You are on page 1of 8

Society (2022) 59:583–590

https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-022-00769-x

BOOK REVIEW

Pragmatist Philosophy for Our Times: Reviewing Rorty’s Legacy


Richard Shusterman 1

Published online: 20 September 2022


# The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2022

Richard Rorty, Philosophy as Poetry Chris Voparil, Reconstructing Pragmatism:


Richard Rorty and the Classical Pragmatists
(University of Virginia Press, 2016), 96 pp., ISBN: 978-
0813939339 (Oxford University Press, New York, 2022), 392 pp., ISBN:
978-0197605721
Richard Rorty, On Philosophy and Philosophers,
edited by W. P. Małecki and Chris Voparil Giancarlo Marchetti (Ed.), The Ethics,
Epistemology, and Politics of Richard Rorty
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2020). 260 pp.,
ISBN: 978-1108488457 (Routledge, New York, 2022), 294 pp., ISBN: 978-
0367342173
Richard Rorty, Pragmatism
as Anti-Authoritarianism
I
(Harvard University Press, Mass, 2021), 256 pp., ISBN: 978-
0674248915
The pathos of death is this, that when the days of one’s
life are ended, those days that were so crowded with
business and felt so heavy in their passing, what remains
Richard Rorty, What Can We Hope For?: Essays of one in memory should usually be so slight a thing.
on Politics The phantom of an attitude, the echo of a certain mode
of thought, a few pages of print, some invention, or
(Princeton University Press, NJ, 2022), 224 pp., ISBN: 978- some victory we gained in a brief critical hour, are all
0691217529 that can survive the best of us. It is as if the whole of a
man’s significance had now shrunk into the phantom of
David Rondel (Ed), The Cambridge Companion an attitude, into a mere musical note or phrase sugges-
to Rorty tive of his singularity — happy are those whose singu-
larity gives a note so clear as to be victorious over the
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2021), 366 pp., inevitable pity of such a diminution and abridgement.
ISBN: 978-1108733953 (James 1962; p. 18)

So remarked the pragmatist William James in memorializ-


ing his philosophical godfather, Ralph Waldo Emerson. By
* Richard Shusterman
this Jamesian criterion, which paradoxically posits happi-
shuster1@fau.edu
ness as a posthumous affair, Richard Rorty (in some sense
1
Florida Atlantic University, Boca Raton, FL, USA my pragmatist godfather) should be very happy.1 Fifteen
584 Society (2022) 59:583–590

years after his June 2007 death, we are witnessing some- a broad array of topics ranging from core philosophical topics
thing of a Rorty Renaissance celebrating his significant of epistemology, ontology, language, ethics, and political the-
singularity in much more than “a few pages of print.” In ory (considered both in terms of historical treatment and con-
the last 2 years, three new books of Rorty’s writing have temporary debates) to commentary on current political issues,
appeared along with comprehensive studies of his work including controversial matters of cultural politics. Rorty’s
published by major academic presses. Two of the Rorty voracious intellect treats far too many topics to discuss in
volumes derive from unpublished papers, selected and my essay, which, to balance the celebratory thrust of the re-
edited from his archived Nachlass at the University of viewed publications, will ultimately focus on some issues in
California, Irvine, while the third claims to be “Rorty’s his views that seem in problematic tension with his key prag-
long-lost, last book,” presenting his “final, mature version matist aims and, more importantly, with those I believe we
and vision of his path-breaking pragmatism.” (Brandom should endorse in our current moment.
2021; p. vii) Interest is not confined to the Anglophone Rorty’s alluring blend of quality, controversy, and range
world. France’s prominent Archives de Philosophie pub- provides a fourth reason for this burst of posthumous
lished the special issue “Relire Rorty” late in 2019, and publication—his marketability in the commercial field of in-
the prestigious Parisian École normale supérieure sched- tellectual goods. For academic philosophical publishing (ob-
uled the international conference “Reconsidering Rorty on viously concerned about declining sales), Rorty is an author of
Politics, Language and Aesthetics” for December 2022. proven broad interest that extends beyond philosophy into
Several reasons can explain this surge of Rorty publica- literary studies and general intellectual culture. Because books
tions and interest. One stems from his prominent posthumous by him are sure to sell, and he is no longer alive to assert his
presence in social media for apparently predicting the election droit moral to control publication, his (published and unpub-
of someone like Donald Trump. In Achieving Our Country lished) works are attractive quarry for edited collections. A
(1998), Rorty imagined how white working-class Americans slim, unremarkable lecture that Rorty gave in Turin in 2005
would continue to lose faith both in mainstream liberal and was puffed up with a Foreword, an Introduction, and a
conservative leaders and therefore elect a populist “strong- Conclusion by other writers and then presented as a book by
man” who would take the country in a dangerously undemo- Rorty, entitled An Ethics for Today (2011). Less dubious was
cratic and “sadistic” direction. Popularity in twitter gossip the venture of two savvy editors who republished, in a 2014
hardly justifies the flood of attention to his philosophical collection, some of Rorty’s uncollected early papers. Another
work, and Rorty would surely reject the status of clairvoyant pair of ambitious editors usefully sifted through the Rorty
prophet, because he tirelessly contends that philosophy holds Nachlass to publish first a volume of unpublished (and some-
no special key to knowledge and that the very philosophical times undated) papers on Philosophy and Philosophers
ideal of truth is a misguided and useless, albeit deeply (2020) that apparently extend from the 1960s to 2000, and
entrenched, traditional value. Rather than truth, Rorty insists then, in 2022, a mixed volume of Rorty’s published and un-
on moral, political, and cultural progress toward greater har- published short journalistic texts on political issues, entitled
mony and beauty as the key aim to which philosophy and What Can We Hope For?
intellectual culture should be directed. A second explanation The apparent cream of this posthumous crop is
for the burst of Rorty’s publications is that his unexpected Pragmatism as Anti-Authoritarianism (2021), meticulously
death from pancreatic cancer prevented him from properly edited by Eduardo Mendietta and graced by a substantive
overseeing the publication of his final texts. His Page- “Foreword” by Rorty’s favorite student Robert Brandom,
Barbour lectures of 2004 were not published until 2016, per- claiming it is Rorty’s “long-lost, last book” and “final” vision.
haps because he was too busy with the publication of his last Innocent readers will need to consult the volume’s back notes
important collection of essays, Philosophy as Cultural Politics to learn that the book was never really lost but was already
(2007), which includes a slightly shorter version of his third published in Catalan (1998) and Spanish (2000) and that all
and final Page-Barbour lecture. but one of the individual papers were previously published in
The most important reason for the Rorty renaissance is English in one form or other, after being delivered as lectures
surely the quality, influence, and controversial character of at the University of Girona in 1996 and then given a preface in
his work. A provocative thinker with clear, stylish, energeti- 1997. Subsequent to those lectures, Rorty published his more
cally flowing, and often colorful prose that is both appealingly accessible books on politics, Achieving our Country (1998)
accessible and rich in erudition, Rorty writes texts that engage and Philosophy and Social Hope (2000), as well as the last
two of his four important collections of philosophical essays
0
Rorty was the person most influential in converting me from analytic phi- with Cambridge University Press, Truth and Politics (1998)
losophy to pragmatism and in bringing me to the USA, when I was already a and Philosophy and Cultural Politics (2007). All this indicates
tenured philosopher in Israel. For detailed discussion of our philosophical
connections and differences, see “Pragmatism and Cultural Politics” in that rather than a set of newly composed lectures to represent
Shusterman 2012; pp. 166–196. Rorty’s final vision, Pragmatism as Anti-Authoritarianism is
Society (2022) 59:583–590 585

simply a collection of essays from the 1990s. One of its chap- issues, which he regards as devoid of utility, even if they once
ters, prepared for a lecture I heard in France in 1993, was served past progress. This makes his philosophy principally
already published in French translation in a book I co-edited therapeutic or negative. One could summarize its core in three
in 1998 (La modernité en questions). key antithetical themes: anti-foundationalism, anti-essential-
The unseemliness of the advertising hype is a regrettable ism, and anti-representationalism. Their challenges to tradi-
blemish on what is otherwise a very finely edited collection of tional philosophical ideals of objectivity make Rorty look like
essays in which Rorty’s undeniable polemical brilliance and a relativist, but he rejects that charge by rejecting the very idea
philosophical knowledge are in full display, even if the book of relativism as relying on a misguided representational view
fails to do justice to the range of Rorty’s vision by concentrat- of belief. That view explains difference in belief as deriving
ing on the standard philosophical problems that Rorty’s argu- from the different ways that perceptions and conceptual
ments hope to sweep away. The book’s account of Rorty’s schemes represent reality or “the way the world really is.”
pragmatism as presenting “an intellectual movement of world- This core notion of a foundational objective reality—“the re-
historical significance” to bring “nothing less than a second ally real” as Rorty sarcastically dubs it (Rorty 2016; p. 10)—
Enlightenment” through “completion of the project of that is differently represented in our subjective experience,
Enlightenment” (Brandom 2021; pp. vi, xxv) seems awk- concepts, and beliefs is an idea that Rorty’s pragmatist anti-
wardly out of step with Rorty’s own admirably modest assess- foundationalism vehemently rejects. We can make no prag-
ment of these lectures: “as having shifted a few pieces around matic sense of such a foundational reality because we have no
on the philosophical chessboard [“to arrange them into slight- direct access to it without the linguistic tools through which
ly more useful patterns”] rather than as having answered any we can understand our dealings with the world and formulate
deep questions or produced any elevating thoughts” (Rorty our beliefs about it. The world of our experience, in this sense,
2021; p. xxxv). Such puffery is also out of tune with Rorty’s is more made than found or given, and what makes it is human
extremely humble view of philosophy’s current significance, linguistic practices as they change and develop over history.
portraying it as a “transitional genre” that (after superseding Anti-essentialism is a clear consequence of Rorty’s anti-
religion) has been superseded by literature as the intellectual foundational and anti-representational historicism. Objects in
engine of moral and political progress through literature’s the world are not ontologically individuated and eternally de-
imaginative powers for inventing new vocabularies and thus fined by a set of essential properties that are necessary to the
new ways of thinking that by improving our language makes object’s identity. Instead, linguistic practices are what deter-
our ethical and political lives richer and better (Rorty 2006; mine how we individuate things and define what their essen-
pp. 89–104). tial properties are. In this sense, the things of this world are
Since his trailblazing Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity of constructed through language and can change through change
1989 (the “favorite among [his] own books” (Rorty, 2010; p. of vocabularies. What chiefly (and rightly) motivates such
17)), Rorty has plied a thoroughly anti-authoritarian line that linguistic change are human desires that reflect practical and
included eschewing the authority of his own philosophical aesthetic interests rather than the purely rational search for
views to compel the assent of others and to claim validity truth. Here, Rorty can appeal to the pragmatist, historicist
for other times or contexts, advocating the pluralist, liberal tradition of William James and John Dewey that drew on
ironist ideal “to overcome authority without claiming author- Charles Darwin. As James defined truth as what is “good in
ity” (Rorty 1989; p. 105). Repeatedly endorsing Hegel’s view the way of belief” (James 2000; p. 38) and explained our sense
that “philosophy is its time held in thought” (Rorty 2006; p. of rationality in terms of “aesthetic and practical interests”
viii) while affirming Emersonian faith in human imagination (James 1983; p.817), so Dewey explained how knowledge
to create “endlessly expanding circles” (Rorty 2016; p. 20), and concepts (including those of philosophy) developed
Rorty humbly avows (and welcomes) that any circle of through changing historical circumstances, particularly
thought he sketches should be overcome by a different, more through the need to adjust beliefs to new social challenges.
expansive one. Believing that linguistic change through new Such historicism, Rorty argues, is fully compatible with a
vocabularies is the key to moral and political progress, Rorty form of naturalism that recognizes brute physical causality
critiques philosophy’s traditional attempts to ground our con- and the fact that human language makers and their webs of
cepts and beliefs by appeal to putative foundational truths rational belief are products of the evolving natural world rath-
regarding reality beyond the web of language. Rather than er than supernatural gifts of a divine spiritual force.
grounding our discourse and principles, “the point is to change Although Rorty dodges the charge of relativism, his anti-
them so as to make them serve our purposes better” by “mak[- essentialist, anti-foundational, anti-representational histori-
ing] them more useful for democratic politics” (Rorty 2021; p. cism entails a form of ethnocentrism, one he cheerfully em-
83). braces (Rorty 2021; pp. 59, 76). Humans always experience
Rorty’s efforts for change focus on disabusing us of and understand things through a particular culture that gives
philosophy’s traditional discourse about so-called essential them not only the language that structures their thought but
586 Society (2022) 59:583–590

also the social circumstances and values that shape their hori- If literature outstrips philosophy as the engine of moral
zons and desires, their sense of what is possible and worth- progress toward “a utopian, inclusivist, human community,”
while. As there is no foundational reality that could justify our then culture should be “no longer dominated by the ideal of
view of things as the true one, so there is no foundational objective cognition but by that of aesthetic enhancement”
rationality to invoke for convincing others that our beliefs through the individual’s “idiosyncratic self-creation” in her
are more rational. There is no neutral space to step out of rival personal life (Rorty 2021; p. 47; 2010; pp.19–20). Rorty then
cultural beliefs so that pure reason could adjudicate between adds, “if we were not the sort of beings who are capable of
rival views and values. Arguments that our secular liberal self-creation, we would not be worth caring about” (Rorty
beliefs are more rational than those of the religious fundamen- 2010; p. 20). Philosophy’s service to the public sphere of
talist will always have some implicit circularity because they politics should be devoted to promoting the possibilities of
will inevitably appeal to concepts, beliefs, and values that such aesthetic fulfillment, to “build our philosophical reflec-
somehow presume the superiority of secular rationality over tions around our political hopes: around the project of fash-
the inscrutable, unfathomable reason of God. ioning institutions and customs which will make human life,
For Rorty, however, such circularity does not mean that we are finite and mortal life, more beautiful” and “see the pursuit of
rationally condemned to believe that all cultures are equally good truth as the pursuit of human happiness” (Rorty 2021; pp.
and that we therefore cannot argue for what we believe is an ideal xxix–xxx). The yearning “for something more than happi-
culture. Rorty’s texts unflaggingly maintain the superiority of sec- ness” and beauty—what Rorty calls “the quest for the infinite”
ular liberal democracy over all other forms of societal and political and “the sublime” (which he identifies with philosophy’s tra-
order. During Reagan’s political reign that witnessed the fall of ditional quest for “the really real” and the absolute ideal)—he
Soviet communism, Rorty defined his position as “postmodernist sees as too dangerous for the public sphere and so must be
bourgeois liberalism”: postmodernist in doubting grand confined to “the realm of individual imagination” (Rorty
metanarratives of coming closer to ultimate truth; bourgeois in 2021; pp. xxxi–xxxii).
recognizing that, historically, capitalism helped shape cherished Recognizing that his own metaphilosophical commitments
notions of rights and freedoms while providing the economic will not allow him to argue for his beliefs by saying that they
wealth that fostered Western culture; and liberal in its commitment are closer to foundational truth, Rorty concedes that any argu-
to personal freedom and tolerance (Rorty 1991; pp. 197–210). ment claiming his views to be more rational than those of an
Though still convinced that no superior substitute for liberal cap- illiberal theocrat will ultimately rely on reasons that presup-
italist society would emerge, Rorty later preferred to describe his pose his claim rather than providing neutral evidence equally
political ideal in different terms: the democratic “culture Whitman acceptable by his opponents. If rational argument is compel-
and Dewey hoped to build” as the distinctive promise America ling only when the arguers share common ground as to what
pledged to embody (Rorty 2021; p. 124). It is the ideal of an counts as proper evidence and right reasoning, then
inclusive liberal democracy devoted to promoting personal free- philosophy’s perennial questions will perennially defy resolu-
dom and social harmony, buttressed by economic security, toler- tion since their rival positions are based on conflicting intui-
ance, and kindness or love for all its citizens. tions about evidence and different preferences of vocabular-
Although critical of certain American realities, Rorty re- ies. Rorty insists, however, that argument’s impotence to re-
mained a patriotic believer in America’s ideals and distinctive solve fundamental disagreement does not mean there is no
exemplary role in advancing democracy. While critical of way to convince others of the superiority of one’s views. His
Christian belief in the supernatural and original sin, his dem- alternative to argument is narrative. Where reasoning finds
ocratic social ideal (built on Dewey’s) endorsed “the Christian insufficient common ground to resolve matters, persuasive
doctrine that love is the only law” (Rorty 2021; p. 44). As storytelling can induce assent. Rather than reason, aesthetic
good democracy advocates the “substitution of love for pow- appeal will crown the winner. Philosophies are not so much
er,” so justice, for Rorty, is “larger loyalty” that extends our disproved as displaced by new philosophical views, vocabu-
concern for fairness and equity to social groups beyond those laries, and problems that seem more attractive, more interest-
close and dear to us. Its verdicts, like other moral judgments, ing and relevant to the particular tastes, hopes, and needs of
are best justified not through rational argument but by “appeal their time.
to sentiment” (Rorty 2021; p. 75). Hence, Rorty sees “moral Though eminently capable of razor-sharp argumentation
progress as a progress of sentiments,” “of increasing (displayed when challenging specific points of analytic inter-
sensitivity” to others, rather than progress toward higher ratio- locutors), Rorty maintains his preferred mode of persuasion is
nality (Rorty 2021; pp. 131, 135). He therefore regards litera- narrative rather than argument, acknowledging Hegel as the
ture (particularly the novel) as superior to philosophy in pro- imaginative genius who created narrative philosophy by es-
moting ethical improvement because of its special powers to tablishing its power. In Philosophy as Poetry, Rorty contrasts
stimulate feelings of sympathy for others who are different analytic philosophy (wholly committed to logical coherence)
and remote from ourselves. with “narrative philosophy” in which “imaginativeness that
Society (2022) 59:583–590 587

gives new uses to old words” and thus redescribes philosophy Even discarding the concept of aesthetics, we still can ask
and its history in new ways. Narrative philosophy maintains what makes Rorty’s redescriptive narratives attractive? Why
coherence while offering more creatively attractive forms of do they continue to fascinate readers? One could describe his
coherence, compelling storytelling that connects philoso- compelling narrative style through the military metaphor of
phers, their ideas, and the scientific, social, and cultural con- shock and awe. Rorty displays the awesome breadth of his
texts that shaped those ideas in interesting new ways (Rorty knowledge of philosophical history (covering ancient and
2016; p. 48). Just 2 months before dying, Rorty confirmed this modern, analytic and continental Western thought) along with
“taste for ambitious, swooshy, Geistesgeschichte,” and most masterful skills of rigorous argument, subtle distinctions, and
of his later essays are in this “big swooshy narrative” style imaginative facility in making surprising and ingenious con-
(Rorty 2010; pp. 6, 17). He describes its ideal form as “a nections. Equally awesome is his rhetorical genius to present
supernarrative – a story that holds the history of science to- such breadth and power in clear, flowing, unpretentious prose
gether with that of politics, history of poetry together with that that carries the narrative so swiftly and effortlessly forward
of theology, the sequence of canonical philosophical texts that the captivated reader would rather relish riding the narra-
together with that of canonical works of architecture,” a nar- tive wave than stop to question it, even when the shocks on
rative of imaginative redescription, which though “too big an that wave threaten balance and credibility.
assignment for a single thinker” is the proper task of intellec- Some of these shocks come from Rorty’s method of
tual culture as a whole (Rorty 2016; pp. 59–60). Philosophy’s connecting seemingly very divergent thinkers and views
contribution should be supplying its own broad redescriptive (Dewey and Heidegger, Peirce and Wittgenstein), demonstrat-
narratives instead of focusing on narrow, scholastic analytic ing the sort of witty discordia concors that made Donne’s
issues by continuing to admire itself as the ultimate seeker and metaphysical poetry scandalously appealing. Other shocks
arbiter of foundational truth, rationality, and justice. come from outlandish claims, delivered as insouciant asides.
According to Rorty, what makes such sweeping “It seems safe to say that if Peirce had never lived, that would
redescriptive narratives convincing is their imaginative in- have made no great difference to the history of philosophy.
terest and aesthetic appeal; this helps keep the philosophical For Frege would have made the linguistic turn single-
conversation from stagnating in scholastic sterility by re- handedly” (Rorty 2021; p. 7). This staggering dismissal of
freshing it with new perspectives and vocabularies. the acknowledged founder of pragmatism by its unstinting
Already in Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Rorty iden- contemporary advocate shows Rorty’s recognition that prov-
tified his philosophical approach as “a turn against theory ocation through radical claims is among the simplest yet most
and toward narrative,” one that conquers through attraction effective methods for getting attention and inciting interest—
not argument. “Conforming to my own precepts, I am not one way to keep philosophical conversation going in hopes of
going to offer arguments against the vocabulary I want to prompting it toward more promising directions. He knows it is
replace. Instead, I am going to try to make the vocabulary I far more difficult to invent ambitiously original philosophical
favor look attractive,” while making “objections [to it] look ideas than to connect or debunk them with critical narratives
bad, thereby changing the subject” (Rorty 1989; pp. 9, 44). of their rise and fall, and pragmatic assessments of their con-
Aesthetic factors are central in Rorty’s thought, not only as temporary use or uselessness. Rorty’s honest modesty is truly
criteria of vocabulary choice and narrative persuasion, but impressive in stating “The function of unoriginal syncretists
also in his private ideal of aesthetic self-creation and even in like myself is to construct narratives which, by fusing hori-
his political ideal of democracy as promoting “a world of zons, link together the products of original minds” to serve the
beautiful Gestelle” of social harmony (Rorty 2021; p. xxxi). purpose of showing which of those philosophical “products of
The failure of recent philosophical commentaries to ade- the imagination of the past have become shopworn and be-
quately address the crucial aesthetic and poetic dimension draggled, and need to be replaced” (Rorty 2010; p. 4).
of Rorty’s thought is regrettable. However, Kloppenberg
and Westbrook (in the most useful essays of The
Cambridge Companion) point to its importance and the dif- II
ficulties that aesthetic experience (with its important non-
linguistic dimensions) poses to Rorty’s textualism. Such Having described Rorty’s philosophy through his posthumous
difficulties make Rorty seem uncomfortable with the aes- publications, I now consider some troubling limitations that
thetic, despite his frequent invocation of aesthetic terms, their views pose to his pragmatist goals of reviving philosophy
criteria, and ideals. In polemics with me, he attacked the by changing its agenda. Rather than redirecting that agenda to
aesthetic field “as another of Kant’s bad ideas” (Rorty important new issues in cultural politics which impact our
2001; p. 156). hopes to realize a better world of harmony, beauty, and
588 Society (2022) 59:583–590

happiness, the major thrust of these posthumous texts by (and but a pragmatic Darwinian adjustment for survival and
about) Rorty is to plunge us back into the traditional philo- flourishing. Philosophy may have started from this recogni-
sophical issues that his narratives seek to sweep away but tion of human limits before the unfathomable, overwhelming
instead continue to resurrect as essential to their narrative powers of nature and the Olympian gods. Its founding injunc-
meaning. Rather than offering new visions of improved har- tion to “Know thyself” was inscribed on Apollo’s Delphic
mony, beauty, and happiness and new ways to achieve this temple to remind humankind of our mortality and vulnerabil-
(by building positive freedom of capabilities), Rorty merely ity, that we should know our humble place in the vast universe
offers the vague and familiar gospel of humanist love and to avoid the catastrophes of hubris. Socrates and Plato crea-
Mill’s negative liberty of noninterference. Exhorting philoso- tively reinterpreted the maxim as advocating the need to know
phy as cultural politics “to suggest further novelties…to mod- one’s soul so as to recognize and cultivate its spiritual, divine
ify people’s sense of who they are, what matters to them, what dimension. That powerful redescription set philosophy on the
is most important,” Rorty embraces Dewey’s definition of quest for the eternal, the infinite, and the sublime that Rorty
philosophy as “social hope reduced to a program of action” denounces.
(Rorty 2006; p. ix). But he falls short in delivering any mean- He claims his “pragmatism is a philosophy of finitude,”
ingful new ones. exhorting us “to give up the quest for the infinite [and]…rest
The exciting appeal of Rorty’s texts in the 1980s converted content with beauty” by abjuring “pursuit of criteria which
me from an Oxford-trained analytic philosopher to an advo- transcend the social practices of a time and place [which] is
cate of the Deweyan-Jamesian pragmatism he championed. an attempt to evade this finitude” (Rorty 2021; p.xxx; 2016;
My enthusiasm diminished with his lack of positive proposals p.57). “So is the attempt to philosophize at a wholesale level”
for creating a new cultural agenda and a lack of substance for (such as saying “something general about…the various things
the aesthetic and eudaimonic values he advocates. Perhaps that different sorts of men and women have found valuable”
Rorty’s insistently deflationary stance, his unrelenting rejec- so as to suggest “a wholesale ideal”) which only serves “to
tion of yearning for any sort of sublimity, greatness, depth, or puff ourselves up, to give us the sense that we are associated
elevation beyond the “darkling two-dimensional plane” of with something that does not share our finitude” (Rorty 2016;
linguistic practices (Rorty 2021; p. 105), is meant to curb pp. 57–58). Rorty describes his philosophy as “finitistic
passionate enthusiasm, which, admittedly, is often misguided. through and through” (Rorty 2021; p. xxxi), even to the par-
But passion is needed to motivate the kind of activism needed adoxical point of challenging its own belief in human finitude,
for significant political and cultural reform. Deflationary iro- considering it as merely a choice of vocabulary. “It is not as if
nist words of flatness are not an adequate spur to action, and human finitude is the ultimate truth of the matter, as if human
Rorty’s textualism eschews the notion of affect along with the beings are intrinsically finite. On our view, human beings are
concept of experience that was crucial to the pragmatism of what they make themselves and one of the things they have
James and Dewey. wanted to make themselves is a divinity” (Rorty 2021; p. 95).
More troubling than these issues and deeply discordant Does mere wanting make it so? Finitude in these posthumous
with the needs of contemporary cultural politics is Rorty’s Rortian texts refers essentially to the limits of any discursive
extreme anthropocentrism, an apparent corollary of his restric- regime, the fact that any vocabulary or world view is finite
tion of the relevant universe to the universe of human dis- because human imagination can always create a new one that
course. In arguing “that we should separate the quest for great- will outflank and displace it. In Rorty’s Emersonian terms,
ness and sublimity from the quest for justice and happiness,” any inclusive circle our thought can draw will eventually be
Rorty claims “our only obligations will be to our fellows and superseded by “new and larger circles” (Rorty 2016; p. 10).
to our own fantasies,” because “The idea of a non-human He does not discuss the finitude of death and the loss of pow-
authority and the quest for sublimity are both products of ers (physical or mental) through injury, old age, and disease.
self-abasement” (Rorty 2021; pp. xxx,xxxii). As pragmatist Can we secular pragmatists effectively talk our way out of
“neo-Darwinians,” he claims “our attitude toward the non- these physical and mental limits, of the degenerative decline
human…is one of Baconian mastery rather than one of re- of aging and death?
spect” (Rorty 2021; p. 191). This radically narrow anthropo- Rorty’s posthumous books speak little of death, nor of pain
centrism is clearly no help in addressing a most crucial issue and suffering. But pain constituted a central theme of
for contemporary cultural politics: the urgent need to save our Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, his transdisciplinary mas-
planet from catastrophic climate change by transforming not terpiece that fruitfully engaged literary as well as philosophi-
only our vocabularies but also our attitudes and lifestyles. cal, psychological, and political culture, with its discussions of
Respecting the nonhuman natural world and the powers Proust, Nabokov, and Orwell alongside those of Marx and
and limits it exerts on us is not a policy of self-abasement Mill, Kant and Hegel, Plato and Nietzsche, and Davidson
Society (2022) 59:583–590 589

and Heidegger. There Rorty defines human solidarity as “not progress as “a progress of sentiments,” his aim of enlarging
discovered by reflection” on a putative shared essence but moral “agreement by persuasion…[through] feeling” using
instead “created by increasing sensitivity to… the pain and forms of “rhetorical manipulation” that appeal to the senti-
humiliation of other, unfamiliar sorts of people” (Rorty ments rather than strict arguments based on reason (Rorty
1989; p. xv). Acknowledging the nonhuman world’s “brute 2021; pp. 131, 156).
power” to inflict “naked pain” that can “inarticulately crush The centrality of affect in moral attitudes and action should
us” (Rorty 1989; p. 40), Rorty also recognizes the nonlinguis- lead to recognizing the value of somaesthetic cultivation for
tic nature of such pain, distinguishing it from the suffering of ethical and political improvement: suggesting a new program
humiliation through the destruction of the cherished language of action for cultural politics. As all sentiments are fundamen-
games essential to one’s sense of selfhood. Rorty here repeat- tally bodily, so are feelings of prejudice (racism, sexism, ho-
edly recognizes here that “pain is nonlinguistic” and that “the mophobia, ethnic hatred, etc.), which often arise from somatic
ability to feel pain” (rather than reasoning ability) is the only feelings of discomfort aroused by the bodies of culturally dif-
thing “we share with all other humans”; that “what unites [a ferent people. The fact that they look, smell, talk, or walk
person] with the rest of the species is not a common language differently than we do makes us feel differently toward them
but just susceptibility to pain, and in particular to that special and less likely to treat them as deserving the same treatment as
form of pain which the brutes do not share with the humans – us. These negative feelings often work beneath the level of full
humiliation” (Rorty 1989; pp. 92, 94). Because it is nonlin- consciousness and linguistic awareness, which is another rea-
guistic, pain is something we have no ability to erase through son why their resulting prejudice resists rational arguments for
linguistic “transformation, only the ability to recognize” it tolerance. By cultivating disciplined somatic consciousness,
along with contingency of existence (Rorty 1989; p. 40). we can improve awareness of such feelings so as to control or
Why does pain’s role disappear in the later writings? A transform them to conquer our prejudices (Shusterman, 2008;
likely answer is the intensification of Rorty’s textualism, a pp. 127–132).
doubling down on his “psychological nominalism” that ad- Feelings can be effectively manipulated through somatic as
mits nothing but language, condemning consciousness, sen- well as linguistic means. We can bring strangers (and even
tience, and experience as invalid concepts for philosophy, and enemies) to feel more comfortable with each other by having
insisting that “all awareness is a linguistic affair” (Rorty 2021; them share the pleasures of eating and drinking together. As
pp. 162, 174). If pain is nonlinguistic, but we are obviously James famously argued, we can also transform our own
aware of pain (certainly our own if not also that of others), moods and feelings by taking on the postures and bodily be-
then not all awareness is linguistic. Pain must therefore be haviors of those affects we wish to feel (James 1983; pp.
marginalized from Rortian theory for the sake of preserving 1077–1078). To imagine empathetically what it feels like to
panlinguistic purity.2 Such purity means rejecting all nonlin- be oppressed or despised (or even simply insulted or offended)
guistic feelings from philosophical relevance by arguing that is an act of somatic consciousness that can be done more
acknowledging them entails the epistemological “myth of the powerfully when we have a more developed somatic imagi-
given” (i.e., that prelinguistic experience gives us direct access nation, when our soma (the sentient, purposive body that
to truth about the world). But feelings have relevance beyond Dewey sometimes called body-mind) is more sensitive and
the epistemological questions on which Rorty remains fo- perceptive. There is thus a deep connection between cultivat-
cused (though seeking to sweep them away). Feelings have ing somatic sensibility and creating the broader sympathy with
a crucial role in visions of the good life. Rejecting feelings others that Rorty advocates as the means to moral progress but
means excluding not only pain but also pleasures. That exclu- identifies too narrowly with literature and language. Our sym-
sion is why Rorty’s talk of aesthetic fulfillment and happiness pathy is narrowed when we focus only on words. This privi-
seems drably vague and abstract, and why he denies a philo- leges the intellectuals who wield verbal power, while ignoring
sophical role to embodiment, the seat of affect that James and (and thus belittling) the feelings of the inarticulate, often dis-
Dewey recognized and cultivated. More puzzling is that Rorty cernible through somatic gesture but worthy of consideration
fails to recognize that in rejecting the philosophical relevance in any case.
of feeling he is undermining his own advocacy of moral In broadening and deepening the palate of our pleasures by
enhancing our perceptual sensibilities, somaesthetic cultiva-
2 tion provides a program of action to give more body to
Another reason for excluding pain from philosophy may be its stubborn
resistance to remedy through language. In Rorty’s beautifully evocative essay Rorty’s admirable ideal of a democratic utopia of harmony
on facing his imminent death from inoperable pancreatic cancer, he writes of and happiness. The aim would be not merely an inclusive
having “found comfort” in poetry rather than other forms of literature, includ- consensual society, but also a con-sensual one where harmony
ing philosophy (Rorty 2007; 130). There is no mention of pain, though it must
surely have been part of his final ordeal in life. Perhaps dismissing it in theory is built on the progressive bonds of shared pleasures (in unity
helped to diminish it in felt experience. and difference) rather than a mere tolerance of otherness.
590 Society (2022) 59:583–590

References Rorty, Richard (2010), “Intellectual Autobiography,” in The Philosophy


of Richard Rorty (Open Court, Chicago), pp. 3-24.
Brandom, Robert (2021), “Foreword,” in Richard Rorty, Pragmatism as Rorty, Richard (2016), Philosophy as Poetry (University of Virginia
Anti-Authoritarianism (Harvard University Press, Cambridge), pp. Press, Charlottesville).
vii-xxvi. Rorty, Richard (2020), On Philosophy and Philosophers, edited by W. P.
James, William (1962), “Address at the Emerson Centenary in Concord,” Małecki and Chris Voparil, (Cambridge University Press,
in Emerson: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by Milton Cambridge).
Konvitz and Stephen Whicher (Spectrum, Englewood Cliffs). Rorty, Richard (2021), Pragmatism as Anti-Authoritarianism (Harvard
James, William (1983), The Principles of Psychology (Cambridge: University Press, Cambridge).
Harvard University Press). Rorty, Richard (2022), What Can We Hope For?: Essays on Politics
James, William (2000), “What Pragmatism Means” in Pragmatism and (Princeton University Press, Princeton).
Other Writings (Penguin Books, New York). Shusterman, Richard (2008), Body Consciousness: A Philosophy of
Marchetti, Giancarlo (2022), The Ethics, Epistemology, and Politics of Mindfulness and Somaesthetics (Cambridge University Press,
Richard Rorty (Routledge, New York). Cambridge).
Rondel, David (2021), The Cambridge Companion to Rorty (Cambridge Shusterman, Richard (2012), Thinking through the Body: Essays in
University Press, Cambridge). Somaesthetics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
Rorty, Richard (1989), Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, (Cambridge Voparil, Chris (2022), Reconstructing Pragmatism: Richard Rorty and
University Press, Cambridge). the Classical Pragmatists (Oxford University Press, New York).
Rorty, Richard (1991), “Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism,” in
Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth (Cambridge University Press,
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdic-
Cambridge), pp. 197-202.
tional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rorty, Richard (2001), “Response to Richard Shusterman,” in Matthew
Festenstein and Simon Thompson (eds.), Richard Rorty: Critical
Dialogues (Polity Press, Cambridge), pp. 197-210.
Rorty, Richard (2006), “Philosophy as a Transitional Genre,” in Reviewer: Richard Shusterman is the Dorothy F. Schmidt Eminent Scholar
Philosophy as Cultural Politics (Cambridge University Press, in the Humanities and Professor of Philosophy at Florida Atlantic University.
Cambridge), pp. 89-104. His most recent books are Ars Erotica: Sex and Somaesthetics in the
Rorty, Richard (2007), “The Fire of Life,” Poetry Magazine, November Classical Arts of Love (2021) and Philosophy and the Art of Writing (2022).
2007, pp. 129-131.

You might also like