You are on page 1of 6

Hum Stud (2008) 31:223–228

DOI 10.1007/s10746-008-9085-x

BOOK REVIEW

Marramao’s Kairós: The Space of ‘‘Our’’ Time


in the Time of Cosmic Disorientation

Silvia Benso

Published online: 22 April 2008


 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Giacomo Marramao, Kairós: Towards an Ontology of ‘‘Due Time.’’


Trans. Philip Larrey and Silvia Cattaneo. The Davies
Group Publishers, Aurora, CO, 2007, 90 pp + xii
Time represents, ‘‘from time immemorial, one of the main themes of Western
metaphysics and philosophical speculation’’ (p. 39)—thus claims Italian philoso-
pher Giacomo Marramao in a book that, because of the interdisciplinary approach it
takes, the variety of interlocutors it addresses, the ground it covers, and the
meditations it develops, should actually be of great interest to a larger public than a
uniquely philosophical readership. In this sense, not only philosophers but also
anthropologists, social scientist, cultural critics, literary theorists, scholars of
rhetoric, theologians, and even physicists and evolutionary biologists among others
are sure to find reasons for excitement in the translation of this work. More
fundamentally, though, the intrigue of time, its nature and meaning are questions
that, at least once in their life (normally at times of birth or death) puzzle the mind
of all human beings. In this sense, Marramao’s book can be of interest to everyone.
Yet, despite the universal encounter with time, there seems to be a fundamental
discrepancy, or at least an ambiguity, between the daily experience of time and its
representations. ‘‘What is ... time? If nobody asks me, I know; if I must explain it to
those who question me, I do not know.’’ Thus writes Augustine in the Confessions
(Bk. IX, chapter 14), identifying with incredible clarity the paradox of time to which
Marramao’s short but important book is devoted. What constitutes the ‘‘temporal
paradox’’ (p. 39) that Augustine first articulates so poignantly? According to
Marramao’s formulation, the paradox is given by ‘‘the intertwinement of natural
and enigmatic, obvious and inexplicable’’ so that, in the end, time can be properly
described as ‘‘a familiar stranger’’ (p. 39). It is such a familiar stranger that Kairós

S. Benso (&)
Department of Philosophy, Siena College, 515 Loudon Road, Siena Hall 423, Loudonville,
NY 12211-1462, USA
e-mail: benso@siena.edu

123
224 S. Benso

confronts head on and in constant conversation with both the twentieth-century


philosophy of the ‘‘temporal flow’’ (especially Henri Bergson, Edmund Husserl, and
Martin Heidegger) and contemporary science (especially physics).
Marramao’s work is regrettably still largely unknown to the Anglo-American
readership. Formed in the socio-critical philosophical tradition of the University of
Florence, always attentive to historico-cultural phenomena, Marramao broadened his
education by studying social sciences at Frankfurt University, in Germany. Having
lectured in numerous major universities around the world, he is currently Professor of
both Theoretical Philosophy and Political Philosophy at the University of Rome-III.
An important work of his, West Passage: Philosophy and Globalization, one of the
first books to consider globalization from a truly philosophical rather than political/
economic/sociological perspective, is due to appear in an English translation with
Verso Publishing. An essay on related themes, ‘‘The World and the West Today: The
Problem of a Global Public Sphere,’’ is contained in Contemporary Italian
Philosophy: Crossing the Boundaries of Ethics, Politics, and Religion, published
by SUNY Press. Hopefully, these translations are only initial steps in the endeavor of
making known to the English-speaking readership works by a thinker who has
written more than 12 books in addition to many journal contributions.
Marramao’s reflection is not new to the question of time. Kairós constitutes in
fact the third volume in an ideal ‘‘triptych’’ (p. xi) that includes also Potere e
secolarizzazione. Le categorie del tempo (Power and Secularization: The Catego-
ries of Time), which was originally published in Italian in 1983 and then reprinted in
2005, and Minima Temporalia. Tempo, spazio, esperienza (Minima Temporalia:
Time, Space, Experience), published in Italy in 1990 and reprinted in 2005.
Curiously enough, in the English title of the volume under review, which in Italian
reads Kairós. Apologia del tempo debito (Kairós: A Defense of Due Time), the term
apologia has been changed to the expression Toward an Ontology (of due time). No
explanation for this alteration is given either in the translators’ Foreword or in
Marramao’s Preface (which, however, dates back to 1992 and was not updated for
the 2005 third Italian reprint).
The term apologia is admittedly difficult to render in English in its Socratic
sense. Besides indicating a difficulty of translation, however, the insertion of the
expression ‘‘toward an ontology’’ also marks the philosophical agenda of
Marramao’s book, which is clearly stronger than the simple provision of an
argument in defense of ‘‘due time.’’ What Marramao wants to present is in fact a
precise philosophically proactive proposal, albeit non-foundational (p. 30), centered
on a notion of kairós, the characteristics and nature of which are still under
investigation and elaboration. His ambition is to replace the philosophically
prevailing (at least in continental philosophy) ‘‘metaphors of the ‘stream’ and the
‘flow’ [of time] with the notions of architecture of time and topology of time’’ (p.
30). In other words, Marramao wants to integrate the insufficient concept of time
modeled on intuitive perception with the measurable, spatialized concept that
emerges in modern science and leads to ‘‘a disintegration of the idea of a universal
flow of time’’ (p. 32).
The goal of the proposed integration would be the reinstitution of the paradox of
which Augustine speaks and which Western philosophy has constantly sought to

123
Marramao’s Kairós 225

neutralize. One way of formulating the question that drives Marramao’s project is to
ask: ‘‘How does one place the dimension of our life, within such an ‘estranging’
picture [as the scientific one], so shocking for the familiar certainties of common
sense?’’ (p. 32). In a clear echoing of Heidegger’s project of a fundamental ontology
based on time and of his concept of ‘‘ontological difference,’’ and yet in an equally
clear and declared opposition to Heidegger’s privileging of authentic over
inauthentic time, Marramao’s book aims at ‘‘identifying the dimension, that is,
the space of ‘our’ time, starting from the cosmic disorientation that the new
scientific image of the universe has transmitted to our experience’’ (p. x). In other
words, it intends to ‘‘identify the constitutive residue of ‘our’ time—starting from
the contemporary and ‘disorienting’ spatial-temporal dimension and far from any
pretense of ‘authenticity’’’ (p. xi). Such a residue will emerge precisely as kairós—
the time in-between, the interval in which something special happens. Beyond
traditionally rhetorical and theological understandings of it, the concept of kairós
Marramao intends to propose is prepared by Aristotle’s ‘‘still unsurpassed’’ (p. 51)
consideration of time in terms of the ‘‘now’’ (pp. 51–54). According to Marramao’s
reading, Aristotle’s ‘‘now’’ is in fact ‘‘pulled away from the abstract, purely
quantitative dimension of mathematics, and is included within the continuum of
time’’ (p. 54). In this manner, a conception of time as paradoxical, that is, as ‘‘both
objective and subjective, physical and psychical, emotional and mental’’ (p. 54)
opens up.
The extensive discussion of what constitutes only the central premise for the
elaboration of such a novel concept of kairós occupies the largest portion of the
book. According to Marramao’s reading, the allegedly most radical twentieth-
century philosophies of the temporal flow (namely, those of Bergson, Husserl, and
Heidegger) bifurcate time into ‘‘a ‘proper’ time—authentic but incommunicable,
which expresses the subjective and inner sense of duration—and an ‘improper’
time—inauthentic but measurable, that manifests itself through its objective and
spatialized representation’’ (p. ix). A divide is thus created between time as
continuous and unfolding and time as discrete and instantaneous. Whereas the
philosophies of the temporal flow intend to concern themselves with the former, the
latter understanding of time is rebutted and ascribed by them to the sciences. By
provoking such a split and territorialization in the understanding of time, such
philosophies in fact forget the twofold nature of time, Marramao claims.
The recognition of the twofoldness of time was instead still present in Plato,
Marramao argues with a suggestive interpretation that goes against many of the
essentialist readings of the great Greek philosopher. According to Plato in fact, or so
Marramao maintains, the ‘‘two sides’’ of the temporal coin, that is, the existential
and the measurable or scientific, ‘‘form an invisible network of reciprocal
implications and references’’ (p. 1). This much is signaled in Plato’s characteriza-
tion of time in the Timaeus (37d), which according to Marramao constitutes ‘‘the
first complete definition of ‘‘time’’ in Western philosophy’’ (p. 7). According to it,
‘‘chronos is the moving image of aión.’’ This expression, usually translated as ‘‘time
is the moving image of eternity,’’ is convincingly reinterpreted by Marramao as
meaning that ‘‘chronos is as eternal as aión. Both are either ‘‘always’’ together or
fall together’’ (p. 12). That is, the scientific and existential aspects of time are

123
226 S. Benso

complementary and not antithetical; in this sense, the rebuttal of the chronological,
that is, scientific understanding of time by the philosophies of the temporal flow
amounts to a reductionist move.
Furthermore, by this move of separation of the two aspects and exclusion of one
of them, twentieth-century philosophy ‘‘has relinquished its original function’’ (p. x)
of being able to link different dimensions of existence. This ability was asserted by
Plato through his invocation of the erotic character of philosophy (pp. 34–8). In the
Symposium, Eros, to whom philosophy is assimilated, is in fact portrayed as an
intermediate being capable of acting as a messenger between immortals and
mortals, between gods and human beings, and ultimately between eternity and time.
That is, Eros is the dimension of existence in which opposites come into meaningful
communication and connection without thereby losing their specific identity and
individual characteristics. The coexistence of opposite, even contradictory features
is precisely what characterizes paradoxes. By privileging the unilateral dimension of
time as flow, twentieth-century philosophy has lost its eroticism insofar as it is no
longer capable of sustaining paradoxes, especially the paradox that time champions.
Stated otherwise, philosophy has lost its timeliness, in the sense of having lost the
challenge of portraying time as the dimension of paradox that time in fact is.
Conversely, as Marramao’s discussion of several scientific theories illustrate,
science has taken the paradox of time ‘‘as both the premise and condition of its
work’’ (p. x), as it becomes clear especially in the case of Einstein’s relativity theory
and the indeterminacy of quantum-mechanics. Despite what the philosophies of the
temporal flow assert, science has thus revealed itself more faithful than philosophy
to the aporetic character of the inquiry that, according to Plato’s myth of Eros,
should characterize the philosophical enterprise. In other words, science reveals
itself more philosophical in its inspiration than philosophy—this seems to be
Marramao’s indication.
Philosophy then needs to rethink experience, including the experience of time,
out of the aporetic, that is, disorienting perspective still known to science.
According to Marramao, this task implies a ‘‘re-think[ing of] our existence in the
universe in light of a radical idea of the limit’’ (p. 66) that also makes possible
the formulation of ‘‘an ‘off-axis’ approach to the question of time’’ (p. 67). The
articulation of the limit that Marramao invokes in turn requires two elements: first, a
rehabilitation of space (pp. 67–9) understood as the ‘‘original symbolic space’’ of
psychoanalysis (p. 67), as ‘‘an oneiric virtual element that circumscribes and
includes in itself the two dimensions of wake and sleep, of the diurnal and nocturnal
realms’’ (p. 68); and second, ‘‘a new understanding of the evolutionary residue of
our universe, within which living forms and our existence in the world find their
‘due’ time’’ (p. 69). In other words, psychoanalytic and evolution theories must
enter the philosophical description of the space and time of our existence, and
exercise a more powerful presence in the meditation on the notion of time.
It is at this point that the concept of ‘‘due time,’’ kairós, after which the book is
titled, unexpectedly appears in the book ‘‘with a coup de the´âtre,’’ as Marramao
promptly acknowledges (p. x). Unfortunately, the reasons for the appearance of such
a central concept are not made more understandable, justifiable, or justified simply
by virtue of the prompt and explicit recognition of the concept’s sudden appearance.

123
Marramao’s Kairós 227

No further help but rather a vague sense of disappointment comes from the
additional fact that only a few pages (pp. 69–74) are devoted to the discussion of a
concept that is intended to be, or indeed could be, a major philosophical
contribution to the theories of time.
What is ‘‘due time,’’ then? What is kairós? As the reader is told in the Preface
(pp. ix–xii), kairós is ‘‘no longer the Chance or the Fortune of the Moderns, nor is it
the eschatological event of the Christians.’’ Rather, as Marramao explains, kairós
‘‘is the fundamental dimension of the appropriate time, of the crucial moment that is
nothing but that part of each ‘identity,’ within which the very phenomenon of the
mind, or Awareness, takes-place’’ (p. x). A supplemental explanation to the
meaning of this concept should come from the (mysterious) etymology of the Latin
‘‘tempus.’’ The Latin term indicates both chronological and meteorological time,
both time and weather, Zeit and Wetter, two phenomena that are generally
considered distant, and even heterogeneous. ‘‘Tempus’’ signifies thus ‘‘the interface
of different elements, from which the reality of evolution derives,’’ Marramao
concludes (p. 70). In this sense, tempus is correlative to what the Greeks called
kairós: due time, appropriate time. Far from the meaning of ‘‘momentary instant’’ or
‘‘opportunity’’ which, as Marramao remarks, was a typical proto-modern under-
standing of the term, ‘‘kairós comes to designate, like tempus, a very complex figure
of temporality, which recalls the ‘quality of conformity’ and the proper mixture of
different elements’’ (p. 71). Kairós is the propitious time at which identities are
formed, including such identities as the mind, consciousness, and all other
evolutionary or historico-cultural phenomena. Not only does the notion of kairós
keep together those paradoxical elements of the temporal coin that twentieth century
philosophy has radically separated; kairological time is also the time of complexity,
of climatic configurations of existence, of living forms, of the world that evolves
‘‘because it is originally ingratiated by the kairós’’ (p. 72). From this concept and its
implications, new paths ‘‘can blaze...from a strictly philosophical point of view,’’
Marramao argues (p. 70)—for example, a reinstating of ‘‘the sense of our
evolutionary residue and with it, of our very existence’’ (p. 71), a reassessing of the
relation between space and time (p.71), and a rethinking of the I (p. 72), death (p.
73), and the other (p. 73). These, however, are all topics that are too quickly
addressed in the conclusive pages, and to which Marramao will hopefully devote
some future work as that which is his kairós to do.
Kairós is admittedly ‘‘one long lecture’’ (p. xii) derived from a cycle of talks that
Marramao gave at the Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici in Naples in 1990. The
lecture format, in which ‘‘expository and analytical-conceptual parts alternate and
… complement each other’’ (p. xii), makes for an easy, even entertaining, although
scholarly engaging reading. Yet, a less colloquial format would have probably
provided a more sustained confrontation and a deeper discussion of the texts and
authors considered (and they are certainly many and varied). Altogether, the main
theses of the book (which are indeed interesting and complex) as well as the
arguments supporting them would have gained in clarity, depth, and, perhaps,
overall persuasiveness. There is no doubt, however, about the vastness of readings,
knowledge, and expertise displayed by Marramao, who enters in equally comfort-
able conversations with Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, Husserl, and Heidegger as well

123
228 S. Benso

as with Isaac Newton, Albert Einstein, and Roger Penrose. And there is no doubt
that, in the current philosophical picture, Marramao’s overall project, although in
need of further elaboration given what he presents the reader in this book,
constitutes an original, rigorous, and imaginative attempt to think through essential
philosophical categories.
A few words must unfortunately be said about the translation and the editing of
the book, a matter that only marginally affects the quality of the content and yet
makes for a less than excellent product. Although this reviewer is not a native
speaker, she was able to detect some evident inaccuracies such as the recurrent use
of the adjective ‘‘disorientating’’ for ‘‘disorienting,’’ or some turns of phrases that
echo the Italian too closely (such as the term ‘‘sapiential,’’ which in English does not
exist, for the Italian sapienziale, p. 36). It is also somewhat annoying that, besides
the translators’ misspelling, no editor detected that the famous character from
Plato’s Symposium repeatedly referred to in chapter 6 is not Diotimus but Diotima (a
woman, not a man as the spelling suggests); this is just one occurrence of a general
laxness in the editing, which seems to lack consistency and defies generally
accepted conventions (for example, foreign terms are italicized randomly, the
German character ß, as in Bewußt, is regularly ignored, and single quotes, which in
English are used only within a previous quotation, are used instead of double
quotes). Moreover, there is no uniformity in the referencing style in the notes with
respect to italicizing titles, providing names and places of publication, and English
translations of the cited works and corresponding page numbers. Thus, the editor’s
initial note, following Marramao’s Preface and claiming ‘‘as for Greek words, we
sometimes preferred to disregard the scientific transliteration criteria’’ (p. xii),
sounds almost as a justification for periodic inattentiveness. Despite these stylistic,
editorial problems, the book remains an exciting, fascinating essay that leaves the
reader with the desire and hope for a continuation—as if this book were just an
interlude. It is perhaps appropriate, then, that Marramao concludes by invoking for
philosophy the Platonic ‘‘role of a powerful hermeneutic [sic], placed within the
tension of the metaxy´’’ (p. 74), since ‘‘in a time of cosmic disorientation, philo-
sophe`in can mean nothing but to stubbornly repeat this interlude’’ (p. 74).

123

You might also like