You are on page 1of 19

Strategic Management Journal, Vol.

12, 119-136 (1991)

MODELING, GAME THEORY, AND STRATEGIC


MANAGEMENT
GARTH SALONER
Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, California, U,S.A.

This paper examines the potential iLwfulne.ss of game-theoretic modeling for the development
of theory in strategic management. It is argued that there is significant potential for the
development of 'metaphorical' models that capture the broad qualitative features of settings
involving .strategic interactions. The paper discus.ses the positive attributes of mathemtUical
modeling, the nature and role of game-theoretic modeling, and its potential for contributing
to empirical work and to providing advice to managers.

INTRODUCTION signaling;^ and the strategic control of information


more generally (Fudenberg and Tirole, 1986).
During the 1970s and 1980s considerable effort While most of the models have focused on
was devoted to applying game-theoretic tech- external strategy issues, recently these tools have
niques to the analytic modeling of issues in been turned increasingly to other questions of
industrial economics. The sophistication and direct relevance to strategic management having
breadth of the models described in The Handbook to do with the internal organization of the firm
of Industrial Organization or in Jean Tirole's The and the appropriate scope of its activities. These
Theory of Itidustriul Organization, bear testament include questions relating to the vertical scope
to the extent of that effort. of the firm's activities (Grossman and Hart,
Many of the issues examined in that body of 1986): and the effect of incentives on the optimal
work are of direct relevance to competitive horizontal scope of the firm (Jensen. 1986); and
strategy, the branch of strategic management the appropriate breadth of the firm's business
concerned with what one might call 'external' and corporate strategies (Rotemberg and Saloner,
strategy issues, i.e. the firm's strategy vis-a-vis 199()b).-*
its rivals. These include issues such as the Finally, issues at the intersection of these
importance of first-mover advantages and the 'internal' and 'external' orientations constitute a
role of commitment in staking out a market growth area within economics. T>ie issues here
position;' reputation formation and exploitation;' include the effect of incentive schemes within the

Key words: game theory, rationality, modeling


' Sec Lieberman and Montgomery (1988) for an overview of and Roberts (1982b), and Kreps et al. (1982) is discussed in
first-mover advantages and Schmalensee (1978. 1982), and Saloncr (1992).
Spcnce (1977. 1981) for specific examples, Dixil (1980) and ' See Spence (1974) for the developmenl of ihe theory and
Judd (I98.'v) contain analyses of the importanee of the ability Milgrom and Roberts (1982a) discussed in Saloncr (1992) for
lo make commitments. an application to entry deterrence.
* See Wcigelt and Camerer (1988) and Krcp^ and Spence ^ In iheir forthcoming book. Economic Organization and
(1984) for overviews, and Kreps (199(la). Roicmberg and Management. Milgrom and Roberts provide a detailed analysis
Saloncr (1986. 1990a). and Green and Poner (1984) for of many of these issues and describe numerous implications
examples. The work of Kreps and Wilson (1982), Milgrom for strategic management.

0143-2095/91/iOOny-18$(m.()0
© 1991 by John Wiley & Sons. Ltd.
120 C. Saloner

firm on product market competilion;'* the ability game-theoretic modeling and the "older' standard
to use vertical integration to achieve competitive neoclassical methods.^
advantage (Ordover, Saloner, and Salop. 1990: However, it is probably also due in part to
Hart and Tirole, forthcoming, and Bolton and the fact thai some observers within strategic
Whinston, 1989); and the effect of distribution management are troubled by the complexity of
channel design on competition (Coughlin and the reasoning of which the agents whose behavior
Wernerfelt, 1988; Moorthy, forthcoming, and is being analyzed are assumed to be capable. For
Bonanno and Vickers, 1988). example, Rumelt. Schendel, and Teece (1990)
Despite the relevance of these issues to strategic write:
management, the impact on that field has mainly
been through "importing' relevant implications Rational models of competitive interaction
from economics. The question arises, however, posit players who engage in very subtle
as to whether there isn't a more direct role and complex reasoning. Yet our common
for game-theoretic modeling within strategic experience is that decision-makers are far
management, as a tool used by scholars who less analytic and perform far less compre-
regard strategic management as their primary hensive analyses than these models posit.
field. If one is a player, is it really 'rational' to
This question is complicated by the difficulty posit such complex behavior in others? (p.
that once a model has the trappings of microeco- 9)
nomics'' there is a tendency to define it as
being about eeonomics rather than strategic The degree of rationality assumed in game-
management. If. however, strategic management theoretic models is often much greater than in
is defined by a set of research questions or by other economic models. In game-theoretic models
the subject matter of the field, however, then each firm's optimal action depends on what it
this problem does not arise. Models of strategic believes its rivals wilt do. In order to decide what
groups, generic strategies, or how organizational to do itself, the firm must put itself in ils rival's
structure influences strategy, all fall within the shoes and analyze the situation from its rival's
domain of strategic management whether they perspective. The analysis therefore requires
have the trappings of microeconomic models or assumptions about the rival's rationality, as well
not. It is the prospect of the development of as the assessment of the rival's belief about one's
such models that we have in mind below. own rationality, and so on. These assumptions
This question of whether there is a role are particularly striking in a field tike strategic
for game-theoretic modeling within strategic management which tolerates a wide variety of
management really has two components. The behavioral assumptions.
first is whether there is a role in strategic The increased burden the assumption of
management for modeling of the microeconomic rationality is asked to bear in game-theoretic
variety at all, whether game-theoretic or not. The models can be seen by contrasting duopoly theory
second, which arises only if the first is answered with the theories of perfect competition and of
in the affirmative, is whether such modeling monopoly. In the case of monopoly the firm
should be game-theoretic. Most of the attention faces a 'simple* optimization problem. The
among strategic management scholars seems to situation is even more straightforward for a
be focused on this latter question. This is perfectly competitive firm which, as a price-
probably, at least in part, a spillover from the taker, only has to ascertain whether or not it can
debate within the economics profession itself profitably produce utiy quantity at the equilibrium
about the relative merits of the more recent price. The duopoHst's optimal decision, on the
other hand, depends on what its rival witt do.
In order to make the critique of the rationatity
assumption in game-theoretic models even more
concrete, consider the following game. In this
^ See Fershiman and Judd (1987), discussed later, for
example.
'' Rational decision-makers with well-defined objective func- ''See. for example, the debate between Fisher (1989) and
tions and possible actions. Shapiro (19K9) in ihe Rand Journal of Economics.
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 121

game you choose "top* or 'bottom' while your Given the degree of rationality assumed in
opponent simultaneously chooses 'left' or 'right'. game-theoretic models, can they usefully be
Your actions lead to the pay-offs in Table 1 employed in strategic management? The answer
where, as usual, the first number in each cett is to this question must depend on the role these
the 'row player's' (your) payoff and the second models are expected to play. One role is a rather
is the "column ptayer's. Thus, for exampte. if literal one in which the model is supposed to
you choose 'top' and your opponent chooses mirror an actual managerial situation and the
'teft", you receive 1 and your opponent receives desired output is an exact prescription as to what
0 (where higher numbers denote more desirable action to take: how much capacity to install, how
outcomes; perhaps the numbers represent dollars much to produce, how to position one's product,
or a measure of utility). etc. In such settings, as in the rationality game,
To the casual observer the most striking feature the burden on the rationality assumption may be
of these payoffs is the *-l()0()" that you receive quite severe.
if the 'bottom left' outcome occurs. From a We argue in the next section, however, that
game-theoretic point of view, however, the most there are many games, including many of the
striking feature is the fact that choosing 'right' kind that arise in strategic management, where
is the best strategy for your opponent regardless the degree of rationality required does not strain
of what you do: he earns 1 if he chooses 'right' the limits of plausibility. We illustrate this by an
and 0 if he chooses 'left'.** examination of the popular Cournot model,
Given the 'compelling logic' that your rival which in many respects provides the best case
should play 'right', your own choice boils down for the plausibility of a literal model.
to choosing 'top' and receiving 1 (the 'top right' In the third section, however, we argue that
outcome) or choosing 'bottom" and receiving 2 literal interpretations of game-theoretic models
("bottom right'). Clearly you 'should' choose are largely irrelevant and that the debate about
'bottom'. Game theory predicts the 'bottom right" whether firms would play the Cournot game as
outcome. game-theorists would is largely academic. Rather
Notice, however, that you stand to lose a great we argue that the appropriate role for microe-
deal (10(X)) if you behave as game theory predicts conomic-style modeling in strategic management
you will while your opponent does not. A generally, and for game-theoretical modeling in
'mistake' by your opponent would not be very particular, is not literal but rather is metaphorical.
costly to him, but it would be extremely costly The nature and role of metaphorieal modeling,
to you. Indeed, the cost to your opponem of his its potential for contributing to strategic manage-
making a mistake could be arbitrarily small ment, and the lower burden placed on the
without changing the structure of the argument.** rationality assumption in such settings is discussed
there.
In the fourth section we discuss the distinction
Table 1. The 'rationality game
between the profit-maximization and rationality
Opponent assumptions, The profit maximization hypothesis
Left Right has two parts: that firms maximize 'something',
and that the 'something' is profits. The rationality
Top 1.0 1,1 assumption is only concerned with the first of
You these, i.e. that firms attempt to maximize
Bottom -1000 .0 2.1

" In Ihe language of game theory, playing 'right' is a dominant


strategy. this kind is called a 'maximin strategy* .since it asks the
" To sec this imagine replacing the zeroes in the above table question 'what is the minimum I ean earn with this action?'
by 1-e and consider « tn be as small as you like. Now image and selects the action that results in the largest of these
what you would in fact choose to do if you were 'playing' minima. In Ihe present case if both players used maximin
this game against a variety of different opponents: David strategies the outcome 'top right" would result. A maximin
Kreps. a fourth grader, an average undergraduate, the CEO strategy is conservative hut noi maximizing and therefore not
of a typical U.S. firm . . . A somewhat cautious player might 'rational'. If you knew your opponent was using a maximin
choose to play top' in ihese circumstances in which case she strategy you would prefer to play 'bottom' to using your own
is assured of earning at least 1. A conservative strategy of maximin strategy.
122 G. Saloner

something although not necessarily profits.'" at which a combined output of the two firms of
Indeed, we show that it may sometimes be in a 0 units can be sold can be represented by P =
profit-maximizing firm's interests to convince its a - 0 . We suppose further that it costs a firm cq,
rivals or employees that it (or its managers) are to produce q, units, so that c is the (constant)
interested in maximizing something other than per unit cost of production.
profits. How 'should' a firm that wants to maximize
In the fifth section we examine the role that profits "play" this game? The firm's optimization
game-theoretic modeling can play in providing problem and its 'solution" are deceptively easy
advice to managers and in conducting empirical to write down. Denoting the firm's own output
work. Finally, the last section contains concluding by qi and its belief about what its rival will
remarks. produce by q^. firm i"s profit can be written as:

(1
A LITERAL INTERPRETATION OF
GAME-THFORETIC MODELING: Differentiating with respect to q,, the 'solution"
RATIONALITY IN THE COURNOT is:
MODEL
(2)
In this section we take a literal approach to
game-theoretic modeling. We examine the role Equation 2 and the corresponding equation for
that the rationality assumption plays in a game firm 2 are depicted in Figure 1.
that is beloved of many industrial organization
economists: Cournot duopoly, perhaps the most
frequently applied game in industrial organi- Predicting outcomes
zation. Our interest is not in the Cournot game To obtain a prediction as to what each firm will
per se., however. We look at it because it in fact produce in the Cournot setting, one must
illustrates the nature and role of rationality in a go considerably further than Equation 2. Each
fairly broad class of the applications of game firm must predict what its rival will do. But how
theory of interest to strategic management. should it do this? The 'standard" solution offered
In the game first considered by Augustin by game theory, the Nash Equilibrium, does not
Cournot more than 150 years ago, two firms specify the logic by which a firm should decide
simultaneously choose how much of a homo- what it should do, but rather 'leaps' directly to
geneous good to produce so that each firm must the solution by specifying desirable properties
make its output decision in ignorance of the that strategies should possess in order to be
other's. The firms' chosen production is 'sent to
the market' where it fetches the highest price at
which the combined output of the firms can be
sold.
In many respects the Cournot model represents
the 'best case" for literal game-theoretic modeling.
It is a 'one-shot" game. (i.e. the firms meet in
this way only once) so that 'repeated play'
considerations do not arise; there is no asymmetric
information, and, as discussed below, there is a a-c
unique equilibrium outcome which does not 3
involve mixed strategies.
To be concrete we assume a particular form
of the demand function, that is the highest price
a-c
'" The question of whether firms maximize profits has 3
received considerable attention elsewhere (see Kreps, 1990b Figure 1. Best response functions in the Cournot
for a discussion). game
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 123

'equilibrium" strategies." In particular, each infinitely many iterations) to the conclusion that
player's strategy must be optimal given the other's each firm should produce (a—c)/3.'^ At each
strategy. stage of the reasoning, a dominance argument is
applied.'^
In this setting this means that for {q*,q?} to The fact that the Cournot game can be 'solved'
be a 'solution" to the game it must be the case through the pure logic of iterated dominance in
that q* = [a-q2-c]/2, i.e. firm I's strategy is this way should not give one enormous comfort.
Recall, for example, that the 'rationality game'
optimal given q*, and q| = [a-qf-c]/2, i.e. firm discussed at the beginning of this section was
2's strategy is optimal given q*. The only way solved there in the identical manner. Even though
both of these conditions can hold is if iterated dominance is a strong argument by game-
theoretic standards, the fact that the argument
qr = q! = (a-c)/3. must be repeated infinitely often may make one
Because of the way in which it is defined, the skeptical about the ability of the 'typical' player
Nash Equilibrium has the attractive property that to apply it successfully.
if, ex post, one observes that the Nash strategies
have been played, it is very easy to rationalize
the firms" behavior. Given what firm 2 did, Robustness
firm 1 behaved optimally and vice versa. Put There is, however, a sense in which one should
differently, each firm"s belief about what its feel much more confident in playing the Cournot-
rival would produce turned out to be correct. Nash strategy than in playing 'bottom' in the
Moreover, this could only be said about strategies •rationality' game because of the robustness
that formed a Nash Equilibrium since if the firms of Cournot to 'small mistakes'. Suppose, for
did not both play their Nash strategies, ex post example, that the firm believes that the rival is
both would regret not having taken a different 'trying' to behave as game theory suggests a
course of action. "rational" opponent should, but that the rival is
As pointed out above, however, the Nash not very good at it and so is likely to make a
Equilibrium does not describe how the firms small mistake in its calculations. What are the
come to have the 'correct' beliefs in the first consequences for the firm? Since the firm's profits
place. In the case of the Cournot game, given are continuous in the decision of the rival, a
profit-maximizing objectives and rationality on 'small' mistake leads to a small loss of profits.
the part of the players, it turns out that logic For this particular example, if the rival produces
alone is enough to derive the solution. To see {l+t)(a-c)/3 instead of just (a-c)/3, the firm's
this note from (2) that firm i's optimal output is profits fall to (l-e)(a-c)-/9, i.e. if the rival's
decreasing in qj the amount that it believes that output is 1 percent higher than the Cournot-
its rival will produce. Therefore the most that Nash level, the firm's profits are I percent lower
firm i should ever produce can be derived from than at the Cournot equilibrium.'"*
(2) by setting q, = 0, i.e. firm i should never
produce more than (a-c)/2, the amount it would
produce if its rival stayed out of the maket. But Communication and learning
if firm j knows that firm i won"t produce more
So far we have considered the harshest test of
than (a-c)/2 then it should produce at least
the rationality assumption by assuming that the
[a-{(a-c)/2}-c]/2 = (a-c)/4. Knowing this,
firm must make its own output decision in
firm i should produce at least [a-{(a-c)/4}-c]/2
= 3(a - c)/8. This reasoning converges (with
' - T h e Hth term in the sequence is given by t,, = |(a-c)/2]
- It,._,/2l. with t,, = 0.
" Notice Ihat the notion of •equilihrium" in game-theoretic '^ Milgrom and Roberts (1990) show ihai a large class of
models is somewhat different from that used elsewhere (even Important games with unique equilibria can be 'solved' in
in other economic applications) Here equilibrium does not this way.
mean ihat. after a long period of adjustment, the system has '•* The loss of profits lo the firm is. however, larger than a
come to rest. Rather, it simply means thai given the strategy corresponding mistake by the firm itself. If the firm produces
that each player is using, no single agenl has an incentive to (1 +€)(a-c)/.l hy mistake, its profits only fall to (I - e ) ( a - c ) - / 9 .
deviate unilaterally from ils proposed strategy. Thus Ihe loss is of second-order importance.
124 G. Saloner

complete ignorance of what its rival will do. In Another setting in which a firm might feel more
practice the firm will often have some information comfortable playing its Cournot-Nash strategy is
about its rival's intentions. In particular, there where it Is playing a rival drawn from a pool of
are at least two settings where the firms might firms with experience at the game. With enough
feel more confident playing their Cournot-Nash experience, the strategies used by the players
strategies. should not remain biased away from the Cournot-
The first of these is where the firms have had Nash prediction. Suppose, for example, that each
an opportunity (whether through the media or firm has developed a strategy that it uses in
in person) to discuss their planned actions ahead playing the one-shot Cournot game and that the
of time. By this we do not mean that the firms average of the strategies of the players in the
are able to enter into discussions leading up to pool is an output of (a-c)/3+c rather than
a binding contractual agreement. Communication (a—c)/3. If this fact were common knowledge
of that kind would more likely lead to a collusive among the players each would soon figure out
agreement than to Cournot behavior. Rather we that it could do better by producing (a-e)/3-e/2.
have in mind that the final output decisions are the best-response to (a-c)/3+e. But if they all
still made independently. behaved this way, of course, this would become
There is a sense in which such preplay the average production of the pool. This learning
communication (known as "cheap talk' in the process would lead them lo (a-c)/3, the only
literature) should have no effect on Ihe outcome 'average* production level that would not induce
since the payoffs and strategic options that the a change in behavior by a rational opponent.
firms face aren't altered at all.'^ However,
preplay communication can remove each firm's
doubts about the reasoning process that the rival Some experimental evidence
is going through. Thus for example, if firm 2 In experimental settings, the Cournot-Nash pre-
claimed it was going to produce (a-c)/2,"* firm dictions are fairly strongly borne out. Moreover,
1 might make the following speech: 'You're only learning of the kind described above does appear
saying that to try to fool me into playing (a-c)/4, to be important in practice. Holt (19K5). for
my best-response to (a-c)/2. However, if you example, conducted experiments on undergrad-
believed you had fooled me into doing that you uates at Minnesota taking introductory and
would produce 3(a-c)/8. your best-response to intermediate economics classes (in which the
(a-c)/4 and not (a-c)/2, so why should I believe instructors had nol discussed the Cournol game).
you?' The only claim that either firm could make Twelve students participated in 11 one-shot plays
that would not be challenged by the rival would of the Cournot game of which the first was a
be the claim that the firm Intended to produce 'trial run". Half of the monopoly output (the
its Cournot-Nash output! And if both firms have collusive outcome) was 6 units, the symmetric
made sueh claims, each will feel quite confident Cournot-Nash was eight, and if each produced
in going ahead and producing its Cournot- 12 units profits would be zero.'**
Nash output.'"'"* Indeed, in this sense, a Nash Unfortunately, Holt's experiment is not as
equilibrium can be viewed as a self-enforcing clean as it might be because with the pay-off
agreement. If the players have agreed to play structure he used there are also asymmetric
their Nash strategies and then go off and Cournot-Nash equilibria: one in which one firm
independently make their decisions, no individual produces six and the other 10. and another in
would have an incentive to deviate from the which one produces seven and the other nine.
agreement. In atl cases, however, the predicted total is the
same: 16. Another shortcoming is that if one's
rival produced its symmetric Cournot-Nash output
'^ See Farrell {I9R7) for a discussion of 'cheap talk*. of eight, the firm would only earn one penny
"• As we shall see later, tirm 2 would like to be able to
commit to producing (a-c)/2 if that commitment eould more by producing eight rather than nine.
credibly be communicated to firm 1.
'^ In contrast to how it would feel in ihc 'rationality' game
al the beginning of this scciion,
"* Cooper et al. (198^) provide some experimental evidence '•' Forty-five cents was added to all profit numbers to give
that suggests that 'cheap talk' can in fact make a difference. subjeets a reasonable return to their time.
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 125

Despite these shortcomings, the results, pre- of the Cournot game to predict behavior in
sented in Table 2 below, are quite striking. experimental settings, game-theoretic models
By the final round the outputs were on average have failed the market test abysmally. For
very close to the Cournot-Nash levels. After the example, ! know of no instance in which the
fifth round all the players except for player 1 Cournot model, or even a sophisticated variant
(and player 12 in round 10 only) chose to produce of it, has been used in practice by the management
either eight or nine units. Notice, however, that of a real world enterprise to guide it in making
almost al! of the players started out some distance its output decisions. Moreover, much the same
away from Cournot-Nash, illustrating the role can be said for most of the vast accumulation of
that learning played. models cited with approval in the Introduction.
Not only are these models not used in their
'purest' form to predict what rivals 'should' do
Evaluation of Miteral* models and hence what one's own best-response should
ln this section we have taken a rather literal be. They are not even used in modified form to
view of the Cournot model in order to explore the predict what rivals will do (even if the firm
role and limitations of the rationality assumption. believes they will not behave as the model says
What does this exploration suggest about how they should) and therfore what the firm should
well we would do predicting behavior in 'real do in that case.-"
world" settings using a game-theoretic analysis Perhaps game-theoretic models will become
assuming the model accurately captured the more useful for these purposes over time as the
setting of interest? techniques improve. I am skeptical, however.^'
Several genera! qualitative conclusions seem Game-theoretic models tend to be so complicated
uneontroversial. First, the burden on the ration- that they defy analysis unless they are boiled
ality assumption is clearly much higher in some down to their essence. For example, a model
circumstances, such as the 'rationality game' than designed to study capacity choices must typically
in others, such as Cournot. This is due in large ignore other issues. However, the world does
part to the robustness of the latter to small not present itself in such a convenient format.
mistakes by the players. Second, one's confidence For managers, capacity decisions come bundled
in the predictive power of the models is likely with product line decisions, quality decisions,
to be significantly greater if the players have had advertising decisions, and so on. The complexity
the opportunity for preplay communication or,
as suggested by the experimental evidence, if
they have some experience with the decisions
'"There arc some exceptions, F<ir cxampte auction theory
being analyzed. has proven useful (or competilive bidding.
Despite the rather sanguine view of the ability -' For a somewhat conirary view, see Camerer (1991).

Table 2. Outcomes of ten ptays of the Cournot Game in an experiment

Subject
Period 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12

Trial 7 8 22 10 5 7 13 7 6 8 10 5
1 5 8 9 10 8 6 11 6 9 8 7 7
2 6 8 9 10 8 10 10 7 9 8 7 8
3 6 8 9 9 8 8 10 7 9 8 8 9
4 6 9 9 8 8 8 9 6 9 8 8 9
5 6 9 9 9 9 8 9 8 9 8 8 9
6 7 8 9 9 9 9 8 8 9 8 8 9
7 7 9 9 9 9 9 9 8 9 8 8 9
8 7 9 9 9 9 8 8 8 9 8 8 9
9 7 9 9 9 9 8 8 8 8 8 8 9
10 7 9 9 8 9 8 8 8 8 8 8 10
126 G. Saloner

of those situations easily overwhelms the ability production, how much inventory to hold, etc).
of simple models to eope with them." When that is achieved, how the algorithm 'works'
Overwhelming complexity also typically arises is of secondary interest.
in 'chess-like' situations; those involving long By contrast, the aim in the kind of microeco-
sequences of moves and countermoves where nomic modeling contemplated here is metaphor-
analysis revolves around questions like 'what ical. The model captures and formalizes only
should firm 1 do if firm 2 does this", how, in selected features of interest; the objective is to
turn, should firm 2 respond, and so on? The create a model which qualitatively simulates a
Kodak-Polaroid and Coke-Pepsi battles, both of type of environment being studied. Thus there
which are the subjects of HBS teaching cases, is no attempt to 'calibrate' the model so that it
are examples of situations of this type. In the is quantitatively true to a particular setting. Once
game of chess itself, for example, while game- the formalism is established it is used to derive
theory yields the result that there is a solution, new qualitative results from the assumptions by
it has virtually nothing to say about how one a process of deduction. Overall, the mode!
should play the game. And yet chess is a provides well-reasoned arguments by which one
remarkably simple game by comparison with, can proceed from the assumptions to the con-
say, the Polaroid-Kodak battle. At least in chess clusions. Understanding why the results obtain,
there is no asymmetric situation, the potential i.e. how the model 'works', is of primary interest.
actions are always well-defined, it is clear whose That understanding is what provides the 'insights'
chance it is to move, and, after they have moved, which are the final outputs of the endeavor.
what their move was, and so on. The Cournot model provides a good example of
the insights that can be gained from metaphorical
models. For example, the model demonstrates
THE ROLE FOR GAME THEORETIC two important features of noncooperative duopoly
MODELING IN STRATEGIC behavior: why firms arc unable to collude
MANAGEMENT: A METAPHORICAL perfectly in a one-period setting, and why they
APPROACH are able to earn higher profits than if there were
many symmetric firms in the industry.--'
Microeconomic mathematical modeling as
The model also illustrates why a first-mover
metaphor
advantage might be important. In particular, if
The rather negative view of the usefulness of firm 1 moves first (the 'Stackelberg' version of
game-theoretic modeling in strategic management this game), it produces more and earns higher
in the previous section results from attempting to profits than in the simultaneous move version.-^"*
give game-theoretic models a literal interpretation
such as mathematical modeling plays in "manage-
-' If the firms 'agreed' in preplay communication lo each
ment science' {or engineering) applications. While produce (a-c)/4, hall" of the monopoly outcome, each would
those models are similar in form to models of have an incentive to renege on the agreement when il aclually
the microeconomic variety, however, they are eame to choosing its produelion level, since from (2) a lirms
best-response lo (a-c)/4 is .1(a-c)/8. The same reasoning
quite different in their objectives. explains why profits fall as ihc number of firms in the industry
In most models in management science the rises. Consider breaking lirm 2 Inui lirms 2 and 3. If lirm I
produced its Cournot output of (a-e)/3 as before, firms 2
goal is to provide an algorithm which, when data and 3. instead of behaving as a monopolist on the 'piece' of
are fed in as inputs, will produce the answer to demand remaining for them and producing (a c)/?. they
some management problem (how to schedule would compete like duopolists and would produce more in
total than firm 2 alone would have.
^•' Suppose, for example, ihat we modify ihe timing of the
original game and assume instead that firm 1 gets to produce
" As an exact predictive model of duopoly, Coumol has its output and send it to market before firm 2 does (and that
many shoricomings. The ciuatitity-setting assumption does firm 2 observes how much firm 1 has produced before it
not mirror most actual settings in which price tends to he must make its own output decision). Since firm 2 knows firm
the variable thai lirms compete wiih, rather ihan quantities. l's output choice when it makes its output decisit)n. ils output
(Although Kreps and Scheinkman (198.1) have shown thai in choice requires no conjecture about what firm I "will do .
some cases the Cournoi model ean he inlcrpreled as a two Its optimization problem is to choose q^ to maximize Uz =
stage model in which the Hrms lirst chouse capacities and {a-q|-q,-c)q,. where now q, is firm I's aatial output. The
ihen choose prices.) Moreover, the model lacks the temporal solution to this problem is that firm 2 produces its
nature of actual competilion. best-response to q,, i.e. q> = (a-q,-c)/2. For its part.
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 127

The reason is that firm 1 can credibly commit to underlying assumptions carefully and explicitly,
a larger output than in the simultaneous move it is easier for the reader to pinpoint what
game when it physically makes its production s/he likes or dislikes about the model, if
decision before firm 2 does. the assumptions are unpalatable so are the
propositions which flow from them. And if the
proposition is unpalatable or unintuitive, the
The case for mathematical modeling of the model provides an audit trail to help point out
microeconomic variety what unreasonable assumption(s) is responsible.
Despite the potential for 'insight-oriented' math- This constant external auditing of the inner
ematical modeling, in strategic management workings of the model and its underlying premises
almost ail development of theory has been via provide strong incentives for authors to build
broad conceptual frameworks, verbally reasoned their models on solid (and palatable) foundations.
arguments, or 'models' of the boxes-and-arrows The second important attribute of formal
kind. Some of this, such as the conceptual modeling is that it is a methodology that is
framework captured in Porter's (1980) 5-forces capable of creating novel insights. These insights
model has been both influential and useful. are often unforseen and sometimes surprising.
However, as Montgomery, Wernerfelt, and They may even seem unintuitive. However, the
Balakrishnan (1989) argue, 'many strategy con- audit trail that the methodology creates enables
tent publications suffer from serious short- one to trace the logic of the argument and reveal
comings' on the theory development side. Those whether the 'surprise' is due to an implausible
authors make an appeal for 'well-reasoned theory' assumption (or assumptions interacting in
but stop short of calling for mathematical implausible ways) or to a feature of the 'story'
modeling. Indeed the examples which they cite being woven which the author did not realize
with satisfaction do not utilize mathematical was there. This virtue of formal modeling stands
modeling but instead proceed by verbal argument. in contrast to 'models' of the boxes-and-arrows
Of course, mathematical modeling is not variety which have no built-in capacity for going
necessary for careful reasoning and the central beyond a mere description of the model itself.
arguments in mathematically derived propositions A third major advantage of formal modeling
can generally be verbally explained in 'well- is that it provides a common language that allows
reasoned' prose. Moreover, formal modeling is related results to be compared, and new results
very costly to both authors and readers in terms to be built on the foundations laid by earlier
of the overhead it imposes. models. It thus provides a basis for cumulative
However, formal modeling has three very learning.
powerful attributes. The first of these is that it For these reasons modeling has proved very
provides an 'audit trail'^'' that allows one to effective in advancing microeconomic theory
distinguish between groundless assertions and (including many fields closely related to strategic
logical propositions. By laying out a set of management) and holds out considerable promise
assumptions and deriving the qualitative prop- for development of theory in strategic manage-
osition of interest from them, the author provides ment as well.
the detailed logic that underlies the assertions.
There is no ambiguity in such a setting about
Game-theoretic modeling
what it means to be 'well-reasoned' and both the
reader and the author can probe the robustness If one accepts the virtues of mathematical
of the results with respect to changes in the modeling of the microeconomics variety, it does
assumptions. not follow that one should embrace game-
Perhaps more importantly, by laying out the theoretic modeling. Yet in strategic management,
game-theoretic modeling is likely to constitute a
knowing that firm 2 will respond according to its best- very high fraction of all 'microeconomic style'
response function, firm 1 choose qi to maximize it, = modeling.
|a-(a-q,-c)/2-c|q|. This maximization problem has the The reason has to do with the nature of the
solution q, = {a-c)/2.
" I am grateful lo Mark Wolfson for the accountant's beast. Game-theoretic modeling is the appropri-
terminology. ate tool when studying strategic interactions
128 G. Saloner
between agents with differing goals. This, of formulas that made it possible to map consumer
course, is precisely what characterizes many specifications into list prices, to announce that it
interesting strategic management issues.-^ would sell to all customers at a specified discount
Two examples illustrate the necessity of stra- off those list prices, and to commit to a
tegic thinking in situations where strategic interac- most-favored-customer policy through which any
tions are of the essence. The first, again, is the customer who after purchasing from GE learned
Cournot model. In order to act sensibly a firm that GE had later sold similar equipment at a
must think about what its rival is going to do. lower price, would be reimbursed the difference.^"
Whether or not one accepts the 'solution' to the This new pricing policy had the effect, within
problem that game theory offers, if one concedes about a year, of ending the deep discounting that
that the duopolists are attempting to maximize had characterized the market previously.
profits, one must accept the 'strategic thinking' To effectively formulate a new pricing policy
that characterizes game-theoretic analyses. GE had to take into account how Westinghouse
The second, is a case that is often taught in would respond. They thus had to put themselves
MBA strategic management classes. General in Westinghouse's shoes and predict how West-
Electric (GE) vs. Westinghouse in Large Turbine inghouse would read the signals contained in any
Generators.~^ That case examines the sharp price change in GE's policy. The policy GE adopted
discounting that plagued the highly concentrated was successful because Westinghouse (ultimately)
large turbine generator market in the early 1960s. understood, as GE correctly predicted they
The difficulty that GE had. as the dominant firm, would, that the standardized pricing book and
in stabilizing prices could be attributed to a commitment to a fixed discount provided an
number of market-specific factors.-" The result opportunity to coordinate pricing.-"' The issues
in a very price sensitive market was that it was that GE had to consider have to do with the
difficult for the firms to achieve a 'mutual essence of game-theoretic models.
understanding' as to what prices should prevail
and to ascertain whether one's rival had 'cheated'
by undercutting those prices. The firms gave in The rationality assumption in metaphorical
to the unilateral temptation to give discounts off models
list prices in order to win sales, leading to a In the previous subsection we stressed the fact
steady erosion in prices. that many of the situations of interest in strategic
GE's response to this 'problem' was, inter alia. management involve strategic interactions among
to produce a pricing book with simplified pricing rivals and therefore require game-theoretic mod-
eling if microeconomic modeling is to be used at
all. Just because it is the appropriate tool doesn't
mean that one has to like it, however, and those
^'' A second reason why most microeconomic style modeling
in strategic managemeni Is likely to he game-theoretic is thai who are skeptical about the degree of rationality
game-theoretic modeling has proven to be useful in a very required to reach the proffered 'insights' might
broad class of settings, including many for which game-theory balk at employing microeconomic modeling at
is not essential to the analysis. An example is the well-known
signaling model due lo Spence (1974). In Spence's original all.
analysis there is a competilive labor market and the analysis Happily, many of the insights that one obtains
is carried out without any of the trappings of gamc-lhcory.
Now. however, models of what lype tetid to be framed in from game-theoretic models do not require an
the language of game-theory: game theory is emerging as extreme degree of rationality. For example, while
the lingua franca of microeeonomic modeling. The reason the implications of the Cournot model do require
for this is probably related to the appealing audit trail
properties of explicitly game theoretic models. As a result, logical reasoning, the logical reasoning required
game theory is approaching the status of calculus in ihe is far more elementary than the infinite regress
curricula of graduate departments of economics, being
required of all students, wiih courses in elementary game
theory often being offered in the first semester of study.
" The '(A) • part of the case is presented in Porter (1983).
^''These include the fad that, at least for sales to private
utilities, sales were made through confidential negotiations -"The details of GE's pricing policy is discussed in the B'
and that the product sold was not standard but rather bids part of the case. Harvard Business School, 1-380-129.
were made to satisfy the idiosyncratic specificmions set by "'The logie behind the GE pricing policy was not lost on
buyers. ihe Justice Department who concluded that il violated the
antitrust laws. (See part (C) of the case).
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 129

of the if I believe that you believe that I believe the degree of modeling discretion is so significant
. . .' type of reasoning suggests is required. that a model can be devised to explain almost
In order to demonstrate that the collusive any fact.
equilibrium is not sustainable in a one-shot game, The second way in which the problem of
for example, all that one has to accept is that diffuse predictions arises is via multiple equilibria.
either firm will perceive that it can profit by A wide range of equilibrium behavior may be
unilaterally deviating. To appreciate that there consistent with the same underlying set of
is a first-mover advantage if one of the firm basic assumptions. TTiis is especially true of
chooses its output before the other (the Stackel- supergames, which consider infinitely repeated
berg game), one simply has to realize that a firm interactions, where multiplicity of equilibria is
can obtain an advantage by committing itself to the focus of the Folk Theorem. We briefly
a course of action and thereby forcing its rival consider each of these issues below.
to respond to a fact of life.
There is a broad class of useful models for
Multiple equilibria
which the degree of rationality is not very
extreme. These are 'two stage" models where the The issue of multiple equilibria is of some
primary focus is on just one action. Examples of importance since we shall argue below that one
this type include how much capacity a firm facing of the criteria for choosing among competing
potential entry should install and how it should models is to consider how their predictions about
price its product, how many products a first- how a particular variable changes as others
mover should have in its product line, whether change (comparative statics). For example, the
firms should make their products compatible or Cournot model predicts that if firm Ts costs go
incompatible, how firms should position their up, firm l's output will fall and by more than
products, and so on. In the first stage of these firm 2's output will rise. In a model in which
models, the action of primary interest is taken there are multiple equilibria, however, such a
and in the second, the firms compete. The issue thought experiment is impossible without also
of interest is typically how the actions taken in specifying which equilibrium to 'look at' as the
the first stage affect competition in the second. variable of interest changes.
Often the Cournot model is used as the model Recently game theory itself has been of some
of second-stage competition. However, only very help in models with asymmetric information by
broad qualitative features of the Cournot mode! providing refinements to the Nash equilibrium
are drawn upon. Thus, in these models, whether concept that help the modeler in selecting among
firms would replicate the Cournot outcome in equilibria.-" In supergames, however, selection
the Cournot setting (the question in the prior among equilibria is often ad hoc. For example,
section) is virtually irrelevant: only its qualitative
sometimes an equilibrium seems particularly
features matter. 'focal'. At other times, preplay communication
would significantly reduce the number of equilib-
ria.
The explanatory power of metaphorical models
In many of the supergame applications of
As in theabove two examples of entry deterrence, interest to strategic management, however, the
game-theoretic models have the ability to explain supergame format is selected because it enables
a wide variety of observed behavior. Unfortu- consideration of such issues as cooperation and
nately, they may be capable of generating too reputation. In such cases, such as where one is
broad an array of predictions. There are two attempting to examine the ability of firms to
different ways in which this problem arises. collude over time, one is interested in the extent
The first is what researchers (somewhat glumly) to which the environment limits the ability of
refer to as the Fundamental Theorem of Industrial the firms to cooperate. One is then interested in
Organization. This is the assertion that since the the maximal amount of cooperation that can be
assumptions in metaphorical models are selected sustained without explicit cooperation. It then
by the modeler rather than strictly being dictated
by a physical setting, and since there is such a
rich set of assumptions from which to choose. " See Kreps (1990b) for details.
130 G. Saloner

makes sense to look at the equilibrium in which RATIONALITY AND PROFIT-


the firms do as well as possible. When, in MAXIMIZATION
addition, the firms are symmetric or are able
to make monetary transfers, this narrows the Rationality is sometimes taken to be synonymous
plethora of possible equilibria to just one and with profit-maximization in microeconomic mod-
renders the comparative statics exercise els. Accordingly, to the extent that firms do not
sensible. seek to maximize profits, this is taken to be a
In other cases, some of the equilibria seem limitation of microeconomic modeling. However,
implausible while others are not. In that case the game-theoretic reasoning can be applied even if
model may be incomplete. Examination of what the objective of the firm, or its management, is
gives rise to the implausible equilibria may enable not that of profit-maximization. Indeed, a profit-
the model to be refined by incorporating some maximizing firm may be better off if its manage-
important element of the institutions being ment is not profit-maximizing!
modeled, eliminating the implausible equilibria In the discussion of the Cournot model we
and improving the mode! overall. repeatedly encountered the fact that either firm
In some settings, however, none of the above would value the ability to commit to producing
mechanisms can be called upon to reduce the set a larger output than it 'rationally' would in the
of equilibria and one is left with an 'embarrass- simultaneous move game. We particularly noted
ment of riches'. Yet for some games there just the fact that a firm would like to be able to
is no obvious way that the game 'should" be credibly make the speech to its rival that it was
played. If game theory were somehow to provide committed to producing (a—c)/2 (its Stackelberg
unique predictions in every setting, it would be output).
too powerful for its own good. In such a setting it would be valuable to the
firm's shareholders if the manager responsible
for the output decision was 'irrational' in that he
The fundamental theorem had a preference for producing more than he
The complaint against the 'Fundamental The- would if he were a profit-maximizer. As an
orem' is that it is somehow 'too easy' to come example, the manager might want to maximize
up with explanations for phenomena using the sales revenue. Supposing that the manager is the
tools of game theory. This is a curious complaint. decision-maker in firm 1, he would seek to
It is the role of theory to come up with maximize;
explanations. Some of these are likely to be good
explanations and others not. And the means for R = (a-q,-q2)q,,
telling them apart is similar whether the theory
is generated by game-theoretic modeling vs other yielding the best-response function:
means. However, the fact that the explanation
has been formally modeled at least ensures that qi = (3)
the explanation is internally consistent.
Moreover, modeling provides additional means Comparing (2) and (3) it is evident that the
for telling good explanations apart from bad manager behaves more aggressively than his
ones. First, the audit trail makes it easier profit-maximizing counterpart. But as discussed
to assess the argument. Second, and more previously, having a manager who behaves in
importantly, in addition to providing the expla- this way may be advantageous to the firm because
nation for the phenomenon of interest, the it effectively 'commits' it to higher outputs which
model typically generates a number of other in turn induces the rival to curtail its own output.
implications, especially of a comparative statics As illustrated in Figure 2, the outcome shifts
nature. This provides a means to put the model from B to B' when the manager's goal shifts
to the test, whether on its surface plausibility or from profit- to sales-maximization. It is easy to
via formal empirical or experimental techniques. show that firm l's profits may be higher at B'
If the corollary implications of the model fail to than at B.
hold then the model must be rejected or at least Thus profit-maximizing shareholders might
modified. have reason to deliberately select a decision-
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 131

make to the worker if management chooses to


implement the proposal, the management will
be reluctant to implement proposals that are
profitable but where the profits do not cover the
additional compensation they must pay the
worker. That is. profit-maximizing senior manage-
ment will be too reluctant to implement projects.
Rotemberg and Saloner (1991) show that this
problem can be overcome by installing senior
management that cares not only about maximizing
profits but also about the welfare of their
employees. Such managers will be more likely
to implement their employee's projects and hence
will earn higher profits than profit-maximizing
managers would! In essence, having nonprofit-
Figure 2. Firtn I as a sales tnaximizer maximizing management commits the organi-
zation to implement the innovative ideas that
employees generate rather than to act opportun-
maker who is not profit-maximizing."*^ Alterna- istically by not implementing them in order to
tively, the shareholders might have an incentive save on incentive compensation.
to provide the manager with incentives that have
the same effect. Thus a firm that can credibly
commit to rewarding its manager based on some
combination of profits and sales (instead of FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE
simply profits) might induce more aggressive
behavior in the manager, and consequently, The preceding has focused on the role of
higher profits.^' game-theoretic modeling in producing theoretical
Similarly, a firm may have an incentive to insights for strategic management. However,
install senior management that is not profit- strategic management has historically had very
maximizing in order to improve incentives within strong normative and empirical orientations. Can
the organization. As an example, suppose that game-theoretic modeling contribute in those
it is desirable for employees to innovate and that areas?
to do this they can exert effort to generate
'proposals' for projects that will enhance profit-
ability. If it is not possible to compensate those Normative role
workers for the effort that they expend in It was argued above that the prospects are slim
researching these proposals (because such effort for using game-theoretic models as mechanisms
is not observable and hence not contractible) and for simulating a managerial situation and provid-
if the 'quality' of a proposal is too subjective ing precise prescriptions for managerial action as
to base compensation on. the only monetary in a 'management science' type model.
incentive the management can provide is to This critique of the direct applicability of game-
reward employees when they generate profitable theoretic models does not mean that they are
proposals that are in fact implemented. normatively irrelevant, however. Only by having
However, the implementation decision itself is a good understanding of how its world works
typically in the hands of the senior management. can a firm's management understand the reper-
Given the ex post compensation that they must cussions of their own actions and hence how they
should behave. The powerful descriptive feature
" Sales maximizing manager's are not the only one's that of models and their normative relevance are
might enhance the firm's performance. A manager with a closely related. The normative role for strategic
passion for market share or for operating near capacity management here is to provide management with
(provided capacity is not too large) ean have similar results.
-^' See Fershtman and Judd (1987) for a model along these a broad qualitative understanding of the effects
lines. of their actions and to ensure that the broad
132 G. Saloner

qualitative prescriptions can be given firm foun- purchase the rival on better terms. Both of these
dations. qualitative features are examined in Burns' (1986)
empirical investigation of the acquisitions by the
American Tobacco Company. He finds that
Empirical role 'alleged predation significantly lowered the acqui-
Significant difficulties arise in directly testing sition costs of the tobacco trust both for asserted
many of the game-theoretic models that have victims and, through reputation effects, for
been developed in industrial organization. One competitors that sold out peacefully" (p. 286).
reason is that the models tend to be rather Moreover, the effects were significant in magni-
specific in that the behavior that emerges in tude: "The estimated direct savings range up to
equilibrium depends on the precise state of the 60 percent of what some targets would have cost
environment that obtains. In empirical work it if they had not been preyed on, and the
is difficult to find large samples of firms that face trust's reputation produced an additional discount
exactly the kinds of environments envisaged by averaging 25 percent' (p. 289).
the models. A second reason pertains to models In addition to directly examining the central
with asymmetric information, such as the qualitative predictions of models as in these
Milgrom-Roberts (1982a) limit pricing model. examples, as discussed above, hypotheses are
The chief implication of that model is that low- often generated from the comparative statics of
cost incumbents will charge less than high- the model. For example, in a supergame-theoretic
cost ones and thereby successfully deter entry. model Rotemberg and Saloner (1986) show that
Unfortunately, the cost structure of the firm must an implicitly colluding oligopoly might find it
be unobservable to the researcher since if it most difficult to collude when demand is at its
were observable by the researcher it would be strongest because the incentive for a firm to
observable by the potential entrant and the model cheat is greatest then. A corollary of that analysis
would not apply. is that price-cost margins should be lower for
Despite the difficulty that is often encountered such firms when demand is high, so that measured
in directly testing game-theoretic models, they price-cost margins should be countercyclical.
have had a tremendous impact on empirical Empirical evidence, much of it supportive of this
research in industrial organization, and hold out hypothesis, has been produced by Rotemberg
similar prospects for strategic management. As and Saloner (1986). Domowitz, Hubbard and
Bresnahan and Schmalensee write: 'The theoreti- Petersen (1987), and Rotemberg and Woodford
cal developments that began in the 1970s prod- (1989, 1991).
uced a rich set of hypotheses, along with a The second role that game-theoretic modeling
powerful set of modeling techniques . . . (1987: plays in empirical work is in generating and testing
374)". structural models. These empirical investigations
This quote is suggestive of two different roles focus on a particular industry over time. Typieally
that game-theoretical modeling plays in empirical demand, costs, and behavior are estimated
work. The first is in developing and refining simultaneously, and the relationships between
hypotheses for reduced form empirical models. the various parameters to be estimated arc
Here the specific structural characteristics of the dictated by oligopoly theory. While detailed
models are not used, but instead the empirical game-theoretic models underlie these structural
investigation examines whether the data are models, the estimation relies on the broad
consistent with the broad qualitative features. qualitative features, especially the relationships
As an example, consider the issue of predatory among the degree of collusion, price-cost mar-
pricing discussed in the previous section. The gins, and demand elasticities, that hold at
models discussed there suggest that a firm that equilibrium, and the comparative static properties
has developed a reputation for predatory behavior of those relationships.
should find it easier to drive rivals out than firms Two of the best examples of this style of work
with no such reputation. Furthermore, Saloner are the papers by Porter (1983) and Bresnahan
(1987), shows that a firm may have an incentive (1987). Porter (1983) uses a switching regression
to predatory price against a rival in anticipation model to estimate periods of cooperation and
of a merger with that rival to enable it to reversion in the railroad cartel of the 1880s. The
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 133

pattern of behavior estimated by the model is assumed in each is within the realm of plausibility.
consistent with that predicted by the Green and That judgement must, however, be made on a
Porter (1984) mode! and the estimated price-cost case-by-case basis. Thus one might well be willing
margins during periods of collusion are consistent to accept the conclusions of game-theoretic
with the exercise of considerable market power. reasoning in some settings and not in others.
Bresnahan (1987) uses a model of product We have argued that one ought to be relatively
differentiation to estimate the degree of collusion more comfortable with the predictions of game-
among US auto manufacturers from 1954 to theoretic analyses in literal models, all else equal,
1956. He finds that the years 1954 and 1956 when the prediction is robust to small mistakes
were collusive while 1955 was competitive. His by the players, when the players have some
structural estimation allows him to estimate experience with the decisions being analyzed, or
price-cost margins during periods of collusion when the players have some basis on which to
and competition for different car models. form beliefs about what their rivals will do
There has been a tendency among some (whether because there has been preplay com-
observers to stress some of the difficulties in munication, or because they have had opportuni-
directly testing some game-theoretic models. ties to observe each others' behavior in the past).
However, the renaissance in empirical work that However, we have argued that there is likely
has followed the theoretical developments has to be a limited role for literal game-theoretic
been remarkable and while the pace of develop- models. In particular, game-theoretic models
ment of theory within industrial organization have not proven very useful, nor are they
seems to be slowing, "the new empirical industrial likely to. for providing precise prescriptions for
organization" continues apace.^'' managerial behavior. Rather, the role of game-
theoretic modeling is to produce insights from
well-reasoned models. That is, the virtues of
CONCLUSIONS game-theoretic modeling have as much to do
with the virtues of modeling as with the virtues
When small numbers of rival compete, a sensible of the game-theoretic approach.
analysis of what a firm should do involves a These virtues of formal modeling are, inter
careful assessment of what its rivals' actions are a/(fl. that it provides an 'audit trail' that documents
likely to be. A formal analysis of such situations that a coherent explanation for the phenomenon
therefore requires assumptions about how rivals under study can be given; it provides a system
behave. Game theory proceeds, for the most of logic to root out the Haw in the reasoning in
part, by assuming that a!l the rivals behave incorrect analyses (as in the case of the maintained
rationally. output hypothesis); that it is a methodology
We have argued that in order to evaluate game- capable of generating new insights (inciuding
theoretic modeling it is important to consider the 'surprises'), and that it provides a common
goals of the analysis. We have argued that one's language which allows related results lo be
appraisal of the rationality assumption and of the compared, and new results to be built on the
usefulness of the models depends on whether foundations laid by earlier models.
one takes a literal or metaphorical view of What does the field have to look forward to
microeconomic style modeling. if there is indeed a large increase in the 'domestic'
Taking the literal view, comparing the role of production of game-theoretic modeling in stra-
the rationality assumption in the Cournot game tegic management? If experience in industrial
and in the rationality game considered in the organization is any indicator, the cumulative
introduction leads to quite different impressions. output is likely to be more in the way of a mosaic
The degree of rationality assumed in the latter with many papers eaeh contributing a small piece
is clearly much greater than in the former. of the puzzle than in the way of broad generalizing
Reasonable people might reach different con- theory. That is, results are more in the way of
clusions about whether the degree of rationality describing what happens in particular circum-
stances rather than on describing behavior that
*•* See Bresnahan (1989) for a detailed discussion of Ihe "new will occur in all. or even in a very broad variety,
empirical Industrial Organization'. of situations. As theory develops, more and more
134 G. Saloner
is learned about the limits of particular models analysis using these tools. These include the
and the circumstances under which their results study of joint ventures and strategic alliances as
hold. Pieces of the mosaic are replaced by others, well as issues relating to the scope of the firm.
and empty spots are filled in. Some, such as The latter includes optima! diversification policy
Fisher (1989) lament the scale of the mosaic. as well as questions such as why firms often set
However, the large scale is due to the enormous narrow strategic objectives for themselves (see
variability of the settings and decisions that senior Mintzberg, 1987).
management most confront. The enormous scope A related set of issues are raised by the
of those settings requires richly textured theory. resource-based view of the firm (Penrose, 1959;
It is the task of the scholars in the field to Wernerfelt 1984). Which resources and core
develop and maintain this richly textured mosaic, competencies are worth developing depends, in
to contribute the pieces to it, and to haggle over part, on the extent to which the firm is able to
which ones belong and how they fit. While it is capture the rents from them. It also depends on
time-consuming, this approach is also cumulative. the firm's ability to commit itself to adequately
Rather than haphazardly generating a myriad rewarding those individuals in the firm who must
of disconnected and conflicting theories, eaeh put forth the effort to develop those resources
starting from scratch, in this approach each and competencies. How the implicit and explicit
contribution builds upon those of its predecessors. contractual relationships that the firm can enter
This task is both theoretical and empirical. into with its employees and the nature of rent-
Theory provides both hypotheses to test and sharing within the firm influence the development
specific structural models in which to test them. of the resource base of the firm are important
Empirical results, in turn, provide evidence on topics that may be amenable to contract-theoretic
the limits, applicability, and failures of the theory, modeling.
pointing to deficiencies in the mosaic and In the finaly analysis, the proof of the pudding
presenting new challenges to theory. is in the eating. Only by applying game-theoretic
As it develops, each part of the mosaic provides modeling to issues in strategic management will
understanding of some aspect of the business we be able to assess its usefulness to the field.
environment which, in turn, enables managers Hopefully the next time a conference of this
to make sensible decisions. Thus, while not nature is convened the debate over the virtues of
narrowly prescriptive, as in literal models, meta- game-theoretic modeling in strategic management
phorical models nonetheless are normatively will be concrete rather than merely philosophical.
useful.
The program being called for in this paper is
not the continued development of game-theoretic
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
modeling in industrial organization for export to
strategie management. Rather it is the develop-
ment, within strategic management, of its own I thank Robert Burgelman, J. Michael Harrison,
mosaic: the rigorous development of theory on Jeffrey Pfeffer. John Roberts. Julio Rotemberg,
topics central to strategic management by scholars Richard Rumelt, Dan Schendel, Birger Werner-
in strategic management. felt and conference participants at the Conference
As far as subject matter is concerned, there on 'Fundamental Issues in Strategy: A Research
are topics to be addressed in both the internal Agenda for the 1990s', Napa, California, for
and external parts of strategie management. On comments and suggestions.
the external side, for example, a topic that has
received a huge amount of attention in the
strategy literature but little formal modeling is REFERENCES
the issue of strategic groups (see Porter, 1980).
On the internal side, many issues are related Bonanno, G. and J, Vickers. 'Vertical separation'.
to the growing body of work in 'contract theory". Journal of Industrial Economics, 36, March 1988.
pp. 257-266.
In particular, questions relating to the appropriate Bolton. P. and M. D. Whinston. 'Incomplete contracts,
boundaries of the firm which are central to vertical integration, and supply assurance'. Harvard
strategic management may be amenable to University, mimeo. December 1989.
Modeling, Game Theory and Strategic Management 135
Bresnahan, T. F. 'Competition and collusion in the on Positive Political Economy, Cambridge. Cam-
American automobile industry: The I95.'i price war". bridge University Press. 1990a, pp. 9()-143.
Journal of Industrial Economics, 35. June 1987. pp. Kreps, D. M. A Course in Microeconomic Theory,
457-482. Princeton University Press, Princeton. NJ, 1990b.
Bresnahan, T. F. "Empirical studies of structure and Kreps, D. M. and J. A. Scheinkman. 'Quantity
performance". In R. Schmalensee and R, Willig precommitment and Bertrand competition yield
(eds.). Handbook of Industrial Organization. Chap- Cournot outcomes". Bell Journal of Economics. 14,
ter 17, North Holland, New York, 1989, pp. Autumn 1983, p. 326-337.
1011-1058. Kreps, D. M. and A. M. Spence. 'Modelling the
Bresnahan, T. F. and R. Schmalensee. 'The empirical role of history in industrial organization and
renaissance in industrial economics: An overview". competition". In G. Feiwel (ed.). Contemporary
Journal of Industrial Economics, 35, 1987. pp. Issues in Modern Microeconomics. Macmillan,
371-377. London. 1984. pp. 340-378,
Burns, M. 'Predatory pricing and acquisition cost of Kreps, D.. P. Milgrom. J. Roberts and R. Wilson.
competitors'. Journal of Political Economy, 94, 'Rational cooperation in the finitely-re pea ted pris-
1986. pp. 286-296. oners" dilemma". Journal of Economic Theory, 27,
Camerer. C. F. 'How much game theory is good for 1982, pp, 245-252.
strategy research?' Wharton School, mimeo, 1991, Kreps. D. and R. Wilson, 'Reputation and imperfect
Cooper. R., D. V. DeJong. R. Forsythe and T. W. information". Journal of Economic Theory, 27.
Ross. 'Communication in the battle of the sexes 1982. pp. 253-279.
game: Some experimental results". Rand Journal of Lieberman, M, and D. Montgomery. "First-mover
'Economics, 20, Winter 1989. pp. 568-587. advantages'. Strategic Management Journal, 9. 1988,
Coughlin. A. and B. Wernerfelt. 'Competition and pp. 41-58.
cooperation in marketing channel choice; Theory Moorthy, K. S. 'Strategic decentralization in channels',
and application". Marketing Science. 4, Spring 1988, Marketing Science, forthcoming.
pp. 11(V129. Montgomery, C. A.. B. Wernerfelt and S. Balakrish-
Dixit. A. The role of investment in entry deterrence". nan. "Strategy content and the research process:
Economic Journal. 90. 1980. pp. 95-106. A critique and summary". Strategic Management
Domowitz, I., R. G. Hubbard and B. C. Petersen, Journal. 10. 1989. pp. 189-197.
•Oligopoly supergames: Some empirical evidence Milgrom, P, and J, Roberts. 'Limit pricing under
on prices and margins". Journal of Industrial incomplete information', Econometrica, 50, March
Economics, 35. June 1987, pp. 379-398. 1982a, pp. 443-460.
Farrell, J. 'Cheap talk, coordination, and entry". Rand Milgrom. P, and J, Roberts. "Predation. reputation,
Journal of Economics, 18, 1987. pp. 34-39. and entry deterrence". Jotirnal of Economic Theory,
Fershtman. C. and K. Judd. 'Equilibrium incentives 27. 1982b. pp. 280-312.
in oligopoly". American Economic Review, 77. Milgrom, P. and J. Roberts. 'Rationalizability, learning
December 1987, pp. 927-940. and equilibrium in games with strategic comp-
Fisher, F. M. 'Games economists play: A noncooperat- lementarities'. Econometrica. 58. November 1990,
ive view". Rand Journal of Economics. 20. Spring pp. 1255-1277.
1989, pp. 113-124. Milgrom. P. and J. Roberts. Economic Organization
Fudenberg, D. and J. Tirole. 'A "signal jamming"' and Management, forthcoming.
Theory of Predation'. Rand Journal of Economics, Mintzberg, H. 'The Strategy Concept IL Another look
17. 1986, pp. 366-376. at why organizations need strategies". In G.
Green. E. J. and R. H. Porter. 'Noncooperative R. Carroll and D, Vogel (eds). Organizational
collusion under imperfect information'. Econo- Aproaches to Strategv, Ballinger, Cambridge. MA,
metrica, 52, January 1984, pp. 87-100. 1987. pp. 21-28.
Grossman, S. and O. Hart. The costs and benefits Ordover. J. A., G. Saloner and S. C. Salop.
of ownership: A theory of vertical and lateral 'Equilibrium vertical foreclosure". American Eco-
integration". Journal of Political Economy, 94, nomic Review, 80. March 1990. pp. 127-142.
August 1986, pp. 691-719. Penrose. E. G. The Theory of the Growth of the Firm,
Hart, O. and J. Tirole. 'Vertical integration and Wiley, New York. 1959,
market foreclosure', Brookings Papers in Economic Porter. M. E. Competitive Strategy. Free Press. New
Activity: Microeconomics, forthcoming. York. 1980,
Holt, C. A. "An experimental test of the consistent- Porter. M. E. Cases in Competitive Strategy, Free
conjectures hypothesis', American Economic Press. New York. 1983.
Review, 75, June 1985, pp. 314-325. Porter. R. H. "A study of cartel stability: The Joint
Jensen. M. 'Agency costs of free cash flow, corporate Executive Committee, 1980-86'. Bell Journal of
finance and takeovers", American Economic Review, Economics. 14. Autumn 1983. pp, 301-314.
76. 1986, pp. 323-329. Rotemberg. J. J. and G. Saloner, 'A Supergame-
Judd, K. 'Credible spatial competition". Rand Journal theoretic model of price-wars during bot^ms',
of Economics, 16, Summer 1985. pp. 153-166. American Economic Review, 76, June 1986. pp.
Kreps, D. M. Corporate culture and economic theory". 390-407.
In J. Alte and K. Shepsle (eds). Rational Perspectives Rotemberg, J. and G. Saloner. 'Collusive price
G. Saloner
leadership'. Journal of Industrial Economics, 34, Schmalensee, R. 'Entry deterrence in the ready-to-
September 1990a, pp. 9.3-111. eat breakfast cereal industry'. Bell Journal of
Rotemberg. J. and G, Saloner. 'Benefits of narrow Economics, 9, Autumn 1978. pp. 305-327.
business strategies', 1990b, mimeo. Sehmalensee, R. "Product differentiation advantages
Rotemberg, J. and G. Saloner. 'Leadership style and of pioneering brands", American Economic Review.
incentives', Stanford GSB Working Paper 1153, 1991. 72, June 1982. pp. 349-365.
Rotemberg. J. and M. Woodford. 'Oligopolistic pricing Schmalensee. R. and R, D. Willig (eds). Handbook
and the effects of aggregate demand on economic of Industrial Organization. North Holland. New
activity". NBER Working Paper No. 3206, Cam- York. 1989.
bridge, MA. December 1989. Shapiro, C. 'The theory of business strategy". Rand
Rotemberg. J. and M, Woodford. 'Markups and the Journal of Economics, 20, Spring 1989. pp. 125-137.
business cycle". MIT mimeo, 1991. Spenee, A. M. Market Signaling. Harvard University
Rumelt, R., D. Schendel and D. Teece, 'Fundamental Press. Cambridge, MA, 1974,
issues in strategy: A research agenda for the 1990s'. Spence. A. M. 'The learning curve and competition".
January 28. 1990, mimeo. Bell Journal of Economics, 12. Spring 1981, pp.
Saloner. G. 'Predation. mergers and incomplete 49-70.
information". Rand Journal of Economics, 18. Spence. A. M, 'Entry, capacity, investment, and
Summer 1987. pp. 165-186. oligopolistic pricing". Bell Journal of Economics, 8.
Saloner, G. 'Essays on Information Transmission 1977. pp. 534-544.
Under Uncertainty'. Unpublished PhD Disser- Tirole, J. The Theory of Industrial Organization, MIT
tation. Stanford University. 1982, Press, Cambridge. MA, 1990.
Saloner. G, 'Game theory and strategic management: Weigelt, K. and C. Camerer, "Reputation and eorpor-
Contributions, applications and limitations'. In ate strategy: Review of recent theory and appli-
R. Rumelt. D. Schendel and D. Teece (eds.). cations". Strategic Management Journal, 9, 19S8.
Fundamental Issues in Strategic Research, Harvard pp. 443-454.
Business Scbool Press, Cambridge, MA, forth- Wernerfelt. B. 'A resource-based view of the firm".
coming 1992. ' Strategic Management Journal, 5, 1984, pp. 171-180.

You might also like