You are on page 1of 18

r Academy of Management Review

2022, Vol. 47, No. 1, 75–92.


https://doi.org/10.5465/amr.2017.0451

SOCIAL OBJECTIVITY AND ENTREPRENEURIAL


OPPORTUNITIES
RUSS MCBRIDE
University of California, Merced

ROBERT WUEBKER
University of Utah

An important conversation in entrepreneurship focuses on the question of whether


entrepreneurial opportunities are objective or subjective. The discovery view suggests
that they are objective. The creation view suggests they are subjective. Resolving the
debate requires first understanding what objectivity is for any social phenomenon. The
debate can then be disaggregated into two questions: Are entrepreneurial opportunities
ontologically subjective, and can they be epistemologically objective? The answer to both
questions is “yes.” Transforming a completely subjective opportunity into an epistemo-
logically objective opportunity requires changing beliefs—of consumers, employees, gov-
ernments, and other stakeholders—along with the rights and responsibilities of these
stakeholders vis-a-vis the entity created to exploit an opportunity. This view of opportu-
nities has important implications for social science research more broadly, as well as
management and entrepreneurship, specifically.

If there is any moral … this may be it: facts in the How entrepreneurial opportunities are formed
social sciences are grounded differently than are and exploited has attracted interest from researchers
those of the natural sciences. Compared to the social (Alvarez & Barney, 2007, 2010, 2013, 2019; Braver &
sciences, the ontology of natural science is a walk in Danneels, 2018; Davidsson, 2015; Dimov, 2007,
the park. (Epstein, 2015: 163)
2011; Ramoglou & Tsang, 2016, 2017, 2018; Shane &
Venkataraman, 2000), and two approaches to analyz-
ing opportunities have emerged in the literature.
The first, building on the work of Kirzner (1973) on
In addition to the field editor, Sharon Alvarez, and vari- entrepreneurial arbitrage, has argued that opportuni-
ous anonymous referees, the authors are grateful for the ties are formed by exogenous shocks to established
following people who provided detailed feedback and markets or industries and are discovered by individ-
engaged in extensive discussions on previous versions of uals with unusual alertness operating under condi-
this manuscript: Jay Barney, Paul Godfrey, Brian Gordon,
tions of risk (Kirzner, 1973, 1979; Shane &
Joep Cornelissen, Todd Zenger, and Randy Westgren. Ver-
sions of this paper were presented at the Academy of Man-
Venkataraman, 2000). The second has suggested that
agement social ontology professional development opportunities are created endogenously by the
workshops; the Entrepreneurship Exemplars Conference actions of entrepreneurs themselves operating under
at the Ohio State University; the Entrepreneurship Exem- conditions of Knightian uncertainty (Alvarez & Bar-
plars Conference in Keystone, CO; University of California ney, 2007; Knight, 1921). Some have argued that
Berkeley Social Ontology Research Group; the University these two ways of thinking about opportunity forma-
of Utah Entrepreneurship & Strategy Department; the Utah tion and exploitation are complementary (Alvarez &
Social Ontology Research Group; the University of Oslo; Barney, 2007, 2010; Dimov, 2011; Foss & Klein,
University College, Bergen; China Europe International 2017; Kirzner, 2009), and others have argued that
Business School; Ernest & Julio Gallo Management Pro-
they are mutually exclusive (Gaglio & Katz, 2001;
gram at the University of California, Merced; the Univer-
Ramoglou & Tsang, 2016; Shane, 2003; Shane & Eck-
sity of Eindhoven; Tsinghua University School of
Economics and Management; SKEMA Knowledge and hardt, 2003); thus, one or the other must logically
Technology Organization Group; the University of St. Gal- dominate research in the field of entrepreneurship.
len; IESE Business School; SASIN Management School; Debates over the importance of these two models
the University of Klagenfurt; Vienna University; and have continued for some time (Alvarez, Barney,
Anglia Ruskin University. McBride, & Wuebker, 2014, 2017; Braver & Danneels,
75
Copyright of the Academy of Management, all rights reserved. Contents may not be copied, emailed, posted to a listserv, or otherwise transmitted without the copyright holder's express
written permission. Users may print, download, or email articles for individual use only.
76 Academy of Management Review January

2018; Cornelissen & Clarke, 2010; Davidsson, 2015; DEFINING KEY TERMS
Eckhardt & Shane, 2012, 2013; Foss & Klein, 2017,
There are several terms that are central to the argu-
2018; McMullen & Shepherd, 2006; Ramoglou &
ments developed in this paper. These terms are
Tsang, 2016, 2017, 2018; Shane, 2012; Venkatara-
defined in this section.
man, Sarasvathy, Dew, & Forster, 2012; Wood &
McKinley, 2010, 2017, 2018). However, these
debates are unlikely to be resolved until a more fun- Entrepreneurial Opportunity
damental issue about entrepreneurial opportunities There have been many definitions of the concept
has been addressed—are opportunities objective or of opportunity, but among the core participants in
subjective? If they are objective (or mostly objec- the debate there has been broad agreement about
tive), then the older discovery approach that recom- what exactly constitutes an entrepreneurial opportu-
mends searching for preexisting opportunities is nity. An opportunity is a situation “in which new
more appropriate; if they are subjective (or mostly goods, services, raw materials, and organizing meth-
subjective), then the creation approach is more ods can be introduced and sold at greater than their
appropriate. cost of production” (Shane & Venkataraman, 2000:
The purpose of this paper is to address the ques- 220) or a situation “in which new goods, services,
tion regarding whether entrepreneurial opportuni- raw materials, markets and organizing methods
ties are objective. Answering this question requires can be introduced through the formation of new
first determining criteria for what counts as objec- means, ends, or means-ends relationships” (Eck-
tive or subjective for any socioeconomic phenom- hardt & Shane, 2003: 336) and sold for more than
ena, and this requires taking a deeper look at the their cost of production.
structure of social reality. We find that entrepre- Alvarez and Barney (2010) have agreed, noting
neurial opportunities are ontologically subjective, that there is “growing consensus about the definition
like all social phenomena, but can be epistemologi- of what constitutes an opportunity in the entrepre-
cally objective if the criteria are met. These two dif- neurship literature: ‘An opportunity exists when-
ferent dimensions of objectivity have often been ever there are competitive imperfections in a factor
overlooked. or product market’” (Alvarez & Barney, 2010: 559).
The paper then addresses an important follow-up Since they consider an “imperfection” to just be situ-
question: What implications does the answer to the ation in which goods and services can be introduced
debate about the objectivity of entrepreneurial op- and sold for more than their cost of production, these
portunities and an understanding of the nature of definitions are effectively equivalent. Interestingly,
social reality have for the evolution of the fields of though, consensus about the definition has not
entrepreneurship, management, and the broader resolved the debate about whether opportunities are
social sciences? First, everything we study, reflect objective.
upon, and theorize about in entrepreneurship and
management involves social entities, so it is criti-
Subjectivity versus Objectivity
cally important to understand what constitutes a
social entity to make it real and objective. Second, Discussions of criteria for determining objectivity
social phenomena are distinct from physical phe- are longstanding, but one straightforward approach
nomena, and what makes a social phenomenon (Searle, 1995, 2010) has grounded the distinction
objective is different from what makes a physical between subjectivity and objectivity as the differ-
object objective. Conflating the two has historically ence between that which is observer independent
led to confusion in the social sciences, and eliminat- (i.e., mind independent) and that which is observer
ing this confusion will clear the way for significant relative (i.e., mind dependent). Mind-independent
progress to be made. Third, a clear understanding of objects or facts do not depend upon any observer for
social entities offers a new lens through which to their existence and are thus objective, while mind-
view a diverse range of activities within firms and dependent objects or facts do, and so they are subjec-
ventures—activities that fundamentally involve the tive. For example, a hydrogen atom exists regardless
difficult labor of forging beliefs and duties among of what anyone thinks about it. It is mind indepen-
those who can help advance the organization to dent. Similarly, the fact that a hydrogen atom has
become increasingly real and objective. This lens one proton is true regardless of whether any humans
serves as a tool that scholars can use to analyze the are alive to confirm it or what they think about it,
objects of their work from this novel perspective. and so it is an objective fact. Although the discovery
2022 McBride and Wuebker 77

of that fact required human minds, the atom itself Ontology and Epistemology
still exists independently of such minds and the dis-
Ontology is the study of what something is,
covery process.
whereas epistemology is the study of what we think
In contrast, a corporation (e.g., IBM) only exists
or believe about that something. The physical scien-
because a diverse collection of people believe that
ces study ontologically objective physical objects.
it does (federal and state governments, the depart-
Psychology, cognitive science, and the social scien-
ment of corporations, shareholders, customers,
employees, partners, contractors, media pundits, ces study people’s thoughts and beliefs about
etc.). If no one believed that IBM existed then it things—in other words, people’s epistemic states
would no longer exist, which makes it mind de- (and the behavior and effects driven by those episte-
pendent and therefore subjective.1 Similarly, the mic states). Physical objects and facts are essentially
fact that Paris is the capital of France is only a fact ontological and objective because they are mind
because some people decided at some point in his- independent, while social objects and facts are
tory that Paris would be the capital of France. If essentially epistemological and subjective because
everyone awoke with the new belief that Marseilles they are dependent upon what people think and
was the capital, then it would become the capital believe.
of France. It is a mind-dependent fact and therefore
subjective.
Ontological Objectivity and Epistemological
The Physical and Social Worlds Objectivity

There are then two types of objects: physical This leads to an important question. Similar to
objects and social objects. Examples of physical physical objects, some social objects are indepen-
objects include a tree, Mt. Everest, and a hydrogen dent of us and relatively stable (like IBM, the capital
atom. Examples of social objects include a corpora- of France, or the Canadian government), yet they are
tion, a capital city, and product or factor markets. obviously not ontologically objective physical
This difference between physical and social objects objects. Where, then, does the objectivity of such
highlights a critical distinction between those fields social objects come from? Social objects and facts are
that study mind-independent phenomena (physics, epistemological, and so their objectivity comes from
chemistry, biology, etc.) and those that study mind- epistemological objectivity. Where does epistemo-
dependent phenomena (management, sociology, logical objectivity come from? It comes from stable
anthropology, social psychology, economics, legal cognitive states (Boghossian, 2007; Bratman, 1987,
studies, strategy, political science, etc.). The objects 2014; Gilbert, 1992, 2015; Hart, 1961; Hume, 1740/
of study in the physical sciences, like hydrogen 1978; Lawson, Latsis, & Martins, 2013; Ludwig,
atoms, are mind independent and therefore objec- 2016, 2017; Searle, 1995, 2010; Tuomela, 2002,
tive. On the other hand, the core objects of study in 2007, 2013), specifically beliefs and rights and obli-
the social sciences, like governments or IBM, are gations—which are referred to as “deontics”—as
mind dependent and therefore subjective.2 well as the behaviors that flow from them, upon
which social objects depend for their existence.
Thus, there are two kinds of objectivity. A physi-
cal object is ontologically objective because it is
1 independent of every human mind. A social object is
Its physical property would still exist but no longer be
owned by IBM since IBM would no longer exist.
ontologically subjective but can be epistemologi-
2 cally objective precisely because of the stable beliefs
Social phenomena are a subset of the larger category of
mind-dependent phenomena. This means that all social and stable deontics of human minds. These are
phenomena are mind dependent, but not all mind- completely distinct dimensions of objectivity. These
dependent phenomena are social. For example, the cogni- two dimensions have often been conflated.
tive activity of an individual is mind dependent in that it
depends on the mind of the individual who is engaged in
that activity, but not all of that activity brings about, consti- THE DEBATE
tutes, or affects social phenomena. One might be day-
dreaming alone in one’s office about climbing a tree, for With these definitions in place, it is now possible
example, which is a cognitive activity that does not relate to address the question of whether entrepreneurial
to anything social. opportunities are objective.
78 Academy of Management Review January

Positions in the Debate The First Argument for the Objectivity of


Opportunities
According to Shane and Venkataraman (2000:
219), entrepreneurial opportunities are objective: The first argument for the objectivity of entrepre-
“To have entrepreneurship, you must first have neurial opportunities is as follows: Opportunities are
entrepreneurial opportunities … the opportunities physical objects, and physical objects are objective;
themselves are objective phenomena.”3 In this view, therefore, opportunities are objective. Ramoglou and
opportunities are formed by exogenous shocks that Tsang (2016: 410) have made this argument, suggest-
disrupt market equilibrium. These shocks can be ing that opportunities are “propensities,” and (quot-
caused by (among other things) technological advan- ing Popper): “we live in a world of propensities …
ces, changes in the political or regulatory environ- [propensities] are not mere possibilities but are phys-
ment, evolving consumer tastes, and social and ical realities.”
demographic trends (Shane, 2003). A straightfor- Limitations to the first argument for the objectiv-
ward program of research has followed from this per- ity of opportunities. Physical objects (like a hydro-
spective. How does one search for and identify gen atom or a mountain) are objective since their
shocks to the socioeconomic landscape, and how existence does not depend on human minds, but it is
and why do some individuals and not others identify difficult to see how an opportunity could be a kind
and exploit them? of physical object. Indeed, to hold this position,
In contrast to the opportunity objectivists, the sub- Ramoglou and Tsang (2016) relied upon an abstruse
jectivists have asserted that opportunities are construct from Popper: “propensity” (a concept that
socially constructed (e.g., Alvarez, Barney, & Ander- never gained much traction in the philosophy
son, 2013; Baker & Nelson, 2005; Sarasvathy, 2001; of science).
Wood & McKinley, 2010, 2017, 2018). This perspec- Suggesting that opportunities are physical is even
tive proposes that opportunities are formed through more problematic because it conflates the socioeco-
entrepreneurial action rather than discovered and nomic world with the physical world. This is a
that the creation process often involves utilizing century-old mistake made by some of the most
resources in unexpected ways and integrating them respected social theorists. This idea that the physical
into existing institutions in unpredictable (i.e., non- and the social are similar underpins many founda-
objective) ways (Baker & Nelson, 2005; Dimov, 2007; tional theories of social structure and many theories
Luksha, 2008; Sarasvathy, 2001; Wood & McKinley, of entrepreneurial opportunity that draw from them.
2010, 2017). Because the agent subjectively con- Durkheim (1901/2013: 146) sometimes suggested
ceives and acts to create a new product or service, that social phenomena “must be treated as natural
and creation itself is a subjective process, propo- [i.e., physical] phenomena, subject to necessary
nents have argued that opportunity is subjective as laws,” and that social phenomena are physical phe-
well. In this view, entrepreneurs create the imperfec- nomena, “only distinguishable from other phenom-
tions in product or factor markets and then exploit ena by virtue of their greater complexity” (102).
the very imperfection they create.4 Scott (2014) and others (e.g., Alexander, 1983) have
held positions that emphasize “the fundamental
3 similarity of the social and physical sciences” (Scott,
The source of the idea that opportunity is objective
2014: 76).
goes back to Kirzner (1973, 1979), but as Kirzner (2009)
later noted, his notion of “seeing” opportunities was only In contrast, the claim advanced in this paper is
metaphorical. For Kirzner, the concept of opportunity was that the social world and the physical world are fun-
intended as a placeholder for an economic function. Shane damentally dissimilar. If this is correct, then Dur-
and Venkataraman (2000) took it and reified it into a full- kheim’s “similarity thesis,” repeated by Ramoglou
blown objectively real phenomenon, one that could be the and Tsang, Scott, Alexander, and others is precisely
target of a search, discovered, exploited, and studied like a the wrong conceptual foundation upon which to
physical object. build any theory of the social world or understand
4
Another branch of subjectivism based on the
“judgment approach” (Casson, 1982; Foss, Klein, Kor, &
Mahoney, 2008; Klein, 2008) has also found that opportu- entrepreneurs who imagine different and often unexpected
nities are subjective but has emphasized the role of thought uses or combinations of scarce resources which determine
and imagination to arrive at this position. Advocates of the objective gains (or losses). Advocates of a judgment-based
judgment approach have viewed opportunities as subjec- view have tended to view the opportunity debate as a dis-
tive because they are judgments in the minds of tracting sideshow (e.g., Foss & Klein, 2017).
2022 McBride and Wuebker 79

any component of that world, including entrepreneur- to the market or lead to the technological advance-
ial opportunity. It fails to discriminate mind-indepen- ment. Neither event is independent of them—rather,
dent physical phenomena from mind-dependent the opposite is true: they are only independent of
social phenomena. some other actor reacting to that shock that they cre-
Most social scientists are sensitive to the fact that ated. This is an example of socioeconomic epistemic
the laws of physics are categorically distinct from objectivity, not physical ontological objectivity.
the “laws” of their field. Economists typically recog-
nize that their laws are not “inexorable laws” (Tay- The Argument Against the Creation Account of
lor, 1929: 20), but they tend to “compare their field Opportunity
to physics” (Thaler, 2015: 5), and some even think of
them as inexorable, immutable, and identical to the A frequent refrain among those who have argued
natural laws of physics (e.g., Mueller, 2016).5 Yet the for the objectivity of opportunities is that the crea-
social sciences are not the physical sciences, and tion approach is a kind of postmodern relativism
social “laws” are not physical laws. where “anything goes.” Accepting that opportunities
are endogenously formed, they have argued, results
in a state of affairs where no objectivity of any kind
The Second Argument for the Objectivity of
is possible. But social constructionism need not
Opportunities
entail extreme “anything goes” relativism (Baghra-
The second argument for the objectivity of oppor- mian & Carter, 2015; Montuschi, 2007). This unwar-
tunities states that the market imperfection that ranted linkage is often a critical part of the argument
defines the opportunity exists independently of the against accounts of entrepreneurial creation. Fleet-
actor that exploits it; therefore, the opportunity is wood and Ackroyd (2004: 1), for example, impugned
objective. A technical revolution (e.g., the invention the “social constructionist ontology [from] which
of 3D printing, as in Shane, 2000) can offer opportu- postmodernist or poststructuralist oriented analysis
nities that did not previously exist, and an entrepre- is rooted.” Ramoglou and Tsang (2016) have also
neurial agent can take advantage of the objective hitched postmodern relativism to social construc-
changes in the external, objective, socioeconomic, tionism, arguing that for social constructivists:
and technological landscape. the idea of an objective world is an illusion. Reality is
Limitations to the second argument for the ultimately reducible to social constructions. There is
objectivity of opportunities. The argument most no single way the world is or can be. Agents can will-
often advanced by discovery theorists (Eckhardt & ingly create their own realities so long as they regard
Ciuchta, 2008; Shane, 2003; Shane & Eckhardt, 2003; them as real. (p. 413)
Shane & Venkataraman, 2000) contains an important
This is one reasonable definition of postmodern
insight—that the market conditions within which an
relativism, but agents cannot willingly create their
agent operates are often independent and outside of
own reality at will; we are subject to the “iron cage”
the control of that agent. But true ontological objec-
of both ontologically objective physical reality and
tive independence—that which a hydrogen atom or
epistemologically objective social reality. As Durk-
Mt. Everest possesses—is objective because its exis-
heim (1895: 70) argued, “a [social] thing is princi-
tence is independent of every human mind. A mar-
pally recognizable by virtue of not being capable of
ket imperfection is only independent of the mind of
modification through a mere act of will … . Far from
the entrepreneurial agent (and even then, it is not if
being a product of our will [social facts] determine it
the agent happens to be the one who caused the
from without.”6
imperfection—Schumpeter, 1942). The thoughts
These kinds of “anything goes” attacks (e.g., Fleet-
and behaviors of many people are what cause shocks
wood, 2005; Reed, 2005) are common, justified
complaints against postmodern relativism, but they
5
See also this quote from Graeber (2014: 44): “Above do not apply to the many institutional theorists,
all, [Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations] was an attempt to
social ontologists (Boghossian, 2007; Ludwig, 2016,
establish the newfound discipline of economics as a sci-
ence. This meant that not only did economics have its own 2017; Tuomela, 2007, 2013), social constructivists
peculiar domain of study … but that this economy oper-
6
ated according to the laws of much the same sort as Sir Durkheim has overstated his case here, since not all
Isaac Newton had so recently identified as governing the social phenomena are independent and objective. This is
physical world.” an important point we will discuss in detail below.
80 Academy of Management Review January

(Alvarez & Barney, 2010, 2013; Alvarez et al., 2014, (Graeber, 2014; Martin, 2015). Money is ontologi-
2017; Berger & Luckmann, 1967; Wood & McKinley, cally subjective, like all socioeconomic phenomena
2010, 2017, 2018), or even critical realists, like Sayer (Searle, 1995, 2010), yet like many social institu-
(2000)—all of whom have acknowledged the socially tions, money is also objective because it exists inde-
constructed nature of social phenomena. pendently of the sole control of any individual—just
Why then does constructivism so often get lumped like markets, bank account balances, organizations,
together with postmodern relativism? The root of the and regulatory agencies. How does this work? It
problem, correctly identified by the objectivists, is works because real socioeconomic phenomena are
that there is a glaring lack of explanation for social epistemologically objective.
objectivity within traditional social construction-
ism. This makes it difficult to understand how schol- The Dual Problems of Objectivity and
ars can objectively study phenomena that are Postmodernism
inherently socially constructed. Sayer (2000: 32), for
example, observed that “if the social world is We have demonstrated that the argument that
socially constructed … how can it be treated as inde- opportunities are objective because they are physical
pendent of the researcher’s knowledge?” Klein objects does not make sense; it commits the age-old
(2008) has also suggested that constructivism does error of conflating mind-dependent social phenom-
not allow for such objectivity: ena with mind-independent physical phenomena.
Neither does it work to say that market conditions
The creation approach is grounded in a social con- are objective because they are independent of all
structivist view of action … . It holds that the market
humans. Humans create such market conditions.
itself is a social construction, and that realized gains
We have also presented two sides of the same
and losses are, in part, subjective. [In my] … approach
described here … realized gains and losses are objec-
error. The first is committed by objectivists who sug-
tive and quantifiable. (p. 183) gest that everything—even socioeconomic phenom-
ena—is really physical, and so everything is
The motivation for the conflation of constructiv- objective and mind independent. The second error
ism with postmodern relativism is understandable is committed by postmodern relativists who suggest
since constructivists do not have an explanation for that everything—even a physical object—is really
socioeconomic objectivity. Objectivists do proffer an social, and thus socially constructed, subjective, and
answer to this problem—any objective socioeco- mind dependent. These are just different ways of
nomic phenomenon, like money, is objective conflating the social world with the physical world.
because it is physical, and physical objects are objec- These are the flip sides of the same mistake—a dual-
tive. Therefore, one side (social constructivism) has ity (Awodey, 2010).
no explanation for objectivity.7 The other side The objectivists have offered a critically important
(objectivism) mistakenly concludes that social phe- insight, however, by pointing to an important gap in
nomena are objective in the same way as a hydrogen constructivist theory and asking how one explains
atom or a rock. social and socioeconomic objectivity, like bank
Some social facts and objects are objective. A bank account balances and corporations. Where could
account balance is an objective fact that can be tested such objective phenomena come from if not from the
by attempting to convince a bank manager that the objectivity of the physical world? If advocates of
account’s balance should be ten times larger than the opportunity creation agree that some socioeconomic
one reflected on the statement. But money is not phenomena are as real as a “brick wall” (Alvarez &
only physical coins or paper, as credit cards and Bit- Barney, 2013), then an explanation of how objectiv-
coin demonstrate. The physical electrons in a com- ity works in the mind-dependent social world is
puter representing a bank balance are also not needed. This is what we will try to do next.
money. Entire village economies run perfectly well
with shopkeepers who keep nothing more than men-
THE OBJECTIVITY OF SOCIAL PHENOMENA
tal tallies of debits and credits (which are just quanti-
fied duties and rights) without any physical tokens If Santa Claus and IBM are both socially con-
structed objects that exist only because we believe
7
Or at least the answers from the constructivists (e.g., that they exist, but only IBM is objectively real, what
Berger & Luckmann, 1967) are answers that the objectivists is the difference? How can any social phenomenon
do not find plausible. be objective if it is not physically objective? The
2022 McBride and Wuebker 81

similarity across physical and social things when chalkboards (Epstein, 2015), and that a company can
they are both “real” is that they are both independent own and mine a real copper mountain. If we are col-
of us and often orthogonal to our desires and wishes. lectively committed to the belief that a social entity,
But therein ends the similarity. like a town, contains a forest, then a fire that deci-
The answer to the puzzle is that Paris is the capital mates the forest has decimated part of the town.
of France because we believe and act as if it is. It is A social entity can own, interact with, cause, and
epistemologically objective. IBM exists because we be affected by objective, physical entities. But,
believe and act as if it is. If no one believed that IBM again, this is only possible because we are commit-
existed, it would no longer exist. And if social enti- ted to the beliefs that Thor, the university, and the
ties constitute cognitive states and the decisions, town are related in those ways to those physical
behaviors, habits, and routines dependent upon phenomena.
such states, then the only possible source for the
independent objectivity of any social entity must be IF OPPORTUNITIES ARE ONTOLOGICALLY
grounded in those same cognitive states. The reality SUBJECTIVE, CAN WE STILL DO SCIENCE?
of any social phenomenon stems from the very struc-
ture that constitutes it—the stable beliefs of people; If opportunities are subjective and only made pos-
in other words, its epistemology. This view is coher- sible by mind-dependent cognitive states, how can
ent with social constructionism, which is the major- they be studied scientifically? Of course, epistemo-
ity view in philosophy and arguably the most logical fields already exist that study ontologically
common position found across a diverse set of per- subjective phenomena. The trick is focusing more
spectives in social theory (e.g., Berger & Luckmann, precisely on the critical components that make pos-
1967; Boghossian, 2007; DiMaggio & Powell, 1983; sible socioeconomic phenomena, and opportunities,
Meyer & Rowan, 1977; Sayer, 2000; Searle, 1995, specifically.
2010; Weick, 1979).
The problem of how to explain social (epistemo- The Core of Social Objectivity
logical) objectivity is explored in the fields of social
ontology and collective intentionality (e.g., Bratman, Though there is much that has been said, and can
1987, 2014; Epstein, 2015; Gilbert, 1992, 2015; be debated, about the specific mechanics of social
Searle, 1995, 2010; Tuomela, 2002, 2007, 2013). objectivity, there is a “center of gravity” of such
How can a social entity be both constituted by peo- efforts. Hume (1740/1978) and Berger and Luck-
ple’s cognitive states but at the same time objective mann (1967) emphasized the habits and behaviors
and independent of them? Because not every belief that establish social reality. March and Simon (1993)
matters equally, and not every belief matters all the emphasized rules (duties) and routines. Bratman
time, a social entity is real when there is some con- (1987, 2014) emphasized the intentions of individu-
sensus about its reality by those that implicitly or als in small teams that determine team behavior.
explicitly behave in ways that assume it exists or Searle (1995, 2010) emphasized beliefs about what
enable its existence. This is true of a game, an he called “status functions”—meaning rights and
exchange relationship, a market, a contract, a firm, duties—established through a declarative speech
or an entrepreneurial venture. A social entity is act. Gilbert (1992, 2015) highlighted the commit-
objectively real precisely because people (in the rele- ments and the obligations (duties) necessary.
vant positions) believe it is real and treat it as such. Although there are a diversity of approaches and def-
By contrast, a physical object is real because it exists initions, there is broad agreement about the crucial
independently of how anyone treats it or what any- importance of cognitive states (broadly construed)
one believes. These are two different and distinct and the behaviors, habits, routines, and dispositions
sources of objectivity. that flow from those cognitive states. It therefore
Though distinct, it is important to note that the seems reasonable to focus on the cognitive states first
physical world and the social world are not mutually and foremost since they determine the downstream
exclusive. The human imagination is capable of flu- behavioral effects. Within the various discussions of
idly integrating the invented social world and the specific cognitive mechanics, and sometimes using
physical world. Just as we might imagine that Thor different terminology, work has orbited around two
is the source of real thunder and lightning, so too can cognitive phenomena specifically—beliefs on the
we imagine that a nation state has boundaries on real one hand, and deontics (rights and duties) on the
geography, that a university owns real buildings and other—and almost every scholar that has studied
82 Academy of Management Review January

the structure of social reality has relied upon both. A such as “Apple makes the iPhone.” This implies the
reasonable generalization then, suggests that beliefs belief that Apple exists and reinforces Apple’s exis-
and deontics are the core cognitive features that tence. These are aggregative convergent beliefs—
make social phenomena objective. This is taken to beliefs where people converge on the same thought.
be “the standard model” in social ontology (Epstein, There are also aggregative coherent beliefs. For exam-
2015; Guala, 2007). ple, Person A believes that “Apple makes the
Beliefs are cognitive representations that depict iPhone,” Person B believes that “Apple has the larg-
some state of the world. Deontics are duties and est market capitalization,” and Person C believes
rights. Duties are the obligations that some individ- something else about Apple. These too imply that
ual or party has; rights are the permissible actions Apple, as a social entity, exists, and so these too rein-
that some individual or party can perform. Deontics force its existence to some degree. Finally, there are
have often been described as a particular set of cogni- aggregative divergent beliefs. These are diverse but
tive beliefs (Gilbert, 1992, 2015; Ludwig, 2016, 2017; contradictory. For example, Person A believes that
Searle, 1995, 2010) or cognitive-behavioral phenom- “Apple is secretly working on a smart car” while Per-
ena (Berger & Luckmann, 1967; Wood & McKinley, son B believes that “Apple is not secretly working on
2017). In what is arguably the dominant view (Gil- a smart car.” Both sides of the contradiction make the
bert, 1992, 2015; Ludwig, 2016, 2017; Searle, 1995, same presupposition about Apple’s existence. We
2010), just as physical particles are the fundamental can refer to these categories more simply as conver-
building blocks of physical objects, beliefs and gent beliefs, coherent beliefs, and divergent beliefs.
deontics are the fundamental building blocks of However, it should be noted that aggregations of
social entities. When a social entity like a marriage beliefs are not equally weighted. For example, deter-
or a role in an organization is created, these actions mining the winner of a gymnastics event in the
bring duties and rights into existence. For example, Olympics depends on the beliefs of the judges more
a married couple in the United States has rights to than the spectators. The beliefs of Apple’s board of
certain tax deductions with both the state and fede- directors that Steve Jobs should have been fired (and
ral governments, and they have the duty to make eventually rehired) counted more than the share-
medical decisions for one another. They have the holders’ (or anyone else’s) beliefs. And Google’s
right to one another’s joint assets and a range of less founders Sergey Brin and Larry Page’s beliefs about
explicit, culturally determined rights and duties. their nascent search engine technology counted for
Similarly, a member of a board of directors might more than their Stanford advisor’s beliefs about the
have the duty to provide advice at board meetings project. Why do some people’s beliefs count more
and the right to compensation as part of that than others? Typically, because some people hold
position. deontic roles that establish their right to influence an
Duties and rights exist when enough people (in associated social phenomenon more than others.
the right positions) believe and act as if they exist.
This is what brings a marriage, a board position, a Deontics
cofounder relationship, or a Delaware C-corporation
into existence. The stability and continuation of Deontics are necessary to shape and establish the
those beliefs and deontics establish and maintain epistemic objective existence of a social entity. It’s
this epistemological objectivity (i.e., the reality of not just that we believe money can be used for trans-
that social entity). Beliefs and deontics are the funda- actions, we also believe that it confers upon the pos-
mental pieces that constitute and shape the objectiv- sessor certain rights and duties. You have the right to
ity of any social entity (Gilbert, 1992, 2015; Gordon use it as “legal tender for all debts, public and
& McBride, 2018; Ludwig, 2016, 2017; Searle, 1995, private.” You also (at least in the United States) have
2010), and focusing on their roles allows us to com- the duty not to burn or otherwise destroy it. You
ment on how exactly this works. might believe that the son of the tribal chief is the
rightful successor to the throne, but you also have
the right to complain if he is not chosen and the duty
Beliefs
to obey him. The cornerstone of civilization, the
We are almost always interested in collections agreement, and the formal version—the contract—is
(i.e., aggregations) of beliefs. If we think of the kinds simply the enumeration of rights and duties that
of beliefs agents can entertain about a corporation, describe the permissible behavior of each party. A
for example, they might all possess the same belief, founder that files articles of incorporation with the
2022 McBride and Wuebker 83

Department of Corporations is establishing their coherent, and some are contradictory and divergent.
legal right to operate, establishing both beliefs and On the deontic side, Apple has a wide variety of rela-
rights from the department, the state, and the federal tionships with diverse agents and other social enti-
government. The incorporated entity now has the ties in the form of software license agreements and
duty to pay taxes as a legal entity, the right to open supplier and employee contracts. Although deontics
bank accounts in the entity’s name, sign contracts on are often structured under some kind of transactive
behalf of the firm, and so on. goal, many deontic relationships, especially those
Although deontic relationships can be divided internal to the firm, have extensive common goal
into several types, the most relevant to consider for structures (firm objectives) under the background of
our purposes here are whether the deontics exist in expected compensation (transactive relationships).
the service of a common goal, a transactive goal, or However, there are many different social entities
are imposed. Steve Jobs, Steve Wozniak, and Ronald and few are so extremely objective. Imagine a “Bird
Wayne came together and formed agreements among of the Week Bird-watching Club” that meets once
themselves as the founders of Apple Computer Com- and might in the future conduct a bird-watching
pany (now Apple). These deontics were established field trip. Is the club an objective social entity?
under the broader common goal of building a suc- Unless there are a wide variety of beliefs and
cessful firm (after they failed to sell their startup). deontics associated with the club, the answer is no.
Apple has an agreement with Samsung to manufac- Only the organizer and a few people have even
ture touchscreens for Apple’s products. The con- thought about it, and the organizer has only one
tractual agreement operates under a transactive vague self-imposed duty (to perhaps organize the
relationship, a situation where each derives benefits field trip). No one else has formed any belief, much
from the exchange and enters into the agreement to less a deontic agreement with the organizer or the
achieve different goals—for Samsung, the goal is to club. Many early startups are much closer to this
receive capital, and for Apple, the goal is to receive bird-watching club than to Apple.
the needed parts. Common goal and transactive goal
agreements are voluntary agreements, but many of The Spectrum of Social Objectivity in
the deontics within which we are entangled are Opportunities
instead imposed upon people without their volun-
tary acceptance. As individuals, we are subject to an It is clear then that the objectivity of social entities
enormous collection of duties, like civil and criminal spans a spectrum, from nonexistent and utterly sub-
codes that govern the part of the world we happen to jective (like the barely existing bird-watching club)
be in, regardless of whether we want these imposed all the way up to a fully objective social entity like
obligations (see McBride, 2021, for a more extensive Apple or the Canadian government. The greater the
discussion about the three core types of deontics— number and the more diverse the beliefs and
imposed, voluntary, and autogenic/entrepreneurial). deontics, the further toward the objective end of the
scale the social entity sits.
How do we assess the objectivity of an opportu-
Determining the Objectivity of Social Entities
nity? The same way that all social phenomena are
The epistemic objectivity of any specific social assessed—we examine whether the beliefs that con-
entity can be determined by looking at whether there stitute the opportunity are widespread and diverse
are aggregative (convergent, coherent, or divergent) and whether the deontics necessary for that opportu-
beliefs about it and whether there are deontics (com- nity are widespread and exist among diverse parties.
mon, transactive, or imposed). The application of If both hold, then it is an epistemically objective
these principles can be abbreviated to a process opportunity. If both fail to hold, then it is an episte-
where, for any given social entity, we simply look mically subjective opportunity. If both exist to some
for a broad collection of beliefs and deontics. Apple moderate degree, then the opportunity falls some-
is an objective social entity because there are an where along the spectrum.
extraordinary number of diverse beliefs about it Opportunities differ in how much agreement there
from both inside and outside the organization, rang- is about their viability, as noted by Sarasvathy, Dew,
ing from beliefs held by governments, partners, Velamuri, and Venkataraman (2003) and others.
employees, customers, suppliers, and more (Padgett They differ in how much objective data exists in sup-
& Powell, 2012). Many of these are identical port of them, they differ in how far along the entre-
beliefs and convergent, many are different but preneurs are in their effort to acquire such data, they
84 Academy of Management Review January

differ in how many objective market conditions exist The ontology–epistemology distinction decom-
to facilitate the realization of the opportunity, and posed the question “Are opportunities objective?”
they differ in how “realized” (i.e., how integrated) into two separate questions, the first of which was
the opportunity already is into other deontic facets of answered quickly: “No.” Opportunities are always
the socioeconomic environment. For example, a ontologically subjective. The more interesting ques-
profitable, stable 30-year-old franchise for sale tion was the second, epistemological one. But social
affords an opportunity of a sort. The knowledge that (epistemological) objectivity cannot be derived from
comprises the purchase, running, and sale of the fran- its physical objectivity. It is derived from the stable,
chise is well-known. There are 30 years of existing consistent beliefs and deontics in the minds of
sales data and a well-established operational infra- people.
structure. There is an extensive and well-established Part of what motivated the constructionist view
collection of beliefs that comprise that vetted knowl- that opportunities are subjective was the belief that
edge and an extensive and well-established collec- the entire socioeconomic environment is socially
tion of deontic relationships including the franchise constructed. It is because it is mind dependent and
owner, the franchisee, customers, and suppliers. The thereby ontologically subjective. What motivated
opportunity is, in other words, an objective opportu- the discovery theorists was the fact that some oppor-
nity. Contrast that with the origins of many technol- tunities are the result of real, objective imperfections
ogy startups that often begin as nothing more than of the socioeconomic environment. This is also cor-
a few beliefs about which there is often no wider rect, but there is no contradiction. The socioeco-
consensus and none of the deontic relationships nomic environment is both objective and subjective
necessary to exercise the opportunity. in the sense that it is ontologically subjective but
The fact that social phenomena, including opportu- often epistemologically objective. These are differ-
nities, fall on an epistemic spectrum is an important ent dimensions of objectivity, ones that are often
point. It implies that there is no categorical answer to conflated.
the question about an opportunity’s epistemological Other than an interesting diversion into a question
objectivity. The epistemic question, unlike the onto- about entrepreneurial opportunity, a tough-minded
logical version, does not have a simple “yes” or “no” management scholar might ask: “Who cares?” We
categorical answer. All entrepreneurial opportuni- care because the fundamental structure that shapes
ties, like all social phenomena, are ontologically sub- an opportunity shapes the entire socioeconomic
jective, but we must look at each specific case and world and all the social phenomena that we study. It
examine whether there is a significant aggregation of is no exaggeration to say that finding the answer to
beliefs (convergent, coherent, and divergent) and the question about what makes any social phenom-
deontics (common goal, transactive goal, or imposed) ena objective might be the single most important
to determine its degree of epistemic objectivity. piece of the foundation for the future success of the
social sciences. Neither is it an exaggeration to say
that the failure to definitively answer this question
IMPLICATIONS FOR ENTREPRENEURSHIP has caused innumerable problems and confusions,
AND MANAGEMENT including hindering advances in entrepreneurship
These arguments have a variety of implications for theory.
entrepreneurship and management and for the social The opportunity debate is merely one instance of
sciences more broadly. Some of these implications the much larger question of how to understand
are discussed in this section. objectivity. Unfortunately, past attempts have often
privileged the physical world over the social world,
to suggest that everything is objectively real, physi-
Broader Implications
cal, and mind independent (which must be false), or
This paper offers an answer to the question: What they have made the postmodern error of privileging
is social objectivity? The answer has three implica- the social world over the physical world, making
tions. It untangles the opportunity debate because everything social, subjective, and mind dependent
there are now criteria for what makes an opportunity (which must also be false). Physical objects are mind
(or any social phenomena) objective, it clarifies a independent. Social entities are mind dependent.
critical divide between the physical sciences and the The physical is frequently conflated with the
social sciences, and it describes the “atomic parti- social, and physical objectivity is frequently con-
cles” of any social phenomena. flated with social objectivity. The temptation to
2022 McBride and Wuebker 85

lump everything under one of these two extremes is epistemically objective, but they do not remain
the central hazard of social theorizing. there. Typically, the goal of a team that exploits the
opportunity is to become, like any successful busi-
Pedagogical Implications ness, tied into a network of collective beliefs and
deontics that promote its existence and persistence.
Taking the endogenous formation of opportunity In other words, the goal is to turn a subjective oppor-
seriously implies that we should not instruct bud- tunity into an objective opportunity.
ding entrepreneurs to search for an opportunity like To accomplish this goal, one must construct deon-
they are searching for a hidden treasure, as discovery tic relationships (Dimov, 2011) which entails build-
theory suggests. Training students to search for a ing production or distribution partnerships, forming
“hidden” opportunity is less useful than coaching relationships with suppliers, attracting customers,
them to develop the skills required to evaluate the opening bank accounts, hiring attorneys to write
beliefs that form the opportunity idea and calibrating agreements, complying with local and federal regu-
those beliefs against estimates about the specific lations, paying taxes to government entities, entering
deontics needed to execute that idea. It is critical to agreements to get electricity in offices, and so on.
learn how to propagate the beliefs that define the Each action is an additional deontic line tethering
idea and how to craft the relevant beliefs and that organization more firmly into an existing web of
deontics among stakeholders that lead them to social structures. The revealed core task of the entre-
assume obligations on behalf of the organization and preneur is to push an idea, theory, or plan from
lead customers to engage in (deontic) transactions to something that might be merely epistemically sub-
purchase goods or services from it. jective into the realm of epistemic objectivity.
Unfortunately, years of inculcating students in the But the early-stage opportunity is often delicate,
practice of information acquisition and assimilation with few beliefs about its viability and few deontic
and years of suggesting that any budding entrepre- agreements in place to establish the initial strands of
neur should be able to answer profit projection ques- objectivity. As noted by Wood and McKinley (2017),
tions ex ante (questions that are often unanswerable) these small strands must be continually reproduced
has taken the focus away from more important train- through consensus among stakeholders about the
ing involving hands-on practice in creating and shap- opportunity’s viability. The loss of these beliefs and
ing social entities. Taking the implications of social deontics leads to a dissolution and loss of the oppor-
ontology seriously implies that the generation of arti- tunity itself.
facts (such as plans, business model specifications,
and pitch decks) and even some entrepreneurial A Different View of the Entrepreneurial Firm
actions (like experimentation) are not always ends
but can also be the means with which to shape the Several strands of conceptual and empirical work
social world (Shelef, Wuebker, & Barney, 2019). Early offer explanations as to why firms exist. Two ration-
lived experience (and university courses) tends to ales for the firm common to these explanations are
subtly reinforce the lesson that the social world is (a) establishing who has the right to make what kinds
fixed and that altering it is incredibly difficult, even of decisions and (b) how to determine the various
dangerous. Entrepreneurship requires unlearning claims for the residual cash flows for the value the
this. Until a student experiences the social world as firm creates and captures (Alvarez & Barney, 2005;
malleable, learns exactly what the levers of malleabil- Barney, 2018; Gibbons, 2005). Entrepreneurship has
ity are, and then accumulates practice creating and historically had an uneasy relationship with tradi-
altering social reality, there is little hope that he will tional theories of the firm, in part because entrepre-
magically do so while building a large organization, neurs often must make choices about decision rights
dexterously assembling all the deontics necessary to and residual claims long before the economic value
design a social vehicle that exercises the opportunity. of those choices can be known, even probabilisti-
cally (Alvarez & Barney, 2005; Garrouste & Saussier,
2005). When these traditional explanations of eco-
The Goal of Transforming Subjective Into
nomic organization are extended to innovative or
Objective Opportunities
entrepreneurial settings, their utility becomes much
An opportunity and the entity that exploits it are less clear.
distinct but intertwined. Both start somewhere along While this paper connects and contributes to other
the spectrum between epistemically subjective and theories of the entrepreneurial firm that focus on
86 Academy of Management Review January

asset ownership (Foss & Klein, 2012), resource coor- beliefs of others for their existence, then the critical
dination (Alvarez & Barney, 2004; Nickerson & task of the entrepreneur is crafting beliefs and
Zenger, 2004), contracting and residual control (Van deontics. Marketing is about shaping beliefs in
Den Steen, 2010), and charismatic authority (Lan- potential customers that might change deontic
glois, 2007), it offers an alternative view of entrepre- behavior. Pitching is about shaping the beliefs of
neurial organization grounded in the identification, potential stakeholders. Recruiting is about persuad-
generation, and eventual distribution of beliefs and ing the most qualified candidates that accepting a
deontic structures (Dimov, 2011). position is in their best interest. The fundamental
In this view, organization building involves build- activity of any opportunity exploitation, which con-
ing a web of deontics (often in the form of agree- tinues as the opportunity matures into a durable and
ments) with cofounders, employees, customers, sustainable economic entity, is the (endless) work of
investors, partners, stakeholders, regulatory agen- shaping the beliefs and deontics both within the
cies, and others that establish the rights and duties of organization and in those individuals and social
the participants in those relationships (Barney, entities within the socioeconomic context that the
2018). This view is coherent with, and provides an opportunity-exploiting vehicles need to grow.
expansion of, the nexus of contracts view (Jensen & Of course, the importance of shaping beliefs in
Meckling, 1976), in that any organization can be entrepreneurial settings is not a new idea (e.g., Gart-
seen as a web of agreements, but those agreements ner, 1985). What is new here is the suggestion that
can be analyzed in more precise detail in terms of doing so is what establishes the reality of the entre-
their deontics—the rights and duties that comprise preneurial effort and as such is the core entrepre-
them. neurial task. At first, entrepreneurs envision those
structures, and each action they take—building
Establishing Beliefs, Rights, and Duties production or distribution partnerships, forming
relationships with suppliers, transacting with cus-
Entrepreneurial action, then, is not necessarily
tomers, complying with local and federal regula-
about manifesting the cognitive biases “appropriate
tions, paying taxes to government entities—tether
for an entrepreneur” (Baron, 2004; Mitchell, Buse-
their nascent social structure more firmly into the
nitz, Lant, McDougall, Morse, & Smith, 2004; Saras-
web of extant social structures. In this view, the core
vathy, 2001), discovering customers (Blank, 2012),
task of the entrepreneur and the heart of entrepre-
validating a business model (Zott, Amit, & Massa,
neurial action is the identification, ordering, and dis-
2011), catalyzing passion (Cardon, Wincent, Singh,
semination of rights and duties that push an idea,
& Drnovsek, 2009), crafting a compelling narrative
theory, or plan from something epistemically subjec-
(Lounsbury & Glynn, 2001), leveraging one’s net-
tive into the realm of the epistemically objective.
work of prior relationships (Stuart & Sorenson,
2007), writing a business plan, or filing a legal
entity—though all of those are relevant tools in the
Who are Entrepreneurs?
right circumstances. It is, at a deeper level, about
establishing beliefs and crafting the deontics that Within the theoretical framework developed here,
escalate the entrepreneurial team toward epistemic entrepreneurs can be thought of as individuals with
objectivity and success. beliefs about how a particular bundle of resources
Telling a compelling story, for example, is only can generate economic value (Alvarez & Barney,
useful and relevant if that story succeeds in estab- 2007; Barney, 1986; Felin & Zenger, 2017; Foss &
lishing a belief and compelling a stakeholder to Klein, 2012) who subsequently enroll stakeholders
assume an obligation that benefits the effort (e.g., to assist in the realization of their idea (Alvarez,
compels an investor to part with needed capital or a Young, & Woolley, 2015; Barney, 2018) through their
manufacturer to extend advantageous credit terms, absorption of deontics. Early-stage efforts typically
or the customers to buy the product). Inexpensive operate under conditions of uncertainty where there
experimentation and learning by doing is only useful is little empirical support for their pivotal assump-
if the results of that experiment calibrate the found- tions (e.g., that people will be willing to exchange
ers’ beliefs so that they can more effectively find a money for a “pet rock”). It is the job of the entrepre-
model for economic profit. neur—the “first believer”—to propagate their beliefs
If entrepreneurial opportunities are essentially in others, building consensus around beliefs that are
social, and social phenomena are dependent on the often impossible to justify.
2022 McBride and Wuebker 87

The discovery view takes value as a given, and entrepreneur toward the end of securing economic
many scholars working at the intersection of entre- profit. This means that lacking the relevant beliefs
preneurship and organization theory (e.g., Alvarez & and lacking the relevant deontics will block the for-
Barney, 2004; 2005; Foss and Klein, 2012; Klein, mation of the opportunity idea and its exercise.
2008) have noted that this assumption has made it Other entrepreneurs did not build Uber or Airbnb
difficult to theorize about why firms come into exis- (in part) because they did not possess the beliefs that
tence and the role that the firm itself might play in constitute those ideas. Such beliefs were also miss-
the search for or creation of new value. It also ing from the wider socioeconomic environment, so
obscures the need for stakeholder enrollment in the they could not be discovered (Chesky, 2015; Wilson,
first place (Barney, 2018; Shelef et al., 2019). 2011). Such an omission from the landscape does
The creation view has implications for entrepre- not prevent the re-creation of the idea or the execu-
neurial action and organizational theory. There is a tion of it, but being forced to regenerate the idea sui
growing body of work exploring the specific organi- generis is nontrivial. Even once regenerated, a team
zational challenges facing actors creating value still faces the detailed, laborious work of building
under conditions of Knightian uncertainty (e.g., out a huge web of deontic agreements that constitute
Alvarez, Young, & Woolley, 2018; Burns et al., 2016; an organization honed to exercise that vision.
Engel, Kaandorp, & Elfring, 2017; Mauer, Wuebker, The collection of beliefs about an entrepreneurial
& Brettel, 2018; Shelef, Wuebker, & Barney, 2020; effort are shaped through careful thinking and imagi-
Shelef et al., 2019). For example, stakeholders have nation. There are pieces critical to the opportunity
rights and responsibilities for the entrepreneurial without which the idea can never come to fruition.
effort—some of which might include working for the The entrepreneurs behind ride-sharing platforms,
firm, but not necessarily. When stakeholders are ver- for example, held two beliefs: first, that millions of
tically integrated, they have one set of rights and private vehicles were an enormous untapped re-
responsibilities; when they are not vertically inte- source; and second, that it would be possible to
grated, they have another set of rights and responsi- change society’s perspective on riding in a stranger’s
bilities. Either way, they possess rights and private vehicle. The more that the critical beliefs are
responsibilities on behalf of the effort. missing, “distant,” or impossible, the bigger the bar-
There are opportunities for future work exploring rier to forming the idea. The more elaborate and dif-
a new set of entrepreneurial traits—those associated ficult the deontic framework required for building
with the instantiation of beliefs and deontics. Some the organization needed to exercise the opportunity,
have argued that the research on distinctive entre- the greater the barrier to building it.
preneurial traits (e.g., Åstebro, Herz, Nanda, & Thiel and Masters (2014: 5–6) asked, “What
Weber, 2014; Low & McMillan, 1998) “appears to important truth do very few people agree with you
have reached a dead end” (Aldrich, 1999: 76), but on?” and answered: “A good answer will take the fol-
this conclusion may be premature. Perhaps distinc- lowing form: ‘Most people believe in x, but the truth
tive traits have not been found because scholars are is the opposite of x.’” Put another way, Thiel and
looking in the wrong place. Entrepreneurship theory Masters referred to a belief that is missing from the
might benefit from looking at the specific traits that general landscape (i.e., is not widely believed) that,
enable agents to propagate beliefs and deontics in if combined with the relevant deontic relationships,
those around them. This work may draw inspiration would generate profits. Heterogeneous beliefs, along
from work in entrepreneurship on social compe- with heterogeneous ability in establishing and main-
tence (e.g., Baron & Markman, 2003), entrepreneurial taining appropriate deontic relationships, are mech-
empathy (McMullen, 2015), and narrative construc- anisms that enable economic profits to be created
tion (Lounsbury & Glynn, 2001), or draw on related and sustained.
insights from marketing (e.g., Cialdini, 1984), negoti-
ation, and relationship building. You Cannot Search for and Discover What Does
Not Exist
Missing Beliefs and Missing Deontics Block the
When it comes to subjective opportunities—very
Execution of an Opportunity
novel, innovative, ambitious, or very early-stage
Beliefs and deontics constitute both the opportu- opportunities—there is a reason why the discovery
nity idea and the organization that executes the idea, theorist’s “treasure hunt model” fails: there is noth-
so they are the core components crafted by the ing there to discover. It is not just that an opportunity
88 Academy of Management Review January

is not a physical object but that there is no object of known and proven beliefs and already-existing
any sort there. Beliefs constitute the idea for an deontic relationships.
opportunity but there is no aggregation of beliefs or This work supplements social constructionist
deontics in a truly subjective opportunity by defini- views of entrepreneurial opportunity and describes a
tion, so there is no noticeable collection of beliefs new path toward an understanding of how economic
that could be discovered. value—and social phenomena more broadly— are
Before Airbnb catalyzed a widespread change in created. The ontology of the social world is far more
people’s beliefs about the viability of treating the complex than the ontology of the physical world,
spare room in their home as a source of revenue, and so the resultant confusions are understandable.
beliefs and deontic agreements to do so simply did However, we have made progress on a basic frame-
not exist (in any noticeable number). In fact, that work that renders some of this complexity approach-
aspect of Airbnb’s model was roundly rejected as able. Understanding that social phenomena are
implausible by the venture capital firms the found- mind dependent and physical phenomena are mind
ers attempted to enroll (Chesky, 2015). Arguing that independent will help avoid conflations of the two
it would have been feasible to “discover” the Airbnb in the future. Much more remains to be said, how-
model like a treasure in the forest is to suggest that ever. We invite others to join us in exploring new
entrepreneurs somehow search the landscape for a applications of this perspective in entrepreneurship
currently nonexistent, invisible belief and miracu- specifically and management and all the social sci-
lously point to something that does not exist. ences generally.
Attempting an “entrepreneurial search” by running
revenue models of socioeconomic worlds with REFERENCES
“unrealistic” and endless missing belief premises is
Aldrich, H. 1999. Organizations evolving. Newbury Park,
an impossible prescription and does not match CA: Sage.
observational accounts of what entrepreneurs do in
Alexander, J. 1983. Theoretical logic in sociology, vol.
practice (e.g., Alvarez et al., 2015, 2018; Sarasvathy,
1–4. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
2001).
Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2004. Organizing rent genera-
tion and appropriation: Toward a theory of the entre-
CONCLUSION preneurial firm. Journal of Business Venturing, 19:
621–635.
Management scholars are interested in a par- Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2005. How do entrepreneurs
ticular class of socioeconomic objects and activities. organize firms under conditions of uncertainty? Jour-
Although the interests of our field span topics, levels nal of Management, 31: 776–793.
of analysis, and units of analysis, what unites Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2007. Discovery and crea-
management scholars is our common interest in tion: Alternative theories of entrepreneurial action.
mind-dependent social phenomena and the social- Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 1: 11–26.
organizational structures that facilitate the develop-
Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2010. Entrepreneurship and
ment and exploitation of economic value. epistemology: The philosophical underpinnings of
Once the question about opportunity’s objectivity the study of entrepreneurial opportunities. Academy
is divided into an ontological and an epistemological of Management Annals, 4: 557–583.
question, the debate is resolved, and we see that that Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2013. Epistemology, oppor-
all social phenomena, including opportunities, are tunities, and entrepreneurship: Comments on Venka-
ontologically subjective but vary on the continuum taraman, et al., (2012) and Shane (2012). Academy of
of epistemic objectivity. Taking seriously the core Management Review, 38: 154–157.
result—that any social phenomenon is made possi- Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. 2019. Has the concept of
ble by beliefs and deontics—made it clear that any opportunities been fruitful in the field of entrepre-
opportunity, and any social structure built to exploit neurship? Academy of Management Perspectives.
it, must consist of beliefs and deontics, the greater doi: 10.5465/amp.2018.0014
the number and diversity of which increases its (epi- Alvarez, S. A., Barney, J. B., & Anderson, P. 2013. Perspec-
stemic) objectivity. Subjective opportunities involve tive—forming and exploiting opportunities: The
implausible, nonexistent, or “lone” beliefs. Objec- implications of discovery and creation processes for
tive opportunities and the entities built to exploit entrepreneurial and organizational research. Organi-
them on the other end of the scale are grounded in zation Science, 24: 301–317.
2022 McBride and Wuebker 89

Alvarez, S. A., Barney, J. B., McBride, R., & Wuebker, R. Braver, L., & Danneels, E. 2018. Propensities return us to
2014. Realism in the study of entrepreneurship. Acad- the discovery-creation debate about entrepreneurial
emy of Management Review, 39: 227–231. opportunities. Academy of Management Review, 43:
Alvarez, S. A., Young, S. L., & Woolley, J. L. 2015. Oppor- 812–815.
tunities and institutions: A co-creation story of the Burns, B. L., Barney, J. B., Angus, R. W., & Herrick, H. N.
king crab industry. Journal of Business Venturing, 2015. Enrolling stakeholders under conditions of risk
30: 95–112. and uncertainty. Strategic Entrepreneurship Jour-
Alvarez, S. A., Young, S. L., & Woolley, J. L. 2018. Creating nal, 10: 97–106.
the world’s deadliest catch: The process of enrolling Cardon, M. S., Wincent, J., Singh, J., & Drnovsek, M. 2009.
stakeholders in an uncertain endeavor. Business & The nature and experience of entrepreneurial passion.
Society, 59: 287–321. Academy of Management Review, 34: 511–532.
Åstebro, T., Herz, H., Nanda, R., & Weber, R. A. 2014. Seek- Casson, M. 1982. The entrepreneur: An economic theory.
ing the roots of entrepreneurship: Insights from behav- Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
ioral economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives, Chesky, B. 2015, June 26. 7 rejections. Medium. Retrieved
28: 49–70. from https://medium.com/@bchesky/7-rejections-
Awodey, S. 2010. Category theory. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford 7d894cbaa084
University Press. Cialdini, R. B. 1984. Influence: The psychology of persua-
Baghramian, M., & Carter, A. 2015. Relativism. In E. N. sion. New York, NY: Harper Collins.
Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philoso- Cornelissen, J. P., & Clarke, J. S. 2010. Imagining and ratio-
phy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/ nalizing opportunities: Inductive reasoning and the
archives/win2015/entries/relativism/. creation and justification of new ventures. Academy
Baker, T., & Nelson, R. E. 2005. Creating something from of Management Review, 35: 539–557.
nothing: Resource construction through entrepreneur- Davidsson, P. 2015. Entrepreneurial opportunities and the
ial bricolage. Administrative Science Quarterly, 50: entrepreneurship nexus: A re-conceptualization. Jour-
329–366. nal of Business Venturing, 30: 674–695.
Barney, J. B. 1986. Strategic factor markets: Expectations, DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. 1983. The iron cage revis-
luck, and business strategy. Management Science, ited: Institutional isomorphism and collective ratio-
10: 1231–1241. nality in organizational fields. American Sociological
Barney, J. B. 2018. Why resource-based theory’s model of Review, 48: 147–160.
profit appropriation must incorporate a stakeholder Dimov, D. 2007. Beyond the single-person, single-insight
perspective. Strategic Management Journal, 39: attribution in understanding entrepreneurial opportu-
3305–3325. nities. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 31:
Baron, R. A. 2004. The cognitive perspective: A valuable tool 713–731.
for answering entrepreneurship’s basic “why” questions. Dimov, D. 2011. Grappling with the unbearable elusive-
Journal of Business Venturing, 19: 221–239. ness of entrepreneurial opportunities. Entrepreneur-
Baron, R. A., & Markman, G. D. 2003. Beyond social capi- ship Theory and Practice, 35: 57–81.
tal: How social skills can enhance entrepreneurs’ suc- Durkkeim, E. 1895/1982. The rules of sociological
cess. Academy of Management Executive, 14: 41–60. method. S. Lukes (Ed.). New York, NY: The Free
Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. 1967. The social construc- Press.
tion of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowl- Eckhardt, J. T., & Ciuchta, M. P. 2008. Selected variation:
edge. New York, NY: Anchor. The population-level implications of multistage selec-
Blank, S., & Dorf, B. 2020. The startup owner's manual: tion in entrepreneurship. Strategic Entrepreneurship
The step-by-step guide for building a great com- Journal, 2: 209–224.
pany. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Eckhardt, J. T., & Shane, S. A. 2003. Opportunities and entre-
Boghossian, P. 2007. Fear of knowledge: Against relativ- preneurship. Journal of Management, 29: 333–349.
ism and constructivism. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Eckhardt, J. T., & Shane, S. A. 2012. Response to the com-
Press. mentaries: The IO nexus integrates objective and sub-
Bratman, M. 1987. Intentions, plans, and practical rea- jective aspects of entrepreneurship. Academy of
son. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Management Review, 38: 160–163.
Bratman, M. 2014. Shared agency: A planning theory of Eckhardt, J. T., & Shane, S. A. 2013. Response to the com-
acting together. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University mentaries: The individual-opportunity (IO) nexus
Press. integrates objective and subjective aspects of
90 Academy of Management Review January

entrepreneurship. Academy of Management Review, (Eds.), Philosophical reflexivity and entrepreneur-


38: 160–163. ship research: 265–361 (ebook numbering). London,
Engel, Y., Kaandorp, M., & Elfring, T. 2017. Toward a U.K.: Routledge.
dynamic process model of entrepreneurial networking Graeber, D. 2014. Debt: The first 5000 years. Brooklyn,
under uncertainty. Journal of Business Venturing, NY: Nelville House Publishing.
32: 35–51. Guala, F. 2007. The philosophy of social science:
Epstein, B. 2015. The ant trap: Rebuilding the founda- Metaphysical and empirical. Philosophy Compass, 2:
tions of the social sciences. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford Uni- 954–980.
versity Press. Hart, H. L. A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford, U.K.:
Felin, T., & Zenger, T. R. 2017. The theory-based view: Clarendon.
Economic actors as theorists. Strategy Science, 2: Hume, D. 1978. A treatise of human nature, 2nd ed. New
258–271. York, NY: Oxford University Press. (Original work
Fleetwood, S. 2005. Ontology in organization and manage- published 1740.)
ment studies: A critical realist perspective. Organiza- Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. H. 1976. Theory of the
tion, 12: 197–222. firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs and owner-
Fleetwood, S., & Ackroyd, S. 2004. Critical realist appli- ship structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3:
cations in organization and management studies. 305–360.
Hove, U.K.: Psychology Press. Kirzner, I. M. 1973. Entrepreneurship and competition.
Foss, N. J., & Klein, P. G. 2012. Organizing entrepreneur- Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
ial judgment: A new approach to the firm. Cam- Kirzner, I. M. 1979. Perception, opportunity and profit:
bridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. Studies in the theory of entrepreneurship. Chicago,
Foss, N. J., & Klein, P. G. 2017. Entrepreneurial discovery IL: University of Chicago Press.
or creation? In search of the middle ground. Academy Kirzner, I. M. 2009. The alert and creative entrepreneur:
of Management Review, 42: 733–736. A clarification. Small Business Economics, 32: 145–152.
Foss, N. J., & Klein, P. G. 2018. Entrepreneurial opportuni- Klein, P. 2008. Opportunity discovery, entrepreneurial
ties: Who needs them? Academy of Management action, and economic organization. Strategic Man-
Perspectives, 34: 366–377. agement Journal, 2: 175–190.
Foss, N. J., Klein, P. G., Kor, Y. Y., & Mahoney, J. T. 2008. Knight, F. 1921. Risk, uncertainty, and profit. Boston,
Entrepreneurship, subjectivism, and the resource- MA: Hart, Schaffner & Marx.
based view: Toward a new synthesis. Strategic Entre-
Langlois, R. N. 2007. The entrepreneurial theory of the
preneurship Journal, 2: 73–94.
firm and the theory of the entrepreneurial firm. Jour-
Gaglio, C. M., & Katz, J. A. 2001. The psychological basis of nal of Management Studies, 44: 1107–1124.
opportunity identification: Entrepreneurial alertness.
Lawson, C., Latsis, J. S., & Martins, N. (Eds.) 2013. Contri-
Small Business Economics, 16: 95–111.
butions to social ontology. London, U.K.: Routledge.
Garrouste, P., & Saussier, S. 2005. Looking for a theory of Lounsbury, M., & Glynn, M. A. 2001. Cultural entrepre-
the firm: Future challenges. Journal of Economic neurship: Stories, legitimacy, and the acquisition
Behavior & Organization, 58: 178–199. of resources. Strategic Management Journal, 22:
Gartner, W. B. 1985. A conceptual framework for describ- 545–564.
ing the phenomenon of new venture creation. Acad- Low, M. B., & MacMillan, I. C. 1988. Entrepreneurship:
emy of Management Review, 10: 696–706. Past research and future challenges. Journal of Man-
Gibbons, R. 2005. Four formal(izable) theories of the firm? agement, 14: 139–161.
Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 58: Ludwig, K. 2016. Understanding collective action: From
200–245. individual to plural agency: Collective action 1.
Gilbert, M. 1992. On social facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.
University Press. Ludwig, K. 2017. Understanding collective action: From
Gilbert, M. 2015. Joint commitment: How we make the plural to institutional agency: Collective action 2,
social world. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.
Gordon, B., & McBride, R. 2018. Toward a unified account Luksha, P. 2008. Niche construction: The process of oppor-
of the firm: Deontic architecture. In A. Fayolle, S. tunity creation in the environment. Strategic Entre-
Ramoglou, M. Karatas-Ozkan, & K. Nicolopoulou preneurship Journal, 2: 269–283.
2022 McBride and Wuebker 91

March, J. G., & Simon, H. A. 1993. Organizations (2nd Sarasvathy, S. 2001. Causation and effectuation: Toward a
ed.). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. theoretical shift from economic inevitability to entre-
Martin, F. 2015. Money: The unauthorized biography preneurial contingency. Academy of Management
from coinage to cryptocurrencies. New York, NY: Review, 26: 243–263.
Vintage. Sarasvathy, S. D., Dew, N., Velamuri, S. R., & Venkatara-
Mauer, R., Wuebker, R., Schl€
uter, J., & Brettel, M. 2018. man, S. 2003. Three views of entrepreneurial opportu-
Prediction and control: An agent-based simulation of nity. In Z. J. Acs & D. B. Audretsch (Eds.), Handbook
search processes in the entrepreneurial problem of entrepreneurship research: 141–160. Boston, MA:
space. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 12: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
237–260. Sayer, A. 2000. Realism and social science. London, U.K.:
McBride, R. 2021. Deontic binding: imposed, voluntary, Sage.
and autogenic. Social Epistemology. doi: 10.1080/ Schumpeter, J. A. 1942. Capitalism, socialism, and
02691728.2021.1996657 democracy. New York, NY: Harper and Brothers.
McMullen, J. S., & Shepherd, D. A. 2006. Entrepreneurial Scott, R. W. 2014. Institutions and organizations. London,
action and the role of uncertainty in the theory of the U.K.: Sage Publications.
entrepreneur. Academy of Management Review, 31:
132–152. Searle, J. R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philoso-
phy of language. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Uni-
Meyer, J. W., & Rowan, B. 1977. Institutionalized organiza- versity Press.
tions: Formal structure as myth and ceremony. Ameri-
can Journal of Sociology, 83: 340–363. Searle, J. R. 1995. Construction of social reality. New
York, NY: Free Press.
Mitchell, R. K., Busenitz, L., Lant, T., McDougall, P. P.,
Morse, E. A., & Smith, J. B. 2004. The distinctive and Searle, J. R. 2010. Making the social world: The structure
inclusive domain of entrepreneurial cognition of human civilization. New York, NY: Oxford Univer-
research. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 28: sity Press.
505–518. Shane, S. 2000. Prior knowledge and the discovery of
Montuschi, E. 2007. Real, invented or applied? Some entrepreneurial opportunities. Organization Science,
reflections on scientific objectivity and social ontol- 11: 448–469.
ogy. Contributions to Social Ontology, 15: 177–191. Shane, S. 2003. A general theory of entrepreneurship:
Mueller, A. 2016, December 20. Ten fundamental laws of The individual-opportunity nexus. Northampton,
economics. Mises Institute. Retrieved from https:// MA: Edward Elgar Publishing.
mises.org/wire/ten-fundamental-laws-economics. Shane, S. 2012. Reflections on the 2010 AMR decade
Nickerson, J. A., & Zenger, T. R. 2004. A knowledge-based award: Delivering on the promise of entrepreneurship
theory of the firm—The problem-solving perspective. as a field of research. Academy of Management
Organization Science, 15: 617–632. Review, 37: 10–20.

Padgett, J. F., & Powell, W. W. 2012. The emergence of Shane, S., & Eckhardt, J. 2003. The individual-opportunity
organizations and markets. Princeton, NJ: Princeton nexus. In Z. J. Acs & D. B. Audretsch (Eds.), Hand-
University Press. book of entrepreneurship research: 161–191. Bos-
ton, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Ramoglou, S., & Tsang, E. W. K. 2016. A realist per-
spective of entrepreneurship: Opportunities as pro- Shane, S., & Venkataraman, S. 2000. The promise of entre-
pensities. Academy of Management Review, 41: preneurship as a field of research. Academy of Man-
410–434. agement Review, 25: 217–226.
Ramoglou, S., & Tsang, E. W. K. 2017. In defense of com- Shelef, O., Wuebker, R, & Barney, J. B. 2020. Heisenberg
mon sense in entrepreneurship theory: Beyond philo- effects in experiments on business ideas. 2020. Avail-
sophical extremities and linguistic abuses. Academy able at SSRN: http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3581255.
of Management Review, 42: 736–744. Stuart, T. E., & Sorenson, O. 2007. Strategic networks and
Ramoglou, S., & Tsang, E. W. K. 2018. Opportunities lie in entrepreneurial ventures. Strategic Entrepreneur-
the demand side: Transcending the discovery- ship Journal, 1: 211–227.
creation debate. Academy of Management Review, Taylor, O. H. 1929. Economics and the idea of natural
43: 815–818. laws. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 44: 1–39.
Reed, M. 2005. Reflections on the “realist turn” in organi- Thaler, R. H. 2015. Misbehaving: The making of behav-
zation and management studies. Journal of Manage- ioral economics. New York, NY: W.W. Norton &
ment Studies, 42: 1621–1644. Company.
92 Academy of Management Review January

Thiel, P. A., & Masters, B. 2014. Zero to one: Notes on Wood, M. S., & McKinley, W. 2017. After the venture: The
startups, or how to build the future. New York, NY: reproduction and destruction of entrepreneurial
Broadway Business. opportunity. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal,
Tuomela, R. 2002. The philosophy of social practices: A 11: 18–35.
collective acceptance view. Cambridge, U.K.: Cam- Wood, M. S., & McKinley, W. 2018. The entrepreneurial
bridge University Press. opportunity construct: Dislodge or leverage? Acad-
Tuomela, R. 2007. The philosophy of sociality. Oxford, emy of Management Perspectives, 34: 352–365.
U.K.: Oxford University Press. Zott, C., Amit, R., & Massa, L. 2011. The business model:
Tuomela, R. 2013. Social ontology: Collective intention- Recent developments and future research. Journal of
ality and group agents. New York, NY: Oxford Uni- Management, 37: 1019–1042.
versity Press.
Van den Steen, E. 2010. Interpersonal authority in a theory
of the firm. American Economic Review, 100:
466–490. Russ McBride (russ.mcbride@ucmerced.edu) is an Assis-
Venkataraman, S., Sarasvathy, S. D., Dew, N., & Forster, tant Professor at the University of California, Merced, in
W. R. 2012. Reflections on the 2010 AMR decade the Department of the Management of Complex Systems
award: Whither the promise? Moving forward with and a Visiting Professor the Entrepreneurship & Strategy
entrepreneurship as a science of the artificial. Acad- Department at the University of Utah. He received his
emy of Management Review, 37: 21–33. PhD from UC Berkeley in philosophy under John Searle
and George Lakoff.
Weick, K. E. 1979. The social psychology of organizing.
New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Robert Wuebker (Robert.Wuebker@eccles.utah.edu) is an
Wilson, F. 2011, March 16. Airbnb. Retrieved from Assistant Professor in the Department of Entrepreneur-
https://avc.com/2011/03/airbnb/. ship and Strategy, David Eccles School of Business, Uni-
Wood, M. S., & McKinley, W. 2010. The production of entre- versity of Utah.
preneurial opportunity: A constructivist perspective.
Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 4: 66–84.

You might also like