You are on page 1of 15

Angelaki: Journal of Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

A TIME FOR DISSONANCE AND NOISE

David Cunningham

To cite this article: David Cunningham (2003) A TIME FOR DISSONANCE AND NOISE, Angelaki:
Journal of Theoretical Humanities, 8:1, 61-74, DOI: 10.1080/09697250301199

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/09697250301199

Published online: 09 Jun 2010.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 170

View related articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 8 number 1 april 2003

it is a history, it is our history, and it is to us


that this has not ceased to happen. We must
still be absolutely modern.
Jean-Luc Nancy1

n a talk first given to a Norwegian conference


I on contemporary art and the function of
critique, published in Angelaki 4.3 (1999),
Simon Critchley argues that music “is no simple
lapse back into the pre-discursive … [I]t rather
produces an endless effort of evaluation, cogni-
david cunningham
tion and judgement … Musical experience is
both pre- and post-reflective” (“Sounding
Desire” 129). Critchley’s guide here is Adorno, A TIME FOR
as he acknowledges early on in the piece,
although given that his central subject is the
DISSONANCE
black “trip hop” artist Tricky, this might well be AND NOISE
considered ironic. (If Adorno had not had the
good fortune to die when he did, such music on adorno, music, and the
would no doubt have finished him off.)
Nonetheless, as Critchley rightly asserts, what-
concept of modernism
ever Adorno’s own “inexcusable ignorance and
elitism,” as regards forms like jazz, if one is to in fact, precisely Adorno’s philosophical concep-
avoid “collapsing into some sort of vapid post- tion of modernism, actually quite different from
modernist inversion of the high into the low,” that articulated by Greenberg, which remains of
then it is Adorno’s claims for the “critical and the utmost importance for critical reflection on
emancipatory function of art” that still provide contemporary art and music, including so-called
the best starting point for any “evaluation, cogni- “mass art.” However, it will also be my argument
tion and judgement” of contemporary musical that the condition of this “importance” must be
forms and practices (123).2 a theoretical disentangling of Adorno’s general
Explicitly connecting Adorno’s “elevation of (abstract) conception of modernism – as
certain forms … of aesthetic production” with something like an immanent dynamic logic of
Clement Greenberg’s theorisation of “aesthetic artistic production or a structure of temporal
modernism” in painting, Critchley asserts a need experience – from the particular objective forms
to move beyond “the now strangely démodé of “aesthetic production” with which he came
conflict between modernism and postmod- (more or less exclusively) to associate it in his
ernism” (123). While I certainly have no wish to postwar writings. What is at stake, in general, in
re-activate such debates – stale as they are – it such a disentanglement is, for reasons that will
will be my contention in what follows that it is, hopefully become obvious, best traced through

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/03/010061-14 © 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd and the Editors of Angelaki
DOI: 10.1080/0969725032000093609

61
dissonance and noise
Adorno’s theories of modern music; I will case of] a composer as immune to the charge
discuss these theories, predominantly, in relation of modernism as Anton Bruckner … [h]is
to Aesthetic Theory and the essay in Prisms enti- symphonies pose the question how the old is
tled simply “Arnold Schoenberg,” before moving after all still possible, which is to say as some-
on in the latter part of this paper to discuss the thing new; the question testifies to the irre-
sistibility of the modern … That the category
possible applications of Adorno’s concept of
of the new cannot be brushed off as art-alien
modernism – beyond his own self-imposed sensationalism is apparent in its irresistibility.
restrictions – in the “evaluation, cognition and (19–20)
judgement” of so-called “non-art” or “popular”
forms. For Adorno, this quite simply is the situation or
The importance of Schoenberg, not only to experience of “modernity” – understood as the
Adorno’s views on music but to his critical philos- non-identity of modernity and tradition – and
ophy as a whole, is well documented. Martin Jay, one which is, irresistibly, shared by proponents
for example, suggests that Adorno’s own thought of both modernism and traditionalism. As he
might plausibly be described as “an ‘atonal’ writes of Bruckner, his desire for the “eternal” is
philosophy deeply indebted to the compositional “substantial exclusively as modern and in oppo-
techniques of the Schoenberg school” (28). sition to the modern” (ibid. 192). In this sense
Nonetheless, more recent accounts have rather (if only in this sense), Bruckner is as much
tended to pass over the specific influence that a “modern” composer as is Schoenberg.
Adorno’s encounter with the musical “avant- Modernism, however, would be understood as
garde” had on his aesthetic theory, opting instead that specifically affirmative articulation of the
to place him within the context of debates ineliminable non-identity of modernity and tradi-
surrounding the visual arts in particular.3 Peter tion, for which “the modern” is “not a chrono-
Osborne, for example, in an excellent account of logical concept but a Rimbaudian postulate of an
Adorno’s understanding of the avant-garde, art of the most advanced consciousness” (ibid.
rightly states that dissonance and the new consti- 33). This is where Adorno’s conception of
tute the two pivotal elements within his concep- modernism has to be distanced from that gener-
tion of modernism, yet nowhere does he refer to ically defined “aesthetic modernism” with which
the particular musical meaning from which the Critchley implicitly associates it. For modernism
notion of dissonance derives in his work.4 here is neither something like a chronologically
Now, by contrast, it will be my claim that by delineated “period style” of art history – to
too hastily detaching the concept of dissonance which a “postmodernist” style might be
from its specific “roots” in an analysis of musi- opposed – nor a specific medium-based
cal form, one may lose sight of a valuable key to “aesthetic” project with the kind of regulating
understanding both the strengths and weak- Idea (of “purity”) assigned to it by Greenberg.
nesses of Adorno’s theory of modernism and of Nor, and this will be the substance of the argu-
the avant-garde. At the same time, this speci- ment developed below, does it, in itself, insist
ficity must indeed be seen to mark, for Adorno, upon any necessary division between “high” and
in a particular form – that is, dissonance’s criti- “low” culture, to the extent that the situation of
cal relation to harmony – a general question of modernity is the common space for both. Rather,
how (what I will term) the non-identity of moder- in its most fundamental form, modernism should
nity and tradition is to be articulated affirma- be understood as identifying an abstract, but
tively. The crucial context for this question is set immanently manifested, temporal logic or
out in an early section of Aesthetic Theory: dynamic of artistic production that is not, in
since the mid-nineteenth century and the rise principle, restricted to any fixed objective refer-
of high capitalism, the category of the new has ent or particular “social” sphere.5 If the concept
been central … Since that moment no artwork of modernism (or indeed avant-garde) is to be
has ever succeeded that rebuffed the ever fluc- viewed as a cognitive category, the cognition it
tuating concept of the modern … Even [in the marks is radically historical – that is, historical

62
cunningham
beyond the hold of “historicism” – in such a way of that between modernity and tradition in
as to always displace any formation of it as a general (and across all the arts). It is in the light
determinate empirical category of art history.6 of this exemplarity that Schoenberg’s music
What has the potential to be cognitively experi- takes on such an important status in Adorno’s
enced or judged as modern (or avant-garde) is aesthetic theory.
radically variable, depending upon shifts and Nonetheless, and this is what I want initially
differences within the context in which it comes to investigate, there is at least one sense in which
forth. Schoenberg is a far from obvious example here.
With regard to music, the particular critical For there is more than a little substance to
moment of dissonance is thus presented, through Boulez’s somewhat provocative description of
the concept of modernism, as an immanent Schoenberg as a “traditionalist,” whose work is,
necessity of the temporal dynamic of musical despite its apparent radicalism, marked by the
development, deriving from “the dynamic of the “presence of the past, the continual awareness of
concept of harmony itself and ultimately from its re-exploiting a revered tradition, the intrusion of
insufficiency”; that is, from its incapacity to old forms” (Orientations 354–55). This, of
efface the non-identity of modernity and tradi- course, accords with the familiar portrait of
tion: “The rejection of the ideal of classicism Schoenberg as reluctant revolutionary, “an
is … the result of the coefficient of friction in explorer in spite of himself” (ibid. 326). And
harmony itself” (Aesthetic Theory 110). Since, certainly it is clear that Schoenberg himself
then, dissonance has concrete meaning only by understood his work as being in continuity with
virtue of its (non-identical) relation to tradition’s tradition in a way that does indeed seem rather
determination of harmony as an ideal, it is also closer to, say, Greenberg’s theorisation of the
inextricably connected to a concept of the new, avant-garde than that of Benjamin’s: “Many
in general, insofar as the destructive momentum people, instead of realising its evolutionary
of dissonance – and, thus, the experience of element, called it a revolution.”8 Adorno tries to
dissonance – can be sustained (that is, non-iden- accommodate this assertion while, at the same
tically repeated) only by the ongoing renewal of time, working against Schoenberg’s own self-
its non-identity to what is encountered as proper understanding of the development of atonality as
to music within the cultural present. As such, the evolutionary continuity. The attempt to do so
concept of dissonance, in the more expansive involves a reworking of the relation between
sense in which Adorno employs it, must not be tradition and modernity which maintains the
understood as an invariant “property” or “char- connection to tradition that Schoenberg himself
acteristic” of a constant musical referent (e.g., insists upon, while simultaneously undermining
particular harmonic relations or intervals), but the (more Greenbergian) “notion that progress in
must be connected, in its historicity, to the artistic technique proceeds in a steady, so to
general theory of what Adorno calls the most speak, organic flow” (“Schoenberg” 154). The
advanced artistic material, where “material” relation between tradition and modernity is not
refers to “everything that artists encounter about to be found in a quasi-organic development of a
which they must make a decision” (ibid. 148). continuous movement from one to the other,
Both critical reflection and composition require which would take place within the progressive
a dynamic encounter with the “congealed logic of the same, but in – to restate the point –
history” – the inherited cultural forms, struc- their critical relation of non-identity at the pres-
tures and techniques – immanent in “artistic ent. It is in this way (and only in this way) that
material”; an encounter which takes place within Schoenberg can be, for Adorno, at the same time
an always altered present where every “repetition both “heir to the tradition” (proving his fidelity
of the sign of modernity is different.”7 Thus, through his “betrayal”) and the exemplary avant-
crucially for Adorno, the particular dynamic gardiste, who, while “inflicting the most deadly
non-identical relation of dissonance and harmony blows on authority,” seeks, simultaneously, “to
can, in broad terms, be understood as exemplary defend the work” before it (ibid. 151).

63
dissonance and noise
Despite his passionate attachment to any attempt to use the twelve-note row as the
Schoenberg’s work, Adorno is, then, signifi- basis for a system around which a new constancy
cantly, not unaware of the reasoning behind and continuity might be founded, suggesting, at
Boulez’s rather stronger depiction of Schoenberg one point, that “the stubborn loyalty of the later
as “respectful” traditionalist, “haunted by Schoenberg to the method, as a guarantee of
History (with a capital h) and by an obsessive comprehensive totality, merely deferred the
desire for order and classification based on aporia.”9 Such deferral would, Adorno continues,
absolute models” (Orientations 358). For Boulez, in denying self-reflection, “cripple the very
Schoenberg’s composition is marked by a impulse that produced the system in the first
“tendency to shrink history … in the hope of place,” through “the rejection of all that is other-
achieving absolute continuity” (ibid. 359); a wise, of anything not already analytically assimi-
search for the “continuity” of an “ideal classi- lated” (“Schoenberg” 166–67). Like modernist
cism,” “eternal law” or “codification” which architecture’s white walls, in seeking to resist the
would deny what Boulez describes as “the hold of the ever-same – as manifested in the tran-
constant reconsideration of what is transitory that sitoriness of “fashion” – serialism risks simply
the artist must accept, and with it reconsideration re-inscribing itself within it on another level, as
of his own beliefs and attitudes” (ibid. 327, 329). a “new” tradition. This is precisely the kind of
Boulez’s phrasing recalls, no doubt intentionally, impasse with which, for example, Greenberg
what is often cited as the founding document of found himself faced, in his particular defence of
artistic modernity as a whole, Baudelaire’s “The “aesthetic modernism” in the mid-1960s, when,
Painter of Modern Life,” where, as is well known, as Osborne puts it, “historical experiences
Baudelaire attempts to resolve the non-identity of imposed themselves at the level of artistic form
modernity and tradition through a “distillation” which, by virtue of their claim on the present,
of “the eternal from the transitory” (“Painter” could no longer be ignored.”10 It is, however,
12). Viewed as a reading of Baudelaire’s essay, within this remorseless logic that Adorno, unlike
Boulez’s comments on Schoenberg emphasise the Greenberg, seeks a fissure. Simon Jarvis
traditionalism still inherent in Baudelaire’s summarises his resulting argument well:
notion. For extended beyond Baudelaire’s own
tentative dialectic, one legacy of this is, as Mark There is … a dialectical, rather than a unilin-
Wigley has argued in relation to the dominant ear, relationship between tradition and the
new … What crucially distinguishes the really
practices of modernist architecture, that the
new from the abstract novelty … is that the
“modern is advertised as the return of transcul-
really new work is made in undiminished
tural and trans-historical truth … In the very awareness of the possibilities afforded by tradi-
name of modernity, time must be brought to a tion rather than by a simple forgetting of tradi-
standstill”; practically, change thus becomes tion. (136)
fixed, codified into a set of constant and invariant
signs of the modern – “once architecture has This distinction is derived from Hegel’s differ-
changed, there cannot be very much additional entiation between abstract and determinate nega-
mobility” – of which, for architecture, the tion. Yet the question I would want to ask is to
supposed purity of the white wall is clearly what extent the “awareness of the possibilities
symbolic (“White Out” 163, 155, 171). afforded by tradition,” which distinguishes the
If this “desire for order and classification” is “really new,” actually does concern possibilities
what Boulez suspects in Schoenberg, it is, afforded by tradition, in the way this phrasing
nonetheless, the case that the apparent difference might be taken to suggest. It is important to
in judgement between Boulez and Adorno is emphasise that “tradition,” “past” and “history”
much smaller than it may seem. For although are not synonyms; tradition is rather a particular
Adorno largely exempts Schoenberg himself (or temporalisation of history. (Benjamin’s attempt,
rather his works) from the kind of “classicism” for example, to conjoin present and past in the
Boulez ascribes to him, he echoes his critique of “now” and “then” of the messianic is precisely

64
cunningham
an attempt to work against the forms of trans- itself, which is obviously key to any understand-
mission of tradition.) For one might argue that ing of modernism as a temporal modality, but
the possibilities Jarvis evokes, following Adorno, the form of continuity within which this negation
are only critical possibilities by being, in a way, might be understood, insofar as it is entirely
received as non-traditional; that is, to paraphrase directed toward (or at least organised around) the
Benjamin, received in a manner other to their progressive dismantling of tonality as a specific
presentation by tradition, through the blasting mode of musical organisation. As Born states
apart of their transmission as anything like again, postwar “total” serialism characteristically
“heritage.” presented itself as an attempt “to purify the
Adorno knew this, of course, and as such the correct, rigorous direction of the avant-garde – a
above may well seem like mere terminological direction that was posed as absolute and
quibbling. Yet I want to suggest that there is inescapable” (ibid. 51).13 It is this implication of
something of significance here, to do with the way a single “inescapable” direction that Adorno
in which the “really new” is understood, in the tends to echo, by, on Peter Bürger’s reading,
particular exemplification Adorno makes of suggesting that there is, as an “authentic” neces-
Schoenberg, and the nature of the critical connec- sity, “only one material in a given epoch.”14 The
tion to a tradition it implies. It is at this point result would be, as Lyotard puts it in relation to
that I want to come back to the importance of the painting rather than music, the subtle judging of
particular role that the concept of dissonance any “true” non-identity at the present in terms of
plays in Adorno’s theory of modernism, with its apparent place within a narrative in which
regard to its specific musical meaning.11 The “[a]fter one pictorial work, another is necessary,
place of Hegel in Adorno’s argument is clearly permitted or forbidden. After one colour, this
crucial. Although Adorno refuses Hegel’s own colour; after this line, that one” (Inhuman 91).
teleological directing of determinate negation, on Yet, of course, Adorno is, at the same time, the
the conventional reading at least, toward the posi- theorist who asserts, against the more strident
tive result of the identity of identity and non- serialists, the dangers of a “rejection of all that is
identity, one might wonder if, at the same time, otherwise.”
he remains still too tied to an “orthodox” Matters are thus far from straightforward, but
Hegelian conception of history in the way in it seems to me that this tension in Adorno’s work
which he thinks what he calls the historical neces- relates, finally, back to the specific way in which
sity of dissonance. For there is a sense in which he develops his own well-known conception of
this conception of necessity works, even if only art’s autonomous status. On this point, almost all
retrospectively, to construct something like a critiques of Adorno have wildly missed the mark,
continuity of negation itself, in which the deter- insofar as the claim Adorno makes that “politics
minate critical movement underlying the progress has migrated into autonomous art” is not, as it is
of material from tradition comes to be inscribed all too often presented, a simple aesthetic “pref-
in the singular, thus returning to the unilinearity erence” or chosen theoretical “standpoint,” but is
of progress in another form by virtue of allowing understood as a historical and irresistible occur-
for only one true direction for artistic experimen- rence resulting from art’s social determination
tation (as negation) to take at any one time. (“Commitment” 194). Contra Greenberg, auton-
Now, despite Adorno’s own ambivalent atti- omy is produced out of the social relations which
tude to serialism, he did, clearly, share many of constitute “art.” It is not simply a property of the
the assumptions of its central postwar adherents object itself that would serve, invariably, to
in so-called “total serialism,” to the extent that, “elevate” certain forms of “aesthetic production”
as Georgina Born notes, “serialist principles (Aesthetic Theory 229). Autonomy is not, there-
[also] prescribe an aesthetic that is completely fore, somehow an option for cultural production.
antithetical to and so a negation of tonality” Conversely, as one critic writes from an Adornian
(Rationalizing Culture 48).12 The problem here perspective – arguing against the utopianist
concerns not this temporal logic of negation vision of an avant-garde sublation of art into life

65
dissonance and noise
famously outlined by Bürger15 – radical art aid critical reflection on recent cultural practices,
“cannot live, qua art, within the everyday as if indeed his social theory can be shown to be
everyday. Rather, qua art, it necessarily inter- “contestable” (as I, like Critchley, believe it can).
rupts the everyday, from within, on the basis of Adorno’s strength, I would argue in line with
the fact that it is always both autonomous and what has already been said, is, in principle, his
‘social fact.’”16 In fact it is a crucial advantage of expansive understanding of modernism as a
Adorno’s work that he displaces the kinds of general abstract temporal dynamic, his refusal to
absolutised dialectical oppositionality which are foreclose upon the indeterminacy of the future in
so evident, from entirely contrary positions, in the face of this abstraction, and, as such, his
both Bürger’s and Greenberg’s understandings of acknowledgement of its necessarily aporetic
the historical character of avant-garde practice. conceptual character which denies its reduction
Nonetheless, before exploring this further, it to any sort of empirical category or invariant,
should be conceded at this point that Adorno’s univocal project. Yet it also seems clear that
version of the history of modernity, in a more Adorno’s own extreme totalising account of capi-
straightforwardly periodising socio-historical talist development means, given the “palpable
sense, is undoubtedly problematic in another dependencies” (Aesthetic Theory 229) between
way, as Critchley rightly asserts, insofar as it is art and society that he himself insists upon, that
specifically built around what the latter describes there is, nonetheless, an unjustifiable limitation
as “the contestable – indeed, dubious – thesis of what might be potentially judged as truly new
that we inhabit totally administered societies, or experienced as avant-garde within the cultural
where the Lebenswelt contains no uncolonised present, which allows for the misplaced critical
moral practices that might function as sites of identification of his work with the kind of
resistance to instrumental rationality” (Very defence of aesthetic modernism to be found in
Little 155).17 Now, it seems to me, it is precisely someone like Greenberg.
this social theory of a movement toward the total In this respect, let me point to two issues
reification of all relations – and not the philo- which suggest the ways in which Adorno’s
sophical elaboration of modernism as a general restricted narrativisation of historical develop-
concept of aesthetic theory – which makes ment would indeed need to be complexified. In
Adorno’s work itself appear so démodé with the case of the first issue, as Witkin states, for
regard to radical artistic and musical practice Adorno, to compose or to listen “involves keep-
since the 1960s. The problem with the unilinear ing an appointment with history” (130). Yet, the
and totalising form of Adorno’s social theory is question is then: which history? It is here,
that it does, as Critchley recognises, finally result perhaps, that the theorisation of determinate
in a questionable equation between the historical negation as an “awareness of the possibilities
development of autonomy and the movement afforded by tradition” takes on, as I suggested
toward a kind of self-destructive formal hermeti- above, a more problematic aspect. In this light,
cism, because of his problematically totalising Adorno’s much-debated readings of jazz seem to
perception of the elimination of all social rela- me, for example, to be not simply a contingent
tions other than those determined by capital.18 subjective expression of Arnoldian distaste, but
(Capitalism, as a social structure, cannot be reflective of an incapacity to understand jazz in
reduced to the sole social determinant of capital relation to any history other than that of
itself, even if it sometimes seems like it.) European art music. As such, the harmonic inno-
Yet countering this should not be a question vations of something like be-bop could only
of asserting a facile populism or optimism appear to him as retrogressive. (See also, for
against Adorno’s supposed high-cultural elitism example, his cringe-inducing description of the
and pessimism. Rather, the question at this point African-derived banjo as an “infantile” instru-
must be to what extent Adorno’s more general ment.19) However, this fails to recognise the
conception of modernism, as an affirmative different way in which these innovations relate to
temporal logic of non-identity, may still serve to the particular history with which they are

66
cunningham
dynamically engaged. Although the “flattened tion of an exotic other, legitimated by dubious
fifth” of be-bop may, when interpreted musico- claims to accessibility.24 By contrast, a piece like
logically, look the same as developments already Can’s “Halleluwah,” for example, from their
established in nineteenth-century art music, 1972 album Tago Mago, collides together
quite simply it is not, because its own immanent Stockhausean harmonies and timbres with James
logic relates to the different harmonic structures Brown funk rhythms. Yet the result is not a
of the blues (which, in their use of note “bend- comforting Aufhebung or “synthesis” of the
ing” and microtonalities,20 have their own two – whatever that might mean – but a produc-
harmonic complexities with little counterpart in tive dislocating and energising of each through
European art music until the postwar period). To their critical juxtaposition, opening up new
take another example, Alan Licht has referred to creative possibilities.25)
the New York band Sonic Youth’s “embrace of Second, and this is my major point, the prob-
atonality” on mid-1980s records such as Bad lematic unilinearity of Adorno’s account of artis-
Moon Rising, Evol, and Sister (Licht 34). Yet tic development is, I think, to some extent
this should not be seen as a belated catching up implicit in the primary musical meaning
with, or borrowing from, early twentieth-century accorded to the very term dissonance itself, inso-
art music. For Sonic Youth’s “embrace of atonal- far as it tends to work, in Adorno, towards a
ity” is actually driven by an immanent produc- restriction of the dynamic of musical non-iden-
tive logic at work within a certain history of rock tity, and the “artistic material” with which it
itself, leading back through the likes of Richard works, to something like a programme of the
Hell and the Voidoids, Pere Ubu, The Stooges, progressive dismantling of the specific identity of
and Bo Diddley.21 It is therefore quite possible tonality as determined as an ideal by the classi-
for such innovations to be experienced in this cal tradition, reflecting, in this sense, like
context as avant-garde – as an interruptive shock Schoenberg himself (whose most important theo-
to continuity – when superficially similar retical writings were on the development of
constructions could no longer be experienced as harmony),26 the prioritisation of harmonic devel-
such in the context of art music’s history. opment (in a more limited musicological sense)
Moreover, the increasing cross-articulation of within that tradition itself from the historical
different histories – art, jazz, rock (and, from the emergence of equal temperament, at least,
1960s, African and Indian musics also) – would onwards. This has the effect of either marginal-
serve only to complicate this further, in what can ising other forms of experimentation, in the
be extremely productive ways, through the spheres, for example, of rhythm or timbre, or, as
particular interruption of one history by another. in total serialism, presuming that such spheres
(This notion of “interruption” needs to be can be assimilated to the same essential proce-
rigorously distinguished from any “vapid post- dures as those underlying the negation of tonal-
modernist inversion of the high into the low.” A ity. The most obvious result of this is a complete
variant upon the latter can be found in theorisa- dismissal of the possibility of avant-garde work
tions of the significance of minimalism as the and experience in relation to forms like rock or
form marking a break with the exemplary funk music – which are far more driven by
modernist “style” of serialism.22 Jameson’s timbral and rhythmic innovations than by
description is typical, presenting musical post- harmonic ones – as well as the difficulty one
modernism (after Cage) as the “synthesis of clas- would have in extending Adorno’s precise theo-
sical and ‘popular’ styles found in composers ries to account for that radical twentieth-century
such as Philip Glass” (my emphasis).23 This art music which does not follow on from the
conception of “synthesis” can all too easily pres- broadly Schoenbergian path of development and
ent itself as a kind of imperialistic sublation the experimental priorities it implies, e.g.,
through which high culture takes up “stylistic” Edgard Varèse, Terry Riley, La Monte Young or
elements of popular culture in order to rejuve- Harry Partch. (And, indeed, Cage would present
nate and reconsolidate itself through the absorp- a tricky case, as he was for Boulez also.)

67
dissonance and noise
In this respect, when read in conjunction with restricted to the path of a unilinear development,
Adorno, Jacques Attali’s notion of “noise” may even retrospectively. Benjamin is often opposed
provide a better conceptual framework for think- to Adorno on the basis of his comparative open-
ing a generality of musical non-identity than that ness to popular culture, but in fact the distance
of dissonance (at least as it is purely defined in between them on this point is, in a sense, not as
harmonic terms): “Subversion in musical wide as it can seem, given that Benjamin’s theo-
production opposes a new syntax to the existing risation of film is itself, I would argue, precisely
syntax from the point of view of which it is a theorisation of it in terms of its potential for
noise” (Noise 34). Regardless of the plausibility avant-garde experience. And, indeed, Adorno
or otherwise of Attali’s particular account of himself asserts his “complete approval” of
musical history, it is this definition of the new in Benjamin’s account of “the disenchantment of
musical production, as having “the nature of art.”30 As such, if Benjamin does have, in certain
noise,” which allows Attali to resist the restric- respects, the advantage here, it is not in terms of
tions implicit in Adorno’s conception of disso- the specifics of his understanding of film’s inher-
nance, thus making possible theorisations of ently revolutionary mass potential – which would
cultural forms like rock and free jazz as having a be very hard to maintain today (although some
revolutionary significance: “Both Cage and the have tried) – but because he does not prejudge
Rolling Stones, Silence and ‘Satisfaction’, where, in either generic or sociological terms,
announce a rupture in the process of musical avant-garde experience might be possible. In this
creation” (ibid. 137).27 Yet this comparative sense, for example, assessing the “legitimacy” of
breadth in Attali’s reference point reflects a definition of 1960s free jazz as avant-garde –
neither a simple populist call for a striving to Ornette Coleman, Albert Ayler, Sun Ra, Cecil
communicate,28 nor an anarchic and utopian Taylor, etc. – would involve a specific analysis of
vision of “anything goes.” As Attali reminds us, the character of its particular intervention within
noise “does not exist in itself, but only in rela- a particular field or historical moment and its
tion to the system within which it is inscribed” own implicit temporalisation of jazz history.31
(ibid. 26). In this sense, although he himself does Discussing Chinese modernism, in painting
not make the connection, Attali’s mobilisation of and film, Peter Osborne has recently argued that
a general concept of “noise” needs to be read it would be a mistake to regard such forms as
back into the temporal structure of experience “culturally specific variants or exotic indigenous
which is described by Adorno’s philosophical inflections of medium-specific modernisms
conception of modernism. For what is experi- conceptually defined in formal-stylistic terms by
enced cognitively as “noise” is precisely subject their Western counterparts” (Philosophy in
to historical variation, depending on the cultural Cultural Theory 60). Rather, he suggests, the
field within which it comes forth. “changes that the concept of modernism under-
It needs to be made quite clear, then, that goes as a result of its translation into ‘non-
this is not, in any sense, an argument for either Western’ contexts,” driven by the globalisation
the false utopianism of a total effacement of of capitalist culture, must be viewed as “histori-
the boundary between high and low culture, cally specific conjunctural relations, constructed
which Critchley associates with postmodernism, by the … terms of identification of particular
or the exchangeability and indifference of a rela- fields of negation” (ibid. 61, 60). As such, the
tivistic pluralism – which is that “eclecticism” “power of generalisation” exhibited by
whose “realism” is, as Lyotard notes, “that of modernism as a “philosophical concept” is
money”29 – because evaluation, cognition and nonetheless dependent for its “concrete mean-
judgement are precisely what is at stake in this; ing” upon “the delimitation of the received
the judgement of what is avant-garde or modern cultural field upon which, and within which, it
now. It is simply that this now cannot be reduced acts” (ibid. 59). Yet, in fact, as the above citation
to the unity of a single present time or social of free jazz shows, one does not necessarily have
space and its opening onto the future cannot be to look to “non-Western” forms and practices, in

68
cunningham
a literal geographical sense, in order to make such would seem to imply the opposite. Yet either
a point. The same is quite true within Western conclusion would fail to recognise the relation
cultures, where different practices and histories between autonomy and anti-art in Adorno’s
inhabit the shared space of modernity. In this theory, insofar as it is only this connection that
sense, there is no reason to suppose that the kind renders the autonomous work socially critical
of differentiation Adorno theorises between the rather than mere “social fact.” For if autonomy
articulations of the non-identity of modernity and is precisely not a transcendentalist separation of
tradition in, say, Bruckner and Schoenberg, the aesthetic (or a mere matter of artistic choice),
cannot be extended to cultural forms and prac- but radically historical, then its own renewal, in
tices other than those of the aesthetic modernism resistance to “stagnation,” depends upon its crit-
with which he himself is more or less exclusively ical engagement with what is already given. As
concerned. The différend – to borrow a term John Roberts puts it:
from Lyotard – between free jazz and the tradi-
tionalist presentation of jazz as black classical in order to distinguish itself from what has
music in the work of someone like Wynton become aesthetic, art is forced to expand into,
or reclaim, non-aesthetic experiences, forms or
Marsalis would be one potential example here.
practices (popular and discursive modes of
Alternatively, to follow up Critchley’s essay, one
attention, the ready-made, the textual etc.) …
could argue that the critical and emancipatory [A]nti-art is a transgression that autonomy
possibilities of Tricky’s music would open them- must undergo in order to reconstitute itself.
selves up to critical reflection, evaluation and (“After Adorno” 232)
cognition most obviously through their contrast
to the nostalgic reinforcing of an existing syntax Yet, for Adorno, this is not, as it is for Bürger,
apparent in something like Britpop (Oasis, Blur, a utopian vision of the dissolution of autonomy
etc.). Indeed, without such contrasts how would (into everyday life) – if it were it would simply
one “judge” or “evaluate” the “dislocating” destroy all possibility of critique itself – but
power of Tricky’s music, or its “original, innova- the condition of its renewal in an always
tive and experimental” character (“Sounding altered form, critically related to the situational
Desire” 129)? It is only some conception of context – what Osborne calls a “field of nega-
modernism – acknowledged or otherwise – which tion” – in which it emerges. Without this
would furnish the conditions of possibility for dynamic of renewal, autonomy relapses into the
such a process of “evaluation” and for a percep- repetition of tradition. As Adorno states in
tion of “emancipatory” potential through it (ibid. Aesthetic Theory, “art must go beyond its own
125).32 At any rate, unless autonomy is indeed concept in order to remain faithful to that
in line with certain reductive sociological concept. The idea of its abolition does it homage
approaches, to be restricted to very specific social by honouring its claim to truth” (29).
institutions and artistic disciplines, evaluation Nonetheless, as Roberts also notes, Adorno
would in each instance require, as a judgement of himself, as a result of his social theory, had such
possibility, detailed readings of particular works. an exaggerated concern about the threat of disso-
The task should thus be one not of sidestepping lution that he always risks disengaging autonomy
the question of the modern (as Critchley might from the temporality of newness which sustains
be taken to imply) but of re-interrogating it, in the process drastically restricting the possi-
Adorno’s exemplification of modernism in rela- bility of the new to a very limited formal domain,
tion to his own, more abstract, conceptualisation which allows for the misplaced identification
of its temporal form. with Greenbergian aestheticism. At the same
Adorno writes in Aesthetic Theory that with- time, this is, I think, the source of Adorno’s
out “the conception of anti-art … art is no longer impasse with serialism. Because, for Adorno,
thinkable” (29). This suggests a convergence serialism, developed from Schoenberg’s twelve-
with someone like Bürger and divergence from note row, is understood as the immanent musical
Greenberg, just as his defence of autonomy necessity of the postwar era, in its continuation

69
dissonance and noise
of the negation of harmony as a formal ideal, interchangeable terms. The ex-Henry Cow and
doubts about its fixing of models mean that the Pere Ubu drummer Chris Cutler argues, in his
possibility of newness itself is put in doubt. important book File Under Popular:
I would suggest that contemporary music is of
the battle for the immediate future of music
particular interest if we are to exceed Adorno’s will be fought out through the medium of
own limitations. Rather more so, in fact, than the recording. The qualities of this medium which
visual arts, with regard to which such issues are are useful to the status quo are already well
customarily debated. Much as I agree with his developed and constitute the imperatives of
central point, if one takes, for example, Roberts’ “mass culture,” mediated through the form of
formulation cited above – “in order to distinguish the commodity. The crucial point about this is
itself from what has become aesthetic, art is that its value to economic and political vested
forced to expand into, or reclaim, non-aesthetic interest is not so much expressive, as commer-
experiences, forms or practices” – it is clear that cial – and in some cases ideological – certainly,
this reflects the particular character of the leaving the profound and innate potential of
the medium for cultural and aesthetic expres-
“reclaiming” of “popular” forms prevalent within
sion essentially undeveloped. (33)
the visual arts since pop art, and which consti-
tutes at least one definition of the distinctive As Cutler recognises, the confusion apparent in
nature of “postmodernism” within that sphere. In many accounts of contemporary music relates to
this, the critical frisson of such “reclamation” is the ambiguities inherent within the term “pop
usually reliant upon a continuing situating of music” itself, which may be understood either in
popular culture as kitsch – at its most extreme in statistical terms, as a form actually “of the
someone like Jeff Koons – such as to enable the people” (like folk), or as something like “a
“vulgarity” of the advert or the comic strip to genus, definable ultimately by its means and
operate as a deflation of Greenbergian aestheti- relations of production, circulation, and
cism or of the “high cultural” aura of the gallery. consumption” (ibid. 9). It is clearly the latter
Yet what this does not allow for is in any real crit- definition which most demands our attention,
ical or emancipatory potential within those but even here, as Cutler goes on to note, further
cultural forms and practices which actually differentiation is required insofar as “popular
emerge out of the technologies of mass produc- forms which live for the market … and whose
tion itself, in their own right. (Film is, of course, role is to reinforce and hypnotise, are made out
a partial, and complex, exception here, develop- of the same stuff as those that struggle to liber-
ing, as it did, its own kinds of “high cultural” ate the communicative and aesthetic power of the
status fairly early on). Although, therefore, new media … and whose aim is to engage and
Roberts himself refers to “the expanded social reveal” (ibid. 14). Such a différend is not, of
content of autonomy” over the course of the post- course, absolute, yet it is of the utmost impor-
war era, what he risks eliding is the modernist tance for any cognition, evaluation and judge-
logic at work within something like (certain forms ment of the critical and emancipatory
of) popular music itself; a logic which is not possibilities of contemporary musical forms and
simply reducible to the repetition of the new as practices.
the ever-same that characterises commodity The advantages of Cutler’s approach are
production, and which may therefore, quite plau- apparent in the specific immanent logic it gives
sibly, be understood as autonomous in the to this music by virtue of its self-defining rela-
dynamic sense in which Roberts, following tion to the “new media” of tape and digital
Adorno, defines it, as a critique of “tradition” recording, electrification and amplification. It is
and a “challenge to the instrumentalities of this, too, which most obviously serves to mark
market and academy” (“After Adorno” 236–37). such music apart from the score-based aesthetic
It is as well to remember, in this light, that of the “classical” or “art” tradition to which
commodification and the mass production of Adorno remains so clearly tied in his under-
technologically reproduced music are not simply standing of dissonance.33 Cutler’s attempted

70
cunningham
breakdown of those factors which constitute the live. Yet the particular importance of pop music,
specific mode of production of pop – debatable I would argue, is in its immanent registerings of
as some of them may be in the details – thus this tension precisely by virtue of its intimate
deserves to form the basis for the future research relation to new media and to the productive
which must be undertaken in this area: mechanisms of commodity production. At the
same time, the condition of this registering is its
(i) its commitment to collective work, espe-
cially collective composition; (ii) its intimate own modernism, an ongoing reconstitution of its
relations with the new means of music produc- always incomplete autonomy through a dynamic
tion, particularly with electric instruments, of negation which poses a “challenge to the
electrification and the use of recording equip- instrumentalities of market and academy.”
ment; (iii) its elision of composition and A final point: with a few honourable excep-
performance, composer and performer – and a tions (mostly outside of the academy, like
propos of this; (iv) the profound status of Cutler), the study of “non-classical” music has
improvisation, both in the formation and re- tended to take two, equally limited, theoretical
creation of musical material; and (v) its roots forms; that is, either sociological accounts of
in a transformed folk music, the music of an
music as a mere soundtrack to the formation of
oppressed people. (Ibid. 10)
subcultural identity – abandoning qualitative or
Despite the shared Marxian vocabulary, Adorno critical judgement altogether – or rather simplis-
may seem an unlikely theoretical resource for tic discussions of aesthetic value of the type
extending Cutler’s analysis. Yet two points are reflected in the tediously recurring “Keats vs.
worth stressing here. First, Adorno is very Dylan” debates. Yet an “experience of critical
emphatic that the “culture industry” is not iden- evaluation” (“Sounding Desire” 123), to use
tical with “mass culture.” Rather, it is some- Critchley’s own term, cannot but take account of
thing, so to speak, done to mass culture.34 In this the ways in which modernity, in its broadest
sense, there is no essential reason why mass sense, impacts upon notions of value in art. (As
forms should not resist such violence; it’s simply in the “Keats vs. Dylan” example, discussions of
that, because of his social theory of modernity, the aesthetic value of pop music, both for and
Adorno was unable to see any hope of this against, all too often assume the most tradition-
happening. Second, and most importantly for my alist conception of the aesthetic, as if, say,
concerns, it is the expansive conception of Duchamp, Rimbaud or Cage had never existed.)
modernism outlined in Adorno’s work which Dimly, perhaps, the sociological/cultural studies
actually provides the best conceptual framework approach recognises this, but at the cost of a
for understanding the différend within pop refusal to judge or evaluate at all. Although this
music that Cutler articulates, as well as the is frequently theorised in “democratic” terms it
immanent logic of the attempted “liberation and does little for its supposed object or for the elab-
development of the revolutionary new musical oration of possible sites of resistance to either
means” (ibid. 36) at work within its most radical commodification or aestheticisation. Somewhat
forms and practices. (This relates, too, to the ironically, given his own ignorance of jazz or
special place of timbral experimentation or rock, it is in this light that Adorno’s conception
“noise” within pop insofar as it is this sonic of the ongoing construction of art, as a dynamic
dimension which such “new musical means” process at once aesthetic and social, is so crucial,
most obviously open up.) Cutler argues that, not least because it refuses to give up on the
despite the “field” of pop music’s undoubtedly necessity of judgement. But such judgement is
“dominant commodity character,” there is a marked by its own radical
tension between “the commercial imperatives historicity which can achieve an
of the commodity” and “the expressive and experience of aesthetic evalua-
progressive imperatives of the new media of tion only through a continual
musical production” (ibid.). Such tension is questioning of the aesthetic
clearly not resolvable in the society in which we itself.

71
dissonance and noise
notes serialism’s organisation of pitch – as structured by
the non-hierarchical ordering of the twelve notes
1 Nancy 286–87. I would like to thank Alex of the octave – to the sonic domains of rhythm,
Warwick, Aden Evens and Greg Hainge for their duration, dynamics and, ultimately, timbre.The key
comments upon this essay, and Barry Thompson, early works here are often said to be Boulez’s
Stephen Lemon and Simon Ward for several Structures for two pianos and Stockhausen’s
discussions concerning dissonance and noise over Kreuzspiel, both composed in 1951.
the years.
13 See also Born, “Music, Modernism and
2 My thanks to Tim Bewes for first pointing out Signification.”
Critchley’s essay to me.
14 Peter Bürger, “The Decline of the Modern
3 See, for example, Roberts, “After Adorno”; Age,” Telos 62 (winter 1984/1985): 120. Cited in
Bernstein,“Social Signs and Natural Bodies.” Osborne,“Adorno” 44.
4 Osborne, “Adorno and the Metaphysics of 15 See Bürger, Theory of the Avant-Garde.
Modernism” 23–48. Despite my criticism of
16 Osborne, “Non-Places and the Spaces of Art”
Osborne on this point, I am considerably indebted
192.
to him for the reading of Adorno’s conception of
modernism that follows. 17 See also Cunningham, “Trying (Not) to
Understand” 135–38.
5 See Osborne, Philosophy in Cultural Theory 53–62.
18 See Osborne,“Adorno” 43–45.
6 See Buck-Morss 62.
19 Adorno,“On the Fetish Character” 45.
7 Osborne, Philosophy in Cultural Theory 82.
20 Microtonalities refer to pitches outside the
8 Schoenberg, “How One Becomes Lonely” in equal-tempered Western scale of the twelve-note
Style and Idea 49–50. octave.
9 The twelve-note row or series refers to the 21 Sonic Youth’s own recent recordings of pieces
compositional form developed by Schoenberg in by Cage, Steve Reich, and Fluxus composers like
the mid-1920s, after his properly atonal period, George Macunias and George Brecht, on the 1999
and pursued by Berg and Webern. In this all the album Goodbye Twentieth Century, should thus be
twelve notes of the octave are given an equal viewed as a recognition of a parallel trajectory, and
(non-hierarchical) status, as opposed to that priv- not as either a revelation of their “sources” or a
ileging of certain notes found in the major–minor late claim for classical respectability – a point
key system. Twelve-note compositions are thus quickly borne out by the character of the
constructed around an implicit theme or formula performances themselves.
in which each of the twelve notes appears once.
Such compositions are also termed “serialist.” 22 “Minimalism,” as it comes to be defined through
the work of Glass, Nyman, and others, needs to be
10 Osborne, Philosophy in Cultural Theory 83. As distinguished from what has come to be described
Osborne rightly argues, this serves to reveal the retrospectively as “early minimalism,” i.e., La
“suppressed contradiction” in Greenberg’s work Monte Young and the work of various composers
between “the historical and the (idealised) associated with the Fluxus group. These early
‘aesthetic’ aspects” of his approach. It is precisely forms had their own immanent productive logic –
because this “contradiction” is not suppressed in which led them towards non-Western and blues
Adorno that his defence of modernism needs to forms – in an exploration of microtonalities and
be distanced from that of Greenberg. non-tempered tuning; a logic which, given its criti-
11 Dissonance is conventionally linked to discord cal relation to the limitations of serialism, can
and, as such, is viewed, musicologically, in specific indeed be regarded as modernist in the expansive
relation to the rules of harmony, and thus of tonal- sense in which I am employing it. Significantly,
ity. perhaps, the most important musicians associated
with Young’s Dream Syndicate – John Cale and
12 Total serialism refers to those composers who, Tony Conrad – both went on to work in a cultural
after the Second World War, sought to extend field usually presented as rock; Cale with the Velvet

72
cunningham
Underground and Conrad in collaborations with 32 Moreover, the possibility of such judgement –
the German group Faust. as regards the likes of Can, Sonic Youth or Tricky –
gives the lie to frankly preposterous statements
23 See Jameson,“Postmodernism” 111. such as Steven Connor’s claim that rock has never
24 Moreover, far from resisting commodity “really explored the nature of its own medium,
culture, this can appear as an especially cynical conventions or institutions.” See Connor,
embrace of it; utilising certain rock stylistic devices Postmodernist Culture 185.
to improve the marketability of particular musical 33 It also marks it apart, of course, from the forms
practices, as well as legitimating an uncritical of “biological memory” which constitute the “folk
return to tonality under the guise of populism.The mode.” See Cutler 24–27.
peculiar end result is a manifestation of art music
which is actually far more aesthetically “con- 34 I am indebted to Ben Watson for this formula-
servative” – in terms of its harmonic or timbral tion.
qualities – than the average techno record.
25 Can are perhaps – like the Velvet Underground bibliography
with ex-La Monte Young sidekick John Cale – an
Adorno, Theodor. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Robert
exceptional case insofar as two of their members,
Hullot-Kentor. London:Athlone, 1997.
Irmin Schmidt and Holger Czukay, actually trained
under Stockhausen. However, my real point here is Adorno, Theodor. “Arnold Schoenberg.” Prisms:
not restricted to the merits of such direct displac- Cultural Criticism and Society. Trans. Samuel and
ing of the institutional separation of high and low. Shierry Weber. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 1981.
If, say, Cale’s exploitation of dissonance and just
intonation in his viola playing on Velvet Adorno, Theodor. “Commitment.” Trans. Francis
Underground recordings can be traced back to McDonagh. Aesthetics and Politics. Ed. Ernst Bloch
earlier pieces performed with La Monte Young, et al. London: New Left, 1977.
other critical and emancipatory practices within Adorno, Theodor. “Letter to Walter Benjamin,
rock or jazz are liable to be misunderstood if they March 18 1936.” Trans. Harry Zohn. Aesthetics and
are seen as somehow derived from the classical Politics. Ed. Ernst Bloch et al. London: New Left,
avant-garde, insofar as they in fact have their own 1977.
immanent productive logics.
Adorno, Theodor. “On the Fetish Character in
26 Schoenberg’s own treatise on harmony written Music and the Regression of Listening.” Trans.
in 1910–11 includes atonality only as a postscript. Maurice Goldbloom. The Culture Industry: Selected
27 Attali does, however, go on to say that this does Essays on Mass Culture. Ed. J.M. Bernstein.
not amount to “the new mode of musical produc- London: Routledge, 1991.
tion, but the liquidation of the old” (ibid. 137).The Adorno, Theodor. Philosophy of Modern Music.
distinction here relates to Attali’s somewhat Trans. Anne G. Mitchell and Wesley V. Blomster.
utopianist projection of a “truly different system of New York: Seabury, 1973.
organisation” which he terms “composition”; a
music produced “for pleasure outside of meaning, Attali, Jacques. Noise:The Political Economy of Music.
usage and exchange” (ibid.). Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis and London:
Minnesota UP, 1985.
28 See Susan McClarey, Afterword to Noise 157.
Baudelaire, Charles.“The Painter of Modern Life.”
29 See Lyotard, “Answering the Question” 76. The Painter of Modern Life and Other Essays. Trans.
Jonathan Mayne. London: Phaidon, 1964.
30 See Adorno, “Letter to Walter Benjamin,
March 18 1936” 120. Bernstein, J.M. “Social Signs and Natural Bodies.”
Radical Philosophy 104 (Nov./Dec. 2000): 25–38.
31 “The Avant-Garde” is the title given to a 1986
Atlantic compilation (including recordings by Born, Georgina. “Music, Modernism and
Coleman and the Art Ensemble of Chicago) as well Signification.” Thinking Art: Beyond Traditional
as to a 1961 album by John Coltrane and Don Aesthetics. Ed. Andrew Benjamin and Peter
Cherry. Osborne. London: ICA, 1991.

73
dissonance and noise
Born, Georgina. Rationalizing Culture: IRCAM, The Problems of Modernity: Adorno and Benjamin.
Boulez and the Institutionalization of the Musical Ed. Andrew Benjamin. London and New York:
Avant-Garde. Berkeley, Los Angeles and London: Routledge, 1989.
California UP, 1995.
Osborne, Peter. “Non-Places and the Spaces of
Boulez, Pierre. Orientations. Trans. Martin Cooper. Art.” Journal of Architecture 6.2 (2001): 183–94.
London: Faber, 1986.
Osborne, Peter. Philosophy in Cultural Theory.
Buck-Morss, Susan. Dreamworld and Catastrophe: London and New York: Routledge, 2000.
The Passing of Mass Utopia in East and West.
Roberts, John. “After Adorno: Art, Autonomy and
Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2000.
Critique.” Historical Materialism 7 (winter 2000):
Bürger, Peter. Theory of the Avant-Garde. Trans. 221–39.
Michael Shaw. Minneapolis: Minnesota UP, 1984.
Schoenberg, Arnold. Style and Idea: Selected
Connor, Steven. Postmodernist Culture: An Writings of Arnold Schoenberg. Trans. Leo Black.
Introduction to Theories of the Contemporary. Berkeley: California UP, 1975.
Oxford and New York: Blackwell, 1989.
Watson, Ben. Art, Class and Cleavage:
Critchley, Simon. “Sounding Desire: On Tricky.” Quantulumcunque Concerning Materialist Esthetix.
Angelaki 4.3 (1999): 110–30. London: Quartet, 1998.

Critchley, Simon. Very Little … Almost Nothing. Wigley, Mark. “White Out: Fashioning the
London and New York: Routledge, 1997. Modern.” Architecture and Fashion. Ed. Deborah
Fausch, Paulette Singley, Rudolphe El-Khoury and
Cunningham, David. “Trying (Not) to Zvi Efrat. New York: Princeton Architectural P,
Understand: Adorno and the Work of Beckett.” 1995.
Beckett and Philosophy. Ed. Richard Lane.
Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave, 2002. Witkin, Robert W. Adorno on Music. London and
New York: Routledge, 1998.
Cutler, Chris. File Under Popular. London and New
York: ReR & Semiotext(e)/Autonomedia, 1991.
Jameson, Frederic. “Postmodernism and
Consumer Society.” Postmodern Culture. Ed. Hal
Foster. London: Pluto, 1985.
Jarvis, Simon. Adorno: A Critical Introduction.
Oxford: Polity, 1998.
Jay, Martin. Adorno. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1984.
Licht, Alan. “Blood of a Poet: Richard Hell.” The
Wire 216 (Feb. 2002): 34–38.
Lyotard, Jean-François. “Answering the Question:
What is Postmodernism?” Trans. Régis Durand.
The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge.
Manchester: Manchester UP, 1984.
Lyotard, Jean-François. The Inhuman. Trans.
Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby. Oxford: David Cunningham
Polity, 1991. English Literature Section
Department of English and Linguistics
Nancy, Jean-Luc. “To Possess Truth in One Soul
University of Westminster
and One Body.” Trans. Rodney Trumble. The
32–38 Wells Street
Birth to Presence. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1993.
London W1T 3UW
Osborne, Peter. “Adorno and the Metaphysics of UK
Modernism: The Problem of a ‘Postmodern’ Art.” E-mail: cunning@totalise.co.uk

You might also like