You are on page 1of 5

https://doi.org/10.

1093/brain/awac194 BRAIN 2022: 145; 2231–2235 | 2231

Homeostatic feelings and the biology

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/brain/article/145/7/2231/6594735 by Universidade Federal da Para�ba user on 26 December 2022


of consciousness

In a new theory of consciousness, Antonio and Hanna Damasio argue that interoception and the generation
of homeostatic feelings are crucial to understanding how conscious states emerge.

Consciousness occurs when mind contents, such as perceptions and instead, on mechanisms underlying other complex processes,
thoughts, are ‘spontaneously identified as belonging to a specific or- such as attention and integration of information.3–5 That is why
ganism/owner’. The identification is provided by a continuous flow we begin by attempting to make clear what we regard as the es-
of ‘homeostatic feelings’, which translate the process of life regulation sence of consciousness.
and include salient fluctuations, e.g. hunger, pain, wellbeing, and
states closer to equilibrium, e.g. plain feelings of life/existence. Consciousness
We propose that homeostatic feelings were the inaugural phe-
nomena of consciousness in biological evolution and were selected Consciousness occurs when the contents of mind—what we per-
because the spontaneous information they provided regarding the ceive and recollect and ponder—are ‘spontaneously identified as
current state of life regulation conferred extraordinary advantages belonging to a specific owner’: our own organism, located in its
to the respective organisms. The ‘knowledge’ carried by conscious body. This definition applies to any ‘scale’ of mind—large and over-
homeostatic feelings enabled overt guidance of life regulation. flowing with contents, as when we contemplate a complex prob-
We also outline a mechanism for generating homeostatic feelings lem, or small, with only a few contents, as when we wake up
based on a two-way interaction between (i) the nervous system, from deep sleep. Consciousness makes its appearance when a
specifically neural elements of early interoceptive systems; and (ii) mind process—of large scale or small—becomes enriched by
non-neural components of the organism, the body’s interior, name- ‘knowledge’ that links it to a specific organism. Consciousness
ly, viscera and circulating chemical molecules. Feelings emerge from should not be confused with the mere integration of images, or
this interaction, as hybrid and continuous phenomena, related with the scale of that integration, or with the attention accorded
simultaneously to neural/representational phenomena, and to non- to some images in detriment of others. ‘We become conscious
neural/bodily processes. They identify the organism in which they when we know, without any question being asked, that the con-
inhere by continuously generating the ‘feelingness’ of traditional tents of our minds belong to our respective bodies.’
philosophical definitions of consciousness.
Sensing and minding
The problem of consciousness The phenomenon of consciousness needs to be distinguished from
the simpler ability to ‘sense’ or ‘detect’ objects and conditions in the
Neuroscience has been remarkably successful at elucidating the
environment.6 Numerous living species, from bacteria to plants,
physiological mechanisms behind some of the most complex func-
are capable of sensing/detecting and even responding to what is
tions of living organisms, namely memory, emotions, language,
sensed. It is likely that sensing, whose physiology hinges on cell
attention, and intelligence. When it comes to consciousness, how- membranes, provides a deep biological foundation for more com-
ever, the situation could not be more different. Although a variety plex processes of ‘minding’ and ‘consciousness proper’ that subse-
of solutions have been proposed, none has emerged as satisfactory. quently appeared in evolution in more complex organisms. But
Strangely, the failure has been accompanied by the notion that the sensing does not require the sensing organism to possess a nervous
problem cannot be solved, at least within the realm of biology,1 and system, nor does the sensing organism make internal representa-
that the solutions, if they exist, might actually be found in the do- tions of what is sensed or detected via generating ‘mapped pat-
main of physics.2 The multiplicity of conceptions associated with terns’ or ‘images’. Sensing dispenses with representations.
the term consciousness looms large among the difficulties faced By contrast, we see consciousness as involving and depending
by these studies. It is often not clear which specific conception is on representations of the kind that constitute minds. The most ob-
targeted by the proposed solutions. In search of mechanisms re- vious and common kind of representation takes the form of a
sponsible for subjectivity, the prominent solutions often focus, ‘mapped pattern’ or ‘image’ of objects, events and qualities (Fig. 1).

Received May 09, 2022. Accepted May 12, 2022. Advance access publication May 30, 2022
© The Author(s) 2022. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Guarantors of Brain. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail:
journals.permissions@oup.com
2232 | BRAIN 2022: 145; 2231–2235 Essay

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/brain/article/145/7/2231/6594735 by Universidade Federal da Para�ba user on 26 December 2022


Figure 1 Photographer Martin Liebscher plays the piano and watches himself play, perhaps the ultimate stage of consciousness! (C-print diasec,
Collection of A. and H. Damasio).

Minds are made of flowing streams of sensory representations naturally provided by the continuous flow of homeostatic feelings
or images constructed with the help of a nervous system.6,7 In es- within that organism. Prominent examples of salient homeostatic
sence, the images are of two kinds. The usually dominant kind of feelings include hunger, thirst, pain, wellbeing, malaise, and desire,
image ‘represents the world surrounding each organism’, a world as well as subtler feelings of existence that follow unimpeded
which includes other living organisms, varied objects and physical regulatory states closer to homeostatic balance. Such feelings are
structures, and their interactions. Those images are based on ex- generated by the ongoing life regulation as it attempts to maintain
teroceptive sensory processes (e.g. vision, hearing, touch, smell operations in the homeostatic range. In brief, homeostatic feelings
and taste) and map an extraordinary repertoire of the universe ex- as dramatic as ‘pain’ or as subtle as a feeling of ‘existence’, are gen-
ternal to the organism: perceptions (actual or recalled from mem- erated continuously in the awake state and support the respective
ory), thoughts we hold relative to some item we perceive or continuity of consciousness, provided they operate above a requis-
retrieve from memory, the verbal and syntactical translation of ite threshold.7
imagetic contents, as well as the conclusions we reach when we How and why do feelings provide the critical knowledge that
reason about a specific issue by logically manipulating images. constitutes consciousness? The answer is transparent: the most
The other kind of images is usually less dominant and originates distinctive aspect of the feeling process comes from the fact that
in the organism’s interior via interoception. Those images re- ‘each homeostatic feeling is itself spontaneously and automatically
present aspects of viscera and visceral states—a racing heartbeat, conscious’. When you feel pain or hunger or wellbeing, you are ne-
the flow of air in the respiratory system, a gut colic, the contraction cessarily conscious of each of these particular states. Your mind is
or dilation of blood vessels in the thick of the skin—and include the being offered important and conscious information about how life
intensity and quality, pleasant or unpleasant, of what is perceived, is progressing inside your organism and about what the organism
e.g. the more or less intense burning pain caused by acid indiges- needs. On the basis of that qualitative and graded ‘knowledge’
tion, or the degree of wellbeing caused by extensive relaxation of you can respond accordingly, by making corrections that may
smooth and striated muscle fibres throughout the body. Such help life continue, e.g. pain signals the possibility of tissue damage
images manifest themselves as the class of feelings generated by while hunger signals the need for additional energy sources; well-
life regulation. Those feelings naturally reflect an organism’s man- being serves notice that the organism does not have a specific
agement of existence and are known as homeostatic, to distinguish need at the moment and can engage in exploration. Had feelings
them from the emotional feelings caused by the triggering of emo- not been spontaneously conscious they would not have been able
tions. As we point out, the physiological apparatus that supports to assist living creatures with curating the life process.
the making of feelings is radically different from that of exterocep- We venture to propose that homeostatic feelings were the in-
tion. (For the sake of brevity, we leave out another perceptual augural phenomena of consciousness and that they were selected
channel, proprioception, which is primarily concerned with repre- and prevailed in biological evolution because the spontaneous
senting musculoskeletal structures and the movements they knowledge they provided concerning the current state of life con-
execute but also contributes to homeostatic feelings.) ferred an extraordinary advantage to the organisms that were so
endowed. The information/knowledge carried by conscious
homeostatic feelings enabled organisms to guide life regulation in
How is consciousness made: a new hypothesis
an overt manner and behave according to their principal interest:
We propose that the critical mechanism behind consciousness— survival. Homeostatic feelings made deliberate life regulation pos-
the identification of a particular mind with a particular organism—is sible by going beyond the already existing covert guidance, which
Essay BRAIN 2022: 145; 2231–2235 | 2233

had been occurring in organisms endowed with sensing/detecting describe aspects of visceral anatomy and document the qualities
but not minding and consciousness. and intensity of visceral events, for example, the duration and in-
In parallel with advancing life regulation, homeostatic feelings tensity of pain. By continuously generating representations of the
also helped generate a platform for ‘self-consciousness’. Self- state of the organism in which they occur, feelings refer to and
consciousness emerges when the contents of ongoing perceptions, identify the living organism in which they inhere, and thus make
the recall of previous perceptions, and the results of reasoning over it known in the mind process. Feelings continuously bring con-
such mental contents become connected to a specific organism and sciousness to the minds of ‘their’ organisms because they unmis-
are coherently organized as the mental counterpart of that organ- takably connect those minds to the body where feelings ‘happen’.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/brain/article/145/7/2231/6594735 by Universidade Federal da Para�ba user on 26 December 2022


ism. Current experiences and a history of past experiences, relative The physiological setting of interoception could not be more
to a specific organism, produce a conscious being in the full sense of distinct from that of exteroception and goes a long way toward
the term. explaining the nature of feelings (Fig. 2). Exteroception produces de-
Homeostatic feelings are not conscious because they borrow tailed maps of structures and events external to the organism, while
consciousness from some other process, but because they naturally interoception attempts to describe structures and events inside the or-
produce knowledge about the current life state. As a consequence, ganism. The conditions are ideal for the nervous system to produce
homeostatic feelings can actually ‘lend’ consciousness to other mapped representations of internal structures and events and for al-
processes, namely, exteroceptive sensory images. For example, lowing those representations to interact directly and bidirectionally
the retinas, visual pathways and visual cortices produce refined with the structures themselves. For example, neural and chemical sig-
maps of the outside world and offer us the respective images. But nals can travel from the gut to the brain and produce images, but the
in order for us to be conscious of those images, we propose that brain can respond to the point of origin of such signals and modify the
homeostatic feelings must be present as well, so that such feelings local conditions. In the interoceptive world, object and map create a
can identify the visual images that provoke them as belonging to hybrid—by which we mean that they not only link up with each other
our respective organism/body. We believe that only then can we be- but interact, literally commingle. There is no such equivalent in the
come conscious of those images. world of exteroception—we cannot have the map of a landscape inter-
Relative to its subjective owner, consciousness emerges from act with the landscape itself, which means that they cannot commin-
the homeostatic feelings conjured by many or by few imagetic con- gle in the same way that they do in the world of interoception. This
tents, on any theme. There is no need to invoke an additional mech- unique physiological setting suggests that the ‘feeling imagery’ pro-
anism to provide consciousness to large arrays of contents. duced by interoception ought to be quite distinct from exteroceptive
imagery. We doubt the physiology of consciousness can be properly
understood without considering this particular point.
How do living organisms generate homeostatic
The distinction becomes even more marked, and physiologically
feelings?
supported, because the neural elements charged with operating in-
At first glance, it might appear that by making homeostatic feelings teroceptive interactions are, in of themselves, quite different from
responsible for consciousness, we would be moving the problem of those that assist exteroception. On the neural side we find that in-
consciousness to a subsidiary domain while leaving the mystery teroceptive axons (i) are not insulated by myelin; (ii) make frequent
unsolved. That is not the case, however, because we also propose non-synaptic contacts; and that (iii) interoceptive neurons are not
a possible mechanism for the generation of homeostatic feelings, systematically protected by a blood–brain barrier. On the body side,
namely, a two-way interaction between (i) the nervous system; we see that the components of the body’s interior, namely viscera
and (ii) non-neural components of the organism.7,8 The typical and circulating chemical molecules, can gain direct access to many
homeostatic feelings emerge from this interaction as a novel kind interoceptive neural elements thanks to the absence of protective
of phenomenon, in the form of ‘hybrid’ representations that barriers such as myelin and the blood–brain barrier (Table 1).

Figure 2 Artist Fatima Mendonça’s dramatic envisioning of interoception as a dialogue of brain and body. (Gouache and ink on paper, Collection of
A. and H. Damasio).
2234 | BRAIN 2022: 145; 2231–2235 Essay

Table 1 Contrasting the anatomical and physiological characteristics of interoception with those that support exteroception,
movement and cognition

Interoception Exteroception, movement, cognition

Predominant nerve type of axons Poorly myelinated or unmyelinated (Aδ/C) Well myelinated (Aα/Aβ)
Mode of signal transmission Both nonsynaptic and synaptic Predominantly synaptic
Time scale Both slow (s/min/h) and fast Very fast (μs–ms)
Neural processes suported Interoception/visceroception, affect Fine perception, learning, reasoning, calculation,

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/brain/article/145/7/2231/6594735 by Universidade Federal da Para�ba user on 26 December 2022


(moods, emotions, feelings) language, movement
Blood–brain barrier Absent or with major gaps Continuous
Main neurotransmitters and Monoamine (dopamine, noradrenaline, serotonin), Glutamate, GABA
neuromodulators acetylcholine, neuropeptides

Impaired consciousness plants.7,11 At first glance, this is astonishing, since plants do not
have nervous systems or feelings or consciousness. However, be-
Disorders of consciousness, a common occurrence in clinical neur- cause general anaesthetics can preclude sensing/detecting pro-
ology, provide an opportunity to interpret the impairment of con- cesses, the animation of plants and the complex transactions
sciousness in our perspective. executed by their roots and leaves, also come to a halt. Plants become
Consciousness can be radically lost in cases of coma caused by just as immobile as anaesthetized patients in the operating room,
focal damage of the nervous system.7,9,10 The critical site for their animation temporally suspended.
lesion-induced coma is the posterior sector of the brainstem region,
where structures such as the nucleus tractus solitarius, the para-
brachial nucleus, and the peri-acqueductal grey collect signals Conclusion
from the body’s interior. The first integration of feeling-related sig-
nals corresponding to large sectors of the body is accomplished in In conclusion, consciousness can be found in many complex living
this region. The consequence of its damage is a direct comprom- organisms though not in all. It cannot be found in inanimate ob-
ise of integrated body representations and a severing of their jects, regardless of how complex they may be. Consciousness is
links to the exteroceptive mental contents; the latter are largely present in living organisms capable of constructing sensory repre-
assembled in the posterior cerebral cortices and integrated in sentations of components and states of their own bodies, but not in
cortical association areas. While the cerebral cortex is the base organisms limited to sensing/detecting. Because nervous systems
of operations for creating the predominant imagetic contents of are a requirement for the building of mapped imagetic representa-
minds, the subcortical regions are needed to support the feelings tions, it follows that only organisms with nervous systems are like-
that identify those imagetic contents as belonging to a specific ly to be conscious. Still, we caution against concluding that because
body. Because of the disparity between the way the CNS handles nervous systems are necessary for consciousness they would be
interoception and exteroception, small brainstem lesions can solely responsible for consciousness, as is commonly assumed.
have a devastating effect on consciousness, whereas even exten- We believe that consciousness ‘requires a partnership of nervous
sive lesions of the cerebral cortex may not. Once the integration systems with the bodies they serve’. Most declarations of failure
of interoceptive information, whose functional culmination in relative to the problem of consciousness, claim that ‘neuroscience’
the CNS occurs at brainstem level, is no longer possible, the world failed to solve the problem but there is no reason why neuroscience
of exteroception—whose wide base is in the temporal, parietal should have solved it alone, because consciousness does not de-
and occipital cortices—can no longer be grounded on the body pend on the nervous system alone.
to which it belongs.
On the matter of impaired consciousness, we must briefly
comment on general anaesthesia, which is by far the most fre- Antonio Damasio and Hanna Damasio
quent cause of lost consciousness and is both benign and con- Brain and Creativity Institute, Dornsife College of Letters, Arts and
trolled. The anaesthetics that are commonly used in surgery Sciences, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, USA
suspend consciousness rapidly, drastically, and temporarily.
Their physiological point of action is the plain ‘sensing and de- Correspondence to: Antonio Damasio
tecting’ process, located well below the functional level of mind- E-mail: damasio@usc.edu
ing at which feelings are generated. As noted above, all living
organisms including bacteria, share a basic ability to sense/de-
Antonio Damasio is University Professor and David Dornsife Professor of
tect and respond. This ability should not be mistaken for the
Neurology, Psychology and Philosophy at the University of Southern
more complex phenomena of feeling and consciousness, which California, where he directs the Brain and Creativity Institute. His most recent
require nervous systems and representations. It is probable, book is Feeling & Knowing: Making Minds Conscious, published by Pantheon.
nonetheless, that sensing/detecting/responding, which depend Hanna Damasio is University Professor and Dana Dornsife Professor of
on the operation of cell membranes, are the foundational level Neurology and Psychology at the University of Southern California, where she
of a functional hierarchical chain that eventually enables feeling directs the Dornsife Cognitive Neuroimaging Center.

and consciousness once nervous systems are present. General


anaesthetics seem to pre-empt the first link in the chain and thus
preclude interoception and exteroception simultaneously. Once
feelings are no longer possible consciousness is also suspended.
Competing interests
Curiously, anaesthetics also interrupt regular life activities in The authors report no competing interests.
Essay BRAIN 2022: 145; 2231–2235 | 2235

References 6. Damasio A. The strange order of things: life, feeling and the making of
cultures. Pantheon; 2018.
1. Chalmers D. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J 7. Damasio A. Feeling and knowing: making minds conscious. Knopf/
Conscious Stud. 1995;2:200–219. Pantheon; 2021.
2. Goff P. Galileo’s error: foundations for a new science of consciousness. 8. Carvalho G, Damasio A. Interoception and the origin of feelings:
Pantheon; 2019. a new synthesis. Bioessays. 2021;43:e2000261.
3. Dehaene S. Consciousness and the brain. Viking Press; 9. Parvizi J, Damasio AR. Consciousness and the brainstem.
2014. Cognition. 2001;79:135–160.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/brain/article/145/7/2231/6594735 by Universidade Federal da Para�ba user on 26 December 2022


4. Tononi G, Boly M, Massimini M, Koch C. Integrated information 10. Parvizi J, Damasio AR. Neuroanatomical correlates of brainstem
theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate. Nat Rev coma. Brain. 2003;126:1524–1536.
Neurosci. 2016;17:450–461. 11. Baluška F, Yokawa K, Mancuso S, Baverstock K. Understanding
5. Graziano MSA. Understanding consciousness. Brain. 2021;144: of anesthesia—why consciousness is essential for life and not
1281–1283. based on genes. Commun Integr Biol. 2016;9:e1238118.

You might also like