You are on page 1of 11

Blackwell Publishing IncMalden, USAPMEPain Medicine1526-2375American Academy of Pain Medicine?

200795613623
RESEARCH ARTICLESDisparity vs InequityMeghani and Gallagher

PA I N M E D I C I N E
Volume 9 • Number 5 • 2008

ETHICS SECTION

Original Research Article


Disparity vs Inequity: Toward Reconceptualization of Pain
Treatment Disparities

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


Salimah H. Meghani, PhD, MBE, CRNP,* and Rollin M. Gallagher, MD, MPH†‡§
*Center for Health Disparities Research, University of Pennsylvania, School of Nursing; †Center for Health Equity Research
and Promotion, Philadelphia Veteran Affairs Medical Center; ‡Center for Pain Medicine, Research and Policy, University
of Pennsylvania; and §Pain Medicine Service, Philadelphia Veteran Affairs Medical Center, Pennsylvania, USA

ABSTRACT

ABSTRACT Context. “Disparity” and “inequity” are two interdependent, yet distinct concepts that inform our
discourse on ethics and morals in pain medicine practice and in health policy. Disparity implies a
difference of some kind, whereas inequity implies unfairness and injustice. An overwhelming body of
literature documents racial/ethnic disparities in health. The debate on health disparities is generally
formulated using the principle of “horizontal equity,” which requires that individuals having the
same needs be treated equally. While some types of health treatments are amenable to the principle
of horizontal equity, others may not be appropriately studied in this way. The existing research
surrounding racial/ethnic disparities in pain treatment presents a conceptual predicament when
placed within the framework of horizontal equity.
Objective. Using pain treatment as a prototype, we advance the conceptual debate about racial/
ethnic disparities in health. More specifically, we ask three questions: (1) When may disparities be
considered inequities? (2) When may disparities not be considered inequities? (3) What are the
uncertainties in the disparity–inequity discourse?
Discussion. Significant policy implications may result from the manner in which health disparities
are conceptualized. Increasingly, researchers and policy makers use the term disparity interchange-
ably with inequity. This usage confuses the meaning and application of these distinct concepts. In
a given health care setting, different types of disparities may operate simultaneously, each requiring
serious scrutiny to avoid categorical interpretation leading to misguided practice and policy. While
the science of pain treatment disparities is still emerging, the authors present one perspective toward
the conceptualization of racial/ethnic disparities in pain treatment.

Key Words. Disparities; Inequities; Pain; Pain Treatment; Race; Ethnicity; Minorities

Introduction

Reprint requests to: Salimah H. Meghani, PhD, MBE,


CRNP, Center for Health Disparities Research, University
“D isparity” and “inequity” are two interde-
pendent, yet distinct concepts. In the lit-
eral sense, disparity merely implies a “difference”
of Pennsylvania, School of Nursing, Claire M. Fagin Hall
418 Curie Blvd., Philadelphia, PA 19104-6096, USA. Tel:
or a “lack of parity” of some kind [1]. Inequity,
215-573-7128; Fax: 215-573-7492; E-mail: meghanis@ on the other hand, implies “a state of being
nursing.upenn.edu. unfair” [1]. In the context of health care, these

© American Academy of Pain Medicine 1526-2375/08/$15.00/613 613–623 doi:10.1111/j.1526-4637.2007.00344.x


614 Meghani and Gallagher

two concepts may have distinct implications for this discussion are normative questions: Are dis-
practice and policy. parities intrinsically undesirable? Do they always
An overwhelming body of literature points to imply a moral error? Alternatively, can there be
differential health care access, disease and symp- just and fair disparities?
tom management, and health care outcomes
between minorities and nonminorities [2]. In
Racial and Ethnic Disparities in Pain Treatment:
2002, the Institute of Medicine (IOM) published
What Is the Evidence?
a 738-page report titled “Unequal Treatment:
Confronting Racial and Ethnic Disparities in A growing body of literature points to differential
Health Care.” This report synthesized data from patterns of analgesic treatment among minority
over 100 studies, focus groups, and testimonies and nonminority patients. In 1993, Todd et al. [3]

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


from experts and concluded that racial/ethnic dis- reported that patients’ race and ethnicity were
parities remain pervasive in the American health independently related to providers’ analgesic pre-
care system [2]. scribing practices in the emergency department
In view of the lingering de facto discrimination and that minority patients with long bone frac-
that prevails in many sectors of American life, it tures were less likely to receive analgesia, despite
can hardly surprise anyone that inequities do exist being insured on a similar level as nonminority
within the health care system. It is concerning, patients. Subsequently, many researchers evalu-
however, that the science of health care disparities ated the problem of undertreatment of pain
suffers from a conceptual lag due to the way in among minorities in a variety of clinical settings
which health care disparities are studied and inter- and contexts, including emergency rooms [3–9];
preted. The existing literature frequently associ- acute postoperative care [10–13]; HIV/AIDS
ates the term disparity with discrimination. This treatments [14]; cancer treatment [15–18], nursing
precludes providers and the public from seeing homes [19]; and chronic pain setting [20]. Many
beyond the expression into the sources of dispar- of these studies suggest that minorities are at a
ities and hampers appropriate measurement and greater risk of receiving less analgesia when
application of this very intricate concept. compared with nonminority individuals.
Another problem with the science of health care In recent years, a number of important articles
disparities is that it has traditionally been based on have synthesized research on disparities in pain
the quantitative measures of “more and less,” which treatment among racial/ethnic minorities [21–23].
appear to have been contemplated using the lens While there is little doubt that minority–nonmi-
of “horizontal equity.” Horizontal equity requires nority differences in analgesic treatment exist, the
that individuals having the same needs be treated pathways leading to these disparities remain elu-
equally. While some types of treatments and out- sive. Most of the available studies on pain treat-
comes are easily amenable to the principles of hor- ment disparities have been conducted within a
izontal equity, others may not be appropriately linear-quantitative paradigm and allude only to the
studied in this way. The existing research sur- technical aspects of disparity, i.e., the types and
rounding racial/ethnic disparities in pain treat- amounts of analgesia received by one group vs
ment presents a conceptual predicament when another group of patients; these studies offer little
placed within the framework of horizontal equity. insight into why such differences may exist. For
Pain treatment therefore can serve as a prototype instance, it is not clear the degree to which pro-
for examining the intricate nature of racial/ethnic viders or patients contribute to these disparities.
disparities in health care and may enable us to Do these differences represent a systematic bias in
conceptualize pain treatment disparities with the providers’ analgesic prescribing practice? Or
regard to its various dimensions. do they represent a systematic difference in the
The purpose of this article is to use pain treat- need for or expressed desire and negotiation for
ment as an example to elucidate the complex analgesics by particular groups of patients? Or,
nature of the concept of disparity and distinguish more likely, do they reflect some interaction of
it from other related concepts such as inequity. these factors.
More specifically, the authors ask three fundamen- Potential sources of disparities in pain treat-
tal questions: (1) When may disparities be consid- ment include differences in access, needs, choice
ered inequities? (2) When may disparities not be or preferences, attitudes, and expressed demand
considered inequities? (3) What are the uncertain- for analgesic treatment. The subjective and cul-
ties in the disparity–inequity discourse? Implicit in tural nature of pain challenges us to conceptualize
Disparity vs Inequity 615

disparities to incorporate these intricate aspects of preferences. In this context, the IOM definition
the pain treatment experience. To this end, the more closely reflects the essence of the term ineq-
following section provides a discussion of the con- uity (discussed later) rather than disparity. Thus,
cepts of disparity and inequity and teases out the it may be evident that the current usage of the
differences in these interdependent concepts using term disparity in the United States ranges from
empirical examples from the pain treatment connoting a mere difference (value-free) to a
disparity literature. judgment of the nature of such differences
(value-laden).
Linguists such as Chomsky believe that
The Term “Disparities,” Its Uses, and Applications
thoughts and mental processes are distorted when
In the United States, health care disparities have crucial terms are divorced from their ordinary

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


produced high profile policy initiatives [24]. sense usage and assigned a technical meaning [28].
Despite the high importance attached to the For instance, when a value-free term (such as dis-
notion of disparity, considerable confusion exists parity) is repeatedly associated with a value-laden
over what the term actually implies and how oper- term (such as inequity), the value-free term even-
ationally to define the term in a meaningful way tually becomes value-laden, obscuring its actual
for research. As mentioned above, increasingly, meaning and application.
researchers and policy makers have used the term
disparity interchangeably with inequity [25], con-
Disparity vs Inequity
fusing the meaning and application of these inter-
dependent, yet distinct concepts. This confusion Etymologically, the term “disparity” originated in
is epitomized by the use of varying definitions the 15th century from the Latin “disparatus,”
of health disparities by agencies and institutions which means “to separate” [29]. The Oxford
when presenting policy arguments or discussing Advanced Learner’s Dictionary defines disparate as
policy initiatives related to health disparities. “(of two or more things) so different from each other
For example, the Healthy People 2010 defines that that they cannot be compared” [1]. It may be
health disparities as “differences that occur by evident that disparity is not inherently a value-
gender, race or ethnicity, education or income, laden term. Consequently, it can be said that dis-
disability, geographic location, or sexual orienta- parity is not undesirable in itself unless it results
tion” [26]. The National Institutes of Health in some consequence that can be understood as
(NIH) defines health disparities as “differences in unfair or unjust.
the incidence, prevalence, mortality, and burden Unlike disparities, inequities are always unde-
of diseases and other adverse health conditions sirable and should be subject to serious moral crit-
that exist among specific population groups in the icism. Inequity, by definition, is the “state of being
United States” [27]. Due to its charge to under- unfair” [1]. Many equity theories have been pro-
stand racial/ethnic disparities in health, the IOM mulgated over the years in an attempt to identify
defines health disparities as “racial or ethnic dif- the best principles of distributive justice for better-
ferences in the quality of health care that are not and worse-off groups [30–39]. Equity implies “the
due to access-related factors or clinical needs, application of the principles of natural justice in a
preferences and appropriateness of intervention” particular circumstance where the existing . . .
(pp. 3–4) [2]. [structures] would not allow fair or reasonable
It may be evident that the above three defini- result” [1] and entails a constant battle between
tions differ conceptually. While Healthy People ideology and existing resources [40]. Equity theo-
2010 defines health disparities in terms of the rists deal with the moral justification and the
sociodemographic characteristics of specific pop- individual and shared social consequences of dis-
ulations, the NIH defines disparities with regard tributive injustice to a given society [41]. While
to differences in health outcomes that occur as a equality is at the core of equity theories, equality
result of having such characteristics. Both defini- in this sense does not necessarily mean a literal
tions use the term disparities to connote “differ- parity, but rather equality per unit of some good in
ences” without assigning any value to the nature question. Units in this sense might be understood
of these differences. The IOM definition, how- as needs, preferences, advantages, disadvantages,
ever, provides a judgment about when differences inputs, outputs, and the like. Thus, equality and
may be considered disparities, i.e., differences in equity are overlapping concepts—the only con-
care despite having equal access and or similar ceivable ideal where equality perfectly equals
616 Meghani and Gallagher

Disparities

Inequality Inequity
(Value-free) (Value-laden)

Behaviors freely Systematically


Inevitable causes Unfair
chosen by rational important
(natural causes) and avoidable
people* differences

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


Who/what we ought to be?
Who we are?
(compared with some reference group)

Figure 1 Disparities vs inequities. Adapted from Whitehead, 1985 [30]. * Utilitarians argue that if a behavior may have bad
consequences for individuals or society, it is unjust for that behavior, even if it is freely chosen by a rational being.

equity is a utopian society, where the needs, pref- way care or services are provided (Figure 1). These
erences, inputs, and outputs of all members are latter differences are termed inequities (Table 1).
exactly the same. Thus, it may be said that not all According to Whitehead, “The term inequity has
disparities are inequities—in effect, equal is not a moral and ethical dimension. It refers to differ-
always equitable and equitable need not be equal. ences which are unnecessary and avoidable but, in
If it may be established that the needs of different addition, are also considered unfair and unjust”
individuals or groups are significantly different [32]. Based on the above definition, the use of the
from the other, then providing an equal treatment term inequity should inevitably imply judgments
may actually be inequitable. about important systematic differences that are
judged to be unfair and result from unnatural and
mutable causes [32].
When Do Disparities Equal Inequities?
Many theorists have promulgated what they
Disparities range from mere differences to differ- consider as the best principle for the attainment of
ences occurring as a result of moral error in the distributional equity. The unsettling debate, how-

Table 1 Definitions and examples of inequities and its dimensions


Construct Definition Examples
Macrolevel inequities Systematic conditions and factors operating • Unavailability of opioids in pharmacies serving minority and
on a system-level limiting equal access and poor neighborhoods [47,48].
opportunities.
Microlevel inequities Systematic conditions and factors operating • Inadequate assessment of pain in a patient with limited
in patient–provider encounter limiting equal English proficiency.
access and opportunities. • Physician failure to treat acute pain after abdominal
surgery with adequate doses of opioids because patient is
on methadone maintenance for heroin addiction.
• Failure to treat pain in a black person with tattoos who
comes to the emergency room with severe back pain or
headache.
Horizontal inequities Failure to provide same treatment to • Lack of access to pain medicine specialists due to
individuals with similar needs. socioeconomic constraints such as poverty or lack of
insurance.
• Failure to provide workers’ compensation support and
access to medical treatment for persons with low back pain
who are black [50–53] or emotionally distressed [54].
Vertical inequities Failure to provide dissimilar but equitable • Provision of similar analgesic treatment despite differential
treatment to those with lesser or greater need or preference, e.g., prescription of codeine or
needs. morphine to individuals or groups with known defects in the
metabolism of these analgesics [63,64].
Disparity vs Inequity 617

ever, has led some to comment that “. . . equity, City was surveyed to determine the availability of
like beauty, is in the mind of the beholder” [42]. commonly prescribed opioids in predominantly
Some theorists have argued that decisions on nonwhite neighborhoods. Only 25% of pharma-
health care distribution ought to be based on cies in predominantly nonwhite areas (<40%
something as instrumental as “need” [43] while white) had opioids that were sufficient to treat
others have argued that equality of access and equal- severe pain, in comparison with 72% of pharma-
ity of opportunity should be the criteria [44]. Yet cies in predominantly white neighborhoods
others have argued that equality of access should (≥80% white).
be interpreted as actual utilization and not merely More recently, research led by Green et al. [48]
the potential for access itself [44]. Finally, some reported a significant gap in the availability of
have asserted that the ultimate criterion for equi- prescription opioid analgesics in minority and

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


table decisions ought to be health itself, which is poor neighborhoods of Michigan. The study was
instrumental for equality of flourishing [36]. The conducted with 190 pharmacies in zip codes with
moral philosopher Rawls, in his theory Justice as predominantly white populations (≥70% white
Fairness, asserts, “All . . . primary goods . . . are to residents) and in zip codes with predominantly
be distributed equally unless an unequal distribu- minority populations (≥70% minority residents).
tion of any or all of these goods is to the advantage After stratifying for income and controlling for zip
of the least favored” [italics added] [45]. code and median age, pharmacies in white areas
(odds ratio, 13.36 high income vs 54.42 low
income) and noncorporate pharmacies (odds ratio,
Macrolevel and Microlevel Inequities
24.92 high income vs 3.61 low income) were more
Inequities can occur both at macro and micro lev- likely to have sufficient opioid analgesic supplies
els (see Table 1). Macrolevel inequities occur when (P < 0.005). The authors concluded that regardless
preconceived notions about groups defined by of income, Michigan pharmacies in predominantly
individual characteristics such as race, ethnicity, minority zip codes were significantly less likely to
gender, or social status systematically operate to carry sufficient prescription opioids than pharma-
limit equal access and opportunities when com- cies in predominantly white zip codes.
pared with reference groups. Microlevel inequities in pain treatment occur
Evidence is accumulating that the members of when individuals or groups lack access to similar
racial/ethnic minorities have different opportuni- advantages such as appropriate assessment, ef-
ties to receive care such that patients with similar fective communication, concordance between
social characteristics, such as similar health insur- patients and providers resulting in differential
ances, may be treated differently [2]. Krieger pain treatment outcomes. For instance, emerging
asserted that while the U.S. social system may have research by Tait, Chibnall, and colleagues suggests
been somewhat successful in minimizing “de jure” that African American Workers’ Compensation
(by law) discrimination, “de facto” (in fact) dis- claimants with low back injuries receive lower
crimination is still highly prevalent in our social compensation, medical expenditures, disability
system [46]. “De facto” discrimination with regard ratings, and settlement awards relative to Cauca-
to health care is problematic, not only because of sians [50–53]. Similarly, Gallagher et al. have
its harmful effects on the health of an individual noted that in persons out of work from low back
or society but because it is bad in itself [46]. pain, controlling for other factors including sever-
A lack of geographic access to opioids in minor- ity of injury and impairment, those with emotional
ity neighborhoods [47,48] is another example of distress are less likely to be awarded workers
macrolevel inequity in pain treatment. The com- compensation [54]. These differential outcomes
partmentalization of social sectors and residential appear to be mediated by a model of social judg-
segregation of minorities in the United States has ment that operates at the level of patient–provider,
created avenues of focal disadvantages [47–49]. case management, and jurisdiction [50,52]. Other
The discharge of two patients from the same hos- clinical examples of microlevel inequities include
pital with similar prescriptions for analgesics does inefficient pain treatment among minorities
not guarantee equal access to the recommended related to provider attitude toward pain [55,56],
treatment. This was epitomized in the study “We reluctance to prescribe pain medications [56], and
don’t carry that,” published in the New England limited concordance between patient and provider
Journal of Medicine [47]. A random sample of 30% estimates of pain [15,17]. Unlike macrolevel ineq-
of pharmacies in the five boroughs of New York uities resulting from lack of access, microlevel
618 Meghani and Gallagher

inequities are difficult to characterize and require access to health services appeals to horizontal
further understanding of pathways leading to such equity, whereas provision of targeted health pro-
disparate outcomes. grams and services based on established needs may
For instance, in the setting of pain treatment, appeal to vertical equity principles [61]. The
“effective pain treatment” is a desirable outcome Veteran Affairs Health System is one example of
for all patients with clinical pain. This outcome is horizontal equity in access, as military veterans,
judged by one or more subjective or objective regardless of their socioeconomic status and their
measures, rather than, simply, by the milligram ability to pay, can receive care in the system. How-
dose of a given medication. Thus, the provider ever, microlevel inequities (see Table 1), such as
would not only necessarily adjust the milligram failure to adequately treat postsurgical pain in
dose of analgesic, but also assure access to other opioid dependent patients, may persist.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


treatments and supports needed to assure similar Vertical equity principles inevitably require
outcomes. In a simplistic example, if a middle- providers and policy makers to interpret and
aged worker presents to the pain clinic with her- define needs based on some reasonable or scientific
niated lumbar disk and radiculopathy, two desired criteria. Equity decisions may not be based on
outcomes are pain control and return to work. “irrelevant” or “immutable” characteristics such as
Equity is assured only if equal access to the indicated race or gender [34], but for a difference of “need”
treatment necessary for both pain control and that may arise from having such characteristics.
return to work is provided—in this case, pain con-
trol with oral analgesics or epidural medications
Race and the Case for Scientific Discrimination?
accompanied by appropriate rehabilitation (not
just “physical therapy” but also behavioral therapy Race remains a contentious notion within the sci-
as necessary). Health managed organizations or entific community. There is considerable debate
entitlement programs often allow basic medical on whether race is a biological construct or a
treatment, but limit access to other treatments that socially determined phenomenon. As the relation-
improve the odds of functional recovery [57,58]. ship between race, ethnicity, and genetics remains
Hence, solutions to macrolevel and microlevel murky, so is the question, “Is there a room for
inequities in access to pain treatment require pol- scientific discrimination based on biological char-
icies in medical education that improve the stan- acteristics of individuals and groups?” This ques-
dards of training for pain care [59] and also tion is subject to further debate and discussion. In
policies that improve the population-based distri- the pain literature, some studies point to signifi-
bution of standard pain treatments [60]. cantly disparate pharmacokinetics and pharmaco-
dynamics of analgesic drugs between and within
different racial/ethnic groups [62–64]. Some
When Are Disparities Not Inequities?
emerging evidence identifies genetic polymor-
Based on the Aristotelian notion of justice, equity phism as an important source of variation in anal-
in health care requires that “patients who are alike gesic metabolism and response among individuals
in relevant respects be treated in like fashion and and groups. Genetic polymorphism results in an
that patients who are unlike in relevant respects be alteration in the enzymatic activity of a hepatic
treated in appropriately unlike fashion” [34] (p. Cytochrome P450 (CYP2D6). The polymorphic
275). The treatment of individuals may be consid- CYP2D6 is a drug-metabolizing enzyme, which is
ered equitable if it relates to some way in which necessary for the conversion and metabolism of a
individuals are reasonably considered similar or number of widely used opioid analgesics [65] and
dissimilar, for instance, with regard to “need” or other medications used in pain medicine practice,
“health” [34]. It follows that, with regard to rele- e.g., anticonvulsants (phenytoin), benzodiazepines
vant characteristics, people with like needs should (diazepam), muscle relaxants (succinylcholine),
receive like treatment (horizontal equity) and antidepressants (imipramine, nortriptyline, ven-
people with lesser or greater needs should, lafaxine), typical neuroleptics, alcohol, antihyper-
respectively, receive lesser or greater treatments tensive medications (propranolol, timolol), local
(vertical equity). These two types of equities have anesthetics (procainamide), l-dopa, nicotine, and
considerably distinct policy implications and must warfarin [66].
appeal to some ethical principle to justify the Two distinct phenotypes, i.e., the poor metab-
deliberate choice of one over the other. For olizer (PM) and the extensive metabolizer (EM),
instance, the idea of universal health coverage or have been documented across general populations.
Disparity vs Inequity 619

Individuals with CYP2D6 PM phenotype are The Gray Areas: What Is Fair and Just?
unable to metabolize codeine to morphine and
thus reap minimal therapeutic benefit from As noted above, equity is a pluralistic concept.
codeine [58]. Evidence suggests that about 10% of While most agree that equity in the context of
Caucasians are characterized as having PM phe- health care implies some mechanism for deter-
notype [67]. The clinical implications of CYP2D6 mining a just system for treatment or allocation,
polymorphism are not well documented. How- no consensus exists on what constitutes a just
ever, at least one recent clinical study of postoper- and fair treatment. Often, policy development in
ative pain suggests that Caucasians with CYP2D6 the domain of social distribution is not based on
PM phenotype had a significantly decreased equity judgments for individuals, but rather for
response rate to analgesic treatment with trama- populations and subpopulations. Policy makers

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


dol, requiring a higher consumption of this anal- often resort to the idea that needs are more mor-
gesic, and more rescue medications than other ally persuasive in the allocation of treatment and
Caucasian patients with EM phenotype [68]. should be interpreted in a more technical sense
The discussion of biological factors as a poten- than mere preferences [36]. Consequently, the
tial lurking variable in the genesis of pain treat- notion of justice often competes with other ethi-
ment disparities is largely absent in present cal values such as individual autonomy, choice,
research. Large-scale studies are needed to deter- wants, and preferences. The health care system
mine if CYP2D6 genotyping has clinical relevance has been traditionally ineffective in incorporat-
in the use of several opioids analgesics between ing these latter values in equity strategy [61]. To
and among groups. Thus, it is not clear if the this end, an important question that needs care-
results of the pain disparity research will be differ- ful discussion remains “can a person’s choice,
ent if the researchers could control for the anal- wants, and preferences take priority over jus-
gesics known to metabolize through CYP2D6 tice?” Again, the setting of pain treatment pro-
enzymatic activity. Notwithstanding our limita- vides an avenue to consider this important
tions in the understanding of pharmacogenomics question.
of analgesics in different individuals and groups, it Some regard pain as “inherently a social
can be said that if relative differences in treatment experience” [69]. Indeed, treatment of pain, due
result from differences in physiological and bio- to its very nature, is an interactive social process.
logical processes, rather than problems with access Like any social interaction, the negotiation of
and availability, they may not be characterized as pain treatment between patients and providers
inequitable. does not occur in isolation from sociocultural
For the sake of exemplifying the above argu- realities. While the precise role of culture in
ment, assume that two individuals are exactly sim- shaping pain experiences across different ethnic
ilar except in their ability to metabolize analgesic groups is not well known, it has been widely
medications. Further, assume that, given the same argued that culture and ethnicity play an impor-
injury and nociceptive stimulus, the person A tant role in the social construction of pain and
requires 10 mg of analgesic X for 4 hours of pain in shaping its experience. Despite significant
relief and the person B requires 20 mg of analgesic advancement in understanding the complex
X for 4 hours of pain relief; then, the equity prin- anatomy, physiology, and molecular biology of
ciple may require that the person A be treated with pain, the multidimensionality of the human pain
60 mg of analgesic X per day and the person B be experience renders its precise definition and
treated with 120 mg of analgesic X per day to measurement elusive. No clinical assay or objec-
provide equitable pain relief. Thus, the vertical tive test to date accurately measures the experi-
equity principle may call for a differential alloca- ence of pain. Treatment of pain necessitates a
tion of goods to those who may be different in covert interpretation of pain and suffering and
their needs. It is important to underscore, how- overt negotiation between patients and provid-
ever, that differential treatment of any sort ers, which then results in a given treatment plan
requires a strong scientific and moral justification [70]. The cycle of pain treatment can potentially
due to the normative risk for “slippery slope.” For break down at several levels during patient–pro-
instance, health providers may illegitimately seek vider interaction, resulting in so-called disparity
refuge in the “biological argument” for lack of [70]. For instance, a cancer patient’s negotiation
equal treatment, resulting in further poor treat- of pain treatment with a provider may depend
ment for some groups. on the meaning and significance that the patient
620 Meghani and Gallagher

attributes to cancer pain. If the patient believes back injury, surgery is the best treatment) and
that analgesics will mask the symptoms of cancer may not necessarily represent a free and informed
progression, he/she may refrain from actively choice. Contrarily, some commentators have
pursuing pain treatment with providers [70]. argued that equity takes priority over preference
The IOM report therefore asserts that “given and that individuals be treated equitably even if a
the role of cultural and linguistic factors in both “majority [of them] may prefer an inequitable
patients’ perception of pain and in physicians’ alternative” (p. 13) [72].
ability to accurately assess patients’ pain . . . it is One seeming paradox in addressing health care
reasonable to suspect that healthcare disparities disparities is that on the one hand, the health sys-
might be greater in pain treatment . . . than in tem is striving to achieve equality of care and out-
treatment of objectively verifiable disease” (p. comes and on the other hand, the flourishing field

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


64) [2]. of culturally congruent and individualized medi-
It has been agreed for a long time now that pain cine is calling attention to plurality of needs and
is “whatever the experiencing person says it is and preferences across different groups. The problem
exists whenever he says it does” (p. 7) [71]. By here is not that the goals of equitable and cultur-
extension, can it also be argued that the “treatment ally appropriate care are antithetical but in what
of pain is whatever the experiencing person says it way can this diversity and multiculturalism be cap-
should be”? Some patients may prefer less pain tured using appropriate measurements so that
medication because they may choose acupuncture legitimate differences are not inadvertently per-
to alleviate their pain; others may resort to spiri- ceived as inequities resulting in misguided practice
tuality and praying to cope with their pain, yet and policy implications.
others may choose to refuse pain medication due
to beliefs in endurance and salvation. Some
Conclusions
individuals, based on how they metabolize pain
medication, and experience side effects (past out- Disparities in health care exist, but the term
comes), may prefer and demand more or less “disparities” is often confused with a related but
analgesia. meaningfully different concept, “inequities.” The
Many philosophers and ethicists agree that the article used pain treatment disparities to examine
arguments in favor of “need” are more compelling the question, are all disparities in health care
morally due to their factual and categorical nature intrinsically bad? Further, it advances the notion
and the ends they are presumed to serve [34]. that disparities are an inevitable reality of any
Unlike “needs,” “wants and preferences” are based institution (e.g., health care) that intimately deals
on subjective things such as meanings, past out- with the diversities of human life and intricacies of
comes with treatments, and social and cultural val- human nature. As disparities are not categorical,
ues. While “health” is an example of a good that their resolution cannot be categorical either. For
is often distributed based on needs, health itself is instance, elimination of gradient in the sense of
not categorical or absolute [34]. It may be implied “more or less treatment” is laudable and appropriate
then that health care ought to improve health. What in the context of access and availability but may
constitutes health for different groups or people, be murky in such settings that deal with a range
however, is based on the meanings they ascribe of human experiences and disparities in needs,
to it. choices, wants, and preferences. The essence of
Thus, it is not clear if cultural appropriateness, this argument may be deduced from the following
patient autonomy, and equal liberty are better vir- observation by Coffin: “We must always press the
tues than equality. This also prompts the ques- socialist questions. But be careful and dubious
tion, does commitment to beneficence take priority about the socialist answers . . . socialist questions
over autonomy? Or should preference, merely are questions about justice . . . you can say . . . let
because it is subjective and difficult to quantify, justice roll down like mighty waters, but figuring
qualify as having inferior moral status than out the irrigation system is complicated . . . what’s
“needs”? According to Whitehead, the so per- the best irrigation system, maybe combination of
ceived “health damaging behavior” that is freely a lot of things” [73].
chosen and results in poor health would be con- While evidence related to system-level barriers
sidered neither unfair nor unjust [30]. One cau- in pain treatment disparities are well documented,
tion with “preference” is that it can be shaped by understanding of patient–provider factors, as well
all the wrong reasons (e.g., the belief that in acute as basic science, e.g., possible variations in drug
Disparity vs Inequity 621

metabolism, remain rudimentary. The framework 12 Ng B, Dimsdale JE, Rollnik JD, Shapiro H. The
we propose in this article will help investigators effect of ethnicity on prescriptions for patient-
consider different factors affecting pain treatment controlled analgesia for post-operative pain. Pain
disparities and help identify areas that need further 1996;66(1):9–12.
study in understanding and addressing these 13 Ng B, Dimsdale JE, Shragg GP, Deutsch R. Ethnic
differences in analgesic consumption for postoper-
disparities.
ative pain. Psychosom Med 1996;58(2):125–9.
14 Sambamoorthi U, Walkup J, McSpiritt E, Warner
L, Castle N, Crystal S. Racial differences in end-of-
Acknowledgments life care for patients with AIDS. AIDS Public Policy
We are extremely thankful to Anne Keane, EdD, CRNP, J 2000;15(3–4):136–48.
15 Anderson KO, Mendoza TR, Valero V, et al.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


FAAN, for her guidance, support, and encouragement with
various aspects of this article. Minority cancer patients and their providers: Pain
management attitudes and practice. Cancer 2000;
88(8):1929–38.
16 Anderson KO, Richman SP, Hurley J, et al. Cancer
References
pain management among underserved minority out-
1 Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary. Oxford: patients: Perceived needs and barriers to optimal
Oxford University Press; 1998. control. Cancer 2002;94(8):2295–304.
2 Smedley BD, Stith AY, Nelson AR, eds. Unequal 17 Cleeland CS, Gonin R, Baez L, Loehrer P, Pandya
Treatment. Confronting Racial and Ethnic Dispar- KJ. Pain and treatment of pain in minority patients
ities in Health Care. Washington, DC: National with cancer. The Eastern Cooperative Oncology
Academic Press; 2002. Group Minority Outpatient Pain Study. Ann Intern
3 Todd KH, Samaroo N, Hoffman JR. Ethnicity as a Med 1997;127(9):813–6.
risk factor for inadequate emergency department 18 Cleeland CS, Gonin R, Hatfield AK, et al. Pain and
analgesia. JAMA 1993;269(12):1537–9. its treatment in outpatients with metastatic cancer.
4 Heins JK, Heins A, Grammas M, Costello M, N Engl J Med 1994;330(9):592–6.
Huang K, Mishra S. Disparities in analgesia and 19 Bernabei R, Gambassi G, Lapane K, et al. Manage-
opioid prescribing practices for patients with mus- ment of pain in elderly patients with cancer. SAGE
culoskeletal pain in the emergency department. Study Group. Systematic Assessment of Geriatric
J Emerg Nurs 2006;32(3):219–24. Drug Use via Epidemiology. JAMA 1998;279(23):
5 Fuentes EF, Kohn MA, Neighbor ML. Lack of asso- 1877–82.
ciation between patient ethnicity or race and fracture 20 Chen I, Kurz J, Pasanen M, et al. Racial differences
analgesia. Acad Emerg Med 2002;9(9):910–5. in opioid use for chronic nonmalignant pain. J Gen
6 Singer AJ, Thode HC Jr. National analgesia Intern Med 2005;20(7):593–8.
prescribing patterns in emergency department 21 Bonham VL. Race, ethnicity, and pain treatment:
patients with burns. J Burn Care Rehabil 2002; Striving to understand the causes and solutions to
23(6):361–5. the disparities in pain treatment. J Law Med Ethics
7 Tamayo-Sarver JH, Dawson NV, Hinze SW, et al. 2001;29(1):52–68.
The effect of race/ethnicity and desirable social 22 Green CR, Anderson KO, Baker TA, et al. The
characteristics on physicians’ decisions to prescribe unequal burden of pain: Confronting racial and eth-
opioid analgesics. Acad Emerg Med 2003;10(11): nic disparities in pain. Pain Med 2003;4(3):277–94.
1239–48. 23 Ezenwa MO, Ameringer S, Ward SE, Serlin RC.
8 Todd KH, Lee T, Hoffman JR. The effect of Racial and ethnic disparities in pain management in
ethnicity on physician estimates of pain severity in the United States. J Nurs Scholarsh 2006;38(3):
patients with isolated extremity trauma. JAMA 225–33.
1994;271(12):925–8. 24 United States Department of Health and Human
9 Yen K, Kim M, Stremski ES, Gorelick MH. Effect Services. HHS awards more than $56 million to
of ethnicity and race on the use of pain medications eliminate health disparities. January 9, 2006.
in children with long bone fractures in the emer- Available at: http://ncmhd.nih.gov/SawardsM.html
gency department. Ann Emerg Med 2003;42(1):41– (accessed November 8, 2006).
7. 25 Almond P. An analysis of the concept of equity and
10 McDonald DD. Gender and ethnic stereotyping its application to health visiting. J Adv Nurs
and narcotic analgesic administration. Res Nurs 2002;37(6):598–606.
Health 1994;17(1):45–9. 26 U.S. Department of Health & Human Services.
11 Adamson J, Ben-Shlomo Y, Chaturvedi N, Dono- Healthy people 2010: Understanding and improv-
van J. Ethnicity, socio-economic position and gen- ing health, 2nd edn. 2000. Available at: http://
der – do they affect reported health-care seeking www.healthypeople.gov/Document/html/uih/
behaviour? Soc Sci Med 2003;57(5):895–904. uih_2.htm#goals (accessed July 5, 2007).
622 Meghani and Gallagher

27 National Institute of Health. Addressing health consequences of discrimination. Int J Health Serv
disparities: The NIH program of action. 2004. 1999;29(2):295–52.
Available at: http://healthdisparities.nih.gov/whatare. 47 Morrison RS, Wallenstein S, Natale DK, Senzel RS,
html (accessed July 5, 2007). Huang LL. “We don’t carry that” – failure of phar-
28 Chomsky N. Thought control in the US: The macies in predominantly nonwhite neighborhoods
media and the “Peace Process.” MERIP Middle to stock opioid analgesics. N Engl J Med
East Report 1986;143:25–9. 2000;34(14):1023–6.
29 Merriam-Webster Online. Disparate. 2006. Avail- 48 Green CR, Ndao-Brumblay SK, West B, Wash-
able at: http://www.m-w.com/ (accessed November ington T. Differences in prescription opioid anal-
10, 2006). gesic availability: Comparing minority and white
30 Whitehead M. The concepts and principles of pharmacies across Michigan. J Pain 2005;6(10):
equity and health. 1985. Available at: http:// 689–99.

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


www.who.dk/Document/PAE/conceptsrpd414.pdf 49 Williams DR, Neighbours HW, Jackson JS. Racial/
(accessed November 10, 2006). ethnic discrimination and health: Findings from
31 Whitehead M, Dahlgren G. What can be done community studies. Am J Public Health
about inequalities in health? Lancet 1991; 2003;93:200–8.
338(8774):1059–63. 50 Chibnall JT, Tait RC. Disparities in occupational
32 Whitehead M, Drever F. Narrowing social inequal- low back injuries: Predicting pain-related disability
ities in health? Analysis of trends in mortality from satisfaction with case management in African
among babies of lone mothers (abridged version 2). Americans and Caucasians. Pain Med 2005;6(1):39–
BMJ 1999;318(7188):912–4. 48.
33 Whitehead M, Scott-Samuel A, Dahlgren G. 51 Chibnall JT, Tait RC, Andresen EM, Hadler NM.
Setting targets to address inequalities in health. Race differences in diagnosis and surgery for occu-
Lancet 1998;351(9111):1279–82. pational low back injuries. Spine 2006;31(11):1272–
34 Culyer AJ. Equity – some theory and its policy 5.
implications. J Med Ethics 2001;27(4):275–83. 52 Tait RC, Chibnall JT. Work injury management of
35 Culyer AJ, van Doorslaer E, Wagstaff A. Utilisation refractory low back pain: Relations with ethnicity,
as a measure of equity by Mooney, Hall, Donaldson legal representation and diagnosis. Pain 2001;91(1–
and Gerard. J Health Econ 1992;11(1):93–8. 2):47–56.
36 Culyer AJ, Wagstaff A. Equity and equality in 53 Tait RC, Chibnall JT, Andresen EM, Hadler NM.
health and health care. J Health Econ 1993;12(4): Management of occupational back injuries: Differ-
431–57. ences among African Americans and Caucasians.
37 Mooney G. Vertical equity in health care res- Pain 2004;112(3):389–96.
ource allocation. Health Care Anal 2000;8(3): 54 Gallagher RM, Williams RA, Skelly J, et al. Work-
203–15. ers’ compensation and return-to-work in low back
38 Mooney G, Hall J, Donaldson C, Gerard K. Utili- pain. Pain 1995;61(2):299–307.
sation as a measure of equity: Weighing heat? 55 Cleeland CS, Cleeland LM, Dar R, Rinehardt LC.
J Health Econ 1991;10(4):475–80. Factors influencing physician management of can-
39 Mooney G, Jan S. Vertical equity: Weighting out- cer pain. Cancer 1986;58(3):796–800.
comes? or establishing procedures? Health Policy 56 Von Roenn JH, Cleeland CS, Gonin R, Hatfield
1997;39(1):79–87. AK, Pandya KJ. Physician attitudes and practice in
40 Carter-Pokras O, Baquet C. What is a “health dis- cancer pain management. A survey from the Eastern
parity?” Public Health Rep 2002;117(5):426–34. Cooperative Oncology Group. Ann Intern Med
41 Cook KS, Messick DM. Psychological and sociolog- 1993;119(2):121–6.
ical perspectives on distributive justice: Convergent, 57 Gallagher RM. Primary care and pain medicine. A
divergent, and parallel lines. In: Cook KS, ed. community solution to the public health problem of
Equity Theory. New York: Praeger Publishers; chronic pain. Med Clin North Am 1999;83(3):555–
1983:1–12. 83, v.
42 McLachlan G, Maynard A. The Public/Private Mix 58 Gallagher RM. The pain medicine and primary care
for Health: The Relevance and Effects of Change. community rehabilitation model: Monitored care
London: Nuffield Provincial Hospitals Trust; 1982. for pain disorders in multiple settings. Clin J Pain
43 Culyer AJ. Need and the National Health Service. 1999;15(1):1–3.
York: Studies in Economics; 1976. 59 Fishman SM, Gallagher RM, Carr DB, Sullivan
44 Mooney GH. Equity in health care: Confronting LW. The case for pain medicine. Pain Med
the confusion. Eff Health Care 1983;1(4):179–85. 2004;5(3):281–6.
45 Rawls J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: The 60 Weiner DK, Kim YS, Bonino P, Wang T. Low
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press; 1971. back pain in older adults: Are we utilizing
46 Krieger N. Embodying inequality: a review of con- healthcare resources wisely? Pain Med 2006;7(2):
cepts, measures, and methods for studying health 143–50.
Disparity vs Inequity 623

61 PAHO/WHO. Principles and basic concepts of events after codeine administration irrespective of
equity and health. 1999. Available at: http:// the genetically determined differences in morphine
www.paho.org/english/hdp/hdd/pahowho.pdf formation. Pain 1998;76(1–2):27–33.
(accessed October 30, 2004). 68 Stamer UM, Lehnen K, Hothker F, et al. Impact
62 Burroughs VJ, Maxey RW, Levy RA. Racial and of CYP2D6 genotype on postoperative tramadol
ethnic differences in response to medicines: analgesia. Pain 2003;105(1–2):231–8.
Towards individualized pharmaceutical treatment. 69 Moore RJ, Spiegel D. Uses of guided imagery for
J Natl Med Assoc 2002;94(10 Suppl.):1–26. pain control by African-American and White
63 Kim K, Johnson JA, Derendorf H. Differences in women with metastatic breast cancer. Integr Med
drug pharmacokinetics between East Asians and 1999;2(2/3):115–26.
Caucasians and the role of genetic polymorphisms. 70 Meghani SH. Factors affecting the negotiation of
J Clin Pharmacol 2004;44(10):1083–105. treatment for cancer pain among African Americans

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/painmedicine/article/9/5/613/1852051 by guest on 29 April 2024


64 Cepeda MS, Farrar JT, Roa JH, et al. Ethnicity influ- [Dissertation]. Philadelphia: University of Pennsyl-
ences morphine pharmacokinetics and pharmacody- vania Diss, 2005. POPM2005.242. University
namics. Clin Pharmacol Ther 2001;70(4):351–61. Microfilm, P38.
65 Dayer P, Desmeules J, Collart L. Pharmacology of 71 McCaffery M. Pain: Clinical Manual for Nursing
tramadol. Drugs 1997;53(Suppl. 2):18–24. Practice, 2nd edn. St. Louis: Mosby; 1989.
66 Fishbain DA, Fishbain D, Lewis J, et al. Genetic 72 Johnson C. Equity: Its Scope and Its Relation to
testing for enzymes of drug metabolism: Does it have Other Objectives. College Park, MD: Center for
clinical utility for pain medicine at the present time? Philosophy and Public Policy; 1978.
A structured review. Pain Med 2004;5(1):81–93. 73 Coffin WS. NOW with Bill Moyers. 2004. Avail-
67 Eckhardt K, Li S, Ammon S, Schanzle G, Mikus G, able at: http://www.zionsherald.org/May2004_
Eichelbaum M. Same incidence of adverse drug interview.html (accessed February 7, 2005).

You might also like