennun diese intentionalen Sinngebungsprozesse zur
etwa einem nach Mitteln und Wegen strukturierten Handlungsablauf die Konstitution einer faktischen Welt von ihrer Zweckursachlichkeit her
Projektion eines Handlungszieles voraus, das daher im Nachhinein als die verntinftig auslegbar sein, so kann jedoch von einer ebensolchen Interpre-
Finalursache des vollzogenen Handlungsganges betrachtet werden kann. tation der absoluten Teleologie des transzendentalen Faktums wohl nicht
Die rationale Begriindung der Handlung liegt in der teleologischen mehr gut die Rede sein. Denn der "Einheitssinn" seiner "Geschichte im
Erklarung des effektiven Zusammenhangs von Ziel und Mitteln. Derart pragnanten Sinn" ist von keiner Endstiftung finalursachlich herleitbar, da
vernunftstrategisch strukturierte Prozesse, wie solche aus praktisch- das transzendentale Faktum, wie beschrieben wurde, eine "IrrationaUtat"
schlussfolgerndem Denken resultierende Handlungsablaufe, konnen ihre ist, also sein Sein sich keiner verntinftig motivierten Setzung verdankt, die
teleologische "Harmonie" aus projektierten "Endstiftungen" heraus dann teleologisch zu bewahren ware. Sofern es also nicht intentional
gewinnen. Erst die Erreichung des Handlungszieles (als Vollzug der Ends- gesetztes Sein ist, ist es finalursachUch auch nicht zu begreifen. So ftihrt
tiftung) vermag eine hinreichende Begrundung der Rationalitat und d.h. uns die Frage nach dem "Sinn" seiner "GeschichtUchkeit" dahin, nun
des "Einheitssinnes" des Handlungsganges zu Uefern. nicht mehr nach einer Final-sondern nach einer mogUchen Wirkursache,
Husserl selbst beschreibt das faktische menschUche Leben in seiner per- also nach einem effektiv-ursSchUchen Grund seines GeschichtUchseins zu
sonalen Lebensumwelt als durch solche teleologische FinaUtat bestimmt. forschen. Dies aber, so eroffnet uns die hier erreichte Aporie, kann eben-
I: sowenig mit phanomenologischen Mitteln geschehen. Denn was wir
So heisst es in einem Manuskript aus 1934/35: "In den menschlichen Per-
sonen und ihrem Weltleben, in ihren praktischen Aktivitaten waltet aber phanomenologisch von der absoluten GeschichtUchkeit des transzenden-
auch die unmittelbar gegebene Teleologie - namUch es ist ein Zweckleben talen Faktums wissen konnen, ist ausschUesslich ihr Dass-Sein, keinesfalls
mit Endzwecken und Mitteln. Nun einerseits die erkennende Praxis mit aber ihr Warum- oder Woher-Sein, da ihr Dass-Sein ftir die phanomenolo-
dem Endzweck der Wahrheit, andererseits die handelnd-umgestaltende gische Betrachtung eben "grundlos" bleiben muss. Die phanomenologis-
. . . Das im Ich als Ich, im Wir als Wir liegende Streben auf Ziele hin kon- che Interpretation kann daher tiber dies Wissen ums Nicht-Wissen nicht
stituiert geltende W e l t . . . " (Ms. K III 1/VIII, S. 7). Es handelt sich hier um hinausfuhren.
eine "unmittelbar gegebene Teleologie" von konstituierten Zwecken und Husserls These, dass es darauf ankame zu untersuchen, "worauf 'es' let-
Mitteln innerhalb einer als geltend gesetzten Welt. Die Rede ist also vom ztlich in der verborgenen Einheit intentionaler Innerlichkeit, welche allein
teleologischen Zusammenhang der transzendenten Faktizitaten einer kon- Einheit der Geschichte ausmacht, . . . 'hinauswoUte'", ftihrt demnach in
stituierten Welt. Dieser Zusammenhang lasst sich jedoch reduzieren. So die 'Verlegenheit', nicht sagen zu konnen, wer oder was denn dies (zwis-
heisst es weiter: "Der Mensch als erkennender, wertender, handelnder . . . chen Anftihrungszeichen gesetzte) "es" sei, das da auf was auch immer

212 213
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S GRENZEN PHANOMENOLOGISCHER GESCHICHTSPHILOSOPHIE

"hinauswill". Und wenn Husserl im Anschluss an seine Feststellung, dass Genesis und mundan geschichtUchem Geschehen, wie er oben nur
die Einheit der Geschichte "menschUcher Zwecklichkeiten" die einer kurz angedeutet worden ist, dann im einzelnen hergeleitet werden.
"ubermenschlichen" Teleologie sei, nun vom Gottesbegriff zu sprechen Hier liegen Moglichkeiten einer phanomenologischen Behandlung der
beginnt (Ms. K III 1/VIII, S. 8; vgl. Ms. K III 2, S. 52-57), so zeigt das Geschichte (auch in wissenschaftstheoretischer Absicht), die m.E.
unmissverstandlich die Richtung an, in die er sich mit diesen Fragen noch tiberhaupt nicht ausgeschopft sind.
bewegt. Bereits 1908/09 heisst es, zwar noch unentschieden, in der hypo- 2 Ftir die geschichtsphilosophische Sinnfrage aber ist entscheidend, dass
thetischen Konsequenz jedoch schon vielsagend: "Aber dass nach den eine Sinndeutung der Faktengeschichte letzten Endes auf das Faktum
ideal normativen Gesetzen sich eine einheitUche und sohin rationale ihres Dass-Seins zuruckgewiesen wtirde, d.h. aber auf das Dass der
Bewusstseins-ordnung muss herstellen lassen, dass es eine Natur muss transzendentalen Konstitution selbst, die das Korrelat des Dass der
geben konnen und eine Kultur und eine Entwicklung der Natur, die faktisch konstituierten geschichtUchen Welt ist. Aber ist nun dieses
Kultur ermoglicht, und eine Entwicklung der Kultur im Sinne idealer transzendentale Faktum in seinem schlechthinnigen Dass-Sein
Kultur, das ist nicht (a priori) 'notwendig'. Oder gibt es daftir eigenttim- phanomenologisch unhinterfragbar, so ist damit ineins die Frage nach
Uche QueUen der Notwendigkeit? Das hiesse Gott demonstrieren." (Ms. B dem ursprungUchen Grund des Dass-Seins der konstituierten Welt als
I 4, S. 2) So kame der Nachweis der bereits genannten "ubermen- geschichtlicher ebenso abgewiesen. Diese Fragen nach einem letzten
schlichen" Teleologie einer Demonstration Gottes gleich - sofern er Sinn des Faktums des absoluten Seins und der Geschichte, diese
gelingt. Doch kann er gelingen? Fragen nach einem effektiv-ursachUchen Grund des geschichtUchen
Damit wird nun aber auch der philosophisch an sich legitime Ansatz Dass-Seins der konstituierenden Subjektivitat fuhren auf eine auf
von Husserls wissenschafts- und kulturtherapeutisch argumentierender phanomenologischem Boden "weiter nicht mehr zu interpretierende
Xraw-Schrift in fragwtirdige Konsequenzen getrieben. Das wird ganz Problematik" (Hua VII, 188 Anm.). Solche Fragen sind vielmehr
deutlich, wenn man in einem Manuskript zur Krisis-Problematik (von "letztmetaphysische" Fragen (Hua VIII, 506), und darum ist ihre
1934/35) eine Bemerkung Uest, die man dann durchaus als Selbstkritik Beantwortung durchaus nicht mehr Sache der Phanomenologie
Husserls auffassen kann, in der es vielsagend heisst: "Hat Geschichte sondern allenfalls Sache einer mit phanomenologischen Mitteln
Wesensgesetze? Denken wir an unser Ausgangsproblem der MogUchkeit freiUch nicht zu entwickelnden "neuen" Metaphysik - in der dann
einer Therapie der Gemeinschaften, der Nationen usw. Was ware eine mogUcherweise, so Husserl, auch ein ganz "neuer Sinn von 'absolut'
solche anderes als eine praktische Kunst, die faktische Geschichte durch erwachst" (Hua VII, 382).
die Erkenntnis der Wesensformen derselben zu regieren! - Ist das nicht eine
Hybris?" (Ms. K III 1/IX, Bl. 228b) So wie der Sinn jeder anderen Wissenschaft, so wird auch der Sinn der
Ftir die Moglichkeit einer Phanomenologie der Geschichte haben diese phanomenologischen Forschung durch das Wesen ihres thematischen
Beobachtungen nun folgende Konsequenzen: "Gebietes", das sie bearbeitet, bestimmt und begrenzt. Und diese Begren-
zung schliesst gewisse Fragestellungen grundsatzlich aus. Warum es also
1 Der genetische Zusammenhang intentional konstituierter Faktizitaten Geschichte gibt, worin sie ihren letzten Grund hat und worauf "es" mit ihr
der Erfahrungswelt kann mogUcherweise teleologisch-geschichtlich "hinauswill" - dies bleiben daher ftir eine nichtmetaphysische Phanom-
interpretiert werden. D.h. wir konnen phanomenologisch verstehen enologie ebenso sinnlose Fragen, wie etwa die Frage danach, warum es
lernen, wie das Bewusstseinsleben als grund-gebendes ftir alle konsti- tiberhaupt konstituierende Subjekte, also Menschen gibt.
tuierte Faktizitat sich wesensmassig genetisch-teleologisch vollzieht;
wir konnen von daher vielleicht auch noch phanomenologisch verste-
hen lernen, warum die Welt der Erfahrung sich ftir die transzenden- Anmerkungen
tale Subjektivitat vorstellungsmassig immer nur als geschichtliche Welt 1 Vgl. Menon 80 d - 86 c; Sophistes 250 d-e.
gibt und wie diese Geschichte, im einzelnen zweckursachUch strukturi- 2 Vgl. Ludwig Landgrebe, Meditation Uber Husserls Wort 'Die Geschichte ist das
ert, stets eine Geschichte der handelnden Menschen ist. Und nur grosse Faktum des absoluten Seins' (1974), in: ders., Faktizitat und Individua-
dieses "Wie", mit dem die Geschichte sich faktisch gibt, und zwar vor- tion. Studien zu den Grundfragen der Phanomenologie (Hamburg 1982), 38-57;
wissenschaftlich wie wissenschaftlich, kann zum Thema einer phanom- vgl. auch: Faktizitat und Individuation, ebd. 102-116.
3 Vgl. auch Hua VII, 390: Das faktische Bewusstsein ist nicht das empirische.
enologischen Kritik der historischen Erfahrung werden. In einer 4 Dass die Terminologie hier allzu leicht Missverstandnisse herausfordert, ist nicht
solchen Kritik mtisste der Zusammenhang von transzendentaler eben hilfreich, ftir Husserl aber ganz typisch. Er zwingt zur genauen Lekture.

214 215
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S

Eines der prominentesten Beispiele: die terminologische Nahe von Geschichte


als Faktengeschichte und 'Geschichte' als Bewusstseinsgeschichte (Bewusst-
seinsgenesis); letzteres gelegentlich, aber auch nicht immer, durch
Anfuhrungszeichen gekennzeichnet. Doch stets dann, wenn derartige Aequiv-
okations-Probleme auftauchen, scheinen sie zugleich auf phanomenologisch
wichtige Zusammenhange, namlich transzendentale Fundierungszusammen- Part 13
hange hinzudeuten: Das Empirisch-Faktische konstituiert sich im Dass und Wie
des faktischen Bewusstseinslebens; die Faktengeschichte reduziert sich auf die
transzendentale Genesis des sinnstiftenden Bewusstseins.
5 Landgrebe, a.a.O. 39. R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D
6 Vgl. beispielhaft die kontroverse Argumentation bei Elisabeth Stroker, Zeit und
Geschichte in Husserls Phanomenologie. Zur Frage ihres Zusammenhangs, in: M E T A P H Y S I C S
E.W. Orth (Hrsg.), Zeit und Zeitlichkeit bei Husserl und Heidegger (Phanom-
enologische Forschungen 14) (Freiburg/Miinchen 1983), 111-137, sowie bei Kurt
Rainer Meist, Die Zeit der Geschichte. Probleme in Husserls transzendentaler
Begrundung einer Theorie der Geschichte, ebd. 58-110.
7 Diese erst spater (vgl. Hua VI, 189f.; Hua XV, 456f.; Hua IX, 294f.) ausfor-
mulierte Idee wird bereits 1913, in der Beilage X zu den Ideen II, im Begriff der
"realisierenden Selbstauffassung" antizipiert (Hua IV, 326f.). - Zwischen 1925
und 1928 bemerkt Husserl zu dieser Beilage in der Ausarbeitung der Ideen II
durch Ludwig Landgrebe: "Sehr wichtig!" (vgl. Hua IV, Textkrit. Anm., 417).
8 Das muss hier vorausgesetzt werden, weil nur bei einem Nachweis der Identitat
des personlich-mundanen mit dem transzendentalen Ich eine Diskussion des
Zusammenhangs des Faktums Geschichte mit der faktischen (mundanen)
Geschichte sinnvoll erscheinen kann. Sollte sich nur eine radikale Differenz
zwischen diesen beiden Ich-Bestimmungen zeigen lassen, wtirde es schwerfaUen,
von der transzendentalen Genesis zum mundanen Geschichtsbegriff zu gelan-
gen.
9 Ernst Wolfgang Orth nennt dies das "Manifestations-Apriori" des transzenden-
talen Subjekts: Husserls Begriff der cogitativen Typen und seine methodologische
Reichweite, in: Phanomenologie heute, hrsg. v. E. W. Orth (Phanomenologische
Forschungen Bd. 1) (Freiburg/Miinchen 1975), 138-167,157.

216
81

H U S S E R L ' S C O N C E P T O F T H E
" A B S O L U T E "

Rudolf Boehm

Source: This article translated by R. O. Elveton, in R. O. Elveton (ed.), The Phenomenology


of Husserl: Selected Critical Readings, Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1970, pp. 174-203.

The subject of dispute often remains unobserved in the dispute itself.


Husserl's most disputed thought doubtlessly was and is the thought of
"absolute consciousness," the basic thought of the Ideas which permitted
this philosophy to be characterized as idealism. The following considera-
tions serve as a clarification of this basic but seldom treated concept of the
absolute in Husserl's thought.

1. Absolute phenomena
The idea of phenomenology, which Husserl developed under this title in
the Five Lectures of 1907,1 is established or "motivated" by the need for a
metaphysics. Husserl's idea of metaphysics is the idea of a science of
beings in an absolute sense. "What is needed is a science of beings in an
absolute sense. This science, which we shall call metaphysics, grows out of
a 'critique' of the natural sciences which is based upon the insight into the
essence of knowledge and into the distinctive basic forms of knowledge-
objectivities (in the sense of the different fundamental correlations
between knowledge and its objectivity) won by the universal critique of
knowledge." 2 Husserl distinguishes the universal critique of knowledge (or
the theory of knowledge) from the critique of knowledge in the narrower
sense of a critique of the "natural" knowledge found in all "natural" sci-
ences. Phenomenology is to serve as the basis for a universal critique or
theory of knowledge. EstabUshed in this way, "the theory of knowledge
can become the critique of the natural knowledge found in aU natural sci-
ences. It will then enable us to interpret the results of the natural sciences
with respect to beings in a correct and definitive manner. For the epis-
temological perplexity into which natural (preepistemological) reflection
upon the possibilities of knowledge (upon a possible correctness of know-
ledge) has cast us is not only the cause of false views concerning the

219

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

essence of knowledge, but is also the source of basicaUy perverse (because reduced, is truly an absolute givenness."9 The sphere of absolute givenness
self-contradictory) interpretations of the being which comes to be known in is "the field of absolute phenomena." 10 This "is a field of absolute know-
the natural sciences. . . . Only epistemological reflection can produce the ledge which offers no opinions concerning the ego, the world, God, the
distinction between natural science and philosophy, and only through this mathematical manifolds or any other scientific objectivity; a knowledge
reflection is it clear that the natural sciences of being are not the ultimate which, therefore, is not dependent upon these objectivities, a knowledge
sciences of being. We require a science of beings in an absolute sense "3 which is to be accepted just as it presents itself whether one is a skeptic
We require a metaphysics, an ultimate science of being, a science of with regard to it or not." 11
beings in an absolute sense; for this purpose we require an epistemological If metaphysics is the science of beings in an absolute sense, the critique of
critique of the natural sciences; in order to provide a basis for this critique knowledge whose purpose is to awaken the need for this metaphysics is
of science we require a theory of knowledge or a universal critique of established apart from aU metaphysical goals as a pure phenomenology by
knowledge, and for this purpose we require phenomenology. means of a return to what is absolutely given. The exclusion of ah questions
Phenomenology stands in the service of a critique of knowledge whose relating to beings in an absolute sense and the return to the absolute phe-
ultimate goals are of a metaphysical order. As the critique of knowledge, nomena as the return to what is absolutely given amounts to one and the
however, phenomenology itself will first establish the need for a meta- same procedure - the phenomenological reduction. Accordingly, the
physics by showing that this need is established by a critique of the natural absolute of phenomenology is not the absolute of metaphysics. The absolute
knowledge found in the natural sciences. Precisely for this reason the of metaphysics is that which exists absolutely (das absolut Seiende).
theory of knowledge must establish itself by ignoring its metaphysical Phenomenology's absolute is that which is absolutely given. Its basic prin-
goals - and this means: as phenomenology. "If we ignore the metaphysical ciple runs: "absolute givenness is something ultimate,"12 and this is so
goals of the critique of knowledge, if we hold ourselves purely to the task because it divorces itself from the critique of the metaphysical goals of
of clarifying the essence of knowledge and of the objectivities which belong knowledge. This is how the idea of phenomenology is defined in Husserl's
to knowledge, then this is the phenomenology of knowledge and of the Five Lectures.
objectivities which belong to knowledge. .. ."4 Only a critique of the
natural knowledge found in all natural sciences which has this kind of
"pure" phenomenology as its basis is capable of bringing to light in a con- 2. Absolute being
vincing manner the fact that the natural sciences of being are not the ulti- Several years after presenting the idea of phenomenology, "the theory of
mate sciences of being and that we thoroughly require metaphysics as a knowledge and the metaphysics which, historically and by way of content,
science of beings in an absolute sense. is bound up with it,"13 and their reciprocal relationships, Husserl published
In the interest of estabUshing the metaphysical needs which lay at its a General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology as the first volume of his
very foundation, the philosophical discipline of phenomenology requires Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy.u
that phenomenology hold itself "purely to the task of clarifying the essence This work is incomplete. Not only was Husserl unable to make up his
of knowledge and the objectivities belonging to knowledge" entirely apart mind with respect to the publication of very extensive and partially com-
from all metaphysical goals, and this means apart from all questions con- pleted sketches (which were then edited from Husserl's posthumous works
cerning beings in an absolute sense. in 1952 and pubUshed as the second and third books of the Ideas, contain-
"Phenomenology designates a science, a connection of scientific disci- ing the Phenomenological Investigations of Constitution and discussions of
plines; at the same time, however, phenomenology primarily designates a Phenomenology and the Foundations of Science)?5 but the entire work is
method and a manner of thinking. .. ."5 Phenomenology's manner of also lacking its conclusion. A glance at Husserl's introduction to the first
thinking is defined by the method of an "epistemological" or "phenom- volume indicates that what are now the "second" and "third" volumes
enological" reduction. This signifies the "exclusion of the transcendent in correspond simply to what in the original plan was envisaged as being two
general as an existence which is not an evident givenness in the genuine parts of the second volume.16 "A third and concluding volume," according
sense, the absolute givenness of pure intuiting (Schauen)."6 The "phenom- to this plan, "wfll be dedicated to the idea of philosophy. Here we are to
enological sphere" is to be "the sphere of absolute clarity, the sphere of awaken the insight that true philosophy, which has as its idea that of real-
immanence in the genuine sense,"7 a "sphere of absolute givenness."8 It is izing absolute knowledge, is rooted in pure phenomenology, and this in
the reduction to the sphere of absolute givenness that establishes a pure such an earnest manner that the systematically rigorous establishing and
phenomenology, for "only the pure phenomenon, that which has been completion of this first of all philosophies is the unavoidable precondition

220 221
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

for every metaphysics and every other philosophy which would desire to foundation-laying function which had at one time been attributed to meta-
emerge as science."17 physics? It can be shown in Husserl's work that this does happen.
The third volume of the Ideas, which was to present the conclusion of In the Five Lectures pure phenomenology is contrasted with meta-
the entire work, was never written.18 Nevertheless, the "insight" of which physics insofar as pure phenomenology does not inquire into beings in an
Husserl speaks and which this volume was to have awakened in the reader absolute sense, but returns solely to what is absolutely given. In the first
must have been fixed clearly in his own mind and must have presented the volume of the Ideas the "absolutely given" (and it alone) is itself posited
basis for his conception of the work. This insight contained one (if not the) and appealed to as absolute being and absolute reality.
basic concept of his Ideas, a concept central not only to a pure phenom- In § 44 of the Ideas Husserl contrasts the mode of givenness of things
enology but also to a phenomenological philosophy. It is in terms of this and of the transcendent in general with the mode of givenness of the
idea that "pure" phenomenology can and must be understood as a basic immanent or experience. He states that "transcendent being in general, no
element of phenomenological philosophy insofar as this pure phenom- matter of what sort, understood as being for an ego, can be brought to
enology is itself the "first of aU philosophies" and proves itself to be "the givenness in a manner analogous to that mode in which a thing comes to
unavoidable precondition . . . for every metaphysics and every other philo- givenness, and thus only through appearances." 22 By contrast, "experience
sophy." does not present itself in this way. This implies that the perception of
In fact, the "insight" in question already appears to have, been experience is the pure intuiting of something which is given as being
expressed in the Five Lectures. The quotations above bear witness to this. absolute in this perception (or which can be given in this way) and is not
One of these quotations must be completed as follows: "phenomenology given as something which is identical throughout its modes of appearing,
designates a science . . . at the same time and above aU, however, phenom- i.e., through perspectival configurations."23 "We therefore conclude that
enology designates a method and a manner of thinking: the specifically while it belongs to the essence of givenness through appearances not to
philosophical manner of thinking, the specificaUy philosophical method."19 give any affair as absolute, but to give it only through partial presenta-
Here "pure" phenomenology is meant in the sense of the Ideas. This is a tions, it belongs to the very essence of immanent givenness just to give
"pure" phenomenology in the sense of the Idea of Phenomenology insofar something which is absolute and which cannot present itself perspectivally
as it holds itself "purely" to the task of returning to the field of absolute and partially."24
phenomena as the sphere of absolute giveness by ignoring all metaphysical This is the sole topic of the paragraph. It discusses the "merely phenom-
goals and by ignoring all questions concerning beings in an absolute sense. enal" givenness of the transcendent and the absolute givenness of the
This "method" and "manner of thinking" can and must be termed the immanent. The title of these paragraphs states, however: "The Merely
"specifically philosophical manner of thinking, the specifically philosophi- Phenomenal Being of the Transcendent and the Absolute Being of the
cal method" because "establishing and carrying out" a pure phenoniT Immanent." 25 Insofar as absolute givenness is thus spoken of directly as
enology in this sense is also "the unavoidable precondition for every absolute being, the Ideas' "Fundamental Phenomenological Observa-
metaphysics and every philosophy." tions," the section in which the passages quoted assume a central role,
It appears as though it is simply the formulation of this "insight" that is directly emerges as a metaphysics insofar as a "science of beings in an
sharpened in the Ideas. It is expressed in this formula: the first of all philo- absolute sense" can be called "metaphysics."
sophies must be a pure phenomenology: pure phenomenology is the First
Philosophy?0
3. Absolute positing
In truth, however, it is not simply a question here of a mere,formula. 21
The name "First Philosophy" is itself the oldest title for "metaphysics." A The direct claim that what is absolutely given is absolute being (presented
phenomenological philosophy in Husserl's sense is a philosophy for which in § 44 of the Ideas) permits us to conjecture that Husserl in general (in
the "First Philosophy" is not metaphysics but pure phenomenology. With accordance with basic principles as much as with self-evidence) makes
the estabUshing of a phenomenological philosophy, metaphysics not only givenness as such the "absolute" measure of being; that he speaks of
loses its title of being the "First Philosophy," but also loses its foundation- absolute givenness as being constitutive of absolute being because in prin-
laying function. It must then cease to be a metaphysics in the sense in ciple (although implicitly) he identifies being with givenness. The self-
which it has been thought of ever since the time of Aristotle. Yet does not evidence which this equation might have had for Husserl appears
Husserl's pure phenomenology itself become metaphysics precisely insofar questionable in view of the care with which the differentiation of the
as it takes on the title of the "First Philosophy," thereby taking over the "objects" of metaphysics from those of a pure phenomenology is carried

222 223
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "
out in the text from 1907. Taking into account the fact that the Five Lec-
tures was unknown to most readers of the Ideas, the "self-evidence" of this "pure" phenomenology) by absolute being nothing more would be under-
step must be something Husserl imagined. stood than absolute givenness. Absolute being would also mean nothing
But this claim is not simply an "immediate" pronouncement. It is other than an absolute (namely, an absolutely indubitable) "being for an
"mediated" by the concept of absolute positing. This occurs in § 46 of the ego."34 Attesting to this would be the fact that, for Husserl, the concept
Ideas. The "Fundamental Phenomenological Observations" 26 reach their which here contrasts with "absolute" is that of the simply "presumptive."
climax in these paragraphs. 27 They are entitled: "IndubitabiUty of Imma- These passages, however, "include premisses" for more radical "con-
nent Perception and Dubitability of Transcendent Perception." 28 The first sequences which we shall want to draw out from the possibility of separat-
lines state: "Every immanent perception necessarily guarantees the exist- ing in principle the entire natural world from the domain of consciousness,
ence of its object. If the reflecting apprehension is directed toward my the sphere of the being of experiences."35 These are drawn out by Husserl
experience I have apprehended an absolute self whose existence is in prin- in § 49 which presents "Absolute Consciousness as the Residuum of the
ciple undeniable, that is, the insight that it does not exist is in principle World-Nullification."36 Regarding "the results . . . we have obtained at the
impossible; it would be absurd to hold it possible that an experience given conclusion of the last chapter" (i.e., the results of § 46), Husserl now main-
in this way does not truly exist."29 Thus "I am simply compelled to state: I tains "that the being of consciousness, of every stream of experience in
exist, this life is, I live: cogito."30 general, is to be sure necessarily modified by nullifying the world of things,
but its ownmost existence is not thereby touched."37
"By contrast, it belongs . . . to the essence of the world of things that no
perception, no matter how perfect, gives us anything absolute in its With this statement Husserl clearly infers relationships of being from
domain, and essentially connected with this is the fact that every encom- positional relationships. If "transcendent being in general . . . understood
passing experience leaves open the possibility that what is given does not as being for an ego, can only be given in a manner analogous to the given-
exist, despite the continuing consciousness of its bodily self-givenness. It is ness of a thing, and therefore only through appearances," 38 then what
an essential law that the existence of things is never a necessity required by holds specifically for "thinglike existence" also holds for all being which is
their being given but is in a certain manner always contingent."31 not the being of consciousness: "its necessity is never a necessity required
"It is clear then . . . that everything which is present for me in the world by its being given."39 For it is possible for consciousness to exist without
of things, in the world of realities in general, is in principle only a presump- the necessity of positing the existence of any real being. Consciousness can
tive reality, and that on the contrary / myself, for whom these things or be posited absolutely without necessarily positing a real being along with
realities are there . . . or the actuality of my experience, is an absolute positing the being of consciousness. Therefore no real being, no being of a
reality given by means of an unconditioned and absolutely retractable kind such that it presents itself and exhibits itself through appearances in
positing."32 "In this absolute sphere there is no place for conflict, illusion, accordance with the consciousness that we have of it, is necessary for the
and being-otherwise. It is a sphere of absolute positings."33 being of consciousness (consciousness in the widest sense as the stream of
experience).
The objects of immanent perception are given-absolutely. But imma-
nent perception guarantees that the being of that which comes to absolute "Immanent being is therefore doubtlessly absolute being in this sense:
givenness in this perception is an absolutely indubitable being. Absolute that in principle nulla 're' indiget ad existendum."40
givenness thereby necessarily requires (and requires as a necessity) the The statement: "Therefore no real being is necessary for the being of
absolute positing of that which is absolutely given as existing. The sphere consciousness" is ambiguous. Indeed, the move asserting the absolute
of absolute givenness is a "sphere of absolute positings." being of consciousness rests upon this ambiguity. Real being, understood
Here it could appear as if the formula: "absolute reality - given by as being for an ego, is never to be posited as necessary: it neither can nor
means of an unconditioned and absolutely unretractable positing" - in the must come to be given to consciousness or come to be posited by con-
end exhaustively defines Husserl's concept of absolute being or absolute sciousness as necessary being. From this Husserl concludes: no real being
reaUty. For actuaUy the expression "absolute being" does not designate a is itself necessary for the being of consciousness.
being which exists in the absolute sense or the mode of being of something Yet Husserl's meaning is clear. Nothing can be posited absolutely, and
which is absolute in the metaphysical sense, but simply designates a posi- hence nothing can come to absolute givenness (which is required by
tional-modality. "Existing absolutely" would then signify nothing other absolute positing), whose very being would not itself be absolute. What-
than "being absolutely indubitable." Absolute givenness would then not ever is given absolutely and, accordingly, whatever requires that it be
be posited as absolute being, but (at least within the framework of a posited absolutely, thereby proves itself to be absolute being. Absolute
being is the necessary foundation for absolute givenness.

224
225
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

The basis for this thought lies in the concept of "absolute being" which can be understood which clearly needs nothing else, namely, God. We per-
Husserl here sets forth. This concept is expressed in the form: immanent ceive that all other things can exist only by the help of the concourse of
being is absolute being insofar as absolute being is the being of something God." 42 Descartes' definition of substance essentially includes the thesis
which "in principle nulla 're' indiget ad existendum." The Latin phrase that God alone is substance.
Husserl employs in this definition of absolute being originates in One is inclined to accept the implication that, in the end, Husserl's defi-
Descartes' definition of substance: "By substance, we can understand nition of absolute being similarly implies the assertion of the absolute
nothing else than a thing which so exists that it needs no other thing in being of consciousness and of consciousness alone. Furthermore, since his
order to exist."41 Quite apart from the fact that Husserl is not speaking of concept of absolute being is the same as Descartes' idea of substance, it is
"substance," his formula would be translated in the following way: impUed that Husserl conceives of consciousness as being the sole sub-
absolute being is being which "in principle requires no other being for its
stance. Since he posits absolute consciousness as the sole substance, this
existence."
absolute consciousness is analogous to God for Husserl.
To the extent that an absolute being is now a being such that it can exist Nevertheless, Descartes proceeds further: "That is why the word sub-
without being "conditioned" in its being by some other being, then clearly stance does not pertain univoce to God and to other things, as they say in
only an absolute being in this sense can be "posited unconditionaUy" on the schools, that is, no common signification for this appellation which wfll
the basis of its coming to "absolute givenness." In principle, the possibility apply equally to God and to them can be distinctly understood." 43 We
of absolute givenness has its foundation in absolute being: absolute being must note a corresponding ambiguity in Husserl's concept of absolute
establishes the possibility of absolute givenness. being, an ambiguity which is attested to by the following: God, in Husserl's
view, is "an 'absolute' in an entirely different sense than the absolute of con-
4. Absolute consciousness sciousness."4*
If the being of God can be thought of a possibility, the definition of
Of course, Husserl's modified Cartesian formula for "absolute being" can absolute being we are now discussing directly sets forth a limited concept
be interpreted this way: by placing the word "re" in quotation marks of absolute being; if by "res" (in quotation marks) we mean solely real
("nulla 're' indiget ad existendum") Husserl signifies that he does not being in the narrow sense of the Ideas, "immanent being" would be
understand this word in Descartes' sense (Husserl does not name the "absolute being only in the sense that it in principle nulla 're' indiget ad
being defined as possessing absolute being a "thing"), but that he under- existendum." Consciousness would be absolute being only insofar as it
stands it in his own and more restricted sense. With this interpretation, does not require being sustained (concursus) by real being in order to exist
however, his definition of absolute being not only presupposes his termino- - although it might indeed require being sustained by another being "and
logical distinction between "consciousness" and "reaUty," but it also have its source in what is ultimately and truly absolute." 45
implies the thesis that consciousness alone is absolute being. Or, it directly
Perhaps the ambiguity of the definition of absolute being concentrated
places this distinction in question and for this reason is reduced to intro-
in the word "res" as set off by quotation marks was intended by Husserl.
ducing another distinction between consciousness, caUed absolute being,
The statement that "immanent being is thus doubtlessly absolute being
and real being. In any case, Husserl's stated definition of absolute being
in the sense that it in principle nulla 're' indiget ad existendum" does not at
can be understood as being modeled upon the presupposed proof of the
aU prejudice the possibility that in addition to consciousness reality is also
absoluteness of consciousness' being: that consciousness requires no other
absolute being. Neither the definition of absolute being nor the thesis that
being for its existence means that it requires no real being (in Husserl's
consciousness is absolute being allows the conclusion that real being is not
sense) for its existence. Formulated in this way, the definition impUes the
absolute being. To be sure, the following occurs immediately after the
further assumption that aU being part from the being of consciousness of
real being, or the definition establishes a possibly more limited concept of statement quoted above.
"absolute being." "On the other hand the world of transcendent 'res' is referable without
qualification to consciousness, and not simply to a logically conceived con-
In this connection, and with particular reference to the already men- sciousness, but to an actual consciousness."46 Here Husserl asserts the non-
tioned possibiUty that Husserl's "nominal definition" of absolute being absolute, purely relative being of reality. But this assertion is not a
already includes his thesis that only the being of consciousness is absolute, consequence of the preceding statement from which it is separated by the
we must not forget that, after the cited definition of "substance," opening phrase "on the other hand."
Descartes immediately continues: "And in fact only one single substance The importance of the relationships encountered in this connection

226 227

^ _
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

rests upon two considerations: first, the relativization of reality - indeed, And finally: "To identify the totality of realities . . . with the totality of
making it relative to absolute consciousness - radically strengthens the being, thereby making the former absolute, is nonsensical. An absolute
absoluteness of absolute consciousness; and, second, the concept of the reality is as valid as a round square."50
absolute being of consciousness does not in itself require this relativity of The basis for the statement that the being of reality is not absolute but
the being of "reaUty." "In themselves," according to Husserl's concept, simply relative is not contained in the fact that consciousness has already
immanent consciousness and transcendent real being could exist next to proven itself to be "the" absolute being, but in the meaning of real being or
each other as two modes of absolute being and could even possibly be sub- in the essence of reality itself: "Reality . . . essentially lacks (in our strong
ordinate to God as the "ultimately and truly absolute," just as in Descartes sense) independence." "To identify the totality of realities . . . with the
res cogitans and res extensa exist as two substances subordinate to the totality of being" is not only false but is also nonsensical to the extent that
"infinite" substance of God. such an identification implies making real being absolute. The thought of
That reality, the being of things, real being, transcendent being in an absolute being of things and realities runs counter to the meaning of the
general, is truly not absolute but relative, and indeed relative to conscious- being of things and reaUties. The concept of an "absolute reality" is not a
ness, is maintained by Husserl in certain well-known and very pointed for- concept at all.
mulations which, quite understandably, caused a sensation among both Insofar as the absoluteness of absolute being, that is, absolute con-
foUowers and opponents of "phenomenology" much more than did the sciousness, does not remain untouched by the relationship in which reality
statements concerning "absolute consciousness." The most important pas- stands to absolute consciousness, we must investigate Husserl's interpreta-
sages are found in the second part of § 49, in the beginning of § 50, and in tion of the meaning of real being over and against which the idea of an
the first of the concluding summarizing paragraphs (§ 55) of the third absolute reality is nonsensical.
chapter of the "Fundamental Phenomenological Observations."
Throughout it is understood that the titles "reality" and "conscious-
ness" do not serve to distinguish two kinds of absolute being: "Between 5. Givenness and being
consciousness and reality there yawns a veritable abyss of meaning. Here a The discussion required to establish the thesis that something real "is in an
being which manifests itself perspectivally and which is never to be given absolute sense nothing at aU" is found in § 43 of the Ideas; hence in those
absolutely, a purely contingent and relative being; there a necessary and paragraphs immediately preceding the ones we have discussed up to this
absolute being which in principle cannot be given perspectivally through point. This part is entitled: "Clarification of a Basic Mistake."51 The essen-
appearances." 47 - tial content of these paragraphs is found in the first fifteen lines, which
"The entire spatio-temporal world within which man includes himself and follow.
the human ego as subordinate individual reaUties, is, according to its very "It is therefore a basic mistake to think that perception (and, in their
meaning, simply intentional being, a being which therefore has the merely own special way, every other kind of intuition of the thing) does not
secondary, relative meaning of a being for a consciousness. It is a being which encounter the thing itself; that the thing is not given to us in itself and in
consciousness posits in its own experiences, which in principle is only the terms of its in-itselfness. To every being there belongs in principle the pos-
identical element which is intuitable and determinable by motivated mani- sibility of intuiting it as it really is, and particularly of perceiving it in an
folds of experience, and which, above and beyond this, is nothing at aU."48 adequate perception which gives us the corporeal thing itself without any
"Thus the common meaning of talk about being is inverted. The being mediation through 'appearances.' God, the subject of absolutely perfect
which for us is first is in itself second, i.e., it is what it is only in 'relation' to knowledge and therefore also of every possible adequate perception, natu-
the being which is first. Not as if a blind order of laws had made things in rally possesses what is denied to us finite beings: the perception of things
such a way that the ordo et connexio rerum must direct itself in accordance in themselves.
with the ordo et connexio idearum. Reality, the reality of individual things "But this view is nonsensical. It implies that there is no essential dif-
as weU as the reality of the entire world, essentially lacks (in our strong ference between transcendent and immanent; that in the postulated divine
sense) independence. Reality is not in itself something absolute whose intuition a spatial thing is a real constituent (and therefore an experience)
bond with some other being is only secondary; it is, in the sense of being belonging with other experiences to the divine stream of consciousness
absolute, nothing at all; it has no 'absolute essence,' but the essentially of and stream of experience." 52
something which in principle is only intentional, only consciously known, If these lines actually seem to contain the entire explanation of
presented, appearing."49 Husserl's view that real being is "a being which is posited by consciousness

228 229
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

in its experience, and which in principle is only the identical element which "a basic mistake to think that perception (and, in their own special way,
can be intuited and determined by motivated manifolds of experience and every other kind of intuition of the thing) does not encounter the thing
is nothing at all above and beyond this," this information is at first disap- itself; that the thing is not given to us in itself and in terms of its in-
pointing. These lines appear to lead us back to the "purely phenomenolog- itselfness."55 What is the source of this mistake? On the one hand, it
ical" questions of givenness, and, more specifically, back to the question clearly lies in establishing the fact (which Husserl does not dispute but
concerning the possibility of reality's being given absolutely in terms of rather stresses) that things and realities in general "are not given to us" in
adequate perceivability. And yet is not the question concerning the absolute givenness; on the other hand, however, it also has its source in a
absolute being of the real contained precisely in the question whether an more fundamental mistake in principle which is concealed within the
absolute being would be conceivable even where absolute givenness is above-mentioned "fact": "To every being there belongs in principle the
absent? In maintaining the absolute being of consciousness, Husserl, on possibility of intuiting it as it really is and particularly of perceiving it in an
the contrary, seems simply to presuppose that the absolute being of what adequate perception which gives us the corporeal thing itself without any
is given absolutely is subordinate to absolute givenness. mediation through 'appearances'."56 From this mistake in principle and
The text of § 43 does not, however, only speak of the factual absence of from the above-mentioned "fact" the following conclusion results: it is
reality's absolute givenness in "our" experience, but also speaks of the simply "an accidental feature of 'our human constitution'" which, in turn,
impossibility in principle of an absolute givenness of beings whose mode of does not at all concern the being-in-itself of things, "that 'our' perception
being is that of reality. However, and we have already estabUshed that this can only encounter things themselves through their perspectival configura-
is Husserl's conviction, absolute being establishes in principle the possibil- tions."57 The impossibility of our having things given to us absolutely, the
ity of absolute givenness. If it can be now shown that the possibility of impossibility of our adequately perceiving them, lies in the imperfect con-
absolute givenness is in principle excluded for real being as such, real stitution of our knowledge-capacity as "finite" beings. "God, the subject of
being is not to be thought of as absolute, and the thought of an absolute absolutely perfect knowledge and therefore also of every possible adeq-
being of things and realities is, as Husserl maintains, contrary to the very uate perception, naturally possesses what is denied to us finite beings, the
meaning of the being of things. perception of things in themselves."58 According to this interpretation, the
By relying upon the results of his preceding analyses, Husserl can absence of the real's absolute givenness as this is experienced by us would
produce the required proof in a few brief words. Yet the task of conduct- not reside in the lack of absolute being on the part of things and realities,
ing this proof is connected with that of "clarifying a basic mistake." What but merely in the deficient constitution of ourselves as beings who
mistake? experience things in a "finite" manner.
Husserl is at the point of establishing the assertion that by its very Husserl clearly reproaches Kant with having made the mistake charac-
essence real being cannot be absolute being by proving that in principle the terized here even though he does not mention him by name.59 The criti-
mode of being which belongs to reality excludes the possibility of a real cism of Kant impUed by the Ideas' § 43 in turn implies a basic
thing's ever being given absolutely: he thereby conceives "the possibility in interpretation of the Critique of Pure Reason which Husserl himself had
principle of absolute givenness" as the measure of absolute being. The not carried out, but which agrees with the "exposition of the Critique of
basic mistake, however, to which he simultaneously turns his attention, is, Pure Reason as laying the foundation for metaphysics" initiated by Hei-
paradoxically enough, the mistaken opinion that "every being has in prin- degger in his book (pubUshed in 1929), Kant and the Problem of Meta-
ciple the possibility" of being given absolutely, and this clearly means that physics?0 This connection appears to us to be important for the history of
the possibility of absolute givenness belongs to every being as a principle philosophy.
because it belongs to being as such. Accordingly, absolute givenness as a The view that "to every being there belongs in principle the possibility"
"possibility in principle" belongs to "beings in an absolute sense" and yet of its absolute givenness, and that this possibiUty therefore belongs to
not at all as a "possibiUty in principle" to beings as such. beings as such, is clarified by Husserl as a "mistake in principle" on the
Husserl's thesis that real being is "a being which consciousness posits in basis of the presuppositions won in providing the demonstration that this
its own experiences and which in principle is only the identical element postulate conflicts with the very meaning of the being of beings whose
which can be intuited and determined by motivated manifolds of mode of existence is that of reality. The requirement of the possibility in
experience and is nothing at aU above and beyond this"53 is based upon the principle of an absolute givenness of the real is the requirement of the pos-
conviction that "the perception of things . . . makes present and appre- sibiUty in principle of its adequate perceivability. Only immanent percep-
hends something itself in its corporeal presence." 54 Hence, for Husserl, it is tion, however, can be an adequate perception, for only in "the case of an

230 231
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "

immanently directed, or, more succinctly, an immanent perception (the so- generally, the phrase "in principle" is used in a rigorous sense with refer-
called 'inner' perception) do perception and perceived essentially constitute ence to the highest, and therefore the most radical, essential universaUties
an unmediated unity, the unity of an individual concrete cogitatio. Here or essential necessities."67 Accordingly, one of the highest and most radical
perception contains its object within itself in such a way that it can be sep- essential necessities must correspond to the difference in principle
arated from it only by abstraction and only as a moment which by its very between the modes of being of consciousness and reaUty. And yet, when
essence cannot be independent."61 The requirement of the possibility in this difference is maintained as an essential necessity, it appears to dissolve
principle of an absolute givenness of the real is thus equivalent to assum- itself through its own consequences.
ing the possibility of converting beings existing in the mode of reality to As we have seen, from these consequences the fact emerges that the
beings existing in the mode of experiences. This runs counter to the "essential difference" between the modes of being of consciousness and
meaning of the being of beings whose mode of existence is that of reality. reality, of the immanent and the transcendent, is none other than the dif-
The assumption of an actual possibility in principle of absolute givenness ference between absolute being and a being which is simply relative to
for beings as such is in truth ultimately equivalent (paradoxically enough) absolute being. That is, real being "is what it is only in 'relation' to"68 the
to a principal misconstrual, if not an actual denial, of the independent absolute being of consciousness. This "relation" is not a fortuitous occur-
,1 mode of existence of the real as a being which is in principle "transcend- rence, but is itself an essential necessity for the being of the real. In § 49
ent" and incapable of being dissolved into "immanence." Husserl himself states: "Thus we see that consciousness (inner experience)
and real being are not coordinate modes of being Uving peacefully next to
each other and occasionally 'relating' to each other or being 'connected'
6. The transcendent and the transcendental absolute
with each other." 69 As a result, it becomes a question as to what meaning
In accordance with the essential meaning of its being, real being in prin- the assertion of a difference in principle between consciousness and reality
ciple excludes the possibility of its absolute givenness. Consequently, real could have. If real being has "the essentiaUty of something which" is "in
being is essentially not absolute being. "Reality is not in itself something principle only intentional, only consciously known, presented, appear-
t." absolute whose bond with some other being is only secondary, but is in the ing,"70 clearly it is merely a mode of being which is subordinate to the
sense of being absolute nothing at all. It has no 'absolute essence'; it has absolute being of consciousness. Real being itself is only in a relative
the essentiality of something which in principle is only intentional, only sense. In this context, real being would in general not be an independent
consciously known, presented, appearing." 62 Not only is consciousness mode of being, but, in accordance with the purely limited sense of its
absolute being, but also consciousness alone is absolute being. By contrast, being, would be ultimately reduced to a relative moment within the one
real being is "a being which merely has the secondary, relative meaning of single totality of absolute consciousness, or consciousness and reality
being for a consciousness."63 "ReaUty, the reality of the individual thing as would ultimately form one single whole which would be the whole of
well as that of the entire world, essentially lacks (in our strong sense) absolute being itself, and that actually means the whole of absolute con-
independence." 64 Real being "in principle" is "being which is relative to sciousness. And yet: "To be connected in the true sense, to form a whole,
consciousness."65 can apply only to what is essentially related, each part having its own
The paradox which we have already touched upon several times is this: essence and on the same lines as the other." 71 Husserl continues with this
Husserl denies the absolute being of the real on the basis of affirming the sentence after he has established that "consciousness (inner experience)
independent mode of existence of the real as the "being-in-itself" of the and real being are not coordinate modes of being. . . . " Husserl himself
transcendent which in principle excludes the possibiUty of its absolute seems to be on the verge of canceling the assertion concerning the "dif-
givenness. The "independent" essence of the real, rooted in the being-in- ference in principle between the modes of being of consciousness and
itself of things, excludes in principle the "independence" of reaUty. In reaUty," for he raises the question: "Can the unity of a whole be unified
Husserl's words: "To the thing as such, to every genuine reality . . . belongs other than through the essence proper to its parts, and which must accord-
in essence and 'in principle' the inability to be perceived immanently and ingly have some community of essence instead of essential
the inability in general to be found within the system of experience. Thus heterogeneity?" 72
the thing itself, simply as such, is transcendent. Disclosed therein is the dif- Yet, surprisingly enough, we must affirm the fact that Husserl denies
ference in principle between modes of being, the most crucial difference just this formation of a "whole" of absolute being out of consciousness and
there is: that between consciousness and reality."66 In a footnote to the reality, and that he furthermore denies any "community of essence"
phrase 'in principle,' Husserl further emphasizes: "Here, as in this work between consciousness and reality. "Only what is essentially related can

232 233
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "
form a whole in the true sense, each part having its own essence and on this absolute being. Such a thought, however, would contain the very
the same lines as the other. Both immanent or absolute being and opposite of what Husserl clearly means, for this would constitute the
transcendent being are indeed termed 'being' (seiend) or 'object,' and each thought of an absolutely unequivocal concept of being - the thought of an
has its objective determination of content. It is evident, however, that what absolute being which, to be sure, would be subject to a relative "phenom-
on either side goes by the name of object and objective determination are enal" influence, but one which would be incapable of compromising not
similar only in terms of empty logical categories. Between consciousness simply the one and only absolute, but also the absolutely unique meaning
and reaUty yawns a veritable abyss of meaning. Here a perspectival, never of being which is construed as the being of the absolute.
absolutely given, merely contingent and relative being; there a necessary
and absolute being "73 Thus Husserl's most extreme formulation: a thing, real being in general,
"is in the absolute sense nothing at all, it has no 'absolute essence',"
What does Husserl's insistence upon the "heterogeneity in principle" cannot mean that reality has "absolutely" no true being at all. It can only
between the essence of the real and the essence of immanent experiences mean that reality is not to be understood in an absolute sense, but in terms
signify? What is the meaning of this steadfast holding to the "difference in of the meaning of being which uniquely belongs to it. To think of measur-
principle" between these two modes of being? Finally, what is the signific- ing the being of things and of the real, no matter in what fashion, in terms
ance of this mention of a "veritable abyss" between the meaning of of absolute being is senseless and absurd.
absolute being and the meaning of that being which is simply relative to
Formerly, it could have been thought that a "dissolution" (Aufhebung)
the former when it appears to be the case that real being, as purely rela-
of reality into the absolute would show itself as capable of being carried
tive, can only establish and draw its ownmost and complete meaning of
out in the form of the phenomenological reduction, a reduction where the
being from the absolute being which is consciousness?
"transcendent" essence of reality would remain directly preserved insofar
Certainly there is a difference between absolute and relative being. as it would be equally "suspended" within the absolute and - thus perish-
Descartes agrees with the scholastic doctrine concerning the equivocal ing within the absolute - would preserve the abysslike differentiation of
nature of the concept of substance in discussions of God's "infinite" sub- the meaning of its being from being in the absolute sense. Thus the dif-
stance and "finite" substances. Accordingly, Husserl's theory of the "abyss ference in principle between the modes of being of consciousness and
of meaning" could be taken as an indication of the concept of being's reality, and the equally essential relativity of aU reaUty to the absolute
ambiguity in its application to absolute being or consciousness on the one being of consciousness as its absolute ground, would be made intelligible
hand, and to purely relative or real being on the other. in one stroke, for the absolute " . . . is the ground into which (reaUty) has
Yet Descartes will say that ultimately God alone-is truly substance (or been swallowed up."75 At the same time, reality would be understood as
"absolute being" in Husserl's sense). That is, Descartes' theory of the having "the absolute for its abyss (Abgrund), and as also having the
"abyss of meaning" between God and finite things in the concept of sub- absolute for its ground (Grund)."76 In this case, absolute being itself - as
stance corresponds to the HusserUan distinction between the "absolute of the necessary ground which is the foundation for (zugrunde liegt) all
consciousness" and an "ultimate and true absolute" which would be "an givenness of transcendent being as a givenness which is always only rela-
'absolute' in a totally different sense."74 If Husserl's theory of an abysslike tive - would be the necessary ground for the reality of that "abyss of
difference between the meaning of consciousness' being and the being of meaning" into which reality would perish through the reduction to what is
reality is to be brought into strict analogy with Descartes' emphasis upon absolutely given.
the equivocal nature of the concept of substance, and, if, accordingly, it is
Such an Hegelian interpretation of the basic relation between the "tran-
also to be understood in terms of Husserl's own further distinction
scendental absolute" and transcendent reality as Husserl views it appears
between absolute consciousness and God, then this would mean that for
to be justified insofar as Husserl himself, directly after the enactment of
Husserl an "abyss of meaning" would not only hold between the being of
the phenomenological reduction in § 50 of the Ideas, explicitly states that
consciousness which, apart from God, is alone truly absolute, and the
"We have lost literally nothing, but have won the whole of absolute being
being of reality which is ultimately not truly absolute, but that it would
which, properly understood, contains aU worldly transcendences within
also hold between that which is alone true being (which would be absolute
itself, 'constituting' them within itself."77 The word "literally" in the
being), and that which, as the simply relative, is not truly being. That is,
phrase, "lost literally nothing," can in this connection mean only that we
viewed as an analogy to the Scholastic-Cartesian doctrine, Husserl's thesis
have lost nothing "in the absolute sense." Only in the absolute sense is real
signifies that being as such would be absolute being (and therefore con-
being not lost through the reduction to consciousness, since, "in the
sciousness), and that in truth, therefore, there would be nothing outside of
absolute sense," it is itself "nothing at aU." The view that even in some

234 235
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "
"postulated divine intuition a spatial thing is a real constituent of
experience, and is therefore itself an experience belonging with other transcendental. The basic relation between absolute being or consciousness
experiences to the divine stream of consciousness and experiences" is and real being (which is simply relative to consciousness) is a fundamental
expressly labeled by Husserl as nonsensical. "This view, however, is non- one insofar as a foundation is a necessary basis or an indispensable and
sensical" insofar as " . . . it implies . . . that there would be no essential dif- essential "condition for the possibility" of the Being of a being; not,
ference between transcendence and immanence." 78 This essential however, that it is thereby a "sufficient reason" or an "efficient cause" of
difference, however, estabUshes "the separability in principle of the entire the Being of this being. Here Husserl's observations concerning the basic
natural world from the domain of consciousness, or the realm of the being relation between "Consciousness and Natural ReaUty"85 are indeed "Fun-
belonging to experience,"79 for "the being of consciousness ... is not damental Observations" 86 in this sense of "foundation." In a fundamental
touched in its ownmost existence ...by nullifying the world of things."80 relation where something is posited in relation to, and is to be necessarily
Accordingly, we can first truly win absolute being by conceiving of a pos- referred to, a ground, and the requisite ground is indifferent to that which
sible "nullification of the world of things." It is only here that the requires it as a ground and does not itself require what it serves to ground
absolutely given first truly comes to absolute givenness, and in the final for its own emergence, is rooted the possibiUty of a relation of conflict.
analysis absolute being is preeminently what it is according to its essential The "fundamental observation" is characteristic of a transcendental
possibility of absolute givenness. philosophy. The transcendental itself is nothing more than something fun-
With Husserl, real being, so to speak, is only "imperfectly dissolved damental which everything that is requires simply in order to be, or in
(aufgehoben)" into the absolute, for "no real being ... is necessary for the order to be capable of being, without the transcendental ground of all
being of consciousness itself."61 The being of things - of the real in general being and all givenness thereby constituting more than an "absolutely"
- is indifferent to the being of consciousness in an absolute sense, just as, necessary "condition for the possibility of —," that is, without this con-
conversely, the meaning of absolute being, in possessing the possibility in dition as such also becoming the sufficient or efficient cause for all being
principle of absolute givenness, is totally foreign to the being of reality: and givenness. A transcendental ground as such is simply a foundation,
"Between consciousness and reality there yawns a veritable abyss of even though it is a transcendental foundation.
meaning." Yet: "On the other hand, the world of transcendent 'res' is refer-
able without qualification to consciousness. .. ."82 By modifying Heideg- 7. The transcendental absolute and the "ultimate"
ger's statement "that Being indeed comes-to-presence without beings, but transcendent absolute
a being never is without Being,"83 Husserl's thought can be reduced to this
formula: "absolute being (consciousness) indeed comes-to-presence Consciousness at first appears as an absolute being in a substantial sense,
(namely, is essentially able to be) without things, but a thing never is in which terms, and by way of exhibiting the possibility in principle of its
without absolute being (the being of consciousness)." This (in the strict absolute givenness, it "requires in principle no other being for its exist-
sense of the word) foundational-problematic relation between the absolute ence." This is how we translated the Cartesian formula employed by
being of consciousness and the being of reaUty as the being of things is Husserl in the sentence "Immanent being is therefore doubtlessly absolute
what occasions Husserl to state: "Thus we see that consciousness (inner being in this sense: that in principle nulla 're' indiget ad existendum." Con-
experience) and real being are not coordinate ways of being, Uving peace- sidered more closely, this formula leaves open the possibiUty that imma-
fully next to each other. .. ."84 The opposition between the "absolute" nent being or consciousness would require "no other being for its
relatedness of reality to absolute consciousness and the "absolute" indif- existence" merely in a limited sense, a sense which could be conditioned
ference of the absolute with regard to the meaning of the being of reality - by the use of the word "res" in place of the word "being."
or the entanglement of indissoluble relation (of reality to the absolute) This absolute and "substantial" being of consciousness was conceived of
and abysslike difference in meaning - create a fundamental conflict within as being independent of some "second" being. It is in fact this "second"
the basic relation of the one mode of being to the other. Corresponding to being which is spoken of in the sentence which directly follows: "On the
this situation are Husserl's "contradictory" assertions, which both deny the other hand, the world of transcendent 'res' is referable without qualifica-
"independence" of reality in principle and steadfastly affirm its "hetero- tion to consciousness, and not simply to a logically conceived conscious-
geneity" in principle over and against the absolute. ness, but to an actual consciousness."87
The basic relation which holds between consciousness and reality can The relativity of all real being to the "substantial" absolute being which
now be characterized in two words: as one which is both fundamental and consciousness already is "in itself" must, we had stated, also serve to
confirm more deeply the absoluteness of absolute consciousness. The

236
237
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "
notion employed here is that consciousness is not only absolute being in a edly indicates and explicitly states that the "transcendental 'absolute'"
"substantial" sense, but is also a transcendental absolute. The meaning of also "constitutes itself in a certain profound and entirely unique sense and
this concept has already been given by our last considerations. Conscious-
. . . has its original source in what is ultimately and truly absolute." Is it
ness is the transcendental absolute insofar as no being, no real being, can
therefore "ultimately" not a "true absolute" in the substantial sense
exist or can be given without the foundation of this "in itself" substantial
granted it at the beginning? If it is not absolute in this sense, how then is it
absolute being.
possible for it to be absolutely given? In this case, how is a phenomenolog-
In an extreme formulation, this signifies that nothing could be if there ical reduction to the "absolute" givenness of this transcendental conscious-
were no absolute consciousness. This does not mean, however, that every- ness possible? By explicitly "disconnecting" the being of God as a
thing which is exists by means of absolute consciousness. Formulated still "transcendent" absolute being? In fact: how does Husserl motivate the
more extremely (a formulation so extreme that its understanding is totally disconnection and reduction enacted here? "We naturally extend the phe-
dependent upon understanding all that has been said above), we could say: nomenological reduction to include this 'absolute' and this 'transcendent.'
there is nothing without absolute consciousness, although there is also It should remain disconnected from the new field of investigation which
nothing with absolute consciousness alone. Namely, consciousness is a tran- we are to institute insofar as this is to be a field of pure consciousness
scendental absolute insofar as it is the "absolutely" necessary foundation itself."89 We italicize: "It should ...": must and can it be disconnected?
for all other (real) being. But by no means does - or can - all other being Why should it be disconnected? " . . . All this does not concern us further.
exist if there is simply absolute consciousness. I speak of "ability to exist" Our immediate aim concerns not theology but phenomenology. .. ."90 Is
in this respect with reference to the heterogeneity in principle of real being this truly a phenomenological reduction, or is it finally only a "convenient"
in opposition to the simply fundamental and essential condition of tran- abstraction?
scendentally absolute consciousness. Transcendental consciousness is not
Husserl now informs us that the return to "the theological principle,
an absolute being such that it is able to create all other (real) being from
which could perhaps be rationally assumed," could also be established on
the being that is its own.
the side of consciousness by means of a "facticity": "the facticity in the
Corresponding with this is the fact that Husserl's concept of absolute given order of the course of consciousness in its differentiation into indi-
consciousness as the transcendental "absolute" clearly deepens the vidual forms and the teleology immanent within them (could) provide the
absolute sense of the "in itself"-purely substantial absolute being of con- occasion for raising the question concerning the ground of this same
sciousness, but at the same time also decisively limits it: "The transcenden- order" 91 - an order which moreover is clearly conditioned by the facticity
tal 'absolute' which we have exposed through the reductions is in truth not of real being. Accordingly, one could perhaps think that transcendental
ultimate; it is something which constitutes itself in a certain profound and consciousness is essentially an absolute being which, in a certain manner,
entirely unique sense and which has its original source in what is ulti- existed factually - as if it were entangled in reality - a manner of existing
mately and truly absolute." 88 In terms of what is "ultimately absolute," which could only be an "outflow" from an "original source in what is ulti-
absolute consciousness, as the simply transcendental absolute, is itself only mately and truly absolute," but which yet could be said to retain posses-
an "absolute" in quotation marks. Thus characterized, the fundamental sion of the possibility in principle of its absolute givenness. Here again,
delimiting of the absolute sense of the being of transcendental conscious- however, intrudes the "abysslike" ("abgriindige") thought that in principle
ness serves as motivation for Husserl's theological ideas concerning the ' the nullification of the world would be the condition for actualizing this
"ultimate and true absolute" here referred to. The idea of God as the idea possibility and therewith a condition for displaying the absolute essence of
of the "ultimate and true absolute" is motivated by the idea of a "sufficient consciousness. Hence we return to our first question concerning the rela-
cause" for the being of everything which, in general, factually exists. tionship of absolute consciousness to the absolute being of God.
From this point on, however, the paths taken by Husserl (or those On the other hand, God, the "ultimate and true absolute," is the
which he could have taken) in the Ideas are lost in obscurity. "'Absolute' and 'Transcendent'" 92 in opposition to the absolute being
How are "both" absolutes, the transcendental absolute and the ultimate which, as consciousness, is "immanent being" as such. Hence "after aban-
and true absolute, absolute consciousness and God, related? The idea of doning the natural world we come up against yet another transcendence
an ultimate and true absolute (correctly termed "God") above and beyond which is not . . . immediately given in connection with the reduced con-
transcendental consciousness seems to me to be estabUshed to the extent sciousness, but which comes to be known in a highly mediated form. .. ."93
that real being appears to be only inadequately grounded in the transcen- Nevertheless, if it is to be a being which is truly absolute, the being of God
dental absolute (consciousness) to which it is relative. Yet Husserl repeat- clearly cannot exclude in principle the possibility of its absolute givenness:

238 239

1
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
HUSSERL'S C O N C E P T OF T H E " A B S O L U T E "
"thus the theological principle which could be rationally assumed . . . Notes
cannot for essential reasons be accepted as a transcendence in the sense of
the world. ... The ordering principle of the absolute must be found in the 1 Husserliana, II, ed. H. L. Van Breda. [English translation by Alston and
Nakhnikian, The Idea of Phenomenology (The Hauge: Martinus Nijhoff,
absolute itself and in pure and absolute reflection. In other words, since a 1964).-ED.]
mundane God is evidently impossible, and since on the other hand the 2 Ibid., p. 23.
immanence of God in absolute consciousness cannot be grasped as the 3 Ibid, pp. 22f.
immanence of being as experience ..., there must be in the absolute 4 Ibid., p. 23.
stream of consciousness and its infinities other ways of manifesting the 5 Ibid.
transcendent than the constituting of thinglike realities as unities of har- 6 Ibid., p. 9.
7 Ibid, p. 10.
monious appearances. .. ."94 These suggestions of Husserl's are clearly 8 Ibid., p. 14.
estabUshed in their contexts, but are still purely postulative. Yet the 9 Ibid, p. 1.
formulation of these postulates bypasses the (in the strict sense) truly fun- 10 Ibid, p. 8.
damental question: does absolute consciousness, even though it is not the 11 Ibid., p. 9.
"ultimate and true absolute," remain "to the end" and without qualifica- 12 Ibid., p. 61.
13 Ibid., p. 22.
tion that transcendental absolute without which there would also be no
14 This work first appeared in 1913. A "new (4th) edition expanded and prepared
God, and, consequently, without which God would not be able to be at on the basis of the author's handwritten supplements" appeared in 1950 as
aU? Does God, in order to be God, require a transcendental consciousness Husserliana, III. I shall limit myself in the following pages to the attempt to
different from him? develop Husserl's concept of the "absolute" in the Ideas. Where I do not note
otherwise I will quote from the text of 1913: yet for the sake of simplicity I
Once the question is raised, Husserl could in fact appear to think so shall refer to the page numbers of the Husserliana edition exclusively.
insofar as he himself views the thought of God as grounded more in the 15 Husserliana, IV and V.
teleology immanently given in the facticity of the being of realities than in 16 Cf. the editor's Introduction to Husserliana, IV.
this facticity itself, "for example, the factual evolution of the series of 17 Husserliana, III, 8.
organisms up to man himself, and within the evolution of humanity the 18 Cf. Husserl's lectures on the First Philosophy (1923-24) in Husserliana, VII
growth of culture with its care for the spirit, etc."95 To be sure, "the trans- and VIII. Also the editor's Introduction to VII.
19 Husserliana, II, 23.
ition to pure consciousness by means of the method of the transcendental 20 As regards the passage quoted above from p. 8 of the first volume of the Ideas,
reduction already necessarily leads to the question concerning the ground Husserl later added this explicit marginal note (this, certainly, was written
for the facticity of the corresponding constituting consciousness which now after 1923): "phenomenology as First Philosophy." Cf. Husserliana, III, 463.
emerges." Yet Husserl immediately proceeds: "It is not the factum in 21 For the earlier history of this formula see my Introduction to Husserliana, VII,
general, but the factum as the source of infinitely extending possible and xvi-xx.
actual values that compels us to seek for the 'ground'" and which fur- 22 Husserliana, III, 101 (Gibson, p. 138). Prior to 1923, Husserl modified this sen-
nishes "rational grounds for the existence of a 'divine' being beyond the tence as follows: "In general we can see that for the ego, transcendent being,
or real being in general, no matter of what sort, can only be given in percep-
world."96 tion through appearances," ibid., p. 472.
For Husserl (as well as for Leibniz97 and Schelling98), the question 23 Ibid.
24 Ibid., p. 102 (Gibson, pp. 139-140). After 1923 Husserl added the following
which Heidegger had formulated and had termed the "basic question of phrase to the end of this sentence: "... and which thus proves to be absolutely
metaphysics":99 "Why are there beings rather than nothing?" 100 immedi- uncancellable," ibid., p. 472.
ately takes on the meaning of the further question: "To what end is every- 25 Ibid, p. 100 (Gibson, p. 137). My italics. Between 1913 and 1923 Husserl
thing that is?" This is the question Husserl has in mind when, going desired to reformulate the title of these paragraphs as follows: "Merely Phe-
beyond the absolute position of transcendental philosophy, he thinks of nomenal Givenness of the Transcendent as (? or rather 'and'?) Absolute
God. A discussion of how these two questions stand related to each other, Givenness of the Immanent." During the same period he added this marginal
note: "The entire § 44 is useless!" Cf. p. 472. This fact is important for the con-
to what extent the one implies the other, and to what extent the one siderations which follow. A particular problem, which we here must ignore, is
cannot find an answer without the other has provided the occasion for our raised by Husserl's speaking of the "merely phenomenal."
observations here. 26 The title of the Ideas' second section.
27 Husserliana, III, 109 (Gibson, p. 146).
28 Ibid., p. 106 (Gibson, p. 143).
29 Ibid.

240 241
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE " A B S O L U T E "
30 Ibid.
in itself which are fundamental to the Critique can be made intelligible and
31 Ibid, p. 108 (Gibson, p. 144). the object of further investigation only if they are based explicitly on the prob-
32 Ibid. Husserl added the phrase "in the world of realities in general" after 1923. lematic of the finitude of man." (Churchill, p. 39. - ED.) Of course Heidegger
Cf. p. 473.
does not see a "mistake in principle" in Kant's "characterization of the fini-
33 Ibid. tude of human knowledge" which reveals "what is essential to the dimension
34 As already cited; ibid., p. 101. Cf. note 22. within which the laying of the foundation for metaphysics takes place." (Ibid.)
35 Ibid, pp. 109f. (Gibson, p. 146). Nevertheless "The Laying of the Foundation for Metaphysics in a Repetition"
36 Ibid., p. 114 (Gibson, p. 150). (the title of the fourth section of Heidegger's Kant book) leads to a radical
37 Ibid, p. 115 (Gibson, p. 151). transformation and revaluation of the idea of finitude itself: especially § 41
38 As cited above; cf. note 22. where the following sentence is found: "There is and must be such as Being
39 As cited above; ibid., p. 108 (Gibson, p. 144). only where finitude has become existent." (Churchill, p. 236. - ED.) Husserl
40 Ibid., p. 115 (Gibson, p. 152). had thoroughly come to terms with Heidegger's Kant book; his marginal nota-
41 Principia Philosophiae, pt. I, 51; eds. Adam and Tannery, VIII, 24. [English tions in his own copy of the book preserved in the Husserl-Archives at
translation by Haldane and Ross, The Philosophical Works of Descartes, I Louvain reminds one in many respects of the discussions in § 43 of the Ideas.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1911), 239. - ED.] There is no Latin 61 Husserliana, III, 85 f. (Gibson, p. 124).
edition of the Principia among the books in Husserl's library (now preserved 62 As quoted above; ibid., p. 118 (Gibson, p. 154).
at the Husserl-Archives at Louvain). In Husserl's copy of Rene Descartes' 63 As quoted above; ibid., p. Ill (Gibson, p. 153).
philosophische Werke, trans. J. H. v. Kirchmann, pt. Ill, Die Prinzipien der 64 As quoted above; ibid., p. 118 (Gibson, p. 154).
Philosophie (Berlin, 1870), the passages here in question and other passages 65 Cf. note 48.
connected with them are underlined or marked out in pencil by Husserl. 66 Ibid., p. 96 (Gibson, pp. 133f.).
42 Ibid. 67 Ibid.
43 Ibid, pp. 239-240. 68 As quoted above; ibid., p. 118 (Gibson, p. 154).
44 Husserliana, III, 140 (Gibson, p. 174). Cf. the concluding section of this essay. 69 Ibid., p. 116 (Gibson, p. 152).
45 Ibid., p. 198 (Gibson, p. 236). Cf. Descartes, Principia Philosophiae, § 52: 70 As quoted above; ibid., p. 118 (Gibson, p. 154).
"Created substances, however, whether corporeal or thinking, may be con- 71 Ibid, p. 116 (Gibson, p. 152).
ceived under this common concept; for they are things which need only the 72 Ibid, p. 88 (Gibson, p. 126).
concurrence of God in order to exist." 73 Ibid, pp. 116f. (Gibson, pp. 152f.).
46 Husserliana, III, 115f. (Gibson, p. 152). 74 Ibid., pp. 140 and 198 (Gibson, pp. 174 and 236)
47 Ibid, p. Ill (Gibson, p. 153). Between 1913 and 1923 Husserl wrote "relative 75 Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik: Zweiter Teil, ed. Lasson (Hamburg: Felix
to consciousness" in place of "relative." Cf. p. 474. Meiner, 1934), p. 158: the chapter entitled "The Absolute" - "A. The
48 Ibid., Between 1913 and 1923 Husserl added, by way of clarification, to the Exposition of the Absolute" [English translation by Johnston and Struthers,
end of the sentence: "or, more precisely, for which the thought of something- Science of Logic, vol. II (London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1929), p. 162. -
beyond is nonsense." In a new formulation of the entire sentence (written ED.]. Here it should be noted that the absolute, which can only be
after 1923) the end of the sentence simply states: "... above and beyond, "approached" at this stage of the Logic, "... is only the Absolute of an external
however, is nonsensical." Cf. p. 474. reflection ... and is not, therefore, the Absolute-Absolute, but only the
49 Ibid, p. 118 (Gibson, p. 154). Absolute given in a determinate form," or, "it is the Absolute as attribute,"
50 Ibid, p. 134 (Gibson, p. 168). ibid., p. 160 [Johnston and Struthers, p. 164].
51 Ibid, p. 98 (Gibson, p. 135).
52 Ibid. (Gibson, pp. 135 f.). 76 Ibid., p. 159 [Johnston and Struthers, p. 163]. [Boehm here alludes to three
complementary terms present in this section of Hegel's Logic: untergehen,
53 As quoted several times above; ibid., p. 117 (Gibson, p. 153). zuruckgehen, and zugrunde-gehen. The essential movement of the dialectic
IS 54 Ibid, p. 99 (Gibson, p. 137). referred to is that of leading a term of the dialectic back (zuruckgehen) to its
55 As quoted above; ibid., p. 98 (Gibson, p. 135). ground (zugrunde-gehen), a movement whereby this element can be said to
56 Ibid. "perish" or be "swallowed up" into its ground in order to shed this term of its
57 Ibid, p. 97 (Gibson, p. 134). abstractness. Boehm here suggests that the phenomenological reduction might
58 As quoted above; ibid, p. 98 (Gibson, pp. 135f.). be said to parallel this Hegelian process of Aufhebung wherein one element of
59 Proof of this is not required here. I will discuss the context of Husserl's rela- the dialectic, which appears as only a partial and "relative" truth, is "nullified"
tionship to Kant in a study of Husserl's Relations to Classical Idealism which in terms of its abstractness by the dialectic advance toward the completion of
will appear shortly. [Cf. Boehm's "Husserl et I'idealisme classique" in Revue its true meaning within some higher synthesis. The phenomenological reduc-
Philosophique de Louvain 57 (August, 1958), 351-396. - ED.] tion suspends or "nullifies" transcendent reality, and leads it back into its true
60 In particular § 4 and § 5 of this work. [Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, ground, or absolute consciousness, a movement which is at the same time the
trans. James S. Churchill (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962) - ED.] disclosure and "preservation" of the true meaning of reality's being by reveal-
Heidegger explicitly acknowledges "that the concepts 'appearance' and 'thing ing its relativity to absolute consciousness. Reality then possesses the

242 243
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y / A N D METAPHYSICS
H U S S E R L ' S CONCEPT OF THE " A B S O L U T E "
"absolute for its abyss (Abgrund)" precisely insofar as the disclosure of the
former's relativity is at the same time its "perishing" as being in an absolute to ask will be, 'Why is there something rather than nothing?' For nothing is
sense, for it is disclosed as fundamentally lacking its own ground, and there- simpler and easier than something. Further, assuming that things must exist, it
fore as ab-grundig. - ED.] must be possible to give a reason why they should exist as they do and not
77 Husserliana, III, 119 (Gibson, pp. 154f.). otherwise." - ED.] The meaning which this question has for Leibniz must be
78 As quoted above; ibid., p. 98 (Gibson, p. 135). drawn from the answer hefinallygives to it.
79 As quoted above; ibid., p. 110 (Gibson, p. 146). 98 Philosophie der Offenbarung, Erste Vorlesung, Collected Works, II—III, 7. The
80 As quoted above; ibid., p. 115 (Gibson, p. 151). meaning which this question has for Schelling is immediately evident from the
81 Ibid. context. [The relevant passage in this text is as follows: "One generation
passes away and another generation comes in order to once again pass away in
82 As quoted above; ibid, pp. 115f. (Gibson, p. 152). its turn. We wait in vain for something new to occur wherein this unrest will
83 Heidegger's Nachwort to Was ist Metaphysik?, fourth edition (1923), p. 25. In finally find its goal; everything that happens takes place only in order for
the fifth edition (1949) this sentence is replaced by another: "Being never something else to happen and which itself becomes past in opposition to
comes-to-presence without beings, ... a being never is without Being"; p. 41
["What is Metaphysics" in Existence and Being (Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., something else. Essentially, therefore, everything happens to no purpose, and
1949),p. 354.-ED.] all of man's actions, endeavors and labors are themselves sheer vanity: every-
84 As quoted above; Husserliana, 111, 116 (Gibson, p. 152). thing is vanity, for vanity is simply that which lacks a true aim. Quite removed
from the view that man and his acts make the world comprehensible, man
85 The title of the central second chapter of the second part of the Ideas. himself is the incomprehensible, and I am unavoidably driven to the view that
86 Cf. above, note 26. all being is wretchedness, a view which announces itself both in our times and
87 As quoted above; Husserliana, III, 115 (Gibson, p. 152). in the past in grievous words. It is precisely man who compels me to raise this
88 Ibid, p. 198 (Gibson, p. 236). It should be noted that § 81, from which this question which is so full of doubt: Why are there beings? Why not nothing?"
passage is taken, nowhere explicitly speaks of God. Husserl's theme is indi- Ibid. - ED.]
cated by the title of this section: "Phenomenological Time and Time- 99 Martin Heidegger, "What Is Metaphysics," trans. R. F. C. Hull and Alan
Consciousness." Because it is within this context that Husserl speaks of the Crick, in Existence and Being (Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1949), p. 349. -
"ultimate and true absolute" which lies beyond the simple "transcendental ED.
absolute," further clarification of this theme can be had only with the investi-
gation of Husserl's still unpublished notes of 1930-35 on the problem of time 100 Ibid. Cf. also Martin Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph
preserved at the Husserl-Archives at Louvain. This is a task which still Mannheim (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959), pp. 1 ff. - ED.
remains to be completed, even after the indispensable preparatory work
accomplished by G. Brand's Welt, Ich und Zeit (1955). [A portion of this work
can be found in an English translation in Joseph J. Kockelman's Phenom-
enology: The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and Its Interpretation (New
York: Doubleday, 1967), pp. 197-217. - ED.] Equally indispensable would be
Husserl's lectures on the Phenomenology of Inner Time-Consciousness from
1905-1910 and edited by Martin Heidegger, where Husserl already refers to
"the absolute time-constituting flow of consciousness."
89 Husserliana, III, 140 (in § 58: "The Disconnection of the Transcendence of
God") (Gibson, p. 175).
90 Ibid., p. 122 (Gibson, p. 157).
91 Ibid, p. 121 (Gibson, p. 157).
92 As quoted above; ibid., p. 140 (Gibson, p. 174).
93 Ibid, pp. 138f. (Gibson, p. 173). Instead of the phrase "highly mediated,"
between 1913 and 1923 Husserl wrote: "in an entirely different way"; cf. p.
477.
94 Ibid., pp. 121 f. (Gibson, p. 157). In the sentence: "The ordering principle of
the absolute must be found in the absolute itself..." the phrase "the absolute
itself" clearly means absolute consciousness; by contrast, "God" means "the
ordering principle of the absolute."
95 Ibid., p. 139 (Gibson, p. 174).
96 Ibid.; also the note to § 51, pp. 121 f. (Gibson, pp. 158f.).
97 Principes de la Nature et de la Grdcefondiss en Raison, § 7; ed. Robinet, p. 45.
[Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, ed. Loemker (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1956), II, 1038. "... The first question which we have a right

244
245
E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

The great theme of Aristotle's philosophy of nature, as both Plotinus


82 and Hegel saw, is not the divine but entelechies or eide or logoi conceived
as kinds of autonomous creative but deficient thoughts, i.e., mere forms,
and not self-thinking thoughts existing with substantial reality in and for
E N T E L E C H Y I N themselves. In the natural order, form is not free as capable of thinking
T R A N S C E N D E N T A L itself but is burdened with exteriority and immersed in and shaping mind-
less hyle and rendering it intelligible by giving it a specific form. It is, as
P H E N O M E N O L O G Y Hedwig Conrad-Martius noted, as if a great artist were able to make from
out of his creative idea and all that it implied, an autonomous, individual,
A sketch of the foundations of Husserlian effective, substantial foundation of his work so that this autonomous idea
now was able to paint the picture, compose the symphony, construct the
metaphysics
building. In such a remarkable case, the artist could not now complain that
what he envisaged in his mind could only imperfectly be realized in his
work.2
James G. Hart
Husserl surely was familiar with the AristoteUan theme of entelechy as
well as with its appropriation by Leibniz and Goethe. It is possible that he
Source: American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 66(2) (1992): 189-212. first encountered the notion of the divine as entelechy in his beginning
philosophy lectures from Friederich Paulsen. 3 But perhaps it was the work
of Hans Driesch, with whom he was personally acquainted and whose
writings commanded the attention of much of Europe, that encouraged
And we here, in relation to the factually given reality, which we
him to conceive the divine as entelechy. 4
have been thinking about as recognizably theoretical, come to an
ultimate ontological problem, which humanity from earliest times I wish to begin with a discussion of entelechy as a theme of interest for
had to face, namely the problem of the real meaning of the idea of regional phenomenological ontology. This helps us to gain conceptual
clarity for later discussions. Then I will begin to integrate it into Husserl's
God or the problem of creation, the problem of the realizing
transcendental phenomenology and then, finally, sketch the parallels
power of absolute ideals. Can an idea, indeed an idea of God, as
between the regional ontological sense of entelechy and the transcenden-
the highest normative idea of possible reality of the world in
tal-phenomenological theory of the divine entelechy.
general regulate factual existence of reality (factual being, being-
such, self-development) not only normatively but in terms of actu-
alization? Can such a regulation have any meaning whatsoever I
and what kind can it have?
Development as morphogenesis is a manifest feature of the change or
(Hua XXVIII, 180-81) motion of some physical bodies in space and time. Development is the sus-
tained motion of a being from its incipiency to its maturity. This motion is
One of the key notions of Husserl's philosophical theology is that of the
the maturing. However, if we think of how even the mature organism or
divine entelechy.1 Entelechy itself might also be said to be one of the oper-
being restores, repairs and regenerates itself we may think of the motion
ative concepts of his philosophy, even if the word itself is infrequently
as continuous throughout its life.5
used.
It seems clear that the motion comes from the organism itself. It is not a
The philosophical problem of organisms (morphogenesis) is indicated motion stemming from outside the organism, as the formation of a snow-
in Aristotle's neologism entelecheia. Hechein (having), telos (end, drift may be said to derive from the winds outside the snowdrift blowing
purpose), and en (within/in) taken together may initially be rendered as the snow. Thus when we say development is a kind of motion from within
either the actuality of having the goal immanently and completely (e.g., or by the organism itself, and not from outside, we must ask, what is it that
Metaphysics 1071a36) or the actuality which brings to its term something moves? When we see things moving or taking shape in the fertilized egg or
whose telos is still being realized (cf., De Anima 412 a27ff.). The latter the sprouting seed, do we want to say that these move or assemble them-
sense is foremost for our topic. selves and the result is the organism? Is the organism a result of the sum of

246 247
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

the finite number of motions of these things? Is it like a bicycle that would gence, psychological trait, etc.6 Preformism is the venerable name for this
get assembled by reason of the parts aU moving themselves into the right view that the whole developed organism is contained in a miniature way in
position at the right time? In which case "It moves or develops" would not its beginnings. Here, morphogenesis is "development" (Ent-wicklung) as
refer to the bicycle itself moving or moving itself but to the many parts: "It the unfolding of what is already there. Epigenesis holds that there is not
develops" means "they move." this character of identity or symmetry of parts between the beginning
Or rather, does not "It develops" refer to the whole organism? Is it not phases and the end, but rather there is novelty, complexity and enrichment
rather the case that it is the whole which moves itself through the manifest in the accretion of form. What is antecedently "there" is dynamis, poten-
motions of the parts which we see? Indeed, the primary motion is the tiality for form; determinate features of the whole completed organism are
development of the parts of the whole which is not yet itself whole but not yet present.
always wholly, that is effectively, there or present from the start, even Doubtless one can always look harder and better at the beginning
though not yet actually present as a whole? materials, still, epigenesis seems closer to the empirical evidence of the
This description becomes more appropriate as we become disposed to unfolding 6rganism as well to as one's experience of oneself growing
regard the motion as belonging to parts of a whole and serving the whole. and/or learning something. In learning or growing one may say that there
Thus one may say the motion is teleological in the sense that its purpose is is potentiality in the sense of a determinable field of possibiUties; but thisls
completion, perfection or, at least, the well-being of the organism. Of not the same as saying that the developed or articulated meanings-are
course, this perfection is that of an individual, and with Plotinus we may there in advance, only hidden or unnoticed. And this is not to say that
speak of "the form of Socrates"; but it is always also the more general there is, in advance, total indeterminacy or indeterminateness. The inde-
form of a species to which the individual belongs. For that reason the terminate situation will permit anything; not so here. For example, one
motion is typical or species-bound. cannot grow up to be just anything; nor can one's learning something, as in
Thus, early on, the motion is evidently that of the parts of a whole the trying to understand some new concept, turn into just anything whatso-
full sense of which is not yet evident; indeed the initial parts themselves ever. One experiences a field of possibilities with vectors for development
are not evidently the parts of what turns out to be the later completed in not yet determinate but not indeterminate directions. It is not a matter
whole. The parts are moving by way of doing things, going somewhere, of "any direction possible," some are excluded and some fields loom more
arranging themselves - but most elementally, by coming into being, i.e., by prominently than others. In any case, these are not yet actual. Further they
themselves developing. If we study the parts apart from the whole and the are all different and some even are incompatible. Yet they are not just
telos we can be inclined to ascribe to them quasi-mental properties anything, not indeterminate or merely logical or empty possibilities.
because they appear to act as if they were heading somewhere or know The case is somewhat different in observing from without an organism
what they are doing. in medias res, that is, in ignorance of the beginning and end. Here, any-
There is a recurrent temptation to speak of the parts as if they were thing seems to be able to happen and what does happen might well appear
self-moving mini-minds. This tendency is evident in the older theory of to be chaotic and disjointed. Yet, if we know only the beginnings (e.g., the
preformism as weU as in modern genetic theory. (Recall that Paracelsus acorn, or the caterpillar's first stages) we begin to get a sense of ranges of
posited a magical mini-master worker in the interior of the organism, an possibflities even though we can be quite surprised. If we know the end,
Archaeus, who knows what he does, has a plan which he is bent on realiz- we will be less surprised. Indeed, we can come to see the novel forms (new
ing, and notes when something is not going right.) cells, organs, etc.) as continuous phases of a unified synthetic whole, each
If we, while being ignorant of the whole, i.e., the purpose or goal, phase of which recapitulates the earUer and prepares for the next.
encounter the motions in their seminal stages, we may not even see in the Ancient and modern forms of gene theory, with their analogies of the
later stages any meaningful patterns until there is almost no distance "Archaeus," "language" of DNA or RNA, the "genetic programing" of
between the concluding stages and the conclusion. When we are aware of protein molecules, "selfish genes" and genes as "throw away survival
the purpose we may look to see in the seminal stages its outline or indica- machines," genes as "interpreters of information" which "choose,"
tions of its basic "grammar." The temptation has been strong to look hard "mold," "aspire," "create," "form," etc., face the enormous difficulty of
and see the end in the beginning. Indeed, most empirical biological genetic accounting for how these metaphors are to be understood. How can the
research is based on, and has its raison d'etre in, the assumption that a nucleus of chemical molecules comprising the embryos or seeds of organ-
detailed knowledge of beginning parts discloses the whole. Thus the claims isms, the acknowledged properties of which exclude anything, like having
that this part or "gene" is "for" this finished quality, e.g., hair color, intelli- plans, intentions, consciousness, directing powers, have these teleological

248 249

i
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y
or teleonomic (adaptive) properties? It would seem that we grant the
analogies when used in artificial intelligence, computers, etc., because technology, and without the mathematical and mechanistic bias of modern
these have to do with created extensions of actual intentions which create research), that "somehow or other we must bring into the story the phys-
the programs; no such comparable actual inteUigence is acknowledged in ical forces which are necessary to push the material about into the appro-
biological research or evident in our experience of development. Further- priate places and mold it into the correct shapes."11 But what is the origin
more, describing chemical changes as such, with or without teleological of these "physical forces" which, analogous to field forces, determine the
metaphors, does not account for how they happen the way they do, that is, coming into being of the parts in an ordered sequence in respect to the
how they function toward morphogenesis. As a recent defender of Driesch formation of the whole? In short, in what sense is the explanatory prin-
has described modern gene theory, "it is as if the delivery of the right ciple itself a physical force? If we grant that the organizing principle is not
building material and machinery to plots of ground resulted in the spon- itself adequately accounted for by the constituent physical parts, and we
taenous growth of houses of just the right form."7 further grant that there is something like a "field force" created by the
i principle, what is the principle itself? Is the field itself the principle? The
In this regard, the analogy between morphogenesis and field theory has field itself would seem to be in need of an explanatory principle in so far as
been noted, for example, by Spemann, Gurwitsch, Andre, Conrad- it, as an "extensive manifold," can be divided. That is, when the field as an
Martius, Weiss, and Waddington. 8 We best think of the organism as a extensive, divisible, whole-making manifold, like that of a sea-urchin, is
whole which is more than the sum of its parts, just as we may envisage divided, on the basis of what can it itself again become whole?
a "Gestalt" in perception as more than the parts that comprise it. In facing
a field of brightly colored mosaic pieces, it is clear that the emergence of a How far does the entelechy reach in the formation of the Uving organ-
definite form from out of the array of pieces, for example, that of a trian- ism? Does it stand over the inorganic and presuppose the chemical-
gle, is more than merely the result or sum of the parts comprising it. The physical processes, as if these could run on their own and the entelechy
formation of the embryonic form is as little grasped from out of the elem- would be like a chemist conducting an experiment? Conrad-Martius faults
ental achievements of the molecules as the Gestalt is derivable from the Driesch for holding such a view and failing to see that life is not something
I parts next to one another in the preUminary amorphous field. As which stands over the inorganic but rather aU the material, inorganic and
the Gestalt-field is distributed throughout the parts as form-giving, so the organic, is thoroughly and fundamentally living material; the entelechy is
organic whole is distributed throughout in the development of the parts not a mere arranger of inorganic processes as if these were outside the
determining these in relationship to the development of the whole. sphere of influence of the entelechy.12 Hyle is never "in itself apart from
some form or some entelechy.
For all the deficiencies in Hans Driesch's theory and experimentation,
he would seem to have raised a fundamental chaUenge to aU theories In the development of the manifold parts of the organism, it seems
which will account for the adult organism in terms of some part of the evident, primarily by reason of the recurrence and stability of the types,
embryonic structure or tissue. As Driesch's experiments showed, the that the organizing principle of the organism is itself not developing;
destruction of parts of the sea-urchin embryo do not give rise to, for rather, it functions typically from the start and remains constantly in tune
example, a quarter or half of a sea-urchin, as would have to be the case if with the telos of the being. It is not the principle which has to develop or
the embryo were Uke a mosaic of more or less independent parts. Rather, which is capable of developing. The organism develops itself as, for
it adjusts to the deprivation and goes on to form a smaller but complete example, a Uon, from the fertilized egg until it is the complete animal.13
organism.9 The work with sea-urchins and other animals, flatworms for And it is equally clear that in the disturbance and slicing of the sea-urchin
example, wherein there is an "equipotentiality" of the embryonic parts to embyro, the organizing principle of its development is not disturbed or
form the whole organism, caused Driesch rightfully to challenge all under- sliced. Indeed, the organization and the organizing forces themselves are
standings of the organism as a machine. That all the separate volumes of not part of what is organized and therefore not in space. And although it
the embryonic organism of, say, the flatworm, can perform morphogenesis constitutes a temporal sequence for the organism, it is not evident that the
completely means that each volume "must possess the machine in its total- organizing principle itself is temporal.
ity A very strange sort of machine indeed, which is the same in aU its If we call entelechy that causal factor which accounts for the bringing
parts." 10 about of the whole organism, it is appropriate to note that it is also what
accounts for a specific meaning-whole. Although the modern post-Darwinian
It would seem that most researchers would agree with the regional
ethos urges that we see the organization of the finished forms (species) as
ontologist (or one seeking to grasp the nature of organisms through per-
phases or even "habits" in further stages of development, nevertheless the
ception and without total dependency on observation through advanced
whole which is brought about is always a typical, specificaUy identical whole.

250
251
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S
E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y
At least in the very specific matter of founding a philosophy of nature
on entelechies, one modern Aristotelian, Conrad-Martius, sees the ent- Good'" (A V 21/128a). For Conrad-Martius, the position of Driesch res-
elechy as the typical general "meaning" of the developing living being. onates with Platonism, because in this formulation of Driesch, the ent-
Driesch, on the other hand, held that entelechy was the organic person or elechy manifests itself by sharing trans-individually in the formation of
individual being itself which builds up the body, repairs it after distur- organic individuals. But ideas are nothing natural; they do not exist on the
bances, etc. Thus, in answer to the question, "what is the lion which has its same plane, so to speak, with natural things. And as such they neither
properties of being a predator, living in the desert, etc.?", Driesch answers, function teleologically nor do they bring about effects in nature. Only the
I category of the entelechy brings together the categories of the ideal and
"entelechy."14 Conrad-Martius rightly finds this absurd. Entelechy does
not live in the desert, have a shaggy mane, etc. Nor does the universal the efficient-causal. (How Husserl wrestles with this charge will be our
term "lion" have such properties. Only the individual existing lion has or concern later.)
acquires these properties. Only the individual concrete animal has the uni- We see that Driesch can use entelechy as a theological category because
versal property of "lion"; but it is the "entelechy" which brings about and he is prepared to commit, according to Conrad-Martius, a categorial con-
maintains the specific nature of this individual organic being. fusion, that is, to assign it, on occasion, quasi-mental properties or, as the
For Driesch, entelechy is clearly not something material but rather a case may be, quasi-ideal properties. For Conrad-Martius, who is drawn to
persisting non-spatial, unchanging, trans-physical substance. Therefore it is the Christian doctrine of creatio ex nihilo, the divine is the author of the
entelechies and therefore is the mediate author of all the necessities of
not an "idea." He calls it a "psychoid" so as to indicate that it is neither
nature.
something material nor something which functions psychologically in a
conscious manner. Because it is the plan-determining, directing, purpose- Although Husserl analyzes in detail nature as material being, there is
ful insertion of the individual partial elements in a whole at the right place but one non-theological passage I know of where he uses entelechy in the
and time, etc., it is soul-like or quasi-psychological and quasi-instinctual. * proper organic developmental context in anything like a noematic,
For Conrad-Martius, this theory confuses the essential distinctions regional-ontological description. (See the letter to Driesch, mentioned in
between the ideal, psychological and merely organic. Further, the ent- n. 5.) In Hua XXVII, 118-119, within the context of discussing the inborn
elechy is not something that needs an ideal plan according to which it must telos of the individual human as weU as that of cultures and eventually of
take its bearings; rather, it itself is the ideal plan, the logos, the typical uni- humanity as a personaUty of a higher order, he speaks of the goal-idea
versal "meaning" of the developing being, which effectively inhabits the (Zweckidee) as the conscious apprehension of the telos. Here he claims
embryo and according to which everything must proceed. As such, it is that the human who has ethical consciousness bears
neither an idea nor a quasi-mental entity.15 Driesch's unconscious quasi-
soul, of course, avoids the Platonic position of explaining development'by in himself his goal-idea as principle of development in the form of
way of an idea and a theory of methexis. For Conrad-Martius, this is a cat- a self-formation through autonomous reason, an entelechy in a
egory confusion: entelechy is a tertium quid, an energized species-logos, completely different, indeed in the most proper sense, in contrast
and in no way something mental or an idea. Indeed, it is captured by the to that of a blind organic entelechy, as a natural end-type toward
fiction of a creator's idea, autonomously realizing itself apart from the which the organic being grows in accord with its type.
creator's agency, embodying the creator's ideas completely, as if a sym- (Hua XXVII, 118)
phony could compose itself. It is best understood by the fiction of the sub-
stantialization of a creative idea. This "most proper sense" of entelechy, then is to be contrasted with that
For Driesch, the consideration that the halving of the sea-urchin less proper form manifest in the realm of "blind" organic nature, of which,
embryo could not be a halving of the entelechy led him to posit the pan- of course, human beings are a part. This latter he earlier characterized as
theist (or panentheist) position that ultimately there is a super-entelechy
encompassing all other entelechies, a unique total entelechy which itself a system of developmental forms which embraces a system of
again cannot fall into many individuals but rather will express itself in dif- developmental ideas (species), with a relatively constant typicality
ferent ways according to the material circumstances. Husserl holds a of development repeating itself in countless individuals in which
similar view. As he once put it, the teleological world would require an the species-ideas realize themselves "normally" more or less per-
Aristotelian God "as the entelchy of its inner development through a man- fectly. And this entire system of ideas and realizing development
ifold of relative entelechies all ordained in the eros toward the 'idea of the (ontogenesis) is itself grasped as in development. There occur new
species with new ontogeneses, and the phylogenesis also shows a

252
253
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

direction upwards, i.e., toward the development of a higher and explicitly Aristotelian terms to describe this founding feature of
highest formation. This "striving after goals," to ideas and to the experience:
conception of new ideas, this more or less "perfect" realization of
ideas and the development of ideas ruling ideas of a higher order . . . before every movement of cognition the object of cognition is
does not mean any goal-directed striving of conscious beings; it already present as dynamis which is to turn into an entelecheia.
does not imply purposefulness. The ideas are not intentional for-
mations of a consciously achieved ideation. Later, at §18, he explicates the movement of cognition to what is passively
(Hua XXVII, 99) pre-given as "attention." Attention is a "tending-toward in realization."

Husserl goes on to say that this contrasts with the animal in whom we find The realization which is brought into being with the turning-
consciousness and bodiliness. The animal has its organism; it is not simply toward, the starting point of the realization of the act, is the begin-
organism. By having its body it is organism in a new sense. And the ning of a continuing realizing directedness of the ego toward the
human, who can transcend the pressure of importunity of particulars and object. The beginning indicates the direction of a further syntheti-
particular cases, and who is able to integrate these in the horizon of simi- cally unified process of realization (although it can perhaps be
lars and wider generalities, indeed, within the entire universe of possi- carried out in more than one way). The original tendency of the
bilities, transcends the inauthentic agency of animals who are under the process, along with what has accrued to it from what has been
sway of drives, instincts, etc. When the human strives after goal-ideas realized hitherto, is fulfilled phase by phase, and it is at the same
which embrace all other goal-ideas, that is, when he strives after the defin- time extended as a tendency and exhibits new stages of fulfill-
ing infinite ideas, then is he most free, and then is the term entelechy most ment. This continues, up to an "end" or breakoff point, which may
properly applied (see Hua XXVII, 98-100 and 118). The authentic use of have the form of "and so forth." The beginning, therefore, has an
the term "entelechy" for Husserl would thus be in regard to the conscious intentional horizon; it points beyond itself in an empty mode,
pursuit of the summum bonum, a theme to which we will return. which is filled only in subsequent realizations. It refers implictly to
a continuous synthetic process (one or another of the directions to
be followed remaining indeterminate in the multidimensionaUty
II of possible processes), through which extends a continuous
Husserl uses Aristotelian themes to illuminate a basic feature of percep- uniform tendency. In its course, it has continuously modified
tion. He notes how the not-yet thematized or expUcated fields or horizons modes of fulfillment, each with the character of mediate fulfill-
of perception are given neither as empty possibilities nor as something ment, which always refer, due to the nature of horizon, to new ful-
determinate or indeterminate. Sometimes the horizons are pre-delineated fillments.17
potentialities. In each case they are potential, not-expUct, and deter-
minable. (See Hua I, esp. §§19 and 46.) But the determinability is different This text of genetic phenomenology may be taken as a properly phenom-
from being indeterminate. In the latter, any possible determination is pos- enological example of entelechy because it is a description of ongoing
sible; what is given as indeterminate is simply given as an empty possibil- morphogenesis wherein there is a synthetic continuous movement from
ity. (Contrast seeing a written page across the room and the written page a potency to act, from dynamis to entelecheia. The teleology (tendency, "up
few feet away; contrast your sense of what is in the stranger's house in to an 'end'," etc.) is described as being within the object that is being
another country and what you do not see nor have looked at but which is attended to (noema) insofar as it is acknowledged to have tendencies and
at the periphery of your vision; contrast stating a sentence which you have phases or stages of fulfillment; but clearly the weight of the teleological
just read or articulated well with one which you now want to say and have description is in the informing or framing tendency of the act (noesis). In
never said before.)16 each case there is an unfolding of the phenomenological object toward its
In discussions of perception (in Hua I and elsewhere), Husserl on occa- true self, its telos, which is inseparable from the actuation of the act of
sion makes reference to the sheer sensible presence or impression before attention.
it is taken in a certain way or before it is articulated with syntax and syn-
categorematicals. This is a sheer pre-given stimulus to cognitive activity But in this firm orientation on the object, in the continuity of the
which enjoys a simple certainty. In Experience and Judgement, §7, he used experience of the object, there is an intention which goes beyond

254 255
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L PHENOMENOLOGY

the given and its momentary mode of givenness and tends toward How are we to properly understand this? In what sense is the idea pos-
a progressive plus ultra. It is not only a progressive having- sibility or potentiaUty? We propose, following the tips of de Muralt, that
consciousness-of but a striving toward a new consciousness in the we think of it after the fashion of entelechy. Entelechy is not actual as
form of an interest in the enrichment of the "self" of the object beings are actual; and, as the telos of what is actual, it is potential vis-a-vis
which is forthcoming eo ipso with the prolongation of the appre- the thing. Thus, the scientific ideal is a possibility in relationship to the
hension. Thus the tendency of the turning-toward continues as a actual state of science. Yet actual science is the realization of the idea; it is
tendency toward complete fulfillment.18 in potentiality to the actual idea which prescribes and informs it from the
!'••• start. From this point of view the idea of science is act, and its (actual)
v Clearly, because here we are dealing with the constitution of a percep- form of realization is potency.21
tual object and working within the noematic-noetic correlation, there is
not a description of properly organic development, that is, there is not a Ill
clear, autonomous, progressive tendency toward stages of fulfillment by
the object/being (organism) itself. Its dynamism rather is informed by the This leads us to our concluding project. It remains to integrate the other
overarching and pervasive activity of intentionality's bringing it to its ideal key HusserUan term for the divine, Idee, with entelechy. To do this we
self-givenness.19 must see the causaUy effective power of the Idea for Husserl.
These later analyses rework the earlier theme of fact/essence, thing/idea. Although "Idea" for Husserl often enough has to do with something
Throughout Husserl's Ufe he enunciated the doctrine that contingent factual which is sheerly ideal and as such cut off from a causal relationship to
things are manifest in terms of the essential meaning-frames which prescribe material objects, it also has other senses and contexts. A most prominent
a priori the path of articulation. The particular concrete things are given one is the "regulative idea." Husserl appropriates Kant's concept of the
within ideal frameworks, the elucidation of which is the expUcation of the regulative idea throughout his work when he is explicating the perceptual
not-given senses of the things. In this sense the thing in its fuU phenomeno- object as what is presumptively meant through the endless manifold of
logical richness does not coincide absolutely with itself but tends toward its appearances: the perceptual object functions as a regulative idea for- the
i:
ideal exemplar. In the transcendental-constitutional context, factual things manifold of appearings. And, similarly, both the field or external horizon
Ii
i.
if
tend progressively toward their ideal eidos and the eidos is always the idea
of a factual thing. From the pre-phenomenological, epistemological, descrip-
of objects of perception as well as the field of fields or ultimate horizon of
world are regarded as infinite ideas. The divine itself is considered an'anal-
tive point of view, what is primary is the factual thing and the idea or ogous transcendence to that of the world (Hua III, §58), indeed it is the
essence as telos is elicited from this datum. Yet, the more reflective and con- "ideal pole-idea" (E III 4/60-61).
stitutional phenomenological point of view reverses this order. Here, it is But it would seem that the ideal pole-idea as horizon (or at least as
seen that the idea of the thing and/or the morphological essence function as inseparable from horizon)22 would be a constitution of the wakeful mind
telos are at the origin of the process of constitution; they are archai, prin- and hi no way constituting. As Kant on occasion maintained, the idea is a
ciples of the process. They regulate from the start the sense of the original mere ideal, merely our heuristic or pragmatic postulate (KRV, B 698 ff.).
datum (which also in arche as hyle) and outline its progressive articulation. In which case, the idea would be a realm of possibility created by inten-
Indeed, the idea or essential meaning frame is the motor of the process of tionality. The idea as infinite regulative ideal thus belongs to the realm of
realization of the full sense of the thing. the not actually existing and the merely potential. The divine idea, in* this
The idea, for example, as the regulative idea of the thing or in the form case, would be a construct and, as a basis for progress in theory and action,
of an essence, "prescribes the rule that determines how an object subordi- an heuristic, fictional or poetic postulate. The divine would be the possibil-
nate to it is to be brought in respect of its meaning and mode of presenta- ity of the world's meliorization only as the emptily-intended constituted
tion to full determinacy, to adequate primordial givenness" (Hua III/l, beckoning penumbra of possibility. In this view, the divine as the consti-
330/341). As de Muralt puts this: "The idea is pre-scribed in the realizing tuting actuality which lures the all of monads is, in fact, a constituted realm
development and it pre-scribes this development normatively." 20 And if of possibiUty.
we think, as Husserl does, of the essence or idea as providing the essential I do not think that this interpretation, which is basically the conclusion
possibiUties, then "the old ontological doctrine," namely, that "the know- of Andre de Muralt,23 is Husserl's position. Let me sketch some reasons.
ledge of 'possibilities' must precede that of actualities," properly under- The first is that as essences are not postulates but given, so for Husserl the
stood, "is a great truth" (Hua III, 194). idea, pole, and horizon of the world are not postulates. The divine, too-,

256 257
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS
E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y
then as the ultimate pole of poles or ideal pole-idea is not postulated.
gested by E III 4/61 where the divine ideal pole-idea is said to be Uber-
Husserl can hold that these are not postulated because he holds that, in
Sein, that is, super- or trans-being, super-real, etc., which means not
contrast to Kant, the world is an object of experience (Hua IX, 95/71).
merely that it is something that cannot be adequately made present but
And, earlier in Ideas, he held that the idea is not something merely posited
rather that it is exemplarily being and real in senses not commensurate
but is an absolutely indubitable datum - in an extended sense of the word
with the mundane senses. .
datum or "givenness" (Gegebenheit) (Hua III/I, 186/197). Thus the
Third, a morphological essence,26 that is, the types, styles, and forms
wakeful sense of the world as having a divine pole is not a postulate but
evident in the flux of experience can be consecutive invariants of this flux
something experienced, a kind of "datum." For Husserl this explicit sense
by thematizing the features of constancy and distinctiveness which are
of the world emerges especially through ethical reflection.24
indeterminately present in the flux. The divine idea, in this respect, is com-
Secondly, as for C. S. Peirce, "The true ideal," vague as it must parable to "world": it is the invariant horizon or frame of the entire flux
necessarily be, "is the Living Power." Whatever generates devotion and, and all the features of the flux. Yet, it is not in the flux.
as beauty and goodness, has the power to attract us irresistably, cannot be
FinaUy, we have seen that from the standpoint of the articulation of
non-actual and merely the outcome of inquiry and evolution.25 Similarly
beings, the essential or ideal meaning-frame appears as the realm of possibil-
for Husserl, the divine as the ideal pole-idea is
ity and the not yet actual sense-telos of the actual perceived thing. But from
the phenomenological constitutional perspective, the ideal meaning frame is
the unum, verum and bonum toward which each being is bound, arche along with hyle. Archai themselves, however, may exist in horizontality!
and toward which all transcendental subjective Ufe, as vital being Essences thus stand in relationship to others which define them, they also are
living toward constituting truth, tends.
within wider essential regions, within the region of regions, world. AU of
(E III 4/60-61) these regions are contexts which determine the meaning of whatever is
encompassed by horizontality. StiU, not everything is so encompassed.
Thirdly, the divine as absolute ideal pole-idea is the absolute logos
which is named Husserl noted in the Crisis that the world does not exist as an object or
a being for which there is always possible a plurality, but rather it exists
uniquely in such a way that the plural is senseless (Hua VI, §37). This is a
an essence (Wesen) that is not an eidos, but rather as essence in true a fortiori for the divine idea.27 Everything which exists within horizon-
absolute truth, as essence in no relativity of situations, as essence tality is one among many. Thus, a morphological essence, say that of a
without horizontality. This idea is to be thought of as essence, person, necessarily exists among other morphological essences (for
which, bearing aU true being in itself in absolute necessity is example, promise, contract, speech-act, oath, duty, claim, etc.) and there-
unique and is actual reality (Wirklichkeit); actual reality in the fore is not unique in itself and receives a meaning-determination from a
sense of being the universal actual reality founding everything and wider context of meanings. Every perceptual real thing which exists within
making everything possible. the horizontality of the world exists with other things and therefore is not
(E III 4/62; see Hua XXVIII, 180 ff. for an equaUy rich but earlier a unique being. Furthermore, it exists within a not-actual possible meaning
version of the themes of this text) space so that its actuality is always in a process of realization of its ideal
meaning-being. The idea of the thing is what determines the unfolding
An adequate commentary on this rich text is here out of the question. We profiles of the thing to be its aspects. The eidetic horizontal meaning-
may make four observations. The first is that Husserl is denying that the frame is what determines the unfolding of the possible essential features of
divine is an eidos. Consider that eide can, through an appropriate ideation the thing; and the horizonal meaning-frame of the world is what deter-
or abstraction, exist merely in the manner of eide, that is, as ingredients of mines the encompassing significance of the essences and things. Things,
the kosmos noetos, or purely meaning topoi. Essence, on the other hand, is Husserl notes, are given to us in principle as objects in the world-horizon.
always essence of something. The divine is, it would seem, in some sense Something is present as something only from out of the world which is
the formal cause (Wesen) as well as the telos (final cause) of the universe. always present to us as horizon (Hua VI, §37).
Second, as essence, the divine would not be an exact essence (Uke a
The divine idea is the essence which both encompasses and determines
circle or the perfect steam engine). Obviously, this is not because the
all other essential-formal meanings (ideas, eide, morphological and exact
divine is immersed in the flux; but rather because the exact essence is a
essences) as weU as particular beings by providing their meaning-rcpos and
perfect, closed whole and the divine is essentially an infinity. This is sug-
formal sense. This is a sense in which it is "founding." Further, the divine

258
259
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

idea exists in no horizontality and therefore is absolutely unique. As the Bergson or Mach); nor an imposition of form upon unadulterated hyle,
eidetic or ideal meaning-frames are the prior condition for the possibiUty forma super materia, (as in Kant), but it is materia praeformata (ab ent-
for the progressive meaning-determination of the particular thing, so elecheia divina) sed non ab actu intellectus. Indeed, prior to the constitu-
world and, a fortiori, the divine are meaning-giving for worldly beings, for tion of the world, the primal-stuff "flows" in such an "instinctual" way that
essences and for more encompassing essential regions of being. The divine the constitution of the entire world is predelineated, and the enabling
idea therefore may be seen to be "the ultimate total meaning-giving prin- foundations of the world, that is, the world's primer and essential
ciple for truth and being, yes, even for the being of the absolute subject grammar, are evident in advance (Hua XV, 385). What Husserl has in
and the totality of subjects" (E III 4/60-61).28 mind here especially is less a performism than the claim that aU possible
A fourth response to an interpretation such as de Muralt's is that the syntheses presuppose the original synthesis of association of original time-
divine idea is not, in its ultimate consideration for transcendental phenom- consciousness. (Cf., e.g., Hua XI, 125.)
enology, something constituted by transcendental subjectivity but rather These considerations, that is, the analysis of the primal hyle and its
constitutive of the very foundations of this subjectivity.29 This final ulti- interwoven hidden intentionalities and the continuity of these with the
mate sense in which the divine idea constitutes transcendental subjectivity telos of aU development, lead Husserl to claim
is perhaps the most appropriate and most basic sense of entelechy and the
ultimate sense in which the divine idea is "founding of everything and God is the entelechy and outside of him there is "nothing"; he is
making everything possible." The ultimate metaphysical consideration for the all-forming. And the irrational material (Stoff) is not some-
transcendental phenomenology is the ground of the facticity of transcen- thing made but precisely that: stuff. And the world has its being
dental subjectivity as not a being or essence and as the source of possible from out of God and is otherwise "nothing" and God is only as
and real values (Hua III/l, §58).30 The facticity here is that of the primal the guiding and besouling principle of perfection.
presencing as the foundation of inner-time consciousness. The phenom- (F124/241b)
enological task, Husserl claims, is to immerse oneself in the hyletic factic-
ity and in the essence of the irrational and rational ingredients found there In effect, one aspect of what one does in the analyses of the proto-
(F124/40b-41a). The upshot of this analysis in summary is: rationality of inner-time consciousness and original passive synthesis is to
show how "from below God creates the world in a perpetual creating."31
Each of our hyletic data is already a "developmental product,"
and therefore it has a hidden intentionality which refers back to a
IV
synthesis. Everything refers back to a prot hyle which is a com-
pletely undifferentiated material (Stoff) and to primal-constitutive It is clear that for Husserl the absolute divine idea, indeed, the idea of the
processes with intentional motivations which belong therein. But Good, is not merely an ideaUty which as such is ineffective as a formative
all development is permeated by guiding "ideas". causaUty in nature. Nor is it an empirical natural reaUty or a reaUty in the
(F124/41b) sense of the spirits or minds of our experience. It, as the source or spring of
aU being, is a reaUty in a new sense, a super- or trans-reality (see E III 4, and
Husserl's ultimate analyses of the foundations of subjectivity in inner-time Hua XXVIII, 181). Husserl is clearly drawn to Aristotle's concept of ent-
consciousness did not lead him to the position of Bergson (of Creative elechy and even to his nouspoetikos (Hua XXVIII, 182), as weU as Leibniz's
Evolution) for whom an original sense of temporality becomes the sole "myth of a central monad out of which aU monads fulgurate" (Hua XXVIII,
source of form and creative power. Rather, at the ultimate foundation, he 182). Indeed, Husserl seems to move toward a synthesis of aU three concepts.
sees this "hyletic" dimension of "temporaUty" in continuity with its devel- There are numerous questions which this position raises. What is
opment and telos and sees it as always already under the sway of "proto- evident is that coeval with an entelechial principle is a hyletic one. These
rationality" and hidden intentionalities (F I 24/41b). The question, "How together form the founding principles of what Husserl hesitantly refers to
can the Idea effectively function in the material realm?" is answered not as "absolute substance." 32 The divine is featured, of course, not as the
by a theory of participation (methexis) but by showing how what conceptu- hyletic principle but rather as the entelechial principle. It goes in advance
aUy is not the idea, hyletic facticity, is nevertheless pervaded already by an and does not have its foundation in the hyletic dimension. Yet it never
informing of the Idea. This dimension of primal sensibility and originary exists independently of it but rather, along with it, is a constitutive
synthesis is not that from which alone form arises, forma ex materia (as in "moment," a coeval principle, of "absolute substance."

260 261
J

L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

The transcendental phenomenological consideration which would elechy or soul of the universe, the world, or "all of monads," must be
establish that the entelechial principle is also an egological one must be understood as a necessary aspect of the divine's Ufe. Does the divine life
here neglected. Suffice it here to say that the ultimate principle of the itself develop in its enabUng the universe to develop? So it would seem,
primal presencing is never merely accounted for as hyle. It is also always but the evidence for Husserl's acceptance of this view is not overwhelm-
"egological," but in a way prior to any I-center of acts (C 10/24).33 If this ing. In speaking, perhaps metaphorically, of the "divine life," Husserl
be so, and given his thesis of the immortaUty and unbeginning character of envisaged it as one "which would continuously posit true goals and would
the primal streaming (cf. Hua XI, 377-381),34 Husserl must also entertain progress from true goals to true goals" (F124/86-87). This is a fuller sense
the thesis that there is some kind of a coincidence of the divine intellectus we may give to our earlier remark that the divine life is essentially infinite
agens/entelechy with the wakeful human monad; this is a dark, unthema- (a "bad infinity" for some philosophers!). There are yet other suggestive
tized aspect of his theology.35 texts to which we may here call attention.
Furthermore, because for Husserl entelechy foremostly arises as a prin- In a text where he speaks of the divine as not the all of monads but as
ciple in the constitution of transcendental subjectivity, Conrad-Martius's the "entelechy functioning with it, as the idea of the infinite telos of devel-
claim that it is neither something ideal nor mental but a tertium ponendum opment," Husserl refers to the share of each monad in the "self-realization
holds less force. That is, whereas, for Conrad-Martius, entelechy is the process of the Godhead." Thus the divine is not only the entelechy of the
"objectively meaningful or purposeful" or a "pure objectivity of meaning- world, but, in the actuation of the monadic potency of the world, the
realization" - and therefore neither a mere idea nor a subjectivity - for divine's own life is actuated, and, seemingly, the world's monadic potency
Husserl, because entelechy is the foundation of transcendental subject- would thus be the divine's own potentiality. He writes of the participation
ivity, which itself is the foundation of being, it is a supreme principle which in the divine's self-actuation as a communication of monads through the
can be no less than mind and in no way a created or constituted realm as is sedimentation of each of their actions and lives in the embyronic monadic
the entelechy ultimately for Conrad-Martius. 36 To what degree and nucleus (Keimzellenmonade) for each newly born monad (Hua XV,
whether it has always been fully "mind" and "subjectively meaningful" - 609-610).38 Another text asks, but does not explicitly answer
and not merely "objectively meaningful" - could perhaps receive the
beginnings of an answer by a consideration of Husserl's transcendental whether and to what extent the absolute being can be regarded
idealism for which mind is the diaphanousness of being and its inseparable and recognized as an existing God or as the self-development of
correlate. Such a lengthy discussion, however, is not possible here.37 the idea of God in factual existence whether there can be an
The material or hyletic principle is reminiscent of Leibniz's theory of absolute point, an absolute goal in the sense of a being at rest, or
the "confusedness" of pre-articulated perceptions in as much as it has to of an always abiding flow amidst formations which remain always
do with the realm of the continuous indeterminate unbegun and undying the same; or whether it belongs to the essence of the existing
"flow" prior to acts. The dormant and dull forms of consciousness serve as Godhood, that it be the development of levels in such a manner
a basic analogate for the undying and unbegun Urhyle as a realm of poten- that an ultimate level of value is inconceivable? In such a case the
tiaUty to be actuated or informed by egological and teleological principles highest value which is thinkable is such only in the progression of
(see, e.g., Hua IX, 486-487). In such a Leibnizian reconstruction, rudimen- an endless development of levels?
tary forms of wakefulness or ego emerge out of a prior dormant state
wherein there is not yet self-awareness and delineation of experiences. In Would we not then come to the Aristotelian metaphysics, there-
this prior state, the I as a central pole around which experiences gather is fore to the poioun, as an animating goal-idea, which at the same
not yet "there" because there is not yet any (act of) "experience" but only time, would have to be grasped as a Platonic Idea? But still it
an undifferentiated, unbegun, and unending "flow." That is, there is only would not be this metaphysics in so far as it would not posit, prop-
dynamis (see, e.g., Hua XIV, 49, 53). In this view, the delineation or defi- erly speaking, an ideal goal (in the sense of the schema of the
niteness of the world is dependent on the actuation and holding sway completed tree as the limiting goal of development).
(Walten) of a divine entelechy or idea of an absolute rational all of "I's" (Hua XXVIII, 226)
which quickens both by awakening into an egological form as weU as by
beckoning to the ideal all of "I's" (see, e.g., Hua XI, 436). Although Husserl may have been encouraged, if not influenced by,
If the divine entelechy is understood, not in Aristotle's first sense (pure Driesch's writings to conceive of the divine as entelechy, he probably was
actuaUty), but in his second sense and therefore, Aristotle, as first ent- not impressed with Driesch's repetition of the traditional procedure of

262 263
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

projecting human or mundane categories onto the divine. In one text (K as I have tried to show in some detail in The Person and the Common Life:
III 1 VIII4-9), he criticizes attempts of Aristotle (and recent followers, as Studies in a Husserlian Social Ethics (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992), Husserl
Brentano) in whose conception of the world as an organism there is an aspired to develop a "universal voluntarism," i.e., an extended sense of will, to
cover both the understanding of the foundations of consciousness as well as
appeal to a mundane teleology in order to derive a divine mind. Such
properly voluntary agency. Texts such as in Hua XV, 378 ff. show how he was
attempts do not take their evidence from where teleology is directly given prepared to extend the concept of will to all cosmic Ufe. In Hua XXVII, 94
but rather tend to remain oblivious of an account of the world such as his Husserl ties the concept of entelechy to an effective Ideal which is not merely
own that takes its bearings from the immanent teleology of subjectivity. ideal but a universal will - central themes of both Schopenhauer and the later
The point Husserl wants to make is not that the appropriate procedure Schelling.
is to take the teleology of subjectivity and to transpose it on the world and 4 See especially Hans Driesch, The Science and Philosophy of the Organism
(London: Adam and Charles Black, 1908), Vol. I and II. The second volume,
thus to derive God. The philosophical theologies in the AristoteUan and pp. 365-73, contains Driesch's theological speculations. He holds that there is
objective, regional ontological mode make sense of the divine by recon- an encompassing but limited teleology throughout the universe, the foundation
structing it from the manifest realm of human personaUty which becomes of which is a "primary entelechy" in (not of) the universe which did not create
the way to understand the teleology in nature. 39 God, thereby is accounted all reality but ordered certain parts of it. Driesch acknowledges a kind of
for in terms of human subjectivity. But, Husserl states, the actual task is to "dualism of hyle and nous" and conceives the primary entelechy as a demiurge
whose intelligibility transcends all science by being its eternal goal. The
account for subjectivity as originating in God. Thus, Husserl sees the task Husserl-Chronik, ed. Karl Schuhmann (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977),
of philosophy to account for the divine as the source and beginning of pp. 139, 140, 186, and 212, contains some indications of the contact between
humanity by way of showing how subjectivity originates in the divine Husserl and Driesch; Schuhmann's forthcoming edition of Husserl's correspon-
rather than being a metaphorical version of humanity and humanity's rela- dence reveals the admiration Husserl had for Driesch's writings. In a letter to
tionship to the world. Driesch (July 18, 1918) Husserl confesses that Driesch's ontology of develop-
ment is of special value because he (Husserl) has not worked out any concepts
It is nevertheless, the concept of entelechy - originaUy a regional ontolog- or insights of his own on these matters and Driesch is the only one from whom
ical category but which, with some modifications, for Husserl, functions he can learn something about the ontology of development. For an Aristotelian
equally well in the transcendental constitutional dimensions - which serves presentation of entelechy and response to Driesch, see Francois Nuyens,
as the prevaUng concept in Husserl's accounting for the divine as the source L'Evolution de la Psychologie d'Aristote (Louvain: L'Institut Superieur de
and beginning of humanity and indeed of the entire "aU of monads." Philosophie, 1948), especially pp. 73-78.
5 Cf. Cicero's determination of Aristotle's entelechy as "a kind of continuous
and enduring motion (quasi quondam continuatam motionem et perennem)" in
Notes Tusculan Disputations 1,10.
6 Rupert Sheldrake, The Presence of the Past: Morphic Resonance and the Habits
1 Among the texts which are especially suggestive are Hua XXVIII, 174-82, of Nature (New York: Vintage, 1988), see all of ch. v but especially 83 ff.
225-30; Hua XV, 380-381, 610; B I 4, 52 ff.; F I 24, 41b; and B IV 6, 105. I 7 Sheldrake, 91.
would like to thank Professor Samuel IJsseling of the Husserl-Archives in 8 For a clear statement of more recent literature and theory, see Sheldrake, op.
Louvain for permission to quote from Husserl's Nachlass. cit.
2 Hedwig Conrad-Martius, Selbstaufbau der Natur: Entelechien und Energien 9 For Driesch, see, e.g., Vol. I of The Philosophy and Science of the Organism.
(Munich: Kosel Verlag, 1961), 81. Conrad-Martius was one of Husserl's early For discussion, see Sheldrake and Conrad-Martius; also CH. Waddington, The
and brilliant students at Gottingen. My presentation of the eidetics of entelechy Nature of Life (London: Unwin, 1963).
is indebted to her. For Hegel, Sdmmtliche Werke (Glockner, ed.) XIV, 296. As 10 Driesch, Science and Philosophy of the Organism, Vol. II, 140.
is well known, Plotinus's philosophy wrestles with fundamental metaphysical 11 Waddington, 65.
and theological themes in Plato and Aristotle. In particular, his wedding of 12 See Selbstaufbau, passim and her Bios und Psyche (Hamburg: Classen and
forms to the realm of nous (e.g., in Enneads V, 9) focuses these issues. In V, 9, Goverts,1949),llff.
6 he wrestles with the problem of preformism, how all the parts are undistin- 13 Conrad-Martius, 57.
guished in the whole of the seed. In III, 8,1 ff., he discusses how the formative 14 Conrad-Martius, 55 ff.
entelechial principles, the logoi, operate both immanent within and transcend- 15 Conrad-Martius, especially 63-88.
ent to organisms by a unique kind of silent but effective "contemplation." 16 See the rich writings of Andrew Ushenko for these topics, especially his Power
3 Friederich Paulsen's Introduction to Philosophy (New York: Henry Holt, 1895) and Events (New York: Greenwood, 1969; reprint of the 1946 Princeton
sketches a Schopenhauer-inspired "universal voluntarism" (113 ff. and 228 ff.) edition). Also, Eugene Gendlin, especially Focusing (New York: Bantam.
in which all the motions of the cosmos may be understood as Will whose ends 1988).
meet in the life of God and his "self realization or entelechy will be the ground 17 Experience and Judgment (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973),
and end of all things" (229). Young Husserl was fond of Schopenhauer; later, 80-81.

264 265
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND M E T A P H Y S I C S E N T E L E C H Y IN T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

18 Experience and Judgment, 82. which God constitutes himself as creator of the world in the conscious life of
19 Parenthetically, it may here be remarked that Husserl's philosophy of nature humans. God constituted as the universal principle of an ego which permeates
centers in a hylomorphism and in the problem of determining in what sense the all absolute subjects, at first in a passive manner" (A V 21/19).
primal hyle may be said to be able to be conceived with or without spiritual for- 28 In this short space there are numerous issues which I can only allude to. My
mations. For the person in the natural attitude the world never is present as a own sense of the matter is that Bruno Bauch's wrestlings with Kant's denial of
pure physis without spiritual formations or besoming. But in what sense is the the regulative idea as being in any way constitutive (for Kant only faule Ver-
besouling resident in nature? Whereas for pre-scientific humans the world was nunft, KRV B 717, would want to make of the regulative idea of God also a
suffused with souls, the rise of natural science has involved a de-spiritualization constitutive idea) serve as a rich Gesprdchspartner to Husserl's ultimate theo-
of the world. Modern thinking is attuned to the notion that the animation of logical meditations. See both his Immanuel Kant (Berlin and Leipzig: de
nature is a result of human constitution. But organic being discloses itself as a Gruyter, 1921), 462-63 and his Die Idee (Leipzig: Reinicke, 1925), 92ff. I know
realm in which subjectivity holds sway in an objective, i.e., non-conscious, non- of no direct influence and doubt that there was any. But perhaps Heinrich
intentional, manner, i.e., as entelechy. For Husserl, cf. below, §§IV-V, there is Rickert, a teacher of Bauch, and quite thoroughly studied by Husserl, is a con-
a primal stuff or hyle which is the core-substrate of all spiritual formations, nection. Rickert's life-long theme of the logic and theory as inseparable from
untimately of the divine entelechy of all entelechies. A V 21, 26b-32b is a rich values, in spite of Husserl's legitimate and sustained criticism of Rickert, finally
discussion of these matters. succeeded in impressing Husserl insofar as he subsumed all ideas and theory
20 Andre" de Muralt, The Idea of Phenomenology: Husserlian Exemplarism, trans. under the idea as a teleological consideration. I touch briefly on some of these
Garry L. Breckon (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1974), 38. I am matters in "Divine Truth in Husserl and Kant: Some Issues in Phenomenologi-
indebted to de Muralt's discussion in these pages. cal Theology," which appears in The Phenomenology of Truth Proper to Reli-
21 de Muralt, 51. Cf. the following text of Husserl: "Actual science is therefore gion, ed. Daniel Guerriere (Albany: SUNY, 1990). See also my "Axiology as
science in the strict sense only in so far as it corresponds to the pure idea of the Form of Purity of Heart: A reading of Husserliana XXVIII," Philosophy
science and corresponds more closely to the idea of the pure science of that Today 34:3 (1990), 214.
general form which is prescribed through the regional category to which the 29 For this reason we can say the divine is di-polar, i.e., it is constitutive of the
factual existent being is ordained" (Hua XXVIII, 178). subjectivity of the aU of monads as well as being the teleological ideal pole-
22 May we say that the infinitely determinable fringe or horizon is the same as idea. See Hua III/l, §§ 52 and 58 as well as my "A Precis of an Husserlian
"the idea?" There are many facets to this issue which we cannot discuss here. Philosophical Theology," in Essays in Phenomenological Theology, ed. Steven
Whereas horizon and the idea may both be said to be apperceived and the Laycock and James Hart (Albany: SUNY, 1986), 134-42.
same referent of the appreception, the presencing of the idea as idea requires 30 For a study of these "metaphysical" matters, a terminus technicus in Husserl,
the intervening acts which disclose the idea as that which withdraws from view see "A Pr6cis of an Husserlian Philosophical Theology," 98-109 and 118-34.
and holds sway as the infinitely determinable horizon of all acts and all bringing 31 See Husserl-Chronik, 295.
into view. That is, in order to appreciate the idea as the ideaUty which presents 32 See "A Precis..."
us with infinite tasks, one must engage in finite tasks which aim at the achieve- 33 See "A Pr6cis ..., 129-45.
ment of the ideal. World/horizon, however, as the apperceived "external 34 I have wrestled with this in "Phenomenological Time: Its Religious Signific-
horizon" may be present (co-present and co-meant) even in passive synthetic ance," forthcoming in Time and Religion, ed. J. N. Mohanty and A. N. Baslev
achievements as gazing, perusing, etc. Which is to say that it may be present (Leiden: Brill, 1992).
without the acts which attempt to make present the possibilities hinted at by 35 Note the willingness of Husserl, in the context of accounting for authentic reli-
world/horizon. gious experiences, to speak of an "original experienced relation to God in
23 See de Muralt, especially 40, and 122-23. which the subject of this intuition knows himself to be addressed not by an
24 Cf. Person and the Common Life. external God who stands over against him and [in which the subject] knows
25 See the discussion of Donna M. Orange, Peirce's Conception of God, Peirce himself determined to be the bearer of a communicated revelation. Rather, he
Studies, N. 2 (Lubbock, Texas: Institute for Studies in Pragmatism, 1984), 70 ff. knows God as intuited in himself as originally one with him. Therefore he
26 For the distinction between exact and morphological essences, see Hua III, §74 knows himself as an embodiment of the divine light itself and so as a mediator
and Hua VI, §41a. See the fine discussion of Robert Sokolowski, "Exact of the message of the divine being (Wesens) from out of a content of the divine
Science and the World in Which We Live," in Lebenswelt und Wissenschaft in nature (Wesens) implanted in him" (Hua XXVII, 65).
der Philosophie Edmund Husserls, ed. Elizabeth Stroker (Frankfurt am Main: 36 Conrad-Martius' view that the essence-entelechies are created finds a notewor-
Klostermann, 1979), 92ff. thy restatement in Robert Sokolowski's theory of creatio ex nihilo as a creation
27 On other occasions he noted that the primal "I" is uniquely unique, i.e., not in even of the necessities we experience in the world. See The God of Faith and
the sense that it has a unique spatial-temporal point of reference, nor as a Reason (South Bend: Notre Dame, 1982), especially ch. ii and v; this elaborates
unique individual which profiles the form of its similarity or commmonness. ch. xv of his masterful Presence and Absence (Bloomington: Indiana University
The unique primal I is not individual or similar. See B 114/XI, 24; cf. Hua XV, Press, 1978). But in Conrad-Martius the necessities of nature, i.e., the "essence-
373-74; Hua VI, 188/184-5; A V 5/8. This obviously has symmetry with the entelechies," are dwelt on at length and are argued to account for the total
divine idea which, as divine, is also referred to as, in some sense, "I": "Genesis: being and essence of the cosmos and, like Thomist angels, are claimed to have
the way of the evolution of humanity to God. The necessary motivation in no intrinsic potency to non-being. See as a supplement to Der Selbstaufbau der

266 267
L I F E - W O R L D , E T H I C S , H I S T O R Y , AND METAPHYSICS

Natur, her other works especially Die Zeit but also: Der Raum, Schriften III,
and Die Geistseele des Menschen - all published by Kosel in Munich. For a syn-
thesis and overview, see my Hedwig Conrad-Martius' Ontological Phenom-
enology (Unpublished Dissertation, University of Chicago Divinity School,
1972). Of course for Husserl, these necessities are part of the divine entelechy
itself, what he once called intellectus ipse (A V 21), and they would seem, like
Plato's demiurge, to have to face the monadic hyletic dimension with persua- ]
sion not omnipotence. This accounts for the inevitable surds and irrationalities
of the world.
37 Cf. my "Being's Mindfulness: The Noema of Transcendental Idealism," in
Phenomenology of the Noema, ed. John J. Drummond and Lester Embree
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992). See also my "Phenomenological Time: Its ReU-
gious Significance."
38 My interest in this speculation has been recently reactivated by Rupert Shel-
drake's Presence of the Past and his notion of "morphic resonance."
39 William Stern, in his Die MenschUche Personlichkeit (Leipzig: Johann Ambrio-
sius Barth Verlag: 1917/1923) used the concept of entelechy for "the tendency
and ability of the person to realize himself (i.e., the system of self-posited
goals).'-' But there does not seem to be any question of influence here.

268

You might also like