You are on page 1of 15

Just Planning

The Art of Situated Ethical Judgment

Heather Campbell

Abstract

The conceptualizations of justice that


C harles Taylor (1993) has lamented the extent of “moral skepticism” inherent
within contemporary intellectual thought that results, as he sees it, in the ero-
sion of the space for reasoning and the triumph of the arbitrary. Such an intellectual
have most influenced recent debates in
planning theory have focused on proce- context poses particular challenges for the development of the conceptual basis of
dural concerns, while questions of value an activity such as planning, premised as it is on the need for action and the ability
and the good have been regarded as to make choices between good and bad, right and wrong, in relation to the making
problematic given a world of plurality
and shaping of places. Recognition of the oppressive and exclusionary capacity of
and difference. This article argues that
questions of value are an inescapable part homogenizing models of identity leaves planners floundering in a sea of difference
of the activity of planning and hence its and fragmentation: if no contention has any more validity than any other, how can
purpose is to identify the key dimensions planners justify arriving at closure, even temporarily, on a particular course of action?
of a reconceptualized notion of justice
The depth of the resulting conundrum is accentuated by the contested nature of the
for planning. The argument is presented
through consideration of two key themes: issues with which planning is concerned. Notions of what makes for good places and
the relationship between the individual the appropriate distribution of the spatial consequences of governmental, market,
and the collective, and the notion of “rea- and individual decisions are characterized by dissent, dispute, and even violence
sonableness” in relation to matters of
(Flyvbjerg 1998; Watson 2003; Yiftachel 1998). Contestation, with respect to both
public policy related to planning. The
implications of this analysis lead on to process and outcome, is inherent in the planning activity (Campbell 2002).
consideration of the scope of collective Moreover, it is not only different worldviews and identities that may be in friction;
obligations and the nature of judgment often basic issues of economics add an edge to the passionately held concerns at
and reasoning in planning. The article
stake. The inadvertent coalition between the implications of the individualism inher-
concludes by arguing that justice in plan-
ning is about situated ethical judgment— ent in the politics of identity and the spread of neoliberalism (Sayer and Storper
a conceptualization of justice that raises 1997; Storper 2001) has if anything further accentuated the underlying conflicts with
significant issues in relation to future which planning (and planners) must engage. There is, however, no formula available
developments in planning thought.
through which the right and the good may be calculated. Consequently, in this con-
Keywords: justice; ethical judgment; planning text of contestation, planners are fundamentally concerned with making ethical judg-
theory ments (Campbell 2002; Campbell and Marshall 1999; Harrison 2002; Upton 2002).
What societies ask of the institutions charged with the responsibility for arriving at
such judgments is that they be just. The concept of justice is therefore central to the
theory and practice of planning (Fainstein 2000, 2005).
The link between planning and concepts of justice is long and enduring. This can
be seen in the initial (and perhaps continuing) influence of utilitarian streams of
Heather Campbell is a professor and head
of the Department of Town and Regional
thought (Campbell and Marshall 2002) and more recently in the way debates within
Planning at the University of Sheffield. planning theory have been shaped, both implicitly and explicitly, by Rawls’s notion
She is also one of the founding coeditors
of the journal Planning Theory and
Practice. Her research interests center on Journal of Planning Education and Research 26:92-106
the interaction between theoretical ideas DOI: 10.1177/0739456X06288090
and planning practices. © 2006 Association of Collegiate Schools of Planning

92
Just Planning 䉳 93

of “justice as fairness” and Habermas’s concept of “discourse concerned, namely, planning, and the existing literature on
ethics” (see Stein and Harper 2002). The communicative or justice and planning.
collaborative turn1 in planning thought has attempted to take
on board the operation of power in its various manifestations
but without descending into fatalism. It therefore seeks to 䉴 Background
develop a normative, rather than purely analytical, frame-
work for planning, with the deontological ethical insights of Crucial to the argument that follows is the assumption
Rawls and Habermas strongly influential. Crucially, however, that debate about justice in planning is about more than
neither Rawls nor Habermas intended his constitutional-level merely summarizing the ideas of the great justice philoso-
conceptualizations of justice to be applied to the everyday sit- phers. Few, if any, of these philosophers had planning in
uated judgments with which planning and many other areas mind as the context in which they intended their ideas to be
of policy making are concerned (see Campbell and Marshall applied. Their concerns are with the constitutional essentials
[2005] for the detailed development of this argument). This of whole societies: appropriate relationships and interrela-
is reflected in debates beyond the planning field, where con- tionships between individuals, communities, governments,
cern has been expressed about the “idealization” at the heart markets, and the wider world, now often including the nat-
of the dominant liberal conceptions of justice, resulting in ural environment. Their horizons are therefore broader than
their failure to connect with everyday problems and contexts a subsection of public policy making concerned with the cre-
(see, for example, Okin 1999; O’Neill 2000; Ricoeur 1992; ation of place and the mediation of space. This is not to dis-
Storper 2001; Young 1990). This in turn has led to calls for a miss this hugely significant body of work but to caution the
reconceptualized framework for justice, one that incorpo- appropriateness of direct translation. Concern about justice
rates universal understandings with an appreciation of the in planning must constantly bear in mind that it is a subset of
particularity of individual situations and contexts (see, for public policy, which assumes that collective intervention, par-
example, Harvey 1996, 2000; Nussbaum 1993; O’Neill 2000). ticularly in land and property markets, will yield benefits to
This article therefore takes as its starting point the search the common good. It is therefore about constraining, restrict-
for a framework for justice that aims to link “abstract princi- ing, or simply raising questions about individual property
ples to particular cases” (O’Neill 2000, 145). This approach, (and to some extent personal) rights and freedoms, on the
which seeks to avoid the idealization inherent in the domi- assumption that this will yield a greater good. As Baum
nant liberal theories of justice, promises much for an activity (2005) has recently written, planning is about “extraordinary
such as planning, which involves situated ethical judgment in behaviour” and, hence, “if people in communities recognised
circumstances of profound contestation. The objective of this the virtues of planning, planners would not be necessary.”
article is to attempt to identify and explore the key dimen- This perspective on planning therefore influences the
sions of such a concept of justice. It should be emphasized range of ideas and sources that is drawn upon in the sub-
that this is seen very much as the start of a process rather than sequent discussion. For example, Hendler’s (1995) edited
a final statement. The parameters of the debate surrounding volume contains summaries of various philosophical posi-
justice in planning are grouped around two key themes. First, tions (see McConnell [1995] on Rawls and Blanco [1995] on
the relationship between the liberty and rights of individuals communitarianism), but debate is not taken much further in
and the extent of the obligations owed to others is consid- terms of the theory and practice of planning. Also, in fairness
ered. In other words, concern is with the relationship to these authors, analysis and critique of the work of thinkers
between the individual and the collective. The second theme such as Rawls has evolved significantly over the past ten years.
is what constitutes “reasonable” in relation to matters of The concern in this article is to explore, or at least start to
public debate such as the issues of right and wrong, good and explore, the nature of justice in planning, not to review jus-
bad with respect to the making and remaking of places. The tice and planning or to focus on the ethical frameworks of
appropriate balance between procedural concerns and ques- individual planners. The article is perhaps closest in spirit, if
tions of value and the good are examined in this connection. not directly congruent in its analysis and conclusions, to
The implications of this analysis for a reconceptualized Fainstein’s recent work on the “just city” (1999, 2000, 2005).
notion of justice in planning are drawn together in the final As noted above, a combination of Rawlsian and Habermasian
part of the article. In particular, the scope of the polity with concepts of justice have underpinned the collaborative or
which planning is concerned to be just and the links between communicative turn in planning thought. In a previous
judgment, reasoning, and justice are explored. However, paper with Marshall, I questioned the appropriateness of
before embarking on the main argument, it is necessary to sit- direct translation of these conceptualizations of justice into
uate the article a little more, both in relation to the underly- planning (Campbell and Marshall 2005). Elements of this
ing assumptions about the arena with which the article is perspective are considered in the course of this article,
94 Campbell

although the intention is not to repeat these arguments but future. But . . . many of these demands can be seen, from
rather to move the discussion forward. The arguments a micro-analytical point of view, as simple extensions of
modern liberal individualism, not as potentially radical
presented in this article are therefore positioned in relation to
forms of new collectivism. (p. 171)
debates within planning theory but, given the limited nature of
existing work in planning, are inspired by ideas and develop-
ments within the wider social sciences and philosophy. The Despite the divergent intellectual inheritance underlying
challenge for the article is to adequately connect these ideas to the current stress on individual liberty, its implications for the
the “extraordinary” qualities of the planning activity. conceptualization of justice in planning are significant. In
certain circumstances such an emphasis even seems to rule
out the possibility of justice in relation to the spatial and
place-related issues with which planning is concerned due to
䉴 Justice, the Individual, and the Polity:
the irreconcilability of individual interests. The following
A Reconsideration
therefore seeks to explore the notion of liberty in relation to
planning, most particularly the nature of the relationship
Justice, within the dominant liberal conceptions, is
between the individual and the collective.
premised on the maintenance of the liberty of the individual.
Moreover, it is not possible to achieve justice where citizens lack
freedom and autonomy. Notwithstanding the tendency for
John Rawls’s conception to be applied to situations with which Individual Liberty and Autonomy?
it was not originally concerned, his “principle of greatest equal
liberty,” which is prioritized above all others, has been very influ- Individual liberty is hugely prized within contemporary
ential. It states (in the final amended restatement), “Each per- thought and rhetoric, as noted above, but what does liberty
son has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme mean in the context of justice in planning? The following
of equal basic liberties, which scheme is compatible with the attempts to show how liberty, without context and a relational
scheme of liberties for all” (2001, 42). Rawls was concerned that understanding of human existence, is both problematic and
in a pluralist world individuals should be able to choose their of limited meaning.
own way of life, free from external influence or coercion except Hart (1975) raised early concerns about the priority Rawls
where this infringed the liberties of others. Consequently liberty attaches to liberty. He was particularly struck by Rawls’s
could only be limited for the sake of liberty and was to be safe- requirement that liberty could only be limited for the sake of
guarded through a comprehensive system of rights. liberty and not as a result of other social and economic advan-
This focus on individual liberty and rights, in contrast to tages. Hart was concerned about the inevitable conflicts
more collectivist aspirations, has been further reinforced in between liberties and argued that restrictions on liberty were
the neoliberal agendas that have underpinned government made not on the basis of liberty itself but rather because of
policies across the world. However, a commitment to individ- the resulting consequences. Justice was not therefore purely
ual self-expression has been stimulated not only by various about the maintenance of liberty. He observes in relation to
strands of liberalism but also by postmodern sensibilities restrictions on the basic liberties of speech and private prop-
about identity and difference (Phillips 1996). The impor- erty (such as the use of land and cars) that they “are com-
tance of a sensitivity toward the lived experience of all within monly accepted as trade-offs not of liberty, but of liberty for
society often seems to render the public sector redundant, as the protection from harm or loss of amenities or other ele-
there can be no “public.” Only the individual, who is the site ments of real utility” (p. 245). Hart’s analysis highlights how
of all interactions with the world, can know his or her own the exercise of individual liberties in practice is likely to result
preferences. Interests are therefore subjectively derived from in conflict that is, moreover, not susceptible to just resolution
within each individual, with collectivist notions of interest purely by recourse to the maintenance of individual liberty.
(and even the very concept of justice itself) treated with sus- The discussion of liberty in relation to justice has so far
picion due to the association with control and oppression.2 taken place largely in the realm of the hypothetical, assuming
There is a striking similarity between this and neoliberalism’s that all have the same opportunities to exercise liberty. Rawls
preoccupation with minimizing regulation to ensure the certainly constructs such a situation by placing his citizens’
unfettered expression of individual preferences, although in representatives in the “original position” behind the “veil of
this case preference is articulated through the operation of ignorance.” In a sense here, and in his work on “basic goods”
the market. As Storper (2001) has observed in relation to the and “basic income,” Rawls is accepting that there are differ-
work of the postmodern and cultural-turn scholars, ences in socioeconomic resources; but he then deals with this
through the creation of a hypothetical situation where
They see the rise of identity-based and community-based
politics as collective expressions of the needs of the down- no one knows the distribution of resources or endowments.
trodden, as essentially linked to a progressive vision of the Such a contrivance may be justified in relation to constitutional
Just Planning 䉳 95

essentials, but it simply does not obtain in the arenas in which through a capacity to express preferences developed from lived
planning practitioners work. In circumstances of socioeco- experiences. However, acts of seeming independence often
nomic inequalities, the capacity to exercise liberty will also be simultaneously entail aspects of dependence; and not all
unequal. Moreover, the poor and relatively powerless are ren- independent actions merit approbation, as in the case of the
dered vulnerable to exploitation by the powerful and well independence employed in the pursuit of acts that are unlaw-
resourced (Daniels 1975; O’Neill 2000). A concept of ful or cause harm to others. Similarly, linking rationality to
justice that concerns itself with the liberty and equality of indi- independence is problematic, as deference or dependence
viduals in the political arena is always going to be rendered could be entirely rational in situations of threat or gross
problematic in the face of gross inequalities in the socioeco- inequalities in power.
nomic context. The scope of the liberty of the poor and vul- Crucially, therefore, autonomy and liberty are not merely
nerable is inevitably constrained. Sen (1999) makes a similar about independence, and to conflate these concepts is to
point in constructing his concept of “freedom” in relation to miss the moral significance of autonomy. For politics, public
development, in much broader terms than traditional liberal policy making and hence planning are about deciding and
versions of “liberty,” thereby including within the notion of acting, not about spectating. This by implication suggests
“freedoms” concerns both with process and substance. agency and a capacity to reason. Justice in such circumstances
Assumptions that individuals are the best judges of their involves an appreciation of dependence, independence, and
interests, or that individuals have no capacity to judge outside perhaps most important, interdependence in relation to the
of their subjective desires, lead to and result from a stress on conduct and development of human societies. It requires, in
individual liberty. It has already been noted that individual the words of O’Neill (2000),
liberties may conflict and are themselves limited by circum- an empirically realistic view of the capacities and capabili-
stance. A further issue of concern, however, centers on ties agents have, of ways in which they are vulnerable to
whether because we desire something we ought to have it others, and of ways in which existing institutions may be
either resilient or fragile. This is the context within which
(Cooke 1999; Taylor 1993). In relation to planning matters,
the construction of more robust and reliable institutions
the nature of interests is often complex and problematic; for which can secure justice even for the relatively weak must
example, individuals generally both desire clean air and to be be undertaken. (p. 7)
able to drive their car(s) freely. Our preferences are there-
The above emphasizes that if a conception of justice is to have
fore often inconsistent and overlapping. This array of indi-
practical application, then individual liberty and autonomy
vidual interests places the activity of planning in a precarious
must be viewed in relation to everyday policy making contexts—
position. On one hand, moral skepticism renders it voiceless,
contexts where liberties conflict and some (perhaps many)
whilst on the other, attempts to adjudicate between conflict-
are vulnerable and where individuals (and the capacity to
ing positions smack of coercion, exclusion, and oppression.
express their identity) exist in relation to others and there-
Space for action is, however, opened up if individuals are
fore as part of an interdependent whole.
seen as part of a larger whole and in relation to one another.
The concern with the maintenance of liberty and the
autonomy of the individual has tended to obscure from view Rights: Moral Rights and Obligations
the extent to which individuals are interdependent and part
of mutually beneficial relational webs. Notwithstanding the Closely linked to the focus on individual liberty and
importance of respecting individual and community identity, autonomy with respect to an account of justice is the notion
Harvey (1996), building on the work of Young (1990), points of rights. The rhetoric of rights now dominates much political
out that difference should not be construed as “absolute oth- debate, but rights in the absence of any sense of associated
erness, a complete absence of relationship or shared attrib- obligations are meaningless (O’Neill 2000). Rights cannot be
utes” (p. 360). Rather, individuals exist within a “community possessed, and more crucially the most significant claim
of common interests” (Harvey 2000, 240) and a “shared com- rights are relational and therefore impossible to realize with-
mon humanity” (Low and Gleeson 1997, 35). This is not a out others being obliged to take certain actions. “Rights refer
precursor to the imposition of a homogenizing discourse but to doing more than having, to social relationships that enable
to a relational understanding of the existence of individuals or constrain action” (Young 1990, 25). Focus on rights, while
within society, captured succinctly in Young’s (1993, 130) leaving the associated obligations obscured, tends to foster
phrase “togetherness in difference.” passivity, at least in terms of a capacity for collective action: a
The domination of notions of individual liberty and preoccupation with “what I ought to get,” and not a concern
autonomy as “mere sheer choice” are shown by O’Neill with “my wider responsibilities.” The latter often implies a
(2000) to be problematic and inappropriate in relation to responsibility that only adds up to something meaningful if it
practical issues. She notes the frequent association between is upheld collectively. Free speech, or the right to be con-
autonomy and independence, whether as rational agents or sulted about a proposed development, is only meaningful if
96 Campbell

others listen or are open at least to considering the views at odds with the assumptions that have long underpinned
being put forward (see Campbell and Marshall 2000). As Sen the idea of planning. In practice, it seems entirely plausible to
(1999) observes, individuals have agency but the state has argue that planning is concerned both with liberty and with
responsibilities. Moreover, a focus on rights overlooks moral rights; the problem comes when a structure of libertar-
entirely those obligations, which do not have associated rights ian rights and obligations is devised to deal with moral rights
attached, that O’Neill (1996) refers to as imperfect. Such concerning goods and services (and vice versa). The desire for
obligations are those, for example, that are concerned with the clarity inherent in negative rights, when applied to issues
showing (unspecified) others care or providing basic shelter. concerned with moral rights, can only mislead and confuse cit-
This lack of reciprocity makes the obligation itself no less izens over the outcomes that a field of public policy such as
great. The interdependent quality of individual existence is planning can be expected to deliver. Consequently a concep-
therefore further emphasized once obligations are brought tion of justice in planning must not be lured into only focusing
into the discussion about rights. Consequently, despite his on liberty rights, but must include a robust analysis of the
general focus on “freedoms” as the most appropriate means nature of the rights with which it is concerned, and its role in
to secure development, Sen emphasizes that the state will at relation to the specification and enforcement of the concomi-
times have a responsibility (or an obligation) to curtail free- tant obligations. Moreover, if planning has any aspiration of
dom in one area to create greater freedoms elsewhere. concern for the poor, needy, and vulnerable, it (and the soci-
A crucial issue in thinking about justice in planning con- eties within which it is embedded) will have to grapple with the
cerns an enduring debate about the nature of rights, cap- complex relations of obligations associated with moral rights.
tured in a disjunction between those taking a broadly These issues are fundamental and deserve the most serious con-
libertarian position and those who are proponents of social sideration, particularly within the large number of countries
justice (O’Neill 2000). Libertarians see rights in terms of neg- worldwide currently involved in identifying and implementing
ative or liberty rights, which are universal, implying an oblig- reforms to their planning systems (see Campbell 2003).
ation not to interfere and enshrined in laws that set out
relationships, including how such rights are to be enforced.
In contrast, those adopting a focus on social justice are con- Summary: The Limitations of a Rights-Based Justice
cerned with positive or moral rights, more particularly rights
to goods and services.3 The difficulty in the latter case is that Overall, these arguments suggest that to frame an account
there is less clarity over the link between the right and the of justice in planning on individualism and rights to liberty is
obligation and also the universality or uniformity of their inappropriate and likely to be unproductive. Individuals exist
application; delivery rests with certain institutions and indi- in relationship to one another and as such are interdepen-
viduals rather than with everyone. This has led the libertari- dent and bound by relations of sometimes nonreciprocal
ans to doubt the validity of the notion of rights to goods and obligation. Such circumstances imply in turn a dependence
services. However, O’Neill (2000) has pointed out that deter- upon the effective action of institutions that embody collec-
mining a scheme of delivery, refraining from obstructing tive concern. This argument has significant implications for
delivery, or contributing proportionally to the costs of deliv- the scope of persons, places, and even creatures (Young
ery can all be universally held obligations. The issue is that 2000) over which obligations of justice extend in relation to
establishing the relationships between what ought to be pro- planning. As the nature and scope of the polity included in
vided and by whom, and who will be accountable for failure the realm of justice says much about the activity which plan-
to deliver, are dependent upon effective institutional and ning is or aspires to be, consideration of this issue will be used
therefore collective action. By contrast, liberty rights are far to draw together the ideas presented in the article and to
more easily and clearly determined. focus more directly on the implications for planning.
The planning activity, with its concern for the spatial impli- However, first it is necessary to explore about what is the plan-
cations of socioeconomic and environmental processes, fre- ning community concerned to act justly?
quently finds itself trapped between libertarian and social
justice conceptions of rights and obligations. Moreover, plan-
ning displays confusion when it attempts to construct law-like 䉴 Being Reasonable:
statements over matters concerning moral rights. Intriguingly, With What Is Justice Concerned?
there is growing evidence of societies favoring a libertarian
approach to the specification of rights and obligations with The emphasis within intellectual thought and popular
respect to place, as can be seen in the legal contracts associated rhetoric on the self-expression of individuals and communi-
with living in gated communities. Justice in this case is secured ties has cast doubt on whether concepts of justice should be
by fair administration of the legal system. This is an entirely concerned with the way people live their lives. In a world of plu-
coherent approach to the creation of just places. It is, however, ralism, where the existence of multiple truths is appreciated,
Just Planning 䉳 97

libertarians celebrate noninterference, and postmodern the nature of the process of public reasoning, a process that,
critiques warn of the oppressive tendencies of homogenizing if reasonable and based on legitimately executed dialogue,
discourses, the legitimacy of choosing between substantive will lead to agreement. Reasonable conduct on the part of cit-
versions of better and worse in relation to politics or planning izens results in a reasonable outcome. This general perspec-
is seen to be inappropriate. Notwithstanding the observation tive on justice has been hugely influential and in the
that Rawls’s concept of “justice as fairness” and Habermas’s planning field can be seen in the development of thought
notion of justice in relation to moral norms in “discourse around deliberative practices, in particular the creation of
ethics” were not intended to be applied to the everyday poli- arenas which facilitate open uncoerced dialogue.
tics of planning decisions, their influence has been consider-
able both within planning and more broadly. Central to the
ideas and lessons that have been derived from this work has Exclusion of Outsider or
been an emphasis on the neutrality of the state in relation to Innovator Voices as “Unreasonable”
different conceptions of the good life. The state upholds jus-
tice by ensuring the rights of free and equal citizens to choose Fundamental to the application of Rawls’s and Habermas’s
between different conceptions of the good. Rawls emphasizes conceptions is the removal of matters of substance from the
that the “right is prior to the good” and hence the ability to realm of the public and moral norms and, therefore, justice.
choose is more important than the choice (Mulhall and Swift The result, however, is something of a circular argument: for
1997). Justice therefore becomes concerned with the processes what is reasonable and just becomes whatever is defined as
and procedures through which choices are made, leading to a reasonable and just, and likewise any other approach is nec-
focus on deliberation and public reasoning and hence the link essarily unreasonable (Mulhall and Swift 1997). Mouffe
(although not total accord) between the work of Rawls and (1996) illustrates this in relation to Rawls’s emphasis on the
Habermas. In a sense, the “what” question about justice has right over the good:
been placed to one side and substantive issues about values and This is why he cannot provide a convincing argument
the good placed in the realm of the private. The just has been for justifying the frontiers of his pluralism, and why he gets
separated from the good and limited to fair procedure caught in a circular form of argumentation: political
(Ricoeur 1992). The influence of such an approach is evident liberalism can provide a consensus among reasonable
persons who by definition are persons who accept the prin-
in much of the work associated with the communicative or col- ciples of political liberalism. (p. 250)
laborative turn in planning thought. However, how far can and
should questions of value be separated from procedural matters She goes on,
in relation to justice? The following discussion explores this
They [citizens] probably have very different and even
crucial issue for an account of justice in planning, as previously
conflicting conceptions of the good, but those are
by drawing on wider debates. strictly private matters and do not interfere with public
life. Conflicts of interests about economics and social
issues—if they still arise—are resolved smoothly through
discussions within the framework of public reason, by
Public Reasoning: Justice as the Ability to Choose?
invoking the principles of justice that everyone
endorses. (p. 252)
The notion that it is inappropriate or even impossible to
Consequently, dissent and disagreement are ruled out,
attempt to resolve disagreements over different conceptions
because that would result from acting unreasonably and
of the good has led to a focus on the processes of public
therefore would be unreasonable. This is somewhat prob-
deliberation. To oversimplify a vast literature, what is just
lematic in relation to planning, where contestation over mat-
(and reasonable) results from a process of open, uncoerced
ters of value and the good are everyday occurrences. Should
reasoning between free and equal citizens. Concern is not
these simply be dismissed as unreasonable? Should unrea-
therefore principally with instrumental rationality, which is
sonable citizens be excluded? The tensions and conflicts
associated with the private realm, but rather with reasonable-
encountered in relation to planning cast doubt on even the
ness, which is linked to the public realm (after Rawls 1993).
ability of a closed self-contained democratic community
Citizens are prepared to accept a decision as reasonable, and
(assumed, for example, by Rawls [1993] in relation to con-
consequently just, if it results from a fair and open process.
stitutional essentials and then applied to other spheres) to
Moreover, they will be reasonable if others agree to be rea-
provide sufficient common ground for the assumptions of
sonable. Reasoning together through this process of open
reasonableness to be fulfilled. A further issue is whether or
deliberation, and hence communicative rationality, is impor-
not it is desirable. O’Neill (1997) suggests that
tantly assumed to lead to agreement and consensus (after
Habermas 1990, 1996). Justice is therefore based on the public reasoning as Rawls construes it is citizens’, hence
premise that what is reasonable (and just) is determined by insiders’, reasoning, so may not convince foreigners or
98 Campbell

outsiders—or citizens who stand back from the way things implication that contemporary procedural accounts of justice
are, and ask whether they should be that way. (p. 422) are neutral with respect to questions of value, when inevitably
Moreover, they embody certain traditions and values (Daniels 1975;
Looked at from the perspective of outsiders, others’ agree- MacIntyre 1981, 1999; Mulhall and Swift 1997; Peffer 1990;
ment might be thought to reflect matters quite other than Vincent 1998). In the planning arena, for example, intellectual
their reasonableness. Their refusal to agree might be thought has argued strongly for uncoerced deliberation as the
thought to reflect either the diversities of identities or con-
flicts between real interests, rather than their unreason- basis of just practice, yet the structure and nature of that delib-
ableness. Their willingness to agree might be thought an eration, including who is invited to participate, embody sets of
indicator of the rawness of domination or of compliant underlying values: they do not (and cannot) avoid such con-
subservience rather than a condition of their reasonable- structions.
ness. (p. 423)
The aspiration in a world of pluralism to avoid imposing a
An unreasonable outcome may therefore be regarded by particular way of life on others by focusing on procedural
some as resulting from a reasonable (and just) process. As concerns in relation to justice therefore appears something
Owens and Cowell (2002, 64) observe in relation to the envi- of a myth. The justification for any procedure or standard
ronmental field, “nor do deliberative and inclusive processes must originate further back than the procedure itself
necessarily produce outcomes compatible with broader prin- (Ricoeur 1992; Williams 1999). Questions of value cannot be
ciples of environmental or social justice.” No principle is separated from procedures; they are intertwined. Murdoch
endorsed just because it is accepted. (1970) makes the observation that we do not find that we
agree about the “facts” but disagree about the “values.” Values
influence the way we see the world in the first place and are
A Shift to Proceduralism Does Not Remove necessarily inscribed in processes of deliberation and reason-
Bias or Avoid Imposition ing. Consequently, to suggest that considerations of value
should be omitted from an account of justice in planning is
The deontological, and hence procedural, focus of the to leave them hidden from scrutiny, not to avoid their oppres-
dominant liberal theories of justice seems to suggest reasoning sive capabilities (Connor 1993). There is also a crucial
takes place in a vacuum. Communitarians have been strongly de-politicizing aspect to the abandonment of values and the
critical of this and the resulting separation between the right good, for the opportunity for reevaluation is removed, not
and the good. MacIntyre (1981, 1999), for example, argues the values themselves (Storper 2001): “value and evaluation
that reasoning occurs in the company of others, others who have not so much been exiled, as driven into the critical
have particular backgrounds and presuppositions. However, it unconscious, where they continue to exercise force but with-
is not only communitarians who are concerned about the out being available for analytic scrutiny” (Connor 1993, 34).
abstraction from specific contexts. Young (1990) emphasizes Citizens, seemingly, may privately have values, but the public
that an account of justice should start from a particular social sector, including politicians and those that work within that
context not from a hypothetical conception of “reasonable arena, should not. Politics and political activities such as
people.”4 O’Neill (1997) goes further, observing that the issue planning become empty without a conception of justice that
is not merely one of abstraction but “idealization.” This ideal- takes on board issues of value (O’Neill 1993). They become
ization assumes a context in which reasoning takes place that “a method of aggregating whatever ideals people happen to
does not accord with existing societies and is also deeply have, without conversation or judgement on those ideals
imbued with unacknowledged values (see also Ricoeur [1992] themselves” (O’Neill 1993, 93). If it is accepted that planning
on Habermas). This notion of idealization is extremely impor- is essentially concerned with ethical questions, such an
tant in relation to thinking about a concept of justice in plan- approach crucially renders the most important aspects of
ning, for it tends to suggest that the world is at fault when there moral argument closed and opaque (after Taylor 1993).
is dissent (for example) and must be corrected, rather than for Whether planners choose to acknowledge the values implicit
the need for a more context-sensitive approach. This is not to in their actions or not, and there seem few reasons to justify
suggest a relativist approach but that normative thinking about why they should not, planning can never be neutral. Fischer
justice needs to start from an understanding of the way con- (1980, 2003) has long made this point in relation to public
texts are and the processes that shape their destinies. Also policy making more generally.
important, the ideal that lies behind these seemingly abstract Nussbaum (1993) neatly captures the conundrum that is
accounts of justice is the Western liberal nation-state. Rawls posed in practical situations, where the concern is to decide
(2001), for example, would not deny this, although it would be “what is the just thing to do,” in a case study of a women’s
unfair to suggest his approach merely mirrors contemporary literacy project in Bangladesh. The study shows the initial
American society, about which he expressed reservations. reticence of the rural women to engage with a government-
However, that is not the crucial issue. More significant is the sponsored project designed to increase literacy, since as far as
Just Planning 䉳 99

they were concerned it did not serve their interests. However, good as a basis for normative theorizing and therefore
rather than abandon the project, the development workers proposals for alternative forms of action (Harvey 1996, 2000;
reappraised their approach, endeavoring to be more sensitive Nussbaum 1993; Soper 1993).
to the lives of the women and their context but not rejecting An account of justice in planning needs to be concerned
the values that stimulated the decision to act in the first place. with “what is to be done,” not only reviewing “what has been
This demonstrates that rejecting matters of value and the done.” This suggests a concern with the interplay between the
good from justice leaves little space to act with respect to mar- universal and the particular, with questions of values and
ginalization, illiteracy, or the absence of basic shelter, but procedure, and also not merely with the analytical but with
actions in these situations must be sensitive to the context. the evaluative and the normative. The final part of the article
Nussbaum writes of the importance of seeing the common seeks to bring these arguments together, starting by consid-
humanity in a situation and that to view the context before us ering the appropriate scope of a concept of justice in plan-
“as an interesting set of local traditions, is not to respond suf- ning and going on to conclude that justice in planning is
ficiently to the concrete situation it is; for whatever it is, it is about situated ethical judgment and practical reasoning.
concretely human” (p. 258). Very similar experiences can be
found in most planning situations. Wilson (2005) and Burley
(2005) vividly demonstrate how as a community development 䉴 Justice for Whom?
worker and planning practitioner, respectively, they found
themselves challenging patronage, corruption, and racism in The scope of the polity included in the remit of planning
the face of strong community opposition to any “outsider” says much about the nature of the activity it is perceived to be
intervention. or aspires to become. In a world of pluralism, the scope over
which principles of justice should extend has been a source
of much debate. Abstract liberal conceptions, which imply
The Limits of Consensus universal application, have been much criticized for their
insensitivity to differences of identity between communities
The dominant liberal accounts accompanied by perspec- and individuals and their idealization of certain versions of
tives based on the politics of identity have together ques- family life and national sovereignty. Communitarians per-
tioned the appropriateness of issues of value and the good ceive identity to be formed within the historical and cultural
being included within the ambit of justice. The way people context of a particular community, and therefore it follows
live their lives is not therefore a concern of the state, beyond that the scope of justice should be similarly bounded (see, for
the maximization of individual liberties and the facilitation of example, Walzer 1983). Community is therefore constitutive
effective deliberation. Notwithstanding the arguments about of justice. Interdependence and obligations are limited to
the value positions that actually underlie such an approach, fellow citizens within the same community. Although Rawls’s
profound issues arise in practice when communities favor concept of justice is usually regarded as universalist, in prac-
morally unacceptable actions—for instance, those that are tice he presupposes that justice as fairness can be established
racist or in some other way exclusionary in nature, or more only within self-contained liberal democratic nation-states;
straightforwardly when reasonable (or unreasonable) people too much pluralism is assumed to make agreement on the
disagree (Ricoeur 1992). As was noted earlier in relation to just impossible (Brown 1998).
the work of Hart (1975), reasonable people may even “differ Concern with community as either constitutive of the self
as to the value of conflicting liberties” (p. 242), and rational or as a basis for deliberation has resulted in the scope of
discourse in a Habermasian sense could lead to rational dis- justice being limited to a focus on that with which citizens
agreement (McCarthy 1999). These situations are very famil- can maintain sufficient common ground. This can lead to
iar to planners, yet much current planning theory leaves extreme localism, as can be seen in some deep green and
them with little guidance for action, beyond upholding due relativist accounts. These approaches appear to cast doubt on
procedures and negating the existence of conflict in the justice outside of communities where there is a regular possi-
search for consensus. Furthermore, they are simultaneously bility of face-to-face contact. Furthermore, some feminist
the subject of severe criticism for imposing policies that are writers are so suspicious of the homogenizing tendencies of
insensitive to the identities of individuals and communities. the dominant liberal theories of justice and their blindness to
Work adopting a Foucauldian perspective, which has exam- the lived experiences of women’s lives that they see the need
ined the “dark side” of the activities of the state, highlights to supplement the term justice, by, for example, the concept
moral injustices (see Flyvbjerg 1998). The difficulty with this of “care” often linked to a sense of interdependency (Gilligan
approach for a concept of justice in planning is that despite 1993). Traditional concepts of justice are regarded as exclud-
the implicit concern with moral values, it explicitly rejects the ing and marginalizing the “other voice,” in turn devaluing
legitimacy of engaging in critical debate about the human alternative moral and ethical concerns, such as “care.” Okin
100 Campbell

(1989) has also observed that the tendency to confine matters communities with the potential for interaction with many
of justice to the political (see Rawls 2001, for example5) has more, including interactions that cross the borders of nation-
particular implications for women, who are often more con- states (Brown 1998; O’Neill 2000; Phillips 1996). The trend
cerned than men with the private realm. Moreover, the pri- toward fixing the boundaries and characteristics of groups
vate realm is far from impervious to the implications of a and communities should therefore be avoided, although this
political conception of justice, as the family is a crucial con- does not imply ignoring the marginalized (Phillips 1996).
text through which justice is nurtured. Young (2000) observes that normative concern with self-
Concepts of justice that embody excessive generalization determination has become too focused on noninterference
across individuals and communities undoubtedly raise issues and independence. Such an approach ignores the relational
of concern, but more particularist or relativist accounts are aspects of human existence, and consequently she argues
not without their problems. The focus on communities of that focus should centre on nondomination rather than non-
shared experience and identity introduces questions of interference. The scope of justice therefore needs to be
authenticity in relation to the definition of legitimate com- extended beyond mere difference to an identification of sig-
munities. In so doing, it is inevitable that exclusion as well as nificant difference (Nussbaum 1993; Squires [1993] after
inclusion will take place: some being placed outside the scope Harvey [1993]) and, given the focus of this article, with
of justice of a particular community, others being embraced respect to the processes influencing different experiences of
by it (Eagleton 1996; Harvey 1996; Phillips 1996). Conse- place. The argument is not that all humans are the same but
quently, the politics of identity or presence that results tends that they exist in relation to one another and that they may
to pit one community against another and may even rein- confront common situations (Nussbaum 1993).
force dogmatism and bigotry. Crucially, also, if the essence of Importantly, this perspective suggests that the scope of
community becomes the site for justice and constitutive of justice is not only limited to those with whom we share a com-
it, there can be no basis for criticism or reevaluation by “out- mon identity and/or encounter through face-to-face contact.
siders,” including state employees (Harvey 2000; O’Neill This implies obligations to strangers. This may seem an obvi-
2000; Storper 2001). Such a perspective in turn “tends to ous observation, for even at the local scale of the city, indi-
prejudice the position of the weak whose weakness is mir- viduals dwell together without knowing one another.
rored and partly constituted by their marginalization in However, much of the literature seems to suggest obligations
received ways of thought and by their subordination and of justice are owed mainly to our own community, ignoring
oppression in established orders” (O’Neill 2000, 145). that politics is inherently about relationships between
Consequently, several feminist writers amongst others have strangers (Young 2000). So, if the scope of justice extends to
begun to question whether relativist accounts in relation to strangers, should strangers in distant lands be included?
justice serve well the interests of women (Nussbaum and Sen Given the interconnectedness of social, economic, and polit-
1993; Okin 1999; Phillips 1993). The essentializing of tradi- ical processes and the increasing potential for interaction, “It
tional, often conservative, community relationships is likely would be arbitrary to exclude distant others from the domain
to have the result of merely reproducing existing patterns of of justice” (O’Neill 2000, 157-58). On what grounds could the
advantage and disadvantage both within and between groups moral standing of strangers in distant lands be denied? This
(Beebeejaun 2003). That said, as Phillips (1993) observes, question still carries force, even with respect to planning-
being a victim does not necessarily make you right. related concerns, because of the relational nature of spatial
processes. Spatial processes impact upon the localities plan-
ners serve, and in turn the actions taken locally have implica-
Relational Justice tions beyond these (arbitrary) local and national boundaries.
This can be seen in the recognition of transnational policy
The apparent choice in considering the scope of justice in frameworks in the European Union but may extend further
planning between universalist and communitarian or rela- afield through, for example, the export of polluting or oth-
tivist positions leaves something of an unhappy dilemma. erwise environmentally degrading industries to other coun-
Abstract liberal theories in their insensitivity to difference tries. It is perhaps concern about the environment, rather
appear uncritical of the social relations of privilege from than long-enduring socioeconomic inequalities, that has in
which they abstract, while in celebrating community identity recent times most profoundly drawn attention to the inter-
relativist accounts focus on existing social forms that are the connectedness of the world and encouraged a broadening of
very source of domination and subordination. However, the scope of justice.
recognition of the relational and interdependent nature of The incorporation of the environment into the debate
human existence suggests a way of navigating between these about justice brings with it not only concern about obligations
two positions. Individuals seldom live their lives within closed with respect to environmental equity across existing genera-
communities; rather, they are simultaneously part of many tions and future generations but also obligations to the natural
Just Planning 䉳 101

environment per se. Deep green perspectives argue that the Limiting the scope of justice in planning to individuals and
natural environment should be treated justly regardless of their subjective preferences implies, as discussed earlier, an
the material, welfare, aesthetic, or spiritual implications for the approach to place making based on legal contract. However, if
human species (Naess 1989; and for a wider discussion of envi- individuals and communities are seen to be interdependent,
ronmental ethics including deep green perspectives, see across both time and space, justice must necessarily embrace
Leopold 1968; Singer 1993). However, as O’Neill (1993, 8) the collective implications of actions. Harvey (1996, 2000) has
notes, “While it is the case that natural entities have an intrin- noted that currently we seem more aware of the differences that
sic value in the strongest sense of the term, i.e. in the sense of divide individuals and communities than what unites (see also
value that exists independently of human valuations, such Phillips 1993). This is not to suggest that differences of identity
value does not as such entail any obligations on the part of or acts of oppression and marginalization should be ignored,
human beings.” That is not to suggest that human well-being is far from it: but a justice which is concerned with more than
independent of the natural environment; it is significantly con- noninterference needs to navigate between the individual,
stitutive of human well-being; and more fundamentally, the or individual community, and the collective—the particular and
human community is dependent on the natural world for its the universal. This is reflected more generally in Young’s (1990,
very survival. The doubt is whether the natural environment 2000) emphasis on “togetherness in difference” and “differen-
has a nonrelational worth. Certainly in relational terms, the tiated solidarity.” Following O’Neill (1996), she argues, “An
socioeconomic and political processes that act upon and often agent stands in relations of justice with all those others whose
degrade the natural environment are not confined within actions that agent assumes in the background of his or her own
localities or nations, and hence the scope of environmental jus- actions” (Young 2000, 223); and therefore, “Differentiated soli-
tice necessarily extends beyond the limit of small communities darity does not presume mutual identification and affinity as an
and even national territories (Harvey 1996; Low and Gleeson explicit or implicit condition for attitudes of respect and inclu-
1998; Owens and Cowell 2002). sion” (Young 2000, 221). Bellamy (1998) goes further, arguing
Justice in relation to intragenerational environmental that given the fragmentation within contemporary societies,
equity has been accompanied (perhaps overshadowed) by a social solidarity needs to be politically constructed. This there-
concern for intergenerational equity. It is now appreciated fore means relating the universal to the particular, asking nor-
that the diversity and qualities of the natural environment are mative questions of situated contexts and being sensitive to
finite and that current inhabitants have a nonreciprocal what they have to say in response.
obligation to future (and also past) generations. They are The final section of the article builds on the preceding
part of “a community with ourselves” and in that sense, arguments to consider more directly the implications for the
O’Neill (1993, 35) argues, are not strangers. More pro- theory and practice of planning. It should be emphasized
foundly, given the concerns of planning, a lack of concern for these comments represent initial thoughts rather than a final
the future suggests a lack of concern for the collective well- statement.
being of society (Arendt 1958).

䉴 Practical Reasoning: Putting Values Back


The Scope of Justice in Planning into a Concept of Justice in Planning

Overall, these arguments suggest that the scope of justice It is crucial to developing an account of justice in plan-
in relation to planning should be based on a relational ning to situate the debate in the context of that activity and,
understanding of human existence that takes on board the hence, the everyday contested decision making about the spa-
interconnectedness and interdependence of individuals and tial implications of various processes for particular places.
communities, rather than only concentrating on differences. Planning is concerned with making ethical choices about
In this way, the collective implications of individual prefer- better and worse with respect to specific contexts; it is about
ences and actions are appreciated, alongside the meaningless action, more particularly collective action, based on an
quality of rights in the absence of an understanding of oblig- understanding of the relational nature of human existence.
ations, which themselves may not be reciprocal. Arendt In contrast, those concepts of justice that have been most
(1958, 58) warns of the erosion of the public realm and its influential within recent intellectual debates in planning are
substitution by a mass society where “men have become focused on constitutional essentials and moral norms, not
entirely private, that is, they have been deprived of seeing and practical action. Most important, to deny or sidestep compet-
hearing others, of being seen and being heard by them. They ing conceptions of value and the good in an effort to respect
are all imprisoned in the subjectivity of their own singular differences in practice removes the capacity for reevaluation
experience, which does not cease to be singular if the same and in turn may inadvertently lead to the further marginal-
experience is multiplied innumerable times.” ization of the least advantaged.
102 Campbell

It should be emphasized that the concern with incorpo- The importance of reasoning on the basis of substantive
rating questions of value within a concept of justice is about understanding of a particular context is emphasized by
much more than economic value. White (1990, 58) notes that Young (1990). She states, “It is impossible to reason about
economics tends to reduce value to self-interest, an approach substantive moral issues without understanding their sub-
that is “intellectually and ethically intolerable,” particularly stance, which always presupposes some particular social and
where issues of collective concern are at stake. Moreover, it historical context: and one has no motive for making moral
should be clear from this that values and the good are not judgements and resolving moral dilemmas unless the out-
regarded in a narrow utilitarian6 sense, often characterized by come matters, unless one has a particular and passionate
cost-benefit analysis—and forcefully critiqued, especially with interest in the outcome” (p. 104). Practical reasoning there-
respect to the environment (see Low and Gleeson 1998; fore takes place within a specific context, in which particular-
O’Neill 1993; Owens and Cowell 2002). Questions of value ities of substance matter. However, without recourse to values
are not therefore conceived in terms of mere preferences (as in a universal sense, it is impossible to know which particulars
discussed earlier in relation to individual liberty). O’Neill or differences are significant and should inform reasoned
(1993) demonstrates this in relation to the environment action (see, for example, Harvey 1993; O’Neill 2000;
by arguing that human well-being is not reflected in the sat- Nussbaum 1993; Ricoeur 1992). As Merrifield (1997) observes
isfaction of preferences. It is the reasons not the preferences in relation to his work on Toxteth in Liverpool, you have to
that matter. have an understanding of universal values before you can
The inheritance of a concern with practical reasoning and determine the importance of the particular. If all that is
the interplay of the universal and the particular, in relation to acknowledged are particulars and the processes of delibera-
justice, are most often linked to Aristotle. The elitism and tion that bring such issues, for example, to the attention of
exclusionary nature of Greek society at that time has led to planners, how can choices be made between better and
much criticism of this approach. The varied interpretations worse? Planning is left in the realm of the arbitrary or, possi-
of Aristotle’s work are far beyond the scope of this discussion; bly more sinisterly, without any defense against force. Bellamy
nor is the perspective explicitly Aristotelian in nature. In the (1998) argues (in a critique of Walzer) that it is universal (or
remainder of the article, however, some of the issues and thick) conceptions of moralities that secure local (or thin)
implications associated with an account of justice that incor- variations and in turn ensure social justice for the poor and
porates questions of value are explored, including the issues marginalized, not the other way around.
associated with reasoning and judgment as well as the twin At a practical level, the introduction of the London con-
concerns of indeterminacy and imposition. gestion charge exemplifies how progressive change is often
dependent on the clear articulation of strong values, often in
the face of controversy and popular opposition (Livingstone
Judgment: The Link between Reasoning and Justice 2004). It is striking that, having decided that the introduction
of a congestion charge was in the long-term social and envi-
Reasoning and justice are inescapably linked, and this ronmental interests of Londoners, the approach of Ken
remains the case when matters of substance and value are Livingstone’s (mayor of London) team was not to ignore
included. The lingering concern is that such an approach dissenting voices but to consult, learn, and educate. The
brings with it uniformity and a singular conception of the detailed insights they gained from this process influenced the
good life. However, incorporating questions of value into an detailed implementation of the scheme, while not dissuading
account of justice in planning does not imply that there is them of the overall merits of the charge. The subsequent
only one “good life.” The just is not determined by an algo- effectiveness of the congestion charge in London is attrib-
rithm, particularly with respect to a situated activity such as uted to the interplay of a clear social justice agenda with a
planning. There is always scope for discretion, which in turn detailed understanding of local particularities. (See also the
emphasizes that practical reasoning is essentially about judg- Bangladesh example presented earlier from Nussbaum’s
ment. On the other hand, to suggest that justice involves judg- [1993] work.) This example suggests that (some) practition-
ment is not to imply it is arbitrary or dependent upon ers (as well as politicians) may know far more about the inter-
“untutored intuition.” Good judgment is founded upon play of the universal and the particular, at least at an intuitive
knowledge, understanding, and experience (O’Neill 1993). level, than is acknowledged within much theoretical work.
Debate about practical reasoning must move on from the The overall argument, therefore, is that politics and asso-
false dichotomy that suggests it results in either uniformity ciated activities such as planning are about moving from indi-
imposed through inflexible rules or arbitrary reflection of vidual and community identity to the good of the collective,
preferences (O’Neill 2000). Rather, it is about negotiating a while attempting to avoid the worst excesses of the oppressive
path between the universal and the particular, leading to state. This embraces a view of human existence discussed
action. earlier, as relational and interdependent in nature, where
Just Planning 䉳 103

obligations are acknowledged, not just rights. Contestation 䉴 Final Thoughts


between multiple obligations with respect to the spatial impli-
cations of various processes for particular places, if not This article did not set out to provide a handbook for just
inevitable, is at the very least highly probable. In such cir- planning practice, were such an enterprise either possible or
cumstances the crucial mediating role is performed primarily desirable. However, in these final observations an attempt is
by the institutions of the state, with the justice of their actions made to highlight the implications of the preceding for the
involving practical reasoning and judgment, which incorpo- theory and practice of planning.
rates questions of value. This is captured in Ricoeur’s (1992) The recent history of planning thought has seen the
statement about what he refers to as practical wisdom: replacement of the planner as instrumental rationalist by the
A morality of obligation . . . produces conflictual situations planner as facilitator.7 Inherent in both these positions is an
where wisdom has no recourse, . . . other than to return to emphasis on the neutrality of the planner and hence on
the initial intuition of ethics, in the framework of moral appropriate procedures and due process, although of a very
judgement in situation; that is to the vision or aim of the different nature in each case. It is therefore assumed that
“good life” with and for others in just institutions. (p. 240)
Rawls’s underlying premise that a just process will lead to just
This suggests that a concept of justice based on practical rea- outcomes applies every bit as much in the realm of everyday
soning does not provide planners with a formula for action or policy making as with constitutional essentials. Perhaps, more
easy answers. If such were possible, the matters with which particularly, it is assumed that active citizenship is the best
planning is concerned would be trivial. This recognition in means to secure progressive change and practitioners are
itself is important. Societies should not expect, nor should urged to be reflexive in all that they do. But are the views of
politicians and those who work with them suggest, that there all active citizen groups necessarily right and good? What
are guarantees. O’Neill (2000, 61) argues that “the real task of grounds do we have for saying we should listen to the views of
practical judgement is simply to seek ways of acting that respect a low-income community that is about to have a waste incin-
multiple obligations. Although there is no algorithm to be fol- erator located on their door step, over and above a middle-
lowed, the process of practical judging may be better or worse, class NIMBY (phrase used intentionally) group protesting
and may improve or deteriorate.” In relation to specific cases, about a low-income housing development, or an economi-
the parameters of justice set out in this article will be indeter- cally demoralized community seeking to limit the growth in
minate, but that, crucially, does not deny their importance or numbers of asylum seekers within their locality? If we do con-
mean that it is impossible to distinguish some actions as more sider there to be differences in the merits of these arguments,
just than others. Sen (1999) makes a similar point by acknowl- and the preceding suggests we should, then we need to
edging that an inability to determine what is absolutely just acknowledge the importance of questions of substance and,
does not prevent us from being able to make a judgment more particularly, value in relation to justice in planning.
about injustice. “Anything goes” only serves the interests of Similarly, it is all very well to suggest that practitioners should
the already dominant, not the weak or the poor, and it is be reflexive—but about what? When has reflexivity been
surely the needs of the latter that must be in the foreground done well, and when poorly? Again, planning is about an
of a just planning activity. Justice is not about absolutes, for engagement with questions of value, and not values as merely
planners can never fully comprehend nor control their con- individual preferences, but in a relational and collective
texts; but planning has no meaning in the absence of action, sense. A relational understanding of justice is necessary to
and that implies closure around a particular course of action. avoid narrow, essentializing forms of localized justice: to help
A greenfield site cannot both be left for future generations to to work out what is significant from what is not, the legitimate
enjoy and provide affordable, or more likely executive, from the morally unacceptable. It is not as if procedural
homes. An appreciation of multiple truths should teach plan- approaches get around the admittedly enormous difficulties
ners not that they should refrain from engaging with matters of determining the nature of the good; they merely leave the
of substance and value but rather the necessity to reflect criti- values hidden from scrutiny, under a myth of value-neutrality.
cally on the basis of substantive value positions on the fallibil- This article has therefore argued that planning is about
ity of the judgments made. It should be noted, moreover, that making decisions, which involves determining what is impor-
it is an appreciation of multiple truths, not of no truths. White tant and significant in a particular situation; that the decisions
(1990) captures this effectively in the suggestion that we made are unlikely to please everyone; and that this task should
should be tentative, not in the sense that I do not mean what be informed by a relational understanding of justice, which
I say but that I acknowledge that one day, maybe soon, I may explicitly acknowledges the values involved in making such
have to change. Similarly, “Openness does not require that judgments, and which does not presume objectivity nor that
one leaves the door open, but that one is always willing to decisions will be correct for all time. Bringing values and sub-
open the door. Responsibility is the experience of that open- stance into the open will provide the public, politicians, and
ness” (Wood 1999, 117). other planners with insights as to why decisions were made and
104 Campbell

hence why in the future, as circumstances, knowledge, and 䉴 Notes


values change, different courses of action might be appropriate.
If there is any validity in these conclusions about justice in 1. It should be noted that the body of work that goes under
planning, they raise particular challenges for the develop- the label of the communicative, or collaborative, turn (see, for
example, key writers such as Forester [1989, 1999] and Healey
ment of planning theory. Fainstein (2005) concludes a recent [1997]) is more divergent in nature than either its proponents or
article, in which she suggests greater attention should be paid critics often suggest. Moreover, as these authors seek to clarify
to the “just city,” by emphasizing Friedmann’s (2002) call for and refine their position, any statement about this body of work
theorists to engage in both critique and vision in the context tends toward oversimplification. (See, for example, Healey’s
[2003] explanation of the origins and intentions behind her
of a global political-economy. I would not dissent from this conceptualization of collaborative planning.)
view in general terms. However, critique must mean more 2. The individual may be constructed in relation to a particu-
than purely analysis. It must also include: a concern with eval- lar community (or even communities), but the tendency is to
uation and hence the development of evaluative frameworks focus on differences rather than similarities and therefore to lose
sight of collectivist concerns. The community and the collective
(what do we need to know to be able to come to a judg- are not the same.
ment?), and in this there may be much to be gained from the 3. This follows Berlin’s (1969) initial distinction between neg-
work of writers such as Sen; an ability to link analysis and eval- ative and positive liberties.
uation to normative concerns; a concern with analysis and 4. Similarly, Benhabib’s (1992) work has sought to incorpo-
rate contextual criteria to make process orientated accounts of
evaluation which is constructive in intent, not merely with the justice more relevant and even “reasonable.”
easy task of deconstruction (Forester 2004); and an under- 5. In Rawls’s (2001) restatement, he does acknowledge Okin’s
standing of context and its relationship to the planning activ- (1989) criticism.
ity that avoids “idealization” (to use O’Neill’s term discussed 6. It should be noted that the strands of thought underpin-
ning the utilitarian tradition are much richer than the formulaic
earlier) once theorizing becomes concerned with the norma- procedure of cost benefit analysis suggests (see Campbell and
tive. Finally, there also needs to be recognition that planning Marshall 2002).
is concerned with spatial processes and the nature of place. 7. The oversimplification inherent to this statement, I hope,
Attention, therefore, needs to be focused on the nature of will be accepted at this point in the article.

spatial justice and spatial equity. Space and place are central to
planning, and with this comes the complicating issue of geo-
䉴 References
graphical scale. What may be “just” at the scale of the locality
may look very different at the level of the city, region, nation, Arendt, H. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: University of
transnational region, or the globe, as well as across genera- Chicago Press.
tions. It seems arguable that much recent work within plan- Baum, H. 2005. How bad structures drive communities—and
planners—crazy, Planning Theory and Practice 6 (4): 536-44.
ning theory has contributed to understanding justice at the
Beebeejaun, Y. 2003. Contextualising difference: Contesting con-
scale of the locality but in so doing has overlooked planning’s structions of ethnic minority groups in plan-making consulta-
vitally important contribution to seeking just outcomes tion. Ph.D. thesis, University of Sheffield, UK.
beyond the confines of the locality. Bellamy, R. 1998. Justice in the community: An overview of some
contemporary debates. In Social justice: From Hume to Walzer,
The association of justice with practical reasoning in this
ed. D. Boucher and P. Kelly, 157-80. London: Routledge.
article is not about the reinstatement of the omnipotent public Benhabib, S. 1992. Situating the self: Gender, community and post-
servant but quite the reverse. Practical reasoning must not be modernism in contemporary ethics. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
static: it must be open to the discomforting specter of constantly Berlin, I. 1969. Four essays on liberty. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
learning and striving to do better. Justice has to be dialectical in
Blanco, H. 1995. Community and four jewels of planning. In A
nature (Harvey 1996, 2000). Planning has been resoundingly reader in planning ethics: Planning theory, practice and education, ed.
criticized for the staid and even oppressive nature of the spatial S. Hendler, 66-82. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
forms that have resulted, yet the celebration of individual and Brown, C. 1998. International social justice. In Social justice: From
Hume to Walzer, ed. D. Boucher and P. Kelly, 102-19. London:
community identity tends to replace one static view of the world
Routledge.
with another or with many others. Consequently an account of Burley, K. 2005. Probity and professional conduct in planning: A
justice based on practical reasoning involves both the universal personal perspective. Planning Theory and Practice 6 (4): 526-36.
and the particular, deliberation and judgment. Justice in Campbell, H. 2002. Planning: An idea of value. Town Planning
Review 73 (3): 271-88.
planning is about situated ethical judgment.
Campbell, H., ed. 2003. Interface: Reforming planning systems?
Planning Theory and Practice 4 (3): 347-70.
Author’s Note: The author is very appreciative of the thoughtful and Campbell, H., and R. Marshall. 1999. Ethical frameworks and
constructive comments provided by the editor and the four anonymous planning theory. International Journal of Urban and Regional
reviewers. The arguments presented in this paper have also benefited con- Research 23 (3): 464-78.
siderably from the support and stimulation provided by Robert Marshall ———. 2000. Public involvement and planning: Looking
and Robert Upton as well as my colleagues in the Department of Town beyond the one to the many. International Planning Studies
and Regional Planning at the University of Sheffield. 5 (3): 321-44.
Just Planning 䉳 105

———. 2002. Utilitarianism’s bad breadth? A re-evaluation of Leopold, A. 1968. A Sand County almanac and sketches here and there.
the public interest justification for planning. Planning Theory London: Oxford University Press.
1 (2): 163-87. Livingstone, K. 2004. The challenge of driving through change:
———. 2005. Towards justice in planning: A reappraisal. Introducing congestion charging in central London. Planning
European Planning Studies 14 (2): 239-52. Theory and Practice 5 (4): 490-98.
Cooke, M. 1999. Questioning autonomy: The feminist challenge Low, N., and B. Gleeson. 1997. Justice in and to the environment:
and the challenge of feminism. In Questioning ethics: Ethical uncertainties and political practices. Environment and
Contemporary debates in philosophy, ed. R. Kearney and M. Dooley, Planning A 29 (1): 21-42.
258-82. London: Routledge. ———. 1998. Justice, society and nature: An exploration of political
Connor, S. 1993. The necessity of value. In Principled positions: ecology. London: Routledge.
Postmodermism and the rediscovery of value, ed. J. Squires, 31-49. MacIntryre, A. 1981. After virtue. London: Duckworth.
London: Lawrence and Wishart. ———. 1999. Some enlightenment projects reconsidered.
Daniels, N. 1975. Introduction. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on In Questioning ethics: Contemporary debates in philosophy, ed.
Rawls’ A Theory of Justice, ed. N. Daniels, xi-xxxiv. Oxford, R. Kearney and M. Dooley, 245-57. London: Routledge.
UK: Basil Blackwell. McCarthy, T. 1999. Enlightenment and the idea of public reason.
Eagleton, T. 1996. The illusions of postmodernism. Oxford, UK: In Questioning ethics: Contemporary debates in philosophy, ed.
Blackwell. R. Kearney and M. Dooley, 164-80. London: Routledge.
Fainstein, S. 1999. Can we make the cities we want? In The urban McConnell, S. 1995. Rawlsian planning theory. In A reader in plan-
question: Cosmopolitan essays on the late-20th-century city, ed. ning ethics: Planning theory, practice and education, ed. S. Handler,
R. Beauregard and S. Body-Gendrot, 249-72. London: Sage. 30-48. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
———. 2000. New directions in planning theory. Urban Affairs Merrifield, A. 1997. Social justice and communities of difference:
Review 35 (4): 451-78. A snapshot from Liverpool. In The urbanisation of injustice, ed.
———. 2005. Planning theory and the city. Journal of Planning by A. Merrifield and E. Swyngedouw, 200-222. New York: New
Education and Research 25 (2): 121-30. York University Press.
Fischer, F. 1980. Politics, values, and public policy: The problem of Mouffe, C. 1996. Democracy, power, and the “political.” In
methodology. Boulder, CO: Westview. Democracy and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political,
———. 2003. Reframing public policy: Discursive politics and delibera- ed. S. Benhabib, 245-56. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
tive practices. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Press.
Flyvbjerg, B. 1998. Rationality and power: Democracy and practice. Mulhall, S., and A. Swift. 1997. Liberals and communitarians, 2nd
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ed. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Forester, J. 1989. Planning in the face of power. Berkeley: University Murdoch, I. 1970. The sovereignty of the good. London: Routledge &
of California Press. Kegan Paul.
———. 1999. The deliberative practitioner: Encouraging participatory Naess, A. 1989. Ecology, community and lifestyle. Cambridge:
planning processes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cambridge University Press.
———. 2004. Reflections on trying to teach planning theory. Nussbaum, M. 1993. Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian
Planning Theory and Practice 5 (2): 242-51. approach. In The quality of life, ed. M. Nussbaum and A. Sen,
Friedmann, J. 2002. The prospect of cities. Minneapolis: University 242-69. Oxford, UK: Clarendon.
of Minnesota Press. Nussbaum, M., and A. Sen. 1993. Introduction. In The quality of life,
Gilligan, C. 1993. In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s ed. M. Nussbaum and A. Sen, 1-6. Oxford, UK: Clarendon.
development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Okin, S. M. 1989. Justice, gender and the family. New York: Basic
Habermas, J. 1990. Moral consciousness and communicative action. Books.
Cambridge, UK: Polity. ———. 1999. Essay: Is multiculturalism bad for women? In Is mul-
———. 1996. Between facts and norms. Translated by W. Rehg. ticulturalism bad for women? ed. J. Cohen, M. Howard, and
London: Polity. M. Nussbaum, 9-24. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Harrison, P. 2002. “On the edge of reason”: Planning and the O’Neill, J. 1993. Ecology, policy and politics: Human well-being and the
futures of Southern African cities. Inaugural lecture pre- natural world. London: Routledge.
sented at the University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, O’Neill, O. 1996. Towards justice and virtue. Cambridge:
South Africa, October. Cambridge University Press.
Hart, H. L. A. 1975. Rawls on liberty and its priority. In Reading ———. 1997. Political liberalism and public reason: A critical
Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls’ A Theory of Justice, ed. notice of John Rawls. Political Liberalism, The Philosophical
N. Daniels, 230-52. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell. Review 106 (3): 411-28.
Harvey, D. 1993. Class relations, social justice and the politics of ———. 2000. Bounds of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University
difference. In Principled positions: Postmodernism and the redis- Press.
covery of value, ed. J. Squires, 85-120. London: Lawrence and Owens, S., and R. Cowell. 2002. Land and limits: Interpreting sus-
Wishart. tainability in the planning process. London: Routledge.
———. 1996. Justice, nature and the geography of difference. Oxford: Peffer, R. G. 1990. Marxism, morality and social justice. Princeton,
Blackwell. NJ: Princeton University Press.
———. 2000. Spaces of hope. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh Phillips, A. 1993. Democracy and difference. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
University Press. ———. 1996. Dealing with difference: A politics of ideas, or a
Healey, P. 1997. Collaborative planning: Shaping places in fragmented politics of presence? In Democracy and difference: Contesting the
societies. Basingstoke, UK: Macmillan. boundaries of the political, ed. S. Benhabib, 139-52. Princeton,
———. 2003. Collaborative Planning in context. Planning Theory NJ: Princeton University Press.
2 (2): 101-23. Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University
Hendler, S., ed. 1995. A reader in planning ethics: Planning theory, Press.
practice and education. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University ———. 2001. Justice as fairness: A restatement. Edited by E. Kelly.
Press. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
106 Campbell

Ricoeur, P. 1992. Oneself as another. Translated by K. Blamey. Vincent, A. 1998. Is environmental justice a misnomer? In Social
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. justice: From Hume to Walzer, ed. D. Boucher and P. Kelly,
Sayer, A., and M. Storper. 1997. Guest editorial essay: Ethics 120-40. London: Routledge.
unbound: For a normative turn in social theory. Environment Walzer, M. 1983. Spheres of justice: A defence of pluralism and equality.
and Planning D 15: 1-17. Oxford, UK: Martin Robertson.
Sen, A. 1999. Development as freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Watson, V. 2003. Conflicting rationalities: Implications for
Press. planning theory and ethics. Planning Theory and Practice 4 (4):
Singer, P. 1993. Practical ethics. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge 395-407.
University Press. White, J. B. 1990. Justice as translation: An essay in cultural and legal
Soper, K. 1993. Postmodernism, subjectivity and the question of criticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
value. In Principled positions: Postmodernism and the rediscovery of Williams, D. L. 1999. Dialogical theories of justice. Telos 30:
value, ed. J. Squires, 17-30. London: Lawrence and Wishart. 109-31.
Squires, J. 1993. Introduction. In Principled positions: Postmodernism Wilson, N. 2005. The dark side of community development.
and the rediscovery of value, ed. J. Squires, 1-13. London: Lawrence Planning Theory and Practice 6 (4): 519-25.
and Wishart. Wood, D. 1999. The experience of the ethical. In Questioning
Stein, S. M., and T. L. Harper. 2002. The Rawlsian “political lib- ethics: Contemporary debates in philosophy, ed. R. Kearney and
eral” basis of dialogical/communicative planning. Paper pre- M. Dooley, 105-19. London: Routledge.
sented at Association of European Schools of Planning Yiftachel, O. 1998. Planning and social control: Exploring the
Congress, Volos, Greece, July 11-13. “dark side.” Journal of Planning Literature 12 (4): 395-406.
Storper, M. 2001. The poverty of radical theory today: From the Young, I. M. 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, NJ:
false promises of Marxism to the mirage of the cultural turn. Princeton University Press.
International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 25: 155-79. ———. 1993. Together in difference: Transforming the logic of
Taylor, C. 1993. Explanation and practical reason. In The quality group political conflict. In Principled positions and the rediscov-
of life, ed. M. Nussbaum and A. Sen, 208-31. Oxford, UK: ery of value, ed. J. Squires, 121-50. London: Lawrence and
Clarendon. Wishart.
Upton, R. 2002. Planning praxis: Ethics, values and theory. Town ———. 2000. Inclusion and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University
Planning Review 73 (3): 253-69. Press.

You might also like