You are on page 1of 8

Quantum suicide and immortality

Quantum suicide is a thought experiment in quantum mechanics and the philosophy of physics.
Purportedly, it can falsify any interpretation of quantum mechanics other than the Everett many-worlds
interpretation by means of a variation of the Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, from the cat's point of
view. Quantum immortality refers to the subjective experience of surviving quantum suicide. This
concept is sometimes conjectured to be applicable to real-world causes of death as well.[1][2]

Most experts hold that neither the experiment nor the related idea of immortality would work in the real
world. As a thought experiment, quantum suicide is an intellectual exercise in which an abstract setup is
followed through to its logical consequences merely to prove a theoretical point. Virtually all physicists and
philosophers of science who have described it, especially in popularized treatments,[3] underscore that it
relies on contrived, idealized circumstances that may be impossible or exceedingly difficult to realize in real
life, and that its theoretical premises are controversial even among supporters of the many-worlds
interpretation. Thus, as cosmologist Anthony Aguirre warns, "[...] it would be foolish (and selfish) in the
extreme to let this possibility guide one's actions in any life-and-death question."[4]

Contents
History
Thought experiment
Analysis of real-world feasibility
David Lewis' commentary and subsequent criticism
Analysis by other proponents of the many-worlds interpretation
Analysis by skeptics of the many-worlds interpretation
See also
Notes
References

History
Hugh Everett did not mention quantum suicide or quantum immortality in writing; his work was intended
as a solution to the paradoxes of quantum mechanics. Eugene Shikhovtsev's biography of Everett states that
"Everett firmly believed that his many-worlds theory guaranteed him immortality: his consciousness, he
argued, is bound at each branching to follow whatever path does not lead to death".[5] Peter Byrne, author
of a biography of Everett, reports that Everett also privately discussed quantum suicide (such as to play
high-stakes Russian roulette and survive in the winning branch), but adds that "[i]t is unlikely, however,
that Everett subscribed to this [quantum immortality] view, as the only sure thing it guarantees is that the
majority of your copies will die, hardly a rational goal."[6]

Among scientists, the thought experiment was introduced by Euan Squires in 1986.[7] Afterwards, it was
published independently by Hans Moravec in 1987[8] and Bruno Marchal in 1988;[9][10] it was also
described by Huw Price in 1997, who credited it to Dieter Zeh,[11] and independently presented formally
by Max Tegmark in 1998.[12] It was later discussed by philosophers Peter J. Lewis in 2000[2] and David
Lewis in 2001.[13]

Thought experiment
The quantum suicide thought experiment involves a similar apparatus to Schrödinger's cat – a box which
kills the occupant in a given time frame with probability one-half due to quantum uncertainty.[note 1] The
only difference is to have the experimenter recording observations be the one inside the box. The
significance of this is that someone whose life or death depends on a qubit could possibly distinguish
between interpretations of quantum mechanics. By definition, fixed observers cannot.[12]

At the start of the first iteration, under both interpretations, the probability of surviving the experiment is
50%, as given by the squared norm of the wave function. At the start of the second iteration, assuming a
single-world interpretation of quantum mechanics (like the widely-held Copenhagen interpretation) is true,
the wave function has already collapsed; thus, if the experimenter is already dead, there is a 0% chance of
survival for any further iterations. However, if the many-worlds interpretation is true, a superposition of the
live experimenter necessarily exists (as also does the one who dies). Now, barring the possibility of life
after death, after every iteration only one of the two experimenter superpositions – the live one – is capable
of having any sort of conscious experience. Putting aside the philosophical problems associated with
individual identity and its persistence, under the many-worlds interpretation, the experimenter, or at least a
version of them, continues to exist through all of their superpositions where the outcome of the experiment
is that they live. In other words, a version of the experimenter survives all iterations of the experiment.
Since the superpositions where a version of the experimenter lives occur by quantum necessity (under the
many-worlds interpretation), it follows that their survival, after any realizable number of iterations, is
physically necessary; hence, the notion of quantum immortality.[12]

A version of the experimenter surviving stands in stark contrast to the implications of the Copenhagen
interpretation, according to which, although the survival outcome is possible in every iteration, its
probability tends towards zero as the number of iterations increases. According to the many-worlds
interpretation, the above scenario has the opposite property: the probability of a version of the experimenter
living is necessarily one for any number of iterations.[12]

In the book Our Mathematical Universe, Max Tegmark lays out three criteria that, in abstract, a quantum
suicide experiment must fulfill:

The random number generator must be quantum, not deterministic, so that the experimenter
enters a state of superposition of being dead and alive.
The experimenter must be rendered dead (or at least unconscious) on a time scale shorter
than that on which they can become aware of the outcome of the quantum
measurement.[note 2]
The experiment must be virtually certain to kill the experimenter, and not merely injure
them.[14]

Analysis of real-world feasibility


In response to questions about "subjective immortality" from normal causes of death, Tegmark suggested
that the flaw in that reasoning is that dying is not a binary event as in the thought experiment; it is a
progressive process, with a continuum of states of decreasing consciousness. He states that in most real
causes of death, one experiences such a gradual loss of self-awareness. It is only within the confines of an
abstract scenario that an observer finds they defy all odds.[1] Referring to the above criteria, he elaborates as
follows: "[m]ost accidents and common causes of death clearly don't satisfy all three criteria, suggesting
you won't feel immortal after all. In particular, regarding criterion 2, under normal circumstances dying isn't
a binary thing where you're either alive or dead [...] What makes the quantum suicide work is that it forces
an abrupt transition."[14]

David Lewis' commentary and subsequent criticism

The philosopher David Lewis explored the possibility of quantum immortality in a 2001 lecture titled
"How Many Lives Has Schrödinger's Cat?", his first - and last, due to his death less than four months
afterwards - academic foray into the field of the interpretation of quantum mechanics. In the lecture,
published posthumously in 2004, Lewis rejected the many-worlds interpretation, allowing that it offers
initial theoretical attractions, but also arguing that it suffers from irremediable flaws, mainly regarding
probabilities, and came to tentatively endorse the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber theory instead. Lewis concluded
the lecture by stating that the quantum suicide thought experiment, if applied to real-world causes of death,
would entail what he deemed a "terrifying corollary": as all causes of death are ultimately quantum-
mechanical in nature, if the many-worlds interpretation were true, in Lewis' view an observer should
subjectively "expect with certainty to go on forever surviving whatever dangers [he or she] may
encounter", as there will always be possibilities of survival, no matter how unlikely; faced with branching
events of survival and death, an observer should not "equally expect to experience life and death", as there
is no such thing as experiencing death, and should thus divide his or her expectations only among branches
where he or she survives. If survival is guaranteed, however, this is not the case for good health or integrity.
This would lead to a cumulative deterioration that indefinitively stops just short of death.[2][15]

Interviewed for the 2004 book Schrödinger's Rabbits, Tegmark rejected this scenario for the reason that
"the fading of consciousness is a continuous process. Although I cannot experience a world line in which I
am altogether absent, I can enter one in which my speed of thought is diminishing, my memories and other
faculties fading [...] [Tegmark] is confident that even if he cannot die all at once, he can gently fade away."
In the same book, philosopher of science and many-worlds proponent David Wallace[16] undermines the
case for real-world quantum immortality on the basis that death can be understood as a continuum of
decreasing states of consciousness not only in time, as argued by Tegmark, but also in space: "our
consciousness is not located at one unique point in the brain, but is presumably a kind of emergent or
holistic property of a sufficiently large group of neurons [...] our consciousness might not be able to go out
like a light, but it can dwindle exponentially until it is, for all practical purposes, gone."[17]

Directly responding to Lewis' lecture, British philosopher and many-worlds proponent David Papineau,
while finding Lewis' other objections to the many-worlds interpretation lacking, strongly denies that any
modification to the usual probability rules is warranted in death situations. Assured subjective survival can
follow from the quantum suicide idea only if an agent reasons in terms of "what will be experienced next"
instead of the more obvious "what will happen next, whether will be experienced or not". He writes: "[...] it
is by no means obvious why Everettians should modify their intensity rule[note 3] in this way. For it seems
perfectly open for them to apply the unmodified intensity rule in life-or-death situations, just as elsewhere.
If they do this, then they can expect all futures in proportion to their intensities, whether or not those futures
contain any of their live successors. For example, even when you know you are about to be the subject in a
fifty-fifty Schrödinger’s experiment, you should expect a future branch where you perish, to just the same
degree as you expect a future branch where you survive."[15]

On a similar note, quoting Lewis' position that death should not be expected as an experience, philosopher
of science Charles Sebens concedes that, in a quantum suicide experiment, "[i]t is tempting to think you
should expect survival with certainty." However, he remarks that expectation of survival could follow only
if the quantum branching and death were absolutely simultaneous, otherwise normal chances of death
apply: "[i]f death is indeed immediate on all branches but one, the thought has some plausibility. But if
there is any delay it should be rejected. In such a case, there is a short period of time when there are
multiple copies of you, each (effectively) causally isolated from the others and able to assign a credence to
being the one who will live. Only one will survive. Surely rationality does not compel you to be maximally
optimistic in such a scenario." Sebens also explores the possibility that death might not be simultaneous to
branching, but still faster than a human can mentally realize the outcome of the experiment. Again, an agent
should expect to die with normal probabilities: "[d]o the copies need to last long enough to have thoughts to
cause trouble?[note 4] I think not. If you survive, you can consider what credences you should have
assigned during the short period after splitting when you coexisted with the other copies."[18]

Writing in the journal Ratio, philosopher István Aranyosi, while noting that "[the] tension between the idea
of states being both actual and probable is taken as the chief weakness of the many-worlds interpretation of
quantum mechanics," summarizes that most of the critical commentary of Lewis' immortality argument has
revolved around its premises. But even if, for the sake of argument, one were willing to entirely accept
Lewis' assumptions, Aranyosi strongly denies that the "terrifying corollary" would be the correct
implication of said premises. Instead, the two scenarios that would most likely follow would be what
Aranyosi describes as the "comforting corollary", in which an observer should never expect to get very sick
in the first place, or the "momentary life" picture, in which an observer should expect "eternal life, spent
almost entirely in an unconscious state", punctuated by extremely brief, amnesiac moments of
consciousness. Thus, Aranyosi concludes that while "[w]e can't assess whether one or the other [of the two
alternative scenarios] gets the lion's share of the total intensity associated with branches compatible with
self-awareness, [...] we can be sure that they together (i.e. their disjunction) do indeed get the lion's share,
which is much reassuring."[19]

Analysis by other proponents of the many-worlds interpretation

Physicist David Deutsch, though a proponent of the many-worlds interpretation, states regarding quantum
suicide that "that way of applying probabilities does not follow directly from quantum theory, as the usual
one does. It requires an additional assumption, namely that when making decisions one should ignore the
histories in which the decision-maker is absent....[M]y guess is that the assumption is false."[20]

Tegmark now believes experimenters should only expect a normal probability of survival, not immortality.
The experimenter's probability amplitude in the wavefunction decreases significantly, meaning they exist
with a much lower measure than they had before. Per the anthropic principle, a person is less likely to find
themselves in a world where they are less likely to exist, that is, a world with a lower measure has a lower
probability of being observed by them. Therefore, the experimenter will have a lower probability of
observing the world in which they survive than the earlier world in which they set up the experiment.[14]
This same problem of reduced measure was pointed out by Lev Vaidman in the Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy.[21] In the 2001 paper, "Probability and the many-worlds interpretation of quantum theory",
Vaidman writes that an agent should not agree to undergo a quantum suicide experiment: "The large
'measures' of the worlds with dead successors is a good reason not to play." Vaidman argues that it is the
instantaneity of death that may seem to imply subjective survival of the experimenter, but that normal
probabilities nevertheless must apply even in this special case: "[i]ndeed, the instantaneity makes it difficult
to establish the probability postulate, but after it has been justified in the wide range of other situations it is
natural to apply the postulate for all cases."[22]

In his 2013 book The Emergent Multiverse, Wallace opines that the reasons for expecting subjective
survival in the thought experiment "do not really withstand close inspection", although he concedes that it
would be "probably fair to say [...] that precisely because death is philosophically complicated, my
objections fall short of being a knock-down refutation". Besides re-stating that there appears to be no
motive to reason in terms of expectations of experience instead of expectations of what will happen, he
suggests that a decision-theoretic analysis shows that "an agent who prefers certain life to certain death is
rationally compelled to prefer life in high-weight branches and death in low-weight branches to the
opposite."[3]

Physicist Sean M. Carroll, another proponent of the many-worlds interpretation, states regarding quantum
suicide that neither experiences nor rewards should be thought of as being shared between future versions
of oneself, as they become distinct persons when the world splits. He further states that one cannot pick out
some future versions of oneself as "really you" over others, and that quantum suicide still cuts off the
existence of some of these future selves, which would be worth objecting to just as if there were a single
world.[23]

Analysis by skeptics of the many-worlds interpretation

Cosmologist Anthony Aguirre, while personally skeptical of most accounts of the many-worlds
interpretation, in his book Cosmological Koans writes that "[p]erhaps reality actually is this bizarre, and we
really do subjectively 'survive' any form of death that is both instantaneous and binary." Aguirre notes,
however, that most causes of death do not fulfill these two requirements: "If there are degrees of survival,
things are quite different." If loss of consciousness was binary like in the thought experiment, the quantum
suicide effect would prevent an observer from subjectively falling asleep or undergoing anesthesia,
conditions in which mental activities are greatly diminished but not altogether abolished. Consequently,
upon most causes of death, even outwardly sudden, if the quantum suicide effect holds true an observer is
more likely to progressively slip into an attenuated state of consciousness, rather than remain fully awake
by some very improbable means. Aguirre further states that quantum suicide as a whole might be
characterized as a sort of reductio ad absurdum against the current understanding of both the many-worlds
interpretation and theory of mind. He finally hypothesizes that a different understanding of the relationship
between the mind and time should remove the bizarre implications of necessary subjective survival.[4]

Physicist and writer Philip Ball, a critic of the many-worlds interpretation, in his book Beyond Weird,
describes the quantum suicide experiment as "cognitively unstable" and exemplificatory of the difficulties
of the many-worlds theory with probabilities. While he acknowledges Lev Vaidman's argument that an
experimenter should subjectively expect outcomes in proportion of the "measure of existence" of the
worlds in which they happen, Ball ultimately rejects this explanation. "What this boils down to is the
interpretation of probabilities in the MWI. If all outcomes occur with 100% probability, where does that
leave the probabilistic character of quantum mechanics?" Furthermore, Ball explains that such arguments
highlight what he recognizes as another major problem of the many-worlds interpretation, connected but
independent from the issue of probability: the incompatibility with the notion of selfhood. Ball ascribes
most attempts of justifying probabilities in the many-worlds interpretation to "saying that quantum
probabilities are just what quantum mechanics look like when consciousness is restricted to only one
world" but that "there is in fact no meaningful way to explain or justify such a restriction." Before
performing a quantum measurement, an "Alice before" experimenter "can't use quantum mechanics to
predict what will happen to her in a way that can be articulated - because there is no logical way to talk
about 'her' at any moment except the conscious present (which, in a frantically splitting universe, doesn't
exist). Because it is logically impossible to connect the perceptions of Alice Before to Alice After [the
experiment], "Alice" has disappeared. [...] [The MWI] eliminates any coherent notion of what we can
experience, or have experienced, or are experiencing right now."[24]

Philosopher of science Peter J. Lewis, a critic of the many-worlds interpretation, considers the whole
thought experiment an example of the difficulty of accommodating probability within the many-worlds
framework: "[s]tandard quantum mechanics yields probabilities for various future occurrences, and these
probabilities can be fed into an appropriate decision theory. But if every physically possible consequence of
the current state of affairs is certain to occur, on what basis should I decide what to do? For example, if I
point a gun at my head and pull the trigger, it looks like Everett's theory entails that I am certain to survive
—and that I am certain to die. This is at least worrying, and perhaps rationally disabling."[25] In his book
Quantum Ontology, Lewis explains that for the subjective immortality argument to be drawn out of the
many-worlds theory, one has to adopt an understanding of probability - the so-called "branch-counting"
approach, in which an observer can meaningfully ask "which post-measurement branch will I end up on?"
- that is ruled out by experimental, empirical evidence as it would yield probabilities that do not match with
the well-confirmed Born rule. Lewis identifies instead in the Deutsch-Wallace decision-theoretic analysis
the most promising (although still, to his judgement, incomplete) way of addressing probabilities in the
many-worlds interpretation, in which it is not possible to count branches (and, similarly, the persons that
"end up" on each branch). Lewis concludes that "[t]he immortality argument is perhaps best viewed as a
dramatic demonstration of the fundamental conflict between branch-counting (or person-counting)
intuitions about probability and the decision theoretic approach. The many-worlds theory, to the extent that
it is viable, does not entail that you should expect to live forever."[26]

See also
Multiverse

Notes
1. The simplest example of this is a weapon triggered by a two level system. Schrödinger
described his as a radioactive decay detector while Moravec's was a device measuring the
spin value of protons.
2. This is not unanimously agreed upon. Sebens argues, as will be detailed infra, that death
must be instantaneous, not merely faster than the brain can process the result of the
experiment.
3. By "intensity rule", Lewis and Papineau mean the Born rule, the rule used to apportion
probabilities in quantum mechanical events.
4. By "cause trouble," Sebens means spoiling the expectations of necessary subjective
survival.

References
1. Tegmark, Max (November 1998). "Quantum immortality" (http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/
quantum.html#immortality). Retrieved 25 October 2010.
2. Lewis, Peter J (1 January 2000). "What is it like to be Schrödinger's cat?" (https://academic.o
up.com/analysis/article/60/1/22/105398). Analysis. 60: 22–29. doi:10.1093/analys/60.1.22 (h
ttps://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F60.1.22).
3. Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett
Interpretation (https://books.google.com/books?id=mqfnu1o26cEC). Oxford University Press.
pp. 369–372. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1.
4. Aguirre, Anthony (2019). "What survives". Cosmological Koans.
5. See Eugene Shikhovtsev's Biography of Everett: Keith Lynch remembers 1979–1980 (http://
space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/everett/everett.html#e23)
6. Byrne, Peter (2010). The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual
Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family. Oxford University Press. p. 342.
ISBN 978-0199659241.
7. Squires, Euan (1986). The Mystery of the Quantum World. Hilger. pp. 72–73.
ISBN 9780852745656.
8. Moravec, Hans (1988). "The Doomsday Device". Mind Children: The Future of Robot and
Human Intelligence (https://archive.org/details/mindchildren00hans). Harvard: Harvard
University Press. p. 188 (https://archive.org/details/mindchildren00hans/page/188).
ISBN 978-0-674-57618-6.
9. Marchal, Bruno (1988). "Informatique théorique et philosophie de l'esprit" [Theoretical
Computer Science and Philosophy of Mind]. Acte du 3ème colloque international Cognition
et Connaissance [Proceedings of the 3rd International Conference Cognition and
Knowledge]. Toulouse: 193–227.
10. Marchal, Bruno (1991). De Glas, M.; Gabbay, D. (eds.). "Mechanism and personal identity"
(https://web.archive.org/web/20200125125451/http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/publications/
M%26PI_15-MAI-91.pdf) (PDF). Proceedings of WOCFAI 91. Paris. Angkor.: 335–345.
Archived from the original (http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/publications/M&PI_15-MAI-91.pdf)
(PDF) on 25 January 2020. Retrieved 13 May 2020.
11. Price, Huw (1997). "The Puzzle of Contemporary Quantum Theory". Time's Arrow and
Archimedes' Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time. OUP USA. pp. 221–222.
ISBN 978-0195117981.
12. Tegmark, Max The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words? (htt
p://www.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9709032/), 1998
13. "How Many Lives Has Schrödinger's Cat? (http://www.andrewmbailey.com/dkl/How_Many_
Lives.pdf)," Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 1, pp. 3–22; March 2004
14. Tegmark, Max (2014). "The Level III Multiverse/Is Time An Illusion?". Our Mathematical
Universe. Vintage Books.
15. "David Papineau, "David Lewis and Schroedinger's Cat", 2004" (https://www.davidpapinea
u.co.uk/uploads/1/8/5/5/18551740/lewis_and_schro%CC%88dinger._final_final.doc).
16. Wallace, David. "About me" (https://dornsife.usc.edu/david-wallace). Retrieved 24 May
2020.
17. Bruce, Colin (2004). "The Terror of Many Worlds". Schrödinger's Rabbits: The Many Worlds
of Quantum.
18. Sebens, Charles (29 January 2015). "Killer Collapse Empirically Probing the
Philosophically Unsatisfactory Region of GRW" (http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/11350/7/Killer
_Collapse_PhilSci_Archive_3.pdf) (PDF). Synthese. 192 (8): 2599–2615.
doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0680-x (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11229-015-0680-x).
S2CID 17259579 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:17259579).
19. Aranyosi, Istvan (15 August 2012). "Should we fear quantum torment?" (http://istvanaranyos
i.net/resources/Should%20we%20fear%20qt%20final.pdf) (PDF). Ratio. 25 (3): 249–259.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-9329.2012.00540.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1467-9329.2012.00540.
x). hdl:11693/21341 (https://hdl.handle.net/11693%2F21341).
20. Deutsch, David (2011). "The Beginning". The Beginning of Infinity. Penguin Group.
21. Vaidman, Lev (2018). "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics" (https://plato.stan
ford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Research Lab, Stanford University.
22. Vaidman, Lev (13 November 2001). "Probability and the Many-Worlds Interpretation of
Quantum Theory". arXiv:quant-ph/0111072 (https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0111072).
23. Carroll, Sean (2019). "The Human Side – Living and Thinking in a Quantum Universe".
Something Deeply Hidden: Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime. Penguin.
ISBN 9781524743024. At Google Books (https://books.google.com/books?id=f16IDwAAQB
AJ).
24. Ball, Philip (2018). "There is no other 'quantum you' ". Beyond Weird: Why Everything You
Thought You Knew About Quantum Physics Is Different. Univ of Chicago Pr. ISBN 978-
0226558387.
25. Lewis, Peter J. (13 November 2001). "Uncertainty and probability for branching selves" (htt
p://users.ox.ac.uk/~everett/docs/Lewis%20Uncertainty.pdf) (PDF).
26. Lewis, Peter J. (2016). "Immortality". Quantum Ontology: A Guide to the Metaphysics of
Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0190469818.

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Quantum_suicide_and_immortality&oldid=1109052370"

This page was last edited on 7 September 2022, at 17:05 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 3.0;


additional terms may apply. By
using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like