You are on page 1of 2

Definition of Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism is a normative ethical theory that defines the good in terms of overall happiness. Actions
that increase pleasure and decrease suffering, such as giving Kayla Chad’s car, are good. Actions that
decrease pleasure and increase pain are bad.

How it Works

18th century English philosopher and utilitarian John Stuart Mill developed what he called the Greatest
Happiness Principle to determine whether an individual action is good or bad. If an act promotes
happiness for the most amount of people, it is good. If it decreases overall happiness, it is bad. The goal
of our actions is to create the greatest happiness for the most amount of people. Since everyone’s
happiness counts equally, utilitarianism considers maximizing the good from an impartial perspective,
meaning that the interests of people close to you should not count higher than those of strangers.

Utilitarianism is focused only on the consequences of actions, which is why it is sometimes called
consequentialism. Therefore, an agent’s reasons for acting are not considered when determining the
rightness of their action. For example, let’s say you want to help your friend Natalie with her homework.
However, when you help her, you end up doing most of the work for her. Not only does she not know
the material for the test, but she is now also in trouble for cheating. Although your action had good
intentions, it resulted in bad consequences and thus is bad from a utilitarian perspective.

One of the main criticisms of utilitarianism is its occasional violation of rights. Stealing one of Chad’s cars
to give to Kayla is a good action under utilitarianism, but it also seems to be violating Chad’s property
right to his car. Many believe that no matter how bad Kayla needs a car, it is always wrong to violate
Chad’s right. Some utilitarians will bite the bullet and admit that rights violations are sometimes morally
acceptable, but others have created ways to reconcile rights and utility. Rule utilitarianism posits rules
whose consequences increase overall happiness. “Don’t steal from others” fits this requirement,
because if everyone stole from each other, society would collapse and overall happiness would
plummet. Therefore, under rule utilitarianism, stealing Chad’s car is still wrong because it violates the
rule, even though in this specific case, it would increase the good.

Another criticism of utilitarianism is that it makes supererogatory actions, which are actions that are
good but not necessary, morally required. For example, suppose you have one million dollars to spend.
If you donated it to charity, you would be morally praised. Yet, if you bought a fancy new house for you
and your family, most people would not say you did anything wrong. Under utilitarianism, donating the
money to charity is not only praiseworthy, but it is morally necessary, as it does more good for the world
than buying a new house. The demandingness of utilitarianism seems to threaten our personal projects
unless we can prove they are maximizing the good.
Applying It

Utilitarianism has been one of the most popular normative theories in modern philosophy.
Contemporary Australian philosopher Peter Singer uses utilitarianism to consider practical ethics topics
such as climate change, abortion, and euthanasia. The theory has been particularly effective in the field
of animal ethics, as it extends moral consideration to the interests of non-human animals. Many animal
ethicists argue that eating and using animal products causes more suffering to animals than pleasure to
humans; therefore, it is morally wrong.

If you don’t agree with some of the implications of utilitarianism, your ethical views may align more with
Aristotelian virtue ethics or Kantian deontology. However, utilitarianism requires us to consider how our
individual daily actions affect the greater community, and whether the personal convenience of things
such as eating meat or using plastic is worth their negative implications on the world.

You might also like