You are on page 1of 13

Other Publication» of the COR N E LIO FABRO

Cornelio Fabro Cultural Project


Essential Thinker
I'hilosophcr of' l3ei ng and f<
) Freedom

Introduction to Cornelio Fabro


8): I:lvio C. Fontana
Acts of the Fabro Symposium
Cotnmernorating 20 Years Since Fabro's Death
Vol. I: Selected Articles on Metaphysics and Participation
Thc C:athnlic University of An>erica
IVtth Introd»ctton b)' John I. IVippel
April 1 — 2, 2016
Vol. 9: God: An Introduction to Problems in Theology
IVith Introduction h? hlichael J. I?odds

FC? KTH(:C?MI I» Cx.

Vol. 2: Selected Articles on S0ren Kierkcgaard


IVi th Introduction fry' Josh»a Fut nal

Vol. 3: Sclccted Articles on Atheism «nd Freedom

Vol. 19: Introduction to St. 'I'homas


F.dited by
Introduction to Seren Kierkcgaard
Nathaniel Dreyer
Cornelio Fabro CI,Iltwral Project

S TUDI A FA B R I A N A

Volume 1
Contents

Preface
Contributors
Abbreviations xltt

Introduction to Cornclio Fabro


.'<)athani el Orever

Jounney through thc Destiny of Being


Gianlaca Ti ontbini
Edited by the Cornclio I-'abro Cultural Project
of' thc Institute of the Incarnate v<'ord
F ather Cornelio Fabro: Stigmatine -- Devotee of Ilis Founder 2 3
Joseph C, Henchey
Cover Design
Q 2017 by IVE Press, Chillum. iVID Cornelio Fabro on Patticipation and Aquinas's Oua).ta Via 41
Insti:ute of thc Incarnate KVord, Inc,
John F. 8'ippel
All rights reserved
I abro's Double Participation and 67
C<~ 2017 by Cornclio I'abro Cultural Project
All rights reserved Aquinas's Double Exemplarism
Grego)3' T. Ooolan

I..'-mail: I'abroproject'<icorncliofabro.org
v Cornelio I abro on Supernatural Participations 89
~vwn.conse! iofabro.org Jason A. h li tchell
Ivy <v. I vcpress. ot'g
Thc Impact of Sr)ren Kierkegaard 117
on thc Thought of Cornclio Fabro
ISI3%'-10: I-939018-7g-I Joshtla Ear)tal
ISBN-13: 97II- I-9390111-7II-6
God in Exile: An Introduction to 137
Library of Congress Control Number: 2017947991
Cornelio Fabro's Appraisal of Modern Thought
Printed in the t.:nited States ol'America Patricia Pintaclo
Fabro's Double Participation and
AcIuinas's Double Exemplarism

(rid.E(i<.)R.Y 'l'. 1)(DOLAN, PhD


I fr<' (;<itltttltr I nivetstty «fi l ut('pic<i
Ass<i<tat<' I>>'<f<s><)r
> of Pft t'f<t<t>phy

or students of Thomas Aquinas, Cornclio Fabr<) is v cll known t'or


his thorough examinations of Thomas's metaphysical doctrine of
participation. Less well known, however, is Fabro's occasional
reference to a doppia, or double, participation of thc creature in thc
divine: one for its essence, the other for its act of existing (e~se).' Looking
at such statements, Jan A. Acrtsen and Rudi tc Vcl<le have scen I abro
as affirming tv o lines of so-called "transccn<lcntal participation" and
consequently as affirming thc problematic view of a double creation for
a single creature. More recently, Jason A. Mitchell has del'ended I:abro
against the critiqucs of'these scholars, arguing that despite his language
Fabro in fact presents only a single line of such participation and hence
does not affirm a double creation.
In this paper, I w i l l e x a mine Fabro's references to ' d o u ble
participation" by looking at another related doubling explicitly affirmed
by Thomas Aquinas: double cxemplarism. l.rom his earliest writings,
Thomas drav s a distinction between two kinds ot divine exentplarism:
one of thc divine ideas and thc other of the divine nature. As I will shov,
despite affirming thi» double cxemplarism — or, morc precisely, because

5< e > 1!I, 31, 1 ' (>,2 >(X I'abru, I <»rr< p<>Z'<'>ir «' '<>><r)rr<>,2' ' cd.. Opere « >rnnlctc ! ');Set>n>:
kDI VI , 2nll>), 24H, 3 9, 43'), 4')(>, 5')1 — 595, (>41. 1>abc<> ala<> urea the tern> r>)<p<i'><when
at>' aint <> u: el<>ub'.c particinati<>n. Scc I'z>renp«Z.'<»er <»u «i>r<i, 379, 55', =))1

67
Gregory T. Doolan
Fabro 's Double Participation and Aquinas's Double Eresnplartsnt

of the way he affirms it — Thomas presents only a single line of what


is, as it were, 'to take a part' [partem capereJ." Going beyond this
Fabro would term "transcendental participation." Moreover, like Mitchell, etymological account, he explains that when something receives in a
I will argue that Fabro in fact follows Thomas on this point, a reading that
particular way what belongs to another in a universal way, the former is
can be strengthened through a careful consideration of what Thomas's
said toparticipate in what belongs to the latter.' Thomas then proceeds,
doctrine of double exemplarism entails.
without providing any technical names, to present three different modes,
What follows, therefore, will be less an interpretation of Thomas in or kinds, of participation.
light of Fabro than an interpretation of Fabro in light of Thomas, To this As regards the first mode, he simply provides two examples:man
end, my paper will have four parts: The first part will look at Fabro's
participates inanimal, and Socrates in titan.' Although Thomas docs not
language of double participation to see how he applies it. The second
tell us as much, we can infer &om these examples that any species can
part will present Thomas's account of a twofold divine exemplarism, be said to participate in its genus and any individual in its species,
along with both Fabro's reading of this account as well as the criticisms because neither participant has the intelligible content(ratio) of what it
of that reading raised by Aertsen and te Velde. The third part of my paper
participates, namely, the more universal notion, Thus, this first mode has
will briefly consider the role of the divine ideas in Thomas's doctrine of
traditionally been interpreted by scholars as a logical, or conceptual,
participation, in an effort to show how he adopts an account of double participation rather than a real one.'
exemplarism without affirming double participation, In light of the As regards the second mode of participation, Thomas again merely
foregoing, my paper will conclude in the fourth part with a consideration
provides examples: a subject participates in an accident, and matter
of how Fabro, in turn, could be read as aflirming a single line of
participates in form, Here, again, something receives in a particular way
transcendental participation despite his language of double participation. what another has in a universal way since, as he explains, both substantial
and accidental forms are common according to their ratio but are
1. FABRO S LANGUAGE OF DOUBLE PARTICIPATION determined by their subject.' Unlike the first mode of participation,
however, this one is presented as an ontological, or real, one. In his
To begin to understand what Fabro means by "double participation," examples of both the subject and matter, Thomas presents a participant
we must first situate this phrase in the context of other distinctly
that really participates in the form that it receives, resulting in a real
Fabroistic terms: notably, "transcendental" vs. "predicamental partici- composition between the receiver and the received perfection.
pation" as well as his language of "diremption" and "derivation." With Finally, as regards the third mode of participation, before giving an
the exception of that last term, none of this language is employed as such example, Thomas provides us with an account this time: an effect is
in Thomas's writings on participation; nevertheless, Fabro's language said to participate in its cause, especially, he notes, when the effect is not
maps onto key notions in those writings. With that in mind, we should equal to the power of its cause. Thus, we are told, air participates in
briefly review the fundamental distinctions made by Thomas regarding the light of the sun since it does not receive that hght with the same
participation to see what Fabro intends by some of his distinctive brightness as is in the sun.' As Thomas presents it, this mode of
terminology.
The topic of participation is addressed in a number of places s Expositie hbri Bostii De ebdomudsbsss,lectio 2 (Leon. 50,271:68 —
71): "Secundam dH'Ierenciam
throughout Thomas's writings, but his most detailed and systematic ponit ibi: gssed est pursiipureetc. Que quidem diEerencia sumitur secundum rationcm
consideration occurs in his Commentary on Boethius's De Itebdomadibsts participationis, Est autem participare quasi p attern caperc. Et ideo quando aliquid
(1257 — 1259),' In chapter 2 of this commentary, Thomas explains that particulatiter recipit id quod ad alterum pertinet universaliter, dicitur participare iiiud."
' Ibid. (Leon. 50.271:74-77).
a being (ens), or "that-which-is" (id quod est), is (exists) because it ' See NMP, 33-34, 143 — 148; Louis-Bertrand Geiger,Lu purtissputie» duns hs pbiksepbis de
participates in esse. And he explains that "'to participate' fparticipareJ S. Thomas d'Aqssin, 2~ ed. (Paris: I.ibrairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1953), 48-49; Rudi A.
te Velde, Pueisipudon aed Substuntiuh'tyin Thomas Aquinas(New York: E.J. Brill, 1995), 7&82;
2 Dating of Thomas's texts followsJean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomus Aquinus,voL 1, Tbe
John F. Wippel, Tbe hfesupbyss'sulThought ef Themes Aquinas(CUA Press, 2000), 96-97.
s &ctesino Ds ebdomudibus,lectio 2 (leon. 50271:77-80).
Perron und His Work,rev. ed., trans. Robert Royal (CUA Press, 2005).
t Ibid. (Leon. 50.271:8&85).
Gregory T. Dooian Fafsro 's Doufsfe Partlet)sation and Aquinas 's Doufsfe Exentpfarfssn

participation appears to entail three kinds of causality: the focus is on Thus, Fabro considers a creature to be a being by participation in a
efficient causality (the air being affected by the sun), but this mode also twofold manner: in one 'way, according to the predicamental order
entails both an intrinsic formal causality (light as presentin the air), as inasmuch as it is a composite either of matter and form, or of substance
well as an extrinsic exemplar causality (the light of the sun). Moreover, and accidents; in another way, inasmuch as the creature is a composite
if we consider Thomas's observation regarding the power of the cause, of essence and esse." Although Fabro emphasizes the distinction between
the sort of efficient cause he seems to have in mind is what he elsewhere these two sorts of participation, he is careful to note that Thomas
terms an equivocal or analogical agent.' And, as with the second mode considers them to be in close relationship to one another." Still, regarding
of participation, this third mode is presented as ontological, or real. this structure of participation, Fabro stresses the importance of the real
Considering these three modes, Fabro identifies what he sees as two composition between essence and esse within a creature."
fundamental kinds of participation, presented both here and throughout As for his language of "double participation," for the most part Fabro
Thomas's writings. One kind Fabro terms "predicamental participation" employs it in the context of drawing this fundamental distinction between
and the other "transcendental participation." Predicamental participation, the predicamental and the transcendental." But there are other note-
he explains, entails individual participants all sharing the same univocal worthy instances when he employs this language to draw a distinction in
formality that they have through their essential content. Although the his treatment of transcendental participation alone. In these contexts,
participants really exist in themselves, what they participate in does not; Fabro seemingly presents two lines of transcendental participation: one
rather, it exists only in the participants.' Furthermore, we are told, both to account for the creature's essence, the other for its esse."
the participant and the participated belong to the realm of finite substance We might well ask, why does Fabro use this language of a twofold
outlined in Aristotle's Categories. It is for this reason that Fabro refers participation in these contexts? As Thomas himself presents his third
to this sort of participation as predicamenta/. And he identifies it mode of participation, there is no immediate indication that it admits of
with the first two modes outlined in Thomas's Commentary on the a further division. The answer comes from what Thomas has to say
De ifebdomadibus. to elsewhere regarding the sort ofsimilitude that participation in the divine
In contrast to predicamental participation, what Fabro terms entails. These considerations are what Fabro has in mind when he speaks
"transcendental participation" does not involve participants sharing in of transcendental participation as twofold: namely, considerations of what
the same way in a formality; rather, they participate in a given perfection Thomas explicitly presents as a double divine exemplarism.
according to a d eficiency
of likeness. Such a perfection, unlike those of
predicamental participation, really exists outside of the participant either
(1) as a property of a higher entity, or (2) in itself as a pure and subsistent
formality in its fuH possession — for example, in the way that beings
participate in esse. Since the participated perfections here are shared in
according to differing degrees, these perfections cannot be predicated ta Corneho Fabro, "The Intensive Hermeneutics of Thomistic Philosophy: The Notion of
univocally of the participants; hence, this sort of participation entails f Mekpphysr'cs 27, no. 3, A Commemorarive
Participation," trans. B. M. Bonansea, Reeietu ss
analogicity. Fabro regards transcendental participation as the strongest Issue: Thomas Aquinas 1224-1274 (March 1974): 48~81.
ts Ibid.; 47'1-472.
meaning of "participation," and he connects it with Thomas's third t4 As Fabro explains, "since the essence of a creature has also its own participated act of
mode." being (adus essencfs),its actualization is not merely a relation of extrinsic dependence; rather,
it is based on the act of esse in which it participates and which it preserves within itself and
' See ST I, q. 13, a. 5, ad 1 (Leon. 4.147). is the proper terminus of divine causality" (Ibid.: 481).
"' AMP, 305-307. ts See Fabro, Parsecijsarvfsne e sasssafsfcf,592-593.
Ibid., 143 — 144. Moreover, Fabro explains that since predicamental participation is the " See ibid., 595: "Secondo Ia doppia partecipazione trascendentale, e quanto all'essenza e
foundation of gencric and specific perfections, it concerns univocal formalities(Pariecspa~ne quanto all'esse, c'e anche un doppio momento dell'analogia; uno formale per imitazione della
e casssailta,650). forms divine, ed un altro reale per derivazione della causalita divina." Fabro cites as support
" NMP, 305 — 306. for this observation De per.,q. 7, a. 7, ad 2 and SCG I, ch. 31.

70
Gregory T. Doolan pabro s Double Participation and Aquinas s Double Exemplarisrn

2. AQUINAS'S DOUBLE EXEMPLARISM AND FABRO S READING OF IT therefore, every single thing attains a perfect imitation of that which
is in the divine intellect (for any kind of thing is of the sort he has
According to Thomas, the fundamental characteristic of an exemplar ordained it to be), then in this sense of "likeness" any creature what-
is the characteristic of likeness, or similitude (similitudo). He tells us soever can be called the "image" of an idea existing in the divine
that a likeness can exist in something in one of two ways: either as in mind. For this reason Boethius says that the forms that are in matter
a principle, or as in something that shares a likeness to a principle. can be called "images" in that they have come from those forms that
The latter sort of likeness has the character (ratio) of an image. Only are without matter."
the former likeness has the character of an exemplar. Hence, Thomas
commonly describes an exemplar as "that in the likeness of which With this distinction, we see Thomas present the divine nature as the
something is made."" He thus presents an exemplar as the measure of exemplar of transcendental and simple perfections in creatures; whereas
its effect and, as such, its formal cause — albeit an extrinsic one whose he presentsthedivine ideas asexemplars ofcreated essences.Fabro sees
causality presupposes both eKcient and final causality." That all three this double exemplarism as two "moments" (conceptually speaking)
kinds of causality are entailed in exemplarism is clear from the case of within the structure of participation, accounting for the formal derivations
human artisanship: for example, the idea of a house in the mind of an of transcendental and predicamental perfections in finite beings. In
architect can actually exemplify a house only if the architect as agent is presenting these derivations, he is careful to explain how such a division
motivated to execute his plan (his end) and in fact does so. can occur both within and I'rom God without compromising the divine
As for God's exemplar causality, Thomas consistently presents it simplicity. To do so, he adopts the Hegelian language of "diremption"
from the time of his earliest writings as twofold. Thus, we find him (shorn of certain Hegelian commitments)."
explaining in 1n II Sententiarum, distinction 16 the following:
The likeness of a work can be said [to be] in the worker in two ways: Thomas Aquinas,In II Seas., d. 16, q. 1, a. 2, ad 2 (Mandonnet, vol. 2, 400): "sirnilirudo
either [1] as that which he has in his own nature, as man generates operis potest dici ad operantem dupliciten aut quantum ad id quod habet in natura sua, sicut
man, or [2] as that which he has in his own intellect, as a work of alt homo generat hominem; aut quantum ad id quod habet in intcllectu suo, sicut artificiatum
ab arti6ce in similitudinem artis suae procedit, Utroque modo procetgt creatura a Deo in
proceeds from the artisan in likeness to his own art. In both ways
similitudinem cjus. Primo modo, quia ab ente sunt entia, et a vivo viventia. Secundo modo,
does a creature proceed from God in his likeness: [1'] according to quia procedunt a rationibus idealibus. Cum ergo unaquaequc res pertingat ad perfectam
the first way because beings are from Being (ab ente sunt entia) and imitationem ejus quod est in intellectu divino, quia talis est qualem earn esse disposuit; ideo
living things from Life; [2'] according to the second way because quantum ad hunc modum similitudinis quaelibet creatura potest dici imago ideae in mentc
they proceed from ideal notions (ratiotu'bus iderdibus). Since, divina existentis; unde dicit Boetius. .. quod formac quae sunt in materia possunt dici
imagines, eo quod ab his formis vcnerunt quac sine materia aunt."
m lmr a consideration of Fabro's adoption of this Hegelian term "diremptjon"
(also
'7 Sana' Tbomae deAquino Super libncmDe eaasir eseposisie, prop. 14, ed. H. D. Saffrey (Fribourg: sometimes spelled "diremtion" ), see Jason A. Mitchell, Being and P~aseb n: Tbe IVlesbodand
Socle' philosophique, 1954), p. 85, lines 1213: — ' *exemplar est id ad cuius similitudinem fit Ssruesuref eMeAiphysieat ~ n c m ording so Contebe I'abro,
vol. 1 (Rome: Ateneo Ponti6cio
aliud." Cf. De eer., q. 3, a. 1 (Leon.22.1.99 177 —
182);guedbbes V III, q. 1, a. 2 (Leon. 25.1.54: Relp'na Apostolorum, 2012), 191-197. Mitchell sums up Fabro's usage of this term as
42 —43); In /ibrum BeasiDianysii De diuinis nemini bus mpesisie, caput 5, lectio 3, no. 665, ed. follows: 'To conclude, the use of 'Oiremsian'by Fabro, when spealdng about Thotnistic
C. Pcra (I'min-Rome: Marietti, 1950), 249; ST I, q. 35, a. 1, ad 1 (Leon. 4.372). By contrast, metaphysics, normany concerns some type of dialectic and refers to a process oF sublation
Thomas notes that an image is called such because it is produced in imitation of something in the sense of a negation and consequent synthesis. Two key uses of the term emerge.
else, namely, in imitation of an exemplar. See SCG IV, ch. 49 (icon. 15.34:51 — 56); ST I, A 6rst use is in the explanation oF the derivation of creatures from God, where, according
q. 35, a. 1, ad 1 (Leon. 4.372); ST I, q. 93, a. 1 (Leon. 5.401). Regarding Thomas's treatment to Fabro, there is a certain negation-conservation of esse. The creature is not esse, but rather
of the different types of czemplarism, see Gregory 'I'. Doolan, rfqainas on sbe Divine ideasas has esse or participates in esse... . A second key use of the term 'Diremsebnregards the
Po p l ar C~ases(CUA Press, 2008), 21 — 25. fimdamental and primary structure of the creature: its composition of esse-essenefa. In this
re As Thomas explains, an effect need not imitate its exemplar in every respect; but this case,Diremse'enrefers to the distinction or dialectic ("negation-synthesis") of essence and esse
much is always the case: "exempiata oportet conforman exemplari secundum rationem within ens. The creatm'e's essence, in this case and in Fabrian terms, is not esse, yet is a
Formac" (ST I, q. 18, a. 4, ad 2 [Leon. 4.230]). I'or a defense of exemplarism as a type of 'positive-negative' which limits arse(negating motnent), determining it to a speci6c mode or
formal causality for Thomas, see Doolan, Dieme Ideas, 33-41, degree (synthetic-conserving moment)" (196 — 197).

72
Gregory T. Doolan Fubro 's Double Participation and Aquinas s Double Exentplanssn

As Fabro explains in his work Participation and Causality, the first from that of esse. It is for this reason, we are told, that Fabro adopts the
moment within the structure of participation is constituted by the language of a "double creation." In te Vclde's estimation, the result
diremption, or division, of the divine essence in the formal order such is "a fatal separation between the categorical causality of form and
that it comprises the multiplicity of divine ideas that are the exemplars the transcendental causality with respect to being as such." Thus, hc
of created things." Because of this diremption, every real created concludes, Fabro "ultimately leaves the unity of God's act of creation
formality is referred to its respective exemplar according to its mode of unexplained.'~'
being. This moment constitutes the derivation of the created essence. More recently, Jason A, Mitchell has responded to both Aertsen
The second moment, he explains, entails the derivation of all the and te Velde, drawing attention to the fact that the French edition of
transcendental perfections that follow from the divine nature, which Participation and Causality on which they rely was updated by Fabro in
embraces esse in all of its intensity.~ And this double exemplarism, Fabro his Italian version, which he describes as his "definitive redaction.""
explains, is founded before all on that very act of intensive esse that is In this edition, Fabro abandons his earlier language of "double
the divine essence." creation," replacing it with the phrase "double participation.'"' Mitchell
It is in Fabro's account of this twofold derivation that some scholars acknowledges, however, that Fabro still employs the phrase "distinct
see him as affirming a twofold creation to account for a single created creation"when discussing the derivations of created essence and esse."
being. Complicating the matter is his explicit use of the very expression Procecihng beyond this terminological consideration, Mitchell addresses
"double creation" (double creation) in the French edition of Participation what Fabro is in fact referring to with this language. According to his
and Causality." Leoking at this edition of the work, Jan A. Aertsen takes reading (with which I am sympathetic), Fabro's terminology is really
issue — not simply with Fabro's language — but with this notion of a intended to convey a notion expressed by the term "concreation," a term
double derivation: one of created essence, the other of created esse. Thomas himself employs when discussing God's simultaneous produc-
Aertsen points out that esse and form are presented by Thomas as tion of co-principles in composite substances."
inseparable, with esse as consequent upon form. Thus, Aertsen explains,
God for Thomas "brings forth, through creation, thc thing together with
all its principles." This leads Acrtsen to ask, "How then can one still
~ Te Veld e, Pa ticipution unct gubstantiuli@ 222.
speak of a 'double creation' (Fabro)!"zs
n Fabro, Purteciparsone e cuusah'tu,9; Mitchell, Being unct Particspution,vol. 2, 488-489. The
A similar concern is raised by Rudi te Velde. Also citing the French volume Partinpatiem encl Cansuhtyresulted from Fabro's 1954 "Chaire Cardinal Mercier"
edition of Participation and Causality, he notes Fabro's position that lecnues on "Participation and Causality according to St. Thomas Aquinas" given at the
essence must have in God its own derivation (derivation propre), distinct University of Louvain. Although both the French and Itahan editions were licensed for their
6rst publication in the same year (1 960), Fabro's Italian translation came after his writing
and redaction of the French; moreover, the Italian edition contains a number of addiinons
n Fabro Parteccpagione e cansahth259 to the French edition text along with some rearrangements of portions oi' that earlier
n Ibid., 505 —
507. version. These changes are nicely cataloged by Mitchell, Being encl Pusn'cipation,vol. 2,
~ Ibid., 259 —
260. In his later I 974 articIe, "Intensive Hermeneutics," Fabro sums up the 438 —
440.
relation between these two modes of divine exetnplarism within the structure of Thomas's ~ The corresponding texn ate as follows (iuthcs in original; bold font added for emphasis):
doctrine of participation: "To the extent that participation allows one to conceive the created "Ilessecommunecomme actus essench,participe par les btres individuels, cst te9u dans I'essence
universe in the complexity of its natures as a reflection of divine ideas or exemplary, one et par consequent multiplie. C' est dire que ce qui est I'esse per essentiumen Dieu, acte pur et
may speak of participation by similitude (per similitnch'nem)in the transcendental order totalitc de la perfection, s'epanche dans la creature par une double creation: de I'essence
according to a relation of dependence of the ftnite on the In6nite" (476). et de i *arse" (Fabro,Purtictpution etcansah'te, 468). "L'essecommscne,come ucisccessench'partecipato
~ As will be discussed shortly, Fabro's use of the expression "double creation" appears only nei singoli esistenti, e ricevuto neil'essenza e cosi moltiplicato: vale a dire, cio ch'e 1'esse per
in, the French version of this work. See C. Fabro,Purticspation et cuasalite scion S. Tbosnas d'Again essentiumin Dio, Atto puro e totalita di perfezione, si dirime neiia creatura in una dupilce
(Louvain: publications universintires, 1961), 468. For a companson of relevant passage in partecipazione, dell'essenza e deil'esse"(Fabro,Purteccparsone e cunsalitu,379).
the French and Italian editions of this work, see n28 below. n CE Fabro, Purtictpation et cansah'ei, 468, and Pastecspaqione e cuusuhta,379.
" Jan A. Aertscn, A~re encl Creature,trans. Herbert Donald Morton (New York: L'.J. Brill, ~ Mitchell, Being unct Purticspation,vol. 2, 488 —89. 4 See ST I, q. 7, a. 2, ad 3 (Leon. 4.74);
I 988), 334. ST I, q. 45, a 4, co. (Leon. 4.468).
Gregory T. Doolan Fabro 's Double Participation and Aquinas s Double Exemplarism

Whether or not Aertsen or te Velde were aware that Fabro had maintains that there must be, within the mind of God, a multiplicity of
abandoned his earlier language of "double creation," this much is divine ideas, yet in such a way that does not compromise the divine
clear: te Velde, at least, is no more comfortable with the language simplicity." It is not a real multiplicity, but a conceptual one consisting
of "double participation." In his estimation, the upshot is the same: of multiple understood intentions. Thomas resolves the tension between
"A double participation makes an empty metaphor of the concept of this multiplicity and the divine simphcity by situating the divine ideas
participation.'"' And so, te Velde concludes that: "There is no place for a within the proper context of his theory of participation.
double participation in Aquinas."' Whether or not Fabro truly espouses In the Prima Pars of the Summarheologiae, among other places, he
a doctrine of double participation, this much we must grant with te Velde: explains that the condition for the possibility of a multiplicity of divine
Thomas himself never speaks in these terms. ideas is grounded in the imitability of the divine essence, We are told
As we have seen,however, Thomas does speak of a twofold divine in question 15, article 2 that every single creature has a proper form
exemplarism. Nevertheless, here again, te Velde is dismissive — this (species) because it participates in some way in a likeness (similirudo)
time not of Fabro, but of Thomas's own words. Granting the explicit of the divine essence. Since God.knows his essence perfectly, he knows
distinction Thomas makes between the two modes of exemplarism, it not only as it is in itself, but also as it can be participated by creatures
te Velde nevertheless insists that the distinction does not have for him according to any manner of likeness. In this way, God knows his essence
what te Velde terms a "principal character." As evidence, he cites the as the proper ratio, or idea, of any and all creatures.~
fact that Thomas often mentions the two modes together, implying Thomas makes clear in his replies to the objections from this article
(presumably) that they arc in fact one and the same." In contrast to that this multiplicity of ideas does not compromise the divine simplicity,
te Velde„ I would contend that we should simply give a face value reading precisely because the multiplicity is according to the order of God *s
of these texts: namely, that when Thomas presents the two modes of understanding rather than the order of reality." The divine ideas are
divine exemplarism together, he wishes to highlight the distinction indeed distinct from each other and from God, but only conceptually
between them. Moreover, I would contend that in such texts, Thomas's distinct. To say this, however, is not to dismiss these distinctions. Thomas
concern is also to indicate (however briefly) the manner in which is careful to make clear time and again that the conceptual multiplicity
these modes of exemplarism are interrelated. A careful consideration of divine ideas is not only according to our understanding a s though it
of these texts reveals — not only that he embraces a doctrine of double were a mere helpful model — but it is according to God's understanding
exemplarism b u t also that Thomas does so in such a way that afIirms as well."
neither double creation nor double participation. To see how the two Regarding these divine ideas, Thomas draws a distinction from the
modes of divine exemplarism are interrelated, it will help to begin with time of his relatively early De verirare (1256-1259), namely, between a
a brief summary of his doctrine of divine ideas. strict and a broad sense of "idea." Given his definition noted earlier,
Thomas holds that ideas strictly speaking belong to practical knowledge
since they are the forms of things that can be made. Since universals such
3. AQUINAS ON PARTICIPATION AND THE DIVINE IDEAS
as genera and species cannot have extramental existence as universals,
Considering the ratio of an idea in general, Thomas tells us that it is they are thus not producible and do not have ideas in the mind of God
"a form that something imitates because of the intention of an agent who according to this strict sense. Only individuals such as Socrates can be
predetermines the end for hi mself."~ In light of this definition, Thomas

" ST I, q. 15, a. 2, co. (Leon. 4.201 202).



n Te Velde, partierpados and Snbstantiabty, 282. ~ Ibid.
~ Ibid., 114n46. " Ibid., ad 1-4 (Leon. 4.202).
" Ibid., 111. ~ See In I Sent., d. 36, q. 2, a. 2, ad 2 (Mandonnet, vol. 1, 842); De pet.,q. 3, a 16, ad 14
~ De ver., q. 3, a. 1, co. (Leon. 22.1.100:209 —23
2 ): "Haec ergo vidctur cssc ratio idcae, quod (1949), 90; De ter., q. 3, a. 2, ad 8 (Leon. 22.L107:5~) . O n t he conceptual distinction
idea sit forms quam aliquid iimitatur cx intentionc agentis qui praedeterminat sibi fmem." between the divine ideas, see Doolan, Divine Ideas,115 ff.
Gregory T, Doola» Fabro 8 Double Parricipano» a»d Aquinas s Double Ere»tplaris»t

made; thus, strictly speaking, Thomas concludes, there are divine ideas (1266 —1268), he comes to reserve the word "exemplar" for those divine
only of individuals." With that said, he acknowledges that according to ideas of individual things that God makesat some point in time, since
a broad sense of the term, an idea can be taken as simply the intelligible only such ideas in fact exemplify anything. All other divine ideas
notion (ratio) or likeness (sinulitudo) of a thing. In this way, they can also (namely, speculative ones) he instead terms "notions" (rationes)."
belong to speculative knowledge. And, Thomas concludes, according to With the foregoing in mind, if we return to the text quoted earlier
this broader sense of the term there are divine ideas of genera and species Irom In II S ententiarum and to consider Thomas's treatment of the
as well."' exemplarism of the divine ideas there, we find a s~ g o bservation. As
The implications of the foregoing distinctions for the doctrine of regards the likeness a created being such as Socrates has to its exemplar
divine exernplarism are brought out mcely in Thomas's reply to one idea, Thomas tells us there that "every single thing attains aperfect
objector's concerns. If there are divine ideas for individual things, the imitation of that which is in the divine intellect.'"' This is a striking claim.
objection goes, there would be many ideas corresponding to one thing, Within the Platonic and Neoplatonic tradition, the ideated always falls
which seems problematic, Thomas replies by acknowledging that if short of the Idea, the exemplified of thc exemplar. Why — how — can
we take the term "idea" according to the broad sense as a like- Thomas claim that the creature's imitation of its divine idea isperfect7
ness (similitudo) or notion (ratio) that belongs to God's speculative An explanation follows immediately in the next line: "for any such
knowledge, then there are indeed different ideas that corrcspond to thing," he explains, "is as he [God] has ordained it to be."~ In other
Socrates as Socrates, as man, and as animal, since he differs in these words, the creature is precisely as God has intended. It is precisely the
various respects according to the order of understanding. But, Thomas intentional character of the divine ideas that allows for the perfect
next explains, if we take the term "idea" according to its proper, or strict, assimilation, here, between exemplified and exemplar: between Socrates
sense as an exemplar belonging to God's practical knowledge, "one idea and God's idea of him.
corresponds to the individual, the species, the genus, and what is Considering again the twofold divine exemplarism in his later
individuated in the individual itself, because Socrates, man, and animal De potentia (1265 — 1266), Thomas explains the basis of this perfect
are not distinguished according to [the order of] being (esse)."' In short, assimilation in terms of the similitude that intellectual exemplarism
divine ideas of genera and species do not tunction as exemplar causes, entails:
but only ideas of singulars do, such as God's idea of Socrates. There is a twofold likeness between a creature and God. One likeness
Thomas's insistence that a divine idea, properly speaking, pertains is of the creature to the divine intellect, and in this way the form
to an individual is reflected in his very use of the term "exemplar." Over that is understood by God is of one and the same formality (unius
the course of his career, he comes to restrict the meaning of this term rationis) as the thing that is understood — although it does not have
when speaking of the divine ideas. By the time he writes the Prima Pars

es ST I, q. 15, a. 3 (Leon. 4.204). In the eadier Dereeiease(1256 —1257), Thomas hdd that
~ Namely, individual substances as well as individual accidents, See De ter., q. 3, a. 7 — 8 something can be called an exemplar simply from the fact that another thing ea» be made in
(Leon. 22.1.113 —
116); ST I, q. 15, a. 3 (Leon. 4.204). See Doolan, Di»i»e Ideas,esp. 143-147. imitation of it even though that other thing is never made (De ver,, q. 3, a. 3, ad 3;
+' Regarding the divine ideas of genera and species, seeDe eer., q, 3, a 3 (Leon. 22.1.106- Leon. 22,1.108:185 — 194). Regarding the development of Thomas's thought on this
109);De ver.,q. 3, a. 8 (Leon. 22.1.1'15 —116); guedhbeeVIII, q. 1, a. 2 (Leon. 25.1.53-55); matter, see Doolan, Diui»e Ideas,143 — 147; Lawrence Dewan, "St. Thomas, James Ross,
ST I, q. 15, a. 3 (Icon. 4.204). See Doolan,Diei»e Ideas,123-155. and Exemplarism: A Reply," America»CaehehePhilasopi»eatg» artery 65, no. 2 (Spring 1991):
4' Dr ver,,q. 3, a. 8, ad 2 (Leon. 22.1.116:74-44): "si loquamur de idea proprie secundum 233-234.
quod est rei co modo quo cst in esse productibilis, sic una idea respondct singulan, speciei 's I» li Snit., d. 16, q. 1, a. 2, ad 2 (Mandonnet, vol. 2, 400): "Cum ergo unaquaeque res
et generi, individuatis in ipso singulati, eo quod Socrates, homo et animal non distinguuntur pertingat ad perfectam imitationem ejus quod est in intellectu divino, quis talis est qualem
secundum esse; si autetn accipiamus ideam communiter pro similitudine vei ratione, sic curn earn esse disposuit." Emphasis added in translation. For the complete Latin text of this
diversa sit consideratio Socratis ut Socrates est et ut homo est et ut est animal, rcspondebunt response, see n19 above.
ei secundum hoc plures ideae vd similitudines." ~ See n43 above for Latin.
Gregory T. Doolan Fobro k Double Participation and Aquinas s Double Exemplansm

the same mode of existing (modusessendi) because the understood God perfectly knows his own essence; hence he knows it according
form exists only in the intellect, whereas the form of the creature to every way by which it is knowable. But it can be known not only
exists also in reality.4' as it is in itself, but also as it is "participable" by creatures according
to any manner of likeness. Now, each and every creature has its
In this text Thomas is indicating to us that the similitude of an effect
proper form (species) insofar as it participates a likeness of the divine
to its intellectual exemplar — even to an idea in the mind of God — is of
essence. Thus, inasmuch as God knows his essence as imitable in
the same formality as its exemplar precisely because the idea is an
such a way by such a creature, he knows it as the proper notion and
intentional similitude. As he makes clear, the relevant point of focus here
idea of that creature. And similarly regarding other creatures."
concerns the formality (ratio) of the exemplar, not its modus essendi. By
contrast, the second sort of likeness — concerning the exemplarism of Notice that in employing the language of participation here, Thomas
the divine nature — necessarily takes into account the modus essettdi does not speak of the divine ideas as participated; rather, what he
of the exemplar because that exemplar is nothing less than subsisting describes as participated is the likeness of the divine nature. The divine
esse. Thomas addresses this mode of divine exemplarism in the same ideas, instead, are presented as God's knowledge of the various ways in
text when he continues by noting: which his likeness canbe participated. As Thomas explains elsewhere,
it is in God's knowing thcsc "participabilities" of his likeness, that
The other way in which there is a likeness between a creature and
he has, as it w erc, "thought out" the divine ideas: rationes quasi
God is insofar as the divine essence itself is the super-excelling
excogitatav." Indeed, this is the way Thomas consistently presents the
likeness of all things and is not of the same formality. From this
manner of likeness, and not the first, it occurs that good and other
such I attributes] are predicated commonly of God and of creatures.
For we do not say "God is good" because he understands the ST I, q. 15, a 2, co. (Leon, 4,202)..
Noa est autem comra simplicitatcm divini inteliectus, quod multa intelligan sed contra
goodness of a creature.~
simplicitatem eius esset, si per plures species eius intellectus formaretur. Unde pluses
Thus, Thomas presents a double divine excmplarism: onc mode that ideae aunt ia mente divina ut intellectae ab ipso.
Quod hoc modo potest videri. Ipse enim essentiam suam pcrfecte cognoscit: unde
entails a perfect simihtude of the exemplified to the cxcmplar (creature
cognoscit earn sccundum omnem modum qua cognoscibilis est. Potest autem cognosci
to divine idea); the other that entails an imperfect similitude (creature to aon solum secuadum quod in se est, sed secundum quod est participabilis secundum
divine nature). But, does that mean that Thomas is thcrcfore presenting aliquem modum simiTitudinis a creaturis. Unaquaequc autcm creatura habet propriam
a corresponding double participation'/ To begin to answer this question, specietn, sccundum quod aliquo modo participat divinae esseatiae similitudinem. Sic
igitur inquantum Deus cognoscit suam essentiam ut sic imitabilem a tali creatura,
let us return to his treatment of the divine ideas in the Prima Pars of thc
cognoscit earn ut propriam taaonem et ideam huius creaturae. Et similiter de aliis. Et
Summa theolagiae and read the text closely in light of our own question. sic patet quod Deus intelliyt plates rationes ptoprias plurium rerum; quae suat plures
In the course of answering the question of whether there are many divine ideae.
ideas (q. 15, a. 2), Thomas explains how the ideas are "constituted" in 's Depot.,q.1, a 5, ad 11 (1949), 20. For another use of ttttagitertin speaking of the divine
the mindof God: ideas, see ST I, q. 44, a. 3 in n49 below. 'I'homas's reference to "excogitation" in these
coatexn; should aot be taken to suggest that he thinks God somehow "comes up +4th" new
ideas in the process of thinking. On this point I foHow Wippel, who differs with Norris
Clarke. Clarke contends that God "does not 6nd them [the divine ideas] somehow ready-
" Dt pot., q. 7, a. 7, ad 6 (1949), 204 — 205: "inter crcatutam et Deum est duplex similitudo. made in His essence(what could that possibly mean ontologically?) but literally *invents,'
'excogitates' th em" (W. Norris Clarke, 'What is Really ReaL>," in
Una creanuae ad intellectum divinum: et sic forma intellects per Deum est unius rationis Pngretti » Philos'@;ed.J.A.
curn te intellects, licet noa habeat eumdem modum essendi; quia forms intellects est tantum McWiliiams [Milwaukee: Bruce, 1955], 85n45). Wippel responds that "I prefer to stress the
in intcllecnt, forma autem crcaturae est etiam in re." fact that God, in knowing his own essence, also knows (or 'discovers') the many ways in
4s Ibid.: "Alia modo secundum quod ipsa divina essentia est omnium rerum similitudo which it is imitable and, therefore, the divine ideas and the possibles" (]ohn E Wippel, '"I'he
superexceliens, et non unius ratioais. Et ex hoc modo simiTitudinis contingit quod bonum Reality of Nonexisting Possibles According to Thomas Aquinas, Henry of Ghent, and
ct huiusmodi praedicantur communiter de Deo et creaturis, aon autcm cx primo. Noa cairn Godfrey of Fontaiaes," Revietr foAfttuphyst?s34, no. 4 I]une 1981]: 738a19). Still, Wippel
haec est ratio Dei curn dicitur, Deus est bonus, quia bonitatem cteatutae intelligit." observes that his difference with Clarke seems to be "mainly a matter of emphasis" (739a19).

80
Gregory T. Doolan Fabro 's Double ParnciPauon and Aquinas's Double Fsernpfarisjn

role of participation wheil discussing divine exemplarism." Well aware unlimited, or absolute, way." Could the divine ideas be participated in
of the Platonic language of participation in ideas, Thomas however never this manner? Here again, the answer for Thomas is "no."
makes that language his own. To see why, let us consider again the texts on double exemplarism
If we consider again his definition of participation offered in his cited earlier. Recall that Thomas presents the divine nature inDe potenria
Comm entary o n the De hebdomadibus as well as the three modes of as the "super-excelling" likeness of creatures which, as such, is not of
participation he identifies there, it becomes clear why Thomas does not the same formality as its exemphfied effects; thus, although Socrates as
treat the divine ideas as participated. Recall that his first mode of partici- a being does indeed share a likeness to God, he does so in a deficient
pation consists of a conceptual relation of participant to participated; by way. It is this sort of divine exemplarism, then, that indeed entails the
contrast, we find that the relation of similitude of a creature to its third mode of participation. By contrast, in the same text, Thomas
exemplar idea is a real one: Socrates is really like the divine idea of presents a divine idea as of the same formality as its exemplified e6ect
Socrates." Thomas's second mode of participation entails an inner Hence, as we have seen in the text &om In II Senrentiarum, God's effect
composition of participant and received perfection; by contrast, he is can, and does, perfectly imitate its exemplar idea. Socrates is exactly as
clear that created beings do not c a nnot — enter into composition with God intends him to be in linc with the divine idea of Socrates. This sort
their divine ideas. Recall that Thomas presents the divine ideas as only of similitude doesnot admit of the degrees of perfection entailed in the
conceptually distinct I'rom God and hence ontologically identical with third mode of participation. Simply put, to be Socrates does not admit of
the divine essence. Werc created beings to participate in them according degrees: he either is Socrates, or he is not, So too, with Socrates's likeness
to Thomas's second mode, they would enter into composition with to his divine idea. The imitation here is either perfect, or there is no
God — a position he decidedly rejects.» imitation at all.
What, then, of Thomas's third mode of participation: that of an eQect Thus, we find that for Thomas the exemplarism of the divine ideas
in its cause? As I noted earlier, the sort of cause he has in mind here seems is accounted for neither by his de6nition of participation nor by any of
to be what he terms elsewhere an equivocal or analogical cause. It the modes of participation that he identi6es. Moreover, as I have noted,
is for this reason that Fabro terms this third mode "transcendental he never employs the language of participation when speaking of the
participation," and others term it participation "by similitude" or "by relation of created beings to their exemplar ideas. Thus, we can con-
formal hierarchy," because it entails the participants sharing in various clude that Thomas's twofold divine exemplarism does nor entail a
degrees a limited similitude of what belongs to their cause in an corresponding double participation in the divine, despite tc Velde's
concern. What I believe te Velde misses in his critique of double
exemplarism is the status of the divine ideas, for Thomas, as intentional
ss Cf, ST I, q. 44, a. 3,co. (Leon. 4.460): similitudes within the mind of God." Whereas God's nature as a
Deus est prima causa exemplaris omnium rerum. Ad cuius evidentiam, considerandum
subsistent exemplar has essereale and its likeness can be participated,
est quod ad productionem alicuius rei ideo necessarium cst exemplar, ut effectus
determinatam forrnam consequatur: artifex enim producit determinatam formam in a divine idea taken as an idea has only esseinlelligibile and so it cannot
materia, propter exemplar ad quod inspicit, sive iliud sit exemplar ad quod extra be participated.~
intuetur, sive sit exemplar intcrius mente conceptum. ~ cst u m est autern quod ea
quae naturalitcr Gunt, determinatas Eormas consequuntur. Haec autem formarum Regarding participation by similitude, or formal hierarchy, Geiger notes"LaparrurP alion
determinatio oportet quod reducatur, sicut in primum principium, in divinam sapientiam, suPrune l'lras Aiminue, parruularsss,er,e» I sem, par6rspi rgune essenre,chequefois qu'slk n'sss
par
quae ordinem universi excogitavit, qui in rerum distinctione consistit. Et ideo oportet dahss'e rknsiapienduck absohredeson cenrsnuferjnsP (Laparruiparien, 28-29).Emphasis in o~
dicere quod in divina sapientia aunt rationes omnium renun: quas supra diximus nisus, " Norris Clarke, in highlighting Thomas's clear break E'rom the Platonic presentation o E the
id est Eormas exemplares in mente divina existentes.Quae quidem licet multiplicentur Ideas as real, subsistent entities, sums up the situation nicdy by noting that "l'he die is cast.
secundum respectum ad res, tamen non aunt realiter aliud a divina essentia, prout eius The divine ideas are no longer the very forms, the true being, of creatures, buttheirinrsnrional
similitudo a diversis participari potest diversimode. Sic igitur ipse Deus est primum rim'&@des,whose only being is that of the one divine act of knowing" ~%'. Norris Ciarlse,
exemplar omnium. "The Problem of the Reality and Multiplicity of Divine Ideas in Christian Neoplatonism,"
~ Moreover, Thomas is dear that Socrates is Socrates, a man and ananimal psr esssnruuu and in ¹e plurenisnsand Christen Thought, ed. Dominic J. O'Meara [Albany: State llniversity of
not by participation. New York Press, 1982], 1221. Emphasis added.
" See ST I q. 3, a. 8 g~on. 4.47-48). ~ Regarding the ssssintelligibile of divine ideas, see ST l, q. 15, a. 1, co. (Leon. 4.1991.

83
Gregory T. Doolan Fabro s Double Participation and Aquinas 's Double Exemptaristn

Granted these distinctions, one might well ask at this point how, really as God has ordained it to be: like his essence inthat respect, as
then, can the divine ideas exercise real exemplar causality given their God really intended. Thus, whereas there is a deficiency on the side of
intenfional status? If their reality is ontologically reduced to that of the the creature in its likeness to the divine nature taken simp/ici ter, there is
divine nature, would not their causality also be so reduced, as te Velde no deficiency on the side of God's intention to make the creature really
suggests? The answer to these questions will provide us with the occasion like himself in this limited way — for example,as Socrates, Moreover, it
to return to a consideration of Fabro to discern whether in fact he affirms should be noted that this intentionality is both an intellectual and
a doctrine of double participation that falls prey to the critiques of both volifional intentionality: the exemplarism of the divine ideas entails a
Aertsen and te Velde. real formal causality, but it is a formal causality that must be "realized"
in the order of efficient causality. For a divine idea to be the formal
likeness of a created being such as Socrates, God must will to make such
4. FABRo s DQUBLE PARTIcIFATIGN READ IN LIGHT oF AQUINAs
a being.
I will begin to answer these questions regarding thc causality of the So much for my ow n r eading of T h omas's doctrine of d i v i ne
divine ideas with my own reading of Thomas before turning to Fabro. exemplarism. What of Fabro's? Does it allow for a double creation? For
When we consider the role of double excmplarisrn in Thomas's account the moment, let us leave aside his language of double participation.
of creation, I would argue that we find him presenting (at least implicitly) Like Thomas, Fabro acknowledges a participation in the likeness of the
the following logical "moments": in the first moment, there is the divine divine nature; and, like Thomas, nowhere does he explicitly say (to my
essence, or nature, which is imitable in itself — the pure, infinite esse knowledge) that the divine ideas are participated. With that said, I must
that is Esse Subsistens; in the next moment, God knows himself; and also grant that nowhere (again, to my knowledge) does Fabro explicitly
consequently, in the third moment he knows his nature as imitable say that the divine ideas are unparti cipated. Nevertheless, I read this view
and participable — in this way "thinking out" or "dicerning" (excogitare) as implicit in his treatment of Thomas's double exemplarism. Consider
the divine ideas;s' finally, in the fourth moment, he looks to some of these the following from Participation and Causality:
ideas and, by an act of his will, creates finite beings whose essences are Thomism does not seem to admit of doubts regarding this order:
perfectly like their exemplar ideas but simultaneously fall short of c reated essences are derived from th e d i v ine essence by t h e
a perfect likeness of the divine nature — which is to say that they intermediary of the divine Ideas, and this derivation formally follows
participate in the likeness of God. the relationship of exemplarity. Next, every cssencc, although it is
Te Vclde has termed such a reading of Thomas whereby a created act in the formal order, is created as potency that becomes actualized
being's essence is determined by its exemplar idea and its actual by the participated esse that it receives: its actuality is thus given by
existence by the divine wil l a s t h e "traditional . . . m e t aphysics of the "mediation" of esse."
creation." And i t i s j u s t such an i nterpretation that, he contends,
"breaks thc unity of the act of creation" leading to an unacceptable
st Here I atn translating the French edition since this is the text upon which both Aertsen
double participation.~ As I have argued, however, the reason such
and te Vdde rely: "IA: thomisme ne semble pas admettre dc doutes quant b cet ordre: les
a double participation docs not in fact result from this reading is duc essences crhhes dhrivent de l'essence divine par l'mtertnediaire des Idhes divines, et cette
to the fact that, for Thomas, a created being does not participate in its dhrivation suit sinai formellement le rapport d'exemplarith. Ensuite, toute essence, bien
divine idea since that exemplar is an intentional similitude and not a qu'elle snit acte tlans I'ordre formel, est crhee comme puissance qui devient actualiseepar
1'ssssparticiph qu'elle reqoin son actualith cst ainsi donnee par la «mediation» de I'ssss"
subsistent entity. (Fabro,
Partitijtatt'on et rausalid, 630).
And yet, despite what he identifies as the intentional status of a divine
The Italian edition admits of n o substantive variation: ' *Nel tomismo la situaaione
idea, Thomas clearly presents its exemp/arism (exemplar causality) as non sembra ammetta contestaxionh le esscnac create sono derivate dali'essenaa divina,
real. How? Because the created being that is made in its likeness is coll'intermediario dclle Idee divine, e quindi formalmente la derimaione h secondo il
tapporto di esemplarits. Agni essenza poi, benche sia atto nell'ordine formale,i: crests come
ta See n48 above regarding Thomas's language of ssssgtlarsin discussing the divine ideas. potenaa che va attuata dali'esse par tecipato che in se riccve: la sua attualita e «mediata» quindi
Tc Velde,P dali'esse" (Fabro, Parteap~ions e causah'ta,643).
artletjtation andSnbstantiahty,282.
Gregory T. Doolun Fubro 's Double Participation und A rtrrinus s Double Exempturism

From the perspective of Aertsen and te Velde, this text at Grst appears What then of Fabro's explicit language of "double participation,"
to advocate the sort of double creation that they accuse Fabro of which seems to affirm a twofold transcendental participation' In light
affirming. If, however, we view his temporal language as referring to of Fabro's presentation of double exemplarism, I would agree with
logical rather than chronological moments (the charitable reading), and Mitchell's response to Aertsen and te Velde. As he puts it, an "attentive
if we also consider that he presents the derivation of essences as prior in reading" shows that Fabro is not in fact affirming two lines of tran-
what he terms the "formal order," Fabro can be read as indicating the scendental participation, but rather two "moments" within its structure:
inef
ficacyof the divine ideas as creative principles taken in themselves. one moment entails what Mitchell terms a "direct" line of transcendental,
Thus, we see his reference to them as intermediaries rather than as direct or causal, participation in esse(exemplarism of the divine nature); the
causal principles. In short, I take Fabro to be indicating that the divine other what Mitchell identiIies as a "mediated" line according to which
ideas are not that which is participated, but that through which or the created being'8 essence "measures" its received actus essendi but is
by which a created being participates in the more foundational exemplary itself"measured" by its divine idea (exemplarism of the divine intellect).
likeness that is the divine nature. From this perspective, what Fabro terms a "double participation" is not
In support of this reading, let us next consider Fabro's interpretation properly double but in fact a single creative act accounting for a single
of the same text on double exemplarism that I presented earlier from created being.~
De potentia. Fabro explains, again in Participation and Causali ot (both As for Fabro himself, we have seen that after his 1961 edition
the French and Italian editions), that as regards the exemplarism of the of Participation et causalite, hc abandoned his language of "double
divine ideas, the resemblance of a created being to its divine idea is of a creation," presumably because he recognized the problematic implica-
formal nature that, in his words, "leaves intact the divine isolation.'"" tions of this expression — implications later brought out by scholars
Here, again, I take him to be highlighting the status of the divine ideas such as Aertsen and te Velde. Unfortunately, Fabro's revised language
as intentional similitudes, whose causality as exemplars depends upon of "double participation" is not much better, lending easily to a reading of
the efficient causal act of the divine will. By contrast, Fabro observes, him such as te Velde's. And yet, despite what I take to be a misreading
with the exemplarism of the divine nature the relationship becomes "real of Fabro, I would agree with te Velde on this point: in Thomas's meta-
and fundamental." An d h e a dds parenthetically fo r c l a rification: physics of creation, there is no place for a double participation. With that
"(causality)."" Hcic, I take liinl to bc icfcrring to tlic sort of cfficiciit in mind, I think Fabro should have avoided the phrase in this context,
causality entailed in Thomas's third mode of participation, whereby the reserving the language of "double participation" to refer instead to that
creature is made like God because he has willed it into existence as a fundamental distinction in Thomas that Fabro was so keen &om the
being with actual existence. Read in this way, Fabro's account of outset to draw our attention to: not between two lines of transcendental
Thomas's double exemplarisrn presents a single line of transcendental participation, but instead between the transcendental and the predica-
participation, namely, a line that entails a participation in the likeness of mental. Otherwise, it would have been better for Fabro to stay true to the
thc divine essence and not in the divine ideas. language of his source and speak simply in terms of that other double
that Thomas himself speaks of so clearly, namely, double exemplarism.

" Fabro, Purtiripusr


b n et suusulit, 5i9: "Dans lc premier cas cn effct ia rcsscmhiancc cst de
nature formelle et laisse intact I'isolemeni rhvin, tanrlis balue dans le second cas le rapport
devient (dans la creature) riel et fondamental (causalitb) et de la nait la possibilitb de
1'analogie." As before, the Italian edition has no substantive variation from the French:
"Si tratta che nel primo casr> la somiglianaa b di natura formaie e lascia inratto il divino
isolamento, mentre nel secondo caso il rapporto diventa (nella creatura) reale e fondante
(causalita) e sorgc percio la possibilita dell'analogia" (Fabro, Purtsapugions c cuttsutitu,506).
s9 See n58 above. ~ Mitchell, Being unrt Purtiapution,vol. 2, 492. Cf. 485.

86

You might also like