You are on page 1of 11

SYST. RES. BEHAV. SCI. VOL.

14, 303–313 (1997)

j Research Paper

Systems Typologies in the Light of


Autopoiesis: A Reconceptualization of
Boulding’s Hierarchy, and a Typology of
Self-Referential Systems
John Mingers*
Warwick Business School, University of Warwick, Coventry, UK

This paper considers two examples of systems typologies in the light of the theory of
autopoiesis. The first is Boulding’s classic typology of types of systems based on their
degree of complexity. Certain inconsistencies are noted, but the main problem is that
there is no definition of the underlying scale of systems complexity. The paper suggests
that the underlying dimension can be seen as the types of relations upon which the
different levels depend. This also allows the inconsistencies to be clarified. The second
typology, presented for the first time, provides an initial classification of different types
of self-referential or organizationally closed systems. © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

No. of Figures: 0 No. of Tables: 3 No. of References: 35

Keywords autopoiesis; Boulding’s hierarchy; complexity; organizational closure; relations; self-


consciousness; self-reference; self-organization

INTRODUCTION theories and explanations of the structures they


portray; and they may reveal gaps or incon-
One of the most fundamental activities of the sistencies that need addressing. Disciplines such
sciences is developing categorizations or typolo- as physics or chemistry were not able to move
gies, sets of distinctions, that try to create some forward until basic conceptual schemes such as
conceptual order. Such classifications are of the periodic table, or the classification of funda-
enormous importance: they separate out the mental particles, were agreed.
various concepts or objects; highlight important Within the area of systems thinking, partic-
relationships between them—the ways in which ularly general systems theory (GST), there are
they differ and the ways in which they are the various ways of classifying types of systems, for
same; they provide stimulus for developing new example, Boulding’s (1956) ‘hierarchy of com-
plexity’, Jordan’s (1968) ‘systems taxonomy’ and
* Correspondence to: John Mingers, Warwick Business School, Uni-
Checkland’s (1971) ‘systems map of the uni-
versity of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL, UK. verse’. Of these, Boulding’s is probably the most

CCC 1092–7026/97/050303–11 $17.50 Received 7 October 1996


© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Accepted 18 February 1997
10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
RESEARCH PAPER Syst. Res. Behav. Sci.

important, both because it was one of the first autopoietic theory. The second typology con-
major steps within GST, and because it aimed to cerns classifying systems that are
provide a structure that could encompass all the organizationally (rather than interactively)
disciplines and sciences. It produced a classifica- closed; that is, systems that are self-referring or
tion of the different types of possible systems, self-referencing in some way. There is currently
ordering them in terms of increasing complexity. much confusion in this area and some con-
Its underlying purposes were to show up gaps in ceptual clarification is vital.
empirical and theoretical knowledge, and to The first section of the paper provides a brief
facilitate interdisciplinary research by revealing introduction to autopoiesis as it forms a basis for
similar concerns (e.g., ‘growth’ or ‘information’) the remainder. The next section presents the re-
in dissimilar disciplines. conceptualization of Boulding’s hierarchy, and
Since those early days of GST, the systems the last section the typology of self-referential
discipline has expanded and fragmented. Some systems.
of the major developments, particularly in
Europe, have been interpretive (‘soft’) systems
(Checkland, 1981; Checkland and Scholes, 1990)
and critical systems (Flood and Jackson, 1991a, AN INTRODUCTION TO AUTOPOIESIS
1991b; Mingers, 1992) that are generally antipa-
thetic to the aspirations and philosophy of GST, Autopoiesis (self-production) is a theory that
while in America some of the major areas of explains the nature of living (as opposed to non-
work in the GST tradition have been in living living) entities. It claims that living systems
systems theory (Miller, 1978), social entropy theory undergo a continual process of internal self-
(Bailey, 1990) and their application to social production whereas non-living systems
systems (Bailey, 1994). The third area that has (allopoietic) produce something other than their
been most productive and, I would argue, own self-components. It is a complex and sophis-
possibly most significant, has been the establish- ticated theory that also explains the biological
ment of second-order cybernetics, especially basis of cognition, self-consciousness, language
Maturana and Varela’s development of the theory and human behaviour. It has also been applied at
of autopoiesis (Maturana and Varela, 1980, 1987; the level of social systems (Luhmann, 1995).
Mingers, 1995a). Autopoiesis, in fact, has a foot Maturana (1987) provides a detailed and com-
in both camps. It is in the tradition of GST: a prehensive treatment, while Maturana and
systems theory generated in the domain of Varela (1987) are more accessible. Mingers
biology that may be applied in other disciplines (1995a) is an introduction to the theory and its
such as social theory; but also it is a theory of the application in different domains. Maturana et al.
observer that emphasizes the interpreted and (1995) is a recent update. This section gives a
constructed nature of social reality. brief introduction to some of the main concepts.
Given the above general context, it is the An observer is a (human) being capable of
purpose of this paper to present two typologies, making distinctions and descriptions through
based on the theory of autopoiesis, that it is language and whose lived experience is always
hoped will contribute to the conceptual under- within language. A unity is an entity or whole
pinnings of systems thinking. The first typology that is distinguished by an observer in relation to
is actually a re-conceptualization of Boulding’s a background or medium. A unity may be simple
original hierarchy. This is necessary for two (unalaysed) or composite (analysed into compo-
reasons: first, in the light of more recent research, nents by further distinctions). The type or
there is some confusion between the levels and identity of a simple unity is characterized in
the examples in each level; and second, because terms of properties of the whole in a meta-
there was no clear definition of the underlying domain to its components. A composite unity is
structure, the definition of complexity. Both these distinguished in terms of components and their
limitations can be rectified using ideas from relations which taken together generate the

Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997) © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

304 John Mingers


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. RESEARCH PAPER

simple unity. tions that produce them, and specify its


Composite unities can be characterized in extension by constituting it boundaries in their
terms of both Organization1 and structure. The domain of existence, is an autopoietic system’
structure of a composite unity is the total set of (Maturana, 1987, p. 349). A living system is a
actual components and relations belonging to a special case of an autopoietic system—one
particular concrete example or instance. The whose components are molecules. The autopoi-
Organization is a subset of the relations between etic Organization can be characterized in terms
components that determine the properties of the of three types of relations between components
unity as a whole and thereby its identity, type or and production processes. Relations of constitu-
class. All unities of a particular type have the tion (where) concern the spatial or topographic
same Organization. A change of Organization features of the system in terms of whatever space
implies a change of identity and vice versa. it is defined. Relations of specificity (what) con-
Unities with the same Organization may have cern the particular types of components or
different structures, and the structure of a partic- processes and their specific characteristics. Rela-
ular entity may change without its Organization tions of order (when) concern the dynamics of the
changing. Organization is abstract, structure is system and the ordering of different processes or
concrete. Composite unities consist of compo- events.
nents and relations (structure), and so any Autopoietic systems are characterized by
change in the unity must be a change in the autonomy since they are not dependent on
structure. Such a change will be determined by external production processes, and self-reference
the properties of the components and their since their Organization closes in on itself and
relations at that particular point in time; that is, it their structure is self-defined—it can be any, so
will be structurally determined. Outside agents long as it supports autopoiesis. Allopoiesis
can only trigger changes, they cannot determine describes all types of Organization that produce
the nature of the change. All composite unities something other than themselves.
are therefore structure-determined systems. The cognitive domain of interactions is the set of
Structural coupling is a mutual relationship or possible interactions that an autopoietic system
correspondence between the structure of a unity may have in a particular environment that are
and the structure of its environment (including effective, that is, that preserve autopoiesis. For
other unities within the environment). This Maturana, effective action is knowledge: ‘living
occurs when a unity undergoes recurrent inter- systems are cognitive systems, and to live is to
actions within its environment whilst know’ (Maturana, 1987, p. 357). The consensual
maintaining its identity and therefore its Organi- domain of interactions is when two or more
zation. The changes in structure that occur must autopoietic systems interact recurrently with
be such as to allow the maintenance of the each other; structural coupling may lead to
Organization within that particular environ- interlinked set of interactions between them
ment. which may appear to an observer to be coordi-
Autopoiesis describes a particular type of nated. Such an ontogenetically established
Organization. Autopoietic systems are organized domain of coordinations of actions is a con-
in such a way that they produce their own sensual domain. To the extent that such
components—they are self-producing systems. coordinations of action have particular effects or
Formally, ‘a composite unity whose organization meaning within the interaction they may be
can be described as a closed network of pro- described as linguistic. Within a consensual
duct ions of components that through their domain, the coordinations of action may become
interactions constitute the network of produc- recursive; that is, particular coordinations of
action may become tokens or symbols for others.
This gives rise to language (or rather languag-
1
Organization with the initial letter capitalized denotes Maturana’s
ing)—a domain of consensual coordinations of
sense of organization. consensual coordinations of action.

© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

Systems Typologies in the Light of Autopoiesis 305


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
RESEARCH PAPER Syst. Res. Behav. Sci.

A RECONCEPTUALIZATION OF say, biology, some of the categories and examples


BOULDING’S HIERARCHY seem wrong or at least confused. For example,
would we really want to put candle flames and
Boulding’s (1956) hierarchy was one of the first living cells at the same level? The early distinc-
examples of work in the general systems area. It tion between systems that were closed and open
offers an intuitive classification of different types (to energy) is little used now as there are
of systems ranked in increasing order of com- virtually no systems that are closed in this sense,
plexity (Table 1). This is done by specifying a except as artificially constructed in the labo-
number of different levels, characteristics and ratory.2 Surely the more important distinction is
examples of each level, and relevant academic between living systems and non-living systems?
disciplines. Each level is said to include, in some Also, splitting levels into cells, plants, animals and
way, the lower levels but to have its own, new, humans does not really correspond to increasing
emergent properties. At first sight, the levels and levels of complexity (are single-celled animals
examples seem very plausible. They do appear more complex than multicellular plants) or with
to pick out distinctively different types of enti- current biological classifications (Margulis and
ties. However, as Checkland (1981, p. 106) has Schwartz, 1988).
noted, there is no explicit definition of the scale The proposal in this paper is that autopoiesis
of ‘systems complexity’ underlying the hier- can provide us with an answer to these difficul-
archy. What is it that actually distinguishes one ties. The main proposition is that the dimension
level from another? It is the number of compo- underlying this hierarchy, the main dimension of
nents? The number of interconnections? The complexity, is the way in which a system’s
degree of functional differentiation? Without Organization is characterized by different types of
this, we cannot really judge the correctness of the relationship. Each new level in the hierarchy
classification. 2
There are systems that are closed in an organizational sense—see next
Moreover, in the light of more recent work in, section.

Table 1 Boulding’s hierarchy of complexity

Level Description Characteristic Example Discipline

1 Structures and Static, spatial pattern Bridge, mountain, Descriptive elements


frameworks crystal, atom of all disciplines
2 Clockworks Predetermined motion Clocks, machines, Physics, astronomy,
solar system engineering
3 Control mechanisms Closed-loop control Thermostat, Cybernetics
homeostasis
4 Open systems Structurally self- Flames, cells Theory of metabolism
maintaining
5 Genetic–societal Society of cells, Plants Botany
systems functional parts
6 Animals Nervous system, self- Birds and beasts Zoology
awareness
7 Humans Self-consciousness, Human beings Biology, psychology
knowledge, language
8 Socio-cultural systems Roles, communication, Families, boy scouts, History, sociology,
values clubs anthropology
9 Transcendental Inescapable God? Philosophy, religion
systems unknowables

Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997) © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

306 John Mingers


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. RESEARCH PAPER

brings in a new and different type of relation, or the actual relations between the structural com-
relation of a relation, as well as involving those ponents of an entity. An observer can distinguish
at previous levels. The idea of relationships different subsets of relations, and therefore dif-
between components is fundamental to the anti- ferent Organizations, for a particular entity. Thus
reductionist stance of systems thinking. It is the a person can be distinguished as a physical
relationships between components in a system, structure, as a biological system, or as a psycho-
rather than the nature of the individual compo- logical or social system. Each distinction gives
nents themselves, that generate its properties rise to a different Organization with a different
and behaviour. All living systems (on earth) are domain of interactions. It is not possible to go the
composed of particular carbon-based molecules, other way, however. An entity at a low level, for
and ultimately of different proportions of vari- example a structure such as a bridge, cannot
ous chemicals. What distinguishes different embody relations from a higher level, such as
organisms is precisely the different ways in linguistic or social ones.
which their components are related. It seems Table 2 shows the hierarchy reconceptualized
entirely appropriate, therefore, that it should be in these terms. Most levels are the same but the
relations that form the basis for the heirarchy of inconsistencies in the original are cleared up. At
complexity. level 1 we have structures, frameworks and
In particular, the scale concerns those relations patterns that are characterized only by relations
that constitute the Organization that is ascribed to of constitution (where), that is, spatial or topo-
a particular system by an observer. As noted in graphic relations. A table is an example.
the previous section, Oganization is a subset of Although it can, of course, move or be moved, or

Table 2 A hierarchy of complexity (developed from Boulding)

Level Description Characteristic Type of relations Example

1 Structures and Static, spatial patterns Topology (where) Bridge, mountain,


frameworks table, crystal
2 Single mechanistic Dynamic, pre- Order (when) Solar system, clock,
systems determined changes, tune, computer
processes
3 Control mechanisms, Error-controlled Specification (what) Thermostat, body
cybernetic systems feedback, information temperature system,
auto-catalytic system
4 Living systems Continuous self- Autopoietic relations Cell, amoeba, single-
production celled bacteria
5 Multicellular system Functional Structural coupling Plants, fungi, moulds,
differentiation between cells (Second- algi
order autopoiesis)
6 Organisms with Interaction with Symbolic, abstract Most animals (except,
nervous systems relations relations e.g., sponges)
7 Observing systems Language, self- Recursive, self-referential Humans
consciousness relations
8 Social systems Rules, meanings, Structural coupling Families, organizations
norms, power between organisms
(third-order
autopoiesis)
9 Transcendental
systems

© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

Systems Typologies in the Light of Autopoiesis 307


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
RESEARCH PAPER Syst. Res. Behav. Sci.

indeed collapse, its distinction as a table only virus is unable to reproduce or metabolize itself
specifies spatial relations between its surface and (i.e., self-produce) unless it is within a host cell.
its supports. At level 2 are what may be called On these grounds, Margulis argues that viruses
simple dynamic systems or processes, such as are not autopoietic and thus not living (Margulis
rivers, clocks or tunes. Their Organization and Sagan, 1995, p. 23).
involves relations of order (when) as well as Levels 4–6 present particular distinctions
constitution. The components of such systems between living systems that are orthogonal to
change their spatial3 position through time. Such those usually made within biology but this is
systems involve both structure and process. because they are based on complexity, as defined
Unlike Boulding, I include simple open systems, in terms of types of relationships, rather than
such as a candle, here. Boulding put these in the evolutionary heritage. One of the most well-
same level as cells which, in the light autopoiesis established taxonomies in biology (Margulis and
as the defining principle of living systems, does Schwartz, 1988) divides living systems into five
not seem appropriate. phyla although there are many unusual or
Level 3 consists of systems that are, or contain, borderline cases. The main distinction is between
feedback loops—control systems or cybernetic prokaryotes—cells that have few components and
systems. These may be self-regulation systems have no separate nuclear membrane—and euk-
such as a thermostat or the body’s temperature aryotes—more complex cells with separate
regulation system, or self-sustaining4 systems nuclei. The prokaryotes are in the main single-
such as auto-catalytic processes. These systems celled bacteria, although some may be
work through feedback loops that maintain multicellular. The eukaryotes are split into four:
certain variables constant or regulate the types fungi (de-
and amounts of particular components. Because veloping from spores, and with no flagella);
of this, their Organization is characterized by plants (developing from embryos, multicellular,
relations of specification (what) as well as ty- and generally based on photosynthesis); animals
pology and order. That is, they maintain varia- (developing from blastula, multicellular, and
bles at specific levels or control the generation of generally based on digestion of organic com-
specific components. This also means that such pounds); and protoctista (microorganisms
systems use or process information (Mingers without the other characteristics), which
1995b, 1996a) as part of their operations. includes amoeba, algae, slime moulds, and pro-
At level 4 we reach living systems whose tozoa. It is clear that no simple transition in
Organization is characterized by relations of terms of degree of complexity can be made from
autopoiesis. That is, within a system, the varied a cell through plants to animals.
relations of typology, order and specification The move to level 5 is therefore made in terms
themselves form a higher-level relationship of of multicellular systems that involve relations of
self-production. This replaces Boulding’s level 4 structural coupling between cells—what Maturana
of open systems which, as discussed above, no calls second-order autopoietic systems, such as
longer seems very useful. Level 4 includes only multicelled bacteria, plants, moulds and fungi.
the simplest living systems—single cells—either Structural coupling is a relationship of corre-
free standing, such as a bacterium or an amoeba, spondence in structure between two systems, or
or part of a larger organism. This provides a very a system and its environment. Such systems
clear line of demarcation between non-living display at least minimal functional differentia-
(level 3 and below) and living systems. One tion of cells, and cell structures. This is a more
borderline case is that of the virus, which is precise definition than Boulding’s ‘genetic-socie-
simply a packet of genes covered in protein. A tal’.
Level 6 comprises organisms that have evolved
3
The ‘space’ involved may not be simply physical but could be a scale some form of nervous system. The main charac-
of sounds.
4
For the distinction between self-regulating and self-sustaining see
teristic of a nervous system, no matter how
the next section. elementary, is that it connects up different parts

Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997) © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

308 John Mingers


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. RESEARCH PAPER

of the organism—both external interfaces to the tion’); and self-consciousness is being able to
environment and internal components and pro- observe the observer (‘I am not feeling well’).
cesses. This allows an organism to have a new These complex, self-referring interactions require
domain of interactions—interactions with rela- a brain that has a highly recursive structure, and
tions between events that impinge upon it. An fully functional languaging capabilities. The
organism without a nervous system can only relations involved are therefore recursive and
have interactions with isolated physico-chemical self-referential. Note that level 6 animals can
events that occur at particular places and times. have linguistic interactions such as a duet of
The nervous system, however, connects different birdsong, but Maturana argues that this is not
parts of the organism, and different times of full languaging, which would require linguistic
interaction, allowing differences and relations interactions about linguistic interactions.5 The
between events to become significant for the main example of a system at this level is human
organism (von Foerster, 1986). Organisms with a beings.
nervous system are therefore able to interact Finally (apart from the transcendental sys-
with pure relations such as before/after, hotter/ tems), we have level 8: social systems. These are
colder, more/less. This category includes all characterized by relations of structural coupling
animals, except the sponge, which is generally between organisms. That is, organisms with nerv-
classified as an animal but has no nervous ous systems coordinating their behaviour with
system. Again, Boulding was somewhat incon- respect to others. Examples are social insects
sistent in using plants as an example within a such as ants, animals such as gorillas, and
level, but animals as a level in its own right. human social systems such as families. Note that
The other main characteristic of the nervous Maturana does not claim that social systems are
system is that it is structurally plastic. That is, it autopoietic, but that they are the medium for the
can change its own interconnections as a result of operation of autopoietic systems. Within such
the experiences that the organism undergoes, systems, regular patterns of behaviour emerge
and thereby enable the possibility of learning— through the structural coupling between mem-
being able to generate different (and more bers. These can be described in terms such as
apropriate) behaviour in apparently similar cir- rules, norms and patterns of meaning. Such
cumstances. The evolutionary advantage gained social Organizations can be highly diverse and
by this greater flexibility led to increasingly ritualized, but once established are highly con-
complex nervous systems, and thus new servative since they generate, in their members,
domains of possible interactions. Within this structural responses that generally conform to
level there are many new developments that the prevailing relations.
could be picked out: for instance, the ability to This completes the description of the revised
interact with abstract or symbolic events such as framework, and we now move to consider those
scent marking; the ability to coordinate behav- systems that involve some form of self-reference.
iour in quite elaborate forms such as a courtship
ritual or the bees’ dance; and ultimately the
possibility of making symbolic reference to one’s CLASSIFYING SELF-REFERENTIAL SYSTEMS
own actions. Maturana terms these consensual
coordinations of behaviour linguistic behaviour, Autopoiesis focuses our attention on self-produc-
but not full languaging. ing, self-referring systems but, as Teubner (1993,
Level 7 brings in systems that can observe; that p. 16) has noted, there is a considerable con-
is, make descriptions of their interactions and, ceptual confusion around such terms in the
ultimately, descriptions of themselves (Maturana general systems literature, within philosophy
et al., 1995). Observing is being able to distinguish (Bartlett and Suber, 1987), and even, on occa-
the act of describing as an object itself (‘this is sions, within Maturana and Varela’s work. What
only a description’); the observer is able to 5
Or, as Maturana would put it: consensual coordinations of con-
recognize who is observing (‘this is my descrip- sensual coordinations of action.

© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

Systems Typologies in the Light of Autopoiesis 309


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
RESEARCH PAPER Syst. Res. Behav. Sci.

is the difference between, for example, ‘self- and itself. Whilst not claiming a complete analy-
reference’, ‘self-production’, ‘self-organization’, sis of such systems, I offer the categorization in
‘self-regulation’, ‘self-observation’, ‘circular cau- Table 3 as a starting point and would welcome
sality’, ‘tautologies and contradictions’, or further contributions to it. This classification has
‘autocatalysis’? This is clearly a problematic area been developed by considering the different
since the prefix ‘self-’ can be applied to a vast levels of complexity in Table 2 and seeing what
range of actions or characteristics—see Hof- types of self-referencing relations there might be
stadter (1980, 1986) for many insightful at each level.
examples. At its most general, what these types The first type, at the structural level since they
of systems have in common is that they make are not dynamic or processual, I have termed
some form of reference to or impact on them- self-referring systems. These systems are usually
selves. It can be said that the Organization of symbolic or representational in a general sense,
such systems must have some form of closure and refer to themselves either by some form of
(Varela et al., 1991), not in the traditional inter- pointing (e.g., a signpost pointing to itself ); by
active sense, but in the sense that one or more of containing an image of themselves within them-
the major relations characterizing these systems selves; or by referring to themselves
must be circular, a relation between the system linguistically. They include all the many para-

Table 3 A classifiction of self-referential systems

Level Type Characteristic Example

1 Self-referring systems Structural reference to self by ‘This is a sentence’, Escher’s


position or symbolism (picto- ‘Drawing Hands’, Magritte’s
rial or linguistic) ‘The Treason of Images’
2 Self-influencing systems Dynamic systems that involve Size and birth rate of popula-
circular causality and causal tion, inflation, the nuclear arms
loops race
3 Self-regulating systems Maintenance of a particular Thermostat, body temperature
variable at a particular level
Self-sustaining systems All parts of the system are nec- Gas pilot light in heating boiler,
essary and sufficient for autocatalysis
operation of the whole, but do
not produce each other
4 Self-producing systems (autop- Autonomy: the system both Cell, computer model of auto-
oietic) produces and is produced by poiesis, Nomic (self-producing
itself legal game)
5 Self-recognizing systems Systems that are able to recog- Immune system within an
nize their own parts and reject organism
others
Self-replicating systems Systems that can build replicas Organisms that reproduce,
of themselves computer viruses
6 Self-cognizing systems Systems that generate cognitive Animals with nervous systems
identity through recursive neu- interacting symbolically
ronal activity
7 Self-conscious systems Able to interact with descrip- A person saying ‘I acted
tions of themselves. The selfishly today’
observer observing the
observer

Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997) © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

310 John Mingers


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. RESEARCH PAPER

doxes and tautologies (Hughes and Brecht, pilot light to function in the first place. Once it is
1978): for example, ‘This sentence is in French’; in operation, it sustains itself. However, once it
or ‘This assertion is not true’. Pictorial examples stops it cannot restart itself—it needs some form
are Escher’s drawing (‘Drawing Hands’) of two of outside intervention to begin the cycle again.
hands drawing each other, and Magritte’s pic- Other examples are systems of auto-catalysis
tures, one (‘the Treason of Images’) of a smoking where a chemical reaction produces at least some
pipe with the words (in French) ‘this is not a of the chemicals necessary that are necessary for
pipe’, and another (‘The Human Condition’) in the reaction to occur; and the nervous system,
which the picture contains a picture of part of the where every state of nervous activity is triggered
scene. by a previous state and triggers, in turn, the next
At level 2 are systems I identify as self- state.
influencing systems. These are examples of what At the next level we have autopoietic systems
are often causal loops or circular causality; that which are self-producing of both their components
is, patterns of causation or influence which and their own boundary. They are more than
become circular: for instance, the larger a pop- self-sustaining in that they actually produce the
ulation, the greater the number of births, and components necessary for their own continua-
thus the larger the population in the next time tion. Such systems have properties such as
period. This is a positive loop leading to expo- autonomy, since they depend mainly on their
nential increase or decrease and, more own self-production, and identity, since they
commonly, there are negative loops which lead maintain their own individual autopoietic
to, at least temporary, stability, for example, the Organization despite changes in their structure.
price/demand relations for a normal good. The The main examples are living systems—molec-
economic and ecological domains are full of ular embodiments of autopoiesis—but it is also
complex patterns of just such mutual causality. possible to conceive of abstract self-producing
At the third level, I distinguish two types of systems such as Nomic, a game that produces its
systems: self-regulating and self-sustaining. Self- own rules (Suber, 1990; Mingers, 1996b), and the
regulating systems are organized so as to keep computer model of autopoiesis produced by
some essential variable(s) within particular lim- Varela (Varela et al., 1974; McMullin and Varela,
its. They rely on negative feedback and specified 1997).
limits. Obvious examples are a thermostat and At level 5 in the hierarchy (multicellular
the blood temperature control system. They are systems), I again distinguish two types: self-
distinct from the self-influencing systems in that recognizing systems and self-replicating systems.
they maintain a pre-specified level determined The prime example of a self-recognizing system
by the wider system of which they are a part. is the body’s immune system (Varela and Cou-
Self-influencing systems may stabilize through tinho, 1989). This is a network of glands and
negative feedback but do so at essentially arbi- chemicals throughout the body, one function of
trary levels. which is to fight off cells and organisms that do
The next type I call self-sustaining systems. In not belong to the body. In order to do this, it
Maturana and Varela’s terms these systems are must be able to recognize its self—that is, its own
Organizationally closed but not self-producing. cells as opposed to another organism’s. Self-
Their components and processes close in upon replicating systems are those that are capable of
themselves so that their own elements are both producing a copy or replica of themselves. This
necessary and sufficient for their own con- includes all living systems as well as, for
tinuance. Such systems do not, however, example, a computer virus. Note that the ability
produce their own components. A good example to reproduce is not definatory of living systems
is the gas heater pilot light found on many since some individuals, or even species such as
central heating systems. In such a system, the gas the mule, are sterile yet living, while most people
pilot light heats a thermocouple which controls would say a computer virus is not living (see
the flow of gas to the pilot light which allows the above concerning chemical viruses).

© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

Systems Typologies in the Light of Autopoiesis 311


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
RESEARCH PAPER Syst. Res. Behav. Sci.

At level 6 are self-cognizing systems that are is no category of self-organizing systems. This
integrated by a brain and nervous system. The seems to me redundant within Maturana’s termi-
nervous system is an Organizationally closed nology. All systems embody a particular
network of interacting neurons in which all Organization—it is what specifies their identity—
states of relative activity lead to, and are pre- and this Organization remains the same so long
ceded by, other states of activity thus leading to as they maintain their identity. What is generally
recursive closure. Certain parts of the nervous meant by the term ‘self-organization’ is actually
system (the effector and sensory surfaces) do structural change rather than a change in the
interface to the bodily or external environment, Organization, and here I would use my other
and can thus be triggered by outside events; the categories depending on the particular type of
vast majority of the nervous system is composed change involved. A genuine change in Organiza-
of interneurons that only interact with each tion would involve a major change in category
other. The coupling of the circular processes of such as an autopoietic system dying and no
the nervous system and the linear interactions of longer being autopoietic. The second is that I
the organism as a whole over time give rise to have not included self-referential systems at the
new domains of behaviour based on abstract and social level. This is because I feel that, at the
symbolic representations of the organisms’ inter- present time, there is insufficient consensus
actions. This allows for the development of about the exact nature of social systems to
increasingly varied and ontogenetic modes of propose some supra-human, self-referential sys-
behaviour in the more developed species. It also tem—see, for example, the different positions of
necessitates, for the individual organism, the Habermas (1996), Luhmann (1995) and Foucault
construction of their own cognitive self. The (1980).
nervous system integrates the perceptions and
actions of the organism as it operates as a whole CONCLUSIONS
within an environment. Through its circular,
recursive operation it continually establishes and This paper has used autopoietic theory to refor-
maintains the distinct, coherent self of the indi- mulate one of the original contributions to
vidual at the same time as projecting onto the general systems—Boulding’s hierarchy. It has
environment a structure of signification that is enabled a consistent view to be taken of the
relevant to its own self-continuance. dimension underlying the typology. This is seen
The symbolic interactions enabled by the to be based on the different types of relations,
nervous system lead to the emergence of many and relations of relations, that emerge at differ-
new domains of interactions. For instance, con- ent levels in the hierarchy. It has also removed
sensually coordinated behaviours, the certain inconsistencies in the original.
distinctions of objects and the relations between As well as this, a new typology of self-
them (observing), and finally self-consciousness; referential or circular systems has been
that is, systems that can, through language, proposed. Although this no doubt needs to be
create descriptions of themselves and then inter- developed further, it is hoped that it will provide
act with these descriptions as if they were a useful framework in an area where there is
independent entities, thus recursively generating much confusion about the usage of different
the conscious self. Human beings are the main terms and will contribute to a more coherent
example of such languaging systems at this point treatment of self-referential systems.
in time. Such interactions are mainly linguistic
utterances, either latent or manifest, such as, ‘I
am lying’; or ‘I hereby promise to. . .’, but can REFERENCES
also be embodied in gestures or facial expres-
Bailey, K. (1990). Social Entropy Theory, State University
sions. of New York Press, Albany.
There are two omissions from the typology Bailey, K. (1994). Sociology and the New Systems Theory,
that should be mentioned. The first is that there State University of New York Press, Albany.

Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997) © 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

312 John Mingers


10991743a, 1997, 5, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/(SICI)1099-1743(199709/10)14:5<303::AID-SRES161>3.0.CO;2-A by Indian Institution Of Mgmt-Ahmedabad, Wiley Online Library on [20/08/2023]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. RESEARCH PAPER

Bartlett, S., and Suber, P. (1987). Self-reference: Reflec- Maturana, H., and Varela, F. (1987). The Tree of
tions on Reflexivity, Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht. Knowlede, Shambhala, Boston, MA.
Boulding, K. (1956). General systems theory: the Maturana, H., Mpodozis, J., and Letelier, J. (1995).
skeleton of science. Management Science 2(3), Brain, language and the origin of human mental
197–208. functions. Biological Research 28, pp. 15–26.
Checkland, P. (1971). A systems map of the universe. McMullin, B., and Varela, F. (1997). Rediscovering
Journal of Systems Engineering 2(2):107–114. computational autopoiesis. SFI Working Paper
Checkland, P. (1981). Systems Thinking, Systems Prac- 97-02-012, Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe.
tice, Wiley, London. Miller, J. (1978). Living Systems, McGraw-Hill, New
Checkland, P., and Scholes, J. (1990). Soft Systems York.
Methodology in Action, Wiley, Chichester. Mingers, J. (1992). Recent developments in critical
Flood, R., and Jackson, M. (1991a). Creative Problem management science. Journal of the Operational
Solving, Wiley, Chichester. Research Society 43(1), 1–10.
Flood, R., and Jackson, M. (1991b). Critical Systems Mingers, J. (1995a). Self-producing Systems: Implications
Thinking: Directed Readings, Wiley, Chichester. and Applications of Autopoiesis, Plenum Press, New
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Inter- York.
views and Other Writings 1972–1977, Harvester, Mingers, J. (1995b). Information and meaning: founda-
Brighton. tions for an intersubjective account. Information
Habermas, J. (1996). Between Facts and Norms, Polity Systems Journal 5(4), 285–306.
Press, Cambridge, UK. Mingers, J. (1996a). An evaluation of theories of
Hofstadter, D. (1980). Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal information with regard to the semantic and prag-
Golden Braid, Penguin, London. matic aspects of information systems. Systems
Hofstadter, D. (1986). Metamagical Themas: Questing for Practice 9(3), 187–209.
the Essence of Mind and Pattern, Penguin, London. Mingers, J. (1996b). A comparison of Maturana’s
Hughes, P., and Brecht, G. (1978). Vicious Circles and autopoietic social theory and Giddens’ theory of
Infinity, Penguin, Harmondsworth. structuration. Systems Research 13(4), 469–482.
Jordan, N. (1968). Themes in Speculative Psychology, Suber, P. (1990). Paradox of Self-amendment, P. Lang,
Tavistock, London. New York.
Luhmann, N. (1995). Social Systems, Stanford Uni- Teubner, G. (1993). Law as an Autopoietic System,
versity Press, Stanford, CA. Blackwell, Oxford.
Margulis, L. and Sagan, D. (1995). What is Life?, Varela, F., and Coutinho, A. (1989). Immune networks:
Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London. getting on the real thing. Research in Immunology 140,
Margulis, L., and Schwartz, K. (1988). Five Kingdoms: 837–845.
An Illustrated Guide to the Five Phyla of Life on Earth, Varela, F., Maturana, H., and Uribe, R. (1974). Auto-
Freeman, New York. poiesis: the organization of living systems, its
Maturana, H. (1987). The biological foundations of characterization and a model. Biosystems 5,
self-consciousness and the physical domain of 187–196.
existence. In Caianiello, E. (ed.), Physics of Cognitive Varela, F., Thompson, E., and Rosche, E. (1991). The
Processes, World Scientific, Singapore, pp. 324–379. Embodied Mind, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Maturana, H., and Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and von Foerster, H. (1986). On constructing a reality. In
Cognition: The Realization of the Living, Reidel, Dor- Observing Systems, Intersystems Publications, Cali-
drecht. fornia, pp. 287–309.

© 1997 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. Vol. 14, 303–313 (1997)

Systems Typologies in the Light of Autopoiesis 313

You might also like