You are on page 1of 26

The British Society for the Philosophy of Science

Theory Structure and Theory Change in Contemporary Molecular Biology


Author(s): Sylvia Culp and Philip Kitcher
Source: The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 40, No. 4 (Dec., 1989), pp. 459-
483
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of The British Society for the Philosophy of
Science
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/687736 .
Accessed: 25/06/2014 04:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Oxford University Press and The British Society for the Philosophy of Science are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 40 (1989), 459-483 Printedin Great Britain

Theory Structure and Theory Change in


Contemporary Molecular Biology
SYLVIA CULP AND PHILIP KITCHER'

ABSTRACT
Traditionalapproachesto theory structure and theory change in science do not
farewell when confrontedwith the practiceof certainfieldsof science. We offeran
account of contemporarypractice in molecular biology designed to addresstwo
questions:Is theorychange in this area of science gradualor saltatory?What is the
relation between molecularbiology and the fieldsof traditionalbiology?Ourmain
focus is a recentepisodein molecularbiology,the discoveryof enzymaticRNA.We
argue that our reconstructionof this episodeshows that traditionalapproachesto
theory structureand theory change need considerablerefinementif they are to be
defendedas generally applicable.

1 Introduction
2 Practicein ContemporaryMolecularBiology
3 The Discoveryof EnzymaticRNA
4 Understandingthe Change
5 DerivativeRevolutionsand ReductionismRevisited

I INTRODUCTION

Despite a plethora of critiques of what used to be known, quite aptly, as the


'received view' of scientific theories, contemporary debates about intertheore-
tic relations and about theory change are still often conducted as if scientific
theories could be unproblematically identified as deductively closed sets of
sentences. In our judgment, the attempt to find some small number of general
laws that can serve as the axioms of the scientific theory under study has
proved especially baneful in the biological sciences. Even where axiomatiza-
tion has been achieved-as in the careful studies of Mary Williams on the
theory of natural selection [1970, 1973]-there are serious questions as to
whether the axiomatization captures what is central to the theory as biologists

1 This paper emerged from discussions between us, and we are both equally responsible for its
errors. We would like to thank Yvonne Paterson for helpful comments.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
460 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
actuallyunderstandit, use it, anddevelopit. Indeed, we believe that the continued
smouldering problems about the 'triviality' or 'unfalsifiability' of neo-
Darwinism are, in large measure, the product of thinking that there has to be
some principle (or principles)of great generality that formulate the core of the
theory of evolution by natural selection (see Kitcher [1982], pp. 55-60).
Similarly, in the debates about the reduction of classical genetics to molecular
biology, the macro-level theory has been essentially divorced from what
geneticists have been doing since approximately 1915 (let alone 1953) by
proposing that classical genetics can be identified with the logical conse-
quences of Mendel's laws (or minor adjustments of those laws). If any scientific
theory worthy of the name is a deductively closed set of sentences whose
axioms include generalizations that range over all the entities in the domain of
the theory, then it seems that either biology has no theories or what theories it
has are both trivial and irrelevant to the thinking and activity of almost all
contemporary biologists.
Nor are things much better if we abandon the syntactic conception of
theories in favor of its chief rival, the so-called 'semantic view of theories',
according to which a theory is a class of models. Although this approach is
valuable in differentiating a theory from its formulations (Suppe [1972]), in
clarifying the relation between theory and observation (Van Fraassen [1980]),
and in reconstructing parts of important biological theories (Lloyd [1984],
Lloyd [forthcoming]), we believe that it encounters problems that are parallel
to those besetting the older conception when it seeks to treat theories at a high
level of generality. The task of specifying the class of models that is Darwinian
evolutionary theory or the class of models that is classical genetics gives us no
more adequate a picture of these biological disciplines than does the task of
specifying the axioms of these theories-and for the obvious reason that the
new-style specifications of sets of models look remarkably like the old-style
axioms (see Beatty [1980] and Giere [1979] for examples). Proponents of the
semantic view have sometimes gone to considerable efforts to reconstruct the
big biological theories and to re-examine the questions of inter-theoretic
relations and theory change (see Balzer and Dawe [1986] for a laudably
thorough attempt). However, like the endeavours on behalf of the 'received
view', their struggles seem to result in reconstructions that are quite remote
from what has been going on in biology for the past fifty years. It is only a little
unfair to conclude that some philosophical reconstructions of major biological
theories reconstruct only the opening chapters of introductory texts.2 We
shall offer a different approach to biology, keyed to a specific, illustrative

2 Ironically, while the


general question of how to approach major biological theories remains
confused, more specificstudies of parts of theoretical biology are thriving as never before.
Witness the important work of David Hull, Elliott Sober, John Beatty, Robert Brandon, John
Dupre, William Wimsatt, ElisabethLloyd,Alexander Rosenberg, RichardBurian, and a number
of other authors.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 461

example. We do not believe that the case we describe is atypical of biology-


indeed, although we shall not defend a sweeping thesis here, we think that it
represents the structure of many areas of science. Our starting point is the
notion that, at any particular stage in the development of a science, there is a
complex state of that science, the aggregate of all that the scientists working in
the field at the time are thinking, saying, writing, and doing. Philosophers,
intent on answering certain questions about the synchronic relations among
sciences or the diachronic development of particular disciplines, try to
reconstruct this state. Prevailing fashions in the philosophy of science suppose
that we can distil from all the sayings and doings a theorythat dominates the
science of the time. We shall identify a multi-dimensional entity that we call a
'scientific practice'. Those who believe that a scientific theory could not be
anything except a set of highly general laws and their logical consequences (or,
if you like, a class of models) may conclude that we have not offeredan account
of the structure of biological theory. We will happily abandon the word, for
what seems to us to be vastly more significant is the delineation of the ways in
which the practice of biological science achieves generality.
Philosophical reconstruction should not be dominated by the preconception
that there is an essence of metascientific concepts that awaits our exposure.
Our phenomena are the sayings, writings, and doings of a group of scientists.3
There is probably no all-purpose reconstruction of the phenomena that will
capture the essence of the science and provide an idiom in which to formulate
all possible epistemological and methodological questions. Instead, we should
start with particular questions and look for an account of the phenomena that
enables us to focus those questions. In the present case, the background
philosophical questions are 'What are the relations between biological theories
and theories in physics and chemistry?' and 'Are changes in biological theories
gradual or saltatory?' (Behind these formulations stand, of course, cloudier
issues about reductionism and about revolutions in science.) We shall try to
reconstruct the phenomena in a way that makes it possible to address these
questions.
While our approach breaks with many traditional ideas about scientific
theories in general and biological theories in particular, it is not bereft of
ancestors. In his discussions of the character of normal science, Thomas Kuhn
offered a multi-dimensional view of the state of a science at a time ([1970]
Chapters 3-5), and our approach can be seen as articulating further some of
the elements that Kuhn discerned as shared among a group of contempora-

For the purposes of this essay, we do not venture into the tricky issue of how the group is to be
demarcated. We also idealize the phenomena by concentrating only on those parts of the
practice that are acknowledged by all members of the group. In fact, one of us (P.S.K.)believes
that it is important to take account of the cognitive diversity within a slice of science if one wants
to address some fundamental problems about progress and rationality in science. But we are
concerned to advance one heresy at a time.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
462 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
neous scientists.4 Moreover, there are affinities between our approach and
ideas of Sylvain Bromberger [1963], Dudley Shapere [1974], and Kenneth
Schaffner [forthcoming]. The present essay also articulates an approach that
has been taken with respect to other biological examples and associated
philosophical problems:the reduction of classical genetics to molecular biology
(Kitcher [1984]), the resolution of the Darwinian revolution (Kitcher
[1985a]), the relation between various ventures in sociobiology and contem-
porary neo-Darwinism (Kitcher[198 5b] chapters 1-4), and theory-change in
cardiology (Lie [unpublished]).

2 PRACTICE IN CONTEMPORARY MOLECULAR BIOLOGY

Philosophers approaching molecular biology for the first time ought to be


struck by the apparent amorphousness of the subject. Generalintroductions to
the field (Watson et al [198 7], Darnell et al [1986]) are both dauntingly long
and full of apparently disparate kinds of information. There is typically some
attention to organic and physical chemistry, and metabolic and physical
biochemistry. This is followed by a review of the main phenomena of
prokaryoticand eukaryotic cell biology and genetics, and (less systematically)
of development and physiology. Considerablespace is given to the presentation
of techniques for deriving information about the molecules present within a
cell. Finally, the bulk of the work consists in bringing all the previous elements
together: there is a whole mass of claims about the molecular interactions in
particular processes in particular kinds of organisms, specifically about the
processes that culminate in the formation of the biologically significant
molecules, the nucleic acids and proteins. These claims are buttressedthrough
the description of the experiments that have led to their adoption. Over-
whelmed by all the detail, the philosopher searches in vain for the display of
core laws, big generalizations analogous to Maxwell's equations, Schrod-
inger's equation, or Newton's laws of dynamics. What makes all this one
subject?
Mattersonly become worse as one probes the technical literature. Moreand
more detail is added to the study of gene replication and expression. The pages
of Science, Nature, and Cell contain reports of discoveries that practitioners
herald as being of theoreticalimportance-but they seem extraordinarily
particular. Here a new RNA polymerase, there a suggestion of a conserved
DNA sequence. Nourished on the philosophical staples about scientific

Kuhn's notion of paradigm (or, later, disciplinary matrix) unfortunately served double duty,
expressing both the idea that there is a complex of shared elements and the view that the history
of a science can be divided into discrete units, punctuated by revolutions (paradigmshifts). As
will become clear below, the former idea is quite independent of the latter-indeed, we believe
that development of the first makes the acceptance of the second quite implausible. For further
discussion of the relation between our notion of practice and Kuhn's conception of paradigm,
see chapter 7 of Kitcher [1983].

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 463
theories, the bewildered reader fails to understand how any old generalization
has been refuted or any new generalization proposed, and, in consequence,
fails to see what makes the work 'theoretically significant'. Molecular biology
continues to look like a vast morass of unconnected detail. Where is the
theory?
Similar questions could easily be generated if our imaginary philosopher
had started with classical genetics-the field that concerned itself with the
transmission of hereditary traits-had chosen any point in the history of the
subject between 1915 and 1953, and had resolutely read beyond the
simplifying Mendelian formulations of the introductory chapter. For some
philosophical purposes, classical genetics can be reconstructed by introducing
the concept of a practiceconsisting of a language, a set of statements, a set of
questions, a set of patterns of reasoning, a set of methodological directives, and
a set of experimental techniques (see Kitcher [1984]). The language is that
used by the community of geneticists, the statements are those that they
accept, the questions are those that they-take to be important to address, the
patterns of reasoning are the forms of argument that they employ in answering
those questions, the methodological directives are the standards by means of
which they appraisecontending solutions and evaluate proposedexperiments,
and the experimental techniques are the methods they employ in interrogating
nature. We shall try to show how a similar approach can bring order to the
apparent amorphousness of contemporary molecular biology.
Let us start with the central problems that molecular biology sets for itself.
Its grand project can be seen as that of tracing the chemical reactions that
occur in biologically significant processes, where, for the molecular biologist,
biologically significant processes are, paradigmatically, processes of nucleic
acid replication, transcription, translation, and their control. The big vague
question is 'How does P occur?' where P is to be replacedby some descriptionof
a biological process. In contemporary work, the big vague question is made far
more precise through the incorporation of particular views about what
processes are biologically significant and about the chemistry of living
organisms.
The traditional disciplines of nonmolecular biology contribute to the
specification. Start with genetics. Classical genetics recognizes the existence of
information-bearing units, genes, that are copied, transmitted to gametes and
combine in zygotes (in asexual organisms, the route into the next generation is
typically more direct). These units, occasionally singly, typically in combina-
tion, are associated with phenotypic traits of the organism, but, from the
perspective of classical genetics, this associatioh is given (indeed, genes are first
identifiedthrough their phenotypic effects, or, more exactly, through differen-
tial phenotypic effects of their mutant alleles, so that the association of gene
and trait is there from the start). To pry into the process through which the
genes in concert with one another and with the environment give rise to the

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
464 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
phenotype of the organism is a task for developmental biology. So, from
genetics proper,we take the important biological processes of gene replication
and gametic segregation: the big vague question becomes 'How do genes copy
themselves?', 'How do gene copies get distributed to gametes?'.
Developmental biology takes up the story where genetics leaves off. We can
divide the enterprise into two unequal parts. The lesser task consists in
accounting for zygote formation, understanding the fusion of sperm and egg,
the incorporation of the DNA of the sperm within the nucleus of the egg. Far
more onerous is the project of tracing the link between genotype and adult
phenotype, showing how adult morphology is generated from the (relatively
unstructured) zygote. With respect to particular organisms and particular
types of structures-limb buds or nervous systems, for example-ontogenesis
can be segmented into stages, and the developmental question can be further
focused by asking how the structures present at one stage are transformedinto
those present at the next. Against the background presupposition that copies
of all the genes present in the zygote are found in (almost) all the cells of the
developing organism, the big vague question can be made more precise. 'When
do cells become differentiated?','What constitutes the differentiationof cells of
a particular type?', 'What signals are involved in differentiation?','How do
different genes become active in different cells?'. All of these questions are
taken up in the context of molecular biology as demands for the specificationof
molecules and of molecular interactions. Differentiation is ultimately to be
understood in terms of the molecular composition of cells, and this molecular
composition is, in its turn, to be traced to the systems of gene control and the
molecules that interact with them.
Besides its contributions to our understanding of processes important to the
transmission of genes (spindle formation) and to the link between gene and
phenotype (the functioning of the cytoskeleton), cell biology also contributes
questions that have nothing to do with genetics or the link between genes and
phenotypes. Cells have to engage in certain kinds of reactions so that the
organism can function physiologically. Here we begin from the physiology of
the organism and from some physiological phenomenon-respiration, diges-
tion, or muscular contraction, say-proceed to a categorization of the cell-
level processes that are involved-for example, the taking up of oxygen in the
lungs and the delivery of oxygen to the blood-and ask how the cells in the
process are acting and what enables them to do the things they do. As with
the phenomena of ontogenesis, the molecular questions come into focus once
we have achieved a decomposition of the process, identifying it as a complex of
subprocesses involving individual cells. At that stage, we can begin to inquire
about the chemical compositions of the cells and about the molecular (or
physical) interactions among them.
We are now able to introduce some structure into molecular biology by

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 465
seeing that the big vague question breaks down into more precise questions
along the lines depicted in Figures 1 and 2. Our use of two illustrations here
suggests a contrast between molecular biology as currently practiced and
molecular biology as it might ultimately develop. On the formerinterpretation,
the biologically significant processes are simply the current paradigms-
nucleic acid replication, gene transcription, protein synthesis, and so forth.
The second view is broader, bringing within the domain of molecular biology
the processes of intermediate metabolism by decomposing them into com-
plexes whose elements are the kinds of processes that are currently studied by
molecular biologists. Across all these families of questions there cuts a
common set of presuppositions about the chemical reactions that occur in
living organisms. The presuppositions begin with claims about the kinds of
molecules found in living organisms, and about the chemistry of these
molecules (organic chemistry). They proceed to claim that typical reactions
found in living things are 'uphill reactions', reactions that need to be catalyzed
if they are to occur. Hence, for typical reactions in organisms, it will be
necessary to specify a catalyst, an enzyme. Finally, in the molecular biology
that held sway up to five years ago, there was a further presupposition:
enzymes are proteins.
Understanding these presuppositions, we can proceed to specify the normal
form of a problem solution in molecular biology. We start with some
biologically significant process P and with our big vague question 'How does P
occur?'. The normalform of an answer is as follows:
[1] P is composed of n elementary processes P1,..., Pn.
[2] For P1 the reactants are r,1...r. , ki, the enzyme is el; for P2 the reactants
are ,. ** r2k2;the enzyme is e2 . . . (continue through all the P1).
For r21•
[3] P1the products are R11,..., Rj11;for P2 the products are R21.**R2*2;
(continue through all the P1).
In accepting this as a complete answer to the question, we make the
following demands: (a) for each Pi, the specification of the products must
be obtained from the specification of the reactants for that Pi by applying
standard principles of chemical kinetics; (b) the reactants for Pj+1 must be
included among the products of Pj;(c) there must be appendedto [1]-[3] a
specification of the initial and final states of the organism showing that the
reactants r1~are initially present and that the final state consists in the
presence of the Rniproducts.5
Let us illustrate this abstract account with an example. In the study of the
relation between genes and phenotypes, an obviously important process is that
s The normal form of solution offered here is a simplified version of the underlying explanatory
schema. For a general account of explanatory schemata, see Kitcher [1981 ], and for articulated
examples in particular cases, including the case of classical genetics, see Kitcher [forthcoming].

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
HOW DOES P OCCUR?

Genetics Developmen

HOW ARE GENES TRANSMITTED? HOW DO ZYGOTES


MATURE ORGAN
Transmission involves copying,
segregation and assortment Genes code for p

HOW ARE HOW ARE HOW DOES HOW ARE PRO


GENES HOMOLOGOUS MEIOSIS SYNTHESIZED FRO
COPIED? CHROMOSOMES WORK?
PAIRED AND Protein formation involve
SEPARATED? translation, and f

The genetic material is DNA HOW DOES HOW DOE


TRANSCRIPTION TRANSLATI
COPIED?
DNA COPIED
IS DNA
HOW HOW WORK? WORK?
IS

DNA copying involves unwinding


of strands and DNA synthesis

HOW IS HOW IS THE


UNWINDING NEW DNA STRAND
INITIATED? SYNTHESIZED?
FIGURE1 The Simple Hierarchy of Molecular Biological Questions.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
HOW DOES P OCCUR?

Genetics Development Cell Biol

[As in Figure 1] HOW DO ZYGOTES BECOME


MATURE ORGANISMS? HOW DO
ORGANISMS
BREATHE?
Genes code Major structures
for proteins formed are: muscles, M
gametes, dermis, c
heart, nervous system.
[As in Figure1] /
HOW DO HOW DO
MUSCLES GAMETES
FORM? FORM? HOW

Muscle cells contain Mu


actin and myosin ac

HOW IS THE PRODUCTION HOW DO


OF ACTIN AND MYOSIN CON
CONTROLLED IN CONTRA
MUSCLE CELLS?

WHAT SIGNALS DOES WHAT IS THE


A DIFFERENTIATING MECHANISM FOR
MYOBLAST RECEIVE ACTIVATINGTHE
THAT INITIATETHE ACTIN AND MYOSIN
MECHANISM FOR GENES?
TRANSCRIBING ACTIN
AND MYOSIN GENES?
FIGURE 2 The Expanded Hierarchy.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
468 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
in which particular genes give rise to proteins: any aspect of development
obviously involves many-typically very many-episodes in which genes are
'read'and proteins synthesized. A first-leveldecomposition of any developmen-
tal process will thus posit numerous processes in which genes 'encode'
proteins. However, each one of these processes is itself regarded as complex:
the gene is selected for transcription; the gene is transcribed to form a
messenger RNA; that mRNA is post-transcriptionally modified;the modified
mRNA is translated, ultimately giving rise to a protein product at the
ribosomes. From this second-level decomposition, we select the process of
transcription for more detailed study. How does transcription occur?
Here are the major features of the story as we currently understand it. There
are protein molecules, RNApolymerases,that can enter into loose associations
with double-strandedDNA. Effectively,these molecules can slide up and down
the DNA, 'scanning' it. If the DNA contains the appropriatekind of sequence, a
promoter, and if the RNA polymerase is in the right configuration, then the
RNA polymerase becomes bound to the DNA at an appropriatepoint and the
DNA becomes unwound. RNA chain synthesis is initiated and elongates along
one of the exposed strands.
Now a full molecular biological account would be able to eliminate some of
the vague and metaphorical terminology that we have employed in the
previous paragraph. That account would be able to specify in molecular detail
the four phases that are discerned in our story: loose association, binding,
unwinding, and chain-synthesis. The task is to identify the chemical structure
of 'loose association', to specify the 'appropriate sites' and to show how, at
these sites, the configuration of RNA polymerases is changed, thence to specify
the altered configuration of the DNA and show how it results, and, finally, to
give the molecular details of chain-elongation along the exposed strand. Parts
of the puzzle are in place for particular gene complexes in particular
organisms-but the past decade has witnessed a number of discoveries of
significant differencesamong differentcases. In terms of our normal form, we
have a working hypothesis about the decomposition of the process of
transcription and some details of the subprocesses for particular cases of
transcription.It is still too early to tell how much generality we may eventually
attain.
We hope that it is now possible to see how the apparently amorphous
literature in molecular biology is organized. The mass of details in the books,
monographs, and research articles, that comprises the set of accepted
statements in the current practice of molecular biology, is structured by the
hierarchy of questions that the discipline addresses, the hierarchy displayedin
Figures 1 and 2. Each of the statements obtains its significance from the part it
plays in answering one of the questions in the hierarchy, and, we believe, that
role can best be understood by seeing how the statement contributes to an
answer in normal form (the pattern delineated above, p. 7).

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 469
Two further aspects of the practice of molecular biology deserve comment
before we offer a more extended illustrative example. First, the language of
contemporary molecular biology is a curious hybrid. For many of the
expressions employed by molecular biologists, the reference is fixed, parasiti-
cally, in the fashion of organic chemistry: terms like 'bond energy' and 'peptide
chain' retain their standard chemical significance in the biological context.
Where terms are taken over from biology or are employed in ways specific to
the biological material, there may, however, be a re-fixing of reference. We
shall see this in more detail in the next Section, when we consider the
modification of the concept of enzyme. Finally, molecular biology uses
metaphorical language in describing important subprocesses: polymerases
'scan' the DNA, introns are 'excised', and so forth. The assumption seems to be
that, ultimately, it will be possible to say in a literal, biochemical language,
what is now expressed in the helpful metaphors. As we shall suggest below,
there are important questions that lurk here.
Finally, no account of molecular biology should overlook the importance of
the experimental techniques. Philosophical views of science (with a few
exceptions-e.g. Hacking [1983]) frequently distort the character of the
enterprise by stressing 'grand theory'. Since contemporary molecular biology
is founded on methods for arriving at the structure of complex molecules-
nucleic acids and proteins-without which there would be no chance of
providing the structural descriptions needed for the normal form of solution to
molecular biological problems,it is impossible simply to regardthis component
of the practice as an afterthought. Those methods are, of course, intertwined
with the large presuppositionsthat, in our view, help to structure the field. If it
were discovered that small fragments of nucleic acids that convey genetic
information were tightly associated in some cells with genomic DNA, then the
techniques for mapping and sequencing genomes that are based on the
presuppositionthat all genetic information is linearly arranged on nucleic acid
molecules would have to be radically revised. In the next section, we shall
consider a real instance that resembles this hypothetical discovery, and
attempt to show both the significance of experimental technique and how
changes in large presuppositions about what experiments show can be
accommodated.

3 THE DISCOVERY OF ENZYMATIC RNA

We have already noted that, for biological reactions to occur under


physiological conditions, they require an enzyme to act as a catalyst. Thus,
when any instance of the big vague question has been decomposed and we are
addressing the normal form of some component question, it is always
significant to inquire after the enzyme involved.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
470 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
Attention to the history of the study of enzymes helps us understand how the
issue is focused, and what presuppositionsare involved in addressingit. In the
absence of catalysts, biological reactions would only occur very slowly.
Enzymes accelerate those reactions from 106 to 1012 times without themselves
being consumed. Enzymes are also highly specific; often an enzyme will
catalyze only a single reaction, or, at most, a set of closely related reactions.
Since Sumner's first isolation of an enzyme, urease, in 1926, hundreds of
enzymes have been purifiedand shown to catalyze specificbiological reactions,
and the total range of reactions catalyzed is now extensive. Likeurease, all the
enzymes that had been isolated until very recently were proteins, so that it was
natural for biologists to assume that all enzymes are proteins, to approach the
problem of finding the enzyme by looking for a protein, and even to define
enzymes as proteins (Westheimer [1986]).6
In [1986], Zaug and Cech reported in Sciencethat a segment of RNA could
act as an RNA synthesizing enzyme. Within two weeks, their discovery was
hailed as 'revolutionary' by Westheimer in the 'News and Views' section of
Nature (Zaug and Cech [1986], Westheimer [1986]). Because all enzymes
were assumed to be proteins, it is surprising that Zaug and Cech designed
experiments to look for an enzyme activity mediated by an RNA molecule.
However, Cech and his colleagues were first led to challenge the presupposi-
tion that all enzymes are proteins by observations that they published five
years earlier (Cech et al [1981]). Cech and his co-workers had been studying
ribosomal RNA (rRNA) splicing in the ciliated protozoan Tetrahymena
thermophilia.In the course of their study they designed experiments for
identifying and isolating the protein enzymes that catalyzed the rRNA
splicing-a part of an instance of a normal form problem. As the pattern
displayed above (p. 465) reveals, one subtask is to identify the enzymes
involved in the constituent subprocesses of the biologically significant process
under investigation, and it was precisely this subtask that Zaug and Cech
addressed. After purifying the RNA precursor (pre-RNA)from T. thermophilia
and mixing it with nuclear extracts from the same cells, they were able to
produce spliced rRNAin a test tube. However, a negative control, in which the
nuclear extract was omitted, also gave rise to spliced rRNA. Assuming that
more stringent purifying methods were needed, they tried several methods to
remove the enzymatic activity by destroying proteins that they supposed to be
associated with the pre-rRNA.None of their procedures were able to destroy
the RNA splicing activity. Thus they were led to conclude that the pre-RNA
might be an enzyme.
However, Cech and his colleagues [1981] buried this embarrassing fact in

6 This assumption was less arbitrarythan it may sound. It was supportedby the recognition that
proteins, built up out of twenty amino acid side chains, would have enough diversityto give the
required enzyme specificity.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 471
their paper among a large body of data on the splicing mechanism. In both the
results and discussion sections, they only mentioned brieflythe possibility that
some part of the pre-rRNAmight be an RNA enzyme. The model of pre-rRNA
splicing that they presented at the end of the discussion emphasized the
structures of the molecules before and after splicing, and did not mention the
possibility that an RNA enzyme might catalyze the reaction. Their paper was
published in Cell,a prestigious and widely-read journal. Yet only readers who
read this paper carefully realized that Cech and his colleagues might have
found an RNA enzyme.
Why was Cech so modest in burying a discovery that would be hailed, live
years later, as revolutionary? The answer is relatively obvious. First, since
protein enzymes had been found for every other biological reaction studied,
there was no reason to expect that an RNA molecule could be an enzyme
(although, we hasten to note, there is nothing in the underlying biochemistry
to preclude the possibility that nucleic acids can catalyze reactions). Second,
because the pre-rRNAhad been isolated from T. thermophiliacells, it would still
be possible to deny the enzymatic RNA interpretation by claiming that a
protein enzyme had become incorporated with the pre-rRNAand had not been
inactivated by the various methods tried by Cech and his colleagues.
If recombinant DNA technology had not been developed four years earlier,
Cech's data would probably have remained buried or, if it had later been
presented more forthrightly, would have engendered an unresolved contro-
versy among molecular biologists. However, Cech's next paper, published
again in Cell in 1982, was entitled 'Self-splicing RNA' (Kruger et al [1982]).
Cech and his co-workers used recombinant DNA technology to clone a portion
of the T. thermophiliarRNA gene into an E. coli (bacterial)plasmid vector. After
purifying the recombinant plasmid DNA from the E. coli cells, they used
purifiedE. coli RNA polymerase to make the pre-RNAin vitro.This pre-rRNA,
separated from all T. thermophiliaproteins, could be judged with confidence to
be nucleic acid and nucleic acid alone.7 By showing that it was able to splice
itself, Cech and his colleagues demonstrated that a protein enzyme was not
necessary for pre-RNAsplicing. However, because the pre-rRNAmodifieditself
during the splicing reaction, it did not meet all the conditions on enzymes.
Kruger et al [1982] decided to dub it a 'ribozyme'.
Between 1982 and 1986, a series of papers on the mechanism and products
of the ribozyme-mediated RNA-splicing reaction appeared from Cech's
laboratory (Zaug et al [1983], Bass and Cech [1984], Zaug et al [1984], Inoue
et al [1985], Sullivan and Cech [1985], Zaug et al [1985]). Using the
information amassed in this period, Cech and his colleagues were eventually
able to show that a piece of the pre-rRNA, removed and modified during the

7 The pre-RNA could have been associated with E. coli proteins, but these were assumed to be
irrelevant because E. coli is a prokaryote and T. thermophiliaan eukaryote.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
472 Sylvia Culpand PhilipKitcher
self-splicing reaction, could act as an enzyme. By 1986, they were preparedto
conclude that this piece of RNA could act as an RNA polymerase, putting
together long strands of RNA (Zaug and Cech [1986]). The segment in
question was shown to meet the three conditions for an enzyme: it could
mediate reactions that could not proceed in its absence, it was reaction-
specific, and it was not modified by these reactions.
Discovering that enzymes can also be made of RNA may seem a small
change in enzyme theory, merely an addition of RNA enzymes to the long list
of protein enzymes. Alternatively, one might defend the 'revolutionary' claim
of Westheimer's review, by maintaining that the concept of enzyme has been
refashioned and that a central generalization of molecular biology-the thesis
that all enzymes are proteins-has been abandoned. In our judgment, neither
of these responses to the incident captures what has been going on. In the
following Section we shall try to show how developments so far achieved
might appear in retrospect either as minor modifications of molecular biology
or as revolutionary.
We conclude our discussion of the case by noting two ways in which it has
reshaped current research. Past experiments (directed at the normal form
question of finding the enzyme) had been designed to look for proteins. Where
such experiments had been inconclusive, it is possible that re-investigation will
disclose the activity of enzymatic nucleic acids-perhaps even possible that
techniques of purification that have been jettisoned as problematic may be
resurrected. In particular, the research on ribosome function may need to be
reevaluated (Moore [1988]). In every biological system, ribosomes are used to
translate protein from mRNA. Ribosomes contain both RNA and protein. Until
now, the enzymatic activities associated with ribosomes had been assigned to
the ribosomal proteins. Cech's work raises the possibility that ribosomal RNAs
have enzymatic activities. In addition, other cellular processes, such as
regulation of RNA transcription and processing, may need to be reevaluated
because they could also be mediated by RNA enzymes.
A second area in which research has been affected is the field of prebiotic
evolution. Only three weeks after the publication of Zaug and Cech [1986],
Gilbertproposedin the 'News and Views' section of Naturethat, at the earliest
stages of evolution, the world was an RNA world (Gilbert[1986]). Since then,
renewed interest in prebiotic evolution has led to the publication of several
speculative papers (Cech [1986], Joyce et al [1987], Weiner and Maizels
[1987]) and to the organization of a major meeting on the evolution of
catalytic function, the annual ColdSpring HarborSymposium on Quantitative
Biology. The renewal of interest has obviously been sparkedby appreciationof
the fact that an RNA-synthesizingenzyme composed of RNA makes it possible
that a molecule could catalyze synthesis of itself. The hypothesis that the same
molecule acts as a synthetase and serves as the template overcomes the
chicken-and-egg problem posed by the conventional theoretical requirement

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 473
that two separate (but interdependent) molecules are needed for replication-
synthetases made of protein and templates made of RNA.8

4 UNDERSTANDING THE CHANGE

In a sense the action is already over. After years of research, Cech and his co-
workers found a segment of RNA capable of performing enzymatic functions.
The discovery was accepted by his colleagues, and, indeed, canonized through
the incorporation of a section on enzymatic RNA in the latest edition of the
most celebratedtextbook in the field (Watson et al [198 7]).* While it is possible
that the discovery of enzymatic RNA will live up to Westheimer's billing of it as
'revolutionary', it seems to us equally possible that the molecular biology of the
twenty-first century will treat Cech's discovery as an isolated curiosity,
relegating it to footnotes of the genre: 'Readersshould be aware that, although
almost all enzymes are proteins, there are exceptional cases in which nucleic
acids can performcertain elementary enzymatic functions. The first such case
discovered emerged from the work of Cech and others on rRNA splicing in
Tetrahymenathermophilia... .' Our aim in this section is to analyze the case of
the discovery of enzymatic RNA from the perspectiveoutlined in Section 2. We
shall use our reconstruction both to show how that discovery might lead to a
revolution in molecular biology, and to draw some general morals about
scientific change.
Consider first what has occurred so far. The practice of contemporary
molecular biology has been affected in the following ways. (1) The referent of
'enzyme' can no longer be fixed by the description 'A proteinthat mediates a
specific biological reaction (or a set of closely related biological reactions) and
that is unmodified at the end of the reaction(s)'. (2) The statement 'All enzymes
are proteins' is no longer accepted; the statement 'A segment of T. thermophila
pre-rRNA can catalyze RNA polymerization' is accepted. (3) Normal form
solutions to normal form questions no longer presuppose that the identifica-
tion of enzymes at step 2 will identify proteins. (4) It is no longer necessary to
contend that an experimental technique for purifying nuclear extracts by
eliminating protein is suspect if its application permits enzymatic activity. At
least four components of the practice-language, statements, schematic
answers, and experimental techniques-have all felt the impact of Cech's
discovery. Perhaps we could also add a fifth, by noting the addition of a new

8 Even if RNA enzymes are not widespread in the present world, that does not mean that they were
not initially prominent. Perhaps enzymatic RNA was relatively primitive, and, once the system
got advanced enough to make proteins, those organisms (Dawkinsian replicators?)that stayed
with enzymatic RNA were at a disadvantage except with respect to very special processes like
rRNA splicing.
* As this
paperwas in press Cech and his colleagues were awarded the Nobel prizein Chemistryfor
their work on enzymatic RNA.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
474 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
theoretical question: What kinds of reactions can we expect nucleic acids to
catalyze?
How were these changes accomplished? Let's start with the state of
molecular biology in 1981. Cech and his co-workers attack a problemthat the
molecular biology of that time counts as significant, the identification of the
enzyme catalyzing pre-rRNA splicing in T. thermophilia(note that the
significance of the protozoan in this case stems simply from the fact that this
was an organism in which the process could be studied using the technology
available at the time). Given the assumption that all enzymes are proteins, they
expect to find a splicing enzyme. The negative control experiment apparently
fails, leaving them with the options of concluding that the splicing is self-
mediated or that the purifying techniques they have employed have not
removed all the relevant protein. Appealing to the standard experimental
techniques of molecular biology, they make further efforts to eliminate the
unwanted protein.
At this stage, resolution of the puzzle could still be obtained by suggesting
that the standard techniques are incapable of dealing with certain highly
recalcitrant proteins that associate tightly with pre-rRNAs.That possibility is
eliminated by appealing to the central techniques of recombinant DNA: it is
takenfor grantedthat applicationof these techniqueswill yield pure pre-rRNA.9
(Alternatively, questioning the applicabilityof the methods used in cloning the
T. thermophiliagene and synthesizing its product in vitro,would entail an even
more massive shift in molecular biology than that provoked by the claim of
enzymatic RNA. At very least, would-be cloners would have had to question
the assumption that E. coli proteins are incapable of splicing eukaryotic RNA,
an assumption fundamental to the developing techniques of cloning and
sequencing.) Cech and his colleagues conclude that RNA can sometimes
function like an enzyme: RNAs can mediate reactions on themselves that are
typically performedby splicing enzymes (proteins)but partsof the RNAs are, of
course, changed in the process. Notice that this conclusion, and even the more
ambitious conclusion that RNAs can act as enzymes, can be accepted while
preserving the underlying biochemistry, for there is nothing in theoretical
biochemistry that declares that enzymatic (or quasi-enzymatic) functioning of
nucleic acids is impossible.
The last phase of the course of experimentation consists in lengthy tinkering
with the biological system so as to achieve a clean example, not something that
is 'very close' to an enzyme but something that meets all the conditions.'l

Here 'pure' means 'free from T. thermophiliaproteins'.


1( It is not clear to us, given the sequence of experiments that Cech and his colleagues actually
performed,whether the demonstration that RNA could fulfilall conditions on enzymes was an
explicit goal of the research. Much of the intervening work is concerned with elucidating
details of the ribozyme mechanism, and the decision to conduct the experiment in which they
showed pure enzymatic RNA may have been taken relatively late.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 475
Here, what Zaug and Cech accomplish is the separation of the active RNA from
its substrate and product. Against the background of accepted experimental
technique in molecular biology, and the biochemical underpinning of that
technique, their experiment leaves no option but to scrap the presupposition
that only proteins can be enzymes. The practice of molecular biology is then
brought into line by modifying the concept of enzyme-changing the
description that is standardly used to fix reference-by explicitly allowing a
new option in the normal form of problem solution, and by reconsidering the
merits of experimental techniques.
All this might be revolutionary. Now that enzymatic RNA has once been
identified, we may find it turning up everywhere. Indeed, another enzymatic
RNA, RNase P, was identifiedby Sidney Altman's group (Guerrier-Takadaet al
[1983]) after Cech's discovery of self-splicing by the Tetrahymenapre-fRNA.
What this means is that the everyday experimentation designed to uncover
and articulate normal form solutions takes advantage of the fact that a
constraint formerly imposed on the schema underlying those solutions has
been removed. Correlatively,the experiments now performedhave to be set up
to control not only for the possible enzymatic effects of proteins, but also for
potential effects of nucleic acids. In general the change that has already
occurred in the practice of molecular biology modifies the schema underlying
normal form solutions-the schema displayed in Section 2-by replacing a
prior constraint (the constraint that the enzymes identified at step 2 be
proteins) with a more liberal condition (the constraint that the enzymes be
either proteins or nucleic acids). A recent review article by Moore [1988]
shows that the practice of molecular biology has already absorbedthis change.
What remains indeterminate is the extent to which instantiationof the new
schema will be different from instances that would have fitted the old. We
suggest that the change will only live up to Westheimer's advertisement if
there is now a significant number of problem solutions that instantiate the
modifiedschema that would not have exemplifiedthe original. This, of course,
is just a way of capturing the commonsensical point that the discovery of
enzymatic RNA only proves revolutionary if cases in which nucleic acids act as
enzymes occur with some reasonable frequency."
But how significant is 'significant', how frequent constitutes a 'reasonable
frequency'? Better, at this point to drop the hard-and-fast categorization of
'revolution', and recognize that our judgments about changes in science ought
to allow for something like a continuum of cases, that differencesin degree are
sometimes large enough to prompt us to talk of a difference in kind, and that
1 Again, we note explicitly that the frequency with which nucleic acids act as enzymes may vary
at differentperiodsof the history of life. In particular, enzymatic RNA may have been prevalent
in the primeval soup but proteins may have taken over the role of enzymes for almost all
reactions over the next three billion years. Were that to be so, the discovery of enzymatic RNA
would cause profound changes for origins-of-life research while only altering molecular
investigations of reactions in contemporary organisms in very minor ways.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
476 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
talk of 'revolutions' is the product of the prompting. The magnitude of the
change in molecular biology stemming from the discovery of enzymatic RNA
will be directly proportionalto the frequency with which molecular biologists
now generate normal form solutions that instantiate the new schema but that
would not have fitted the old. Where, if anywhere, one wants to say that the
frequency has become big enough so that the discovery is genuinely
revolutionary seems to us a matter of little importance. It is enough that our
way of reconstructing the episode allows us to distinguish scenarios involving
changes great and small, and that it permits us to see how the magnitude of the
change is not yet determined.
We can now venture some general morals about scientific change. The first
point to notice is that, whether the transformation of molecular biology turns
out to be relatively large or relatively small, there is no indication that any
problematic methodological principles will be needed to resolve disputes. As
we have reconstructed the evidence and the reasoning from it, the past
practice of molecular biology was a background against which rather simple
arguments led to the modification of some components in the light of new
evidence. With the new practice in place, similar arguments are likely to be
used to construct particular problem-solutions from specific experiments, and
there is no reason to believe that judgments about the frequency of cases in
which nucleic acids act as enzymes will be any more controversial than the
initial judgment made by Zaug and Cech. As we look at the micro-structureof
a scientific change-whether it turns out to be major or minor-we see how
large effects can occur from the succession of epistemologically unproblematic
modificationsof practice. Indeed, we believe that it is illuminating to focus on a
case in which the eventual magnitude of the transformation is presently
unknown, for it brings home to us the point that the same kinds of reasons are
operative both in the small and in the large. As Laudan has argued [1984], we
tend to make the big shifts in science appear incomprehensible by juxtaposing
the endpoints and omitting the intervening steps. Our study reinforces the
argument, by showing that the primary shift may leave open the extent of the
total change, so that the reasons behind it are reasons that can be involved in
the minutiae of 'normal scientific development' or in the excitement of
'revolutionary change'.
Our second moral is that an adequate account of the state of a science at a
time must have some way of assessing the ways in which particularconcepts,
statements or assumptions are involved in the activity of scientific problem-
solving. The 'receivedview' of theories sees that a statement, 'All enzymes are
proteins', has been replaced with another statement, 'Many enzymes are
proteins, but at least a few enzymes are nucleic acids', but, fromthe perspective
of the 'received view', there's no way of evaluating the involvement of these
statements in the work of molecular biologists. (Note that neither statement
seems to be a promising candidate for a law; thus, from the perspective of the

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 477
'received view', one accidental generalization has given way to another.) By
emphasizing the structure of normal form problems and normal form problem
solutions, we have tried to show how statements function in the scientist's
vision of the world and so to express how the modification of a statement-
even of a statement that is not a law---can profoundly affect that vision.
Here we have deliberately used Kuhnian language, because we think that
there is something importantly right about Kuhn's much-derided suggestion
that 'revolutions are changes in world-view'. However, Kuhn's way of
developing the point seems to us to go in the wrong direction. Instead of
thinking that the change of view is linked to conceptual shifts, associated with
conceptual incommensurability, we take up ideas from Kuhn's analysis of
normalscience,and suppose that the change of view is constituted by the use of
different schemata in the solution of scientific problems. If Cech's work does
have the far-reaching implications prophesiedby Westheimer, then molecular
biologists will see many phenomena differently,and the change in view will be
revealed in their design and pursuit of experiments. But, we suggest, there will
be no Gestalt switches, no Kuhnian conceptual incommensurability, no shift
in methodological standards. For understanding the change, it is necessary to
take very seriously the idea of problem-solvingthat Kuhn so insightfully placed
at the center of normal science.

5 DERIVATIVE REVOLUTIONS AND REDUCTIONISM REVISITED

We want to conclude with a brief look at the impact of changes in one field on
other areas of science, and with some even briefercomments on the timeworn
topic of reductionism. As we noted at the end of Section 3, the research of Cech
and his colleagues has sparkednew interest in the topic of pre-bioticevolution.
This is a topic that might be assigned either to evolutionary biology or to
molecular biology, if the latter were conceived a bit more broadly than in our
treatment by enriching the set of questions to include functional as well as
structural/mechanistic questions. For present purposes, we will adopt what
we will take to be a purely conventional delineation of molecular biology by
opting for the narrower characterization of its problemsthat we offeredabove,
and, in consequence, we will suppose that issues of present function ('What
selection pressure, if any, maintains this molecular structure?') or of original
function ('Under what selection pressure, if any, did this molecular structure
evolve?') are the province of a subfield of evolutionary biology. Our first task is
to show how Cech's discovery might cause a derivative revolutionin this
subfield.
The current practice of evolutionary theory contains a number of state-
ments that jointly generate a major theoretical problem. Organisms evolved
from primitive self-replicating systems. If these self-replicating systems were
similar to contemporary primitive organisms, then they contained both

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
478 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
nucleic acids and proteins. Moreover,bothnucleicacidsandproteinsareessential
to the self-replication.Hence the problem 'How could self-replicating systems
have appeared in a primitive soup?' becomes 'How could both proteins and
nucleic acids have appeared in a primitive soup?'.
The last question has seemed so difficult to answer, given the findings of
typical origins-of-life experiments, that researchers have considered various
possible exotic precursors (protenoids, clays) and Creationists have gleefully
exploited the embarrassment to lobby for their own favorite hypothesis (which
also involves an exotic precursor).Cech's discovery promises a way of resisting
the reformulation of the last paragraph. The major theoretical problem of the
emergence of self-replicating systems can be tackled by showing how it is
possible to generate RNAs with sufficientenzymatic activity to direct their own
replication from hypothetical primitive conditions and subsequently showing
how descendants of such systems (modifiedthrough a succession of analyzable
chemical transformations) could generate proteins.
Once again, there is a change in normal form of a problem solution. The
form of solution previously accepted was to specify an environmental
condition for a primitive earth (subject to constraints imposed by geology,
astronomy, chemistry, and so forth) and to derive, using principles of physics
and chemistry, a descriptionof a subsequent state in which there occur nucleic
acids and proteins in association, so that these molecules can replicate
themselves; it is presupposedthat this state constitutes thefirst state in which a
self-replicatingsystem exists. The new form of solution envisaged replaces the
description of the products with a description of enzymatic RNAs that are
capable of self-replication (we set on one side the subsequent problem of
accounting for the emergence of proteins).
Here the criteria for revolution are relatively clear cut. Cech's work would
have revolutionary significance if you can solve the later problem and not the
former.Once again, we do not know at this stage whether or not the revolution
will occur. The outcome is related to but differentfromthe extent of the change
within molecular biology (conceived in our preferred narrow way). For if
RNAs are shown to be capable of only a very few enzymatic functions, then it is
highly unlikely that RNA could catalyze enough reactions to get the RNA
world going. On the other hand, the frequency of cases in which nucleic acids
serve as enzymes in the currentbiosphere is independent of the possibility of
discovering a solution that meets the new normal form. It does not matter how
many biological reactions are currently RNA-driven. What is significant is
whether the right reactions could once have been RNA-mediated.
The relationship between the change in molecular biology and the field of
biotic evolution might turn out to resemble one facet of that between early
molecular genetics and classical genetics. As noted in Kitcher [1984], the
discovery of the structure of DNA resolved a major question that had seemed
insoluble from the perspective of classical genetics-How do mutant alleles,

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 479
that cannot function normally to produce physiologically required products,
manage to function to replicate themselves? Understanding the structure of
DNA allowed for an account of mutation and replication that resolved the
mystery.
We close by switching our attention from diachronic to synchronic
relationships. The account of theory structure in molecular biology that we
have offered develops the idea, advanced in Kitcher [1984], that the
intertheoretic relationships that philosophers have often tried to describe in
terms of notions of reduction are best reconceived in terms of the embedding of
the problem-solving schemata of one field of science in those of another. So, for
example, molecular genetics furnishes an explanatoryextension of classical
genetics by opening the black box of the relationship between genotype and
phenotype. The normal form of a problem-solution in classical genetics takes
the association of allelic combinations with phenotypic traits for granted.
Molecular biology tries to replace the assertion of association with a derivation
of a sequence of reactions (see Kitcher [1984] section V, and, for more detail,
Kitcher [forthcoming]). Other parts of the classical problem solution survive
unmodified. There is, for example, no molecular replacement for the classical
understanding of meiotic segregation.
Anti-reductionists typically want to emphasize the important fact that there
are patterns revealed by the nonmolecular theory that cannot be captured in
molecular language. Thus, from the classical point of view, the essence of
meiosis is that it is a process of pairing and segregation that can, in principle,be
realizedin a motley of molecular mechanisms. Similarly,the goal of molecular
biology in charting the relationship between genotype and phenotype may not
succeed because the classical understanding of a developmental process may
involve properties that are not expressible in the language of molecular
biology. Geometricrelations among tissues that correspond to no molecularly
specifiable property may be critical to the development of some structures in
some organisms (Oster and Alberch [1982]).
We want to end by reconsidering this issue in the light of our current
understanding of molecular biology. Anti-reductionists suppose that certain
kinds of properties ('emergent' properties,or 'higher-level' properties)can not
be expressed in the language of molecular biology, and their complaint can be
formulated in ways that make it completely unmysterious. (There are no
vitalist spooks lurking in the background.) But, we should ask, what is this
language of molecular biology that is supposed to be inadequate? Is it the
language that molecular biologists actually use in devising their problem
solutions-the language used, for example, in giving a normal form account of
transcription?If so, then, despite the fact that no specification of some of the
most plausible candidates for emergent properties(meiotic division, geometri-
cal relations among tissues) has yet been given, it is not so obvious that it could
not be given. The anti-reductionist point is much stronger if one thinks of the

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
480 Sylvia Culpand Philip Kitcher
language of molecular biology as ultimately confined to describing the world
in terms of the situations, internal states and interrelations among individual
molecules-specifications of shell-filling and geometrical relationships at the
molecular level, possibly translated in terms of (hypothetical!) Schrodinger
state-functions. If thatis what the language of molecular biology is like, then it
does appear very likely that molecular biologists will not be able to specify all
the properties that the developmental biologist adduces in solving classical
developmental problems.
But there is no reason to limit molecular biology to so austere a language. If
reductionists were preparedto accept the limit, then we could even claim that
molecular biology, as currently practiced, is irreducibleto molecular biology.
Consider the normal form account of transcription. It is full of talk of 'loose
association', 'site recognition', and 'unwinding'. We do not believe that there
is any austerely specifiable property that will subsume all and only the
molecular structures covered by any one of these frequently used terms. Our
moral is that the language of molecular biology is opportunistic. It expands to
specify the properties that are needed for giving normal form explanations.
Thus, as developmentalists build a powerful case for saying that certain
propertiesare emergent, we should expect the language of molecular biology
to accommodate.
So who wins? Everybody.No sensible reductionist should ever have thought
of the language of molecular biology as frozen to the austere idiom-or if the
thought appeared, it was surely belied by practice. Moreover, it is only a brief
step to the acknowledgement that change in molecular biology involves
interactionwith classical fields of biology, the point, of course, on which all
sensible anti-reductionists have wanted to insist. Our perspective on theory
structure and theory change is intended to make plausible the idea that
molecular biology is directed at problems furnished by parts of non-molecular
biology, and that its problem-solutions integrate in interesting ways with the
problem-solutions developed autonomously by these other disciplines. The
final wrinkle is that the language of molecular biology itself can be expected to
develop through interaction with such autonomous problem-solutions. Once
the achievements of the various disciplines are exhibited and compared-as
we have tried to do in a preliminaryway here-it seems to us that light dawns
and heat dissipates.
Departmentof Immunology,
ResearchFoundationof ScrippsClinic,LaJolla
Departmentof Philosophy,
Universityof California,
San Diego

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Theory Structure/Change in Contemporary Molecular Biology 481

REFERENCES
BALZER, WOLFGANG ANDDAWE,C. M. [1986]: 'Structure and Comparison of Genetic
Theories [(1) Classical Genetics, and (2) The Reduction of Character-Factor
Genetics to Molecular Genetics]', BritishJournalforthe Philosophyof Science,37, pp.
55-69, 177-91.
BASS,B. L. ANDCECH, T. R. [1984]: 'SpecificInteraction between the Self-SplicingRNA
of Tetrahymenaand its Guanosine Substrate: Implications for Biological Catalysis
by RNA', Nature, 308, pp. 820-26.
BEATTY,JOHN [1980]: 'What's Wrong with the Received View of Evolutionary Theory?',
in P. Asquith and R. Giere (eds.):PSA 1980. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science
Association.
BROMBERGER, SYLVAIN [1963]: 'A Theory about the Theory of Theory and about the
Theory of Theories', in W. L. Reese (ed.): Philosophy of Science, The Delaware
Seminar.New York: Wiley.
CECH,T. R. [1986]: 'A Model for the RNA-CatalyzedReplication of RNA', Proceedingsof
the NationalAcademyof Sciences(USA), 83, pp. 4360-63.
CECH,T. R., ZAUG,A. J. ANDGRABOWSKI, P. J. [1981]: 'In Vitro Splicing of the Ribosomal
RNA Precursor of Tetrahymena:Involvement of a Guanosine Nucleotide in the
Excision of the Intervening Sequence', Cell, 27, pp. 487-96.
DARNELL,J., LODISH, H. ANDBALTIMORE, D. [1986]: MolecularCell Biology. New York:
Scientific American Books.
GIERE,RONALD [1979]: UnderstandingScientificReasoning.New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston.
GILBERT,WALTER [1986]: 'The RNA World', Nature, 319, pp. 618.
GUERRIER-TAKADA, K., MARSH,T., PACE,N. ANDALTMAN,S. [1983]: 'The
C., GARDINER,
RNA Moiety of Ribonuclease P is the CatalyticSubunit of the Enzyme', Cell,35, pp.
849-57.
HACKING,IAN[1983]: Representingand Intervening.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity
Press.
INOUE, F. X. ANDCECH,
T., SULLIVAN, T. R. [1985]: 'IntermolecularExon Ligation of the
rRNA Precursor of Tetrahymena: Oligonucleotides can Function as 5' Exons', Cell,
43, pp. 431-7.
JOYCE,G. F., SCHWARTZ,
A. W., MILLER,S. L. ANDORGEL,L. E. [1987]: 'The Case for an
Ancestral Genetic System Involving Simple Analogues of the Nucleotides',
Proceedingsof the National Academyof Sciences(USA), 84, pp. 4398-402.
PHILIP[1981]: 'Explanatory Unification', Philosophyof Science,48, 507-31.
KITCHER,
PHILIP[1982]: AbusingScience:TheCaseAgainstCreationism.CambridgeMA:
KITCHER,
MITPress.
KITCHER,PHILIP [1983]: The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge. New York: Oxford
University Press.
KITCHER,PHILIP [1984]: '1953 And All That. A Tale of Two Sciences', Philosophical
Review, 93, pp. 335-73.
KITCHER,PHILIP [1985a]: 'Darwin's Achievement', in N. Rescher (ed.): Reason and
Rationalityin Natural Science.Washington DC:University Press of America.
KITCHER,PHILIP[1985b]: Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiologyand the Quest for Human
Nature. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
482 Sylvia Culp and Philip Kitcher

KITCHER, PHILIP[forthcoming]: 'Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of


the World', to appear in Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon (eds.): Scientific
Explanation.Minneapolis:University of Minnesota Press (Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, Volume XIII).
KRUGER, K., GRABOWSKI, P. J., ZAUG,A. J.,SANDS, J.,GOTTSCHLING,D. E. ANDCECH,T. R.
[1982]: 'Self-SplicingRNA: Auto-excision and Autocyclization of the Ribosomal
RNA Intervening Sequence of Tetrahymena',Cell, 31, pp. 147-57.
KUHN, THOMAS[1970]: The Structureof ScientificRevolutions.Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
LAUDAN, LAURENS [1984]: Scienceand Values.Berkeley:University of CaliforniaPress.
LIE,REIDAR [unpublished]:TheoryChangein Cardiology,Ph.D. Dissertation,Universityof
Minnesota, 1987.
LLOYD,ELISABETH [forthcoming]: TheStructureand Confirmationof EvolutionaryTheory.
Westport CT:Greenwood Press.
LLOYD, ELISABETH [1984]: 'A Semantic Approach to the Structure of Population
Genetics', Philosophyof Science, 51, pp. 242-64.
MOORE, P. B. [1988]: 'The Ribosome Returns', Nature, 331, pp. 223-7.
OSTER,GEORGEANDALBERCH, PERE[1982]: 'Evolution and Bifurcationof Developmental
Programs', Evolution,36, pp. 444-59.
RAILTON, PETER[1981]: 'Probability, Explanation, and Information', Synthese, 48,
233-56.
SCHAFFNER, KENNETH [forthcoming]: TheStructureof BiomedicalScience.
SHAPERE, DUDLEY[1974]: 'Scientific Theories and their Domains', in Frederick Suppe
(ed.) TheStructureof ScientificTheories,Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
SULLIVAN, F. X. AND CECH, T. R. [1985]: 'Reversibilityof Cyclizationof the Tetrahymena
rRNA Intervening Sequence: Implication for the Mechanism of Splice Site Choice',
Cell,42, pp. 639-48.
SUPPE, FREDERICK
[1972]: 'What's Wrong with the Received View on the Structure of
Scientific Theories?', Philosophy of Science, 39, pp. 1-19.
VAN FRAASSEN,BAS [1980]: TheScientificImage.Oxford:OxfordUniversity Press.
WATSON,J. D., HOPKINS,N.H., ROBERTS, J. W., STEITZ,J. A. ANDWEINER,A. M. [1987]:
Molecular Biology of the Gene (fourth edition). Menlo Park: Benjamin Cummins.
WEINER,A. M. ANDMAIZELS,N. [1987]: 'tRNA-like Structures Tag the 3' Ends of
Genomic RNA Molecules for Replication: Implications for the Origin of Protein
Synthesis', Proceedingsof the NationalAcademyof Sciences(USA), 84, pp. 7383-8 7.
WESTHEIMER, F. H. [1986]: 'PolyribonucleicAcids as Enzymes',Nature,319, pp. 534-6.
WILLIAMS, MARY [1970]: 'Deducing the Consequences of Evolution', Journal of
TheoreticalBiology, 29, pp. 343-85.
WILLIAMS, MARY [1973]: 'FalsifiablePredictions of EvolutionaryTheory', Philosophyof
Science,40, pp. 518-37.
ZAUG,A. J., GRABOWSKI, P. J. AND CECH, T. R. [1983]: 'Autocatalytic Cyclization of an
Excised Intervening Sequence RNA is a Cleavage-Ligation Reaction', Nature, 301,
pp. 578-83.
ZAUG,A. J., KENT, J. R. AND CECH, T. R. [1984]: 'A Labile Phosphodiester Bond at
the Ligation Junction in a Circular Intervening Sequence RNA', Science, 224,
pp. 574-8.
ZAUG, A. J., KENT, J. R. AND CECH, T. R. [198 5]: 'Reactionsof the Intervening Sequence of

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TheoryStructure/Changein ContemporaryMolecularBiology 483
the TetrahymenaRibosomal Ribonucleic Acid Precursor: pH Dependence of
Cyclization and Site-SpecificHydrolysis', Biochemistry,24, pp. 6211-18.
ZAUG, A. J. AND CECH, T. R. [1986]: 'The Intervening Sequence RNA of Tetrahymena
is an
Enzyme', Science,231, pp. 470-5.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.251 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 04:52:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like