You are on page 1of 9

P

Psychological Mechanisms dramatically different ways, with very different


meanings, depending upon the particular school
Ulrich Koch1 and Kelso Cratsley2 or tradition of psychology (and specific research
1
George Washington University, Washington, program therein). In fact, usage has been so
DC, USA diverse as to defy easy categorization or defini-
2
American University, Washington, DC, USA tion. But a historical perspective, even if rather
selective, can trace the broad outlines of the sig-
nificance of psychological mechanisms for the
Synonyms study of the mind. Perhaps most notable is the
role they have played in the psychoanalytic tradi-
Psychological processes; Mental mechanisms; tion; research efforts within behaviorism and cog-
Cognitive systems nitive science have also made liberal use of
versions of the concept in their explanatory frame-
works (for discussion of evolutionary psychology,
Definition see the entry “evolved psychological mecha-
nisms”). Cutting across all of these traditions are
Psychological mechanisms are the processes and several key themes relating to psychological
systems, or activities and entities, frequently mechanisms, including questions concerning the
appealed to in causal explanations within the psy- scope of the relevant causal claims, debates about
chological sciences. causal determinism and regularity, and the
unresolved relation between mind and body.

Introduction
Mechanisms and Natural Philosophy
In the most inclusive sense, psychological mech-
anisms offer a type of causal explanation of men- The appeal to mechanisms in contemporary psy-
tal states and behavior, often with reference to chology has historical precedents extending far
underlying processes, systems, activities, or enti- beyond the study of the mind, at its broadest
ties. By postulating and investigating such mech- representing a comprehensive mechanistic world-
anisms, researchers have sought explanations of a view (Andersen 2014). Although such an
wide range of psychological phenomena. How- approach is no longer associated with the use of
ever, the concept has been deployed in the term mechanism in the sciences, early modern

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020


V. Zeigler-Hill, T. K. Shackelford (eds.), Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28099-8_1562-1
2 Psychological Mechanisms

philosophers such as René Descartes, Thomas particular mechanisms, nor in conducting inves-
Hobbes, Robert Hooke, and Gottfried Wilhelm tigations to isolate and study them. In other words,
Leibniz viewed nature as constituted by corpus- it is questionable whether a mechanistic explana-
cular bodies and their mechanical movements, tory strategy for psychological phenomena imme-
essentially as an all-encompassing mechanism. diately evolved from mechanical philosophy,
This philosophical background is helpful not which mostly offered explanations that did not
only for delineating current uses of the term but seek to expand physiological knowledge.
also for understanding why theoretical and exper- With the advent of the scientific revolution,
imental efforts to extend mechanistic explanations empiricist philosophers such as John Locke, in
to the mind were initially met with criticism in the pursuit of conceptual clarity, were reluctant to
late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. employ metaphorical language drawn from natu-
Descartes’ mechanical philosophy, for ral philosophy as they proposed their respective
instance, started from the precept that “this earth theories of the mind. “Anti-metaphorical linguis-
and indeed the whole universe” can be described tic attitudes,” stymied, perhaps ironically, the
“as if it were a machine” (1644/1973, IV, para. development of empirical investigations into psy-
188). However, following a tradition that made a chic life in the seventeenth and eighteenth centu-
clear distinction between the explanation of pur- ries (Richards 2010, p. 23). Empiricist
posive human actions and that of inanimate mat- philosophers referred to mental processes using
ter, Descartes limited the scope of mechanistic technical philosophical terms such as “sensa-
explanation (see also Wright and Bechtel 2006). tions,” “ideas,” and by invoking “principles” or
What are now often called higher mental func- “laws” of association – which were only later, by
tions, particularly the use of language and the the end of the nineteenth century, frequently
ability to reason, he claimed, could not be labeled as “mechanisms.” Moreover, theirs was a
explained in mechanistic terms, since these capac- philosophical project, namely, to ground knowl-
ities were rooted in reflexive consciousness, the edge claims in mental structures and processes. It
res cogitans, an indivisible, unextended sub- was therefore largely left to the slowly emerging
stance. Although, Descartes did apply mechanis- medical sciences to expand mechanistic explana-
tic explanations to areas of enquiry that today fall tions to include the more intricate mechanisms of
within the scope of psychological science, such as the mind.
perception, memory, and the effects of what he
understood as the “passions.”
As the historian of psychology Graham The Psychoanalytic Tradition
Richards notes, Descartes is thus frequently
assigned a dual role in the “mechanization of the In the 1902 edition of the Dictionary of Philoso-
world view”: at once committed to mechanistic phy and Psychology, edited by James Mark
explanations of the material world but also deeply Baldwin, the entry for “mechanism (of mind or
concerned with carving out within it a place for ideas)” ends with a starkly negative assessment:
reflexive consciousness, supposedly only know- “The term is not good, since it lends itself to
able by reason (1992, p. 23). It is because of his interpretation in terms of physical analogy”
mechanistic descriptions of mental phenomena (Baldwin 1902, p. 59). This criticism presupposed
such as memory and perception that he and other that mental activities are fundamentally different
early modern philosophers, especially Thomas from physical processes, and that applying termi-
Hobbes, have been regarded as proposing an nology taken from the natural sciences may be
early variant of a “mechanistic psychology” and misleading. The only example of a mental mech-
as the proto-scientific forerunners of twentieth anism mentioned in the entry was the psycholog-
century behaviorism (e.g., Leahey 1987). ical theory proposed by the German philosopher
Richards (1992) further points out, however, that Johann Friedrich Herbart. His Vorstellungs-
Descartes and Hobbes did not show interest in mechanik [mechanics of ideas] was an early
Psychological Mechanisms 3

nineteenth century attempt to apply the principles employed the term in two rather distinct ways.
of Newtonian mechanics to the mind, which was Toward the end of his presentation, he used it
conceived of as populated by atomistic ideas with reference to not just one causal relationship
amongst which forces of attraction and repulsion but to a set of mechanisms that make up a whole, a
operated (letting some never rise into awareness, system of interlocking parts. Within this context
for instance). Herbart’s writings on pedagogy, Freud discusses the means by which der gesunde
which drew on these deliberations, enjoyed great psychische Mechanismus [the healthy psycholog-
popularity in nineteenth century America. In ical mechanism] rids itself of the residual quantity
Europe, the young neurologist Sigmund Freud of affect left in the wake of a traumatic experience
was surely acquainted with, and perhaps also namely, assoziative Verarbeitung [associative
inspired by, Herbart’s speculative mechanistic integration], and the conjuring of presumably
account as he developed his own theories about soothing mental imagery (Freud 1893, p. 193).
unconscious processes. In this case, the mechanism in question seems to
Despite the significance of the Freudian notion coincide with what Freud would later call
of “defense mechanisms,” which would soon dis- psychische Apparat [psychic apparatus] (e.g.,
place Herbart’s ideas as the exemplar in dictionar- Freud 1915b/1999). In the same talk, Freud had
ies of psychology, Freud only made sporadic use also designated the process of symbolization
of the word “mechanism” in his writings (see also through which the content of a mental state is
Laplanche and Pontalis 1967). The term expressed through bodily symptoms (i.e., conver-
psychologischer Mechanismus (translated as sion) as a psychological mechanism (Freud 1983/
“psychical mechanism” in the Standard Edition), 1999, p. 190).
however, does appear at a crucial moment in his This last use of the term suggests that Freud
work, namely, in the title of the seminal 1893 may no longer have sought to ground such mech-
paper “On The Psychical Mechanism of Hysteri- anisms in the functioning of the nervous system.
cal Phenomena,” which he co-authored with Josef In the same talk, Freud had also differentiated
Breuer and was reissued 2 years later as the first between trauma’s psychological and “mechani-
part of his groundbreaking Studies on Hysteria cal” effects (Freud 1983/1999, p. 187). At the
(1895/1999). Although the term is mentioned time, so-called traumatic neuroses had been
only once in the body of the paper, in the final observed among victims of workplace accidents,
paragraph, its use suggests that the psychological often involving industrial machinery. Some neu-
mechanism alluded to in the title is the rologists, such as Hermann Oppenheim (1889),
traumatogenic etiology, which Freud, at this who had proposed this disease entity, had argued
early point in his career, proposed for forms of that post-traumatic symptoms were caused by the
hysteria previously thought to be unrelated to jarring impact of physical forces, damaging the
traumatic events. (He would later reassess and neural substrate on a molecular level. Freud and
ultimately revise the causative role of trauma in Breuer, on the other hand, now claimed that since
the etiology of hysteria; cf. Leys 2000). At the seemingly more benign yet deeply upsetting
very end of the paper, Freud and Breuer added the events could still lead to hysterical symptoms,
caveat that their studies had uncovered “only . . . the causes were more likely psychological than
the mechanism of hysterical symptoms,” leaving “mechanical” in nature.
aside the “. . . internal causes of hysteria. We have Far from being applied in a systematic fashion
done no more than touch upon the aetiology of the term still oscillated between referring to one
hysteria,” elucidating merely the role of “acciden- particular mechanism and to a functioning
tal factors” in its acquired forms (Breuer & Freud mechanical whole. In a later paper that also car-
1895/1955, p. 17). ried the word mechanism in its title while
In early January 1893, Freud also gave a talk employing it only occasionally (“Some Neurotic
bearing the same title to the Wiener Medizinischer Mechanisms in Jealousy, Paranoia, and
Club [Viennese Medical Club]. In this version he Homexuality”), Freud (1922/1999) did use the
4 Psychological Mechanisms

term more consistently to refer to the unconscious which in turn provide ample material for further
processes that could be drawn on to explain jeal- analysis.
ousy, symptoms of paranoia, and homosexuality Later, more consistent uses of the term
(for an analogous use of Verdrängungsme- “defense mechanisms” by Freud postdate the
chanismus [mechanism of repression], see Freud major publication of his daughter on the topic. In
1915b/1999). But still, as Laplanche and Pontalis The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense Anna
(1967) point out in their Vocabulaire de la Freud (1937/1946) provided the concept’s most
Psychanalyse, Freud seems to have used the influential exposition. The book would go on to
term largely as a rhetorical device, signaling the become a foundational text for psychoanalytic
author’s conviction that psychological phenom- ego psychology, a current within psychoanalysis
ena could indeed be scientifically explained. It closely associated with so-called classical or
should be added that by appealing to mechanisms, orthodox Freudianism in the post-war United
Freud could infer underlying causal processes States. Anna Freud distinguished nine defense
whose operational principles were distinct from mechanisms (regression, repression, reaction-
conscious mental states and intentional actions. formation, isolation, undoing, projection, intro-
With regard to “defense mechanism,” Freud jection, turning against the self, and reversal),
frequently relied on the use of other terms to which she culled from the psychoanalytic litera-
replace the German Abwehrmechanismus such ture, and added a tenth (sublimation) to the
as Abwehrvorgang [defense process], preliminary list.
handlungen [acts], aktionen [actions], or - Drawing on her father’s essay “Inhibition,
reaktionen [reactions] (Freud 1968/1999). Most Symptom and Anxiety”, she pointed to the iden-
frequently, after reintroducing the term in “Inhi- tical function or “purpose” of this set of rather
bition, Symptom, and Anxiety” (1926/1999), he diverse mechanisms: “namely, ‘the protection of
merely used the term Abwehr [defense]. As the ego against instinctual demands’” (Freud
Laplanche and Pontalis (1967) have observed, 1936/1942, p. 46). Defense mechanisms in this
“defense mechanism” is used somewhat inconsis- classical rendering involve, on an abstract level,
tently throughout his oeuvre. In two of his meta- two types of psychological entities (the ego and
psychological essays from 1915, for instance, instinctual demands), while tensions between
Freud invoked the term, first, to designate repres- them set in motion varied unconscious responses.
sion a mechanism of defense (Freud 1915a/1999), The types of processes that are put into action and
and in the second instance he used it with refer- the entities involved in each, however, vary con-
ence to the collection of neurotic symptoms he siderably. Yet it is also because of such variation
had observed in a particular clinical case, thus that psychoanalysts are able to use the observation
applying it to the patient’s neurosis as a whole of defenses as a diagnostic tool. The specific kind
(Freud 1915b/1999). In both contexts, he draws of mechanism observed in a given case gives an
on his clinical experience, highlighting what one indication of the degree to which psychic func-
could call a defense mechanism’s automaticity – tions have matured. The grouping of observations
the fact that behavioral, emotional, and affective under the term “defense mechanism,” in other
patterns have emerged over the course of the words, serves as an important clinical heuristic.
patient’s life, may have surfaced during treatment The ego-psychological conception of defense
and have become second nature. Indeed, the evo- mechanisms gained further plausibility, and per-
lution of the psychoanalytic concept of defense is haps also interest beyond psychoanalytic circles,
closely linked to the treatment method developed because of a growing emphasis on the ego as an
by Freud, during which the patient’s defenses agent of adaptation (see, e.g., Hartmann 1939).
become tangible as obstacles, complications in Keeping the ego uncorrupted by conflict serves an
the treatment process (as strong affective reactions adaptive function. Around the same time, psy-
to the analyst’s interpretations, for instance), chologists working in the behaviorist tradition
were also guided by the assumption that the
Psychological Mechanisms 5

mechanisms they hoped to identify ensured an century, vigorously pursued a reductionist strat-
organism’s survival (see below). It remains to be egy that sought to extend mechanistic explana-
explored, however, to what extent evolutionary tions to a hitherto unprecedented degree.
ideas shaped the notion of psychological mecha-
nisms at this point in history, perhaps more so than
the mechanistic worldview associated with classi- Behaviorism and Neo-Behaviorism
cal physics.
Given Freud’s scant usage of the term, it may Whereas amongst psychoanalysts the words
appear as ironic that his theories would later be “mechanism” and “mechanistic” had become rhe-
criticized as too mechanistic by those deviating torical markers signaling either a commitment to
from psychoanalytic orthodoxy, particularly pro- scientific explanation or misguided determinism
ponents of so-called object relations theory. At the and reductionism, depending on one’s theoretical
heart of the criticism of authors such as Ronald alliances, amongst behaviorists they again took on
Fairbairn or Harry Guntrip was the rejection of a broader, programmatic significance in two dis-
deterministic claims put forth by ego psycholo- cernable ways. First, its early proponents
gists and other strong proponents of drive theory endorsed a mechanistic worldview that came
(for discussion, see Greenberg and Mitchell with strong ontological assumptions about the
1983). On the one hand, it was a rejection of the uniform nature of reality and an unwavering com-
type of explanation offered by orthodox psycho- mitment to the methods of the natural sciences as
analysis. As neo-Freudians, interpersonal psychi- the only viable method to gain scientific knowl-
atrists, and object relations theorists moved away edge about the world, including the mind. “That
from a one-person psychology and developed the- the organism is a machine,” John B. Watson wrote
oretical perspectives that envisioned the uncon- in Behavior, “is taken for granted in our work”;
scious as imbued with the experiences of past and further stating that the goal of a behaviorist’s
present relations to others, linear cause-and-effect analysis was “the reduction of complex congenital
relationships no longer seemed germane. On the (instinct) and acquired (habit) forms of response
other hand, their rejection of the term was also to simple reflexes” (Watson 1914/1967,
directed against the biological underpinnings of pp. 52–53). Second, in a more practical sense,
the Freudian drive model, pointing to the still behaviorists were naturally drawn to mechanical
unresolved issue of how bodily states relate to devices of different kinds through their experi-
mental processes. mental work, relying on them to model human
In the United States, Harry Stack Sullivan, who behavior. Behaviorists explained behavior by
sought to fuse psychiatry with the social sciences, controlling it in their laboratories and by
deliberately sidestepped the term and spoke of establishing new stimulus-response patterns in
“dynamisms” instead. The psychiatrist and psy- their subjects. The practical ethos of the behavior-
choanalyst Jules Masserman, to name another ists’ undertaking has been related to the influence
example, critiqued both Freud’s and Ivan Pavlov’s of the German-American biologist Jacques Loeb,
theories as mechanistic on the grounds that they a teacher of John B. Watson’s during his years at
paid little to no attention to language and symbol the University of Chicago. A staunch believer in
use, the consideration of which supposedly leads technical feasibility, Loeb propagated what the
to a more “dynamic” view of human development historian of science Philip Pauly has called the
(Masserman 1943). The opposition between a “engineering ideal in biology”; claiming that the
“mechanistic” vision of human nature and a main problem of his discipline was not the “anal-
“dynamic” one also highlights the contrast ysis of the existent” but “the production of the
between a reductionist explanatory strategy and new” (Pauly 1987, pp. 7–8).
holistic approaches. Proponents of the school of Despite Watson’s quite literal application of a
behaviorism, which dominated academic psy- mechanist science to the living organism, the term
chology in the middle decades of the twentieth “mechanism” itself is only occasionally used in
6 Psychological Mechanisms

his more well-known essays. In “Psychology as Hull speculated, could provide an “experimental
the Behaviorist Views it” from 1913, for instance, shortcut to the determination of the ultimate
although he does mention the “mental machinery” nature of adaptive behavior” (Hull 1937, p. 29).
of learning, he uses the term only with reference to An earlier paper, “Knowledge and Purpose as
the “Darwinian mechanisms” of variation and Habit Mechanisms,” gives a better impression of
selection and (Watson 1913, p. 167), in a footnote, what may constitute a psychological mechanism
the “associative mechanisms” (Watson 1913, according to Hull (Hull 1930). A “habit mecha-
p. 174). For Watson, mechanism and more so the nism” is thought of as consisting of an activity
adjective “mechanistic” were programmatic but sequence that connects environmental stimuli
not technical terms. Psychological mechanisms, with organismic reactions and internal stimuli
in the narrow sense, may have fallen out of the according to behavioral principles. In contrast to
mechanistic picture altogether. the hypothetical physical mechanism that is the
Things are different in the case of the neo- automaton, the description of habit mechanisms
behaviorist Clark L. Hull, who developed an did not involve the material properties of its com-
ambitious, theory-driven program that expanded ponents, as both stimuli and responses were
stimulus-response theory to include the “interven- treated as abstract entities to comply with behav-
ing variables” of the organism. Hull was also iorism’s strict methodological prescriptions.
inspired by classical physics, particularly Isaac In Principles of Behavior, Hull used the term
Newton’s Principia Mathematica, whose method “mechanism” quite frequently and not only with
he reportedly espoused for his own major work, reference to biological and physicochemical
Principles of Behavior, published in 1943. What mechanisms. Behavioral mechanisms are found
Hull set out to achieve was nothing less than a on various levels of his theoretical system. For
comprehensive theory that would lay out the laws example, he described “experimental extinction,”
governing all forms of behavior, preferably in one of his postulates, as “the mechanism which
mathematical form, by applying “the recognized protects organisms from the evil effects of the
scientific methodology” (Hull 1937, p. 9); that is, unadaptive habits inevitably set up by the law of
the hypothetico-deductive method. Like the natu- reinforcement” (Hull 1943, p. 277). He mentioned
ral sciences, he recommended that the study of “primitive automatic mechanisms,” but also des-
behavior should start out with explicitly stated ignated some “secondary principles” as mecha-
postulates, from which theorems can be deduced, nisms (Hull 1943, pp. 395–396). And again he
which in turn will generate empirical predictions. conceived of the whole organism as a “more or
A strong believer in the unity of the sciences, Hull less successfully self-sustaining mechanism”; as
also asserted that his science of animal behavior which it allegedly appears from an evolutionary
would ultimately provide the basis “for all the perspective. It is in this context that Hull provided
social (behavioral) sciences” (Hull 1943, p. v). the only definition of mechanism contained in the
In 1937, Hull had already published a pro- Principles: “a physical aggregate whose behavior
grammatic article titled “Mind, Mechanism, and occurs under ascertainable conditions according
Adaptive Behavior.” The term “mechanism” is to definitely statable [sic] rules or laws” (p. 406).
only mentioned once, however, although he did In short, mechanisms were construed mainly for
endorse the construction of a “mechanistic the- heuristic purposes and situated on the different
ory” (Hull 1937, p. 10). In a revealing footnote, levels of his hierarchical explanatory system.
Hull described a hypothetical “mechanism.” This Insofar as they were placed on a higher level,
device or “psychic machine,” he argued, could they had integrative functions for the associated
potentially be “constructed from inorganic mate- mechanisms on a lower level. And, although habit
rials” to “display” the postulated behavioral prin- mechanisms could only be identified by way of
ciples. Studying its reactions to specific abstraction, Hull asserted that, essentially, all
environmental stimuli and comparing them with mechanisms are made up of physical parts.
the behavioral patterns predicted by the theorems,
Psychological Mechanisms 7

In hindsight, a tension within Hull’s explana- Cognitive Science


tory project becomes apparent, a tension with
which perhaps all experimenters in the life and Explanatory appeals to mechanisms have been
behavioral sciences who had adopted the pervasive in the allied cognitive sciences. This
so-called mechanistic worldview had to grapple. has its roots in the early efforts of cognitive neu-
On the one hand, he presupposed that the parts ropsychology to link impairments in basic psy-
that make up the world, as well as the laws and chological capacities to localized brain damage,
principles governing them are homogeneous. On from the late nineteenth century onwards. Though
the other hand, the materials and processes that rarely couched in strictly mechanistic terms, such
make up adaptive mechanisms studied in experi- work helped establish the idea that mental func-
ments varied considerably they also differed tions were grounded in the machinery of the brain
markedly from the entities and laws studied by (Shallice 1988). In this literature, it is more com-
physicists. Once researchers in the life and behav- mon to find discussion of the related concept
ioral sciences became absorbed by isolating spe- “modularity,” best understood in this context as
cific mechanisms and the experimental systems specialized, separately modifiable neural systems.
that sustained them, they lost sight, as it were, of But this is not to imply a uniformity of explana-
the natural laws that Hull and other behaviorists tory commitments; not all of neuropsychology is
hoped to reveal (regarding the epistemic role of overly reductive. Modularity has remained highly
experimental systems in the life sciences see contentious, with some preferring the notion of
Rheinberger 1997, 2010). Outside of thought cognitive or psychological modularity, and many
experiments, natural laws do not make experi- neuropsychologists have endorsed a relatively
ments work, nor do they make machines run, the loose, even decoupled relation between mind
machine’s working parts do. and brain. For example, what has been termed
This turn to the study of specific, experimen- “ultra-cognitive neuropsychology” holds that
tally replicable behavioral phenomena was well investigations of impairments to mental function
underway as behaviorist research became more can proceed without undue attention to neural
standardized in its techniques and diversified in detail (Coltheart 2006).
its topics. For various reasons, by the 1960s More recently, there has been an explicit
behaviorists had abandoned the project of a gen- embrace of the concept of mechanism across a
eral theory of learning that laid out the principles number of research programs in cognitive psy-
of all forms of behavior. As a consequence, the chology and cognitive neuroscience. Here again
study of animal behavior became more there are diverse uses of the term, all representing
fragmented (Amsel and Rashotte 1977). The a species of causal claim. But amongst this vari-
abandonment of the basic social science project ance, what has been called the “new mechanism”
of determining natural laws and basic behavioral paradigm has become increasingly influential
principles did not, however, lead to the abandon- (Andersen 2014). First elaborated by philosophers
ment of mechanistic explanations. By the second of science directly engaged with the biological
half of the twentieth century, the mechanistic sciences, this approach signals a further shift
worldview had clearly become anachronistic; away from the search for law-like relations
however, mechanistic explanations drawing inspi- towards a focus on the explanatory practices of
ration from biology rather than classical physics working scientists. In the simplest terms, explana-
continued to be employed in the laboratory-based tions of mechanisms target regularities, or patterns
psychological sciences. of causal relation, in the natural world and then
work to identify the underlying entities and activ-
ities. For instance, in Discovering Complexity, the
philosophers William Bechtel and Robert Rich-
ardson have illustrated how this strategy has been
8 Psychological Mechanisms

applied (1993/2010) to research on genetics, cell social and environmental factors in many research
biology, and cognitive neuroscience. programs within cognitive science, which may
Within neuroscience, the investigation of require the expansion of mechanistic models.
mechanisms, as working parts that regularly pro- The increased attention to network models will
duce phenomena, has obvious implications for the also require reconciliation with more traditional
study of psychological mechanisms. The most notions of mechanism (for discussion of related
relevant, and influential, account is probably the issues, see Craver and Tabery 2016).
philosopher Carl Craver’s Explaining the Brain
(2007), which developed a theoretical framework
for describing the investigation of the components
Conclusion
that make up the mind and brain. In order to
capture all of the entities and activities that are
The concept of mechanism has played a consis-
relevant to the explanation of any particular func-
tent, if quite varied, role in the history of psychol-
tion or capacity, this approach to mechanisms is
ogy. Different traditions have used it in very
relatively inclusive, positing multi-level models.
different ways. This can be seen clearly in the
For example, Craver’s well-known mechanistic
work of the leading theorists of the psychoana-
sketch of spatial memory in mice includes appeal
lytic, behaviorist, and cognitive paradigms, not to
to the animal’s behavior under experimental con-
mention specific research programs operating in
ditions (i.e., navigating a maze), its hippocampus
each tradition. Significant points of divergence
creating a spatial map of sorts, neurons inducing
center on several key themes, including the
long-term potentiation, as well as the activation of
scope of explanation, deterministic commitments,
N-methyl-D-aspartate (NMDA) receptors. While
and views on the relationship between the mind
largely concerned with neurobiology, such
and body. This diversity of usage arguably shares
models are nonreductive, and pragmatic, in that
at least one methodological feature, however,
they require the inclusion of any and all variables
which is simply that the appeal to psychological
that contribute to the overall explanation of the
mechanisms has served as an explanatory heuris-
phenomenon in question, including observable
tic, or even as an organizing metaphor. There are
behavior and, potentially, internal mental states.
certainly researchers committed to an ontic con-
Psychological variables are likely to have a
ception of mechanisms (as entities and activities
place within mechanistic models, as important
that actually exist in the world). But for many
parts of the broader explanatory story (Bechtel
research programs, mechanisms are a kind of
2008). But of course this leaves a number of
placeholder or promissory note, to be filled out
unresolved issues. First and foremost, the rela-
empirically through ongoing investigation. Thus
tions between different types of entities and activ-
psychological mechanisms will inevitably take on
ities placed on different levels are an ongoing
new and perhaps unforeseen configurations and
challenge. In other words, if a model includes
applications.
psychological variables as well as neurobiological
variables, then there may be lingering questions
about causal prioritization (i.e., which compo-
nents are the most causally relevant?). And of Cross-References
course there will always be deeper metaphysical
questions (i.e., the mind-body problem). The rap- ▶ Defense Mechanisms
idly changing landscape in the cognitive sciences ▶ Evolved Psychological Mechanisms
also poses challenges to the development of com- ▶ Freud, Sigmund
prehensive and convincing mechanistic explana- ▶ Hull, Clark
tions. Newly emerging empirical findings ▶ Reaction Formation (Defense Mechanism)
continue to force adjustments to specific models. ▶ Watson, John
This includes the increasingly significant role of
Psychological Mechanisms 9

References Greenberg, J. R., & Mitchell, S. (1983). Object relations in


psychoanalytic theory. Cambridge: Harvard University
Amsel, A., & Rashotte, M. E. (1977). Entwicklungs- Press.
richtungen der S-R-Lerntheorien in Amerika. Mit Hartmann, H. (1939). Ego psychology and the problem of
spezieller Berücksichtigung Clark L. Hulls, seiner adaptation. New York: International Universities
Vorgänger und Nachfolger. In H. Zeier (Ed.), Die Press.
Psychologie des 20. Jahrhunderts (Vol. 4, pp. 57–82). Hull, C. L. (1930). Knowledge and purpose as habit mech-
Zurich: Kindler. anisms. Psychological Review, 37(6), 511–525.
Andersen, H. (2014). A field guide to mechanisms: Part I & Hull, C. L. (1937). Mind, mechanism, and adaptive behav-
II. Philosophy Compass, 9(4), 274–293. ior. Psychological Review, 44(1), 1–31.
Baldwin, J. M. (1902). Dictionary of philosophy and psy- Hull, C. L. (1943). Principles of behavior: An introduction
chology. New York: Macmillan. to behavior theory. Oxford: Appleton Century.
Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical Laplanche, J., & Pontalis, J. B. (1967). Vocabulaire de la
perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York: psychanalyse. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Routledge. Leahey, T. H. (1987). A history of psychology: Main cur-
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering rents in psychological thought. Englewood Cliffs:
complexity: Decomposition and localization as strate- Prentice Hall.
gies in scientific research. MIT Press. (Originally Leys, R. (2000). Trauma. A genealogy. Chicago: Univer-
published by Princeton University Press in 1993). sity of Chicago Press.
Breuer, J., & Freud, S. (1893–1895). On the psychical Masserman, J. H. (1943). Behavior and neurosis. Chicago:
mechanism of hysterical phenomena. In The standard University of Chicago Press.
edition of the complete psychological works of Oppenheim, H. (1889). Die traumatischen Neurosen nach
Sigmund Freud (Studies on Hysteria, Vol. II, den in der Nervenklinik Charité in den letzten 5 Jahren
pp. 1–17). London: Hogarth. gesammelten Beobachtungen. Berlin: Hirschwald.
Coltheart, M. (2006). What has functional neuroimaging Pauly, P. J. (1987). Controlling life: Jacques Loeb and the
told us about the mind (so far)? Cortex, 42, 323–331. engineering ideal in biology. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and sity Press.
the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford Uni- Rheinberger, H. J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic
versity Press. things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford:
Craver, C. & Tabery, J. (2016). Mechanisms in science. In Stanford University Press.
N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philoso- Rheinberger, H. J. (2010). An epistemology of the concrete:
phy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/ Twentieth-century histories of life. Durham: Duke Uni-
science-mechanisms/. versity Press.
Descartes, R. (1644/1973). Principia philosophiae. Richards, G. (1992). Mental machinery. The origins and
Amsterdam: Apud Ludovicum Elzevirium. consequences of psychological ideas. Part I:
Freud, S. (1893/1999). Über den psychischen 1600–1850. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Mechanismus hysterischer Phänomene (Vortrag). In Press.
Sigmund Freud. Gesammelte Werke (Nachtragsband, Richards, G. (2010). Putting psychology in its place. Crit-
pp. 181–195). Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer. ical historical perspectives. London: Routledge.
Freud, S. (1915a). Die Verdrängung. In Sigmund Freud. Shallice, T. (1988). From neuropsychology to mental struc-
Gesammelte Werke (Vol. 10, pp. 248–261). Frankfurt a. ture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
M.: Fischer. Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views
Freud, S. (1915b). Das Unbewusste. In Sigmund Freud. it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158–177.
Gesammelte Werke (Vol. 10, pp. 264–303). Frankfurt a. Watson, J. B. (1914/1967). Behavior: An introduction to
M.: Fischer. comparative psychology. New York: Holt, Rinehart &
Freud, S. (1926/1999). Hemmung, Symptom und Angst. In Winston.
Sigmund Freud. Gesammelte Werke (Vol. Wright, C., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanisms and psy-
14, pp. 111–205). Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer. chological explanation. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Handbook
Freud, A. (1937/1946). The ego and the mechanisms of of the philosophy of science. Philosophy of psychology
defense. London: Hogarth. and cognitive science (pp. 31–79). Amsterdam:
Freud, S. (1968/1999). Abwehrmechanismus. In Sigmund Elsevier.
Freud. Gesammelte Werke (Registerband 18th ed.).
Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.

You might also like