You are on page 1of 14

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/223959775

A History of the Term Radical Behaviorism: From Watson to Skinner

Article in The Behavior analyst / MABA · April 1987


DOI: 10.1007/BF03392404 · Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS

70 3,545

2 authors:

Susan M Schneider Edward Morris


Western Michigan University University of Kansas
31 PUBLICATIONS 316 CITATIONS 126 PUBLICATIONS 2,002 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Susan M Schneider on 03 December 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


The Behavior Analyst 1987, 10, 27-39 No. 1 (Spring)

A History of the Term Radical Behaviorism:


From Watson to Skinner
Susan M. Schneider and Edward K. Morris
University of Kansas
This paper describes the origins and evolution of the term radical behaviorism. John B. Watson's coining
of behaviorism in 1913 is presented first, followed by a discussion ofthe uses of "radical" within psychology
during these early years. When the term radical behaviorism first emerged in the early 1920s, its referent
was Watson's behaviorism, most specifically his stance on consciousness. In the 1930s, B. F. Skinner
described his own position with the term radical behaviorism in an unpublished manuscript, and then in
1945 first referred in print to his views as such. Today, radical behaviorism is generally applied to Skinner's
views alone. The paper concludes with a briefdiscussion of a similarity in Watson's and Skinner's positions
on consciousness, which seems a possible historical and philosophical connection between their respective
radical behaviorisms.
Key words: radical behaviorism, behaviorism, "radical," history, John B. Watson, B. F. Skinner

Although the term radical behaviorism' behaviorism and, in particular, to suggest


today generally refers to the views of B. how Skinner's views came to be so
F. Skinner, its origins and historical evo- named.
lution remain largely unexplored. Skin- As an etymological and historical ex-
ner, himself, seems to have been the first ercise, we hope that what we present will
to use radical behaviorism in published be of interest in itself. But there is pos-
reference to his views-in his 1945 paper sibly another benefit: Our findings may
on subjective terms (Skinner, 1945, p. clarify to some degree what it is to be a
294)-but the term had existed before radical behaviorist, for by describing the
then. Indeed, Skinner had used the term origins of radical behaviorism, we are also
to describe his views in the 1930s, but in exploring the evolution of its meaning
an unpublished manuscript; moreover, (cf. Mach, 1883/1960; Skinner, 1931;
radical behaviorism was in use even prior see Marr, 1985). This does not make our
to this. The purpose of this paper, then, exercise essentially philosophical in na-
is twofold -to describe the origins and ture -for it is not. Rather, we are simply
historical evolution of the term radical suggesting that the meaning of the term
radical behaviorism may be found, in part,
in the historical evolution of its use or,
This article was written while the first author was more technically, among the variables
supported by a Graduate Honors Fellowship from
the University of Kansas, and is based on a paper that have come to control its emission
given at the 1986 meeting of the Association for (i.e., its being "tacted"; see Skinner, 1957,
Behavior Analysis, Milwaukee, WI. We would like pp. 13-14). This historical approach to-
to express our gratitude to the respondents to a letter wards understanding scientific terminol-
of inquiry on the origins of the term radical be-
haviorism, in particular, A. C. Catania, S. R. Cole- ogy may contribute to an appreciation of
man, J. A. Dinsmoor, E. Hearst, T. J. Knapp, K. what behavior analysts and others mean
MacCorquodale, B. F. Skinner, and G. Zuriff. We when speaking of radical behaviorism.
also acknowledge helpful comments on earlier ver- Finally, we would like to comment
sions of the manuscript by S. R. Coleman, Lisa M. briefly about the character of the material
Johnson, Steven E. Larsen, Bryan D. Midgley, and
James T. Todd. Reprints may be obtained from the to follow. Our research was primarily ar-
first author, Department of Human Development, chival in nature, and the raw data for our
University of Kansas, Lawrence, KS 66045. analysis are the written etymological and
' When reference is made to a technical term qua historical records of psychologists and
term, it is italicized, unless it is given as a quote philosophers who have come before us
from another source (and therefore within quota-
tion marks). Nontechnical terms are set off with (see Parrott & Hake, 1983). Just as do
quotation marks (see the Publication Manual of the other researchers, we present our data for
American PsychologicalAssociation, 3rd ed., 1983). scrutiny by the scientific community, and
27
28 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS

thus have included more quoted and he had coined these terms: "In these three
footnoted material than is usual. In doing publications [J. B. Watson, 1913a, 1913b,
so, however, we provide readers with ac- 1914] the terms 'behaviorism,' 'behav-
cess to many of the variables that led us ioristic,' and 'behaviorist' were first used"
to our conclusions. (J. B. Watson, 1927, p. 248). That Wat-
That said, let us turn to our task, first, son coined the term behaviorism and its
by describing John B. Watson's coining variants is also affirmed by his contem-
of behaviorism, and second, by discussing poraries (Boring, 1929, p. 582; Wood-
the various uses of "radical" during the worth, 1924, p. 259) and by modem et-
early years of behaviorism's develop- ymological sources (e.g., Finkenstaedt,
ment. Following that, we describe the Leisi, & Wolff, 1970, p. 1370).2 More-
emergence and evolution of radical be- over, our consultation ofdictionaries and
haviorism. psychological and philosophical works
prior to 1913 did not turn up any pre-
BEHA VIORISM vious use of the term. Warren (1914b, p.
The term behaviorism as now used rep- 11) suggested that Angell coined the term
resents so many different points of view, independently (see also Rucker, 1969, pp.
and these will change so frequently during 38-39), but the first use we located by
the next decade that the word "behavior- Angell (1913, p. 261) was accompanied
ism" will hardly survive. (Weiss, 1929, p. by a citation to Watson's (1913b) paper.
147) Perhaps this new name, as well as Wat-
son's energy and ability in disseminating
Originally, there was just one behav- behaviorism and applying it to practical
iorism-Watson's, and Watson was ap- concerns, helped it quickly to become an
parently the first to use the term (and its object of psychological, philosophical,
variants) in print. He did so in his 1913 and public discussion. Restricting our-
challenge to psychology, "Psychology as selves to the first, psychologists certainly
the Behaviorist Views It" (J. B. Watson, began discussing the perspective under
1913b). To quote from the classic intro- its new name without delay. For exam-
duction of Watson's (1913b) manifesto: ple, as alluded to above, in the second
Psychology as the behaviorist views it is a purely issue of the Psychological Review after
objective experimental branch of natural science. the one containing Watson's (1913b) be-
... Introspection forms no essential part of its haviorist manifesto, Angell (1913, pp.
methods, nor is the scientific value of its data de- 261, 264) cited Watson's article and used
pendent upon the readiness with which they lend the term behaviorist; and in 1914, in the
themselves to interpretation in terms of conscious- same journal, both Bode (1914) and War-
ness. The behaviorist ... recognizes no dividing
line between man and brute. (p. 158) ren (1914a) published articles using Wat-
son's terminology. The new terms also
Although not entirely original, these rec- appeared before long in journals such as
ommendations were bolder and more far- the Psychological Bulletin (see, e.g., Wells,
reaching than those of Watson's prede- 1913) and the Journal ofPhilosophy, Psy-
cessors (Burnham, 1968; Harrell & Har- chology, and Scientific Methods (see, e.g.,
rison, 1938, pp. 368-369, 373-375, 380; Melville, 1914, p. 357). Although occa-
Leahey, 1980, pp. 287-295; Marx & Hil- sionally enclosed in quotation marks
lix, 1979, pp. 126-132), and essentially even as late as 1953 ("so-called 'Behav-
established behaviorism as a system of iourists,' "Drew & George, p. 173)-the
psychology. term behaviorism and its variants caught
In 1914, Watson commented on his on quickly.
choice of words to describe his new psy-
chology: "A few terms have been used in "RADICAL"
this discussion of behavior-such as be- The year 1913 marks the birth of the
haviorist, behavioristic, behaviorism. ... most radical ofallpsychological concepts,
it is admitted that these words sound
somewhat barbaric on a first hearing" (p. 2 For an account of the etymology of "behavior"

1). Later, Watson stated more clearly that in general, see Williams (1976, pp. 35-37).
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 29

that of "behaviorism. " (J. S. Moore, 1921, jective terms in their definition of the science and
p. 31) to prefer the simple statement that Psychology is
the science of behavior. (J. S. Moore, 1921, p. 29)
The standard dictionary definitions of The two most radical doctrines put forward by
"radical" have remained basically the the behaviorist are, first, that consciousness does
same throughout this century (see Wil- not exist, and second, that psychology should whol-
liams, 1976, pp. 209-21 1 for an etymolo- ly abandon the introspective method. (Washburn,
gy of "radical"). Warren's 1934 Diction- 1922, p. 89)
ary of Psychology provides a good The most radical of [animal psychologists, with
summary of psychological use: "radi- an allusion to Watson] are for excluding altogether
cal = a loose term signifying thorough- the study ofconsciousness. (Woodworth, 1922, pp.
29-30)
going or extreme. [Lit. going to the root]
[sic].... in psychology it is usually ap- Second, in its senses of both extreme and
plied loosely to the holder of any very iconoclastic:
unusual views" (pp. 221-222). The re- For Watson, however, behavior and consciousness
lated uses of radical as "iconoclastic" and were mutually exclusive, and to define psychology
"political" are also found in psychology. as the science of behavior meant making a radical
The word "radical" has been used often departure and ruling out all introspection, all ref-
in psychology in these four senses-ex- erence to consciousness, and, as he conceived, prac-
tically all of psychology as it had developed up to
treme, thoroughgoing, iconoclastic, and 1912. (Woodworth, 1931, p. 51)
political-of which all might be relevant There have come down wolf-like on the psycho-
to the term radical behaviorism. Radical logical fold the already mentioned behaviourists.
in the sense of thoroughgoing, however, The most extreme of these would deny to man the
is found less frequently in the literature power of observing his own consciousness at all;
and on the radical ground that, in truth, no such
(e.g., Morgan, 1922, p. 162) and was pre- consciousness is known to exist! (Spearman, 1937,
sumably less influential, and will not be p. 79)
discussed here (but see Michael, 1985, Third, in its general political sense,
pp. 100I 0 1 for a current interpretation "radical" has often implied the far left
of "radical" behaviorism as thorough- (cf. Williams, 1976, pp. 209-211). Cor-
going). Some pertinent and representa- respondingly, during the early years of
tive examples of the other three usages
from the period of early behaviorism fol- behaviorism, an analogy was occasion-
low, both from before and after the first ally drawn between the far left and "rad-
use of radical behaviorism in 1921 (Calk- ical" views of consciousness and intro-
ins, 1921). These selections illustrate that spection (e.g., Jastrow, 1927, p. 175 for
"radical" in psychology often referred to a reference to Watsonian radical behav-
an "extreme" or "iconoclastic" depar- iorism as "this extreme left wing of Be-
ture from the widely accepted views on haviorism"; see also Pear, 1922, p. 231;
consciousness and the use of introspec- Warden, Jenkins, & Warner, 1934, p. 3;
tion. First, in its sense of "extreme": the analogy to the far right, however, may
also be found3). We might also note that
To be a science, [psychology] must turn its back on radicalism itself was occasionally a sub-
all purely private data, and concern itself with ma- ject matter for psychology in the early
terial as objective as that which the physicist or 1920s (e.g., Wolfe, 1921), and discus-
biologist studies.... As one would expect, this rad-
ical suggestion has not escaped criticism. (Jones, sions of it may have had some influence
1915, p. 469) over the general use of "radical" in psy-
Now comes Professor Bode, and accuses me of
chology.
not being sufficiently and consistently radical.... That "radical" should come to be
According to him, Professor Lovejoy and myself paired with behaviorism, then, is perhaps
both ruin our arguments at the outset by postulating
a transcendent power of thought. (Dunlap, 1916, p.
53) 3 "1... the left wing, made up of those who con-
fine their attention to the introspection of their
The close relationship offunctionalist psychology own mental states, 'experience subjectively regard-
to biology, however, has led many of the more rad- ed'; that keen and fighting band on the right, which
ical followers ofthis general viewpoint (as Pillsbury refuses to truckle with 'consciousness' and con-
and W. McDougall) to renounce all mental or sub- siders only behavior" (Humphrey, 1929, p. 59).
30 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS
not surprising. "Radical" also became a conscious entities, however, was com-
modifier in other psychological termi- patible with Watson's views, and this fact
nology, such as radicalfunctionalism (J. was not lost on psychologists (see, e.g.,
S. Moore, 1921, p. 31) and radical pos- the title and foreword of the behaviorist
itivism (D. L. Evans, 1924, p. 348). A Holt's 1931 text).4 Although there is no
similar term- radical empiricism -which direct evidence for a connection between
possibly influenced the use of "radical" radical empiricism and the naming of
in psychology, and the naming of radical radical behaviorism, it seems not unlikely
behaviorism, originates from the field of that William James at least contributed
philosophy. to the linguistic Zeitgeist that led to that
naming.
Radical Empiricism
In the 1900s, William James intro- WATSONIAN RADICAL
duced radical empiricism, which he him- BEHA VIORISM
selfnamed (James, 1904b, p. 534; Runes, Is it not true that, as in the case of our
1962, p. 90; see James, 1909, pp. xii-xiii philosophies, there are behaviorisms and
for a brief summary). Two features ofthis behaviorists? (Yerkes, 1917, p. 155)
philosophical view were described in
James's (1 904a) article, "Does 'Con- There was a time when the term 'be-
sciousness' Exist?," which was reprinted haviorism'in the title ofa speech required
as the first of James's Essays in Radical no further specification. Every psycholo-
Empricism. One feature reflects James's gist at least knew the referent to be that
stance on consciousness, which seems new brand of psychology, introduced by
compatible with Watson's: Watson, which proposed to break with
tradition and deny that psychology had
A number of... authors seemed just on the point anything to do either with a mentalistic
of abandoning the notion ofconsciousness.... But
they were not quite radical enough.... I mean only entity called consciousness or a method
to deny that the word stands for an entity.... [There known as introspection. Today the situ-
is] no aboriginal stuff or quality of being contrasted ation is not so simple. (Spence, 1948, p.
with that of which material objects are made; but 67)
there is a function in experience which thoughts
perform, and for the performance of which this Yerkes could have pointed out to
quality of being is invoked. (James, 1904a, pp. 477- Spence that the situation was "not so
478) simple" even in 1917, for the original
A second and more central feature of behaviorism soon had rivals for its title.
James's radical empiricism is an expan- Watson had barely introduced behavior-
sion of these ontological views: ism when others who did not outright
There is only one primal stuff or material in the
accept or reject it wanted to alter it (Heid-
world, a stuff of which everything is composed, and breder, 1933, p. 260; see J. B. Watson,
if we call that stuff 'pure experience,' then knowing 1924, p. viii on "half-way behaviorists"),
can easily be explained as a particular sort of re- and modifiers were soon added to the
lation towards one another into which portions of term behaviorism in order to differentiate
pure experience may enter. (James, 1904a, p. 478) the varieties. Formal technical terms for
As this passage suggests, James's form of precisely specified referents evolved and,
anti-dualism did not imply materialism in some cases, modifiers that seemed at
(see also, e.g., Chakrabarti, 1975), though first purely descriptive became part of
Watson's did (see J. B. Watson, 1930, p. formal terminology (e.g., "extreme" in
3). As one commentator states, "It would
be an inexcusable error to think of James
as a behaviorist in the Watsonian sense 4Skinner has been referred to as a radical em-
of this term.... His radical empiricism piricist (Neel, 1977, p. 173; Spence, 1952, p. 153),
the usage is ambiguous and, at such a distance
stood in the way ofany such move" (Wild, but from James, may not be referring to James's phi-
1969, p. 365). Radical empiricism's first losophy (but see Hillner, 1984, p. 169 for a possibly
feature concerning the nonexistence of Jamesian use).
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 31

extreme behaviorism, which, when for- extreme behaviorists" might mean (a)
mal, lost many of its negative connota- Watson and holders of very similar views,
tions). In the first part of this section, we (b) a less specific group of psychologists
examine the use of some modifiers other and philosophers, or (c) the extremeness
than "radical" and "Watsonian." We then of the views of either group. In any case,
discuss the first published reference to other than radical behaviorism, extreme
radical behaviorism that we were able to behaviorism was the term we found most
locate (Calkins, 1921). Finally, we trace often as the designation for Watson's
the usage of the term for Watson's psy- psychology.
chology from the 1920s through 1955. Of the other labels, strict behaviorism
Watson himself, by the way, is not known first appeared in the same article where
to have used the term radical behavior- radical behaviorism originated (strict be-
ism, and in going through his writing, we haviorism was used in a footnote in Calk-
did not come across it. (See, however, J. ins, 1921, p.4, and then by Lashley, 1923
B. Watson, 1913a, p. 421, repeated in and Roback, 1923), and occurred fairly
1914, p. 16, for a use of "radical" in often, relatively speaking, but apparently
connection with his denial of imagery, only in the twenties and very early thir-
and J. B. Watson, 1920, p. 54, for a use ties. Its formal use by McDougall (1926)
of "radical" with reference to thinking as in Psychologies of 1925 may have con-
only a reflection of behavior.) tributed to strict behaviorism's popular-
ity during this period. Other modifiers for
Other Termsfor Watsonian Behaviorism Watsonian or near-Watsonian behavior-
ism or behaviorists between 1912 and
As described in the last section, "rad- 1955 included "monistic" (Weiss, 1919,
ical" was a common descriptor for be- p. 327), "orthodox" (Wieman, 1919, p.
havioristic ideas and, as might be ex- 241), "parallelistic" (Kantor, 1921, p.
pected, several of the synonyms of radical 231), "pure" (Gregory, 1922, p. 586),
given above -"extreme" and "thorough- "ideal" (Weiss, 1924, p. 48), "meta-
going"-were also used in conjunction physical" (Brightman, 1930, p. 309),
with behaviorism. Thoroughgoing behav- "negative" (Dotterer, 1933, p. 198),
iorism, however, occurred only infre- "classical" (Heidbreder, 1933, p. 276),
quently, apparently beginning in 1921 (J. "physiological" (Pepper, 1934, p. 110),
S. Moore, 1921, p. 33). and "rigid" (Young, 1943, p. 27). Two
"Extreme" was probably the most further designations were "behaviorist of
common adjective used in connection the severe type" (Young, 1924, p. 292)
with behaviorism for many years, and may and "ultra-behaviorists" (Garrison, 1930,
still be found today (e.g., Chaplin & Kra- p. 163). All of these terms, however, seem
wiec, 1979, p. 55; see Margolis, 1984, p. to have been used infrequently.
34 for a reference to Skinner as an "ex- We might point out that so many mod-
treme behaviorist"). Back in 1914, Sidis ifiers were available that authors some-
referred to Watson's "extreme view of times switched from one to another, even
the denial of introspection" (p. 44; see in the same work. A good example ofthis
also Marvin, 1914, p. 3). Then, in 1915, is Roback's (1923) use of four different
extreme behaviorists (MacIntosh, 1915, terms: "behaviorism in its extreme form"
p. 277) and extreme behaviorism (Mar- (p. 138), "orthodox behaviorism" (p.
vin, 1915, p. 14) appeared and began to 187), "thoroughgoing behaviorist" (p.
be used. In general, the modifier was used 217), and "strict behaviorists" (p. 271).
to emphasize the differences between
Watsonian (or close-to-Watsonian, e.g., Radical Behaviorism
Weissian) views and more traditional
views. Usage was both descriptive and The first apparent use of radical be-
formal, a distinction that may be impos- haviorism in print is, interestingly, large-
sible to make. For instance, without ad- ly formal. In the first article of the 1921
equate context, an author referring to "the volume of the Psychological Review,
32 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS

Calkins compared and contrasted three Review, the foremost theoretical journal
forms of behaviorism: Warren's "mod- in psychology then as now. For example,
ified behavioristic psychology," Calkins' Warren used radical behaviorist later in
own "behavioristic self-psychology," and 1921 (p. 463) in a Psychological Review
what she called Watson's "radical be- article on visual after-effects. He was not
haviorism." The crucial feature setting replying to Calkins' paper, but it seems
apart Watson from the other two was his possible that he picked up the term from
position on consciousness: "Extreme be- that source, especially since his use is for-
havioristic psychology denies or ignores mal.7 Wheeler (1923) also used the term
what are known as mental phenomena" formally. Koffka (1924, p. 160) and Sell-
(Calkins, 1921, p. 1; see also p. 4). Calk- ars (1926, p. 315) are worth citing here
ins, who had earlier spoken of her "rad- to illustrate the spread of the term to
ical disagreement with Watson's main journals outside of the Psychological Re-
thesis" (1913, p. 289), went on to de- view and outside of the country. Finally,
scribe Watson as "the most prominent Jastrow's (1927) argument against radi-
upholder of radically behavioristic psy- cal behaviorism shows that the original
chology" (1921, p. 2), and then intro- reactions to and descriptions of behav-
duced the terms radical behaviorists (p. iorism were still very much current. Jas-
4) and radical behaviorism (p. 5). As trow spoke of "the tilting by the radical
mentioned, strict behaviorism was used behaviorists against the windmills of
once in this article in a footnote (p. 4). consciousness" (p. 173).
Although Calkins did not make consis- In the 1930s, the denial or ignoring of
tent use of radical behaviorism thereafter consciousness was still seen as the main
(e.g., she did not use it in Calkins, 1930), feature of radical behaviorism (e.g., Carr,
the term she apparently originated was 1930, p. 77; McDougall, 1930, p. 42).
soon accepted within psychology.5 Although fewer articles were written con-
Not surprisingly, most of the other oc- cerning Watson during this period, com-
currences of radical behaviorism during pared to the 1920s (Logue, 1985, p. 178;
the 1920S6 were also in the Psychological R. I. Watson, 1976), nearly as many ci-
tations using radical behaviorism (or its
variants) can be listed; thus, perhaps rad-
I The type of enterprise to which radical behav-
ical behaviorism had more clearly be-
iorism refers, however, has not always been clear. come an established formal term. For ex-
In Watson's time, behaviorism (i.e., his radical be-
haviorism) was considered, singly or in various ample, whereas Roback had not used the
combinations, a program, science, method, and/or term in 1923, he did in his second anti-
philosophy (see, e.g., Brightman, 1930, p. 309; behaviorism book (1937, pp. 150, 152).8
Burnham & Wheelwright, 1932, p. 328; Calverton,
1924, pp. 422-423; Rall, 1930, pp. 290-291;
Woodworth, 1924, p. 260). Watson's own view on ofinterest. In addition, where pertinent, entire jour-
this matter was that behaviorism had started out nal volumes and books were examined. The total
cautiously as method and then become "a true nat- search for information on Watsonian radical be-
ural science" (J. B. Watson, 1930, p. 19; cf. J. B. haviorism (and also on early Skinnerian radical be-
Watson, 1927, p. 249). Later, Skinner treated the haviorism) covered the period 1912-1955; how-
features separately. For him, "Behaviorism is not ever, because the subject was discussed less
the science of human behavior; it is the philosophy frequently over time, the years after the early 1930s
of that science" (1974, p. 3; see also 1964, p. 79; were checked less thoroughly.
but cf. 1979, p. 331). 7 It is, of course, possible that Warren coined the
6 About a dozen references using the term radical
behaviorism or its variants were located in our search term independently. If the quick manuscript turn-
of the professional literature of the 1920s. This may around time of 1913 (see description ofAngell [1913]
not seem like very many, but it was more than any in the section on behaviorism) is any guide, how-
comparable term for Watsonian or near-Watsonian ever, Warren, whose article was published in No-
views. The search consisted largely of a check of vember, might reasonably have seen the Calkins
the indexes and tables of contents of the books and article (January issue) before final changes had been
journals of the period. Articles and book chapters made in his manuscript.
that appeared relevant because of their titles or au- 8 Roback (1937, p. 197) also cites a doctoral dis-
thors, as well as text material indexed by "Watson," sertation on the history of radical behaviorism
"behaviorism," etc., were searched thoroughly for (Diehl, 1932-listed by Roback as 1934, under a
the occurrence of radical behaviorism or other items shorter title).
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 33

And Harrell and Harrison (1938) used invented the phrase 'radical behavior-
the term extensively in their comprehen- ism.' I think it was in the air at the time"
sive paper, "The Rise and Fall of Behav- (personal communication, January 31,
iorism"-in which they referred to "the 1985). Clearly, in the early 1930s, the
recent demise ofradical behaviorism" (p. term was still current for Watson's views,
381). Indeed, by this time, Watson had and Skinner had, perhaps, come across
been out of psychology for some years, it in his contacts with the philosophy and
and his behaviorism was virtually mor- psychology of the time (see Coleman,
ibund. 1985, for some of these). Further, Skin-
Correspondingly, few references to ner's depiction of radical behaviorism is,
Watsonian radical behaviorism as such in some respects, in accord with Wat-
are to be found in the literature of the son's philosophical views, as is suggested
1940s and early 1950s (but see, e.g., Grif- in the last major section of our paper, as
fith's 1943 chapter section, "Radical Be- well as in what follows.
haviorism"). As Watson's version of be- In the Sketch, methodological behav-
haviorism faded, however, B. F. Skinner iorism was described as a position that
was in the process of fashioning his own distinguishes between the scientifically
version, based partly on Watson's (Skin- amenable public and the scientifically
ner, 1976, pp. 298-301; 1979, pp.4, 115). untreatable private. Many behaviorists
He began using the term radical behav- since Watson, and even some present-
iorism as well. day psychologists who might not call
themselves behaviorists, could be con-
sidered to be behaviorists ofthis sort (see
SKINNERIAN RADICAL Brunswik, 1952, p. 66-67; Day, 1980, p.
BEHA VIORISM 241; Leahey, 1984, pp. 131-132; Marx
[Skinnerian] radical behaviorist philos- & Hillix, 1979, p. 160). But, as Skinner
ophy as explicit, extant doctrine can rea- stated in his autobiography, occasionally
sonably be timedfrom Skinner's 1945 pa- quoting from the Sketch, "I preferred the
per, "The operational analysis of position of radical behaviorism, in which
psychological terms. " It was this extraor- the existence of subjective entities is de-
dinary work that put the "radical" in rad- nied. I proposed to regard subjective
ical behaviorism. (Marr, 1984, p. 356) terms 'as verbal constructs, as grammat-
ical traps into which the human race in
In Skinner's 1945 paper mentioned by the development of language has fall-
Marr above, not only did Skinner first en'" (Skinner, 1979, p. 117). This view
discuss philosophical matters in any of subjective terms is similar to one pre-
depth, but he first referred in print to his sented by Watson in Behaviorism (1930,
philosophy as "radical" behaviorism P. 10).
(Skinner, 1945, p. 294)-apparently the These points in the Sketch are expand-
first time anyone had done so. In this ed in Skinner's 1945 paper, where his first
section, we trace the use of the term for published use of radical behaviorism (p.
Skinner's views. 294) occurs in connection with another
As a postgraduate at Harvard in the discussion of the distinction between
early 1930s, Skinner was "at work on methodological and radical behaviorism.
something called A Sketch for an Epis- Also reminiscent of topics discussed in
temology" (Skinner, 1979, p. 15). In this the Sketch, Skinner (1945) wrote that
Sketch, Skinner made a not uncommon early behaviorism did not fulfill its po-
distinction between what he called "rad- tential because "it never finished an ac-
ical behaviorism" (his own view) and ceptable formulation of the 'verbal re-
"methodological behaviorism" (see Day, port.'19' The conception ofbehavior which
1983; J. Moore, 1981). Why did Skinner
use the term radical behaviorism in this 9 Both Watson and Skinner acknowledged the po-
manner in the Sketch? In response to our tential inaccuracy and unreliability of verbal reports
inquiry concerning his early usage of the in general (Skinner, 1979, p. 119, quoting from the
term, Skinner stated, "I don't believe I Sketch; J. B. Watson, 1924, p. 42).
34 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS
[early behaviorism] developed could not ness, verbal behavior, and private events
convincingly embrace the 'use of sub- were elaborated on in more detail in 1953
jective terms' " (p. 271). Skinner's paper and then in Verbal Behavior (1957), where
is largely an analysis of how a verbal he used the term radical behaviorism for
community might teach its members to the second time (p. 459). Later, he used
use subjective terms in describing their the term in further discussion of philo-
private events (e.g., toothaches). sophical matters, including problems
Given these correspondences in cov- concerning private events and conscious-
erage between the Sketch and the 1945 ness, in his important paper, "Behavior-
paper, it seems quite possible that Skin- ism at Fifty" (1963, p. 951; or see 1964,
ner might have used the term radical be- p. 80; see also p. 106)."
haviorism in his 1945 paper due to the Returning to the general chronology of
influence of the Sketch on the manuscript usage, from about 1940 to about 1960,
that eventually became Verbal Behavior radical behaviorism was being used in-
(Skinner, 1957), for earlier versions of frequently by others to refer to Watson,
this latter manuscript were the source for as we have seen, or to Skinner. Skinner-
the 1945 paper (Skinner, 1979, p. 294; ian psychology, itself, was typically given
1983, p. 395). Two other possible influ- other labels during this period,'2 one of
ences on Skinner's choice of term in 1945 the most common of which was descrip-
can also be provided. First, in The Be- tive behaviorism (esp. Hilgard, 1948, p.
havior of Organisms, Skinner cited (1938, 116;'3 also, e.g., Marx, 1951, p. 439;
p. 35) a paper that used the term radical Munn, 1950, p. 364; Stolurow, 1953, p.
behavioristic psychology (Kantor, 1933, 77). "Descriptive" stuck for some time,
p. 330). And second, Pratt (1945, p. 263) though Skinner did not use it (and even
mentioned "radical behaviorists" (prob- Hilgard did not use it in the second edi-
ably Watsonian, but his use is ambigu- tion [1956] of the influential Theories of
ous) in his paper for the same special Learning). According to Skinner, " 'De-
issue of the Psychological Review on op- scriptive behaviorism' is too close to mere
erationism for which Skinner's paper was structuralism. We are dealing with func-
written. The contributors' papers were tional relations. They are not carried by
circulated prior to publication so that fol- 'radical behaviorism,' either but no con-
low-up comments could be included trary suggestion is made" (personal com-
(Langfeld, 1945, p. 241; Skinner, 1979, munication, March 4, 1986).'4 In any
p. 295). Skinner thus had an opportunity event, from the mid- 1960s on, use of the
to see Pratt's paper, and we might note term radical behaviorism for Skinner's
that Skinner used the term radical be- views began to take hold within psy-
haviorism only in his follow-up section.'0
As we have seen, not only did Skinner
first refer in print in 1945 to his philos-
ophy as radical behaviorism, but he also "Bibliographies by Epstein (1982) and Knapp
described one of the most important and (1974) were used in conducting the seach of Skin-
ner's works.
unique features of that philosophy for the 12 See, however, Scriven (1956, p. 88), who used
first time-its treatment of private events radical behaviorism with reference to Skinner's views
(Day, 1983, p. 94; Marr, 1984, p. 356; on private events.
Michael, 1985, p. 117). Skinner's treat- II Hilgard states that: "[Skinner] prefers a
straight
ments of the related areas of conscious- descriptive account of what is found in experi-
ments. It is because of this preference that his sys-
tem has been referred to in the title of this chapter
as a descriptive behaviorism. It might have been
10 The term radical operationists was used in one called equally well a positivistic behaviorism" (1948,
of the questions on operationism that were circu- p. 135).
lated to the contributors beforehand in order to 14 Skinner has also had some doubts about the
focus their discussions (Langfeld, 1945, p. 242). term behaviorism, due to its connection with the
Radical operationists were said to equate the mean- denial of genetic differences falsely attributed to
ing of a quantitative concept with the operations Watson (Skinner, 1979, p. 331; cf. R. I. Evans,
used to define the concept. 1968/1981, p. 24).
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 35
chology.'5 In 1973, for example, Keller Just as Skinner made a distinction
noted that Skinner's system "has been between methodological and radical
called descriptive behaviorism or, more behaviorism, Lashley (1923) had earlier
recently, radical behaviorism" (p. 133). presented an incisive account of behav-
In the 1970s and 1980s, a review of ioristic views ofconsciousness (that Wat-
behavioral journals (e.g., Behaviorism, son praised in 1924, p. viii) contrasting
The Behavior Analyst, and Journal ofthe "methodological behaviorism" (a very
ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior) shows early use of this term) and "strict behav-
that radical behaviorism is the commonly iorism" (equivalent to Watsonian radical
accepted designation for Skinner's phil- behaviorism).'6 For methodological be-
osophical views among behaviorists (see haviorism, Lashley wrote, "Facts of con-
Footnote 5 on the term's referent). The scious experience exist but are unsuited
term has also been used in the same sense, to any form of scientific treatment. This
but to a lesser extent, in the general psy- is the most common formulation of the
chological and philosophical literature (e.g., behaviorist's position. It seems to have
Fodor, 1981, pp. 114-116; Kaufman, been Watson's view in his earlier writ-
1967, p. 272; Mackintosh, 1983, p. 56). ings" (p. 238). As Lashley noted, how-
ever, methodological behaviorism's ac-
FROM WATSON TO SKINNER count of consciousness had some
[Skinnerian] radical behaviorism is the potential drawbacks, one of the most
direct intellectual heir of classical Wat- prominent of which was that "as long as
sonian behaviorism. (Hillner, 1984, p. [the behaviorist] admits the existence of
168; see also Buss, 1979, p. 12; Leahey, a universe of consciousness he lays open
1984, p. 132; Wolman, 1981, p. 137) to attack his major premise, that behav-
iorism can account for all human activ-
To whatever extent the quotation ities" (p. 240). Lashley stated, "Watson
above is true, it is fitting that, after Wat- seems now to have abandoned this po-
son, Skinner should "inherit" the title of sition for the more extreme one" (p. 239),
radical behaviorist and become its chief that is, strict behaviorism, in which
proponent. Although their philosophical the supposedly unique facts of consciousness do not
and scientific perspectives differ in im- exist. An account of the behavior of the physiolog-
portant ways (see Leahey, 1980, chaps. ical organism leaves no residue of pure psychics.
10, 11, 12; Marx & Hillix, 1979, chaps. Mind is behavior and nothing else. This view is
6, 10; Skinner, 1974, e.g., pp. 244-245), implied in much of Watson's writing, although it
is not stated in so many words.... This is the ex-
the use of the same term to describe both treme behavioristic view. It makes no concessions
views may not be entirely inappropriate: to dualistic psychology and affirms the continuity
Both Watson and Skinner have promot- in data and method of the physical, biological, and
ed behaviorism as a natural science of psychological sciences. "Consciousness is behav-
psychology, one common aspect ofwhich ior." (p. 240)
is worth pointing out in particular. We Most historians agree that Watson be-
focus here on a major defining feature of came, at some point, a "strict behavior-
both Weltanschauungs: their treatment ist" in Lashley's sense (e.g., Harrell &
of consciousness. This feature may link Harrison, 1938, pp. 374-375; Leahey,
the two views historically, philosophi- 1984, p. 131; Marx & Hillix, 1979, p.
cally, and etymologically. 138), and that he proposed naturalistic
processes to explain the phenomena de-
scribed as "conscious" (e.g., subvocal
,s The term first appeared as an index item of the
Psychological Abstracts in 1964, in reference to
Skinner. Its appearance, however, often seems to 16 Indeed, Skinner made 4-5
pages of notes from
depend on its occurrence in a work's title. For in- this article (including its continuation later in 1923),
stance, a 1958 use of "behavior, radical" as an probably during 1928-1929 (personal communi-
index item referred to an article on Skinnerian rad- cation, S. R. Coleman, September 4, 1986; the notes
ical behaviorism which, like the 1964 paper, used are now most likely in the Harvard University Ar-
the term in its title. chives).
36 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS
thought, as in J. B. Watson, 1930, chaps. CONCLUSION
10, 11; see also Lashley, 1923, pp. 244- Currently, radical behaviorism is the
245). These views resemble Skinner's in established formal designation for B. F.
some ways, although, again, the details Skinner's philosophy ofthe science ofbe-
ofthe two theories are very different (e.g., havior. The term, however, originated in
we leave discussion of issues such as in-
tersubjective verifiability to others). reference to the views of John B. Watson,
As for Skinner's position on conscious- most likely because Watson's metaphys-
ness, his own writings are the best source ical position on controversial matters
(e.g., Skinner, 1957, chaps. 5, 19; 1964; such as the nature of consciousness was
1974, chaps. 1, 2, 14; 1980, p. 201). The considered extreme and iconoclastic. In
following can serve as a brief summary becoming a formal term, radical behav-
of his views, in which we see some sim- iorism lost many of the negative conno-
ilarities to Watson's views.'7 tations of those two descriptors, so that
today the term carries a generally more
What one observes and talks about is always the neutral meaning (or in some cases more
'real' or 'physical' world (or at least the 'one' world) positive; see, e.g., Michael, 1985, pp. 100-
and ... 'experience' is a derived construct to be 101 on "radical" meaning "thorough-
understood only through an analysis of verbal (not,
of course, merely vocal) processes. (Skinner, 1945, going").
p. 293) Although Watson himself never
A science of behavior must consider the place of pri- seemed to have used the term, Skinner
vate stimuli as physical things, and in doing so it was apparently the first to apply "radi-
provides an alternative account of mental life. The cal" to his own behaviorism, perhaps
question, then is this: What is inside the skin, and simply as an accepted and appropriate
how do we know about it? The answer is, I believe,
the heart of radical behaviorism. (Skinner, 1974, p. formal term for views bearing some re-
233) semblance to his own. In particular,
Skinner shares with Watson the view that
Ironically, however, radical behaviorists could deal consciousness is a nonexistent entity, but
with descriptions of private events, with the pro- that the events labeled "conscious" are,
vision that the descriptions were inaccurate and
perhaps never to be trusted, and that the events in principle, amenable to scientific anal-
described were physical. (Skinner, 1979, p. 295) ysis. This latter feature of Watson's and
I had heard it said that my 1945 paper on how Skinner's views-"radical" or not-can
we learn to talk about private events had brought be considered important in setting their
sensations back into behaviorism, but I was not respective radical behaviorisms apart
preserving consciousness in any form. (Skinner, from methodological behaviorism.
1983, p. 279)
Zuriff(1 984) provides further perspec- REFERENCES
tive: "What distinguishes Skinner from
... other behaviorists is not his legitimi- American Psychological Association. (1983).
zation of private events but the fact that Publication manual of the American Psycholog-
ical Association (3rd ed.). Washington, DC: Au-
he provides the most coherent account thor.
of how these events come to function as Angell, J. R. (1913). Behavior as a category of
stimuli for verbal behavior" (p. 572). In psychology. Psychological Review, 20, 255-270.
any case, to whatever extent that Skin- Bode, B. H. (1914). Psychology as a science of
ner's and Watson's later positions on behavior. Psychological Review, 21, 46-6 1.
Boring, E. G. (1929). A history of experimental
consciousness share some points of sim- psychology. New York: Appleton.
ilarity, they have been distinguished, at Brightman, E. S. (1930). Behaviorism and expe-
least, from methodological behaviorism. rience. In W. P. King (Ed.), Behaviorism: A battle
line (pp. 307-330). Nashville, TN: Cokesbury.
Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework
ofpsychology. Chicago: University of Chicago.
17 We also see in these quotations some of Skin- Bumham, J., & Wheelwright, P. (1932). Intro-
ner's views on materialism (which are not unequiv- duction to philosophical analysis. New York: Holt.
ocal-see, e.g., 1964, p. 79; 1969, p. 248; 1979, p. Bumham, J. C. (1968). On the origins of behav-
117; for commentary, see Marr, 1985, p. 134; J. iorism. Journal of the History of the Behavioral
Moore, 1985, p. 59). Sciences, 4, 143-151.
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 37
Buss, A. R. (1979). The emerging field of the so- Griffith, C. R. (1943). Principles ofsystematicpsy-
ciology ofpsychological knowledge. In A. R. Buss chology. Urbana: University of Illinois.
(Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 1-24). New Harrell, W., & Harrison, R. (1938). The rise and
York: Irvington. fall of behaviorism. Journal of General Psychol-
Calkins, M. W. (1913). Psychology and the be- ogy, 18, 367-421.
haviorist. Psychological Bulletin, 10, 288-291. Heidbreder, E. (1933). Seven psychologies. Engle-
Calkins, M. W. (1921). The truly psychological wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
behaviorism. Psychological Review, 28, 1-18. Hilgard, E. R. (1948). Theories oflearning. New
Calkins, M. W. (1930). The case against behav- York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
iorism. Sewanee Review, 38, 199-209. Hilgard, E. R. (1956). Theories of learning (2nd
Calverton, V. F. (1924). The rise of objective psy- ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
chology. Psychological Review, 31, 418-426. Hillner, K. P. (1984). History and systems ofmod-
Carr, H. (1930). Functionalism. In C. Murchison ern psychology. New York: Gardner.
(Ed.), Psychologies of 1930 (pp. 59-78). Worces- Holt, E. B. (1931). Animal drive and the learning
ter, MA: Clark University. process: An essay toward radical empiricism (Vol.
1). New York: Holt.
Chakrabarti, C. (1975). James and the identity Humphrey, G. (1929). Freud and the configura-
theory. Behaviorism, 3, 152-155. tionists. In C. J. Herrick, G. Humphrey, J. Jas-
Chaplin, J. P., & Krawiec, T. S. (1979). Systems trow, F. H. Allport, & E. A. Burtt, Mind and
and theories of psychology (4th ed.). New York: behavior (pp. 47-69). New York: Van Nostrand.
Holt, Rinehart and Winston. James, W. (1 904a). Does 'consciousness' exist?
Coleman, S. R. (1985). B. F. Skinner, 1926-1928: Journal ofPhilosophy, Psychology, and Scientific
From literature to psychology. The Behavior An- Methods, 1, 477-491.
alyst, 8, 77-92. James, W. (1904b). A world of pure experience,
Day, W. F., Jr. (1980). The historical antecedents I. Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Sci-
of contemporary behaviorism. In R. W. Rieber entific Methods, 1, 533-543.
& K. Salzinger (Eds.), Psychology: Theoretical- James, W. (1909). The meaning oftruth. London:
historical perspectives (pp. 203-262). New York: Longmans, Green.
Academic. Jastrow, J. (1927). The reconstruction of psy-
Day, W. (1983). On the difference between radical chology. Psychological Review, 34, 169-195.
and methodological behaviorism. Behaviorism, Jones, A. H. (1915). The method of psychology.
11, 89-102. Journal ofPhilosophy, Psychology, and Scientific
Diehl, F. (1932). An historical and critical study Methods, 12, 462-471.
ofradical behaviorism as a philosophical doctrine. Kantor, J. R. (1921). An objective interpretation
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Johns Hop- of meanings. American Journal of Psychology,
kins University, Baltimore, MD. 32, 231-248.
Dotterer, R. H. (1933). Philosophy by way of the Kantor, J. R. (1933). In defense of stimulus-re-
sciences: An introductory textbook. New York: sponse psychology. PsychologicalReview, 40,324-
Macmillan. 336.
Drew, G. C., & George, F. H. (1953). Studies of Kaufman, A. S. (1967). Behaviorism. In P. Ed-
animal learning. In E. A. Mace (Ed.), Current wards (Ed.), The encyclopedia ofphilosophy (Vol.
trends in British psychology (pp. 172-184). Lon- 1, pp. 268-273). New York: Macmillan.
don: Methuen. Keller, F. S. (1973). The definition ofpsychology
Dunlap, K (1916). Thought-content and feeling. (2nd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Psychological Review, 23, 49-70. Knapp, T. J. (1974). ReferenceguidetoB. F. Skin-
Epstein, R. (1982). Bibliography. In B. F. Skinner, ner: A comprehensive bibliography of published
Skinner for the classroom (R. Epstein, Ed., pp. works by and concerningB. F. Skinnerfrom 1929
277-284). Champaign, IL: Research Press. through 1973. Reno, NV: Clifford.
Evans, D. L. (1924). The reactions of a religionist Koffica, K. (1924). Introspection and the method
to behaviorism. Journal ofReligion, 4, 347-360. of psychology. The British Journal ofPsychology,
Evans, R. I. (1981). Dialogue with B. F. Skinner. 15, 149-161.
New York: Praeger. (Original work published Langfeld, H. S. (1945). Symposium on operation-
1968) ism: Introduction. Psychological Review, 52, 241-
Finkenstaedt, T., Leisi, E., & Wolff, D. (1970). A 242.
chronological English dictionary: Listing 80,000 Lashley, K. S. (1923). The behavioristic interpre-
words in order of their earliest known occurrence. tation of consciousness, I. Psychological Review,
Heidelberg: Carl Winter. 30, 237-272.
Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind-body problem. Sci- Leahey, T. H. (1980). A history of psychology.
entific American, 244, 114-123. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Garrison, W. E. (1930). Behaviorism-A tech- Leahey, T. H. (1984). Behaviorism. In R. J. Cor-
nique of control, not a measure of values. In W. sini (Ed.), Encyclopedia ofpsychology (Vol. 1, pp.
P. King (Ed.), Behaviorism:A battle line(pp. 149- 130-133). New York: Wiley.
170). Nashville, TN: Cokesbury. Logue, A. W. (1985). The growth ofbehaviorism:
Gregory, J. C. (1922). Three witnesses against be- Controversy and diversity. In C. Buxton (Ed.),
haviourism. The Philosophical Review, 31, 581- Points ofview in the modern history ofpsychology
592. (pp. 169-196). New York: Academic.
38 SUSAN M. SCHNEIDER & EDWARD K. MORRIS
Mach, E. (1960). The science of mechanics (T. J. Pepper, S. C. (1934). The conceptual framework
McCormack, Trans.). LaSalle, IL: Open Court. of Tolman's purposive behaviorism. Psycholog-
(Original work published 1883) ical Review, 41, 108-133.
MacIntosh, D. C. (1915). The problem of knowl- Pratt, C. C. (1945). Operationism in psychology.
edge. New York: Macmillan. Psychological Review, 52, 262-269.
Mackintosh, N. J. (1983). Behaviorism. In R. Rall, H. F. (1930). What does behaviorism mean
Harre & R. Lamb (Eds.), The encyclopedic dic- for religion? In W. P. King (Ed.), Behaviorism: A
tionary of psychology (p. 56). Cambridge, MA: battle line (pp. 288-304). Nashville, TN: Cokes-
MIT Press. bury.
Margolis, J. Z. (1984). Philosophy of psychology. Roback, A. A. (1923). Behaviorism and psychol-
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. ogy. Cambridge, MA: University Bookstore.
Marr, M. J. (1984). Conceptual approaches and Roback, A. A. (1937). Behaviorism at twenty-five.
issues. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Cambridge, MA: Sci-Art.
Behavior, 42, 353-362. Rucker, D. (1969). The Chicago pragmatists.
Marr, M. J. (1985). 'Tis the gift to be simple: A Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
retrospective appreciation of Mach's The science Runes, D. D. (Ed.). (1962). Dictionary ofphilos-
of mechanics. Journal of the Experimental Anal- ophy. Totowa, NJ: Littlefield, Adams.
ysis ofBehavior, 44, 129-138. Scriven, M. (1956). A study of radical behavior-
Marvin, W. T. (1914). General problems; Mind ism. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota
and body. Psychological Bulletin, 11, 1-7. studies in the philosophy of science: Vol. 1. The
Marvin, W. T. (1915). General problems; Mind foundations of science and the concepts of psy-
and body. Psychological Bulletin, 12, 12-17. chology and psychoanalysis (pp. 88-130). Min-
Marx, M. H. (Ed.). (1951). Psychological theory: neapolis: University of Minnesota.
Contemporary readings. New York: Macmillan. Sellars, R. W. (1926). Theprinciples and problems
Marx, M. H., & Hillix, W. A. (1979). Systems and ofphilosophy. New York: Macmillan.
theories in psychology (3rd ed.). New York: Sidis, B. (1914). The foundations of normal and
McGraw-Hill. abnormal psychology. Boston: Badger.
McDougall, W. (1926). Men or robots, I. In M. Skinner, B. F. (1931). The concept of the reflex
Bentley, K. Dunlap, W. S. Hunter, K. Koffika, W. in the description ofbehavior. Journal ofGeneral
Kohler, W. McDougall, M. Prince, J. B. Watson, Psychology, 5, 427-458.
& R. S. Woodworth, Psychologies of 1925 (pp. Skinner, B. F. (c. 1934). A sketch for an episte-
273-291). Worcester, MA: Clark University. mology. Unpublished manuscript.
McDougall, W. (1930). The psychology they teach Skinner, B. F. (1938). Thebehavioroforganisms.
in New York. In W. P. King (Ed.), Behaviorism: Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
A battle line (pp. 31-62). Nashville, TN: Cokes- Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis of
bury. psychological terms. Psychological Review, 52,
Melville, N. J. (1914). [Review of La psychologie 270-277, 291-294.
objective, by W. Bechterew]. Journal of Philos- Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behav-
ophy, Psychology, and ScientificMethods, 11, 357- ior. New York: Free Press.
359. Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbalbehavior. Englewood
Michael, J. L. (1985). Behavior analysis: A radical Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
perspective. In B. L. Hammonds (Ed.), The mas- Skinner, B. F. (1963). Behaviorism at fifty. Sci-
ter lecture series: Vol. 4. Psychology and learning ence, 140, 951-958.
(pp. 99-12 1). Washington: American Psycholog- Skinner, B. F. (1964). Behaviorism at fifty. In T.
ical Association. W. Wann (Ed.), Behaviorism andphenomenology
Moore, J. (1981). On mentalism, methodological (pp. 79-97). Chicago: University of Chicago.
behaviorism, and radical behaviorism. Behav- Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies ofreinforce-
iorism, 9, 55-77. ment. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Moore, J. (1985). Some historical and conceptual Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New
relations among logical positivism, operation- York: Random House.
ism, and behaviorism. The Behavior Analyst, 8, Skinner, B. F. (1976). Particulars of my life. New
53-63. York: Knopf.
Moore, J. S. (1921). Thefoundations ofpsychol- Skinner, B. F. (1979). Theshapingofa behaviorist.
ogy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University. New York: Knopf.
Morgan, C. L. (1922). Consciousness and the un- Skinner, B. F. (1980). The experimental analysis
conscious. Report of the British Association for of operant behavior: A history. In R. W. Rieber
the Advancement of Science (pp. 143-169). Lon- & K. Salzinger (Eds.), Psychology: Theoretical-
don: John Murray. historical perspectives (pp. 191-202). New York:
Munn, N. L. (1950). Handbook of psychological Academic.
research on the rat. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Skinner, B. F. (1983). A matter of consequences.
Neel, A. (1977). Theories ofpsychology: A hand- New York: Knopf.
book (rev. & enl. ed.). New York: Schenkman. Spearman, C. (1937). Psychology down the ages
Parrott, L. J., & Hake, D. F. (1983). Toward a (Vol. 1). London: Macmillan.
science of history. The Behavior Analyst, 6, 121 - Spence, K. W. (1948). The postulates and meth-
132. ods of 'behavorism.' Psychological Review, 55,
Pear, T. H. (1922). Remembering andforgetting. 67-78.
London: Methuen. Spence,K.W. (1952). Mathematicalformulations
THE TERM RADICAL BEHA VIORISM 39
of learning phenomena. Psychological Review, 59, Weiss, A. P. (1919). The mind and the man-with-
152-160. in. Psychological Review, 26, 327-334.
Stolurow, L. M. (Ed.). (1953). Readings in learn- Weiss, A. P. (1924). Behaviorism and behavior,
ing. New York: Prentice-Hall. I. Psychological Review, 31, 32-50.
Warden, C. J., Jenkins, T. N., & Warner, L. H. Weiss, A. P. (1929). A theoretical basis ofhuman
(1934). Introduction to comparative psychology. behavior (2nd ed., rev.). Columbus, OH: R. G.
New York: Ronald. Adams.
Warren, H. C. (1914a). The mental and the phys- Wells, F. L. (1913). [Review of The science of
ical. Psychological Review, 21, 79-100. human behavior, by M. Parmelee]. Psychological
Warren, H. C. (1914b). Terminology. Psycholog- Bulletin, 10, 280-281.
ical Bulletin, 11, 10-11. Wheeler, R. H. (1923). Introspection and behav-
Warren, H. C. (1921). Some unusual visual after- ior. Psychological Review, 30, 103-115.
effects. Psychological Review, 28, 453-463. Wieman, H. N. (1919). The nature of mentality.
Warren, H. C. (1934). Dictionary of psychology. Psychological Review, 26, 230-246.
Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Wild, J. (1969). The radical empiricism of Wil-
Washburn, M. F. (1922). Introspection as an ob- liam James. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
jective method. Psychological Review, 29, 89-112. Williams, R. (1976). Keywords. New York: Ox-
Watson, J. B. (1913a). Image and affection in be- ford University.
havior. Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Wolfe, A. B. (1921). The motivation of radical-
Scientific Methods, 10, 421-428. ism. Psychological Review, 28, 280-300.
Watson, J. B. (1913b). Psychology as the behav- Wolman, B. B. (1981). Contemporarytheories and
iorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158- systems in psychology (2nd ed., rev.). New York:
177. Plenum.
Watson, J. B. (1914). Behavior: An introduction Woodworth, R. S. (1922). Dynamic psychology.
to comparative psychology. New York: Holt. New York: Columbia University.
Watson, J. B. (1920). Practical and theoretical Woodworth, R. S. (1924). Four varieties of be-
problems in instinct and habit. In H. S. Jennings, haviorism. Psychological Review, 31, 257-264.
J. B. Watson, A. Meyer, & W. I. Thomas, Sug- Woodworth, R. S. (1931). Contemporary schools
gestions of modern science concerning education ofpsychology. New York: Ronald.
(pp. 53-99). New York: Macmillan. Yerkes, R. M. (1917). Behaviorism and genetic
Watson, J. B. (1924). Psychologyfrom the stand- psychology. Journal of Philosophy, Psychology,
point ofa behaviorist (2nd ed.). Philadelphia: Lip- and Scientific Methods, 14, 154-160.
pincott. Young, P. T. (1924). The phenomenological point
Watson, J. B. (1927). The origin and growth of of view. Psychological Review, 31, 288-296.
behaviorism. Archiv fur Systematische Philoso- Young, P. T. (1943). Emotion in man and animal:
phie und Sociologie, 30, 247-262. Its nature and relation to attitude and motive.
Watson, J. B. (1930). Behaviorism (rev. ed.). New New York: Wiley.
York: Norton. Zuriff, G. E. (1984). Radical behaviorism and the-
Watson, R. I. (Ed.). (1976). Eminent contributors oretical entities. The Behavioral and Brain Sci-
to psychology (Vol. 2). New York: Springer. ences, 7, 572.

View publication stats

You might also like