You are on page 1of 14

The Psychology of Preferences

When people make risky choices, they often do not do so objectively.

Experimental surveys indicate that such departures from objectivity

tend to follow regular patterns that can be described mathematically

by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky

magine yourself on your way to a Daniel Bernoulli. In the essay Bernoulli fer the gamble to the loss. The mone­

I Broadway play with a pair of tickets


tor which you have paid $40. On
discussed a widespread characteristic of
human preferences: risk aversion. To
tary expectation of the gamble ( $85).
-

however, is worse than that of the cer­


tain loss ( $80). The majority prefer­
entering the theater you discover that understand risk aversion, imagine that -

you have lost the tickets. Would you pay you are given a choice between two op­ ence is thus an instance of risk seeking.
$40 for another pair of tickets? Now tions. The first is a sure gain of $80. The The contrast between the majority
imagine you are on your way to the second is a risky prospect that offers an choices observed in these two problems
same play without having bought tick­ 85 percent chance of winning $100 and suggests that preferences between gains
ets. On entering the theater you realize a 15 percent chance of winning nothing. are risk-averse and that preferences be­
that you have lost $40 in cash. Would Most people who are presented with tween losses are risk-seeking. This pat­
you now buy tickets to the play? this choice prefer the certain gain to the tern has been observed both in answers
In objective terms the two situations gamble, in spite of the fact that the gam­ to hypothetical questions and in real de­
are identical: in both cases you are poor­ ble has a higher "monetary expectation" cision problems where people were paid
er by $40 than you were earlier, and you than the certain outcome. The monetary according to their choices. The same
face the decision of whether or not to expectation of a gamble is the sum of its pattern has been confirmed for hypo­
pay $40 to see the play. Nevertheless, outcomes weighted by their probabili­ thetical problems that involve outcomes
most people presented with such a situa­ ties. The monetary expectation of the other than money, such as duration of
tion say they would be more likely to gamble offered in this case is $100 mul­ pain and the number of lives that may be
buy new tickets if they had lost money tiplied by its probability (. 85), added to lost in an epidemic or saved by medical
than if they had lost tickets. One in­ $0 multiplied by its probability (.15), or intervention.
terpretation of the difference between a total of $85. The monetary expecta­ When people make risk-averse or
·
the two situations is that the same loss tion reflects the average monetary value risk-seeking choices they forgo the op­
can be assigned to different "mental ac­ of the gamble; if one were to play this tion that offers the highest monetary
counts." The loss of $40 in cash is en­ gamble many times, the average gain expectation. In order to explain such
tered in an account distinct from that of would be about $85 per play. The mone­ choices Bernoulli replaced the objective
the play. The loss therefore has little ef­ tary expectation of the certain gain is criterion of monetary expectation with
fect on the decision to buy new tickets. $80 multiplied by 1 (certainty), or $80. the subjective criterion of expected utili­
In contrast, the cost of the lost tickets is A choice is risk-averse if a certain out­ ty. According to expected utility theory,
posted to the account of the play. The come is preferred to a gamble with an each outcome gives rise to a particular
unexpected doubling of the cost of the equal or greater monetary expectation. degree of pleasure or utility. The utility
play is difficult to accept. A choice is risk-seeking, on the other of a risky prospect is the weighted sum
Recent investigations of the psychol­ hand, if a certain outcome is rejected in of the utilities of its outcomes, each mul­
ogy of preferences have demonstrated favor of a gamble with an equal or lower tiplied by its probability. The central
several intriguing discrepancies between monetary expectation. idea of the theory is that utility is not
subjective and objective conceptions of a linear function of money: a gain of
he hypothesis that people generally $2,000 contributes less than twice as
decisions. For example, the threat of a
loss has a greater impact on a decision T make risk-averse choices has been much to utility as a gain of $1,000. As a
than the possibility of an equivalent widely accepted by economists who nor­ consequence the prospect with the high­
gain. Most people are also very sensitive mally assume that a consumer or an en­ est monetary expectation does not nec­
to the difference between certainty and trepreneur will choose a risky venture essarily have the highest expected utili­
high probability and relatively insensi­ over a sure thing only when the mone­ ty. The decision maker is assumed to
tive to intermediate gradations of prob­ tary expectation of the venture is suffi­ select the option with the highest utility,
ability. The regret associated with a loss ciently high to compensate the decision whether or not that option also has the
that was incurred by an action tends to maker for taking the risk. Psychological greatest monetary expectation.
be more intense than the regret associat­ studies, however, indicate that risk-seek­ How do people identify the outcomes
ed with inaction or a missed opportuni­ ing preferences are common when peo­ of a decision? It has generally been as­
ty. These observations and others of a ple must choose between a sure loss and sumed, following Bernoulli, that utili­
similar character contribute to the un­ a substantial probability of a larger loss. ties are assigned to states of wealth. We
derstanding of how people make deci­ To get a sense of risk seeking imagine depart from this tradition and analyze
sions and to the elucidation of some you are forced to choose between a sure choices in terms of changes of wealth
puzzles of rational choice. loss of $80 and a risk that involves an 85 rather than states of wealth. The classi­
The origin of the psychology of pref­ percent chance of losing $100 and a 15 cal analysis implies that preferences re­
erences can be traced to an essay pub­ percent chance of losing nothing. Faced flect a comprehensive view of the options.
lished in 173 8 by the mathematician with this choice a large majority pre- In contrast. we propose that people

160

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC
commonly adopt a limited view of the mon impression that the difference be­ To explain the common observation
outcomes of decisions: they identify tween a gain of $100 and one of $200 of risk-seeking preferences in choices
consequences as gains or losses relative is more significant than the difference that involve losses, we assume that the
to a neutral point. This form of men­ between a gain of $1,100 and one of value function for losses is convex, so
tal accounting can lead to inconsistent $1,200. This shape of the value function that each extra dollar lost causes a
choices, because the same objective favors risk aversion. smaller change in value than the preced­
consequence can be evaluated in more ing one. This proposal is compatible
than one way. onsider the choice between a sure with the common impression that the
To explain choices we introduce a C gain and a gamble that offers some difference between a loss of $100 and
function that associates a subjective val­ probability of a larger gain and some one of $200 appears more significant
ue to any amount that may be gained probability of no gain at all. The ad­ than the difference between a loss of
or lost. We call it a value function. As in vantage of the large gain over the sure $1,100 and one of $1,200. The convexi­
classical utility theory, risk seeking and thing is evaluated in a shallow region ty of the value function for losses favors
risk aversion are explained by the curva­ of the value function, where increments a risk-seeking preference for a gamble
ture of the function that relates subjec­ of money produce relatively small incre­ over a sure loss. The advantage of the
tive values to objective outcomes. Con­ ments of value. The advantage of the best outcome of the gamble (no loss)
sider first the value function for gains. sure outcome over no gain is evaluated over the StIre loss is evaluated in the
We assume that gains have positive val­ in the steepest region of the function, steepest region of the value function. On
ue and that a zero gain, which merely where each dollar makes a greater dif­ the other hand, the advantage of the sure
retains the status quo, has a subjective ference. Because value is nonlinear the loss over the worst outcome of the gam­
value of zero. We also propose that the sure outcome is closer to the large gain ble is evaluated in a flatter region. As a
value function for gains is concave in terms of value than in terms of mon­ result the sure loss is relatively closer to
downward, so that each extra dollar ey. The shape of the value function the worst outcome on the value scale
gained adds less to value than the pre­ thus favors a risk-averse preference for than it is on the money scale [see illustra­
ceding one. The concavity of the value sure outcomes over risky prospects [see tion on page 164].
function is compatible with the com- illustration below]. The properties of the value function
can be inferred from observed choices.
To undertand how this procedure works
imagine you have been offered a choice
VALUE ----------------------------------------------------�
OF$100 .- between winning a cash prize and hav­
ing a 50 percent chance of winning $100.
VALUE --------------------------------------------� What amount would make the sure
OF$80 � prize just as attractive as the bet? A
.85 ;<' choice of $3 5 as the matching prize is
VALUE common. If you find $3 5 as attractive as
OF$100 the gamble, your value for this amount
must equal your value for the gamble.
On the assumptions that we introduced
above the value of the gamble is 1/2 the
value of $100, since the probability of
winning $100 is 1/2 and the value of the
other outcome (winning nothing) was

i assumed to be zero. Consequently the


choice of $3 5 to match the gamble indi­
cates that the value of $3 5 is half the
value of $100.
Now find the prize amounts that
match a 50 percent chance of winning
$200, $500, $1,000 and $2,000. If you
try this thought experiment, you will
naturally find that the amount of the
prize increases with the size of the bet.
You may also observe that the prize
is roughly proportional to the stake. A
person who matches a prize of $3 5 to an
even chance of winning $100 is likely to
match a prize of $3 00 or $3 50 to an even
chance of winning $1,000. Thus as the
amount of the bet has increased by a
factor of 10 the prize has grown by al­
o 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
most the same factor.
GAINS (DOLLARS)

CONCAVE VALUE FUNCTION helps to explain preferences where gains are concerned.
A value represents the subjective attractiveness of a gain (or loss). The function assigns a value I t the
can be proved mathematically that
value function of an individual
to each possible gain. Gains are indicated on the horizontal axis, values on the vertical axis. The who sets prizes exactly proportional to
status quo is assigned the value of zero. (The units of value are arbitrary.) The concave function stakes can be described by a power func­
becomes progressively flatter as the amount of the gain is increased. Risk-averse preferences tion. In such a function the value of an
are common when people make choices among gains. In a risk-averse choice a sure gain is pre­
amount of money equals that amount,
ferred to a gamble with a higher monetary expectation. The monetary expectation of a gamble
raised to some power. The exponent of
is the sum of its outcomes multiplied by their probabilities. Hence an 85 percent chance of win­
the value function can be estimated
ning $100 has a monetary expectation of .85 multiplied by $100, or $85. This is greater than
the monetary expectation of a sure gain of $80 ($80 multiplied by certainty, or $80). The value
from choices. If the prize that matches
of the sure gain, however, is greater than that of the gamble, which is .85 multiplied by the val­ a 50 percent chance of winning an
ue of $100. The value function thus predicts that the sure gain will be preferred to the gamble. amount of money is always 3 5 percent

162

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC
of that amount, the exponent of the val­ that would make this bet acceptable to tern of choices and not a universal law.
ue function for gains is about 2/3 . Ac­ you? It is a commonplace that the plea­ Naturally individuals differ in their
tually the proportionality of prizes to sure of winning a sum of money is much attitudes toward risk and toward mon­
stakes is only approximate. The prize less intense than the pain of losing the ey, and no single value function can de­
generally increases more slowly than same sum. Accordingly people accept a scribe the preferences of all individuals.
the stake. Because the deviation from gamble at even odds only when the pos­ Choices also can vary substantially with
proportionality is small, however, a sible gain from the gamble is substan­ the method used to elicit preferences.
power function provides a convenient tially larger than the possible loss. For For example, the acceptability of a risky
description of the values of gains. example, you may find that a 50 percent prospect may depend on whether the re­
A similar analysis can be applied to chance to lose $100 is unacceptable un­ spondent matches a gain to a set loss,
losses. An even chance of losing $100 less it is combined with an equal chance matches a loss to a set gain or adjusts
or losing nothing is often matched by a to win $200 or more. the odds when the amounts at stake are
sure loss of about $40, and an even By observing the choices people make fixed. In addition the near proportional­
chance of losing $1,000 or nothing by a among gains and losses we have spec­ ity of prizes to stakes breaks down be­
sure loss of about $400. If the sure loss ified some features of the value func­ yond the range of moderate gains and
that matches a 50 percent chance to lose tion. The approximate proportionality losses. For extremely lafge gains the val­
an amount is always 40 percent of that of prizes and bets is reflected in the pow­ ue function becomes practically flat as
amount, the exponent of the value func­ er relation between gains and their val­ individuals can no longer distinguish
tion for losses is about 3 /4. ues. Risk aversion and risk seeking are one huge gain from another. In the nega­
In order to piece together the value described by the concave and the con­ tive domain, however, the function can
functions for both gains and losses it is vex segments of the value function. The be very steep in the vicinity of mone­
necessary to study risky prospects that asymmetry in the response to gains and tary losses that would force a substan­
involve both positive and negative out­ to losses is expressed in the greater tial change in a person's way of life.
comes. Consider a gamble in which you steepness of the value function for los­
face a 50 percent chance of losing $100
and a 50 percent chance of winning a
ses. It is important to emphasize, how­
ever, that the value function is merely a T he discussion to this point has as­
sumed that the contribution of each
cash prize. What is the smallest prize convenient summary of a common pat- outcome to the value of a risky prospect
is weighted by its probability. There is
evidence that this assumption is often
LOSSES (DOLLARS) violated and that the "decision weights"
-100 -90 -80 -70 -60 -50 -40 -30 -20 -10 -0 that multiply the values of outcomes do
not coincide with the probabilities.
Some properties of decision weights
can be explored by the following infor­
mal experiment. Imagine that you can
improve your chances to win a very de­
sirable prize. Would you pay as much to
raise your chance of winning from 30 to
40 percent as you would to raise your
chance from 90 percent to certainty? It
is generally agreed that the former offer
is less valuable than the latter. It is also
agreed that an increase from impossibil­
:;;
r ity to a probability of 10 percent is more
C
m significant than an increase from 30 to
40 percent. Thus the difference between
certainty and possibility and the differ­
ence between possibility and impossibil­
ity loom larger than comparable differ­
ences in the intermediate range of prob­
ability [see illustration on page 140].
Investigations of risky choices tend to
confirm these hypotheses. Low proba­
bilities are commonly overweighted but
.85 x intermediate and high probabilities are
VALUE usually underweighted relative to cer­
OF-$100
tainty. The impossible event is naturally
VALUE assigned a weight of zero and the certain
��--------------------------------------� OF-$80
event is assigned a weight of one. The
overweighting of small probabilities can
u£�--------------------------------------------------� VALUE
- give rise to risk seeking in the positive
OF $100
domain and risk aversion in the negative
CONVEX VALUE FUNCTION explains preferences where losses are concerned. The func­ domain, in contrast to the prevalent pat­
tion assigns a unique negative value to each monetary loss. Losses are indicated on the horizon­ tern of preferences described above.
tal axis to the left of the origin; values are shown on the vertical axis downward. The status quo The inflated effect of small probabili­
is assigned the value of zero. The convex function becomes progressively flatter for larger los­ ties contributes to the appeal of lottery
ses. Risk-seeking preferences are common when people make choices among possible losses. In
tickets and accident insurance, which
a risk-seeking choice a gamble is preferred to a sure loss that has a greater monetary expecta­
are concerned with events that are high­
tion. The value function predicts that a gamble offering an 85 percent chance of losing $100
and a 15 percent chance of losing nothing will be preferred to a sure loss of $80. The monetary ly significant and relatively improbable.
expectation of the gamble (-$85) is less than that of the sure loss (-$80). The value of the The underweighting of intermediate and
gamble, however (which is .85 multiplied by the value of -$100), is greater (has a smaller high probabilities, on the other hand,
negative magnitude) than that of the sure loss. Because the gamble has a greater value it will reduces the attractiveness of possible
be preferred. The convex value function therefore helps to explain risk-seeking preferences. gains relative to sure ones. It also reduc-

164

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC
es the threat of possible losses relative to We have so far been concerned with tween (A) a sure gain of $50 and (B) a 25
sure ones. The contribution of decision rules that govern the evaluation of percent chance of winning $200 and a
weights was neglected in the construc­ risky options. Another important as­ 75 percent chance of winning nothing.
tion of the value function we described pect of the psychology of preferences is Most people given these options make
above. In that function all observed risk how people define the consequences of a risk-averse choice, preferring the sure
aversion and risk seeking were assumed their choices. The same decision can gain (A) over the gamble (B), which has
to be the result of curvature of the value be framed in several different ways; dif­ the same expected value. Now consider
function. If the probability of .5 that was ferent frames can lead to different de­ the following problem:
applied in the construction of the func­ cisions. For example, consider the fol­
tion were replaced by a slightly small­ lowing problem:
er decision weight, the value function Imagine that in addition to whatev­ I magine that in addition to whatever
you have, you have been given a
would become less curved, although it er else you have, you have been given cash gift of $400. You are now asked to
would retain its general S shape. $200. You are now asked to choose be- choose between (C) a sure loss of $150
and (D) a 75 percent chance of losing
$200 and a 25 percent chance of losing
+
nothing. .,.-
w
:::> Most people have a risk-seeking pref­
...J
erence for the gamble (D) over the sure
VALUE §
OF$1,000 ±:-�---------� loss (C). The options presented in the
two problems are identical, however, in
objective terms. There is no valid reason
to prefer the gamble in one version and
.50 x VALUE the sure outcome in the other. Choosing
OF$1,000 ....--��
... the sure gain in the first problem yields
VALUE a total gain of $200 plus $50, or $250.
OF$200 Choosing the sure loss in the second
version yields the same result through
the deduction of $150 from $400. The
choice of the gamble in either problem
200 400 600 800 1,000 1,200
yields a 75 percent chance of winning
LOSSES GAINS $200 and a 25 percent chance of win­
ning $400.
If our respondents took a comprehen­
sive view of the consequences, as is as­
sumed by theories of rational decision,
they would combine the bonus with the
available options and evaluate the com­
posite outcome. Instead they ignore the
1-----+ .50 x VALUE bonus and evaluate the first problem as
OF -$1,000
a choice between gains and the second
as a choice between losses. The reversal
of preferences is induced by altering the
description of outcomes. We call such
reversals framing effects.
Framing effects arise when the same
objective alternatives are evaluated in
relation to different points of reference.
We asked a large number of physicians
VALUE to consider the following problem:
I-----------+ OF -$1,000
Imagine that the U.S. is preparing for
the outbreak of a rare Asian disease,
which is expected to kill 600 people.
Two alternative programs to combat the
disease have been proposed. Assume
that the exact scientific estimates of the
S-SHAPED VALUE FUNCTION combines a concave segment representing the values of consequences of the programs are as
gains and a convex segment representing the values of losses. The concave segment to the right follows: If Program A is adopted, 200
of the origin reflects risk aversion in choices between gains; the convex segment to the left re­ people will be saved. If Program B is
flects risk seeking in choices between losses. The segment for gains represents preferences in
adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that
which a 50 percent chance to win a given amount is just as acceptable as a sure gain of 35 per­
600 people will be saved and a 2/3 prob­
cent of that amount. For example, a 50 percent chance of winning $1,000 is as acceptable as
a sure gain of $350. The value of $350 is therefore half the value of $1,000. Such a pattern
ability that no people will be saved.
of preferences can be expressed by a power function with an exponent of 2/3. (In a power Which of the two programs would you
function the value of a gain is equal to the magnitude of the gain raised to a fixed exponent.) favor?
The segment for losses represents preferences in which a 50 percent chance of losing a given The majority response to this problem
amount is just as acceptable as a sure loss of 40 percent of that amount: a 50 percent chance to is a risk-averse preference for Program
lose $1,000 is as acceptable as a sure loss of about $400. The negative value of $400 is there­
-
A over Program B.
fore half the negative value of -$1,000. Preferences where losses are concerned can be ex­
pressed by a power function with an exponent of 3/4. The S-shaped function reflects the com­
ther respondents were presented
mon observation that a loss has a greater subjective effect than an eqllivalent gain. Because the
slope of the function for losses is steeper than that for gains, the negative value of a loss of
O with the same problem but a differ­
$100 is equal to the positive value of a gain of $200. The function therefore represents the ent formulation of the programs: If Pro­
preference of a person who finds an even chance of winning $200 or of losing $100 just ac­ gram C is adopted, 400 people will die.
ceptable; this is a typical pattern. The function shown summarizes some common features of If Program D is adopted, there is a 1/3
preferences observed in tests of many people; individual value functions can vary greatly. probability that nobody will die and a

166

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


Quick check-in at the
First Class counter. Priority
baggage handling.
Whenever possible,
a drink on us at the Captain's
Club before boarding.
A special section aboard
your Qantas 747. Wide chairs in
pairs so you're never more than one
seat from an aisle.
Free bar service and in-flight
entertainment.
A special menu with a choice
of entrees and fine wines, followed
by a selection of liqueurs.
Enjoy these and other
first-class touches on Qantas
Business Class. Twelve
flights a week to
Australia. T hree flights
a week to Tahiti.
Ask your
Travel Agent about
Qantas Business
Class. Only $100
or so more than the
Economy Class Fare
to Australia.
And that's perfect.

OR NTR!S T he Australian Airline.

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


2/3 probability that 600 people will die. after which one has more goods and less were asked to imagine they had lost the
The majority choice in this problem is money than before. A transaction must ticket said they would not.
risk-seeking: the certain death of 400 be evaluated according to the balance of Mental accounting is dominated by
people is less acceptable than a 2/3 costs and benefits in a mental account. the tendency to group the costs and ben­
chance that 600 people will die. The framing of a transaction can alter efits associated with an object, as the
It is easy to see that the two versions its attractiveness by controlling the costs following example illustrates:
of the problem describe identical out­ and benefits that are assigned to its ac­ Imagine you are about to buy a jacket
comes. The only difference is that in the count, as in our example of the theater for $125 and a calculator for $15. The
first version the death of 600 people is tickets. Going to the theater is normally calculator salesman tells you that the
the normal reference point and the out­ framed as a transaction, in which the calculator you want to buy is on sale for
comes are evaluated as gains (lives cost of the ticket is exchanged for the $10 at the other branch of the store, a
saved), whereas in the second version experience of seeing the play. If the tick­ 20-minute drive away. Would you make
no deaths is the normal reference point et has been lost, buying a new one effec­ the trip to the other store?
and the programs are evaluated in terms tively doubles the cost of the play. In, The majority of the respondents who
of lives lost. Because of the S-shaped contrast the loss of the cash is not con­ answered this question said they would
value function and the overweighting of sidered a debit to the account of the drive to the other store. Another group
certainty the two frames elicit different play. The cash loss affects the decision answered a-similar question in which
preferences. to buy a new ticket only to the extent the cost of the jacket was changed to
that a minor reduction of wealth reduc­ $15 and the cost of the calculator was

T he decisions we have discussed so far


involve a single dimension. Many
es the tendency to make optional pur­
chases. When we asked a sample of stu­
changed to $125 in the original store and
$120 in the other branch. Of the respon­
decisions, however, concern transac­ dents a version of this question involv­ dents presented with this version, the
tions, in which the possible outcomes ing a single lost ticket, the majority of majority said they would not make the
include connected changes in several di­ those who were asked to imagine they trip. The total purchase and the conse­
mensions of value. The basic example of had lost the money said they would buy quences are the same in both versions:
a transaction is the purchase of goods a ticket, but the majority of those who one has to decide whether to drive 20
minutes to save $5. The contrasting
choices in the two versions suggest that
1.0 r-------� the respondents evaluated the saving
of $5 in relation to the price of the cal­
culator. In relative terms a reduction
from $15 to $10 is more impressive
than a reduction from $125 to $120.
Framing effects in consumer behavior
may be particularly pronounced in situ­
ations that have a single dimension of
cost (usually money) and several dimen­
sions of benefit. An elaborate tape deck
is a distinctive asset in the purchase of a
new car. Its cost, however, is naturally

treated as a small increment over the
I
(!)
price of the car. The purchase is made
W easier by judging the value of the tape
� deck. independently and its cost as an
z .50
o increment. Many buyers of homes have
iii similar experiences. Furniture is often
o
w bought with little distress at the same
o
time as a house. Purchases that are post­
poned, perhaps because the desired
items were not available, often appear
extravagant when contemplated sepa­
. 25 rately: their cost looms larger on its
own. The attractiveness of a course of
action may thus change if its cost or
benefit is placed in a larger account.

I f ence
a decision is influenced by the refer­
point with which possible out­
comes are compared, what determines
. 25 .50 .75 1 .0
the reference point? The dependence of
PROBABILITY impressions, judgments and responses
on a point of reference is a ubiquitous
DECISION WEIGHTS express the subjective evaluation of probabilities. The classical analy­ psychological phenomenon. The same
sis of decisions assumes that decision weights (heavy line) coincide with probabilities (light line). tub of tepid water may be felt as hot to
Recent investigations, however, suggest that decision weights do not coincide with probabili­ one hand and cold to the other if the
ties. Because probabilities are used to derive the value of gambles, the subjective response to hands have been exposed to water of
probabilities complicates the task of formulating a realistic value function. In particular, the different temperatures. A given income
difference between certainty and possibility and the difference between possibility and impos­
may be considered lavish or inadequate
sibility are given more weight than comparable differences in the intermediate range of proba­
depending on whether one's earnings
bility. The main properties of decision weights are illustrated by the curve shown. Impossibili­
ty is assigned a weight of zero; certainty is assigned a weight of one. Small probabilities are
have recently increased or decreased.
overweighted in relation to impossibility; moderate and large probabilities are underweigbted In these cases the reference point is the
in relation to certainty. The overweighting of small probabilities contributes to the attractive­ state to which one has become adapted.
ness of both lottery tickets and insurance policies by enbancing the impact of unlikely events. In many cases, however, the reference

168

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC
point is determined by events that are
How to Argue and Win!
Voyager Visions Here is a clear simply written basic guide to
only imagined. Consider the following
incident:
logical thinking, showing how to spot the
fallacies; the prejudices and emotionalism, Mr. Crane and Mr. Thomas were
the inappro�riate analogies, etc., in the
other fellow s argument and how to watch
scheduled to leave the airport on dif­
for and avoid the irrational in your own ferent flights at the same time. They
judgments. The author makes plain not
only '- but also why people . resist facing
traveled from town in the same limou­
the truth.
A tool for clear tIIInklng as well as con­
sine, were caught in a traffic jam and ar­
vincing others. rived at the airport 30 minutes after the
58.95 plus 51.25 handhng
THE ART OF ARGUMENT by Giles St. Aubvn scheduled departure of their flights.
Mr. Crane is told that his flight left on
GEM TESTING time. Mr. Thomas is told that his flight
was delayed and just left five minutes
FOR FUN AND PROFIT ago. Who is the more upset?
This exciting pursuij combines the chal-
lenge of detective work . .. the thrill of
Almost everyone presented with this
spotting sensational"buys" ... the satis- incident agrees that Mr. Thomas is more
faction of knowing when someone else's
big flashy "diamond isn't ... and the op­ upset than �Mr. Crane, although their
We now offer five stunning fUll-color portunoly for highly paid, spare-time earn­
lOgs. GfM TESTING, bible of amateur and objective conditions are identical: both
posters featuring highlights of the Voyager
missions to Jupiter and Saturn. These pos­ . . professional r
alike, is a remarkabl simple,
laVishly Illustrated book by B. W. Anderson; director of ondon's
have missed their flight. Furthermore,
ters measure 22Y, x 29 " , are mailed rolled,
and are suitable for framing
world famed PrecIOus Stone laboratory. Anderson has examined both had expected to miss their flight,
more gems than any man in history.
o APVJ-1 Jupiter Now he shows you step-by'-step the high speed methods by so that Mr. Thomas has no reason to
which he unerringly idenhfies precious stones. Emphasis
o APVS-1 Saturn throughout the book IS on rapid examination with the naked eye be more surprised or disappointed than
o APVJ-2 Jupiter with Four Moons This FIRST AMERICAN EDITION of GEM TESTING tells shows Mr. Crane, If Mr. Thomas is the more
and explains everything you need to know. Copiously Illusinted.
o APVS-2 Saturn with Six Moons
only $11.95 plus $1.25 handling upset, it is presumably because in the act
o APVS-3 Final Look at Saturn
of imagination Mr. Thomas comes clos­
Math Without Tears
$8.50 for three posters
$13.00 for all live posters er than Mr. Crane to catching his flight.
($2.00 lor complete catalog. credit Using non-technical language and a light The frustration experienced in an unsat­
touch Roy Hartkopf gives you a basic un­
applied toward next purchase) derstanding of many everyday applications isfactory situation increases when it is
Foreign orders add $2.00 for postage. of mathematics. He takes the reader from easy to imagine a more desirable alter­
simple counting to trigonometry and cal­
Satisfaction Guaranteed
culus, emphasizing the practical aspects of native. For another example of the same
Send check or money order to: math. Humorously written.
learn math In tile comfort of your own home notion, consider the following:
Hansen Planetarium at minimum cost.
$10.95 plus 51.25 handling The winning number in a lottery was
DEPT. SA-1 1098 South 200 West 865304. Three individuals compare the
Salt Lake City, Utah 84101 ticket they hold to the winning number.
Dealer inquiries welc.ome John holds 361204; Mary holds 965304;
Peter holds 865305. How upset are they
respectively?
Introducing the world's only There is general agreement that the
experience is devastating for Peter,

Circadian quite severe for Mary and very mild


for. John. Here again the ranking cor­

Clock responds to the degree to which the


individuals can be described as having
The LunatimTe "come close" to winning the prize.

a precision quartz clock specially engineered An individual's experience of pleasure


to rotate once every 24 hours and 50 minutes .I\. or frustration may therefore de­
-THE CIRCADIAN DAY! (Which is also the
pend on an act of imagination that de­
Lunar Day.) Designed and manufactured by
Schelling Research Corp., the largest manu­
termines the reference level to which
facturer of TIDE CLOCKS in the world. reality is compared. It is notable that
Enables you to keep track of the 25 hour
the act of imagination by which one cre­
ates alternative realities reflects many re­

Circadian Day-the body's natural cycle.


Clearly shows you when the moon will alistic constraints. If there were no

p------------------------
rise, when it will set, and exactly where it Schelling Research constraints, Mr. Crane would find it as
is at all times-regardless of the weather!
2 Meadow Lane, North Caldwell, NJ 07006 easy as Mr. Thomas to imagine himself
The Lunatime even enables you to deter­
catching his flight and John would find it
mine at a glance, the phase of the moon. YES-Send my FREE copy of Dr. Arnold
as easy as Peter to imagine himself with
You can also use the Lunatime to tell the Lieber's book, "The Lunar Effect-Biological
the winning ticket. Imagination appears

tides, and to keep track of the Solunar Tides and Human Emotions" along with
Periods for best fishing and hunting ... my Lunatime Clock at $39.95 + $1.95 for to be governed by rules, and the rules of
and there are many who say the moon shipping. If not delighted I may return imagination affect our experience of re­
clock within 30 days for full refund, and I
influences our moods and even our sexual ality by controlling the alternatives to
keep the book at no charge.
desires!
which it is compared.
D I enclose $39.95 + $1.95 shipping ($41.90
The LunatimeT'" is crafted of 6"x6"xs;." spark­
total ) (Orders from Canada payable In U.S. Dolla rs)
Regret is a special form of frustration
ling acrylic. It s appearance is as exciting as
D Charge my D VISA D MasterCard in which the event one would change is
its concept Full instructions are included as
well as a complete brochure on the history Card No. Exp. ____ an action one has either taken or failed
of the Lunatime. Name __________ to take. A natural extension of the hy­
If you order within 7 days you will receive a Address ----- pothesis we have developed for the anal­
free book written by psychiatrist Arnold City/State/Zip __________ ysis of frustration is that regret is felt if
Lieber, M.D. "The Lunar Effect-Biological one can readily imagine having taken an
Tides and Human Emotions." (Dell 220 pp.) ORDER TOLL FREE BY PHONE:
action that would have led to a more
The documented information in this pioneer­ Call 800-526-2597
ing work will astound you-and provide you (in New Jersey: 201-226-43(0) desirable outcome. This interpretation
with cocktail conversation for weeks! (N_J. residents add 5% tax_) explains the close link between the expe­
L-___________________ .,••••••••, .... ________________ .I rience of regret and the availability of

170

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


Medicine is always changing�
now there� s a text that
changes right along with it.
SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine. Trial Offer. We invite you to try
SCIENTIFIC AMERICANMedicine for two
The answers that you get from months with our compliments. Send
SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine are us the coupon and you will receive the
current, because each month new two-volume text and two monthly up­
chapters replace the old. You wi11 dates. You may also take a CME test for
know where to look for the answers, credit. At the end of 60 days, if you
because this advanced text follows the decide to continue the subscription,
Echocardiograms from patients with
familiar struCture of medical knowl­ $220 for the first 12
you will owe us aortic regurgitation.
edge, changing as medicine changes. months (current renewal is $170);
otherwise, return the volumes; there
Comprehensive. Leading authori­ will be no charge.
ties from Harvard and Stanford cover Please mail the coupon today so that
the full range of medicine for you the we can put medical progress to work
seasoned clirtician. for you.

As an organization accredited for continuing


Complimentary CME. At no extra *

medical education, the Stanford University School of


cost, we offer a CME program through Medicine designates this continuing medical educa­
tion activity as meeting the criteria for 32 credit hours
which you can earn 32 top credits* per in Category I for Educational Materials for the
year. Physician's Recognition Award of the American Med·
ical Association, provided it has been completed ac­
cording CO inscfuccions.
This program is approved by the American Acad­
emy of Family Physicians for 32 elective hours of
CME credit.

r--
Computerized scintigraphy reveals
pulmonary thromboembolism.
�:���� MEDICINE
415 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10017

Please enroll me as a subscriber to SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine. On receipt of this coupon you
will send me the advanced two-volume text described in your announcemenr and update it
regularly by sending me new monthly subsections. I understand that the annual subscription of
$220 for SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine is tax deductible. If I am not e� tirely satisfied, I may
cancel at any time during the first 60 days, returning all materials for a complete refund.
o Please enter my subscription for SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine
o I shall also enroll in the CME Ptogram
o I enclose a check made our to SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN Medicine for $220*
o Please bill me.
"'Please add sales tax for California, Illinois, Massachu5errs, Michigan, Ohio and New York

Name _______ MD Specialty ________


Address ______________________________
Ci ty ______ State ______ Zip ________
Abdominal computed tomogram reveals
Signature _________________________________
large renal carcinoma replacing part of
Subscribers outside the U.S. and possessions will be charged extra for shipping and handling: updates will be �nt by surface routes unless
right kidney. airmail delivery is reques(�. Please allow 6-8 w�ks for delivery. DI

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


Phil and Steve Mahre, World Cup Race at Aspen

You have Vlhat it takes to Vlin.


Help support the U.S. Ski Tealli.
The U. S. Ski Team is on a winning streak. athletes devote years of their lives training to
They need your help to keep it going. win. They depend on you, the American public,
World Cup VIctories by Phil Mahre and to support their efforts. Please send your
Tamara McKinney highlighted the 1981 season.

li,, j
tax-deductible donations to the
• II.:!!
The Team's wins provide high hopes for the 1982 U.S. Ski Educational Foundation, &II;;;:'
World Championships. Box 100M, Park City, Utah 84060' EA
Our Alpine and Nordic Teams are not
subsidized by the government. These fine Please help. •j

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC


choic e : act ions taken under d ur e s s gen­
e r a te little regret. The rel uctance to vio­
late standard proc e d ures and to act in­
novatively can also be an effective d e ­
f e n s e a g a i n s t s u bseq uent r e g r e t because
it is e a s y to imagine doing the conven­
tional thing and more d iffi c u l t to imag­
ine d o ing the unconventional one.
A closely related hypothe sis is that
Play and Invention with Language
it is often e a s ier to mentally delete an
event from a chain of occ urrences than
. it is to imagine the insertion of an event HERBERT KOHL
into the chain. S uch a d ifference in imag­
i n a b i l i ty c o u l d help to explain the obser­ More than 300 games, puzzles, and
vation that the regret associated with
other challenges of language-from
failures to act is often less intense than
' comic alphabets to pictograms, codes,
the regre t associated w i th the fail ure of
and ciphers; from proverbs, riddles,
an action. Consider the following :
P a u l owns shares in Company A. D ur­ and fables to palindromes-all calcu­
ing the past year he considered switch­ lated to exercise the mind, stretch the
ing to stock in Company B, b u t he decid­ imagination, and provide hours of fu n .
e d against it. He now finds that he would
have been better off by $ 1 ,200 if he "This is t h e most varied, ingenious, i n ­
had switched to the stock of Company formative , and altogether delightful
B. George owned shares in Company collection of word games and puzzles
B. During the past year he switched to that I have seen. Ideal for ( among
stock in Company A. He now finds that others) families teaching children at
he w o u l d have been better off by $ 1 ,200 home (or anywhere ) . A treasure house
if he had kept his stock in C ompany B. for all ages:'�ohn Holt
Who fe e l s more re gret?

At all bookstores
H ere again it is generally agreed that
G e orge is more upset than Pa ul,
Schocken Books
although the ir objective s i t u a tions are
200 Madison Avenue, New York 1 00 1 6
now identical ( both own the stock of
Company A) and each reached his s i t u ­
a t i o n by d e l i berate d e c i s ion.
Apparently it is e a s ier for George to
imagine not taking an action (and there ­
,� - - - - - - - - - - - - - - �,
, Sp�ak e�rman
by r e t a i n ing the more advantage o u s
s t o c k ) t h a n it w o u l d b e for P a u l to imag­ t
I
ine taking the action. F urthermore, one

lik¢ a 'i)iplomat! II
w o u l d e x p e c t both men to anticipate the
p o s s i b i l i t y of regret and to act accor d ­
i n g l y . I n general the anticipation of r e ­
g r e t is l i k e l y to favor inact ion o v e r ac­
I What sort of peo p l e need to l earn a forei g n Th i s Program med Co u rse comes in two

I
tion and r o u t ine behavior over innova­ l a n g uage as q u i c k l y and effectively as p o s s i - vol u mes. O rder one or both.
tive behavior. O ur analysis traces these ble? Fore i g n serv i c e perso n n e l , t h at ' s w ho.
Now you can learn to speak German with
0 Vo l ume I . Pro grammed I n troduction to
German, 9 cassettes, ( 1 2 h rs.)
I
I I
biases of d e c ision to the r ules of the cog­ the same materials used by the U,S. State 647·page text, $ 115.
n itive operations by which alternat ive Department - t h e Fore i g n Servi ce I n st i t ute's 0 Volume I I . Basic Course, Continued
Programmed In troduction to G erman
I I
realities are constr u c t e d . and 8 cassettes, (8 1/, h rs.), and a 333·page text,
Basic Course, Continued.
I
W e h a v e c o n s i d e r e d a v a r i e t y of ex­ $98 .

I
The F S I s p e n t t h o u s a n d s of d o l l a rs and
amples in which a d e c i s ion, a prefer­ (Co n n . a n d N .Y. residen t s add sales t a x . )
m a n y years deve l o p i n g these m ateri al s for
e nce or an e m o t ional reaction was con­ Sh i pped i n ha ndso me l i brary binder s .

I
use by m e m bers of A m e r i c a ' s d i p l o m at i c
trolled by factors that may appear irre l ­ corps. Today peo p l e in a l l w a l k s of l i fe w ho
need to l e a rn to speak a fore i g n l a n g u ag e are
TO O R DER, J U ST C LI P T H I S AD and mail
wi t h y our name and ad dress, aAd a check or I
I
e v a n t o r inconse q ue n t i a l . S o m e of these
examples ill u s trate impediments to the
t u r n i n g to t h i s outstand i n g aud i O program.
The Fore i g n Serv i c e I n st i t u t e ' s G e r m a n
mone y order. O r charge to y o u r c redit card
I
( A m e r i c a n Ex p r e s s , V I SA , M a s t e r C a r d ,
achievement of rational dec ision that
I
D i n e r s Cl ub). Enclose card n u mber e x

I
Co u rse is by far t h e most effect i ve w ay to p i ratio n
were d isc ussed by Herbert A . Simon un­ learn G er m a n at yo u r ow n conven i en c e an d date, a n d y o u r signat u re .

der the heading of "bo unded rationali­


ty . " The difficulty people have in main­
I
pace. I t c o n s i st s of a s e r i e s o f c a s s e t t e s an d
accom pa n y i n g textbook . S i m p l y fo l l ow t h e
Th e F oreign S ervice I ns ti tute' s G erman
course i s uncondit i onall y guaranteed . Try it
f o r three weeks . If you ' re not convin ced i t ' s
I
I
s p o k e n a n d w r i t t e n i n st r u c t i o n s , l i st e n i n g
taining a comprehensive view of con­
sequences and their s us c e p t i b i l i t y to
and learn i n g . By the e n d of t h e course yo u ' l l
find yoursel f l e a rn i n g and spea k i n g e n t i r e l y
the most conve n i e n t a nd most pa i n less way
to learn G e r m an , ret u rn it a n d we 'll re f u ;] d I
the vagaries of fr aming are examples I in G erman ! A nat i ve German speaker, c l ea rly
recorded on t h e cassettes, p rovides an excel·
e very pen n y you paid. O rde r toda y !
M a n y other FSI I
l a n g uage courses a l s o

I
of s uch impediments. The descriptive
I
l e n t model to h e l p you deve l o p your s k i l l s . avai l a b l e . W r i t e u s .
study of preferences also presents chal­ This course turns your cassette player Into Audio-Forum
lenges to the theory of rational choice
because it is often far from clear wheth­ I a "teaching machine." With i t s unique " p ro·
grammed" learn i n g method, you set y o u r o w n
Suite 20
On The G reen, I
Gu ilford, CT. 06437
I
pace - te s t i n g y o u r s e l f , correc t i n g e rrors,
er the effects of decision weights, refer­
ence points, framing and regret should
re i n fo rc i n g accurate responses. (203 ) 453-9794 I
,, iIIUDIC·':CRUm®
,,
be treated as errors or biases or whe th­
er they sho u l d be accepted as valid e l e ­ O r v i s i t o u r N ew York s a l e s o f f i c e : 1 45 E. 49 t h S t . , N ew York, N . Y. 10017 (212)753- 1 783

----------------
m e n t s of human experience.

1 73

© 1981 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC

You might also like