You are on page 1of 11

RICHARD SHUSTERMAN

Photography as Performative Process

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


i Heterogeneity and novelty are familiar themes
in theorizing photography. Faced with its in-
Photography pervades our lives. Its multiple and tractable diversity (that he described as an “un-
wide-ranging roles make it not only ubiquitous classifiable” “disorder”), Roland Barthes won-
but also immensely diverse. There are photo IDs, dered whether photography had an essence but
all sorts and styles of advertising images, docu- then argued that its “essence . . . can only be (if it
mentary shots of news and sports events, criminal exists at all) the New of which it has been the ad-
“wanted” posters, scientific photographs to serve vent.”2 Walter Benjamin even more influentially
either as heuristics in the process of discovery or as characterized photography in terms of its trans-
evidentiary tools for proof and teaching, portrait formational novelty. Besides generating the fur-
shots of individuals, families, or other groups (in- ther novelty of cinema, photography’s powers of
cluding school or conference pictures), candidly mechanical reproduction “transformed the entire
intimate photos reserved for someone special, per- nature of art” by shifting art from its original es-
sonal travel photos (now typically in digital form sentially ritualistic use (with its auratic cult value
and shared with friends through some Internet of the authentic original) to an “absolute empha-
network), and then there is art photography, which sis on its exhibition value” instead. Moreover, its
is what concerns me here and which constitutes a automatic mechanism of capturing attractive, ac-
diversely mixed genre in itself. curate pictorial images likewise removed the tra-
A distinctively modern art (one not to be found ditional need for skilled artistic hands to create
in Hegel’s famous nineteenth-century classifica- them: “For the first time in the process of picto-
tory rankings), photography’s association with rial reproduction, photography freed the hand of
newness is not merely temporal, but indeed re- the most important artistic functions which hence-
flects a tendency toward continuing innovation. forth devolved only upon the eye looking into a
Its original photochemical film technique engen- lens.”3
dered new forms such as movies and videos, but it Given such heterogeneous and innovative ten-
also led to the new varieties of digital photography dencies, I dare not presume that there must be
that dispense with the photochemistry of film and a distinct and permanent essence of photography
instead use sensors that convert light into elec- whose identity it is my duty as theorist to define.
trical charges that are then digitally analyzed and If there is such an essence, I hope this article will
converted back into images. Photography’s artistic shed light on it, but my purpose here is rather
uses display continuing innovation, such as the dis- to highlight a dimension of photographic art that
tinctive trend that began in the late 1970s of creat- has been largely neglected but that can constitute
ing very large-scale photographs expressly meant the locus of real aesthetic experience and value.
for posting on the gallery wall and typically “sum- This dimension concerns the performative process
moning a confrontational experience on the part of making a photograph of a human subject and
of the spectator that sharply contrasts with the the sorts of artistic performances and aesthetic
habitual processes of appropriation and projec- experiences that this process involves.4 These per-
tion whereby photographic images are normally formances and experiences have a clearly somatic
received and consumed.”1 aspect that I initially failed to recognize despite my


c 2012 The American Society for Aesthetics
68 The Media of Photography

interest in developing a somaesthetic perspective aspects of artistic creativity and aesthetic expe-
on art.5 There is likewise a salient dramatic dimen- rience. These can be manifested not only in the
sion to the photographic performative process photographer’s mise-en-scène of himself, his cam-
that also escaped me, despite my having advanced era, and his subject within the photographic con-
a general theory of art as dramatization.6 The text and process, but also in the photographed
import of these somatic and dramatic aspects of subject’s posing, self-presentation, or self-styling
photography only recently became evident to me before the camera within the mise-en-scène of the
through collaborations with photographic artists photographic situation and in critical communi-
and curators interested in somaesthetics.7 I then cation with the photographer. Indeed, if commu-
realized that photography’s dimension of somatic, nicative expression in artistic creation contributes
dramatic, performative process (and its potential significantly to the value of aesthetic experience,

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


for enhanced artistic use and aesthetic experience) then the communicative interaction between pho-
is occluded by our one-sided concentration on the tographer and subject in the process of setting up
photograph itself (a static object), with which we and taking the shot could provide a rich source for
tend to identify photographic art. such experiential value.
I argue, however, that an important distinction Why have these aesthetic aspects of photogra-
can be made between photography and the pho- phy as process been neglected? It is not enough to
tograph.8 Although the photograph (whether in posit our one-sided preoccupation with the pho-
hard-copy print or in digital display) is surely the tograph as the sole explanation of this neglect, be-
standard end product of photography and con- cause that preoccupation may itself be partly the
ventionally recognized as the goal and work of result of other reasons that discourage attention
photographic art, there is more to photography to photography as performative process. I there-
than the photograph. To appreciate this distinc- fore devote a brief concluding section to discussing
tion and see that the photograph and its aesthetic those other reasons.
perception are only part of a larger complex of el-
ements that constitutes photography as an activity
and as an art, we first need to examine these other ii
elements, which include the photographer, the tar-
get that he photographs, the photographic equip- In its simplest form, the photographic situation
ment, and the spatiotemporal context or scene treated here involves a photographer, a human
in which the target is posed and photographed. subject who knowingly and willingly serves as the
In reducing photography to the photograph, we photographic target, the camera (with its neces-
diminish its aesthetic scope and power by limit- sary accessory photographic equipment), and the
ing the elements that can manifest artistic value scene or context in which the photography ses-
and provide aesthetic experience. Moreover, as sion takes place.10 What I wish to highlight as
the essential meaning of the photograph (at least the photographic process of performance is es-
in philosophical discussions) often gets reduced to sentially what goes on in the process of setting up,
the object photographed, so reducing the aesthet- preparing, and taking the photographic shots in a
ics of photography to the photograph risks reduc- photography session. Although the technique of
ing it to the aesthetics of an object (that is, the film photography involves the further process of
real-world referent) actually outside the photo- developing the film to produce a negative (or pos-
graph, hence allegedly beyond photography, and itive) image, this procedure does not involve the
this would leave the aesthetic value of photogra- artistic process and interaction between photogra-
phy gravely in question.9 pher and subject whose neglected aesthetic poten-
Given the diversity of photographic art, I limit tial I explore in this article.11 For the same reason,
my analysis to photographic art that takes a know- although art photography also includes the subse-
ing, voluntary individual human subject as its pho- quent critical process of selecting which shots are
tographic target. By that I mean a human subject worth exhibiting and what the best ways to mount
who is both aware that she is being photographed or show them are, I do not discuss that process
and is also willing to be. In articulating key ele- here but instead focus on the aesthetic experience
ments of the artistic photographic process, I sug- of photography before the existence of the photo-
gest how some of them can display significant graph that is its product.
Shusterman Photography as Performative Process 69

i. Taking a photographic shot, like any action Because we typically associate somatic effort with
we perform, always involves some bodily action. large and strenuous movements, we are apt to ig-
At the bare minimum one must use a body part nore the sort of somaesthetic skills of fine-motor
to activate the camera’s shutter release, usually control that are involved in mastering the art of
by an action involving one’s fingers. But there operating a camera, even in everyday snapshots.
are obviously further somatic skills, like properly Moreover, in certain kinds of art photography, the
steadying the camera in one’s hands to ensure a photographer’s somatic efforts can be much more
clear shot and also being able to maneuver effec- demanding.
tively one’s photographic equipment along with Besides the somatic skill of controlling one’s
one’s own bodily position, posture, and balance camera, posture, and balance, there is also the pho-
so that one can best aim the camera to get the tographer’s skill in winning the confidence of the

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


desired optical image. Taking a picture is a bod- person photographed. This is important for mak-
ily act that requires a certain effort and compe- ing the subject feel more comfortable and coop-
tence of somatic self-use, despite the advertising erative rather than guarded and ill at ease, thus
myth that photographic technology is so mag- rendering her more suitable for photography’s
ically simple that even a child or dumb brute dominant dual aims of not only portraying the
can produce an excellent photo. This need for real, but also producing aesthetic objects and ex-
somatic skill despite photography’s mechanical periences, even from people who in real life are
magic is comically thematized in Buster Keaton’s painfully unattractive. Susan Sontag thus praises
The Cameraman (Edward Sedgwick, 1928), where Diane Arbus’s frontal photographs of “freaks and
the hero clumsily struggles with his photographic pariahs” for capturing “subjects . . . one would not
equipment, knocking out windows and doors expect to surrender themselves so amiably and
with his tripod, while his pet monkey man- generously to the camera. . . . To get these people
ages to load and aim the camera with consider- to pose, the photographer has had to gain their
ably less clumsiness and more success, producing confidence,” and this requires social skills that also
some excellent footage of fighting in New York’s have a somaesthetic dimension.12 For instance, the
Chinatown. photographer’s body language must not be threat-
In real life, I have witnessed many comic in- ening; it must be friendly, even in a way intimate,
stances of the photographer’s need for somatic but not intrusive. Her somatic style needs to dis-
control and awareness, such as friends losing their play a quality of keen attentiveness and interest
balance and falling off a curb or into a pool as regarding the person photographed (even if that
they backed up to get a better shot, eyes locked attention and interest are merely transitory and
on the optical image in the camera, hands tightly professional and thus not really genuine in a sub-
grasping the camera itself. Some people like pho- stantively ethical sense). This quality of attention
tography but dislike taking pictures because of and interest, somaesthetically projected by the
its somatic constraints; they prefer having their photographer and perceived by the subject (often
hands unencumbered and their gaze free to sur- only implicitly by both parties), will be displayed
vey the horizon rather than narrowly fixed on a in posture, gesture, and facial expression.13
small aperture or screen held in their hands. There The photographer’s expression of sympathetic,
are good evolutionary reasons why one would in- attentive interest is not simply necessary for
stinctively want to have one’s hands free for ac- putting a subject at ease, but further aids as a
tion and one’s gaze free to survey the horizon and stimulus in engaging the subject’s own attentive in-
thus more readily able to identify friends, prey, terest and heightened focus on the photographic
and predators at a distance. Though many peo- situation or event. It is as if the photographer’s
ple, on the contrary, love to use cameras and feel quality of attention and presence infects the pho-
empowered by wielding them, it is obvious that tographed subject as well, thus raising her quality
handling, looking through a camera, and taking a of presence that can then be captured in the result-
good shot involve sensorimotor skills that need to ing photograph, a presence that transfigures even
be learned. Some people need considerable prac- ordinary faces into beautifully expressive ones.
tice to master the control of breathing and steadi- The masterful Richard Avedon describes this pro-
ness of hands to keep the camera firmly fixed to cess of contagion where the subjects come to him
take a clear picture, and some never master it. “to be photographed as they would go to a doctor
70 The Media of Photography

or a fortune teller—to find out how they are” and Barthes knows his image will ultimately be con-
in the hope of feeling better through the transfigu- trolled by the photographer and the photographic
rative experience of self-exposure before a charis- equipment, so there is the added anxiety of having
matic observer: no real control of the self that will emerge from
his creative posing, “the anguish” of not knowing
I have to engage them. Otherwise there’s nothing to whether one will be reborn as an “antipathetic in-
photograph. The concentration has to come from me dividual” or “a good sort”; and this anxiety exacer-
and involve them. Sometimes the force of it grows so bates the discomfort or awkwardness of posing.17
strong that sounds in the studio go unheard. Time stops. A further difficulty is how to organize oneself
We share a brief, intense intimacy. But . . . when the sit- somatically in the pose to achieve the look one
ting is over . . . there’s nothing left except the photo- wants to convey. It is not easy to control one’s fa-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


graph . . . the photograph and a kind of embarrassment.14 cial and postural expression, especially when one
cannot use a mirror but must instead rely only on
This experience of deeply felt and focused com- proprioception. Barthes provides a wonderful de-
municative expression structured through the scription of this effort to strike the right pose: “I
mise-en-scène of the photographic process is a don’t know how to work on my skin from within.
form of aesthetic experience whose transfiguring I decide to ‘let drift’ over my lips and eyes a faint
intensity can indeed leave its participants embar- smile which I mean to be indefinable, in which
rassed once the drama of the shooting is over and I might suggest, along with the qualities of my
they return to their everyday selves and routine. nature, my amused consciousness of the whole
Of course, photography that seeks veracity and photographic ritual.”18 For Barthes, there are two
drama by catching its subject up close yet totally essential and discomforting paradoxes in the act
unaware involves an altogether different sort of of photographic posing or self-presentation. First
photographic skill. Its secrecy generally includes is the desire for the photographic image to “co-
a dimension of somatic virtuosity in order to keep incide with my (‘profound’) self,” while knowing
the camera (or at least its use) concealed. Think, that “‘myself’ never coincides with my image”; the
for example, of how Walker Evans secretly took “Photograph is the advent of myself as other.”19
his close-up, frontal shots of New York subway Second, the posing subject is made into an ob-
passengers, “with the lens of his camera peering ject, not only in the actual photographic print but
between two buttons of his topcoat,” so that he in the very process of objectifying oneself before
could catch them unaware that they were being the camera, by representing or reshaping oneself
considered as photographic objects and thus cap- through one’s pose. Such a process, Barthes con-
ture a look free from any posing, posturing, or fesses, makes him “invariably suffer from a sensa-
self-consciousness. Some prefer such candid shots; tion of inauthenticity, sometimes of imposture.”20
others find them ethically suspect. But there is lit- “I am neither subject nor object but a subject who
tle doubt that people display a different demeanor feels he is becoming an object.”21 Such feelings
when they know they are being photographed, make it difficult to achieve an attractive pose.
and often there is something awkward, artificial, The subject who poses for a photograph there-
or false about it.15 fore has an important aesthetic role to perform: to
escape these feelings of inauthenticity and render
ii. Overcoming the awkwardness of posing also her pose less awkward, forced, and false or, to put
requires from the photographic subject a certain it positively, to render herself more photographi-
talent or effort, no matter how skillful the pho- cally attractive by being more vitally or authenti-
tographer is at making his subject feel natural cally present. Though Barthes himself lacked this
and uninhibited in exposing herself to the cam- skill, he recognized it in his mother, a skill in posing
era. Barthes poignantly confesses his own complex through which “she ‘let’ herself be photographed”
problems as a posing subject. On the one hand, in a free and natural way that would suggest her
as soon as he knows that he is “observed by the “essential identity,” even when the different pho-
lens,” Barthes feels the need to reconstitute him- tographs did not fully capture it: “she triumphed
self “in the process of posing. . . . I instantaneously over this ideal of placing herself in front of the lens
make another body for myself, I transform myself (an inevitable action) with discretion (but without
in advance into an image.”16 On the other hand, a touch of the tense theatricalism of humility or
Shusterman Photography as Performative Process 71

sulkiness). . . . She did not trouble with her image, harmony of understanding, even a sense of inti-
as I do with mine: she did not suppose herself.”22 mate collaborative expression. I suspect that there
Knowing the camera’s power to make a perma- are implicit hints or diminished analogues of such
nent and widely reproducible image, the person at feelings in the participatory pleasures of snapshots
whom the camera is directed instinctively recom- in everyday popular photographic art. In the hur-
poses his image, transforms his expression or pos- ried, pressured flow of life and its hectic activities
ture, and typically arrests his movement in order to in which individuals are bent on achieving their
strike an effective pose. He stylizes himself, even own ends and meeting their duties, one pauses
if only minimally and barely self-consciously, for and poses for a photographic moment while one’s
the camera. Barthes laments this posing effect as companion (in tourism, in partying, in business or
a betrayal of personal identity, as the objectifying family affairs) also pauses and concentrates her at-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


of a subject, as the transformation of an indefin- tention on making the best of this shared moment
able essence of lived, inner identity into a frozen by taking a snapshot that both she and the posing
external image that traps and stifles his felt flow subject (or subjects) can enjoy. The performative
of subjectivity. But the problem here (as Barthes process of photography provides a heightened,
almost seems to recognize) may be that he takes framed moment of enjoying something together
himself or his identity too seriously and essentially. and underlying that sharing by an intentionally
With a more creative, fluid attitude, one can see collaborative creative act that witnesses it.
the camera’s invitation to pose as an opportunity
to create a new look, a new posture, a new element iii. The camera is the essential element in the
in the construction of the self whose identity is not photographic situation that turns the encounter
a fixed essence but an ongoing project whose con- between photographer and the voluntary subject
tinuous construction can either reinforce habitual into a scene of posing that so often renders the
modes of being or creatively seek new ones. In subject ill at ease despite her willingness to be
some forms of art photography, the subject can photographed. This is not merely the feeling of
be creatively spurred to creative self-fashioning, wanting to project a certain look to the public,
to experiment with different poses, costumes, ex- to be seen by others in a specific way that may
pressions, attitudes; and the special situation of an not be precisely the way one actually is or feels
art photography session provides a circumscribed, at that moment. Such a desire is present in many
protected stage to try out such experiments and kinds of social situations where we perform the
then resume one’s habitual modes of being and role playing of self-presentation in everyday life
self-presentation if one prefers them (or requires without feeling especially self-conscious. But the
them) for dealing with the needs of everyday life. camera thematizes this self-presentation, making
For purposes of analysis, I have separately ar- it explicit by focusing on framing a particular mo-
ticulated the somaesthetic skills and aesthetic ex- ment of such self-presentation and fixing it in a
perience of photographer and subject. But as the permanent image that objectifies and defines the
discussion of Arbus and Avedon has already sug- self in terms of that experiential moment, an image
gested, the somatic comportment and aesthetic ex- that can be indefinitely reproduced and circulated
perience of photographer and subject (though ob- as a representation of what the self really is.
viously distinguishable and often very different) The camera thus creates a particular pressure
cannot be completely separated because what is of posing not only because it typically requires the
involved is an essentially communicative, partici- subject to arrest her movement (or at least con-
patory process, an interactive dance of pose and trol it) to ensure that her image is captured clearly
gestures, even if the subject’s movement is con- but also because it raises the stakes of one’s self-
fined to positioning of the head and facial expres- presentation by harboring the threat of perma-
sions. In cases where there is excellently empa- nently representing the self as an object in ways
thetic communication, subject and photographer that the self as subject may not want to be rep-
can inspire each other toward creative improvisa- resented or defined. Though experience itself is
tions in the mise-en-scène and realization of the elusively evanescent and significantly subjective,
shot, and they can thus enjoy a powerfully shared the photograph has the powers of durability, fixity,
aesthetic experience of creativity, a pleasurable and objectivity that belong to real physical things.
72 The Media of Photography

These powers constitute one reason why the expe- of picture-taking, which must be the sole activ-
riential process of photography is obscured by the ity resulting in accredited works of art in which
photograph as object. In thus framing a real mo- a single movement, a touch of the finger, pro-
ment and giving it permanence, public represen- duces a complete work.”25 The instantaneous act
tation, and wide-ranging reproducibility and cir- of shutter release likewise suggests that there is
culation, the camera intensifies or magnifies that no sustained duration of effort involved as one
moment; it dramatizes it in precisely the way in would expect in a performative process.26 These
which I argue that all art dramatizes things by reasons, however, neglect the complex performa-
putting them in an intensifying frame and thus tive process that occurs before the shutter release
giving them a sense of heightened reality or vivid- and the camera’s ensuing mechanism of producing
ness.23 the photographic image. But that prior process—

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


involving the mise-en-scène performative activ-
iv. The performative process of having a subject ity of the photographer and the posing subject—is
pose for the camera always involves posing that necessary for achieving the desired optical image
subject in some setting—a situational or environ- in the camera lens that one then seeks to fix in the
mental background that, if successful, can enhance photographic image.
the interest and quality of the photographic act The fact that this performative process is onto-
and resulting photograph. Important situations logically complex and difficult to demarcate in its
(such as a wedding or a funeral) can give special experiential dimensions provides further reasons
meaning and gravitas to a work of photography for its neglect. The process is complex in that it
and provide a characteristic background with rele- involves the action and thought of both the pho-
vant props imbued with situational meaning. If the tographer and the subject; it is difficult to define
posing subject can be likened to an actor, then de- not only because it involves the elusive experien-
termining the background can be likened to stage tial flow of these two subjectivities but also be-
setting. If the photography studio offers only a cause its physical actions of positioning and pos-
limited range of situations and backgrounds, then ing are typically performed without a formal script
it compensates by providing better control of the or scenario that defines the mise-en-scène, clearly
settings it does provide (for example, by regulat- demarcating its essential components and struc-
ing conditions of light and temperature and pre- ture.27 Moreover, as an experiential event, the per-
venting excessive noise, crowds, or other factors formance is transient and cannot strictly speaking
that would interfere with producing a desired im- be perfectly repeated, if we admit that the sub-
age of the subject). Here again, in the choice and ject’s expression and state of consciousness (if not
regulation of situations or backgrounds, there is also the photographer’s posture and feelings) will
considerable room for aesthetic mise-en-scène— always change in some way, even if only through
an artistic dramatization that intensifies experi- the recognition that one is repeating the mise-en-
ence through formal framing or stage setting well scène of a prior shooting. Though the photograph
before the photographer decides to release the documents in some way the performative process
mechanism that produces the photograph. through which it is engendered, it only documents
a particular moment in that process and does so
iii from a particular angle and in terms of its visual
qualities. But the performative process itself in-
Besides our preoccupation with the photograph cludes also other sensory, semantic, and affective
as object, other factors contribute to obscuring qualities that have aesthetic import and whose re-
the aesthetic significance of photography as per- sources for aesthetic experience in photography
formative process. First, the automatic mechanism should not be ignored.
involved in making a photograph—the fact that Still another likely reason for such neglect
pressing the release of the camera shutter requires is that the photographer and the subject—who
no special skill or thought and that the camera are the best (and often the only) candidates
mechanism automatically does all the rest to pro- for observing and appreciating the performative
duce a realistic photograph—diminishes the sense process—may be too absorbed in performing the
of photography as a performance achievement.24 process to pay proper attention to its aesthetic
Thus, Susan Sontag speaks of “the effortlessness qualities and potential. Because our powers of
Shusterman Photography as Performative Process 73

consciousness are limited, the efficacy of actions while its performative, temporal dimension was
is often harmed if we also pay distinct reflexive at- neglected.
tention to the precise feelings that we have or the We should recall, however, that photography’s
qualities that we experience in performing those early history had strong links to theater as well as
actions. So it is understandable for photographer to painting. Daguerre, an influential photography
and subject to execute the performative process pioneer in Paris, “was running a panorama the-
without thematizing its actions and qualities in ex- ater animated by light shows and movements in
plicit, reflective consciousness, even if they implic- the Place du Château” when he began his photo-
itly feel them and use them to guide and inspire graphic work, while Baudelaire condemned pho-
their performance. tography for “committing a double sacrilege and
If such “parsimony of consciousness” is a psy- insulting at one and the same time the divine art

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


chological commonplace, it has an analogue or a of painting and the noble art of the actor.”32 To
corollary in the familiar notion of aesthetic dis- dismiss photography’s performative, dramatizing
tance—namely, that a certain psychological dis- process as not really belonging to photography
tance or detachment from an object or event aids per se but instead pertaining merely to theater is
the appreciation of its aesthetic features. When not only wrong historically—it errs conceptually in
one is in the performative moment, one is by presuming that photographic art exists in a pure
definition very close to it; when one is looking form, unmarked by other arts that helped engen-
at a photograph, one is by definition distanced der it.
from the real moment taken by the photograph, Walter Benjamin’s influential views on pho-
a moment that has already passed or died. “Aes- tography, as formulated in his most famous and
thetic distance seems built into the very experi- oft-cited essay “The Work of Art in the Age of
ence of looking at photographs,” writes Sontag.28 Mechanical Reproduction,” can generate a fur-
For such reasons, she and Barthes link photogra- ther line of reasoning for theory’s ignoring the
phy very closely with death. “All photographs are aesthetics of photography’s performative process
momento mori,” Sontag claims: “To take a pho- while focusing on the photograph as the sole site
tograph is to participate in another person’s (or for photography’s aesthetic experience. Benjamin
thing’s) mortality. . . . Precisely by slicing out this (whom Sontag describes as “photography’s most
moment and freezing it, all photographs testify original and important critic”) argued that pho-
to time’s relentless melt.”29 For Barthes, because tography’s epoch-making transformation of art
the photograph presents “the absolute past of the through mechanical reproduction involved chang-
pose,” it constitutes “an image which produces ing art’s essential nature from cult value to ex-
Death while trying to preserve life.”30 hibition value.33 If art originally emerged from
The history of photography’s theoretical recep- “magic” and religious ritual “with ceremonial ob-
tion provides two other reasons for neglect of its jects destined to serve in a cult” whose transcen-
art of performative process. From the outset, pho- dent quality imbued artworks with an elevated
tography was seen as an analogue and rival to sense of “aura” and “unique existence,” then pho-
the art of painting. If Baudelaire described “the tography (as “the first truly revolutionary means
photographic industry [as] the refuge of every of reproduction”) “emancipates the work of art
would-be painter, every painter too ill-endowed from its parasitical dependence on ritual” and “the
or too lazy to complete his studies,” and thus unique value of the ‘authentic’ work” that has its
“art’s most mortal enemy,” others defended pho- role in ritual or cultic use, for “to ask for the [one]
tography for liberating painting from the duty authentic print makes no sense.”34
of mimetic exactness that the photograph could Art’s essential nature, Benjamin claims, was
more easily and better provide instead.31 As paint- therefore transformed from emphasizing “cult
ing is grouped with the nontemporal, nonper- value” (where the work could serve effectively
formative arts, whose end product is a flat ob- even when hidden from view but recognized as
ject portraying a two-dimensional image and is being kept in its hallowed place) to instead em-
immediately grasped without unfolding in time, phasizing “the exhibition value of a work,” be-
so photography (through association with paint- cause the work’s “fitness for exhibition increased”
ing) came to be identified entirely with its two- through photography’s new powers of “mechani-
dimensional end product or photograph as object cal reproduction.”35 What gets widely exhibited
74 The Media of Photography

through such mechanical reproduction is the long duration of these shots they grew as it were
photographic print (or now, ever increasingly, the into the picture and in this way presented an
digital photographic image). So if art has essen- extreme opposite to the figures on a snapshot.”
tially lost its function as ritual (which is a perfor- And this absorption of the subject, Benjamin fur-
mative process), but instead is constituted by an ther suggests, had a counterpart in the photogra-
“absolute emphasis on exhibition value,” then one pher’s absorption and his ability to make his sub-
might argue that the art of photography should jects feel comfortably “at home,” for example, by
be identified with the photograph (where exhi- deploying the camera with “discrete reserve.” If
bition value is manifest), while its performative, Benjamin gives the impression that such early
experiential process (rarely exhibited and, in its photography provided a profound, sustained ex-
inner experiential dimensions, difficult to exhibit) perience of performative process, then this kind

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


should be conversely dismissed as irrelevant or of experience could still be available today if one
anachronistic.36 only took the time, care, and effort to develop this
Despite the apparent force of this argument, dimension of photographic art.
there remains a distinctive ritualistic element in I close this article by cautioning against two
photography. Many ritual events (weddings, grad- possible misunderstandings. In arguing that there
uations, baptisms, conference meetings, award cer- is more to photography than the photograph and
emonies, and so on) expressly include the taking that photography can be aesthetically appreciated
of posed pictures that serve not simply to recall as performative process, I do not mean to neglect
the event in future times, but also to mark out and or diminish the undeniable aesthetic importance
heighten the current moment as one worth savor- of photographs. Photography is a mixed art serv-
ing in present experience by putting that moment ing multiple ends, and its diverse values are best
in a formal frame or mise-en-scène that drama- appreciated in a framework of pragmatic plural-
tizes its qualitative presence and meaning. Though ism. Second, I do not believe that photography
serving as the relentless motor of exhibition value, is unique among the arts in offering an aesthetic
photography still displays a ritual dimension of experience not only of its standard artistic end
performative, dramatizing process. Is it mere co- product but also of its creative process. Portrait
incidence that contemporary cultures still strongly painting provides a very clear analogue of the sort
shaped by rich aesthetic traditions of ritual (such of collaborative performative process that I have
as Japan’s) display an especially strong tendency described in photography, and, in fact, it seems
to perform the process of taking photographs in some ways somatically far more demanding on
with a dedication and style suggestive of ritual both subject and artist, which may be why some
performance? artists now prefer to paint from photographs of
Moreover, a closer look at Benjamin’s views their subjects. To highlight a neglected aspect of
on photography reveals that he indeed recognized the art of photography is not to erect that aspect
the photograph’s power to maintain art’s auratic into the distinctive, defining essence of that art, if
“cult value,” for instance, in “the cult of remem- it indeed has one.39
brance of loved ones, absent or dead.”37 In an ear-
lier, less familiar essay explicitly devoted to pho- RICHARD SHUSTERMAN
tography, he insists on this “magical value” and College of Arts and Letters
“auratic appearance,” affirming that the portrait Florida Atlantic University
subjects of “early photography” indeed “had an Boca Raton, Florida 33431
aura about them.”38 But this was destroyed when
photography was “invaded on all sides by busi- internet: shuster1@fau.edu
nessmen” who, “more concerned with eventual
saleability than with understanding,” pandered to 1. Jean-François Chevrier, “The Adventures of the Pic-
“changing lights of fashion” and reduced the ex- ture Form in the History of Photography,” trans. Michael
perienced time and absorption of posing toward Gilson, in The Last Picture Show: Artists Using Photogra-
phy, 1960–1982 (Minneapolis: Walker Art Center), exhibi-
the momentary “snapshot.” Benjamin also praises
tion catalogue curated by Douglas Fogle, pp. 113–127, at
early photography for the way it required its sub- p. 116. Michael Fried cites and develops Chevrier’s insight
jects “to live inside rather than outside the mo- in Why Photography Matters as Art as Never Before (Yale
ment” of the photographic shoot: “During the University Press, 2008). Susan Sontag claims that earlier
Shusterman Photography as Performative Process 75

“the book has been the most influential way of arranging thetics: Principles and Scope,” Journal of Aesthetic Educa-
(and usually miniaturizing) photographs,” in her influen- tion 40 (2006): 104–117; and the articles of the special issue
tial On Photography (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, devoted to somaesthetics in Action, Criticism, and Theory
1977), p. 4. for Music Education 9 (2010). The article there by Fred
2. Roland Barthes, Camera Lucida: Reflections on Pho- Maus is especially illuminating. See also the somaesthetic
tography, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Hill and Wang, anthology Penser en corps: soma-esthétique, art et philoso-
1981), p. 4. Later, however, when Barthes focuses his discus- phie, ed. Barbara Formis (Paris: L’harmattan, 2009). For
sion of photography on the photograph, he describes its a full bibliography of work on somaesthetics by authors
“very essence” in terms of reference to the past. “What I other than me, see http://www.fau.edu/humanitieschair/
intentionalize in a photograph is neither Art nor Communi- Somaesthetics_Bibliography_Others.php.
cation, it is reference. . . . The name of Photography’s noeme 6. See Richard Shusterman, “Art as Dramatization,” The
would therefore be ‘That has been’” (pp. 76–77). As an “em- Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (2001): 361–372.
anation of past reality,” he continues, “the Photograph . . . is 7. Since June 2010, I have been working with the Parisian

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


without future (this is its pathos, its melancholy)” (pp. 88, artist Yann Toma on a series of photographic works in the
90). Barthes’s paradoxical identification of photography’s genre he calls “Radiant Flux,” in which he tries to capture
essence with both future and past might be mitigated by and visually represent (with lights and camera) the invisible
insisting on a distinction between photography and the pho- aura of the person posing for him, an aura he conceives and
tograph. In this article, I will argue for this distinction but perceives as a temporally changing energetic force emanat-
primarily for reasons other than this paradox of Barthes. ing from the person’s body. He builds on the etymological
3. Walter Benjamin, “The Work of Art in the Age of meaning of “photography” as drawing with light, but also on
Mechanical Reproduction,” in Illuminations, trans. Harry the work of Man Ray, the first known photographer to use
Zohn (New York: Schocken, 1969), pp. 227, 225, 219. this technique in his series called “Space Writing” of 1935.
4. David Davies, Art as Performance (Oxford: I describe Toma’s work and our collaboration in my (illus-
Blackwell, 2004), has argued for the far more extreme claim trated) essay “A Philosopher in Darkness and in Light,” in
that artworks in general (not just in photography) are not Lucidité. Vues de l’intérieur / Lucidity. Inward Views: Le
the physical objects with which they are commonly identi- Mois de la Photo à Montréal 2011, ed. Anne-Marie Ni-
fied but rather the actual performances of artists that create nacs (Montreal: Le Mois de la Photo à Montréal, 2011).
such objects and that to appreciate those objects properly Some photographs of our collaboration have been pub-
always requires relating them to the actual performance lished as part of a French article and interview on my work
that (according to this theory) is the work. I do not sub- in somaesthetics (see http://www.tales-magazine.fr/style-
scribe to this radically revisionist ontological and aesthetic harmony-life-vision/richard_shusterman). For further dis-
theory that departs too much from our established (and cussion of this collaboration and its relationship to so-
far more complex) conceptual scheme to be convincing. In maesthetics, see Richard Shusterman, Thinking Through the
arguing for the artistic dimension and aesthetic value of Body: Essays in Somaesthetics (Cambridge University Press,
the (dramatic, somatic) performative process of photogra- forthcoming).
phy, I am not urging that this process deprive the photo- 8. In his historically rich and instructive book, Patrick
graph of its artwork status by usurping its role as the stan- Maynard also insists on distinguishing photography as some-
dard end product of photography. Nor am I arguing that thing different from and more than the photograph. But he
the photograph must be evaluated in terms of the perfor- uses this distinction to argue his central thesis that “pho-
mance that engenders it: process and product can be judged tography is a kind of technology” or, more precisely, “a
separately and with different evaluative verdicts. My mod- branching family of technologies” or “set of technological
est position is rather that photography is a complex art procedures” rather than to argue, as I do here, for the aes-
that offers various objects for aesthetic appreciation (such thetic dimensions of the performative and experiential pro-
as photographs and photographic performance processes cess of photographic art. See Patrick Maynard, The Engine
or events) and that these objects are differently individu- of Visualization: Thinking Through Photography (Cornell
ated for our purposes of aesthetic appreciation. Our indi- University Press, 1997), pp. x, 3, 9.
viduation of the performative process of a photo session 9. Both continental and analytic theorists often insist on
would diverge sharply from the way we identify a partic- the photograph’s direct and transparent presentation of the
ular photographic image or a photographic print that re- object it renders (rather than being a mediated represen-
sults from a particular moment or part of that performative tation of it) because it results from a mechanical, causal
process. process. Barthes describes the photograph as “pure deic-
5. For an introductory outline of the somaesthetic tic language; . . . a photograph is always invisible: it is not it
project, see Richard Shusterman, “Somaesthetics: A Dis- that we see,” but “its referent,” the object photographed
ciplinary Proposal,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criti- (Barthes, Camera Lucida, pp. 5, 6). Sontag speaks of such
cism 57 (1999): 299–313; for the most comprehensive discus- transparency in terms of the photograph’s “identity of image
sion, see my Body Consciousness: A Philosophy of Mindful- and object,” its presenting “a piece of the world” through
ness and Somaesthetics (Cambridge University Press, 2008). “mechanical genesis”; hence in appreciating photography,
For discussions relating somaesthetics to the arts, see, for ex- the object or “what the photographic is of is always of pri-
ample, Martin Jay, “Somaesthetics and Democracy: Dewey mary importance” (Sontag, On Photography, pp. 98, 158).
and Contemporary Body Art,” Journal of Aesthetic Ed- Roger Scruton, from the perspective of analytic aesthetics,
ucation 36 (2002): 55–68; Peter Arnold, “Somaesthetics, claims, “the photograph is transparent to its subject, and
Education, and the Art of Dance,” Journal of Aesthetic Edu- if it holds our interest, it does so because it acts as a sur-
cation 39 (2005): 48–64; Eric Mullis, “Performative Somaes- rogate for the thing which it shows.” This is because the
76 The Media of Photography

relationship of the photograph to its generating process is 23. See Richard Shusterman, “Art as Dramatization.” In
“causal not intentional”; hence “photography is not a rep- his influential work on photography, Laszlo Moholy-Nagy
resentational art.” See his “Photography and Representa- (of the Bauhaus) speaks of how this art can produce a
tion,” in The Aesthetic Understanding (London: Methuen, “heightened reality of an everyday object.” See his Paint-
1983), pp. 103, 114. Kendall Walton also speaks of the pho- ing, Photography, Film, trans. Janet Seligman (1925; repr.
tograph’s transparency in “Transparent Pictures: On the Na- MIT Press, 1987), p. 62.
ture of Photographic Realism,” Noûs 18 (1984): 67–72. For 24. Sontag writes, “The sales pitch for the first Kodak,
a useful analytic reconstruction and response to Scruton’s in 1888, was: ‘You press the button, we do the rest.’ The
argument, see Dominic McIver Lopes, “The Aesthetics of purchaser was guaranteed that the picture would be ‘without
Photographic Transparency,” Mind 36 (2003): 335–348. error’” (Sontag, On Photography, p. 53).
10. The photographer and the subject photographed can, 25. Sontag, On Photography, p. 164.
in principle, be the same person, though performing the 26. It is interesting that in contrast to the art of paint-
different functions. ing, whose noun has a gerund form suggesting action over

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024


11. Digital photography, which immediately provides a time, photography does not. Though we do use the verb
photographic image, does not require the process of devel- “to photograph,” we more often speak of “taking/making a
oping and fixing the image but does allow further creative photograph” or “taking a picture.”
processes such as enlarging and cropping the photographic 27. One structural issue of demarcation is when the per-
image. formative process begins. Clearly, the photographer can plan
12. Sontag, On Photography, p. 38. the setting, the camera settings, the desired poses, or outfit
13. For more on somatic style and its relation to qualities of the subject well before he meets with the subject at the
of character, including ethical qualities, see Richard Shus- chosen photographic setting. This perhaps means that the
terman, “Somatic Style,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art performative process can begin without the photographic
Criticism 69 (2011): 143–155. target or subject, even though some such subject will always
14. This quote from Avedon is taken from Sontag, On be implied.
Photography, p. 187. 28. Sontag, On Photography, p. 21.
15. See Sontag, On Photography, pp. 36–37, for these 29. Sontag, On Photography, p. 15.
points. Important ethical issues can also arise when sub- 30. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 92.
jects know they are posing for the camera. For example, the 31. See Charles Baudelaire, “The Salon of 1859,” in
photographer may abuse the confidence and trust that the Art in Paris, 1845–1862, trans. Jonathan Mayne (London:
posing subject grants him and exploit the subject’s openness Phaidon, 1965), pp. 153–154. Delacroix offered early praise
and cooperation by creating a photograph that presents the of photography for its benefits to painting in providing a
subject in a way she does not want to be presented, in a far clearer vision of real objects than drawing could, while
permanent, infinitely reproducible and displayable image Weston in the following century argued that photography
that violates the subject’s own self-image. Arthur Danto was a great gift to painting by relieving it of “public de-
notes how Richard Avedon cruelly violates the trust of a mands” for “representation,” by making “realistic painting
transvestite subject—the psychologically delicate and phys- superfluous,” so painting could focus on other goals than
ically “willowy” Candy Darling—by photographing “her” exact representation. See Edward Weston, “Photography—
“in makeup and garter belt, and with her long hair” but in Not Pictorial,” Camera Craft 37 (1930): 313–320.
frontal nudity with the penis displayed, making her look not 32. Barthes links photography to theater, though not in
like the delicate feminine personality she identified herself terms of aesthetics of experiential process; he does so in-
with but rather as “a sexual freak.” Danto rightly describes stead through “the singular intermediary . . . of Death.” Just
this as an “exceedingly cruel image” that is ethically suspect, as “the first actors separated themselves from the commu-
and he goes on to argue more generally (using the further nity by playing the role of the Dead” (a theme he sees con-
example of Avedon’s portrait of Isaiah Berlin) that Avedon tinued in the makeup and masks of traditional theater), so
“has no interest in the sitter’s wishes” but selfishly “asserts “the Photograph . . . is . . . a figuration of the motionless and
his autonomy over the subject.” See Arthur Danto, “The made-up face beneath which we see the dead” (Barthes,
Naked Truth,” in Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Inter- Camera Lucida, pp. 31–32). See Baudelaire, “The Salon of
section, ed. Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge University Press, 1859,” p. 154.
2001), pp. 257–282, at pp. 270, 274–275. Danto’s analysis 33. Sontag, On Photography, p. 76.
suggests that the intense engagement and intimacy Ave- 34. Benjamin, “The Work of Art,” p. 225.
don describes as having with his subjects is essentially ex- 35. Benjamin, “The Work of Art,” pp. 220, 221, 224, 225.
ploitative or even feigned rather than ethically honest. This 36. Benjamin’s remarks on photography’s reproductive
predatory, manipulative falseness may well explain Ave- powers are rich and polysemically suggestive. He does not
don’s feeling of “embarrassment” once “the sitting is over” merely assert that photography provides a revolutionary
and he has the photograph that he (rather than the sitter) way of mechanically reproducing existing artworks that
wanted. were already produced by other means (such as painting
16. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 10. or lithography), but also suggests that it further provides a
17. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 11. way to create (and reproduce) new artworks by mechani-
18. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 11. cally reproducing and fixing visual images seen through the
19. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 12. camera but not yet represented through other pictorial me-
20. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 13. dia: “photography freed the hand of the most important
21. Barthes, Camera Lucida, p. 14. artistic functions which henceforth devolved only upon the
22. Barthes, Camera Lucida, pp. 66–67. eye looking into a lens,” thus letting the camera create the
Shusterman Photography as Performative Process 77

pictorial work by reproducing and fixing the pictorial image citations are from pages 7, 8, 17, 18, 19, and 24. I thank
seen by the eye (Benjamin, “The Work of Art,” p. 219). Diarmuid Costello for reminding me of this important
37. Benjamin, “The Work of Art,” p. 219. article.
38. See Walter Benjamin, “A Short History of Photog- 39. I thank the guest editors of this special issue for help-
raphy,” trans. Stanley Mitchell, Screen 13 (1972), 5–26. My ful comments in revising this article.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/1/67/5980239 by guest on 22 April 2024

You might also like