You are on page 1of 21

25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Archive
Spring 2018 Edition

The Common Good


First published Mon Feb 26, 2018

In ordinary political discourse, the “common good” refers to those facilities—whether material, cultural or
institutional—that the members of a community provide to all members in order to fulfill a relational
obligation they all have to care for certain interests that they have in common. Some canonical examples of
the common good in a modern liberal democracy include: the road system; public parks; police protection
and public safety; courts and the judicial system; public schools; museums and cultural institutions; public
transportation; civil liberties, such as the freedom of speech and the freedom of association; the system of
property; clean air and clean water; and national defense. The term itself may refer either to the interests that
members have in common or to the facilities that serve common interests. For example, people may say, “the
new public library will serve the common good” or “the public library is part of the common good”.

As a philosophical concept, the common good is best understood as part of an encompassing model for
practical reasoning among the members of a political community. The model takes for granted that citizens
stand in a “political” or “civic” relationship with one another and that this relationship requires them to
create and maintain certain facilities on the grounds that these facilities serve certain common interests. The
relevant facilities and interests together constitute the common good and serve as a shared standpoint for
political deliberation.[1] When citizens face various questions about legislation, public policy or social
responsibility, they resolve these questions by appeal to a conception of the relevant facilities and the
relevant interests. That is, they argue about what facilities have a special claim on their attention, how they
should expand, contract or maintain existing facilities, and what facilities they should design and build in the
future.

The common good is an important concept in political philosophy because it plays a central role in
philosophical reflection about the public and private dimensions of social life. Let’s say that “public life” in a
political community consists of a shared effort among members to maintain certain facilities for the sake of
common interests. “Private life” consists of each member’s pursuit of a distinct set of personal projects. As
members of a political community, we are each involved in our community’s public life and in our own
private lives, and this raises an array of questions about the nature and scope of each of these enterprises. For
example, when are we supposed to make decisions based on the common good? Most of us would agree that
we are required to do so when we act as legislators or civil servants. But what about as journalists, corporate
executives or consumers? More fundamentally, why should we care about the common good? What would
be wrong with a community whose members withdraw from public life and focus exclusively on their own
private lives? These are some of the questions that motivate philosophical discussions of the common good.

This article reviews the philosophical literature, covering various points of agreement among traditional
conceptions of the common good, such as those favored by Plato, Aristotle, John Locke, J.J. Rousseau,
Adam Smith, G.W.F. Hegel, John Rawls and Michael Walzer. It also covers some important disagreements,
especially the disagreement between “communal” and “distributive” views. It concludes by considering three
important topics in the literature: democracy, communal sharing, and competitive markets. In order to
understand the issues, it is helpful to start by distinguishing the common good from various notions of the
good that play a prominent role in welfare economics and welfare consequentialist accounts of political
morality.

1. First Contrast: Welfare Consequentialism


2. Second Contrast: Public Goods
3. Why Does Political Philosophy Need This Concept? Defects in a “Private Society”
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 1/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

4. Central Features of the Common Good


4.1 A Shared Standpoint for Practical Reasoning
4.2 A Set of Common Facilities
4.3 A Privileged Class of Common Interests
4.4 A Solidaristic Concern
4.5 A Nonaggregative Concern
5. Common Interests (i): Joint Activity
6. Common Interests (ii): Private Individuality
7. The Common Good Perspective: Communal or Distributive?
8. The Common Good in Politics: Democracy and Collective Decision-Making
9. The Common Good in Civic Life: Burden Sharing and Resource Pooling
10. Markets, Competition and the Invisible Hand
11. Conclusion: Social Justice and the Common Good
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. First Contrast: Welfare Consequentialism


The common good belongs to a family of concepts that relate to goodness rather than rightness (Sidgwick
1874). What makes the common good different from other concepts in this family is that it is a notion of the
good that is understood to be internal to the requirements of a social relationship. In any community, the
common good consists of the facilities and interests that members have a special obligation to care about in
virtue of the fact that they stand in a certain relationship with one another. In a family, for instance, the
family home is part of the common good because the familial bond requires members to take care of the
home as part of a shared effort to care for one another’s interests in shelter and safety. In a university, the
climate of academic freedom on campus is part of the common good because the special relationship among
members of the university community requires them to care for this climate as part of a shared effort to care
for one another’s interests in teaching, learning and inquiring.

The common good differs from the various notions of the good that play a foundational role in welfare
consequentialist accounts of political morality. Among the notions in the latter category, we can include: the
sum of pleasure over pain, total satisfaction of rational desire, aggregate welfare adjusted for distributive
considerations, welfare prioritarianism, equality of welfare (in certain formulations), Pareto optimality, and
so on. Unlike the common good, these notions make no essential reference to the requirements of a social
relationship. They set out fully independent standards for the goodness of actions, motivations and states of
affairs, and the independent character of these standards allows them to serve as foundational elements in a
normative theory that has a consequentialist structure.[2]

According to classical utilitarianism, for example, the correct course of action is the optimal course of action
as judged from the standpoint of an impartial concern for the pleasures and pains of all sentient creatures
(Sidgwick 1874). Suppose that a relationship consists of a set of requirements for how people who stand in
the relationship should act towards one another—e.g., parents should feed their children, parents should
clothe their children, children should defer to their parents’ judgment, etc. According to classical
utilitarianism, an agent should perform the action that satisfies the requirements of a relationship only when
her doing so would result in the greatest sum of pleasure over pain. The notion of the good here—i.e., the
sum of pleasure over pain—is defined independently of the requirements of any relationship, so it sets out a
criterion for goodness that can tell us, among other things, when it would be good for people to comply with
any particular relational requirements.

Some welfare consequentialist notions of the good incorporate a distributive element—e.g., welfare
prioritarianism—and this feature may make it more plausible to see these notions as internal to the
requirements of a relationship. For example, some may think that welfare prioritarianism could be internal to
the family relationship, where the relationship is understood to require family members to perform the action
that is optimal from the standpoint of the worst off member of the group. But keep in mind that even more
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 2/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

distributionally sensitive notions of the good, such as welfare prioritarianism, retain other features of a
consequentialist understanding of goodness that make it difficult to see how these notions could be internal
to a relationship in the relevant sense.

Take agent neutrality. Insofar as welfare prioritarianism is a genuinely consequentialist notion, it says that the
correct course of action is the course of action that is optimal as judged from a standpoint that does not
change with the position of the agent or the relationships that the agent happens to stand in (Williams 1973;
Nagel 1986; cf. Sen 1993). Understood in this way, welfare prioritarianism does not require an agent to
perform the action that is optimal from the standpoint of the worst off member of her own family. Instead, it
requires an agent to perform the action that is optimal from the agent neutral standpoint of, say, the welfare
of the worst off person in the world or the average welfare of all those in the class of people who are worst
off in their respective families. If people have reason to pay special attention to the worst off member of their
own families, on this view, it is because a pattern of reasoning along these lines leads to the highest level of
welfare for the worst off person in the world or the highest average welfare for those in the relevant class.

Because it is an agent neutral notion, welfare prioritarianism may require parents to harm their own children
if circumstances arise such that doing so would bring about the best result from the standpoint of the welfare
of the worst off person in the world or the average welfare of those in the relevant class. A parent might be
required to act this way, even when lowering the welfare of her own child would lead to only a slightly
higher level of welfare for the other people affected. These implications are clearly at odds with our ordinary
understanding of the agent relative character of relational requirements.

The upshot is that welfare consequentialist accounts of political morality are not based, at the most
fundamental level, on conceptions of the common good. They are based instead on notions of the good that
are understood to be prior to and independent of any social relationship. Nonetheless, it is worth stressing
that a welfare consequentialist account of political morality may incorporate a conception of the common
good as part of a more specific account of the ethical obligations of citizens in public life. After all, a certain
pattern of agent relative motivation among citizens may be the optimal pattern as judged from the standpoint
of aggregate welfare (or some other suitably agent neutral perspective). John Stuart Mill sets out a theory
along these lines in Considerations on Representative Government (1862). On his view, citizens should take
an active interest in the public affairs of their community and social institutions should be designed to
generate this pattern of motivation among citizens. The reason for this is that an orientation among citizens
towards the common affairs of their community is part of the best political arrangement overall, as judged
from the standpoint of the principle of utility.[3]

2. Second Contrast: Public Goods


Another important contrast to draw is between the common good and a public good. In economic theory, a
public good is a particular type of good that members of a community would not possess if they were each
motivated only by their own self-interest.[4] Here is an example. Imagine that the residents in a town could
enjoy a mosquito free summer if most every resident treats her lawn with a bug spray. The spray costs
money, but every resident would be better off having paid for the spray and enjoying life without
mosquitoes. If most every resident sprays her lawn, everyone in the town will enjoy the benefit, even those
residents who do not spray their lawns. But there is no feasible way to exclude the nonsprayers from
enjoying the benefit.

The problem posed by a public good is that the optimal course of action for each individual, from the
standpoint of her egoistic rationality, is for her not to contribute to the provision of the good, even though
everyone would be better off if they all did so (see Olson 1965). Take any resident in the town I just
described. From the standpoint of her own self-interest, she should not spray her lawn: If the other residents
spray their lawns, she would get the benefit without paying the cost. And if the other residents do not spray
their lawns, she would save herself the cost of spraying her lawn. It follows that as long as residents are
moved only by their own self-interest, they will not produce the good of a mosquito free summer.

In both academic and nonacademic discussions, people often confuse the common good with a public good
or a set of public goods. But it is important to keep the two ideas distinct. The facilities that make up the
common good resemble public goods because they are often facilities that are supposed to be open and
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 3/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

available to everyone (e.g., a public library). This means that it is not possible to exclude those who do not
contribute from enjoying the benefits. Nonetheless, the facilities that make up the common good are
conceptually different from public goods because these facilities may not be a net benefit for each member of
the community. The facilities that make up the common good serve a special class of interests that all
citizens have in common, i.e., the interests that are the object of the civic relationship. But each citizen will
have various private interests in addition to these common interests, so for any particular citizen, the private
interests affected by some facility may be more important from the standpoint of her egoistic rationality than
the interests that belong to the special class of common interests. As such, the facility may not be a net
benefit to her.

Consider the case of a public library. Suppose that a certain library is part of the common good in a political
community because it serves an interest in the privileged class of common interests. Suppose the relevant
interest is an interest in guaranteed access to the storehouse of human knowledge. Some individual X owns a
bakery. Her bakery is profitable, but it would be even more profitable if people were not able to read certain
cookbooks at the library and so could not make her carrot muffins at home. X has an interest in guaranteed
access to the storehouse of human knowledge, but she also has an interest in her bakery’s profitability. If her
private interest in a muffin monopoly is more important from her egoistic perspective than her interest in
guaranteed access to the storehouse of human knowledge, then she is actually worse off because of the public
library.[5] In this case, the public library is part of the common good, but it is not a public good because there
is someone in the community who is worse off in virtue of the library’s existence.

Before moving on, note that people sometimes use “the public good” to refer to something other than the
technical notion of a public good in economic theory. In academic and nonacademic discussions, people
sometimes use “the public good” in a way that is more or less synonymous with “the common good”. This
use of the term was especially prevalent among political philosophers, roughly from the 16th century to the
19th century. For example, in the Second Treatise of Government (1698), John Locke defines political power
as the right to make binding laws and the right to mobilize the community in defense of these laws, where
both of these powers are

to be directed to no other end, but the Peace, Safety, and publick good of the People. (1698
[1988: 353]).

Here Locke uses the term “public good” to refer to interests that are common to all members of a political
community (e.g., the interest in bodily security and property), where members have a relational obligation to
care for these common interests. The “public good” in this sense basically refers to the common good,
though philosophers who use the term “public good” typically favor a thinner conception of the political
relationship and a more limited view of the powers of government.

3. Why Does Political Philosophy Need This Concept? Defects in a


“Private Society”
Why does political philosophy need the concept of the common good? What’s the rationale for having this
concept in addition to other concepts, such as welfare, justice, or human rights? To understand the
importance of the common good, it is helpful to think about the moral defects in a private society.

A private society is a society whose members care only about their lives as private individuals (Tocqueville
1835–1840; Hegel 1821; Rawls 1971; see also Dewey 1927). Members are not necessarily rational egoists—
they may care about their family and friends. What is central is that their motivational horizons do not extend
beyond the people and projects that are the focus of their personal lives.[6] As an individual in a private
society, I might be interested in acquiring a better home for my family or improving the local school for my
children and the other children in my neighborhood. I might even vote in national elections insofar as the
results could affect my home or my local school. But I take no interest in national elections insofar as the
results affect citizens I don’t know, those in other states or provinces. And I take no interest in national
elections insofar as the results affect the basic fairness of my society’s laws and institutions. Having
withdrawn into private life, I care about the common affairs of the community only insofar as these touch my
private world.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 4/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Many philosophers believe that there is something morally defective about a private society. One type of
defect bears especially on the case of a private society that consists of rational egoists. As I noted in the last
section, a community of rational egoists will not perform the actions necessary to generate public goods.
Since these goods are desirable, the absence of public goods may be suboptimal, both from the standpoint of
aggregate welfare and from the standpoint of each member’s egoistic rationality.[7] So there are good
instrumental reasons for people to create a public agency—i.e., a state—that can use taxes, subsidies and
coercive threats to draw people into mutually beneficial patterns of cooperation.[8]

The common good, however, points to a different kind of defect in a private society. The defect in this case
extends to all forms of private society, not just to a society of rational egoists, and the defect is
noninstrumental. The defect in this case is that the members of a political community have a relational
obligation to care about their common affairs, so the fact that they are exclusively concerned with their
private lives is itself a moral defect in the community, whether or not this pattern of concern leads to a
suboptimal outcome.

To appreciate the point, think about the various public roles that people may occupy in a liberal democracy
(see Hegel 1821; Dewey 1927; J. Cohen 2010: 54–58). Most obviously, citizens act in a public capacity
when they occupy positions as legislators, civil servants, judges, prosecutors, jurors, police officers, soldiers,
school teachers, and so on. They also act in a public capacity when they participate in the political process,
voting in elections and taking part in policy discussions in the public sphere (Habermas 1992; Mill 1862;
Rawls 1993 [2005]). And many philosophers argue that citizens act in a public capacity—or at least in a
partly public capacity—when they act as executives in large business enterprises (McMahon 2013;
Christiano 2010); as high-ranking officials in colleges and universities (Scanlon 2003); as journalists,
lawyers, and academics (Habermas 1992, e.g., [1996: 373–9]); as protesters engaged in civil disobedience
(Rawls 1971); and as socially conscious consumers (Hussain 2012).

When citizens occupy public roles, political morality requires them to think and act differently than they
would if they were acting as private individuals. If you are a judge in a criminal trial, you might stand to
benefit personally if the defendant were found guilty. But political morality does not allow you to decide
cases as if you were a private individual, looking to advance your own private objectives. As a judge, you are
required to make decisions based on the evidence presented at trial and the standards set out in the law. These
legal standards themselves are supposed to answer to common interests. So, in effect, political morality
directs you to think and act from the standpoint of a shared concern for common interests.

Citizens who occupy public roles may also be required to make personal sacrifices. Consider an historical
example. During the Watergate scandal, President Richard Nixon ordered the Attorney General of the United
States, Elliot Richardson, to fire the Watergate special prosecutor in order to stop an investigation into
Nixon’s abuses of power. Rather than carry out Nixon’s order, Richardson resigned his position. Many would
argue that Richardson did the right thing, and that, in fact, he had an obligation to refuse Nixon’s order, even
if this resulted in a significant setback to his career. As Attorney General, Richardson had an obligation to
uphold the rule of law in the United States, a practice that serves common interests, even if this meant
significant sacrifices in terms of his career aspirations.

Now consider the following possibility. Imagine that we are living in a liberal democracy with a full array of
social roles in which people act in a public capacity. But imagine that our society is a private society: citizens
care only about their own private affairs. In order to ensure that various public roles are filled, our
institutions create private incentives for people to take on these responsibilities. High salaries draw people
into positions as judges and legislators, and mutual surveillance gives these people private incentives to carry
out their duties. Suppose that our institutions are well structured and private incentives are adequate to fill all
of the important public positions. Is there anything missing in our society? Does our society suffer from a
moral defect of some kind?

Philosophers in the common good tradition believe that the answer is yes: there is something morally
significant that is missing from our society. What is missing is a genuine concern for the common good. No
one in our society actually cares about shared facilities, such as the rule of law, or the common interests that
these facilities serve. Citizens fill various public roles simply for the sake of the private benefits that they get
from doing so. According to a common good conception of political morality, this lack of concern for the

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 5/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

common good is itself a moral defect in a political community, even if private incentives lead people to fill
all of the relevant positions.

A central challenge for theorists in the common good tradition is to explain why a genuine commitment to
the common good matters. Why should it matter whether citizens actually care about the common good?
Some philosophers in the tradition cite a practical problem. Even in a well-designed arrangement,
circumstances are likely to arise where social institutions do not provide people with an adequate private
incentive to act in a publicly oriented way. For example, political morality may require public officials to
stand up for the rule of law, even in situations where this will damage their careers. Or political morality may
require citizens to protest against an unjust law, even if this means a private risk of being jailed or
blacklisted. Political morality may even require citizens to run the risk of losing their lives in order to defend
the constitutional order against a foreign threat (see Walzer 1970; Rousseau 1762b [1997: 63–4]). In each of
these cases, no matter how well designed institutions are, citizens may not have an adequate private incentive
to do what political morality requires, so a genuine concern for the common good may be essential.

A different explanation—perhaps the most important one in the common good tradition—stresses the idea of
a social relationship. Think of the relationship between parents and their children. This relationship requires
not only that the people involved act in certain ways towards one another, but also that they care about one
another in certain ways. For instance, parents are required not only to feed and clothe their children, perhaps
to avoid getting fined by the Department of Child and Family Services. Parents are also required to care
about their children: they must give their children’s interests a certain status in their practical reasoning.
Many philosophers argue that our relation to our fellow citizens has similar features. The political bond
requires not only that we act in certain ways, but also that we give the interests of our fellow citizens a
certain status in our practical reasoning. It would be unacceptable, on this view, for citizens to fulfill certain
public roles purely for the sake of private incentives. A Supreme Court justice, for example, must care about
the rule of law and the common interests that this practice serves. If she were making consistent rulings just
to cash her paycheck every two weeks, she would not be responding in the right way to her fellow citizens,
who act for the sake of common interests in doing things such as voting, following the law, and standing
ready to defend the constitutional order.[9]

Many philosophers believe that there is something morally defective about a private society, even one in
which private incentives move people to fill all of the important public roles. A conception of the common
good provides us with an account of what is missing from the practical reasoning of citizens in a private
society, and it connects this with a wider view about the relational obligations that require citizens to reason
in these ways.

4. Central Features of the Common Good


According to a common good conception of political morality, members of a political community stand in a
social relationship with one another. This relationship is not as intimate as the relationship among family
members or the members of a church. But it is a genuine social relationship nonetheless, and it requires
members not only to act in certain ways, but also to give one another’s interests a certain status in their
practical reasoning. This basic outlook leads most conceptions of the common good to share certain features.

4.1 A Shared Standpoint for Practical Reasoning


The first feature that most conceptions share is that they describe a pattern of practical reasoning that is
meant to be realized in the actual thought processes of the members of a political community. A conception
of the common good is not just a criterion for correct action, such that citizens would satisfy the conception
so long as they performed the correct action, regardless of their subjective reasons for doing so. The point of
a conception of the common good is to define a pattern of practical reasoning, a way of thinking and acting
that constitutes the appropriate form of mutual concern among members. In order to satisfy the conception,
the activities of the members of the community must be organized, at some level, by thought processes that
embody the relevant pattern.[10]

4.2 A Set of Common Facilities


https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 6/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Most conceptions of the common good identify a set of facilities that citizens have a special obligation to
maintain in virtue of the fact that these facilities serve certain common interests. The relevant facilities may
be part of the natural environment (e.g., the atmosphere, a freshwater aquifer, etc.) or human artifacts (e.g.,
hospitals, schools, etc.). But the most important facilities in the literature are social institutions and practices.
For example, a scheme of private property exists when members of a community conform to rules that assign
individuals certain forms of authority over external objects. Private property, as a social institution, serves a
common interest of citizens in being able to assert private control over their physical environment, and so
many conceptions include this institution as part of the common good.

4.3 A Privileged Class of Common Interests


A conception of the common good will define a privileged class of abstract interests. Citizens are understood
to have a relational obligation to create and maintain certain facilities because these facilities serve the
relevant interests. The interests in the privileged class are “common” in the sense that every citizen is
understood to have these interests to a similar degree.[11] The interests are “abstract” in the sense that they
may be served by a variety of material, cultural or institutional facilities. A wide variety of interests figure
prominently in the literature, including: the interest in taking part in the most choiceworthy way of life
(Aristotle Pol. 1323a14–1325b31); the interest in bodily security and property (e.g., Locke 1698; Rousseau
1762b); the interest in living a responsible and industrious private life (Smith 1776); the interest in a fully
adequate scheme of equal basic liberties (Rawls 1971 and 1993); the interest in a fair opportunity to reach
the more attractive positions in society (Rawls 1971); and the interest in security and welfare, where these
interests are understood as socially recognized needs that are subject to ongoing political determination
(Walzer 1983).

4.4 A Solidaristic Concern

Most conceptions of the common good define a form of practical reasoning that fits the model of solidarity.
Many social relationships require a form of solidarity among those who stand in the relationship. Solidarity
here basically involves one person giving a certain subset of the interests of another person a status in her
reasoning that is analogous to the status that she gives to her own interests in her reasoning (see, e.g.,
Aristotle NE 1166a1–33). For example, if my friend needs a place to sleep tonight, friendship requires that I
should offer him my couch. I have to do this because friendship requires that I reason about events that affect
my friend’s basic interests as if these events were affecting my own basic interests in a similar way. A
conception of the common good typically requires citizens to maintain certain facilities because these
facilities serve certain common interests. So when citizens reason as the conception requires, they effectively
give the interests of their fellow citizens a status in their reasoning that is analogous to the status that they
give to their own interests in their reasoning.

An example will make the idea more intuitive. According to Rousseau, a properly ordered political
community is “a form of association that will defend and protect the person and goods of each associate with
the full common force” (1762b [1997: 49]). Citizens in this community are united by a solidaristic form of
mutual concern that is focused on (among other things) their common interests in physical security and
property. This form of mutual concern requires each citizen to respond to an attack on the body or property
of a fellow citizen as if this were an attack on her own body and property. When extended over all members,
this form of mutual concern requires the whole community to respond to an attack on any individual member
as if this were an attack on every member. In this sense, “the full common force” stands behind each person’s
physical security and property. Or, as Rousseau sometimes puts it, “one cannot injure one of the members
without attacking the body, and still less can one injure the body without the members being affected”
(1762b [1997: 52]).[12]

4.5 A Nonaggregative Concern


A closely related feature is that most conceptions of the common good do not take an aggregative view of
individual interests. The aggregative view treats the satisfaction of individuals’ interests as commensurable
values, and it directs citizens to maximize the sum of these values. Because it focuses on the aggregate, the

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 7/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

aggregative view may require citizens to impose a debilitating condition on some of their fellow citizens
when this would generate sufficient gains for others.

Solidarity rules out the aggregative view. Starting with an appropriate view of her own interests, solidarity
requires each citizen to give certain interests of her fellow citizens a status in her reasoning that is similar to
the status that she gives to her own interests. This way of thinking does not allow citizens to abandon the
interests of any of their fellow citizens for the sake of aggregate gains. For instance, solidarity would not
allow citizens to subject some of their fellow citizens to slavery, even if this might produce substantial
benefits for others, because enslavement would involve a failure on the part of each citizen to give the
interests of each of her enslaved comrades the right status in her reasoning.

5. Common Interests (i): Joint Activity


Let’s turn now to some of the ways that conceptions of the common good differ from each other. One way
has to do with how they define the privileged class of common interests that are the object of the political
relationship. We can divide the important views in the literature into two main categories: (a) joint activity
conceptions and (b) private individuality conceptions.

A joint activity conception defines the privileged class of common interests as interests that members have in
taking part in a complex activity that involves all or most members of the community. Among those who
endorse this kind of view are ancient philosophers, such as Plato (Republic) and Aristotle (Politics), secular
natural law theorists such as John Finnis (1980), and most natural law theorists in the Catholic tradition.
Aspects of the joint activity view are also important in the work of communitarian thinkers such as Charles
Taylor (1984) and, to a lesser extent, Michael Sandel (2009). The most important and influential view is
Aristotle’s.

Aristotle holds that members of a political community are not just involved in a military alliance or an
especially dense network of contractual agreements (Pol. 1280b29–33). Members are also involved in a
relationship that he describes as a form of friendship (NE 1159b25–35). This friendship consists in citizens
wishing one another well, their being aware of the fact that their fellow citizens wish them well, and their
taking part in a shared life that answers to this mutual concern (Pol. 1280b29–1281a3). In caring about one
another and wishing one another well, what citizens care about in particular is that they and their fellow
citizens live well, that is, live the most choiceworthy life.[13]

The most choiceworthy life, on Aristotle’s view, is a pattern of activity that fully engages and expresses the
rational parts of human nature. This pattern of activity is a pattern of joint activity because, like a play, it has
various interdependent parts that can only be realized by the members of a group together. The pattern is
centered on an array of leisured activities that are valuable in themselves, including philosophy, mathematics,
art and music. But the pattern also includes the activity of coordinating the social effort to engage in leisured
activities (i.e., statesmanship) and various supporting activities, such as the education of citizens and the
management of resources.

On Aristotle’s view, a properly ordered society will have an array of material, cultural and institutional
facilities that answer to the common interest of citizens in living the most choiceworthy life. These facilities
form an environment in which citizens can engage in leisured activities and in which they can perform the
various coordinating and supporting activities. Some facilities that figure into Aristotle’s account include:
common mess halls and communal meals, which provide occasions for leisured activities (Pol. 1330a1–10;
1331a19–25); a communal system of education (Pol. 1337a20–30); common land (Pol. 1330a9–14);
commonly owned slaves to work the land (Pol. 1330a30–3); a shared set of political offices (Pol. 1276a40–
3; 1321b12–a10) and administrative buildings (Pol. 1331b5–11); shared weapons and fortifications (Pol.
1328b6–11; 1331a9–18); and an official system priests, temples and public sacrifices (Pol. 1322b17–28).

Aristotle’s account may seem distant from modern sensibilities, but a good analogy for what he has in mind
is the form of community that we associate today with certain universities. Think of a college like Princeton
or Harvard. Members of the university community are bound together in a social relationship marked by a
certain form of mutual concern: members care that they and their fellow members live well, where living
well is understood in terms of taking part in a flourishing university life. This way of life is organized around

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 8/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

intellectual, cultural and athletic activities, such as physics, art history, lacrosse, and so on. Members work
together to maintain an array of facilities that serve their common interest in taking part in this joint activity
(e.g., libraries, computer labs, dorm rooms, football fields, etc.). And we can think of public life in the
university community in terms of a form of shared practical reasoning that most members engage in, which
focuses on maintaining common facilities for the sake of their common interest.[14]

6. Common Interests (ii): Private Individuality


Private individuality conceptions offer a different account of the privileged class of common interests.
According to these views, members of a political community have a relational obligation to care about their
common interest in being able to lead lives as private individuals. Citizens each have an interest in being able
to shape their lives through their own private choices about what activities to pursue and what associations to
form. Choices are “private” in the relevant sense when citizens are not required to consult with anyone in
making these choices and they are not required to reach a decision through any form of shared deliberation.
[15] Among the philosophers who endorse this kind of view are many important thinkers in the liberal
tradition, including John Locke (1698), J.J. Rousseau (1762b), Adam Smith (1776), and G.W.F. Hegel
(1821). More recent figures who endorse this kind of view include John Rawls (1971) and Michael Walzer
(1983).

A sophisticated example of a private individuality conception is Rawls’s. On Rawls’s view, members of a


political community have a relational obligation to care for the interests attached to the “position of equal
citizenship” which all citizens share (1971 [1999: 82–83]). These interests are (a) the interest in a fully
adequate scheme of equal basic liberties and (b) the interest in a fair opportunity to reach the more attractive
positions in society. Rawls uses the term “the common good” to refer to the sum total of social conditions
that answer to the interests attached to the position of equal citizenship (1971 [1999: 217]). Understood in
this way, the common good consists, inter alia, of: a legal order that provides citizens with the liberty of
expression, the liberty of conscience and the other liberal freedoms; a democratic system of government that
provides citizens with political liberties, such as the liberty to vote, hold office and participate in collective
rule-making; a system of courts to enforce the rule of law; as well as police protection and national defense
to protect the basic liberties. The common good also consists of legal protections for free choice of
occupation; mass media mechanisms that gather and disperse information about job possibilities; a
transportation system to give people access to work; and a system of education (whether public or private)
that ensures conditions in which people with similar talents and motivations have similar prospects,
regardless of their class or family background.

Rawls’s conception has the core features of a private individuality view. The facilities that answer to the
common interest in equal liberty and fair opportunity put citizens in a position to join or withdraw from
various activities and associations as private persons who can make their own independent choices. For
example, the liberty of conscience gives citizens the legal right to join or leave a religious association based
on their own private beliefs. They need not consult with other citizens about these choices or make these
choices as part of a wider deliberative process that involves other citizens.

Rawls’s view takes the common good to consist partly in a system of bodily security, private property and
civil liberty. In this way, his view resembles Rousseau’s, which also focuses on these common interests.
Where Rawls’s view differs from Rousseau’s is that it extends the privileged class of common interests to
include an interest in a wider set of basic liberties and an interest in a fair opportunity to reach the more
attractive positions in society. These interests involve a more extensive array of institutions and social
conditions, especially when it comes to education, communication, and economic redistribution. But it is
worth emphasizing that neither Rawls nor Rousseau incorporates a full account of distributive justice into
their conceptions of the common good.[16] I will say more about this in the next section.

7. The Common Good Perspective: Communal or Distributive?


One of the most important differences among different conceptions of the common good has to do with how
they take private and sectional interests to factor into determining the relational obligations of citizens. Here

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 9/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

we can distinguish two main types of views: (a) communal conceptions of the common good and (b)
distributive conceptions of the common good.

Members of a political community have a relational obligation to care for certain interests that they have in
common. A “communal” conception of the common good takes these interests to be interests that citizens
have as citizens, where the status of being a citizen and the interests attached to this status are both
understood to be prior to the various statuses and interests that make up each member’s identity as a private
individual. When citizens engage in social deliberation about their laws and institutions, a communal
conception typically directs them to abstract away from their private interests and the sectional interests they
may have as members of one subgroup or another and to focus instead on their common interests as citizens.

For example, imagine that citizens are considering changes to trade rules in their society. They may be
inclined to assess proposals in terms of how attractive these are from the standpoint of their sectional
interests as members of a certain profession or participants in a certain industry. But a communal conception
of the common good directs citizens to set these interests aside and assess proposals in terms of how well
they answer to common civic interests, such as the interest in national security or the interest in a productive
economy.[17]

A “distributive” conception of the common good differs from a “communal” conception in that it does not
direct citizens to abstract away from their private and sectional interests in the same way. A distributive
conception starts with the idea that citizens belong to various groups with distinct sectional interests. These
interests make partly competing claims on the material, cultural and institutional facilities in a community.
The distributive conception incorporates a distributive principle that determines how social facilities should
answer to these sectional interests, and the conception says that members have a relational obligation to
maintain a set of facilities that answers to everyone’s sectional interests in the way that the distributive
principle prescribes.

As an example of a distributive view, consider the view held by many philosophers, which defines the
common good in terms of Rawls’s difference principle (see, e.g., J. Cohen 1996 [2009: 169–170]; see also
section 8 below). According to this view, we can think of citizens as belonging to various subgroups, each
consisting of all those born into a certain “starting position” in social life. Citizens in each group share
certain choice-independent characteristics, such as their class position at birth and their level of innate talent.
Group members have sectional interests in better life prospects (as measured in terms of primary goods),
where these interests make partly competing claims on the basic structure of society. The difference principle
says that social institutions should answer to the interests of each group equally, with the caveat that
institutions should incorporate whatever inequalities would serve to maximize the prospects of the least
advantaged group. Citizens are then understood to have a relational obligation to maintain a scheme of
institutions that attends to everyone’s sectional interests in the way that the difference principle prescribes.

The disagreement between communal and distributive conceptions of the common good is perhaps the most
important disagreement among different conceptions, and it raises some important questions about the nature
of the political relationship. Let me make two general points.

The first has to do with the moral underpinnings of the communal view. It is helpful to think of communal
accounts of the common good as appealing to a certain conception social life (e.g., Rousseau 1762b; Hegel
1821; Walzer 1983). According to this conception, citizens form their various private and sectional interests
within the framework of a more fundamental effort to maintain certain social conditions together. The
political bond is prior to their private interests in a certain way, so the political relationship may sometimes
require citizens to set their private interests aside in order to act collectively to maintain the relevant social
conditions. Perhaps the clearest example of this is national defense (see section 9 below). When defending
the constitutional order against a foreign threat, political morality requires citizens to act collectively in
defense of common interests, without organizing their efforts in a way that answers specifically to their
competing private interests in different levels of protection.

An analogy may help here. Members of a family each have distinct interests as private individuals—e.g., in
developing their talents, pursuing relationships, cultivating career prospects, and so on. At some level, the
household must be organized in a way that answers to these private interests. But there are some matters
where the familial relationship requires members to act together in a way that sets their competing private
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 10/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

interests aside. If the family home is on fire, members are required to save the home, without special regard
for how resources are being deployed in ways that are more likely to save one member’s room rather than
another’s. In certain domains, members are supposed to act from a communal point of view that focuses on
common interests that are essential to their social bond, rather than their distinct and potentially competing
interests as private individuals. Communal conceptions of the common good see the political relationship as
having a similar character.[18]

The second point is that—surprisingly—Rawls himself favours a substantially communal rather than
distributive conception of the common good. In A Theory of Justice, he does not define the common good in
terms of his full conception of social justice. He defines it instead in terms of the “principle of common
interest”. This principle assesses social institutions from the position of equal citizenship. As he says, “as far
as possible, the basic structure should be appraised from the position of equal citizenship” where this
position “is defined by the rights and liberties required by the principle of equal liberty and the principle of
fair equality of opportunity” (1971 [1999: 82–83]). Rawls thinks that a wide variety of policy questions can
be settled by appeal to the principle of common interest, including “reasonable regulations to maintain public
order”, “efficient measures for public health and safety”, and “collective efforts for national defense in a just
war” (1971 [1999: 83]).[19]

Social deliberation, on Rawls’s view, should unfold, as far as possible, within a framework of reasoning that
focuses on interests that are common to all citizens, where the difference principle enters the discussion
mainly when the appeal to common interests alone could not properly decide an issue. But why should
political deliberation unfold in this way? Why does Rawls think that, “as far as possible, the basic structure
should be appraised from the position of equal citizenship”?

One possible rationale has to do with the kind of solidarity that citizens realize through their shared status as
“citizens”. When members of a society reason in terms of the principle of common interest, they set their
private and sectional interests aside whenever possible in order to focus on their common interests as
citizens. Setting their sectional interests aside (e.g., as members of the least advantaged group, the second
least advantaged group, the third least advantaged group, etc.), citizens treat their shared interests as
“citizens” as being more fundamental than their distinct and potentially competing interests as private
individuals. Each citizen effectively tells her fellow citizens, “What unites us is more important than what
divides us”. Bringing the status of “citizen” to the center of how citizens relate to one another in public life is
particularly important for Rawls because mutual recognition on the basis of this shared status is important to
his account of how a just social order will prevent envy and positional competition from undermining the
basic liberties (1971 [1999: 476–9]).

A closely related idea has to do with mutuality (section 4.4 and 4.5 above). When members of society reason
in terms of their common interests in liberty and opportunity, they assess policies from a standpoint that does
not distinguish between one citizen and another. They each accord the interests of their fellow citizens the
very same status in their reasoning that they accord to their own interests. When citizens do their parts in a
social arrangement that answers to common interests, and they do so on the grounds that the arrangement
serves common interests, citizens realize a form of solidarity that is perfectly mutual: each citizen works for
the interests of each her fellow citizens in exactly the same way that each of her fellow citizens works for her
interests.

Social cooperation on the basis of the difference principle does not embody the same kind of mutuality.
Imagine that citizens are reasoning about their institutions. Starting with an arrangement that creates equal
prospects for those born into every starting position, they consider different arrangements that would yield
Pareto improvements over the egalitarian scheme.[20] Citizens must now choose between different
possibilities: one arrangement would maximize the prospects for the least advantaged group; another would
maximize the prospects for the second least advantaged group; a third would maximize the prospects for the
third least advantaged group; and so on. Given these possibilities, the difference principle requires citizens to
choose the arrangement that is best from the standpoint of one group in particular—i.e., those in the least
advantaged position.

Imagine now that we live in a social order that satisfies the difference principle. There are certain facilities in
society—say, certain educational facilities—that answer distinctively to the interests of those in the least
advantaged group. The resources involved could have been deployed in ways that would have been better for
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 11/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

those in the second least advantaged group, or the third least advantaged group, etc., so the arrangement as a
whole is tilted in favour of one group in particular. Because it is tilted in this way, the pattern of interaction
lacks the property of perfect mutuality: each citizen does not work for the interests of each of her fellow
citizens in exactly the same way each of her fellow citizens works for her interests. Everyone works in a way
that is distinctively oriented towards the interests of the least advantaged.

Of course, citizens realize a form of solidarity insofar as social cooperation is organized in light of the
difference principle; the point is just that citizens realize a distinctive form of solidarity insofar as social
cooperation is organized in light of the principle of common interest. In the latter case, they realize a more
communal form of solidarity, as citizens set their private interests aside to focus on common interests and
citizens attach no special significance to the distinctions between different groups. A more communal form
of solidarity answers better to the social dimension of the political relationship and this may be one reason
why Rawls favors a form of public reasoning in which the principle of common interest governs “matters
which concern the interests of everyone and in regard to which distributive effects are immaterial or
irrelevant” (1971 [1999: 82–83]).

8. The Common Good in Politics: Democracy and Collective


Decision-Making
In the vast literature on the common good, several topics stand out as important subjects of concern. One
important topic is democracy. Democracy figures prominently in philosophical reflection about the common
good because there is broad agreement among philosophers—though by no means universal agreement!—
that a private society would be defective in terms of the way that members make collective decisions.
Collective decision-making in a political community must unfold in its public life, that is, in the sphere of
interaction in which citizens transcend their own private concerns and reason from the standpoint of the
common good.

On some accounts of democracy, citizens are not required to take up the perspective of the common good.
According to pluralism, for example, democracy is best understood as a collective decision-making process
that disperses power and influence among many different groups in society (see Dahl 1956 and 1989).
Citizens each have their own private interests and groups of citizens with similar interests advance these
interests in various rule-making forums. The overall process is essentially a form of bargaining, where each
group strategically trades concessions with other groups in order to maximize the satisfaction of their policy
preferences. A properly ordered democratic regime will maintain fair bargaining conditions, where all
important groups are able to exercise a meaningful degree of influence on the collective decisions that affect
their interests. But on the pluralist view no one needs to take an interest in the common affairs of the
community: each citizen may care only about her own private affairs, entering the public forum to advance
her private interests against the interests of others.

Many philosophers criticize pluralism and other similarly privatized views of democratic reasoning because
these views fail to capture an important aspect of political life. As Jeremy Waldron notes, citizens often vote
on the basis of something other than their own private interests:

People often vote on the basis of what they think is the general good of society. They are
concerned about the deficit, or about abortion, or about Eastern Europe, in a way that reflects
nothing more about their own personal interests than that they have a stake in the issues.
Similarly, the way they vote will usually take into account their conception of the special
importance of certain interests and liberties. (Waldron 1990 [1993: 408])

Many critics also contend that pluralism does not distinguish properly between the form of practical
reasoning appropriate to democratic decision-making and the form that is appropriate in market contexts.
Managers in a firm may justify one business strategy over another on the grounds that this strategy will
improve the bottom line for the firm, taking no account of how the strategy might harm competitors or other
groups. But citizens in a democratic process are not supposed to reason this way:

…it is a political convention of a democratic society to appeal to the common interest. No


political party publicly admits to pressing for legislation to the disadvantage of any recognized
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 12/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

social group. (Rawls 1971 [1999: 280])

If a privatized approach to democratic decision-making is morally defective, what exactly is the problem?
What is wrong with citizens assessing laws and voting on laws based on how well these will serve their
private interests?

One prominent line of reasoning in democratic theory appeals to an epistemic conception of democracy (e.g.,
Rousseau 1762b; J. Cohen 1986). According to this view, there is an independent standard of correctness for
legislation, which says that laws must serve common interests. Democratic decision-making is a requirement
of political morality because the legislative process is more likely to generate laws that meet the standard
when the process is democratic. Moreover, a democratic process is more likely to generate laws that meet the
standard when those taking part in the process are actually trying to identify laws that meet the standard. So
citizens taking part in the democratic process should assess legislative proposals in terms of how well these
proposals serve common interests because this is the best way to identify and enact laws that are justified.

The other main line of reasoning in democratic theory appeals to a deliberative conception of democracy (J.
Cohen 1996, 2009; Habermas 1992; Gutman & Thompson 1996). According to Joshua Cohen’s deliberative
conception, political morality requires citizens to make binding collective decisions through a process of
public reasoning in which citizens recognize one another as equal members of the political community (J.
Cohen 1989, 1996). The process of public reasoning requires that each citizen should offer reasons to
convince others to adopt a legislative proposal, where these reasons are reasons that she could properly
expect others to accept, given the facts of reasonable pluralism.

Cohen argues that the ideal of deliberative democracy, as he understands it, provides a compelling account of
the common good orientation of democratic decision-making (1996 [2009: 168–170]). No citizen could
reasonably expect others to accept a legislative proposal simply because it serves her own interests, so there
is a basic requirement that any legislative proposal must be responsive to the interests of all citizens.
Furthermore, the background idea that citizens are equal members of the political community imposes an
additional requirement. Citizens

can reject, as a reason within [the] process, that some are worth less than others or that the
interests of one group are to count less than the interests of other groups. (1996 [2009: 169])

This constraint on acceptable reasons leads to a substantive requirement that legislation must be consistent
with a public understanding of the common good that treats people as equals in the relevant sense.

Cohen cites Rawls’s difference principle as one example of a public understanding of the common good that
satisfies the relevant requirement.

Treating equality as a baseline, [the difference principle] requires that inequalities established or
sanctioned by state action must work to the maximal advantage of the least advantaged. That
baseline [i.e., equality] is a natural expression of the constraints on reasons that emerge from the
background equal standing of citizens: it will not count as a reason for a system of policy that
that system benefits the members of a particular group singled out by social class or native talent
or any other feature that distinguishes among equal citizens. […In addition, the principle]
insists, roughly speaking, that no one be left less well off than anyone needs to be—which is
itself a natural expression of the deliberative conception. (J. Cohen 1996 [2009: 169–170])

Note that Cohen argues here for a “distributive” rather than a “communal” conception of the common good
(see section 7 above). On Cohen’s view, members of a political community have a relational obligation to
provide one another with a set of facilities that answers to everyone’s sectional interests in the way that a
certain distributive principle prescribes (i.e. the difference principle). This differs from a communal
conception, which does not conceive of the relational obligation of citizens in terms of a distributive
principle.

Cohen is probably right that the difference principle is a natural expression of the deliberative ideal against
the background of an assumption that all citizens are equal members of the political community. But
defenders of a communal conception might argue that the political relationship among citizens has a social
dimension that goes beyond equal membership in the political community. Like the relationship among
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 13/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

friends or among members of a sports team, the political relationship must be understood to impose
obligations on people that embody relational ideals such as solidarity and mutuality. This means that the
political relationship may require citizens to reason with each other in ways that embody these values. For
instance, the political relationship may require citizens to set their private and sectional interests aside in
certain deliberative contexts in order to focus on their common interests as citizens. An implicit concern for
social ideals such as solidarity and mutuality may be one reason why Rawls identifies the common good with
the principle of common interest and gives this principle a special role to play in political reasoning.

9. The Common Good in Civic Life: Burden Sharing and Resource


Pooling
Many philosophers agree that citizens must transcend their private concerns when they take part in the
political process. But some philosophers believe that there are other aspects of social life in which citizens
have a relational obligation to transcend their private concerns. Two especially prominent examples in the
literature involve burden sharing and resource pooling. Michael Walzer’s discussion of conscription and
national defense highlights several important issues (1983: 64–71, 78–91, 97–9, and 168–70; see also Walzer
1970).

When a foreign power threatens the constitutional order in a liberal democracy, political morality seems to
direct citizens to defend the order in a particular way. Citizens must approach national defense as a
communal enterprise in which they organize themselves to achieve a certain common level of security
together through various forms of burden sharing and resource pooling. Burden sharing, in this case, requires
every member of the community to participate in some way in carrying the collective burden of fighting the
threat. Some citizens will do the actual fighting, but others will contribute by treating the wounded,
developing weapons, taking care of children, sending care packages to soldiers, rationing essential resources,
and so on.

The moral importance of burden sharing comes out most clearly when we consider certain highly privatized
ways of organizing national defense. Consider, for example, a market based approach. A political community
might allow entrepreneurs to set up “protection agencies” that would act as firms, hiring mercenaries, buying
weapons, and selling varying levels of protection to individual citizens based on their preferences and their
ability to pay (see Nozick 1974). Even if it were possible to defend people’s constitutional liberties through a
mechanism of this kind,[21] political morality seems to rule it out. One reason is that the market scheme
would allow citizens who are wealthy enough to buy protection services for themselves, but then leave it to
others to face the actual dangers of combat. This would violate the communal ideal that all citizens must
share in some way in carrying the collective burden of defending the community (see Walzer 1983: 98–9 and
169).

Another problem with a highly privatized approach to national defence has to do with the injured. When
soldiers get injured in combat, their injuries have a different moral status as compared to the injuries that
they might suffer if they decide to do things as private individuals like ride a motorcycle or work in a circus.
The difference is that combat injuries are not private injuries that citizens must bear as private persons. Even
in the case where soldiers volunteer for combat, they perform a public service and we treat their injuries as
part of a collective burden that the community as a whole must bear, e.g., by providing medical care and
rehabilitation services to the wounded free of charge.

The communal ideal of public service and burden sharing might extend beyond national defence to other
forms of socially necessary work that is difficult or dangerous.

Miners today are free citizens, but we might think of them…as citizens in the service of the
nation. And then we might treat them as if they were conscripts, not sharing their risks, but
sharing the costs of the remedy: research into mine safety, health care designed for their
immediate needs, early retirement, decent pensions, and so on. (Walzer 1983: 170)

A more extensive application of the communal ideal might require citizens to treat the burdens associated
with other occupations as parts of a shared social burden, including the burdens faced by police officers,

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 14/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

firefighters, teachers, day care workers, nurses, nursing home workers, and so on (cf. Brennan & Jaworski
2015).

Besides burden sharing, resource pooling is another way that citizens may organize their activities in light of
the common good. Many facilities in a modern liberal democracy serve common interests, including the
armed forces, public health services, and the education system. These facilities require material resources,
and this raises an array of questions about how to generate these resources and incorporate them into the pool
of assets that serve common interests.

Aristotle favors an approach that works through private ownership. In Plato’s Republic, almost all of the
resources held by the guardians are held as collective assets that the guardians may use for the sake of the
common interest of the community.[22] Importantly, because the guardians hold almost nothing as private
property, they do nothing that is analogous to the choices that a group of friends might make on a camping
trip to voluntarily pool their resources for the sake of common interests. In other words, the guardians do not
express their concern for the members of the community through gifts, donations or other forms of private
contribution. Partly for this reason, Aristotle favors an arrangement in which citizens have private ownership
and control over assets and a civic obligation to pool these assets for the sake of common interests (see Kraut
2002: 327–56). For example, if the community faces a naval threat, wealthy citizens in Aristotle’s ideal
community would be responsible for building warships and contributing these ships to the war effort.

Aristotle’s view draws attention to an important set of questions in contemporary market societies. The civic
obligation he has in mind comes closest to our notion of private philanthropy. But is private philanthropy
really the right way for a community to maintain common facilities for the sake of common interests? In
2015, Mark Zuckerberg, the billionaire founder of Facebook, announced that he would donate 99% of his
shares in the company to charitable causes, including public education (Kelly 2015). From Aristotle’s point
of view, this reflects well on our society: our institutions put wealth in private hands, thereby allowing
citizens to make meaningful choices to pool their wealth for common interests. But many would argue that
our arrangements are seriously defective insofar as they put some individuals in a position to control a private
fortune worth over $45 billion, even if these individuals will eventually devote these resources to common
interests. Plato is on to something when he says that political solidarity requires that social institutions
channel some wealth directly into the public domain. But Plato seems to go too far in the other direction, and
this leaves us with an important set of questions about when society should pool resources through the state
and when society should pool resources through private philanthropy.

10. Markets, Competition and the Invisible Hand


A third important topic in philosophical reflection about the common good is the market. Citizens have a
relational obligation to care about certain common interests, and social coordination through markets can
draw citizens into a pattern of production activity and consumption activity that answers to these interests.
For example, markets can lead citizens to make better use of land and labor in society, thereby generating
more resources for everyone to use in pursuing their various ends. The problem is that market coordination
involves a privatized form of reasoning, and the proper functioning of the market may require citizens not to
reason from the standpoint of the common good.

To illustrate, suppose that a society uses markets to coordinate the education of citizens (see Friedman 1962).
A system of for-profit schools would operate as firms, hiring teachers, buying computers, and selling
education services to the public. Parents, in turn, would act as consumers, buying the best education for their
children at the lowest cost. Each citizen in this arrangement would reason from the standpoint of her own
private concerns: as school managers, citizens would aim to maximize profits, and as parents, citizens would
aim to get the best education for their children at the lowest cost. No one would act out of a concern for the
education system as a shared facility that serves common interests. In fact, the market may require citizens to
avoid this perspective. After all, to lower costs effectively, school managers must not show too much concern
for the education of their students. And in order to improve the education of their own children, parents must
not show too much concern for the education of other people’s children.

We can divide the philosophical debate into two camps. The first camp says that market society—i.e., a
social order that relies extensively on markets to coordinate social life—is compatible with the requirements
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 15/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

of the political relationship. Theorists in this camp include Adam Smith (1776), G.W.F. Hegel (1821), John
Rawls (1971), Michael Sandel (2009) and perhaps Michael Walzer (1983). We might also include
deliberative democrats such as Jürgen Habermas (1992) and Joshua Cohen (Cohen & Sabel 1997).[23]

As an example of someone in the first camp, consider Hegel (1821) and his view of the market. Hegel
follows Adam Smith in thinking that the market draws citizens into a pattern of specialization that serves
common interests. The market does this through prices. Each citizen finds that she can do better for herself
by developing her talents and selling her labor at the going rate, then buying the goods that she needs from
others. But following price signals involves a form of reasoning that is focused only on private interests, not
the common good. As a result, it is essential, on Hegel’s view, that the realm of market activity must be
integrated into a wider political community. As members of a political community, citizens (or at least some
citizens) discuss their common interests in the public sphere, vote in elections, and find their views
represented in legislative deliberations that shape an official conception of the common good. This official
conception shapes the laws and guides the government in managing the economy. So even if citizens do not
reason from the standpoint of the common good as market actors, their lives as a whole are organized by a
form of reasoning that is focused on maintaining shared facilities for the sake of common interests.

The other camp in the disagreement says that market society is not compatible with the requirements of the
political relationship. Theorists in this camp include Aristotle (see Pol. 1256b39–1258a17), Rousseau
(1762b), Marx (1844, 1867), and G.A. Cohen (2009). Marx’s view provides an interesting contrast to
Hegel’s.

Marx agrees with Hegel that members of a political community must organize their activities in light of a
conception of the common good. But he does not think that members live up to the ideal if most of them
never actually reason from this standpoint. A political community must be “radically democratic” in the
sense that ordinary citizens participate directly in the collective effort to organize social life by appeal to a
conception of the common good (Marx 1844). What makes social coordination through markets problematic
is that market actors are drawn into certain patterns of activity through prices, which means that they never
actually reason with each other in terms of the common good. On Marx’s view, a properly ordered political
community would move beyond this opaque form of social coordination:

The life-process of society, which is based on the process of material production, does not strip
off its mystical veil until it is treated as production by freely associated men, and is consciously
regulated by them in accordance with a settled plan. (Marx 1867 [1967:84]).

In a properly ordered political community, members will transcend the authoritarian mysticism of price
coordination and organize their production and consumption activities through an open and transparent
process of reasoning that makes explicit to everyone how their activities serve common interests.

Many contemporary issues in political philosophy revolve around questions about the market and the
standpoint of the common good. Most theorists today hold views that fall somewhere between the two camps
I just described: they argue for some more nuanced view about when citizens are supposed to adopt a
privatized perspective and when they must reason from the standpoint of the common good.

When it comes to corporations and corporate executives, for example, Thomas Christiano (2010) argues for a
certain kind of socially conscious orientation: corporate leaders must reason from the standpoint of the
common good at least in limiting their strategic pursuit of private objectives in a way that is consistent with
the broader social objectives established by democratic majorities.[24] Joseph Heath (2014) argues for a more
limited view, such that market actors must not take a purely privatized perspective in cases where
externalities and other market failures would prevent the market process from generating attractive results. A
great deal of work remains to be done when it comes to other aspects of market life that may require citizens
to reason from a more socially conscious perspective, particularly when it comes to labor rights, political
liberties and climate change.

Another important set of contemporary issues has to do with competition. Market coordination typically
works through a process in which citizens compete with one another for important goods. In the United
States, for instance, labor market participants compete for jobs that substantially determine who gets access
to different levels of income, and by extension, different levels of health care, police protection,
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 16/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

consideration in the justice system, and political influence. As citizens square off against each other, each
one strives to secure important goods for herself, knowing that her activities will—if successful—effectively
deprive some other citizen of these same goods. In this way, labor market competition requires citizens to act
with an extreme form of disregard for how their actions affect one another’s basic interests.

Many philosophers believe that the antagonistic structure of market competition is inconsistent with the
relational obligation that members of a political community have to care about certain common interests.
G.A. Cohen (2009: 34–45) articulates the problem in terms of a “socialist principle of community” that rules
out social arrangements that require people to view one another simply as obstacles that must be overcome.
Hussain (forthcoming) takes a more moderate view, arguing that there is a difference between a “friendly
competition” and a “life or death struggle”. The political relationship allows for a certain degree of
competition among citizens, but it limits how severely institutions can pit citizens against each other when it
comes to goods that are part of the common good, e.g., health care, education, and the social bases of self-
respect.

11. Conclusion: Social Justice and the Common Good


This article has covered the main points of agreement and disagreement among different conceptions of the
common good, as well as a few central topics of concern. Let me conclude by saying something about the
relation between the common good and social justice.

Consider the case of friendship. Friendship is a social relationship that requires those who stand in the
relationship to think and act in ways that embody a particular form of mutual concern. The relevant form of
concern incorporates the basic requirements of morality—i.e., what Scanlon (1998) calls “the morality of
right and wrong”—as friends must not lie to each other, assault each other, or take unfair advantage of each
other. But even strangers are required to conform to these basic moral standards. What distinguishes
friendship is that the form of mutual concern it involves goes beyond basic morality and requires friends to
maintain certain patterns of conduct on the grounds that these patterns serve certain common interests.

Members of a political community stand in a social relationship, and this relationship also requires them to
think and act in ways that embody a certain form of mutual concern. The common good defines this form of
concern. The common good incorporates certain basic requirements of social justice, as citizens must
provide one another with basic rights and freedoms and they must not exploit each other. But the common
good goes beyond the basic requirements of justice because it requires citizens to maintain certain patterns of
conduct on the grounds that these patterns serve certain common interests.

The analogy with friendship should make it clear that the common good is distinct from, but still closely
related to social justice. According to most of the major traditional views, the facilities and interests that
members of a political community have a relational obligation to care about are partly defined in terms of
social justice. For instance, Rousseau (1762b), Hegel (1821) and Rawls (1971) all hold that a basic system of
private property is both a requirement of justice and an element of the common good. Similarly, in Natural
Law and Natural Rights, Finnis holds that respect for human rights is a requirement of justice and that “the
maintenance of human rights is a fundamental component of the common good” (1980: 218). But the
common good goes beyond the requirements of justice because (1) it describes a pattern of inner motivation,
not just a pattern of outer conduct and (2) it may incorporate facilities and interests that are not general
requirements of justice.

All of this leaves us with some important questions. Many contemporary social issues turn on disagreements
about when citizens may take up a privatized perspective and when they must reason from the standpoint of
the common good. Social justice is often silent on these issues because people could, in principle, act as
justice requires, whether they are moved by a scheme of private incentives or by a concern for common
interests. These social issues are best understood as turning on disagreements about the nature of the political
relationship and the form of mutual concern that it requires. Philosophical reflection has an important role to
play in shedding light on this relationship and what it requires of us beyond what we owe to each other as a
matter of justice.

Bibliography
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 17/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Aristotle, 1984 [Pol.], Politics, Carnes Lord (trans.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
–––, 1985 [NE], Nichomachean Ethics, Terence Irwin (trans.), Indianapolis: Hackett.
Axelrod, Robert, 1981, “The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists”, American Political Science
Review, 75(2): 306–318. doi:10.2307/1961366
–––, 1984, The Evolution of Cooperation, New York: Basic Books.
Barbieri, William J., Jr., 2001, “Beyond the Nations: The Expansion of the Common Good in Catholic Social
Thought”, The Review of Politics, 63(4): 723–754. doi:10.1017/S0034670500032149
Brennan, Jason and Peter Martin Jaworski, 2015, “Markets Without Symbolic Limits”, Ethics, 125(4): 1053–
1077. doi:10.1086/680907
Cahill, Lisa Sowle, 1987, “The Catholic Tradition: Religion, Morality, and the Common Good”, Journal of
Law and Religion, 5(1): 75–94. doi:10.2307/1051018
Christiano, Thomas, 2010, “The Uneasy Relationship between Democracy and Capital”, Social Philosophy
and Policy, 27(1): 195–217. doi:10.1017/S0265052509990082
Cohen, G.A., 2009, Why Not Socialism?, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Cohen, Joshua, 1986, “An Epistemic Conception of Democracy”, Ethics, 97(1): 26–38. doi:10.1086/292815
–––, 1989 [2009], “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”, in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the
State, Alan Hamlin and Phillip Petit (eds), New York: Blackwell, pp. 17–34. Reprinted in J. Cohen
2009: ch. 1.
–––, 1996 [2009], “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy”, in Democracy and Difference:
Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, Seyla Benhabib (ed.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, pp. 95–119. Reprinted in J. Cohen 2009: ch. 5.
–––, 2009, Philosophy, Politics, Democracy: Selected Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
–––, 2010, Rousseau: A Free Community of Equals, (Founders of modern political and social thought),
Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199581498.001.0001
Cohen, Joshua and Charles Sabel, 1997 [2009], “Directly Deliberative Polyarchy”, European Law Journal,
3(4): 313–342. Reprinted in J. Cohen 2009: ch. 6.
Cooper, John M., 1990, “Political Animals and Civic Friendship”, Aristoteles “Politik”: Akten des XI.
Symposium Aristotelicum (Proceedings of the XIth Symposium Aristotelicum), Gunther Patzip (ed.),
Friedrichshafen/Bodensee: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, pp. 220–241. Reprinted in Aristotle’s Politics:
Critical Essays, Richard Kraut and Steven Skultety (eds), New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers,
2005.
Dahl, Robert A., 1956, A Preface to Democratic Theory, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
–––, 1989, Democracy and Its Critics, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Dewey, John, 1927 [2012], The Public and its Problems, University Park: Penn State Press.
Dworkin, Ronald, 1986, Law’s Empire, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Friedman, Milton, 1962, Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Finnis, John, 1980, Natural Law and Natural Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gauthier, David P., 1986, Morals by Agreement, Oxford: Clarendon. doi:10.1093/0198249926.001.0001
Gutman, Amy and Dennis Thompson, 1996, Democracy and Disagreement, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Habermas, Jürgen, 1981a [1984], A Theory of Communicative Action (Theorie des kommunikativen
Handelns), vol. 1, Reason and the Rationalization of Society, Thomas McCarthy (trans.), Boston:
Beacon Press. Originally published in German in 1981.
–––, 1981b [1989], A Theory of Communicative Action (Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns), vol. 2,
Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason, Thomas McCarthy (trans.), Boston: Beacon
Press. Originally published in German in 1981.
–––, 1992 [1996], Between Facts and Norms (Faktizität und Geltung), William Rehg (trans.), Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press. Originally published in German in 1992, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Heath, Joseph, 2001, Communicative Action and Rational Choice, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
–––, 2006, “The Benefits of Cooperation”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 34(4): 313–351. doi:10.1111/j.1088-
4963.2006.00073.x
–––, 2014, Morality, Competition and the Firm: The Market Failures Approach to Business Ethics, New
York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199990481.001.0001
Hegel, G.W.F., 1821 [1991], Elements of the Philosophy of Right (Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts),
Allen W. Wood (ed.), H.B. Nisbet (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1651 [1991], Leviathan, Richard Tuck (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hussain, Waheed, 2012, “Is Ethical Consumerism an Impermissible Form of Vigilantism?”, Philosophy &
Public Affairs, 40(2): 112–143. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2012.01218.x
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 18/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

–––, forthcoming. “Why should we care about competition?”, Critical Review of International Social and
Political Philosophy, first published online: 08 Nov 2017. doi:10.1080/13698230.2017.1398859
Kelly, Heather, 2015, “Zuckerberg pledges 99% of Facebook stock to charitable causes”, CNN Money, 2
December 2015. [available online]
Kraut, Richard, 2002, Aristotle: Political Philosophy, (Founders of modern political and social thought),
New York: Oxford University Press.
Locke, John, 1698 [1988], Two Treatises of Government, Peter Laslett (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lewis, David K., 1969, Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Marx, Karl, 1844 [1978], “On the Jewish Question” (Zur Judenfrage), in The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd
edition, Robert C. Tucker (ed.), New York: W. W. Norton.
–––, 1867 [1967], Capital (Das Kapital), volume one, New York: International Publishers
McMahon, Christopher, 2013, Public Capitalism: The Political Authority of Corporate Executives,
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Mill, John Stuart, 1859, “On Liberty”, Reprinted in Mill 2015.
–––, 1862, “Considerations on Representative Government”, Reprinted in Mill 2015.
–––, 2015, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and other Essays, Mark Philp and Frederick Rosen (eds), Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Nagel, Thomas, 1986, The View from Nowhere, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nagle, John Copeland, 2015, “Pope Francis, Environmental Anthropologist”, Regent University Law Review,
28(1): 7–47.
Nozick, Robert, 1974, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.
Olson, Mancur, 1965, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups, revised
edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Revised edition, 1971.
Ostrom, Elinor, 1990, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plato, The Republic of Plato, Allan Bloom (trans.), 2nd edition, New York: Basic Books, 1991.
Rawls, John, 1971 [1999], A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Page numbers
from the revised edition 1999.
–––, 1982 [2005], “The Basic Liberties and Their Priority”, Tanner Lectures on Human Values, volume 3,
Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, pp. 3–87. Reprinted in Rawls 1993 [2005].
–––, 1988 [2005], “Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 17(4): 251–276.
Reprinted in Rawls 1993 [2005].
–––, 1993 [2005], Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press. Expanded edition 2005.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1758, “Lettre a M. D'Alembert sur les spectacles”. Translated in Politics and the
Arts: Letter to M. D’Alembert on the Theatre, Alan Bloom (trans.), New York: Free Press, 1960.
–––, 1762a [1979], Émile, ou De l’éducation, Translated as Emile: or, On Education, Alan Bloom (trans.),
New York: Basic Books.
–––, 1762b [1997], Du contrat social; ou Principes du droit politique (On the Social Contract), France.
Translated in Rousseau 1997: 39–152.
–––, 1772 [1997], “Considérations sur le gouvernement de Pologne” (Considerations on the Government of
Poland). Translated in Rousseau 1997: 177–260.
–––, 1997, ‘The Social Contract’ and Other Later Political Writings , (Cambridge Texts in the History of
Political Thought), Victor Gourevitch (ed./trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sandel, Michael J., 2005, Public Philosophy: Essays on Morality in Politics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
–––, 2009, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do?, New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Scanlon, Thomas M., 1977 [2003], “Due Process”, NOMOS, 18: 93–125. Reprinted in his The Difficulty of
Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 42–69.
–––, 1998, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Schofield, Malcolm, 2006, Plato: Political Philosophy, (Founders of modern political and social thought),
New York: Oxford University Press.
Sen, Amartya, 1993 [2002], “Positional Objectivity”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 22(2): 126–145.
Reprinted in his Rationality and Freedom, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sidgwick, Henry, 1874, The Methods of Ethics, London: Macmillan & Co.; 7th edition, 1907, London:
Macmillan; 7th edition reprinted (with a foreword by John Rawls) by Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981.
Smith, Adam, 1776 [2000], The Wealth of Nations, New York: Modern Library.

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 19/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Smith, Thomas W., 1999, “Aristotle on the Conditions for and the Limits of the Common Good”, American
Political Science Review, 93(3): 625–636. doi:10.2307/2585578
Taylor, Charles, 1984 [1985], “Kant’s Theory of Freedom”, in Conceptions of Liberty in Political
Philosophy, Zbigniew A. Pelczynski and John Gray (eds), New York: St. Martin's Press: 100–121.
Reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, (Philosophical Papers, volume 2), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 318–338. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139173490.013
Taylor, Michael, 1987, The Possibility of Cooperation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tocqueville, Alexis de, 1835–1840, Democracy in America (De la démocratie en Amérique), J.P. Mayer (ed.)
and George Lawrence (trans.), 2 volumes, New York: Harper & Rowe, 1966.
Vlastos, Gregory, 1999, “The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato”, in Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion,
and the Soul, Gail Fine, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ch. 5.
Waldron, Jeremy, 1988, “When Justice Replaces Affection: The Need for Rights”, Harvard Journal of Law
& Public Policy, 11(3): 625–648. Reprinted in Waldron 1993.
–––, 1990 [1993], “Rights and Majorities: Rousseau Revisited”, NOMOS, 32: 44–75. Reprinted in Waldron
1993.
–––, 1993, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Walzer, Michael, 1970, Obligations: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
–––, 1983, Spheres of Justice, New York: Basic Books.
Williams, Bernard, 1973, “A Critique of Utilitarianism”, in Utilitarianism: For and Against, J.J.C. Smart and
Bernard Williams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 82–118. Reprinted as
“Consequentialism and Integrity” in Consequentialism and its Critics, Samuel Scheffler (ed.), Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1988, pp. 20–50.

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources


Simply philosophy, a blog with a good Ted Talk on the economy for the common good.
The Concept of the Common Good, working paper by Maximilian Jaede (University of Edinburgh), at
the British Academy project.
The Common Good, Section II of Article 2, from Part Three, Section One, Chapter Two of Catechism
of the Catholic Church, maintained by the Vatican. (Contains an important religious statement about
the common good.)
Catechism Commentary: The Common Good, post by David Cloutier (Theology, Catholic University
of America) at Catholic Moral Theology website.
Economy for the Common Good, a volunteer organization that advocates a model for a market
economy organized around the idea of the common good.
The Economy for the Common Good, paper by Christian Felber (Vienna University of Economics and
Business) and Gus Hagelberg (Coordinator for International Expansion of the Economy for the
Common Good), at the Next System Project website.
Catholic Healthcare and the Common Good, by Rev. Charles E. Bouchard, OP, S.T.D., at the Catholic
Health Association website. (Catholic statement about the common good in the context of doctor-
patient relations.)
Government And The Common Good, a resolution by the American Federation of Teachers.

Related Entries

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 20/21
25/02/2021 The Common Good (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Spring 2018 Edition)

Aristotle | communitarianism | democracy | friendship | justice | justice: distributive | public goods | Rawls,
John | republicanism | Rousseau, Jean Jacques

Copyright © 2018 by
Waheed Hussain <waheed.hussain@utoronto.ca>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.


Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2016 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for
the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ 21/21

You might also like