You are on page 1of 20

HOW COME A LIBERAL STILL

BELIEVES IN DEMOCRACY?
A RIDDLE OF POLITICS
AND FAITH
About the book by James Miller
Can Democracy Work? A Short History of a Radical Idea from Ancient Athens
to Our World
Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New York, 2018.

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
Krešimir Petković
Faculty of Political Science DOI: 10.20901/an.15.10
University of Zagreb Essay
E-mail: kpetkovic@fpzg.hr Accepted: December 2018

Abstract This critical essay deals with the book Can Democracy Work? by James Mi-
ller, which, warning of the problems of democratic politics, retains democratic faith.
By combining political science and historiography, and intertwining the history of
ideas with political biography in portraying different episodes in the history of de-
mocracy, the book seeks to give insight into the riddle of democracy. This riddle is
exhibited in various theoretical and practical tensions: between the Rousseauian
demand for sovereignty of the people and the general will on the one hand, and
the Platonistic epistemic skepticism about the ability of the people to decide and
the political demands of liberalism on the other; between the need to control the
rulers and the political-economic dynamics of corruption and clientelism incited by
democratic politics; between rebellion against the elites as a species of functional
political hygiene in a polity, and uncertainty of outcomes brought by the inherent
instability of democracy and its aptitude to excess; and between the seeming ine-
vitability of elections and their cooptational trap. Between the liberalism of fear à
la Judith Shklar and the thrills of populism à la Chantal Mouffe, the author retains
democratic faith – a political version of Kierkegaardian existentialism which goes
beyond the undecided, forever doubting reflection and a political good that is sha-
red with others, in spite of the uncertainties of public opinion and the ascertained
questionability of civic virtue in the open field of the political in history.
Keywords democracy, liberalism, riddle, genealogy, populism, public opinion

I. ince, with about 200 people according to


the media reports – the party members
In late August 2018, Darko Milinović,
former Croatian Minister of Health and of the Croatian Democratic Community
the Governor of Ličko-senjska County, (HDZ), the leading party in the ruling
coalition – arrived in Zagreb in front
231

mobilized local party members for an


unusual quest. Four buses from the prov- of the national party headquarters, to
protest the issues concerning intraparty democracy mean today and how is this
elections and politics. Lovro Kuščević, associated to what it has meant in vari-
the Minister of Public Administration ous historical, cultural and geographical
and the political secretary of HDZ, ac- settings? Can it work?
cused the organizers for manipulation,
stating that "they don't know democra- While the answers to the former ques-
cy".1 On the other hand, Milinović, who tions demand careful empirical analysis
was expelled from the party, called the and theoretical prowess, the last one
procedure of his deletion "unashamedly also implies a telos, a purpose, a vision
undemocratic".2 of good life, which should be attained by
democratic politics. Discussions of such
A relatively insignificant event from big questions reveal not only one's ability
contemporary Croatian politics still to analyze but thus also reveal, so to say,
points to big issues, both in conceptual one's normative persona. What does one
history of democracy and the contem- aspire and what does one loathe? What
porary political discourse obsessed with does one inadvertently or voluntarily
it. Does democracy refer to the tidy pro- hide and reveal? What does one hope for
cedure of aggregating individual wills or or believe in? The question of democra-
to the fuzzy expressions of collective will cy, today as ever, is not only a question
on various levels of political life? And in of political analysis, but also of values,
terms of Begriffsgeschichte, where Carl identity, and even esthetics and escha-
Schmitt, an astute critic of liberal demo- tology of an author discussing politics.
cracy, diagnosed the times of neutrali- Histories and evaluations of democracy
zations and depoliticizations, the que- tackling these big and ages old questions
stion is how come that the same actions that haunt political thought at least from
are called (un)democratic by political the Greek times, could very well offer
opponents and antagonists, typically in a full confession of a zoon politikon or,
the situations when specific criteria of more humanely, a homo politicus, striv-
a meritocratic or professional system to ing for the beautiful and the good in a
judge one's actions are absent? It seems political community. Or, perhaps, a less
that in the clashes of political discourse optimistic confession of the frailness of
everyone likes to have "democracy" on an attempt to offer a vindication of de-
his side. mocracy in the context of an inability to
provide a convincing answer about its
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

But what is "democracy" after all? Asi- future based on levelheaded evaluation
de of the questions of grass roots acti- of its historical experience.
ons and institutional procedures, is it
applicable solely to demos or to the no- II.
toriously oligarchic parties as well, the
particular political organizations com- What if James Miller, a New School
peting in the political arena with their Professor and an historian of ideas, set
general programs claiming the knowl- out to answer these questions, offering
edge of the common good? What does a history of democracy as an idea and
historical practice? Well, he did, and
1
"Milinovićev čin podijelio HDZ, Kušče- his interesting and sincere book, en-
vić za njegovo izbacivanje iz stranke, no
Kujundžić poručuje: 'Ne treba mahati sank-
compassing about 300 pages (about 250
cijama'", dnevnik.hr, August 30th 2018. without endnotes), confirms this hunch:
2
"Zaštitari na izborima: 'Koliko je trebalo the book is at the same time a political
232

biti demokracije na ovim izborima?'", analysis, a biography and a confession


dnevnik.hr, September 9th 2018. of faith. Miller, a former rock'n'roll crit-
ic and Foucault's biographer who wrote with each title summing the different
on the lives of philosophers, is not new concept of democracy emerging in the
to the subject. It's his third book about political history of the West. The book
democracy, the first one being Rousseau: also provides introductory synopses of
Dreamer of Democracy (1984) published the chapters, stylistically evocative of pi-
by Yale University Press, while the sec- caresque novels (an old Spanish genre,
ond one, Democracy Is in the Streets (Si- precisely recounting life histories of the
mon & Schuster 1987), republished by likeable scapegraces). As the synopsis of
Harvard University Press (1994), dealt "Prelude" has it, the book deals with the
with the "miracles" and "monsters" of riddle of democracy (one of the work-
the New Left, vividly portraying radical ing titles of the book was "The Riddle
leftism in the US, one of the Western of Democracy"): "The riddle posed, and
polities that also produced its pictur- some answers explored, in five historical
esque soixante-huitards (Miller did par- essays" (vi). And the collaged pillar on

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
take in the said political carnivals). In the covers already reflects the variety of
other words, the author has something the chosen historical episodes: the as-
to say on the subject of democracy, judg- sembled artwork contains both bits of
ing both from his experience and his Greek alphabet and violent Delacroix's
scholarly expertise and work. Liberty Leading the People on the top –
the famous lady with a flag, a bayoneted
Can democracy work? is a work of ma- musket and a nipple, paying homage to
turity. It puts youth ideals on the trial of the French July Revolution of 1830. In
skepticism that one acquires with age, the following sections, I will lead the
when one is more or less retired from potential reader through the content of
the streets, rarely dreaming of person- the book's introduction (the mentioned
al future prospects and mostly look- "Prelude") and its chapters to come to
ing back to reassess the past. The book its conclusion (the "Coda"), quite un-
goes beyond the sometimes barren and settling for the uncritical proponents of
abstract language of contemporary po- democracy. The readers will ultimate-
litical theory. Miller's knowledge of the ly have to decide for themselves if the
history of political ideas is paired with book solves the riddle posed suggested
the stylistic qualities of prose and the already in the abstract of the essay and
richness of language. He interveawes the the strange lyrics, ironically evoked in
personal and the political in his narra- its epigraph. On my part, I shall offer
tive. The book comes off neither as an some reflections on the titular question
empirically banal, recycling textbook associated both with democracy and
interpretations, nor as a dullish pam- with the profile of the author as a propo-
phlet. As in the case of the lives of phi- nent of political hope, still willing to use
losophers from Miller's Examined Lives Whitman and Brecht in his exalted epi-
(Picador, 2012), the well-researched ep- graphs albeit all the skepticism he tends
isodes have many intriguing facets and, to express.
although there are passages that do not
lack overly archaic pathos, Miller does III.
not proselytize: a seemingly Manichean
distribution of roles is usually put down The introduction provides the usual dis-
to earth by a skeptical nod or a touch of tinctions, modest disclaimers and rea-
(auto)irony. sonable caveats. It correctly states that
liberalism and democracy are terms
233

The episodes from the history of de- "almost hopelessly conflated and con-
mocracy are recounted in five chapters, fused" (14) in the contemporary politi-
cal discourse; that the story recounted tical form is honored mainly in the
is Eurocentric and that the choice of the breach? (7)
cases highly selective. The work is, as
the author confesses, a specific product I see two things important to under-
of an epistemological tradition of writ- stand Miller's political effort suggest-
ing intellectual history and of a political ed in the quoted paragraph. Following
tradition of democracy he was raised in. Tocqueville, whose historical analysis
Although Miller is aware of the tensions (even if he wasn't bashful in his gener-
and faults of that tradition, he can still alizations, as Miller observes) became a
write the introduction as a proud Amer- sort of a gospel of American democracy,
ican, raised on Whitman's Democratic democracy is normatively posited as a
Vistas, claiming that he is "struck by the sort of vibrant political culture of a col-
progress" they "have made as a nation", lective that shares common future and
further expressing his pride with "the faith. It refers, then, to the cultivation
polyglot expansion of " American "citi- of a finer temperament, contrasted with
zenry as a whole, and the generosity with the often brutal and cruel mob instincts,
which Americans, at their best, have diagnosed and theorized by Gustave Le
conceived of popular sovereignty in plu- Bon's Psychologie des foules. It appears in
ralistic terms": in Miller's eyes, "the Unit- the realm of political sociology against
ed States has evolved into the world's the psychology of the masses ignited
most striking ongoing experiment in by irresponsible, charlatan or deranged
populist leaders. This mechanism of ma-
cosmopolitan self-governance" (17).
nipulation is in Miller's narrative associ-
The introduction explicitly poses the ated with the "bad guys" of the chosen
seemingly simple question "What is de- episodes from Ancient Greece to Jackso-
nian democracy in the US, providing it
mocracy?" It makes some sense to re-
with a moralist quasi-Manichean touch
count Miller's preliminary suggestion
and at the same time supplying it with
of an answer before going to specific
one of the important leitmotifs that hold
episodes. He does not provide an ab-
the episodes together (another one may
stract scholastic definition but points to
be a historically grounded premonition
a political tension, present both in my
about the limited lifetime of any given
vignette from the European periphery
democracy).
and in the episodes analyzed. This ten-
sion appears within an ambitious swathe
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

To be sure, in Miller's narrative, it's


of a culture and a way of life. It is framed never a haughty aristocratic pose despis-
as a doubt and followed by a paradox: ing "the great unwashed". His contempt
is reserved for the populist irrespon-
Perhaps, as Tocqueville and others sibility, charlatanry, demagoguery and
have argued, democracy isn't merely scheming that gives mobs a mandate to
a form of government, it is also a way do harm, and that so easily transforms
of life, and a shared faith, instantia- itself to despotism when in power. And
ted in other forms of association, in this seems to be morally right, about
modes of thought and belief, in the as Montaigne's essay against cruelty.
attitudes and inclinations of indivi- However, there is more to the tension
duals who have absorbed a kind of between political life and political form
democratic temperament. But how haunting democratic life, to which I will
can democratic habits of association, have to return at the end.
234

conduct, and conviction survive in a


setting where democracy as a poli- IV.
The title of the first chapter, "A Closed in assembly were perfectly free to reject
Community of Self-Governing Citi- previously approved laws, even to estab-
zens," summarizes, somewhat idealisti- lish completely new institutions" (36)
cally, what democracy meant in Greece. – and the political problems associat-
As the Greeks had it: "'Our city is called ed with "empowering an impoverished
a democracy because it is governed by multitude" (37).
the many, not the few'" is "one of the ear-
liest, and simplest, definitions of the new Thucydides' skepticism concerning
political form" (30), that is relevant to the "demos in action," ignited and moved
this day. Many of the problems and di- by popular leaders such as Cleon (38),
lemmas of today's democracy were also feels as a contemporary if not a timeless
there at the beginning, in Athens, where warning in Miller's narrative, especially
the term and the practice was born for when affiliated with David Runciman's
the Western political history, before the general remarks echoing Plato – of how

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
large democratic hiatus filled by monar- "democracy pandered to desire": "It gave
chic political form: nativism versus the people what they wanted day to day, but
outsiders; military service forging fra- it did nothing to make sure they wanted
ternity and citizen spirit, i.e. "democracy the right things. It had no capacity for
based on citizen-soldiers poised to shed wisdom, for difficult decisions, or for
blood" (52), as later in France; masses hard truths. Democracies were founded
manipulated by the demagogues, all to- on flattery and lies" (42). To this, read-
gether paired with a lack of rights in spe- er can add Miller's skepticism towards
cifically modern liberal constitutional Arendt's idealistic visions of Greek de-
mocracy and to her intellectual progeny
sense, and the largely forgotten lottery
of armchair philosophers (44), and an
as, when one thinks of it, logical method
affirmative nod to Paul Cartledge's sum-
of choice, at least if political equality is
mary of Antic democratic experience as
understood as an empirical fact.
"participatory democracy with a ven-
geance" (48). After all, the big political
Miller notes the fact that "only a small
invention did not end up in glory but
fraction of the Athenian population
in vulnerable and dependent shrinking
participated in politics" and this came
oligarchies that withered away to be in-
in hand with "[t]he myth of Athenian
corporated into larger empires.
autochthony – a strong form of nativ-
ism, stressing that citizens must spring V.
from the land" which "enabled even the
poorest citizen to regard himself as well- The motif of a republican military ser-
born" (29). Although he uses all the ca- vice introduces the French case, reco-
veats, Miller is keen to see the parallels unted under the title "A Revolutionary
between the Greek and the French case, Assertion of Popular Sovereignty": "the
Athenian democracy and the republic French Revolution had made it clear that
established in the course of the French Athens would not be the last example of
Revolution, while further democratic a democracy based on citizen-soldiers
episodes in his narrative also demon- poised to shed blood. Fraternity, solida-
strate similar tensions present already in rity, and the kinds of virtues forged thro-
Athens. Among other things, he men- ugh conflict and struggle would prove
tions Josiah Ober's comparison of the alluring for a number of subsequent de-
Athenian uprising of 508 B.C. and the mocrats of different persuasions" (52).
235

storming of the Bastille (24), the volatili- Not surprisingly, Machiavelli's ideas
ty of the will of the demos – the "citizens also appear in Miller's analysis: the gre-
at Florentine political thinker's claims much later, Miller abhors revolutionary
that armed people make a better army bloodshed (like Chateaubriand in his
than shifty mercenaries and, even if very days), pointing to the September Massa-
cautiously, the controversial concept of cres of 1792 and other episodes of "in-
"Machiavellian democracy". However, discriminate slaughter" (74). However,
the basic structure of the chapter, if one this is not only an aesthetic sentiment,
omits few details and focuses instead but a theoretical claim. Miller nods pos-
on the distribution of forces struggling itively to Simon Schama, who posits
in the clash of political good and evil, an inherent tie between revolution and
is almost opera-like in its simplicity; or, bloodshed by the masses, those by defi-
if one really wants to stretch the com- nition being opposed to the checks and
parisons and put aside the many di- balances of a moderate rational govern-
fferences that spring from the usage of ment: "If Schama is correct – and I be-
Orwell's satirical October allegory, it is lieve he is," writes Miller, "then previous
the old Major, Napoleon and Snowball, scholars have been wrong to imply that
transposed from an animal farm to the the ardent desire of ordinary people for
French Revolution. Let me explain this public freedom can be separated, in fact,
strange association. from their willingness to use force in its
pursuit" (72).
Rousseau, "the Genevan-born sage"
(whose Social Contract was banned in If Rousseau's vision can be vaguely
his native republic, since it was judged to associated with that of the old Major
be dangerous for the Genevan constitu- (Marx), and if Robespierre, the terror
tion) prophesized "the century of revo- and the violent masses, can be asso-
lutions" (56). His love for the people was ciated with Napoleon (the hog not the
recognized by Robespierre, who uttered general), referring in Orwell's narrative
many ambivalent and contradictory to Stalin and the purges, who is then
ideas about politics – e.g. Miller writes Snowball (Trotsky, hammered to death
on his "complete about-face from the ul- in Mexico) of the French Revolution?
trademocratic views" (87). But as a pol- Maybe we could find one on closer in-
icy practitioner, Robespierre wasn't that spection, but he would not be that im-
ambivalent. In the course of the French portant for Miller's narrative. The calls
Revolution, democratic ideas have cor- for permanent revolution cannot be
related with violent impulses, expressed compared with the project of a rational
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

by the often blood-thirsty sans-culottes liberal-democratic constitution, and it


(in Miller's opinion wrongly exculpated is not that clear that Snowball is a good
by Arendt). Rousseau's ultimate polit- guy, but there is a good guy in Miller's
ical ideals, freedom and equality, and chapter though. It is Marquis de Con-
his vision of a republic with citizens as dorcet, a "mathematical prodigy" and
sovereign, making laws that express "methodological individualist in the
general will, ended up (or, more exact- tradition of Adam Smith" (75), who al-
ly, began) with "a carnival of atrocities" ready then was a proponent of women
(72). As the very end of the chapter has rights, an enemy of slavery, and an ex-
it, the French Revolution was "a hec- treme skeptic in the matters of religion,
atomb on a grand scale" (89). Unlike as a posthumous biographical note put
Foucault – who was ambivalent, if not it (76). Condorcet, an author interested
cynical, when he discussed the bloody in the finesses of l'arthimétique politique,
236

assertions of revolutionary power with was instrumental in translating the ob-


Chomsky in the early 1970s – and Žižek scure idea about pluses, minuses and the
general will from the Social Contract into century. It's a motley array of revolu-
French constitutional order. His mission tionaries, presidents, ethnographically
was to "rationalize the drafting of laws disposed aristocrats, transcendentalists
for the public good" (75). His problem? and poets: Paine, Jackson, Tocqueville,
"He knew perfectly well that his fond- Emerson, and Whitman. Thomas Paine,
est hopes for an enlightened regime of the author of the pamphlet Common
political freedom had been hijacked by Sense, advocated simple government
Robespierre and a few other fanatics of accountable to the people, a "common-
virtue" (88). His destiny? Although he wealth of self-reliant individuals" (93).
did not end up guillotined as Robespi- Society, not the state (as in Hegel), was
erre himself, after a period of hiding, the place of freedom and happiness for
Condorcet was imprisoned. He died in him, a place of voluntary associations
his cell, poisoned, perhaps taking poison and organizations and market transac-
voluntarily like Socrates, or simply from tions between individuals, i.e. the place

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
stroke: it is not clear to this day. of "commerce" (96), but Miller reminds
the reader that Paine later advocated
VI. some rudimentary forms of social pol-
icy, such as grants and pensions funded
The next chapter discusses Miller's own
by an estate tax (97).
polity, under the title "A Commer-
cial Republic of Free Individuals," that
If Paine is there to account for the
sums up the ideas of the founding fat-
chapter title and the early theoretical
hers – the same thing that the Canadian
foundations of American polity, Jackson
interpreter of Hobbes and Locke C. B.
is there to demonstrate the noxious pop-
Macpherson, called "possessive indivi-
ulist dynamics as a recurring interest of
dualism". There is of course much more
Miller's democratic analysis. Miller is
in the complex story about the nascence
of the American republic, since, after all, not lonely in not being too fond of Jack-
"Republican Rome was their model, not son, citing, among many other things,
Periclean Athens" (92), and Madisonian Jackson's support of Indian resettle-
distrust of the people, the unconstrained ment, "America's unique contribution
popular sovereignty without checks and to the art of 'ethnic cleansing'" (110), and
balances, was there from the beginning, ignoring the rule of law embodied in the
echoing in Miller's own doubts about Supreme Court's decisions. Assuming
the real status of democracy in Ameri- the role of a national "tribune," Miller's
ca. In other words, the "characteristi- Jackson is a figure similar to Athenian
cally guarded American approach to demagogues, mobilizing commoners
popular sovereignty made elections a against the elite in a new setting of a
crucial feature of the new regime – and grand scale federal polity, "trying to turn
struggles over the right to vote a focus the quadrennial vote for the most pow-
of subsequent efforts to ensure that all erful figure in the federal government
Americans, regardless of race, gender, or into a national plebiscite" (112). Miller's
wealth, felt they had standing in a repu- interpretation of Jackson does not only
blic of equals" (92). function as a critique of Trump's presi-
dency thus far, in the ruse of an historical
Miller's versatility in combining histo- analysis; it also helps to further profile
ry of ideas and biographical work finds Miller's normative understanding of de-
its focus in several important persons mocracy, juxtaposing a culture of eman-
237

that helped to shape American demo- cipated individuals – where there are no
cratic imaginary formed in 18th and 19th slaves, but also no masters, according
to Lincoln's definition (118) – with the with cultural tastes as worthy and legit-
authoritarian patterns of populist poli- imate as those of any European aristo-
tics. Jackson is not to be revered: "one is crat" (124).
struck by the discrepancy between what
Jackson, based on the evidence, seems Enter Emerson and Whitman, au-
actually to have accomplished in the way thors immensely important to under-
of democratizing reforms, and the out- stand Miller's writings on democracy in
size role he assumes in the national lore America. The first one "provided a qua-
(at least the lore I was taught growing si-religious sanction for the American
up about this putative hero of the com- cult of individualism" which justifies the
mon man)" (112). By the way, Miller's usage of the term "Emersonian ideology"
analysis of the case of Thomas Wilson as opposed to the rigidities of a puritan
Dorr, and the so-called Dorr Rebellion, religion (125). This gospel of "self-re-
associated with the struggle for suffrage liance," preached by an author whom
in Rhode Island, demonstrates similar Miller sees as similar to Nietzsche in
sentiments: a loathing of populism and certain aspects, was associated with civ-
all "venal demagogues running on disin- il disobedience as a form of democratic
genuous policy platforms" (124). politics.3 This phenomenon is portrayed
affirmatively in the book, although with
De Tocqueville, who was in a mission the caveat about the problem of "real
with de Beaumont to inspect the Ameri- political justice", with an accent put on
can prison system, met Jackson and was the problem of racial discrimination.
not too impressed with the finesse of Namely, Miller observes how "noncon-
his character and abilities. Tocqueville formism and defiant individualism can
based his insights in the observations of flourish while … the quest to create a
more inclusive democratic society lan-
"Jacksonian democracy", a term Miller
guishes" (128). Whitman who, paradox-
himself uses in (scare) quotes. Howev-
ically (perhaps as Miller himself), saw
er, Miller does not seem to be impressed
the development of "perfect individu-
with conclusions of the author, "regard-
alism" as the telos of democracy (130),
ed as an uncanny prophet" (116), over-
"had exalted America's democracy as he
prone to generalize. It is not only Toc-
had experienced it inwardly, as a kind of
queville's misfires concerning the issues
sublime pantheism, egalitarian in sub-
of universal suffrage and its practices
stance and cosmic in scope" (129). Mill-
– Miller seems to like Lijphart's sugges-
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

er acutely notes the interesting discrep-


tions to make voting in the US obliga-
ancy between Whitman's hymns and
tory, not a right, but a "civic duty" (123)
the disgust he expressed in private let-
– that did not stand the test of time in
ters with his "dark-skinned compatriots
Miller's opinion. Unlike Adorno, anoth-
who were intoxicated by their first taste
er American visitor much later, Miller
did not find Tocqueville's "worries about
3
To be sure, Nietzsche was no democrat at
all. Socrates, Jesus, Luther and Rousseau
conformism" reasonable: "the United
belonged to the same democratic lot (die
States had already begun to elaborate a vier großen Demokraten; Nietzsche 1887a)
distinctively clamorous style of public as, in Nietzsche's equation, proponents of
culture" and "an emergent culture in- equality, epistemic or political, religious or
dustry made it both possible – and prof- secular. To him, democracy is a sign of soci-
etal decadence, a political form that is both
itable – to market cultural artifacts that
an introduction to anarchy and an equiva-
strove to satisfy the otherwise frustrated lent to misarchism, hate of the many for the
238

yearnings of ordinary Americans to be natural rule of the few that have the will to
regarded as free and equal individuals, power (Nietzsche 1887b).
of political power" (130), the disgust shady milieu of secret societies, anarc-
similar to Miller's when he discusses hist bombs and insurrections:
historical cases of various politically ig-
nited mobs, be it Athenians led by dem- Marx abhorred the votaries of con-
agogues or blood-thirsty sans-culottes spiratorial insurrection – Blanqui,
of the French Revolution. They seem Bakunin, the whole lot. Their secret
to fit in Whitman's definition of "many societies and obsessive scheming
wild brutes let loose" (130). offended his core rationalism and his
(Hegelian) hope that the sharp, open
VII. conflict produced by truly popular
social movements would produce, in
The fourth chapter, "A Struggle for Po- time, and in the crucible of civil wars,
litical and Social Equality," returns the new men and new women, equipped
narrative back to the old continent, to establish a new world of emanci-

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
dealing with the Chartists and the cha- pated, and enlightened, equals. (154)
racters such as Marx, Mazzini, Michels
and Weber. The first political group Not surprisingly, the negative minor
expectedly did not fare to well by Miller's character here is Raoul Rigault, an out-
standards, since they treated "the Jaco- spoken atheist and revolutionary, master
bin constitution of 1793 as sacred scrip- of the manipulative art of rhetoric and
ture" and "idolized Robespierre" (135). a bon-vivant, a small scale Robespierre
Their "promises were, in a strong sense, of Paris Commune, a principal of police
democratic – but their methods were in- terror, executions and feasts, "legendary
creasingly revolutionary and hinged on for his outlandish tabs (one breakfast af-
the actions of a relatively small minority ter a long night supposedly consisted of
of committed militants" (139). Marx is two fine Burgundies and Chateaubriand
treated without awe, in the recognizable aux truffes)" (153). Speaking of the good
style Miller employed in the book about and the bad guys within this chapter,
philosophers, dissecting their biograp- Miller seems to be much more conge-
hies in defiance to any mind-numbing nial to Giuseppe Mazzini than to Marx.
sacralisation. Marx "felt that democracy Mazzini, an Italian republican and one
was not an end in itself but only a means of the key characters in the unification
toward the ultimate aim of fully realizing of Italy, whom Marx understood as a
human freedom in a peaceful society of reactionary, noticed the discrepancy be-
equals" (142), and "he speculated that tween the egalitarianism of Christianity
an economy organized on egalitarian and the hierarchical nature of political
principles would, eventually, be able to societies. In Schmittian terms, it might
do without the hierarchical methods be said that Mazzini offered a sort of po-
of command and control characteristic litical theology of democracy, deriving
even of representative governments like the principles of national politics from
that of the United States" (143). A history the sacral grounding premises of the
of Yugoslav self-management might add Christian doctrine: "We cannot logically
to this theme: long ago Miller was a fan declare the children of God to be equal
of that literature but soon enough he got before God and unequal before men", he
disenchanted with that "brand of cynical stated (145).
Marxism", as he explained to me in an
e-mail. In any case, he still seems to be Opposing Marxism, Mazzini mused
fond enough of Hegel and a connoisseur on the gradual change – the evolution of
239

of the rationalist history of ideas whi- societies and human species, against the
ch helps him delineate Marx from the lethal revolutionary experiments such as
Paris Commune. Miller seems to follow problems, such as Eduard Bernstein and
him, opposing the carnivals of violence. Rosa Luxemburg, rising broader issues
In Miller's meta-narrative that cuts about the relationship between socialism
across the historical episodes, they are and democracy, as in the famous "gene-
associated with a formula of "delirious alogy" written by Laclau and Mouffe.
community of equals" (151). It is one of However, the lead role belongs to Robert
the possible succinct definitions of de- Michels, an observer of actual practices
mocracy Miller plays against. While I of social democracy that exemplified the
doubt that the party members from the discrepancy between socialism and de-
buses in the introduction were delirious, mocracy, equated in a naive idealist un-
they might still fall into this camp of derstanding of some of the proponents
democratic phenomenology, associated of socialism. Michels, under influence
with temporary intoxicating moments of of Pareto and Mosca, was famous for his
fraternity on various levels. It is Le Bon's formulation of the iron law of oligarchy,
material, often with lots of corpses on which is in accord with their theory of
the barricades, similar to those beneath elites that, as ever, successfully eschew
Delacroix's Liberty's nipple. However, nominally democratic forms. Miller
Miller also notices a paradox of chang- rightly finds great interest in the long-
es associated with bloody revolutions term correspondence between Michels
(a sort of historical dialectics, although and Weber, "a priceless record of how
he doesn't use such language): fear of two astute observers viewed the modern
violence and popular pressures bring struggle for political and social equality,
up changes to political order, which and the divergent ways they evaluated
is a point traditionally made by Marx- its prospects" (167).
ists who tend to notice that violence is
a midwife of the new order. In another Weber, a diagnostician of the fossil-
paradox characteristic for a democratic ized Western civilization, explained to
believer, he seems to be abhorred with his young and still idealistic syndicalist
violence but still thrilled by the oppor- friend, how Rousseauian notions of the
tunity democratic moments bring to will of the people are but fictions. If one
political history. In one of the possible does not to adhere to revolutionary eth-
readings, the ambivalences of democra- ics of the will, formally a secular variant
cy trump the quasi-Manichaeism of po- of the Sermon on the Mount, as is Kant's
litical actors spawned by the democratic categorical imperative, one must accept
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

moments and the liberal from the title "the sociological conditions underlying
of the essay perhaps appears more dem- all 'technologies,' be they economic, po-
ocratic than he is willing to admit, warts, litical, or whatever" (168-169), which
populism and all. makes talk of revolution a (farcical) uto-
pian call. Weber's patronizing is not the
Enter modern political parties, orga- whole story, assuming a recognizable
nizations unbeknownst to the Greeks. form of a dialogue between an older
They open the questions of political (complacent) cynic and a younger (na-
form and content, partially intimated ive) idealist who will grow up (both of
in the beginning of this essay: "Should course bourgeois). An unexpected par-
a party that advocated democracy orga- allel emerges, accentuating another pos-
nize itself democratically? Did it matter sible normative layer in Miller's complex
if its rhetoric was revolutionary while narrative: "Weber could see the advan-
240

its policies were reformist?" (159) Many tage of handing effective political power
figures appear in association to these in avowed democracies to shrewd dema-
gogues, just as Athens had handed pow- notice his parochialism when Wilson
er to Pericles, who was able, according deals with democracy in Europe, as well
to Thucydides, to harness productively as his "white supremacist assumptions"
the otherwise dangerous passions of un- (177). In the choice between natural ar-
ruly and uninformed citizens" (170). To istocracy (Adams) and plebeian democ-
put it differently, it comes down to good racy (Jackson), Wilson is closer to the
leadership (for Weber, this was paired former option. During his times, one
with political ethics of responsibility) can observe the formation of a gap, very
in "[t]he democratic currents of histo- important in Miller's opinion, between
ry", which "resemble successive waves" the discourse of democracy and actual
where, as Michels further observed, practices of governing, associated with
revolutionary leaders become the part the development of federal bureaucra-
of a new establishment to be in "turn cy, the ambitious policing schemes and
attacked by fresh opponents who appeal the imperatives of secrecy associated

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
to the name of democracy", which lead with the maintenance of national se-
him to a somewhat mystical conclusion: curity. The Patriot Act is nothing new,
"It is probable that this cruel game will in other words. It is a part of a century
continue without end" (172). old American tradition. Together with
Weberian concept of bureaucracy and
VIII. the distinction between politics and
administration (a founding moment of
The last of the chapters, "A Hall of Mi-
the Wilsonian science of administra-
rrors," is the first one with a composite
tion), another Weberian uneasy motif
metaphorical layer in the title, possibly
referring not only to Versailles, but also appears. The Führerdemokratie shows
to the structure of the chapter, where up in Miller's narrative about Wilson,
narrative jumps from America to Eu- and he even sees Wilson's war speech
rope, from the United States to Russia. as "a fine example of an eloquent dem-
The chapter deals with Wilson and Le- agogue in full oratorical flight" (181).
nin – the two champions of quite diffe- "God helping her, she can do no other,"
rently understood right of self-determi- Wilson concluded his speech, and Mill-
nation – with Bernays (a bad guy) and er added: "The final, Protestant flour-
Lippmann and Dewey (the good guys). ish is telling" (181). Indeed it is, as yet
Moreover, the mirrors might also refer another example of Miller's analytical
to the mirrors of democratic experience heed for the issues of political spiritual-
across history, which is repetitively por- ity which I discuss at the very end, and
trayed in the book, in a sort of structure of the normative complexity of the nar-
of fugue, where similar musical motifs rative where leadership appears both as
are repeated and reworked as democra- necessary and dangerous for democracy.
cy as the rule of the people is, in new And that is another democratic aporia
historical and geographical settings. or antinomy (the reader may choose) –
a "tension" that continues the list offered
Wilson, a professor of politics at in the abstract of the essay.
Princeton and university's president –
the first and thus far last American pres- The account of Soviet experience is
ident with a PhD, as Miller notices (174) intertwined with biographic bits on Le-
– had a lofty vision of "a concert of dem- nin, a strategist of a great willpower as
ocratic nations, each one established described by Gorky (187). The result
241

through a democratic process of self-de- did not fare to well on the test of dem-
termination", but Miller is also quick to ocratic evaluation: "in theory, a prole-
tarian and peasant democracy; in real- Edward Bernays, cherished as rever-
ity, a new state ruled by one party, the ent figure, at least in the Croatian pub-
Bolsheviks, and, ultimately, by one man" lic relations milieu and establishments4,
(189). It was a dictatorship, but this is appears in a very negative light. Miller
not especially new or controversial find- portrays him as a sort of a cynical ma-
ing. Much more interesting are Miller's nipulator in a post-truth world avant
discussions about the relationship be- la lettre – the world, in Bernays' own
tween public opinion and democracy. words, of "the so-called truths by which
society lives" which "are born of com-
The problem is not only in the biased
promise among conflicting desires and
media, the said secretive bureaucracy,
of interpretation by many minds" (204).
and various manipulative political ac-
This also brings out yet another seman-
tors, but also in the stereotypes that in- tic facet to the title: "At Versailles, the
fluence the political thinking of the citi- Hall of Mirrors was a symbol of absolute
zens. No wonder that Walter Lippmann power, with the long corridor of mirrors
appears as a skeptical hero in Miller's reflecting a controlled landscape that,
narrative. His analyses seem to put En- seen through the windows on the other
lightenment dreams of Condorcet & co. side, seemed to stretch to infinity. What
to serious test, but one of the proposed Bernays had called the 'mirrors of the
solutions, setting hope on the "trained public mind' evoked not Versailles but a
civil servants with an in-depth knowl- fun house maze" (205). Need it be said
edge of the facts pertinent to formulat- that this metaphor, evoking an older al-
ing reasonable public policies" (201), is legory of the cave, does not sound too
not unambivalently comforting (in the good for democracy?
literature about critical policy analysis, However, even if democracy often
which I happen to know quite well, this appears as a sham, especially when as-
is criticized "technocracy"). In any case, sessed by more ambitious criteria, Mill-
Lippmann's well-known idealist coun- er, still a skeptical proponent of Enlight-
terpart, who with Wilson (and Miller) enment (I think), sticks to the project,
shared a vision of democracy, under- since even this "'sham'" "represents an
standing it as "a matter of shared faith" epochal transformation": "the rulers of
(201), is James Dewey. Dewey's broad every contemporary regime that pro-
understanding of democracy infused fesses democratic values, however fee-
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

Miller's initial answer with even more bly realized, must periodically face the
religious overtones. Democracy was "a mundane threat posed by ordinary citi-
kind of church writ large, a communion zens, however uninformed, periodically
of souls sharing the same faith in free- queuing at a polling station, to exercise
dom and equality and fraternity" (202). their right to vote, and so to transfer
power, if they choose, to an entirely new
However, Miller is quick to see the prob-
set of political leaders" (211).
lem. Dewey does not refute Lippmann
empirically, as Miller's notices, and his IX.
skeptical face thus shows itself in an as-
"The Coda" tries to provide an answer to
sessment of Dewey's visions: it's "Em-
Huntington's question of "Who are we?",
erson and Whitman redux: democracy
in America as a 'state of vision,' an elu-
4
One private higher education institution in
Zagreb bears his name: "Edward Bernays
sive dream, a redemptive ideal, yet still University College", offering degrees in
242

worth struggling toward, even against communication as well as in tourism man-


the current of events" (203). agement.
a question that much haunts Miller and politics producing conflict, Huntington
other Americans for the last several de- fathomed in the 1970s, as Miller does
cades. Miller, himself being involved in now. Add to this Huntington's omi-
the activities of the anti-Trump opposi- nous implications that, as in some neg-
tion, offers a piece of prose reflecting the ative eschatology of political decadence,
current political moment. However, the American democracy does not have
text is once again ironic and skeptical. the freshest outlook: that what seemed
In lack of a better interlocutor, old Mi- preposterous and absurd to young Mill-
ller speaks to the young Miller here, as er now becomes sensible, namely the
Weber does to Michels. It is a testimony idea that perhaps "John Adams had been
of a young leftist idealist who with age right to warn, almost two hundred years
turned into a more conservative politi- ago (roughly the life span of the Athe-
cal adult. It is a political coming of age nian democracy), that 'there never was
essay. To be sure, the portrait of Trump a democracy yet that did not commit

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
is not flattering. Miller doesn't seem to suicide'" (218).
like him: "A cartoon of self-reliant coc-
kiness, the candidate adored being the Huntington is another prodigy in
center of attention and, like a louche Miller's story, as Condorcet was in his
comedian, merrily defying the norms times – a conservative who saw West-
of civil discourse" (214). There is much Point as "a bit of Sparta in the midst of
more, but the point is in the wider pi- Babylon", a remark that, in one of Mill-
cture Miller draws, transforming the er's ironical quips, disabled Huntington
recent American experience into anot- to teach at Harvard, at least right away,
her vignette in the history of democracy. since he still ended there, at the richest
Protesters against Trump on the streets and probably most prestigious Amer-
of New York shouted "This is what de- ican university, "after only five years in
mocracy looks like!", but Miller, himself the wilderness, teaching at Columbia"
part of the crowd, was mature enough (221). Huntington, perceived by the
to understand the similar sentiments young leftists as a war criminal, had his
of their political opponents. He and his portion of graffiti on his house (in a fin-
co-protesters felt as "people in a bitterly er version of the similar political senti-
divided country feeling like strangers in ment, Chomsky saw him as one of the
their own land" (216), but so did many mandarins of new American power).
others after Obama's two successive Skeptical and far-sighted in the realm
elections: "Now it was my turn" (217), of international relations, unlike his tri-
Miller observed. Moreover, he also un- umphant Hegelian student Fukuyama
derstood that it was American identity back in the early 1990s, Huntington saw
at stake in these struggles, generating the rise of power of China and Islamic
tensions and challenges for American world, leading him to conclude that rea-
democracy, and he turned to Samuel sonable (American) politics would have
Huntington to look for the answers. to eschew universalism (223), perhaps
just another, finer name for the failed
Rereading of Huntington today may project of global empire. Parallel to his
appear as common sense, but it is a analysis of international relations, Hun-
controversy at least in the New School tington's last book dealt with American
milieu. What once angered the young identity, providing the title to Miller's
Miller, became a set of "sensible obser- coda. In that book, Huntington tried
243

vations" (217) for the old Miller. It is to take into account "the long-term im-
not capitalist economy but democratic plications of demographic and cultural
trends on America's sense of national acknowledge, that there are many in-
identity" (224). compatible forms of life and forms of
politics, not always directly democra-
Miller's reading of Huntington, who tic or participatory, in which humans
back then saw prospects of "white na- can flourish. This, in part, is what I
tivism" in the United States, is not too understand by the aspiration to cre-
reassuring for American democratic ate a liberal democracy. (234)
prospects. American identity, historical-
ly speaking, was not at all universal but The finale of the book is not too re-
more or less white, Anglo-Saxon prot- assuring, offering parallels between
estant, paired with democratic ideology radical democrats and populist leaders
that produced conflicts (225). Political not protesting against democracy but
skeptics, and political believers with against its limits. Dahl's and other com-
skeptical face such as Miller, recognize prehensive definitions of democracy,
Huntington's historical lesson that po- such as the one employed by the Vari-
litical principles are not enough to keep eties of Democracy project (V-Dem),
the polity together. Huntington wasn't include liberal components, and Miller
optimistic at all: "For Samuel P. Hun- reminds us that illiberal doesn't mean
tington at the end of his life, this is what undemocratic. Ultimately, democracy,
American democracy looked like: a in the more mundane repetition of the
fragile ideology, with cloudy prospects" introductory motif, emerges not only
(226). as a name or an ideology, but also as
"a moral vision, of free institutions as a
And Miller? A disappointed radical better solution to the problems of hu-
democrat of the 1960s, rooted his skep- man coexistence than the authoritarian
ticism in personal political experience – alternatives" (240), threatened today as
"my own experiments in radical democ- the Enlightenment project championed
racy quickly fell apart, as my friends and by Condorcet and others. Secretive bu-
I tired of the endless meetings and sup- reaucracy and PR operations manipu-
pressed disagreements that the quest for lating public opinion, as in Habermas'
consensus entailed" (228). The author of early critique of contemporary public
Can Democracy Work? is thus aware that sphere, contribute to a world of "disin-
the efforts such as the Occupy move- formation" loved by "suspicious, even
ment most probably will not produce a paranoid" recipients (244). A bleak out-
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

set of viable alternative institutions. The look, which still doesn't liberate Miller
account of his own experience of direct from his democratic faith: "however
democratic failures helps him to finally skeptically, and knowing that these
tie together the whole narrative about words represent a riddle, not a recipe",
historical democratic episodes: he evokes "Abraham Lincoln's charac-
teristically American hope, especially in
Instead of single-mindedly pursuing the darkest of times: 'that government of
a new form of "collective thinking" the people, by the people, for the people
through endless meetings meant shall not perish from the earth'" (245).
to forge consensus – a quixotic and
self-destructive goal that led astray X.
the sans-culottes in 1793, the soviets
in 1905 and 1917, and the New Left I am indeed not sure if the book ultima-
of the 1960s – I think we would do tely solves the riddle of democracy. I am
244

better to explore new ways to foster not even sure that author had such an
a tolerant ethos that accepts, and can intention, as the last lines suggest. Does
it offer a clear and simple normative so- Capitalism is also not the one to
lution? Not quite. There is no "recipe". blame. Miller seems to follow Hun-
However, in the final assessment, it can tington in putting democracy first in
be said that the book instead issues a re- some situations: democracy is the cause,
asonable skeptical warning and a sincere not the effect. Unlike some other New
confession. School professors, like Nancy Fraser, he
does not muse against progressive liber-
Can Democracy Work? offers a history alism. (He may well be one of them pro-
of democratic and despotic episodes, a gressive liberals – a Deweyan optimist.)
set of comparisons and parallels, empir- As Rousseau himself, Miller is not a
ically informed insights in the genre of theorist of political economy. The story
history of ideas, biography and political about hegemonic bloc associated with
history. It is penned by an old skeptic the destruction of the middle class, to be
still wanting to believe in democracy, politically assailed with justice as recog-

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
warning the reader of its pitfalls. It skill- nition and (re)distribution (from the ac-
fully poses the problem of democracy, ademic corridors), is simply not his cup
by warning about its dark side, its (auto) of tea. He is no social justice warrior as,
destructive force coming out of the un- on the other hand, a vision of democra-
healthy association of demagogues and cy as a militaristic ethnic nativist band
mobs but it also offers some enthusiasm of brothers is as far as possible from his
for the possibilities opened by the dem- normative universe of the true and the
ocratic vistas. In the end, Miller per- good. Moreover, it seems to me that
haps wrote a book that more resembles Miller doesn't attempt to solve the riddle
a repetitive fugue than to an evolving by the means of a theory of distributive
genealogy, a recollection of democrat- justice: the problem of who should get
ic episodes perhaps making a step for- what and when – and how this should be
ward in history with vague promises of solved, e.g. by market, love, religion, war,
collective freedom and empowerment, struggle, collective will (or whatever) – is
but too often mutating into destructive not his problem. As he is no Rawls, he is
hecatombs. Since people seem to have no Alasdair MacIntyre. He doesn't seem
passions and interests, and society is not to have a substantive telos in the sense of
and cannot be an impassioned scholas- a "comprehensive doctrine". He is a lib-
tic seminar, as Miller's historical analysis eral. His darling metaphor is hijacking:
exemplifies, Miller's more precise solu- democracy is hijacked by the bad guys,
tion, as far as one can surmise, would violent fanatics or simply sadists. It's an
not propose a Habermasian deliberative old threat lurking from the Greek times
democracy for democracy to work. He when democracy sentenced Socrates to
seems to be quite clear about that. Gen- death, suggesting it can become a bigger
erally speaking, he also doesn't seem to tyranny than any oligarchy. Can Democ-
buy the story of positively reevaluating racy Work? is in that sense also a story of
populism, a taming of the notoriously various hijackers destroying liberal pro-
violent Schmittian political proposed by tections far beyond the episodes of civic
Laclau and Mouffe. As he seems to ab- or intraparty disobedience, employing
hor the occasional cruelty of the masses, buses or provisional protest tents.
or doesn't see the constructive point in
the direct democratic discussions, he However, all that said, Miller still pro-
as well despises the facility of armchair fesses a democratic faith in the tradition
245

philosophy dealing with democracy, ig- of Whitman and Dewey. He shares a


noring its real historical dynamics. picture with them of a democratic cul-
ture, maybe hopelessly intertwined with be religious: a secularized puritanism
liberalism, perhaps a telos itself, elusive will easily find new witches to hunt. In
and uncertain, as Whitman's visions. other words, a democratic society may
This is not a forced reading. Albeit the not constitute a brake but a fuel for the
skeptical irony and self-awareness of fire of despotism. This is not problem
ethnocentric, even idiosyncratic na- that, in my opinion, preoccupies Miller
ture of this faith, or perhaps any faith, seriously enough. Be it as it may, a his-
Miller's democratic belief is clearly ex- torical sociology of political religions
pressed. It is a paradox of credo quia ab- could tell a part of the story about this
surdum. With a reference to Whitman democratic faith since the sources of the
and a question mark, Miller still sees self are historical, cultural and politi-
democracy as "future-oriented" (10), cal. And the personal dimension of the
as any faith is, and starts his story with faith?
a rational reflection upon his political
faith: "it is also a deeply personal nar- Miller is not shy about it. When he
rative, if only because I am inescapably writes of Mazzini, "[t]he child of a Jaco-
the product of a typically modern dem- bin father and a Jansenist mother" who
ocratic faith that was drummed into me "tried to reconcile the democratic prin-
from birth. This makes it hard for me to ciples of his father with the austere faith
draw a sharp line between my consid- of his mother" (145), it almost reads
ered political beliefs and an internalized like an oblique autobiographic refer-
ideology that, in fact, typifies the present ence. On the one side, it's the story of
age" (12). the father, not a fully-fledged Jacobin
to be sure, but an academic expert on
It then remains to be answered at the Whitman. Miller was "raised to revere
end of this essay what is the nature of Walt Whitman" whose "strange vision"
this faith, surviving even the dark fina- of democracy, in Miller's interpretation,
le of the book? It is perhaps something becomes "a prophecy, a voice raised to
typically American, as Miller again ad- keep faith with a future to which our
mits at the very end. There is historical shared past has committed us", and "a
and personal dimension to this ques- supreme fiction," with a reference to
tion of faith. In the third chapter, Mill- elusive "orgastic future" from Fitzger-
er reminds the reader that Tocqueville ald's The Great Gatsby: "But this is what
saw "America's political piety at work", democracy in America often seems like:
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.

observing a "civic religion, rooted in an elusive fantasy, forever out of reach,


a Protestant form", a species of demo- forever unrealized, even as its most elo-
cratic and republican Christianity: he quent bards, trapped in their own prej-
understood this as a moderating fac- udices, are 'borne ceaselessly back into
tor, "a brake on the potential wildness the past'" (131). And how can we reach
of self-reliant self-rule" (115). However, the author's mother? If the book has a
when bereft of pathos, a much bleaker prelude and a coda, Dewey is, musically
outlook of a tyranny, not of state but of speaking, the bridge between democra-
society, could emerge, following another cy and religion, leading us to the part of
Tocqueville's insight. Instead of a socie- the story about the mother. Miller writes
tal culture working against political tyr- about Dewey's "disarming candor";
anny, one can imagine a society self-sat- Dewey was a philosopher of democracy,
isfied and unaware of its own potential but "explicit about the religious motives
246

for tyranny, quite zealous to uphold to behind an ostensibly scientific theory",


its tradition of witch hunts. It need not claiming that the next prophet who will
succeed "in pointing out the religious Albeit all the skepticism, Miller is still
meaning of democracy" (202). able to project hope on the American
democratic project. He warns us, associ-
On the other side of this Deweyan
ating this with Wilson's understanding
bridge, we can then see how the moth-
of democracy, that democracy rests on
er sets the tone. She provides the spirit
public opinion as do the interpretations
to infuse the democratic form with a
of no less than our "deepest moral and
religious belief, as Dewey tried to do.
political convictions": "Unlike Martin
Miller writes: "And I was taught that I
Luther, Woodrow Wilson was taking
had a duty (my mother believed it was
a stand on shifting sands" (182). That
God-given) to make this exceptional
may be the most important single sen-
society an even better place, in part by
tence in the whole book. It points to
exercising my political rights, not only
the riddle of democratic faith. How can
to vote but also to think for myself and
one believe when a history of collective

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
to speak out against perceived injus-
tices" (7). Democracy is a moral duty visions of justice and good life of Rous-
in the historical struggle for justice. But seauians giving themselves to each and
will the good prevail in this Manichean every other citizen at the same time,
story that suddenly acquires an almost and thus in theory not giving oneself
eschatological telos? An anecdote may to no one, looks like a history of those
help here. I remember how, after a sym- foolish enough to give themselves to
posium in his apartment, Miller pointed demagogues and despots, witch-hunts
to the apocalyptic illustrations in a re- and propaganda? In other words, what
printed 16th century Lutheran Bible, and a strange faith, to entrust oneself to the
exclaimed, perhaps ironically: "These whims of a historical political mecha-
are my people".5 Democratic faith, in nism built on shifting sands, certainly
this strange perspective, appears like not stranger than a belief in God. To
a political sublimation of a mysterium justify the belief in democracy with its
coniunctionis, a mystical synthesis of record of hecatombs becomes almost a
the opposites in the familial tree of life: theodicy, an old and demanding spiritu-
"father" and "mother," bringing together al sport of justifying the belief in God in
hope for democracy with some hints of spite of all the suffering in the history of
a dark eschatology. A secularized faith the world.
in liberal democracy is still religious in
its spiritual core. Unlike Ken Toole's Ignatius Reilly,
lamenting on the horrors of decadence
5
In case the reader is still wondering how
come I wrote such a lengthy essay concer-
brought about by democracy in Amer-
ning yet another book on democracy: I've ica, there are those still dreaming, at
spent two autumn semesters as a visiting least because they cannot see a viable
scholar at the New School. Miller was my alternative, as the theodicies have no
academic host, I read the book before pub- choice but to accept this world with all
lication and I am credited in the acknowl-
its horrors. This is the book for them. It
edgments. If there was a Dionysian social-
ism, referring to the fact that Praxis school is not a condemnation of a farcical "con-
philosophers and their German colleagues federacy of dunces" but an exercise in
periodically discussed the intricacies of political spirituality. It espouses a belief
"Being" with the little help of red wine, Mill- in democracy after all – a belief which
er's symposia can perhaps be described as a
is, to be sure, bereft of all rationalistic
species of Dionysian liberalism. No wonder
that they did not take place on Korčula or protection of the American reception
247

in Dubrovnik, but in a small Manhattan of French Hegelianism. It is a pure pro-


apartment crammed with books and CDs. fession of faith in the dark times. It is
neither Kojève's history vindicating its Can Democracy Work? are thus much
own rationality, as Fukuyama, a recent more modest. It is a testimony of a frag-
theorist of political decay, ended his still ile democratic faith in the times of Hun-
most famous book, nor a sad time from tington's clash. The sympathetic readers
the vantage point of political boredom, may only hope that democracy will pre-
as he intimated earlier in his famous vail and that the clash will not turn into
article. The wedding of a historical a tangible apocalypse prophesized by
Weltgeist and American democracy has religious eschatologies as depicted in an
ended up in a divorce. The ambitions of illustrated Lutherbibel.

References
Miller, James. 1984. Rousseau: Dreamer World? New York: Farrar, Straus &
of Democracy. New Haven: Yale Uni- Giroux.
versity Press. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887a. Fragment
Miller, James. 1994. Democracy is in from Autumn 1887 (group 9, no. 25).
the Streets. Cambridge, MA: Harvard http://www.nietzschesource.org/#eK-
University Press. GWB/NF-1887,9[25]. Accessed Octo-
Miller, James. 2012. Examined Lives: ber 15th 2018.
From Socrates to Nietzsche. New York: Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887b. Zur Genea-
Picador. logie der Moral: Eine Streitschrift.
Miller, James. 2018. Can Democracy Leipzig: C. G, Neumann. http://www.
Work? A Short History of a Radi- nietzschesource.org/#eKGWB/GM.
cal Idea from Ancient Athens to Our Accessed October 15th 2018
Anali Hrvatskog politiološkog društva 2018.
248
Kako to da liberal još uvijek vjeruje u demokraciju?
Zagonetka politike i vjere

Povodom knjige Jamesa Millera


Može li demokracija biti djelotvorna?
Kratka povijest radikalne ideje od antičke Atene do danas
New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2018.
Sažetak Ovaj se kritički esej bavi knjigom Može li demokracija biti djelotvorna? Ja-
mesa Millera koja, upozoravajući na probleme demokratske politike, zadržava de-
mokratsku vjeru. Kombinirajući političku znanost i historiografiju te ispreplećući
povijest ideja i političke biografije u prikazu različitih epizoda u povijesti demokra-
cije, knjiga nastoji dati uvid u zagonetku demokracije. Ta se zagonetka pokazuje u
različitim teorijskim i praktičkim napetostima: između rusoovskog zahtjeva za su-
verenošću naroda i općenite volje s jedne strane te platonističke epistemičke skep-

K. Petković, How Come a Liberal Still Believes in Democracy? A Riddle of Politics and Faith, Anali 15 (1) 231-250 (2018)
se prema sposobnosti naroda da odlučuje i političkih zahtjeva liberalizma s druge
strane; između potrebe za kontrolom vladajućih i političkoekonomske dinamike
korupcije i klijentelizma koju potiče demokratska politika; između pobuna protiv
elita kao nekovrsne političke higijenske funkcije poretka i neizvjesnih ishoda koje
donosi inherentna nestabilnost i sklonost demokracije ekscesima te između izgled-
ne nezaobilaznosti izbora i njihove kooptacijske zamke. Između liberalizma straha
na tragu Judith Shklar i populističkog uzbuđenja na tragu Chantal Mouffe, autor
zadržava demokratsku vjeru – političku inačicu kjerkagorovskog egzistencijalizma
koji stupa s onu stranu neodlučne, vječito sumnjajuće refleksije i političko dobro
koje se dijeli s drugima, unatoč svim neizvjesnostima javnog mnijenja i dokazane
upitnosti građanske vrline u otvorenom polju političkog u povijesti.
Ključne riječi demokracija, liberalizam, zagonetka, genealogija, populizam, javno
mnijenje

249

You might also like