You are on page 1of 5

Historical Explanation: Re-enactment and Practical Inference by Rex Martin

Review by: William Dray


The American Historical Review, Vol. 83, No. 5 (Dec., 1978), pp. 1218-1221
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the American Historical Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1854693 .
Accessed: 11/04/2014 09:28

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Oxford University Press and American Historical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The American Historical Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 163.13.35.40 on Fri, 11 Apr 2014 09:28:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviewsof Books

GENERAL

REX MARTIN. Historical Explanation: Re-enactmentand Mandelbaum, TheAnatomy of HistoricalKnowledge


Practical Ithaca, N.Y.: CornellUniversity [1977].) Still,thequestionofhow past actionsare
Inference.
Press. 1977. Pp. 267. $I5.00. to be explained,if somewhatlimited,is one that
historianswithan interestin theconceptualfoun-
Currenttheorizingabout historyby analyticphi- dations of their disciplinecan hardly affordto
losophersstilltendsto take as its pointofdepar- ignore.This is especiallytrueof thosehistorians
ture two enormouslyinfluential pieces of writing who, Martin insists, practically"glow" at the
thatappearedin the 1940s:C. G. Hempel'sincisive mentionofCollingwood'sname.
article,"The Functionof General Laws in His- What especiallyconcernsMartinis explanation
tory" (Journal ofPhilosophy, 39 [1942]: 35-48),and ofactionsby reference to the motivations, beliefs,
R. G. Collingwood'sflawedbut eloquentclassic, intentions,purposes, or, to use Collingwoodian
The Idea of History(I94). The mutual con- language, to the "thoughts" of those who per-
frontationof the positionsparadigmaticallyex- formedthem.His centralquestionis thenatureof
pressedin thesetwo workshas generateda lively, the "tie" thatmustbind such explanatorydata to
interlocking, and increasingly technicalliterature. thedeeds theyare said to explain.The Hempelian
One of the meritsof Rex Martin'sbook is thatit answerto thisquestionis well known.According
providesguidancethroughthemaze ofphilosophi- to Hempel, the natureof the "tie" is determined
cal argumentand counterargument whileseeking by the logical formof explanationas such. It con-
in somemeasureto providea "via media" between sists of universalempiricallaws which show the
theso-calledpositivist and idealistviewsofhistory. action performedto have occurred necessarily,
In spiteofdisclaimers,theworkdoes oftenseems given antecedentconditionswhich may include
to take forgranted-a bit disconcertingly-that the the agent's"thoughts."Hempel concededthat,in
conceptofhistoricalexplanationis and oughtto be actual practice,all thathistoriansmay be able to
the centralproblemof historicaltheoryand that do is showtheprobabilityofwhatwas done,in the
thisproblemis primarilyone ofdetermining how lightofgeneralizations thatare less thanuniversal.
individualhuman actions should be understood. But he regardedsuchan alternative as explanatory
This somewhatmyopicstandpointis surelywhat only to the extentto which it approximatedthe
leads the authorto observethat,althoughhistory more rigorous ideal-that is, the probability
is "the least developedof the social sciences" (a would have to be high.
judgmentforwhichno reasonsare given),in the Three decades of philosophicalbombardment
hands of analyticphilosophersthe philosophyof have producedmanyingeniousvariationson this
historyhas, surprisingly, become "more sophisti- basic position.Most of them endeavorto retain
cated" than the philosophyof otherbranchesof some importantresidueoftheclaim thattheforce
social inquiry(p. I5). This alleged sophistication of an explanationderivesultimatelyfromits con-
has largelybeen borrowedfromtheoriesof ex- nectiveempiricallaws whiletryingto do justice to
planationin generalor fromwhat,in the analytic apparentlyquite respectable historicalpractice
tradition,has sometimesbeen called "action the- that suggeststhe contrary.Martinconsidersand
ory"; and it has oftencoexistedwitha ratherlow rejectsa numberofthesevariations,includingper-
level of interestin the broad rangeof historians' haps the most ingeniousof all-Morton White's
preoccupations.(For a recentworkin this tradi- contentionin Foundations of HistoricalKnowledge
tionabout whichthiscan notbe said, see Maurice (1965), that, althoughan explanationcan be no

1 218

This content downloaded from 163.13.35.40 on Fri, 11 Apr 2014 09:28:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
General I219

betterthan the laws which it statesor assumes, the agentbelongedto a class ofagentswho in fact
historiansmayjustifiablyofferexplanationsin ig- act in accordance withthat principleso that the
norance of the latter provided they have good explanationwould be grounded,afterall, in em-
reasons forthinkingthat appropriatelaws exist. piricalgeneralization.
Martin finds this "existentialregularism" un- Most ofMartin'sbookis devotedto an examina-
satisfactoryon what would appear to be the em- tion of a quite different ofColling-
interpretation
inentlyreasonable groundthatone cannot know wood's re-enactment doctrine-one proposedfirst
that a law "exists" withoutbeing able to estab- by Alan Donagan (The LaterPhilosophy of R. G.
lish it. And he concludes,in the end, that the Collingwood [i 962] ) and developedfurtherby G. H.
wholeenterprise ofsearchingfortheforceofaction von Wright(Explanation and Understanding
[I971)
explanationsin empiricallaws involvesa concep- and a numberof other authors. Referredto in
tual errorof a fundamentalkind. recentanalyticphilosophyofactionas "the logical
A better guide to the nature of such ex- connectionargument,"this conceptionof the na-
planations,he suggests,is to be foundin Colling- tureofactionexplanationis too complicatedto be
wood's controversialnotionthat historiansmust set forthin its fullyelaboratedformin a review.
re-enactthe thoughtof the agents whose actions (For an example,see F. Stoutland,"The Logical
theywishto understand;and he devotestheearly Connection Argument,"in N. Rescher, editor,
chaptersof his book to an "archeologicalrecon- Studiesin theTheoryofKnowledge[1970], pp. I1 7-29.)
struction"of this claim. He takes issue with the But the main principleon which it turnsis not
view popularized by W. H. Walsh that it was hard to state: the explanatoryrelation,or "tie,"
Collingwood'sintentionin thisconnectionto pro- betweenwhatan agent"thinks"and whathe does
mote an intuitivetheoryof historicalunderstand- takes the formneitherof an empiricalregularity
ing. He denies,further, thatthe re-enactment re- norofa normative principle,butofa logicaltruism
quirementis to be interpreted primarily as a point or analyticjudgment;theagent'sactingas he does
ofhistoricalmethodology:it is a claim,he argues, thus is logically entailed by his thinkingthe
about what the understanding of actionsconsists "thoughts" attributedto him. To illustratethis
of,not about how such understanding, otherwise claim as simplyas possible: ifa personintendsto
defined,is to be achieved. achievea certaingoal and believesthata certain
The problemis how one is to contrastthe re- actionis requiredfortheachievement ofthatgoal,
enactmentdoctrine,so interpreted, withan analy- thenit is a matterof sheerlogic,a matterof the
sis likethat ofHempel. Collingwoodflatlydenied verymeaningof the termsemployed(so it is ar-
that laws play any necessaryrole in the under- gued), thathe perform the actionin question.For
standingof actions via re-enactment-inspiteof if he does not, that in itselfwould show that he
allowing,as is not always noticedby those who lacks (or has lost) eithertheintention or thebelief;
commenton his views,that historiansmay often to say otherwiseinvolvesa contradiction.
be able to formulategeneralizationswhich hold Actually,this schema needs some refinement
good at least forcertaintimesand places. But he beforeit can be said to be entirelytrue.It would
neverworkedout the logical implicationsof his have to be understood,forexample,thatthe per-
denial; he nevermade clear thenatureofthe"tie" son concernedwas not preventedfromacting in
that, in the absence of laws, makes certain accordance with his alleged intentionand belief,
"thoughts"explanatoryand others not. Martin thathe possessedthe abilityso to act,thathe was
notesan attemptsome years ago by the present aware ofthe natureofwhat he was doing,and so
reviewerto workout an essentiallyCollingwood- on. But thosewho adopt the approachofthe logi-
ian position in this connection-one in which cal connectionargumentcontendthatsuchrefine-
"thoughts"were said to be explanatorywhenre- mentscould be fullystatedwithoutthereintroduc-
lated to actionsby rationalprinciplesratherthan tionofeitherconnectiveempiricallaws or rational
by empiricallaws. This quasi-normative account principlesofaction.Givenan analysisofthissort,
(Laws and Explanations in History[I957]) he com- Donagan has interpreted Collingwoodas implying
mendsforseeingactionexplanations,notas weak (he admittedlydoes not quite say this) thathisto-
law subsumptions,but as attemptsat an under- rians explain actions by formulating hypotheses
standingofan entirelydifferent kind.But he finds regardingagents'"thoughts"fromwhichtheycan
it ultimatelyunsatisfactory,
chieflybecausewhata deduce, logically,what the agents in question
principleof action would explain is not why an would do. These hypothesesare thenaccepted as
actionwas actuallyperformed butonlywhyitwas true and explanatoryto the extentto which the
rationalforthe agentto perform it. Hempel simi- agentsact accordingly.
larly argued that such a principlewould be ex- Martinoffers two sortsofobjectionsagainstthe
planatoryonlyifreinforced bytheassumptionthat claim that the "tie" in action explanationsis

This content downloaded from 163.13.35.40 on Fri, 11 Apr 2014 09:28:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1220 ReviewsofBooks

analytic.On the one hand he argues-although planatorypremisesare true. But Martin insists
rather too casually in the opinion of this re- thatthisis not in itselfenough.Accordingto him,
viewer-that, for the vast majorityof such ex- there is in addition the requirementthat an in-
planations (he seems willingto make exceptions stantiationof the schema must be shown to be
forunusuallyfirmintentions,like the resolveof empirically"plausible"; and this plausibility,he
Brutus to protectthe Roman Republic "at all argues,restoresa vestigeoftheoriginalHempelian
costs") it does notfollQwstrictly
fromthemeaning position.Hence,he can claimto havefounda "via
of the conceptsemployedthatthe agent acted in media." For to show empiricalplausibilityin-
theway he did. Martindoes not,however,entirely volvesshowingthat the "thoughts"in question
reject the thesis that the connectioninvolvedis were at least "causally relevant" to the action
conceptualin nature.For whileit is not,according performed; and thiscannotbe done withoutrefer-
to him,impossiblein logicthata personshouldfail ence to at least weak empiricalgeneralizations.
to act in accordancewithhis own intentionsand Martinemploysconsiderabletechnicalapparatus
beliefs(he speculatesin this connectionon what to elucidatethe notionofcausal relevance;butthe
might conceivablyhave happened when Booth essential point seems to be that such relevance
pointedhis gun at Lincoln), it is nevertheless in cannotbe establishedwithoutshowingthatpeople
some sense an a prioritruth,and notjust a factual reallydo (occasionally)act in the way envisaged
discovery,that he will act forthe most part in forthe reason cited.
accordancewiththem. Martin'sown plausibilityseemsto evaporateat
Martin is not easy to followwhen he triesto this point,along with his "Collingwoodianism."
explain in exactlywhat sense the connectionin For the suggestedcriterionis surelyat once too
such cases shouldbe considereda priori.He sees strongand too weak. It is too strongbecause it
some likenessbetweenthebasic schemaforaction excludesthepossibilitythata historianmightcor-
explanationsand the a prioriprinciplethatevery rectlyjudge an agent to have acted in a certain
eventhas a cause, the latteroftenbeingsaid to be way fora certainreason forthe veryfirsttime,
neitherlogicallynecessary(it does notjust follow whichit is difficult
to believehe could notdo. And
fromthemeaningoftheword"cause") norempir- it is too weak because, if an action explanation
ically refutable(when we fail to findcauses we required the support of other cases at all, some
generallyblame ourselves,not the phenomena). othercases wouldsurelybe insufficient. We should
But he is not preparedto call it a "synthetic"a want,withHempel,enoughofthemto renderthe
prioriprinciplein the sense in which Kant, for action in question probable, a requirementthat
example,regardedthe causal principleas one; for Martingoes out ofhis way to repudiate.Further-
Martin cannotsee thatit is a principleofhuman more,in theverystatementofhis additionalcrite-
reason as such: it mightlack validityforsome rion,Martin seems to fallinto anotherdifficulty.
societies,he thinks,althoughthesewould have to Whatwe are toldis that,forplausibleexplanation,
be different fromour own in waysthatare almost we need to knowthatothershave in factacted for
unimaginable.He takesrefugefinallyin Wittgen- the reasonsattributedin the presentcase. But if
stein'snotionofa "language-game,"holdingthat we can knowthatin othercases people haveacted
somethingliketheindicatedschemais constitutive for those reasons (presumably not because of our
ofour wholeenterpriseofinterpreting our experi- knowledge of still other cases), why cannot we
ence in termsof human agency. Historianswill know this independently in the case under exami-
perhapsbe contentto let philosophersfightit out nation?
as to whetherthe "tie" in actionexplanationsis a Whatis missingis anyadequate accountofwhat
priori in a Kantian or a Wittgensteinian sense. it is to act fora reasonat all, ratherthansimnply to
The importantthingis thatthe connectionis al- have one and to act in accordance with it. It is
leged to be, in some importantsense,conceptual discouragingthat,afterall thephilosophicalactiv-
ratherthan empiricalor normative.For if true, ity (and all the "sophistication")of recentyears,
thismakestheexplanationofpast humanactions, thisnotion,so crucialforany attemptto providea
as Collingwoodhimselfhad insisted,a verydiffer- rationale forhistoryas a humanisticdiscipline,
ent sortofthingfromthe scientific explanationof and perhapsforthe foundations ofthesocial stud-
events-a logicallydifferent sortof thing. ies generally,remainsso murky.This complaint
Martin's otherobjectionto the analyticinter- mustnot,however,be allowedto obscurethevery
pretationis also somewhatelusive. A candidate real contribution made by Martin's book both to
action explanationmust not only conformto the theongoingdiscussionofhistoricalinquiryin gen-
generalschemasketchedabove but also, ofcourse, eral and to the interpretation of Collingwoodin
cite "thoughts"whichare attributedto the agent particular.His argumentis richlytextured,rang-
on adequate empiricalgrounds-thatis,historians ing over manyimportantissues thatcould not be
must have reasons for thinkingthat their ex- consideredhere: forexample,the relativity of ex-

This content downloaded from 163.13.35.40 on Fri, 11 Apr 2014 09:28:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
General 1221

planation to description,the difference between secutively,but which also overlapor divergede-


explainingand understanding, the Collingwood- pendingon thesocial classes involved:i.) theopen
ian notion of historyas "the science of human lineage or traditionalfamily(sixteenthcentury);
nature," and Collingwood's "transhistorical" 2.) therestricted patriarchalnuclearfamily(end of
commitments. the sixteenthand firsttwo-thirdsof the seven-
In discussingtheseand otherquestions,Martin teenthcentury),whichI would call therepressive
exploits,withgenerousacknowledgment, some of patriarchalfamily,typeI; 3.) the closed domesti-
the best workdone in the field,notablythatofA. cated nuclear family(late seventeenth and eigh-
C. Danto, whose Analytical Philosophyof History teenthcenturies),whichI would call the affective-
(I965) is perhapsthe mostoriginalof the current individualist-permissive family,typeI; 4.) theVic-
spate ofmonographson historyby analyticphilos- torian family,or repressivepatriarchalfamily,
ophers,and thatofW. H. Walsh,whoseinfluence typeII; 5.) thefamilytypicalofthemid-twentieth
has been continuousand salutaryever since the century,or the affective-individualist-permissive
appearanceofhis Introduction toPhilosophyofHistory family,typeII. Types fourand fiveare character-
(I95I), stillthebestentreeto thesubject.Martinis ized by a relativereturnto typestwo and three.
not always easy to read: his style ratherawk- Five different types in roughlyfivecenturies
wardlycombinesthe technicaland the conversa- amountto a lotofchange! Social phenomenasuch
tional. But he will be read-and, doubtless,an- as family,love,and death are located,I believe,at
swered. a levelverynear the biologicalbasis ofour being,
WILLIAM DRAY at the boundarybetweenthe biological and the
University
ofOttawa mental. Only recentlyhave we begun to under-
standthattheychange,butchangeveryslowly,so
slowlythat theirtransformations have until now
LAWRENCE STONE. TheFamily,Sex andMarriagein eluded theperceptionofcontemporaries. The very
England,I500-I800. New York:Harperand Row. factthat thesephenomenaremainat the levelof
1977. Pp. xxxi,8oo. $30.00. the unconsciousadd to theirinertia.That is why
one is surprisedbytheabundanceofmodelsin this
In spiteofits monumentaldimensions,thisbeau- book. This atomizationby Stoneofa massivephe-
tifulbookby LawrenceStone is delightful to read, nomenoncan be explained,I think,by two meth-
thanksto the flavorof the exampleshe citesand odologicalconsiderations.
theslyironyofhis commentary (an ironythathas First,Stonesituatesattitudestowardthefamily,
also informed his excellentchoiceofillustrations). love,and sex in thesame highermentalcategories
The logic of compositionand the clarityof his as religious doctrines, for example, Puritanism,
writingare two qualities which have become so evangelism,or deism,and politicaland philosoph-
rare in historicalliteraturethatone cannotfailto ical ideas,that is to say, the more consciousand
applaud them! On the one hand, the book offers therefore the moremalleableand mobile aspectsof
access to primarysources: a rich anthologyof our total behavior.I think,on the contrary,that
animatedtextsand biographicaldata, whichthe family,love,and sex belongto anotherlevel,where
reader can exploit as he pleases. On the other thepsychologicalcan hardlybe separatedfromthe
hand, Stone offersa personalinterpretation ofthe biological.Betweenthese two levels,interactions
historyofthe familyovera periodofthreeor four are rare,and each evolvesat an independentpace
hundredyears,fromthe fifteenth to the twentieth withoutmuch interference fromthe other.Stone
centuries.The centralpart ofthe argumentbears readilyacknowledgesthisautonomybut does not
on the periodfromthe beginningof the sixteenth drawany radical conclusionsforhis chronological
centuryto the beginningof the nineteenth. scheme. Thus he findsas many changes in the
ClearlyStone preferred to limithimselfto Eng- familyas in the higherreligiousculture.
land withonlya fewverybriefincursionsintoNew Second,Stone has been influencedby,or rather
England,and, alas, equally few,amongthe more against,the social sciencesand theirinnumerable
"backward" peoples of ContinentalEurope. Nev- theorieson the family.In general,these always
ertheless,in spiteofa determinedbeliefin British tend to oppose a traditionalfamilyto a modern
particularism,Stone's study is less "provincial" family,whileinvokingvariousexplanationsforthe
than he intended;it appliesto thewholeofnorth- contrast.Stone has rejected,and I thinkrightly,
westernEurope, whose deeper cultural unityis thisdualistsimplification whichdoes nottakeinto
played out against a backgroundof variouslan- accountthe diversity of social reality.In reaction,
guages,politicalsystems,religiousfaiths,and na- however,he has become involvedin pulverizing
tionalstyles. the sociologicalmodelsand exaggeratingthe fac-
The periodizationemployedby Stonecomprises torsofdiversity, overbothtimeand space, so that
five main family types, which appear con- he obliterates a fundamentaldistinction,one

This content downloaded from 163.13.35.40 on Fri, 11 Apr 2014 09:28:30 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like