You are on page 1of 16

Angelaki

Journal of the Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

TOWARDS A NEW PHILOSOPHICAL IMAGINARY

Pamela Sue Anderson, Sabina Lovibond & A.W. Moore

To cite this article: Pamela Sue Anderson, Sabina Lovibond & A.W. Moore (2020)
TOWARDS A NEW PHILOSOPHICAL IMAGINARY, Angelaki, 25:1-2, 8-22, DOI:
10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717766

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717766

Published online: 26 Feb 2020.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 455

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Citing articles: 3 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 25 numbers 1–2 feb–apr 2020

introduction
t is my contention that a new philosophical
I imaginary – which would transform the
myths we live by2 – is needed to reconceive
our affections, love and vulnerability. In this
paper, I would like to appropriate Judith
Butler’s relational ontology for the purpose of
transforming a patriarchal myth which projects
pamela sue anderson
onto “vulnerability” only negative affects,
notably fear and shame. The result of this pro- edited by sabina lovibond and
jection has been violence in the name of paterna-
listic control and/or excessive “protection” of a a.w. moore
class, named “the vulnerable,” who, as I will
show, are treated as another class, or separate
group; this control and so-called protection of
the vulnerable merely generates more fear
and/or greater inhibitions overall, undermining TOWARDS A NEW
social and political relations.
My proposal for transformation aims at liber-
PHILOSOPHICAL
ating love and vulnerability from the excessive IMAGINARY 1
fear and violence which has been conveyed
mythically by our (Western) philosophical ima-
ginary. This transformation would mean that, concept of love: reciprocity would facilitate
for instance, the affect of shame, which arises loving affection in mutual, self and other
after intimate violence, could become reparative relations. But this affecting needs to be learnt
(or, in other words, redemptive) and not only by allowing ourselves to attend to each other –
negative (shameful). Moreover, there is the as I will try to show – “tenderly,” respectfully,
capability for mutual affection in vulnerability. sincerely and so, lovingly.
Ultimately the aim of my current research is In all seriousness, we would need to attend to
to set out possibilities for a new philosophical politically induced “vulnerabilities” – what
imaginary, in which vulnerability is (re)con- Butler might call “precarity” – for instance,
ceived as a capability for an openness to homelessness. Insofar as concrete manifes-
mutual affection; but developing this new (or, tations of these vulnerabilities are generated
possibly renewed), more nuanced concept of affectively by politically motivated patriarchal
vulnerability will require reciprocity in our myth, they can be extremely difficult to recog-
affective, conative and cognitive relations. In nize, in order to bring about new action-
particular, developing reciprocal affections in guiding concepts (of love and vulnerability).
vulnerability would help to revise a weak Negative affections are embedded in the

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/20/01–20008-15 © 2020 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1717766

8
anderson

differential privileging of (e.g., white Western; response is supposedly made on behalf of the
or Middle-Eastern …) fathers above all other vulnerable. My points about paternalism and
social types; and mythical gender types have dif- patriarchal control are not new; but I maintain
ferentiated the vulnerable in this hierarchical them, in order to support my argument that
and divisive manner. Instead, it will be crucial paternalism decisively damages the life-enhan-
to see vulnerability as a universal, while its con- cing capability of the vulnerable. Generally
crete manifestations will be socially and histori- speaking, we can see how myth is implicit in
cally differentiated. In other words, I will follow our twenty-first-century lives, guided globally
Butler’s lead with a relational ontology, in which by the social media which now span political
vulnerability is a (universal) mode of relational- worlds; but this complex, global network often
ity and not “the human condition.” obscures the extent to which “we” are controlled
by (mythical) gender impositions. Feminist phi-
losophers are all too aware of how a philosophi-
(how) do religions interpret, or cal imaginary of violence is “the shameful face”
of (Western) philosophy.3
project, gender (on) vulnerability? In response I am arguing that we begin to re-
Religions can be agencies for care of “the vulner- vision the gender implicit in that pervasive ima-
able”; but if treating the latter as an inferior class, ginary, hierarchically structured by myth con-
or problematic/pitiful people, we do an injustice: cerning vulnerability; this re-visioning would
we reduce their humanity, giving them lesser aim to liberate the loving qualities, which
social identities; we see this in demeaning on freely emerge in response to a new narrative/
the grounds of “differences” in gender, race, myth. Inspired by Michèle Le Doeuff, I am con-
sexual orientation, ethnicity and so on. sidering how to reconfigure the vulnerability of
My focus might appear both abstract and a young girl, named “Dawn.”4 This new narra-
ambitious when I claim that our (current/domi- tive about Dawn develops images for transform-
nant) philosophical imaginary has configured, in ing the philosophical imaginary of gender/
its mythical images, narratives and symbols, a vulnerability and violence into a new philoso-
separate class of “the vulnerable.” Yet a phical imaginary of love, vulnerability and
certain degree of abstraction is necessary for affection.
us, in order to gain the larger picture of how The renewed mythical, conceptual persona of
pejorative meanings of “the vulnerable” are the young girl, Dawn, helps to imagine the light
often unwittingly attributed to “the feminine,” of a new day, “Daybreak” – as Nietzsche
when the latter is conceived as weak and wound- describes it – generating imagery of affection
able; this is especially the case in (general) which enlightens, rather than reactive fear
descriptions of women, children, the disabled, which darkens, our lives and loves. In a relation-
etc. In this rendering of vulnerability, the vul- ally autonomous process, each of us in relation
nerable/feminine is in need of protection, to Dawn, who reasons with her heart, can
even when this means (more) violent acts; and learn to cultivate our attentive, cognitive and
love here tends to become a patronizing form conative capability. Dawn’s pre-adolescent vul-
of – to be honest – unhelpful, and possibly nerability – especially her heart which is vulner-
oppressive, control. able, yet motivates her reason – can be
That this ideologically driven myth associates cultivated in mutual responses of reciprocal
vulnerability with “the wound,” affecting nega- attentiveness and tenderness, in herself as
tive forms of (on the one hand) dependency and much as in others. Instead of oppressive forms
(on the other hand) over-protection, and issuing of control, fear and violence, our reciprocally
in controlling forms of violence (e.g., getting the cultivated relations to Dawn will allow her
upper hand in the global war on terror), is heart to remain free: she is and we are free to
clearly apparent in a (major) paternalistic reason with one another, in order to grow up
response to vulnerability; and this paternalistic both loving freely and, at the same time, being

9
a new philosophical imaginary

tenderly loved. Thus Dawn symbolizes – for a she aims to bring together corporeal vulner-
new philosophical imaginary – love’s capability ability, political life, exposure to violence,
to see reality, to know the world and to strive and mourning loss of life, e.g., the death of
to love humanity. Both men and women, in a loved one. What connects these lived experi-
becoming enlightened (by Dawn) would have ences is, according to Butler, “a constitutive
to seek the reparative ground of vulnerability, sociality”; this means that our relationally or,
if we are to recover love’s capable vulnerability if you like, “socially” constituted bodies exist
from humanity’s self-inflicted incapability (to prior to an “I”; and this means that relational-
love and become open to mutual affection).5 ity is prior to a self. In the past I have rejected
Narrative imagery expresses Dawn’s enlighten- the very idea of a relational ontology – assum-
ing qualities. In particular, the imaginary portrays ing, instead, a fundamental ontology of a self
the movement of stories about appropriately was necessary on largely Kantian grounds.
attending to her “heart” which, in this mythology, However, my more recent reading and think-
would liberate love’s capability.6 The task will be ing about vulnerability, its affects and connec-
to recognize that vulnerability as wound-ability tions to love, have made Butler’s account of
conditions the possibility not only of hurting and relationality – and vulnerability as “a mode
healing, but of transforming fear and violence of relationality” – a serious challenge to my
(that has been perpetuated out of excessive fear previous thinking; so much so that I have
for oneself and for one’s beloved) into loving had to allow myself to be transformed by a
affects allowing for our graceful differences. new understanding of affects and affections
Roughly, the myths implicit in our philoso- in motivating love, and in reconceiving vulner-
phical (social) imaginary motivate us either to ability. In particular, Butler’s proposals have
retain or to reconceive the imagery, stories and motivated me to open up new insight on vul-
values associated with vulnerability; rethinking nerability as a mode of relationality, and to
those myths is a first step towards transforming argue against certain myths of vulnerability
our reciprocal affections – of either violence, by which we currently – largely unwittingly
and fear due to that violence, or love, and confi- – live. Or, at least I would like to develop a
dence in that love. In other words, we can learn cogent argument which would change our
new, reciprocal relations of love by attending to assumptions about vulnerability – and, by
what is most precious – and here I am reminded extension, change our assumptions about
of Saint-Exupéry’s story of “the Little Prince” love. In the longer term, as imagined in the
who not only learns how to “tame” the fox, first section of my paper, my aim is a new phi-
but recognizes the sense in which regularly losophical imaginary.
attending to his “rose” has made her unique in Butler’s main thesis, in “Violence, Mourning,
all the world.7 Thus, in responding to vulner- Politics,” is not exactly the heart of an “argu-
ability as an openness to mutual affection we ment.” Instead, what I take to be her main
create love and friendship, while still knowing thesis is an assertion that bodily vulnerability’s
that violence might disrupt this picture; and relation to loss (of love) – where loss is a form of
yet we are able to transform the affects which (or, due to) violence – necessitates a political
cut us off from love and from a life which (where the political is also personal) task of
counts (if lost, this life would be grieved); that mourning. Butler demonstrates our need for
is, this life would be liveable and grievable. mourning loss of life, showing that this need is
not a matter of choice. In mourning we accept
the loss and a process; but we also accept (in
vulnerability as a mode of the sense of an active passion, not a free
choice) that, if we do not undergo this process,
relationality we are missing something … (Perhaps she
In Judith Butler’s essay “Violence, Mourning, means the revelation that the other had a role
Politics” (chapter 2 of her Precarious Life), creating who “I am” in “we were” …)

10
anderson

In fact, Butler claims we “submit to” a trans- into question. Desire in sexual relations
formation in the process of mourning. However, already does this. For this reason, Butler
I would like to question two things which describes both gender and sex as modes of dis-
remain mysterious in the sense of (apparently) possession: and dispossession means that we
ineffable here: are beside ourselves in desire, grief and,
Butler also mentions here, rage. But her
(i) to what transformation do “we submit” in
central examples are of loss/death – due to
the process of mourning?
AIDS, due to terrorism, and so on.
(ii) What exactly is missing, if we do not
Butler later admits that talking about vulner-
mourn loss of another’s life?
ability has been especially problematic for
The first of these is also twofold: to what do women, and for all those who have been
we submit; and what is the significance in sub- treated like “a separate class”: here “the vulner-
mitting to a transformation? As Butler insists, able” is a label that discriminates. Butler boldly
we undergo this transformation in the process states that “Women have too long been associ-
of mourning, once we accept, in the sense of ated with vulnerability, and there is no clear
allow, the loss (of a loved one) to change us way to derive an ethics, much less a politics,
forever. In brief, she says that we are undone from that notion” (Notes toward a Performa-
by another. Notice that a crucial part of tive Theory of Assembly 123; underline and
Butler’s assertion (above) is provocative: we bold added).8 This might seem to challenge
are led to ask the second question: what does what I have also elsewhere claimed was an argu-
it mean that if we are not undone by the loss ment for “ethical” vulnerability. Yet perhaps
of another, then we are missing something? Butler means by “that notion” (from which
What would we miss? “there is no clear way to derive an ethics,
I think that her reply would be that we would much less a politics”) that “vulnerable,” pro-
miss the life that counts; and a life which counts jected as an attribute onto women, has been
is one that is grievable; and we grieve a life when given excessively negative meaning. “The vul-
loss leaves us beside ourselves: dispossessed. nerable,” in that context, is fixed to women,
Butler’s answer to what is missing seems to gays, lesbians, trans, the disadvantaged and so
be: a life that counts is a life that is valued, on. It is undeniable that this attribution has
and a life that is valued is a life we grieve denigrated and patronized those identities
because it was part of who “we” were; and this called “vulnerable,” as if a separate class of
can be no one. So, she says, loss unites “us” in second-class citizens or worse.
corporeal vulnerability; we see another matters Nevertheless, aiming to avoid this negative
for “the self who I was” prior to loss. And yet stereotype, Butler continues to advocate
Butler is hesitant here because she does not thinking of vulnerability as a mode of rela-
want to make vulnerability “the human con- tionality which is differentially visible –
dition.” Instead, vulnerability differentiates us according to historical, social and material
socially, historically and materially – in (economic) conditions. And I am very intri-
complex, perhaps mysterious ways! We don’t gued by something more in Butler: that
experience vulnerability as either simply one her ontology is relational, and that vulner-
individual thing, or as one universal (a priori) ability is not ontological but rather is socially
condition: it is somewhere between these two constitutive of our bodies, and so our corpor-
poles of the specific and the universal; vulner- eal vulnerability is socially and political sig-
ability seems to happen to us, since we are nificant for “us.” The question is how do
wound-able. we think and act in light of this vulner-
And yet Butler adds that, although recog- ability? In the opening to this paper I
nition of loss and of vulnerability follows suggested we consider a contemporary appro-
from our constitutive relationality (or social- priation of an old (classical) myth about
ity), it is not just grief which calls the “I” Dawn and daybreak.

11
a new philosophical imaginary

ontology a self must “de-create” (Weil’s concept), in


order to either find herself in or connect
I have been challenged to rethink my own onto- herself to loving relations.
logical assumptions for my contributions to the Yet in the past year or so I have been led to
Enhancing Life Project.9 I have tended to reconsider how we are socially constituted
assume a Kantian, or neo-Kantian, account of (bodies) in a relational ontology; this is an ontol-
a primordial (or transcendental) self, existing ogy by which “we” are both created and dispos-
prior to our knowledge and actively unifying sessed by our relations to others. Of course, this
our experiences, prior to any of our relations. raises a question about the very existence of an
Roughly speaking, a fundamental ontology of isolated or autonomous self. For Butler, the
a capable (active, even if phenomenologically question is how do we find, in the sense of recog-
vulnerable) self would have been my ontological nize, our self; and one of her answers (perhaps
starting point; this ontology of the self would her only answer) is that we find our self in
have been necessary first of all – for any capa- others; and we know this to be the case when
bility – and notably for being able to understand we are “dis-possessed” by the loss of another:
vulnerable life in its affective, conative and cog- to repeat, in her examples, this is in grief, rage
nitive relations. However, I have very recently or desire. Why is this so significant for me?
been challenged to consider whether in fact I Clearly it is because it offers us more positive
could have this fundamental ontology of a (uni- possibilities in being vulnerable, wounded,
fying) self, by thinking and reading – as men- lost … and in knowing that life counts when
tioned already – Butler on a relational we are loved, or have been loved.
ontology of socially constituted bodies! In turn, my recent study of Butler’s relational
Could I have been mistaken about the (auton- ontology has led me to try to reconceive vulner-
omous) self and its relationality? Is it necessary ability today as an openness – an open wound –
to presuppose “a self” prior to (our) socially which is neither necessarily negative nor wholly
constituted bodies? In other words, Butler positive. Instead, as a mode of relationality, vul-
has ultimately forced me – and others, appar- nerability provides us with the capability for
ently – to question any ontological assumption being affected by, and affecting, change. Not
of a self, on whose capable relations, relations only do I think that I need to change my onto-
of self to another have been built. Why begin logical assumption, in order to grasp an
this way with an a priori or transcendental self account of a love which is worth expressing,
as a condition of all of our experience? giving and receiving, but “we” need to be
Over ten years ago I argued that Iris Mur- changed so that fear and violence are not what
doch’s conception of “un-selfing” involved a we first of all associate with life’s vulnerabilities.
contradiction in terms: a self – in Murdoch’s Moreover, I think that both Butler and living a
conception – seemed to me to be both necessary life have helped me see that it is denying one’s
and unnecessary, to be both “done” and vulnerability that is counter-productive to
“undone” by the reality of love.10 Previously, living and loving.
I tried to indicate contradictions in her self-con- Basically, I am asking you to consider what it
cerned search both to un-find herself and to find would mean to leave behind any resistance to
a non-illusory vision of the reality of selves.11 I the possibility of ontological relations being
took the question to be, how could (do) we get prior to selfhood, or what you and I might con-
out of our self, in order to find it or create it? sider to be “the self.” According to Murdoch, it
At that time, I maintained that the very idea is only by “un-doing” the self that we find it; and
of un-selfing presupposes a self who is according to Butler, it is only in “un-doing”
capable of loving relationships: that is, I gender in the sense of unbinding what has
thought that a self has to exist before it can bound us to social stereotypes – that we un-do
“have” relationships. It seemed to me self-deception, and so gender and sexual oppres-
Murdoch, following Simone Weil, insisted that sion. Such un-doing seeks to liberate our vision

12
anderson

of social reality. In turn, this liberation frees the stock of images, myths and other symbolic
self to perceive “the real” as the genuine object relations which structure, largely unwittingly,
or the subject of love. how we think and act.
Yet Murdoch adds that the un-doing of self The contemporary British philosopher Mary
should not leave the self “denuded.”12 I guess Midgley defends the existence of myth as, in
that “denuded” suggests something of the self her words, “symbolic stories which play a
is taken away, but something also remains … crucial role in our imaginative and intellectual
Is the “something” which remains simply the life by expressing the patterns that underlie
capability of making sense of ourselves? If so, our thought.”15 She maintains that anyone
then what is taken away in denuding? who denies that myth underlies their thinking
Appropriate attempts to confront self-con- simply has not become aware of “the general
tradiction, or possible confusion, in trying background within which all detailed thought
both “to un-self” and “to self” in specific, con- develops.”16 Midgley even employs myth and
crete situations have highly significant impli- its symbolism to make sense of the significance
cations for philosophical critiques of ethics, of philosophy in her own personal life. She
religion and moral psychology, but also introduces her memoirs, The Owl of
serious implications for what I am saying Minerva,17 with two non-human figures from
about love and vulnerability.13 To approach ancient mythology: the female deity Minerva
this capability we seem to need to make sense (Athene is the equivalent in ancient Greek
of ourselves, notably of the myths which we myth), and her owl, representing wisdom. The
live by. So, for the significant implications con- figure of Minerva is also famously employed
cerning how we understand ourselves as loving, by G.W.F. Hegel in the nineteenth century to
but also vulnerable, I turned to further think- describe the moment in the history of philos-
ing on the level of myth. ophy when an era would seem to be at an end.
We can glimpse the role of this figure in
Hegel’s own words:
myths by which we live: the dark […] on the subject of issuing instructions on
and difficult symbolism of wisdom how the world ought to be: philosophy, at any
rate, always comes too late to perform this
Instead of focusing on everyday stories of love, function […] it is only when actuality has
family life and vulnerability, which normally reached maturity that the ideal appears oppo-
go on without any philosophical reflection, I site the real and reconstructs this real world,
have sought to make sense of love’s motivation which it has grasped in its substance, in the
in the philosophical imaginary. The stories shape of an intellectual realm. When philos-
which remain decisive for philosophy – as the ophy paints its grey in grey, a shape of life
wisdom of love rather than merely the love of has grown old, and it cannot be rejuvenated,
wisdom – contain significant symbolic and but only recognized, by the grey in grey of
philosophy; the owl of Minerva begins its
mythical elements, especially narratives which
flight only with the onset of dusk.18
in their telling bring together human and
divine characters. If we add gender to the mix Similarly to Hegel, I suggest that Midgley
of the crucial attributes of these characters, points to “the love of wisdom” being recognized
then we come close to the necessary ingredients at dusk, at a moment of difficult transition, of
for configuring and, hopefully, reconfiguring loss or death. Her choice of the imagery of
the relations which have been crucial to “the Minerva and dusk later in her own life, as well
myths we live by.”14 Basically, this means to as in the wake of the philosophical life which
undo the hierarchy and discrimination accord- she shared with her husband who is deceased,19
ing to gender, sexuality, race, religion, ethni- tells us something about her view of “the love of
city; but I will only take one example of a wisdom”: it emerges in difficult or darkening
myth from our philosophical imaginary – the times. Minerva’s owl symbolizes the capability

13
a new philosophical imaginary

of seeing – wisdom – in the dark at the end of a than that of the primary maternal object rep-
day or of an era. So the owl sees in the dark. Yet resents a gigantic elaboration in which a
I would like to stress that the darkening at dusk woman cathexes a psychic potential greater
is not permanent; nor is the imagery of dusk than what is demanded of the male sex.
alone adequate for a fair picture of Mary Midg- When this process is favourably carried out,
it is evidenced by the precocious awakening
ley’s philosophical wisdom.
of girls, their intellectual performances
Returning to my new mythical persona, often more brilliant during the school years,
Dawn, we know that each night is followed by and their continuing female maturity. Never-
a new dawn. The break of day, the rising of theless, it has its price in the constant ten-
the sun, the beginning of a new day, and dency to extol the problematic mourning
similar images constitute imagery for thinking for the lost object […] not so fully lost […]22
after – for instance – the long dark night of
late twentieth-century post-modernism. Speak- Melancholia, as represented by the young girl in
ing metaphorically, this is the night when the Kristeva’s account (above), which follows after
light of modernity’s reason is eclipsed by uncer- the loss of love, can generate, according to Kris-
tainty and obscurity. Moreover, the symbolism teva, great psychic potential for intellectual per-
of light remains most appropriate to a philoso- formance. But to use Kristeva’s other well-
phical imaginary which recognizes a lasting known imagery of the “black sun,” this dark-
debt to ethically significant aspects of seven- ness haunts the wisdom of a melancholic
teenth- and eighteenth-century Enlightenment woman; this is the woman who is unable to
philosophy in Europe at least. grieve. Recall that Butler insists that we
And yet we know that Midgley employs submit to a transformation in the process of
imagery from ancient Greek mythology and mourning … – again Butler does not see this
modern German philosophy to capture the as a choice, but resistance seems to be the
nature of wisdom in the context of the dark dif- obstacle: one resists when mourning is not
ficulties of fear, violence and death: “Going out allowed to happen.
in the dark brings danger of death. But if you Previously I have explored critical problems
have to go out, then it is surely a good thing with Kristeva’s Black Sun. Yet for one
to have with you a creature that can penetrate additional aside, the late feminist philosopher
the darkness.”20 In this, she is pragmatic: of religion Grace M. Jantzen might well have
when things get tough we have to turn to the argued that Midgley remains caught up in the
wisdom in philosophy; thus the wise philoso- masculinist symbolic of death which displaces
pher is a necessity. And what subject is more both beauty and natality insofar as she
difficult to grasp, or is darker in its depths, remains within the darkness of death. Instead,
especially in its loss, than excessive love! Jantzen advocates that we embrace natality
At this point I offer a possibly contentious rather than mortality as life-affirming.23 But
reading of Midgley’s discovery of wisdom in none of these other women approach the large
certain philosophical difficulties. This wisdom ontological question which has bothered me. Is
expressed symbolically as the danger brought there a choice to be made concerning selfhood
about by death could be explained by psycholin- and relationality?
guists as the mode of the philosopher who A less contentious reading than Kristeva’s or
remains in melancholia.21 To treat this as one Jantzen’s psycholinguistic readings would
possible explanation, consider Julia Kristeva’s recognize, in the texts of Western philosophy,
psycholinguistic description of the woman who the myths of patriarchy – which have shaped
has successfully shifted her attachments away our philosophical imaginary and configured
from the security of maternal love: Western relations between men, women and
the divine. Under patriarchy love’s capability
[…] shifting the symbolic at the same time as is configured in ways which variously empower
[shifting] to a sexual object of a sex other love’s characters; patriarchal myths have given

14
anderson

authority on matters of ethical wisdom to structure our love stories are about time and
fathers and sons over mothers and daughters, the variable relations of human subjects to eter-
as well as men generally over other women nity and divinity. In my writings on feminist
and young girls. Think of the ways in which philosophy of religion, I have been repeatedly
the myth of Oedipus determined twentieth- struck by how much philosophy has relied
century accounts of familial and other love unwittingly or wittingly upon myths to
relations. Think of the unforgettable myth of support its gender norms.30
Eve’s eating the forbidden fruit of the tree of Midgley presents a highly relevant account
knowledge of good and evil. In the patriarchal of imagery concerning wisdom. But I
telling of these myths, love is portrayed both contend that the imagery of Minerva’s owl is
to liberate and to constrain relationships, only part of the picture of wisdom. A
according to gender differentiation. Ultimately, network of symbolic relations certainly consti-
the patriarchal “resolution” of the gender con- tutes the structure of myths, portraying
straints on sexual relations has over time wisdom. This network gives significance to
eclipsed the ethical wisdom of many women.24 stories and to a whole range of interrelated
Le Doeuff demonstrates, with a creative dis- imagery. In addition, a myth is cultivated by
covery of a liberating myth, the (constant) composing narratives which make sense of
need to unearth the obstacle in relations the lived experiences of individuals; this com-
between women and everything or everyone position brings together the rational, attentive
else. The difficulty is the identification of the and conative31 capability of individual women
obstacle: “that barely perceptible reality which and men. I employ “capability” in line with
does not speak its name.”25 In this paper my the later writings of Ricoeur to describe
contention is that we should seek to create, or human subjects in terms of their potentiality,
recreate, myths which can liberate that eclipsed especially the power which enables us to
capability which has been hidden by oppressive relate and to love as moral beings.32 Ricoeur’s
or dark forms of love. This means liberating our own final portrait of the capable human being
gendered forms of love according to the specifi- is neo-Aristotelian and Kantian (but not inten-
cities of the lives of actual women and men who tionally post-Hegelian).33 His self-description
are each distinguished by age, race, class, ethni- is revealing, but it also fits nicely with the
city and sexual orientation. Agape (charity), picture developing here.
philia (friendship), eros (desire) and other affec-
tions each contain an element of that capa-
bility26 which is integral to yet often enslaved a myth for wise lovers: the joyful
by human love. and hopeful symbolism of
In his last writings on memory, forgiveness
and love, Paul Ricoeur describes how human
enlightenment
capability has been wounded by painful affec- It is Le Doeuff who has uncovered – for me at
tion.27 His mythical descriptions of the enslave- least – a significantly different symbolic figure
ment of the triad freedom–goodness–love and myth from Minerva and her owl, from
assume the loss of human capability.28 In Psyche and Cupid, and from Eve and Adam.
various ways across the course of his writings, In her 2006 Weidenfeld Lectures, Le Doeuff
Ricoeur contends that the symbolic and mythi- demonstrates the ethical significance of a
cal language of slavery expresses this loss as an highly distinctive myth for twenty-first-
enslaved freedom (or as “the captive free will” century men and women.34 Essentially the sig-
which is enslaved to evil). Nevertheless, we nificance of this myth is its message: in order
can and should recover freedom’s more primor- to gain reciprocal affections, we should take
dial (original) ground of goodness.29 care not to force a girl to grow up to be a
In one sense, our myths about love are time- goddess of maternal love with sacrificial and
less. But in another sense, the myths which tragic relations to men, to other women, to

15
a new philosophical imaginary

gods and goddesses. An original (classical) another woman writer: Maria Zambrano.36 Zam-
story told by Le Doeuff lends itself to a recrea- brano was educated in philosophy, wrote fiction
tion of a timely contemporary myth about a and non-fiction in Spanish, and contributed to a
young girl, Dawn, whose vulnerability needs conception of poetic reasoning in which the
to be enhanced, in order for her heart which symbolic has a philosophically significant role.
is reason to enlighten us. Here, affection Le Doeuff picks up crucial elements from
becomes mutual insofar as we allow Dawn’s what becomes “la philosophie imaginaire” of
vulnerability to provoke in us qualities of Zambrano to challenge traditional stereotypes
both tenderness and firmness, attentiveness about young girls, reason, mature women,
and wise generosity, joy and enjoyment, in motherhood and divinity; “Dawn” does have
those who love her. Here I will end with both classical and religious (or, at least spiritual)
encouragement: that we can and should recog- origins. In telling Dawn’s story, Le Doeuff
nize the critical role of affects and affections in appropriates Zambrano’s poetic reasoning
vulnerability and love; this is necessary, I about a girl whose heart is reason, in order to
submit, in order to rethink our relations to create an ethical figure of hope for women and
Dawn, that mythical persona who enlightens men in philosophy. The heart becomes a
each daybreak, with new possibilities for symbol for a fresh understanding of a human
freeing the so-called vulnerable – that separ- soul in loving reciprocal relations. If we extrap-
ated and denigrated group – from the con- olate a bit more, then this mythical language
straints of fear and violence, in order to about a young girl’s heart begins to personify
transform our socially constituted bodies into liberated love – not the bonded love of a
love and vulnerability. female deity, whether a goddess of wisdom or
Le Doeuff’s reference to “the heart” of of motherhood. (Here I think of Etty Hillesum
Dawn derives from her own reading of the who describes how, in her words: “Much has
Spanish philosopher Maria Zambrano’s sym- been changed in my relationship with my
bolic poetics. Zambrano portrays Dawn’s parents, many tight bonds have snapped,
heart as significantly different from either and as a result I have gained the strength to
the mind or the body, of either eternal male love the more genuinely.”)37 Le Doeuff
or eternal female essence. Instead, the heart asserts that Dawn should not be forced to
encompasses aspects of both the incorporeal become divine.
and the corporeal. But the heart is not My own contention is that Le Doeuff’s
exactly the soul either. Yet it is clearly signifi- retelling of Dawn’s story offers us a new
cant for the distinctive identity of the young Enlightenment narrative. Of course, other nar-
girl prior to her adolescence, at which time ratives could be created and/or similarly
her self-identity becomes challenged by her reconfigured to avoid the pernicious dangers
changing body, her sexuality, her female in apotheosis, but in the present context con-
beauty, her sexually specific pleasure – a joy sider this retelling of a (mythical) story
which will be more than sexual. We might about Dawn. Each dawn begins anew, offering
compare Dawn’s joy with Spinoza’s intellectual us hope for each woman and each man to be
love of God. In this light, the heart is a funda- attentive and tender to one another; to learn
mental and encompassing term for what needs to love this young girl involves practising ten-
to be protected in the young girl as she grows derness, not unthinking force. A revised ethics
up, generating the wisdom of love. Le Doeuff is implicit in a new enlightenment narrative,
leaves us to wonder whether the heart of a whereby a young girl holds out a promise
young boy is more easily protected from the for practical wisdom, while women and men
illusions and oppression of imposed social- create new ethical dispositions (e.g., tender-
sexual stereotypes.35 ness) in being drawn to the vulnerability of
Le Doeuff herself discovers the main Dawn. Le Doeuff insists that European
elements of this story from her reading of Enlightenment philosophy was unethical

16
anderson

when it came to women and the potential of a references to joy and hope in the light which
woman’s ethical wisdom. Yet Le Doeuff’s new continues to dawn across the horizon of the
myth, unlike Midgley’s memoir, does not take sea every morning:
its starting point from the symbolism of dusk.
The waves of hope rise and fall: “The grey
Instead, dawn is the starting point of this
cloth becomes barred with thick strokes
alternative myth, which comes after “the
moving, one after another, beneath the
dark”: whether this imagery refers to the era surface, following each other, pursuing
of medieval or of post-modern darkness each other, perpetually. As they neared
Dawn brings light to certain unfathomable dif- the shore each bar rose, heaped itself,
ficulties, especially to the sexual violence and broke and swept a thin veil of white
living death which have enslaved women. water across the sand. The wave paused,
Le Doeuff is not preoccupied with any post- and then drew out again, sighing.” These
modern imaginary or any assumed death of opening sentences from Virginia Woolf’s
Enlightenment philosophy, which can arguably The Waves might well contain the poetics
be read as melancholia. In sharp contrast to of our collective historical experience. Suc-
cessive waves of women have joyfully
either a medieval or a post-modern imaginary,
fought, convinced that once we had at
Le Doeuff’s story is about a new Dawn who/
last gained the right to, for example, a
which has the capacity to enlighten; to teach job, education, citizen’s rights, or a sexu-
us unwittingly how to protect a heart which ality freed from the chains of reproduction,
symbolizes un-enslaved reason. This Enlighten- something fundamental would have
ment narrative does not oppose reason to love, changed in the general female condition.
or mind to body. Instead, reason, like a pre-ado- A thin veil of white water across the
lescent heart, if it is cultivated, can enlighten sand: those gains have hardly even yet
love in others, too. Thus the mutually produced been gained and the radical transformation
wisdom of love comes with Dawn, at the break that we expected along with civil equality
of day, and not exclusively with Minerva at or birth control has not come. Besides,
like harbour pools governed by a complex
dusk.
system of locks and sluices, particular
Elsewhere I have pointed out that Le
social spaces open to us and then close
Doeuff draws productively on the imagery in off again.40
women’s writings to make sense of a move-
ment for women’s recognition.38 She focuses Le Doeuff confirms that each woman’s joyful
on the imagery of dark and light in the move- struggle to express her own wisdom is shaped
ment of waves as they break seemingly around the collective history of an ethical move-
between sea and sky. Perhaps unaware of the ment for reciprocal equality, or recognition.41
result, Le Doeuff nevertheless shifts an ima- This history includes the ebb and flow of the
ginary relationship from dusk and darkness imagery and political ideas of each woman.
to the dark and light oscillations reflected on Here feminism is implicit as a politics con-
the sea at dawn. For example, she appropriates stantly moved forward by both successes and
the imagery with which Virginia Woolf begins failures of women individually and collectively.
her twentieth-century novel The Waves: “The This movement creates shifts in what Le Doeuff
sun had not yet risen. The sea was indistin- has articulated as the philosophical imaginary:
guishable from the sky, except that the sea this is essentially the symbolic and narrative
was slightly creased as if a cloth had wrinkles patterns of thought which shape (often unwit-
in it. Gradually as the sky whitened a dark tingly) philosophical texts. For Le Doeuff,
line lay on the horizon dividing the sea from Woolf becomes a paradigmatic figure of and
the sky and […]”39 for a woman’s writing speaking profoundly to
In this way, Le Doeuff reveals her own enligh- her readers, even in this new century, about
tened preference for hope, even when the politi- how patriarchy has dis-inherited women.42
cal climate is dark or darkening. Consider her This lack of inheritance means that women

17
a new philosophical imaginary

have mainly been separated from their own capability; perhaps they have learned about
ideas which have been given away, or cast off, love from a reason freely expressed and a heart
without any rightful recognition of their owner- tenderly received.
ship by or origin in a specific female thinker. “Not a goddess, she!” is Le Doeuff’s crucial
The imagery of the waves is a case in point. cry. If Dawn grows up without having
To illustrate how the failure of inheritance imposed those humanly impossible, patriarchal
might be reversed, Le Doeuff picks up and gender roles which enshrine a goddess in
exploits the metaphorical and mystical language bonded love and stereotypical beauty – and
making up Woolf’s novel, in order to express yes, ethereal beauty can also be sexist – then
the rise and fall of hope in a woman’s collective her reason will enable non-oppressive love and
inheritance. This exploitation means that Le so goodness to shine upon humanity and its
Doeuff makes suggestions with this imagery relations. This myth implies that a woman’s
which go beyond the intended significance in oppression begins in adolescence, at which
The Waves. But she also disagrees with point the myths of patriarchy enslave the
Woolf’s writings on women when the latter relations of men and women. Yet liberation
fail to recognize ideas which have been gener- can be achieved when the young girl develops
ated by women from past centuries.43 So an adolescent heart which is treated tenderly;
“waves of feminism” present themselves on a but this must be prior to her (maternal) sacrifice
political scene as historical movements of indi- to the god(s).
vidual women: they are like the recurring lines There are plenty of good reasons to reflect
rising and falling on the sea waters each dawn. upon the wisdom of love rather than the love
Thus the imagery of waves gives expression to of wisdom. My argument is that such wisdom
the complex patterns and shifts in the relations derives from “liberated love” rather than
of each woman to each other and to all of those “bonded love” – a distinction which, however
others whom they love. Love relates them indi- contentious, I employ from the outset of this
vidually and collectively to the larger reality of paper. It is also my view that the practical
patriarchy. wisdom of contemporary women and men
The crucial point is that Le Doeuff would find finds itself at a moment when our critical reflec-
any exclusive stress upon the grey on grey, tions should be compelled to reject the bonded
whether taken from Woolf or Hegel, as love which is associated both literally with vio-
missing the significant light shed on the crest lence and symbolically with death. To support
of waves. The symbolism and myth of this this, it is imperative to reject the symbolism of
ethical wisdom emerge like the light shining a self-destructive bonding to an unenlightened
from the lives of each woman who is part of a other and begin to recognize the nature of liber-
vibrant, if hidden, collective historical experi- ated lovers. Looking closely at symbols and
ence. The task is to claim each woman’s myth is a highly abstract exercise; nevertheless,
wisdom as part of our philosophical inheritance; this is substantially supported by cutting-edge
that is, an inheritance of the ideas of past women work like that of Le Doeuff on “the philosophi-
whose writings were quickly cast off. My present cal imaginary”44 – the decisive significance of
argument takes support from Le Doeuff to which should become clear.
contend that love’s capability can be found in To end this critical reflection, consider two
both the imagery of kindly cultivating a young claims:
girl’s heart and the larger picture of our collec-
tive inheritance. So, the philosophical imaginary Liberated love is superior to bonded love:
Wise lovers are not only more joyous, but
would no longer picture a woman exclusively in
more effective and beneficent than unenligh-
the shadow of a man: not just Geoffrey Midgley
tened lovers.45
with Mary, or Hegel with the owl of Minerva,
but Mary Midgley with the wise men and By refusing to accompany her father in his
women who have learned to liberate love’s blindness, by saving herself and her child

18
anderson

instead of obeying her husband, by opening environment. In the telling and retelling of love
her eyes and seeing with whom she is stories, we try to imagine how the vulnerability
living, Psyche has walked out of the which remains latent in the mythical configur-
Oedipus plot.46 ations of these relations both
The first quotation (above) concerning liberated affects and is affected by love’s
love assumes that love can and should be freed capability. Remember that this
from a certain sort of bondage. This is a huge capability is the openness to
and contentious assumption. Can and, if so, mutual affection which I would
should love be liberated? It might be thought like to rename vulnerability.
that by its very nature love binds those who
love to others – so that love is always in some
sense bonded – and certainly love which notes
requires obedience to a higher authority is in Completion of this paper was made possible through
bondage to, say, a divine or absolute law. For the support of a grant from the John Templeton
the sake of my argument let us suppose that Foundation, via the Enhancing Life Project. The
love can be liberated; and see if I can persuade opinions expressed in it are those of the author
you. The question is, from whom or what pre- and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John
cisely – and to what degree – is love freed? Templeton Foundation. The paper will eventually
be part of a monograph on Love, Vulnerability and
At the very least love can be freed from total
Affection: New Concepts to Live By … or, Enhancing Vul-
passivity.
nerable Life: Love, Confidence and Affection …
The second quotation (above) suggests an
answer in the interpretation of mythical 1 Editors’ note: we have restricted editorial
imagery: the blindness of a familial relation, as changes to the correction of typographical errors
portrayed in this case by the plot of the and the amendment of clear infelicities of “draft”
style. In Anderson’s original text, some passages
Oedipus myth, renders these bonds of love
were highlighted in yellow, others were typed in
less effective by preventing the daughter from
red, and others were typed in bold. In none of
seeing reality; she only “knows” the man-made these cases was there any indication what the
structures of authority and obedience in love. rationale for the typographical device was. We
Roughly, we will see that the young girl, have registered her use of yellow highlighting by
Psyche (who is mentioned in the quotation means of underlining, her use of red type by
and is taken from the Cupid and Venus story), means of bold, and her own use of bold (which
has the capability to reject the plot in which it seems clear was just her way of emphasizing
the man literally or symbolically marries his material) by means of italics.
mother and the woman simply accepts the patri- 2 Here I am thinking of myths which have been
archal authority. The first quotation points out constructed by “the philosophical imaginary” (cf.
that wisdom liberates and creates “enlightened Michèle Le Doeuff, Recherches sur l’imaginaire philo-
lovers.” But from where does the wisdom of sophique (Paris: Payot, 1980); The Philosophical Ima-
love arise?47 ginary, trans. Colin Gordon (London: Athlone,
I have tried to argue that a new philosophical 1989; Berkeley: Stanford UP, 1990; republished
imaginary – which would no longer connect vul- London: Continuum, 2002); cf. Max Deutscher,
nerability exclusively to fear and violence – ed., Operative Philosophy and Imaginary Practice:
Michèle Le Doeuff (New York: Humanity, 2000)),
would motivate us to liberate love’s capability,
especially those about fathers and their daughters,
especially from the bondage of patriarchal
wives, mothers; when living by patriarchal myths,
myths (those of blind obedience to a higher we are motivated by hierarchical, asymmetrical
“authority”); and that liberated capability is affections, including violence, fear and vulnerability.
expressed in the retelling of the stories about
the gendered relations between human beings 3 Le Doeuff, The Philosophical Imaginary.
themselves, between human and divine, and 4 Michèle Le Doeuff, “Not a Goddess, She!,”
humans and their internal and external Lecture 4 of “The Spirit of Secularism: On Fables,

19
a new philosophical imaginary

Gender and Ethics,” Weidenfeld Professorial Lec- where society expected her to be: see Michèle
tures, University of Oxford, Trinity Term 2006. Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice: An Essay Concerning
See also Friedrich Nietzsche, Daybreak: Thoughts Women, Philosophy, Etc., trans. Trista Selous
on the Prejudices of Morality, trans. Maudemarie (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991) 206; 2nd ed. and rev.
Clark, Brian Leiter, and R.J. Hollingdale (Cam- trans. (New York: Columbia UP, 2007); this
bridge: Cambridge UP, 1997). could be explored further as the (un)selfing necess-
ary for doing philosophy, that is, for both finding
5 Paul Ricoeur, “Ethics and Human Capability: A
oneself and losing oneself in the wisdom of love.
Response” in Paul Ricoeur and Contemporary Moral
Thought, eds. John Wall, William Schweiker, and 12 Iris Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good (London:
David Hall (New York and London: Routledge, Routledge, 1970) 47. Concerning a woman who
2002) 284. “unfinds herself” through exile from her social
identity, see Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 206.
6 For another example of a new story of vulner-
ability and loving attention, which liberates – 13 At the same time, if we follow Le Doeuff’s argu-
“tames” (from the French verb apprivoiser) – ment, then this multiplicity of specific concrete
love, see Antoine de Saint-Exupéry, The Little situations of (un)selfing would be most evident in
Prince (Harmondsworth: Heinemann, 1945; rpt. the times and places in history when and where
by Puffin, 1962) 79–84. women’s “identity” in reality makes up “a collective
disarray”: Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 207.
7 Ibid. 83–84.
14 Mary Midgley, The Myths We Live By (London:
8 See Judith Butler, Notes toward a Performative
Routledge, 2004) xi, 1, 2, 5.
Theory of Assembly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
2015); Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and 15 Mary Midgley, The Ethical Primate: Humans,
Violence (London: Verso, 2004). Freedom and Morality (London: Routledge, 1994)
109: Midgley asserts that “Myths are not lies, nor
9 See the unnumbered note at the head of this
need they be taken as literally true,” and gives a
Notes section.
highly useful, philosophical definition of myth; this
10 The present attempt to expose the contradic- basic, relatively uncontentious treatment renders
tion of “selfing and un-selfing” should be distin- mythical symbolism a necessary addition to scienti-
guished from the concerns of Weil and of fic facts. For her initial use of the term, see Mary
Murdoch, who each have slightly different con- Midgley, Wickedness: A Philosophical Essay
ceptions and conclusions concerning love of self (London: Routledge, 1984) 10–12, 162. For the
from my own and each other. Yet both Murdoch more technical use of myth, see Midgley, The
and Weil have a common reaction to their Euro- Ethical Primate 109, 117–18; the latter is repeated
pean contemporary philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre, and elaborated ten years later in Midgley, The
whose conceptions of unbearable freedom and Myths We Live By xi, 1, 2, 5.
self-deception render genuine love impossible.
16 Midgley, The Ethical Primate 117; more generally
For discussion of Sartre’s influence on Murdoch,
109–20. To read more from this: the way in which
see Maria Antonaccio, Picturing the Human: The
myths work is often very obscure to us. But,
Moral Thought of Iris Murdoch (Oxford: Oxford
besides their value-implications – which are often
UP, 2000) 62–75; and again, see my discussion of
very subtle – they also function as summaries of
Newton-Smith’s reading of Sartre in “‘Moralizing’
certain selected sets of facts (117) … When we
Love in Philosophy of Religion” in Philosophy of Reli-
attend to the range of facts that any particular
gion for a New Century, eds. Jerald T. Wallulis and
myth sums up, we are always strongly led to
Jeremiah Hackett (Amsterdam: Kluwer, 2004)
draw the moral that belongs to that myth. But
235–37.
that range of facts is always highly selective. It is
11 Compare this search to Le Doeuff’s account of limited by the imaginative vision that lies behind
the “I” who seeks identity which is not that pro- that particular story. This vision can, of course,
posed by social representation. Le Doeuff illus- generate actual lies, which is what makes it plaus-
trates this with the choice of the ancient woman ible to think of the myth itself as a lie. Thus,
philosopher of mathematics, Hipparchia, seeking myths about the inferiority of women, or of par-
knowledge rather than remaining “at the loom” ticular ethnic groups, have supported themselves

20
anderson

by false factual beliefs about these people (ibid. (Chicago: Regnery, 1965); rev. trans. Kelbley with a
117–18). new Introduction by Walter J. Lowe (New York:
Fordham UP, 1986) 9–15, 144–45; The Symbolism
17 Mary Midgley, The Owl of Minerva: A Memoir
of Evil, trans. Emerson Buchanan (New York and
(London: Routledge, 2005) x–xii.
London: Harper, 1967) 152, 156–57.
18 G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of
30 Pamela Sue Anderson, A Feminist Philosophy of
Right, ed. Allen W. Wood; trans. H.B. Nisbet
Religion: The Rationality and Myths of Religious Belief
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1991) 23.
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), especially 4, 21–22,
19 If one wanted to make this argument, a premise 113–14, 138–43, 245–47; Pamela Sue Anderson,
would need to be defended; that is, Mary’s memoirs “Myth and Feminist Philosophy” in Thinking
testify to Geoff Midgley’s wisdom which lives in the Through Myths: Philosophical Perspectives, ed. Kevin
various forms of her love and her practices of phil- Schilbrack (New York and London: Routledge,
osophy. But it is unfair to push the argument this far. 2002) 101–22. Midgley’s understanding of symbo-
The reverse is more likely to be true: Mary is the lism and myth in the wisdom of our living, learning
source of inspiration for Geoff’s wisdom. and knowing bears similarities to Le Doeuff, The
Philosophical Imaginary 1–20; cf. Midgley, The
20 Midgley, The Owl of Minerva xi. Myths We Live By, especially 1–5, 88–93, 97–101.
21 Cecilia Sjoholm, Kristeva and the Political
31 The adjective “conative” recalls Baruch Spino-
(London: Routledge, 2006) 50, 54–58; cf. Julia Kris-
za’s conception of conatus as the human striving
teva, Black Sun: Depression and Melancholy, trans.
to persist in one’s own being.
Leon Roudiez (New York: Columbia UP, 1989)
27–30. 32 Ricoeur, “Ethics and Human Capability” 282–
83.
22 Kristeva, Black Sun 30.
33 Paul Ricoeur, The Course of Recognition, trans.
23 Grace M. Jantzen died on 2 May 2006. So this
David Pellauer (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
present claim extrapolates from the project on
2005) 91; and more generally chapter 2.
which she was working – a first volume of which
is published: Grace M. Jantzen, Foundations of Vio- 34 See note 4 above.
lence: Death and the Displacement of Beauty, vol. 1
(London: Routledge, 2004) 11–20. 35 For a crucial backdrop to Le Doeuff’s thinking
on “le coeur,” see Maria Zambrano, Les Clairières
24 For the examples and implications of this du bois, trans. from Spanish Marie Laffranque
eclipse, see Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 28. Cf. (Paris: L’Éclat, 1989) 65–80; see also note below.
Michèle Le Doeuff, The Sex of Knowing, trans.
Kathryn Hamer and Lorraine Code (New York 36 Maria Zambrano is born in 1904 in Andalusia,
and London: Routledge, 2003), especially Part 1, attends the University of Madrid where she
“Cast-Offs.” studies philosophy and dies in 1991. Zambrano
wrote numerous books in Spanish – one of
25 Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 28; cf. Le Doeuff, which inspired Le Doeuff with a story about
The Philosophical Imaginary 100–28. Dawn who remains human, unlike the goddess
“Dawn” of classical literature. For the challenge
26 Paul Ricoeur, “Ethics and Human Capability: A
of “la philosophie imaginaire” in Zambrano to the
Response” in Paul Ricoeur and Contemporary Moral
traditional gender stereotypes of divine women,
Thought, eds. John Wall, William Schweiker, and
see Maria Zambrano, De l’Aurore, trans. from
David Hall (New York and London: Routledge,
Spanish Marie Laffranque (Paris: L’Éclat, 1989).
2002) 280, 282, 284.
37 An Interrupted Life: The Diaries of Etty Hillesum,
27 Paul Ricoeur, Memory, History, Forgetting, trans.
ed. J.G. Gaarlandt (New York: Washington
Kathleen Blamey (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2005)
Square, 1985) 119. [Editors’ note: Etty Hillesum
460.
(1914–43) was a Dutch Jewish victim of the
28 Ibid. 459–66. Holocaust.]
29 Ricoeur, “Ethics and Human Capability” 284; cf. 38 Pamela Sue Anderson, “Feminism and Patriar-
Paul Ricoeur, Fallible Man, trans. Charles A. Kelbley chy” in The Oxford Handbook of English Literature

21
a new philosophical imaginary

and Theology, eds. David Jasper, Andrew Hass, and Spinoza, Ethics, trans. and ed. G.H.R. Parkinson
Elizabeth Jay (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2006) 810–26. (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000) 314–16.
39 Virginia Woolf, The Waves, Biographical 46 Carol Gilligan, The Birth of Pleasure: A New Map
Preface by Frank Kermode, ed. with an Introduc- of Love (London: Chatto, 2002) 40.
tion and Notes by Gillian Beer (Oxford: Oxford
47 For the claim that philosophy is “the wisdom of
UP, 1992) 3. For an example where Woolf
love in the service of love,” see Emmanuel Levinas,
moves from the light–dark imagery of waves
Otherwise than Being, trans. Alphonso Lingis (The
rising and falling to the figure of a rider on a
Hague: Nijhoff, 1981) 162. For a gloss on Levinas’s
proud horse who faces a dark enemy advancing
statement on “the Said said in the service of the
against her or him, see ibid. 247–48.
Saying, the ‘justified Said’, in which wisdom has
40 Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 242–43; cf. Woolf, learnt from love, or in which politics is not unin-
The Waves 3. For a contextualization of French fem- formed by ethics,” see Stella Sandford, The Meta-
inism in terms of waves, see Lisa Walsh, “Introduc- physics of Love: Gender and Transcendence in
tion: The Swell of the Third Wave” in Contemporary Levinas (London: Athlone, 2000) 91.
French Feminism, eds. Kelly Oliver and Lisa Walsh
(Oxford: Oxford UP, 2004) 1–11.
41 For more on recognition, or reciprocal equal-
ity, see Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice 278–79;
Pamela Sue Anderson, “Life, Death and (Inter)sub-
jectivity: Realism and Recognition in Continental
Philosophy,” International Journal of Philosophy of
Religion 13, Special Issue, Issues in Continental Philos-
ophy of Religion (2006).
42 Hamer and Code translate Le Doeuff’s French
term déshérences as “cast-offs”: see Le Doeuff, The
Sex of Knowing 18. Instead, to emphasize the lack
of inheritance in this context, the (albeit
awkward) “dis-inherited women” is the present
translation.

43 For example, Le Doeuff points out that Woolf


fails to recognize any renaissance or medieval
woman writer; so Le Doeuff singles out a
counter-example: Christine de Pisan is a four-
teenth-century woman writer who did much to
demonstrate the crucial significance of the imagin-
ary for the successful living and thinking of women;
see Le Doeuff, The Sex of Knowing ix–x, 119, 135– Sabina Lovibond
38. Cf. Christine de Pisan, The Book of the City of
Worcester College
Ladies, trans. and with Notes by Rosalind Brown-
Grant (London: Penguin, 1999).
Walton Street
Oxford OX1 2HB
44 Concerning the urgent need for a feminist ima- UK
ginary, see also Penelope Deutscher, “When Fem- E-mail: sabina-mary.lovibond@worc.ox.ac.uk
inism is ‘High’ and Ignorance is ‘Low’: Harriet
Taylor Mill on the Progress of the Species,” A.W. Moore
Hypatia 21.3 (2006): 147. St Hugh’s College
45 Amélie Rorty, “Spinoza on the Pathos of Idola- St Margaret’s Road
trous Love and the Hilarity of True Love” in Femin- Oxford OX2 6LE
ism and the History of Philosophy, ed. Genevieve UK
Lloyd (New York: Oxford UP, 2002) 222; cf. E-mail: adrian.moore@st-hughs.ox.ac.uk

You might also like