You are on page 1of 12

3

WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL
LAW FOR?
Martti Koskenniemi

SUMMARY

The objectives of international law appear differently depending on one's standpoint.


International law certainly seeks to realize the political values, interests, and preferences
of various international actors. But it also appears as a standard of criticism and means.of
controlling those in powerful positions. Instrumentalism and formalism connote two
opposite sensibilities of what it means to be an international lawye~ and two cultures of
professional practice, the stereotypes of \the advisor' to a powerful actor with many
policy-alternatives and \the judge' scrutinizing the legality of a particular international
behaviour. Beyond pointing to the oscillation between instrumentalism and formalism
as styles of legal thought and practice, howeve~ the question \what is international law
for?' also invokes popular aspirations about peace, justice, and human rights, and thus
acts as a platform for an international political community. Whatever its shortcomings,
international law also exists as a promise of justice, and thus as encouragement for
political transformation.

I. THE PARADOX OF OBJECTIVES

Attempting to answer the question in the tide one meets with a familiar paradox. On
the one hand, it seems indisputable that international law 'has a general function to
fulfil, namely to safeguard international peace, security and justice in relations
between states' (Tomuschat, 1999, p 23). Or as Article 1 of the UN Charter puts it, the
organization has the purpose to 'be a centre for harmonizing the actions of nations in
the attainment of ... common ends' such as international peace and security, friendly
relations among nations, and international cooperation. Such objectives seem self-
evident and have never been seriously challenged. On the other hand, it is hard to see
how or why they could be challenged-or indeed why one should be enthusiastic
90 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 91

about. them-because they exist at such high level of abstraction as to fail to indicate international society is free to decide on its own ends, and to that extent, they are all
concrete preferences for action. What do 'peace', 'security', or 'justice' really mean? As equal. The law that governs them is not natural but artificial, created by the sovereigns
soon as such words are defined more closely, disagreement emerges. To say that through the processes that are acceptable because neutral (cf, eg, Nardin, 1983). To say
international law aims at peace between States is perhaps already to have narrowed that international law is for 'peace', 'security', and 'justice' is to say that it is for peace,
down its scope unacceptably. Surely it must also seek to advance 'human rights as well security, and justice as agreed and understood between the members of the system. 2
as the rule of law domestically inside States for the benefit of human beings ... ' What this means for international legal argument can be gleaned, for instance, from
(Tomuschat, 1999, p 23). But what if advancing human rights would call for the the opinion of the International Court of Justice in th~951). Here
destruction of an unjust peace?
the Court was called upon to examine the admissibility of reservations to the 1948
In the end, very little seems to depend on any general response to the question Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide. The Court
'what is international law for?' The real problem seems always to be less about first outlined what seemed a natural consequence of the principles of neutrality and
whether international law should aim for 'peace', 'security', or 'human rights' than sovereignty, namely that no reservation should be effective against a State that has not
about how to resolve interpretative controversies over or conflicts between such agreed to it. To stay with this understanding, however, might have undermined the
notions that emerge when defending or attacking particular policies. There is no Convention by creating a system in which some reservations were in force in regard to
disagreement about the objective of peace in the Middle East between Israel and the some States (namely those accepting them) but not against others, while each non-
Palestinian people. But if asked what 'peace' might mean for them, the protagonists accepting State would be free to regard the reservation-making State as not a party to
would immediately give mutually exclusive answers. Nor is the 'Asian values' debate the Convention at all. This would have gone against the universal nature of the
about being 'for' or 'against' human rights but about what might such rights be and Convention. Thus, the Court continued, a State having made a reservation that has
how they should be translated into social practices in the relevant societies. To enquire been objected to by some of the parties, may still be held a party to the Convention if
about the objectives of international law is to study the political preferences of int~r­ the reservation is compatible with the 'object and purpose' of the Convention. At this
national actors-what it is that they wish to attain by international law. And because point, then, the Court moved to think of the law expressly in terms of its objectives.
those preferences differ, the answer to the question in the title can only either remain However, there were no objectives to the Convention that were independent from the
controversial or be formulated in such broad terms as to contain the controversy objectives of the parties to the Convention. Thus, it was up to each party to make the
within itself-in which case it is hard to see how it could be used to resolve it. determination 'individually and from its own standpoint'.3
lt would therefore be wrong to think of the paradox of objectives as a technical Such an argument defines the objectives of international law in terms of the objec-
problem that could be disposed of by reflecting more closely on the meaning of words tives of the (sovereign) members of the international society-in this case the society
such as 'peace', 'security', or 'justice' or by carrying out more sophisticated social or formed by the parties to the Genocide Convention-bringing to the fore two types of
economic analyses about the way the international world is. Such notions provide an problems: what will happen in cases where States disagree about the objectives? And
acceptable response to the question 'what is international law for?' precisely because why would only State objectives count?
of their ability to gloss over existing disagreement about political choices and dis-
tributional priorities. If they did not work in this way, and instead permanently
preferred some choices over other choices, they would no longer be able to do the
service we expect of them. In accordance with the founding myth of the system, the II. CONVERGING INTERESTS?
Peace of Westphalia in 1648 lay the basis for an agnostic, procedural international law
whose merit consisted in its refraining from imposing any external normative ideal on If no antecedent order establishes a firm priority between what States want, then any
the international society. The objectives of that society would now arise from itself: <;:ontroversy either will have to remain open or we shall have to assume that the
there were no religious or other transcendental notions of the good that international procedure in which the disagreement is revealed will somehow be able to dispose of it
law should realize. If there is an 'international community', it is not a teleological but
a practical association, a system not designed to realize ultimate ends but to co-
2 Henkin writes that instead of 'human values', the system is centred upon 'State values' (Henkin, 1989,
ordinate practical action to further the objectives of existing communities.} Sovereign
p 109). This polemical contrast undermines the degree to which States-including principles of sovereignty
equality builds on this: because ¢.ere are no natural ends, every member of the and non-interference-find their moral justification in late eighteenth century liberal individualism and the
ideal of national self-rule: 'State values' persist because they channel 'human values' within a political
community. See also Paulus, 2001, pp 69-97.
} This is why it is so easy to discuss it in terms of the ethics of Immanuel Kant, an ethics of universalizable 3 Reservations to the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Advisory
principles of right action rather than as instrumental guidelines for attaining the Good. Cf, eg, O'Neill, 2000. Opinion, IC! Reports 1951, p 15 at p 26.
92 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 93

to the satisfaction of all. The latter suggestion embodies the idea of the (harmony of jurisprudential techniques that often emerge into each other. Even the hardest
interests', the presence of an underlying convergence between apparently conflicting 'realism' reveals itself as a moral position (for example by highlighting the priority of
State interests. Under this view, any actual dispute would always be only superficial. the national interest) inasmuch as, 'philosophically speaking, realism is unthinkable
At a deeper level, State interests would coalesce and the objective of international law without the background of a prior idealistic position deeply committed to the univer-
would then be to lead from the former level to the latter. 4 salism of the Enlightenment and democratic political theory' (Guzzini, 1998, p 16).
It has been difficult to defend this view against realist criticisms. Why would har- On the other hand, any serious idealism is able to point to aspects of international
mony, instead of conflict, be the true nature of international politics? What evidence reality that support it, and needs such reference in order to seem professionally
is there that, rightly understood, the interests of States are compatible? Might the credible. Much of the controversy is about political preference, including the question
harmony not rather seem a form of wishful thinking that prevents people from clearly of what element of a many-faceted 'reality' should be chosen as the starting point of
seeing where their interests lie, and' acting accordingly? Hans Morgenthau, one of the one's analysis. Disciplinary progress has occurred by recurrent cycles oflawyers reject-
fathers of realist thought, attacked the inter-war legalism precisely for having made ing the previous generation as either 'utopian' (typically because excessively idealist)
this mistake. To believe in harmony under the League of Nations had left the world or as 'apologist' (typically because too impressed by sovereignty) and the correspond-
unprepared for Hitler's aggression in 1939 (Morgenthau, 1940, pp 261-284). EH Carr, ing critiques are as available today as they were a century ago. Care must be taken not
another powerful realist thinker, described the' harmony as an ideological smoke- to associate any legal position or doctrine permanently with either: idealism and
screen: (Biologically and economically, the doctrine of the harmony of interests was realism are best understood as forms of critique and channels for institutional reform
tenable only if you left out of account the interest of the weak who must be driven to in accordance with particular political agendas, disciplinary manoeuvring rather than
the wall, or called in the next world to redress the balance of the present' (Carr, 1946, qualities of an independent international world. 6
p 50). This is not to say that international law would not often be helpful for the limited
International lawyers have responded to such criticisms in two ways. Many have resolution of conflicts, resulting in temporary accommodations or even settlement.
accepted the marginal scope that power leaves for law and defined the legal regimes as This is, after all, why the S:ieneral Assembly posed its question to the ICJ in the
variables dependent on a central power (Schmitt, 1988; Grewe, 2001), or developed Reservations case in the first place. The Court was not asked to rule on the admissi-
purely instrumental accounts of the use of law in the defence of particular interests 'bility of particular reservations but to indicate how to go about implementing the
or preferences (McDougal, 1953, pp 137-259). Others have sought to articulate the Convention so as to minimize any distorting effect that controversial reservations
harmony under a more elaborate interdependence or globalization theory. 'Inter- 'might have.
national trade and commerce, international finance, international communication- , Many lawyers make a more ambitious defence of international law in terms of such
all are essential to the survival of States, and all require an international legal system practical effects. However neutral in regard to political principles, they would say, the
to provide a stable framework within which they may function' (Watts, 2000, p 7). structure is not devoid of normative direction. In their view, international law is
Institutional, procedural, and even linguistic theories have been used to argue that accompanied by a cunning logic that slowly socializes initially egoistic States into the
even the articulation of State interests is based on an internalization of legal notions law's internationalist spirit.? It is possible (though not necessary) to picture this ethic
such as 'sovereignty', 'treaty', and 'binding force' that delimit and define what may as the (inner morality of law' that accompanies any serious commitment to work in a
count as State interests or even State identity in the first place. 5 legal system. 8 An alternative but parallel approach would be to characterize the system
But the opposition between 'realism' and 'idealism' is only of limited heuristic in terms of a 'culture of civility' shared by its administrators and excluding certain
usefulness. The labels invoke contrasting political sensibilities and different types of secrecy, dishonesty, fraud, or manipulation. Such an explanation resonates
with international law's emergence in the late nineteenth century as an aspect of
4 This argument, always implicit in moral objectivism and theories of natural law, was made in a dramatic optimistic evolutionism among the liberal elites of Europe and North America. To
way by Hersch Lauterpacht, speaking at Chatham House in 1941, as bombs were falling over Coventry and his view international law as a process of education is to assume that, by entering into
family was being destroyed by the Nazis in Poland: 'The disunity of the modern world is a fact; but so, in a
truer sense, is its unity. Th[e] essential and manifold solidarity, coupled with the necessity of securing the rule
of law and the elimination of war, constitutes a harmony of interests which has a basis more real and tangible 6 This is one of the central arguments in Koskenniemi, 1989.
than the illusions of the sentimentalist or the hypocrisy of those satisfied with the existing status quo. The ? A defence of the view that law socializes States not by constraint but by 'compliance strategies [that] seek
ultimate harmony of interests which within the State finds expression in the elimination of private violence is to remove obstacles, clarify issues, and convince parties to change their behavior', as well as by 'various
not a misleading invention of nineteenth century liberalism' (Lauterpacht, 1975, p 26). manifestations of disapproval: exposure, shaming, and diffuse impacts on the reputations and international
5 This is the 'constructivist' explanation of international law's impact on States, much used today
relationships of a resisting party', is found in Chayes and Chayes, 1995, pp 109, 110.
in international relations studies. See, eg, Finnemore, 1996. For a discussion, see Brunnee and Toope, 2000, 8 The point about law necessarily containing certain 'aspirations of excellence' without which an order
pp 19-74; Kratochwil, 2000, pp 55-59.
would not be recognized as 'law' in the first place, is made, of course, in Fuller, 1969, especially pp 41-94.
94 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 95

the processes it provides, States come to define not only their objectives but perhaps This outlook was reaffirmed by the International Court of Justice in the Nuclear
even their identity by principles offered by international law (Koskenniemi, 2001a). Weapons Opinion in 1996. In response to the question about the lawfulness of the
threat or use of such weapons, the Court concluded that whatever the consequences,
"It could not exclude that such use would be lawful 'in an extreme circumstance of
'self-defence, when the very survival of a State would be at stake'. 10 State objectives and
III. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF STATEHOOD State survival remain the highest objectives of the system. Likewise, bodies such as the
European Court of Human Rights or the UN Human Rights Committee recognize
But the Westphalian myth leaves also unexplained why only State objectives count. that the treaties they administer function in a State-centred world: the margin of
At least since Immanuel Kant published his essay on the Perpetual Peace (1795), appreciation ~d the wide scope of derogations allow for national security reasons
philosophers, political theorists, and lawyers have routinely challenged the State- if 'necessary in a democratic society' to operate with notions of 'security' and
centrism of the international system, arguing that whatever instrumental value States 'democracy' that are embedded in a world of States. 11
may have for the coordination of affairs of particular communities, the 'ultimate' But the defence of international law's state-centredness is thoroughly practical.
members of those communities are individuals and that many other human groups 'Stated quite simply', James Brierly once wrote, 'what [international law] tries to do
apart from States ('peoples', 'nations', 'minorities', 'international organizations', is to define or delimit the respective spheres within which each of the ... States into
'corporations') also play important roles (Westlake, 1910, p 16). Globalization and the which the world is divided for political purposes is entitled to exercise its authority'
crisis of sovereignty have intensified the criticisms of the nature of international law (Brierly, 1944, p 3). Little of this justification has changed. A form and a process is
as State law from sociological, functional, and ethical standpoints. These critiques needed that channels interpretative conflicts into peaceful avenues. This is not to say
have often sought to project a material value or an idea of social justice outside that non-State values such as 'human rights', 'efficient economies', 'clean environ-
of statehood that they suggest should be enforced by international law (Koskenniemi, ment' , or 'justice' would be unworthy objectives of political action. Disagreement
1994, pp 22-29). about them provides the life and blood of political community. The defenders of
The universalizing vocabularies of human rights, liberalism, economic, and the State-system would only note that such values conflict and that 'States alone
ecological interdependence have no doubt complicated inter-sovereign law by the have provided the structures of authority needed to cope with the incessant claims
insertion of public law notions such as jus cogens and 'obligations owed to the inter- of competing social groups and to provide public justice essential to social order
national community as a whole' and by 'fragmenting' the international system and responsibility' (Schachter, 1997, p 22). States may be set aside, of course, by
through the fluid dynamics of globalization (cf Section VIII below). But it has not consent or revolution but there are dangers in such transformations, some of which
been replaced by something recognizeably non-Westphalian. None of the normative are well known, and something about those dangers results from their teleological
directions-human rights, economic or environmental values, religious ideals-has nature.
been able to establish itself in a dominating position. On the contrary, what these On the other hand, there is no doubt that international politics is far from
values may mean and how conflicts between them should be resolved is decided the Westphalian ideal. The informal networks and epistemic communities that
largely through 'Westphalian' institutions. This is not to say that new institutions influence international developments beyond the rigid forms of sovereign equality
would not enjoy a degree of autonomy from the policies of States. Human rights and are populated by experts from the developed West. It is hard to justify the attention
many economic and environmental regimes provide examples of such. The European given and the resources allocated to the 'fight against terrorism' in the aftermath
Union has developed into an autonomous system that functions largely outside of the attacks on New York and Washington in September 2001 in which nearly
the frame of international law. How far these other regimes are from that of the EU 3,000 people lost their lives, while simultaneously six million children under five years
can, however, be gleaned from the recent characterization of the WTO system by the old die annually of malnutrition by causes that could be prevented by existing
Appeals Body in the Alcoholic Beverages case (1996):

The WTO Agreement is a treaty-the international equivalent of a contract. It is self-evident


that in an exercise of their sovereignty,· and in pursuit of their own respective national 10 Legality of the Threat or Use ~f Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, leI Reports 1996, p 226, paras 96,
interests, the Members of the WTO have made a bargain. In exchange for the benefits they 101(E).
expect to derive as members of the WTO they have .agreed to exercise their sovereignty 11 Or in other words, these mechanisms are only subsidiary: 'The [European Convention on Human
according to commitments they have made in the WTO Agreement. 9 Rights] leaves to each contracting State ... the task of securing the rights and freedoms it enshrines',
Handysidev UK, Judgment of7 December 1976, Ser A, No 24, (1979) 1 EHRR 737, para 4S. As Susan Marks
points out, liberal reformers conceive of 'democratization' in terms of reform of domestic (and not inter-
9 lapan-Taxes on Alcoholic Beverages, Report of the Appeals Body (AB-1996-2) DSR 1996: I p lOS. national) institutions (Marks, 2000, pp 76-100).
MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 97

economic and technical resources. 12 What becomes a (crisis' in the world and will
involve the political energy and resources of the international system is determined in IV. INTO PRAGMATISM?
a thoroughly Western-do.r;ninated process (Charlesworth, 2002).
It is widely believed that the informal and fluid economic, technological, and The paradox of objectives shows that the formal law of Westphalia cannot be replaced
cultural processes termed (globalization' strengthen the political position of the most by social objectives or ethical principles without invoking controversies that exist in
powerful actors-transnational networks, large corporations, Western developed regard to the latter. (Whoever invokes humanity wants to cheat', Carl Schmitt once
States-and marginalize public international law (eg Hurrell and Woods, 1999). wrote (Schmitt, 1996, p 54), citing the nineteenth century French socialist Pierre
Weak States despair over their inability to hold on to achieved positions and privileges Joseph Proudhon and making a useful point about the use of abstract humanitarian-
by the antiquated rhetoric of sovereignty. But the latter's awkward defence of the ism to label one's political adversary as an enemy of humanity so as to justify extreme
conservative system of sovereign equality undermines the extent to which globaliza- measures against him-a point that applied in today's context (lacks neither lucidity
tion may also open avenues for contestatory transgovernmental action within inter- nor relevance' (Kervegan, 1999, p 61). One need not think only of the extreme case of
national civil society, or by what Hardt and Negri call the (multitude' (Hardt and the (war against terrorism' to canvass the slippery slope from anti-formal reasoning to
Negri, 1999, pp 393-413). There is room for conflict and consensus both within and human rights violation. Quite everyday legal argument assumes the analytical priority
beyond the Westphalian system and little political worth lies in d~ciding a priori in of the reasons for the law over the form of the law in a fashion that underwrites
favour of either. Formal rules as well as anti-formal objectives and standards may each Stanley Fish's perceptive dictum: (once you start down the anti-formalist road, there is
be used for progressive or conservative causes. 13 The choice of technique must reflect a no place to stop' (Fish, 1989, p 2).
historically informed assessment of the effect of particular institutional alternatives. . For example, the right of self-defence urIder Article 51 of the Charter is formally
In the following sections I will try respond to the question (what is international conditioned by the presence of an (armed attack'. But what about the case of a threat
law fort by describing its role in a world that is not one of pre-established harmony -~f attack by mass destruction weapons? Here we are tempted to look for guidance
or struggle but of both cooperation and conflict. I will argue that international ·from the objective of Article 51. The rationale for allowing self-defence lies, pre-
law operates-and should operate-as a relatively autonomous formal technique as sumably, in the objective of protecting the State. Surely we cannot expect a State to
well as an instrument for advancing particular claims and agendas in the context of wait for an attack if this would bring about precisely the consequence-the destruc-
political struggle. If international law as a system seeks the assent of States by claiming tion of the State-that the rule was intended to prevent. Because the rule itself is no
rigorous impartiality, as a profession and a sensibility it has been unabashedly partial more valuable than the reason for its existence, we erase the condition of prior
I

in favour of urIiversal objectives beyond the State. Such objectives can be advanced \ i armed attack and entitle the State to act in an anticipatory wayY Or the other way
only by two means: imposition or inclusion. There is no third alternative. Much around: surely formal sovereignty should not be a bar for humanitarian intervention
instrumental thinking about international law today adopts the point of view of against a tyrannical regime; in oppressing its own population, the State undermines
the decision-maker in a relatively prosperous State or transnational network, in its sovereignty. We honour (sovereignty' as an expression of a people's self-rule. If
possession of resources and policy-options and seeking guidance on how to fit their instead of self-rule there is oppression, then it would seem nonsensical to allow formal
objectives with international legality. Clearly, international law exists (for' such sovereignty to constitute a bar to intervention in support of the people. is
decision-makers. But it should not exist exclusively for them. In this chapter I shall try In other words, we do not honour the law because of the sacred aura of its text or
to explain why there is often a reason to adopt a (formalist' view on international origin but because it enables us to reach valuable human purposes. We follow the
law that refuses to engage with the question of its objectives precisely in order to emission reduction schedule of chlorofluorocarbons (CFCs) in Article 2 of the 1987
constrain those in powerful positions. But I shall also argue that the question (what is Montreal Protocol on the Protection of the Ozone Layer because we assume that it
international law for?' needs to be removed from the context of legal routines to the will reduce the depletion of the ozone layer and the incidence of skin cancer. We
political arenas in which it might be used to articulate claims by those who are honour the domestic jurisdiction clause in Article 2(7) of the UN Charter because we
sidelined from formal diplomacy and informal networks and feel that something assume ·it upholds the ability of self-determining communities to lead the kinds oflife
about the routines of both is responsible for the deprivations they suffer. they choose. But what if it were shown that ozone depletion or skin cancer bears no

14 This is the argument for the 'Bush doctrine' of pre-emptive self-defence, as made in the United States

12 'The State of Food Insecurity in the World 2002', www.fao.orgiDOCREP/005!Y7352e!Y7352eOO.HTM security strategy, published on 20 September 2002. Cf the text in, eg, Financial Times, 21 September 2002,
(last visited 24 October 2002). p4.
13 For the varying use of the rule/principle opposition in self-determination arguments about change, IS This position is often combined with the argument for pro-democratic intervention. For useful analysis,
participation, and community, see Knop, 2002, pp 29-49. see Chesterman, 2001, pp 88-111.
MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI
WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 99

relationship to the emissions of CFCs, or that domestic jurisdiction merely shields the their purposes-hence their frequent aversion against rules in the first place: the
arbitrary reign of tyrants? In such cases we would immediately look for an equitable International Criminal Court, disarmament or human rights treaties, environmental
exception or a counter-rule so as to avoid the-now unnecessary-costs that would or law of the sea regimes, and so on (see Byers and Nolte, 2003).
be incurred by bowing to the empty form of the original rule. Article 10(1) of the The difficulty with the instrumentalist mindset is that there never are simple,
European Convention on Human Rights provides for freedom of speech. If applying well-identified objectives behind formal rules. Rules are legislative compromises,
the right would enable the distribution of fascist propaganda, it is always possible open-ended and bound in clusters expressing conflicting considerations. To refer to
to interfere and prohibit it by the counter-rule in Article 10(2) that enables the objectives is to tell the law-applier: 'please choose'. There is no doubt that Article 2(4)
'prevention of disorder or crime' and to ensure 'the protection of morals', with a of the UN Charter aims towards 'peace'. Yet it is equally certain that 'peace' cannot
margin of appreciation lying with State authorities. Enabling those authorities to quite mean what it seems to say. It cannot mean, for instance, that nobody can ever
protect 'national security' is indispensable if they are to secure the liberal rights- .take up arms. 'Perhaps the most serious problem with outlawing force is that some-
regime. Yet, because setting the 'balance' between security and rights lies with the times it is both necessary and desirable' (Watts, 2000, p 10). J\rticles 42 and 51 of
authorities against whom the rights-regime was established, the door to abuse 'the UN Charter expressly allow for the use of military force under the authority of the
remains open (see Cameron, 2000, pp 62-68).
~ecurity Council or in pursuance of the inherent right of self-defence. The positive
We often allow the reason for the rule to override the rule. We do this because law of the Charter is both pacifist and militarist-and receives its acceptability by
we believe the rule itself has no intrinsic worth. If it fails to support the purpose such schizophrenia. The European Convention on Human. Rights seeks to protect
for which it was enacted-or worse, prevents its attainment-why should it be individuals' rights to both freedom and security. But one person's freedom conflicts
honoured? In domestic society, abstract law-obedience can be defended in view of the with another's security. Whether or nof authorities should be entitled to censor
routine nature of the cases that arise, and the dangers attached to entitling citizens to prisoners' letters or prohibit the publication of obscene materials, for instance, cannot
think for themselves. Such arguments are weak in the international realm where be reached through instrumental reasoning that would be independent from a
situations of law-application are few, and disadvantages of obedience often signifi- political choice (see Koskenniemi, 2000, pp 99-106). The will of the drafters is the
cant. Few States that were economically or politically dependent on Iraq fully imple- language of the instrument. Beyond that, there is only speculation about what might
mented the sanctions set up in 1990. Though they were in formal breach of Articles 25 be a good (acceptable, workable, realistic, or fair) way to apply it.
and 48 of the Charter, the UN preferred to look the other way. The European Union is Practitioners usually understand international law as being more about routine
not going to give up the prohibition of importation of hormone meat merely because application of standard solutions, ad hoc accommodation, and compromise than dis-
a WTO dispute settlement organ may have decided it should do so. The importance course about large objectives. Providing advice to a non-governmental organization
of the interest in living peacefully with a powerful neighbour and of deciding on or drafting judgments at the International Court of Justice are usually held to require
national health standards vastly outweighs any consideration about the importance of pragmatic reconciliation of conflicting considerations, balancing between 'equitable
abstract law-obedience (see Koskenniemi, 2001b).
principles', conflicting rights, or other prima facie relevant aspects of the case at hand.
And yet, as the argument by Schmitt shows, there is a dark side to such anti- Dispute-resolution during the dissolution of the Former Yugoslavia in the early 1990s
formalism. A legal technique that reaches directly to law's purposes is either was understood to involve conflicting considerations about stability of frontiers
compelled to think that it can access the right purpose in some politics-independent and expectations of justice on the part of the different protagonists. This required
fashion-in which case it would stand to defend its implicit moral naturalism-or it the management of the uti possidetis principle as against the provision of minority
transforms itself to a licence for those powers in position to realise their own purposes rights for populations left on the wrong side of the boundary.17 The balance struck
to do precisely that. Instrumentalism inculcates a heroic mindset: we can do it! It between these considerations did not come from any anterior directive but from the
is the mindset of well-placed, powerful actors, confident in their possessing the negotiators' pragmatic assessment of what might work (Lam, 2000, pp 141-151).
'right' purpose, the mindset that drove Stalin to collectivization, or Israel to destroy At the European Court of Human Rights, individual freedoms are constantly
the Osiraq nuclear power plant in 1981. Instrumental action mayor may not be weighted against the need for interference by public authorities. In regard to the
acceptable in view of the circumstances. But the instrumentalist mindset creates a pacific enjoyment of possession or protection of private life, it is established case-law
consistent bias in favour of dominant actors with many policy-alternatives from that 'an interference must achieve a "fair balance" between the demands of the general
which to choose and sufficient resources to carry out their objectives. 16 To always look interests of the community and the requirements of the protection of the individual's
for reasons, instead of rules, liberates public authorities to follow their reasoning, and

16 For a description of instrumentalism as a culture, see Binder, 1988, pp 906-909. 17 Cf Opinions 2 and 3 of the Arbitration Commission of the Peace Conference on the Former Yugoslavia
(1992) 31 ILM 1497-1500.
100 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 101

fundamental rights'. 18 In a like manner, the law concerning the delimitation of policy-oriented in favour of the West or in a more social-democratic way highlighting
frontier areas or the sharing of natural resources resolves itself into a more or less the needs of international cooperation (see Kennedy, 2000, pp 380-387). Legal
flexible cluster of considerations about distributive justice-sometimes described realism always had its Hawks and its Doves but for both, it seemed useful to criticize
in an altogether open-ended fashion in terms of 'equitable principles' or 'equitable old law for its 'formalism' in order to support 'dynamic' political change.
use' -that enables the decision-maker to arrive at a pragmatically acceptable end- Interdisciplinary studies in the 1990s highlighted the extent to which the formal
19
result. Even decision-making concerning the use of force involves setting a balance validity of a standard was independent from its compliance pull (see, eg, Shelton,
between restraint and the need for action, while hard cases in this field invariably turn 2000). As the law was seen instrumentally, its formality seemed to bear no particular
into a contextual assessment of what number of non-combatant casualties might still merit: 'hard law' was just one choice among other possible regulative techniques,
be within the limits of proportionality by reference to the military objective. including soft standards or the absence of any standards at all in cases where the
Few international lawyers think of their craft as the application of pre-existing imposition of one's preference seemed within the limits of the possible and preferable
formal rules or great objectives. What rules are applied, and how, which interpretative given that it might 'minimise transaction and sovereignty costs'. 21 In such debates
principles are used and whether to invoke the rule or the exception-including many formal law has nobody speaking in its favour and is indicted as a utopianism
other techniques-all point to pragmatic weighing of conflicting considerations in supporting conservative causes. Anti-formalism is always a call for transformation: to
particular cases (Corten, 1997). What is sought is something practical, perhaps the overrule existing law either because it does not really exist at all, or if it does, because it
'fairness' of the outcome, as Thomas M Franck has suggested. Under this image, law is should not. The debate on soft law and jus cogens in the 1980s and 1990s manifested
not about peace or justice, freedom or security, stability or change, but always about both of these criticisms and Prosper Weil's famous analysis of the pathological
both one and the other simultaneously. 'The tension between stability and change, if problems (the 'dilution' and 'graduation' of normativity) introduced in international
not managed, can disorder the system. Fairness is the rubric under which the tension law by such notions were unpersuasive to anti-formalist critics who wanted to realize
is discursively managed' (Franck, 1995, p 7). The lawyer's task is now seen in terms of the good society now and had no doubt that they knew how to go about this (see Weil,
contextual 'wisdom', or 'prudence', rather than the employment of formal techniques 1983; Tasioulas, 1996). Avant-garde instrumentalism at the end of the century reads
or instrumental calculations.20 In a fluid, fragmented world, everything hinges on the like German public law conservatism at its beginning: over every international rule
sensitivity of the practising lawyer to the pull of contextually relevant considerations. hangs the sword of clausula rebus sic stantibus (see Kaufmann, 1911).
What makes the formalism/anti-formalism debate suspect is the extent to which
anything may be and has been attacked as 'formalism' (see Kennedy, 2001). The
following views, at least, have been so targeted:
v. A TRADITION OF ANTI-FORMALISM
(a) rationalistic natural-law theories;
The movement towards pragmatism has been accompanied by a series of criticisms of (b) views emphasizing the importance of (formal) sovereignty;
international law's alleged 'formalism'. The first generation of professional inter- (c) views limiting international law's scope to treaties or other (formal)
national lawyers in the last third of the nineteenth century used a flexible notion of expressions of consent;
'civilization' and a historically oriented political jurisprudence to expand its horizon (d) views highlighting the importance of international institutions;
beyond diplomatic protocol and outdated natural law. The inter-war generation (e) views emphasizing 'rigour' in law-application;
attacked the formalism of sovereignty that it saw in pre-war doctrines and advocated
(f) views stressing the significance of formal dispute-settlement;
tradition and interdependenc~ as bases for a more solid international law. After the
(g) views insisting on a clear boundary between law and politics.
next war, reformist lawyers especially in the United States indicted the formalism
of the League and based their 'realism' on Cold War themes, either expressly The list is by no means exhaustive. In fact, anything' can be labelled 'formalism'
because the term is purely relational. When a speaker advocates something (a norm,

18 Fredin v Sweden, Judgment of 18 February 1991, Ser A, No 192, (1991) 13 EHRR 784, para 51; Lopez 21 An interdisciplinary research on the recent 'move to law' uses a method of assessing 'legalization' by
Ostra v Spain, Judgment of9 December 1994, Ser A, No 303-C, (1995) 20 EHRR 277, para 5l. reference to the standards' obligatory nature, precision, and the presence of a centralized authority. The
19 Cf, eg, Separate Opinion of Judge Jimenez de Arechaga, Continental Shelf (Tunisia/Libyan Arab project examines 'legalization' instrumentally, by concentrating on the conditions under which it constitutes
Jamahiriya), Judgment, ICJ Reports 1982, p 18, pp 103-108 (paras 11-31) and, eg, the International Conven- a rational choice. See, eg, Abbott and Snidal, 2001, pp 37-72. Such instrumentalism is not neutral: to assess
tion on the Non-Navigational Uses of International Watercourses, A/RES151/229 (8 July 1997). I have ana- law from the perspective of rational choice is to occupy the perspective of a small number of actors
lysed this 'turn to equity' in, among other places, Koskenniemi, 1999b, pp 27-50. that actually may choose their options by agendas they set. It celebrates the managerial culture of Western
20 For a celebration of judicial creativity in this regard, see Lauterpacht, 1958. experts at work to advance Western interests.
102 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 103

a practice) by its material fullness, the opposite view will inevitably appear to be one member of the community must apply to every other member as well. In the
holding fast to the dead weight of some 'form'. The almost uniformly pejorative use end, competent lawyers may disagree about what this means in practice. But the legal
of the term 'formalism' in international law reflects the predominance of the instru- idiom itself reaffirms the political pluralism that underlies the Rule of Law, however
mentalist mindset in diplomacy and international politics. The way the legal idiom inefficiently it has been put into effect.
constructs and upholds the structures of diplomacy and politics is left invisible. There is a constant push and pull in the international world between a culture of
The contrast between instrumentalism and formalism is quite fundamental when instrumentalism and a culture of formalism. It would be wrong to associate this dia-
seeking to answer the question 'what is international law for?' From the instrumental lectic with fixed positions representing particular interests or preferences. Instru-
perspective, international law exists to realise objectives of some dominant part of mental action is a necessary part of the search for good rules or institutions beyond
the community; from the formalist perspective, it provides a platform to evaluate the status quo. And any present rules are always also mechanisms to support particular
behaviour, including the behaviour of those in dominant positions. The instrumental interests and privileges. 'Power' and 'law' are entangled in such complex ways that it is
perspective highlights the role of law as social engineering, formalism views it as an difficult to interpret particular events as manifesting either one or the other: power
interpretative scheme. The instrumental perspective is typically that of an active and works through 'formal rules' -just like instead of 'naked power', we see everywhere
powerful actor in possession of alternative choices; formalism is often the perspective power defined, delimited, and directed by rules.
of the weak actor relying on law for protection. But the two cultures do play distinct political roles in particular historical situ-
If instrumentalism today needs no particular defence, it may be useful to highlight ations. As the debates around the fluid dynamism of globalization have demonstrated,
the twin virtues of formalism. First, it is indispensable. Every standard is always formal standards and institutions may now offer some protection for the weak actors,
formal and substantive at the same time. The very ideas of treaty and codification and pose demands on the powerful ones?2 There is no magic about formalism, how-
make sense only if one assumes that at some point there emerges an agreement, an ever. It does not automatically produce protection but may also buttress privilege.
understanding, a standard that is separate from its legislative background. When Hence my reference to instrumentalism and formalism as 'cultures', sensibilities and
States enter an agreement, or when some behaviour is understood to turn from habit biases, traditions and frameworks, sets of rituals and self-understandings among
into custom, the assumption is that something that was loose and disputed crystallizes institutional actors. As pointed out above, whereas instrumentalism possesses a
into something that is fixed and ascertainable. The point of law is to give rise to 'heroic' mindset, formalism, with its associated tropes about the rule of law, rights,
standards that are no longer merely 'proposed' or 'useful' or 'good', and which there- and constitutionalIsm, associates with impartiality and pluralism less in terms of
fore can be deviated from if one happens to share a deviating notion of what in fact is definite institutional models than as regulative ideals for a profession without which
useful or good. Instead, they are assumed to possess 'validity'. To accept that positive no community could rule itself by standards it recognizes as its own (instead of
law enjoys that property is not to say anything about how it is recognized in individual those of some influential faction). For this purpose, the community needs servants
rules or standards, nor indeed of whether any actual standard so recognized would that administer those standards (instead of trying to invent them)-the class of
possess any particular meaning as against some other putative meaning. Validity lawyers-whose traditions and practices are defined by their closeness to the 'flat,
indicates a formal property that leaves the norm so characterized a 'flat, substanceless substanceless surface' of the law.
surface' - but a surface without which no 'law' could exist at all.
Secondly, the fact that the legal form is a 'flat substanceless surface' expresses the
universalist principle of inclusion at the outset and makes possible the regulative
ideal of a pluralistic international world. '[O]nly a regime of noninstrumental rules, VI. INSTRUMENTALISM, FORMALISM, AND
understood to be authoritative independent of particular beliefs or purposes is com- THE PRODUCTION OF AN INTERNATIONAL
patible with the freedom of its subjects to be different' (Nardin, 1998, p 31). Between
the form of the law and a decision to project on it meaning 'x' instead of 'y', is a
POLITICAL COMMUNITY
professional technique that excludes no interpretation a priori, that enables stake-
Modern international law puts the international lawyer at the heart of the legal
holders to articulate their grievances as legal claims on conditions of equality,
system. It is possible to represent that position schematically by reference to the two
including them in the normative universe as subjects of rights and duties or carriers of
types oflogic at play in the international rule oflaw. Here is the international relations
distinct identities. The form of law constructs political adversaries as equals, entitled
to express their subjectively felt injustices in terms of breaches of the rules of the theorist Hedley Bull:
community to which they belong no less than their adversaries-:-thus affirming both
that inclusion and the principle that the conditions applying to the treatment of any 22 Out of a burgeoning literature, see, eg, Tsagourias, 2000.
lO4 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 105

The special interests of the dominant elements in a society are reflected in the way in which sufficient elements to enable it to decide with certainty that the use of nuclear
the rules are defined. Thus the particular kinds of limitations that are imposed on resort to weapons would be necessarily at variance with the principles and rules applicable in
violence, the kinds of agreements whose binding character is upheld, or the kinds of right armed conflict in any circumstance'.23
to property that are enforced, will have the stamp of those dominant elements. But that I have defended elsewhere the Court's silence inasmuch as it protected the need for a
there should be limits of some kind to violence, and an expectation in general that agree-
sustained political condemnation of the killing of the innocent, lifting it from the banal
ments should be carried out, and rules or property of some kind, is not a special interest of
instrumentalism and formalism of modern law (Koskenniemi, 1999a). Irrespect~ve of
some members of a society but a general interest of all of them. (Bull, 1977, P 55.)
that position, however, the case illustrates the indeterminacy of both of the two types
So described, law unites an instrumentalist logic, one that looks for the realization of logic behind the Rule of Law, as outlined by Bull above. Neither instrumental
of objectives through law, with a formalist logic, one that establishes standards of calculation nor a purely formal analysis could grasp the status of such weapons: a
behaviour. Now it is obvious that neither logic is fully constraining. The instrumental decision was needed that was irreducible to the two logics. Here the decision was
logic is indeterminate as the objectives always . leave a number of possible choices: silence. In other cases, the Court may have recourse to literalism, balancing, con-
what does 'peace and security' mean and how should it be realized in the Middle East, textualization, and bilateralization, among a host of other techniques, to complete the
for example? Nor is the formalist logic ever fully formal, but always in practice some- instrumental and formal structures within which it works (Koskenniemi, 1989,
how partial and biased. However general the rules of law are, their equal application pp 410-421). Each of such techniques is, again, indeterminate. None of them explain
may appear unjust because the reality to which they are applied is profoundly why this argument was held relevant, why that interpretation was chosen. The decision
unequal: should large and small States, democracies, and dictatorships really be treated always comes about, as the political theorist Ernesto Laclau has put it, as a kind of
alike? The form of law is realized in particular rules or decisions that are no longer 'regulated madness', undetermined by any structure outside it (Laclau, i996, p 58).
formal but that always institute a bias in favour of some substantive politics. A court's decision or a lawyer's opinion is always a genuinely political act, a choice
In the Nuclear Weapons case (1996), the ICJ was requested by the UN General between alternatives not fully dictated by external criteria. It is even a hegemonic act
Assembly to give an advisory opinion on the legal status of nuclear weapons. From the in the precise sense that though it is partial and subjective, it claims to be universal
perspective of the instrumentalist logic, the relevant regulation (human rights law, and objective. But it is this very partiality and political nature of the decision that
environmental law, humanitarian law, and the law concerning the use of force) sought ensures that it is an aspect of, or even a creative moment of, a political community.
to accomplish several types of objectives: above all protection of human life and the Here finally, is the significance of the under-determination of the two logics behind
environment, as well as the survival of States. These objectives proved indeterminate, the Rule of Law. The society upheld by international law is not an effect of instru-
however, and both opponents and supporters of nuclear weapons argued by reference mental reason, nor even of (some conception) of formal reason tout court. It is an
to them: are people better protected with or without nuclear weapons? The instru- effect of decisions, made under conditions of uncertainty and conflict and amenable
mental logic did set some limits to what the Court could say, but it did not-indeed for immediate criticism from alternative standpoints. That international law is not a
could not-fully constrain it. A decision by the Court was needed to supplement the passive reproduction of deductions from some globalizing logic or other (economic,
instrumental logic-a decision that would, then, leave that logic under-determined. environmental, humanitarian) structure beyond itself, institutes the international
The formalist logic was equally under-determined. To decide that nuclear weapons society it governs as a political community that seeks to decide for itself what rules
were illegal would have created a consistent material bias in favour of States in posses- govern it. It is, as Bull noted, a union of 'dominant elements' and 'general interest'.
sion of conventional weapons or in de facto possession of undisclosed nuclear Not reducible to either one or the other, international law is the terrain in which the
weapons. To require the dismantling of disclosed nuclear arsenals would have never-ending struggle between the two is being waged.
revolutionized the existing military-political relationships in unforeseen ways. But
to decide that nuclear weapons were lawful would have maintained the systemic bias
in security policy in favour of the Great Powers and gone against the deep-rooted
popular sense that the existence of such weapons constitutes a permanent hostage- VII. BEYOND INSTRUMENTALISM AND FORMALISM
taking by nuclear weapons States of most of the world's population. Neither illegality
nor legality could remain fully within the formalist logic. Both broke through pure And yet this cannot be the whole story. Although notions such as 'peace', 'justice',
form and created one or another type of material bias. Indeed, it was impossible to or 'human rights' do not fit well within the techniques of legal formalism, and are
decide either way without the decision seeming 'political'. And because the political quite disappointing as behavioural directives, they give voice to individuals and
choice in this case seemed too important for the Court to take, it chose the path of
recognizing the insufficiency of both logics: 'the Court considers it does not have 23 Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, ICJ Reports 1996, p 226, para 95.
106 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 107

groups struggling for spiritual or material well-being, fighting against oppression, tranSItions that have passed from Latin America through Eastern Europe and
and seeking to express their claims in the language of something greater than South Africa. 'Peace', too may be an empty notion, perfectly capable of coexisting
merely their personal interests. Law-including international law-has a 'utopian, with economic deprivation and suppression of human rights. On the other hand,
aspirational face' (Cotterell, 1995, p 17) expressed in large notions such as peace movements have been an invaluable aspect of political contestation
'peace', 'justice', or 'human rights' that in countless international law texts inasmuch as they 'mobilise support and highlight the inconsistencies in international
appeal to solidarity within community. They do this in three distinct, but related concepts of peace and security' (Charlesworth and Chinkin, 2000, P 272). Even
ways. if 'justice' does lie in the eye of the beholder, without a language of justice, the
First, they redescribe individuals and groups as claimants of rights or beneficiaries international struggles for resources, recognition, democracy or, for instance, 'ending
of entitlements and in so doing provide them with an identity that they may the culture of impunity' would have seemed like so many meaningless games played
assert against the homogenizing pull of formal law. As Karen Knop has recently by diplomats.
pointed out, the treatment of claims of self-determination by marginalized groups In other words, though the question 'what is international law for?' is seldom useful
such as indigenous peoples in legal institutions has sometimes enabled those groups as an aspect of the deliberations over particular problems among international law-
to be represented by an identity 'that might resonate with those represented' and yers, it is absolutely crucial as a focus for international law's emancipatory potential.
thus to 'equalize cultures in international law' (Knop, 2002, p 210). Secondly, While the culture of formalism is a necessary though often misunderstood aspect
such principles give an international voice to communities by allowing them to of the legal craft, as a historical matter, it has often provided a recipe for indifference
read their particular grievances as claims of universal entitlement, at the same level and needs to be accompanied by a live sense of its political justification. To lift the
as claims made by other members of the community. To be able to say that some act debate about objectives from diplomatic instruments or academic treatises to the level
is an 'aggression' or that the deprivation of a benefit is a 'human rights violation' of political struggles is a necessary counterweight to the bureaucratic spirit often
is to lift a private grievance to the level of a public law violation, of concern not associated with formalism.
only to the victim but to the community. Such notions-and the whole debate This would also enable the reconstruction of international law as a political project.
about the objectives of international law-act in the political realm to challenge As modern international la~ arose in the last decades of the Nineteenth Century, it
what Norman Geras has termed the 'contract of mutual indifference' -the tendency did so as a part of the elitist politics of European liberal internationalism that
to regard violations as a private matter between the victim and the perpetrator, and expected public opinion and democracy to pave the way for a rationally administered
therefore not of concern to others (Geras, 1998). They challenge the way world (see Koskenniemi, 2001a; Pemberton, 2001). The last articulations of that spirit
claims are blocked in the international realm as matters of 'domestic jurisdiction' date from the first decade following the Second World War (see, eg, Lauterpacht,
or 'private law', thus helping to express cosmopolitan ideas about a genuinely 1946). Since then, a gap has been created between the utopian and the pragmatic parts
political international public realm. And thirdly, to make those claims as legal claims of international law, the former becoming a rather grandiose justification over the
(instead of moral aspirations or political programmes) is to imagine-and thus latter. But when formalism loses political direction, formalism itself is lost.24 Hence the
to create-the international world as a set of public institutions within which turn to pragmatism as surveyed above.
public authorities should use their power in roughly predictable ways and with The question 'what is international law for ?' needs to be resuscitated from the
public accountability. paralysis that it is infected with because of the indeterminacy of the responses given to
The fact that public law notions such as jus cogens or of obligations erga omnes it. But this necessitates a reformulation of the relationship of international law to
tend to be formulated in such large terms as to restate the 'paradox of objectives' has politics, in either of its two guises, as principles and doctrines on the one hand, and as
made them seem quite useless from an instrumental perspective. But, we may now institutional practices on the other. Both political realism and institutional pragma-
assume, their role may be precisely to counteract the ideological effects of instrumen- tism arose as reactions to failed expectations about international law's autonomy:
talism. Again, the form of those ideas-of an 'international legal community' -is realists rejected legal institutions as a sham and told politicians to aim directly at their
important in allowing their use for the articulation of the most varied types of objectives. Institutionalists were wary of such objectives and instead relied on tech-
claims, and thus providing a surface for the inclusion of the claimants as members niques of adjustment and compromise.
of a pluralistic community. 'Self-determination', typically, may be constructed
analytically to mean anything one wants it to mean, and many studies have invoked
its extreme flexibility. Examined in the light of history, however, it has given form
and strength to claims for national liberation and self-rule from the French 24 For a useful reconstruction of Hans Kelsen's formalism in terms of the political project that inspired it,
Revolution to decolonization in 1960s, the fall of the Berlin Wall, and the political see von Bernstorff, 2001.
108 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI
WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 109

national lawyers was a hegemonic technique, embedded in an understanding of the


VIII. BETWEEN HEGEMONY AND FRAGMENTATION: law as not simply a technical craft or a set of formal instruments and institutions.
It was a spontaneous aspect of 'civilization' which had the natural tendency to
A MINI-HISTORY
become universal.
If the First World War destroyed whatever was left of the civilizing mission, it also
These reaction formations are intellectually disappointing and politically dubious.
gave rise to a series of efforts to articulate anew the universal basis of international
Neither provides space for anything but a most formal debate about 'what is inter-
law, sometimes in terms of a law-like movement of societies to ever more complex
national law for?' and no space at all for responding to that question by reference to
forms of division of labour and interdependence (eg, Huber, 1910), sometimes
popular aspirations about peace, order, and justice. A first step in trying to account for
through a reinstatement of the hierarchical principles that were a natural part of legal
such aspirations is to accept that these notions are subject to political struggle and
systems (eg, Verdross, 1923). Most of the reconstructive scholarship of the inter-war
that even as they are formulated in universal terms, they are constantly appropriated
period, however, simply generalized the legal experience of European societies into
by particular agents and interests so as to support their agendas and causes. To
the international level, bringing into existence a universal international law through
say that one's actions embody those of an 'international community' is one such
private law analogies, conceiving the Covenant of the League of Nations as a constitu-
technique (see Klein, 2001). They are aspects of hegemonic struggle, that is to say,
tion of the world and by allocating to the juristic class the function of 'filling the gaps'
struggle in which a particular claims to represent that which is universal (see Mouffe
in an otherwise primitive-looking legal system (see Lauterpacht, 1933; Koskenniemi,
and Laclau, 2001). That the question 'what is international law for?' is a terrain of
1997). The particular European experience with the Rule of Law became the place-
~truggle is a na:ural aspect of a pluralistic society and a precondition for conceiving
holder for the aspirations of peace and justice that lawyers saw were demanded by
Its government m democratic terms.
populations struggling with industrialism and social conflict.
. The hegemonic nature of the debate about international law's objectives may be
In the more recent post-war er,a, much of that kind oflanguage-like the political
illustrated in terms of its history. When Spain and Portugal at the end of the fifteenth
liberalism with which it was associated-has lost credibility. When somebody today
c~ntu~ divided ~e non-European world between themselves by reference to a Papal
claims to be acting on behalf on the 'international community', we immediately
dIrectIve, they claImed to be speaking as Christian powers on behalf of humankind as
recognize the hegemonic technique at work (see Klein, 2001; Feher, 2000). As against
a whole. When the Spanish theologians Vitoria or Las Casas later were claiming that
the pragmatic spirit of to day's public international law, new specializations carry
God had given the Indians a soul just as He had given it to the Spanish, a particular
ideals of universalism and progress. Recently, this has occasioned a lively debate
form of Christian scholasticism-Dominican theology-came to speak in terms of
about the 'fragmentation of international law' - the emergence and consolidation
universal principles, equally constraining on the Princes and the Indians. And when
of special regimes and technical sub-disciplines: human rights law, environmental
Hugo Grotius in 1608 challenged the Iberian claims, he was redefining the objectives
law, trade law, the use of force, and so on (see Barnhoorn and Wellens, 1995).
of international law within a hegemonic struggle that opposed a Reformation-
In each of such realms, particular interests and standards are projected as universal
inspired commercial universalism against the ancien regime of (Catholic) Christianity.
ones, resulting in normative and jurisdictional conflicts. In its Tadic Judgment of
The. narrative of international law from those days to the Nineteenth Century may be
1999,.the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) expressly
depIct~d as a succession of natural law arguments that were united by their always
deviated from the practice of the International Court of Justice, as laid out in its
emergmg from some European intelligentsia that claimed it was speaking on behalf
!"icaragua case in 1986 concerning the attribution of conduct by military irregulars
of the world as a whole. When de Emmerich Vattel in 1758 formulated his 'necessary
to a State. To move from a standard of 'effective control' to one of 'overall control'
law of nations' in terms of the co:r:nmands of natural reason, and found that it
significantly. enhanced the accountability of foreign States indirectly involved in
consecrated a balance of power between European sovereigns, he already filled the
internal conflicts, constituting a shift of normative preference with respect to one set
category of the 'universal' with a profoundly particular understanding that was a part
of international problems.25 The continuing debate about the relevance of environ-
of the (European) Enlightenment.
mental, human rights, or labour standards within the WTO system reflects a search for
. Since the ~rst appearance of the (modern) international law profession in Europe
the relative priority of political objectives within WTO institutions as those priorities
m the late nmeteenth century, that profession imagined itself as, in the words of
have not been set at the level of the relevant agreements themselves. The autonomy
the Statute of the Institut de droit international (1873), the 'juridical conscience
invoked by human rights regimes constitutes a subtle manoeuvre by human rights
of the civilised world'. This understanding, too, was born in a cultural environment
that imagined its own experience-which it labelled (civilization' -as universal
and postulated it as the end-result of the development of societies everywhere. The 25 The Prosecutor v Dusko Tadic, Judgment, Case No IT-94-1-A, Appeals Chamber (15 July 1999),

civilizing mission enthusiastically propagated by late nineteenth-century inter- p 57, para 137.
110 MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL LAW FOR? 111

implementation organs to universalize their jurisdiction. 'Dynamic' arguments and political community among social agents-States, other communities, individuals-
the object and purpose test allow the creation of a systemic bias in favour of the who disagree about social purposes but do this within a structure that invites them to
protected individuals that could be difficult to justify under traditional law. argue in terms of an assumed universality.
Now 'fragmentation' is not. a technical problem resulting from lack of co- But there is a fourth response as well: international law exists as a promise of
ordination: the normative preferences of environmental and trade bodies differ, justice. The agnosticism of political modernity has made the articulation of this last
as do preferences of human rights lawyers and international law 'generalists' teleological principle extremely difficult. For the justice towards which international
(Koskenniemi and Leino, 2002). Such differences are like differences between States: law points cannot be enumerated in substantive values, interests, or objectives.
what is at issue is a hegemonic struggle where each institution, though partial, tries to All such languages express inadequate and reified images, (partial) points of view.
occupy the space of the whole. Far from being a problem to resolve, the proliferation A return to morality-in contrast to 'moralization' -is not available (Koskenniemi,
of autonomous or semi-autonomous normative regimes is an unavoidable reflection 2002). As a promise of justice, international law describes the international world
of a 'postmodern' social condition and a beneficial prologue to a pluralistic as a political community in which questions of just distribution and entitlement are
community in which the degrees of homogeneity and fragmentation reflect shifts constantly on the agenda. Such a self-image supports an administrative culture in
of political preference and the fluctuating successes of hegemonic pursuits (Stark, which the acts of public officials are constantly assessed by a language of community
2002). standards. The instrumentalist mindset understands the law only as a technique
of domination, a coercive order to make 'nations behave'. Its underlying image is the
Hobbesian view of law as a melancholy technique to prevent human groups from
self-destruction. The image oflaw as. a pointer towards justice challenges this self-view
and encourages support for transformation: a world of-for lack of better words-
IX. LEGAL FORMALISM AND peace, equality, and freedom. Iflaw is used to compel (as it is), it is so used to because
INTERNATIONAL JUSTICE the violations cannot coexist with such aspirations. They are singular until the law lifts
them from the purely subjective into public illegality:
Let me close by four responses to the question 'what is international law for?'. Two
Law is the name of the semblance of order-the assembling, the ordering, the establishing of
are rather straight-forward. First, international law exists to advance the repertory
commonality-that is made of our otherwise (subjective) differences when we take, or
of substantive values, preferences, and practices that those in dominant positions interpret them to be a world that can be judged, rather than mere subjective experiences
seek to realize in the world. Secondly, it also gives voice to those who have been (Constable, 2000, p 95).
excluded from decision-making positions and are regularly treated as the objects of
other peoples' policies; it provides a platform on which claims about violence, But the justice that animates political community is not one that may be fully
injustice, and social deprivation may be made even against the dominant elements. attained. Not only is law never justice itself, the two cannot exist side by side. If
To bring these two aspects of international law together means that there is no there is justice, then no law is needed -and if there is law, then there is only a (more or
fixed set of objectives, purposes, or principles that would exist somewhere 'outside' less well-founded) expectation of justice. Here is the truth in Instrumentalism about
or beyond international law itself, that they are always the objectives of particular positive law being a pointer beyond itself. There is a Messianic structure to inter-
actors involved in hegemonic pursuits. The law is instrumental, but what it is an national law, the announcement of something that remains eternally postponed. It is
instrument for cannot be fixed outside the political process of which it is an this 'to-come' that enables the criticism of the law's own violence, its biases and
inextricable part. exclusions. No doubt, law and justice are linked in the activity of lawyers, para-
This is why, thirdly, international law's objective is always also international digmatically in the legal judgment. This is the wisdom grasped by legal pragmatism.
law itself For as I have tried to argue above, it is international law's formalism that. But the judgment is always insufficiently grounded in law, just like positive law is
brings political antagonists together as they invoke contrasting instrumental under- always insufficiently expressive of justice. In the gap between positive law and justice
standings of its rules and institutions. In the absence of agreement over, or knowledge lies the necessary (and impossible) realm of the politics oflaw. Without it, law becomes
of the 'true' objectives of political community-that is to say, in an agnostic world- pure positivity, its violence a mere fact of power.
the pure form of international law provides the shared surface-the only such
surface-on which political adversaries recognize each other as such and pursue their
adversity in terms of something shared, instead of seeking to attain full exclusion-
'outlawry' -of the other. Its value and its misery lie in its being the fragile surface of

You might also like